category
stringclasses 27
values | case
stringlengths 11
90
| case_link
stringlengths 48
57
| document
stringlengths 1.58k
697k
| summary
stringlengths 153
2.35k
|
---|---|---|---|---|
Free Speech | Cantwell v. Connecticut | https://supreme.justia.com/cases/federal/us/310/296/ | U.S. Supreme Court Cantwell v. Connecticut, 310
U.S. 296 (1940) Cantwell v.
Connecticut No. 632 Argued March 29, 1940 Decided May 20, 1940 310
U.S. 296 APPEAL FROM AND CERTIORARI TO THE
SUPREME COURT OF ERRORS OF
CONNECTICUT Syllabus 1. The fundamental concept of liberty embodied in the Fourteenth
Amendment embraces the liberties guaranteed by the First Amendment.
P. 310 U. S.
303 .
2. The enactment by a State of any law respecting an
establishment of religion or prohibiting the free exercise thereof
is forbidden by the Fourteenth Amendment. P. 310 U. S.
303 .
3. Under the constitutional guaranty, freedom of conscience and
of religious belief is absolute; although freedom to act in the
exercise of religion is subject to regulation for the protection of
society. Such regulation, however, in attaining a permissible end,
must not unduly infringe the protected freedom. Pp. 310 U. S.
303 -304.
4. A state statute which forbids any person to solicit money or
valuables for any alleged religious cause, unless a certificate
therefor shall first have been procured from a designated official,
who is required to determine whether such cause is a religious one
and who may withhold his approval if he determines that it is not,
is a previous restraint upon the free exercise of religion, and a
deprivation of liberty without due process of law in violation of
the Fourteenth Amendment. P. 310 U. S.
304 .
So held as it was applied to persons engaged in
distributing literature purporting to be religious, and soliciting
contributions to be used for the publication of such
literature.
A State constitutionally may, by general and nondiscriminatory
legislation, regulate the time, place and manner of soliciting upon
its streets, and of holding meetings thereon, and may in other
respects safeguard the peace, good order and comfort of the
community. Page 310 U. S. 297 The statute here, however, is not such a regulation. If a
certificate is issued, solicitation is permitted without other
restriction; but if a certificate is denied, solicitation is
altogether prohibited.
5. The fact that arbitrary or capricious action by the licensing
officer is subject to judicial review cannot validate the statute.
A previous restraint by judicial decision after trial is as
obnoxious under the Constitution as restraint by administrative
action. P. 310 U. S.
306 .
6. The common law offense of breach of the peace may be
committed not only by acts of violence, but also by acts and words
likely to produce violence in others. P. 310 U. S.
308 .
7. Defendant, while on a public street endeavoring to interest
passerby in the purchase of publications, or in making
contributions, in the interest of what he believed to be true
religion, induced individuals to listen to the playing of a
phonograph record describing the publications. The record contained
a verbal attack upon the religious denomination of which the
listeners were members, provoking their indignation and a desire on
their part to strike the defendant, who thereupon picked up his
books and phonograph and went on his way. There was no showing that
defendant's deportment was noisy, truculent, overbearing, or
offensive; nor was it claimed that he intended to insult or affront
the listeners by playing the record; nor was it shown that the
sound of the phonograph disturbed persons living nearby, drew a
crowd, or impeded traffic. Held, that defendant's conviction of the common law
offense of breach of the peace was violative of constitutional
guarantees of religious liberty and freedom of speech. Pp. 310 U. S. 307 et seq. 126 Conn. 1; 8 A.2d 533, reversed.
APPEAL from, and certiorari (309 U.S. 626) to review, a judgment
which sustained the conviction of all the defendants on one count
of an information and the conviction of one of the defendants on
another count. The convictions were challenged as denying the
constitutional rights of the defendants. Page 310 U. S. 300 MR. JUSTICE ROBERTS delivered the opinion of the Court.
Newton Cantwell and his two sons, Jesse and Russell, members of
a group known as Jehovah's Witnesses and claiming to be ordained
ministers, were arrested in New Haven, Connecticut, and each was
charged by information in five counts, with statutory and common
law offenses. After trial in the Court of Common Pleas of New Haven
County, each of them was convicted on the third count, which
charged a violation of § 294 of the General Statutes of
Connecticut, [ Footnote 1 ] and
on the fifth count, which charged commission of the common law
offense of inciting a breach of the peace. On appeal to the Supreme
Court, the conviction of all three on the third count was affirmed.
The conviction of Jesse Cantwell on the fifth count was also
affirmed, but the conviction of Newton and Russell on that count
was reversed, and a new trial ordered as to them. [ Footnote 2 ]
By demurrers to the information, by requests for rulings of law
at the trial, and by their assignments of error in the State
Supreme Court, the appellants pressed the contention that the
statute under which the third count was drawn was offensive to the
due process clause of the Fourteenth Amendment because, on its face
and as construed and applied, it denied them freedom of speech and
prohibited their free exercise of religion. In like manner, Page 310 U. S. 301 they made the point that they could not be found guilty on the
fifth count without violation of the Amendment.
We have jurisdiction on appeal from the judgments on the third
count, as there was drawn in question the validity of a state
statute under the Federal Constitution and the decision was in
favor of validity. Since the conviction on the fifth count was not
based upon a statute, but presents a substantial question under the
Federal Constitution, we granted the writ of certiorari in respect
of it.
The facts adduced to sustain the convictions on the third count
follow. On the day of their arrest, the appellants were engaged in
going singly from house to house on Cassius Street in New Haven.
They were individually equipped with a bag containing books and
pamphlets on religious subjects, a portable phonograph, and a set
of records, each of which, when played, introduced, and was a
description of, one of the books. Each appellant asked the person
who responded to his call for permission to play one of the
records. If permission was granted, he asked the person to buy the
book described, and, upon refusal, he solicited such contribution
towards the publication of the pamphlets as the listener was
willing to make. If a contribution was received, a pamphlet was
delivered upon condition that it would be read.
Cassius Street is in a thickly populated neighborhood where
about ninety percent of the residents are Roman Catholics. A
phonograph record, describing a book entitled "Enemies," included
an attack on the Catholic religion. None of the persons interviewed
were members of Jehovah's Witnesses.
The statute under which the appellants were charged
provides:
"No person shall solicit money, services, subscriptions or any
valuable thing for any alleged religious, charitable Page 310 U. S. 302 or philanthropic cause, from other than a member of the
organization for whose benefit such person is soliciting or within
the county in which such person or organization is located unless
such cause shall have been approved by the secretary of the public
welfare council. Upon application of any person in behalf of such
cause, the secretary shall determine whether such cause is a
religious one or is a bona fide object of charity or philanthropy
and conforms to reasonable standards of efficiency and integrity,
and, if he shall so find, shall approve the same and issue to the
authority in charge a certificate to that effect. Such certificate
may be revoked at any time. Any person violating any provision of
this section shall be fined not more than one hundred dollars or
imprisoned not more than thirty days or both."
The appellants claimed that their activities were not within the
statute, but consisted only of distribution of books, pamphlets,
and periodicals. The State Supreme Court construed the finding of
the trial court to be that,
"in addition to the sale of the books and the distribution of
the pamphlets, the defendants were also soliciting contributions or
donations of money for an alleged religious cause, and thereby came
within the purview of the statute."
It overruled the contention that the Act, as applied to the
appellants, offends the due process clause of the Fourteenth
Amendment because it abridges or denies religious freedom and
liberty of speech and press. The court stated that it was the
solicitation that brought the appellants within the sweep of the
Act, and not their other activities in the dissemination of
literature. It declared the legislation constitutional as an effort
by the State to protect the public against fraud and imposition in
the solicitation of funds for what purported to be religious,
charitable, or philanthropic causes.
The facts which were held to support the conviction of Jesse
Cantwell on the fifth count were that he stopped Page 310 U. S. 303 two men in the street, asked, and received, permission to play a
phonograph record, and played the record "Enemies," which attacked
the religion and church of the two men, who were Catholics. Both
were incensed by the contents of the record, and were tempted to
strike Cantwell unless he went away. On being told to be on his
way, he left their presence. There was no evidence that he was
personally offensive or entered into any argument with those he
interviewed.
The court held that the charge was not assault or breach of the
peace or threats on Cantwell's part, but invoking or inciting
others to breach of the peace, and that the facts supported the
conviction of that offense. First. We hold that the statute, a construed and
applied to the appellants, deprives them of their liberty without
due process of law in contravention of the Fourteenth Amendment.
The fundamental concept of liberty embodied in that Amendment
embraces the liberties guaranteed by the First Amendment. [ Footnote 3 ] The First Amendment
declares that Congress shall make no law respecting an
establishment of religion or prohibiting the free exercise thereof.
The Fourteenth Amendment has rendered the legislatures of the
states as incompetent as Congress to enact such laws. The
constitutional inhibition of legislation on the subject of religion
has a double aspect. On the one hand, it forestalls compulsion by
law of the acceptance of any creed or the practice of any form of
worship. Freedom of conscience and freedom to adhere to such
religious organization or form of worship as the individual may
choose cannot be restricted by law. On the other hand, it
safeguards the free exercise of the chosen form of religion. Thus,
the Amendment embraces two concepts -- freedom to believe and
freedom to act. The first is absolute, but, in the nature of
things, the Page 310 U. S. 304 second cannot be. Conduct remains subject to regulation for the
protection of society. [ Footnote
4 ] The freedom to act must have appropriate definition to
preserve the enforcement of that protection. In every case, the
power to regulate must be so exercised as not, in attaining a
permissible end, unduly to infringe the protected freedom. No one
would contest the proposition that a State may not, by statute,
wholly deny the right to preach or to disseminate religious views.
Plainly, such a previous and absolute restraint would violate the
terms of the guarantee. [ Footnote
5 ] It is equally clear that a State may, by general and
nondiscriminatory legislation, regulate the times, the places, and
the manner of soliciting upon its streets, and of holding meetings
thereon, and may in other respects safeguard the peace, good order,
and comfort of the community without unconstitutionally invading
the liberties protected by the Fourteenth Amendment. The appellants
are right in their insistence that the Act in question is not such
a regulation. If a certificate is procured, solicitation is
permitted without restraint, but, in the absence of a certificate,
solicitation is altogether prohibited.
The appellants urge that to require them to obtain a certificate
as a condition of soliciting support for their views amounts to a
prior restraint on the exercise of their religion within the
meaning of the Constitution. The State insists that the Act, as
construed by the Supreme Court of Connecticut, imposes no previous
restraint upon the dissemination of religious views or teaching,
but merely safeguards against the perpetration of frauds under the
cloak of religion. Conceding that this is so, the question remains
whether the method adopted by Connecticut to Page 310 U. S. 305 that end transgresses the liberty safeguarded by the
Constitution.
The general regulation, in the public interest, of solicitation,
which does not involve any religious test and does not unreasonably
obstruct or delay the collection of funds is not open to any
constitutional objection, even though the collection be for a
religious purpose. Such regulation would not constitute a
prohibited previous restraint on the free exercise of religion or
interpose an inadmissible obstacle to its exercise.
It will be noted, however, that the Act requires an application
to the secretary of the public welfare council of the State; that
he is empowered to determine whether the cause is a religious one,
and that the issue of a certificate depends upon his affirmative
action. If he finds that the cause is not that of religion, to
solicit for it becomes a crime. He is not to issue a certificate as
a matter of course. His decision to issue or refuse it involves
appraisal of facts, the exercise of judgment, and the formation of
an opinion. He is authorized to withhold his approval if he
determines that the cause is not a religious one. Such a censorship
of religion as the means of determining its right to survive is a
denial of liberty protected by the First Amendment and included in
the liberty which is within the protection of the Fourteenth.
The State asserts that, if the licensing officer acts
arbitrarily, capriciously, or corruptly, his action is subject to
judicial correction. Counsel refer to the rule prevailing in
Connecticut that the decision of a commission or an administrative
official will be reviewed upon a claim that
"it works material damage to individual or corporate rights, or
invades or threatens such rights, or is so unreasonable as to
justify judicial intervention, or is not consonant with justice, or
that a legal duty has not Page 310 U. S. 306 been performed. [ Footnote
6 ]"
It is suggested that the statute is to be read as requiring the
officer to issue a certificate unless the cause in question is
clearly not a religious one, and that, if he violates his duty, his
action will be corrected by a court.
To this suggestion there are several sufficient answers. The
line between a discretionary and a ministerial act is not always
easy to mark, and the statute has not been construed by the state
court to impose a mere ministerial duty on the secretary of the
welfare council. Upon his decision as to the nature of the cause
the right to solicit depends. Moreover, the availability of a
judicial remedy for abuses in the system of licensing still leaves
that system one of previous restraint which, in the field of free
speech and press, we have held inadmissible. A statute authorizing
previous restraint upon the exercise of the guaranteed freedom by
judicial decision after trial is as obnoxious to the Constitution
as one providing for like restraint by administrative action.
[ Footnote 7 ]
Nothing we have said is intended even remotely to imply that,
under the cloak of religion, persons may, with impunity, commit
frauds upon the public. Certainly penal laws are available to
punish such conduct. Even the exercise of religion may be at some
slight inconvenience in order that the State may protect its
citizens from injury. Without doubt, a State may protect its
citizens from fraudulent solicitation by requiring a stranger in
the community, before permitting him publicly to solicit funds for
any purpose, to establish his identity and his authority to act for
the cause which he purports to represent. [ Footnote 8 ] The State is likewise free to regulate the
time Page 310 U. S. 307 and manner of solicitation generally, in the interest of public
safety, peace, comfort or convenience. But to condition the
solicitation of aid for the perpetuation of religious views or
systems upon a license, the grant of which rests in the exercise of
a determination by state authority as to what is a religious cause,
is to lay a forbidden burden upon the exercise of liberty protected
by the Constitution. Second. We hold that, in the circumstances disclosed,
the conviction of Jesse Cantwell on the fifth count must be set
aside. Decision as to the lawfulness of the conviction demands the
weighing of two conflicting interests. The fundamental law declares
the interest of the United States that the free exercise of
religion be not prohibited and that freedom to communicate
information and opinion be not abridged. The State of Connecticut
has an obvious interest in the preservation and protection of peace
and good order within her borders. We must determine whether the
alleged protection of the State's interest, means to which end
would, in the absence of limitation by the Federal Constitution,
lie wholly within the State's discretion, has been pressed, in this
instance, to a point where it has come into fatal collision with
the overriding interest protected by the federal compact.
Conviction on the fifth count was not pursuant to a statute
evincing a legislative judgment that street discussion of religious
affairs, because of its tendency to provoke disorder, should be
regulated, or a judgment that the playing of a phonograph on the
streets should in the interest of comfort or privacy be limited or
prevented. Violation of an Act exhibiting such a legislative
judgment and narrowly drawn to prevent the supposed evil would pose
a question differing from that we must here answer. [ Footnote 9 ] Such a declaration of the State's
policy Page 310 U. S. 308 would weigh heavily in any challenge of the law as infringing
constitutional limitations. Here, however, the judgment is based on
a common law concept of the most general and undefined nature. The
court below has held that the petitioner's conduct constituted the
commission of an offense under the state law, and we accept its
decision as binding upon us to that extent.
The offense known as breach of the peace embraces a great
variety of conduct destroying or menacing public order and
tranquility. It includes not only violent acts, but acts and words
likely to produce violence in others. No one would have the
hardihood to suggest that the principle of freedom of speech
sanctions incitement to riot, or that religious liberty connotes
the privilege to exhort others to physical attack upon those
belonging to another sect. When clear and present danger of riot,
disorder, interference with traffic upon the public streets, or
other immediate threat to public safety, peace, or order appears,
the power of the State to prevent or punish is obvious. Equally
obvious is it that a State may not unduly suppress free
communication of views, religious or other, under the guise of
conserving desirable conditions. Here we have a situation analogous
to a conviction under a statute sweeping in a great variety of
conduct under a general and indefinite characterization, and
leaving to the executive and judicial branches too wide a
discretion in its application.
Having these considerations in mind, we note that Jesse
Cantwell, on April 26, 1938, was upon a public street, where he had
a right to be and where he had a right peacefully to impart his
views to others. There is no showing that his deportment was noisy,
truculent, overbearing or offensive. He requested of two
pedestrians permission to play to them a phonograph record. The
permission was granted. It is not claimed that he Page 310 U. S. 309 intended to insult or affront the hearers by playing the record.
It is plain that he wished only to interest them in his propaganda.
The sound of the phonograph is not shown to have disturbed
residents of the street, to have drawn a crowd, or to have impeded
traffic. Thus far, he had invaded no right or interest of the
public, or of the men accosted.
The record played by Cantwell embodies a general attack on all
organized religious systems as instruments of Satan and injurious
to man; it then singles out the Roman Catholic Church for
strictures couched in terms which naturally would offend not only
persons of that persuasion, but all others who respect the honestly
held religious faith of their fellows. The hearers were, in fact,
highly offended. One of them said he felt like hitting Cantwell,
and the other that he was tempted to throw Cantwell off the street.
The one who testified he felt like hitting Cantwell said, in answer
to the question "Did you do anything else or have any other
reaction?" "No, sir, because he said he would take the victrola,
and he went." The other witness testified that he told Cantwell he
had better get off the street before something happened to him, and
that was the end of the matter, as Cantwell picked up his books and
walked up the street.
Cantwell's conduct, in the view of the court below, considered
apart from the effect of his communication upon his hearers, did
not amount to a breach of the peace. One may, however, be guilty of
the offense if he commit acts or make statements likely to provoke
violence and disturbance of good order, even though no such
eventuality be intended. Decisions to this effect are many, but
examination discloses that, in practically all, the provocative
language which was held to amount to a breach of the peace
consisted of profane, indecent, or abusive remarks directed to the
person of the hearer. Resort to epithets or Page 310 U. S. 310 personal abuse is not in any proper sense communication of
information or opinion safeguarded by the Constitution, and its
punishment as a criminal act would raise no question under that
instrument.
We find in the instant case no assault or threatening of bodily
harm, no truculent bearing, no intentional discourtesy, no personal
abuse. On the contrary, we find only an effort to persuade a
willing listener to buy a book or to contribute money in the
interest of what Cantwell, however misguided others may think him,
conceived to be true religion.
In the realm of religious faith, and in that of political
belief, sharp differences arise. In both fields the tenets of one
man may seem the rankest error to his neighbor. To persuade others
to his own point of view, the pleader, as we know, at times resorts
to exaggeration, to vilification of men who have been, or are,
prominent in church or state, and even to false statement. But the
people of this nation have ordained, in the light of history, that,
in spite of the probability of excesses and abuses, these liberties
are, in the long view, essential to enlightened opinion and right
conduct on the part of the citizens of a democracy.
The essential characteristic of these liberties is that, under
their shield, many types of life, character, opinion and belief can
develop unmolested and unobstructed. Nowhere is this shield more
necessary than in our own country, for a people composed of many
races and of many creeds. There are limits to the exercise of these
liberties. The danger in these times from the coercive activities
of those who in the delusion of racial or religious conceit would
incite violence and breaches of the peace in order to deprive
others of their equal right to the exercise of their liberties, is
emphasized by events familiar to all. These and other
transgressions of those limits the States appropriately may
punish. Page 310 U. S. 311 Although the contents of the record not unnaturally aroused
animosity, we think that, in the absence of a statute narrowly
drawn to define and punish specific conduct as constituting a clear
and present danger to a substantial interest of the State, the
petitioner's communication, considered in the light of the
constitutional guarantees, raised no such clear and present menace
to public peace and order as to render him liable to conviction of
the common law offense in question. [ Footnote 10 ]
The judgment affirming the convictions on the third and fifth
counts is reversed, and the cause is remanded for further
proceedings not inconsistent with this opinion. Reversed. [ Footnote 1 ]
General Statutes § 6294, as amended by § 860d of the 1937
supplement.
[ Footnote 2 ]
126 Conn. 1, 8 A.2d 533.
[ Footnote 3 ] Schneider v. State, 308 U. S. 147 , 308 U. S.
160 .
[ Footnote 4 ] Reynolds v. United States, 98 U. S.
145 ; Davis v. Beason, 133 U.
S. 333 .
[ Footnote 5 ] Compare Near v. Minnesota, 283 U.
S. 697 , 283 U. S.
713 .
[ Footnote 6 ] Woodmont Assn. v. Milford, 85 Conn. 517, 522; 84 A.
307, 310; see also Connecticut Co. v. Norwalk, 89 Conn.
528, 531; 94 A. 992.
[ Footnote 7 ] Near v. Minnesota, 283 U. S. 697 .
[ Footnote 8 ] Compare Lewis Publishing Co. v. Morgan, 229 U.
S. 288 , 229 U. S.
306 -310; New York ex rel. Bryant v. Zimmerman, 278 U. S. 63 , 278 U. S.
72 .
[ Footnote 9 ] Compare Gitlow v. New York, 268 U.
S. 652 , 268 U. S.
670 -671; Thornhill v. Alabama, ante, pp. 310 U. S.
98 -105.
[ Footnote 10 ] Compare Schenck v. United States, 249 U. S.
47 , 249 U. S. 52 ; Herndon v. Lowry, 301 U. S. 242 , 301 U. S. 256 ; Thornhill v. Alabama, ante, p. 310 U. S. 88 . | In Cantwell v. Connecticut, the Supreme Court ruled that a state law prohibiting the solicitation of money for any alleged religious cause without a government-issued certificate is unconstitutional. The Court held that this law violated the Fourteenth Amendment, which includes the liberties guaranteed by the First Amendment, such as freedom of religion and speech. The Court also affirmed that while states can regulate the time, place, and manner of soliciting and holding meetings, they cannot unduly infringe on these protected freedoms. Additionally, the Court discussed the common law offense of breach of the peace, which can include acts and words likely to produce violence in others. In this case, the defendant's actions, though arousing animosity, did not pose a clear and present danger to public peace and order, and thus did not constitute a breach of the peace. |
Free Speech | Chaplinsky v. New Hampshire | https://supreme.justia.com/cases/federal/us/315/568/ | U.S. Supreme Court Chaplinsky v. New Hampshire, 315
U.S. 568 (1942) Chaplinsky v. New
Hampshire No. 255 Argued February 5,
1942 Decided March 9, 1942 315
U.S. 568 APPEAL FROM THE SUPREME COURT OF
NEW HAMPSHIRE Syllabus 1. That part of c. 378, § 2, of the Public Law of New Hampshire
which forbids under penalty that any person shall address "any
offensive, derisive or annoying word to any other person who is
lawfully in any street or other public place," or "call him by any
offensive or derisive name," was construed by the Supreme Court of
the State, in this case and before this case arose, as limited to
the use in a public place of words directly tending to cause a
breach of the peace by provoking the person addressed to acts of
violence. Held: (1) That, so construed, it is sufficiently definite and specific
to comply with requirements of due process of law. P. 315 U. S.
573 .
(2) That, as applied to a person who, on a public street,
addressed another as a "damned Fascist" and a "damned racketeer,"
it does not substantially or unreasonably impinge upon freedom of
speech. P. 315 U.S.
574 .
(3) The refusal of the state court to admit evidence offered by
the defendant tending to prove provocation and evidence bearing on
the truth or falsity of the utterances charged is open to no
constitutional objection. P. 315
U.S. 574 .
2. The Court notices judicially that the appellations "damned
racketeer" and "damned Fascist" are epithets likely to provoke the
average person to retaliation, and thereby cause a breach of the
peace. P. 315 U.S. 574 91 N.H. 310, 18 A.2d 754, affirmed.
APPEAL from a judgment affirming a conviction under a state law
denouncing the use of offensive words when addressed by one person
to another in a public place. Page 315 U. S. 569 MR. JUSTICE MURPHY delivered the opinion of the Court.
Appellant, a member of the sect known as Jehovah's Witnesses,
was convicted in the municipal court of Rochester, New Hampshire,
for violation of Chapter 378, § 2, of the Public Laws of New
Hampshire:
"No person shall address any offensive, derisive or annoying
word to any other person who is lawfully in any street or other
public place, nor call him by any offensive or derisive name, nor
make any noise or exclamation in his presence and hearing with
intent to deride, offend or annoy him, or to prevent him from
pursuing his lawful business or occupation."
The complaint charged that appellant,
"with force and arms, in a certain public place in said city of
Rochester, to-wit, on the public sidewalk on the easterly side of
Wakefield Street, near unto the entrance of the City Hall, did
unlawfully repeat the words following, addressed to the
complainant, that is to say, 'You are a God damned racketeer' and
'a damned Fascist and the whole government of Rochester are
Fascists or agents of Fascists,' the same being offensive, derisive
and annoying words and names."
Upon appeal, there was a trial de novo of appellant
before a jury in the Superior Court. He was found guilty, and the
judgment of conviction was affirmed by the Supreme Court of the
State. 91 N.H. 310, 18 A.2d 754.
By motions and exceptions, appellant raised the questions that
the statute was invalid under the Fourteenth Amendment of the
Constitution of the United States in that it placed an unreasonable
restraint on freedom of speech, freedom of the press, and freedom
of worship, and because it was vague and indefinite. These
contentions were overruled, and the case comes here on appeal.
There is no substantial dispute over the facts. Chaplinsky was
distributing the literature of his sect on the streets Page 315 U. S. 570 of Rochester on a busy Saturday afternoon. Members of the local
citizenry complained to the City Marshal, Bowering, that Chaplinsky
was denouncing all religion as a "racket." Bowering told them that
Chaplinsky was lawfully engaged, and then warned Chaplinsky that
the crowd was getting restless. Some time later, a disturbance
occurred and the traffic officer on duty at the busy intersection
started with Chaplinsky for the police station, but did not inform
him that he was under arrest or that he was going to be arrested.
On the way, they encountered Marshal Bowering, who had been advised
that a riot was under way and was therefore hurrying to the scene.
Bowering repeated his earlier warning to Chaplinsky, who then
addressed to Bowering the words set forth in the complaint.
Chaplinsky's version of the affair was slightly different. He
testified that, when he met Bowering, he asked him to arrest the
ones responsible for the disturbance. In reply, Bowering cursed him
and told him to come along. Appellant admitted that he said the
words charged in the complaint, with the exception of the name of
the Deity.
Over appellant's objection, the trial court excluded, as
immaterial, testimony relating to appellant's mission "to preach
the true facts of the Bible," his treatment at the hands of the
crowd, and the alleged neglect of duty on the part of the police.
This action was approved by the court below, which held that
neither provocation nor the truth of the utterance would constitute
a defense to the charge.
It is now clear that
"Freedom of speech and freedom of the press, which are protected
by the First Amendment from infringement by Congress, are among the
fundamental personal rights and liberties which are protected by
the Fourteenth Amendment from invasion by state Page 315 U. S. 571 action." Lovell v. Griffin, 303 U. S. 444 , 303 U. S. 450 .
[ Footnote 1 ] Freedom of worship
is similarly sheltered. Cantwell v. Connecticut, 310 U. S. 296 , 310 U. S.
303 .
Appellant assails the statute as a violation of all three
freedoms, speech, press and worship, but only an attack on the
basis of free speech is warranted. The spoken, not the written,
word is involved. And we cannot conceive that cursing a public
officer is the exercise of religion in any sense of the term. But
even if the activities of the appellant which preceded the incident
could be viewed as religious in character, and therefore entitled
to the protection of the Fourteenth Amendment, they would not cloak
him with immunity from the legal consequences for concomitant acts
committed in violation of a valid criminal statute. We turn,
therefore, to an examination of the statute itself.
Allowing the broadest scope to the language and purpose of the
Fourteenth Amendment, it is well understood that the right of free
speech is not absolute at all times and under all circumstances.
[ Footnote 2 ] There are certain
well defined and narrowly limited classes of speech, the
prevention Page 315 U. S. 572 and punishment of which have never been thought to raise any
Constitutional problem. [ Footnote
3 ] These include the lewd and obscene, the profane, the
libelous, and the insulting or "fighting" words -- those which, by
their very utterance, inflict injury or tend to incite an immediate
breach of the peace. [ Footnote
4 ] It has been well observed that such utterances are no
essential part of any exposition of ideas, and are of such slight
social value as a step to truth that any benefit that may be
derived from them is clearly outweighed by the social interest in
order and morality. [ Footnote
5 ]
"Resort to epithets or personal abuse is not in any proper sense
communication of information or opinion safeguarded by the
Constitution, and its punishment as a criminal act would raise no
question under that instrument." Cantwell v. Connecticut, 310 U.
S. 296 , 310 U. S.
309 -310.
The state statute here challenged comes to us authoritatively
construed by the highest court of New Hampshire. It has two
provisions -- the first relates to words or names addressed to
another in a public place; the second refers to noises and
exclamations. The court said:
"The two provisions are distinct. One may stand separately from
the other. Assuming, without holding, that the second were
unconstitutional, the first could stand if constitutional."
We accept that construction of severability and limit our
consideration to the first provision of the statute. [ Footnote 6 ] Page 315 U. S. 573 On the authority of its earlier decisions, the state court
declared that the statute's purpose was to preserve the public
peace, no words being "forbidden except such as have a direct
tendency to cause acts of violence by the persons to whom,
individually, the remark is addressed." [ Footnote 7 ] It was further said:
"The word 'offensive' is not to be defined in terms of what a
particular addressee thinks. . . . The test is what men of common
intelligence would understand would be words likely to cause an
average addressee to fight. . . . The English language has a number
of words and expressions which, by general consent, are 'fighting
words' when said without a disarming smile. . . . [S]uch words, as
ordinary men know, are likely to cause a fight. So are threatening,
profane or obscene revilings. Derisive and annoying words can be
taken as coming within the purview of the statute as heretofore
interpreted only when they have this characteristic of plainly
tending to excite the addressee to a breach of the peace. . . . The
statute, as construed, does no more than prohibit the face-to-face
words plainly likely to cause a breach of the peace by the
addressee, words whose speaking constitutes a breach of the peace
by the speaker -- including 'classical fighting words,' words in
current use less 'classical' but equally likely to cause violence,
and other disorderly words, including profanity, obscenity and
threats."
We are unable to say that the limited scope of the statute as
thus construed contravenes the Constitutional right of free
expression. It is a statute narrowly drawn and limited to define
and punish specific conduct lying within the domain of state power,
the use in a public place of words likely to cause a breach of the
peace. Cf. Cantwell v. Connecticut, 310 U.
S. 296 , 310 U. S. 311 ; Thornhill v.
Alabama , Page 315 U. S. 574 310 U. S. 88 , 310 U. S. 105 .
This conclusion necessarily disposes of appellant's contention that
the statute is so vague and indefinite as to render a conviction
thereunder a violation of due process. A statute punishing verbal
acts, carefully drawn so as not unduly to impair liberty of
expression, is not too vague for a criminal law. Cf. Fox v.
Washington 236 U.S.
273 , 236 U. S. 277 .
[ Footnote 8 ]
Nor can we say that the application of the statute to the facts
disclosed by the record substantially or unreasonably impinges upon
the privilege of free speech. Argument is unnecessary to
demonstrate that the appellations "damned racketeer" and "damned
Fascist" are epithets likely to provoke the average person to
retaliation, and thereby cause a breach of the peace.
The refusal of the state court to admit evidence of provocation
and evidence bearing on the truth or falsity of the utterances is
open to no Constitutional objection. Whether the facts sought to be
proved by such evidence constitute a defense to the charge, or may
be shown in mitigation, are questions for the state court to
determine. Our function is fulfilled by a determination that the
challenged statute, on its face and as applied, doe not contravene
the Fourteenth Amendment. Affirmed. [ Footnote 1 ] See also Bridges v. California, 314 U.
S. 252 ; Cantwell v. Connecticut, 310 U.
S. 296 , 310 U. S. 303 ; Thornhill v. Alabama, 310 U. S. 88 , 310 U. S. 95 ; Schneider v. State, 308 U. S. 147 , 308 U. S. 160 ; De Jonge v. Oregon, 299 U. S. 353 , 299 U. S. 364 ; Grosjean v. American Press Co., 297 U.
S. 233 , 297 U. S. 243 ; Near v. Minnesota, 283 U. S. 697 , 283 U. S. 707 ; Stromberg v. California, 283 U. S. 359 , 283 U. S. 368 ; Whitney v. California, 274 U. S. 357 , 274 U. S. 362 , 274 U. S. 371 , 274 U. S. 373 ; Gitlow v. New York, 268 U. S. 652 , 268 U. S.
666 .
Appellant here pitches his argument on the due process clause of
the Fourteenth Amendment.
[ Footnote 2 ] Schenck v. United States, 249 U. S.
47 ; Whitney v. California, 274 U.
S. 357 , 274 U. S. 373 (Brandeis, J., concurring); Stromberg v. California, 283 U. S. 359 ; Near v. Minnesota, 283 U. S. 697 ; De Jonge v. Oregon, 299 U. S. 353 ; Herndon v. Lowry, 301 U. S. 242 ; Cantwell v. Connecticut, 310 U. S. 296 .
[ Footnote 3 ]
The protection of the First Amendment, mirrored in the
Fourteenth, is not limited to the Blackstonian idea that freedom of
the press means only freedom from restraint prior to publication. Near v. Minnesota, 283 U. S. 697 , 283 U. S.
714 -715.
[ Footnote 4 ]
Chafee, Free Speech in the United States (1941), 149.
[ Footnote 5 ]
Chafee, op. cit., 150.
[ Footnote 6 ]
Since the complaint charged appellant only with violating the
first provision of the statute, the problem of Stromberg v.
California, 283 U. S. 359 , is
not present.
[ Footnote 7 ] State v. Brown, 68 N.H. 200, 38 A. 731; State v.
McConnell, 70 N.H. 294, 47 A. 267.
[ Footnote 8 ]
We do not have here the problem of Lanzetta v. New
Jersey, 306 U. S. 451 .
Even if the interpretative gloss placed on the statute by the court
below be disregarded, the statute had been previously construed as
intended to preserve the public peace by punishing conduct the
direct tendency of which was to provoke the person against whom it
was directed to acts of violence. State v. Brown, 68 N.H.
200, 38 A. 731 (1894). | Here is a summary of the Supreme Court case Chaplinsky v. New Hampshire (1942):
The case concerned a New Hampshire law that prohibited individuals from using offensive or derisive language towards others in public places. The appellant, a member of Jehovah's Witnesses, was convicted for violating this law after calling someone a "damned Fascist" and a "damned racketeer" on a public street.
The Supreme Court upheld the conviction, ruling that the law, as interpreted by the state court, was sufficiently clear and did not violate the appellant's freedom of speech rights. The Court agreed with the state court's interpretation that the law only prohibited words that directly incited violence or a breach of the peace.
The Court also held that the specific words used by the appellant were likely to provoke a violent response and cause a breach of the peace. Evidence of provocation or the truth of the appellant's statements was deemed irrelevant to the charge and posed no constitutional issue.
In conclusion, Chaplinsky v. New Hampshire set a precedent for regulating speech that is likely to incite violence, establishing the "fighting words" doctrine, which exempts such speech from First Amendment protection. |
Free Speech | Feiner v. New York | https://supreme.justia.com/cases/federal/us/340/315/ | U.S. Supreme Court Feiner v. New York, 340
U.S. 315 (1951) Feiner v. New York No. 93 Argued October 17,
1950 Decided January 15,
1951 340
U.S. 315 CERTIORARI TO THE COURT OF APPEALS
OF NEW YORK Syllabus Petitioner made an inflammatory speech to a mixed crowd of 75 or
80 Negroes and white people on a city street. He made derogatory
remarks about President Truman, the American Legion, and local
political officials, endeavored to arouse the Negroes against the
whites, and urged that Negroes rise up in arms and fight for equal
rights. The crowd, which blocked the sidewalk and overflowed into
the street, became restless; its feelings for and against the
speaker were rising, and there was at least one threat of violence.
After observing the situation for some time without interference,
police officers, in order to prevent a fight, thrice requested
petitioner to get off the box and stop speaking. After his third
refusal, and after he had been speaking over 30 minutes, they
arrested him, and he was convicted of violating § 722 of the Penal
Code of New York, which, in effect, forbids incitement of a breach
of the peace. The conviction was affirmed by two New York courts on
review. Held: The conviction is sustained against a claim that
it violated petitioner's right of free speech under the First and
Fourteenth Amendments. Pp. 340 U. S. 316 -321.
(a) Petitioner was neither arrested nor convicted for the making
or the content of his speech, but for the reaction which it
actually engendered. Pp. 340 U. S.
319 -320.
(b) The police cannot be used as an instrument for the
suppression of unpopular views; but, when a speaker passes the
bounds of argument or persuasion and undertakes incitement to riot,
the police are not powerless to prevent a breach of the peace. P. 340 U. S.
321 .
300 N.Y. 391, 91 N.E.2d 316, affirmed.
The case is stated in the first paragraph of the opinion. The
decision below is affirmed, p. 340 U. S.
321 . Page 340 U. S. 316 MR. CHIEF JUSTICE VINSON delivered the opinion of the Court.
Petitioner was convicted of the offense of disorderly conduct, a
misdemeanor under the New York penal laws, in the Court of Special
Sessions of the City of Syracuse and was sentenced to thirty days
in the county penitentiary. The conviction was affirmed by the
Onondaga County Court and the New York Court of Appeals, 300 N.Y.
391, 91 N.E.2d 316 (1950). The case is here on certiorari, 339 U.S.
962 (1950), petitioner having claimed that the conviction is in
violation of his right of free speech under the Fourteenth
Amendment.
In the review of state decisions where First Amendment rights
are drawn in question, we, of course, make an examination of the
evidence to ascertain independently whether the right has been
violated. Here, the trial judge, who heard the case without a jury,
rendered an oral decision at the end of the trial, setting forth
his determination of the facts upon which he found the petitioner
guilty. His decision indicated generally that he believed the
state's witnesses, and his summation of the testimony was used by
the two New York courts on review in stating the facts. Our
appraisal of the facts is therefore based upon the uncontroverted
facts and, where controversy exists, upon that testimony which the
trial judge did reasonably conclude to be true.
On the evening of March 8, 1949, petitioner Irving Feiner was
addressing an open-air meeting at the corner of South McBride and
Harrison Streets in the City of Syracuse. At approximately 6:30
p.m., the police received a telephone complaint concerning the
meeting, and two officers were detailed to investigate. One of
these officers went to the scene immediately, the other arriving
some twelve minutes later. They found a crowd of about seventy-five
or eighty people, both Negro and white, filling the sidewalk and
spreading out into the street. Petitioner, Page 340 U. S. 317 standing on a large wooden box on the sidewalk, was addressing
the crowd through a loud-speaker system attached to an automobile.
Although the purpose of his speech was to urge his listeners to
attend a meeting to be held that night in the Syracuse Hotel, in
its course, he was making derogatory remarks concerning President
Truman, the American Legion, the Mayor of Syracuse, and other local
political officials.
The police officers made no effort to interfere with
petitioner's speech, but were first concerned with the effect of
the crowd on both pedestrian and vehicular traffic. They observed
the situation from the opposite side of the street, noting that
some pedestrians were forced to walk in the street to avoid the
crowd. Since traffic was passing at the time, the officers
attempted to get the people listening to petitioner back on the
sidewalk. The crowd was restless, and there was some pushing,
shoving, and milling around. One of the officers telephoned the
police station from a nearby store, and then both policemen crossed
the street and mingled with the crowd without any intention of
arresting the speaker.
At this time, petitioner was speaking in a "loud, high-pitched
voice." He gave the impression that he was endeavoring to arouse
the Negro people against the whites, urging that they rise up in
arms and fight for equal rights. The statements before such a mixed
audience "stirred up a little excitement." Some of the onlookers
made remarks to the police about their inability to handle the
crowd, and at least one threatened violence if the police did not
act. There were others who appeared to be favoring petitioner's
arguments. Because of the feeling that existed in the crowd both
for and against the speaker, the officers finally "stepped in to
prevent it from resulting in a fight." One of the officers
approached the petitioner, not for the purpose of arresting him,
but to get him to break up the crowd. He asked petitioner to get
down Page 340 U. S. 318 off the box, but the latter refused to accede to his request and
continued talking. The officer waited for a minute and then
demanded that he cease talking. Although the officer had thus twice
requested petitioner to stop over the course of several minutes,
petitioner not only ignored him, but continued talking. During all
this time, the crowd was pressing closer around petitioner and the
officer. Finally, the officer told petitioner he was under arrest
and ordered him to get down from the box, reaching up to grab him.
Petitioner stepped down, announcing over the microphone that "the
law has arrived, and I suppose they will take over now." In all,
the officer had asked petitioner to get down off the box three
times over a space of four or five minutes. Petitioner had been
speaking for over a half hour.
On these facts, petitioner was specifically charged with
violation of § 722 of the Penal Law of New York, Mc.K.Consol.Laws,
c. 40, the pertinent part of which is set out in the margin.
[ Footnote 1 ] The bill of
particulars, demanded by petitioner and furnished by the State,
gave in detail the facts upon which the prosecution relied to
support the charge of disorderly conduct. Paragraph C is
particularly pertinent here:
"By ignoring and refusing to heed and obey reasonable police
orders issued at the time and place mentioned in the Information to
regulate and control said crowd and to prevent a breach or breaches
of the peace and to prevent injury to pedestrians Page 340 U. S. 319 attempting to use said walk, and being forced into the highway
adjacent to the place in question, and prevent injury to the public
generally."
We are not faced here with blind condonation by a state court of
arbitrary police action. Petitioner was accorded a full, fair
trial. The trial judge heard testimony supporting and contradicting
the judgment of the police officers that a clear danger of disorder
was threatened. After weighing this contradictory evidence, the
trial judge reached the conclusion that the police officers were
justified in taking action to prevent a breach of the peace. The
exercise of the police officers' proper discretionary power to
prevent a breach of the peace was thus approved by the trial court,
and later by two courts on review. [ Footnote 2 ] The courts below recognized petitioner's right
to hold a street meeting at this locality, to make use of
loudspeaking equipment in giving his speech, and to make derogatory
remarks concerning public officials and the American Legion. They
found that the officers in making the arrest were motivated solely
by a proper concern for the preservation of order and protection of
the general welfare, and that there was no evidence which could
lend color to a claim that the acts of the police were a cover for
suppression of petitioner's views and opinions. Petitioner was thus
neither arrested nor convicted for the Page 340 U. S. 320 making or the content of his speech. Rather, it was the reaction
which it actually engendered.
The language of Cantwell v. Connecticut, 310 U.
S. 296 (1940), is appropriate here.
"The offense known as breach of the peace embraces a great
variety of conduct destroying or menacing public order and
tranquility. It includes not only violent acts, but acts and words
likely to produce violence in others. No one would have the
hardihood to suggest that the principle of freedom of speech
sanctions incitement to riot, or that religious liberty connotes
the privilege to exhort others to physical attack upon those
belonging to another sect. When clear and present danger of riot,
disorder, interference with traffic upon the public streets, or
other immediate threat to public safety, peace, or order, appears,
the power of the State to prevent or punish is obvious."
310 U.S. at 310 U. S. 308 .
The findings of the New York courts as to the condition of the
crowd and the refusal of petitioner to obey the police requests,
supported as they are by the record of this case, are persuasive
that the conviction of petitioner for violation of public peace,
order, and authority does not exceed the bounds of proper state
police action. This Court respects, as it must, the interest of the
community in maintaining peace and order on its streets. Schneider v. State, 308 U. S. 147 , 308 U. S. 160 (1939); Kovacs v. Cooper, 336 U. S.
77 , 336 U. S. 82 (1949). We cannot say that the preservation of that interest here
encroaches on the constitutional rights of this petitioner.
We are well aware that the ordinary murmurings and objections of
a hostile audience cannot be allowed to silence a speaker, and are
also mindful of the possible danger of giving overzealous police
officials complete discretion to break up otherwise lawful public
meetings.
"A State may not unduly suppress free communication of views,
religious or other, under the guise of conserving desirable
conditions." Cantwell v. Connecticut, supra, at Page 340 U. S. 321 310 U. S. 308 .
But we are not faced here with such a situation. It is one thing to
say that the police cannot be used as an instrument for the
suppression of unpopular views, and another to say that when, as
here, the speaker passes the bounds of argument or persuasion and
undertakes incitement to riot, they are powerless to prevent a
breach of the peace. Nor, in this case, can we condemn the
considered judgment of three New York courts approving the means
which the police, faced with a crisis, used in the exercise of
their power and duty to preserve peace and order. The findings of
the state courts as to the existing situation and the imminence of
greater disorder, coupled with petitioner's deliberate defiance of
the police officers, convince us that we should not reverse this
conviction in the name of free speech. Affirmed. [For opinion of MR. JUSTICE FRANKFURTER, concurring in the
result, see ante, p. 340 U. S.
273 .]
[ Footnote 1 ]
"Section 722. Any person who, with intent to provoke a breach of
the peace, or whereby a breach of the peace may be occasioned,
commits any of the following acts shall be deemed to have committed
the offense of disorderly conduct: "
"1. Uses offensive, disorderly, threatening, abusive or
insulting language, conduct or behavior;"
"2. Acts in such a manner as to annoy, disturb, interfere with,
obstruct, or be offensive to others;"
"3. Congregates with others on a public street and refuses to
move on when ordered by the police. . . ."
[ Footnote 2 ]
The New York Court of Appeals said:
"An imminent danger of a breach of the peace, of a disturbance
of public order, perhaps even of riot, was threatened . . . ; the
defendant, as indicated above, disrupted pedestrian and vehicular
traffic on the sidewalk and street, and, with intent to provoke a
breach of the peace and with knowledge of the consequences, so
inflamed and agitated a mixed audience of sympathizers and
opponents that, in the judgment of the police officers present, a
clear danger of disorder and violence was threatened. Defendant
then deliberately refused to accede to the reasonable request of
the officer, made within the lawful scope of his authority, that
the defendant desist in the interest of public welfare and
safety."
300 N.Y. 391, 400, 402, 91 N.E.2d 316, 319, 321.
MR. JUSTICE BLACK, dissenting.
The record before us convinces me that petitioner, a young
college student, has been sentenced to the penitentiary for the
unpopular views he expressed [ Footnote
2/1 ] on matters of public interest while lawfully making a
street corner Page 340 U. S. 322 speech in Syracuse, New York. [ Footnote 2/2 ] Today's decision, however, indicates that
we must blind ourselves to this fact because the trial judge fully
accepted the testimony of the prosecution witnesses on all
important points. [ Footnote 2/3 ]
Many times in the past, this Court has said that, despite findings
below, we will examine the evidence for ourselves to ascertain
whether federally protected rights have been denied; otherwise,
review here would fail of its purpose in safeguarding
constitutional guarantees. [ Footnote
2/4 ] Even a partial Page 340 U. S. 323 abandonment of this rule marks a dark day for civil liberties in
our Nation.
But still more has been lost today. Even accepting every
"finding of fact" below, I think this conviction makes a mockery of
the free speech guarantees of the First and Fourteenth Amendments.
The end result of the affirmance here is to approve a simple and
readily available technique by which cities and states can, with
impunity, subject all speeches, political or otherwise, on streets
or elsewhere, to the supervision and censorship of the local
police. I will have no part or parcel in this holding, which I view
as a long step toward totalitarian authority.
Considering only the evidence which the state courts appear to
have accepted, the pertinent "facts" are: Syracuse city authorities
granted a permit for O. John Rogge, a former Assistant Attorney
General, to speak in a public school building on March 8, 1948, on
the subject of racial discrimination and civil liberties. On March
8th, however, Page 340 U. S. 324 the authorities cancelled the permit. The Young Progressives,
under whose auspices the meeting was scheduled, then arranged for
Mr. Rogge to speak at the Hotel Syracuse. The gathering on the
street where petitioner spoke was held to protest the cancellation
and to publicize the meeting at the hotel. In this connection,
petitioner used derogatory but not profane language with reference
to the city authorities, President Truman, and the American Legion.
After hearing some of these remarks, a policeman, who had been sent
to the meeting by his superiors, reported to Police Headquarters by
telephone. To whom he reported or what was said does not appear in
the record, but, after returning from the call, he and another
policeman started through the crowd toward petitioner. Both
officers swore they did not intend to make an arrest when they
started, and the trial court accepted their statements. They also
said, and the court believed, that they heard and saw "angry
mutterings," "pushing," "shoving and milling around" and
"restlessness." Petitioner spoke in a "loud, high-pitched voice."
He said that colored people "don't have equal rights, and they
should rise up in arms and fight for them." [ Footnote 2/5 ] One man who heard this told the officers
that, if they did not take that "S . . . O . . . B . . ." off the
box, he would. The officers then approached petitioner for the
first time. Page 340 U. S. 325 One of them first "asked" petitioner to get off the box, but
petitioner continued urging his audience to attend Rogge's speech.
The officer next "told" petitioner to get down, but he did not. The
officer finally "demanded" that petitioner get down, telling him he
was under arrest. Petitioner then told the crowd that "the law had
arrived, and would take over," and asked why he was arrested. The
officer first replied that the charge was "unlawful assembly," but
later changed the ground to "disorderly conduct." [ Footnote 2/6 ]
The Court's opinion apparently rests on this reasoning: the
policeman, under the circumstances detailed, could reasonably
conclude that serious fighting or even riot was imminent;
therefore, he could stop petitioner's speech to prevent a breach of
peace; accordingly, it was "disorderly conduct" for petitioner to
continue speaking in disobedience of the officer's request. As to
the existence of a dangerous situation on the street corner, it
seems far-fetched to suggest that the "facts" show any imminent
threat of riot or uncontrollable disorder. [ Footnote 2/7 ] It Page 340 U. S. 326 is neither unusual nor unexpected that some people at public
street meetings mutter, mill about, push, shove, or disagree, even
violently, with the speaker. Indeed, it is rare, where
controversial topics are discussed, that an out-door crowd does not
do some or all of these things. Nor does one isolated threat to
assault the speaker forebode disorder. Especially should the danger
be discounted where, as here, the person threatening was a man
whose wife and two small children accompanied him, and who, so far
as the record shows, was never close enough to petitioner to carry
out the threat.
Moreover, assuming that the "facts" did indicate a critical
situation, I reject the implication of the Court's opinion that the
police had no obligation to protect petitioner's constitutional
right to talk. The police, of course, have power to prevent
breaches of the peace. But if, in the name of preserving order,
they ever can interfere with a lawful public speaker, they first
must make all reasonable efforts to protect him. [ Footnote 2/8 ] Here, the policemen did not even
pretend to try to protect petitioner. According to the officers'
testimony, the crowd was restless, but there is Page 340 U. S. 327 no showing of any attempt to quiet it; pedestrians were forced
to walk into the street, but there was no effort to clear a path on
the sidewalk; one person threatened to assault petitioner, but the
officers did nothing to discourage this, when even a word might
have sufficed. Their duty was to protect petitioner's right to
talk, even to the extent of arresting the man who threatened to
interfere. [ Footnote 2/9 ] Instead,
they shirked that duty and acted only to suppress the right to
speak.
Finally, I cannot agree with the Court's statement that
petitioner's disregard of the policeman's unexplained request
amounted to such "deliberate defiance" as would justify an arrest
or conviction for disorderly conduct. On the contrary, I think that
the policeman's action was a "deliberate defiance" of ordinary
official duty, as well as of the constitutional right of free
speech. For, at least where time allows, courtesy and explanation
of commands are basic elements of good official conduct in a
democratic society. Here, petitioner was "asked," then "told," then
"commanded" to stop speaking, but a man making a lawful address is
certainly not required to be silent merely Page 340 U. S. 328 because an officer directs it. Petitioner was entitled to know
why he should cease doing a lawful act. Not once was he told. I
understand that people in authoritarian countries must obey
arbitrary orders. I had hoped that there was no such duty in the
United States.
In my judgment, today's holding means that, as a practical
matter, minority speakers can be silenced in any city. Hereafter,
despite the First and Fourteenth Amendments, the policeman's club
can take heavy toll of a current administration's public critics.
[ Footnote 2/10 ] Criticism of
public officials will be too dangerous for all but the most
courageous. [ Footnote 2/11 ] This
is true regardless of the fact that, in Page 340 U. S. 329 two other cases decided this day, Kunz v. New York, 340 U. S. 290 ; Niemotko v. Maryland, 340 U. S. 268 , a
majority, in obedience to past decisions of this Court, provides a
theoretical safeguard for freedom of speech. For whatever is
thought to be guaranteed in Kunz and Niemotko is
taken away by what is done here. The three cases, read together,
mean that, while previous restraints probably cannot be imposed on
an unpopular speaker, the police have discretion to silence him as
soon as the customary hostility to his views develops.
In this case, I would reverse the conviction, thereby adhering
to the great principles of the First and Fourteenth Amendments as
announced for this Court in 1940 by Mr. Justice Roberts:
"In the realm of religious faith, and in that of political
belief, sharp differences arise. In both fields, the tenets of one
man may seem the rankest error to his neighbor. To persuade others
to his own point of view, the pleader, as we know at times, resorts
to exaggeration, to vilification of men who have been, or are,
prominent in church or state, and even to false statement. But the
people of this nation have ordained in the light of history that,
in spite of the probability of excesses and abuses, these liberties
are, in the long view, essential to enlightened opinion and right
conduct on the part of the citizens of a democracy." Cantwell v. Connecticut, 310 U.
S. 296 , 310 U. S. 310 .
I regret my inability to persuade the Court not to retreat from
this principle.
[ Footnote 2/1 ]
The trial judge framed the question for decision as follows:
"The question here is what was said and what was done? And it
doesn't make any difference whether whatever was said was said with
a loudspeaker or not. There are acts and conduct an individual can
engage in when you don't even have to have a crowd gathered around
which would justify a charge of disorderly conduct. The question
is, what did this defendant say and do at that particular time, and
the Court must determine whether those facts, concerning what the
defendant did or said, are sufficient to support the charge."
There is no suggestion in the record that petitioner "did"
anything other than (1) speak and (2) continue for a short time to
invite people to a public meeting after a policeman had requested
him to stop speaking.
[ Footnote 2/2 ]
There was no charge that any city or state law prohibited such a
meeting at the place or time it was held. Evidence showed that it
was customary to hold public gatherings on that same corner every
Friday night, and the trial judge who convicted petitioner admitted
that he understood the meeting was a lawful one. Nor did the judge
treat the lawful meeting as unlawful because a crowd congregated on
the sidewalk. Consequently, any discussion of disrupted pedestrian
and vehicular traffic, while suggestive coloration, is immaterial
under the charge and conviction here.
It is implied in a concurring opinion that the use of sound
amplifiers in some way caused the meeting to become less lawful.
This fact, however, had nothing to do with the conviction of
petitioner. In sentencing him, the trial court said: "You had a
perfect right to appear there and to use that implement, the
loudspeaker. You had a right to have it in the street." See
also 340
U.S. 315 fn2/1|>note 1, supra. [ Footnote 2/3 ]
The trial court made no findings of fact as such. A decision was
rendered from the bench in which, among other things, the trial
judge expressed some views on the evidence. See 340
U.S. 315 fn2/11|>note 11, infra. [ Footnote 2/4 ]
In Norris v. Alabama, 294 U. S. 587 , the
evidence as to whether Negroes had been discriminated against in
the selection of grand juries was conflicting. Chief Justice
Hughes, writing for the Court, said at pages 294 U. S.
589 -590:
"The question is of the application of this established
principle [equal protection] to the facts disclosed by the record.
That the question is one of fact does not relieve us of the duty to
determine whether, in truth, a federal right has been denied. When
a federal right has been specially set up and claimed in a state
court, it is our province to inquire not merely whether it was
denied in express terms, but also whether it was denied in
substance and effect. If this requires an examination of evidence,
that examination must be made. Otherwise, review by this Court
would fail of its purpose in safeguarding constitutional rights.
Thus, whenever a conclusion of law of a state court as to a federal
right and findings of fact are so intermingled that the latter
control the former, it is incumbent upon us to analyze the facts in
order that the appropriate enforcement of the federal right may be
assured."
This same rule has been announced in the following cases, as
well as in numerous others: Truax v. Corrigan, 257 U. S. 312 , 257 U. S. 324 ; Hooven & Allison Co. v. Evatt, 324 U.
S. 652 , 324 U. S. 659 ; Chambers v. Florida, 309 U. S. 227 , 309 U. S. 228 ; Pierre v. Louisiana, 306 U. S. 354 , 306 U. S. 358 ; Pennekamp v. Florida, 328 U. S. 331 , 328 U. S. 335 ; Patton v. Mississippi, 332 U. S. 463 , 332 U. S. 466 ; Craig v. Harney, 331 U. S. 367 , 331 U. S. 373 ; Oyama v. California, 332 U. S. 633 , 332 U. S. 636 ; Pollock v. Williams, 322 U. S. 4 , 322 U. S. 13 ; Fay v. New York, 332 U. S. 261 , 332 U. S. 272 ; Akins v. Texas, 325 U. S. 398 , 325 U. S. 401 ; Kansas City Southern R. Co. v. C. H. Albers Comm'n Co., 223 U. S. 573 , 223 U. S. 591 ; First National Bank v. Hartford, 273 U.
S. 548 , 273 U. S. 552 ; Fiske v. Kansas, 274 U. S. 380 , 274 U. S. 385 ; Great Northern R. Co. v. Washington, 300 U.
S. 154 , 300 U. S.
165 -167. This Court has used varying phraseology in
stating the circumstances under which it would review state court
findings of fact, but it has not hesitated to make such review when
necessary to protect a federal right. Compare Great Northern R.
Co. v. Washington, supra, with Taylor v. Mississippi, 319 U. S. 583 , 319 U. S.
585 -586.
[ Footnote 2/5 ]
I am accepting this although I believe the record demonstrates
rather conclusively that petitioner did not use the phrase "in
arms" in the manner testified to by the officers. Reliable
witnesses swore that petitioner's statement was that his listeners
"could rise up and fight for their rights by going arm in arm to
the Hotel Syracuse, black and white alike, to hear John Rogge." The
testimony of neither of the two officers contained the phrase "in
arms" when they first testified on this subject; they added it only
after counsel for the prosecution was permitted by the court, over
petitioner's objection, to propound leading and suggestive
questions. In any event, the statement ascribed to petitioner by
the officers seems clearly rhetorical when read in context.
[ Footnote 2/6 ]
"A charge of using language likely to cause a breach of the
peace is a convenient catchall to hold unpopular soapbox orators."
Chafee, Free Speech in the United States 524. The related charge of
conducting a "disorderly house" has also been used to suppress and
punish minority views. For example, an English statute of 1799
classified as disorderly houses certain unlicensed places ("House,
Room, Field, or other Place") in which "any Lecture or Discourse
shall be publickly delivered, or any publick Debate shall be had on
any Subject . . . " or which was used "for the Purpose of reading
Books, Pamphlets, Newspapers, or other Publications. . . ." 39 Geo.
III, c. 79, § 15.
[ Footnote 2/7 ]
The belief of the New York Court of Appeals that the situation
on the street corner was critical is not supported by the record,
and accordingly should not be given much weight here. Two
illustrations will suffice: the Court of Appeals relied upon a
specific statement of one policeman that he interfered with Feiner
at a time when the crowd was "getting to the point where they would
be unruly." But this testimony was so patently inadmissible that it
was excluded by the trial judge in one of the rare instances where
the defendant received a favorable ruling. Secondly, the Court of
Appeals stated that, after Feiner had been warned by the police, he
continued to "blare out his provocative utterances over
loudspeakers to a milling, restless throng. . . ." I am unable to
find anything in the record to support this statement, unless the
unsworn arguments of the assistant district attorney are accepted
as evidence. The principal prosecution witness testified that,
after he asked Feiner to get down from the box, Feiner merely "kept
telling [the audience] to go to the Syracuse Hotel and hear John
Rogge." And this same witness even answered "No" to the highly
suggestive question which immediately followed, "Did he say
anything more about arming and fighting at that time?"
[ Footnote 2/8 ] Cf. Hague v. CIO, 307 U. S. 496 ; Terminiello v. Chicago, 337 U. S. 1 ; Sellers v. Johnson, 163 F.2d 877; see also summary of Brief for Committee on the Bill of Rights of the
American Bar Association as amicus curiae, Hague v. CIO,
supra, reprinted at 307 U.S. 678-682.
[ Footnote 2/9 ]
In Schneider v. State, 308 U.
S. 147 , we held that a purpose to prevent littering of
the streets was insufficient to justify an ordinance which
prohibited a person lawfully on the street from handing literature
to one willing to receive it. We said at page 308 U. S.
162 ,
"There are obvious methods of preventing littering. Amongst
these is the punishment of those who actually throw papers on the
streets."
In the present case, as well, the threat of one person to
assault a speaker does not justify suppression of the speech. There
are obvious available alternative methods of preserving public
order. One of these is to arrest the person who threatens an
assault. Cf. Dean Milk Co. v. Madison, 340 U.
S. 349 , in which the Court invalidates a municipal
health ordinance under the Commerce Clause because of a belief that
the city could have accomplished its purposes by reasonably
adequate alternatives. The Court certainly should not be less alert
to protect freedom of speech than it is to protect freedom of
trade.
[ Footnote 2/10 ]
Today the Court characterizes petitioner's speech as one
designed to incite riot, and approves suppression of his views.
There is an alarming similarity between the power thus possessed by
the Syracuse (or any other) police and that possessed by English
officials under an act passed by Parliament in 1795. In that year,
Justices of the Peace were authorized to arrest persons who spoke
in a manner which could be characterized as "inciting and stirring
up the People to Hatred or Contempt . . . " of the King or the
Government. 36 Geo. III, c. 8, § 7. This statute "was manifestly
intended to put an end forever to all popular discussion, either on
political or religious matters." 1 Buckle, History of Civilization
in England (2d London ed.) 350.
[ Footnote 2/11 ]
That petitioner and the philosophy he espoused were objects of
local antagonism appears clearly from the printed record in this
case. Even the trial judge in his decision made no attempt to
conceal his contempt for petitioner's views. He seemed outraged by
petitioner's criticism of public officials and the American Legion.
Moreover, the judge gratuitously expressed disapproval of O. John
Rogge by quoting derogatory statements concerning Mr. Rogge which
had appeared in the Syracuse press. The court approved the view
that freedom of speech should be denied those who pit "class
against class . . . and religion against religion." And, after
announcing its decision, the court persistently refused to grant
bail pending sentence.
Although it is unnecessary for me to reach the question of
whether the trial below met procedural due process standards, I
cannot agree with the opinion of the Court that "Petitioner was
accorded a full, fair trial."
MR. JUSTICE DOUGLAS, with whom MR. JUSTICE MINTON concurs,
dissenting.
Feiner, a university student, made a speech on a street corner
in Syracuse, New York, on March 8, 1949. The purpose of the speech
was to publicize a meeting of the Page 340 U. S. 330 Young Progressives of America to be held that evening. A permit
authorizing the meeting to be held in a public school auditorium
had been revoked, and the meeting shifted to a local hotel.
Feiner delivered his speech in a small shopping area in a
predominantly colored residential section of Syracuse. He stood on
a large box and spoke over loudspeakers mounted on a car. His
audience was composed of about 75 people, colored and white. A few
minutes after he started, two police officers arrived.
The speech was mainly devoted to publicizing the evening's
meeting and protecting the revocation of the permit. It also
touched on various public issues. The following are the only
excerpts revealed by the record:
"Mayor Costello [of Syracuse] is a champagne-sipping bum; he
does not speak for the negro people."
"The 15th Ward is run by corrupt politicians, and there are
horse rooms operating there."
"President Truman is a bum."
"Mayor O'Dwyer is a bum."
"The American Legion is a Nazi Gestapo."
"The negroes don't have equal rights; they should rise up in
arms and fight for their rights."
There was some pushing and shoving in the crowd and some angry
muttering. That is the testimony of the police. But there were no
fights and no "disorder," even by the standards of the police.
There was not even any heckling of the speaker.
But after Feiner has been speaking about 20 minutes, a man said
to the police officers, "If you don't get that son of a bitch off,
I will go over and get him off there myself." It was then that the
police ordered Feiner to stop speaking; when he refused, they
arrested him.
Public assemblies and public speech occupy an important role in
American life. One high function of Page 340 U. S. 331 the police is to protect these lawful gatherings so that the
speakers may exercise their constitutional rights. When unpopular
causes are sponsored from the public platform, there will commonly
be mutterings and unrest and heckling from the crowd. When a
speaker mounts a platform it is not unusual to find him resorting
to exaggeration, to vilification of ideas and men, to the making of
false charges. But those extravagances, as we emphasized in Cantwell v. Connecticut, 310 U. S. 296 , do
not justify penalizing the speaker by depriving him of the platform
or by punishing him for his conduct.
A speaker may not, of course, incite a riot, any more than he
may incite a breach of the peace by the use of "fighting words." See Chaplinsky v. New Hampshire, 315 U.
S. 568 . But this record shows no such extremes. It shows
an unsympathetic audience and the threat of one man to haul the
speaker from the stage. It is against that kind of threat that
speakers need police protection. If they do not receive it, and
instead the police throw their weight on the side of those who
would break up the meetings, the police become the new censors of
speech. Police censorship has all the vices of the censorship from
city halls which we have repeatedly struck down. See Lovell v.
City of Griffin, 303 U. S. 444 ; Hague v. CIO, 307 U. S. 496 ; Cantwell v. Connecticut, supra; Murdock v. Pennsylvania, 319 U. S. 105 ; Saia v. New York, 334 U. S. 558 . | The Supreme Court upheld the conviction of a petitioner who was arrested and charged with inciting a breach of the peace during a speech that criticized political figures and encouraged African Americans to rise up in arms to fight for equal rights. The Court found that the petitioner's right to free speech under the First and Fourteenth Amendments was not violated because he was arrested and convicted based on the reaction his speech engendered, which included unrest and a threat of violence. The police are responsible for maintaining peace and order during public assemblies and have the authority to intervene when a speaker incites a riot or breach of the peace. |
Free Speech | Curtis Publishing Co. v. Butts | https://supreme.justia.com/cases/federal/us/388/130/ | U.S. Supreme Court Curtis Pub. Co. v. Butts, 388
U.S. 130 (1967) Curtis Publishing Co. v.
Butts No. 37 Argued February 23,
1967 Decided June 12, 1967 388
U.S. 130 ast|>* 388
U.S. 130 CERTIORARI TO THE UNITED STATES
COURT OF APPEALS FOR THE FIFTH
CIRCUIT Syllabus In No. 37, respondent brought a diversity libel action in
federal court seeking compensatory and punitive damages for an
article which was published in petitioner's magazine accusing
respondent of conspiring to "fix" a football game between the
University of Alabama and the University of Georgia, where he was
privately employed as the athletic director. The article was based
upon an affidavit concerning a telephone conversation between
respondent and the Alabama coach which the affiant, Burnett, had
accidentally overheard. Respondent challenged the truth of the
article and claimed a serious departure by the magazine from good
investigative standards of the accuracy of its charges amounting to
reckless and wanton conduct. He submitted evidence at the trial
showing, inter alia, that petitioner's magazine, which had
instituted a policy of "sophisticated muckraking," knew that
Burnett was on criminal probation but had published the story
without any independent support for his affidavit; that it did not,
before publication, view his notes (the information in which, if
not valueless, would be readily available to any coach); that the
magazine did not interview a person with Burnett when the phone
call was overheard, view the game films, or check for any
adjustments in Alabama's plans after the information was divulged,
and that the magazine assigned the story to a writer not a football
expert and made no effort to have such an expert check the story.
The jury was instructed on the issue of truth as a defense and was
also instructed that it could award punitive damages and could
assess the reliability and the nature of the sources of the
magazine's information and its care in checking the assertions,
considerations relevant tn determining whether the magazine had
proceeded with "wanton and reckless indifference." The jury
returned a verdict of general and punitive damages which was
reduced by remittitur. The trial court rejected the defense's new
trial motion based on New York Times Co. v. Sullivan, 376 U. S. 254 (which was decided after the filing of the complaint in and trial
of this case), holding that decision Page 388 U. S. 131 inapplicable to one like petitioner not a public official. It
also held the evidence amply supported the conclusion that the
magazine had acted in reckless disregard of whether the article was
false or not. The Court of Appeals affirmed on the merits. It did
not reach the constitutional claim based on New York
Times, holding that petitioner had waived the right to make
that challenge, since some of its lawyers had been involved in the
latter case, yet the defense was based solely on the issue of
truth. In No. 150, petitioner, a news association, published a
dispatch about a massive riot on the University of Mississippi
campus attending federal efforts to enforce a court decree ordering
a Negro's enrollment. The dispatch stated that respondent, a
politically prominent figure whose statements on federal
intervention had been widely publicized, had taken command of the
violent crowd and led a charge against federal marshals trying to
enforce the court's decree, had encouraged violence and given
technical advice to the rioters. Respondent brought a libel action
in the Texas state courts for compensatory and punitive damages.
Petitioner's defense was based on truth and constitutional rights.
The evidence showed that the dispatch had been made on the scene
and almost immediately reported to the petitioner by a competent
correspondent. There was no significant showing of improper
preparation of the dispatch, or any prejudice by petitioner or its
correspondent. The jury was instructed that compensatory damages
could be awarded if the dispatch was not substantially true and
that punitive damages could be added if the article was actuated by
ill will or entire want of care. The jury returned a verdict for
both compensatory and punitive damages. The trial court refused to
enter an award for the latter. The court held New York
Times inapplicable, but that, if applicable, it would require
a verdict for the petitioner, since there was no evidence of
malice. Both sides appealed. The Texas Court of Civil Appeals
affirmed, and the Texas Supreme Court denied review. Held: The judgment in No. 37 is affirmed. The judgment
in No. 150 is reversed, and the case remanded. Pp. 133-174.
No. 37, 351 F.2d 702, affirmed; No. 150, 393 S.W.2d 671,
reversed and remanded.
MR. JUSTICE HARLAN, joined by MR. JUSTICE CLARK, MR. JUSTICE
STEWART, and MR. .JUSTICE FORTAS, concluded that:
1. Petitioner's failure in No. 37 to raise the constitutional
defense before trial constituted no waiver of its right to do so
after New York Times was decided. Pp. 388 U. S.
142 -145. Page 388 U. S. 132 2. The New York Times rule prohibiting a public
official from recovering damages for defamatory falsehood relating
to his official conduct absent actual malice as therein defined,
though necessary there to protect against prosecutions close to
seditious libel for criticizing official conduct, should not be
inexorably applied to defamation actions by "public figures" like
those here, where different considerations are present. Pp. 388 U. S. 148 , 388 U. S.
152 -154.
3. A "public figure" who is not a public official may recover
damages for defamatory falsehood substantially endangering his
reputation on a showing of highly unreasonable conduct constituting
an extreme departure from the standards of investigation and
reporting ordinarily adhered to by responsible publishers. P. 388 U. S.
155 .
4. In view of the court's instructions in No. 37, the jury must
have decided that the magazine's investigation was grossly
inadequate, and the evidence amply supported a finding of the
highly unreasonable conduct referred to above. Pp. 388 U. S.
156 -158.
5. In No. 150, where the courts found the evidence insufficient
to support more than a finding of even ordinary negligence,
respondent is not entitled to damages. Pp. 388 U. S.
158 -159.
6. Misconduct sufficient to justify compensatory damages also
justifies punitive damages; the same constitutional standards apply
to both. Pp. 388 U. S.
159 -161.
THE CHIEF JUSTICE concluded that:
1. The New York Times standard applies to defamation
actions by "public figures" as well as those by "public officials."
Pp. 388 U. S.
162 -165.
2. The judgment in No. 150, being in clear conflict with New
York Times, must be reversed. P. 388 U. S.
165 .
3. Retrial of No. 37 is not necessary, since the jury's verdict
therein, in view of instructions which invoked the elements later
held necessary in New York Times, most probably was based
on the requirement of reckless disregard for the truth enunciated
in that case. Pp. 388 U. S.
165 -167.
4. The overlapping of counsel in No. 37 with counsel in New
York Times and in a libel action against petitioner by the
Alabama coach, in which a First Amendment defense was also made,
compels the conclusion that the failure to defend on those grounds
here was deliberate. Pp. 388 U. S.
167 -168.
5. The evidence shows that petitioner in No. 37 acted in
reckless disregard for the truth. Pp. 388 U. S.
168 -170. Page 388 U. S. 133 MR. JUSTICE BLACK, joined by MR. JUSTICE DOUGLAS, concluded
that, in order to dispose of No. 150, he concurs in the grounds
stated by THE CHIEF JUSTICE which are summarized in paragraphs 1
and 2, supra, of THE CHIEF JUSTICES conclusions, but does
not recede from his previously expressed views about the much wider
press and speech freedoms of the First and Fourteenth Amendments.
P. 388 U. S.
170 .
MR. JUSTICE BRENNAN, joined by MR. JUSTICE WHITE, concluded that
the grounds stated by THE CHIEF JUSTICE which are summarized in
paragraphs 1 and 2, supra, of THE CHIEF JUSTICE's
conclusions in No. 150 govern that case. P. 388 U. S.
172 .
MR. JUSTICE HARLAN announced the judgments of the Court and
delivered an opinion in which MR. JUSTICE CLARK, MR. JUSTICE
STEWART, and MR. JUSTICE FORTAS join.*
In New York Times Co. v. Sullivan, 376 U.
S. 254 , 376 U. S.
279 -280, this Court held that
"[t]he constitutional guarantees Page 388 U. S. 134 [of freedom of speech and press] require . . . a federal rule
that prohibits a public official from recovering damages for a
defamatory falsehood relating to his official conduct unless he
proves that the statement was made with 'actual malice' -- that is,
with knowledge that it was false or with reckless disregard of
whether it was false or not."
We brought these two cases here, 385 U.S. 811, 385 U. S. 385 U.S. 812, to consider the impact of that decision on libel actions
instituted by persons who are not public officials, but who are
"public figures" and involved in issues in which the public has a
justified and important interest. The sweep of the New York
Times rule in libel actions brought under state law was a
question expressly reserved in that case, 376 U.S. at 376 U. S. 283 ,
n. 23, and while that question has been involved in later cases, Garrison v. Louisiana, 379 U. S. 64 ; Rosenblatt v. Baer, 383 U. S. 75 ; Time, Inc. v. Hill, 385 U. S. 374 , it
has not been fully settled.
The matter has, however, been passed on by a considerable number
of state and lower federal courts, and has produced a sharp
division of opinion as to whether the New York Times rule
should apply only in actions brought by public officials or whether
it has a longer reach. Compare, e.g., Pearson v. Fairbanks
Publishing Co., 413 P.2d 711 (Alaska), with Clark v. Pearson, 248 F.
Supp. 188 . [ Footnote 1 ] Page 388 U. S. 135 The resolution of the uncertainty in this area of libel actions
requires, at bottom, some further exploration and clarification of
the relationship between libel law and the freedom of speech and
press, lest the New York Times rule become a talisman
which gives the press constitutionally adequate protection only in
a limited field, or, what would be equally unfortunate, one which
goes far to immunize the press from having to make just reparation
for the infliction of needless injury upon honor and reputation
through false publication. These two libel actions, although they
arise out of quite different sets of circumstances, provide that
opportunity. We think they are best treated together in one
opinion. I No. 37, Curtis Publishing Co. v. Butts, stems from an
article published in petitioner's Saturday Evening Post which
accused respondent of conspiring to "fix" a football game between
the University of Georgia and the University of Alabama, played in
1962. At the time of the article, Butts was the athletic director
of the University of Georgia, and had overall responsibility for
the administration of its athletic program. Georgia is a state
university, but Butts was employed by the Georgia Athletic
Association, a private corporation, rather than by the State
itself. [ Footnote 2 ] Butts had
previously served as head Page 388 U. S. 136 football coach of the University, and was a well known and
respected figure in coaching ranks. He had maintained an interest
in coaching, and was negotiating for a position with a professional
team at the time of publication.
The article was entitled "The Story of a College Football Fix,"
and prefaced by a note from the editors stating:
"Not since the Chicago White Sox threw the 1919 World Series has
there been a sports story as shocking as this one. . . . Before the
University of Georgia played the University of Alabama . . . ,
Wally Butts . . . gave [to its coach] . . . Georgia's plays,
defensive patterns, all the significant secrets Georgia's football
team possessed."
The text revealed that one George Burnett, an Atlanta insurance
salesman, had accidentally overheard, because of electronic error,
a telephone conversation between Butts and the head coach of the
University of Alabama, Paul Bryant, which took place approximately
one week prior to the game. Burnett was said to have listened
while
"Butts outlined Georgia's offensive plays . . . and told . . .
how Georgia planned to defend. . . . Butts mentioned both players
and plays by name."
The readers were told that Burnett had made notes of the
conversation, and specific examples of the divulged secrets were
set out.
The article went on to discuss the game and the players'
reaction to the game, concluding that "[t]he Georgia players, their
moves analyzed and forecast like those of rats in a maze, took a
frightful physical beating," and said that the players, and other
sideline observers, were aware that Alabama was privy to Georgia's
secrets. It set out the series of events commencing with Burnett's
later presentation of his notes to the Georgia head coach, Page 388 U. S. 137 Johnny Griffith, and culminating in Butts' resignation from the
University's athletic affairs, for health and business reasons. The
article's conclusion made clear its expected impact:
"The chances are that Wally Butts will never help any football
team again. . . . The investigation by university and Southeastern
Conference officials is continuing; motion pictures of other games
are being scrutinized; where it will end no one so far can say. But
careers will be ruined, that is sure."
Butts brought this diversity libel action in the federal courts
in Georgia seeking $5,000,000 compensatory and $5,000,000 punitive
damages. The complaint was filed, and the trial completed, before
this Court handed down its decision in New York Times, and
the only defense raised by petitioner Curtis was one of substantial
truth. No constitutional defenses were interposed, although Curtis'
counsel were aware of the progress of the New York Times case, and although general constitutional defenses had been raised
by Curtis in a libel action instituted by the Alabama coach who was
a state employee.
Evidence at trial was directed both to the truth of the article
and to its preparation. The latter point was put in issue by the
claim for punitive damages, which required a finding of "malice"
under Georgia law. The evidence showed that Burnett had indeed
overheard a conversation between Butts and the Alabama coach, but
the content of that conversation was hotly disputed. It was Butts'
contention that the conversation had been general football talk,
and that nothing Burnett had overheard would have been of any
particular value to an opposing coach. Expert witnesses supported
Butts by analyzing Burnett's notes and the films of the game
itself. The Saturday Evening Post's version of the game and of the
players' remarks about the game was severely contradicted. Page 388 U. S. 138 The evidence on the preparation of the article, on which we
shall focus in more detail later, cast serious doubt on the
adequacy of the investigation underlying the article. It was Butts'
contention that the magazine had departed greatly from the
standards of good investigation and reporting, and that this was
especially reprehensible, amounting to reckless and wanton conduct,
in light of the devastating nature of the article's assertions.
The jury was instructed that, in order for the defense of truth
to be sustained, it was "necessary that the truth be substantially
portrayed in those parts of the article which libel the plaintiff."
The "sting of the libel" was said to be
"the charge that the plaintiff rigged and fixed the 1962
Georgia-Alabama game by giving Coach Bryant [of Alabama]
information which was calculated to or could have affected the
outcome of the game."
The jury was also instructed that it could award punitive
damages "to deter the wrongdoer from repeating the trespass" in an
amount within its sole discretion if it found that actual malice
had been proved. [ Footnote
3 ]
The jury returned a verdict for $60,000 in general damages and
for $3,000000 in punitive damages. The trial court reduced the
total to $460,000 by remittitur. Soon thereafter, we handed down
our decision in New York Times, and Curtis immediately
brought it to the attention of the trial court by a motion for new
trial. The trial judge rejected Curtis' motion on two grounds.
He Page 388 U. S. 139 first held that New York Times was inapplicable because
Butts was not a public official. He also held that
"there was ample evidence from which a jury could have concluded
that there was reckless disregard by defendant of whether the
article was false or not."
Curtis appealed to the Court of Appeals for the Fifth Circuit,
which affirmed the judgment of the District Court by a two-to-one
vote. The majority there did not reach the merits of petitioner's
constitutional claim, holding that Curtis had "clearly waived any
right it may have had to challenge the verdict and judgment on any
of the constitutional grounds asserted in Times, " 351 F.2d
702, 713, on the basis of Michel v. Louisiana, 350 U. S. 91 . It
found Curtis chargeable with knowledge of the constitutional
limitations on libel law at the time it filed its pleadings below
because of its "interlocking battery of able and distinguished
attorneys" some of whom were involved in the New York
Times litigation. This holding rendered the compensatory
damage decision purely one of state law, and no error was found in
its application. Turning to the punitive damage award, the majority
upheld it as stemming from the "enlightened conscience" of the jury
as adjusted by the lawful action of the trial judge. It was in
"complete accord" with the trial court's determination that the
evidence justified the finding "that what the Post did was done
with reckless disregard of whether the article was false or not."
351 F.2d at 719.
Judge Rives dissented, arguing that the record did not support a
finding of knowing waiver of constitutional defenses. He concluded
that the New York Times rule was applicable because Butts
was involved in activities of great interest to the public. He
would have reversed because
"the jury might well have understood the district court's charge
to allow recovery on a showing of Page 388 U. S. 140 intent to inflict harm or even the culpably negligent infliction
of harm, rather than the intent to inflict harm through falsehood.
. . ."
351 F.2d at 723.
Rehearing was denied, 351 F.2d at 733, and we granted
certiorari, as indicated above. For reasons given below, we would
affirm. II No. 150, Associated Press v. Walker, arose out of the
distribution of a news dispatch giving an eyewitness account of
events on the campus of the University of Mississippi on the night
of September 30, 1962, when a massive riot erupted because of
federal efforts to enforce a court decree ordering the enrollment
of a Negro, James Meredith, as a student in the University. The
dispatch stated that respondent Walker, who was present on the
campus, had taken command of the violent crowd and had personally
led a charge against federal marshals sent there to effectuate the
court's decree and to assist in preserving order. It also described
Walker as encouraging rioters to use violence and giving them
technical advice on combating the effects of tear gas.
Walker was a private citizen at the time of the riot and
publication. He had pursued a long and honorable career in the
United States Army before resigning to engage in political
activity, and had, in fact, been in command of the federal troops
during the school segregation confrontation at Little Rock,
Arkansas, in 1957. He was acutely interested in the issue of
physical federal intervention, and had made a number of strong
statements against such action which had received wide publicity.
Walker had his own following, the "Friends of Walker," and could
fairly be deemed a man of some political prominence.
Walker initiated this libel action in the state courts of Texas,
seeking a total of $2,000,000 in compensatory and punitive damages.
Associated Press raised both the Page 388 U. S. 141 defense of truth and constitutional defenses. At trial, both
sides attempted to reconstruct the stormy events on the campus of
the University of Mississippi. Walker admitted his presence on the
campus, and conceded that he had spoken to a group of students. He
claimed, however, that he had counseled restraint and peaceful
protest, and exercised no control whatever over the crowd, which
had rejected his plea. He denied categorically taking part in any
charge against the federal marshals.
There was little evidence relating to the preparation of the
news dispatch. It was clear, however, that the author of this
dispatch, Van Savell, was actually present during the events
described, and had reported them almost immediately to the
Associated Press office in Atlanta. A discrepancy was shown between
an oral account given the office and a later written dispatch, but
it related solely to whether Walker had spoken to the group before
or after approaching the marshals. No other showing of improper
preparation was attempted, nor was there any evidence of personal
prejudice or incompetency on the part of Savell or the Associated
Press.
The jury was instructed that an award of compensatory damages
could be made if the dispatch was not substantially true, [ Footnote 4 ] and that punitive damages
could be added if the article was actuated by
"ill will, bad or evil motive, or that entire want of care which
would raise the belief that the act or omission complained of was
the result of a conscious indifference to the right or welfare of
the person to be affected by it."
A verdict of $500,000 compensatory damages and $300,000 punitive
damages was returned. The trial judge, however, found that there
was "no evidence to support the jury's answers that there was
actual malice" Page 388 U. S. 142 and refused to enter the punitive award. He concluded that the
failure further to investigate the minor discrepancy between the
oral and written versions of the incident could not
"be construed as that entire want of care which would
amount to a conscious indifference to the rights of
plaintiff. Negligence, it may have been; malice, it was not.
Moreover, the mere fact that AP permitted a young reporter to cover
the story of the riot is not evidence of malice."
(Emphasis in original.) The trial judge also noted that this
lack of "malice" would require a verdict for the Associated Press
if New York Times were applicable. But he rejected its
applicability, since there were "no compelling reasons of public
policy requiring additional defenses to suits for libel. Truth
alone should be an adequate defense."
Both sides appealed, and the Texas Court of Civil Appeals
affirmed both the award of compensatory damages and the striking of
punitive damages. It stated without elaboration that New York
Times was inapplicable. As to the punitive damage award, the
plea for reinstatement was refused because,
"[i]n view of all the surrounding circumstances, the rapid and
confused occurrence of events on the occasion in question, and in
the light of all the evidence, we hold that appellee failed to
prove malice . ."
393 S.W.2d 671, 683.
The Supreme Court of Texas denied a writ of error, and we
granted certiorari, as already indicated. For reasons given below,
we would reverse. III Before we reach the constitutional arguments put forward by the
respective petitioners, we must first determine whether Curtis has
waived its right to assert such arguments by failing to assert them
before trial. As our dispositions of Rosenblatt v. Baer, 383 U. S. 75 , Page 388 U. S. 143 and other cases involving constitutional questions indicate,
[ Footnote 5 ] the mere failure
to interpose such a defense prior to the announcement of a decision
which might support it cannot prevent a litigant from later
invoking such a ground. Of course, it is equally clear that even
constitutional objections may be waived by a failure to raise them
at a proper time, Michel v. Louisiana, supra, at 350 U. S. 99 ,
[ Footnote 6 ] but an effective
waiver must, as was said in Johnson v. Zerbst, 304 U. S. 458 , 304 U. S. 464 ,
be one of a "known right or privilege."
Butts makes two arguments in support of his contention that
Curtis' failure to raise constitutional defenses amounted to a
knowing waiver. The first is that the general state of the law at
the time of this trial was such that Curtis should, in the words of
the Fifth Circuit majority, have seen "the handwriting on the
wall." 351 F.2d at 734. We cannot accept this contention. Although
our decision in New York Times did draw upon earlier
precedents in state law, e.g., Coleman v. MacLennan, 78
Kan. 711, 98 P. 281, and there were intimations in a prior opinion
and the extrajudicial comments of one Justice [ Footnote 7 ] that some applications of libel law
might be in conflict with the guarantees of free speech and press,
there was strong precedent indicating that civil libel actions Page 388 U. S. 144 were immune from general constitutional scrutiny. [ Footnote 8 ] Given the state of the law prior
to our decision in New York Times, we do not think it
unreasonable for a lawyer trying a case of this kind, where the
plaintiff was not even a public official under state law, to have
looked solely to the defenses provided by state libel law. Nor do
we think that the previous grant of certiorari in New York
Times alone indicates a different conclusion. The questions
presented for review there were premised on Sullivan's status as an
elected public official, and elected officials traditionally have
been subject to special rules of libel law. [ Footnote 9 ]
Butts' second contention is that whatever defenses might
reasonably have been apparent to the average lawyer, some of
Curtis' trial attorneys were involved in the New York
Times litigation, and thus should have been especially alert
to constitutional contentions. This was the argument which swayed
the Court of Appeals, but we do not find it convincing.
First, as a general matter, we think it inadvisable to determine
whether a "right or privilege" is "known" by relying on information
outside the record concerning the special legal knowledge of
particular attorneys. Second, even a lawyer fully cognizant of the
record and briefs in the New York Times litigation might
reasonably have expected the resolution of that case to have no
impact Page 388 U. S. 145 on this litigation, since the arguments advanced there depended
so heavily on the analogy to seditious libel. We think that it was
our eventual resolution of New York Times, rather than its
facts and the arguments presented by counsel, which brought out the
constitutional question here. We would not hold that Curtis waived
a "known right" before it was aware of the New York Times decision. It is agreed that Curtis' presentation of the
constitutional issue after our decision in New York Times was prompt.
Our rejection of Butts' arguments is supported by factors which
point to the justice of that conclusion. See Hormel v.
Helvering, 312 U. S. 552 , 312 U. S.
556 -557. Curtis' constitutional points were raised early
enough so that this Court has had the benefit of some ventilation
of them by the courts below. The resolution of the merits of
Curtis' contentions by the District Court makes it evident that
Butts was not prejudiced by the time at which Curtis raised its
argument, for it cannot be asserted that an earlier interposition
would have resulted in any different proceedings below. [ Footnote 10 ] Finally, the
constitutional protection which Butts contends that Curtis has
waived safeguards a freedom which is the "matrix, the indispensable
condition, of nearly every other form of freedom." Palko v.
Connecticut, 302 U. S. 319 , 302 U. S. 327 .
Where the ultimate effect of sustaining a claim of waiver might be
an imposition on that valued freedom, we are unwilling to find
waiver in circumstances which fall short of being clear and
compelling. Cf. New York Times Co. v. Connor, 365 F.2d
567, 572. Page 388 U. S. 146 IV We thus turn to a consideration, on the merits, of the
constitutional claims raised by Curtis' in Butts and by
the Associated Press in Walker. Powerful arguments are
brought to bear for the extension of the New York Times rule in both cases. In Butts, it is contended that the
facts are on all fours with those of Rosenblatt v. Baer,
supra, since Butts was charged with the important
responsibility of managing the athletic affairs of a state
university. It is argued that, while the Athletic Association is
financially independent from the State and Butts was not
technically a state employee, as was Baer, his role in state
administration was so significant that this technical distinction
from Rosenblatt should be ignored. Even if this factor is
to be given some weight, we are told that the public interest in
education in general, and in the conduct of the athletic affairs of
educational institutions in particular, justifies constitutional
protection of discussion of persons involved in it equivalent to
the protection afforded discussion of public officials.
A similar argument is raised in the Walker case, where
the important public interest in being informed about the events
and personalities involved in the Mississippi riot is pressed. In
that case, we are also urged to recognize that Walker's claims to
the protection of libel laws are limited, since he thrust himself
into the "vortex" of the controversy.
We are urged by the respondents, Butts and Walker, to recognize
society's "pervasive and strong interest in preventing and
redressing attacks upon reputation," and the "important social
values which underlie the law of defamation." Rosenblatt v.
Baer, supra, at 383 U. S. 86 . It
is pointed out that the publicity in these instances was not
directed at employees of government, and that these cases cannot be
analogized to seditious libel prosecutions. Id. at 383 U. S. 92 (STEWART, J., concurring). We are Page 388 U. S. 147 told that
"[t]he rule that permits satisfaction of the deep-seated need
for vindication of honor is not a mere historic relic, but promotes
the law's civilizing function of providing an acceptable substitute
for violence in the settlement of disputes," Afro-American Publishing Co. v. Jaffe, 125 U.S.App.D.C.
70, 81, 366 F.2d 649, 660, and that:
"Newspapers, magazines, and broadcasting companies are
businesses conducted for profit, and often make very large ones.
Like other enterprises that inflict damage in the course of
performing a service highly useful to the public . . . , they must
pay the freight, and injured persons should not be relegated [to
remedies which] make collection of their claims difficult or
impossible unless strong policy considerations demand." Buckley v. New York Post Corp., 373 F.2d 175, 182.
We fully recognize the force of these competing considerations
and the fact that an accommodation between them is necessary not
only in these cases, but in all libel actions arising from a
publication concerning public issues. In Time, Inc. v.
Hill, 385 U. S. 374 , 385 U. S. 388 ,
we held that "[t]he guarantees for speech and press are not the
preserve of political expression or comment upon public affairs . .
.", and affirmed that freedom of discussion
"must embrace all issues about which information is needed or
appropriate to enable the members of society to cope with the
exigencies of their period." Thornhill v. Alabama, 310 U. S. 88 , 310 U. S. 102 .
This carries out the intent of the Founders, who felt that a free
press would advance "truth, science, morality, and arts in
general," as well as responsible government. Letter to the
Inhabitants of Quebec, 1 Journals of the Continental Cong. 108.
From the point of view of deciding whether a constitutional
interest of free speech and press is properly involved in the
resolution of a libel question, a rational Page 388 U. S. 148 distinction
"cannot be founded on the assumption that criticism of private
citizens who seek to lead in the determination of . . . policy will
be less important to the public interest than will criticism of
government officials." Pauling v. Globe-Democrat Publishing Co., 362 F.2d 188,
196.
On the other hand, to take the rule found appropriate in New
York Times to resolve the "tension" between the particular
constitutional interest there involved and the interests of
personal reputation and press responsibility, Rosenblatt v.
Baer, supra, at 383 U. S. 86 , as
being applicable throughout the realm of the broader constitutional
interest would be to attribute to this aspect of New York
Times an unintended inexorability at the threshold of this new
constitutional development. In Time, Inc. v. Hill, supra, at 385 U. S. 390 ,
we counseled against "blind application of New York Times Co.
v. Sullivan ", and considered "the factors which arise in the
particular context." Here we must undertake a parallel evaluation.
[ Footnote 11 ]
The modern history of the guarantee of freedom of speech and
press mainly has been one of a search for the outer limits of that
right. From the fountainhead opinions of Justices Holmes and
Brandeis in Schenck, Abrams, and Whitney, [ Footnote 12 ] which
considered the problem when the disruptive effects of speech might
strip the protection from the speaker, to our recent decision in Adderley v. Florida, 385 U. S. 39 , where
we found freedom of speech not to include a freedom to trespass,
the Court's primary concern has been to determine the extent of the
right and the surrounding safeguards necessary to give it
"breathing space." NAACP v. Page 388 U. S. 149 Button, 371 U. S. 415 , 371 U. S. 433 .
That concern has perhaps omitted from searching consideration the
"real problem" of defining or delimiting the right itself. See Freund, Mr. Justice Black and the Judicial Function,
14 U.C.L.A.L.Rev. 467, 471.
It is significant that the guarantee of freedom of speech and
press falls between the religious guarantees and the guarantee of
the right to petition for redress of grievances in the text of the
First Amendment, the principles of which are carried to the States
by the Fourteenth Amendment. It partakes of the nature of both, for
it is as much a guarantee to individuals of their personal right to
make their thoughts public and put them before the community, see Holt, Of the Liberty of the Press, in Nelson, Freedom
of the Press from Hamilton to the Warren Court 18-19, as it is a
social necessity required for the "maintenance of our political
system and an open society." Time, Inc. v. Hill, supra, at 385 U. S. 389 .
It is because of the personal nature of this right that we have
rejected all manner of prior restraint on publication, Near v.
Minnesota, 283 U. S. 697 ,
despite strong arguments that, if the material was unprotected, the
time of suppression was immaterial. Pound, Equitable Relief Against
Defamation and Injuries to Personality, 29 Harv.L.Rev. 640. The
dissemination of the individual's opinions on matters of public
interest is for us, in the historic words of the Declaration of
Independence, an "unalienable right" that "governments are
instituted among men to secure." History shows us that the Founders
were not always convinced that unlimited discussion of public
issues would be "for the benefit of all of us," [ Footnote 13 ] but that they firmly adhered
to the proposition that the "true liberty of the press" permitted
"every man to publish Page 388 U. S. 150 his opinion." Respublica v. Oswald, 1 Dall. 319, 325
(Pa.).
The fact that dissemination of information and opinion on
questions of public concern is ordinarily a legitimate, protected
and indeed cherished activity does not mean, however, that one may
in all respects carry on that activity exempt from sanctions
designed to safeguard the legitimate interests of others. A
business
"is not immune from regulation because it is an agency of the
press. The publisher of a newspaper has no special immunity from
the application of general laws. He has no special privilege to
invade the rights and liberties of others." Associated Press v. Labor Board, 301 U.
S. 103 , 301 U. S.
132 -133. Federal securities regulation, [ Footnote 14 ] mail fraud statutes, [ Footnote 15 ] and common law actions
for deceit and misrepresentation [ Footnote 16 ] are only some examples of our understanding
that the right to communicate information of public interest is not
"unconditional." See Note, Freedom of Expression in a
Commercial Context, 78 Harv.L.Rev. 1191. However, as our decision
in New York Times makes explicit, while protected activity
may, in some respects, be subjected to sanctions, it is not open to
all forms of regulation. The guarantees of freedom of speech and
press were not designed to prevent
"the censorship of the press merely, but any action of the
government by means of which it might prevent such free and general
discussion of public matters as seems absolutely essential. . .
."
2 Cooley, Constitutional Limitations 886 (8th ed.). Our
touchstones are that acceptable Page 388 U. S. 151 limitations must neither affect "the impartial distribution of
news" and ideas, Associated Press v. Labor Board, supra, at 301 U. S. 133 ,
nor because of their history or impact constitute a special burden
on the press, Grosjean v. American Press Co., Inc., 297 U. S. 233 , nor
deprive our free society of the stimulating benefit of varied ideas
because their purveyors fear physical or economic retribution
solely because of what they choose to think and publish.
The history of libel law leaves little doubt that it originated
in soil entirely different from that which nurtured these
constitutional values. Early libel was primarily a criminal remedy,
the function of which was to make punishable any writing which
tended to bring into disrepute the state, established religion, or
any individual likely to be provoked to a breach of the peace
because of the words. Truth was no defense in such actions, and,
while a proof of truth might prevent recovery in a civil action,
this limitation is more readily explained as a manifestation of
judicial reluctance to enrich an undeserving plaintiff than by the
supposition that the defendant was protected by the truth of the
publication. The same truthful statement might be the basis of a
criminal libel action. See Commonwealth v. Clap, 4 Mass.
163; see generally Veeder, The History and Theory of the
Law of Defamation, 3 Col.L.Rev. 546, 4 Col.L.Rev. 33.
The law of libel has, of course, changed substantially since the
early days of the Republic, and this change is "the direct
consequence of the friction between it . . . and the highly
cherished right of free speech." State v. Browne, 86
N.J.Super. 217, 228, 206 A.2d 591 , 597. The emphasis has shifted from criminal to
civil remedies, from the protection of absolute social values to
the safeguarding of valid personal interests. Truth has become an
absolute defense in almost all cases, [ Footnote 17 ] and privileges designed to foster free
communication are almost universally Page 388 U. S. 152 recognized. [ Footnote 18 ]
But the basic theory of libel has not changed, and words defamatory
of another are still placed "in the same class with the use of
explosives or the keeping of dangerous animals." Prosser, The Law
of Torts § 108, at 792. Thus, some antithesis between freedom of
speech and press and libel actions persists, for libel remains
premised on the content of speech and limits the freedom of the
publisher to express certain sentiments, at least without
guaranteeing legal proof of their substantial accuracy.
While the truth of the underlying facts might be said to mark
the line between publications which are of significant social value
and those which might be suppressed without serious social harm,
and thus resolve the antithesis on a neutral ground, we have
rejected, in prior cases involving materials and persons commanding
justified and important public interest, the argument that a
finding of falsity alone should strip protections from the
publisher. New York Times Co. v. Sullivan, supra, at 376 U. S. 272 .
We have recognized "the inevitability of some error in the
situation presented in free debate," Time, Inc. v. Hill,
supra, at 385 U. S. 406 (opinion of this writer), and that "putting to the preexisting
prejudices of a jury the determination of what is true' may
effectively institute a system of censorship." Our resolution of New York Times Co. v. Sullivan, in
the context of the numerous statutes and cases which allow
ideologically neutral and generally applicable regulatory measures
to be applied to publication, makes clear, however, that neither
the interests of the publisher nor those of society necessarily
preclude a damage award Page 388 U. S. 153 based on improper conduct which creates a false publication. It
is the conduct element, therefore, on which we must principally
focus if we are successfully to resolve the antithesis between
civil libel actions and the freedom of speech and press.
Impositions based on misconduct can be neutral with respect to
content of the speech involved, free of historical taint, and
adjusted to strike a fair balance between the interests of the
community in free circulation of information and those of
individuals in seeking recompense for harm done by the circulation
of defamatory falsehood.
In New York Times, we were adjudicating in an area
which lay close to seditious libel, and history dictated extreme
caution in imposing liability. The plaintiff in that case was an
official whose position in government was such "that the public
[had] an independent interest in the qualifications and performance
of the person who [held] it." Rosenblatt v. Baer, supra, at 383 U. S. 86 .
Such officials usually enjoy a privilege against libel actions for
their utterances, see, e.g., Barr v. Matteo, 360 U.
S. 564 , and there were analogous considerations involved
in New York Times, supra, at 376 U. S. 282 .
Thus, we invoked
"the hypothesis that speech can rebut speech, propaganda will
answer propaganda, free debate of ideas will result in the wisest
governmental policies," Dennis v. United States, 341 U.
S. 494 , 341 U. S. 503 ,
and limited recovery to those cases where "calculated falsehood"
placed the publisher
"at odds with the premises of democratic government and with the
orderly manner in which economic, social, or political change is to
be effected." Garrison v. Louisiana, 379 U. S.
64 , 379 U. S. 75 .
That is to say, such officials were permitted to recover in libel
only when they could prove that the publication involved was
deliberately falsified, or published recklessly despite the
publisher's awareness of probable falsity. Investigatory failures
alone were held insufficient to satisfy this standard. See New
York Page 388 U. S. 154 Times, at 376 U. S.
286 -288, 376 U. S. 292 ; Garrison v. Louisiana, supra, at 379 U. S. 73 -75, 379 U. S.
79 .
In the cases we decide today, none of the particular
considerations involved in New York Times is present.
These actions cannot be analogized to prosecutions for seditious
libel. Neither plaintiff has any position in government which would
permit a recovery by him to be viewed as a vindication of
governmental policy. Neither was entitled to a special privilege
protecting his utterances against accountability in libel. We are
prompted, therefore, to seek guidance from the rules of liability
which prevail in our society with respect to compensation of
persons injured by the improper performance of a legitimate
activity by another. Under these rules, a departure from the kind
of care society may expect from a reasonable man performing such
activity leaves the actor open to a judicial shifting of loss. In
defining these rules, and especially in formulating the standards
for determining the degree of care to be expected in the
circumstances, courts have consistently given much attention to the
importance of defendants' activities. Prosser, The Law of Torts §
31, at 151. The courts have also, especially in libel cases,
investigated the plaintiff's position to determine whether he has a
legitimate call upon the court for protection in light of his prior
activities and means of self-defense. See Brewer v. Hearst
Publishing Co., 185 F.2d 846; Flanagan v. Nicholson
Publishing Co., 137 La. 588, 68 So. 964. We note that the
public interest in the circulation of the materials here involved,
and the publisher's interest in circulating them, is not less than
that involved in New York Times. And both Butts and Walker
commanded a substantial amount of independent public interest at
the time of the publications; both, in our opinion, would have been
labeled "public figures" under ordinary tort rules. See Spahn
v. Julian Messner, Inc., 18 N.Y.2d 324, 221 N.E.2d 543, remanded Page 388 U. S. 155 on other grounds, 387 U. S. 239 .
Butts may have attained that status by position alone, and Walker
by his purposeful activity amounting to a thrusting of his
personality into the "vortex" of an important public controversy,
but both commanded sufficient continuing public interest and had
sufficient access to the means of counterargument to be able "to
expose through discussion the falsehood and fallacies" of the
defamatory statements. Whitney v. California, 274 U.
S. 357 , 274 U. S. 377 (Brandeis, J., dissenting).
These similarities and differences between libel actions
involving persons who are public officials and libel actions
involving those circumstanced as were Butts and Walker, viewed in
light of the principles of liability which are of general
applicability in our society, lead us to the conclusion that libel
actions of the present kind cannot be left entirely to state libel
laws, unlimited by any overriding constitutional safeguard, but
that the rigorous federal requirements of New York Times are not the only appropriate accommodation of the conflicting
interests at stake. We consider and would hold that a "public
figure" who is not a public official may also recover damages for a
defamatory falsehood whose substance makes substantial danger to
reputation apparent, on a showing of highly unreasonable conduct
constituting an extreme departure from the standards of
investigation and reporting ordinarily adhered to by responsible
publishers. Cf. Sulzberger, Responsibility and Freedom, in
Nelson, Freedom of the Press from Hamilton to the Warren Court 409,
412.
Nothing in this opinion is meant to affect the holdings in New York Times and its progeny, including our recent
decision in Time, Inc. v. Hill, [ Footnote 19 ] Page 388 U. S. 156 V Having set forth the standard by which we believe the
constitutionality of the damage awards in these cases must be
judged, we turn now, as the Court did in New York Times, to the question whether the evidence and findings below meet that
standard. We find the standard satisfied in No. 37, Butts, and not satisfied by either the evidence or the findings in No.
150, Walker. The Butts jury was instructed, in considering punitive
damages, to assess
"the reliability, the nature of the sources of the defendant's
information, its acceptance or rejection of the sources, and its
care in checking upon assertions."
These considerations were said to be relevant to a determination
whether defendant had proceeded with "wanton and reckless
indifference." In this light, we consider that the jury must have
decided that the investigation undertaken by the Saturday Evening
Post, upon which much evidence and argument was centered, [ Footnote 20 ] was grossly inadequate
in the circumstances. The impact of a jury instruction
"is not to be ascertained by Page 388 U. S. 157 merely considering isolated statements, but by taking into view
all the instructions given and the tendencies of the proof in the
case to which they could possibly be applied." Seaboard Air Line R. Co. v. Padgett, 236 U.
S. 668 , 236 U. S.
672 .
This jury finding was found to be supported by the evidence by
the trial judge and the majority in the Fifth Circuit. Given the
extended history of the case, the amount of the evidence pointing
to serious deficiencies in investigatory procedure, and the severe
harm inflicted on Butts, we would not feel justified in ordering a
retrial of the compensatory damage issue, either on the theory that
this aspect of the case was submitted to the jury only under the
issue of "truth," [ Footnote
21 ] or on the very slim possibility that the jury finding
regarding punitive damages might have been based on Curtis'
attitude toward Butts, rather than on Curtis' conduct.
The evidence showed that the Butts story was in no sense "hot
news," and the editors of the magazine recognized the need for a
thorough investigation of the serious charges. Elementary
precautions were, nevertheless, ignored. The Saturday Evening Post
knew that Burnett had been placed on probation in connection with
bad check charges, but proceeded to publish the story on the basis
of his affidavit, without substantial independent support.
Burnett's notes were not even viewed by any of the magazine's
personnel prior to publication. John Carmichael, who was supposed
to have been with Burnett when the phone call was overheard, was
not interviewed. No attempt was made to screen the films of the
game to see if Burnett's information was accurate, and no attempt
was made to find out whether Alabama had adjusted its plans after
the alleged divulgence of information. Page 388 U. S. 158 The Post writer assigned to the story was not a football expert,
and no attempt was made to check the story with someone
knowledgeable in the sport. At trial, such experts indicated that
the information in the Burnett notes was either such that it would
be evident to any opposing coach from game films regularly
exchanged, or valueless. Those assisting the Post writer in his
investigation were already deeply involved in another libel action,
based on a different article, brought against Curtis Publishing Co.
by the Alabama coach and unlikely to be the source of a complete
and objective investigation. The Saturday Evening Post was anxious
to change its image by instituting a policy of "sophisticated
muckraking," and the pressure to produce a successful expose might
have induced a stretching of standards. In short, the evidence is
ample to support a finding of highly unreasonable conduct
constituting an extreme departure from the standards of
investigation and reporting ordinarily adhered to by responsible
publishers.
The situation in Walker is considerably different.
There, the trial court found the evidence insufficient to support
more than a finding of even ordinary negligence, and the Court of
Civil Appeals supported the trial court's view of the evidence.
Ordinarily we would, under the governing constitutional standard,
reverse the decision below on the concurrent findings rule. Graver Tank Mfg. Co. v. Linde Air Products Co., 336 U. S. 271 , 336 U. S. 275 .
But, as in New York Times, we think it better to face for
ourselves the question whether there is sufficient evidence to
support the finding we would require.
In contrast to the Butts article, the dispatch which
concerns us in Walker was news which required immediate
dissemination. The Associated Press received the information from a
correspondent who was present at the scene of the events and gave
every indication of being trustworthy and competent. His dispatches
in this instance, Page 388 U. S. 159 with one minor exception, were internally consistent, and would
not have seemed unreasonable to one familiar with General Walker's
prior publicized statements on the underlying controversy.
[ Footnote 22 ] Considering
the necessity for rapid dissemination, nothing in this series of
events gives the slightest hint of a severe departure from accepted
publishing standards. We therefore conclude that General Walker
should not be entitled to damages from the Associated Press. VI We come finally to Curtis' contention that, whether or not it
can be required to compensate Butts for any injury it may have
caused him, it cannot be subjected to an assessment for punitive
damages limited only by the "enlightened conscience" of the
community. Curtis recognizes that the Constitution presents no
general bar to the assessment of punitive damages in a civil case, Day v.
Woodworth , 13 How. 363, 54 U. S.
370 -371, but contends that an unlimited punitive award
against a magazine publisher constitutes an effective prior
restraint by giving the jury the power to destroy the publisher's
business. We cannot accept this reasoning. Publishers like Curtis
engage in a wide variety of activities which may Page 388 U. S. 160 lead to tort suits where punitive damages are a possibility. To
exempt a publisher, because of the nature of his calling, from an
imposition generally exacted from other members of the community
would be to extend a protection not required by the constitutional
guarantee. Associated Press v. Labor Board, 301 U.
S. 103 . We think the constitutional guarantee of freedom
of speech and press is adequately served by judicial control over
excessive jury verdicts, manifested in this instance by the trial
court's remittitur and by the general rule that a verdict based on
jury prejudice cannot be sustained even when punitive damages are
warranted. See, e.g., Minneapolis, St. P. & S.S.M. R. Co.
v. Moquin, 283 U. S. 520 , 283 U. S.
521 .
Despite this conclusion, it might be argued that an award of
punitive damages cannot be justified constitutionally by the same
degree of misconduct required to support a compensatory award. The
usual rule in libel actions, and other state-created tort actions,
is that a higher degree of fault is necessary to sustain a punitive
imposition than a compensatory award. And it might be asserted that
the need to compensate the injured plaintiff is not relevant to the
issue of punitive damages in libel, since an award of general
damages compensates for any possible pecuniary and intangible harm.
Thus, the argument would be that the strong speech and press
interest in publishing material on public issues, which we have
recognized as parallel to the interest in publishing political
criticism present in New York Times, must be served by a
limitation on punitive damages restricting them to cases of "actual
malice" as defined in New York Times and Garrison v.
Louisiana, supra. We find the force of any such argument quite
insufficient to overcome the compelling contrary considerations,
and there is, moreover, nothing in any of our past cases which
suggests that compensatory and punitive damages are subject to
different constitutional standards of misconduct. Page 388 U. S. 161 Where a publisher's departure from standards of press
responsibility is severe enough to strip from him the
constitutional protection our decision acknowledges, we think it
entirely proper for the State to act not only for the protection of
the individual injured, but to safeguard all those similarly
situated against like abuse. Moreover, punitive damages require a
finding of "ill will" under general libel law, and it is not unjust
that a publisher be forced to pay for the "venting of his spleen"
in a manner which does not meet even the minimum standards required
for constitutional protection. Especially in those cases where
circumstances outside the publication itself reduce its impact
sufficiently to make a compensatory imposition an inordinately
light burden, punitive damages serve a wholly legitimate purpose in
the protection of individual reputation. We would hold, therefore,
that misconduct sufficient to justify the award of compensatory
damages also justifies the imposition of a punitive award, subject,
of course, to the limitation that such award is not demonstrated to
be founded on the mere prejudice of the jury. As we have already
noted ( supra, pp. 388 U. S. 156 -158) the case on punitive damages was put
to the jury under instructions which satisfied the constitutional
test we would apply in cases of this kind, and the evidence amply
supported the jury's findings. [ Footnote 23 ]
The judgment of the Court of Appeals for the Fifth Circuit in
No. 37 is affirmed. The judgment of the Page 388 U. S. 162 Texas Court of Civil Appeals in No. 150 is reversed, and the
case is remanded to that court for further proceedings not
inconsistent with the opinions that have been filed herein by THE
CHIEF JUSTICE, MR. JUSTICE BLACK, and MR. JUSTICE BRENNAN. It is so ordered. * Together with No. 150, Associated Press v Walker, on
certiorari to the Court of Civil Appeals of Texas, 2d Supreme
Judicial District.
* Five members of the Court, while concurring in the result
reached in No. 150, would rest decision on grounds other than those
stated in this opinion. See separate opinions of THE CHIEF
JUSTICE ( post, p. 388 U. S. 162 ), of MR. JUSTICE BLACK ( post, p. 388 U. S.
170 ), and of MR. JUSTICE BRENNAN ( post, p. 388 U. S.
172 ).
[ Footnote 1 ] See also Afro-American Publishing Co. v. Jaffe, 125
U.S.App.D.C. 70, 366 F.2d 649; Washington Post Co. v.
Keogh, 125 U.S.App.D.C. 32, 365 F.2d 965; Pauling v.
Globe-Democrat Publishing Co., 362 F.2d 188; Pape v. Time,
Inc., 354 F.2d 558; Pauling v. News Syndicate Co.,
Inc., 335 F.2d 659; Fignole v. Curtis Publishing
Co., 247 F.
Supp. 595 ; Walker v. Courier-Journal & Louisville Times
Co., 246 F.
Supp. 231 ; United Medical Labs v. CBS,
Inc., 258 F.
Supp. 735 ; Klahr v. Winterble, 4 Ariz.App. 158, 418
P.2d 404; Walker v. Associated Press, ___ Colo. ___, 417 P.2d 486 ; Powell v. Monitor Publishing Co., Inc., 107 N.H. 83, 217
A.2d 193; Eadie v. Pole, 91 N.J.Super. 504, 221 A.2d 547 ; State v. Browne, 86 N.J.Super. 217, 206 A.2d 591 ; People v. Mager, 25 App.Div.2d 363, 69
N.Y.S.2d 848; Gilberg v. Goffi, 21 App.Div.2d 517, 251
N.Y.S.2d 823; Krutech v. Schimmel, 50 Misc.2d 1052, 272
N.Y.S.2d 261; Cabin v. Community Newspapers, Inc., 50
Misc.2d 574, 270 N.Y.S.2d 913; Pauling v. National Review, 49 Misc.2d 975, 269 N.Y.S.2d 11; Block v. Benton, 44
Misc.2d 1053, 255 N.Y.S.2d 767; Fegley v. Morthimer, 204
Pa.Super. 54, 202 A.2d 125; Tucker v.
Kilgore, 388
S.W.2d 112 (Ky.).
[ Footnote 2 ]
In Allen v. Regents of the University System of
Georgia, 304 U. S. 439 ,
this Court described the Athletic Association as a body carrying on
"a business comparable in all essentials to those usually conducted
by private owners." Id. at 304 U. S. 451 .
Section 32-153 of the Georgia Code specifically provides that
athletic associations are not to be considered agencies of the
State.
[ Footnote 3 ]
Actual malice was defined by the charge as encompassing
"the notion of ill will, spite, hatred and an intent to injure
one. Malice also denotes a wanton or reckless indifference or
culpable negligence with regard to the rights of others."
The jury was told that whether "actual malice or wanton or
reckless indifference has been established must be determined from
all of the evidence in the case." The trial court then directed the
jury's attention to the circumstances of preparation. The impact of
the charge is considered in more detail at 388 U. S.
156 -158, infra. [ Footnote 4 ]
Two particular statements were at issue, the remark that "Walker
assumed command of the crowd," and the accusation that Walker led a
charge against the marshals.
[ Footnote 5 ] See Tehan v. Shott, 382 U. S. 406 , 382 U. S. 409 ,
n. 3; Linkletter v. Walker, 381 U.
S. 618 , 381 U. S.
622 -629; Griffin v. California, 380 U.
S. 609 ; White v. Maryland, 373 U. S.
59 .
[ Footnote 6 ] See also Ackermann v. United States, 340 U.
S. 193 , 340 U. S.
198 .
[ Footnote 7 ]
In Beauharnais v. Illinois, 343 U.
S. 250 , the Court had upheld an Illinois group libel
statute, but the majority had warned that,
"'While this Court sits,' it retains and exercises authority to
nullify action which encroaches on freedom of utterance under the
guise of punishing libel." Id. at 343 U. S.
263 -264. There were also four vigorous dissenters to the
holding in that case. An article appearing in the June, 1962, New
York University Law Review had quoted MR. JUSTICE BLACK as
believing that "there should be no libel or defamation law in the
United States. . . ." Cahn, Justice Black and First Amendment
"Absolutes": A Public Interview, 37 N.Y.U.L.Rev. 549, 557.
[ Footnote 8 ]
In Robertson v. Baldwin, 165 U.
S. 275 , 165 U. S. 281 ,
the Court said:
"Thus, the freedom of speech and of the press (art. 1) does not
permit the publication of libels, blasphemous or indecent articles,
or other publications injurious to public morals or private
reputation. . . ."
That sentiment was repeated in a number of cases, including Beauharnais v. Illinois, supra, n 7. See Near v. Minnesota, 283 U.
S. 697 , 283 U. S. 715 ; Chaplinsky v. New Hampshire, 315 U.
S. 568 .
[ Footnote 9 ] See, e.g., Sweeney v. Patterson, 76 U.S.App.D.C. 23,
128 F.2d 457; Hendrix v. Mobile Register, 202 Ala. 616, 81
So. 558.
[ Footnote 10 ]
Even after our decision in New York Times was before
him, the trial judge held it inapplicable. It is almost certain
that he would have rebuffed any effort to interpose general
constitutional defenses at the time of trial. See Comment,
Waiver of a Previously Unrecognized Defense: Must Lawyers Be
Seers?, 114 U.Pa.L.Rev. 451.
[ Footnote 11 ]
The majority opinion in Time, Inc. v. Hill, 385 U. S. 374 , was
limited to the consideration of nondefamatory matter. Id. at 385 U. S.
391 .
[ Footnote 12 ] Schenck v. United States, 249 U. S.
47 (Holmes, J.); Abrams v. United States, 250 U. S. 616 , 250 U. S. 624 (Holmes, J., dissenting); Whitney v. California, 274 U. S. 357 , 274 U. S. 372 (Brandeis, J., concurring).
[ Footnote 13 ] See Levy, Legacy of Suppression. The phrase is from the
Court's opinion in Time, Inc. v. Hill, supra, at 385 U. S.
389 .
[ Footnote 14 ] E.g., 48 Stat. 82, as amended, 15 U.S.C. § 77k
(penalizing negligent misstatement).
[ Footnote 15 ]
18 U.S.C. § 1341.
[ Footnote 16 ] See Traylor Engineering & Mfg. Co. v. National Container
Corp., 45 Del. 143, 70 A.2d 9; Restatement, Torts § 525
(deceit); Nash v. Minnesota Title Ins. & Trust Co., 163 Mass. 574, 40 N.E. 1039 (negligent misrepresentation).
[ Footnote 17 ] See 1 Harper & James, The Law of Torts § 5.20.
[ Footnote 18 ]
Some privileges, such as the one pertaining to reports of
judicial proceedings, are recognized as absolute. Others, such as
the fair comment privilege, are recognized only as conditional
privileges, and may be vitiated by proof of actual malice. See
generally Prosser, The Law of Torts §§ 109, 110.
[ Footnote 19 ]
Nor does anything we have said touch, in any way, libel or other
tort actions not involving public figures or matters of public
interest.
[ Footnote 20 ]
Counsel for Butts continually pressed upon the jury in argument
that the defendant had failed to exercise a minimum of care. He did
not seriously contend that the Saturday Evening Post was actuated
by preexisting animosity toward Butts. Arguing that the
misquotations which were shown to be present were proof of malice,
he stated: "I say that is not fair journalism; I say that is not
true, careful reporting." After reviewing the failure of Curtis to
interview Carmichael ( see p. 388 U. S. 157 , infra ) or to check the game films, he asked the jury:
"Again, is that good reporting? Is that what the field or the
profession of journalism owes you and owes me . . . when it is
getting ready to write an article which it knows and which it
states therein that it is going to ruin us. . . ."
The gist of Butts' contention on "actual malice" was that Curtis
had been anxious to publish an expose, and had thus wantonly and
recklessly seized on a questionable affidavit from Burnett. It is
this theory which we feel that the jury must have accepted in
awarding punitive damages.
[ Footnote 21 ]
It is inconceivable that the jury might have treated the
"investigatory" evidence differently if it had been presented with
respect to compensatory damages, rather than with regard to
punitive damages.
[ Footnote 22 ]
On September 26, 1962, Walker had made a statement on radio
station KWKH at Shreveport, Louisiana, urging people to "[r]ise to
a stand beside Governor Ross Barnett at Jackson, Mississippi." He
contended that the people had "talked, listened and been pushed
around far too much. . . ." He promised that he would "be there,"
on "the right side." The next morning, in a television appearance
in Dallas, he repeated the same sentiments, and he set out his
views once again from New Orleans on the evening of September 28,
1962. On September 29, 1962, Walker arrived in Jackson,
Mississippi, and held another press and television conference in
which he called for "violent vocal protest." On the afternoon of
September 30, 1962, Walker held a final press conference at which
he again urged defiance of court orders and federal power.
[ Footnote 23 ]
It should also be noted that, prior to publication, the Saturday
Evening Post had been notified both by Butts and his daughter that
the material about to be printed was false. Despite these warnings,
and the fact that no member of the staff had ever even seen
Burnett's crucial notes, no further efforts at investigation were
undertaken prior to publication. It might indeed be argued that
this conduct would have sufficed, under proper instructions, to
satisfy even the "actual malice" standard of New York
Times, the notice to the Saturday Evening Post being
considered as furnishing the necessary "mental element." New
York Times, supra, at 376 U. S. 287 .
MR. CHIEF JUSTICE WARREN, concurring in the result.
While I agree with the results announced by MR. JUSTICE HARLAN
in both of these cases, I find myself in disagreement with his
stated reasons for reaching those results. Our difference stems
from his departure from the teaching of New York Times Co. v.
Sullivan, 376 U. S. 254 (1964), to which we both subscribed only three years ago. I In the New York Times case, we held that a State
cannot, consistently with the First and Fourteenth Amendments,
award damages to a "public official" for a defamatory falsehood
relating to his official conduct unless the verdict is based on
proof of "actual malice" -- that is, proof that the defamatory
statement was made "with knowledge that it was false or with
reckless disregard of whether it was false or not." 376 U.S. at 376 U. S. 280 .
The present cases involve not "public officials," but "public
figures" whose views and actions with respect to public issues and
events are often of as much concern to the citizen as the attitudes
and behavior of "public officials" with respect to the same issues
and events.
All of us agree that the basic considerations underlying the
First Amendment require that some limitations be placed on the
application of state libel laws to "public figures" as well as
"public officials." Similarly, the seven members of the Court who
deem it necessary to pass upon the question agree that the
respondents in these cases are "public figures" for First Amendment
purposes. Page 388 U. S. 163 Having reached this point, however, MR. JUSTICE HARLAN's opinion
departs from the standard of New York Times and
substitutes in cases involving "public figures" a standard that is
based on "highly unreasonable conduct" and is phrased in terms of
"extreme departure from the standards of investigation and
reporting ordinarily adhered to by responsible publishers"
( ante, p. 388 U. S.
155 ). I cannot believe that a standard which is based on
such an unusual and uncertain formulation could either guide a jury
of laymen or afford the protection for speech and debate that is
fundamental to our society and guaranteed by the First
Amendment.
To me, differentiation between "public figures" and "public
officials" and adoption of separate standards of proof for each
have no basis in law, logic, or First Amendment policy.
Increasingly in this country, the distinctions between governmental
and private sectors are blurred. Since the depression of the 1930's
and World War II, there has been a rapid fusion of economic and
political power, a merging of science, industry, and government,
and a high degree of interaction between the intellectual,
governmental, and business worlds. Depression, war, international
tensions, national and international markets, and the surging
growth of science and technology have precipitated national and
international problems that demand national and international
solutions. While these trends and events have occasioned a
consolidation of governmental power, power has also become much
more organized in what we have commonly considered to be the
private sector. In many situations, policy determinations which
traditionally were channeled through formal political institutions
are now originated and implemented through a complex array of
boards, committees, commissions, corporations, and associations,
some only loosely connected with the Government. This blending of
positions and power has also occurred in Page 388 U. S. 164 the case of individuals, so that many who do not hold public
office at the moment are nevertheless intimately involved in the
resolution of important public questions or, by reason of their
fame, shape events in areas of concern to society at large.
Viewed in this context, then, it is plain that, although they
are not subject to the restraints of the political process, "public
figures," like "public officials," often play an influential role
in ordering society. And surely, as a class, these "public figures"
have as ready access as "public officials" to mass media of
communication, both to influence policy and to counter criticism of
their views and activities. Our citizenry has a legitimate and
substantial interest in the conduct of such persons, and freedom of
the press to engage in uninhibited debate about their involvement
in public issues and events is as crucial as it is in the case of
"public officials." The fact that they are not amenable to the
restraints of the political process only underscores the legitimate
and substantial nature of the interest, since it means that public
opinion may be the only instrument by which society can attempt to
influence their conduct.
I therefore adhere to the New York Times standard in
the case of "public figures" as well as "public officials." It is a
manageable standard, readily stated and understood, which also
balances to a proper degree the legitimate interests traditionally
protected by the law of defamation. Its definition of "actual
malice" is not so restrictive that recovery is limited to
situations where there is "knowing falsehood" on the part of the
publisher of false and defamatory matter. "Reckless disregard" for
the truth or falsity, measured by the conduct of the publisher,
will also expose him to liability for publishing false material
which is injurious to reputation. More significantly, however, the New York Times standard is an important safeguard for the
rights of the Page 388 U. S. 165 press and public to inform and be informed on matters of
legitimate interest. Evenly applied to cases involving "public men"
-- whether they be "public officials" or "public figures" -- it
will afford the necessary insulation for the fundamental interests
which the First Amendment was designed to protect. II I have no difficulty in concluding that No. 150, Associated
Press v. Walker, must be reversed since it is in clear
conflict with New York Times. The constitutional defenses
were properly raised and preserved by the petitioner. The trial
judge expressly ruled that no showing of malice in any sense had
been made, and he reversed an award of punitive damages for that
reason. The seven members of this Court who reach the question
agree with that conclusion, and all agree that the courts below
erred in holding the First Amendment inapplicable. Under any
reasoning, General Walker was a public man in whose public conduct
society and the press had a legitimate and substantial
interest. III But No. 37, Curtis Publishing Co. v. Butts, presents an
entirely different situation. There, no First Amendment defenses
were raised by the petitioner until after the trial. Because of
this failure and because the case was tried before our decision in New York Times, the trial judge did not instruct the jury
in terms of the precise formulation we adopted. In connection with
the issue of punitive damages, however, the trial judge did give an
"actual malice" instruction which invoked the elements we later
held necessary in New York Times. He instructed the jury
that it would have to find "actual malice" before awarding punitive
damages, and he continued by defining "actual malice" as denoting
"wanton or reckless indifference or culpable negligence with
regard Page 388 U. S. 166 to the rights of others" and as including notions of "ill will,
spite, hatred and an intent to injure one." Under the Georgia law
of defamation which governed the case, the jury was also
specifically required to find that the defamatory statements were
false before it could award any damages, and it was so instructed.
With the jury's attention thus focused on this threshold
requirement of falsity, the references in the instructions to
wanton or reckless indifference and culpable negligence most
probably resulted in a verdict based on the requirement of reckless
disregard for the truth of which we spoke in New York
Times. [ Footnote 2/1 ] Although
the "actual malice" instructions were not also given in connection
with the compensatory damage issue, it is difficult to conceive how
petitioner could have been prejudiced by that failure in view of
the fact that the jury, guided by "actual malice" instructions,
awarded $3,000,000 in punitive damages. [ Footnote 2/2 ]
Unquestionably, in cases tried after our decision in New
York Times, we should require strict compliance with the
standard we established. We should not, however, Page 388 U. S. 167 be so inflexible in judging cases tried prior thereto,
especially when, as here, the trial judge -- unaided by advice or
objections from counsel -- recognized the essential principle and
conformed with it to a substantial degree. Moreover, after the New York Times rule was brought to the trial judge's
attention in a post-trial motion, he reviewed the record in light
of that precise standard and held that the jury verdict should not
be disturbed, since
"there was ample evidence from which a jury could have concluded
that there was reckless disregard by the [petitioner] of whether
the article was false or not."
An additional factor leads me to the conclusion that we should
not insist on the financial and emotional expenses of a retrial
here merely because the trial judge's instructions were not given
in the precise terms of the present constitutional standard.
[ Footnote 2/3 ] That factor, to
which I briefly adverted above, was the choice of the petitioner in
this case to raise only truth as a defense, and to omit in its
pleadings and at the trial any reference to possible First
Amendment defenses, or even to the conditional privilege provided
by Georgia law for "[c]omments upon the acts of public men in their
public capacity and with reference thereto." [ Footnote 2/4 ] I use the word "choice" in this Page 388 U. S. 168 connection, because the facts lead me, as they did the Court of
Appeals, to the firm conclusion that the omissions were deliberate.
Although this trial occurred before our decision in New York
Times, we had granted certiorari to review that case even
before the complaint here was filed. [ Footnote 2/5 ] The Alabama law firm which had represented
the New York Times in the state courts was involved in the
trial of this case. Lead counsel in the cases conferred
periodically, and one of the members of the Alabama law firm
referred to above sat at the counsel table throughout this trial.
The same Alabama law firm was retained to represent petitioner in a
lawsuit filed by Coach Paul Bryant, who was also libeled by the
magazine article here in question. First Amendment defenses were
raised both at the trial of the New York Times case and by
the pleadings in the Bryant lawsuit, which was settled for a
substantial sum of money. But counsel did not raise such defenses
here. Given the importance of this case to petitioner and the
interplay between overlapping counsel aligned on the same sides of
related lawsuits, I can only conclude that tactical or public
relations considerations explain the failure here to defend on
First Amendment grounds. IV Satisfied, as I am, that, under the circumstances of the Butts case, no retrial should be ordered merely because of
the instructions, I turn now to the final duty which this Court has
when violations of fundamental constitutional Page 388 U. S. 169 principles are alleged. We must review the evidence to ascertain
whether the judgment can stand consistently with those principles. New York Times Co. v. Sullivan, 376 U.
S. 254 , 376 U. S. 285 (1964); Speiser v. Randall, 357 U.
S. 513 , 357 U. S. 525 (1958).
The petitioner in this case is a major factor in the publishing
business. Among its publications is the Saturday Evening Post,
which published the defamatory falsehoods here in question.
Apparently because of declining advertising revenues, an editorial
decision was made to "change the image" of the Saturday Evening
Post with the hope that circulation and advertising revenues would
thereby be increased. The starting point for this change of image
was an announcement that the magazine would embark upon a program
of "sophisticated muckraking," [ Footnote 2/6 ] designed to "provoke people, make them
mad."
Shortly thereafter, and as an apparent implementation of the new
policy, the Saturday Evening Post purchased the rights to the
article which formed the subject matter of this case. The slipshod
and sketchy investigatory techniques employed to check the veracity
of the source and the inferences to be drawn from the few facts
believed to be true are detailed at length in the opinion of MR.
JUSTICE HARLAN. Suffice it to say that little investigative effort
was expended initially, and no additional inquiries were made even
after the editors were notified by respondent and his daughter that
the account Page 388 U. S. 170 to be published was absolutely untrue. Instead, the Saturday
Evening Post proceeded on its reckless course with full knowledge
of the harm that would likely result from publication of the
article. This knowledge was signaled by the statements at the
conclusion of the article that "Wally Butts will never help any
football team again," and "careers will be ruined, that is
sure."
I am satisfied that the evidence here discloses that degree of
reckless disregard for the truth of which we spoke in New York
Times and Garrison. Freedom of the press under the
First Amendment does not include absolute license to destroy lives
or careers.
[ Footnote 2/1 ]
We held unconstitutional in Garrison v. Louisiana, 379 U. S. 64 (1964), a criminal defamation statute which authorized conviction
on proof that a defamatory statement had been motivated by ill
will. The statute did not require that the defamatory statement be
false to sustain such a conviction.
[ Footnote 2/2 ]
In the New York Times case, "actual malice"
instructions were given in connection with punitive damages.
However, we noted:
"While Alabama law apparently requires proof of actual malice
for an award of punitive damages, where general damages are
concerned, malice is 'presumed.' Such a presumption is inconsistent
with the federal rule. . . . Since the trial judge did not instruct
the jury to differentiate between general and punitive damages, it
may be that the verdict was wholly an award of one or the other.
But it is impossible to know in view of the general verdict
returned. Because of this uncertainty, the judgment must
be reversed, and the case remanded."
376 U.S. at 376 U. S.
283 -284. (Emphasis added.) The jury in the present case
was required to separate compensatory and punitive damages.
[ Footnote 2/3 ] Cf. Time, Inc. v. Hill, 385 U.
S. 374 , 385 U. S. 411 (1967) (dissenting opinion of MR. JUSTICE FORTAS).
[ Footnote 2/4 ]
Ga.Code Ann. § 105-709(6) provides:
"Privileged communications. -- The following are deemed
privileged communications: "
" * * * *" "6. Comments upon the acts of public men in their public
capacity and with reference thereto."
This privilege is qualified by Ga.Code Ann. § 105-710, which
provides:
"Malicious use of privilege. -- In every case of privileged
communications, if the privilege is used merely as a cloak for
venting private malice, and not bona fide in promotion of
the object for which the privilege is granted, the party defamed
shall have a right of action."
[ Footnote 2/5 ]
Certiorari was granted in New York Times Co. v.
Sullivan on January 7, 1963. 371 U.S. 946. The complaint in
this case was filed approximately 2 months later, on March 25,
1963. Counsel here could not have anticipated the precise standard
we announced in New York Times. In the Bryant lawsuit and,
of course, in the New York Times case itself, counsel did,
however, raise general First Amendment defenses. No reference
whatever to the First Amendment was made by defense counsel in the
trial of this case.
[ Footnote 2/6 ]
Webster's New International Dictionary (2d ed., unabr.), p.
1606, reports the source of the term "muckrake" as follows:
"On April 14, 1906, President Roosevelt delivered a speech in
which he used the term muckrake in attacking the practice of making
sweeping and unjust charges of corruption against public men and
corporations. . . ."
Roget's International Thesaurus § 934(3) lists the following as
synonyms: muckrake, throw mud at, throw or fling dirt at, drag
through the mud and bespatter.
MR. JUSTICE BLACK, with whom MR. JUSTICE DOUGLAS joins,
concurring in the result in No. 150, and dissenting in No. 37.
I concur in reversal of the judgment in No. 150, Associated
Press v. Walker, based on the grounds and reasons stated in
Parts I and II of THE CHIEF JUSTICE's opinion. I do this, however,
as in Time, Inc. v. Hill, 385 U.
S. 374 , 385 U. S.
398 ,
"in order for the Court to be able at this time to agree on [a
disposition of] this important case based on the prevailing
constitutional doctrine expressed in New York Times Co. v.
Sullivan, 376 U. S. 254 . [THE CHIEF
JUSTICE's] . . . opinion [would decide] the case in accordance with
this doctrine, to which the majority adhere. In agreeing to . . .
[that] opinion, I do not recede from any of the views I have
previously expressed about the much wider press and speech freedoms
I think the First and Fourteenth Amendments were designed to grant
to the people of the Nation. See, e.g., New York Times Co
. v. Sullivan, 376 U.S. at 376 U. S.
293 ( concurring opinion); Rosenblatt v. Baer, 383 U. S.
75 , 383 U. S. 94 (concurring and
dissenting opinion)."
I would reverse the judgment in No. 37 for the reasons given in
my concurring opinion in New York Times Co. v. Page 388 U. S. 171 Sullivan, 376 U. S. 254 , 376 U. S. 293 ,
and my concurring and dissenting opinion in Rosenblatt v.
Baer, 383 U. S. 75 , 383 U. S. 94 ,
but wish to add a few words.
These cases illustrate, I think, the accuracy of my prior
predictions that the New York Times constitutional rule
concerning libel is wholly inadequate to save the press from being
destroyed by libel judgments. Here, the Court reverses the case of Associated Press v. Walker, but affirms the judgment of Curtis Publishing Co. v. Butts. The main reason for this
quite contradictory action, so far as I can determine, is that the
Court looks at the facts in both cases as though it were a jury,
and reaches the conclusion that the Saturday Evening Post, in
writing about Butts, was so abusive that its article is more of a
libel at the constitutional level than is the one by the Associated
Press. That seems a strange way to erect a constitutional standard
for libel cases. If this precedent is followed, it means that we
must, in all libel cases hereafter, weigh the facts and hold that
all papers and magazines guilty of gross writing or reporting are
constitutionally liable, while they are not if the quality of the
reporting is approved by a majority of us. In the final analysis,
what we do in these circumstances is to review the factual
questions in cases decided by juries -- a review which is a flat
violation of the Seventh Amendment.
It strikes me that the Court is getting itself in the same
quagmire in the field of libel in which it is now helplessly
struggling in the field of obscenity. No one, including this Court,
can know what is and what is not constitutionally obscene or
libelous under this Court's rulings. Today, the Court will not give
the First Amendment its natural and obvious meaning by holding that
a law which seriously menaces the very life of press freedom
violates the First Amendment. In fact, the Court is suggesting
various experimental expedients in libel cases, Page 388 U. S. 172 all of which boil down to a determination of how offensive to
this Court a particular libel judgment may be, either because of
its immense size or because the Court does not like the way an
alleged libelee was treated. Again, I suggest ( see Time, Inc.
v. Hill, 385 U. S. 374 , 385 U. S. 399 )
that we are rapidly but surely getting ourselves in the dilemma we
found ourselves in when we were compelled to overrule the
ill-starred case of Betts v. Brady, 316 U.
S. 455 ,* in order that the state courts of the country
might be able to determine with some degree of certainty when an
indigent person was entitled to the benefit of a lawyer and avoid
the spawning of hundreds of habeas corpus cases that finally raised
questions that a lawyer could and would have raised at the
trial.
I think it is time for this Court to abandon New York Times
Co. v. Sullivan and adopt the rule to the effect that the
First Amendment was intended to leave the press free from the
harassment of libel judgments.
*Gideon v. Wainwright, 372 U. S. 335 .
MR. JUSTICE BRENNAN, with whom MR. JUSTICE WHITE joins,
concurring in the result in No. 150, and dissenting in No. 37.
I join-Parts I and II of the opinion of THE CHIEF JUSTICE and
the disposition in No. 150, Associated Press v.
Walker. In No. 37, Curtis Publishing Co. v. Butts, insofar as
THE CHIEF JUSTICE's opinion demonstrates that the evidence
unmistakably would support a judgment for Butts under the New
York Times standard, I agree. I would, however, remand for a
new trial, since the charge to the jury did not comport with that
standard. [ Footnote 3/1 ] The charge
on compensatory damages directed that the jury find Page 388 U. S. 173 liability on a finding of mere falsehood. And the trial court
stated that punitive damages might be awarded on a finding of
"actual malice," which it defined to encompass "the notion of ill
will, spite, hatred and an intent to injure one," and also to
denote "a wanton or reckless indifference or culpable negligence
with regard to the rights of others." The court detailed some
factors the jury could consider in applying this standard. It said,
for example, that "[a] publication may be so extravagant in its
denunciation and so vituperative in its character as to justify an
inference of malice," and that
"proof that the plaintiff did demand a retraction, but that the
defendant failed to retract the article, may be considered by you
on the question of punitive damages."
But
"[d]ebate on public issues will not be uninhibited if the
speaker must run the risk that it will be proved in court that he
spoke out of hatred; even if he did speak out of hatred, utterances
honestly believed contribute to the free interchange of ideas and
the ascertainment of truth." Garrison v. Louisiana, 379 U. S.
64 , 379 U. S. 73 .
The "good motives" of the publisher can be no more relevant in the
context of "public men" than in the context of criticism of "public
officials." See Garrison, supra. The court added that the
Post could show in mitigation of punitive damages that "it in good
faith relied upon certain matters which had come to its attention."
This makes crystal clear that the standard announced authorized the
jury to award punitive damages even though it found that the Post
had in good faith relied on matters which had come to its
attention. The charge undoubtedly fails to comport with New
York Times. [ Footnote 3/2 ] Page 388 U. S. 174 That the evidence might support a verdict under New York
Times cannot justify our taking from the jury the function of
determining, under proper instructions, whether the New York
Times standard has been met. The extent of this Court's role
in reviewing the facts, in a case such as this, is to ascertain
whether there is evidence by which a jury could reasonably find
liability under the constitutionally required instructions. See
New York Times Co. v. Sullivan, 376 U.
S. 254 , 376 U. S.
284 -292; Time, Inc. v. Hill, 385 U.
S. 374 , 385 U. S.
391 -394. When, as in this case, such evidence appears,
the proper disposition in this federal case is to reverse and
remand with direction for a new trial. See Time, Inc. v. Hill,
supra. [ Footnote 3/1 ]
For the reasons expressed in the opinion of MR. JUSTICE HARLAN,
I agree that petitioner did not waive his contentions under New
York Time.
[ Footnote 3/2 ]
The statement by the trial court that "[m]alice also denotes a
wanton or reckless indifference or culpable negligence with regard
to the rights of others" could reasonably have been regarded by the
jury to relate not to the truth or falsity of the matter, but to
the Post's attitude toward Butts' reputation, akin to the spite and
ill will in which terms the court had just defined "malice." See Time Inc. v. Hill, 385 U. S. 374 , 385 U. S. 396 ,
n. 12. | In Curtis Publishing Co. v. Butts (1967), the Supreme Court considered a libel case brought by a college athletic director, Wally Butts, against Curtis Publishing Co. for an article accusing him of conspiring to fix a football game. The Court extended the constitutional protections for free speech established in New York Times Co. v. Sullivan (1964) to cases involving public figures, not just public officials.
The Court held that while the First Amendment protects free speech and press, it does not protect reckless falsehoods that harm others. The jury was instructed to consider the magazine's reliability, sources, and care in checking assertions when determining if it acted with "wanton and reckless indifference." The Court of Appeals affirmed, finding that Curtis Publishing Co. had waived its right to challenge the constitutional claim.
The Supreme Court's decision clarified the standard for awarding punitive damages in defamation cases involving public figures, emphasizing the need for proper jury instructions and evidence to support liability under constitutionally mandated instructions. |
Free Speech | Brandenburg v. Ohio | https://supreme.justia.com/cases/federal/us/395/444/ | U.S. Supreme Court Brandenburg v. Ohio, 395
U.S. 444 (1969) Brandenburg v. Ohio No. 492 Argued February 27,
1969 Decided June 9, 1969 395
U.S. 444 APPEAL FROM THE SUPREME COURT OF
OHIO Syllabus Appellant, a Ku Klux Klan leader, was convicted under the Ohio
Criminal Syndicalism statute for
"advocat[ing] . . . the duty, necessity, or propriety of crime,
sabotage, violence, or unlawful methods of terrorism as a means of
accomplishing industrial or political reform"
and for
"voluntarily assembl[ing] with any society, group or assemblage
of persons formed to teach or advocate the doctrines of criminal
syndicalism."
Neither the indictment nor the trial judge's instructions
refined the statute's definition of the crime in terms of mere
advocacy not distinguished from incitement to imminent lawless
action. Held: Since the statute, by its words and as applied,
purports to punish mere advocacy and to forbid, on pain of criminal
punishment, assembly with others merely to advocate the described
type of action, it falls within the condemnation of the First and
Fourteenth Amendments. Freedoms of speech and press do not permit a
State to forbid advocacy of the use of force or of law violation
except where such advocacy is directed to inciting or producing
imminent lawless action and is likely to incite or produce such
action. Whitney v. California, 274 U.
S. 357 , overruled. Reversed. PER CURIAM.
The appellant, a leader of a Ku Klux Klan group, was convicted
under the Ohio Criminal Syndicalism statute for "advocat[ing] . . .
the duty, necessity, or propriety Page 395 U. S. 445 of crime, sabotage, violence, or unlawful methods of terrorism
as a means of accomplishing industrial or political reform" and
for
"voluntarily assembl[ing] with any society, group, or assemblage
of persons formed to teach or advocate the doctrines of criminal
syndicalism."
Ohio Rev.Code Ann. § 2923.13. He was fined $1,000 and sentenced
to one to 10 years' imprisonment. The appellant challenged the
constitutionality of the criminal syndicalism statute under the
First and Fourteenth Amendments to the United States Constitution,
but the intermediate appellate court of Ohio affirmed his
conviction without opinion. The Supreme Court of Ohio dismissed his
appeal sua sponte "for the reason that no substantial
constitutional question exists herein." It did not file an opinion
or explain its conclusions. Appeal was taken to this Court, and we
noted probable jurisdiction. 393 U. S. 94 (196). We reverse.
The record shows that a man, identified at trial as the
appellant, telephoned an announcer-reporter on the staff of a
Cincinnati television station and invited him to come to a Ku Klux
Klan "rally" to be held at a farm in Hamilton County. With the
cooperation of the organizers, the reporter and a cameraman
attended the meeting and filmed the events. Portions of the films
were later broadcast on the local station and on a national
network.
The prosecution's case rested on the films and on testimony
identifying the appellant as the person who communicated with the
reporter and who spoke at the rally. The State also introduced into
evidence several articles appearing in the film, including a
pistol, a rifle, a shotgun, ammunition, a Bible, and a red hood
worn by the speaker in the films.
One film showed 12 hooded figures, some of whom carried
firearms. They were gathered around a large wooden cross, which
they burned. No one was present Page 395 U. S. 446 other than the participants and the newsmen who made the film.
Most of the words uttered during the scene were incomprehensible
when the film was projected, but scattered phrases could be
understood that were derogatory of Negroes and, in one instance, of
Jews. [ Footnote 1 ] Another
scene on the same film showed the appellant, in Klan regalia,
making a speech. The speech, in full, was as follows:
"This is an organizers' meeting. We have had quite a few members
here today which are -- we have hundreds, hundreds of members
throughout the State of Ohio. I can quote from a newspaper clipping
from the Columbus, Ohio, Dispatch, five weeks ago Sunday morning.
The Klan has more members in the State of Ohio than does any other
organization. We're not a revengent organization, but if our
President, our Congress, our Supreme Court, continues to suppress
the white, Caucasian race, it's possible that there might have to
be some revengeance taken."
"We are marching on Congress July the Fourth, four hundred
thousand strong. From there, we are dividing into two groups, one
group to march on St. Augustine, Florida, the other group to march
into Mississippi. Thank you. " Page 395 U. S. 447 The second film showed six hooded figures one of whom, later
identified as the appellant, repeated a speech very similar to that
recorded on the first film. The reference to the possibility of
"revengeance" was omitted, and one sentence was added: "Personally,
I believe the nigger should be returned to Africa, the Jew returned
to Israel." Though some of the figures in the films carried
weapons, the speaker did not.
The Ohio Criminal Syndicalism Statute was enacted in 1919. From
1917 to 1920, identical or quite similar laws were adopted by 20
States and two territories. E. Dowell, A History of Criminal
Syndicalism Legislation in the United States 21 (1939). In 1927,
this Court sustained the constitutionality of California's Criminal
Syndicalism Act, Cal.Penal Code §§ 11400-11402, the text of which
is quite similar to that of the laws of Ohio. Whitney v.
California, 274 U. S. 357 (1927). The Court upheld the statute on the ground that, without
more, "advocating" violent means to effect political and economic
change involves such danger to the security of the State that the
State may outlaw it. Cf. Fiske v. Kansas, 274 U.
S. 380 (1927). But Whitney has been thoroughly
discredited by later decisions. See Dennis v. United
States, 341 U. S. 494 , at 341 U. S. 507 (1951). These later decisions have fashioned the principle that the
constitutional guarantees of free speech and free press do not
permit a State to forbid or proscribe advocacy of the use of force
or of law violation except where such advocacy is directed to
inciting or producing imminent lawless action and is likely to
incite or produce such action. [ Footnote 2 ] As we Page 395 U. S. 448 said in Noto v. United States, 367 U.
S. 290 , 367 U. S.
297 -298 (1961),
"the mere abstract teaching . . . of the moral propriety or even
moral necessity for a resort to force and violence is not the same
as preparing a group for violent action and steeling it to such
action." See also Herndon v. Lowry, 301 U.
S. 242 , 301 U. S.
259 -261 (1937); Bond v. Floyd, 385 U.
S. 116 , 385 U. S. 134 (1966). A statute which fails to draw this distinction
impermissibly intrudes upon the freedoms guaranteed by the First
and Fourteenth Amendments. It sweeps within its condemnation speech
which our Constitution has immunized from governmental control. Cf. Yates v. United States, 354 U.
S. 298 (1957); De Jonge v. Oregon, 299 U.
S. 353 (1937); Stromberg v. California, 283 U. S. 359 (1931). See also United States v. Robel, 389 U.
S. 258 (1967); Keyishian v. Board of Regents, 385 U. S. 589 (1967); Elfbrandt v. Russell, 384 U. S.
11 (1966); Aptheker v. Secretary of State, 378 U. S. 500 (1964); Baggett v. Bullitt, 377 U.
S. 360 (1964).
Measured by this test, Ohio's Criminal Syndicalism Act cannot be
sustained. The Act punishes persons who "advocate or teach the
duty, necessity, or propriety" of violence "as a means of
accomplishing industrial or political reform"; or who publish or
circulate or display any book or paper containing such advocacy; or
who "justify" the commission of violent acts "with intent to
exemplify, spread or advocate the propriety of the doctrines of
criminal syndicalism"; or who "voluntarily assemble" with a group
formed "to teach or advocate the doctrines of criminal
syndicalism." Neither the indictment nor the trial judge's
instructions to the jury in any way refined the statute's bald
definition of the crime Page 395 U. S. 449 in terms of mere advocacy not distinguished from incitement to
imminent lawless action. [ Footnote
3 ]
Accordingly, we are here confronted with a statute which, by its
own words and as applied, purports to punish mere advocacy and to
forbid, on pain of criminal punishment, assembly with others merely
to advocate the described type of action. [ Footnote 4 ] Such a statute falls within the
condemnation of the First and Fourteenth Amendments. The contrary
teaching of Whitney v. California, supra, cannot be
supported, and that decision is therefore overruled. Reversed. [ Footnote 1 ]
The significant portions that could be understood were:
"How far is the nigger going to -- yeah."
"This is what we are going to do to the niggers."
"A dirty nigger."
"Send the Jews back to Israel."
"Let's give them back to the dark garden."
"Save America."
"Let's go back to constitutional betterment."
"Bury the niggers."
"We intend to do our part."
"Give us our state rights."
"Freedom for the whites."
"Nigger will have to fight for every inch he gets from now
on."
[ Footnote 2 ]
It was on the theory that the Smith Act, 54 Stat. 670, 18 U.S.C.
§ 35, embodied such a principle and that it had been applied only
in conformity with it that this Court sustained the Act's
constitutionality. Dennis v. United States, 341 U.
S. 494 (1951). That this was the basis for Dennis was emphasized in Yates v. United States, 354 U. S. 298 , 354 U. S.
320 -324 (1957), in which the Court overturned
convictions for advocacy of the forcible overthrow of the
Government under the Smith Act, because the trial judge's
instructions had allowed conviction for mere advocacy, unrelated to
its tendency to produce forcible action.
[ Footnote 3 ]
The first count of the indictment charged that appellant
"did unlawfully by word of mouth advocate the necessity, or
propriety of crime, violence, or unlawful methods of terrorism as a
means of accomplishing political reform. . . ."
The second count charged that appellant "did unlawfully
voluntarily assemble with a group or assemblage of persons formed
to advocate the doctrines of criminal syndicalism. . . ." The trial
judge's charge merely followed the language of the indictment. No
construction of the statute by the Ohio courts has brought it
within constitutionally permissible limits. The Ohio Supreme Court
has considered the statute in only one previous case, State v.
Kassay, 126 Ohio St. 177, 184 N.E. 521 (1932), where the
constitutionality of the statute was sustained.
[ Footnote 4 ]
Statutes affecting the right of assembly, like those touching on
freedom of speech, must observe the established distinctions
between mere advocacy and incitement to imminent lawless action,
for, as Chief Justice Hughes wrote in De Jonge v. Oregon,
supra, at 299 U. S. 364 :
"The right of peaceable assembly is a right cognate to those of
free speech and free press, and is equally fundamental." See
also United States v. Cruikshank, 92 U. S.
542 , 92 U. S. 552 (1876); Hague v. CIO, 307 U. S. 496 , 307 U. S. 513 , 307 U. S. 519 (1939); NAACP v. Alabama ex rel. Patterson, 357 U.
S. 449 , 357 U. S.
460 -461 (1958).
MR. JUSTICE BLACK, concurring.
I agree with the views expressed by MR. JUSTICE DOUGLAS in his
concurring opinion in this case that the "clear and present danger"
doctrine should have no place Page 395 U. S. 450 in the interpretation of the First Amendment. I join the Court's
opinion, which, as I understand it, simply cites Dennis v.
United States, 341 U. S. 494 (1951), but does not indicate any agreement on the Court's part
with the "clear and present danger" doctrine on which Dennis purported to rely.
MR. JUSTICE DOUGLAS, concurring.
While I join the opinion of the Court, I desire to enter a caveat. The "clear and present danger" test was adumbrated by Mr.
Justice Holmes in a case arising during World War I -- a war
"declared" by the Congress, not by the Chief Executive. The case
was Schenck v. United States, 249 U. S.
47 , 249 U. S. 52 ,
where the defendant was charged with attempts to cause
insubordination in the military and obstruction of enlistment. The
pamphlets that were distributed urged resistance to the draft,
denounced conscription, and impugned the motives of those backing
the war effort. The First Amendment was tendered as a defense. Mr.
Justice Holmes, in rejecting that defense, said:
"The question in every case is whether the words used are used
in such circumstances and are of such a nature as to create a clear
and present danger that they will bring about the substantive evils
that Congress has a right to prevent. It is a question of proximity
and degree." Frohwerk v. United States, 249 U.
S. 204 , also authored by Mr. Justice Holmes, involved
prosecution and punishment for publication of articles very
critical of the war effort in World War I. Schenck was
referred to as a conviction for obstructing security "by words of
persuasion." Id. at 249 U. S. 206 .
And the conviction in Frohwerk was sustained because "the
circulation of the paper was Page 395 U. S. 451 in quarters where a little breath would be enough to kindle a
flame." Id. at 249 U. S.
209 . Debs v. United States, 249 U.
S. 211 , was the third of the trilogy of the 1918 Term.
Debs was convicted of speaking in opposition to the war where his
"opposition was so expressed that its natural and intended effect
would be to obstruct recruiting." Id. at 249 U. S.
215 .
"If that was intended, and if, in all the circumstances, that
would be its probable effect, it would not be protected by reason
of its being part of a general program and expressions of a general
and conscientious belief." Ibid. In the 1919 Term, the Court applied the Schenck doctrine to affirm the convictions of other dissidents in World War
I. Abrams v. United States, 250 U.
S. 616 , was one instance. Mr. Justice Holmes, with whom
Mr. Justice Brandeis concurred, dissented. While adhering to Schenck, he did not think that, on the facts, a case for
overriding the First Amendment had been made out:
"It is only the present danger of immediate evil or an intent to
bring it about that warrants Congress in setting a limit to the
expression of opinion where private rights are not concerned.
Congress certainly cannot forbid all effort to change the mind of
the country." Id. at 250 U. S.
628 .
Another instance was Schaefer v. United States, 251 U. S. 466 , in
which Mr. Justice Brandeis, joined by Mr. Justice Holmes,
dissented. A third was Pierce v. United States, 252 U. S. 239 , in
which, again, Mr. Justice Brandeis, joined by Mr. Justice Holmes,
dissented.
Those, then, were the World War I cases that put the gloss of
"clear and present danger" on the First Amendment. Whether the war
power -- the greatest leveler of them all -- is adequate to sustain
that doctrine is debatable. Page 395 U. S. 452 The dissents in Abrams, Schaefer, and Pierce show how easily "clear and present danger" is manipulated to crush
what Brandeis called "[t]he fundamental right of free men to strive
for better conditions through new legislation and new institutions"
by argument and discourse ( Pierce v. United States, supra, at 252 U. S. 273 )
even in time of war. Though I doubt if the "clear and present
danger" test is congenial to the First Amendment in time of a
declared war, I am certain it is not reconcilable with the First
Amendment in days of peace.
The Court quite properly overrules Whitney v.
California, 274 U. S. 357 ,
which involved advocacy of ideas which the majority of the Court
deemed unsound and dangerous.
Mr. Justice Holmes, though never formally abandoning the "clear
and present danger" test, moved closer to the First Amendment ideal
when he said in dissent in Gitlow v. New York, 268 U. S. 652 , 268 U. S.
673 :
"Every idea is an incitement. It offers itself for belief, and,
if believed, it is acted on unless some other belief outweighs it
or some failure of energy stifles the movement at its birth. The
only difference between the expression of an opinion and an
incitement in the narrower sense is the speaker's enthusiasm for
the result. Eloquence may set fire to reason. But whatever may be
thought of the redundant discourse before us, it had no chance of
starting a present conflagration. If, in the long run, the beliefs
expressed in proletarian dictatorship are destined to be accepted
by the dominant forces of the community, the only meaning of free
speech is that they should be given their chance and have their
way."
We have never been faithful to the philosophy of that
dissent. Page 395 U. S. 453 The Court, in Herndon v. Lowry, 301 U.
S. 242 , overturned a conviction for exercising First
Amendment rights to incite insurrection because of lack of evidence
of incitement. Id. at 301 U. S.
259 -261. And see Hartzel v. United States, 322 U. S. 680 . In Bridges v. California, 314 U. S. 252 , 314 U. S.
261 -263, we approved the "clear and present danger" test
in an elaborate dictum that tightened it and confined it to a
narrow category. But in Dennis v. United States, 341 U. S. 494 , we
opened wide the door, distorting the "clear and present danger"
test beyond recognition. [ Footnote
2/1 ]
In that case, the prosecution dubbed an agreement to teach the
Marxist creed a "conspiracy." The case was submitted to a jury on a
charge that the jury could not convict unless it found that the
defendants "intended to overthrow the Government as speedily as
circumstances would permit.'" Id. at 341 U. S.
509 -511. The Court sustained convictions under that
charge, construing it to mean a determination of
""whether the gravity of the evil,' discounted by its
improbability, justifies such invasion of free speech as is
necessary to avoid the danger." [ Footnote 2/2 ]" Id. at 341 U. S. 510 ,
quoting from United States v. Dennis, 183 F.2d 201,
212.
Out of the "clear and present danger" test came other offspring.
Advocacy and teaching of forcible overthrow of government as an
abstract principle is immune from prosecution. Yates v. United
States, 354 U. S. 298 , 354 U. S. 318 .
But an "active" member, who has a guilty knowledge and intent of
the aim to overthrow the Government Page 395 U. S. 454 by violence, Noto v. United States, 367 U.
S. 290 , may be prosecuted. Scales v. United
States, 367 U. S. 203 , 367 U. S. 228 .
And the power to investigate, backed by the powerful sanction of
contempt, includes the power to determine which of the two
categories fits the particular witness. Barenblatt v. United
States, 360 U. S. 109 , 360 U. S. 130 .
And so the investigator roams at will through all of the beliefs of
the witness, ransacking his conscience and his innermost
thoughts.
Judge Learned Hand, who wrote for the Court of Appeals in
affirming the judgment in Dennis, coined the "not
improbable" test, 183 F.2d 201, 214, which this Court adopted and
which Judge Hand preferred over the "clear and present danger"
test. Indeed, in his book, The Bill of Rights 59 (1958), in
referring to Holmes' creation of the "clear and present danger"
test, he said, "I cannot help thinking that, for once, Homer
nodded."
My own view is quite different. I see no place in the regime of
the First Amendment for any "clear and present danger" test,
whether strict and tight, as some would make it, or free-wheeling,
as the Court in Dennis rephrased it.
When one reads the opinions closely and sees when and how the
"clear and present danger" test has been applied, great misgivings
are aroused. First, the threats were often loud, but always puny,
and made serious only by judges so wedded to the status
quo that critical analysis made them nervous. Second, the test
was so twisted and perverted in Dennis as to make the
trial of those teachers of Marxism an all-out political trial which
was part and parcel of the cold war that has eroded substantial
parts of the First Amendment.
Action is often a method of expression, and within the
protection of the First Amendment.
Suppose one tears up his own copy of the Constitution in
eloquent protest to a decision of this Court. May he be
indicted? Page 395 U. S. 455 Suppose one rips his own Bible to shreds to celebrate his
departure from one "faith" and his embrace of atheism. May he be
indicted?
Last Term, the Court held in United States v. O'Brien, 391 U. S. 367 , 391 U. S. 382 ,
that a registrant under Selective Service who burned his draft card
in protest of the war in Vietnam could be prosecuted. The First
Amendment was tendered as a defense and rejected, the Court
saying:
"The issuance of certificates indicating the registration and
eligibility classification of individuals is a legitimate and
substantial administrative aid in the functioning of this system.
And legislation to insure the continuing availability of issued
certificates serves a legitimate and substantial purpose in the
system's administration."
391 U.S. at 391 U. S.
377 -378.
But O'Brien was not prosecuted for not having his draft card
available when asked for by a federal agent. He was indicted,
tried, and convicted for burning the card. And this Court's
affirmance of that conviction was not, with all respect, consistent
with the First Amendment.
The act of praying often involves body posture and movement, as
well as utterances. It is nonetheless protected by the Free
Exercise Clause. Picketing, as we have said on numerous occasions,
is "free speech plus." See Bakery Drivers Local v. Wohl, 315 U. S. 769 , 315 U. S. 775 (DOUGLAS, J., concurring); Giboney v. Empire Storage Co., 336 U. S. 490 , 336 U. S. 501 ; Hughes v. Superior Court, 339 U.
S. 460 , 339 U. S. 465 ; Labor Board v. Fruit Packers, 377 U. S.
58 , 377 U. S. 77 (BLACK, J., concurring), and id. at 377 U.S. 93 (HARLAN, J., dissenting); Cox v. Louisiana, 379 U. S. 559 , 379 U. S. 578 (opinion of BLACK, J.); Food Employees v. Logan Plaza, 391 U. S. 308 , 391 U. S. 326 (DOUGLAS, J., concurring). That means that it can be regulated when
it comes to the "plus" or "action" side of the protest. It can be
regulated as to Page 395 U. S. 456 the number of pickets and the place and hours ( see Cox v.
Louisiana, supra ), because traffic and other community
problems would otherwise suffer.
But none of these considerations is implicated in the symbolic
protest of the Vietnam war in the burning of a draft card.
One's beliefs have long been thought to be sanctuaries which
government could not invade. Barenblatt is one example of
the ease with which that sanctuary can be violated. The lines drawn
by the Court between the criminal act of being an "active"
Communist and the innocent act of being a nominal or inactive
Communist mark the difference only between deep and abiding belief
and casual or uncertain belief. But I think that all matters of
belief are beyond the reach of subpoenas or the probings of
investigators. That is why the invasions of privacy made by
investigating committees were notoriously unconstitutional. That is
the deep-seated fault in the infamous loyalty security hearings
which, since 1947, when President Truman launched them, have
processed 20,000,000 men and women. Those hearings were primarily
concerned with one's thoughts, ideas, beliefs, and convictions.
They were the most blatant violations of the First Amendment we
have ever known.
The line between what is permissible and not subject to control
and what may be made impermissible and subject to regulation is the
line between ideas and overt acts.
The example usually given by those who would punish speech is
the case of one who falsely shouts fire in a crowded theatre.
This is, however, a classic case where speech is brigaded with
action. See Speiser v. Randall, 357 U.
S. 513 , 357 U. S.
536 -537 (DOUGLAS, J., concurring). They are indeed
inseparable, and a prosecution can be launched for the overt Page 395 U. S. 457 acts actually caused. Apart from rare instances of that kind,
speech is, I think, immune from prosecution. Certainly there is no
constitutional line between advocacy of abstract ideas, as in Yates, and advocacy of political action, as in Scales. The quality of advocacy turns on the depth of the
conviction, and government has no power to invade that sanctuary of
belief and conscience. [ Footnote
2/3 ]
[ Footnote 2/1 ] See McKay, The Preference For Freedom, 34 N.Y.U.L.Rev.
1182, 1203-1212 (1959).
[ Footnote 2/2 ] See Feiner v. New York, 340 U.
S. 315 , where a speaker was arrested for arousing an
audience when the only "clear and present danger" was that the
hecklers in the audience would break up the meeting.
[ Footnote 2/3 ] See MR. JUSTICE BLACK, dissenting, in Communications Assn. v. Douds, 339 U.
S. 382 , 339 U. S. 446 , 339 U. S. 449 et seq. | In Brandenburg v. Ohio, the Supreme Court ruled that the First and Fourteenth Amendments protect freedom of speech and prohibit states from punishing mere advocacy of ideas, even those promoting lawlessness or violence. The Court overturned a conviction under Ohio's Criminal Syndicalism statute, which criminalized advocating for crime or violence as a means to achieve reform. The Court established that speech can only be regulated when it incites imminent lawless action and is likely to produce such action. This case set a precedent for protecting speech, even when it may be controversial or unpopular. |
Free Speech | Tinker v. Des Moines Independent Community School District | https://supreme.justia.com/cases/federal/us/393/503/ | U.S. Supreme Court Tinker v. Des Moines Sch. Dist., 393
U.S. 503 (1969) Tinker v. Des Moines Independent Community School
District No. 21 Argued November 12, 1968 Decided February 24, 1969 393
U.S. 503 CERTIORARI TO THE UNITED STATES COURT OF APPEALS FOR THE EIGHTH CIRCUIT MR. JUSTICE FORTAS delivered the opinion of the Court.
Petitioner John F. Tinker, 15 years old, and petitioner
Christopher Eckhardt, 16 years old, attended high schools in Des
Moines, Iowa. Petitioner Mary Beth Tinker, John's sister, was a
13-year-old student in junior high school.
In December, 1965, a group of adults and students in Des Moines
held a meeting at the Eckhardt home. The group determined to
publicize their objections to the hostilities in Vietnam and their
support for a truce by wearing black armbands during the holiday
season and by fasting on December 16 and New Year's Eve.
Petitioners and their parents had previously engaged in similar
activities, and they decided to participate in the program.
The principals of the Des Moines schools became aware of the
plan to wear armbands. On December 14, 1965, they met and adopted a
policy that any student wearing an armband to school would be asked
to remove it, and, if he refused, he would be suspended until he
returned without the armband. Petitioners were aware of the
regulation that the school authorities adopted.
On December 16, Mary Beth and Christopher wore black armbands to
their schools. John Tinker wore his armband the next day. They were
all sent home and suspended from school until they would come back
without their armbands. They did not return to school until after
the planned period for wearing armbands had expired -- that is,
until after New Year's Day.
This complaint was filed in the United States District Court by
petitioners, through their fathers, under § 1983 of Title 42 of the
United States Code. It prayed for an injunction restraining the
respondent school officials and the respondent members of the board
of directors of the school district from disciplining the
petitioners, and it sought nominal damages. After an evidentiary
hearing, the District Court dismissed the complaint. It upheld [505 ]
the constitutionality of the school authorities' action on the
ground that it was reasonable in order to prevent disturbance of
school discipline. 258 F.
Supp. 971 (1966). The court referred to, but expressly declined
to follow, the Fifth Circuit's holding in a similar case that the
wearing of symbols like the armbands cannot be prohibited unless it
"materially and substantially interfere[s] with the requirements of
appropriate discipline in the operation of the school." Burnside v. Byars , 363 F.2d 744, 749 (1966). [ Footnote 1 ]
On appeal, the Court of Appeals for the Eighth Circuit
considered the case en banc. The court was equally divided, and the
District Court's decision was accordingly affirmed without opinion.
383 F.2d 988 (1967). We granted certiorari. 390 U.S. 942
(1968). I The District Court recognized that the wearing of an armband for
the purpose of expressing certain views is the type of symbolic act
that is within the Free Speech Clause of the First Amendment. See West Virginia v. Barnette , 319 U. S. 624 (1943); Stromberg v. California , 283 U. S. 359 (1931). Cf. Thornhill v. Alabama , 310 U. S. 88 (1940); Edwards v. South Carolina , 372 U. S. 229 (1963); Brown v. Louisiana , 383 U. S. 131 (1966). As
we shall discuss, the wearing of armbands in the circumstances of
this case was entirely divorced from actually or potentially
disruptive conduct by those participating in it. It was closely
akin to "pure speech" [506 ]
which, we have repeatedly held, is entitled to comprehensive
protection under the First Amendment. Cf. Cox v.
Louisiana , 379
U. S. 536 , 555 (1965); Adderley v. Florida , 385 U. S. 39 (1966).
First Amendment rights, applied in light of the special
characteristics of the school environment, are available to
teachers and students. It can hardly be argued that either students
or teachers shed their constitutional rights to freedom of speech
or expression at the schoolhouse gate. This has been the
unmistakable holding of this Court for almost 50 years. In Meyer v. Nebraska , 262 U. S. 390 (1923), and Bartels v. Iowa , 262 U. S. 404 (1923),
this Court, in opinions by Mr. Justice McReynolds, held that the
Due Process Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment prevents States from
forbidding the teaching of a foreign language to young students.
Statutes to this effect, the Court held, unconstitutionally
interfere with the liberty of teacher, student, and parent. [ Footnote 2 ] See also Pierce v. Society of
Sisters , 268 [507 ]
U.S. 510 (1925); West Virginia v. Barnette , 319 U. S. 624 (1943); McCollum v. Board of Education , 333 U. S. 203 (1948); Wieman v. Updegraff , 344 U. S. 183 , 195 (1952)
(concurring opinion); Sweezy v. New Hampshire , 354 U. S. 234 (1957); Shelton v. Tucker , 364 U. S. 479 , 487
(1960); Engel v. Vitale , 370 U. S. 421 (1962); Keyishian v. Board of Regents , 385 U. S. 589 , 603
(1967); Epperson v. Arkansas, ante , p. 97 (1968).
In West Virginia v. Barnette, supra , this Court held
that, under the First Amendment, the student in public school may
not be compelled to salute the flag. Speaking through Mr. Justice
Jackson, the Court said: "The Fourteenth Amendment, as now applied to the States,
protects the citizen against the State itself and all of its
creatures -- Boards of Education not excepted. These have, of
course, important, delicate, and highly discretionary functions,
but none that they may not perform within the limits of the Bill of
Rights. That they are educating the young for citizenship is reason
for scrupulous protection of Constitutional freedoms of the
individual, if we are not to strangle the free mind at its source
and teach youth to discount important principles of our government
as mere platitudes."319 U.S. at 637. On the other hand, the Court has repeatedly emphasized the need
for affirming the comprehensive authority of the States and of
school officials, consistent with fundamental constitutional
safeguards, to prescribe and control conduct in the schools. See Epperson v. Arkansas, supra , at 104; Meyer v.
Nebraska, supra , at 402. Our problem lies in the area where
students in the exercise of First Amendment rights collide with the
rules of the school authorities. II The problem posed by the present case does not relate to
regulation of the length of skirts or the type of clothing, [508 ]
to hair style, or deportment. Cf. Ferrell v. Dallas
Independent School District , 392 F.2d 697 (1968); Pugsley
v. Sellmeyer , 158 Ark. 247, 250 S.W. 538 (1923). It does not
concern aggressive, disruptive action or even group demonstrations.
Our problem involves direct, primary First Amendment rights akin to
"pure speech."
The school officials banned and sought to punish petitioners for
a silent, passive expression of opinion, unaccompanied by any
disorder or disturbance on the part of petitioners. There is here
no evidence whatever of petitioners' interference, actual or
nascent, with the schools' work or of collision with the rights of
other students to be secure and to be let alone. Accordingly, this
case does not concern speech or action that intrudes upon the work
of the schools or the rights of other students.
Only a few of the 18,000 students in the school system wore the
black armbands. Only five students were suspended for wearing them.
There is no indication that the work of the schools or any class
was disrupted. Outside the classrooms, a few students made hostile
remarks to the children wearing armbands, but there were no threats
or acts of violence on school premises.
The District Court concluded that the action of the school
authorities was reasonable because it was based upon their fear of
a disturbance from the wearing of the armbands. But, in our system,
undifferentiated fear or apprehension of disturbance is not enough
to overcome the right to freedom of expression. Any departure from
absolute regimentation may cause trouble. Any variation from the
majority's opinion may inspire fear. Any word spoken, in class, in
the lunchroom, or on the campus, that deviates from the views of
another person may start an argument or cause a disturbance. But
our Constitution says we must take this risk, Terminiello v.
Chicago , 337 U. S.
1 (1949); and our history says that it is this sort of
hazardous freedom -- this kind of openness -- that is [509 ]
the basis of our national strength and of the independence and
vigor of Americans who grow up and live in this relatively
permissive, often disputatious, society.
In order for the State in the person of school officials to
justify prohibition of a particular expression of opinion, it must
be able to show that its action was caused by something more than a
mere desire to avoid the discomfort and unpleasantness that always
accompany an unpopular viewpoint. Certainly where there is no
finding and no showing that engaging in the forbidden conduct would
"materially and substantially interfere with the requirements of
appropriate discipline in the operation of the school," the
prohibition cannot be sustained. Burnside v. Byars, supra at 749.
In the present case, the District Court made no such finding,
and our independent examination of the record fails to yield
evidence that the school authorities had reason to anticipate that
the wearing of the armbands would substantially interfere with the
work of the school or impinge upon the rights of other students.
Even an official memorandum prepared after the suspension that
listed the reasons for the ban on wearing the armbands made no
reference to the anticipation of such disruption. [ Footnote 3 ] [510 ]
On the contrary, the action of the school authorities appears to
have been based upon an urgent wish to avoid the controversy which
might result from the expression, even by the silent symbol of
armbands, of opposition to this Nation's part in the conflagration
in Vietnam. [ Footnote 4 ] It is
revealing, in this respect, that the meeting at which the school
principals decided to issue the contested regulation was called in
response to a student's statement to the journalism teacher in one
of the schools that he wanted to write an article on Vietnam and
have it published in the school paper. (The student was dissuaded.
[ Footnote 5 ])
It is also relevant that the school authorities did not purport
to prohibit the wearing of all symbols of political or
controversial significance. The record shows that students in some
of the schools wore buttons relating to national political
campaigns, and some even wore the Iron Cross, traditionally a
symbol of Nazism. The order prohibiting the wearing of armbands did
not extend to these. Instead, a particular symbol -- black armbands
worn to exhibit opposition to this Nation's involvement [511 ]
in Vietnam -- was singled out for prohibition. Clearly, the
prohibition of expression of one particular opinion, at least
without evidence that it is necessary to avoid material and
substantial interference with schoolwork or discipline, is not
constitutionally permissible.
In our system, state-operated schools may not be enclaves of
totalitarianism. School officials do not possess absolute authority
over their students. Students in school, as well as out of school,
are "persons" under our Constitution. They are possessed of
fundamental rights which the State must respect, just as they
themselves must respect their obligations to the State. In our
system, students may not be regarded as closed-circuit recipients
of only that which the State chooses to communicate. They may not
be confined to the expression of those sentiments that are
officially approved. In the absence of a specific showing of
constitutionally valid reasons to regulate their speech, students
are entitled to freedom of expression of their views. As Judge
Gewin, speaking for the Fifth Circuit, said, school officials
cannot suppress "expressions of feelings with which they do not
wish to contend." Burnside v. Byars, supra , at 749.
In Meyer v. Nebraska, supra , at 402, Mr. Justice
McReynolds expressed this Nation's repudiation of the principle
that a State might so conduct its schools as to "foster a
homogeneous people." He said: "In order to submerge the individual and develop ideal citizens,
Sparta assembled the males at seven into barracks and intrusted
their subsequent education and training to official guardians.
Although such measures have been deliberately approved by men of
great genius, their ideas touching the relation between individual
and State were wholly different from those upon which our
institutions rest; and it hardly will be affirmed that any
legislature could impose such restrictions upon the people of a [512 ] State without doing violence to both letter and spirit of the
Constitution." This principle has been repeated by this Court on numerous
occasions during the intervening years. In Keyishian v. Board
of Regents , 385
U. S. 589 , 603, MR. JUSTICE BRENNAN, speaking for the Court,
said: "'The vigilant protection of constitutional freedoms is nowhere
more vital than in the community of American schools.' Shelton
v. Tucker , [ 364 U.S.
479 ,] at 487. The classroom is peculiarly the 'marketplace of
ideas.' The Nation's future depends upon leaders trained through
wide exposure to that robust exchange of ideas which discovers
truth 'out of a multitude of tongues, [rather] than through any
kind of authoritative selection.'" The principle of these cases is not confined to the supervised
and ordained discussion which takes place in the classroom. The
principal use to which the schools are dedicated is to accommodate
students during prescribed hours for the purpose of certain types
of activities. Among those activities is personal
intercommunication among the students. [ Footnote 6 ] This is not only an inevitable part of the
process of attending school; it is also an important part of the
educational process. A student's rights, therefore, do not embrace
merely the classroom hours. When he is in the cafeteria, or on the
playing field, or on [513 ]
the campus during the authorized hours, he may express his
opinions, even on controversial subjects like the conflict in
Vietnam, if he does so without "materially and substantially
interfer[ing] with the requirements of appropriate discipline in
the operation of the school" and without colliding with the rights
of others. Burnside v. Byars, supra , at 749. But conduct
by the student, in class or out of it, which for any reason --
whether it stems from time, place, or type of behavior --
materially disrupts classwork or involves substantial disorder or
invasion of the rights of others is, of course, not immunized by
the constitutional guarantee of freedom of speech. Cf.
Blackwell v. Issaquena County Board of Education. , 363 F.2d
740 (C.A. 5th Cir.1966).
Under our Constitution, free speech is not a right that is given
only to be so circumscribed that it exists in principle, but not in
fact. Freedom of expression would not truly exist if the right
could be exercised only in an area that a benevolent government has
provided as a safe haven for crackpots. The Constitution says that
Congress (and the States) may not abridge the right to free speech.
This provision means what it says. We properly read it to permit
reasonable regulation of speech-connected activities in carefully
restricted circumstances. But we do not confine the permissible
exercise of First Amendment rights to a telephone booth or the four
corners of a pamphlet, or to supervised and ordained discussion in
a school classroom.
If a regulation were adopted by school officials forbidding
discussion of the Vietnam conflict, or the expression by any
student of opposition to it anywhere on school property except as
part of a prescribed classroom exercise, it would be obvious that
the regulation would violate the constitutional rights of students,
at least if it could not be justified by a showing that the
students' activities would materially and substantially disrupt the
work and discipline of the school. Cf. Hammond [514 ] v. South Carolina State College , 272 F.
Supp. 947 (D.C.S.C.1967) (orderly protest meeting on state
college campus); Dickey v. Alabama State Board of
Education , 273 F.
Supp. 613 (D.C.M.D. Ala. 967) (expulsion of student editor of
college newspaper). In the circumstances of the present case, the
prohibition of the silent, passive "witness of the armbands," as
one of the children called it, is no less offensive to the
Constitution's guarantees.
As we have discussed, the record does not demonstrate any facts
which might reasonably have led school authorities to forecast
substantial disruption of or material interference with school
activities, and no disturbances or disorders on the school premises
in fact occurred. These petitioners merely went about their
ordained rounds in school. Their deviation consisted only in
wearing on their sleeve a band of black cloth, not more than two
inches wide. They wore it to exhibit their disapproval of the
Vietnam hostilities and their advocacy of a truce, to make their
views known, and, by their example, to influence others to adopt
them. They neither interrupted school activities nor sought to
intrude in the school affairs or the lives of others. They caused
discussion outside of the classrooms, but no interference with work
and no disorder. In the circumstances, our Constitution does not
permit officials of the State to deny their form of expression.
We express no opinion as to the form of relief which should be
granted, this being a matter for the lower courts to determine. We
reverse and remand for further proceedings consistent with this
opinion. Reversed and remanded. MR. JUSTICE STEWART, concurring.
Although I agree with much of what is said in the Court's
opinion, and with its judgment in this case, I [515 ]
cannot share the Court's uncritical assumption that, school
discipline aside, the First Amendment rights of children are
coextensive with those of adults. Indeed, I had thought the Court
decided otherwise just last Term in Ginsberg v. New York , 390 U. S. 629 . I
continue to hold the view I expressed in that case:
"[A] State may permissibly determine that, at least in some
precisely delineated areas, a child -- like someone in a captive
audience -- is not possessed of that full capacity for individual
choice which is the presupposition of First Amendment guarantees." Id. at 649-650 (concurring in result). Cf. Prince v.
Massachusetts , 321 U. S. 158 .
MR. JUSTICE WHITE, concurring.
While I join the Court's opinion, I deem it appropriate to note,
first, that the Court continues to recognize a distinction between
communicating by words and communicating by acts or conduct which
sufficiently impinges on some valid state interest; and, second,
that I do not subscribe to everything the Court of Appeals said
about free speech in its opinion in Burnside v. Byars , 363
F.2d 744, 748 (C.A. 5th Cir.1966), a case relied upon by the Court
in the matter now before us.
MR. JUSTICE BLACK, dissenting.
The Court's holding in this case ushers in what I deem to be an
entirely new era in which the power to control pupils by the
elected "officials of state supported public schools . . ." in the
United States is in ultimate effect transferred to the Supreme
Court. [ Footnote 1 ] The
Court brought [516 ]
this particular case here on a petition for certiorari urging
that the First and Fourteenth Amendments protect the right of
school pupils to express their political views all the way "from
kindergarten through high school." Here, the constitutional right
to "political expression" asserted was a right to wear black
armbands during school hours and at classes in order to demonstrate
to the other students that the petitioners were mourning because of
the death of United States soldiers in Vietnam and to protest that
war which they were against. Ordered to refrain from wearing the
armbands in school by the elected school officials and the teachers
vested with state authority to do so, apparently only seven out of
the school system's 18,000 pupils deliberately refused to obey the
order. One defying pupil was Paul Tinker, 8 years old, who was in
the second grade; another, Hope Tinker, was 11 years old and in the
fifth grade; a third member of the Tinker family was 13, in the
eighth grade; and a fourth member of the same family was John
Tinker, 15 years old, an 11th grade high school pupil. Their
father, a Methodist minister without a church, is paid a salary by
the American Friends Service Committee. Another student who defied
the school order and insisted on wearing an armband in school was
Christopher Eckhardt, an 11th grade pupil and a petitioner in this
case. His mother is an official in the Women's International League
for Peace and Freedom.
As I read the Court's opinion, it relies upon the following
grounds for holding unconstitutional the judgment of the Des Moines
school officials and the two courts below. First, the Court
concludes that the wearing of armbands is "symbolic speech," which
is "akin to pure speech,'" and therefore protected by the First
and Fourteenth Amendments. Secondly, the Court decides that the
public schools are an appropriate place to exercise "symbolic
speech" as long as normal school functions [517 ] are not "unreasonably" disrupted. Finally, the Court
arrogates to itself, rather than to the State's elected officials
charged with running the schools, the decision as to which school
disciplinary regulations are "reasonable." Assuming that the Court is correct in holding that the conduct
of wearing armbands for the purpose of conveying political ideas is
protected by the First Amendment, cf., e.g., Giboney v. Empire
Storage & Ice Co. , 336 U. S. 490 (1949), the
crucial remaining questions are whether students and teachers may
use the schools at their whim as a platform for the exercise of
free speech -- "symbolic" or "pure" -- and whether the courts will
allocate to themselves the function of deciding how the pupils'
school day will be spent. While I have always believed that, under
the First and Fourteenth Amendments, neither the State nor the
Federal Government has any authority to regulate or censor the
content of speech, I have never believed that any person has a
right to give speeches or engage in demonstrations where he pleases
and when he pleases. This Court has already rejected such a notion.
In Cox v. Louisiana , 379 U. S. 536 , 554
(1965), for example, the Court clearly stated that the rights of
free speech and assembly "do not mean that everyone with opinions
or beliefs to express may address a group at any public place and
at any time."
While the record does not show that any of these armband
students shouted, used profane language, or were violent in any
manner, detailed testimony by some of them shows their armbands
caused comments, warnings by other students, the poking of fun at
them, and a warning by an older football player that other
nonprotesting students had better let them alone. There is also
evidence that a teacher of mathematics had his lesson period
practically "wrecked," chiefly by disputes with Mary Beth Tinker,
who wore her armband for her "demonstration." [518 ]
Even a casual reading of the record shows that this armband did
divert students' minds from their regular lessons, and that talk,
comments, etc., made John Tinker "self-conscious" in attending
school with his armband. While the absence of obscene remarks or
boisterous and loud disorder perhaps justifies the Court's
statement that the few armband students did not actually "disrupt"
the classwork, I think the record overwhelmingly shows that the
armbands did exactly what the elected school officials and
principals foresaw they would, that is, took the students' minds
off their classwork and diverted them to thoughts about the highly
emotional subject of the Vietnam war. And I repeat that, if the
time has come when pupils of state-supported schools,
kindergartens, grammar schools, or high schools, can defy and flout
orders of school officials to keep their minds on their own
schoolwork, it is the beginning of a new revolutionary era of
permissiveness in this country fostered by the judiciary. The next
logical step, it appears to me, would be to hold unconstitutional
laws that bar pupils under 21 or 18 from voting, or from being
elected members of the boards of education. [ Footnote 2 ]
The United States District Court refused to hold that the state
school order violated the First and Fourteenth Amendments. 258 F.
Supp. 971 . Holding that the protest was akin to speech, which
is protected by the First [519 ]
and Fourteenth Amendments, that court held that the school order
was "reasonable," and hence constitutional. There was at one time a
line of cases holding "reasonableness," as the court saw it, to be
the test of a "due process" violation. Two cases upon which the
Court today heavily relies for striking down this school order used
this test of reasonableness, Meyer v. Nebraska , 262 U. S. 390 (1923), and Bartels v. Iowa , 262 U. S. 404 (1923). The
opinions in both cases were written by Mr. Justice McReynolds; Mr.
Justice Holmes, who opposed this reasonableness test, dissented
from the holdings, as did Mr. Justice Sutherland. This
constitutional test of reasonableness prevailed in this Court for a
season. It was this test that brought on President Franklin
Roosevelt's well known Court fight. His proposed legislation did
not pass, but the fight left the "reasonableness" constitutional
test dead on the battlefield, so much so that this Court, in Ferguson v. Skrupa , 372 U. S. 726 , 729, 730,
after a thorough review of the old cases, was able to conclude in
1963: "There was a time when the Due Process Clause was used by this
Court to strike down laws which were thought unreasonable, that is,
unwise or incompatible with some particular economic or social
philosophy." * * * * "The doctrine that prevailed in Lochner, Coppage, Adkins,
Burns , and like cases -- that due process authorizes courts to
hold laws unconstitutional when they believe the legislature has
acted unwisely -- has long since been discarded." The Ferguson case totally repudiated the old
reasonableness-due process test, the doctrine that judges have the
power to hold laws unconstitutional upon the belief of judges that
they "shock the conscience," or that they are [520 ]
"unreasonable," "arbitrary," "irrational," "contrary to
fundamental decency,'" or some other such flexible term without
precise boundaries. I have many times expressed my opposition to
that concept on the ground that it gives judges power to strike
down any law they do not like. If the majority of the Court today,
by agreeing to the opinion of my Brother FORTAS, is resurrecting
that old reasonableness-due process test, I think the
constitutional change should be plainly, unequivocally, and
forthrightly stated for the benefit of the bench and bar. It will
be a sad day for the country, I believe, when the present-day Court
returns to the McReynolds due process concept. Other cases cited by
the Court do not, as implied, follow the McReynolds reasonableness
doctrine. West Virginia v. Barnette , 319 U. S. 624 , clearly
rejecting the "reasonableness" test, held that the Fourteenth
Amendment made the First applicable to the States, and that the two
forbade a State to compel little school children to salute
the United States flag when they had religious scruples against
doing so. [ Footnote 3 ]
Neither Thornhill v. Alabama , 310 U. S. 88 ; Stromberg v. California , 283 U. S. 359 ; Edwards [521 ] v. South Carolina , 372 U. S. 229 ; nor Brown v. Louisiana , 383 U. S. 131 , related to
school children at all, and none of these cases embraced Mr.
Justice McReynolds' reasonableness test; and Thornhill,
Edwards , and Brown relied on the vagueness of state
statutes under scrutiny to hold them unconstitutional. Cox v.
Louisiana , 379
U. S. 536 , 555, and Adderley v. Florida , 385 U. S. 39 , cited by the
Court as a "compare," indicating, I suppose, that these two cases
are no longer the law, were not rested to the slightest extent on
the Meyer and Bartels "reasonableness-due
process-McReynolds" constitutional test. I deny, therefore, that it has been the "unmistakable holding of
this Court for almost 50 years" that "students" and "teachers" take
with them into the "schoolhouse gate" constitutional rights to
"freedom of speech or expression." Even Meyer did not hold
that. It makes no reference to "symbolic speech" at all; what it
did was to strike down as "unreasonable," and therefore
unconstitutional, a Nebraska law barring the teaching of the German
language before the children reached the eighth grade. One can well
agree with Mr. Justice Holmes and Mr. Justice Sutherland, as I do,
that such a law was no more unreasonable than it would be to bar
the teaching of Latin and Greek to pupils who have not reached the
eighth grade. In fact, I think the majority's reason for
invalidating the Nebraska law was that it did not like it, or, in
legal jargon, that it "shocked the Court's conscience," "offended
its sense of justice," or was "contrary to fundamental concepts of
the English-speaking world," as the Court has sometimes said. See, e.g., Rochin v. California , 342 U. S. 165 , and Irvine v. California , 347 U. S. 128 . The truth
is that a teacher of kindergarten, grammar school, or high school
pupils no more carries into a school with him a complete right to
freedom of speech and expression than an anti-Catholic or
anti-Semite carries with him a complete freedom of [522 ]
speech and religion into a Catholic church or Jewish synagogue.
Nor does a person carry with him into the United States Senate or
House, or into the Supreme Court, or any other court, a complete
constitutional right to go into those places contrary to their
rules and speak his mind on any subject he pleases. It is a myth to
say that any person has a constitutional right to say what he
pleases, where he pleases, and when he pleases. Our Court has
decided precisely the opposite. See, e.g., Cox v.
Louisiana , 379
U. S. 536 , 555; Adderley v. Florida , 385 U. S. 39 .
In my view, teachers in state-controlled public schools are
hired to teach there. Although Mr. Justice McReynolds may have
intimated to the contrary in Meyer v. Nebraska, supra ,
certainly a teacher is not paid to go into school and teach
subjects the State does not hire him to teach as a part of its
selected curriculum. Nor are public school students sent to the
schools at public expense to broadcast political or any other views
to educate and inform the public. The original idea of schools,
which I do not believe is yet abandoned as worthless or out of
date, was that children had not yet reached the point of experience
and wisdom which enabled them to teach all of their elders. It may
be that the Nation has outworn the old-fashioned slogan that
"children are to be seen, not heard," but one may, I hope, be
permitted to harbor the thought that taxpayers send children to
school on the premise that, at their age, they need to learn, not
teach.
The true principles on this whole subject were, in my judgment,
spoken by Mr. Justice McKenna for the Court in Waugh v.
Mississippi University , 237 U. S. 589 , 596-597.
The State had there passed a law barring students from peaceably
assembling in Greek letter fraternities and providing that students
who joined them could be expelled from school. This law would
appear on the surface to run afoul of the First Amendment's [523 ]
freedom of assembly clause. The law was attacked as violative of
due process and of the privileges and immunities clause, and as a
deprivation of property and of liberty under the Fourteenth
Amendment. It was argued that the fraternity made its members more
moral, taught discipline, and inspired its members to study harder
and to obey better the rules of discipline and order. This Court
rejected all the "fervid" pleas of the fraternities' advocates and
decided unanimously against these Fourteenth Amendment arguments.
The Court, in its next to the last paragraph, made this statement
which has complete relevance for us today: "It is said that the fraternity to which complainant belongs is
a moral and, of itself, a disciplinary, force. This need not be
denied. But whether such membership makes against discipline was
for the State of Mississippi to determine. It is to be remembered
that the University was established by the State, and is under the
control of the State, and the enactment of the statute may have
been induced by the opinion that membership in the prohibited
societies divided the attention of the students and distracted from
that singleness of purpose which the State desired to exist in its
public educational institutions. It is not for us to entertain
conjectures in opposition to the views of the State and annul its
regulations upon disputable considerations of their wisdom or
necessity." (Emphasis supplied.) It was on the foregoing argument that this Court sustained the
power of Mississippi to curtail the First Amendment's right of
peaceable assembly. And the same reasons are equally applicable to
curtailing in the States' public schools the right to complete
freedom of expression. Iowa's public schools, like Mississippi's
university, are operated to give students an opportunity to learn,
not to talk politics by actual speech, or by "symbolic" [524 ]
speech. And, as I have pointed out before, the record amply
shows that public protest in the school classes against the Vietnam
war "distracted from that singleness of purpose which the State
[here Iowa] desired to exist in its public educational
institutions." Here, the Court should accord Iowa educational
institutions the same right to determine for themselves to what
extent free expression should be allowed in its schools as it
accorded Mississippi with reference to freedom of assembly. But
even if the record were silent as to protests against the Vietnam
war distracting students from their assigned class work, members of
this Court, like all other citizens, know, without being told, that
the disputes over the wisdom of the Vietnam war have disrupted and
divided this country as few other issues ever have. Of course,
students, like other people, cannot concentrate on lesser issues
when black armbands are being ostentatiously displayed in their
presence to call attention to the wounded and dead of the war, some
of the wounded and the dead being their friends and neighbors. It
was, of course, to distract the attention of other students that
some students insisted up to the very point of their own suspension
from school that they were determined to sit in school with their
symbolic armbands.
Change has been said to be truly the law of life, but sometimes
the old and the tried and true are worth holding. The schools of
this Nation have undoubtedly contributed to giving us tranquility
and to making us a more law-abiding people. Uncontrolled and
uncontrollable liberty is an enemy to domestic peace. We cannot
close our eyes to the fact that some of the country's greatest
problems are crimes committed by the youth, too many of school age.
School discipline, like parental discipline, is an integral and
important part of training our children to be good citizens -- to
be better citizens. Here a very small number of students have
crisply and summarily [525 ]
refused to obey a school order designed to give pupils who want
to learn the opportunity to do so. One does not need to be a
prophet or the son of a prophet to know that, after the Court's
holding today, some students in Iowa schools -- and, indeed, in all
schools -- will be ready, able, and willing to defy their teachers
on practically all orders. This is the more unfortunate for the
schools since groups of students all over the land are already
running loose, conducting break-ins, sit-ins, lie-ins, and
smash-ins. Many of these student groups, as is all too familiar to
all who read the newspapers and watch the television news programs,
have already engaged in rioting, property seizures, and
destruction. They have picketed schools to force students not to
cross their picket lines, and have too often violently attacked
earnest but frightened students who wanted an education that the
pickets did not want them to get. Students engaged in such
activities are apparently confident that they know far more about
how to operate public school systems than do their parents,
teachers, and elected school officials. It is no answer to say that
the particular students here have not yet reached such high points
in their demands to attend classes in order to exercise their
political pressures. Turned loose with lawsuits for damages and
injunctions against their teachers as they are here, it is nothing
but wishful thinking to imagine that young, immature students will
not soon believe it is their right to control the schools, rather
than the right of the States that collect the taxes to hire the
teachers for the benefit of the pupils. This case, therefore,
wholly without constitutional reasons, in my judgment, subjects all
the public schools in the country to the whims and caprices of
their loudest-mouthed, but maybe not their brightest, students. I,
for one, am not fully persuaded that school pupils are wise enough,
even with this Court's expert help from Washington, to run the
23,390 public school [526 ]
systems [ Footnote 4 ] in our 50 States. I
wish, therefore, wholly to disclaim any purpose on my part to hold
that the Federal Constitution compels the teachers, parents, and
elected school officials to surrender control of the American
public school system to public school students. I dissent.
MR. JUSTICE HARLAN, dissenting.
I certainly agree that state public school authorities, in the
discharge of their responsibilities, are not wholly exempt from the
requirements of the Fourteenth Amendment respecting the freedoms of
expression and association. At the same time, I am reluctant to
believe that there is any disagreement between the majority and
myself on the proposition that school officials should be accorded
the widest authority in maintaining discipline and good order in
their institutions. To translate that proposition into a workable
constitutional rule, I would, in cases like this, cast upon those
complaining the burden of showing that a particular school measure
was motivated by other than legitimate school concerns -- for
example, a desire to prohibit the expression of an unpopular point
of view, while permitting expression of the dominant opinion.
Finding nothing in this record which impugns the good faith of
respondents in promulgating the armband regulation, I would affirm
the judgment below. Footnotes [ Footnote 1 ]
In Burnside , the Fifth Circuit ordered that high school
authorities be enjoined from enforcing a regulation forbidding
students to wear "freedom buttons." It is instructive that, in Blackwell v. Issaquena County Board of Education , 363 F.2d
749 (1966), the same panel on the same day reached the opposite
result on different facts. It declined to enjoin enforcement of
such a regulation in another high school where the students wearing
freedom buttons harassed students who did not wear them, and
created much disturbance.
[ Footnote 2 ] Hamilton v. Regents of Univ. of Cal. , 293 U. S. 245 (1934), is
sometimes cited for the broad proposition that the State may attach
conditions to attendance at a state university that require
individuals to violate their religious convictions. The case
involved dismissal of members of a religious denomination from a
land grant college for refusal to participate in military training.
Narrowly viewed, the case turns upon the Court's conclusion that
merely requiring a student to participate in school training in
military "science" could not conflict with his constitutionally
protected freedom of conscience. The decision cannot be taken as
establishing that the State may impose and enforce any conditions
that it chooses upon attendance at public institutions of learning,
however violative they may be of fundamental constitutional
guarantees. See, e.g., West Virginia v. Barnette , 319 U. S. 624 (1943); Dixon v. Alabama State Board of Education , 294 F.2d 150
(C.A. 5th Cir.1961); Knight v. State Board of Education , 200 F.
Supp. 174 (D.C. M.D. Tenn.1961); Dickey v. Alabama State
Board of Education , 273 F.
Supp. 613 (D.C. M.D. Ala.1967). See also Note,
Unconstitutional Conditions, 73 Harv.L.Rev. 1595 (1960); Note,
Academic Freedom, 81 Harv.L.Rev. 1045 (1968).
[ Footnote 3 ]
The only suggestions of fear of disorder in the report are
these:
"A former student of one of our high schools was killed in Viet
Nam. Some of his friends are still in school, and it was felt that,
if any kind of a demonstration existed, it might evolve into
something which would be difficult to control."
"Students at one of the high schools were heard to say they
would wear armbands of other colors if the black bands
prevailed."
Moreover, the testimony of school authorities at trial indicates
that it was not fear of disruption that motivated the regulation
prohibiting the armbands; the regulation was directed against "the
principle of the demonstration" itself. School authorities simply
felt that "the schools are no place for demonstrations," and if the
students
"didn't like the way our elected officials were handling things,
it should be handled with the ballot box, and not in the halls of
our public schools."
[ Footnote 4 ]
The District Court found that the school authorities, in
prohibiting black armbands, were influenced by the fact that
"[t]he Viet Nam war and the involvement of the United States
therein has been the subject of a major controversy for some time.
When the armband regulation involved herein was promulgated, debate
over the Viet Nam war had become vehement in many localities. A
protest march against the war had been recently held in Washington,
D.C. A wave of draft card burning incidents protesting the war had
swept the country. At that time, two highly publicized draft card
burning cases were pending in this Court. Both individuals
supporting the war and those opposing it were quite vocal in
expressing their views."
258 F. Supp. at 92-973.
[ Footnote 5 ]
After the principals' meeting, the director of secondary
education and the principal of the high school informed the student
that the principals were opposed to publication of his article.
They reported that
"we felt that it was a very friendly conversation, although we
did not feel that we had convinced the student that our decision
was a just one."
[ Footnote 6 ]
In Hammond v. South Carolina State College , 272 F.
Supp. 947 (D.C. S.C.1967), District Judge Hemphill had before
him a case involving a meeting on campus of 300 students to express
their views on school practices. He pointed out that a school is
not like a hospital or a jail enclosure. Cf. Cox v.
Louisiana , 379
U. S. 536 (1965); Adderley v. Florida , 385 U. S. 39 (1966). It is
a public place, and its dedication to specific uses does not imply
that the constitutional rights of persons entitled to be there are
to be gauged as if the premises were purely private property. Cf. Edwards v. South Carolina , 372 U. S. 229 (1963); Brown v. Louisiana , 383 U. S. 131 (1966).
[ Footnote 1 ]
The petition for certiorari here presented this single
question:
"Whether the First and Fourteenth Amendments permit officials of
state supported public schools to prohibit students from wearing
symbols of political views within school premises where the symbols
are not disruptive of school discipline or decorum."
[ Footnote 2 ]
The following Associated Press article appeared in the
Washington Evening Star, January 11, 1969, p. A-2, col. 1:
"BELLINGHAM, Mass. (AP) -- Todd R. Hennessy, 16, has filed
nominating papers to run for town park commissioner in the March
election."
"'I can see nothing illegal in the youth's seeking the elective
office,' said Lee Ambler, the town counsel. 'But I can't overlook
the possibility that, if he is elected, any legal contract entered
into by the park commissioner would be void because he is a
juvenile.'"
"Todd is a junior in Mount St. Charles Academy, where he has a
top scholastic record."
[ Footnote 3 ]
In Cantwell v. Connecticut , 310 U. S. 296 , 303-304
(1940), this Court said:
"The First Amendment declares that Congress shall make no law
respecting an establishment of religion or prohibiting the free
exercise thereof. The Fourteenth Amendment has rendered the
legislatures of the states as incompetent as Congress to enact such
laws. The constitutional inhibition of legislation on the subject
of religion has a double aspect. On the one hand, it forestalls
compulsion by law of the acceptance of any creed or the practice of
any form of worship. Freedom of conscience and freedom to adhere to
such religious organization or form of worship as the individual
may choose cannot be restricted by law. On the other hand, it
safeguards the free exercise of the chosen form of religion. Thus,
the Amendment embraces two concepts -- freedom to believe and
freedom to act. The first is absolute but, in the nature of things,
the second cannot be. Conduct remains subject to regulation for the
protection of society."
[ Footnote 4 ]
Statistical Abstract of the United States (1968), Table No. 578,
p. 406. | Here is a summary of the case:
In *Tinker v. Des Moines Independent Community School District* (1969), the United States Supreme Court ruled that public school students have the right to express their political views on campus as long as it does not cause any disruption. The case involved several students who wore black armbands to school to protest the Vietnam War and were subsequently suspended. The Court held that the students' First Amendment rights were violated as their actions did not cause any substantial disruption to school operations. This case established the "material and substantial interference" test, which allows schools to regulate student speech if it interferes with the educational process. |
Free Speech | U.S. v. O'Brien | https://supreme.justia.com/cases/federal/us/391/367/ | U.S. Supreme Court United States v. O'Brien, 391
U.S. 367 (1968) United States v.
O'Brien No. 232 Argued January 24,
1968 Decided May 27, 1968 391
U.S. 367 ast|>* 391
U.S. 367 CERTIORARI TO THE UNITED STATES
COURT OF APPEALS FOR THE FIRST
CIRCUIT Syllabus O'Brien burned his Selective Service registration certificate
before a sizable crowd in order to influence others to adopt his
anti-war beliefs. He was indicted, tried, and convicted for
violating 50 U.S.C.App. § 462(b), a part of the Universal Military
Training and Service Act, subdivision (3) of which applies to any
person "who forges, alters, knowingly destroys, knowingly
mutilates, or in any manner changes any such certificate . . .
," the words italicized herein having been added by amendment in
1965. The District Court rejected O'Brien's argument that the
amendment was unconstitutional because it was enacted to abridge
free speech and served no legitimate legislative purpose. The Court
of Appeals held the 1965 Amendment unconstitutional under the First
Amendment as singling out for special treatment persons engaged in
protests, on the ground that conduct under the 1965 Amendment was
already punishable, since a Selective Service System regulation
required registrants to keep their registration certificates in
their "personal possession at all times," 32 CFR § 1617.1, and
willful violation of regulations promulgated under the Act was made
criminal by 50 U.S.C.App. § 462(b)(6). The court, however, upheld
O'Brien's conviction under § 462(b)(6), which, in its view, made
violation of the nonpossession regulation a lesser included offense
of the crime defined by the 1965 Amendment. Held: 1. The 1965 Amendment to 50 U.S.C.App. § 462(b)(3) is
constitutional as applied in this case. Pp. 391 U. S. 375 , 391 U. S.
376 -382.
(a) The 1965 Amendment plainly does not abridge free speech on
its face. P. 391 U. S.
375 .
(b) When "speech" and "nonspeech" elements are combined in the
same course of conduct, a sufficiently important governmental
interest in regulating the nonspeech element can justify incidental
limitations on First Amendment freedoms. P. 391 U. S.
376 .
(c) A governmental regulation is sufficiently justified if it is
within the constitutional power of the Government and furthers Page 391 U. S. 368 an important or substantial governmental interest unrelated to
the suppression of free expression, and if the incidental
restriction on alleged First Amendment freedom is no greater than
is essential to that interest. The 1965 Amendment meets all these
requirements. P. 391 U. S.
377 .
(d) The 1965 Amendment came within Congress'."broad and
sweeping" power to raise and support armies and make all laws
necessary to that end. P. 391 U. S.
377 .
(e) The registration certificate serves purposes in addition to
initial notification, e.g., it proves that the described
individual has registered for the draft; facilitates communication
between registrants and local boards, and provides a reminder that
the registrant must notify his local board of changes in address or
status. The regulatory scheme involving the certificates includes
clearly valid prohibitions against alteration, forgery, or similar
deceptive misuse. Pp. 391 U. S.
378 -380.
(f) The preexistence of the nonpossession regulation does not
negate Congress' clear interest in providing alternative statutory
avenues of prosecution to assure its interest in preventing
destruction of the Selective Service certificates. P. 391 U. S.
380 .
(g) The governmental interests protected by the 1965 Amendment
and the nonpossession regulation, though overlapping, are not
identical. Pp. 391 U. S.
380 -381.
(h) The 1965 Amendment is a narrow and precisely drawn provision
which specifically protects the Government's substantial interest
in an efficient and easily administered system for raising armies.
Pp. 391 U. S.
381 -382.
(i) O'Brien was convicted only for the willful frustration of
that governmental interest. The noncommunicative impact of his
conduct for which he was convicted makes his case readily
distinguishable from Stromberg v. California, 283 U.
S. 359 (1931). P. 391 U. S.
382 .
2. The 1965 Amendment is constitutional as enacted. Pp. 391 U. S.
382 -385.
(a) Congress' purpose in enacting the law affords no basis for
declaring an otherwise constitutional statute invalid. McCray
v. United States, 195 U. S. 27 (1904). Pp. 391 U. S.
383 -384.
(b) Grosjean v. American Press Co., 297 U.
S. 233 (1936) and Gomillion v. Lightfoot, 364 U. S. 339 (1960), distinguished. Pp. 391 U. S. 384 -385.
376 F.2d 538, vacated; judgment and sentence of District Court
reinstated. Page 391 U. S. 369 MR. CHIEF JUSTICE WARREN delivered the opinion of the Court.
On the morning of March 31, 1966, David Paul O'Brien and three
companions burned their Selective Service registration certificates
on the steps of the South Boston Courthouse. A sizable crowd,
including several agents of the Federal Bureau of Investigation,
witnessed the event. [ Footnote
1 ] Immediately after the burning, members of the crowd began
attacking O'Brien and his companions. An FBI agent ushered O'Brien
to safety inside the courthouse. After he was advised of his right
to counsel and to silence, O'Brien stated to FBI agents that he had
burned his registration certificate because of his beliefs, knowing
that he was violating federal law. He produced the charred remains
of the certificate, which, with his consent, were photographed.
For this act, O'Brien was indicted, tried, convicted, and
sentenced in the United States District Court for the District of
Massachusetts. [ Footnote 2 ] He
did not contest the fact Page 391 U. S. 370 that he had burned the certificate. He stated in argument to the
jury that he burned the certificate publicly to influence others to
adopt his anti-war beliefs, as he put it,
"so that other people would reevaluate their positions with
Selective Service, with the armed forces, and reevaluate their
place in the culture of today, to hopefully consider my
position."
The indictment upon which he was tried charged that he
"willfully and knowingly did mutilate, destroy, and change by
burning . . . [his] Registration Certificate (Selective Service
System Form No. 2); in violation of Title 50, App. United States
Code, Section 462(b)."
Section 462(b) is part of the Universal Military Training and
Service Act of 1948. Section 462(b)(3), one of six numbered
subdivisions of § 462(b), was amended by Congress in 1965, 79 Stat.
586 (adding the words italicized below), so that, at the time
O'Brien burned his certificate, an offense was committed by any
person,
"who forges, alters, knowingly destroys, knowingly
mutilates, or in any manner changes any such certificate. . .
."
(Italics supplied.) In the District Court, O'Brien argued that
the 1965 Amendment prohibiting the knowing destruction or
mutilation of certificates was unconstitutional because it was
enacted to abridge free speech, and because it served no legitimate
legislative purpose. [ Footnote
3 ] The District Court rejected these arguments, holding that
the statute, on its face, did not abridge First Amendment rights,
that the court was not competent to inquire into the motives of
Congress in enacting the 1965 Amendment, and that the Page 391 U. S. 371 Amendment was a reasonable exercise of the power of Congress to
raise armies.
On appeal, the Court of Appeals for the First Circuit held the
1965 Amendment unconstitutional as a law abridging freedom of
speech. [ Footnote 4 ] At the
time the Amendment was enacted, a regulation of the Selective
Service System required registrants to keep their registration
certificates in their "personal possession at all times." 32 CFR §
1617.1 (1962). [ Footnote 5 ]
Willful violations of regulations promulgated pursuant to the
Universal Military Training and Service Act were made criminal by
statute. 50 U.S.C.App. § 462(b)(6). The Court of Appeals,
therefore, was of the opinion that conduct punishable under the
1965 Amendment was already punishable under the nonpossession
regulation, and consequently that the Amendment served no valid
purpose; further, that, in light of the prior regulation, the
Amendment must have been "directed at public, as distinguished from
private, destruction." On this basis, the court concluded that the
1965 Amendment ran afoul of the First Amendment by singling out
persons engaged in protests for special treatment. The court ruled,
however, that O'Brien's conviction should be affirmed under the
statutory provision, 50 U.S.C.App. § 462(b)(6), which, in its view,
made violation of the nonpossession regulation a crime, because it
regarded such violation to be a lesser included offense of the
crime defined by the 1965 Amendment. [ Footnote 6 ] Page 391 U. S. 372 The Government petitioned for certiorari in No. 232, arguing
that the Court of Appeals erred in holding the statute
unconstitutional, and that its decision conflicted with decisions
by the Courts of Appeals for the Second [ Footnote 7 ] and Eighth Circuits [ Footnote 8 ] upholding the 1965 Amendment against
identical constitutional challenges. O'Brien cross-petitioned for
certiorari in No. 233, arguing that the Court of Appeals erred in
sustaining his conviction on the basis of a crime of which he was
neither charged nor tried. We granted the Government's petition to
resolve the conflict in the circuits, and we also granted O'Brien's
cross-petition. We hold that the 1965 Amendment is constitutional
both as enacted and as applied. We therefore vacate the judgment of
the Court of Appeals and reinstate the judgment and sentence of the
District Court without reaching the issue raised by O'Brien in No.
233. I When a male reaches the age of 18, he is required by the
Universal Military Training and Service Act to register with a
local draft board. [ Footnote 9 ]
He is assigned a Selective Service number, [ Footnote 10 ] and within five days he is issued
a Page 391 U. S. 373 registration certificate (SSS Form No. 2). [ Footnote 11 ] Subsequently, and based on a
questionnaire completed by the registrant, [ Footnote 12 ] he is assigned a classification
denoting his eligibility for induction, [ Footnote 13 ] and, "[a]s soon as practicable"
thereafter, he is issued a Notice of Classification (SSS Form No.
110). [ Footnote 14 ] This
initial classification is not necessarily permanent, [ Footnote 15 ] and if, in the interim
before induction, the registrant's status changes in some relevant
way, he may be reclassified. [ Footnote 16 ] After such a reclassification, the local
board, "as soon as practicable," issues to the registrant a new
Notice of Classification. [ Footnote 17 ]
Both the registration and classification certificates are small
white cards, approximately 2 by 3 inches. The registration
certificate specifies the name of the registrant, the date of
registration, and the number and address of the local board with
which he is registered. Also inscribed upon it are the date and
place of the registrant's birth, his residence at registration, his
physical description, his signature, and his Selective Service
number. The Selective Service number itself indicates his State of
registration, his local board, his year of birth, and his
chronological position in the local board's classification record.
[ Footnote 18 ]
The classification certificate shows the registrant's name,
Selective Service number, signature, and eligibility
classification. It specifies whether he was so classified by his
local board, an appeal board, or the President. It Page 391 U. S. 374 contains the address of his local board and the date the
certificate was mailed.
Both the registration and classification certificates bear
notices that the registrant must notify his local board in writing
of every change in address, physical condition, and occupational,
marital, family, dependency, and military status, and of any other
fact which might change his classification. Both also contain a
notice that the registrant's Selective Service number should appear
on all communications to his local board.
Congress demonstrated its concern that certificates issued by
the Selective Service System might be abused well before the 1965
Amendment here challenged. The 1948 Act, 62 Stat. 604, itself
prohibited many different abuses involving
"any registration certificate, . . . or any other certificate
issued pursuant to or prescribed by the provisions of this title,
or rules or regulations promulgated hereunder. . . ."
62 Stat. 622. Under §§ 12(b)(1)-(5) of the 1948 Act, it was
unlawful (1) to transfer a certificate to aid a person in making
false identification; (2) to possess a certificate not duly issued
with the intent of using it for false identification; (3) to forge,
alter, "or in any manner" change a certificate or any notation
validly inscribed thereon; (4) to photograph or make an imitation
of a certificate for the purpose of false identification, and (5)
to possess a counterfeited or altered certificate. 62 Stat. 622. In
addition, as previously mentioned, regulations of the Selective
Service System required registrants to keep both their registration
and classification certificates in their personal possession at all
times. 32 CFR § 1617.1 (1962) (Registration Certificates);
[ Footnote 19 ] 32 CFR §
1623.5 Page 391 U. S. 375 (1962) (Classification Certificates). [ Footnote 20 ] And § 12(b)(6) of the Act, 62 Stat. 622,
made knowing violation of any provision of the Act or rules and
regulations promulgated pursuant thereto a felony.
By the 1965 Amendment, Congress added to § 12(b)(3) of the 1948
Act the provision here at issue, subjecting to criminal liability
not only one who "forges, alters, or in any manner changes", but
also one who "knowingly destroys, [or] knowingly mutilates" a
certificate. We note at the outset that the 1965 Amendment plainly
does not abridge free speech on its face, and we do not understand
O'Brien to argue otherwise. Amended § 12(b)(3), on its face, deals
with conduct having no connection with speech. It prohibits the
knowing destruction of certificates issued by the Selective Service
System, and there is nothing necessarily expressive about such
conduct. The Amendment does not distinguish between public and
private destruction, and it does not punish only destruction
engaged in for the purpose of expressing views. Compare
Stromberg v. California, 283 U. S. 359 (1931). [ Footnote 21 ] A law
prohibiting destruction of Selective Service certificates no more
abridges free speech on its face than a motor vehicle law
prohibiting the destruction of drivers' licenses, or a tax law
prohibiting the destruction of books and records. Page 391 U. S. 376 O'Brien nonetheless argues that the 1965 Amendment is
unconstitutional in its application to him, and is unconstitutional
as enacted because what he calls the "purpose" of Congress was "to
suppress freedom of speech." We consider these arguments
separately. II O'Brien first argues that the 1965 Amendment is unconstitutional
as applied to him because his act of burning his registration
certificate was protected "symbolic speech" within the First
Amendment. His argument is that the freedom of expression which the
First Amendment guarantees includes all modes of "communication of
ideas by conduct," and that his conduct is within this definition
because he did it in "demonstration against the war and against the
draft."
We cannot accept the view that an apparently limitless variety
of conduct can be labeled "speech" whenever the person engaging in
the conduct intends thereby to express an idea. However, even on
the assumption that the alleged communicative element in O'Brien's
conduct is sufficient to bring into play the First Amendment, it
does not necessarily follow that the destruction of a registration
certificate is constitutionally protected activity. This Court has
held that, when "speech" and "nonspeech" elements are combined in
the same course of conduct, a sufficiently important governmental
interest in regulating the nonspeech element can justify incidental
limitations on First Amendment freedoms. To characterize the
quality of the governmental interest which must appear, the Court
has employed a variety of descriptive terms: compelling; [ Footnote 22 ] substantial; [ Footnote 23 ] subordinating;
[ Footnote 24 ] Page 391 U. S. 377 paramount; [ Footnote 25 ]
cogent; [ Footnote 26 ]
strong. [ Footnote 27 ]
Whatever imprecision inheres in these terms, we think it clear that
a government regulation is sufficiently justified if it is within
the constitutional power of the Government; if it furthers an
important or substantial governmental interest; if the governmental
interest is unrelated to the suppression of free expression, and if
the incidental restriction on alleged First Amendment freedoms is
no greater than is essential to the furtherance of that interest.
We find that the 1965 Amendment to § 12(b)(3) of the Universal
Military Training and Service Act meets all of these requirements,
and consequently that O'Brien can be constitutionally convicted for
violating it.
The constitutional power of Congress to raise and support armies
and to make all laws necessary and proper to that end is broad and
sweeping. Lichter v. United States, 334 U.
S. 742 , 334 U. S.
755 -758 (1948); Selective Draft Law Cases, 245 U. S. 366 (1918); see also Ex parte Quirin, 317 U. S.
1 , 317 U. S. 25 -26
(1942). The power of Congress to classify and conscript manpower
for military service is "beyond question." Lichter v. United
States, supra, at 334 U. S. 756 ; Selective Draft Law Cases, supra. Pursuant to this power,
Congress may establish a system of registration for individuals
liable for training and service, and may require such individuals,
within reason, to cooperate in the registration system. The
issuance of certificates indicating the registration and
eligibility classification of individuals is a legitimate and
substantial administrative aid in the functioning of this system.
And legislation Page 391 U. S. 378 to insure the continuing availability of issued certificates
serves a legitimate and substantial purpose in the system's
administration.
O'Brien's argument to the contrary is necessarily premised upon
his unrealistic characterization of Selective Service certificates.
He essentially adopts the position that such certificates are so
many pieces of paper designed to notify registrants of their
registration or classification, to be retained or tossed in the
wastebasket according to the convenience or taste of the
registrant. Once the registrant has received notification,
according to this view, there is no reason for him to retain the
certificates. O'Brien notes that most of the information on a
registration certificate serves no notification purpose at all; the
registrant hardly needs to be told his address and physical
characteristics. We agree that the registration certificate
contains much information of which the registrant needs no
notification. This circumstance, however, does not lead to the
conclusion that the certificate serves no purpose, but that, like
the classification certificate, it serves purposes in addition to
initial notification. Many of these purposes would be defeated by
the certificates' destruction or mutilation. Among these are:
1. The registration certificate serves as proof that the
individual described thereon has registered for the draft. The
classification certificate shows the eligibility classification of
a named but undescribed individual. Voluntarily displaying the two
certificates is an easy and painless way for a young man to dispel
a question as to whether he might be delinquent in his Selective
Service obligations. Correspondingly, the availability of the
certificates for such display relieves the Selective Service System
of the administrative burden it would otherwise have in verifying
the registration and classification of all suspected delinquents.
Further, since both certificates are in the nature of "receipts"
attesting that the registrant Page 391 U. S. 379 has done what the law requires, it is in the interest of the
just and efficient administration of the system that they be
continually available, in the event, for example, of a mix-up in
the registrant's file. Additionally, in a time of national crisis,
reasonable availability to each registrant of the two small cards
assures a rapid and uncomplicated means for determining his fitness
for immediate induction, no matter how distant in our mobile
society he may be from his local board.
2. The information supplied on the certificates facilitates
communication between registrants and local boards, simplifying the
system and benefiting all concerned. To begin with, each
certificate bears the address of the registrant's local board, an
item unlikely to be committed to memory. Further, each card bears
the registrant's Selective Service number, and a registrant who has
his number readily available so that he can communicate it to his
local board when he supplies or requests information can make
simpler the board's task in locating his file. Finally, a
registrant's inquiry, particularly through a local board other than
his own, concerning his eligibility status is frequently answerable
simply on the basis of his classification certificate; whereas, if
the certificate were not reasonably available and the registrant
were uncertain of his classification, the task of answering his
questions would be considerably complicated.
3. Both certificates carry continual reminders that the
registrant must notify his local board of any change of address,
and other specified changes in his status. The smooth functioning
of the system requires that local boards be continually aware of
the status and whereabouts of registrants, and the destruction of
certificates deprives the system of a potentially useful notice
device.
4. The regulatory scheme involving Selective Service
certificates includes clearly valid prohibitions against the
alteration, forgery, or similar deceptive misuse of
certificates. Page 391 U. S. 380 The destruction or mutilation of certificates obviously
increases the difficulty of detecting and tracing abuses such as
these. Further, a mutilated certificate might itself be used for
deceptive purposes.
The many functions performed by Selective Service certificates
establish beyond doubt that Congress has a legitimate and
substantial interest in preventing their wanton and unrestrained
destruction and assuring their continuing availability by punishing
people who knowingly and willfully destroy or mutilate them. And we
are unpersuaded that the preexistence of the nonpossession
regulations in any way negates this interest.
In the absence of a question as to multiple punishment, it has
never been suggested that there is anything improper in Congress'
providing alternative statutory avenues of prosecution to assure
the effective protection of one and the same interest. Compare the majority and dissenting opinions in Gore
v. United States, 357 U. S. 386 (1958). [ Footnote 28 ] Here,
the preexisting avenue of prosecution was not even statutory.
Regulations may be modified or revoked from time to time by
administrative discretion. Certainly, the Congress may change or
supplement a regulation.
Equally important, a comparison of the regulations with the 1965
Amendment indicates that they protect overlapping but not identical
governmental interests, and that they reach somewhat different
classes of wrongdoers. [ Footnote
29 ] The gravamen of the offense defined by the statute is the
deliberate rendering of certificates unavailable for the various
purposes which they may serve. Whether registrants keep their
certificates in their personal Page 391 U. S. 381 possession at all times, as required by the regulations, is of
no particular concern under the 1965 Amendment, as long as they do
not mutilate or destroy the certificates so as to render them
unavailable. Although as we note below we are not concerned here
with the nonpossession regulations, it is not inappropriate to
observe that the essential elements of nonpossession are not
identical with those of mutilation or destruction. Finally, the
1965 Amendment, like § 12(b), which it amended, is concerned with
abuses involving any issued Selective Service
certificates, not only with the registrant's own certificates. The
knowing destruction or mutilation of someone else's certificates
would therefore violate the statute, but not the nonpossession
regulations.
We think it apparent that the continuing availability to each
registrant of his Selective Service certificates substantially
furthers the smooth and proper functioning of the system that
Congress has established to raise armies. We think it also apparent
that the Nation has a vital interest in having a system for raising
armies that functions with maximum efficiency and is capable of
easily and quickly responding to continually changing
circumstances. For these reasons, the Government has a substantial
interest in assuring the continuing availability of issued
Selective Service certificates.
It is equally clear that the 1965 Amendment specifically
protects this substantial governmental interest. We perceive no
alternative means that would more precisely and narrowly assure the
continuing availability of issued Selective Service certificates
than a law which prohibits their willful mutilation or destruction. Compare Sherbert v. Verner, 374 U.
S. 398 , 374 U. S.
407 -408 (1963), and the cases cited therein. The 1965
Amendment prohibits such conduct and does nothing more. In other
words, both the governmental interest and the operation of the 1965
Amendment are limited to the noncommunicative Page 391 U. S. 382 aspect of O'Brien's conduct. The governmental interest and the
scope of the 1965 Amendment are limited to preventing harm to the
smooth and efficient functioning of the Selective Service System.
When O'Brien deliberately rendered unavailable his registration
certificate, he willfully frustrated this governmental interest.
For this noncommunicative impact of his conduct, and for nothing
else, he was convicted.
The case at bar is therefore unlike one where the alleged
governmental interest in regulating conduct arises in some measure
because the communication allegedly integral to the conduct is
itself thought to be harmful. In Stromberg v. California, 283 U. S. 359 (1931), for example, this Court struck down a statutory phrase
which punished people who expressed their "opposition to organized
government" by displaying "any flag, badge, banner, or device."
Since the statute there was aimed at suppressing communication it
could not be sustained as a regulation of noncommunicative conduct. See also NLRB v. Fruit & Vegetable Packers Union, 377 U. S. 58 , 377 U. S. 79 (1964) (concurring opinion).
In conclusion, we find that, because of the Government's
substantial interest in assuring the continuing availability of
issued Selective Service certificates, because amended § 462(b) is
an appropriately narrow means of protecting this interest and
condemns only the independent noncommunicative impact of conduct
within its reach, and because the noncommunicative impact of
O'Brien's act of burning his registration certificate frustrated
the Government's interest, a sufficient governmental interest has
been shown to justify O'Brien's conviction. III O'Brien finally argues that the 1965 Amendment is
unconstitutional as enacted because what he calls the "purpose" of
Congress was "to suppress freedom of Page 391 U. S. 383 speech." We reject this argument because under settled
principles the purpose of Congress, as O'Brien uses that term, is
not a basis for declaring this legislation unconstitutional.
It is a familiar principle of constitutional law that this Court
will not strike down an otherwise constitutional statute on the
basis of an alleged illicit legislative motive. As the Court long
ago stated:
"The decisions of this court from the beginning lend no support
whatever to the assumption that the judiciary may restrain the
exercise of lawful power on the assumption that a wrongful purpose
or motive has caused the power to be exerted." McCray v. United States, 195 U. S.
27 , 195 U. S. 56 (1904). This fundamental principle of constitutional adjudication
was reaffirmed and the many cases were collected by Mr. Justice
Brandeis for the Court in Arizona v. California, 23 U. S. 423 , 23 U. S. 455 (1931).
Inquiries into congressional motives or purposes are a hazardous
matter. When the issue is simply the interpretation of legislation,
the Court will look to statements by legislators for guidance as to
the purpose of the legislature, [ Footnote 30 ] because the benefit to sound decisionmaking
in Page 391 U. S. 384 this circumstance is thought sufficient to risk the possibility
of misreading Congress' purpose. It is entirely a different matter
when we are asked to void a statute that is, under well settled
criteria, constitutional on its face, on the basis of what fewer
than a handful of Congressmen said about it. What motivates one
legislator to make a speech about a statute is not necessarily what
motivates scores of others to enact it, and the stakes are
sufficiently high for us to eschew guesswork. We decline to void
essentially on the ground that it is unwise legislation which
Congress had the undoubted power to enact and which could be
reenacted in its exact form if the same or another legislator made
a "wiser" speech about it.
O'Brien's position, and, to some extent, that of the court
below, rest upon a misunderstanding of Grosjean v. American
Press Co., 297 U. S. 233 (1936), and Gomillion v. Lightfoot, 364 U.
S. 339 (1960). These cases stand not for the proposition
that legislative motive is a proper basis for declaring a statute
unconstitutional, but that the inevitable effect of a statute on
its face may render it unconstitutional. Thus, in Grosjean, the Court, having concluded that the right of
publications to be free from certain kinds of taxes was a freedom
of the press protected by the First Amendment, struck down a
statute which on its face did nothing other than impose Page 391 U. S. 385 just such a tax. Similarly, in Gomillion, the Court
sustained a complaint which if true, established that the
"inevitable effect," 364 U.S. at 364 U. S. 341 ,
of the redrawing of municipal boundaries was to deprive the
petitioners of their right to vote for no reason other than that
they were Negro. In these cases, the purpose of the legislation was
irrelevant, because the inevitable effect -- the "necessary scope
and operation," McCray v. United States, 195 U. S.
27 , 195 U. S. 59 (1904) -- abridged constitutional rights. The statute attacked in
the instant case has no such inevitable unconstitutional effect,
since the destruction of Selective Service certificates is in no
respect inevitably or necessarily expressive. Accordingly, the
statute itself is constitutional.
We think it not amiss, in passing, to comment upon O'Brien's
legislative purpose argument. There was little floor debate on this
legislation in either House. Only Senator Thurmond commented on its
substantive features in the Senate. 111 Cong.Rec.19746, 20433.
After his brief statement, and without any additional substantive
comments, the bill, H.R. 10306, passed the Senate. 111 Cong.Rec.
20434. In the House debate only two Congressmen addressed
themselves to the Amendment -- Congressmen Rivers and Bray. 111
Cong.Rec.19871, 19872. The bill was passed after their statements
without any further debate by a vote of 393 to 1. It is principally
on the basis of the statements by these three Congressmen that
O'Brien makes his congressional "purpose" argument. We note that,
if we were to examine legislative purpose in the instant case, we
would be obliged to consider not only these statements, but also
the more authoritative reports of the Senate and House Armed
Services Committees. The portions of those reports explaining the
purpose of the Amendment are reproduced in the 391
U.S. 367 app|>Appendix in their entirety. While both reports
make clear a concern with the "defiant" Page 391 U. S. 386 destruction of so-called "draft cards" and with "open"
encouragement to others to destroy their cards, both reports also
indicate that this concern stemmed from an apprehension that
unrestrained destruction of cards would disrupt the smooth
functioning of the Selective Service System. IV Since the 1965 Amendment to § 12(b)(3) of the Universal Military
Training and Service Act is constitutional as enacted and as
applied, the Court of Appeals should have affirmed the judgment of
conviction entered by the District Court. Accordingly, we vacate
the judgment of the Court of Appeals, and reinstate the judgment
and sentence of the District Court. This disposition makes
unnecessary consideration of O'Brien's claim that the Court of
Appeals erred in affirming hie conviction on the basis of the
nonpossession regulation. [ Footnote 31 ] It is so ordered. MR. JUSTICE MARSHALL took no part in the consideration or
decision of these cases.
| 391
U.S. 367 app| APPENDIX TO OPINION OF THE COURT PORTIONS OF THE REPORTS OF THE COMMITTEES ON ARMED SERVICES OF THE SENATE AND HOUSE EXPLAINING THE 1965 AMENDMENT The "Explanation of the Bill" in the Senate Report is as
follows:
"Section 12(b)(3) of the Universal Military Training and Service
Act of 1951, as amended, provides, among other things, that a
person who forges, alters, or changes Page 391 U. S. 387 a draft registration certificate is subject to a fine of not
more than $10,000 or imprisonment of not more than 5 years, or
both. There is no explicit prohibition in this section against the
knowing destruction or mutilation of such cards."
"The committee has taken notice of the defiant destruction and
mutilation of draft cards by dissident persons who disapprove of
national policy. If allowed to continue unchecked, this
contumacious conduct represents a potential threat to the exercise
of the power to raise and support armies."
"For a person to be subject to fine or imprisonment, the
destruction or mutilation of the draft card must be 'knowingly'
done. This qualification is intended to protect persons who lose or
mutilate draft cards accidentally."
S.Rep. No. 589, 89th Cong., 1st Sess. (1965). And the House
Report explained:
"Section 12(b)(3) of the Universal Military Training and Service
Act of 1951, as amended, provides that a person who forges, alters,
or in any manner changes his draft registration card, or any
notation duly and validly inscribed thereon, will be subject to a
fine of $10,000 or imprisonment of not more than 5 years. H.R.
10306 would amend this provision to make it apply also to those
persons who knowingly destroy or knowingly mutilate a draft
registration card."
"The House Committee on Armed Services is fully aware of, and
shares in, the deep concern expressed throughout the Nation over
the increasing incidences in which individuals and large groups of
individuals openly defy and encourage others to defy the authority
of their Government by destroying or mutilating their draft
cards."
"While the present provisions of the Criminal Code with respect
to the destruction of Government property Page 391 U. S. 388 may appear broad enough to cover all acts having to do with the
mistreatment of draft cards in the possession of individuals, the
committee feels that, in the present critical situation of the
country, the acts of destroying or mutilating these cards are
offenses which pose such a grave threat to the security of the
Nation that no question whatsoever should be left as to the
intention of the Congress that such wanton and irresponsible acts
should be punished."
"To this end, H.R. 10306 makes specific that knowingly
mutilating or knowingly destroying a draft card constitutes a
violation of the Universal Military Training and Service Act and is
punishable thereunder, and that a person who does so destroy or
mutilate a draft card will be subject to a fine of not more than
$10,000 or imprisonment of not more than 5 years."
H.R.Rep. No. 747, 89th Cong., 1st Sess. (1965).
* Together with No. 233, O'Brien v. United States, also
on certiorari to the same court.
[ Footnote 1 ]
At the time of the burning, the agents knew only that O'Brien
and his three companions had burned small white cards. They later
discovered that the card O'Brien burned was his registration
certificate, and the undisputed assumption is that the same is true
of his companions.
[ Footnote 2 ]
He was sentenced under the Youth Corrections Act, 18 U.S.C. §
5010(b), to the custody of the Attorney General for a maximum
period of six years for supervision and treatment.
[ Footnote 3 ]
The issue of the constitutionality of the 1965 Amendment was
raised by counsel representing O'Brien in a pretrial motion to
dismiss the indictment. At trial and upon sentencing, O'Brien chose
to represent himself. He was represented by counsel on his appeal
to the Court of Appeals.
[ Footnote 4 ] O'Brien v. United States, 376 F.2d 538 (C.A. 1st
Cir.1967).
[ Footnote 5 ]
The portion of 32 CFR relevant to the instant case was revised
as of January 1, 1967. Citations in this opinion are to the 1962
edition, which was in effect when O'Brien committed the crime and
when Congress enacted the 1965 Amendment.
[ Footnote 6 ]
The Court of Appeals nevertheless remanded the case to the
District Court to vacate the sentence and resentence O'Brien. In
the court's view, the district judge might have considered the
violation of the 1965 Amendment as an aggravating circumstance in
imposing sentence. The Court of Appeals subsequently denied
O'Brien's petition for a rehearing, in which he argued that he had
not been charged, tried, or convicted for nonpossession, and that
nonpossession was not a lesser included offense of mutilation or
destruction. O'Brien v. United States, 376 F.2d 538, 542
(C.A. 1st Cir. 1967).
[ Footnote 7 ] United States v. Miller, 367 F.2d 72 (C.A.2d Cir.1966), cert. denied, 386 U.S. 911 (1967).
[ Footnote 8 ] Smith v. United States, 368 F.2d 529 (C.A. 8th
Cir.1966).
[ Footnote 9 ] See 62 Stat. 605, as amended, 65 Stat. 76, 50
U.S.C.App. § 453; 32 CFR § 1613.1 (1962).
[ Footnote 10 ]
32 CFR § 1621.2 (1962).
[ Footnote 11 ]
32 CFR § 1613.43a (1962).
[ Footnote 12 ]
32 CFR §§ 1621.9, 1623.1 (1962).
[ Footnote 13 ]
32 CFR §§ 1623.1, 1623.2 (1962).
[ Footnote 14 ]
32 CFR § 1623.4 (1962).
[ Footnote 15 ]
32 CFR § 1625.1 (1962).
[ Footnote 16 ]
32 CFR §§ 1625.1, 1625.2, 1625.3, 1625.4, and 1625.11
(1962).
[ Footnote 17 ]
32 CFR § 1625.12 (1962).
[ Footnote 18 ]
32 CFR § 1621.2 (1962).
[ Footnote 19 ]
32 CFR § 1617.1 (1962), provides, in relevant part:
"Every person required to present himself for and submit to
registration must., after he is registered, have in his personal
possession at all times his Registration Certificate (SSS Form No.
2) prepared by his local board which has not been altered and on
which no notation duly and validly inscribed thereon has been
changed in any manner after its preparation by the local board. The
failure of any person to have his Registration Certificate (SSS
Form No. 2) in his personal possession shall be prima
facie evidence of his failure to register."
[ Footnote 20 ]
32 CFR § 1623.5 (1962), provides, in relevant part:
"Every person who has been classified by a local board must have
in his personal possession at all times, in addition to his
Registration Certificate (SSS Form No. 2), a valid Notice of
Classification (SSS Form No. 110) issued to him showing his current
classification."
[ Footnote 21 ] See text, infra at 391 U. S.
382 .
[ Footnote 22 ] NAACP v. Button, 371 U. S. 415 , 371 U. S. 438 (1963); see also Sherbert v. Verner, 374 U.
S. 398 , 374 U. S. 403 (1963).
[ Footnote 23 ] NAACP v. Button, 371 U. S. 415 , 371 U. S. 444 (1963); NAACP v. Alabama ex rel. Patterson, 357 U.
S. 449 , 357 U. S. 464 (1958).
[ Footnote 24 ] Bates v. Little Rock, 361 U. S. 516 , 361 U. S. 524 (1960).
[ Footnote 25 ] Thomas v. Collins, 323 U. S. 516 , 323 U. S. 530 (1945); see also Sherbert v. Verner, 374 U.
S. 398 , 374 U. S. 406 (1963).
[ Footnote 26 ] Bates v. Little Rock, 361 U. S. 516 , 361 U. S. 524 (1960).
[ Footnote 27 ] Sherbert v. Verner, 374 U. S. 398 , 374 U. S. 408 (1963).
[ Footnote 28 ] Cf. Milanovich v. United States, 365 U.
S. 551 (1961); Hein v. United States, 358 U. S. 415 (1959); Prince v. United States, 352 U.
S. 322 (1957).
[ Footnote 29 ] Cf. Milanovich v. United States, 365 U.
S. 551 (1961); Heflin v. United States, 358 U. S. 415 (1959); Prince v. United States, 352 U.
S. 322 (1957).
[ Footnote 30 ]
The Court may make the same assumption in a very limited and
well defined class of cases where the very nature of the
constitutional question requires an inquiry into legislative
purpose. The principal class of cases is readily apparent -- those
in which statutes have been challenged as bills of attainder. This
Court's decisions have defined a bill of attainder as a legislative
Act which inflicts punishment on named individuals or members of an
easily ascertainable group without a judicial trial. In determining
whether a particular statute is a bill of attainder, the analysis
necessarily requires an inquiry into whether the three definitional
elements -- specificity in identification, punishment, and lack of
a judicial trial -- are contained in the statute. The inquiry into
whether the challenged statute contains the necessary element of
punishment has on occasion led the Court to examine the legislative
motive in enacting the statute. See, e.g., United States v.
Lovett, 328 U. S. 303 (1946). Two other decisions not involving a bill of attainder
analysis contain an inquiry into legislative purpose or motive of
the type that O'Brien suggests we engage in in this case. Kennedy v. Mendoza-Martinez, 372 U.
S. 144 , 372 U. S.
169 -184 (1963); Trop v. Dulles, 356 U. S.
86 , 356 U. S. 95 -97
(1958). The inquiry into legislative purpose or motive in Kennedy and Trop, however, was for the same
limited purpose as in the bill of attainder decisions -- i.e., to determine whether the statutes under review were
punitive in nature. We face no such inquiry in this case. The 1965
Amendment to § 462(b) was clearly penal in nature, designed to
impose criminal punishment for designated acts.
[ Footnote 31 ]
The other issues briefed by O'Brien were not raised in the
petition for certiorari in No. 232 or in the cross-petition in No.
233. Accordingly, those issues are not before the Court.
MR. JUSTICE HARLAN, concurring.
The crux of the Court's opinion, which I join, is, of course,
its general statement, ante at 391 U. S. 377 that:
"a government regulation is sufficiently justified if it is
within the constitutional power of the Government; if it furthers
an important or substantial governmental interest; if the
governmental interest is unrelated to the suppression of free
expression, and if the incidental restriction on alleged First
Amendment freedoms is no greater than is essential to the
furtherance of that interest."
I wish to make explicit my understanding that this passage does
not foreclose consideration of First Amendment claims in those rare
instances when an "incidental" restriction upon expression, imposed
by a regulation which furthers an "important or substantial"
governmental interest and satisfies the Court's other criteria, in
practice has the effect of entirely preventing a "speaker" Page 391 U. S. 389 from reaching a significant audience with whom he could not
otherwise lawfully communicate. This is not such a case, since
O'Brien manifestly could have conveyed his message in many ways
other than by burning his draft card.
MR. JUSTICE DOUGLAS, dissenting.
The Court states that the constitutional power of Congress to
raise and support armies is "broad and sweeping", and that
Congress' power "to classify and conscript manpower for military
service is beyond question.'" This is undoubtedly true in times
when, by declaration of Congress, the Nation is in a state of war.
The underlying and basic problem in this case, however, is whether
conscription is permissible in the absence of a declaration of war.
[ Footnote 2/1 ] That question has
not been briefed nor was it presented in oral argument; but it is,
I submit, a question upon which the litigants and the country are
entitled to a ruling. I have discussed in Holmes v. United
States, post, p. 936, the nature of the legal issue, and it
will be seen from my dissenting opinion in that case that this
Court has never ruled on Page 391 U. S. 390 the question. It is time that we made a ruling. This case should
be put down for reargument and heard with Holmes v. United
States and with Hart v. United States, post, p. 956,
in which the Court today denies certiorari. [ Footnote 2/2 ]
The rule that this Court will not consider issues not raised by
the parties is not inflexible, and yields in "exceptional cases"
( Duignan v. United States, 274 U.
S. 195 , 274 U. S. 200 ) to
the need correctly to decide the case before the court. E.g.,
Erie R. Co. v. Tompkins, 304 U. S. 64 ; Terminiello v. Chicago, 337 U. S. 1 .
In such a case, it is not unusual to ask for reargument
( Sherman v. United States, 356 U.
S. 369 , 356 U. S. 379 ,
n. 2, Frankfurter, J., concurring) even on a constitutional
question not raised by the parties. In Abel v. United
States, 362 U. S. 217 , the
petitioner had conceded that an administrative deportation arrest
warrant would be valid for its limited purpose even though not
supported by a sworn affidavit stating probable cause; but the
Court ordered reargument on the question whether the warrant had
been validly issued in petitioner's case. 362 U.S. at 362 U. S. 219 ,
n., par. 1; 359 U.S. 940. In Lustig v United States, 338 U. S. 74 , the
petitioner argued that an exclusionary rule should apply to the
fruit of an unreasonable search by state officials solely because
they acted in concert with federal officers ( see Weeks v.
United States, 232 U. S. 383 ; Byars v. United States, 273 U. S. 28 ). The
Court ordered reargument on the question raised in a then pending
case, Wolf v. Colorado, 338 U. S. 25 :
applicability of the Fourth Amendment to the States. U.S.Sup.Ct.
Journal, October Term, 1947, p. 298. In Donaldson v. Read
Magazine, 333 U. S. 178 , the
only issue presented, Page 391 U. S. 391 according to both parties, was whether the record contained
sufficient evidence of fraud to uphold an order of the Postmaster
General. Reargument was ordered on the constitutional issue of
abridgment of First Amendment freedoms. 333 U.S. at 333 U. S.
181 -182; Journal, October Term, 1947, p. 70. Finally, in Musser v. Utah, 333 U. S. 95 , 333 U. S. 96 ,
reargument was ordered on the question of unconstitutional
vagueness of a criminal statute, an issue not raised by the parties
but suggested at oral argument by Justice Jackson. Journal, October
Term, 1947, p. 87.
These precedents demonstrate the appropriateness of restoring
the instant case to the calendar for reargument on the question of
the constitutionality of a peacetime draft and having it heard with Holmes v. United States and Hart v. United
States. [ Footnote 2/1 ]
Neither of the decisions cited by the majority for the
proposition that Congress' power to conscript men into the armed
services is " beyond question'" concerns peacetime conscription.
As I have shown in my dissenting opinion in Holmes v. United
States, post, p. 936, the Selective Draft Law Cases, 245 U. S. 366 ,
decided in 1918, upheld the constitutionality of a conscription act
passed by Congress more than a month after war had been declared on
the German Empire and which was then being enforced in time of war. Lichter v. United States, 334 U.
S. 742 , concerned the constitutionality of the
Renegotiation Act, another wartime measure, enacted by Congress
over the period of 1942-1945 ( id. at 334 U. S. 745 ,
n. 1) and applied in that case to excessive war profits made in
1942-1943 ( id. at 334 U. S. 753 ). War had been declared, of course, in
1941 (55 Stat. 795). The Court referred to Congress' power to raise
armies in discussing the "background" (334 U.S. at 334 U. S. 753 )
of the Renegotiation Act, which it upheld as a valid exercise of
the War Power. [ Footnote 2/2 ]
Today the Court also denies stays in Shiffman v. Selective
Service Board No. 5, and Zigmond v. Selective Service
Board No. 16, post, p. 930, where punitive delinquency
regulations are invoked against registrants, decisions that present
a related question. | The Supreme Court upheld the conviction of O'Brien for burning his Selective Service registration certificate, rejecting his argument that the amendment under which he was charged was unconstitutional. The Court found that the amendment did not violate the First Amendment as it targeted conduct, not speech, and served a legitimate legislative purpose under Congress' power to raise and support armies. The Court also clarified that when "speech" and "nonspeech" elements are combined, the government can regulate the nonspeech element if it has a sufficiently important interest. |
Free Speech | Roth v. U.S. | https://supreme.justia.com/cases/federal/us/354/476/ | U.S. Supreme Court Roth v. United States, 354
U.S. 476 (1957) Roth v. United States No. 582 Argued April 22, 1957 Decided June 24, 1957 354
U.S. 476 ast|>* 354
U.S. 476 CERTIORARI TO THE UNITED STATES
COURT OF APPEALS FOR THE SECOND
CIRCUIT Syllabus 1. In the Roth case, the constitutionality of 18 U.S.C.
§ 1461, which makes punishable the mailing of material that is
"obscene, lewd, lascivious, or filthy . . . or other publication of
an indecent character," and Roth's conviction thereunder for
mailing an obscene book and obscene circulars and advertising, are
sustained. Pp. 354 U. S.
479 -494.
2. In the Albert case, the constitutionality of § 311
of West's California Penal Code Ann., 1955, which, inter
alia, makes it a misdemeanor to keep for sale, or to
advertise, material that is "obscene or indecent," and Alberts'
conviction thereunder for lewdly keeping for sale obscene and
indecent books and for writing, composing, and publishing an
obscene advertisement of them, are sustained. Pp. 354 U. S.
479 -494.
3. Obscenity is not within the area of constitutionally
protected freedom of speech or press either (1) under the First
Amendment, as to the Federal Government, or (2) under the Due
Process Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment, as to the States. Pp. 354 U. S.
481 -485.
(a) In the light of history, it is apparent that the
unconditional phrasing of the First Amendment was not intended to
protect every utterance. Pp. 354 U. S.
482 -483.
(b) The protection given speech and press was fashioned to
assure unfettered interchange of ideas for the bringing about of
political and social changes desired by the people. P. 354 U. S.
484 .
(c) All ideas having even the slightest redeeming social
importance -- unorthodox ideas, controversial ideas, even ideas
hateful to the prevailing climate of opinion -- have the full
protection of the guaranties, unless excludable because they
encroach upon the limited area of more important interests; but
implicit in the history of the First Amendment is the rejection of
obscenity as utterly without redeeming social importance. Pp. 354 U. S.
484 -485. Page 354 U. S. 477 4. Since obscenity is not protected, constitutional guaranties
were not violated in these cases merely because, under the trial
judges' instructions to the juries, convictions could be had
without proof either that the obscene material would perceptibly
create a clear and present danger of antisocial conduct, or
probably would induce its recipients to such conduct. Beauharnais v. Illinois, 343 U. S. 250 . Pp. 354 U. S.
485 -490.
(a) Sex and obscenity are not synonymous. Obscene material is
material which deals with sex in a manner appealing to prurient
interest -- i.e., material having a tendency to excite
lustful thoughts. P. 354 U. S.
487 .
(b) It is vital that the standards for judging obscenity
safeguard the protection of freedom of speech and press for
material which does not treat sex in a manner appealing to prurient
interest. Pp. 354 U. S.
487 -488.
(c) The standard for judging obscenity, adequate to withstand
the charge of constitutional infirmity, is whether, to the average
person, applying contemporary community standards, the dominant
theme of the material, taken as a whole, appeals to prurient
interest. Pp. 354 U. S.
488 -489.
(d) In these cases, both trial courts sufficiently followed the
proper standard and used the proper definition of obscenity. Pp. 354 U. S.
489 -490.
5. When applied according to the proper standard for judging
obscenity, 18 U.S.C. § 1461, which makes punishable the mailing of
material that is "obscene, lewd, lascivious, or filthy . . . or
other publication of an indecent character," does not (1) violate
the freedom of speech or press guaranteed by the First Amendment,
or (2) violate the constitutional requirements of due process by
failing to provide reasonably ascertainable standards of guilt. Pp. 354 U. S.
491 -492.
6. When applied according to the proper standard for judging
obscenity, § 311 of West's California Penal Code Ann., 1955, which, inter alia, makes it a misdemeanor to keep for sale or to
advertise material that is "obscene or indecent," does not (1)
violate the freedom of speech or press guaranteed by the Fourteenth
Amendment against encroachment by the States, or (2) violate the
constitutional requirements of due process by failing to provide
reasonably ascertainable standards of guilt. Pp. 354 U. S.
491 -492.
7. The federal obscenity statute, 18 U.S.C. § 1461, punishing
the use of the mails for obscene material, is a proper exercise of
the postal power delegated to Congress by Art. I, § 8, cl. 7, and
it Page 354 U. S. 478 does not unconstitutionally encroach upon the powers reserved to
the States by the Ninth and Tenth Amendments. Pp. 354 U. S.
492 -493.
8. The California obscenity statute here involved is not
repugnant to Art. I, § 8, cl. 7, since it does not impose a burden
upon, or interfere with, the federal postal functions -- even when
applied to a mail-order business. Pp. 354 U. S.
493 -494.
237 F.2d 796, affirmed. 138 Cal.
App. 2d Supp. 909 , 292 P.2d 90, affirmed. Page 354 U. S. 479 MR. JUSTICE BRENNAN delivered the opinion of the Court.
The constitutionality of a criminal obscenity statute is the
question in each of these cases. In Roth, the primary
constitutional question is whether the federal obscenity statute
[ Footnote 1 ] violates the
provision of the First Amendment that "Congress shall make no law .
. . abridging the freedom of speech, or of the press. . . ." In Alberts, the primary constitutional question is whether
the obscenity provisions of the California Penal Code [ Footnote 2 ] invade the freedoms of
speech and press as they may be incorporated in Page 354 U. S. 480 the liberty protected from state action by the Due Process
Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment.
Other constitutional questions are: whether these statutes
violate due process, [ Footnote
3 ] because too vague to support conviction for crime; whether
power to punish speech and press offensive to decency and morality
is in the States alone, so that the federal obscenity statute
violates the Ninth and Tenth Amendments (raised in Roth ),
and whether Congress, by enacting the federal obscenity statute,
under the power delegated by Art. I, § 8, cl. 7, to establish post
offices and post roads, preempted the regulation of the subject
matter (raised in Alberts ).
Roth conducted a business in New York in the publication and
sale of books, photographs and magazines. He used circulars and
advertising matter to solicit sales. He was convicted by a jury in
the District Court for the Southern District of New York upon 4
counts of a 26-count indictment charging him with mailing obscene
circulars and advertising, and an obscene book, in violation of the
federal obscenity statute. His conviction was affirmed by the Court
of Appeals for the Second Circuit. [ Footnote 4 ] We granted certiorari. [ Footnote 5 ] Page 354 U. S. 481 Alberts conducted a mail-order business from Los Angeles. He was
convicted by the Judge of the Municipal Court of the Beverly Hills
Judicial District (having waived a jury trial) under a misdemeanor
complaint which charged him with lewdly keeping for sale obscene
and indecent books, and with writing, composing and publishing an
obscene advertisement of them, in violation of the California Penal
Code. The conviction was affirmed by the Appellate Department of
the Superior Court of the State of California in and for the County
of Los Angeles. [ Footnote 6 ] We
noted probable jurisdiction. [ Footnote 7 ]
The dispositive question is whether obscenity is utterance
within the area of protected speech and press. [ Footnote 8 ] Although this is the first time the
question has been squarely presented to this Court, either under
the First Amendment or under the Fourteenth Amendment, expressions
found in numerous opinions indicate that this Court has always
assumed that obscenity is not protected by the freedoms of speech
and press. Ex parte Jackson, 96 U. S.
727 , 96 U. S.
736 -737; United States v. Chase, 135 U.
S. 255 , 135 U. S. 261 ; Robertson v. Baldwin, 165 U. S. 275 , 165 U. S. 281 ; Public Clearing House v. Coyne, 194 U.
S. 497 , 194 U. S. 508 ; Hoke v. United States, 227 U. S. 308 , 227 U. S. 322 ; Near v. Minnesota, 283 U. S. 697 , 283 U. S. 716 ; Chaplinsky v. New Hampshire, 315 U.
S. 568 , 315 U. S.
571 -572; Hannegan v. Esquire, Inc., 327 U. S. 146 , 327 U. S. 158 ; Winters v. New York, 333 U. S. 507 , 333 U. S. 510 ; Beauharnais v. Illinois, 343 U. S. 250 , 343 U. S. 266 .
[ Footnote 9 ] Page 354 U. S. 482 The guaranties of freedom of expression [ Footnote 10 ] in effect in 10 of the 14 States
which by 1792 had ratified the Constitution, gave no absolute
protection for every utterance. Thirteen of the 14 States provided
for the prosecution of libel, [ Footnote 11 ] and all of those States made either
blasphemy or profanity, or both, statutory crimes. [ Footnote 12 ] As early as Page 354 U. S. 483 1712, Massachusetts made it criminal to publish "any filthy,
obscene, or profane song, pamphlet, libel or mock sermon" in
imitation or mimicking of religious services. Acts and Laws of the
Province of Mass. Bay, c. CV, § 8 (1712), Mass.Bay Colony Charters
& Laws 399 (1814). Thus, profanity and obscenity were related
offenses.
In light of this history, it is apparent that the unconditional
phrasing of the First Amendment was not intended to protect every
utterance. This phrasing did not prevent this Court from concluding
that libelous utterances are not within the area of
constitutionally protected speech. Beauharnais v.
Illinois, 343 U. S. 250 , 343 U. S. 266 .
At the time of the adoption of the First Amendment, obscenity law
was not as fully developed as libel law, but there is sufficiently
contemporaneous evidence to show that obscenity, too, was outside
the protection intended for speech and press. [ Footnote 13 ] Page 354 U. S. 484 The protection given speech and press was fashioned to assure
unfettered interchange of ideas for the bringing about of political
and social changes desired by the people. This objective was made
explicit as early as 1774 in a letter of the Continental Congress
to the inhabitants of Quebec:
"The last right we shall mention regards the freedom of the
press. The importance of this consists, besides the advancement of
truth, science, morality, and arts in general, in its diffusion of
liberal sentiments on the administration of Government, its ready
communication of thoughts between subjects, and its consequential
promotion of union among them, whereby oppressive officers are
shamed or intimidated into more honourable and just modes of
conducting affairs."
1 Journals of the Continental Congress 108 (1774).
All ideas having even the slightest redeeming social importance
-- unorthodox ideas, controversial ideas, even ideas hateful to the
prevailing climate of opinion -- have the full protection of the
guaranties, unless excludable because they encroach upon the
limited area of more important interests. [ Footnote 14 ] But implicit in the history of the
First Amendment is the rejection of obscenity as utterly without
redeeming social importance. This rejection for Page 354 U. S. 485 that reason is mirrored in the universal judgment that obscenity
should be restrained, reflected in the international agreement of
over 50 nations, [ Footnote
15 ] in the obscenity laws of all of the 48 States, [ Footnote 16 ] and in the 20 obscenity
laws enacted by the Congress from 1842 to 1956. [ Footnote 17 ] This is the same judgment
expressed by this Court in Chaplinsky v. New Hampshire, 315 U. S. 568 , 315 U. S.
571 -572:
". . . There are certain well defined and narrowly limited
classes of speech, the prevention and punishment of which have
never been thought to raise any Constitutional problem. These
include the lewd and obscene. . . . It has been well observed that
such utterances are no essential part of any exposition of ideas,
and are of such slight social value as a step to truth that any
benefit that may be derived from them is clearly outweighed by the
social interest in order and morality. . . ."
(Emphasis added.) We hold that obscenity is not within the area
of constitutionally protected speech or press.
It is strenuously urged that these obscenity statutes offend the
constitutional guaranties because they punish Page 354 U. S. 486 incitation to impure sexual thoughts, not shown to be
related to any overt antisocial conduct which is or may be incited
in the persons stimulated to such thoughts. In Roth, the trial Judge instructed the jury:
"The words 'obscene, lewd and lascivious' as used in the law,
signify that form of immorality which has relation to sexual
impurity and has a tendency to excite lustful thoughts. "
(Emphasis added.) In Alberts, the trial judge applied
the test laid down in People v. Wepplo, 78 Cal. App.
2d Supp. 959 , 178 P.2d 853, namely, whether the material has "a
substantial tendency to deprave or corrupt its readers by inciting
lascivious thoughts or arousing lustful desires."
(Emphasis added.) It is insisted that the constitutional guaranties
are violated because convictions may be had without proof either
that obscene material will perceptibly create a clear and present
danger of anti-social conduct, [ Footnote 18 ] or will probably induce its recipients to
such conduct. [ Footnote 19 ]
But, in light of our holding that obscenity is not protected
speech, the complete answer to this argument is in the holding of
this Court in Beauharnais v. Illinois, supra, at 343 U. S.
266 :
"Libelous utterances not being within the area of
constitutionally protected speech, it is unnecessary, either for us
or for the State courts, to consider the issues behind the phrase
'clear and present danger.' Certainly no one would contend that
obscene speech, Page 354 U. S. 487 for example, may be punished only upon a showing of such
circumstances. Libel, as we have seen, is in the same class."
However, sex and obscenity are not synonymous. Obscene material
is material which deals with sex in a manner appealing to prurient
interest. [ Footnote 20 ] The
portrayal of sex, e.g., in art, literature and scientific
works, [ Footnote 21 ] is not
itself sufficient reason to deny material the constitutional
protection of freedom of speech and press. Sex, a great and
mysterious motive force in human life, has indisputably been a
subject of absorbing interest to mankind through the ages; it is
one of the vital problems of human interest and public concern. As
to all such problems, Page 354 U. S. 488 this Court said in Thornhill v. Alabama, 310 U. S.
88 , 310 U. S.
101 -102:
"The freedom of speech and of the press guaranteed by the
Constitution embraces at the least the liberty to discuss publicly
and truthfully all matters of public concern without
previous restraint or fear of subsequent punishment. The exigencies
of the colonial period and the efforts to secure freedom from
oppressive administration developed a broadened conception of these
liberties as adequate to supply the public need for information
and education with respect to the significant issues of the
times. . . . Freedom of discussion, if it would fulfill its
historic function in this nation, must embrace all issues about
which information is needed or appropriate to enable the members of
society to cope with the exigencies of their period. "
(Emphasis added.)
The fundamental freedoms of speech and press have contributed
greatly to the development and wellbeing of our free society and
are indispensable to its continued growth. [ Footnote 22 ] Ceaseless vigilance is the
watchword to prevent their erosion by Congress or by the States.
The door barring federal and state intrusion into this area cannot
be left ajar; it must be kept tightly closed, and opened only the
slightest crack necessary to prevent encroachment upon more
important interests. [ Footnote
23 ] It is therefore vital that the standards for judging
obscenity safeguard the protection of freedom of speech and press
for material which does not treat sex in a manner appealing to
prurient interest.
The early leading standard of obscenity allowed material to be
judged merely by the effect of an isolated Page 354 U. S. 489 excerpt upon particularly susceptible persons. Regina v.
Hicklin, [1868] L.R. 3 Q.B. 360. [ Footnote 24 ] Some American courts adopted this
standard, [ Footnote 25 ] but
later decisions have rejected it and substituted this test:
whether, to the average person, applying contemporary community
standards, the dominant theme of the material, taken as a whole,
appeals to prurient interest. [ Footnote 26 ] The Hicklin test, judging obscenity
by the effect of isolated passages upon the most susceptible
persons, might well encompass material legitimately treating with
sex, and so it must be rejected as unconstitutionally restrictive
of the freedoms of speech and press. On the other hand, the
substituted standard provides safeguards adequate to withstand the
charge of constitutional infirmity.
Both trial courts below sufficiently followed the proper
standard. Both courts used the proper definition of obscenity. In
addition, in the Alberts case, in ruling on a motion to
dismiss, the trial judge indicated that, as the Page 354 U. S. 490 trier of facts, he was judging each item as a whole as it would
affect the normal person, [ Footnote 27 ] and, in Roth, the trial judge
instructed the jury as follows:
". . . The test is not whether it would arouse sexual desires or
sexual impure thoughts in those comprising a particular segment of
the community, the young, the immature or the highly prudish or
would leave another segment, the scientific or highly educated or
the so-called worldly wise and sophisticated indifferent and
unmoved. . . ."
" * * * *" "The test in each case is the effect of the book, picture or
publication considered as a whole not upon any particular class,
but upon all those whom it is likely to reach. In other words, you
determine its impact upon the average person in the community. The
books, pictures and circulars must be judged as a whole, in their
entire context, and you are not to consider detached or separate
portions in reaching a conclusion. You judge the circulars,
pictures and publications which have been put in evidence by
present-day standards of the community. You may ask yourselves does
it offend the common conscience of the community by present-day
standards."
" * * * *" "In this case, ladies and gentlemen of the jury, you and you
alone are the exclusive judges of what the common conscience of the
community is, and, in determining that conscience, you are to
consider the community as a whole, young and old, educated and
uneducated, the religious and the irreligious -- men, women and
children. " Page 354 U. S. 491 It is argued that the statutes do not provide reasonably
ascertainable standards of guilt, and therefore violates the
constitutional requirements of due process. Winters v. New
York, 333 U. S. 507 . The
federal obscenity statute makes punishable the mailing of material
that is "obscene, lewd, lascivious, or filthy . . . or other
publication of an indecent character." [ Footnote 28 ] The California statute makes punishable, inter alia, the keeping for sale or advertising material
that is "obscene or indecent." The thrust of the argument is that
these words are not sufficiently precise, because they do not mean
the same thing to all people, all the time, everywhere.
Many decisions have recognized that these terms of obscenity
statutes are not precise. [ Footnote 29 ] This Court, however, has consistently held
that lack of precision is not itself offensive to the requirements
of due process. ". . . [T]he Constitution does not require
impossible standards"; all that is required is that the language
"conveys sufficiently definite warning as to the proscribed conduct
when measured by common understanding and practices. . . ." United States v. Petrillo, 332 U. S.
1 , 332 U. S. 7 -8.
These words, applied according to the proper standard for judging
obscenity, already discussed, give adequate warning of the conduct
proscribed, and mark
". . . boundaries sufficiently distinct for judges and juries
fairly to administer the law. . . . That there may be marginal
cases in which it is difficult to determine the side of the line
on Page 354 U. S. 492 which a particular fact situation falls is no sufficient reason
to hold the language too ambiguous to define a criminal offense. .
. ." Id. at 332 U. S. 7 . See also United States v. Harriss, 347 U.
S. 612 , 347 U. S. 624 ,
n. 15; Boyce Motor Lines, Inc. v. United States, 342 U. S. 337 , 342 U. S. 340 ; United States v. Ragen, 314 U. S. 513 , 314 U. S.
523 -524; United States v. Wurzbach, 280 U. S. 396 ; Hygrade Provision Co. v. Sherman, 266 U.
S. 497 ; Fox v. Washington, 236 U.
S. 273 ; Nash v. United States, 229 U.
S. 373 . [ Footnote
30 ]
In summary, then, we hold that these statutes, applied according
to the proper standard for judging obscenity, do not offend
constitutional safeguards against convictions based upon protected
material, or fail to give men in acting adequate notice of what is
prohibited.
Roth's argument that the federal obscenity statute
unconstitutionally encroaches upon the powers reserved by the Ninth
and Tenth Amendments to the States and to the people to punish
speech and press where offensive to decency and morality is hinged
upon his contention that obscenity is expression not excepted from
the sweep of the provision of the First Amendment that "Congress
shall make no law . . . abridging the freedom of speech,
or of the press. . . ." (Emphasis added.) That argument falls in
light of our holding that obscenity is not expression protected by
the First Amendment. [ Footnote
31 ] We Page 354 U. S. 493 therefore hold that the federal obscenity statute punishing the
use of the mails for obscene material is a proper exercise of the
postal power delegated to Congress by Art. I, § 8, cl. 7. [ Footnote 32 ] In United Public
Workers v. Mitchell, 330 U. S. 75 , 330 U. S. 95 -96,
this Court said:
". . . The powers granted by the Constitution to the Federal
Government are subtracted from the totality of sovereignty
originally in the states and the people. Therefore, when objection
is made that the exercise of a federal power infringes upon rights
reserved by the Ninth and Tenth Amendments, the inquiry must be
directed toward the granted power under which the action of the
Union was taken. If granted power is found, necessarily the
objection of invasion of those rights, reserved by the Ninth and
Tenth Amendments, must fail. . . ."
Alberts argues that, because his was a mail-order business, the
California statute is repugnant to Art. I, § 8, cl. 7, under which
the Congress allegedly preempted the regulatory field by enacting
the federal obscenity statute punishing the mailing or advertising
by mail of obscene material. The federal statute deals only with
actual Page 354 U. S. 494 mailing; it does not eliminate the power of the state to punish
"keeping for sale" or "advertising" obscene material. The state
statute in no way imposes a burden or interferes with the federal
postal functions.
". . . The decided cases which indicate the limits of state
regulatory power in relation to the federal mail service involve
situations where state regulation involved a direct, physical
interference with federal activities under the postal power or some
direct, immediate burden on the performance of the postal
functions. . . ." Railway Mail Assn. v. Corsi, 326 U. S.
88 , 326 U. S.
96 .
The judgments are Affirmed. * Together with No. 61, Albert v. California, appeal
from the Superior Court of California, Los Angeles County,
Appellate Department, argued and decided on the same dates.
[ Footnote 1 ]
The federal obscenity statute provided, in pertinent part:
"Every obscene, lewd, lascivious, or filthy book, pamphlet,
picture, paper, letter, writing, print, or other publication of an
indecent character, and --"
" * * * *" "Every written or printed card, letter, circular, book,
pamphlet, advertisement, or notice of any kind giving information,
directly or indirectly, where, or how, or from whom, or by what
means any of such mentioned matters, articles, or things may be
obtained or made, . . . whether sealed or unsealed . . ."
" * * * *" "Is declared to be nonmailable matter and shall not be conveyed
in the mails or delivered from any post office or by any letter
carrier."
"Whoever knowingly deposits for mailing or delivery, anything
declared by this section to be nonmailable, or knowingly takes the
same from the mails for the purpose of circulating or disposing
thereof, or of aiding in the circulation or disposition thereof,
shall be fined not more than $5,000 or imprisoned not more than
five years, or both."
18 U.S.C. § 1461.
The 1955 amendment of this statute, 69 Stat. 13, is not
applicable to this case.
[ Footnote 2 ]
The California Penal Code provides, in pertinent part:
"Every person who willfully and lewdly, either:"
" * * * *" "3. Writes, composes, stereotypes, prints, publishes, sells,
distributes, keeps for sale, or exhibits any obscene or indecent
writing, paper, or book; or designs, copies, draws, engraves,
paints, or otherwise prepares any obscene or indecent picture or
print; or molds, cuts, casts, or otherwise makes any obscene or
indecent figure; or,"
"4. Writes, composes, or publishes any notice or advertisement
of any such writing, paper, book, picture, print or figure; . .
."
" * * * *" "6. . . . is guilty of a misdemeanor. . . ."
West's Cal.Penal Code Ann., 1955, § 311.
[ Footnote 3 ]
In Roth, reliance is placed on the Due Process Clause
of the Fifth Amendment, and, in Alberts, reliance is
placed upon the Due Process Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment.
[ Footnote 4 ]
237 F.2d 796.
[ Footnote 5 ]
352 U.S. 964. Petitioner's application for bail was granted by
MR. JUSTICE HARLAN in his capacity as Circuit Justice for the
Second Circuit. 1 L. Ed. 2d 34, 77 Sup.Ct. 17.
[ Footnote 6 ] 138 Cal.
App. 2d Supp. 909 , 292 P.2d 90. This is the highest state
appellate court available to the appellant. Cal.Const., Art. VI, §
5; see Edwards v. California, 314 U.
S. 160 .
[ Footnote 7 ]
352 U.S. 962.
[ Footnote 8 ]
No issue is presented in either case concerning the obscenity of
the material involved.
[ Footnote 9 ] See also the following cases in which convictions under
obscenity statutes have been reviewed: Grimm v. United
States, 156 U. S. 604 ; Rosen v. United States, 161 U. S. 29 ; Swearingen v. United States, 161 U.
S. 446 ; Andrews v. United States, 162 U.
S. 420 ; Price v. United States, 165 U.
S. 311 ; Dunlop v. United States, 165 U.
S. 486 ; Bartell v. United States, 227 U.
S. 427 ; United States v. Limehouse, 285 U. S. 424 .
[ Footnote 10 ]
Del.Const., 1792, Art. I, § 5; Ga.Const., 1777, Art. LXI;
Md.Const., 1776, Declaration of Rights, § 38; Mass.Const., 1780,
Declaration of Rights, Art. XVI; N.H.Const., 1784, Art. I, § XXII;
N.C. Const., 1776, Declaration of Rights, Art. XV; Pa.Const., 1776,
Declaration of Rights, Art. XII; S.C.Const., 1778, Art. XLIII;
Vt.Const., 1777, Declaration of Rights, Art. XIV; Va. Bill of
Rights, 776, § 12.
[ Footnote 11 ]
Act to Secure the Freedom of the Press (1804), 1
Conn.Pub.Stat.Laws 355 (1808); Del.Const., 1792, Art. I, § 5;
Ga.Penal Code, Eighth Div., §VIII (1817), Digest of the Laws of Ga.
364 (Prince 1822); Act of 1803, c. 54, II Md.Public General Laws
1096 (Poe 1888); Commonwealth v. Kneeland, 37 Mass. 206,
232 (1838); Act for the Punishment of Certain Crimes Not Capital
(1791), N.H.Laws 1792, 253; Act Respecting Libels (1799),
N.J.Rev.Laws 411 (1800); People v. Croswell, 3 Johns.
(N.Y.) 337 (1804); Act of 1803, c. 632, 2 Laws of N.C. 999 (1821);
Pa.Const., 1790, Art. IX, § 7; R.I.Code of Laws (1647), Proceedings
of the First General Assembly and Code of Laws 44-45 (1647);
R.I.Const., 1842, Art. I, § 20; Act of 1804, 1 Laws of Vt. 366
(Tolman 1808); Commonwealth v. Morris, 1 Brock. & Hol.
(Va.) 176 (1811).
[ Footnote 12 ]
Act for the Punishment of Divers Capital and Other Felonies,
Acts and Laws of Conn. 66, 67 (1784); Act Against Drunkenness,
Blasphemy, §§ 4, 5 (1737), 1 Laws of Del. 173, 174 (1797); Act to
Regulate Taverns (1786), Digest of the Laws of Ga. 512, 513 (Prince
1822); Act of 1723, c. 16, § 1, Digest of the Laws of Md. 92 (Herty
1799); General Laws and Liberties of Mass. Bay, c. XVIII, § 3
(1646), Mass. Bay Colony Charters & Laws 58 (1814); Act of
1782, c. 8, Rev.Stat. of Mass. 741, § 15 (1836); Act of 1798, c.
33, §§ 1, 3, Rev.Stat. of Mass. 741, § 16 (1836); Act for the
Punishment of Certain Crimes Not Capital (1791), N.H.Laws 1792,
252, 256; Act for the Punishment of Profane Cursing and Swearing
(1791), N.H.Laws 1792, 258; Act for Suppressing Vice and
Immorality, §§ VIII, IX (1798), N.J.Rev.Laws 329, 331 (1800); Act
for Suppressing Immorality, § IV (1788), 2 Laws of N.Y. 257, 258
(Jones & Varick 1777-1789); People v. Ruggles, 8
Johns. (N.Y.) 290 (1811); Act . . . for the More Effectual
Suppression of Vice and Immorality, § III (1741), 1 N.C.Laws 52
(Martin Rev. 1715-1790); Act to Prevent the Grievous Sins of
Cursing and Swearing (1700), II Statutes at Large of Pa. 49
(1700-1712); Act for the Prevention of Vice and Immorality, § II
(1794), 3 Laws of Pa. 177, 178 (1791-1802); Act to Reform the Penal
Laws, §§ 33, 34 (1798), R.I.Laws 1798, 584, 595; Act for the More
Effectual Suppressing of Blasphemy and Prophaneness (1703), Laws of
S.C. 4 (Grimke 1790); Act, for the Punishment of Certain Capital,
and Other High Crimes and Misdemeanors, § 20 (1797), 1 Laws of Vt.
332, 339 (Tolman 1808); Act for the Punishment of Certain Inferior
Crimes and Misdemeanors, § 20 (1797), 1 Laws of Vt. 352, 361
(Tolman 1808); Act for the Effectual Suppression of Vice, § 1
(1792), Acts of General Assembly of Va. 286 (1794).
[ Footnote 13 ]
Act Concerning Crimes and Punishments, § 69 (1821), Stat.Laws of
Conn. 109 (1824); Knowles v. State, 3 Day (Conn.) 103
(1808); Rev.Stat. of 1835, c. 130, § 10, Rev.Stat. of Mass. 740
(1836); Commonwealth v. Holmes, 17 Mass. 335 (1821);
Rev.Stat. of 1842, c. 113, § 2, Rev.Stat. of N.H. 221 (1843); Act
for Suppressing Vice and Immorality, § XII (1798), N.J.Rev.Laws
329, 331 (1800); Commonwealth v. Sharpless, 2 S. & R.
(Pa.) 91 (1815).
[ Footnote 14 ] E.g., United States v. Harriss, 347 U.
S. 612 ; Breard v. Alexandria, 341 U.
S. 622 ; Teamsters Union v. Hanke, 339 U.
S. 470 ; Kovacs v. Cooper, 336 U. S.
77 ; Prince v. Massachusetts, 321 U.
S. 158 ; Labor Board v. Virginia Elec. & Power
Co., 314 U. S. 469 ; Cox v. New Hampshire, 312 U. S. 569 ; Schenck v. United States, 249 U. S.
47 .
[ Footnote 15 ]
Agreement for the Suppression of the Circulation of Obscene
Publications, 37 Stat. 1511; Treaties in Force 209 (U.S. Dept.
State, October 31, 1956).
[ Footnote 16 ]
Hearings before Subcommittee to Investigate Juvenile Delinquency
of the Senate Committee on the Judiciary, pursuant to S.Res. 62,
84th Cong., 1st Sess. 49-52 (May 24, 1955).
Although New Mexico has no general obscenity statute, it does
have a statute giving to municipalities the power "to prohibit the
sale or exhibiting of obscene or immoral publications, prints,
pictures, or illustrations." N.M.Stat.Ann., 1953, §§ 14-21-3,
14-21-12.
[ Footnote 17 ]
5 Stat. 548, 566; 11 Stat. 168; 13 Stat. 504, 507; 17 Stat. 302;
17 Stat. 598; 19 Stat. 90; 25 Stat. 187, 188; 25 Stat. 496; 26
Stat. 567, 614-615; 29 Stat. 512; 33 Stat. 705; 35 Stat. 1129,
1138; 41 Stat. 1060; 46 Stat. 688; 48 Stat. 1091, 1100; 62 Stat.
768; 64 Stat. 194; 64 Stat. 451; 69 Stat. 183; 70 Stat. 699.
[ Footnote 18 ] Schenck v. United States, 249 U. S.
47 . This approach is typified by the opinion of Judge
Bok (written prior to this Court's opinion in Dennis v. United
States, 341 U. S. 494 ) in Commonwealth v. Gordon, 66 Pa. D. & C. 101, aff'd
sub nom. Commonwealth v. Feigenbaum, 166 Pa.Super. 120, 70
A.2d 389.
[ Footnote 19 ] Dennis v. United States, 341 U.
S. 494 . This approach is typified by the concurring
opinion of Judge Frank in the Roth case, 237 F.2d at 801. See also Lockhart & McClure, Literature, The Law of
Obscenity, and the Constitution, 38 Minn.L.Rev. 295 (1954).
[ Footnote 20 ] I.e., material having a tendency to excite lustful
thoughts. Webster's New International Dictionary (Unabridged,2d
ed., 1949) defines prurient, in pertinent part, as
follows:
". . . Itching; longing; uneasy with desire or longing; of
persons, having itching, morbid, or lascivious longings; of desire,
curiosity, or propensity, lewd. . . ." Pruriency is defined, in pertinent part, as
follows:
". . . Quality of being prurient; lascivious desire or thought.
. . ." See also Mutual Film Corp. v. Industrial Comm'n, 236 U. S. 230 , 236 U. S. 242 ,
where this Court said as to motion pictures:
". . . They take their attraction from the general interest,
eager and wholesome it may be, in their subjects, but a prurient interest may be excited and appealed to. . .
."
(Emphasis added.)
We perceive no significant difference between the meaning of
obscenity developed in the case law and the definition of the
A.L.I., Model Penal Code, § 207.10(2) (Tent.Draft No. 6, 1957), viz.: ". . . A thing is obscene if, considered as a whole, its
predominant appeal is to prurient interest, i.e., a
shameful or morbid interest in nudity, sex, or excretion, and if it
goes substantially beyond customary limits of candor in description
or representation of such matters. . . ." See Comment, id. at 10, and the discussion at
page 29 et seq. [ Footnote 21 ] See, e.g., United States v. Dennett, 39 F.2d 564.
[ Footnote 22 ]
Madison's Report on the Virginia Resolutions, 4 Elliot's Debates
571.
[ Footnote 23 ] See note 14 supra. [ Footnote 24 ] But see the instructions given to the jury by Mr.
Justice Stable in Regina v. Martin Secker Warburg, [1954]
2 All Eng. 683 (C.C.C.).
[ Footnote 25 ] United States v. Kennerley, 209 F. 119; MacFadden
v. United States, 165 F. 51; United States v.
Bennett, 24 Fed.Cas. 1093; United States v. Clarke, 38 F. 500; Commonwealth v. Buckley, 200 Mass. 346, 86 N.E.
910.
[ Footnote 26 ] E.g., Walker v. Popence, 80 U.S.App.D.C. 129, 149 F.2d
511; Parmelee v. United States, 72 App.D.C. 203, 113 F.2d
729; United States v. Levine, 83 F.2d 156; United
States v. Dennett, 39 F.2d 564; Khan v. Feist,
Inc., 70 F. Supp.
450 , aff'd, 165 F.2d 188; United States v. One
Book Called "Ulysses," 5 F. Supp.
182 , aff'd, 72 F.2d 705; American Civil Liberties
Union v. Chicago, 3 Ill. 2d
334 , 121 N.E.2d
585 ; Commonwealth v. Isenstadt, 318 Mass. 543, 62
N.E.2d 840; Missouri v. Becker, 364 Mo. 1079, 272 S.W.2d
283 ; Adams Theatre Co. v. Keenan, 12 N.J. 267, 96 A.2d
519 ; Bantam Books, Inc. v. Melko, 25 N.J.Super. 292, 96 A.2d 47 ; Commonwealth v. Gordon, 66 Pa. D. & C.
101, aff'd sub nom. Commonwealth v. Feigenbaum, 166
Pa.Super. 120, 70 A.2d 389; cf. Roth v. Goldman, 172 F.2d
788, 794-795 (concurrence).
[ Footnote 27 ]
In Alberts, the contention that the trial judge did not
read the materials in their entirety is not before us because not
fairly comprised within the questions presented. U.S.Sup.Ct.Rules,
15(1)(c)(1).
[ Footnote 28 ]
This Court, as early as 1896, said of the federal obscenity
statute:
". . . Every one who uses the mails of the United States for
carrying papers or publications must take notice of what, in this
enlightened age, is meant by decency, purity, and chastity in
social life, and what must be deemed obscene, lewd, and
lascivious." Rosen v. United States, 161 U. S.
29 , 161 U. S.
42 .
[ Footnote 29 ] E.g., Roth v. Goldman, 172 F.2d 788, 789; Parmelee
v. United States, 72 App.D.C. 203, 204, 113 F.2d 729, 730; United States v. 4200 Copies International
Journal, 134 F.
Supp. 490 , 493; United States v. One Unbound
Volume, 128 F.
Supp. 280 , 281.
[ Footnote 30 ]
It is argued that, because juries may reach different
conclusions as to the same material, the statutes must be held to
be insufficiently precise to satisfy due process requirements. But
it is common experience that different juries may reach different
results under any criminal statute. That is one of the consequences
we accept under our jury system. Cf. Dunlop v. United
States, 165 U. S. 486 , 165 U. S.
499 -500.
[ Footnote 31 ]
For the same reason, we reject, in this case, the argument that
there is greater latitude for state action under the word "liberty"
under the Fourteenth Amendment than is allowed to Congress by the
language of the First Amendment.
[ Footnote 32 ]
In Public Clearing House v. Coyne, 194 U.
S. 497 , 194 U. S.
506 -508, this Court said:
"The constitutional principles underlying the administration of
the Post Office Department were discussed in the opinion of the
court in Ex parte Jackson, 96 U. S.
727 , in which we held that the power vested in Congress
to establish post offices and post roads embraced the regulation of
the entire postal system of the country; that Congress might
designate what might be carried in the mails and what excluded. . .
. It may . . . refuse to include in its mails such printed matter
or merchandise as may seem objectionable to it upon the ground of
public policy. . . . For more than thirty years, not only has the
transmission of obscene matter been prohibited, but it has been
made a crime, punishable by fine or imprisonment, for a person to
deposit such matter in the mails. The constitutionality of this law
we believe has never been attacked. . . ."
MR. CHIEF JUSTICE WARREN, concurring in the result.
I agree with the result reached by the Court in these cases,
but, because we are operating in a field of expression and because
broad language used here may eventually be applied to the arts and
sciences and freedom of communication generally, I would limit our
decision to the facts before us and to the validity of the statutes
in question as applied.
Appellant Alberts was charged with willfully, unlawfully and
lewdly disseminating obscene matter. Obscenity has been construed
by the California courts to mean having a substantial tendency to
corrupt by arousing lustful desires. People v.
Wepplo, 78 Cal. App.
2d Supp. 959 , 178 P.2d 853. Petitioner Roth was indicted for
unlawfully, willfully and knowingly mailing obscene material that
was calculated to corrupt and debauch the minds and morals of those
to whom it was sent. Each was accorded all the protections of a
criminal trial. Among other things, they contend that the statutes
under which they were convicted violate the constitutional
guarantees of freedom of speech, press and communication. Page 354 U. S. 495 That there is a social problem presented by obscenity is
attested by the expression of the legislatures of the forty-eight
States, as well as the Congress. To recognize the existence of a
problem, however, does not require that we sustain any and all
measures adopted to meet that problem. The history of the
application of laws designed to suppress the obscene demonstrates
convincingly that the power of government can be invoked under them
against great art or literature, scientific treatises, or works
exciting social controversy. Mistakes of the past prove that there
is a strong countervailing interest to be considered in the
freedoms guaranteed by the First and Fourteenth Amendments.
The line dividing the salacious or pornographic from literature
or science is not straight and unwavering. Present laws depend
largely upon the effect that the materials may have upon those who
receive them. It is manifest that the same object may have a
different impact, varying according to the part of the community it
reached. But there is more to these cases. It is not the book that
is on trial; it is a person. The conduct of the defendant is the
central issue, not the obscenity of a book or picture. The nature
of the materials is, of course, relevant as an attribute of the
defendant's conduct, but the materials are thus placed in context
from which they draw color and character. A wholly different result
might be reached in a different setting.
The personal element in these cases is seen most strongly in the
requirement of scienter. Under the California law, the
prohibited activity must be done "willfully and lewdly." The
federal statute limits the crime to acts done "knowingly." In his
charge to the jury, the district judge stated that the matter must
be "calculated" to corrupt or debauch. The defendants in both these
cases were engaged in the business of purveying textual or Page 354 U. S. 496 graphic matter openly advertised to appeal to the erotic
interest of their customers. They were plainly engaged in the
commercial exploitation of the morbid and shameful craving for
materials with prurient effect. I believe that the State and
Federal Governments can constitutionally punish such conduct. That
is all that these cases present to us, and that is all we need to
decide.
I agree with the Court's decision in its rejection of the other
contentions raised by these defendants.
MR. JUSTICE HARLAN, concurring in the result in No. 61, and
dissenting in No. 582.
I regret not to be able to join the Court's opinion. I cannot do
so, because I find lurking beneath its disarming generalizations a
number of problems which not only leave me with serious misgivings
as to the future effect of today's decisions, but which also, in my
view, call for different results in these two cases. I My basic difficulties with the Court's opinion are threefold.
First, the opinion paints with such a broad brush that I fear it
may result in a loosening of the tight reins which state and
federal courts should hold upon the enforcement of obscenity
statutes. Second, the Court fails to discriminate between the
different factors which, in my opinion, are involved in the
constitutional adjudication of state and federal obscenity cases.
Third, relevant distinctions between the two obscenity statutes
here involved, and the Court's own definition of "obscenity," are
ignored.
In final analysis, the problem presented by these cases is how
far, and on what terms, the state and federal governments have
power to punish individuals for disseminating books considered to
be undesirable because of their Page 354 U. S. 497 nature or supposed deleterious effect upon human conduct.
Proceeding from the premise that "no issue is presented in either
case, concerning the obscenity of the material involved," the Court
finds the "dispositive question" to be "whether obscenity is
utterance within the area of protected speech and press," and then
holds that "obscenity" is not so protected, because it is "utterly
without redeeming social importance." This sweeping formula appears
to me to beg the very question before us. The Court seems to assume
that "obscenity" is a peculiar genus of "speech and
press," which is as distinct, recognizable, and classifiable as
poison ivy is among other plants. On this basis, the constitutional question before us simply becomes, as the
Court says, whether "obscenity," as an abstraction, is protected by
the First and Fourteenth Amendments, and the question whether a particular book may be suppressed becomes a mere matter of
classification, of "fact," to be entrusted to a factfinder and
insulated from independent constitutional judgment. But surely the
problem cannot be solved in such a generalized fashion. Every
communication has an individuality and "value" of its own. The
suppression of a particular writing or other tangible form of
expression is, therefore, an individual matter, and in the
nature of things every such suppression raises an individual
constitutional problem, in which a reviewing court must determine
for itself whether the attacked expression is suppressable
within constitutional standards. Since those standards do not
readily lend themselves to generalized definitions, the
constitutional problem, in the last analysis, becomes one of
particularized judgments which appellate courts must make for
themselves.
I do not think that reviewing courts can escape this
responsibility by saying that the trier of the facts, be it a jury
or a judge, has labeled the questioned matter as "obscene," for, if
"obscenity" is to be suppressed, the Page 354 U. S. 498 question whether a particular work is of that character involves
not really an issue of fact, but a question of constitutional judgment of the most sensitive and delicate kind. Many
juries might find that Joyce's "Ulysses" or Bocaccio's "Decameron"
was obscene, and yet the conviction of a defendant for selling
either book would raise, for me, the gravest constitutional
problems, for no such verdict could convince me, without more, that
these books are "utterly without redeeming social importance." In
short, I do not understand how the Court can resolve the
constitutional problems now before it without making its own
independent judgment upon the character of the material upon which
these convictions were based. I am very much afraid that the broad
manner in which the Court has decided these cases will tend to
obscure the peculiar responsibilities resting on state and federal
courts in this field, and encourage them to rely on easy labeling
and jury verdicts as a substitute for facing up to the tough
individual problems of constitutional judgment involved in every
obscenity case.
My second reason for dissatisfaction with the Court's opinion is
that the broad strides with which the Court has proceeded has led
it to brush aside with perfunctory ease the vital constitutional
considerations which, in my opinion, differentiate these two cases.
It does not seem to matter to the Court that, in one case, we
balance the power of a State in this field against the restrictions
of the Fourteenth Amendment, and, in the other, the power of the
Federal Government against the limitations of the First Amendment.
I deal with this subject more particularly later.
Thirdly, the Court has not been bothered by the fact that the
two cases involve different statutes. In California, the book must
have a "tendency to deprave or corrupt its readers"; under the
federal statute, it must tend "to stir sexual impulses and lead to
sexually impure Page 354 U. S. 499 thoughts." [ Footnote 2/1 ] The
two statutes do not seem to me to present the same problems. Yet
the Court compounds confusion when it superimposes on these two
statutory definitions a third, drawn from the American Law
Institute's Model Penal Code, Tentative Draft No. 6: "A thing is
obscene if, considered as a whole, its predominant appeal is to
prurient interest." The bland assurance that this definition is the
same as the ones with which we deal flies in the face of the
authors' express rejection of the "deprave and corrupt" and "sexual
thoughts" tests:
"Obscenity [in the Tentative Draft] is defined in terms of
material which appeals predominantly to prurient interest in sexual
matters and which goes beyond customary freedom of expression in
these matters. We reject the prevailing test of tendency to arouse
lustful thoughts or desires because it is Page 354 U. S. 500 unrealistically broad for a society that plainly tolerates a
great deal of erotic interest in literature, advertising, and art,
and because regulation of thought or desire, unconnected with overt
misbehavior, raises the most acute constitutional as well as
practical difficulties. We likewise reject the common definition of
obscene as that which 'tends to corrupt or debase.' If this means
anything different from tendency to arouse lustful thought and
desire, it suggests that change of character or actual misbehavior
follows from contact with obscenity. Evidence of such consequences
is lacking. . . . On the other hand, 'appeal to prurient interest'
refers to qualities of the material itself: the capacity to attract
individuals eager for a forbidden look. . . . [ Footnote 2/2 ]"
As this passage makes clear, there is a significant distinction
between the definitions used in the prosecutions before us and the
American Law Institute formula. If, therefore, the latter is the
correct standard, as my Brother BRENNAN elsewhere intimates,
[ Footnote 2/3 ] then these
convictions should surely be reversed. Instead, the Court merely
assimilates the various tests into one indiscriminate
potpourri.
I now pass to the consideration of the two cases before us. II I concur in the judgment of the Court in No. 61, Alberts v.
California. The question in this case is whether the defendant was deprived
of liberty without due process of law when he was convicted for
selling certain materials found by the judge to be obscene because
they would have a "tendency Page 354 U. S. 501 to deprave or corrupt its readers by exciting lascivious
thoughts or arousing lustful desire."
In judging the constitutionality of this conviction, we should
remember that our function in reviewing state judgments under the
Fourteenth Amendment is a narrow one. We do not decide whether the
policy of the State is wise, or whether it is based on assumptions
scientifically substantiated. We can inquire only whether the state
action so subverts the fundamental liberties implicit in the Due
Process Clause that it cannot be sustained as a rational exercise
of power. See Jackson, J., dissenting in Beauharnais
v. Illinois, 343 U. S. 250 , 343 U. S. 287 .
The States' power to make printed words criminal is, of course,
confined by the Fourteenth Amendment, but only insofar as such
power is inconsistent with our concepts of "ordered liberty." Palko v. Connecticut, 302 U. S. 319 , 302 U. S.
324 -325.
What, then, is the purpose of this California statute? Clearly
the state legislature has made the judgment that printed words can
"deprave or corrupt" the reader -- that words can incite to
antisocial or immoral action. The assumption seems to be that the
distribution of certain types of literature will induce criminal or
immoral sexual conduct. It is well known, of course, that the
validity of this assumption is a matter of dispute among critics,
sociologists, psychiatrists, and penologists. There is a large
school of thought, particularly in the scientific community, which
denies any causal connection between the reading of pornography and
immorality, crime, or delinquency. Others disagree. Clearly it is
not our function to decide this question. That function belongs to
the state legislature. Nothing in the Constitution requires
California to accept as truth the most advanced and sophisticated
psychiatric opinion. It seems to me clear that it is not
irrational, in our present state of knowledge, to consider that
pornography can induce a type of sexual conduct which a State may
deem obnoxious to the Page 354 U. S. 502 moral fabric of society. In fact, the very division of opinion
on the subject counsels us to respect the choice made by the
State.
Furthermore, even assuming that pornography cannot be deemed
ever to cause, in an immediate sense, criminal sexual conduct,
other interests within the proper cognizance of the States may be
protected by the prohibition placed on such materials. The State
can reasonably draw the inference that, over a long period of time,
the indiscriminate dissemination of materials the essential
character of which is to degrade sex will have an eroding effect on
moral standards. And the State has a legitimate interest in
protecting the privacy of the home against invasion of unsolicited
obscenity.
Above all stands the realization that we deal here with an area
where knowledge is small, data are insufficient, and experts are
divided. Since the domain of sexual morality is preeminently a
matter of state concern, this Court should be slow to interfere
with state legislation calculated to protect that morality. It
seems to me that nothing in the broad and flexible command of the
Due Process Clause forbids California to prosecute one who sells
books whose dominant tendency might be to "deprave or corrupt" a
reader. I agree with the Court, of course, that the books must be
judged as a whole, and in relation to the normal adult reader.
What has been said, however, does not dispose of the case. It
still remains for us to decide whether the state court's
determination that this material should be suppressed is consistent
with the Fourteenth Amendment, and that, of course, presents a
federal question as to which we, and not the state court, have the
ultimate responsibility. And so, in the final analysis, I concur in
the judgment because, upon an independent perusal of the material
involved, and in light of the considerations discussed Page 354 U. S. 503 above, I cannot say that its suppression would so interfere with
the communication of "ideas" in any proper sense of that term that
it would offend the Due Process Clause. I therefore agree with the
Court that appellant's conviction must be affirmed. III I dissent in No. 582, Roth v. United States. We are faced here with the question whether the federal
obscenity statute, as construed and applied in this case, violates
the First Amendment to the Constitution. To me, this question is of
quite a different order than one where we are dealing with state
legislation under the Fourteenth Amendment. I do not think it
follows that state and federal powers in this area are the same,
and that, just because the State may suppress a particular
utterance, it is automatically permissible for the Federal
Government to do the same. I agree with Mr. Justice Jackson that
the historical evidence does not bear out the claim that the
Fourteenth Amendment "incorporates" the First in any literal sense. See Beauharnais v. Illinois, supra. But laying aside any
consequences which might flow from that conclusion, cf. Mr. Justice Holmes in Gitlow v. New York, 268 U.
S. 652 , 268 U. S. 672 ,
[ Footnote 2/4 ] I prefer to rest my
views about this case on broader and less abstract grounds.
The Constitution differentiates between those areas of human
conduct subject to the regulation of the States and those subject
to the powers of the Federal Government. The substantive powers of
the two governments, in many Page 354 U. S. 504 instances, are distinct. And in every case where we are called
upon to balance the interest in free expression against other
interests, it seems to me important that we should keep in the
forefront the question of whether those other interests are state
or federal. Since, under our constitutional scheme, the two are not
necessarily equivalent, the balancing process must needs often
produce different results. Whether a particular limitation on
speech or press is to be upheld because it subserves a paramount
governmental interest must, to a large extent, I think, depend on
whether that government has, under the Constitution, a direct
substantive interest, that is, the power to act, in the particular
area involved.
The Federal Government has, for example, power to restrict
seditious speech directed against it, because that Government
certainly has the substantive authority to protect itself against
revolution. Cf. Pennsylvania v. Nelson, 350 U.
S. 497 . But, in dealing with obscenity, we are faced
with the converse situation, for the interests which obscenity
statutes purportedly protect are primarily entrusted to the care
not of the Federal Government, but of the States. Congress has no
substantive power over sexual morality. Such powers as the Federal
Government has in this field are but incidental to its other
powers, here, the postal power, and are not of the same nature as
those possessed by the States, which bear direct responsibility for
the protection of the local moral fabric. [ Footnote 2/5 ] Page 354 U. S. 505 What Mr. Justice Jackson said in Beauharnais, supra, 343 U.S. at 343 U. S.
294 -295, about criminal libel is equally true of
obscenity:
"The inappropriateness of a single standard for restricting
State and Nation is indicated by the disparity between their
functions and duties in relation to those freedoms. Criminality of
defamation is predicated upon power either to protect the private
right to enjoy integrity of reputation or the public right to
tranquillity. Neither of these are objects of federal cognizance
except when necessary to the accomplishment of some delegated
power. . . . When the Federal Government puts liberty of press in
one scale, it has a very limited duty to personal reputation or
local tranquillity to weigh against it in the other. But state
action affecting speech or press can and should be weighed against
and reconciled with these conflicting social interests."
Not only is the federal interest in protecting the Nation
against pornography attenuated, but the dangers of federal
censorship in this field are far greater than anything the States
may do. It has often been said that one of the great strengths of
our federal system is that we have, in the forty-eight States,
forty-eight experimental social laboratories.
"State statutory law reflects predominantly this capacity of a
legislature to introduce novel techniques of social control. The
federal system has the immense advantage of providing forty-eight
separate centers for such experimentation. [ Footnote 2/6 ]"
Different States will have different attitudes toward the same
work of literature. The same book which is freely read in one State
might be Page 354 U. S. 506 classed as obscene in another. [ Footnote 2/7 ] And it seems to me that no overwhelming
danger to our freedom to experiment and to gratify our tastes in
literature is likely to result from the suppression of a borderline
book in one of the States so long as there is no uniform nationwide
suppression of the book, and so long as other States are free to
experiment with the same or bolder books.
Quite a different situation is presented, however, where the
Federal Government imposes the ban. The danger is perhaps not great
if the people of one State, through their legislature, decide that
"Lady Chatterley's Lover" goes so far beyond the acceptable
standards of candor that it will be deemed offensive and
non-sellable, for the State next door is still free to make its own
choice. At least we do not have one uniform standard. But the
dangers to free thought and expression are truly great if the
Federal Government imposes a blanket ban over the Nation on such a
book. The prerogative of the States to differ on their ideas of
morality will be destroyed, the ability of States to experiment
will be stunted. The fact that the people of one State cannot read
some of the works of D. H.Lawrence seems to me, if not wise or
desirable, at least acceptable. But that no person in the United
States should be allowed to do so seems to me to be intolerable,
and violative of both the letter and spirit of the First
Amendment.
I judge this case, then, in view of what I think is the
attenuated federal interest in this field, in view of the very real
danger of a deadening uniformity which can result from nationwide
federal censorship, and in view of the Page 354 U. S. 507 fact that the constitutionality of this conviction must be
weighed against the First, and not the Fourteenth, Amendment. So
viewed, I do not think that this conviction can be upheld. The
petitioner was convicted under a statute which, under the judge's
charge, [ Footnote 2/8 ] makes it
criminal to sell books which "tend to stir sexual impulses and lead
to sexually impure thoughts." I cannot agree that any book which
tends to stir sexual impulses and lead to sexually impure thoughts
necessarily is "utterly without redeeming social importance." Not
only did this charge fail to measure up to the standards which I
understand the Court to approve, but, as far as I can see, much of
the great literature of the world could lead to conviction under
such a view of the statute. Moreover, in no event do I think that
the limited federal interest in this area can extend to mere
"thoughts." The Federal Government has no business, whether under
the postal or commerce power, to bar the sale of books because they
might lead to any kind of "thoughts." [ Footnote 2/9 ]
It is no answer to say, as the Court does, that obscenity is not
protected speech. The point is that this statute, as here
construed, defines obscenity so widely that it encompasses matters
which might very well be protected speech. I do not think that the
federal statute can be constitutionally construed to reach other
than what the Government has termed as "hard-core" pornography. Nor
do I think the statute can fairly be read as directed Page 354 U. S. 508 only at persons who are engaged in the business of
catering to the prurient minded, even though their wares fall short
of hard-core pornography. Such a statute would raise constitutional
questions of a different order. That being so, and since, in my
opinion, the material here involved cannot be said to be hard-core
pornography, I would reverse this case with instructions to dismiss
the indictment.
[ Footnote 2/1 ]
In Alberts v. California, the state definition of
"obscenity" is, of course, binding on us. The definition there used
derives from People v. Wepplo, 78 Cal. App.
2d Supp. 959 , 178 P.2d 853, the question being whether the
material has "a substantive tendency to deprave or corrupt its
readers by exciting lascivious thoughts or arousing lustful
desire."
In Roth v. United States, our grant of certiorari was
limited to the question of the constitutionality of the statute,
and did not encompass the correctness of the definition of
"obscenity" adopted by the trial judge as a matter of statutory
construction. We must therefore assume that the trial judge
correctly defined that term, and deal with the constitutionality of
the statute as construed and applied in this case.
The two definitions do not seem to me synonymous. Under the
federal definition, it is enough if the jury finds that the book as
a whole leads to certain thoughts. In California, the further
inference must be drawn that such thoughts will have a substantive
"tendency to deprave or corrupt" -- i.e., that the
thoughts induced by the material will affect character and action. See American Law Institute, Model Penal Code, Tentative
Draft No. 6, § 207.10(2), Comments, p. 10.
[ Footnote 2/2 ] Ibid. [ Footnote 2/3 ] See dissenting opinion of MR. JUSTICE BRENNAN in Kingsley Books, Inc. v. Brown, No. 107, ante, p. 354 U. S.
447 .
[ Footnote 2/4 ]
"The general principle of free speech, it seems to me, must be
taken to be included in the Fourteenth Amendment, in view of the
scope that has been given to the word 'liberty' as there used,
although perhaps it may be accepted with a somewhat larger latitude
of interpretation than is allowed to Congress by the sweeping
language that governs or ought to govern the laws of the United
States."
[ Footnote 2/5 ]
The hoary dogma of Ex parte Jackson, 96 U. S.
727 , and Public Clearing House v. Coyne, 194 U. S. 497 ,
that the use of the mails is a privilege on which the Government
may impose such conditions as it chooses, has long since
evaporated. See Brandeis, J., dissenting, in Milwaukee
Social Democratic Publishing Co. v. Burleson, 255 U.
S. 407 , 255 U. S.
430 -433; Holmes, J., dissenting, in Leach v.
Carlile, 258 U. S. 138 , 258 U. S. 140 ; Cates v. Haderline, 342 U.S. 804, reversing 189
F.2d 369; Door v. Donaldson, 90 U.S.App.D.C. 188, 195 F.2d
764.
[ Footnote 2/6 ]
Hart, The Relations Between State and Federal Law, 54 Col.L.Rev.
489, 493.
[ Footnote 2/7 ]
To give only a few examples: Edmund Wilson's "Memoirs of Hecate
County" was found obscene in New York, see Doubleday & Co.
v. New York, 335 U.S. 848; a bookseller indicted for selling
the same book was acquitted in California. "God's Little Acre" was
held to be obscene in Massachusetts, not obscene in New York and
Pennsylvania.
[ Footnote 2/8 ]
While the correctness of the judge's charge is not before us,
the question is necessarily subsumed in the broader question
involving the constitutionality of the statute as applied in this
case.
[ Footnote 2/9 ] See American Law Institute, Model Penal Code, Tentative
Draft No. 6, § 207.10, Comments, p. 20:
"As an independent goal of penal legislation, repression of
sexual thoughts and desires is hard to support. Thoughts and
desires not manifested in overt antisocial behavior are generally
regarded as the exclusive concern of the individual and his
spiritual advisors."
MR. JUSTICE DOUGLAS, with whom MR. JUSTICE BLACK concurs,
dissenting.
When we sustain these convictions, we make the legality of a
publication turn on the purity of thought which a book or tract
instills in the mind of the reader. I do not think we can approve
that standard and be faithful to the command of the First
Amendment, which, by its terms, is a restraint on Congress and
which by the Fourteenth is a restraint on the States.
In the Roth case, the trial judge charged the jury that
the statutory words "obscene, lewd and lascivious" describe "that
form of immorality which has relation to sexual impurity and has a
tendency to excite lustful thoughts." He stated that the term
"filthy" in the statute pertains "to that sort of treatment of
sexual matters in such a vulgar and indecent way, so that it tends
to arouse a feeling of disgust and revulsion." He went on to say
that the material "must be calculated to corrupt and debauch the
minds and morals" of "the average person in the community," not
those of any particular class.
"You judge the circulars, pictures and publications which have
been put in evidence by present-day standards of the community. You
may ask yourselves does it offend the common conscience of the
community by present-day standards."
The trial judge who, sitting without a jury, heard the Alberts case, and the appellate court that sustained
the Page 354 U. S. 509 judgment of conviction, took California's definition of
"obscenity" from People v. Wepplo, 78 Cal. App.
2d Supp. 959 , 961, 178 P.2d 853, 855. That case held that a
book is obscene "if it has a substantial tendency to deprave or
corrupt its readers by inciting lascivious thoughts or arousing
lustful desire."
By these standards, punishment is inflicted for thoughts
provoked, not for overt acts nor antisocial conduct. This test
cannot be squared with our decisions under the First Amendment.
Even the ill-starred Dennis case conceded that speech, to
be punishable, must have some relation to action which could be
penalized by government. Dennis v. United States, 341 U. S. 494 , 341 U. S.
502 -511. Cf. Chafee, The Blessings of Liberty
(1956), p. 69. This issue cannot be avoided by saying that
obscenity is not protected by the First Amendment. The question
remains, what is the constitutional test of obscenity?
The tests by which these convictions were obtained require only
the arousing of sexual thoughts. Yet the arousing of sexual
thoughts and desires happens every day in normal life in dozens of
ways. Nearly 30 years ago, a questionnaire sent to college and
normal school women graduates asked what things were most
stimulating sexually. Of 409 replies, 9 said "music"; 18 said
"pictures"; 29 said "dancing"; 40 said "drama"; 95 said "books",
and 218 said "man." Alpert, Judicial Censorship of Obscene
Literature, 52 Harv.L.Rev. 40, 73.
The test of obscenity the Court endorses today gives the censor
free range over a vast domain. To allow the State to step in and
punish mere speech or publication that the judge or the jury thinks
has an undesirable impact on thoughts, but that is not shown to be
a part of unlawful action, is drastically to curtail the First
Amendment. As recently stated by two of our outstanding authorities
on obscenity,
"The danger of influencing a change in the current moral
standards of the community, or of shocking Page 354 U. S. 510 or offending readers, or of stimulating sex thoughts or desires
apart from objective conduct, can never justify the losses to
society that result from interference with literary freedom."
Lockhart & McClure, Literature, The Law of Obscenity, and
the Constitution, 38 Minn.L.Rev. 295, 387.
If we were certain that impurity of sexual thoughts impelled to
action, we would be on less dangerous ground in punishing the
distributors of this sex literature. But it is by no means clear
that obscene literature, as so defined, is a significant factor in
influencing substantial deviations from the community
standards.
"There are a number of reasons for real and substantial doubts
as to the soundness of that hypothesis. (1) Scientific studies of
juvenile delinquency demonstrate that those who get into trouble,
and are the greatest concern of the advocates of censorship, are
far less inclined to read than those who do not become delinquent.
The delinquents are generally the adventurous type, who have little
use for reading and other non-active entertainment. Thus, even
assuming that reading sometimes has an adverse effect upon moral
conduct, the effect is not likely to be substantial, for those who
are susceptible seldom read. (2) Sheldon and Eleanor Glueck, who
are among the country's leading authorities on the treatment and
causes of juvenile delinquency, have recently published the results
of a ten-year study of its causes. They exhaustively studied
approximately 90 factors and influences that might lead to or
explain juvenile delinquency, but the Gluecks gave no consideration
to the type of reading material, if any, read by the delinquents.
This is, of course, consistent with their finding that delinquents
read very little. When those who know so much about the problem of
delinquency among youth -- the very Page 354 U. S. 511 group about whom the advocates of censorship are most concerned
-- conclude that what delinquents read has so little effect upon
their conduct that it is not worth investigating in an exhaustive
study of causes, there is good reason for serious doubt concerning
the basic hypothesis on which obscenity censorship is defended. (3)
The many other influences in society that stimulate sexual desire
are so much more frequent in their influence, and so much more
potent in their effect, that the influence of reading is likely, at
most, to be relatively insignificant in the composite of forces
that lead an individual into conduct deviating from the community
sex standards. The Kinsey studies show the minor degree to which
literature serves as a potent sexual stimulant. And the studies
demonstrating that sex knowledge seldom results from reading
indicates [ sic ] the relative unimportance of literature in
sex thoughts, as compared with other factors in society."
Lockhart & McClure, op. cit. supra, pp.
385-386.
The absence of dependable information on the effect of obscene
literature on human conduct should make us wary. It should put us
on the side of protecting society's interest in literature, except
and unless it can be said that the particular publication has an
impact on action that the government can control.
As noted, the trial judge in the Roth case charged the
jury in the alternative that the federal obscenity statute outlaws
literature dealing with sex which offends "the common conscience of
the community." That standard is, in my view, more inimical still
to freedom of expression.
The standard of what offends "the common conscience of the
community" conflicts, in my judgment, with the command of the First
Amendment that "Congress shall make no law . . . abridging the
freedom of speech, or Page 354 U. S. 512 of the press." Certainly that standard would not be an
acceptable one if religion, economics, politics or philosophy were
involved. How does it become a constitutional standard when
literature treating with sex is concerned?
Any test that turns on what is offensive to the community's
standards is too loose, too capricious, too destructive of freedom
of expression to be squared with the First Amendment. Under that
test, juries can censor, suppress, and punish what they don't like,
provided the matter relates to "sexual impurity" or has a tendency
"to excite lustful thoughts." This is community censorship in one
of its worst forms. It creates a regime where, in the battle
between the literati and the Philistines, the Philistines are
certain to win. If experience in this field teaches anything, it is
that "censorship of obscenity has almost always been both
irrational and indiscriminate." Lockhart & McClure, op.
cit. supra at 371. The test adopted here accentuates that
trend.
I assume there is nothing in the Constitution which forbids
Congress from using its power over the mails to proscribe conduct on the grounds of good morals. No one would
suggest that the First Amendment permits nudity in public places,
adultery, and other phases of sexual misconduct.
I can understand (and at times even sympathize) with programs of
civic groups and church groups to protect and defend the existing
moral standards of the community. I can understand the motives of
the Anthony Comstocks who would impose Victorian standards on the
community. When speech alone is involved, I do not think that
government, consistently with the First Amendment, can become the
sponsor of any of these movements. I do not think that government,
consistently with the First Amendment, can throw its weight behind
one school or another. Government should be Page 354 U. S. 513 concerned with anti=social conduct, not with utterances. Thus,
if the First Amendment guarantee of freedom of speech and press is
to mean anything in this field, it must allow protests even against
the moral code that the standard of the day sets for the community.
In other words, literature should not be suppressed merely because
it offends the moral code of the censor.
The legality of a publication in this country should never be
allowed to turn either on the purity of thought which it instills
in the mind of the reader or on the degree to which it offends the
community conscience. By either test, the role of the censor is
exalted, and society's values in literary freedom are
sacrificed.
The Court today suggests a third standard. It defines obscene
material as that "which deals with sex in a manner appealing to
prurient interest."* Like the standards applied by the trial judges
below, that standard does not require any nexus between the
literature which is prohibited and action which the legislature can
regulate or prohibit. Under the First Amendment, that standard is
no more valid than those which the courts below adopted.
I do not think that the problem can be resolved by the Court's
statement that "obscenity is not expression protected Page 354 U. S. 514 by the First Amendment." With the exception of Beauharnais
v. Illinois, 343 U. S. 250 ,
none of our cases has resolved problems of free speech and free
press by placing any form of expression beyond the pale of the
absolute prohibition of the First Amendment. Unlike the law of
libel, wrongfully relied on in Beauharnais, there is no
special historical evidence that literature dealing with sex was
intended to be treated in a special manner by those who drafted the
First Amendment. In fact, the first reported court decision in this
country involving obscene literature was in 1821. Lockhart &
McClure, op. cit. supra at 324, n. 200. I reject too the
implication that problems of freedom of speech and of the press are
to be resolved by weighing against the values of free expression
the judgment of the Court that a particular form of that expression
has "no redeeming social importance." The First Amendment, its
prohibition in terms absolute, was designed to preclude courts as
well as legislatures from weighing the values of speech against
silence. The First Amendment puts free speech in the preferred
position.
Freedom of expression can be suppressed if, and to the extent
that, it is so closely brigaded with illegal action as to be an
inseparable part of it. Giboney v. Empire Storage Co., 336 U. S. 490 , 336 U. S. 498 ; Labor Board v. Virginia Power Co., 314 U.
S. 469 , 314 U. S.
477 -478. As a people, we cannot afford to relax that
standard. For the test that suppresses a cheap tract today can
suppress a literary gem tomorrow. All it need do is to incite a
lascivious thought or arouse a lustful desire. The list of books
that judges or juries can place in that category is endless.
I would give the broad sweep of the First Amendment full
support. I have the same confidence in the ability of our people to
reject noxious literature as I have in their capacity to sort out
the true from the false in theology, economics, politics, or any
other field.
* The definition of obscenity which the Court adopts seems in
substance to be that adopted by those who drafted the A.L.I., Model
Penal Code. § 207.10(2) (Tentative Draft No. 6, 1957).
"Obscenity is defined in terms of material which appeals
predominantly to prurient interest in sexual matters and which goes
beyond customary freedom of expression in these matters. We reject
the prevailing tests of tendency to arouse lustful thoughts or
desires because it is unrealistically broad for a society that
plainly tolerates a great deal of erotic interest in literature,
advertising, and art, and because regulation of thought or desire,
unconnected with overt misbehavior, raises the most acute
constitutional, as well as practical, difficulties." Id. at 10. | In the case of Roth v. United States (1957), the Supreme Court upheld the constitutionality of federal and state laws prohibiting the distribution of obscene materials, defining obscenity as content that appeals to prurient interests and lacks redeeming social value. This decision set a precedent for regulating obscene expression without violating free speech protections. |
Free Speech | New York Times Co. v. Sullivan | https://supreme.justia.com/cases/federal/us/376/254/ | U.S. Supreme Court New York Times Co. v. Sullivan, 376
U.S. 254 (1964) New York Times Co. v.
Sullivan No. 39 Argued January 6,
1964 Decided March 9, 1964 376
U.S. 254 ast|>* 376
U.S. 254 CERTIORARI TO THE SUPREME COURT OF
ALABAMA Syllabus Respondent, an elected official in Montgomery, Alabama, brought
suit in a state court alleging that he had been libeled by an
advertisement in corporate petitioner's newspaper, the text of
which appeared over the names of the four individual petitioners
and many others. The advertisement included statements, some of
which were false, about police action allegedly directed against
students who participated in a civil rights demonstration and
against a leader of the civil rights movement; respondent claimed
the statements referred to him because his duties included
supervision of the police department. The trial judge instructed
the jury that such statements were "libelous per se, "
legal injury being implied without proof of actual damages, and
that, for the purpose of compensatory damages, malice was presumed,
so that such damages could be awarded against petitioners if the
statements were found to have been published by them and to have
related to respondent. As to punitive damages, the judge instructed
that mere negligence was not evidence of actual malice, and would
not justify an award of punitive damages; he refused to instruct
that actual intent to harm or recklessness had to be found before
punitive damages could be awarded, or that a verdict for respondent
should differentiate between compensatory and punitive damages. The
jury found for respondent, and the State Supreme Court
affirmed. Held: A State cannot, under the First and Fourteenth
Amendments, award damages to a public official for defamatory
falsehood relating to his official conduct unless he proves "actual
malice" -- that the statement was made with knowledge of its
falsity or with reckless disregard of whether it was true or false.
Pp. 376 U. S.
265 -292.
(a) Application by state courts of a rule of law, whether
statutory or not, to award a judgment in a civil action, is "state
action" under the Fourteenth Amendment. P. 376 U. S.
265 .
(b) Expression does not lose constitutional protection to which
it would otherwise be entitled because it appears in the form of a
paid advertisement. Pp. 376 U. S.
265 -266. Page 376 U. S. 255 (c) Factual error, content defamatory of official reputation, or
both, are insufficient to warrant an award of damages for false
statements unless "actual malice" -- knowledge that statements are
false or in reckless disregard of the truth -- is alleged and
proved. Pp. 376 U. S.
279 -283.
(d) State court judgment entered upon a general verdict which
does not differentiate between punitive damages, as to which, under
state law, actual malice must be proved, and general damages, as to
which it is "presumed," precludes any determination as to the basis
of the verdict, and requires reversal, where presumption of malice
is inconsistent with federal constitutional requirements. P. 376 U. S.
284 .
(e) The evidence was constitutionally insufficient to support
the judgment for respondent, since it failed to support a finding
that the statements were made with actual malice or that they
related to respondent. Pp. 376 U. S. 285 -292.
273 Ala. 656, 144
So. 2d 25 , reversed and remanded. Page 376 U. S. 256 MR. JUSTICE BRENNAN delivered the opinion of the Court.
We are required in this case to determine for the first time the
extent to which the constitutional protections for speech and press
limit a State's power to award damages in a libel action brought by
a public official against critics of his official conduct.
Respondent L. B. Sullivan is one of the three elected
Commissioners of the City of Montgomery, Alabama. He testified that
he was
"Commissioner of Public Affairs, and the duties are supervision
of the Police Department, Fire Department, Department of Cemetery
and Department of Scales."
He brought this civil libel action against the four individual
petitioners, who are Negroes and Alabama clergymen, and against
petitioner the New York Times Company, a New York corporation which
publishes the New York Times, a daily newspaper. A jury in the
Circuit Court of Montgomery County awarded him damages of $500,000,
the full amount claimed, against all the petitioners, and the
Supreme Court of Alabama affirmed. 273 Ala. 656, 144 So. 2d
25 .
Respondent's complaint alleged that he had been libeled by
statements in a full-page advertisement that was carried in the New
York Times on March 29, 1960. [ Footnote 1 ] Entitled "Heed Their Rising Voices," the
advertisement began by stating that,
"As the whole world knows by now, thousands of Southern Negro
students are engaged in widespread nonviolent demonstrations in
positive affirmation of the right to live in human dignity as
guaranteed by the U.S. Constitution and the Bill of Rights."
It went on to charge that,
"in their efforts to uphold these guarantees, they are being met
by an unprecedented wave of terror by those who would deny and
negate that document which the whole world looks upon as setting
the pattern for modern freedom. . . ."
Succeeding Page 376 U. S. 257 paragraphs purported to illustrate the "wave of terror" by
describing certain alleged events. The text concluded with an
appeal for funds for three purposes: support of the student
movement, "the struggle for the right to vote," and the legal
defense of Dr. Martin Luther King, Jr., leader of the movement,
against a perjury indictment then pending in Montgomery.
The text appeared over the names of 64 persons, many widely
known for their activities in public affairs, religion, trade
unions, and the performing arts. Below these names, and under a
line reading "We in the south who are struggling daily for dignity
and freedom warmly endorse this appeal," appeared the names of the
four individual petitioners and of 16 other persons, all but two of
whom were identified as clergymen in various Southern cities. The
advertisement was signed at the bottom of the page by the
"Committee to Defend Martin Luther King and the Struggle for
Freedom in the South," and the officers of the Committee were
listed.
Of the 10 paragraphs of text in the advertisement, the third and
a portion of the sixth were the basis of respondent's claim of
libel. They read as follows:
Third paragraph:
"In Montgomery, Alabama, after students sang 'My Country, 'Tis
of Thee' on the State Capitol steps, their leaders were expelled
from school, and truckloads of police armed with shotguns and
tear-gas ringed the Alabama State College Campus. When the entire
student body protested to state authorities by refusing to
reregister, their dining hall was padlocked in an attempt to starve
them into submission."
Sixth paragraph:
"Again and again, the Southern violators have answered Dr.
King's peaceful protests with intimidation and violence. They have
bombed his home, almost killing his wife and child. They have Page 376 U. S. 258 assaulted his person. They have arrested him seven times -- for
'speeding,' 'loitering' and similar 'offenses.' And now they have
charged him with 'perjury' -- a felony under which they
could imprison him for ten years. . . ."
Although neither of these statements mentions respondent by
name, he contended that the word "police" in the third paragraph
referred to him as the Montgomery Commissioner who supervised the
Police Department, so that he was being accused of "ringing" the
campus with police. He further claimed that the paragraph would be
read as imputing to the police, and hence to him, the padlocking of
the dining hall in order to starve the students into submission.
[ Footnote 2 ] As to the sixth
paragraph, he contended that, since arrests are ordinarily made by
the police, the statement "They have arrested [Dr. King] seven
times" would be read as referring to him; he further contended that
the "They" who did the arresting would be equated with the "They"
who committed the other described acts and with the "Southern
violators." Thus, he argued, the paragraph would be read as
accusing the Montgomery police, and hence him, of answering Dr.
King's protests with "intimidation and violence," bombing his home,
assaulting his person, and charging him with perjury. Respondent
and six other Montgomery residents testified that they read some or
all of the statements as referring to him in his capacity as
Commissioner.
It is uncontroverted that some of the statements contained in
the two paragraphs were not accurate descriptions of events which
occurred in Montgomery. Although Negro students staged a
demonstration on the State Capitol steps, they sang the National
Anthem and not "My Page 376 U. S. 259 Country, 'Tis of Thee." Although nine students were expelled by
the State Board of Education, this was not for leading the
demonstration at the Capitol, but for demanding service at a lunch
counter in the Montgomery County Courthouse on another day. Not the
entire student body, but most of it, had protested the expulsion,
not by refusing to register, but by boycotting classes on a single
day; virtually all the students did register for the ensuing
semester. The campus dining hall was not padlocked on any occasion,
and the only students who may have been barred from eating there
were the few who had neither signed a preregistration application
nor requested temporary meal tickets. Although the police were
deployed near the campus in large numbers on three occasions, they
did not at any time "ring" the campus, and they were not called to
the campus in connection with the demonstration on the State
Capitol steps, as the third paragraph implied. Dr. King had not
been arrested seven times, but only four, and although he claimed
to have been assaulted some years earlier in connection with his
arrest for loitering outside a courtroom, one of the officers who
made the arrest denied that there was such an assault.
On the premise that the charges in the sixth paragraph could be
read as referring to him, respondent was allowed to prove that he
had not participated in the events described. Although Dr. King's
home had, in fact, been bombed twice when his wife and child were
there, both of these occasions antedated respondent's tenure as
Commissioner, and the police were not only not implicated in the
bombings, but had made every effort to apprehend those who were.
Three of Dr. King's four arrests took place before respondent
became Commissioner. Although Dr. King had, in fact, been indicted
(he was subsequently acquitted) on two counts of perjury, each of
which carried a possible five-year sentence, respondent had nothing
to do with procuring the indictment. Page 376 U. S. 260 Respondent made no effort to prove that he suffered actual
pecuniary loss as a result of the alleged libel. [ Footnote 3 ] One of his witnesses, a former
employer, testified that, if he had believed the statements, he
doubted whether he "would want to be associated with anybody who
would be a party to such things that are stated in that ad," and
that he would not reemploy respondent if he believed "that he
allowed the Police Department to do the things that the paper say
he did." But neither this witness nor any of the others testified
that he had actually believed the statements in their supposed
reference to respondent. The cost of the advertisement was
approximately $4800, and it was published by the Times upon an
order from a New York advertising agency acting for the signatory
Committee. The agency submitted the advertisement with a letter
from A. Philip Randolph, Chairman of the Committee, certifying that
the persons whose names appeared on the advertisement had given
their permission. Mr. Randolph was known to the Times' Advertising
Acceptability Department as a responsible person, and, in accepting
the letter as sufficient proof of authorization, it followed its
established practice. There was testimony that the copy of the
advertisement which accompanied the letter listed only the 64 names
appearing under the text, and that the statement, "We in the south
. . . warmly endorse this appeal," and the list of names
thereunder, which included those of the individual petitioners,
were subsequently added when the first proof of the advertisement
was received. Each of the individual petitioners testified that he
had not authorized the use of his name, and that he had been
unaware of its use until receipt of respondent's demand for a
retraction. The manager of the Advertising Acceptability Page 376 U. S. 261 Department testified that he had approved the advertisement for
publication because he knew nothing to cause him to believe that
anything in it was false, and because it bore the endorsement of "a
number of people who are well known and whose reputation" he "had
no reason to question." Neither he nor anyone else at the Times
made an effort to confirm the accuracy of the advertisement, either
by checking it against recent Times news stories relating to some
of the described events or by any other means.
Alabama law denies a public officer recovery of punitive damages
in a libel action brought on account of a publication concerning
his official conduct unless he first makes a written demand for a
public retraction and the defendant fails or refuses to comply.
Alabama Code, Tit. 7, § 914. Respondent served such a demand upon
each of the petitioners. None of the individual petitioners
responded to the demand, primarily because each took the position
that he had not authorized the use of his name on the
advertisement, and therefore had not published the statements that
respondent alleged had libeled him. The Times did not publish a
retraction in response to the demand, but wrote respondent a letter
stating, among other things, that "we . . . are somewhat puzzled as
to how you think the statements in any way reflect on you," and
"you might, if you desire, let us know in what respect you claim
that the statements in the advertisement reflect on you."
Respondent filed this suit a few days later without answering the
letter. The Times did, however, subsequently publish a retraction
of the advertisement upon the demand of Governor John Patterson of
Alabama, who asserted that the publication charged him with
"grave misconduct and . . . improper actions and omissions as
Governor of Alabama and Ex-Officio Chairman of the State Board of
Education of Alabama."
When asked to explain why there had been a retraction for the
Governor but not for respondent, the Page 376 U. S. 262 Secretary of the Times testified:
"We did that because we didn't want anything that was published
by The Times to be a reflection on the State of Alabama, and the
Governor was, as far as we could see, the embodiment of the State
of Alabama and the proper representative of the State, and,
furthermore, we had by that time learned more of the actual facts
which the and purported to recite and, finally, the ad did refer to
the action of the State authorities and the Board of Education,
presumably of which the Governor is the ex-officio chairman. . .
."
On the other hand, he testified that he did not think that "any
of the language in there referred to Mr. Sullivan."
The trial judge submitted the case to the jury under
instructions that the statements in the advertisement were
"libelous per se, " and were not privileged, so that
petitioners might be held liable if the jury found that they had
published the advertisement and that the statements were made "of
and concerning" respondent. The jury was instructed that, because
the statements were libelous per se, "the law . . .
implies legal injury from the bare fact of publication itself,"
"falsity and malice are presumed," "general damages need not be
alleged or proved, but are presumed," and "punitive damages may be
awarded by the jury even though the amount of actual damages is
neither found nor shown." An award of punitive damages -- as
distinguished from "general" damages, which are compensatory in
nature -- apparently requires proof of actual malice under Alabama
law, and the judge charged that
"mere negligence or carelessness is not evidence of actual
malice or malice in fact, and does not justify an award of
exemplary or punitive damages."
He refused to charge, however, that the jury must be "convinced"
of malice, in the sense of "actual intent" to harm or "gross
negligence and recklessness," to make such an award, and he also
refused to require that a verdict for respondent differentiate
between compensatory and punitive damages. The judge rejected
petitioners' contention Page 376 U. S. 263 that his rulings abridged the freedoms of speech and of the
press that are guaranteed by the First and Fourteenth
Amendments.
In affirming the judgment, the Supreme Court of Alabama
sustained the trial judge's rulings and instructions in all
respects. 273 Ala. 656, 144 So. 2d
25 . It held that,
"where the words published tend to injure a person libeled by
them in his reputation, profession, trade or business, or charge
him with an indictable offense, or tend to bring the individual
into public contempt,"
they are "libelous per se "; that "the matter complained
of is, under the above doctrine, libelous per se, if it
was published of and concerning the plaintiff", and that it was
actionable without "proof of pecuniary injury . . . . such injury
being implied." Id. at 673, 676, 144 So. 2d at 37, 41. It
approved the trial court's ruling that the jury could find the
statements to have been made "of and concerning" respondent,
stating:
"We think it common knowledge that the average person knows that
municipal agents, such as police and firemen, and others, are under
the control and direction of the city governing body, and, more
particularly, under the direction and control of a single
commissioner. In measuring the performance or deficiencies of such
groups, praise or criticism is usually attached to the official in
complete control of the body." Id. at 674-675, 144 So. 2d at 39. In sustaining the
trial court's determination that the verdict was not excessive, the
court said that malice could be inferred from the Times'
"irresponsibility" in printing the advertisement while
"the Times, in its own files, had articles already published
which would have demonstrated the falsity of the allegations in the
advertisement;"
from the Times' failure to retract for respondent while
retracting for the Governor, whereas the falsity of some of the
allegations was then known to the Times and "the matter contained
in the advertisement was equally false as to both parties", and
from the testimony of the Times' Secretary that, Page 376 U. S. 264 apart from the statement that the dining hall was padlocked, he
thought the two paragraphs were "substantially correct." Id. at 686-687, 144 So. 2d at 50-51. The court reaffirmed
a statement in an earlier opinion that "There is no legal measure
of damages in cases of this character." Id. at 686, 144
So. 2d at 50. It rejected petitioners' constitutional contentions
with the brief statements that "The First Amendment of the U.S.
Constitution does not protect libelous publications," and "The
Fourteenth Amendment is directed against State action, and not
private action." Id. at 676, 144 So. 2d at 40.
Because of the importance of the constitutional issues involved,
we granted the separate petitions for certiorari of the individual
petitioners and of the Times. 371 U.S. 946. We reverse the
judgment. We hold that the rule of law applied by the Alabama
courts is constitutionally deficient for failure to provide the
safeguards for freedom of speech and of the press that are required
by the First and Fourteenth Amendments in a libel action brought by
a public official against critics of his official conduct.
[ Footnote 4 ] We Page 376 U. S. 265 further hold that, under the proper safeguards, the evidence
presented in this case is constitutionally insufficient to support
the judgment for respondent. I .
We may dispose at the outset of two grounds asserted to insulate
the judgment of the Alabama courts from constitutional scrutiny.
The first is the proposition relied on by the State Supreme Court
-- that "The Fourteenth Amendment is directed against State action,
and not private action." That proposition has no application to
this case. Although this is a civil lawsuit between private
parties, the Alabama courts have applied a state rule of law which
petitioners claim to impose invalid restrictions on their
constitutional freedoms of speech and press. It matters not that
that law has been applied in a civil action and that it is common
law only, though supplemented by statute. See, e.g., Alabama Code, Tit. 7, §§ 908-917. The test is not the form in which
state power has been applied but, whatever the form, whether such
power has, in fact, been exercised. See Ex parte Virginia, 100 U. S. 339 , 100 U. S.
346 -347; American Federation of Labor v. Swing. 312 U. S. 321 .
The second contention is that the constitutional guarantees of
freedom of speech and of the press are inapplicable here, at least
so far as the Times is concerned, because the allegedly libelous
statements were published as part of a paid, "commercial"
advertisement. The argument relies on Valentine v.
Chrestensen, 316 U. S. 52 , where
the Court held that a city ordinance forbidding street distribution
of commercial and business advertising matter did not abridge the
First Amendment freedoms, even as applied to a handbill having a
commercial message on one side but a protest against certain
official action, on the other. The reliance is wholly misplaced.
The Court in Chrestensen reaffirmed the constitutional
protection for "the freedom of communicating Page 376 U. S. 266 information and disseminating opinion"; its holding was based
upon the factual conclusions that the handbill was "purely
commercial advertising" and that the protest against official
action had been added only to evade the ordinance.
The publication here was not a "commercial" advertisement in the
sense in which the word was used in Chrestensen. It
communicated information, expressed opinion, recited grievances,
protested claimed abuses, and sought financial support on behalf of
a movement whose existence and objectives are matters of the
highest public interest and concern. See NAACP v. Button, 371 U. S. 415 , 371 U. S. 435 .
That the Times was paid for publishing the advertisement is as
immaterial in this connection as is the fact that newspapers and
books are sold. Smith v. California, 361 U.
S. 147 , 361 U. S. 150 ; cf. Bantam Books, Inc., v. Sullivan, 372 U. S.
58 , 372 U. S. 64 , n.
6. Any other conclusion would discourage newspapers from carrying
"editorial advertisements" of this type, and so might shut off an
important outlet for the promulgation of information and ideas by
persons who do not themselves have access to publishing facilities
-- who wish to exercise their freedom of speech even though they
are not members of the press. Cf. Lovell v. Griffin, 303 U. S. 444 , 303 U. S. 452 ; Schneider v. State, 308 U. S. 147 , 308 U. S. 164 .
The effect would be to shackle the First Amendment in its attempt
to secure "the widest possible dissemination of information from
diverse and antagonistic sources." Associated Press v. United
States, 326 U. S. 1 , 326 U. S. 20 . To
avoid placing such a handicap upon the freedoms of expression, we
hold that, if the allegedly libelous statements would otherwise be
constitutionally protected from the present judgment, they do not
forfeit that protection because they were published in the form of
a paid advertisement. [ Footnote
5 ] Page 376 U. S. 267 II Under Alabama law, as applied in this case, a publication is
"libelous per se " if the words "tend to injure a person .
. . in his reputation" or to "bring [him] into public contempt";
the trial court stated that the standard was met if the words are
such as to "injure him in his public office, or impute misconduct
to him in his office, or want of official integrity, or want of
fidelity to a public trust. . . ." The jury must find that the
words were published "of and concerning" the plaintiff, but, where
the plaintiff is a public official, his place in the governmental
hierarchy is sufficient evidence to support a finding that his
reputation has been affected by statements that reflect upon the
agency of which he is in charge. Once "libel per se " has
been established, the defendant has no defense as to stated facts
unless he can persuade the jury that they were true in all their
particulars. Alabama Ride Co. v. Vance, 235 Ala. 263, 178
So. 438 (1938); Johnson Publishing Co. v. Davis, 271 Ala.
474, 494 495, 124 So. 2d
441 , 457-458 (1960). His privilege of "fair comment" for
expressions of opinion depends on the truth of the facts upon which
the comment is based. Parsons v. Age-Herald Publishing
Co., 181 Ala. 439, 450, 61 So. 345, 350 (1913). Unless he can
discharge the burden of proving truth, general damages are
presumed, and may be awarded without proof of pecuniary injury. A
showing of actual malice is apparently a prerequisite to recovery
of punitive damages, and the defendant may, in any event, forestall
a punitive award by a retraction meeting the statutory
requirements. Good motives and belief in truth do not negate an
inference of malice, but are relevant only in mitigation of
punitive damages if the jury chooses to accord them weight. Johnson Publishing Co. v. Davis, supra, 271 Ala., at 495,
124 So. 2d at 458. Page 376 U. S. 268 The question before us is whether this rule of liability, as
applied to an action brought by a public official against critics
of his official conduct, abridges the freedom of speech and of the
press that is guaranteed by the First and Fourteenth
Amendments.
Respondent relies heavily, as did the Alabama courts, on
statements of this Court to the effect that the Constitution does
not protect libelous publications. [ Footnote 6 ] Those statements do not foreclose our inquiry
here. None of the cases sustained the use of libel laws to impose
sanctions upon expression critical of the official conduct of
public officials. The dictum in Pennekamp v. Florida, 328 U. S. 331 , 328 U. S.
348 -349, that "when the statements amount to defamation,
a judge has such remedy in damages for libel as do other public
servants," implied no view as to what remedy might constitutionally
be afforded to public officials. In Beauharnais v.
Illinois, 343 U. S. 250 , the
Court sustained an Illinois criminal libel statute as applied to a
publication held to be both defamatory of a racial group and
"liable to cause violence and disorder." But the Court was careful
to note that it "retains and exercises authority to nullify action
which encroaches on freedom of utterance under the guise of
punishing libel"; for "public men are, as it were, public
property," and "discussion cannot be denied, and the right, as well
as the duty, of criticism must not be stifled." Id. at 343 U. S.
263 -264, and n. 18. In the only previous case that did
present the question of constitutional limitations upon the power
to award damages for libel of a public official, the Court was
equally divided and the question was not decided. Schenectady
Union Pub. Co. v. Sweeney, 316 U.S. 642. Page 376 U. S. 269 In deciding the question now, we are compelled by neither
precedent nor policy to give any more weight to the epithet "libel"
than we have to other "mere labels" of state law. NAACP v.
Button, 371 U. S. 415 , 371 U. S. 429 .
Like insurrection, [ Footnote 7 ]
contempt, [ Footnote 8 ] advocacy
of unlawful acts, [ Footnote 9 ]
breach of the peace, [ Footnote
10 ] obscenity, [ Footnote
11 ] solicitation of legal business, [ Footnote 12 ] and the various other formulae for the
repression of expression that have been challenged in this Court,
libel can claim no talismanic immunity from constitutional
limitations. It must be measured by standards that satisfy the
First Amendment.
The general proposition that freedom of expression upon public
questions is secured by the First Amendment has long been settled
by our decisions. The constitutional safeguard, we have said, "was
fashioned to assure unfettered interchange of ideas for the
bringing about of political and social changes desired by the
people." Roth v. United States, 354 U.
S. 476 , 354 U. S.
484 .
"The maintenance of the opportunity for free political
discussion to the end that government may be responsive to the will
of the people and that changes may be obtained by lawful means, an
opportunity essential to the security of the Republic, is a
fundamental principle of our constitutional system." Stromberg v. California, 283 U.
S. 359 , 283 U. S. 369 .
"[I]t is a prized American privilege to speak one's mind, although
not always with perfect good taste, on all public institutions," Bridges v. California, 314 U. S. 252 , 314 U. S. 270 ,
and this opportunity is to be afforded for "vigorous advocacy" no
less than "abstract discussion." NAACP v. Button, 371 U. S. 415 , 371 U. S.
429 . Page 376 U. S. 270 The First Amendment, said Judge Learned Hand,
"presupposes that right conclusions are more likely to be
gathered out of a multitude of tongues than through any kind of
authoritative selection. To many, this is, and always will be,
folly, but we have staked upon it our all." United States v. Associated Press, 52 F. Supp.
362 , 372 (D.C.S.D.N.Y.1943). Mr. Justice Brandeis, in his
concurring opinion in Whitney v. California, 274 U.
S. 357 , 274 U. S.
375 -376, gave the principle its classic formulation:
"Those who won our independence believed . . . that public
discussion is a political duty, and that this should be a
fundamental principle of the American government. They recognized
the risks to which all human institutions are subject. But they
knew that order cannot be secured merely through fear of punishment
for its infraction; that it is hazardous to discourage thought,
hope and imagination; that fear breeds repression; that repression
breeds hate; that hate menaces stable government; that the path of
safety lies in the opportunity to discuss freely supposed
grievances and proposed remedies, and that the fitting remedy for
evil counsels is good ones. Believing in the power of reason as
applied through public discussion, they eschewed silence coerced by
law -- the argument of force in its worst form. Recognizing the
occasional tyrannies of governing majorities, they amended the
Constitution so that free speech and assembly should be
guaranteed."
Thus, we consider this case against the background of a profound
national commitment to the principle that debate on public issues
should be uninhibited, robust, and wide-open, and that it may well
include vehement, caustic, and sometimes unpleasantly sharp attacks
on government and public officials. See Terminiello v.
Chicago, 337 U. S. 1 , 337 U. S. 4 ; De Jonge v. Oregon, 299 U. S. 353 , Page 376 U. S. 271 299 U. S. 365 .
The present advertisement, as an expression of grievance and
protest on one of the major public issues of our time, would seem
clearly to qualify for the constitutional protection. The question
is whether it forfeits that protection by the falsity of some of
its factual statements and by its alleged defamation of
respondent.
Authoritative interpretations of the First Amendment guarantees
have consistently refused to recognize an exception for any test of
truth -- whether administered by judges, juries, or administrative
officials -- and especially one that puts the burden of proving
truth on the speaker. Cf. Speiser v. Randall, 357 U.
S. 513 , 357 U. S.
525 -526. The constitutional protection does not turn
upon "the truth, popularity, or social utility of the ideas and
beliefs which are offered." NAACP v. Button, 371 U.
S. 415 , 371 U. S. 445 .
As Madison said, "Some degree of abuse is inseparable from the
proper use of every thing, and in no instance is this more true
than in that of the press." 4 Elliot's Debates on the Federal
Constitution (1876), p. 571. In Cantwell v. Connecticut, 310 U. S. 296 , 310 U. S. 310 ,
the Court declared:
"In the realm of religious faith, and in that of political
belief, sharp differences arise. In both fields, the tenets of one
man may seem the rankest error to his neighbor. To persuade others
to his own point of view, the pleader, as we know, at times resorts
to exaggeration, to vilification of men who have been, or are,
prominent in church or state, and even to false statement. But the
people of this nation have ordained, in the light of history, that,
in spite of the probability of excesses and abuses, these liberties
are, in the long view, essential to enlightened opinion and right
conduct on the part of the citizens of a democracy."
That erroneous statement is inevitable in free debate, and that
it must be protected if the freedoms of expression Page 376 U. S. 272 are to have the "breathing space" that they "need . . . to
survive," NAACP v. Button, 371 U.
S. 415 , 371 U. S. 433 ,
was also recognized by the Court of Appeals for the District of
Columbia Circuit in Sweeney v. Patterson, 76 U.S.App.D.C.
23, 24, 128 F.2d 457, 458 (1942), cert. denied, 317 U.S.
678. Judge Edgerton spoke for a unanimous court which affirmed the
dismissal of a Congressman's libel suit based upon a newspaper
article charging him with anti-Semitism in opposing a judicial
appointment. He said:
"Cases which impose liability for erroneous reports of the
political conduct of officials reflect the obsolete doctrine that
the governed must not criticize their governors. . . . The interest
of the public here outweighs the interest of appellant or any other
individual. The protection of the public requires not merely
discussion, but information. Political conduct and views which some
respectable people approve, and others condemn, are constantly
imputed to Congressmen. Errors of fact, particularly in regard to a
man's mental states and processes, are inevitable. . . . Whatever
is added to the field of libel is taken from the field of free
debate. [ Footnote 13 ]"
Injury to official reputation affords no more warrant for
repressing speech that would otherwise be free than does factual
error. Where judicial officers are involved, this Court has held
that concern for the dignity and Page 376 U. S. 273 reputation of the courts does not justify the punishment as
criminal contempt of criticism of the judge or his decision. Bridges v. California, 314 U. S. 252 .
This is true even though the utterance contains "half-truths" and
"misinformation." Pennekamp v. Florida, 328 U.
S. 331 , 328 U. S. 342 , 328 U. S. 343 ,
n. 5, 328 U. S. 345 .
Such repression can be justified, if at all, only by a clear and
present danger of the obstruction of justice. See also Craig v.
Harney, 331 U. S. 367 ; Wood v. Georgia, 370 U. S. 375 . If
judges are to be treated as "men of fortitude, able to thrive in a
hardy climate," Craig v. Harney, supra, 331 U.S. at 331 U. S. 376 ,
surely the same must be true of other government officials, such as
elected city commissioners. [ Footnote 14 ] Criticism of their official conduct does not
lose its constitutional protection merely because it is effective
criticism, and hence diminishes their official reputations.
If neither factual error nor defamatory content suffices to
remove the constitutional shield from criticism of official
conduct, the combination of the two elements is no less inadequate.
This is the lesson to be drawn from the great controversy over the
Sedition Act of 1798, 1 Stat. 596, which first crystallized a
national awareness of the central meaning of the First Amendment. See Levy, Legacy of Suppression (1960), at 258 et
seq.; Smith, Freedom's Fetters (1956), at 426, 431, and passim. That statute made it a crime, punishable by a
$5,000 fine and five years in prison,
"if any person shall write, print, utter or publish . . . any
false, scandalous and malicious Page 376 U. S. 274 writing or writings against the government of the United States,
or either house of the Congress . . . or the President . . . with
intent to defame . . . or to bring them, or either of them, into
contempt or disrepute; or to excite against them, or either or any
of them, the hatred of the good people of the United States."
The Act allowed the defendant the defense of truth, and provided
that the jury were to be judges both of the law and the facts.
Despite these qualifications, the Act was vigorously condemned as
unconstitutional in an attack joined in by Jefferson and Madison.
In the famous Virginia Resolutions of 1798, the General Assembly of
Virginia resolved that it
"doth particularly protest against the palpable and alarming
infractions of the Constitution in the two late cases of the 'Alien
and Sedition Acts,' passed at the last session of Congress. . . .
[The Sedition Act] exercises . . . a power not delegated by the
Constitution, but, on the contrary, expressly and positively
forbidden by one of the amendments thereto -- a power which, more
than any other, ought to produce universal alarm because it is
leveled against the right of freely examining public characters and
measures, and of free communication among the people thereon, which
has ever been justly deemed the only effectual guardian of every
other right."
4 Elliot's Debates, supra, pp. 553-554. Madison
prepared the Report in support of the protest. His premise was that
the Constitution created a form of government under which "The
people, not the government, possess the absolute sovereignty." The
structure of the government dispersed power in reflection of the
people's distrust of concentrated power, and of power itself at all
levels. This form of government was "altogether different" from the
British form, under which the Crown was sovereign and the people
were subjects. "Is Page 376 U. S. 275 it not natural and necessary, under such different
circumstances," he asked, "that a different degree of freedom in
the use of the press should be contemplated?" Id., pp.
569-570. Earlier, in a debate in the House of Representatives,
Madison had said:
"If we advert to the nature of Republican Government, we shall
find that the censorial power is in the people over the Government,
and not in the Government over the people."
4 Annals of Congress, p. 934 (1794). Of the exercise of that
power by the press, his Report said:
"In every state, probably, in the Union, the press has exerted a
freedom in canvassing the merits and measures of public men, of
every description, which has not been confined to the strict limits
of the common law. On this footing, the freedom of the press has
stood; on this foundation it yet stands. . . ."
4 Elliot's Debates, supra, p. 570. The right of free
public discussion of the stewardship of public officials was thus,
in Madison's view, a fundamental principle of the American form of
government. [ Footnote
15 ] Page 376 U. S. 276 Although the Sedition Act was never tested in this Court,
[ Footnote 16 ] the attack
upon its validity has carried the day in the court of history.
Fines levied in its prosecution were repaid by Act of Congress on
the ground that it was unconstitutional. See, e.g., Act of
July 4, 1840, c. 45, 6 Stat. 802, accompanied by H.R.Rep. No. 86,
26th Cong., 1st Sess. (1840). Calhoun, reporting to the Senate on
February 4, 1836, assumed that its invalidity was a matter "which
no one now doubts." Report with Senate bill No. 122, 24th Cong.,
1st Sess., p. 3. Jefferson, as President, pardoned those who had
been convicted and sentenced under the Act and remitted their
fines, stating:
"I discharged every person under punishment or prosecution under
the sedition law because I considered, and now consider, that law
to be a nullity, as absolute and as palpable as if Congress had
ordered us to fall down and worship a golden image."
Letter to Mrs. Adams, July 22, 1804, 4 Jefferson's Works
(Washington ed.), pp. 555, 556. The invalidity of the Act has also
been assumed by Justices of this Court. See Holmes, J.,
dissenting and joined by Brandeis, J., in Abrams v. United
States, 250 U. S. 616 , 250 U. S. 630 ;
Jackson, J., dissenting in Beauharnais v. Illinois, 343 U. S. 250 , 343 U. S.
288 -289; Douglas, The Right of the People (1958), p. 47. See also Cooley, Constitutional Limitations (8th ed.,
Carrington, 1927), pp. 899-900; Chafee, Free Speech in the United
States (1942), pp. 27-28. These views reflect a broad consensus
that the Act, because of the restraint it imposed upon criticism of
government and public officials, was inconsistent with the First
Amendment.
There is no force in respondent's argument that the
constitutional limitations implicit in the history of the Sedition
Act apply only to Congress, and not to the States. It is true that
the First Amendment was originally addressed only to action by the
Federal Government, and Page 376 U. S. 277 that Jefferson, for one, while denying the power of Congress "to
controul the freedom of the press," recognized such a power in the
States. See the 1804 Letter to Abigail Adams quoted in Dennis v. United States, 341 U. S. 494 , 341 U. S. 522 ,
n. 4 (concurring opinion). But this distinction was eliminated with
the adoption of the Fourteenth Amendment and the application to the
States of the First Amendment's restrictions. See, e.g., Gitlow
v. New York, 268 U. S. 652 , 268 U. S. 666 ; Schneider v. State, 308 U. S. 147 , 308 U. S. 160 ; Bridges v. California, 314 U. S. 252 , 314 U. S. 268 ; Edwards v. South Carolina, 372 U.
S. 229 , 372 U. S.
235 .
What a State may not constitutionally bring about by means of a
criminal statute is likewise beyond the reach of its civil law of
libel. [ Footnote 17 ] The
fear of damage awards under a rule such as that invoked by the
Alabama courts here may be markedly more inhibiting than the fear
of prosecution under a criminal statute. See City of Chicago v.
Tribune Co., 307 Ill. 595, 607, 139 N.E. 86, 90 (1923).
Alabama, for example, has a criminal libel law which subjects to
prosecution "any person who speaks, writes, or prints of and
concerning another any accusation falsely and maliciously importing
the commission by such person of a felony, or any other indictable
offense involving moral turpitude," and which allows as punishment
upon conviction a fine not exceeding $500 and a prison sentence of
six months. Alabama Code, Tit. 14, § 350. Presumably, a person
charged with violation of this statute enjoys ordinary criminal law
safeguards such as the requirements of an indictment and of proof
beyond a reasonable doubt. These safeguards are not available to
the defendant in a civil action. The judgment awarded in this case
-- without the need for any proof of actual pecuniary loss -- was
one thousand times greater than the maximum fine provided by the
Alabama criminal statute, and one hundred times greater than that
provided by the Sedition Act. Page 376 U. S. 278 And since there is no double jeopardy limitation applicable to
civil lawsuits, this is not the only judgment that may be awarded
against petitioners for the same publication. [ Footnote 18 ] Whether or not a newspaper can
survive a succession of such judgments, the pall of fear and
timidity imposed upon those who would give voice to public
criticism is an atmosphere in which the First Amendment freedoms
cannot survive. Plainly the Alabama law of civil libel is
"a form of regulation that creates hazards to protected freedoms
markedly greater than those that attend reliance upon the criminal
law." Bantam Books, Inc. v. Sullivan, 372 U. S.
58 , 372 U. S.
70 .
The state rule of law is not saved by its allowance of the
defense of truth. A defense for erroneous statements honestly made
is no less essential here than was the requirement of proof of
guilty knowledge which, in Smith v. California, 361 U. S. 147 , we
held indispensable to a valid conviction of a bookseller for
possessing obscene writings for sale. We said:
"For, if the bookseller is criminally liable without knowledge
of the contents, . . . He will tend to restrict the books he sells
to those he has inspected, and thus the State will have imposed a
restriction upon the distribution of constitutionally protected, as
well as obscene, literature. . . . And the bookseller's burden
would become the public's burden, for, by restricting him, the
public's access to reading matter would be restricted. . . . [H]is
timidity in the face of his absolute criminal liability thus would
tend to restrict the public's access to forms of the printed word
which the State could not constitutionally Page 376 U. S. 279 suppress directly. The bookseller's self-censorship, compelled
by the State, would be a censorship affecting the whole public,
hardly less virulent for being privately administered. Through it,
the distribution of all books, both obscene and not obscene, would
be impeded."
( 361 U. S. 361 U.S.
147, 361 U. S.
153 -154.) A rule compelling the critic of official
conduct to guarantee the truth of all his factual assertions -- and
to do so on pain of libel judgments virtually unlimited in amount
-- leads to a comparable "self-censorship." Allowance of the
defense of truth, with the burden of proving it on the defendant,
does not mean that only false speech will be deterred. [ Footnote 19 ] Even courts accepting
this defense as an adequate safeguard have recognized the
difficulties of adducing legal proofs that the alleged libel was
true in all its factual particulars. See, e.g., Post Publishing
Co. v. Hallam, 59 F. 530, 540 (C.A. 6th Cir. 1893); see
also Noel, Defamation of Public Officers and Candidates, 49
Col.L.Rev. 875, 892 (1949). Under such a rule, would-be critics of
official conduct may be deterred from voicing their criticism, even
though it is believed to be true and even though it is, in fact,
true, because of doubt whether it can be proved in court or fear of
the expense of having to do so. They tend to make only statements
which "steer far wider of the unlawful zone." Speiser v.
Randall, supra, 357 U.S. at 357 U. S. 526 .
The rule thus dampens the vigor and limits the variety of public
debate. It is inconsistent with the First and Fourteenth
Amendments. The constitutional guarantees require, we think, a
federal rule that prohibits a public official from recovering
damages for a defamatory falsehood relating to his official conduct
unless he proves that the statement was made Page 376 U. S. 280 with "actual malice" -- that is, with knowledge that it was
false or with reckless disregard of whether it was false or not. An
oft-cited statement of a like rule, which has been adopted by a
number of state courts, [ Footnote 20 ] is found in the Kansas case of Coleman
v. MacLennan, 78 Kan. 711, 98 P. 281 (1908). The State
Attorney General, a candidate for reelection and a member of the
commission charged with the management and control of the state
school fund, sued a newspaper publisher for alleged libel in an
article purporting to state facts relating to his official conduct
in connection with a school-fund transaction. The defendant pleaded
privilege and the trial judge, over the plaintiff's objection,
instructed the jury that
"where an article is published and circulated among voters for
the sole purpose of giving what the defendant Page 376 U. S. 281 believes to be truthful information concerning a candidate for
public office and for the purpose of enabling such voters to cast
their ballot more intelligently, and the whole thing is done in
good faith and without malice, the article is privileged, although
the principal matters contained in the article may be untrue, in
fact, and derogatory to the character of the plaintiff, and in such
a case the burden is on the plaintiff to show actual malice in the
publication of the article."
In answer to a special question, the jury found that the
plaintiff had not proved actual malice, and a general verdict was
returned for the defendant. On appeal, the Supreme Court of Kansas,
in an opinion by Justice Burch, reasoned as follows (78 Kan., at
724, 98 P. at 286):
"It is of the utmost consequence that the people should discuss
the character and qualifications of candidates for their suffrages.
The importance to the state and to society of such discussions is
so vast, and the advantages derived are so great, that they more
than counterbalance the inconvenience of private persons whose
conduct may be involved, and occasional injury to the reputations
of individuals must yield to the public welfare, although at times
such injury may be great. The public benefit from publicity is so
great, and the chance of injury to private character so small, that
such discussion must be privileged."
The court thus sustained the trial court's instruction as a
correct statement of the law, saying:
"In such a case the occasion gives rise to a privilege,
qualified to this extent: any one claiming to be defamed by the
communication must show actual malice or go remediless. This
privilege extends to a great variety of subjects, and includes
matters of Page 376 U. S. 282 public concern, public men, and candidates for office."
78 Kan. at 723, 98 P. at 285.
Such a privilege for criticism of official conduct [ Footnote 21 ] is appropriately
analogous to the protection accorded a public official when he is
sued for libel by a private citizen. In Barr v. Matteo, 360 U. S. 564 , 360 U. S. 575 ,
this Court held the utterance of a federal official to be
absolutely privileged if made "within the outer perimeter" of his
duties. The States accord the same immunity to statements of their
highest officers, although some differentiate their lesser
officials and qualify the privilege they enjoy. [ Footnote 22 ] But all hold that all
officials are protected unless actual malice can be proved. The
reason for the official privilege is said to be that the threat of
damage suits would otherwise "inhibit the fearless, vigorous, and
effective administration of policies of government" and "dampen the
ardor of all but the most resolute, or the most irresponsible, in
the unflinching discharge of their duties." Barr v. Matteo,
supra, 360 U.S. at 360 U. S. 571 .
Analogous considerations support the privilege for the
citizen-critic of government. It is as much his duty to criticize
as it is the official's duty to administer. See Whitney v.
California, 274 U. S. 357 , 274 U. S. 375 (concurring opinion of Mr. Justice Brandeis), quoted supra, p. 376 U. S. 270 .
As Madison said, see supra p. 376 U. S. 275 ,
"the censorial power is in the people over the Government, and not
in the Government over the people." It would give public servants
an unjustified preference over the public they serve, if critics of
official conduct Page 376 U. S. 283 did not have a fair equivalent of the immunity granted to the
officials themselves.
We conclude that such a privilege is required by the First and
Fourteenth Amendments. III We hold today that the Constitution delimits a State's power to
award damages for libel in actions brought by public officials
against critics of their official conduct. Since this is such an
action, [ Footnote 23 ] the
rule requiring proof of actual malice is applicable. While Alabama
law apparently requires proof of actual malice for an award of
punitive damages, [ Footnote
24 ] where general damages are concerned malice is "presumed."
Such a presumption is inconsistent Page 376 U. S. 284 with the federal rule. "The power to create presumptions is not
a means of escape from constitutional restrictions," Bailey v.
Alabama, 219 U. S. 219 , 219 U. S. 239 ,
"the showing of malice required for the forfeiture of the privilege
is not presumed but is a matter for proof by the plaintiff. . . ." Lawrence v. Fox, 357 Mich. 134, 146, 97 N.W.2d
719 , 725 (1959). [ Footnote
25 ] Since the trial judge did not instruct the jury to
differentiate between general and punitive damages, it may be that
the verdict was wholly an award of one or the other. But it is
impossible to know, in view of the general verdict returned.
Because of this uncertainty, the judgment must be reversed and the
case remanded. Stromberg v. California, 283 U.
S. 359 , 283 U. S.
367 -368; Williams v. North Carolina, 317 U. S. 287 , 317 U. S.
291 -292; see Yates v. United States, 354 U. S. 298 , 354 U. S.
311 -312; Cramer v. United States, 325 U. S.
1 , 325 U. S. 36 , n.
45.
Since respondent may seek a new trial, we deem that
considerations of effective judicial administration require us to
review the evidence in the present record to determine Page 376 U. S. 285 whether it could constitutionally support a judgment for
respondent. This Court's duty is not limited to the elaboration of
constitutional principles; we must also in proper cases review the
evidence to make certain that those principles have been
constitutionally applied. This is such a case, particularly since
the question is one of alleged trespass across "the line between
speech unconditionally guaranteed and speech which may legitimately
be regulated." Speiser v. Randall, 357 U.
S. 513 , 357 U. S. 525 .
In cases where that line must be drawn, the rule is that we
"examine for ourselves the statements in issue and the
circumstances under which they were made to see . . . whether they
are of a character which the principles of the First Amendment, as
adopted by the Due Process Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment,
protect." Pennekamp v. Florida, 328 U. S. 331 , 328 U. S. 335 ; see also One, Inc., v. Olesen, 355 U.
S. 371 ; Sunshine Book Co. v. Summerfield, 355 U. S. 372 . We
must "make an independent examination of the whole record," Edwards v. South Carolina, 372 U.
S. 229 , 372 U. S. 235 ,
so as to assure ourselves that the judgment does not constitute a
forbidden intrusion on the field of free expression. [ Footnote 26 ]
Applying these standards, we consider that the proof presented
to show actual malice lacks the convincing Page 376 U. S. 286 clarity which the constitutional standard demands, and hence
that it would not constitutionally sustain the judgment for
respondent under the proper rule of law. The case of the individual
petitioners requires little discussion. Even assuming that they
could constitutionally be found to have authorized the use of their
names on the advertisement, there was no evidence whatever that
they were aware of any erroneous statements or were in any way
reckless in that regard. The judgment against them is thus without
constitutional support.
As to the Times, we similarly conclude that the facts do not
support a finding of actual malice. The statement by the Times'
Secretary that, apart from the padlocking allegation, he thought
the advertisement was "substantially correct," affords no
constitutional warrant for the Alabama Supreme Court's conclusion
that it was a
"cavalier ignoring of the falsity of the advertisement [from
which] the jury could not have but been impressed with the bad
faith of The Times, and its maliciousness inferable therefrom."
The statement does not indicate malice at the time of the
publication; even if the advertisement was not "substantially
correct" -- although respondent's own proofs tend to show that it
was -- that opinion was at least a reasonable one, and there was no
evidence to impeach the witness' good faith in holding it. The
Times' failure to retract upon respondent's demand, although it
later retracted upon the demand of Governor Patterson, is likewise
not adequate evidence of malice for constitutional purposes.
Whether or not a failure to retract may ever constitute such
evidence, there are two reasons why it does not here. First, the
letter written by the Times reflected a reasonable doubt on its
part as to whether the advertisement could reasonably be taken to
refer to respondent at all. Second, it was not a final refusal,
since it asked for an explanation on this point -- a request that
respondent chose to ignore. Nor does the retraction upon the demand
of the Governor supply the Page 376 U. S. 287 necessary proof. It may be doubted that a failure to retract,
which is not itself evidence of malice, can retroactively become
such by virtue of a retraction subsequently made to another party.
But, in any event, that did not happen here, since the explanation
given by the Times' Secretary for the distinction drawn between
respondent and the Governor was a reasonable one, the good faith of
which was not impeached.
Finally, there is evidence that the Times published the
advertisement without checking its accuracy against the news
stories in the Times' own files. The mere presence of the stories
in the files does not, of course, establish that the Times "knew"
the advertisement was false, since the state of mind required for
actual malice would have to be brought home to the persons in the
Times' organization having responsibility for the publication of
the advertisement. With respect to the failure of those persons to
make the check, the record shows that they relied upon their
knowledge of the good reputation of many of those whose names were
listed as sponsors of the advertisement, and upon the letter from
A. Philip Randolph, known to them as a responsible individual,
certifying that the use of the names was authorized. There was
testimony that the persons handling the advertisement saw nothing
in it that would render it unacceptable under the Times' policy of
rejecting advertisements containing "attacks of a personal
character"; [ Footnote 27 ]
their failure to reject it on this ground was not unreasonable. We
think Page 376 U. S. 288 the evidence against the Times supports, at most, a finding of
negligence in failing to discover the misstatements, and is
constitutionally insufficient to show the recklessness that is
required for a finding of actual malice. Cf. Charles Parker Co.
v. Silver City Crystal Co., 142 Conn. 605, 618, 116 A.2d 440,
446 (1955); Phoenix Newspapers, Inc., v. Choisser, 82
Ariz. 271, 277-278, 312 P.2d 150 ,
154-155 (1957).
We also think the evidence was constitutionally defective in
another respect: it was incapable of supporting the jury's finding
that the allegedly libelous statements were made "of and
concerning" respondent. Respondent relies on the words of the
advertisement and the testimony of six witnesses to establish a
connection between it and himself. Thus, in his brief to this
Court, he states:
"The reference to respondent as police commissioner is clear
from the ad. In addition, the jury heard the testimony of a
newspaper editor . . . ; a real estate and insurance man . . . ;
the sales manager of a men's clothing store . . . ; a food
equipment man . . . ; a service station operator . . . , and the
operator of a truck line for whom respondent had formerly worked. .
. . Each of these witnesses stated that he associated the
statements with respondent. . . ."
(Citations to record omitted.) There was no reference to
respondent in the advertisement, either by name or official
position. A number of the allegedly libelous statements -- the
charges that the dining hall was padlocked and that Dr. King's home
was bombed, his person assaulted, and a perjury prosecution
instituted against him -- did not even concern the police; despite
the ingenuity of the arguments which would attach this significance
to the word "They," it is plain that these statements could not
reasonably be read as accusing respondent of personal involvement
in the acts Page 376 U. S. 289 in question. The statements upon which respondent principally
relies as referring to him are the two allegations that did concern
the police or police functions: that "truckloads of police . . .
ringed the Alabama State College Campus" after the demonstration on
the State Capitol steps, and that Dr. King had been "arrested . . .
seven times." These statements were false only in that the police
had been "deployed near" the campus, but had not actually "ringed"
it, and had not gone there in connection with the State Capitol
demonstration, and in that Dr. King had been arrested only four
times. The ruling that these discrepancies between what was true
and what was asserted were sufficient to injure respondent's
reputation may itself raise constitutional problems, but we need
not consider them here. Although the statements may be taken as
referring to the police, they did not, on their face, make even an
oblique reference to respondent as an individual. Support for the
asserted reference must, therefore, be sought in the testimony of
respondent's witnesses. But none of them suggested any basis for
the belief that respondent himself was attacked in the
advertisement beyond the bare fact that he was in overall charge of
the Police Department and thus bore official responsibility for
police conduct; to the extent that some of the witnesses thought
respondent to have been charged with ordering or approving the
conduct or otherwise being personally involved in it, they based
this notion not on any statements in the advertisement, and not on
any evidence that he had, in fact, been so involved, but solely on
the unsupported assumption that, because of his official position,
he must have been. [ Footnote
28 ] This reliance on the bare Page 376 U. S. 290 fact of respondent's official position [ Footnote 29 ] was made explicit by the Supreme
Court of Alabama. That court, in holding that the trial court "did
not err in overruling the demurrer [of the Times] in the aspect
that the libelous Page 376 U. S. 291 matter was not of and concerning the [plaintiff,]" based its
ruling on the proposition that:
"We think it common knowledge that the average person knows that
municipal agents, such as police and firemen, and others, are under
the control and direction of the city governing body, and more
particularly under the direction and control of a single
commissioner. In measuring the performance or deficiencies of such
groups, praise or criticism is usually attached to the official in
complete control of the body."
273 Ala., at 674-675, 144 So. 2d at 39.
This proposition has disquieting implications for criticism of
governmental conduct. For good reason,
"no court of last resort in this country has ever held, or even
suggested, that prosecutions for libel on government have any place
in the American system of jurisprudence." City of Chicago v. Tribune Co., 307 Ill. 595, 601, 139
N.E. Page 376 U. S. 292 86, 88 (1923). The present proposition would sidestep this
obstacle by transmuting criticism of government, however impersonal
it may seem on its face, into personal criticism, and hence
potential libel, of the officials of whom the government is
composed. There is no legal alchemy by which a State may thus
create the cause of action that would otherwise be denied for a
publication which, as respondent himself said of the advertisement,
"reflects not only on me but on the other Commissioners and the
community." Raising as it does the possibility that a good faith
critic of government will be penalized for his criticism, the
proposition relied on by the Alabama courts strikes at the very
center of the constitutionally protected area of free expression.
[ Footnote 30 ] We hold that
such a proposition may not constitutionally be utilized to
establish that an otherwise impersonal attack on governmental
operations was a libel of an official responsible for those
operations. Since it was relied on exclusively here, and there was
no other evidence to connect the statements with respondent, the
evidence was constitutionally insufficient to support a finding
that the statements referred to respondent.
The judgment of the Supreme Court of Alabama is reversed, and
the case is remanded to that court for further proceedings not
inconsistent with this opinion. Reversed and remanded. Page 376 U. S. 293 * Together with No. 40, Abernathy et al. v. Sullivan, also on certiorari to the same court, argued January 7, 1964.
[ Footnote 1 ]
A copy of the advertisement is printed in the Appendix
[omitted].
[ Footnote 2 ]
Respondent did not consider the charge of expelling the students
to be applicable to him, since "that responsibility rests with the
State Department of Education."
[ Footnote 3 ]
Approximately 394 copies of the edition of the Times containing
the advertisement were circulated in Alabama. Of these, about 35
copies were distributed in Montgomery County. The total circulation
of the Times for that day was approximately 650,000 copies.
[ Footnote 4 ]
Since we sustain the contentions of all the petitioners under
the First Amendment's guarantees of freedom of speech and of the
press as applied to the States by the Fourteenth Amendment, we do
not decide the questions presented by the other claims of violation
of the Fourteenth Amendment. The individual petitioners contend
that the judgment against them offends the Due Process Clause
because there was no evidence to show that they had published or
authorized the publication of the alleged libel, and that the Due
Process and Equal Protection Clauses were violated by racial
segregation and racial bias in the courtroom. The Times contends
that the assumption of jurisdiction over its corporate person by
the Alabama courts overreaches the territorial limits of the Due
Process Clause. The latter claim is foreclosed from our review by
the ruling of the Alabama courts that the Times entered a general
appearance in the action, and thus waived its jurisdictional
objection; we cannot say that this ruling lacks "fair or
substantial support" in prior Alabama decisions. See Thompson
v. Wilson, 224 Ala. 299, 140 So. 439 (1932); compare NAACP
v. Alabama, 357 U. S. 449 , 357 U. S.
454 -458.
[ Footnote 5 ] See American Law Institute, Restatement of Torts, §
593, Comment b (1938).
[ Footnote 6 ] Konigsberg v. State Bar of California, 366 U. S.
36 , 366 U. S. 49 ,
and n. 10; Times Film Corp. v. City of Chicago, 365 U. S. 43 , 365 U. S. 48 ; Roth v. United States, 354 U. S. 476 , 354 U. S.
486 -487; Beauharnais v. Illinois, 343 U.
S. 250 , 343 U. S. 266 ; Pennekamp v. Florida, 328 U. S. 331 , 328 U. S.
348 -349; Chaplinsky v. New Hampshire, 315 U. S. 568 , 315 U. S. 572 ; Near v. Minnesota, 283 U. S. 697 , 283 U. S.
715 .
[ Footnote 7 ] Herndon v. Lowry, 301 U. S. 242 .
[ Footnote 8 ] Bridges v. California, 314 U.
S. 252 ; Pennekamp v. Florida, 328 U.
S. 331 .
[ Footnote 9 ] De Jonge v. Oregon, 299 U. S. 353 .
[ Footnote 10 ] Edwards v. South Carolina, 372 U.
S. 229 .
[ Footnote 11 ] Roth v. United States, 354 U.
S. 476 .
[ Footnote 12 ] NAACP v. Button, 371 U. S. 415 .
[ Footnote 13 ] See also Mill, On Liberty (Oxford: Blackwell, 1947), at
47:
". . . [T]o argue sophistically, to suppress facts or arguments,
to misstate the elements of the case, or misrepresent the opposite
opinion . . . , all this, even to the most aggravated degree, is so
continually done in perfect good faith by persons who are not
considered, and in many other respects may not deserve to be
considered, ignorant or incompetent that it is rarely possible, on
adequate grounds, conscientiously to stamp the misrepresentation as
morally culpable, and still less could law presume to interfere
with this kind of controversial misconduct."
[ Footnote 14 ]
The climate in which public officials operate, especially during
a political campaign, has been described by one commentator in the
following terms:
"Charges of gross incompetence, disregard of the public
interest, communist sympathies, and the like usually have filled
the air, and hints of bribery, embezzlement, and other criminal
conduct are not infrequent."
Noel, Defamation of Public Officers and Candidates, 49
Col.L.Rev. 875 (1949).
For a similar description written 60 years earlier, see Chase, Criticism of Public Officers and Candidates for Office, 23
Am.L.Rev. 346 (1889).
[ Footnote 15 ]
The Report on the Virginia Resolutions further stated:
"[I]t is manifestly impossible to punish the intent to bring
those who administer the government into disrepute or contempt,
without striking at the right of freely discussing public
characters and measures, . . . which, again, is equivalent to a
protection of those who administer the government, if they should
at any time deserve the contempt or hatred of the people, against
being exposed to it by free animadversions on their characters and
conduct. Nor can there be a doubt . . . that a government thus
entrenched in penal statutes against the just and natural effects
of a culpable administration will easily evade the responsibility
which is essential to a faithful discharge of its duty."
"Let it be recollected, lastly, that the right of electing the
members of the government constitutes more particularly the essence
of a free and responsible government. The value and efficacy of
this right depends on the knowledge of the comparative merits and
demerits of the candidates for public trust, and on the equal
freedom, consequently, of examining and discussing these merits and
demerits of the candidates respectively."
4 Elliot's Debates, supra, p. 575.
[ Footnote 16 ]
The Act expired, by its terms, in 1801.
[ Footnote 17 ] Cf. Farmers Union v. WDAY, 360 U.
S. 525 , 360 U. S.
535 .
[ Footnote 18 ]
The Times states that four other libel suits based on the
advertisement have been filed against it by others who have served
as Montgomery City Commissioners and by the Governor of Alabama;
that another $500,000 verdict has been awarded in the only one of
these cases that has yet gone to trial, and that the damages sought
in the other three total $2,000,000.
[ Footnote 19 ]
Even a false statement may be deemed to make a valuable
contribution to public debate, since it brings about "the clearer
perception and livelier impression of truth, produced by its
collision with error." Mill, On Liberty (Oxford: Blackwell, 1947),
at 15; see also Milton, Areopagitia, in Prose Works (Yale,
1959), Vol. II, at 561.
[ Footnote 20 ] E.g., Ponder v. Cobb, 257 N.C. 281, 299, 126
S.E.2d 67 , 80 (1962); Lawrence v. Fox, 357 Mich. 134,
146, 97 N.W.2d
719 , 725 (1959); Stice v. Beacon Newspaper Corp., 185
Kan. 61, 65-67, 340 P.2d 396 ,
400-401 (1959); Bailey v. Charleston Mail Assn., 126 W.Va.
292, 307, 27 S.E.2d 837, 844 (1943); Salinger v. Cowles, 195 Iowa 873, 889, 191 N.W. 167, 174 (1922); Snively v. Record
Publishing Co., 185 Cal. 565, 571-576, 198 P. 1 (1921); McLean v. Merriman, 42 S.D. 394, 175 N.W. 878 (1920).
Applying the same rule to candidates for public office, see,
e.g., Phoenix Newspapers v. Choisser, 82 Ariz. 271, 276-277, 312 P.2d 150 ,
154 (1957); Friedell v. Blakely Printing Co., 163 Minn.
226, 230, 203 N.W. 974, 975 (1925). And see Chagnon v.
Union-Leader Corp., 103 N.H. 426, 438, 174 A.2d 825, 833
(1961), cert. denied, 369 U.S. 830.
The consensus of scholarly opinion apparently favors the rule
that is here adopted. E.g., Harper and James, Torts, §
5.26, at 449-450 (1956); Noel, Defamation of Public Officers and
Candidates, 49 Col.L.Rev. 875, 891-895, 897, 903 (1949); Hallen,
Fair Comment, 8 Tex.L.Rev. 41, 61 (1929); Smith, Charges Against
Candidates, 18 Mich.L.Rev. 1, 115 (1919); Chase, Criticism of
Public Officers and Candidates for Office, 23 Am.L.Rev. 346,
367-371 (1889); Cooley, Constitutional Limitations (7th ed., Lane,
1903), at 604, 616-628. But see, e.g., American Law
Institute, Restatement of Torts, § 598, Comment a (1938)
(reversing the position taken in Tentative Draft 13, § 1041(2)
(1936)); Veeder, Freedom of Public Discussion, 23 Harv.L.Rev. 413,
419 (1910).
[ Footnote 21 ]
The privilege immunizing honest misstatements of fact is often
referred to as a "conditional" privilege, to distinguish it from
the "absolute" privilege recognized in judicial, legislative,
administrative and executive proceedings. See, e.g., Prosser, Torts (2d ed., 1955), § 95.
[ Footnote 22 ] See 1 Harper and James, Torts, § 5.23, at 429-430
(1956); Prosser, Torts (2d ed., 1955), at 612-613; American Law
Institute, Restatement of Torts (1938), § 591.
[ Footnote 23 ]
We have no occasion here to determine how far down into the
lower ranks of government employees the "public official"
designation would extend for purposes of this rule, or otherwise to
specify categories of persons who would or would not be included. Cf. Barr v. Matteo, 360 U. S. 564 , 360 U. S.
573 -575. Nor need we here determine the boundaries of
the "official conduct" concept. It is enough for the present case
that respondent's position as an elected city commissioner clearly
made him a public official, and that the allegations in the
advertisement concerned what was allegedly his official conduct as
Commissioner in charge of the Police Department. As to the
statements alleging the assaulting of Dr. King and the bombing of
his home, it is immaterial that they might not be considered to
involve respondent's official conduct if he himself had been
accused of perpetrating the assault and the bombing. Respondent
does not claim that the statements charged him personally with
these acts; his contention is that the advertisement connects him
with them only in his official capacity as the Commissioner
supervising the police, on the theory that the police might be
equated with the "They" who did the bombing and assaulting. Thus,
if these allegations can be read as referring to respondent at all,
they must be read as describing his performance of his official
duties.
[ Footnote 24 ] Johnson Publishing Co. v. Davis, 271 Ala. 474, 487, 124 So. 2d
441 , 450 (1960). Thus, the trial judge here instructed the jury
that
"mere negligence or carelessness is not evidence of actual
malice or malice, in fact, and does not justify an award of
exemplary or punitive damages in an action for libel."
The court refused, however, to give the following instruction
which had been requested by the Times:
"I charge you . . . that punitive damages, as the name
indicates, are designed to punish the defendant, the New York Times
Company, a corporation, and the other defendants in this case, . .
. and I further charge you that such punitive damages may be
awarded only in the event that you, the jury, are convinced by a
fair preponderance of the evidence that the defendant . . . was
motivated by personal ill will, that is actual intent to do the
plaintiff harm, or that the defendant . . . was guilty of gross
negligence and recklessness, and not of just ordinary negligence or
carelessness in publishing the matter complained of so as to
indicate a wanton disregard of plaintiff's rights."
The trial court's error in failing to require any finding of
actual malice for an award of general damages makes it unnecessary
for us to consider the sufficiency under the federal standard of
the instructions regarding actual malice that were given as to
punitive damages.
[ Footnote 25 ] Accord, Coleman v. MacLennan, supra, 78 Kan., at 741,
98 P. at 292; Gough v. Tribune-Journal Co., 75 Idaho 502,
510, 275 P.2d 663, 668 (1954).
[ Footnote 26 ]
The Seventh Amendment does not, as respondent contends, preclude
such an examination by this Court. That Amendment, providing that
"no fact tried by a jury shall be otherwise reexamined in any Court
of the United States than according to the rules of the common
law," is applicable to state cases coming here. Chicago, B.
& Q. R. Co. v. Chicago, 166 U. S. 226 , 166 U. S.
242 -243; cf. 76 U. S. Murray, 9 Wall. 274. But its ban on reexamination of facts
does not preclude us from determining whether governing rules of
federal law have been properly applied to the facts.
"[T]his Court will review the finding of facts by a State court
. . . where a conclusion of law as to a Federal right and a finding
of fact are so intermingled as to make it necessary, in order to
pass upon the Federal question, to analyze the facts." Fiske v. Kansas, 274 U. S. 380 , 274 U. S.
385 -386. See also Haynes v. Washington, 373 U. S. 503 , 373 U. S.
515 -516.
[ Footnote 27 ]
The Times has set forth in a booklet its "Advertising
Acceptability Standards." Listed among the classes of advertising
that the newspaper does not accept are advertisements that are
"fraudulent or deceptive," that are "ambiguous in wording and . . .
may mislead," and that contain "attacks of a personal character."
In replying to respondent's interrogatories before the trial, the
Secretary of the Times stated that,
"as the advertisement made no attacks of a personal character
upon any individual and otherwise met the advertising acceptability
standards promulgated,"
it had been approved for publication.
[ Footnote 28 ]
Respondent's own testimony was that,
"as Commissioner of Public Affairs, it is part of my duty to
supervise the Police Department, and I certainly feel like it [a
statement] is associated with me when it describes police
activities."
He thought that, "by virtue of being Police Commissioner and
Commissioner of Public Affairs," he was charged with "any activity
on the part of the Police Department." "When it describes police
action, certainly I feel it reflects on me as an individual." He
added that "[i]t is my feeling that it reflects not only on me, but
on the other Commissioners and the community."
Grover C. Hall testified that, to him, the third paragraph of
the advertisement called to mind "the City government -- the
Commissioners," and that,
"now that you ask it, I would naturally think a little more
about the police Commissioner, because his responsibility is
exclusively with the constabulary."
It was "the phrase about starvation" that led to the
association; "the other didn't hit me with any particular
force."
Arnold D. Blackwell testified that the third paragraph was
associated in his mind with "the Police Commissioner and the police
force. The people on the police force." If he had believed the
statement about the padlocking of the dining hall, he would have
thought
"that the people on our police force or the heads of our police
force were acting without their jurisdiction, and would not be
competent for the position."
"I would assume that the Commissioner had ordered the police
force to do that, and therefore it would be his
responsibility."
Harry W. Kaminsky associated the statement about "truckloads of
police" with respondent, "because he is the Police Commissioner."
He thought that the reference to arrests in the sixth paragraph
"implicates the Police Department, I think, or the authorities
that would do that -- arrest folks for speeding and loitering and
such as that."
Asked whether he would associate with respondent a newspaper
report that the police had "beat somebody up or assaulted them on
the streets of Montgomery," he replied:
"I still say he is the Police Commissioner and those men are
working directly under him, and therefore I would think that he
would have something to do with it."
In general, he said, "I look at Mr. Sullivan when I see the
Police Department."
H. M. Price, Sr., testified that he associated the first
sentence of the third paragraph with respondent because:
"I would just automatically consider that the Police
Commissioner in Montgomery would have to put his approval on those
kind of things as an individual."
William M. Parker, Jr., testified that he associated the
statements in the two paragraphs with "the Commissioners of the
City of Montgomery," and, since respondent "was the Police
Commissioner," he "thought of him first." He told the examining
counsel: "I think, if you were the Police Commissioner, I would
have thought it was speaking of you."
Horace W. White, respondent's former employer, testified that
the statement about "truckloads of police" made him think of
respondent "as being the head of the Police Department." Asked
whether he read the statement as charging respondent himself with
ringing the campus or having shotguns and tear gas, he replied:
"Well, I thought of his department being charged with it, yes, sir.
He is the head of the Police Department, as I understand it." He
further said that the reason he would have been unwilling to
reemploy respondent if he had believed the advertisement was "the
fact that he allowed the Police Department to do the things that
the paper say he did."
[ Footnote 29 ] Compare Ponder v. Cobb, 257 N.C. 281, 126 S.E.2d
67 (1962).
[ Footnote 30 ]
Insofar as the proposition means only that the statements about
police conduct libeled respondent by implicitly criticizing his
ability to run the Police Department, recovery is also precluded in
this case by the doctrine of fair comment. See American
Law Institute, Restatement of Torts (1938), § 607. Since the
Fourteenth Amendment requires recognition of the conditional
privilege for honest misstatements of fact, it follows that a
defense of fair comment must be afforded for honest expression of
opinion based upon privileged, as well as true, statements of fact.
Both defenses are, of course, defeasible if the public official
proves actual malice, as was not done here.
MR. JUSTICE BLACK, with whom MR. JUSTICE DOUGLAS joins,
concurring.
I concur in reversing this half-million-dollar judgment against
the New York Times Company and the four individual defendants. In
reversing, the Court holds that
"the Constitution delimits a State's power to award damages for
libel in actions brought by public officials against critics of
their official conduct." Ante, p. 376 U. S. 283 .
I base my vote to reverse on the belief that the First and
Fourteenth Amendments not merely "delimit" a State's power to award
damages to "public officials against critics of their official
conduct," but completely prohibit a State from exercising such a
power. The Court goes on to hold that a State can subject such
critics to damages if "actual malice" can be proved against them.
"Malice," even as defined by the Court, is an elusive, abstract
concept, hard to prove and hard to disprove. The requirement that
malice be proved provides, at best, an evanescent protection for
the right critically to discuss public affairs, and certainly does
not measure up to the sturdy safeguard embodied in the First
Amendment. Unlike the Court, therefore, I vote to reverse
exclusively on the ground that the Times and the individual
defendants had an absolute, unconditional constitutional right to
publish in the Times advertisement their criticisms of the
Montgomery agencies and officials. I do not base my vote to reverse
on any failure to prove that these individual defendants signed the
advertisement or that their criticism of the Police Department was
aimed at the plaintiff Sullivan, who was then the Montgomery City
Commissioner having supervision of the city's police; for present
purposes, I assume these things were proved. Nor is my reason for
reversal the size of the half-million-dollar judgment, large as it
is. If Alabama has constitutional power to use its civil libel law
to impose damages on the press for criticizing the way public
officials perform or fail Page 376 U. S. 294 to perform their duties, I know of no provision in the Federal
Constitution which either expressly or impliedly bars the State
from fixing the amount of damages.
The half-million-dollar verdict does give dramatic proof,
however, that state libel laws threaten the very existence of an
American press virile enough to publish unpopular views on public
affairs and bold enough to criticize the conduct of public
officials. The factual background of this case emphasizes the
imminence and enormity of that threat. One of the acute and highly
emotional issues in this country arises out of efforts of many
people, even including some public officials, to continue
state-commanded segregation of races in the public schools and
other public places despite our several holdings that such a state
practice is forbidden by the Fourteenth Amendment. Montgomery is
one of the localities in which widespread hostility to
desegregation has been manifested. This hostility has sometimes
extended itself to persons who favor desegregation, particularly to
so-called "outside agitators," a term which can be made to fit
papers like the Times, which is published in New York. The scarcity
of testimony to show that Commissioner Sullivan suffered any actual
damages at all suggests that these feelings of hostility had at
least as much to do with rendition of this half-million-dollar
verdict as did an appraisal of damages. Viewed realistically, this
record lends support to an inference that, instead of being
damaged, Commissioner Sullivan's political, social, and financial
prestige has likely been enhanced by the Times' publication.
Moreover, a second half-million-dollar libel verdict against the
Times based on the same advertisement has already been awarded to
another Commissioner. There, a jury again gave the full amount
claimed. There is no reason to believe that there are not more such
huge verdicts lurking just around the corner for the Times or any
other newspaper or broadcaster which Page 376 U. S. 295 might dare to criticize public officials. In fact, briefs before
us show that, in Alabama, there are now pending eleven libel suits
by local and state officials against the Times seeking $5,600,000,
and five such suits against the Columbia Broadcasting System
seeking $1,700,000. Moreover, this technique for harassing and
punishing a free press -- now that it has been shown to be possible
-- is by no means limited to cases with racial overtones; it can be
used in other fields where public feelings may make, local as well
as out-of-state, newspapers easy prey for libel verdict
seekers.
In my opinion, the Federal Constitution has dealt with this
deadly danger to the press in the only way possible without leaving
the free press open to destruction -- by granting the press an
absolute immunity for criticism of the way public officials do
their public duty. Compare Barr v. Matteo, 360 U.
S. 564 . Stopgap measures like those the Court adopts
are, in my judgment, not enough. This record certainly does not
indicate that any different verdict would have been rendered here
whatever the Court had charged the jury about "malice," "truth,"
"good motives," "justifiable ends," or any other legal formulas
which, in theory, would protect the press. Nor does the record
indicate that any of these legalistic words would have caused the
courts below to set aside or to reduce the half-million-dollar
verdict in any amount.
I agree with the Court that the Fourteenth Amendment made the
First applicable to the States. [ Footnote 2/1 ] This means to me that, since the adoption
of the Fourteenth Amendment, a State has no more power than the
Federal Government to use a civil libel law or any other law to
impose damages for merely discussing public affairs and criticizing
public officials. The power of the United Page 376 U. S. 296 States to do that is, in my judgment, precisely nil. Such was
the general view held when the First Amendment was adopted, and
ever since. [ Footnote 2/2 ] Congress
never has sought to challenge this viewpoint by passing any civil
libel law. It did pass the Sedition Act in 1798, [ Footnote 2/3 ] which made it a crime -- "seditious
libel" -- to criticize federal officials or the Federal Government.
As the Court's opinion correctly points out, however, ante, pp. 376 U. S.
273 -276, that Act came to an ignominious end and, by
common consent, has generally been treated as having been a wholly
unjustifiable and much to be regretted violation of the First
Amendment. Since the First Amendment is now made applicable to the
States by the Fourteenth, it no more permits the States to impose
damages for libel than it does the Federal Government.
We would, I think, more faithfully interpret the First Amendment
by holding that, at the very least, it leaves the people and the
press free to criticize officials and discuss public affairs with
impunity. This Nation of ours elects many of its important
officials; so do the States, the municipalities, the counties, and
even many precincts. These officials are responsible to the people
for the way they perform their duties. While our Court has held
that some kinds of speech and writings, such as "obscenity," Roth v. United States, 354 U. S. 476 , and
"fighting words," Chaplinsky v. New Hampshire, 315 U. S. 568 , are
not expression within the protection of the First Amendment,
[ Footnote 2/4 ] freedom to discuss
public affairs and public officials Page 376 U. S. 297 is unquestionably, as the Court today holds, the kind of speech
the First Amendment was primarily designed to keep within the area
of free discussion. To punish the exercise of this right to discuss
public affairs or to penalize it through libel judgments is to
abridge or shut off discussion of the very kind most needed. This
Nation, I suspect, can live in peace without libel suits based on
public discussions of public affairs and public officials. But I
doubt that a country can live in freedom where its people can be
made to suffer physically or financially for criticizing their
government, its actions, or its officials.
"For a representative democracy ceases to exist the moment that
the public functionaries are by any means absolved from their
responsibility to their constituents, and this happens whenever the
constituent can be restrained in any manner from speaking, writing,
or publishing his opinions upon any public measure, or upon the
conduct of those who may advise or execute it. [ Footnote 2/5 ]"
An unconditional right to say what one pleases about public
affairs is what I consider to be the minimum guarantee of the First
Amendment. [ Footnote 2/6 ]
I regret that the Court has stopped short of this holding
indispensable to preserve our free press from destruction.
[ Footnote 2/1 ] See cases collected in Speiser v. Randall, 357 U. S. 513 , 357 U. S. 530 (concurring opinion).
[ Footnote 2/2 ] See, e.g., 1 Tucker, Blackstone's Commentaries (1803),
297-299 (editor's appendix). St. George Tucker, a distinguished
Virginia jurist, took part in the Annapolis Convention of 1786, sat
on both state and federal courts, and was widely known for his
writings on judicial and constitutional subjects.
[ Footnote 2/3 ]
Act of July 14, 1798, 1 Stat. 596.
[ Footnote 2/4 ] But see Smith v. California, 361 U.
S. 147 , 361 U. S. 155 (concurring opinion); Roth v. United States, 354 U.
S. 476 , 354 U. S. 508 (dissenting opinion).
[ Footnote 2/5 ]
1 Tucker, Blackstone's Commentaries (1803), 297 (editor's
appendix); cf. Brant, Seditious Libel: Myth and Reality,
39 N.Y.U.L.Rev. 1.
[ Footnote 2/6 ] Cf. Meiklejohn, Free Speech and Its Relation to
Self-Government (1948).
MR. JUSTICE GOLDBERG, with whom MR. JUSTICE DOUGLAS joins,
concurring in the result.
The Court today announces a constitutional standard which
prohibits
"a public official from recovering damages for a defamatory
falsehood relating to his official conduct unless he proves that
the statement was made with Page 376 U. S. 298 'actual malice' -- that is, with knowledge that it was false or
with reckless disregard of whether it was false or not." Ante at 376 U. S.
279 -280. The Court thus rules that the Constitution
gives citizens and newspapers a "conditional privilege" immunizing
nonmalicious misstatements of fact regarding the official conduct
of a government officer. The impressive array of history [ Footnote 3/1 ] and precedent marshaled by
the Court, however, confirms my belief that the Constitution
affords greater protection than that provided by the Court's
standard to citizen and press in exercising the right of public
criticism.
In my view, the First and Fourteenth Amendments to the
Constitution afford to the citizen and to the press an absolute,
unconditional privilege to criticize official conduct despite the
harm which may flow from excesses and abuses. The prized American
right "to speak one's mind," cf. Bridges v California, 314 U. S. 252 , 314 U. S. 270 ,
about public officials and affairs needs "breathing space to
survive," NAACP v. Button, 371 U.
S. 415 , 371 U. S. 433 .
The right should not depend upon a probing by the jury of the
motivation [ Footnote 3/2 ] of the
citizen or press. The theory Page 376 U. S. 299 of our Constitution is that every citizen may speak his mind and
every newspaper express its view on matters of public concern, and
may not be barred from speaking or publishing because those in
control of government think that what is said or written is unwise,
unfair, false, or malicious. In a democratic society, one who
assumes to act for the citizens in an executive, legislative, or
judicial capacity must expect that his official acts will be
commented upon and criticized. Such criticism cannot, in my
opinion, be muzzled or deterred by the courts at the instance of
public officials under the label of libel.
It has been recognized that "prosecutions for libel on
government have [no] place in the American system of
jurisprudence." City of Chicago v. Tribune Co., 307 Ill.
595, 601, 139 N.E. 86, 88. I fully agree. Government, however, is
not an abstraction; it is made up of individuals -- of governors
responsible to the governed. In a democratic society, where men are
free by ballots to remove those in power, any statement critical of
governmental action is necessarily "of and concerning" the
governors, and any statement critical of the governors' official
conduct is necessarily "of and concerning" the government. If the
rule that libel on government has no place in our Constitution is
to have real meaning, then libel on the official conduct of the
governors likewise can have no place in our Constitution.
We must recognize that we are writing upon a clean slate.
[ Footnote 3/3 ] As the Court notes,
although there have been Page 376 U. S. 300 "statements of this Court to the effect that the Constitution
does not protect libelous publications . . . , [n]one of the cases
sustained the use of libel laws to impose sanctions upon expression
critical of the official conduct of public officials." Ante at 376 U. S. 268 .
We should be particularly careful, therefore, adequately to protect
the liberties which are embodied in the First and Fourteenth
Amendments. It may be urged that deliberately and maliciously false
statements have no conceivable value as free speech. That argument,
however, is not responsive to the real issue presented by this
case, which is whether that freedom of speech which all agree is
constitutionally protected can be effectively safeguarded by a rule
allowing the imposition of liability upon a jury's evaluation of
the speaker's state of mind. If individual citizens may be held
liable in damages for strong words, which a jury finds false and
maliciously motivated, there can be little doubt that public debate
and advocacy will be constrained. And if newspapers, publishing
advertisements dealing with public issues, thereby risk liability,
there can also be little doubt that the ability of minority groups
to secure publication of their views on public affairs and to seek
support for their causes will be greatly diminished. Cf.
Farmers Educational & Coop. Union v. WDAY, Inc., 360 U. S. 525 , 360 U. S. 530 .
The opinion of the Court conclusively demonstrates the chilling
effect of the Alabama libel laws on First Amendment freedoms Page 376 U. S. 301 in the area of race relations. The American Colonists were not
willing, nor should we be, to take the risk that "[m]en who injure
and oppress the people under their administration [and] provoke
them to cry out and complain" will also be empowered to "make that
very complaint the foundation for new oppressions and
prosecutions." The Trial of John Peter Zenger, 17 Howell's St. Tr.
675, 721-722 (1735) (argument of counsel to the jury). To impose
liability for critical, albeit erroneous or even malicious,
comments on official conduct would effectively resurrect "the
obsolete doctrine that the governed must not criticize their
governors." Cf. Sweeney v. Patterson, 76 U.S.App.D.C. 23,
24, 128 F.2d 457, 458.
Our national experience teaches that repressions breed hate, and
"that hate menaces stable government." Whitney v.
California, 274 U. S. 357 , 274 U. S. 375 (Brandeis, J., concurring). We should be ever mindful of the wise
counsel of Chief Justice Hughes:
"[I]mperative is the need to preserve inviolate the
constitutional rights of free speech, free press and free assembly
in order to maintain the opportunity for free political discussion,
to the end that government may be responsive to the will of the
people and that changes, if desired, may be obtained by peaceful
means. Therein lies the security of the Republic, the very
foundation of constitutional government." De Jonge v. Oregon, 299 U. S. 353 , 299 U. S.
365 .
This is not to say that the Constitution protects defamatory
statements directed against the private conduct of a public
official or private citizen. Freedom of press and of speech insures
that government will respond to the will of the people, and that
changes may be obtained by peaceful means. Purely private
defamation has little to do with the political ends of a
self-governing society. The imposition of liability for private
defamation does not Page 376 U. S. 302 abridge the freedom of public speech or any other freedom
protected by the First Amendment. [ Footnote 3/4 ] This, of course, cannot be said
"where public officials are concerned, or where public matters
are involved. . . . [O]ne main function of the First Amendment is
to ensure ample opportunity for the people to determine and resolve
public issues. Where public matters are involved, the doubts should
be resolved in favor of freedom of expression, rather than against
it."
Douglas, The Right of the People (1958), p. 41.
In many jurisdictions, legislators, judges and executive
officers are clothed with absolute immunity against liability for
defamatory words uttered in the discharge of their public duties. See, e.g., Barr v. Matteo, 360 U.
S. 564 ; City of Chicago v. Tribune Co., 307
Ill., at 610, 139 N.E. at 91. Judge Learned Hand ably summarized
the policies underlying the rule:
"It does indeed go without saying that an official who is, in
fact, guilty of using his powers to vent his spleen upon others, or
for any other personal motive not connected with the public good,
should not escape liability for the injuries he may so cause; and,
if it were possible in practice to confine such complaints to the
guilty, it would be monstrous to deny recovery. The justification
for doing so is that it is impossible to know whether the claim is
well founded until the Page 376 U. S. 303 case has been tried, and that to submit all officials, the
innocent as well as the guilty, to the burden of a trial and to the
inevitable danger of its outcome would dampen the ardor of all but
the most resolute, or the most irresponsible, in the unflinching
discharge of their duties. Again and again, the public interest
calls for action which may turn out to be founded on a mistake, in
the face of which an official may later find himself hard put to it
to satisfy a jury of his good faith. There must indeed be means of
punishing public officers who have been truant to their duties; but
that is quite another matter from exposing such as have been
honestly mistaken to suit by anyone who has suffered from their
errors. As is so often the case, the answer must be found in a
balance between the evils inevitable in either alternative. In this
instance, it has been thought in the end better to leave
unredressed the wrongs done by dishonest officers than to subject
those who try to do their duty to the constant dread of
retaliation. . . ."
"The decisions have, indeed, always imposed as a limitation upon
the immunity that the official's act must have been within the
scope of his powers, and it can be argued that official powers,
since they exist only for the public good, never cover occasions
where the public good is not their aim, and hence that to exercise
a power dishonestly is necessarily to overstep its bounds. A
moment's reflection shows, however, that that cannot be the meaning
of the limitation without defeating the whole doctrine. What is
meant by saying that the officer must be acting within his power
cannot be more than that the occasion must be such as would have
justified the act, if he had been using his power for any of the
purposes on whose account it was vested in him. . . ." Gregoire v. Biddle, 177 F.2d 579, 581. Page 376 U. S. 304 If the government official should be immune from libel actions,
so that his ardor to serve the public will not be dampened and
"fearless, vigorous, and effective administration of policies of
government" not be inhibited, Barr v. Matteo, supra, at 360 U. S. 571 ,
then the citizen and the press should likewise be immune from libel
actions for their criticism of official conduct. Their ardor as
citizens will thus not be dampened, and they will be free "to
applaud or to criticize the way public employees do their jobs,
from the least to the most important." [ Footnote 3/5 ] If liability can attach to political
criticism because it damages the reputation of a public official as
a public official, then no critical citizen can safely utter
anything but faint praise about the government or its officials.
The vigorous criticism by press and citizen of the conduct of the
government of the day by the officials of the day will soon yield
to silence if officials in control of government agencies, instead
of answering criticisms, can resort to friendly juries to forestall
criticism of their official conduct. [ Footnote 3/6 ]
The conclusion that the Constitution affords the citizen and the
press an absolute privilege for criticism of official conduct does
not leave the public official without defenses against
unsubstantiated opinions or deliberate misstatements.
"Under our system of government, counterargument and education
are the weapons available to expose these matters, not abridgment .
. . of free speech. . . ." Wood v. Georgia, 370 U. S. 375 , 370 U. S. 389 .
The public Page 376 U. S. 305 official certainly has equal, if not greater, access than most
private citizens to media of communication. In any event, despite
the possibility that some excesses and abuses may go unremedied, we
must recognize that
"the people of this nation have ordained, in the light of
history, that, in spite of the probability of excesses and abuses,
[certain] liberties are, in the long view, essential to enlightened
opinion and right conduct on the part of the citizens of a
democracy." Cantwell v. Connecticut, 310 U.
S. 296 , 310 U. S. 310 .
As Mr. Justice Brandeis correctly observed, "sunlight is the most
powerful of all disinfectants." [ Footnote 3/7 ]
For these reasons, I strongly believe that the Constitution
accords citizens and press an unconditional freedom to criticize
official conduct. It necessarily follows that, in a case such as
this, where all agree that the allegedly defamatory statements
related to official conduct, the judgments for libel cannot
constitutionally be sustained.
[ Footnote 3/1 ]
I fully agree with the Court that the attack upon the validity
of the Sedition Act of 1798, 1 Stat. 596, "has carried the day in
the court of history," ante at 376 U. S. 276 ,
and that the Act would today be declared unconstitutional. It
should be pointed out, however, that the Sedition Act proscribed
writings which were "false, scandalous and malicious. "
(Emphasis added.) For prosecutions under the Sedition Act charging
malice, see, e.g., Trial of Matthew Lyon (1798), in
Wharton, State Trials of the United States (1849), p. 333; Trial of
Thomas Cooper (1800), in id. at 659; Trial of Anthony
Haswell (1800), in id. at 684; Trial of James Thompson
Callender (1800), in id. at 688.
[ Footnote 3/2 ]
The requirement of proving actual malice or reckless disregard
may, in the mind of the jury, add little to the requirement of
proving falsity, a requirement which the Court recognizes not to be
an adequate safeguard. The thought suggested by Mr. Justice Jackson
in United States v. Ballard, 322 U. S.
78 , 322 U. S. 92 -93,
is relevant here:
"[A]s a matter of either practice or philosophy, I do not see
how we can separate an issue as to what is believed from
considerations as to what is believable. The most convincing proof
that one believes his statements is to show that they have been
true in his experience. Likewise, that one knowingly falsified is
best proved by showing that what he said happened never did
happen." See note 376
U.S. 254 fn3/4|>4, infra. [ Footnote 3/3 ]
It was not until Gitlow v. New York, 268 U.
S. 652 , decided in 1925, that it was intimated that the
freedom of speech guaranteed by the First Amendment was applicable
to the States by reason of the Fourteenth Amendment. Other
intimations followed. See Whitney v. California, 274 U. S. 357 ; Fiske v. Kansas, 274 U. S. 380 . In
1931, Chief Justice Hughes, speaking for the Court in Stromberg
v. California, 283 U. S. 359 , 283 U. S. 368 ,
declared:
"It has been determined that the conception of liberty under the
due process clause of the Fourteenth Amendment embraces the right
of free speech."
Thus, we deal with a constitutional principle enunciated less
than four decades ago, and consider for the first time the
application of that principle to issues arising in libel cases
brought by state officials.
[ Footnote 3/4 ]
In most cases, as in the case at bar, there will be little
difficulty in distinguishing defamatory speech relating to private
conduct from that relating to official conduct. I recognize, of
course, that there will be a gray area. The difficulties of
applying a public-private standard are, however, certainly of a
different genre from those attending the differentiation between a
malicious and nonmalicious state of mind. If the constitutional
standard is to be shaped by a concept of malice, the speaker takes
the risk not only that the jury will inaccurately determine his
state of mind, but also that the jury will fail properly to apply
the constitutional standard set by the elusive concept of malice. See 376
U.S. 254 fn3/2|>note 2, supra. [ Footnote 3/5 ]
MR. JUSTICE BLACK, concurring in Barr v. Matteo, 360 U. S. 564 , 360 U. S. 577 ,
observed that:
"The effective functioning of a free government like ours
depends largely on the force of an informed public opinion. This
calls for the widest possible understanding of the quality of
government service rendered by all elective or appointed public
officials or employees. Such an informed understanding depends, of
course, on the freedom people have to applaud or to criticize the
way public employees do their jobs, from the least to the most
important."
[ Footnote 3/6 ] See notes 2 4 supra. [ Footnote 3/7 ] See Freund, The Supreme Court of the United States
(1949), p. 61. | In New York Times Co. v. Sullivan, the US Supreme Court held that public officials cannot be awarded damages for defamatory statements relating to their official conduct unless they can prove "actual malice." This means that the statement was made with knowledge of its falsity or with reckless disregard for the truth. The Court found that the First and Fourteenth Amendments protect expression, even if it is in the form of a paid advertisement, and that factual error or defamatory content are not enough to warrant damages without proof of actual malice. This case set an important precedent for freedom of speech and press, especially in the context of criticizing public officials. |
Free Speech | Beauharnais v. Illinois | https://supreme.justia.com/cases/federal/us/343/250/ | U.S. Supreme Court Beauharnais v. Illinois, 343
U.S. 250 (1952) Beauharnais v.
Illinois No. 118 Argued November 28,
1951 Decided April 28,
1952 343
U.S. 250 CERTIORARI TO THE SUPREME COURT OF
ILLINOIS Syllabus Over his claim that the statute violated the liberty of speech
and of the press guaranteed as against the States by the Due
Process Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment and was void for
vagueness, petitioner was convicted in a state court for
distributing on the streets of Chicago anti-Negro leaflets in
violation of Ill.Rev.Stat., 1949, c. 38, § 471, which makes it a
crime to exhibit in any public place any publication which
"portrays depravity, criminality, unchastity, or lack of virtue of
a class of citizens, of any race, color, creed or religion" which
"exposes the citizens of any race, color, creed or religion to
contempt, derision, or obloquy." Held: 1. As construed and applied in this case, the statute does not
violate the liberty of speech and of the press guaranteed as
against the States by ihe Due Process Clause of the Fourteenth
Amendment. Pp. 343 U. S.
251 -264.
2. As construed and applied in this case, the statute is not
void for vagueness. Winters v. New York, 333 U.
S. 507 ; Stromberg v. California, 283 U.
S. 359 ; Thornhill v. Alabama, 310 U. S.
88 ; and Terminiello v. Chicago, 337 U. S.
1 , distinguished. P. 343 U. S.
264 .
3. Since petitioner did not, by appropriate steps in the trial
court, seek to justify his utterance as "fair comment" or as
privileged as a means for redressing grievances, those hypothetical
defenses cannot be considered by this Court. Pp. 343 U. S.
264 -265.
4. Since the Illinois Supreme Court construed this statute as a
form of criminal libel law, and truth of the utterance is not a
defense to a charge of criminal libel under Illinois law unless the
publication is also made "with good motives and for justifiable
ends," petitioner was not denied due process by the trial court's
rejection of a proffer of proof which did not satisfy this
requirement. Pp. 343 U. S.
253 -254, 343 U. S.
265 -266.
5. Since libelous utterances are not within the area of
constitutionally protected speech, it is not necessary for this
Court to consider the issues raised by the denial of petitioner's
request that the jury be instructed that, in order to convict, they
must find that the publication complained of was likely to produce
a "clear and present danger" of a substantial evil. Pp. 343 U. S. 253 , 343 U. S.
266 . 408 Ill. 512 , 97 N.E.2d
343 , affirmed. Page 343 U. S. 251 The Supreme Court of Illinois sustained petitioner's conviction
of a violation of Ill.Rev.Stat., 1949, c. 38 § 471, over his
objection that the statute was invalid under the Fourteenth
Amendment. 408 Ill. 512 , 97 N.E.2d
343 . This Court granted certiorari. 342 U.S. 809. Affirmed, p. 343 U. S.
267 .
MR. JUSTICE FRANKFURTER delivered the opinion of the Court.
The petitioner was convicted upon information in the Municipal
Court of Chicago of violating § 224a of Division 1 of the Illinois
Criminal Code, Ill.Rev.Stat.1949, c. 38, § 471. He was fined $200.
The section provides:
"It shall be unlawful for any person, firm or corporation to
manufacture, sell, or offer for sale, advertise or publish, present
or exhibit in any public place in this state any lithograph, moving
picture, play, drama or sketch, which publication or exhibition
portrays depravity, criminality, unchastity, or lack of virtue of a
class of citizens, of any race, color, creed or religion which said
publication or exhibition exposes the citizens of any race, color,
creed or religion to contempt, derision, or obloquy or which is
productive of breach of the peace or riots. . . ."
Beauharnais challenged the statute as violating the liberty of
speech and of the press guaranteed as against the States by the Due
Process Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment, and as too vague, under
the restrictions implicit in the Page 343 U. S. 252 same Clause, to support conviction for crime. The Illinois
courts rejected these contentions and sustained defendant's
conviction. 408 Ill. 512 , 97 N.E.2d
343 . We granted certiorari in view of the serious questions
raised concerning the limitations imposed by the Fourteenth
Amendment on the power of a State to punish utterances promoting
friction among racial and religious groups. 342 U.S. 809.
The information, cast generally in the terms of the statute,
charged that Beauharnais
"did unlawfully . . . exhibit in public places lithographs,
which publications portray depravity, criminality, unchastity or
lack of virtue of citizens of Negro race and color and which
exproses [ sic ] citizens of Illinois of the Negro race and
color to contempt, derision, or obloquy. . . ."
The lithograph complained of was a leaflet setting forth a
petition calling on the Mayor and City Council of Chicago "to halt
the further encroachment, harassment and invasion of white people,
their property, neighborhoods and persons, by the Negro. . . ."
Below was a call for "One million self-respecting white people in
Chicago to unite . . . ," with the statement added that,
"If persuasion and the need to prevent the white race from
becoming mongrelized by the negro will not unite us, then the
aggressions . . . rapes, robberies, knives, guns and marijuana of
the negro, surely will."
This, with more language, similar if not so violent, concluded
with an attached application for membership in the White Circle
League of America, Inc.
The testimony at the trial was substantially undisputed. From it
the jury could find that Beauharnais was president of the White
Circle League; that, at a meeting on January 6, 1950, he passed out
bundles of the lithographs in question, together with other
literature, to volunteers for distribution on downtown Chicago
street corners the following day; that he carefully organized that
distribution, giving detailed instructions for it; and that Page 343 U. S. 253 the leaflets were in fact distributed on January 7 in accordance
with his plan and instructions. The court, together with other
charges on burden of proof and the like, told the jury,
"if you find . . . that the defendant, Joseph Beauharnais, did .
. . manufacture, sell, or offer for sale, advertise or publish,
present or exhibit in any public place the lithograph . . . , then
you are to find the defendant guilty. . . ."
He refused to charge the jury, as requested by the defendant,
that, in order to convict, they must find
"that the article complained of was likely to produce a clear
and present danger of a serious substantive evil that rises for
above public inconvenience, annoyance or unrest."
Upon this evidence and these instructions, the jury brought in
the conviction here for review.
The statute before us is not a catchall enactment left at large
by the State court which applied it. Cf. Thornhill v.
Alabama, 310 U. S. 88 ; Cantwell v. Connecticut, 310 U. S. 296 , 310 U. S. 307 .
It is a law specifically directed at a defined evil, its language
drawing from history and practice in Illinois and in more than a
score of other jurisdictions a meaning confirmed by the Supreme
Court of that State in upholding this conviction. We do not,
therefore, parse the statute as grammarians, or treat it as an
abstract exercise in lexicography. We read it in the animating
context of well-defined usage, Nash v. United States, 229 U. S. 373 , and
State court construction which determines its meaning for us. Cox v. New Hampshire, 312 U. S. 569 ; Chaplinsky v. New Hampshire, 315 U.
S. 568 .
The Illinois Supreme Court tells us that § 224a "is a form of
criminal libel law." 408 Ill. 512 ,
517, 97 N.E.2d
343 , 346. The defendant, the trial court and the Supreme Court
consistently treated it as such. The defendant offered evidence
tending to prove the truth of parts of the utterance, and the
courts below considered and disposed of Page 343 U. S. 254 this offer in terms of ordinary criminal libel precedents.
[ Footnote 1 ] Section 224a does
not deal with the defense of truth, but by the Illinois
Constitution, Art. II, § 4, S.H.A., "in all trials for libel, both
civil and criminal, the truth, when published with good motives and
for justifiable ends, shall be a sufficient defense." See
also Ill.Rev.Stat., 1949, c. 38, § 404. Similarly, the action
of the trial court in deciding as a matter of law the libelous
character of the utterance, leaving to the jury only the question
of publication, follows the settled rule in prosecutions for libel
in Illinois and other States. [ Footnote 2 ] Moreover, the Supreme Court's characterization
of the words prohibited by the statute as those "liable to cause
violence and disorder" paraphrases the traditional justification
for punishing libels criminally, namely their "tendency to cause
breach of the peace." [ Footnote
3 ]
Libel of an individual was a common law crime, and thus criminal
in the colonies. Indeed, at common law, truth or good motives was
no defense. In the first decades after the adoption of the
Constitution, this was changed by judicial decision, statute or
constitution in most States, but nowhere was there any suggestion
that Page 343 U. S. 255 the crime of libel be abolished. [ Footnote 4 ] Today, every American jurisdiction -- the
forty-eight States, the District of Columbia, Alaska, Hawaii and
Puerto Rico -- punish libels directed at individuals. [ Footnote 5 ]
"There are certain well defined Page 343 U. S. 256 and narrowly limited classes of speech the prevention and
punishment of which has never been thought to raise any
Constitutional problem. These include the lewd and obscene, the
profane, the libelous, and the insulting or 'fighting' words --
those which, by their very utterance, inflict injury or tend to
incite an immediate breach of the peace. It has been well observed
that such utterances Page 343 U. S. 257 are no essential part of any exposition of ideas, and are of
such slight social value as a step to truth that any benefit that
may be derived from them is clearly outweighed by the social
interest in order and morality."
"Resort to epithets or personal abuse is not in any proper sense
communication of information or opinion safeguarded by the
Constitution, and its punishment as a criminal act would raise no
question under that instrument."
" Cantwell v. Connecticut, 310 U. S.
296 , 310 U. S. 309 -310."
Such were the views of a unanimous Court in Chaplinsky v.
New Hampshire, supra, at 315 U. S.
571 -572. [ Footnote
6 ]
No one will gainsay that it is libelous falsely to charge
another with being a rapist, robber, carrier of knives and Page 343 U. S. 258 guns, and user of marijuana. The precise question before us,
then, is whether the protection of "liberty" in the Due Process
Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment prevents a State from punishing
such libels -- as criminal libel has been defined, limited and
constitutionally recognized time out of mind -- directed at
designated collectivities and flagrantly disseminated. There is
even authority, however dubious, that such utterances were also
crimes at common law. [ Footnote
7 ] It is certainly clear that some American jurisdictions have
sanctioned their punishment under ordinary criminal libel statutes.
[ Footnote 8 ] We cannot say,
however, that the question is concluded by history and practice.
But if an utterance directed at an individual may be the object of
criminal sanctions, we cannot deny to a State power to punish the
same utterance directed at a defined group unless we can say that
this a willful and purposeless restriction unrelated to the peace
and wellbeing of the State.
Illinois did not have to look beyond her own borders or await
the tragic experience of the last three decades [ Footnote 9 ] Page 343 U. S. 259 to conclude that wilful purveyors of falsehood concerning racial
and religious groups promote strife and tend powerfully to obstruct
the manifold adjustments required for free, ordered life in a
metropolitan, polyglot community. From the murder of the
abolitionist Lovejoy in 1837 to the Cicero riots of 1951, Illinois
has been the scene of exacerbated tension between races, often
flaring into violence and destruction. [ Footnote 10 ] In many of these outbreaks, utterances of
the character here in question, so the Illinois legislature could
conclude, played a significant part. [ Footnote 11 ] The law was passed on June 29, 1917, at a
time when the State was struggling to assimilate vast numbers of
new inhabitants, as yet concentrated in discrete racial or national
or religious groups -- foreign-born brought to it by the crest of
the great wave of immigration, and Negroes attracted by jobs in war
plants and the allurements Page 343 U. S. 260 of northern claims. [ Footnote
12 ] Nine years erlier, in the very city where the legislature
sat, what is said to be the first northern race riot had cost the
lives of six people, left hundreds of Negroes homeless, and shocked
citizens into action far beyond the borders of the State. [ Footnote 13 ] Less than a month
before the bill was enacted, East St. Louis had seen a day's
rioting, prelude to an outbreak, only four days after the bill
became law, so bloody that it led to Congressional investigation.
[ Footnote 14 ] A series of
bombings had begun which was to culminate two years later in the
awful race riot which held Chicago in its grip for seven days
in Page 343 U. S. 261 the summer of 1919. [ Footnote
15 ] Nor has tension and violence between the groups defined in
the statute been limited in Illinois to clashes between whites and
Negroes.
In the face of this history and its frequent obligato of extreme
racial and religious propaganda, we would deny experience to say
that the Illinois Legislature was without reason in seeking ways to
curb false or malicious defamation of racial and religious groups,
made in public places and by means calculated to have a powerful
emotional impact on those to whom it was presented.
"There are limits to the exercise of these liberties [of speech
and of the press]. The danger in these times from the coercive
activities of those who in the delusion of racial or religious
conceit would incite violence and breaches of the peace in order to
deprive others of their equal right to the exercise of their
liberties, is emphasized by events familiar to all. These and other
transgressions of those limits the states appropriately may punish.
[ Footnote 16 ]"
This was the conclusion, again of a unanimous Court, in 1940. Cantwell v. Connecticut, supra, at 310 U. S.
310 .
It may be argued, and weightily, that this legislation will not
help matters; that tension and on occasion Page 343 U. S. 262 violence between racial and religious groups must be traced to
causes more deeply embedded in our society than the rantings of
modern Know-Nothings. [ Footnote
17 ] Only those lacking responsible humility will have a
confident solution for problems as intractable as the frictions
attributable to differences of race, color or religion. This being
so, it would be out of bounds for the judiciary to deny the
legislature a choice of policy, provided it is not unrelated to the
problem and not forbidden by some explicit limitation on the
State's power. That the legislative remedy might not in practice
mitigate the evil, or might itself raise new problems, would only
manifest once more the paradox of reform. It is the price to be
paid for the trial and error inherent in legislative efforts to
deal with obstinate social issues.
"The science of government is the most abstruse of all sciences
if, indeed, that can be called a science which has but few fixed
principles, and practically consists in little more than the
exercise of a sound discretion, applied to the exigencies of the
state as they arise. It is the science of experiment." Anderson v.
Dunn , 6 Wheat. 204, 19 U. S. 226 .
Certainly the Due Process Clause does not require the legislature
to be in the vanguard of science -- especially sciences as young as
human ecology and cultural anthropology. See Tigner v.
Texas, 310 U. S. 141 , 310 U. S.
148 .
Long ago, this Court recognized that the economic rights of an
individual may depend for the effectiveness of their enforcement on
rights in the group, even though not formally corporate, to which
he belongs. American Steel Foundries v. Tri-City Council, 257 U. S. 184 , 189
[argument of counsel -- omitted]. Such group protection on behalf
of the individual may, for all we know, be a need not confined to
the part that a trade union plays in effectuating rights abstractly
recognized as belonging Page 343 U. S. 263 to its members. It is not within our competence to confirm or
deny claims of social scientists as to the dependence of the
individual on the position of his racial or religious group in the
community. It would, however, be arrant dogmatism, quite outside
the scope of our authority in passing on the powers of a State, for
us to deny that the Illinois Legislature may warrantably believe
that a man's job and his educational opportunities and the dignity
accorded him may depend as much on the reputation of the racial and
religious group to which he willy-nilly belongs, as on his own
merits. This being so, we are precluded from saying that speech
concededly punishable when immediately directed at individuals
cannot be outlawed if directed at groups with whose position and
esteem in society the affiliated individual may be inextricably
involved.
We are warned that the choice open to the Illinois legislature
here may be abused, that the law may be discriminatorily enforced;
prohibiting libel of a creed or of a racial group, we are told, is
but a step from prohibiting libel of a political party. [ Footnote 18 ]
Every power may be abused, but the possibility of abuse is a
poor reason for denying Illinois the power to adopt measures
against criminal libels sanctioned by centuries of Anglo-American
law. "While this Court sits," it retains and exercises authority to
nullify action which encroaches on freedom of utterance Page 343 U. S. 264 under the guise of punishing libel. Of course discussion cannot
be denied and the right, as well as the duty, of criticism must not
be stifled.
The scope of the statute before us, as construed by the Illinois
court, disposes of the contention that the conduct prohibited by
the law is so ill-defined that judges and juries in applying the
statute and men in acting cannot draw from it adequate standards to
guide them. The clarifying construction and fixed usage which
govern the meaning of the enactment before us were not present, so
the Court found, in the New York law held invalid in Winters v.
New York, 333 U. S. 507 .
Nor, thus construed and limited, is the act so broad that the
general verdict of guilty on an indictment drawn in the statutory
language might have been predicated on constitutionally protected
conduct. On this score, the conviction here reviewed differs from
those upset in Stromberg v. California, 283 U.
S. 359 ; Thornhill v. Alabama, 310 U. S.
88 ; and Terminiello v. City of Chicago, 337 U. S. 1 . Even
the latter case did not hold that the unconstitutionality of a
statute is established because the speech prohibited by it raises a
ruckus.
It is suggested that, while it was clearly within the
constitutional power of Illinois to punish this utterance if the
proceeding were properly safeguarded, in this particular case,
Illinois denied the defendant rights which the Due Process Clause
commands. Specifically, it is argued that the defendant was not
permitted to raise at the trial defenses constitutionally
guaranteed in a criminal libel prosecution: (1) the defense of
truth; (2) justification of the utterance as "fair comment"; and
(3) its privilege as a means for redressing grievances.
Neither by proffer of evidence, requests for instructions, nor
motion before or after verdict did the defendant seek to justify
his utterance as "fair comment" or as privileged. Nor has the
defendant urged as a ground for reversing his Page 343 U. S. 265 conviction in this Court that his opportunity to make those
defenses was denied below. And so, whether a prosecution for libel
of a racial or religious group is unconstitutionally invalid where
the State did deny the defendant such opportunities is not before
us. [ Footnote 19 ] Certainly
the State may cast the burden of justifying what is patent
defamation upon the defamer. The benefits of hypothetical defenses,
never raised below or pressed upon us, are not to be invoked in the
abstract.
As to the defense of truth, Illinois, in common with many
States, requires a showing not only that the utterance state the
facts, but also that the publication be made "with good motives and
for justifable ends." Ill.Const. Art. II, § 4. [ Footnote 20 ] Both elements are necessary if
the defense is to prevail. What has been called "the common sense
of American criminal law," as formulated, with regard to necessary
safeguards in criminal libel prosecutions, in the New York
Constitutional of 1821, Art. VII, §8, has been adopted in terms by
Illinois. The teaching of a century and a half of criminal libel
prosecutions in this country Page 343 U. S. 266 would go by the board if we were to hold that Illinois was not
within her rights in making this combined requirement. Assuming
that defendant's offer of proof directed to a part of the defense
was adequate, [ Footnote 21 ]
it did not satisfy the entire requirement which Illinois could
exact. [ Footnote 22 ]
Libelous utterances not being within the area of
constitutionally protected speech, it is unnecessary, either for us
or for the State courts, to consider the issues behind the phrase
"clear and present danger." Certainly no one would contend that
obscene speech, for example, may be punished only upon a showing of
such circumstances. Libel, as we have seen, is in the same
class.
We find no warrant in the Constitution for denying to Illinois
the power to pass the law here under attack. [ Footnote 23 ] But Page 343 U. S. 267 it bears repeating -- although it should not -- that our finding
that the law is not constitutionally objectionable carries no
implication of approval of the wisdom of the legislation or of its
efficacy. These questions may raise doubts in our minds, as well as
in others. It is not for us, however, to make the legislative
judgment. We are not at liberty to erect those doubts into
fundamental law. Affirmed. [ Footnote 1 ] 408 Ill. 512 ,
518, 97 N.E.2d
343 , 346, 347. Illinois law requires that, for the defense to
prevail, the truth of all facts in the utterance must be shown
together with good motive for publication. People v.
Strauch, 247 Ill. 220, 93 N.E. 126; People v. Fuller, 238 Ill. 116, 87 N.E. 336; cf. Ogren v. Rockford Star Printing
Co., 288 Ill. 405, 123 N.E. 587.
[ Footnote 2 ] See, e.g., State v. Sterman, 199 Iowa 569, 202 N.W.
222; State v. Howard, 169 N.C. 312, 313, 84 S.E. 807, 808; cf. Ogren v. Rockford Star Printing Co., supra. [ Footnote 3 ] See, e.g., People v. Spielman, 318 Ill. 482, 489, 149
N.E. 466, 469; Odgers, Libel and Slander (6th ed.), 368; Kennerly v. Hennessy, 68 Fla. 138, 66 So. 729, 19 A.L.R.
1470. Some States hold, however, that injury to reputation, as in
civil libel, and not tendency to breach of the peace, is the
gravamen of the offense. See Tanenhaus, Group Libel, 35
Cornell L.Q. 261, 273 and n. 67.
[ Footnote 4 ]
For a brief account of this development see Warren,
History of the American Bar, 236-239. See also correspondence between Chief Justice Cushing of Massachusetts and
John Adams, published in 27 Mass.L.Q. 11-16 (Oct.1942). Jefferson
explained in a letter to Abigail Adams, dated September 11, 1804,
that to strike down the Alien and Sedition Act would not
"remove all restraint from the overwhelming torrent of slander
which is confounding all vice and virtue, all truth and falsehood
in the US. The power to do that is fully possessed by the several
state legislatures." See Dennis v. United States, 341 U.
S. 494 , 341 U. S. 522 ,
note 4. See Miller, Crisis in Freedom, 168-169, 231-232. See also provisions as to criminal libel in Edward
Livingston's famous draft System of Penal Law for Louisiana, 2
Works of Edward Livingston 100-108.
[ Footnote 5 ]
In eight States, the offense is punished as at common law,
without legislative enactment. State v. Roberts, 2 Marv.
(Del.), 450, 43 A. 252; Cole v. Commonwealth, 222 Ky. 350,
300 S.W. 907; Robinson v. State, 108 Md. 644, 71 A. 433; Commonwealth v. Canter, 269 Mass. 359, 168 N.E. 790; State v. Burnham, 9 N.H. 34; State v. Spear, 13
R.I. 324; State v. Sutton, 74 Vt. 12, 52 A. 116; State
v. Payne, 87 W.Va. 102, 104 S.E. 288. Twelve other
jurisdictions make "libel" a crime by statute, without defining the
term. Ala.Code 1940, Tit. 14, § 347; Alaska Comp.Laws Ann.1949, §
65-4-28; D.C.Code 1940, § 22-2301; Fla.Stat.Ann. § 836.01; Burns'
Ind.Stat.1933, § 10-3201; Miss.Code 1942, § 2268;
Neb.Rev.Stat.1943, §28-440; N.J.Stat.Ann. § 2:146-1;
N.C.Gen.Stat.1943, § 14-47; Page's Ohio Gen.Code 1939, § 13383;
Wis.Stat.1949, § 348.41; Wyo.Comp.Stat.1945, § 9-1601. Thus, twenty
American jurisdictions punish "libel" as defined by the
case-by-case common law development.
The remaining jurisdictions have sought to cast the common law
definition in a statutory form of words. Two formulas have been
popular. Eleven jurisdictions, Illinois among them, have accepted
with minor variations the following:
"A libel is a malicious defamation, expressed either by
printing, or by signs or pictures, or the like, tending to blacken
the memory of one who is dead, or to impeach the honesty,
integrity, virtue or reputation or publish the natural defects of
one who is alive, and thereby to expose him to public hatred,
contempt, ridicule, or financial injury."
Smith-Hurd Ill.Ann.Stat.1936, c. 38, § 402. Ariz.Code Ann.1939,
§43-3501; Ark.Stat.1947, § 41-2401; Deering's Cal.Penal Code 1949,
§ 248; Colo.Stat.Ann.1935, c. 48, § 199; Ga.Code Ann.1936, §
26-2101; Idaho Code 1947, § 18-4801; Mont.Rev.Codes 1947, §
94-2801; Nev.Comp.Laws 1929, § 10110; P.R.Codigo Penal 1937, § 243;
Utah Code Ann.1943, § 103-38-1; cf. Virgin Islands Code
1921, Tit. IV, c. 5, § 36.
The other version, again with minor variations, has found favor
in twelve jurisdictions.
"A libel is a malicious defamation of a person, made public by
any printing, writing, sign, picture, representation, or effigy,
tending to provoke him to wrath or expose him to public hatred,
contempt, or ridicule, or to deprive him of the benefits of public
confidence and social intercourse; or any malicious defamation,
made public as aforesaid, designed to blacken and vilify the memory
of one who is dead, and tending to scandalize or provoke his
surviving relatives or friends."
Iowa Code Ann. § 737.1; Kan.Gen.Stat.1949, § 21-2401; Dart's
La.Crim.Code 1935, Art. 740-47; Me.Rev.Stat.1944, c. 117, § 30;
Minn.Stat.1949, § 619.51; Mo.Rev.Stat.1949, § 559.410; McKinney's
N.Y.Laws, Penal Law, § 1340; N.D.Rev.Code 1943, § 12-2801;
Okl.Stat.Ann. Tit. 21, § 771; Purdon's Pa.Stat.Ann. Tit. 18, §
4412; Williams Tenn.Code 1934, §§ 11021, 11022; Remington's
Wash.Rev.Stat.1932, § 2424.
The remaining nine jurisdictions have definitions of criminal
libel which fall into no common pattern. See Conn.Gen.Stat.1949, § 8218; Hawaii Rev.Laws 1945, § 11450;
Mich.Comp.Laws 1948, § 750-370; N.M.Stat.1941, §§ 41-2701, 41-2708;
Ore.Comp.Laws 1940, § 23-437; S.C.Code 1942, § 1395; S.D.Code 1939,
§13. 3401; Vernon's Tex.Penal Stat. 1948, Arts. 1269, 1275; Va.Code
1950, § 18-133.
Our examination of the homogeneity of these statutory definitons
of criminal libel might well begin and end with the words "virtue"
and "ridicule." Of thirty-two jurisdictions, twelve outlaw
statements impeaching the "virtue" of another; eleven of these, and
fifteen more-twenty-six in all-prohibit utterances tending to bring
another into "public ridicule."
For the common law definition, applicable in the twenty
jurisdictions first noted above, see L. Hand, J., in Grant v. Reader's Digest Ass'n, 151 F.2d 733, 735, where
he speaks of defining libel "in accordance with the usual rubric,
as consisting of utterances which arouse "hatred, contempt, scorn,
obloquy or shame," and the like." Cf. Restatement, Torts,
§ 559, comment (b); Odgers, Libel and Slander (6th ed.), 16-17;
Newell, Slander and Libel (4th ed.), 1-2.
Even a cursory examination of these enactments and common law
pronouncements demonstrates that Illinois, in § 224a, was using a
form of words which invoked the familiar common law of libel to
define the prohibited utterances. The defendant and the Illinois
courts, as we have seen, understood this and acted upon it.
[ Footnote 6 ]
In all but five States, the constitutional guarantee of free
speech to every person is explicitly qualified by holding him
"responsible for the abuse of that right." See Pennekamp v.
Florida, 328 U. S. 331 , 328 U. S. 356 ,
note 5. See Jefferson in Kentucky Resolutions of 1798 and
1799, 4 Elliot's Debates 540-541, and in an undated draft prepared,
but not used, for his December 8, 1801, Message to Congress,
Library of Congress Jefferson Papers, Vol. 119, Leaf 20569. In Carlson v. California, 310 U. S. 106 , 310 U. S. 112 ,
we noted that the statute there invalidated made "no exceptions
with respect to the truthfulness and restraint of the information
conveyed. . . ."
[ Footnote 7 ] Compare reports of King v. Osborne in 2
Barn.K.B. 138, 166, 94 Eng.Rep. 406, 425; 2 Swans. 503, n
( c ), 36 Eng.Rep. 705, 717; W.Kel. 230, 25 Eng.Rep. 584
(1732). The present Attorney General of England asserted that this
case obviated the need of special group libel legislation for Great
Britain. See The (London) Times, March 26, 1952, p. 2,
col. 4. See also Odgers, Libel and Slander (6th ed.), 369;
Tanenhaus, Group Libel, 35 Cornell L.Q. 261, 267-269.
[ Footnote 8 ]
One of the leading cases arose in Illinois. People v.
Spielman, 318 Ill. 482, 149 N.E. 466 (1925), sustaining a
conviction for libel on the members of the American Legion. The
authorities are collected and discussed in Tanenhaus, Group Libel,
35 Cornell L.Q. 261, 269-276.
[ Footnote 9 ] See, e.g., Loewenstein, Legislative Control of
Political Extremism in European Democracies, 38 Col.L.Rev. 591 and
725; Riesman, Democracy and Defamation, 42 Col.L.Rev. 727, 1085 and
1282; Public Order Act, 1936, 1 Edw. VIII and 1 Geo. VI, c. 6, and
317 H.C.Deb. 1349-1473 (5th ser. 1936); 318 H.C.Deb. 49-193,
581-710, 1659-1785, 2781-2784 (5th ser. 1936); 103 H.L.Deb.
741-773, 961-972 (5th ser. 1936).
[ Footnote 10 ] See generally The Chicago Commission on Race Relations,
The Negro in Chicago, 1-78, and passim (University of
Chicago Press, 1922); Research Memorandum No. 5, First Annual
Rep.Ill. Inter-Racial Comm'n (1944).
[ Footnote 11 ]
The May 28, 1917, riot in East St. Louis, Illinois, was preceded
by a violently inflammatory speech to unemployed workmen by a
prominent lawyer of the town. Report of the Special Committee
Authorized by Congress to Investigate the East St. Louis Riots,
H.R. Doc. No. 1231, 65th Cong., 2d Sess. 11; Chicago Commission on
Race Relations, The Negro in Chicago, 75. And see id. at
118-122 for literature circulated by real estate associations and
other groups during the series of bombings leading up to the
Chicago riots of 1919. For the Commission's comments on the role of
propaganda in promoting race frictions, see id. at 589,
638-639.
[ Footnote 12 ]
Tables in Drake and Cayton, Black Metropolis, 8, show that,
between 1900 and 1920, the number of foreign-born in Chicago
increased by over 1/3, and the Negro population trebled. United
States census figures show the following population growth for the
State as a whole and selected counties:
bwm:
Illinois Cook County St. Clair County
(Chicago) (East St. Louis)
Total Negro Total Negro Total Negro
1900 4,821,550 85,078 1,838,735 31,838 86,685 3,987
1910 5,638,591 109,049 2,405,233 46,627 119,870 8,110
1920 6,485,280 182,274 3,053,017 115,238 136,520 10,136
1930 7,630,654 328,972 3,982,123 246,992 157,775 15,550
1940 7,897,241 387,446 4,063,342 249,157 166,899 21,567
1950 8,712,176 645,989 4,508,792 521,007 205,995 34,566
ewm:
For an account of these vast population movements entailing
great social maladjustments, see Drake and Cayton, Black
Metropolis, 8-18, 31-65; Chicago Commission on Race Relations, The
Negro in Chicago, 79-105; Carl Sandburg, The Chicago Race Riots,
9-30.
[ Footnote 13 ] See Walling, Race War in the North, 65 The Independent
529 (1908). This article apparently led to the founding of the
National Association for the Advancement of Colored People.
Ovington, How the National Association for the Advancement of
Colored People Began, 8 Crisis 184 (1914). See also Chicago Commission on Race Relations, The Negro in Chicago,
67-71.
[ Footnote 14 ]
Report of the Special Committee Authorized by Congress to
Investigate the East St. Louis Riots, H.R. Doc. No. 1231, 65th
Cong., 2d Sess. See also The Massacre of East St. Louis,
14 Crisis 219 (1917).
[ Footnote 15 ]
Chicago, Commission on Race Relations, The Negro in Chicago
122-133.
[ Footnote 16 ]
The utterances here in question "are not," as a detached student
of the problem has noted,
"the daily grist of vituperative political debate. Nor do they
represent the frothy imaginings of lunatics, or the 'idle' gossip
of a country town. Rather, they indicate the systematic avalanche
of falsehoods which are circulated concerning the various groups,
classes and races which make up the countries of the western
world."
Riesman, Democracy and Defamation; Control of Group Libel, 42
Col.L.Rev. at 727. Professor Riesman continues:
"Such purposeful attacks are nothing new, of course. . . . What
is new, however, is the existence of a mobile public opinion as the
controlling force in politics, and the systematic manipulation of
that opinion by the use of calculated falsehood and
vilification." Id. at 728.
[ Footnote 17 ] See, e.g., L. Hand, J., in a symposium in The Saturday
Review of Literature, Mar. 15, 1947, pp. 23-24; Report of the
Committee on the Law of Defamation, Cmd. 7536, 11 (1948).
[ Footnote 18 ]
It deserves emphasis that there is no such attempt in this
statute. The rubric "race, color, creed or religion" which
describes the type of group, libel of which is punishable, has
attained too fixed a meaning to permit political groups to be
brought within it. If a statute sought to outlaw libels of
political parties, quite different problems not now before us would
be raised. For one thing, the whole doctrine of fair comment as
indispensable to the democratic political process would come into
play. See People v. Fuller, supra, 238 Ill. at 125, 87
N.E. 336 at 338-339; Commonwealth v. Pratt, 208 Mass. 553,
559, 95 N.E. 105, 106. Political parties, like public men, are, as
it were, public property.
[ Footnote 19 ]
Indeed, such defenses are evidently protected by Illinois law. See Ill.Const. Art. II, § 17, guaranteeing the right of
the people to apply for redress of grievances. And see People
v. Fuller, 238 Ill. 116, 125, 87 N.E. 336, 338-339, on the
defense of "fair comment" in criminal libel prosecutions.
[ Footnote 20 ]
The present constitution, adopted in 1870, is Illinois' third.
The first two preserved the defense of truth in certain types of
libel prosecutions:
"In prosecutions for the publication of papers investigating the
official conduct of officers, or of men acting in a public
capacity, or where the matter published is proper for public
information, the truth thereof may be given in evidence. And in all
indictments for libels, the jury shall have the right of
determining both the law and the fact, under the direction of the
court, as in other cases."
Ill.Const.1818, Art. VIII, § 23; Ill.Const.1848, Art. XIII,
§
24. The combined requirement of truth and good motives and
justifiable ends, available as a defense in all libel suits, was
adopted with the Constitution of 1870.
[ Footnote 21 ]
Defendant offered to show (1) that crimes were more frequent in
districts heavily populated by Negroes than in those where whites
predominated; (2) three specific crimes allegedly committed by
Negroes, and (3) that property values declined when Negroes moved
into a neighborhood. It is doubtful whether such a showing is as
extensive as the defamatory allegations in the lithograph
circulated by the defendant.
[ Footnote 22 ]
The defense attorney put a few questions to the defendant on the
witness stand which tended toward elaborating his motives in
circulating the lithograph complained of. When objections to these
questions were sustained, no offer of proof was made, in contrast
to the rather elaborate offer which followed the refusal to permit
questioning tending to show the truth of the matter. Indeed, in
that offer itself, despite its considerable detail, no mention was
made of the necessary element of good motive or justifiable ends.
In any event, the question of exclusion of this testimony going to
motive was not raised by motion in the trial court, on appeal in
Illinois, or before us.
[ Footnote 23 ]
The law struck down by the New Jersey court in New Jersey v.
Klapprott, 127 N.J.L. 395, 22 A.2d 877, 880, was quite
different than the one before us, and was not limited, as is the
Illinois statute, by construction or usage. Indeed, in that case,
the court emphasized that "[i]t is not a case of libel," and
contrasted the history at common law of criminal prosecutions for
written and spoken defamation.
MR. JUSTICE BLACK, with whom MR. JUSTICE DOUGLAS concurs,
dissenting.
This case is here because Illinois inflicted criminal punishment
on Beauharnais for causing the distribution of leaflets in the city
of Chicago. The conviction rests on the leaflet's contents, not on
the time, manner or place of distribution. Beauharnais is head of
an organization that opposes amalgamation and favors segregation of
white and colored people. After discussion, an assembly of his
group decided to petition the mayor and council of Chicago to pass
laws for segregation. Volunteer members of the group agreed to
stand on street corners, solicit signers to petitions addressed to
the city authorities, and distribute leaflets giving information
about the group, its beliefs and its plans. In carrying out this
program, a solicitor handed out a leaflet which was the basis of
this prosecution. Since the Court opinion quotes only parts of the
leaflet, I am including all of it as an 343
U.S. 250 app|>appendix to this dissent. I That Beauharnais and his group were making a genuine effort to
petition their elected representatives is not disputed. Even as far
back as 1689, the Bill of Rights exacted of William & Mary
said: "It is the Right of the Subjects to petition the King, and
all Commitments and Page 343 U. S. 268 Prosecutions for such petitioning are illegal." [ Footnote 2/1 ] And, 178 years ago, the Declaration
of Rights of the Continental Congress proclaimed to the monarch of
that day that his American subjects had
"a right peaceably to assemble, consider of their grievances,
and petition the King; and that all prosecutions, prohibitory
proclamations, and commitments for the same, are illegal. [ Footnote 2/2 ]"
After independence was won, Americans stated as the first
unequivocal command of their Bill of Rights:
"Congress shall make no law . . . abridging the freedom of
speech, or of the press; or the right of the people peaceably to
assemble, and to petition the Government for a redress of
grievances."
Without distortion, this First Amendment could not possibly be
read so as to hold that Congress has power to punish Beauharnais
and others for petitioning Congress as they have here sought to
petition the Chicago authorities. See e.g., Bridges v.
California, 314 U. S. 252 , 314 U. S. 277 .
And we have held in a number of prior cases that the Fourteenth
Amendment makes the specific prohibitions of the First Amendment
equally applicable to the states. [ Footnote 2/3 ]
In view of these prior holdings, how does the Court justify its
holding today that states can punish people for exercising the
vital freedoms intended to be safeguarded from suppression by the
First Amendment? The prior holdings are not referred to; the Court
simply acts on the bland assumption that the First Amendment is
wholly irrelevant. It is not even accorded the respect of a passing
mention. This follows logically, I suppose, Page 343 U. S. 269 from recent constitutional doctrine which appears to measure
state laws solely by this Court's notions of civilized "canons of
decency," reasonableness, etc. See, e.g., Rochin v.
California, 342 U. S. 165 , 342 U. S. 169 .
Under this "reasonableness" test, state laws abridging First
Amendment freedoms are sustained if found to have a "rational
basis." But in Board of Education v. Barnette, 319 U. S. 624 , 319 U. S. 639 ,
we said:
"In weighing arguments of the parties, it is important to
distinguish between the due process clause of the Fourteenth
Amendment as an instrument for transmitting the principles of the
First Amendment and those cases in which it is applied for its own
sake. The test of legislation which collides with the Fourteenth
Amendment, because it also collides with the principles of the
First, is much more definite than the test when only the Fourteenth
is involved. Much of the vagueness of the due process clause
disappears when the specific prohibitions of the First become its
standard. The right of a State to regulate, for example, a public
utility may well include, so far as the due process test is
concerned, power to impose all of the restrictions which a
legislature may have a 'rational basis' for adopting. But freedoms
of speech and of press, of assembly, and of worship may not be
infringed on such slender grounds."
Today's case degrades First Amendment freedoms to the "rational
basis" level. It is now a certainty that the new "due process"
coverall offers far less protection to liberty than would adherence
to our former cases compelling states to abide by the unequivocal
First Amendment command that its defined freedoms shall not be
abridged.
The Court's holding here and the constitutional doctrine behind
it leave the rights of assembly, petition, Page 343 U. S. 270 speech and press almost completely at the mercy of state
legislative, executive, and judicial agencies. I say "almost"
because state curtailment of these freedoms may still be
invalidated if a majority of this Court conclude that a particular
infringement is "without reason," or is "a willful and purposeless
restriction unrelated to the peace and well being of the State."
But lest this encouragement should give too much hope as to how and
when this Court might protect these basic freedoms from state
invasion, we are cautioned that state legislatures must be left
free to "experiment" and to make "legislative" judgments. We are
told that mistakes may be made during the legislative process of
curbing public opinion. In such event, the Court fortunately does
not leave those mistakenly curbed, or any of us for that matter,
unadvised. Consolation can be sought, and must be found, in the
philosophical reflection that state legislative error in stifling
speech and press "is the price to be paid for the trial and error
inherent in legislative efforts to deal with obstinate social
issues." My own belief is that no legislature is charged with the
duty or vested with the power to decide what public issues
Americans can discuss. In a free country, that is the individual's
choice, not the state's. State experimentation in curbing freedom
of expression is startling and frightening doctrine in a country
dedicated to self-government by its people. I reject the holding
that either state or nation can punish people for having their say
in matters of public concern. II The Illinois statute upheld by the Court makes it a crime:
"1. for 'any person, firm or corporation,'"
"2. to 'manufacture, sell, or offer for sale, advertise or
publish, present or exhibit in any public place,' " Page 343 U. S. 271 "3. any 'lithograph [construed to include any printed matter],
moving picture, play, drama or sketch,'"
"4. which portrays 'depravity, criminality, unchastity, or lack
of virtue,'"
"5. of 'a class of citizens, of any race, color, creed or
religion,'"
"6. and exposes such a class to 'contempt, derision, or
obloquy,'"
"7. or 'is productive of breach of the peace or riots.'"
This statute imposes state censorship over the theater, moving
pictures, radio, television, leaflets, magazines, books and
newspapers. No doubt the statute is broad enough to make criminal
the "publication, sale, presentation or exhibition" of many of the
world's great classics, both secular and religious.
The Court condones this expansive state censorship by
painstakingly analogizing it to the law of criminal libel. As a
result of this refined analysis, the Illinois statute emerges
labeled a "group libel law." This label may make the Court's
holding more palatable for those who sustain it, but the
sugar-coating does not make the censorship less deadly. However
tagged, the Illinois law is not that criminal libel which has been
"defined, limited and constitutionally recognized time out of
mind." [ Footnote 2/4 ] For, as Page 343 U. S. 272 "constitutionally recognized," that crime has provided for
punishment of false, malicious, scurrilous charges against
individuals, not against huge groups. This limited scope of the law
of criminal libel is of no small importance. It has confined state
punishment of speech and expression to the narrowest of areas
involving nothing more than purely private feuds. Every expansion
of the law of criminal libel so as to punish discussions of matters
of public concern means a corresponding invasion of the area
dedicated to free expression by the First Amendment.
Prior efforts to expand the scope of criminal libel beyond its
traditional boundaries have not usually met with widespread popular
acclaim. "Seditious libel" was such an expansion, and it did have
its day, particularly in the English Court of Star Chamber. But the
First Amendment repudiated seditious libel for this country. And
one need only glance through the parliamentary discussion of Fox's
Libel Law, passed in England in 1792, to sense the bad odor of
criminal libel in that country even when confined to charges
against individuals only.
The Court's reliance on Chaplinsky v. New Hampshire, 315 U. S. 568 , is
also misplaced. New Hampshire had a state law making it an offense
to direct insulting words at an individual on a public street.
Chaplinsky had violated that law by calling a man vile names
"face-to-face." We pointed out in that context that the use of such
"fighting" words was not an essential part of exposition of ideas.
Whether the words used in their context here are "fighting" words
in the same sense is doubtful, but, whether so or Page 343 U. S. 273 not, they are not addressed to or about individuals. Moreover,
the leaflet used here was also the means adopted by an assembled
group to enlist interest in their efforts to have legislation
enacted. And the fighting words were but a part of arguments on
questions of wide public interest and importance. Freedom of
petition, assembly, speech and press could be greatly abridged by a
practice of meticulously scrutinizing every editorial, speech,
sermon or other printed matter to extract two or three naughty
words on which to hang charges of "group libel." The Chaplinsky case makes no such broad inroads on First
Amendment freedoms. Nothing Mr. Justice Murphy wrote for the Court
in that case or in any other case justifies any such inference.
Unless I misread history, the majority is giving libel a more
expansive scope and more respectable status than it was ever
accorded even in the Star Chamber. For here it is held to be
punishable to give publicity to any picture, moving picture, play,
drama or sketch, or any printed matter which a judge may find
unduly offensive to any race, color, creed or religion. In other
words, in arguing for or against the enactment of laws that may
differently affect huge groups, it is now very dangerous indeed to
say something critical of one of the groups. And any "person, firm
or corporation" can be tried for this crime. "Person, firm or
corporation" certainly includes a book publisher, newspaper, radio
or television station, candidate or even a preacher.
It is easy enough to say that none of this latter group have
been proceeded against under the Illinois Act. And they have not --
yet. But emotions bubble and tempers flare in racial and religious
controversies, the kind here involved. It would not be easy for any
court, in good conscience, to narrow this Act so as to exclude from
it any of those I have mentioned. Furthermore, persons tried under
the Act could not even get a jury trial except Page 343 U. S. 274 as to the bare fact of publication. Here, the court simply
charged the jury that Beauharnais was guilty if he had caused
distribution of the leaflet. Such trial by judge, rather than by
jury, was outlawed in England in 1792 by Fox's Libel Law.
This Act sets up a system of state censorship which is at war
with the kind of free government envisioned by those who forced
adoption of our Bill of Rights. The motives behind the state law
may have been to do good. But the same can be said about most laws
making opinions punishable as crimes. History indicates that urges
to do good have led to the burning of books, and even to the
burning of "witches."
No rationalization on a purely legal level can conceal the fact
that state laws like this one present a constant overhanging threat
to freedom of speech, press and religion. Today, Beauharnais is
punished for publicly expressing strong views in favor of
segregation. Ironically enough, Beauharnais, convicted of crime in
Chicago, would probably be given a hero's reception in many other
localities, if not in some parts of Chicago itself. Moreover, the
same kind of state law that makes Beauharnais a criminal for
advocating segregation in Illinois can be utilized to send people
to jail in other states for advocating equality and nonsegregation.
What Beauharnais said in his leaflet is mild compared with usual
arguments on both sides of racial controversies.
We are told that freedom of petition and discussion are in no
danger "while this Court sits." This case raises considerable
doubt. Since those who peacefully petition for changes in the law
are not to be protected "while this Court sits," who is? I do not
agree that the Constitution leaves freedom of petition, assembly,
speech, press or worship at the mercy of a case-by-case, day-by-day
majority of this Court. I had supposed that our people could rely
for their freedom on the Constitution's commands, rather Page 343 U. S. 275 than on the grace of this Court on an individual case basis. To
say that a legislative body can, with this Court's approval, make
it a crime to petition for and publicly discuss proposed
legislation seems as far-fetched to me as it would be to say that a
valid law could be enacted to punish a candidate for President for
telling the people his views. I think the First Amendment, with the
Fourteenth, "absolutely" forbids such laws without any "ifs" or
"buts" or "whereases." Whatever the danger, if any, in such public
discussions, it is a danger the Founders deemed outweighed by the
danger incident to the stifling of thought and speech. The Court
does not act on this view of the Founders. It calculates what it
deems to be the danger of public discussion, holds the scales are
tipped on the side of state suppression, and upholds state
censorship. This method of decision offers little protection to
First Amendment liberties "while this Court sits."
If there be minority groups who hail this holding as their
victory, they might consider the possible relevancy of this ancient
remark:
"Another such victory and I am undone."
[For appendix to opinion of MR. JUSTICE BLACK, see
post, p. 343 U. S.
276 .]
[For dissenting opinion of MR. JUSTICE REED, see post, p. 343 U. S.
277 .]
[For dissenting opinion of MR. JUSTICE DOUGLAS, see
post, p. 343 U. S.
284 .]
[For dissenting opinion of MR. JUSTICE JACKSON, see
post, p. 343 U. S.
287 .] Page 343 U. S. 276 [ Footnote 2/1 ]
1 William & Mary, Sess. 2, c. 2 (1689).
[ Footnote 2/2 ]
Eighth Resolution of the Continental Congress of 1774.
[ Footnote 2/3 ] E.g., Grosjean v. American Press Co., 297 U.
S. 233 , 297 U. S.
244 -245, 297 U. S. 249 ; Lovell v. City of Griffin, 303 U.
S. 444 , 303 U. S. 450 ; Schneider v. New Jersey, 308 U. S. 147 , 308 U. S. 160 ; Thornhill v. Alabama, 310 U. S. 88 , 310 U. S. 95 ; Minersville School District v. Gobitis, 310 U.
S. 586 , 310 U. S. 593 ; West Virginia State Board of Education v. Barnette, 319 U. S. 624 , 319 U. S. 639 ; Thomas v. Collins, 323 U. S. 516 , 323 U. S.
529 -530, concurring opinion, 323 U. S. 545 ; Pennekamp v. Florida, 328 U. S. 331 , 328 U. S.
349 .
[ Footnote 2/4 ]
The Court's finding of a close kinship between "criminal libel"
and "group libel" because both contain the word "libel" and have
some factors in common is reminiscent of what Earl Stanhope said in
1792 in discussing Mr. Fox's Libel Bill. He was arguing that a jury
of laymen might more likely protect liberty than judges, because
judges were prone to rely too heavily on word books.
"He put the case that an action for a libel was brought for
using a modern word, not to be found in any grammar or glossary, viz., for saying that a man was 'a great bore;' a jury
would laugh at such a ground of prosecution, but the judges would
turn to their grammars and glossaries, and, not being able to meet
with it, would say they could not find such a phrase as 'a great
bore,' but they had found a wild boar, which no doubt it meant; and
yet it could not be, as a wild boar had four legs, and a man was a
two-legged animal; then it must mean, that the plaintiff was like a
wild boar in disposition, which was a wicked libel, and therefore
let the defendant be hanged."
29 Hansard, Parliamentary History of England, p. 1412.
| 343
U.S. 250 app| APPENDIX TO OPINION OF MR. JUSTICE BLACK image:a Page 343 U. S. 277 MR. JUSTICE REED, with whom MR. JUSTICE DOUGLAS joins,
dissenting.
The Fourteenth Amendment of our Constitution forbids that any
person be deprived by a state of liberty or property without due
process of law. This Illinois conviction subjects petitioner to a
fine of $200. The petitioner challenges the validity of the
sentence on the ground that his conviction under § 224a, Division
1, of the Illinois Criminal Code [ Footnote 3/1 ] violates substantive due process. The
petition for certiorari phrases the issue thus:
"Is the Illinois statute . . . as construed . . . or applied . .
. invalid . . . because it infringes upon the constitutional
guarantee of free speech, press and of assemblage as
guaranteed"
by the Fourteenth Amendment?
The Supreme Court of Illinois upheld the conviction of
petitioner under an information which charged:
"that defendant, on January 7, 1950, at the City of Chicago, did
unlawfully publish, present and exhibit in public places,
lithographs, which publications portrayed depravity, criminality,
unchastity, or lack of virtue of citizens of Negro race and color
and which exposes citizens of Illinois of the Negro race and Page 343 U. S. 278 color to contempt, derision, or obloquy, which more fully
appears in Exhibit A, which is attached hereto and made a part
thereof. [ Footnote 3/2 ]"
The evidence was sufficient to justify the jury in finding that
Beauharnais caused the lithograph referred to in the information to
be published and distributed in public places. The jury did so find
under certain general instructions as to the proper attitude of
jurors, but essentially and specifically under the following
instruction:
"(1) The Court instructs the jury that if you find from the
evidence that the defendant, Joseph Beauharnais, did on or about
January 7, 1950, manufacture, sell, or offer for sale, advertise or
publish, present or exhibit in any public place the lithograph
which was allowed in evidence in this case as Peoples Exhibit
Number 3, then you are to find the defendant guilty and fine him
not less than $50.00 nor more than $200.00."
Thus, the judge did not leave to the jury, but decided himself,
doubtless as a matter of law, that the publication of the
lithograph violated the statute. No complaint was made of this
state method of trial.
At trial, petitioner filed a motion to quash the information and
objected to the above specific instruction. He also moved for a
peremptory instruction of "not guilty" and for judgment
notwithstanding the verdict. All these contentions were overruled
by the trial court, and, although the record does not show a
precisely pleaded objection to the conviction on the ground that §
224a is unconstitutional, nonetheless the Supreme Court of Illinois
treated petitioner's contention that the statute was Page 343 U. S. 279 too vague and by virtue of that fact was so broad that it
abridged free speech in violation of the Fourteenth Amendment.
[ Footnote 3/3 ] The petition for
certiorari brings these questions here.
In carrying out its obligation to conform state legal
administration to the "fundamental principles of liberty and
justice" imposed on the states by the Fourteenth Amendment,
[ Footnote 3/4 ] this Court has
steadily affirmed that the general principle against abridgment of
free speech, protected by the First Amendment, is included in the
command of the Fourteenth. [ Footnote
3/5 ] So important to a constitutional democracy is the right of
discussion that any challenge to legislative abridgment of those
privileges of a free people calls for careful judicial appraisal.
[ Footnote 3/6 ] It is when speech
becomes an incitement to crime that the right freely to exhort may
be abridged. American Communications Ass'n v. Douds, 339 U. S. 382 , 339 U. S. 395 ; Herndon v. Lowry, 301 U. S. 242 , 301 U. S.
255 . Page 343 U. S. 280 When a state conviction is challenged here on the ground that
free speech has been abridged, this Court must first decide whether
the portion of the statute upon which the charge is based is so
broad "as to permit within the scope of its language the punishment
of incidents fairly within the protection of the guarantee of free
speech." Winters v. New York, 333 U.
S. 507 , 333 U. S. 509 .
In the Winters case, we set aside the conviction because
the indefinite character of the statutory language, as construed by
the Court of Appeals of New York, was so broad that protected
speech was prohibited. This Court reversed, even though it assumed
that Winters' conduct could constitutionally be punished by a
statute expressing its prohibitions in reasonably narrow and
definite form. [ Footnote 3/7 ]
This requirement means that, when the verdict and judgment flow,
as here, from the information as a whole, each and every portion of
the statute upon which the information was drawn must be
constitutional. In Stromberg v. California, 283 U.
S. 359 , Stromberg had been convicted in the California
courts for violating a statute of that state forbidding the display
of a red flag. [ Footnote 3/8 ] On
appeal, this Court did not consider whether Stromberg's conduct, as
shown by the record, was protected by the Constitution. Instead,
despite the fact that the second and third clauses of the
California statute were unquestionably valid under the Federal
Constitution, this Court Page 343 U. S. 281 reversed the state court because its conviction of Stromberg
might have been based upon the first clause, holding that, "if any
of the clauses in question is invalid under the Federal
Constitution, the conviction cannot be upheld." [ Footnote 3/9 ] The first clause, forbidding a
display of a red flag as a symbol of opposition to organized
government, was deemed invalid because it was so broad that it
permitted
"punishment of the fair use of [the] opportunity [for free
political discussion, and was therefore] repugnant to the guaranty
of liberty contained in the Fourteenth Amendment." Id. at 283 U. S.
369 .
The judgment in this present case followed from a determination
of judge and jury that petitioner's publication of the lithograph
violated the statute. From the general verdict of guilty, nothing
appears to show what particular words of the statute the Illinois
courts determined the lithograph offended. This conviction must
stand or fall upon a determination whether all definitions of the
acts proscribed by the statute and charged in the information may
be banned under the principles of the First Amendment, for, as the
foregoing discussion shows, it is impossible to tell upon what
phrase of the statute petitioner's conviction was based. Our
examination can begin and end with the inquiry as to what meaning
lies in the act's declaration, as charged in the information, that
it is unlawful to portray in a lithograph a "lack of virtue of a
class of citizens . . . which . . . exposes [them to] derision, or
obloquy."
The majority opinion asserts that Illinois has given
sufficiently clear and narrow meaning to the words "virtue,"
"derision" and "obloquy" by characterizing § 224a as "a form of
criminal libel law." But the mere description of this statute as a
criminal libel law does not Page 343 U. S. 282 clarify the meaning of these vague words in the statute. To say
that the mere presence of the word "virtue" in the individual libel
statute [ Footnote 3/10 ] makes its
meaning clear in the group libel statute is a non
sequitur. No case is cited which defines and limits the
meaning of these words. Reliance is also placed by the Court upon
Illinois' unfortunate experience with clashes between races. How
that experience gives content to the vague words is not explained.
The opinion further relies upon "the clarifying
construction and fixed usage which govern the meaning
of the enactment before us." (Emphasis added.) No opinions
containing such clarification are cited. In addition to the case
before us, we find only two reported adjudications on § 224a in the
Illinois courts. [ Footnote 3/11 ]
Without caviling that one of these cases is so recent that it
follows the instant case in the reports, certainly neither of them
contains any words which give that "clarifying construction"
claimed for Illinois law.
The majority certainly do not supply that construction by
intimating that the publications prohibited by § 224a are only
those "liable to cause violence and disorder." Moreover, that
phrase was used by the Illinois court, not to limit the prohibition
of § 224a, but to describe the lithograph published by Beauharnais. See 408 Ill. at 517, 97 N.E.2d at 346. The quoted language
does not limit the statutory words "virtue," "derision" or
"obloquy." [ Footnote 3/12 ] Page 343 U. S. 283 The Court speaks at length of the constitutional power of a
state to pass group libel laws to protect the public peace. This
dissent assumes that power. What is under discussion is whether the
conviction of Beauharnais on a general charge of violation of the
statute can stand when the statute contains without statutory or
judicial definition words of such ambiguous meaning and uncertain
connotation as "virtue," "derision," or "obloquy." The Court does
not attempt to speak specifically as to that contention.
The importance of a definite ruling on that point is manifest.
Racial, religious, and political biases and prejudices lead to
charge and countercharge, acrimony and bitterness. If words are to
be punished criminally, the Constitution at least requires that
only words or expressions or statements that can be reasonably well
defined, or that have through long usage an accepted meaning, shall
furnish a basis for conviction. [ Footnote 3/13 ]
These words -- "virtue," "derision," and "obloquy" -- have
neither general nor special meanings well enough known to apprise
those within their reach as to limitations Page 343 U. S. 284 on speech. Compare Connally v. General Construction
Co., 269 U. S. 385 , 269 U. S.
391 -392. Philosophers and poets, thinkers of high and
low degree from every age and race have sought to expound the
meaning of virtue, but each teaches his own conception of the moral
excellence that satisfies standards of good conduct. Are the tests
of the Puritan or the Cavalier to be applied, those of the city or
the farm, the Christian or non-Christian, the old or the young?
Does the Bill of Rights permit Illinois to forbid any reflection on
the virtue of racial or religious classes which a jury or a judge
may think exposes them to derision or obloquy, words themselves of
quite uncertain meaning as used in the statute? I think not. A
general and equal enforcement of this law would restrain the
mildest expressions of opinion in all those areas where "virtue"
may be thought to have a role. Since this judgment may rest upon
these vague and undefined words, which permit within their scope
the punishment of incidents secured by the guarantee of free
speech, the conviction should be reversed.
[ Footnote 3/1 ]
"It shall be unlawful for any person, firm or corporation to
manufacture, sell, or offer for sale, advertise or publish, present
or exhibit in any public place in this state any lithograph, moving
picture, play, drama or sketch, which publication or exhibition
portrays depravity, criminality, unchastity, or lack of virtue of a
class of citizens, of any race, color, creed or religion which said
publication or exhibition exposes the citizens of any race, color,
creed or religion to contempt, derision, or obloquy or which is
productive of breach of the peace or riots. Any person, firm or
corporation violating any of the provisions of this section shall
be guilty of a misdemeanor, and, upon conviction thereof, shall be
punished by a fine of not less than fifty dollars ($50.00), nor
more than two hundred dollars ($200.00)."
[ Footnote 3/2 ] People v. Beauharnais, 408 Ill.
512 , 514, 97 N.E.2d
343 , 344-345. The Exhibit A referred to in the information is
the lithograph referred to in the instructions to the jury as
People's Exhibit 3.
[ Footnote 3/3 ] 408 Ill. 512 ,
at 515-516 and 517, 97 N.E.2d
343 , at 345-346. If the highest court of the state treats the
federal question as properly before it, and decides the question,
the question is reviewable here, regardless of the manner in which
it was raised in the inferior courts of the state. See Whitney
v. California, 274 U. S. 357 , 274 U. S. 361 ,
and cases there cited.
[ Footnote 3/4 ] Hebert v. Louisiana, 272 U. S. 312 , 272 U. S. 316 ; Palko v. Connecticut, 302 U. S. 319 ; Adamson v. California, 332 U. S. 46 , 332 U. S.
66 .
[ Footnote 3/5 ] Gitlow v. New York, 268 U. S. 652 , 268 U. S. 666 , 268 U. S. 672 ; Near v. Minnesota, 283 U. S. 697 , 283 U. S. 707 ; Pennekamp v. Florida, 328 U. S. 331 , 328 U. S.
335 .
[ Footnote 3/6 ] De Jonge v. Oregon, 299 U. S. 353 , 299 U. S.
365 :
"The greater the importance of safeguarding the community from
incitements to the overthrow of our institutions by force and
violence, the more imperative is the need to preserve inviolate the
constitutional rights of free speech, free press and free assembly
in order to maintain the opportunity for free political discussion,
to the end that government may be responsive to the will of the
people and that changes, if desired, may be obtained by peaceful
means. Therein lies the security of the Republic, the very
foundation of constitutional government."
[ Footnote 3/7 ] See 333 U.S. at 333 U. S. 520 . Cf. Thornhill v. Alabama, 310 U. S.
88 ; Herndon v. Lowry, 301 U.
S. 242 , 301 U. S.
263 -264.
[ Footnote 3/8 ]
283 U.S. at 283 U. S.
361 :
"Any person who displays a red flag, banner or badge or any
flag, badge, banner, or device of any color or form whatever in any
public place or in any meeting place or public assembly, or from or
on any house, building or window as a sign, symbol or emblem of
opposition to organized government or as an invitation or stimulus
to anarchistic action or as an aid to propaganda that is of a
seditious character is guilty of a felony."
Then § 403a of the California Penal Code.
[ Footnote 3/9 ]
283 U.S. at 283 U. S. 368 . See also Williams v. North Carolina, 317 U.
S. 287 , 317 U. S.
291 -292. Cf. Thomas v. Collins, 323 U.
S. 516 , 323 U. S. 529 ; Cramer v. United States, 325 U. S. 1 , 325 U. S. 36 , n.
45.
[ Footnote 3/10 ]
Smith-Hurd Ill.Ann.Stat.1936, c. 38, § 402, quoted in majority
opinion at note 5.
[ Footnote 3/11 ] People v. Simcox, 379 Ill. 347, 40 N.E.2d 525; People v. White Circle League of America, 408 Ill. 564 , 97 N.E.2d 811 (1951). See also Fox Film Corp. v. Collins, 236 Ill.App.
281; Bevins v. Prindable, 39 F.
Supp. 708 , affirmed, 314 U.S. 573.
[ Footnote 3/12 ]
Indeed, if the Illinois courts had been inclined to interpret
their statute as this Court now interprets it, they could have done
so only by reading out of their statute the disjunctive clause "or
which is productive of breach of the peace or riots." (Quoted at p. 343 U. S. 251 of majority opinion.) If the Illinois courts were inclined to read
this disjunctive as a conjunctive, they would presumably have
reversed Beauharnais' conviction, for the information in this case
did not charge that publication of his lithograph would be
productive of breach of the peace or riots.
[ Footnote 3/13 ]
". . . the constitution never intended to invest judges with a
discretion which cannot be tried and measured by the plain and
palpable standard of law. . . . On a special verdict for murder,
the life of the prisoner does not depend upon the religious, moral,
or philosophical ideas of the judges. . . . If he is condemned . .
. , his conduct is brought to a precise, clear, intelligible
standard, and cautiously measured by it; it is the law, therefore,
and not the judge, which condemns him. . . ."
Argument in the King's Bench in the Dean of St. Asaph's case
(1783-1784), 21 Howell's State Trials 847, 1006.
MR. JUSTICE DOUGLAS, dissenting.
Hitler and his Nazis showed how evil a conspiracy could be which
was aimed at destroying a race by exposing it to contempt,
derision, and obloquy. I would be willing to concede that such
conduct directed at a race or group in this country could be made
an indictable offense. For such a project would be more than the
exercise of free speech. Like picketing, it would be free speech
plus.
I would also be willing to concede that, even without the
element of conspiracy, there might be times and occasions when the
legislative or executive branch might call a halt to inflammatory
talk, such as the shouting of "fire" in a school or a theatre.
My view is that if, in any case, other public interests are to
override the plain command of the First Amendment, Page 343 U. S. 285 the peril of speech must be clear and present, leaving no room
for argument, raising no doubts as to the necessity of curbing
speech in order to prevent disaster.
The First Amendment is couched in absolute terms -- freedom of
speech shall not be abridged. Speech has therefore a preferred
position [ Footnote 4/1 ] as
contrasted to some other civil rights. For example, privacy,
equally sacred to some, is protected by the Fourth Amendment only
against unreasonable searches and seizures. There is room for
regulation of the ways and means of invading privacy. No such
leeway is granted the invasion of the right of free speech
guaranteed by the First Amendment. Until recent years, that had
been the course and direction of constitutional law. Yet, recently,
the Court in this and in other cases [ Footnote 4/2 ] has engrafted the right of regulation onto
the First Amendment by placing in the hands of the legislative
branch the right to regulate "within reasonable limits" the right
of free speech. This, to me is, an ominous and alarming trend. The
free trade in ideas which the Framers of the Constitution
visualized disappears. In its place there is substituted a new
orthodoxy -- an orthodoxy that changes with the whims of the age or
the day, an orthodoxy which the majority by solemn judgment
proclaims to be essential to the safety, welfare, security,
morality, or health of society. Free speech in the constitutional
sense disappears. Limits are drawn -- limits dictated by
expediency, political opinion, prejudices or some other desideratum
of legislative action.
An historic aspect of the issue of judicial supremacy was the
extent to which legislative judgment would be Page 343 U. S. 286 supreme in the field of social legislation. The vague contours
of the Due Process Clause were used to strike down laws deemed by
the Court to be unwise and improvident. [ Footnote 4/3 ] That trend has been reversed. In matters
relating to business, finance, industrial and labor conditions,
health and the public welfare, great leeway is now granted the
legislature, [ Footnote 4/4 ] for
there is no guarantee in the Constitution that the status
quo will be preserved against regulation by government.
Freedom of speech, however, rests on a different constitutional
basis. The First Amendment says that freedom of speech, freedom of
press, and the free exercise of religion shall not be abridged.
That is a negation of power on the part of each and every
department of government. Free speech, free press, free exercise of
religion are placed separate and apart; they are above and beyond
the police power; they are not subject to regulation in the manner
of factories, slums, apartment houses, production of oil, and the
like.
The Court in this and in other cases places speech under an
expanding legislative control. Today a white man stands convicted
for protesting in unseemly language against our decisions
invalidating restrictive covenants. Tomorrow a negro will be
haliled before a court for denouncing lynch law in heated terms.
Farm laborers in the west who compete with field hands drifting up
from Mexico; whites who feel the pressure of orientals; a minority
which finds employment going to members of the dominant religious
group -- all of these are caught in the mesh of today's decision.
Debate and argument, even in the courtroom, are not always calm and
dispassionate. Emotions sway speakers and audiences alike.
Intemperate Page 343 U. S. 287 speech is a distinctive characteristic of man. Hotheads blow off
and release destructive energy in the process. They shout and rave,
exaggerating weaknesses, magnifying error, viewing with alarm. So
it has been from the beginning; and so it will be throughout time.
The Framers of the Constitution knew human nature as well as we do.
They too had lived in dangerous days; they too knew the suffocating
influence of orthodoxy and standardized thought. They weighed the
compulsions for retrained speech and thought against the abuses of
liberty. They chose liberty. That should be our choice today, no
matter how distasteful to us the pamphlet of Beauharnais may be. It
is true that this is only one decision which may later be
distinguished or confined to narrow limits. But it represents a
philosophy at war with the First Amendment -- a constitutional
interpretation which puts free speech under the legislative thumb.
It reflects an influence moving ever deeper into our society. It is
notice to the legislatures that they have the power to control
unpopular blocs. It is a warning to every minority that, when the
Constitution guarantees free speech, it does not mean what it
says.
[ Footnote 4/1 ] Murdock v. Pennsylvania, 319 U.
S. 105 , 319 U. S. 115 ; Thomas v. Collins, 323 U. S. 516 , 323 U. S. 530 ; Saia v. New York, 334 U. S. 558 , 334 U. S.
561 .
[ Footnote 4/2 ] Dennis v. United States, 341 U.
S. 494 ; Feiner v. New York, 340 U.
S. 315 . Cf. Breard v. Alexandria, 341 U.
S. 622 ; American Communications Ass'n v. Douds, 339 U. S. 382 ; Osman v. Douds, 339 U. S. 846 .
[ Footnote 4/3 ] Lochner v. New York, 198 U. S. 45 ; Coppage v. Kansas, 236 U. S. 1 ; Ribnik v. McBride, 277 U. S. 350 .
[ Footnote 4/4 ] Nebbia v. New York, 291 U. S. 502 ; West Coast Hotel Co. v. Parrish, 300 U.
S. 379 ; Lincoln Union v. Northwestern Co., 335 U. S. 525 ; Day-Brite Lighting, Inc. v. Missouri, 342 U.
S. 421 .
MR. JUSTICE JACKSON, dissenting.
An Illinois Act, construed by its Supreme Court to be a "group
libel" statute, has been used to punish criminally the author and
distributor of an obnoxious leaflet attacking the Negro race. He
answers that, as applied, the Act denies a liberty secured to him
by the Due Process Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment. What is the
liberty which that clause underwrites?
The spectrum of views expressed by my seniors shows that
disagreement as to the scope and effect of this Amendment underlies
this, as it has many another, division of the Court. All agree that
the Fourteenth Amendment does confine the power of the State to
make printed Page 343 U. S. 288 words criminal. Whence we are to derive metes and bounds of the
state power is a subject to the confusion of which, I regret to
say, I have contributed -- comforted in the acknowledgment,
however, by recalling that this Amendment is so enigmatic and
abstruse that judges more experienced than I have had to reverse
themselves as to its effect on state power.
The assumption of other dissents is that the "liberty" which the
Due Process Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment protects against
denial by the States is the literal and identical "freedom of
speech, or of the press" which the First Amendment forbids only
Congress to abridge. The history of criminal libel in America
convinces me that the Fourteenth Amendment did not "incorporate"
the First, that the powers of Congress and of the States over this
subject are not of the same dimensions, and that, because Congress
probably could not enact this law, it does not follow that the
States may not. I As a limitation upon power to punish written or spoken words,
Fourteenth Amendment "liberty" in its context of state powers and
functions has meant and should mean something quite different from
"freedom" in its context of federal powers and functions. [ Footnote 5/1 ]
This Court has never sustained a federal criminal libel Act. One
section of the Sedition Act of 1798 was close to being a "group
libel" Act. [ Footnote 5/2 ] While
there were convictions Page 343 U. S. 289 under it, no attack on its validity reached this Court. I think
today's better opinion regards the enactment as a breach of the
First Amendment, and certainly Mr. Justice Holmes and Mr. Justice
Brandeis thought so. [ Footnote 5/3 ]
But even in the absence of judicial condemnation, the political
disapproval of the Sedition Act was so emphatic and sustained that
federal prosecution of the press ceased for a century. It was
resumed with indictment of The Indianapolis News and The New York
World for disclosures and criticisms of the Panama Canal
acquisition. Both were indicted in the District of Columbia and
under the District Code, on the ground that some copies circulated
there. That prosecution collapsed when Judge Anderson refused the
Government's application to remove the Indiana defendants to the
District of Columbia for trial. [ Footnote 5/4 ]
The World, circulated at West Point, was indicted in New York on
the theory that an 1825 Act to protect Page 343 U. S. 290 fortifications assimilated the New York State law punishing
criminal libel. That venture likewise came to grief when Judge
Hough rejected that construction of the federal statute and was
upheld by this Court. United States v. Press Publishing
Co., 219 U. S. 1 (1911).
While there has been a demand from official sources for a
resumption of criminal libel prosecution, it has not been acceded
to. [ Footnote 5/5 ] Thus, while the
jeopardy of such federal prosecutions has never been removed by any
decision of this Court, I should think the validity of a federal
enactment such as this would be extremely doubtful, to say the
least.
The effect of the First Amendment on congressional power to make
seditious utterance criminal did receive consideration in the
aftermath of the First World War. In such a case, Mr. Justice
Holmes formulated for the Court as "the question in every case" the
"clear and present danger" test. Schenck v. United States, 249 U. S. 47 , 249 U. S. 52 . He
and Mr. Justice Brandeis adhered to it as a "rule of reason,"
dissenting when they thought the rest of the Court apostate. Abrams v. United States, 250 U. S. 616 , 250 U. S.
627 -628; Schaefer v. United States, 251 U. S. 466 , 251 U. S.
482 .
Only after research and deliberation in these cases had
sharpened their perception did these Justices face the free speech
issue as to state power which Mr. Justice Holmes first adverted to,
but left undecided, in Patterson v. Colorado, 205 U.
S. 454 . In 1922, they joined the Court's first decision
on the subject, which declared that
". . . neither the Fourteenth Amendment nor any other provision
of Page 343 U. S. 291 the Constitution of the United States imposes upon the states
any restrictions about 'freedom of speech.' . . ." Prudential Insurance Co. v. Cheek, 259 U.
S. 530 , 259 U. S.
543 .
However, these two Justices, who made the only original
contribution to legal thought on the difficult problems bound up in
these Amendments, soon reversed and took the view that the
Fourteenth Amendment did impose some restrictions upon the States.
But it was not premised upon the First Amendment, nor upon any
theory that it was incorporated in the Fourteenth. What they wrote,
with care and circumspection, I accept as the wise and historically
correct view of the Fourteenth Amendment. It was:
" The general principle of free speech, it seems to me,
must be taken to be included in the Fourteenth Amendment, in view
of the scope that has been given to the word 'liberty' as there
used, although perhaps it may be accepted with a somewhat
larger latitude of interpretation than is allowed to Congress by the sweeping language that governs or ought to govern the laws
of the United States."
(Emphasis supplied.) Gitlow v. New York, 268 U.
S. 652 , 268 U. S.
672 .
That reasoning was echoed so recently as 1937, when the Court
explicitly rejected the theory of incorporation and, through Mr.
Justice Cardozo, announced a view, unanimous except for Mr. Justice
Butler, that the Fourteenth did not deflect against the States the
literal language of amendments designed to circumscribe federal
power but qualified state power only by such general restraints as
are essential to "the concept of ordered liberty." Palko v.
Connecticut, 302 U. S. 319 , 302 U. S.
324 -325.
It is clear that these do not proscribe state criminal libel
Acts. Justices Holmes and Brandeis in 1931 joined Chief Justice
Hughes, who spoke for the Court, in striking down a state Act
because it authorized restraint by injunction Page 343 U. S. 292 previous to publication. He said:
"For whatever wrong the appellant has committed or may commit by
his publications, the state appropriately affords both public and
private redress by its libel laws."
This was amplified:
"But it is recognized that punishment for the abuse of the
liberty accorded to the press is essential to the protection of the
public, and that the common law rules that subject the libeler to
responsibility for the public offense, as well as for the private
injury, are not abolished by the protection extended in our
Constitutions. . . . The law of criminal libel rests upon that
secure foundation." Near v. Minnesota, 283 U. S. 697 , 283 U. S.
715 .
So recently as 1942, a unanimous Court, speaking of state power,
said that punishment of libelous words "which by their very
utterance inflict injury or tend to incite an immediate breach of
the peace" has never been thought to raise any constitutional
problem. Chaplinsky v. New Hampshire, 315 U.
S. 568 , 315 U. S.
571 -572.
More than forty State Constitutions, while extending broad
protections to speech and press, reserve a responsibility for their
abuse and implicitly or explicitly recognize validity of criminal
libel laws. [ Footnote 5/6 ] We are
justified Page 343 U. S. 293 in assuming that the men who sponsored the Fourteenth Amendment
in Congress, and those who ratified it in the state legislatures,
knew of such provisions then in many of their state constitutions.
Certainly they were not consciously canceling them or calling them
into question, or we would have some evidence of it. Congresses,
during the period while this Amendment was being considered or was
but freshly adopted, approved constitutions of "reconstructed"
States that expressly mentioned state libel laws, [ Footnote 5/7 ] and also approved similar
constitutions for States erected out of the federal domain.
[ Footnote 5/8 ] Page 343 U. S. 294 Certainly this tolerance of state libel laws by the very authors
and partisans of the Fourteenth Amendment shows either that they
were not intending to incorporate the First Amendment or that they
believed it would not prevent federal libel laws. Adoption of the
incorporation theory today would lead to the dilemma of either
confining the States as closely as the Congress or giving the
Federal Government the latitude appropriate to state governments.
The treatment of libel powers corroborates the conclusions against
the incorporationist theory reached by the most comprehensive and
objective studies of the origin and adoption of the Fourteenth
Amendment. [ Footnote 5/9 ]
The inappropriateness of a single standard for restricting State
and Nation is indicated by the disparity between their functions
and duties in relation to those freedoms. Criminality of defamation
is predicated upon power either to protect the private right to
enjoy integrity of reputation or the public right to tranquility.
Neither of these are objects of federal cognizance except when
necessary to the accomplishment of some delegated power, such
as Page 343 U. S. 295 protection of interstate commerce. When the Federal Government
puts liberty of press in one scale, it has a very limited duty to
personal reputation or local tranquillity to weigh against it in
the other. But state action affecting speech or press can and
should be weighed against and reconciled with these conflicting
social interests.
For these reasons, I should not, unless clearly required,
confirm to the Federal Government such latitude as I think a State
reasonably may require for orderly government of its manifold
concerns. The converse of the proposition is that I would not limit
the power of the State with the severity appropriately prescribed
for federal power.
As the principle by which to judge the constitutionality of this
statute, I accept the dissent in Gitlow and the decision
in Palko. II What restraints upon state power to punish criminal libel are
implied by the "concept of ordered liberty"? Experience by
Anglo-Saxon peoples with defamation and laws to punish it extends
over centuries, and the statute and case books exhibit its
teachings. If one can claim to announce the judgment of legal
history on any subject, it is that criminal libel laws are
consistent with the concept of ordered liberty only when applied
with safeguards evolved to prevent their invasion of freedom of
expression.
Oppressive application of the English libel laws was partially
checked when Fox's Libel Act of 1972 allowed the jury to determine
whether an accused publication was libelous in character, and more
completely when Lord Campbell's Libel Act of 1943 allowed truth to
be proved as a defense.
American experience teaches similar lessons. The leading state
case is People v. Croswell, 3 Johns.Cas. 337. Page 343 U. S. 296 Since, as the opinion of this Court now points out, the
Jeffersonian's objection to federal sedition prosecutions was
largely fear of federal usurpation of state powers over the
subject, it was consistent for them to prosecute libels under state
law. Croswell, publisher of the aptly named Wasp, was indicted for
libeling Thomas Jefferson by representing him as unworthy of the
confidence, respect, and attachment of the people. The trial judge
pronounced his statements libelous as a matter of law and allowed
the jury to decide no question except whether the accused had
published them. The defendant was convicted, and, on his appeal,
argued by Alexander Hamilton, the appellate court divided equally.
Justice Kent, however, filed a characteristically learned and
vigorous opinion that the trial court must submit the libelous
character of the article and libelous intent of its printer to
decision by the jury, which was entitled to determine both law and
fact. The public response was such that an early session of the
legislature substantially enacted Kent's contentions. Inasmuch as
no judgment had been entered upon the earlier equal division, the
court, at its August, 1805, term, "in consequence of this
declaratory statute," unanimously awarded a new trial. [ Footnote 5/10 ]
The New York Constitution at that time contained no free speech
provision, but the case led to a provision included in the
Constitution of 1821 which both followed Fox's Libel Act and
anticipated Lord Campbell's Act, and has remained in the several
constitutions of that State since:
"Every citizen may freely speak, write, and publish his
sentiments on all subjects, being responsible for the abuse of that
right; and no law shall be passed to restrain or abridge the
liberty to speech, or of the press. In all prosecutions or
indictments Page 343 U. S. 297 for libels, the truth may be given in evidence to the jury; and
if it shall appear to the jury that the matter charged as libellous
is true, and was published with good motives and for justifiable
ends, the party shall be acquitted; and the jury shall have the
right to determine the law and the fact. [ Footnote 5/11 ]"
It would not be an exaggeration to say that, basically, this
provision of the New York Constitution states the common sense of
American criminal libel law. Twenty-four States of the Union whose
constitutions were framed later substantially adopted it. [ Footnote 5/12 ] Twelve States provide that
press and speech shall be free, but there shall be responsibility
for the abuse. [ Footnote 5/13 ]
Five others provide substantially the same, but add that truth may
be given in evidence in a libel prosecution. [ Footnote 5/14 ] Only five States, whose
constitutions were framed earlier, were content with the generality
about the free press similar to that of Massachusetts. [ Footnote 5/15 ] But all of these States,
apart from constitutional Page 343 U. S. 298 provision, have by decisional law recognized the validity of
criminal libel prosecutions. [ Footnote 5/16 ]
Because of these safeguards, state libel laws have presented no
threat to a free press comparable to that from federal sources, and
have not proved inconsistent with fundamental liberties. Attacks on
the press by States which were frustrated by this Court in Near
v. Minnesota, supra, and Grosjean v. American Press
Co., 297 U. S. 233 ,
were not by libel laws. For near a century and a half, this Court's
decisions left state criminal libel prosecutions entirely free of
federal constitutional limitations. It is a matter of notoriety
that the press often has provoked hostility, that editors have been
mobbed and horsewhipped, but criminal libel prosecutions have not
been frequent, and, as safeguarded by state law, they have been so
innocuous that chronicles of American journalism give them only
passing mention. [ Footnote
5/17 ]
This Court, by construction of the Fourteenth Amendment, has
imposed but one addition to the safeguards voluntarily taken upon
the States by themselves. It is that, where expression, oral or
printed, is punished, although it has not actually caused injuries
or disorders, but is thought to have a tendency to do so, the
likelihood of such consequence must not be remote or speculative.
That is the "clear and present danger" test which Mr. Justice
Holmes and Mr. Justice Brandeis, eventually with support of the
Court, thought implied in both the First [ Footnote 5/18 ] and Fourteenth Amendments, [ Footnote 5/19 ] although the former
was Page 343 U. S. 299 not bodily bound up in the latter. Any superficial inconsistency
between applying the same standard but permitting a wider range of
action to the States is resolved upon reference to the latter part
of the statement of the formula: clear and present danger of those
substantive evils which the legislature has a right to prevent. The
evils at which Congress may aim, and in so doing come into conflict
with free speech, will be relatively few, since it is a government
of limited powers. Because the States may reach more evils, they
will have wider range to punish speech which presents clear and
present danger of bringing about those evils.
In few subjects so much as libel does local law, in spite of
varying historical influences, afford a consensus of American legal
opinion as to what is reasonable and essential to the concept of
ordered government. The boundaries are roughly outlined, to be
sure, and cannot be stated or applied with mathematical precision,
but those widely accepted state constitutional provisions on which
is superimposed the "clear and present danger" test for "tendency"
cases seem to be our best guide.
I agree with the Court that a State has power to bring classes
"of any race, color, creed, or religion" within the protection of
its libel laws, if indeed traditional forms do not already
accomplish it. [ Footnote 5/20 ]
But I am equally clear that, in doing so, it is essential to our
concept of ordered liberty that the State also protect the accused
by those safeguards the necessity for which is verified by legal
history. III The Illinois statute, as applied in this case, seems to me to
have dispensed with accepted safeguards for the accused. Trial of
this case ominously parallels the trial of Page 343 U. S. 300 People v. Croswell, supra, in that the Illinois court
here instructed the jury, in substance, that if it found that
defendant published this leaflet ,he must be found guilty of
criminal libel.
Rulings of the trial court precluded the effort to justify
statements of fact by proving their truth. The majority opinion
concedes the unvarying recognition by the States that truth plus
good motives is a defense in a prosecution for criminal libel. But
here, the trial court repeatedly refused defendant's offer of proof
as to the truth of the matter published. Where an offer to prove
the dominant element of a defense is rejected as immaterial, we can
hardly refuse to consider defendant's constitutional question
because he did not go through the useless ceremony of offering
proof of a subsidiary element of the defense. If the court would
not let him try to prove he spoke truth, how could he show that the
spoke truth for good ends? Furthermore, the record indicates that
defendant was asked to state what he had meant by the use of
certain phrases, and the reason for forming the White Circle League
-- statements which apparently bore on the issue of motive and
ends. But the trial court sustained a sweeping objection "to this
whole line of examination." The Supreme Court of Illinois noted the
offer of proof of truth and its exclusion, and apparently went on
to rule as a matter of law that the statement was not published for
justifiable ends. At all events, it is clear that the defense was
ruled out as matter of law, and defendant was never allowed to
present it for decision by either court or jury upon the facts, a
practice which I think is contrary to the overwhelming verdict of
Anglo-Saxon history and practice. I do not intimate that this
defendant stood even a remote chance of justifying what impresses
me, as it did the trial court, as reckless and vicious libel. But
the point is that his evidence, proffered for that purpose, was
excluded instead of being Page 343 U. S. 301 received and evaluated. Society has an interest in preserving
truth as a justification, however obnoxious the effort may be. A
publication which diffuses its attack over unnamed and impersonal
multitudes is likely to be harder to justify than one which
concentrates its attack on named individuals, but the burden may
properly be cast on an accused and punishment follow failure to
carry it.
The same may be said of the right to comment upon matters of
public interest insofar as the statement includes matters of
opinion, a point, however, which the defense may have inadequately
raised. When any naturally cohesive or artificially organized group
possesses a racial or sectarian solidarity which is or may be
exploited to influence public affairs, that group becomes a
legitimate subject for public comment. Of course, one can only
deplore the habitual intemperance and bitter disparagement which
characterizes most such comment. While I support the right of a
State to place decent bounds upon it, I am not ready to hold that
group purposes, characteristics and histories are to be immunized
from comment or may be discussed only at the risk of prosecution
free of all usual safeguards.
Another defense almost universally recognized, which it seems
the jury were not allowed to consider here, is that of privilege.
Petition for redress of grievances is specifically privileged by
many State Constitutions. I do not think we should hold this whole
document to be constitutionally privileged just because, in part,
it stimulates a petition for redress of grievances. A court or jury
could have found that its primary purpose was not to petition, but
to appeal for members and contributions to the White Circle League.
If some part of it were privileged, that, so it has been held, does
not extend constitutional protection to unprivileged matter. Cf. Valentine v. Chrestensen, 316 U. S.
52 . But the question of privilege seems Page 343 U. S. 302 not to have been specifically passed on by the court, and
certainly was not submitted for the jury's consideration.
In this case, neither the court nor jury found or were required
to find any injury to any person, or group, or to the public peace,
nor to find any probability, let alone any clear and present
danger, of injury to any of these. Even though no individuals were
named or described as targets of this pamphlet, if it resulted in a
riot or caused injury to any individual Negro, such as being
refused living quarters in a particular section, house or
apartment, or being refused employment, certainly there would be no
constitutional obstacle to imposing civil or criminal liability for
actual results. But, in this case, no actual violence and no
specific injury was charged or proved.
The leaflet was simply held punishable as criminal libel per
se, irrespective of its actual or probable consequences. No
charge of conspiracy complicates this case. The words themselves do
not advocate the commission of any crime. The conviction rests on
judicial attribution of a likelihood of evil results. The trial
court, however, refused to charge the jury that it must find some
"clear and present danger," and the Supreme Court of Illinois
sustained conviction because, in its opinion, the words used had a
tendency to cause a breach of the peace.
Referring to the clear and present danger doctrine in Dennis
v. United States, 341 U. S. 494 , 341 U. S. 568 ,
I said:
"I would save it, unmodified, for application as a 'rule of
reason' in the kind of case for which it was devised. When the
issue is criminality of a hotheaded speech on a street corner, or
circulation of a few incendiary pamphlets, or parading by some
zealots behind a red flag, or refusal of a handful of school
children to salute our flag, it is not beyond the capacity of the
judicial process to gather, comprehend, and weigh the necessary
materials for decision whether it is a clear and present danger
of Page 343 U. S. 303 substantive evil or a harmless letting off of steam. It is not a
prophecy, for the danger in such cases has matured by the time of
trial or it was never present. The test applies and has meaning
where a conviction is sought to be based on a speech or writing
which does not directly or explicitly advocate a crime but to which
such tendency is sought to be attributed by construction or by
implication from external circumstances. The formula in such cases
favors freedoms that are vital to our society, and, even if
sometimes applied too generously, the consequences cannot be grave.
. . ."
Not the least of the virtues of this formula in such tendency
cases is that it compels the prosecution to make up its mind what
particular evil it sought or is seeking to prevent. It must relate
its interference with speech or press to some identifiable evil to
be prevented. Words on their own account are not to be punished in
such cases, but are reachable only as the root of punishable
evils.
Punishment of printed words, based on their tendency either to
cause breach of the peace or injury to persons or groups, in my
opinion, is justifiable only if the prosecution survives the "clear
and present danger" test. It is the most just and workable standard
yet evolved for determining criminality of words whose injurious or
inciting tendencies are not demonstrated by the event but are
ascribed to them on the basis or probabilities.
Its application is important in this case because it takes
account of the particular form, time, place, and manner of
communication in question.
"The moving picture screen, the radio, the newspaper, the
handbill, the sound truck and the street corner orator have
differing natures, values, abuses and dangers. Each, in my view, is
a law unto itself. . . ." Kovacs v. Cooper, 336 U. S. 77 , 336 U. S. 97 . It
would consider whether a leaflet is so emotionally exciting to
immediate action as the spoken word, especially Page 343 U. S. 304 the incendiary street or public speech. Terminiello v. City
of Chicago, 337 U. S. 1 , 337 U. S. 13 ; Kunz v. New York, 340 U. S. 290 , 340 U. S. 295 .
It will inquire whether this publication was obviously so foul and
extreme as to defeat its own ends, whether its appeals for money --
which has a cooling effect on many persons -- would not negative
its inflammatory effect, whether it would not impress the passer-by
as the work of an irresponsible who needed mental examination.
One of the merits of the clear and present danger test is that
the triers of fact would take into account the realities of race
relations and any smouldering fires to be fanned into holocausts.
Such consideration might well warrant a conviction here when it
would not in another and different environment.
Group libel statutes represent a commendable desire to reduce
sinister abuses of our freedoms of expression -- abuses which I
have had occasion to learn can tear apart a society, brutalize its
dominant elements, and persecute, even to extermination, its
minorities. While laws or prosecutions might not alleviate racial
or sectarian hatreds and may even invest scoundrels with a specious
martyrdom, I should be loath to foreclose the States from a
considerable latitude of experimentation in this field. Such
efforts, if properly applied, do not justify frenetic forebodings
of crushed liberty. But these acts present most difficult policy
and technical problems, as thoughtful writers who have canvassed
the problem more comprehensively than is appropriate in a judicial
opinion have well pointed out. [ Footnote 5/21 ]
No group interest in any particular prosecution should forget
that the shoe may be on the other foot in some prosecution
tomorrow. In these, as in other matters, our Page 343 U. S. 305 guiding spirit should be that each freedom is balanced with a
responsibility, and every power of the State must be checked with
safeguards. Such is the spirit of our American law of criminal
libel, which concedes the power to the State, but only as a power
restrained by recognition of individual rights. I cannot escape the
conclusion that, as the Act has been applied in this case, it lost
sight of that rights.
[ Footnote 5/1 ]
First Amendment: "Congress shall make no law . . . abridging the
freedom of speech, or of the press. . . ." Fourteenth Amendment: "
. . . nor shall any State deprive any person of life, liberty, or
property, without due process of law. . . ."
[ Footnote 5/2 ]
1 Stat. 596 (1798) § 2:
" And be it further enacted, That if any person shall
write, print, utter or publish . . . any false, scandalous and
malicious writing or writings against the government of the United
States, or either house of the Congress of the United States, or
the President of the United States, with intent to defame the said
government, or either house of the said Congress, or the said
President, or to bring them, or either of them, into contempt or
disrepute . . . , such person . . . shall be punished by a fine not
exceeding two thousand dollars, and by imprisonment not exceeding
two years."
Section 3:
". . . it shall be lawful for the defendant . . . to give in
evidence in his defence, the truth of the matter contained in the
publication charged as a libel. And the jury who shall try the
cause shall have a right to determine the law and the fact, under
the direction of the court, as in other cases."
[ Footnote 5/3 ] Abrams v. United States, 250 U.
S. 616 , 250 U. S.
630 .
[ Footnote 5/4 ] United States v. Smith, 173 F. 227. In discharging the
defendants, Judge Anderson said:
"To my mind, that man has read the history of our institutions
to little purpose who does not look with grave apprehension upon
the possibility of the success of a proceeding such as this. If the
history of liberty means anything, if constitutional guaranties are
worth anything, this proceeding must fail."
"If the prosecuting officers have the authority to select the
tribunal, if there be more than one tribunal to select from, if the
government has that power, and can drag citizens from distant
states to the capital of the nation, there to be tried, then, as
Judge Cooley says, this is a strange result of a revolution where
one of the grievances complained of was the assertion of the right
to send parties abroad for trial."
173 F. at 232.
[ Footnote 5/5 ]
Riesman, "Group Libel," 42 Col.L.Rev. 727, 748. See
also 87 Cong.Rec. 5830-5841.
[ Footnote 5/6 ]
The following is a list of such state constitutional provisions,
coupled with the year of the adoption of the constitution in which
they are contained: Alabama, 1901, Art. I, §§ 4, 12; Arizona, 1912,
Art. II, § 6; Arkansas, 1874, Art. II, § 6; California, 1879, Art.
I, § 9; Colorado, 1876, Art. II, § 10; Delaware, 1897, Art. I, § 5;
Florida, 1887, Declaration of Rights, § 13; Georgia, 1945, Art. I,
§ 1, par. 15; Idaho, 1890, Art. I, § 9; Illinois, 1870, Art. II, §
4; Indiana, 1851, Art. I, § 9; Iowa, 1857, Art. I, § 7, I.C.A.;
Kansas, 1859, Bill of Rights, § 11; Kentucky, 1891, §§ 8, 9;
Louisiana, 1921, Art. I, §3; Maine, 1876, Art. I, § 4; Maryland,
1867, Declaration of Rights, Art. 40; Michigan, 1908, Art. II, § 4;
Minnesota, 1857, Art. I, § 3; Mississippi, 1890, Art. III, § 13;
Missouri, 1945, Art. I, § 8; Montana, 1889, Art. III, § 10;
Nebraska, 1875, Art. I, § 5; Nevada, 1864, Art. I, § 9; New Jersey,
1947, Art. I, par. 6; New Mexico, 1912, Art. II, § 17; New York,
1938, Art. I, § 8; North Carolina, 1876, Art. I, § 20; North
Dakota, 1889, Art. I, § 9; Ohio, 1851, Art. I, § 11; Oklahoma,
1907, Art. II, § 22; Oregon, 1859, Art. I, § 8; Pennsylvania, 1874,
Art. I, § 7; Rhode Island, 1843, Art. I, § 20; South Dakota, 1889,
Art. VI, § 5; Tennessee, 1870, Art. I, § 19; Texas, 1876, Art. I, §
8; Utah, 1895, Art. I, § 15; Virginia, 1902, Art. I, § 12;
Washington, 1889, Art. I, § 5; West Virginia, 1872, Art. III, § 7;
Wisconsin, 1848, Art. I, § 3; Wyoming, 1889, Art. I, § 20.
[ Footnote 5/7 ]
Congress required that reconstructed States approve state
constitutions consistent with the Federal Constitution, and also
that each State ratify the Fourteenth Amendment. Examples of state
constitutional provisions expressly referring to libel, but which
constitutions were nevertheless approved by Congress, follow:
Arkansas: Const.1868, Art. I, § 2 provides that truth coupled with
good motives shall be a complete defense to a criminal libel
prosecution; Arkansas, readmitted by 15 Stat. 72 (1868); Florida:
Const. 1868, Art. I, § 10, provides that truth coupled with good
motives shall be a complete defense to a criminal libel
prosecution; Florida, readmitted by 15 Stat. 73 (1868);
Mississippi: Const.1868, Art. I, § 4 enacts Fox's Libel Act in
substance; Mississippi, readmitted by 16 Stat. 67 (1870); South
Carolina: Const.1868, Art. I, § 8 enacts Fox's Libel Act in
substance, and provides that truth and good motives shall be a
complete defense to a criminal libel prosecution; South Carolina,
readmitted by 15 Stat. 73 (1868); Texas: Const. 1868, Art. I, § 6
enacts Fox's Libel Act in substance; Texas, readmitted by 16 Stat.
80 (1870).
[ Footnote 5/8 ]
In the case of States erected out of the public domain, one of
two procedures was generally followed. Either Congress would itself
enact a statute admitting a particular State, stating therein that
the constitution of the State in question was consistent with the
Federal Constitution, or else the Congressional Act would provide
that the State would be admitted upon its adoption of a
constitution consistent with the Federal Constitution. In the
latter case, the actual admission occurred by proclamation of the
President.
Colorado: Art. II, § 10 enacts Fox's Libel Act in substance, and
provides that truth and good motives shall constitute a complete
defense in a libel prosecution; admitted by 18 Stat. 474 (1875), 19
Stat. 665 (1876); Montana: Art. III, § 10 enacts Fox's Libel Act in
substance; admitted by 25 Stat. 676 (1889), 26 Stat. 1551 (1889);
New Mexico: Art. II, § 17 provides that truth and good motives
shall constitute a complete defense to a criminal libel
prosecution; admitted by 36 Stat. 557 (1910), 37 Stat. 39 (1911);
Utah: Art. I, § 15, like Colorado provisions; admitted by 28 Stat.
107 (1894), 29 Stat. 876 (1896); Wyoming: Art. I, § 20, like
Colorado provisions; admitted by 26 Stat. 222 (1890).
[ Footnote 5/9 ] See Fairman and Morrison, Does the Fourteenth Amendment
Incorporate the Bill of Rights? 2 Stan.L.Rev. 5-173.
[ Footnote 5/10 ]
3 Johns.Cas. 337, 413.
[ Footnote 5/11 ]
Const.1821, Art. VII, § 8; Const.1846, Art. I, § 8; Const.1894,
Art. I, § 8; Const.1938, Art. I, § 8.
[ Footnote 5/12 ]
Arkansas, California, Colorado, Delaware, Florida, Iowa, Kansas,
Maine, Mississippi, Missouri, Montana, Nebraska, Nevada, New
Jersey, New Mexico, North Dakota, Ohio, Oklahoma, Pennsylvania,
Tennessee, Texas, Utah, Wisconsin, and Wyoming. For citations to
article and section, see 343
U.S. 250 fn5/6|>n. 6, supra. [ Footnote 5/13 ]
Arizona, Georgia, Idaho, Kentucky, Louisiana, Maryland,
Michigan, Minnesota, North Carolina, Oregon, Virginia, and
Washington. The Georgia provision, Const.1945, Art. I, § 1, par.
15, representative of the rest, reads: " . . . any person may
speak, write and publish his sentiments, on all subjects, being
responsible for the abuse of that liberty." For citations to
article and section, see 343
U.S. 250 fn5/6|>n. 6, supra. [ Footnote 5/14 ]
Alabama, Illinois, Indiana, Rhode Island, and West Virginia. For
citations to article and section, see 343
U.S. 250 fn5/6|>n. 6, supra. [ Footnote 5/15 ]
Connecticut, Const.1818, Art. I, § 6; New Hampshire, Const.1784,
Part I, Art. 22; South Carolina, Const.1895, Art. I, § 4; Vermont,
Const.1793, c. I, Art. 13. The Massachusetts provision, Const.1780,
Part I, Art. XVI reads as follows: "The liberty of the press is
essential to the security of freedom in a state; it ought not,
therefore, to be restrained in this Commonwealth."
[ Footnote 5/16 ] State v. Gardner, 112 Conn. 121, 151 A. 349; Commonwealth v. Szliakys, 254 Mass. 424, 150 N.E. 190; Noyes v. Thorpe, 73 N.H. 481, 62 A. 787, 12 L.R.A., N.S.,
636; State v. Gurry, 163 S.C. 1, 161 S.E. 191; State
v. Colby, 98 Vt. 96, 126 A. 510. Decisional law of other
States is collected in Note, 1 Bflo.L.Rev. 258.
[ Footnote 5/17 ]
Lee, "A History of American Journalism" (Garden City, 1923).
[ Footnote 5/18 ] Schenck v. United States, 249 U. S.
47 , 249 U. S.
52 .
[ Footnote 5/19 ] Gitlow v. New York, 268 U. S. 652 , 268 U. S.
672 .
[ Footnote 5/20 ]
It appears that group libel was not unknown to common law. See Scott, Publishing False News, 30 Can.B.Rev. 37,
42-43.
[ Footnote 5/21 ]
Tannenhaus, Group Libel, 35 Cornell L.Q. 261; Riesman, Democracy
and Defamation: Control of Group Libel, 42 Col.L.Rev. 727; see
also Note, 1 Bflo.L.Rev. 258. | Here is a summary of the Supreme Court case Beauharnais v. Illinois (1952):
The Supreme Court upheld an Illinois statute that criminalized the distribution of materials that exposed a group to contempt or ridicule based on race, color, creed, or religion. Beauharnais was convicted for distributing anti-Black leaflets in Chicago and argued that the Illinois statute violated his freedom of speech and press rights under the Fourteenth Amendment. The Court rejected this argument, finding that the statute did not violate the Constitution as applied in this case. The Court also ruled that the statute was not void for vagueness and distinguished this case from previous cases involving restrictions on free speech. The Court further held that Beauharnais could not raise hypothetical defenses of "fair comment" or privilege and that his offer of proof was rightfully rejected by the trial court as it did not satisfy the requirement of good motives and justifiable ends under Illinois law. Finally, the Court did not consider the issue of whether the jury should have been instructed to find a "clear and present danger" of a substantial evil, as libelous speech is not constitutionally protected. |
Free Speech | Joseph Burstyn, Inc. v. Wilson | https://supreme.justia.com/cases/federal/us/343/495/ | U.S. Supreme Court Joseph Burstyn, Inc. v. Wilson, 343
U.S. 495 (1952) Joseph Burstyn, Inc. v.
Wilson No. 522 Argued April 24, 1952 Decided May 26, 1952 343
U.S. 495 APPEAL FROM THE COURT OF APPEALS OF
NEW YORK Syllabus Provisions of the New York Education Law which forbid the
commercial showing of any motion picture film without a license and
authorize denial of a license on a censor's conclusion that a film
is "sacrilegious," held void as a prior restraint on
freedom of speech and of the press under the First Amendment, made
applicable to the states by the Fourteenth Amendment. Pp. 343 U. S.
497 -506.
1. Expression by means of motion pictures is included within the
free speech and free press guaranty of the First and Fourteenth
Amendments. Pp. 343 U. S.
499 -502.
(a) It cannot be doubted that motion pictures are a significant
medium for the communication of ideas. Their importance as an organ
of public opinion is not lessened by the fact that they are
designed to entertain as well as to inform. P. 343 U. S.
501 .
(b) That the production, distribution and exhibition of motion
pictures is a large-scale business conducted for private profit
does not prevent motion pictures from being a form of expression
whose liberty is safeguarded by the First Amendment. Pp. 343 U. S.
501 -502.
(c) Even if it be assumed that motion pictures possess a greater
capacity for evil, particularly among the youth of a community,
than other modes of expression, it does not follow that they are
not entitled to the protection of the First Amendment or may be
subjected to substantially unbridled censorship. P. 343 U. S.
502 .
(d) To the extent that language in the opinion in Mutual
Film Corp. v. Industrial Comm'n, 236 U.
S. 230 , is out of harmony with the views here set forth,
it is no longer adhered to. P. 343 U. S.
502 .
2. Under the First and Fourteenth Amendments, a state may not
place a prior restraint on the showing of a motion picture film on
the basis of a censor's conclusion that it is "sacrilegious." Pp. 343 U. S.
502 -506.
(a) Though the Constitution does not require absolute freedom to
exhibit every motion picture of every kind at all times and all
places, there is no justification in this case for making an Page 343 U. S. 496 exception to the basic principles of freedom of expression
previously announced by this Court with respect to other forms of
expression. Pp. 343 U. S.
502 -503.
(b) Such a prior restraint as that involved here is a form of
infringement upon freedom of expression to be especially condemned. Near v. Minnesota, 283 U. S. 697 . Pp. 343 U. S.
503 -504.
(c) New York cannot vest in a censor such unlimited restraining
control over motion pictures as that involved in the broad
requirement that they not be "sacrilegious." Pp. 343 U. S.
504 -505.
(d) From the standpoint of freedom of speech and the press, a
state has no legitimate interest in protecting any or all religions
from views distasteful to them which is sufficient to justify prior
restraints upon the expression of those views. P. 343 U. S.
505 . 303 N.Y.
242 , 101 N.E.2d 665, reversed.
The New York Appellate Division sustained revocation of a
license for the showing of a motion picture under § 122 of the New
York Education Law on the ground that it was "sacrilegious." 278
App.Div. 253, 104 N.Y.S.2d 740. The Court of Appeals of New York
affirmed. 303 N.Y.
242 , 101 N.E.2d 665. On appeal to this Court under 28 U.S.C. §
1257(2), reversed, p. 343 U. S.
506 . Page 343 U. S. 497 MR. JUSTICE CLARK delivered the opinion of the Court.
The issue here is the constitutionality, under the First and
Fourteenth Amendments, of a New York statute which permits the
banning of motion picture films on the ground that they are
"sacrilegious." That statute makes it unlawful
"to exhibit, or to sell, lease or lend for exhibition at any
place of amusement for pay or in connection with any business in
the state of New York, any motion picture film or reel [with
specified exceptions not relevant here], unless there is at the
time in full force and effect a valid license or permit therefor of
the education department. . . . [ Footnote 1 ]"
The statute further provides:
"The director of the [motion picture] division [of the education
department] or, when authorized by the regents, the officers of a
local office or bureau shall cause to be promptly examined every
motion picture film submitted to them as herein required, and
unless such film or a part thereof is obscene, indecent, immoral,
inhuman, sacrilegious, or is of such a character that its
exhibition would tend to corrupt morals or incite to crime, shall
issue a license therefor. If such director or, when so authorized,
such officer shall not license any film submitted, he shall furnish
to the applicant therefor a written report of the reasons for his
refusal and a description of each rejected part of a film not
rejected in toto. [ Footnote
2 ]"
Appellant is a corporation engaged in the business of
distributing motion pictures. It owns the exclusive rights to
distribute throughout the United States a film produced in Italy
entitled "The Miracle." On November 30, 1950, after having examined
the picture, the motion picture division of the New York education
department, Page 343 U. S. 498 acting under the statute quoted above, issued to appellant a
license authorizing exhibition of "The Miracle," with English
subtitles, as one part of a trilogy called "Ways of Love."
[ Footnote 3 ] Thereafter, for a
period of approximately eight weeks, "Ways of Love" was exhibited
publicly in a motion picture theater in New York City under an
agreement between appellant and the owner of the theater whereby
appellant received a stated percentage of the admission price.
During this period, the New York State Board of Regents, which
by statute is made the head of the education department, [ Footnote 4 ] received "hundreds of
letters, telegrams, post cards, affidavits and other
communications" both protesting against and defending the public
exhibition of "The Miracle." [ Footnote 5 ] The Chancellor of the Board of Regents
requested three members of the Board to view the picture and to
make a report to the entire Board. After viewing the film, this
committee reported to the Board that, in its opinion, there was
basis for the claim that the picture was "sacrilegious."
Thereafter, on January 19, 1951, the Regents directed appellant to
show cause, at a hearing to be held on January 30, why its license
to show "The Miracle" should not be rescinded on that ground.
Appellant appeared at this hearing, which was conducted by the same
three-member committee of the Regents which had previously viewed
the picture, and challenged the jurisdiction of the committee and
of the Regents to proceed with the case. With the consent of the
committee, various interested persons and Page 343 U. S. 499 organizations submitted to it briefs and exhibits bearing upon
the merits of the picture and upon the constitutional and statutory
questions involved. On February 16, 1951, the Regents, after
viewing "The Miracle," determined that it was "sacrilegious," and
for that reason ordered the Commissioner of Education to rescind
appellant's license to exhibit the picture. The Commissioner did
so.
Appellant brought the present action in the New York courts to
review the determination of the Regents. [ Footnote 6 ] Among the claims advanced by appellant were
(1) that the statute violates the Fourteenth Amendment as a prior
restraint upon freedom of speech and of the press; (2) that it is
invalid under the same Amendment as a violation of the guaranty of
separate church and state and as a prohibition of the free exercise
of religion; and, (3) that the term "sacrilegious" is so vague and
indefinite as to offend due process. The Appellate Division
rejected all of appellant's contentions and upheld the Regents'
determination. 278 App.Div. 253, 104 N.Y.S.2d 740. On appeal the
New York Court of Appeals, two judges dissenting, affirmed the
order of the Appellate Division. 303 N.Y.
242 , 101 N.E.2d 665. The case is here on appeal. 28 U.S.C. §
1257(2).
As we view the case, we need consider only appellant's
contention that the New York statute is an unconstitutional
abridgment of free speech and a free press. In Mutual Film
Corp. v. Industrial Comm'n, 236 U. S. 230 (1915), a distributor of motion pictures sought to enjoin the
enforcement of an Ohio statute which required the prior approval of
a board of censors before any motion Page 343 U. S. 500 picture could be publicly exhibited in the state, and which
directed the board to approve only such films as it adjudged to be
"of a moral, educational or amusing and harmless character." The
statute was assailed in part as an unconstitutional abridgment of
the freedom of the press guaranteed by the First and Fourteenth
Amendments. The District Court rejected this contention, stating
that the first eight Amendments were not a restriction on state
action. 215 F. 138, 141 (D.C.N.D. Ohio 1914). On appeal to this
Court, plaintiff in its brief abandoned this claim and contended
merely that the statute in question violated the freedom of speech
and publication guaranteed by the Constitution of Ohio. In
affirming the decree of the District Court denying injunctive
relief, this Court stated:
"It cannot be put out of view that the exhibition of moving
pictures is a business pure and simple, originated and conducted
for profit, like other spectacles, not to be regarded, nor intended
to be regarded by the Ohio constitution, we think, as part of the
press of the country or as organs of public opinion. [ Footnote 7 ]"
In a series of decisions beginning with Gitlow v. New
York, 268 U. S. 652 (1925), this Court held that the liberty of speech and of the press
which the First Amendment guarantees against abridgment by the
federal government is within the liberty safeguarded by the Due
Process Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment from invasion by state
action. [ Footnote 8 ] That
principle has been Page 343 U. S. 501 followed and reaffirmed to the present day. Since this series of
decisions came after the Mutual decision, the present case
is the first to present squarely to us the question whether motion
pictures are within the ambit of protection which the First
Amendment, through the Fourteenth, secures to any form of "speech"
or "the press." [ Footnote
9 ]
It cannot be doubted that motion pictures are a significant
medium for the communication of ideas. They may affect public
attitudes and behavior in a variety of ways, ranging from direct
espousal of a political or social doctrine to the subtle shaping of
thought which characterizes all artistic expression. [ Footnote 10 ] The importance of
motion pictures as an organ of public opinion is not lessened by
the fact that they are designed to entertain as well as to inform.
As was said in Winters v. New York, 333 U.
S. 507 , 333 U. S. 510 (1948):
"The line between the informing and the entertaining is too
elusive for the protection of that basic right [a free press].
Everyone is familiar with instances of propaganda through fiction.
What is one man's amusement, teaches another's doctrine."
It is urged that motion pictures do not fall within the First
Amendment's aegis because their production, distribution, and
exhibition is a large-scale business conducted for private profit.
We cannot agree. That books, newspapers, and magazines are
published and sold for profit does not prevent them from being a
form of expression whose liberty is safeguarded by the First
Amendment. [ Footnote 11 ] Page 343 U. S. 502 We fail to see why operation for profit should have any
different effect in the case of motion pictures.
It is further urged that motion pictures possess a greater
capacity for evil, particularly among the youth of a community,
than other modes of expression. Even if one were to accept this
hypothesis, it does not follow that motion pictures should be
disqualified from First Amendment protection. If there be capacity
for evil it may be relevant in determining the permissible scope of
community control, but it does not authorize substantially
unbridled censorship such as we have here.
For the foregoing reasons, we conclude that expression by means
of motion pictures is included within the free speech and free
press guaranty of the First and Fourteenth Amendments. To the
extent that language in the opinion in Mutual Film Corp. v.
Industrial Comm'n, supra, is out of harmony with the views
here set forth, we no longer adhere to it. [ Footnote 12 ]
To hold that liberty of expression by means of motion pictures
is guaranteed by the First and Fourteenth Amendments, however, is
not the end of our problem. It does not follow that the
Constitution requires absolute freedom to exhibit every motion
picture of every kind at all times and all places. That much is
evident from the series of decisions of this Court with respect to
other Page 343 U. S. 503 media of communication of ideas. [ Footnote 13 ] Nor does it follow that motion pictures are
necessarily subject to the precise rules governing any other
particular method of expression. Each method tends to present its
own peculiar problems. But the basic principles of freedom of
speech and the press, like the First Amendment's command, do not
vary. Those principles, as they have frequently been enunciated by
this Court, make freedom of expression the rule. There is no
justification in this case for making an exception to that
rule.
The statute involved here does not seek to punish, as a past
offense, speech or writing falling within the permissible scope of
subsequent punishment. On the contrary, New York requires that
permission to communicate ideas be obtained in advance from state
officials who judge the content of the words and pictures sought to
be communicated. This Court recognized many years ago that such a
previous restraint is a form of infringement upon freedom of
expression to be especially condemned. Near v. Minnesota ex
rel. Olson, 283 U. S. 697 (1931). The Court there recounted the history which indicates that
a major purpose of the First Amendment guaranty of a free press was
to prevent prior restraints upon publication, although it was
carefully pointed out that the liberty of the press is not limited
to that protection. [ Footnote
14 ] It was further stated that "the protection even as to
previous restraint is not absolutely unlimited. But the limitation
has been recognized only Page 343 U. S. 504 in exceptional cases." Id. at 283 U. S. 716 .
In the light of the First Amendment's history and of the Near decision, the State has a heavy burden to demonstrate
that the limitation challenged here presents such an exceptional
case.
New York's highest court says there is "nothing mysterious"
about the statutory provision applied in this case:
"It is simply this: that no religion, as that word is understood
by the ordinary, reasonable person, shall be treated with contempt,
mockery, scorn and ridicule. . . . [ Footnote 15 ]"
This is far from the kind of narrow exception to freedom of
expression which a state may carve out to satisfy the adverse
demands of other interests of society. [ Footnote 16 ] In seeking to apply the broad and
all-inclusive definition of "sacrilegious" given by the New York
courts, the censor is set adrift upon a boundless sea amid a myriad
of conflicting currents of religious views, with no Page 343 U. S. 505 charts but those provided by the most vocal and powerful
orthodoxies. New York cannot vest such unlimited restraining
control over motion pictures in a censor. Cf. Kunz v. New
York, 340 U. S. 290 (1951). [ Footnote 17 ] Under
such a standard the most careful and tolerant censor would find it
virtually impossible to avoid favoring one religion over another,
and he would be subject to an inevitable tendency to ban the
expression of unpopular sentiments sacred to a religious minority.
Application of the "sacrilegious" test, in these or other respects,
might raise substantial questions under the First Amendment's
guaranty of separate church and state with freedom of worship for
all. [ Footnote 18 ] However,
from the standpoint of freedom of speech and the press, it is
enough to point out that the state has no legitimate interest in
protecting any or all religions from views distasteful to them
which is sufficient to justify prior restraints upon the expression
of those views. It is not the business of government in our nation
to suppress real or imagined attacks upon a particular religious
doctrine, whether they appear in publications, speeches, or motion
pictures. [ Footnote 19 ]
Since the term "sacrilegious" is the sole standard under attack
here, it is not necessary for us to decide, for example, Page 343 U. S. 506 whether a state may censor motion pictures under a clearly drawn
statute designed and applied to prevent the showing of obscene
films. That is a very different question from the one now before
us. [ Footnote 20 ] We hold
only that, under the First and Fourteenth Amendments, a state may
not ban a film on the basis of a censor's conclusion that it is
"sacrilegious." Reversed. [ Footnote 1 ]
McKinney's N.Y. Laws, 1947, Education Law, § 129.
[ Footnote 2 ] Id., § 122
[ Footnote 3 ]
The motion picture division had previously issued a license for
exhibition of "The Miracle" without English subtitles, but the film
was never shown under that license.
[ Footnote 4 ]
McKinney's N.Y.Laws, 1947, Education Law, § 101; see
also N.Y.Const., Art. V, § 4.
[ Footnote 5 ]
Stipulation between appellant and appellee, R. 86.
[ Footnote 6 ]
The action was brought under Article 78 of the New York Civil
Practice Act, Gilbert-Bliss N.Y.Civ.Prac., Vol. 6B, 1944, 1949
Supp., § 1283 et seq. See also McKinney's
N.Y.Laws, 1947, Education Law, § 124.
[ Footnote 7 ]
236 U.S. at 236 U. S.
244 .
[ Footnote 8 ] Gitlow v. New York, 268 U. S. 652 , 268 U. S. 666 (1925); Stromberg v. California, 283 U.
S. 359 , 283 U. S. 368 (1931); Near v. Minnesota ex rel. Olson, 283 U.
S. 697 , 283 U. S. 707 (1931); Grosjean v. American Press Co., 297 U.
S. 233 , 297 U. S. 244 (1936); De Jonge v. Oregon, 299 U.
S. 353 , 299 U. S. 364 (1937); Lovell v. Griffin, 303 U.
S. 444 , 303 U. S. 450 (1938); Schneider v . State, 308 U.
S. 147 , 308 U. S. 160 (1939).
[ Footnote 9 ] See Lovell v. Griffin, 303 U.
S. 444 , 303 U. S. 452 (1938).
[ Footnote 10 ] See Inglis, Freedom of the Movies (1947), 20-24;
Klapper, The Effects of Mass Media (1950), passim; Note,
Motion Pictures and the First Amendment, 60 Yale L.J. 696, 70708
(1951), and sources cited therein.
[ Footnote 11 ] See Grosjean v. American Press Co., 297 U.
S. 233 (1936); Thomas v. Collins, 323 U.
S. 516 , 323 U. S. 531 (1945).
[ Footnote 12 ] See United States v. Paramount Pictures, Inc., 334 U. S. 131 , 334 U. S. 166 (1948):
"We have no doubt that moving pictures, like newspapers and
radio, arc included in the press whose freedom is guaranteed by the
First Amendment."
It is not without significance that talking pictures were first
produced in 1926, eleven years after the Mutual decision.
Hampton, A History of the Movies (1931), 382-383.
[ Footnote 13 ] E.g., Feiner v. New York, 340 U.
S. 315 (1951); Kovacs v. Cooper, 336 U. S.
77 (1949); Chaplinsky v. New Hampshire, 315 U. S. 568 (1942); Cox v. New Hampshire, 312 U.
S. 569 (1941).
[ Footnote 14 ] Near v. Minnesota ex rel. Olson, 283 U.
S. 697 , 283 U. S.
713 -719 (1931); see also Lovell v. Griffin, 303 U. S. 444 , 303 U. S.
451 -452 (1938); Grosjean v. American Press Co., 297 U. S. 233 , 297 U. S.
245 -250 (1936); Patterson v. Colorado, 205 U. S. 454 , 205 U. S. 462 (1907).
[ Footnote 15 ] 303 N.Y.
242 , 258, 101 N.E.2d 665, 672. At another point, the Court of
Appeals gave "sacrilegious" the following definition: "the act of
violating or profaning anything sacred." Id. at 255, 101
N.E.2d at 670. The Court of Appeals also approved the Appellate
Division's interpretation:
"As the court below said of the statute in question, 'All it
purports to do is to bar a visual caricature of religious beliefs
held sacred by one sect or another. . . .'" Id. at 258, 101 N.E.2d at 672. Judge Fuld, dissenting,
concluded from all the statements in the majority opinion that
"the basic criterion appears to be whether the film treats a
religious theme in such a manner as to offend the religious beliefs
of any group of persons. If the film does have that effect, and it
is 'offered as a form of entertainment,' it apparently falls within
the statutory ban regardless of the sincerity and good faith of the
producer of the film, no matter how temperate the treatment of the
theme, and no matter how unlikely a public disturbance or breach of
the peace. The drastic nature of such a ban is highlighted by the
fact that the film in question makes no direct attack on, or
criticism of, any religious dogma or principle, and it is not
claimed to be obscene, scurrilous, intemperate or abusive." Id. at 271-272, 101 N.E.2d at 680.
[ Footnote 16 ] Cf. Thornhill v. Alabama, 310 U. S.
88 , 310 U. S. 97 (1940); Stromberg v. California, 283 U.
S. 359 , 283 U. S.
369 -370 (1931).
[ Footnote 17 ] Cf. Niemotko v. Maryland, 340 U.
S. 268 (1951); Saia v. New York, 334 U.
S. 558 (1948); Largent v. Texas, 318 U.
S. 418 (1943); Lovell v. Griffin, 303 U.
S. 444 (1938).
[ Footnote 18 ] See Cantwell v. Connecticut, 310 U.
S. 296 (1940).
[ Footnote 19 ] See the following statement by Mr. Justice Roberts,
speaking for a unanimous Court in Cantwell v. Connecticut, 310 U. S. 296 , 310 U. S. 310 (1940):
"In the realm of religious faith, and in that of political
belief, sharp differences arise. In both fields, the tenets of one
man may seem the rankest error to his neighbor. To persuade others
to his own point of view, the pleader, as we know, at times,
resorts to exaggeration, to vilification of men who have been, or
are, prominent in church or state, and even to false statement. But
the people of this nation have ordained in the light of history,
that, in spite of the probability of excesses and abuses, these
liberties are, in the long view, essential to enlightened opinion
and right conduct on the part of the citizens of a democracy."
"The essential characteristic of these liberties is, that, under
their shield, many types of life, character, opinion and belief can
develop unmolested and unobstructed. Nowhere is this shield more
necessary than in our own country, for a people composed of many
races and of many creeds."
[ Footnote 20 ]
In the Near case, this Court stated that "the primary
requirements of decency may be enforced against obscene
publications." 283 U. S. 697 , 283 U. S. 716 .
In Chaplinsky v. New Hampshire, 315 U.
S. 568 , 315 U. S.
571 -572 (1942), Mr. Justice Murphy stated for a
unanimous Court:
"There are certain well defined and narrowly limited classes of
speech, the prevention and punishment of which have never been
thought to raise any Constitutional problem. These include the lewd
and obscene, the profane, the libelous, and the insulting or
'fighting' words -- those which, by their very utterance, inflict
injury or tend to incite an immediate breach of the peace." But see Kovacs v. Cooper, 336 U. S.
77 , 336 U. S. 82 (1949):
"When ordinances undertake censorship of speech or religious
practices before permitting their exercise, the Constitution
forbids their enforcement."
MR. JUSTICE REED, concurring in the judgment of the Court.
Assuming that a state may establish a system for the licensing
of motion pictures, an issue not foreclosed by the Court's opinion,
our duty requires us to examine the facts of the refusal of a
license in each case to determine Page 343 U. S. 507 whether the principles of the First Amendment have been honored.
This film does not seem to me to be of a character that the First
Amendment permits a state to exclude from public view.
MR. JUSTICE FRANKFURTER, whom MR. JUSTICE JACKSON joins,
concurring in the judgment of the Court; MR. JUSTICE BURTON, having
concurred in the opinion of the Court, also joins this opinion.
A practised hand has thus summarized the story of "The Miracle":
[ Footnote 2/1 ]
"A poor, simple-minded girl is tending a herd of goats on a
mountainside one day when a bearded stranger passes. Suddenly it
strikes her fancy that he is St. Joseph, her favorite saint, and
that he has come to take her to heaven, where she will be happy and
free. While she pleads with him to transport her, the stranger
gently plies the girl with wine, and when she is in a state of
tumult, he apparently ravishes her. (This incident in the story is
only briefly and discreetly implied.)"
"The girl awakens later, finds the stranger gone, and climbs
down from the mountain not knowing whether he was real or a dream.
She meets an old priest who tells her that it is quite possible
that she did see a saint, but a younger priest scoffs at the
notion. 'Materialist,' the old priest says."
"There follows now a brief sequence -- intended to be symbolic,
obviously -- in which the girl is reverently sitting with other
villagers in church. Moved by a whim of appetite, she snitches an
apple from the basket of a woman next to her. When she leaves the
church, a cackling beggar tries to make her share Page 343 U. S. 508 the apple with him, but she chases him away, as by habit, and
munches the fruit contentedly."
"Then, one day, while tending the village youngsters as their
mothers work at the vines, the girl faints and the women discover
that she is going to have a child. Frightened and bewildered, she
suddenly murmurs, 'It is the grace of God,' and she runs to the
church in great excitement, looks for the statue of St. Joseph, and
then prostrates herself on the floor."
"Thereafter she meekly refuses to do any menial work, and the
housewives humor her gently, but the young people are not so kind.
In a scene of brutal torment, they first flatter and laughingly
mock her, then they cruelly shove and hit her and clamp a basin as
a halo on her head. Even abused by the beggars, the poor girl
gathers together her pitiful rags and sadly departs from the
village to live alone in a cave."
"When she feels her time coming upon her, she starts back
towards the village. But then she sees the crowds in the streets;
dark memories haunt her; so she turns towards a church on a high
hill and instinctively struggles towards it, crying desperately to
God. A goat is her sole companion. She drinks water dripping from a
rock. And when she comes to the church and finds the door locked,
the goat attracts her to a small side door. Inside the church, the
poor girl braces herself for her labor pains. There is a dissolve,
and when we next see her sad face, in close-up, it is full of a
tender light. There is the cry of an unseen baby. The girl reaches
towards it and murmurs, 'My son, My love, My flesh!'"
"The Miracle" -- a film lasting forty minutes -- was produced in
Italy by Roberto Rossellini. Anna Magnani played the lead as the
demented goat-tender. It was first shown at the Venice Film
Festival in August, 1948, Page 343 U. S. 509 combined with another moving picture, "L'Umano Voce," into a
diptych called "Amore." According to an affidavit from the Director
of that Festival, if the motion picture had been "blasphemous," it
would have been barred by the Festival Committee. In a review of
the film in L'Osservatore Romano, the organ of the Vatican, its
film critic, Piero Regnoli, wrote:
"Opinions may vary, and questions may arise -- even serious ones
-- of a religious nature (not to be diminished by the fact that the
woman portrayed is mad [because] the author who attributed madness
to her is not mad). . . . [ Footnote
2/2 ]"
While acknowledging that there were "passages of undoubted
cinematic distinction," Regnoli criticized the film as being "on
such a pretentiously cerebral plane that it reminds one of the
early d'Annunzio." The Vatican newspaper's critic concluded: "we
continue to believe in Rossellini's art, and we look forward to his
next achievement." [ Footnote 2/3 ]
In October, 1948, a month after the Rome premiere of "The Miracle,"
the Vatican's censorship agency, the Catholic Cinematographic
Centre, declared that the picture "constitutes in effect an
abominable profanation from religious and moral viewpoints."
[ Footnote 2/4 ] By the Lateran
agreements and the Italian Constitution, the Italian Government is
bound to bar whatever may offend the Catholic religion. However,
the Catholic Cinematographic Centre did not invoke any governmental
sanction thereby afforded. The Italian Government's censorship
agency gave "The Miracle" the regular nulla osta clearance. The film was freely shown throughout Italy, but was not
a great success. [ Footnote 2/5 ]
Italian movie critics divided in opinion. The critic for II Popolo,
speaking for the Christian Democratic Party, the Catholic Page 343 U. S. 510 party, profusely praised the picture as a "beautiful thing,
humanly felt, alive, true and without religious profanation as
someone has said, because, in our opinion, the meaning of the
characters is clear, and there is no possibility of
misunderstanding." [ Footnote 2/6 ]
Regnoli again reviewed "The Miracle" for L'Osservatore Romano.
[ Footnote 2/7 ] After criticising
the film for technical faults, he found "the most courageous and
interesting passage of Rossellini's work" in contrasting portrayals
in the film; he added: "Unfortunately, concerning morals, it is
necessary to note some slight defects." He objected to its
"carnality" and to the representation of illegitimate motherhood.
But he did not suggest that the picture was "sacrilegious." The
tone of Regnoli's critique was one of respect for Rossellini, "the
illustrious Italian producer." [ Footnote 2/8 ]
On March 2, 1949, "The Miracle" was licensed in New York State
for showing without English subtitles. [ Footnote 2/9 ] However, it was never exhibited until
after a second license was issued on November 30, 1950, for the
trilogy, "Ways of Love," combining "The Miracle" with two French
films, Jean Renoir's "A Day in the Country" and Marcel Pagnol's
"Jofroi." [ Footnote 2/10 ] All had
English subtitles. Both licenses Page 343 U. S. 511 were issued in the usual course after viewings of the picture by
the Motion Picture Division of the New York State Education
Department. The Division is directed by statute to "issue a
license"
"unless [the] film or a part thereof is obscene, indecent,
immoral, inhuman, sacrilegious, or is of such a character that its
exhibition would tend to corrupt morals or incite to crime."
N.Y. Education Law, § 122. The trilogy opened on December 12,
1950, at the Paris Theatre on 58th Street in Manhattan. It was
promptly attacked as "a sacrilegious and blasphemous mockery of
Christian religious truth" [ Footnote
2/11 ] by the National Legion of Decency, a private Catholic
organization for film censorship, whose objectives have
intermittently been approved by various non-Catholic church and
social groups since its formation in 1933. [ Footnote 2/12 ] However, the National Board of Review (a
non-industry lay organization devoted to raising the level of
motion pictures by mobilizing public opinion, under the slogan
"Selection Not Censorship") [ Footnote
2/13 ] recommended the picture as "especially worth seeing." New
York critics on the whole praised "The Miracle"; those who
dispraised did not suggest sacrilege. [ Footnote 2/14 ] On December 27, the critics selected the
"Ways of Love" as the best foreign language Page 343 U. S. 512 film in 1950. [ Footnote 2/15 ]
Meanwhile, on December 23, Edward T. McCaffrey, Commissioner of
Licenses for New York City, declared the film "officially and
personally blasphemous" and ordered it withdrawn at the risk of
suspension of the license to operate the Paris Theatre. [ Footnote 2/16 ] A week later, the program
was restored at the theatre upon the decision by the New York
Supreme Court that the City Page 343 U. S. 513 License Commissioner had exceeded his authority in that he was
without powers of movie censorship. [ Footnote 2/17 ]
Upon the failure of the License Commissioner's effort to cut off
showings of "The Miracle," the controversy took a new turn. On
Sunday, January 7, 1951, a statement of His Eminence, Francis
Cardinal Spellman, condemning the picture and calling on "all
right-thinking citizens" to unite to tighten censorship laws, was
read at all masses in St. Patrick's Cathedral. [ Footnote 2/18 ]
The views of Cardinal Spellman aroused dissent among other
devout Christians. Protestant clergymen, representing Page 343 U. S. 514 various denominations, after seeing the picture, found in it
nothing "sacrilegious or immoral to the views held by Christian men
and women," and, with a few exceptions, agreed that the film was
"unquestionably one of unusual artistic merit." [ Footnote 2/19 ]
In this estimate, some Catholic laymen concurred. [ Footnote 2/20 ] Their opinion is
represented by the comment by Otto L. Spaeth, Director of the
American Federation of Arts and prominent in Catholic lay
activities:
"At the outbreak of the controversy, I immediately arranged for
a private showing of the film. I invited a group of Catholics,
competent and respected for their writings on both religious and
cultural subjects. The essential approval of the film was
unanimous."
"There was indeed 'blasphemy' in the picture -- but it was the
blasphemy of the villagers, who stopped at nothing, not even the
mock singing of a Page 343 U. S. 515 hymn to the Virgin, in their brutal badgering of the tragic
woman. The scathing indictment of their evil behavior, implicit in
the film, was seemingly overlooked by its critics. [ Footnote 2/21 ]"
William P. Clancy, a teacher at the University of Notre Dame,
wrote in The Commonweal, the well known Catholic weekly, that "the
film is not obviously blasphemous or obscene, either in its
intention or execution." [ Footnote
2/22 ] The Commonweal itself questioned the wisdom of
transforming Church dogma which Catholics may obey as "a free act"
into state-enforced censorship for all. [ Footnote 2/23 ] Allen Tate, the well known Catholic poet
and critic, wrote:
"The picture seems to me to be superior in acting and
photography but inferior dramatically. . . . In the long run, what
Cardinal Spellman will have succeeded in doing is insulting the
intelligence and faith of American Catholics with the assumption
that a second-rate motion picture could in any way undermine their
morals or shake their faith. [ Footnote 2/24 ]"
At the time "The Miracle" was filmed, all the persons having
significant positions in the production -- producer, director, and
cast -- were Catholics. Roberto Rossellini, who had Vatican
approval in 1949 for filming a life of St. Francis, using in the
cast members of the Franciscan Page 343 U. S. 516 Order, cabled Cardinal Spellman protesting against boycott of
"The Miracle":
"In The Miracle men, are still without pity because
they still have not come back to God, but God is already present in
the faith, however confused, of that poor, persecuted woman, and
since God is wherever a human being suffers and is misunderstood, The Miracle occurs when at the birth of the child the
poor, demented woman regains sanity in her maternal love. [ Footnote 2/25 ]"
In view of the controversy thus aroused by the picture, the
Chairman of the Board of Regents appointed a committee of three
Board members to review the action of the Motion Picture Division
in granting the two licenses. After viewing the picture on Jan. 15,
1951, the committee declared it "sacrilegious." The Board four days
later issued an order to the licensees to show cause why the
licenses should not be cancelled in that the picture was
"sacrilegious." The Board of Regents rescinded the licenses on Feb.
16, 1951, saying that the "mockery or profaning of these beliefs
that are sacred to any portion of our citizenship is abhorrent to
the laws of this great State." On review the Appellate Division
upheld the Board of Regents, holding that the banning of any motion
picture "that may fairly be deemed sacrilegious to the adherents of
any religious group . . . is directly related to public peace and
order," and is not a denial of religious freedom, and that there
was "substantial evidence upon which the Regents could act." 278
App.Div. 253, 257, 258, 260, 104 N.Y.S.2d 740, 743, 744-745,
747.
The New York Court of Appeals, with one judge concurring in a
separate opinion and two others dissenting, Page 343 U. S. 517 affirmed the order of the Appellate Division. 303 N.Y.
242 , 101 N.E.2d 665. After concluding that the Board of Regents
acted within its authority and that is determination was not "one
that no reasonable mind could reach," id. at 250-255,
256-257, 101 N.E.2d 665, 667-671, the majority held, first, that
"sacrilegious" was an adequately definite standard, quoting a
definition from Funk & Wagnalls' Dictionary and referring to
opinions in this Court that, in passing used the term "profane,"
which the New York court said was a synonym of "sacrilegious";
second, that the State's assurance
"that no religion . . . shall be treated with contempt, mockery,
scorn and ridicule . . . by those engaged in selling entertainment
by way of motion pictures"
does not violate the religious guarantee of the First Amendment,
and third, that motion pictures are not entitled to the immunities
from regulation enjoyed by the press, in view of the decision in Mutual Film Corp. v. Ohio Industrial Comm'n, 236 U.
S. 230 . Id. at 255-256 [argument of counsel --
omitted], 236 U. S.
258 -260, 260 U. S.
260 -262, 101 N.E.2d 670-674. The two dissenting judges,
after dealing with a matter of local law not reviewable here, found
that the standard "sacrilegious" is unconstitutionally vague, and,
finally, that the constitutional guarantee of freedom of speech
applied equally to motion pictures, and prevented this censorship. 303 N.Y.
242 , 264, 101 N.E.2d 665, 675. Both State courts, as did this
Court, viewed "The Miracle."
Arguments by the parties and in briefs amici invite us
to pursue to their farthest reach the problems in which this case
is involved. Positions are advanced so absolute and abstract that,
in any event, they could not properly determine this controversy. See Ashwander v. Tennessee Valley Authority, 297 U.
S. 288 , 297 U. S. 341 , 297 U. S.
346 -348. We are asked to decide this case by choosing
between two mutually exclusive alternatives: that motion pictures
may be subjected to unrestricted censorship, or that they Page 343 U. S. 518 must be allowed to be shown under any circumstances. But only
the tyranny of absolutes would rely on such alternatives to meet
the problems generated by the need to accommodate the diverse
interests affected by the motion pictures in compact modern
communities. It would startle Madison and Jefferson and George
Mason, could they adjust themselves to our day, to be told that the
freedom of speech which they espoused in the Bill of Rights
authorizes a showing of "The Miracle" from windows facing St.
Patrick's Cathedral in the forenoon of Easter Sunday, [ Footnote 2/26 ] just as it would startle
them to be told that any picture, whatever its theme and its
expression, could be barred from being commercially exhibited. The
general principle of free speech, expressed in the First Amendment
as to encroachments by Congress, and included as it is in the
Fourteenth Amendment, binding on the States, must be placed in its
historical and legal contexts. The Constitution, we cannot recall
too often, is an organism, not merely a literary composition.
If the New York Court of Appeals had given "sacrilegious" the
meaning it has had in Catholic thought since St. Thomas Aquinas
formulated its scope, and had sustained a finding by the Board of
Regents that "The Miracle" came within that scope, this Court would
have to meet some of the broader questions regarding the relation
to the motion picture industry of the guarantees of the First
Amendment so far as reflected in the Fourteenth. But the New York
court did not confine "sacrilegious" within such technical, Thomist
limits, nor within any specific, or even approximately specified,
limits. It may fairly be said that that court deemed "sacrilegious"
a self-defining term, a word that carries a well known, settled
meaning in the common speech of men. Page 343 U. S. 519 So far as the Court of Appeals sought to support its notion that
"sacrilegious" has the necessary precision of meaning which the Due
Process Clause enjoins for statutes regulating men's activities, it
relied on this definition from Funk & Wagnalls' Dictionary:
"The act of violating or profaning anything sacred." But this
merely defines by turning an adjective into a noun and bringing in
two new words equally undefined. It leaves wide open the question
as to what persons, doctrines or things are "sacred." It sheds no
light on what representations on the motion picture screen will
constitute "profaning" those things which the State censors find to
be "sacred."
To criticize or assail religious doctrine may wound to the quick
those who are attached to the doctrine and profoundly cherish it.
But to bar such pictorial discussion is to subject non-conformists
to the rule of sects.
Even in Mutual Film Corp. v. Ohio Industrial Comm'n, 236 U. S. 230 , it
was deemed necessary to find that the terms "educational, moral,
amusing or harmless" do not leave "decision to arbitrary judgment."
Such general words were found to "get precision from the sense and
experience of men." Id. at 236 U. S. 245 , 236 U. S. 246 .
This cannot be said of "sacrilegious." If there is one thing that
the history of religious conflicts shows, it is that the term
"sacrilegious" -- if by that is implied offense to the deep
convictions of members of different sects, which is what the Court
of Appeals seems to mean so far as it means anything precisely --
does not gain "precision from the sense and experience of men."
The vast apparatus of indices and digests, which mirrors our
law, affords no clue to a judicial definition of sacrilege. Not one
case, barring the present, has been uncovered which considers the
meaning of the term in any context. Nor has the practice under the
New York law contributed light. The Motion Picture Division of the
Education Department does not support with explanatory Page 343 U. S. 520 statements its action on any specific motion picture, which we
are advised is itself not made public. Of the fifty-odd reported
appeals to the Board of Regents from denials of licenses by the
Division, only three concern the category "sacrilegious." [ Footnote 2/27 ] In these cases, as in
others under the Act, the Board's reported opinion confines itself
to a bare finding that the film was or was not "sacrilegious,"
without so much as a description of the allegedly offensive matter,
or even of the film as a whole to enlighten the inquirer. Well
equipped law libraries are not niggardly in their reflection of
"the sense and experience of men," but we must search elsewhere for
any which gives to "sacrilege" its meaning.
Sacrilege, [ Footnote 2/28 ] as
a restricted ecclesiastical concept, has a long history. Naturally
enough, religions have sought to protect their priests and anointed
symbols from physical injury. [ Footnote 2/29 ] But history demonstrates that the term
is hopelessly vague when it goes beyond such ecclesiastical
definiteness and is used at large as the basis for punishing
deviation from doctrine.
Etymologically, "sacrilege" is limited to church-robbing: sacer, sacred, and legere, to steal or pick out.
But we are Page 343 U. S. 521 told that "already in Cicero's time it had grown to include in
popular speech any insult or injury to [sacred things]." [ Footnote 2/30 ] "In primitive religions
[sacrilege is] inclusive of almost every serious offence even in
fields now regarded as merely social or political. . . ." [ Footnote 2/31 ] The concept of "tabu" in
primitive society is thus close to that of "sacrilege." [ Footnote 2/32 ] And in
"the Theodosian Code the various crimes which are accounted
sacrilege include -- apostasy, heresy, schism, Judaism, paganism,
attempts against the immunity of churches and clergy or privileges
of church courts, the desecration of sacraments, etc., and even
Sunday. Along with these crimes against religion went treason to
the emperor, offences against the laws, especially counterfeiting,
defraudation in taxes, seizure of confiscated property, evil
conduct of imperial officers, etc. [ Footnote 2/33 ]"
During the Middle Ages the Church considerably delimited the
application of the term. St. Thomas Aquinas classified the objects
of "sacrilege" as persons places, and thing. [ Footnote 2/34 ] The injuries which would
constitute Page 343 U. S. 522 "sacrilege" received specific and detailed illustration.
[ Footnote 2/35 ] This teaching of
Aquinas is, I believe, still substantially the basis of the
official Catholic doctrine of sacrilege. Thus, for the Roman
Catholic Church, the term came to have a fairly definite meaning,
but one, in general, limited to protecting things physical against
injurious acts. [ Footnote 2/36 ]
Apostasy, heresy, and blasphemy coexisted as religious crimes
alongside sacrilege; they were peculiarly in the realm of religious
dogma and doctrine, as "sacrilege" was not. It is true that
Spelman, writing "The History and Fate of Sacrilege" in 1632,
included in "sacrilege" acts whereby
"the very Deity is invaded, profaned, or robbed of its glory. .
. . In this high sin are blasphemers, Page 343 U. S. 523 sorcerers, witches, and enchanters. [ Footnote 2/37 ]"
But his main theme was the "spoil of church lands done by Henry
VIII" and the misfortunes that subsequently befell the families of
the recipients of former ecclesiastical property as divine
punishment.
To the extent that English law took jurisdiction to punish
"sacrilege," the term meant the stealing from a church, or
otherwise doing damage to church property. [ Footnote 2/38 ] This special protection against
"sacrilege," that is, property damage, was granted only to the
Established Church. [ Footnote
2/39 ] Since the repeal less than a century ago of the English
law punishing "sacrilege" against the property of the Established
Church, religious property has received little special protection.
The property of all sects has had substantially the same protection
as is accorded non-religious property. [ Footnote 2/40 ] At no time up to the present has English
law known "sacrilege" to be used in any wider sense than the
physical injury to church property. It is true that, at times in
the past, English law has Page 343 U. S. 524 taken jurisdiction to punish departures from accepted dogma or
religious practice or the expression of particular religious
opinions, but never have these "offenses" been denominated
"sacrilege." Apostasy, heresy, offenses against the Established
Church, blasphemy, profanation of the Lord's Day, etc., were
distinct criminal offenses, characterized by Blackstone as
"offences against God and religion." [ Footnote 2/41 ] These invidious reflections upon
religious susceptibilities were not covered under sacrilege as they
might be under the Court of Appeals' opinion. Anyone doubting the
dangerous uncertainty of the New York definition, which makes
"sacrilege" overlap these other "offenses against religion," need
only read Blackstone's account of the broad and varying content
given each of these offenses.
A student of English lexicography would despair of finding the
meaning attributed to "sacrilege" by the New York court. [ Footnote 2/42 ] Most dictionaries define
the concept in the limited sense of the physical abuse of physical
objects. The definitions given for "sacrilege" by two dictionaries
published in 1742 and 1782 are typical. Bailey's defined it as
"the stealing of Sacred Things, Church Robbing; an Alienation to
Laymen, and to profane and common Purposes, of what was given to
religious Persons, and to pious Uses. [ Footnote 2/43 ]"
Barclay's said it is "the crime of taking any thing dedicated to
divine worship, or profaning any thing sacred," where "to profane"
is defined "to apply any thing sacred to common uses. To be
irreverent to sacred persons or things." [ Footnote 2/44 ] The Page 343 U. S. 525 same dictionaries defined "blasphemy," a peculiarly verbal
offense, in much broader terms than "sacrilege," indeed in terms
which the New York court finds encompassed by "sacrilegious." For
example, Barclay said "blasphemy" is "an offering some indignity to
God, any person of the Trinity, any messengers from God, his holy
writ, or the doctrines of revelation." [ Footnote 2/45 ] It is hardly necessary to comment that
the limits of this definition remain too uncertain to justify
constraining the creative efforts of the imagination by fear of
pains and penalties imposed by a necessarily subjective censorship.
It is true that some earlier dictionaries assigned to "sacrilege"
the broader meaning of "abusing Sacraments or holy Mysteries,"
[ Footnote 2/46 ] but the broader
meaning is more indefinite, not less. Noah Webster first published
his American Dictionary in 1828. Both it and the later dictionaries
published by the Merriam Company, Webster's International
Dictionary and Webster's New International Dictionary, have gone
through dozens of editions and printings, revisions and expansions.
In all editions throughout 125 years, these American dictionaries
have defined "sacrilege" and "sacrilegious" to echo substantially
the narrow, technical definitions from the earlier British
dictionaries collected in the Appendix, post, p. 343 U. S. 533 .
[ Footnote 2/47 ] Page 343 U. S. 526 The New York Court of Appeals' statement that the dictionary
"furnishes a clear definition," justifying the vague scope it gave
to "sacrilegious," surely was made without regard to the
lexicographic history of the term. As a matter of fact, the
definition from Funk & Wagnalls' used by the Court of Appeals
is taken straight from 18th Century dictionaries, particularly
Doctor Johnson's. [ Footnote 2/48 ]
In light of that history, it would seem that the Funk & Page 343 U. S. 527 Wagnalls' definition uses "sacrilege" in its historically
restricted meaning, which was not, and could hardly have been, the
basis for condemning "The Miracle." If the New York court reads the
Funk & Wagnalls' definition in a broader sense, in a sense for
which history and experience provide no gloss, it inevitably left
the censor free to judge by whatever dogma he deems "sacred" and to
ban whatever motion pictures he may assume would "profane"
religious doctrine widely enough held to arouse protest.
Examination of successive editions of the Encyclopaedia
Britannica over nearly two centuries up to the present day gives no
more help than the dictionaries. From 1768 to the eleventh edition
in 1911, merely a brief dictionary-type definition was given for
"sacrilege." [ Footnote 2/49 ] The
eleventh edition, which first published a longer article, was
introduced as follows:
"the violation or profanation of sacred things, a crime of
varying scope in different religions. It is naturally much more
general and accounted more dreadful in those primitive religions
in Page 343 U. S. 528 which cultural objects play so great a part, than in more highly
spiritualized religions where they tend to disappear. But wherever
the idea of sacred exists, sacrilege is possible. [ Footnote 2/50 ]"
The article on "sacrilege" in the current edition of the
Encyclopaedia Britannica is substantially the same as that, in the
1911 edition.
History teaches us the indefiniteness of the concept
"sacrilegious" in another respect. In the case of most countries
and times where the concept of sacrilege has been of importance,
there has existed an established church or a state religion. That
which was "sacred," and so was protected against "profaning," was
designated in each case by ecclesiastical authority. What might
have been definite when a controlling church imposed a detailed
scheme of observances becomes impossibly confused and uncertain
when hundreds of sects, with widely disparate and often directly
conflicting ideas of sacredness, enjoy, without discrimination and
in equal measure, constitutionally guaranteed religious freedom. In
the Rome of the late emperors, the England of James I, or the
Geneva of Calvin, and today in Roman Catholic Spain, Mohammedan
Saudi Arabia, or any other country with a monolithic religion, the
category of things sacred might have clearly definable limits. But
in America, the multiplicity of the ideas of "sacredness" held with
equal but conflicting fervor by the great number of religious
groups makes the term "sacrilegious" too indefinite to satisfy
constitutional demands based on reason and fairness.
If "sacrilegious" bans more than the physical abuse of sacred
persons, places, or things, if it permits censorship of religious
opinions, which is the effect of the holding below, the term will
include what may be found to be "blasphemous." England's experience
with that treacherous word should give us pause, apart from our Page 343 U. S. 529 requirements for the separation of Church and State. The crime
of blasphemy in Seventeenth Century England was the crime of
dissenting from whatever was the current religious dogma. [ Footnote 2/51 ] King James I's "Book of
Sports" was first required reading in the churches; later all
copies were consigned to the flames. To attack the mass was once
blasphemous; to perform it became so. At different times during
that century, with the shifts in the attitude of government towards
particular religious views, persons who doubted the doctrine of the
Trinity ( e.g., Unitarians, Universalists, etc.) or the
divinity of Christ, observed the Sabbath on Saturday, denied the
possibility of witchcraft, repudiated child baptism or urged
methods of baptism other than sprinkling, were charged as
blasphemers, or their books were burned or banned as blasphemous.
Blasphemy was the chameleon phrase which meant the criticism of
whatever the ruling authority of the moment established as orthodox
religious doctrine. [ Footnote
2/52 ] While it is true that blasphemy prosecutions Page 343 U. S. 530 have continued in England -- although in lessening numbers --
into the present century, [ Footnote
2/53 ] the existence there of an established church gives more
definite contours to the crime in England than the term
"sacrilegious" can possibly have in this country. Moreover, the
scope of the English common law crime of blasphemy has been
considerably limited by the declaration that "if the decencies of
controversy are observed, even the fundamentals of religion may be
attacked," [ Footnote 2/54 ] a
limitation which the New York court has not put upon the Board of
Regents' power to declare a motion picture "sacrilegious."
In Cantwell v. Connecticut, 310 U.
S. 296 , 310 U. S. 310 ,
Mr. Justice Roberts, speaking for the whole Court, said:
"In the realm of religious faith, and in that of political
belief, sharp differences arise. In both fields, the tenets of one
man may seem the rankest error to his neighbor."
Conduct and beliefs dear to one may seem the rankest "sacrilege"
to another. A few examples suffice to show the difficulties facing
a conscientious censor or motion picture producer or distributor in
determining what the New York statute condemns as sacrilegious. A
motion picture portraying Christ as divine -- for example, a movie
showing medieval Church art -- would offend the religious opinions
of the members of several Protestant denominations who do not
believe in the Trinity, as well as those of a non-Christian faith.
Conversely, one showing Christ as merely an ethical teacher could
not but offend millions of Christians of many denominations. Which
is "sacrilegious"? The doctrine of transubstantiation, and the
veneration of relics or particular stone and wood embodiments of
saints or divinity, both sacred to Page 343 U. S. 531 Catholics, are offensive to a great many Protestants, and
therefore, for them, sacrilegious in the view of the New York
court. Is a picture treating either subject, whether
sympathetically, unsympathetically, or neutrally, "sacrilegious"?
It is not a sufficient answer to say that "sacrilegious" is
definite, because all subjects that in any way might be interpreted
as offending the religious beliefs of any one of the 300 sects of
the United States [ Footnote 2/55 ]
are banned in New York. To allow such vague, undefinable powers of
censorship to be exercised is bound to have stultifying
consequences on the creative process of literature and art -- for
the films are derived largely from literature. History does not
encourage reliance on the wisdom and moderation of the censor as a
safeguard in the exercise of such drastic power over the minds of
men. We not only do not know, but cannot know, what is condemnable
by "sacrilegious." And if we cannot tell, how are those to be
governed by the statute to tell?
It is this impossibility of knowing how far the form of words by
which the New York Court of Appeals explained "sacrilegious"
carries the proscription of religious subjects that makes the term
unconstitutionally vague. [ Footnote
2/56 ] To stop short of proscribing all subjects that might
conceivably be interpreted to be religious, inevitably creates a
situation whereby the censor bans only that against which Page 343 U. S. 532 there is a substantial outcry from a religious group. And that
is the fair inference to be drawn, as a matter of experience, from
what has been happening under the New York censorship. Consequently
the film industry, normally not guided by creative artists, and
cautious in putting large capital to the hazards of courage, would
be governed by its notions of the feelings likely to be aroused by
diverse religious sects, certainly the powerful ones. The effect of
such demands upon art and upon those whose function is to enhance
the culture of a society need not be labored.
To paraphrase Doctor Johnson, if nothing may be shown but what
licensors may have previously approved, power, the
yea-or-nay-saying by officials, becomes the standard of the
permissible. Prohibition through words that fail to convey what is
permitted and what is prohibited for want of appropriate objective
standards, offends Due Process in two ways. First, it does not
sufficiently apprise those bent on obedience of law of what may
reasonably be foreseen to be found illicit by the law-enforcing
authority, whether court or jury or administrative agency.
Secondly, where licensing is rested, in the first instance, in an
administrative agency, the available judicial review is in effect
rendered inoperative. On the basis of such a portmanteau word as
"sacrilegious," the judiciary has no standards with which to judge
the validity of administrative action which necessarily involves,
at least in large measure, subjective determinations. Thus, the
administrative first step becomes the last step. Page 343 U. S. 533 From all that has been said, one is compelled to conclude that
the term "sacrilegious" has come down the stream of time encrusted
with a specialized, strictly confined meaning, pertaining to things
in space, not things in the mind. The New York Court of Appeals did
not give the term this calculable content. It applied it to things
in the mind, and things in the mind so undefined, so at large, as
to be more patently in disregard of the requirement for
definiteness, as the basis of proscriptions and legal sanctions for
their disobedience, than the measures that were condemned as
violative of Due Process in United States v. Cohen Grocery
Co., 255 U. S. 81 ; A. B. Small Co. v. American Sugar Refining Co., 267 U. S. 233 ; Connally v. General Construction Co., 269 U.
S. 385 ; Winters v. New York, 333 U.
S. 507 ; Kunz v. New York, 340 U.
S. 290 . This principle is especially to be observed when
what is so vague seeks to fetter the mind and put within
unascertainable bounds the varieties of religious experience.
| 343
U.S. 495 app| APPENDIX TO OPINION OF MR. JUSTICE FRANKFURTER 343
U.S. 495 app|>* Cockeram, English Dictionarie (10th ed., London, 1651).
Blasphemy: No entry.
Sacrilege: "The robbing of a Church, the stealing of holy
things, abusing of Sacraments or holy Mysteries."
Sacrilegious: "Abominable, very wicked."
Blount, Glossographia (3d ed., London, 1670).
Blasphemy: No entry.
Sacrilege: "the robbing a Church, or other holy consecrated
place, the stealing holy things, or abusing Sacraments or holy
Mysteries."
Sacrilegious: "that robs the Church; wicked, extremely bad." Page 343 U. S. 534 Blount, A Law-Dictionary (London, 1670).
Blasphemy: No entry.
Sacrilege: No entry.
Phillips, The New World of Words (3d ed., London, 1671).
Blasphemy: "an uttering of reproachfull words, tending either to
the dishonour of God, or to the hurt and disgrace of any man's name
and credit."
Sacrilegious: "committing Sacriledge, i.e. a robbing of
Churches, or violating of holy things."
Cowel, The Interpreter of Words and Terms (Manley ed., London,
1701).
Blasphemy: No entry.
Sacrilege: "an Alienation to Lay-Men, and to profane or common
purposes, of what was given to Religious Persons, and to Pious
Uses, etc."
Rastell, Law Terms (London, 1708).
Blasphemy: No entry.
Sacrilege: "is, when one steals any Vessels, Ornaments, or Goods
of Holy Church, which is felony, 3 Cro. 153, 154."
Kersey, A General English Dictionary (3d ed., London, 1721).
Blasphemy: "an uttering of reproachful Words, that tend to the
Dishonour of God, &c."
Sacrilege: "the stealing of Sacred Things, Church robbing."
Cocker, English Dictionary (London, 1724).
Blasphemy: No entry.
Sacrilege: "robbing the Church, or what is dedicated
thereto."
Bailey, Universal Etymological English Dictionary (London,
1730).
Blasphemy: "an uttering of reproachful words tending to the
dishonour of God, &c. vile, base language." Page 343 U. S. 535 Sacrilege: "the stealing of sacred Things, Church-Robbing; the
Crime of profaning sacred Things, or alienating to Laymen, or
common Uses, what was given to pious Uses and religious
Persons."
Coles, An English Dictionary (London, 1732).
Blasphemy: "reproach."
Sacrilege: "the robbing of God, the church, &c."
Bullokar, The English Expositor (14th ed., London, 1731).
Blasphemy: No entry.
Sacrilege: "The Robbing of a Church; the Stealing of holy
things, or Abusing of Sacraments or holy Mysteries."
Defoe, A Compleat English Dictionary (Westminster, 1735).
Blasphemy: "vile or opprobrious Language, tending to the
Dishonour of God."
Sacrilege: "the stealing of sacred Things, Church robbing."
Bailey, An Universal Etymological English Dictionary (London,
1742).
Blasphemy: "Cursing and Swearing, vile reproachful Language,
tending to the Dishonour of God."
Sacrilege: "the stealing of Sacred Things, Church Robbing; an
Alienation to Laymen, and to profane and common Purposes, of what
was given to religious Persons, and to pious Uses."
Martin, A New Universal English Dictionary (London, 1754).
Blasphemy: "cursing, vile language tending to the dishonour of
God or religion."
Sacrilege: "the stealing things out of a holy place, or the
profaning things devoted to God." Page 343 U. S. 536 Johnson, A Dictionary of the English Language (2d ed., London,
1755).
Blasphemy: "strictly and properly, is an offering of some
indignity, or injury, unto God himself, either by words or
writing."
Sacrilege: "The crime of appropriating to himself what is
devoted to religion; the crime of robbing heaven; the crime of
violating or profaning things sacred."
Rider, A New Universal English Dictionary (London, 1759).
Blasphemy: "an offering some indignity to God, any person of the
Trinity, any messengers from God; his holy writ, or the doctrines
of revelation, either by speaking or writing any thing ill of them,
or ascribing any thing ill to them inconsistent with their natures
and the reverence we owe them."
Sacrilege: "the crime of taking any thing dedicated to divine
worship. The crime of profaning any thing sacred."
Profane: "to apply any thing sacred to common use. To be
irreverent to sacred persons or things. To put to a wrong use."
Gordon and Marchant, A New Complete English Dictionary (London,
1760).
Blasphemy: "is an offering some indignity to God himself."
Sacrilege: "is the crime of appropriating to himself what is
devoted to religion; the crime of robbing Heaven."
Buchanan, A New English Dictionary (London, 1769).
Blasphemy: "Language tending to the dishonour of God."
Sacrilege: "The stealing things out of a holy place." Page 343 U. S. 537 Cunningham, A New and Complete Law-Dictionary (London,
1771).
Blasphemy: A long definition reading in part: "Is an injury
offered to God, by denying that which is due and belonging to him,
or attributing to him what is not agreeable to his nature."
Sacrilege: "Is church robbery, or a taking of things out of a
holy place; as where a person steals any vessels, ornaments, or
goods of the church. And it is said to be a robbery of God, at
least of what is dedicated to his service." 2 Cro. 153, 154.
" . . . an alienation to lay-men, and to profane or common
purposes, of what was given to religious persons, and to pious
uses."
Kenrick, A New Dictionary of the English Language (London,
1773).
Blasphemy: "Treating the name and attributes of the Supreme
Being with insult and indignity."
Sacrilege: "The crime of appropriating to himself what is
devoted to religion; the crime of robbing heaven, says Johnson; the
crime of violating or profaning things sacred."
Profane: "To violate; to pollute. -- To put to wrong use."
Ash, The New and Complete Dictionary of the English Language
(London, 1775).
Blasphemy: "The act of speaking or writing reproachfully of the
Divine Being, the act of attributing to the creature that which
belongs to the Creator."
Sacrilege: "The act of appropriating to one's self what is
devoted to religion, the crime of violating sacred things." Page 343 U. S. 538 Dyche, A New General English Dictionary (London, 1777).
Blasphemy: "the reproaching or dlshonouring God, religion, and
holy things."
Sacrilege: "the stealing or taking away those things that were
appropriated to religious uses or designs."
Sacrilegious: "of a profane, thievish nature, sort, or
disposition."
Barclay, A Complete and Universal English Dictionary (London,
1782).
Blasphemy: "an offering some indignity to God, any person of the
Trinity, any messengers from God, his holy writ, or the doctrines
of revelation."
Sacrilege: "the crime of taking any thing dedicated to divine
worship, or profaning any thing sacred."
Profane: "to apply any thing sacred to common use. To be
irreverent to sacred persons or things."
Lemon, English Etymology (London, 1783).
Blaspheme: "to speak evil of any one; to injure his fame, or
reputation."
Sacrilege: No entry.
Entick, New Spelling Dictionary (London, 1786).
Blasphemy: "indignity offered to God."
Blasphemer: "one who abuses God."
Sacrilege: "the robbery of a church or chapel."
Sacrilegious: "violating a thing made sacred."
Burn, A New Law Dictionary (Dublin, 1792).
Blasphemy: "See Prophaneness."
Profaneness: A long definition, not reproduced here.
Sacrilege: "robbing of the church, or stealing things out of a
sacred place."
Sheridan, A Complete Dictionary of the English Language (6th
ed., Phila., 1796).
Blasphemy: "Offering of some indignity to God."
Sacrilege: "The crime of robbing a church." Page 343 U. S. 539 Scott, Dictionary of the English Language (Edinburgh, 1797).
Blasphemy: "indignity offered to God."
Sacrilege: "the robbery of a church, &c."
Richardson, A New Dictionary of the English Language (London,
1839).
Blasphemy: "To attack, assail, insult, (the name, the
attributes, the ordinances, the revelations, the will or government
of God.)"
Sacrilege: "to take away, to steal any thing sacred, or
consecrated, or dedicated to holy or religious uses."
Bell, A Dictionary and Digest of the Law of Scotland (Edinburgh,
1861).
Blasphemy: "is the denying or vilifying of the Deity, by speech
or writing."
Sacrilege: "is any violation of things dedicated to the offices
of religion."
Staunton, An Ecclesiastical Dictionary (N.Y. 1861).
Blasphemy: A long entry.
Sacrilege: "The act of violating or subjecting sacred things to
profanation; or the desecration of objects consecrated to God.
Thus, the robbing of churches or of graves, the abuse of sacred
vessels and altars by employing them for unhallowed purposes, the
plundering and misappropriation of alms and donations, are acts of
sacrilege, which in the ancient Church were punished with great
severity."
Bouvier, A Law Dictionary (11th ed., Phila., 1866).
Blasphemy: "To attribute to God that which is contrary to his
nature, and does not belong to him, and to deny what does; or it is
a false reflection uttered with a malicious design of reviling
God." Page 343 U. S. 540 Sacrilege: "The act of stealing from the temples or churches
dedicated to the worship of God, articles consecrated to divine
uses."
Shipley, A Glossary of Ecclesiastical Terms (London, 1872).
Blasphemy: "Denying the existence or providence of God;
contumelous reproaches of Jesus Christ; profane scoffing at the
holy Scriptures, or exposing any part thereof to contempt or
ridicule."
Sacrilege: "The profanation or robbery of persons or things
which have been solemnly dedicated to the service of God. v. 24
& 25 Vict. c. 96, s. 50."
Brown, A Law Dictionary (Sprague ed., Albany, 1875).
Blasphemy: "To revile at or to deny the truth of Christianity as
by law established, is a blasphemy, and as such is punishable by
the common law. . . ."
Sacrilege: "A desecration of any thing that is holy. The
alienation of lands which were given to religious purposes to
laymen, or to profane and common purposes, was also termed
sacrilege."
| 343
U.S. 495 app|
* See Mathews, A Surrey of English Dictionaries
(1933).
[ Footnote 2/1 ]
Crowther, "The Strange Case of The Miracle,'" Atlantic
Monthly, April, 1951, pp. 35, 36-37. [ Footnote 2/2 ]
L'Osservatore Romano, Aug. 25, 1948, p. 2, col. 1, translated in
part in The Commonweal, Mar. 23, 1951, p 592, col. 2.
[ Footnote 2/3 ] Ibid. [ Footnote 2/4 ]
N.Y. Times, Feb. 11, 1951, § 2, p. 4, cols. 4-5.
[ Footnote 2/5 ]
Time, Feb.19, 1951, pp. 60-61.
[ Footnote 2/6 ]
II Popolo, Nov. 3, 1948, p. 2, col. 9, translated by Camille M.
Cianfarra, N.Y. Times, Feb. 11, 1951, § 2, p. 4, col. 5.
[ Footnote 2/7 ]
L'Osservatore Romano, Nov. 12, 1948, p. 2, cols. 3-4.
[ Footnote 2/8 ] Ibid. [ Footnote 2/9 ]
"The Miracle" was passed by customs. To import "Any obscene
lewd, lascivious, or filthy . . . motion-picture film" is a
criminal offense, 35 Stat. 1088, 1138, 18 U.S.C. (Supp. IV) § 1462,
and importation of any obscene "print" or "picture" is barred. 46
Stat. 590, 688, 19 U.S.C. § 1305. Compare the provision,
"all photographic-films imported . . . shall be subject to such
censorship as may be imposed by the Secretary of the Treasury." 38
Stat. 114 151 (1913), 42 Stat. 858, 920 (1922), repealed 46 Stat.
590, 762 (1930). See Inglis, Freedom of the Movies,
68.
[ Footnote 2/10 ]
Life, Jan. 15, 1951, p. 63; Sat.Rev. of Lit., Jan. 27, 1951, pp.
28-29.
[ Footnote 2/11 ]
N.Y. Times, Dec. 31, 1950, p. 23, col. 4.
[ Footnote 2/12 ]
Inglis, Freedom of the Movies, 120 et seq. [ Footnote 2/13 ] Id. at 74-82.
[ Footnote 2/14 ]
Howard Barnes, N.Y. Herald Tribune, Dec. 13, 1950, p. 30, cols.
1-3: "it would be wise to time a visit to the Paris in order to
skip [ The Miracle']. . . . Altogether it leaves a very bad
taste in one's mouth." Bosley Crowther, N.Y. Times, Dec. 13, 1950, p. 50, cols.
2-3:
"each one of the [three] items . . . stacks up with the major
achievements of the respective directors. . . . ['The Miracle'] is
by far the most overpowering and provocative of the lot."
N.Y. Times, Dec. 17, 1950, § 2, p. 3, cols. 7-8:
"a picture of mounting intensity that wrings the last pang of
emotion as it hits its dramatic peak . . . vastly compassionate
comprehension of the suffering and the triumph of birth."
Wanda Hale, N.Y. Daily News, Dec. 13, 1950, p. 82, cols. 1-3:
"Rossellini's best piece of direction since his greatest, "Open
City." . . . artistic and beautifully done by both the star and the
director."
Archer Winsten, N.Y. Post, Dec. 13, 1950, p. 80, cols. 1-3:
"Magnani's performance is a major one and profoundly impressive.
This reviewer's personal opinion marked down the film as
disturbingly unpleasant and slow."
Seymour Peck, N.Y. Daily Compass, Dec. 13, 1950, 3, cols. 3-5:
" The Miracle' is really all Magnani. . . . one of the most
exciting solo performances the screen has known." Alton Cook, N.Y. World-Telegram, Dec. 13, 1950, p. 50, cols.
1-2:
"['The Miracle' is] charged with the same overwrought hysteria
that ran through his 'Stromboli.' . . . the picture has an
unpleasant preoccupation with filth and squalor . . . exceedingly
trying experience."
Time, Jan. 8, 1951, p. 72, cols. 2-3: "[ The Miracle'] is
second-rate Rossellini despite a virtuoso performance by Anna
Magnani." Newsweek, Dec. 18, 1950, pp. 93-94, col. 3:
"strong medicine for most American audiences. However, it shows
what an artist of Rossellini's character can do in the still
scarcely explored medium of the film short story."
Hollis Alpert, Sat.Rev. of Lit., Jan. 27, 1951, pp. 28-29:
"Pictorially the picture is a gem, with its sensitive evocation
of a small Italian town and the surrounding countryside near
Salerno. . . . Anna Magnani again demonstrates her magnificent
qualities of acting. The role is difficult. . . ."
"But my quarrel would be with Mr. Rossellini, whose method of
improvisation from scene to scene . . . can also result in
extraneous detail that adds little, or even harms, the over-all
effect."
[ Footnote 2/15 ]
N.Y. Times, Dec. 28, 1950, p. 22, col. 1.
[ Footnote 2/16 ] Id., Dec. 24, 1950, p. 1, cols. 2-3.
[ Footnote 2/17 ] Joseph Burstyn, Inc. v. McCaffrey, 198 Misc. 884, 101
N.Y.S.2d 892.
[ Footnote 2/18 ]
N.Y. Times, Jan. 8, 1951, p. 1, col. 2. The Cardinal termed "The
Miracle" "a vile and harmful picture," "a despicable affront to
every Christian" ("We believe in miracles. This picture ridicules
that belief"), and finally "a vicious insult to Italian womanhood."
As a consequence, he declared:
"we, as the guardians of the moral law, must summon you and all
people with a sense of decency to refrain from seeing it and
supporting the venal purveyors of such pictures. . . ." Id. at p. 14, cols. 2-3.
For completeness' sake, later incidents should be noted.
Picketers from the Catholic War Veterans, the Holy Name Society,
and other Catholic organizations -- about 1,000 person in all
during one Sunday -- paraded before the Paris Theatre. Id. Dec. 29, 1950, p. 36, col. 3; Jan. 8, 1951, p. 1, col. 2; Jan. 9,
1951, p. 34, col. 7; Jan. 10, 1951, p. 22, col. 6; Jan. 15, 1951,
p. 23, col. 3. A smaller number of counterpickets appeared on
several days. Id., Jan. 10, 1951, p. 22, col. 6; Jan. 20,
1951, p. 10, cols. 4-5. See also id. Jan. 23, 1951, p. 21,
col. 8; Jan. 25, 1951, p. 27, col. 7.
The Paris Theatre on two different evenings was emptied on
threat of bombing. Id., Jan. 21, 1951, p. 1, cols. 2-3;
Jan. 28, 1951, p. 1, cols. 2-3. Coincidentally with the proceedings
before the New York Board of Regents which started this case on the
way to this Court, the Paris Theatre also was having difficulties
with the New York City Fire Department. The curious may follow the
development of those incidents, not relevant here, in the N.Y.
Times, Jan. 21, 1951, p. 53, cols. 4-5; Jan. 27, 1951, p. 11, col.
3; Feb. 6, 1951, p. 29, col. 8; Feb. 10, 1951, p. 15, col. 8; Feb.
15, 1951, p. 33, col. 2.
[ Footnote 2/19 ]
Excerpts from letters and statements by a great many clergymen
are reproduced in the Record before this Court, pages 95-140. The
representative quotations in the text are from letters written by
the Rev. H. C. DeWindt, Minister of the West Park Presbyterian
Church, New York City, R. 97, and the Rev. W. J. Beeners of
Princeton, New Jersey, R. 98, respectively.
[ Footnote 2/20 ]
Catholic opinion generally, as expressed in the press, supported
the view of the Legion of Decency and of Cardinal Spellman. See, for example, The [New York] Catholic News, Dec. 30,
1950, p. 10; Jan. 6, 1951, p. 10; Jan. 20, 1951, p. 10; Feb. 3,
1951, p. 10; Feb. 10, 1951, p. 12, and May 19, 1951, p. 12;
Commonweal, Jan. 12, 1951, p. 351, col. 1; The [Brooklyn] Tablet,
Jan. 20, 1951, p- 8, col. 4; id. Jan. 27, 1951, p. 10,
col. 3; id. Feb. 3, 1951, p. 8, cols. 3-4; Martin Quigley,
Jr., " The Miracle' -- An Outrage"; The [San Francisco] Monitor,
Jan. 12, 1951, p. 7, cols. 3-4 (reprinted from Motion Picture
Herald, Jan. 6, 1951); The [Boston] Pilot, Jan. 6, 1951, p. 4.
There doubtless were comments on "The Miracle" in other diocesan
papers which circulate in various parts of the country, but which
are not on file in the Library of Congress or the library of the
Catholic University of America. [ Footnote 2/21 ]
Spaeth, "Fogged Screen," Magazine of Art, Feb., 1951, p. 44;
N.Y. Herald Tribune, Jan. 30, 1951, p. 18, col. 4.
[ Footnote 2/22 ]
Clancy, "The Catholic as Philistine," The Commonweal, Mar. 16,
1951, pp. 567-569.
[ Footnote 2/23 ]
The Commonweal, Mar. 2, 1951, pp. 507-508. Much the same view
was taken by Frank Getlein writing in The Catholic Messenger, Mar.
22, 1951, p. 4, cols. 1-8, in an article bearing the headline:
"Film Critic Gives Some Aspects of The Miracle' Story: Raises
Questions Concerning Tactics of Organized Catholic Resistance
Groups in view York." See also "Miracles Do Happen," The
New Leader, Feb. 5, 1951, p. 30, col. 2. [ Footnote 2/24 ]
N.Y. Times, Feb. 1, 1951, p. 24, col. 7.
[ Footnote 2/25 ] Id., Jan. 13, 1951, p. 10, col. 6; translation by
Chworowsky, "The Cardinal: Critic and Censor," The Churchman, Feb.
1, 1951, p. 7, col. 2.
[ Footnote 2/26 ]
That such offensive exploitation of modern means of publicity is
not a fanciful hypothesis, see N.Y. Times, April 14, 1952,
p. 1, col. 4.
[ Footnote 2/27 ] In the Matter of "The Puritan," 60 N.Y.St.Dept. 163
(1939); In the Matter of "Polygamy," 60 N.Y.St.Dept. 217
(1939); In the Matter of "Monja y Casada -- Virgen y
Martir" ("Nun and Married -- Virgin and Martyr"), 52
N.Y.St.Dept. 488 (1935).
[ Footnote 2/28 ]
Since almost without exception "sacrilegious" is defined in
terms of "sacrilege," our discussion will be directed to the latter
term. See Bailey, Universal Etymological English
Dictionary (London, 1730), "Sacrilegious" -- "of, pertaining to, or
guilty of Sacrilege"; Funk & Wagnalls' New Standard Dictionary
(1937), "Sacrilegious" -- "Having committed or being ready to
commit sacrilege. Of the nature of sacrilege; as, sacrilegious
deeds."
[ Footnote 2/29 ]
For general discussions of "sacrilege," see Encyclopaedia of Religion and Ethics (Hastings ed., 1921),
"Sacrilege" and "Tabu"; Rev. Thomas Slater, A Manual of Moral
Theology (1908), 226-230; The Catholic Encyclopedia (1912),
"Sacrilege", and Encyclopaedia Britannica, "Sacrilege."
[ Footnote 2/30 ]
Encyclopaedia Britannica (1951), "Sacrilege."
[ Footnote 2/31 ] Ibid. [ Footnote 2/32 ] See Encyclopaedia of Religion and Ethics (Hastings ed.,
191), "Tabu."
[ Footnote 2/33 ]
Encyclopaedia Britannica (1951), "Sacrilege."
[ Footnote 2/34 ]
St. Thomas Aquinas, Summa Theologica, part II-II, question 99.
The modern Codex Juris Canonici does not give any definition of
"sacrilege," but merely says it "shall be punished by the Ordinary
in proportion to the gravity of the fault, without prejudice to the
penalties established by law. . . ." See Bouscaren and
Ellis, Canon Law (1946), 857. 2 Woywod, A Practical Commentary on
the Code of Canon Law (1929), par. 2178, 477 478, thus defines
sacrilege:
"Sacrilege consists in the unworthy use or treatment of sacred
things and sacred persons. Certain things are of their nature
sacred ( e.g., the Sacraments); others become so by
blessing or consecration legitimately bestowed on things or places
by authority of the Church. Persons are rendered sacred by
ordination or consecration or by other forms of dedication to the
divine service by authority of the Church ( e.g., by first
tonsure, by religious profession)."
[ Footnote 2/35 ]
After his method of raising objections and then refuting them,
St. Thomas Aquinas defends including within the proscription of
"sacrilege," anyone "who disagree[s] about the sovereign's
decision, and doubt[s] whether the person chosen by the sovereign
be worthy of honor" and "any man [who] shall allow the Jews to hold
public offices." Summa Theologica, part II-II, question 99, art.
1.
[ Footnote 2/36 ]
Rev. Thomas Slater, S. J., A Manual of Moral Theology (1908), c.
VI, classifies and illustrates the modern theological view of
"sacrilege":
Sacrilege against sacred persons: to use physical violence
against a member of the clergy; to violate "the privilege of
immunity of the clergy from civil jurisdiction, as far as this is
still in force"; to violate a vow of chastity.
Sacrilege against sacred places: to violate the immunity of
churches and other sacred places "as far as this is still in
force"; to commit a crime such as homicide, suicide, bloody attack
there; to break by sexual act a vow of chastity there; to bury an
infidel, heretic, or excommunicate in churches or cemeteries
canonically established; or to put the sacred place to a profane
use, as a secular courtroom, public market, banquet hall, stable,
etc.
Sacrilege against sacred things: to treat with irreverence,
contempt, or obscenity the sacraments (particularly the Eucharist),
Holy Scriptures, relics, sacred images, etc., to steal sacred
things, or profane things from sacred places; to commit simony; or
to steal, confiscate, or damage willfully ecclesiastical property. See also The Catholic Encyclopedia, "Sacrilege."
[ Footnote 2/37 ]
Sir Henry Spelman, The History and Fate of Sacrilege (2d ed.,
1853), 121-122. Two priests of the Anglican Church prepared a long
prefatory essay to bring Spelman's data up to the date of
publication of the 1853 edition. Their essay shows their
understanding also of "sacrilege" in the limited sense. Id. at 1-120.
[ Footnote 2/38 ]
2 Russell, Crime (10th ed., 1950), 975-976; Stephen, A Digest of
the Criminal Law (9th ed., 1950), 348-349. See 23 Hen.
VIII, c. 1, § III; 1 Edw. VI, c. 12, § X; 1 Mary, c. 3, §§
IV-VI.
[ Footnote 2/39 ]
7 & 8 Geo. IV, e. 29, § X, which the marginal note
summarized as "Sacrilege, when capital," read: "if any Person shall
break and enter any Church or Chapel, and steal therein any Chattel
. . . [he] shall suffer Death as a Felon." This statute was
interpreted to apply only to buildings of the established church. Rex v. Nixon, 7 Car. & P. 442 (1836).
[ Footnote 2/40 ]
7 & 8 Geo. IV, c. 29, § X, was repealed by 24 & 25
Vict., c. 95. The Larceny Act and the Malicious Injuries to
Property Act, both of 1861, treated established church property
substantially the same as all other property. 24 & 25 Vict., c.
96, § 50; e. 97, §§ 1, 11, 39, superseded by Larceny Act, 1916, 6
& 7 Geo. V, c. 50, § 24.
[ Footnote 2/41 ]
Blackstone, bk. IV, c. 4, 41-64.
[ Footnote 2/42 ] Compare the definitions Of "sacrilege" and "blasphemy"
in the dictionaries, starting with Cockeram's 1651 edition, which
are collected in the Appendix, post, p. 343 U. S.
533 .
[ Footnote 2/43 ]
Bailey An Universal Etymological English Dictionary (London,
1742), "Sacrilege."
[ Footnote 2/44 ]
Barclay, A Complete and Universal English Dictionary (London,
1782), "Sacrilege."
[ Footnote 2/45 ] Id., "Blasphemy."
[ Footnote 2/46 ]
Thomas Blount, Glossographia (3d ed., London, 1670).
[ Footnote 2/47 ]
Webster's Compendious Dictionary of the English Language (1806):
"Sacrilege" -- "the robbery of a church or chapel." "Sacrilegious"
-- "violating a thing made sacred."
Webster's American Dictionary (1828): "Sacrilege" -- "The crime
of violating or profaning sacred things; or the alienating to
laymen or to common purposes what has been appropriated or
consecrated to religious persons or uses." " Sacrilegious" --
"Violating sacred things; polluted with the crime of
sacrilege."
Webster's International Dictionary (G. & C. Merriam &
Co., 1890): "Sacrilege" -- "The sin or crime of violating or
profaning sacred things; the alienating to laymen, or to common
purposes, what has been appropriated or consecrated to religious
persons or uses." "Sacrilegious" -- "violating sacred things;
polluted with sacrilege; involving sacrilege; profane;
impious."
Webster's New International Dictionary (G. & C. Merriam Co.,
1st ed., 1909): "Sacrilege" -- "The sin or crime of violating or
profaning sacred things; specif., the alienating to laymen, or to
common purposes, what has been appropriated or consecrated to
religious persons or uses." "Sacrilegious" -- "Violating sacred
things; polluted with, or involving, sacrilege; impious." Repeated
in the 1913, 1922, 1924, 1928, 1933 printings, among others.
Webster's New International Dictionary (G. & C. Merriam
Co.,2d ed., 1934): "Sacrilege" -- "The crime of stealing, misusing,
violating, or desecrating that which is sacred, or holy, or
dedicated to sacred uses. Specif.: a R. C. Ch. The sin of
violating the conditions for a worthy reception of a sacrament. b
Robbery from a church; also, that which is stolen. c Alienation to
laymen, or to common purposes, of what has been appropriated or
consecrated to religious persons or uses." "Sacrilegious" --
"Committing sacrilege; characterized by or involving sacrilege;
polluted with sacrilege; as, sacrilegious robbers, depredations, or
acts." Repeated in the 1939, 1942, 1944, 1949 printings, among
others.
[ Footnote 2/48 ]
1 Funk & Wagnalls' Standard Dictionary of the English
Language, which was first copyrighted in 1890, defined sacrilege as
follows in the 1895 printing: "1. The act of violating or profaning
anything sacred. 2. Eng.Law (1) The larceny of consecrated
things from a church; the breaking into a church with intent to
commit a felony, or breaking out after a felony. (2) Formerly, the
selling to a layman of property given to pious uses." This
definition remained unchanged through many printings of that
dictionary. The current printing of Funk & Wagnalls' New
Standard Dictionary of the English Language, first copyrighted in
1913, carries exactly the same definition of "sacrilege" except
that the first definition has been expanded to read: "The act of
violating or profaning anything sacred, including sacramental vows
."
Funk & Wagnalls' Standard Dictionary (1895) defined "to
profane" as "1. To treat with irreverence or abuse; make common or
unholy; desecrate; pollute. 2. Hence, to put to a wrong or
degrading use; debase." The New Standard Dictionary adds a third
meaning: "3. To vulgarize; give over to the crowd."
[ Footnote 2/49 ]
Encyclopaedia Britannica,2d ed., 1782: "Sacrilege" -- "the crime
of profaning sacred things, or those devoted to the service of
God."
3d ed., 1797: "Sacrilege" -- "the crime of profaning sacred
things, or things devoted to God; or of alienating to laymen, for
common purposes, what was given to religious persons and pious
uses."
8th ed., 1859: "Sacrilege" -- same as 3d ed., 1797.
9th ed., 1886: "Sacrilege" -- A relatively short article the
author of which quite apparently had a restricted definition for
"sacrilege": "robbery of churches," "breaking or defacing of an
altar, crucifix, or cross," etc.
[ Footnote 2/50 ]
Encyclopaedia Britannica (11th ed., 1911), "Sacrilege."
[ Footnote 2/51 ]
Schroeder, Constitutional Free Speech (1919), 178-373, makes a
lengthy review of "Prosecutions for Crimes Against Religion." The
examples in the text are from Schroeder. See also Encyclopaedia of the Social Sciences, "Blasphemy"; Encyclopaedia of
Religion and Ethics, "Blasphemy"; Nokes, A History of the Crime of
Blasphemy (1928).
[ Footnote 2/52 ]
1 Yorke, The Life of Lord Chancellor Hardwicke (1913), 80,
writes thus of the prosecution of Thomas Woolston for
blasphemy:
"The offence, in the first place, consisted in the publication
in 1725 of a tract entitled A Moderator between an Infidel and
an Apostate, in which the author questioned the historical
accuracy of the Resurrection and the Virgin Birth. Such
speculations, however much they might offend the religious feeling
of the nation, would not now arouse apprehensions in the civil
government, or incur legal penalties; but at the time of which we
are writing, when the authority of government was far less stable
and secure and rested on far narrower foundations than at present,
such audacious opinions were considered, not without some reason,
as a menace, not only to religion but to the state."
[ Footnote 2/53 ] See, e.g., Rex v. Boulter, 72 J.P. 188 (1908); Bowman v. Secular Society, Ltd., [1917] A.C. 406.
[ Footnote 2/54 ] Reg. v. Ramsay, 15 Cox's C.C. 231, 238 (1883) (Lord
Coleridge's charge to the jury); Bowman v. Secular Society,
Ltd., [1917] A.C. 406.
[ Footnote 2/55 ]
The latest available statistics of the Bureau of the Census give
returns from 256 denominations; 57 other denominations, which did
not report, are listed. Bureau of the Census, Religious Bodies:
1936, Vol. I, iii, 7.
[ Footnote 2/56 ]
It is not mere fantasy to suggest that the effect of a ban of
the "sacrilegious" may be to ban all motion pictures dealing with
any subject that might be deemed religious by any sect. The
industry's self-censorship has already had a distorting influence
on the portrayal of historical figures.
"Pressure forced deletion of the clerical background of Cardinal
Richelieu from The Three Musketeers. The [Motion Picture
Production] code provision appealed to was the section providing
that ministers should not be portrayed as villains."
Note, "Motion Pictures and the First Amendment," 60 Yale L.J.
696, 716, n. 42.
The press recently reported that plans are being made to film a
"Life of Martin Luther." N.Y. Times, April 27, 1952, § 2, p. 5,
col. 7. Could Luther be sympathetically portrayed and not appear
"sacrilegious" to some; or unsympathetically, and not to
others? | In Joseph Burstyn, Inc. v. Wilson, the Supreme Court ruled that expression through motion pictures falls under the protection of the First Amendment, which guarantees freedom of speech and freedom of the press. The Court struck down a New York law that allowed censors to deny licenses to films deemed "sacrilegious," holding that such prior restraint on speech was unconstitutional. The Court recognized the significance of motion pictures as a medium for ideas and expression, regardless of their entertainment value or profit motive. While acknowledging concerns about potential negative influences on youth, the Court emphasized that motion pictures are entitled to First Amendment protection like other forms of expression. This case set an important precedent for safeguarding free speech in the film industry and limiting government censorship. |
Free Speech | Dennis v. U.S. | https://supreme.justia.com/cases/federal/us/341/494/ | U.S. Supreme Court Dennis v. United States, 341
U.S. 494 (1951) Dennis v. United
States No. 336 Argued December 4,
1950 Decided June 4, 1951 341
U.S. 494 CERTIORARI TO THE UNITED STATES
COURT OF APPEALS FOR THE SECOND
CIRCUIT Syllabus 1. As construed and applied in this case, §§ 2(a)(1), 2(a)(3)
and 3 of the Smith Act, 54 Stat. 671, making it a crime for any
person knowingly or willfully to advocate the overthrow or
destruction of the Government of the United States by force or
violence, to organize or help to organize any group which does so,
or to conspire to do so, do not violate the First Amendment or
other provisions of the Bill of Rights and do not violate the First
or Fifth Amendments because of indefiniteness. Pp. 341 U. S.
495 -499, 341 U. S.
517 .
2. Petitioners, leaders of the Communist Party in this country,
were indicted in a federal district court under § 3 of the Smith
Act for willfully and knowingly conspiring (1) to organize as the
Communist Party a group of persons to teach and advocate the
overthrow and destruction of the Government of the United States by
force and violence, and (2) knowingly and willfully to advocate and
teach the duty and necessity of overthrowing and destroying the
Government of the United States by force and violence. The trial
judge instructed the jury that they could not convict unless they
found that petitioners intended to overthrow the Government "as
speedily as circumstances would permit," but that, if they so
found, then, as a matter of law, there was sufficient danger of a
substantive evil that Congress has a right to prevent to justify
application of the statute under the First Amendment. Petitioners
were convicted, and the convictions were sustained by the Court of
Appeals. This Court granted certiorari, limited to the questions:
(1) Whether either § 2 or § 3 of the Smith Act, inherently or as
construed and applied in the instant case, violates the First
Amendment and other provisions of the Bill of Rights, and (2)
whether either § 2 or § 3, inherently or as construed and applied
in the instant case, violates the First and Fifth Amendments
because of indefiniteness. Held: The convictions are affirmed. Pp. 341 U. S.
495 -499, 341 U. S.
511 -512, 341 U. S.
517 .
183 F.2d 201, affirmed. Page 341 U. S. 495 For the opinions of the Justices constituting the majority of
the Court, see: Opinion of THE CHIEF JUSTICE, joined by MR. JUSTICE REED, MR.
JUSTICE BURTON and MR. JUSTICE MINTON, p. 341 U. S.
495 .
Opinion of MR. JUSTICE FRANKFURTER, p. 341 U. S.
517 .
Opinion of MR. JUSTICE JACKSON, p. 341 U. S.
561 .
For the dissenting opinion of MR. JUSTICE BLACK, see p. 341 U. S.
579 .
For the dissenting opinion of MR. JUSTICE DOUGLAS, see p. 341 U. S.
581 .
The case is stated in the opinion of THE CHIEF JUSTICE, pp. 341 U. S.
495 -499. Affirmed, p. 341 U. S.
517 .
MR. CHIEF JUSTICE VINSON announced the judgment of the Court and
an opinion in which MR. JUSTICE REED, MR. JUSTICE BURTON and MR.
JUSTICE MINTON join.
Petitioners were indicted in July, 1948, for violation of the
conspiracy provisions of the Smith Act, 54 Stat. 671, 18 U.S.C.
(1946 ed.) § 11, during the period of April, 1945, to July, 1948.
The pretrial motion to quash the indictment on the grounds, inter alia, that the statute was unconstitutional was
denied, United States v. Foster, 80 F. Supp.
479 , and the case was set for trial on January 17, 1949. A
verdict of guilty as to all the petitioners was returned by the
jury on October 14, 1949. The Court of Appeals affirmed the
convictions. 183 F.2d 201. We granted certiorari, 340 U.S. 863,
limited to the following two questions: (1) Whether either § 2 or §
3 of the Smith Page 341 U. S. 496 Act, inherently or as construed and applied in the instant case,
violates the First Amendment and other provisions of the Bill of
Rights; (2) whether either § 2 or § 3 of the Act, inherently or as
construed and applied in the instant case, violates the First and
Fifth Amendments because of indefiniteness.
Sections 2 and 3 of the Smith Act, 54 Stat. 671, 18 U.S.C. (1946
ed.) §§ 10, 11 ( see present 18 U.S.C. § 2385), provide as
follows:
"SEC. 2.(a) It shall be unlawful for any person --"
"(1) to knowingly or willfully advocate, abet, advise, or teach
the duty, necessity, desirability, or propriety of overthrowing or
destroying any government in the United States by force or
violence, or by the assassination of any officer of any such
government;"
"(2) with intent to cause the overthrow or destruction of any
government in the United States, to print, publish, edit, issue,
circulate, sell, distribute, or publicly display any written or
printed matter advocating, advising, or teaching the duty,
necessity, desirability, or propriety of overthrowing or destroying
any government in the United States by force or violence;"
"(3) to organize or help to organize any society, group, or
assembly of persons who teach, advocate, or encourage the overthrow
or destruction of any government in the United States by force or
violence; or to be or become a member of, or affiliate with, any
such society, group, or assembly of persons, knowing the purposes
thereof."
"(b) For the purposes of this section, the term 'government in
the United States' means the Government of the United States, the
government of any State, Territory, or possession of the United
States, the government of the District of Columbia, or the Page 341 U. S. 497 government of any political subdivision of any of them."
"SEC. 3. It shall be unlawful for any person to attempt to
commit, or to conspire to commit, any of the acts prohibited by the
provisions of this title."
The indictment charged the petitioners with willfully and
knowingly conspiring (1) to organize as the Communist Party of the
United States of America a society, group and assembly of persons
who teach and advocate the overthrow and destruction of the
Government of the United States by force and violence, and (2)
knowingly and willfully to advocate and teach the duty and
necessity of overthrowing and destroying the Government of the
United States by force and violence. The indictment further alleged
that § 2 of the Smith Act proscribes these acts and that any
conspiracy to take such action is a violation of § 3 of the
Act.
The trial of the case extended over nine months, six of which
were devoted to the taking of evidence, resulting in a record of
16,000 pages. Our limited grant of the writ of certiorari has
removed from our consideration any question as to the sufficiency
of the evidence to support the jury's determination that
petitioners are guilty of the offense charged. Whether, on this
record, petitioners did, in fact, advocate the overthrow of the
Government by force and violence is not before us, and we must base
any discussion of this point upon the conclusions stated in the
opinion of the Court of Appeals, which treated the issue in great
detail. That court held that the record in this case amply supports
the necessary finding of the jury that petitioners, the leaders of
the Communist Party in this country, were unwilling to work within
our framework of democracy, but intended to initiate a violent
revolution whenever the propitious occasion appeared. Petitioners
dispute the meaning to be drawn from the evidence, contending that
the Marxist-Leninist Page 341 U. S. 498 doctrine they advocated taught that force and violence to
achieve a Communist form of government in an existing democratic
state would be necessary only because the ruling classes of that
state would never permit the transformation to be accomplished
peacefully, but would use force and violence to defeat any peaceful
political and economic gain the Communists could achieve. But the
Court of Appeals held that the record supports the following broad
conclusions: by virtue of their control over the political
apparatus of the Communist Political Association, [ Footnote 1 ] petitioners were able to
transform that organization into the Communist Party; that the
policies of the Association were changed from peaceful cooperation
with the United States and its economic and political structure to
a policy which had existed before the United States and the Soviet
Union were fighting a common enemy, namely, a policy which worked
for the overthrow of the Government by force and violence; that the
Communist Party is a highly disciplined organization, adept at
infiltration into strategic positions, use of aliases, and double
meaning language; that the Party is rigidly controlled; that
Communists, unlike other political parties, tolerate no dissension
from the policy laid down by the guiding forces, but that the
approved program is slavishly followed by the members of the Party;
that the literature of the Party and the statements and activities
of its leaders, petitioners here, advocate, and the general goal of
the Party was, during the period in question, to achieve a
successful overthrow of the existing order by force and
violence. Page 341 U. S. 499 I It will be helpful in clarifying the issues to treat next the
contention that the trial judge improperly interpreted the statute
by charging that the statute required an unlawful intent before the
jury could convict. More specifically, he charged that the jury
could not find the petitioners guilty under the indictment unless
they found that petitioners had the intent to "overthrow . . . the
Government of the United States by force and violence as speedily
as circumstances would permit."
Section 2(a)(1) makes it unlawful
"to knowingly or willfully advocate, . . . or teach the duty,
necessity, desirability, or propriety of overthrowing or destroying
any government in the United States by force or violence. . . .
;"
Section 2(a)(3), "to organize or help to organize any society,
group, or assembly of persons who teach, advocate, or encourage the
overthrow. . . ." Because of the fact that § 2(a)(2) expressly
requires a specific intent to overthrow the Government, and because
of the absence of precise language in the foregoing subsections, it
is claimed that Congress deliberately omitted any such requirement.
We do not agree. It would require a far greater indication of
congressional desire that intent not be made an element of the
crime than the use of the disjunctive "knowingly or willfully" in §
2(a)(1), or the omission of exact language in § 2(a)(3). The
structure and purpose of the statute demand the inclusion of intent
as an element of the crime. Congress was concerned with those who
advocate and organize for the overthrow of the Government.
Certainly those who recruit and combine for the purpose of
advocating overthrow intend to bring about that overthrow. We hold
that the statute requires as an essential element of the crime
proof of the intent of those who are charged with its violation to
overthrow the Government by force and violence. See Page 341 U. S. 500 Williams v. United States, 341 U. S.
97 , 341 U. S.
101 -102 (1951); Screws v. United States, 325 U. S. 91 , 325 U. S.
101 -105 (1945); Cramer v. United States, 325 U. S. 1 , 325 U. S. 31 (1945).
Nor does the fact that there must be an investigation of a state
of mind under this interpretation afford any basis for rejection of
that meaning. A survey of Title 18 of the U.S. Code indicates that
the vast majority of the crimes designated by that Title require,
by express language, proof of the existence of a certain mental
state, in words such as "knowingly," "maliciously," "willfully,"
"with the purpose of," "with intent to," or combinations or
permutations of these and synonymous terms. The existence of a mens rea is the rule of, rather than the exception to, the
principles of Anglo-American criminal jurisprudence. See
American Communications Assn. v. Douds, 339 U.
S. 382 , 339 U. S. 411 (1950).
It has been suggested that the presence of intent makes a
difference in the law when an "act otherwise excusable or carrying
minor penalties" is accompanied by such an evil intent. Yet the
existence of such an intent made the killing condemned in Screws, supra, and the beating in Williams,
supra, both clearly and severely punishable under state law,
offenses constitutionally punishable by the Federal Government. In
those cases, the Court required the Government to prove that the
defendants intended to deprive the victim of a constitutional
right. If that precise mental state may be an essential element of
a crime, surely an intent to overthrow the Government of the United
States by advocacy thereof is equally susceptible of proof.
[ Footnote 2 ] Page 341 U. S. 501 II The obvious purpose of the statute is to protect existing
Government not from change by peaceable, lawful and constitutional
means, but from change by violence, revolution and terrorism. That
it is within the power of the Congress to protect the Government of
the United States from armed rebellion is a proposition which
requires little discussion. Whatever theoretical merit there may be
to the argument that there is a "right" to rebellion against
dictatorial governments is without force where the existing
structure of the government provides for peaceful and orderly
change. We reject any principle of governmental helplessness in the
face of preparation for revolution, which principle, carried to its
logical conclusion, must lead to anarchy. No one could conceive
that it is not within the power of Congress to prohibit acts
intended to overthrow the Government by force and violence. The
question with which we are concerned here is not whether Congress
has such power, but whether the means which it has employed
conflict with the First and Fifth Amendments to the
Constitution.
One of the bases for the contention that the means which
Congress has employed are invalid takes the form of an attack on
the face of the statute on the grounds that, by its terms, it
prohibits academic discussion of the merits of Marxism-Leninism,
that it stifles ideas and is contrary to all concepts of a free
speech and a free press. Although we do not agree that the language
itself has that significance, we must bear in mind that it is the
duty of the federal courts to interpret federal legislation in a
manner not inconsistent with the demands of the Constitution. American Communications Assn. v. Douds, 339 U.
S. 382 , 339 U. S. 407 (1950). We are not here confronted with cases similar to Thornhill v. Alabama, 310 U. S. 88 (1940); Herndon v. Lowry, 301 U.
S. 242 (1937), and De Jonge v. Oregon, 299 U. S. 353 (1937), Page 341 U. S. 502 where a state court had given a meaning to a state statute which
was inconsistent with the Federal Constitution. This is a federal
statute which we must interpret as well as judge. Herein lies the
fallacy of reliance upon the manner in which this Court has treated
judgments of state courts. Where the statute as construed by the
state court transgressed the First Amendment, we could not but
invalidate the judgments of conviction.
The very language of the Smith Act negates the interpretation
which petitioners would have us impose on that Act. It is directed
at advocacy, not discussion. Thus, the trial judge properly charged
the jury that they could not convict if they found that petitioners
did "no more than pursue peaceful studies and discussions or
teaching and advocacy in the realm of ideas." He further charged
that it was not unlawful
"to conduct in an American college or university a course
explaining the philosophical theories set forth in the books which
have been placed in evidence."
Such a charge is in strict accord with the statutory language,
and illustrates the meaning to be placed on those words. Congress
did not intend to eradicate the free discussion of political
theories, to destroy the traditional rights of Americans to discuss
and evaluate ideas without fear of governmental sanction. Rather
Congress was concerned with the very kind of activity in which the
evidence showed these petitioners engaged. III But although the statute is not directed at the hypothetical
cases which petitioners have conjured, its application in this case
has resulted in convictions for the teaching and advocacy of the
overthrow of the Government by force and violence, which, even
though coupled with the intent to accomplish that overthrow,
contains an element of speech. For this reason, we must pay
special Page 341 U. S. 503 heed to the demands of the First Amendment marking out the
boundaries of speech.
We pointed out in Douds, supra, that the basis of the
First Amendment is the hypothesis that speech can rebut speech,
propaganda will answer propaganda, free debate of ideas will result
in the wisest governmental policies. It is for this reason that
this Court has recognized the inherent value of free discourse. An
analysis of the leading cases in this Court which have involved
direct limitations on speech, however, will demonstrate that both
the majority of the Court and the dissenters in particular cases
have recognized that this is not an unlimited, unqualified right,
but that the societal value of speech must, on occasion, be
subordinated to other values and considerations.
No important case involving free speech was decided by this
Court prior to Schenck v. United States, 249 U. S.
47 (1919). Indeed, the summary treatment accorded an
argument based upon an individual's claim that the First Amendment
protected certain utterances indicates that the Court at earlier
dates placed no unique emphasis upon that right. [ Footnote 3 ] It was not until the classic
dictum of Justice Holmes in the Schenck case that speech per se received that emphasis in a majority opinion. That
case involved a conviction under the Criminal Espionage Act, 40
Stat. 217. The question the Court faced was whether the evidence
was sufficient to sustain the conviction. Writing for a unanimous
Court, Justice Holmes stated that the
"question in every case is whether the words used are used in
such circumstances and are of such a nature as to create a clear
and present danger that they will bring about the substantive evils
that Congress has a right Page 341 U. S. 504 to prevent."
249 U.S. at 249 U. S. 52 .
But the force of even this expression is considerably weakened by
the reference at the end of the opinion to Goldman v. United
States, 245 U. S. 474 (1918), a prosecution under the same statute. Said Justice
Holmes,
"Indeed, [ Goldman ] might be said to dispose of the
present contention if the precedent covers all media
concludendi. But as the right to free speech was not referred
to specially, we have thought fit to add a few words."
249 U.S. at 249 U. S. 52 .
The fact is inescapable, too, that the phrase bore no connotation
that the danger was to be any threat to the safety of the Republic.
The charge was causing and attempting to cause insubordination in
the military forces and obstruct recruiting. The objectionable
document denounced conscription and its most inciting sentence was,
"You must do your share to maintain, support and uphold the rights
of the people of this country." 249 U.S. at 249 U. S. 51 .
Fifteen thousand copies were printed, and some circulated. This
insubstantial gesture toward insubordination in 1917 during war was
held to be a clear and present danger of bringing about the evil of
military insubordination.
In several later cases involving convictions under the Criminal
Espionage Act, the nub of the evidence the Court held sufficient to
meet the "clear and present danger" test enunciated in Schenck was as follows: Frohwerk v. United
States, 249 U. S. 204 (1919) -- publication of twelve newspaper articles attacking the
war; Debs v. United States, 249 U.
S. 211 (1919) -- one speech attacking United States'
participation in the war; Abrams v. United States, 250 U. S. 616 (1919) -- circulation of copies of two different socialist
circulars attacking the war; Schaefer v. United States, 251 U. S. 466 (1920) -- publication of a German language newspaper with allegedly
false articles, critical of capitalism and the war; Pierce v.
United States, 252 U. S. 239 (1920) -- circulation of copies of a four-page pamphlet written by
a clergyman, attacking Page 341 U. S. 505 the purposes of the war and United States' participation
therein. Justice Holmes wrote the opinions for a unanimous Court in Schenck, Frohwerk and Debs. He and Justice
Brandeis dissented in Abrams, Schaefer and Pierce. The basis of these dissents was that, because of
the protection which the First Amendment gives to speech, the
evidence in each case was insufficient to show that the defendants
had created the requisite danger under Schenck. But these
dissents did not mark a change of principle. The dissenters doubted
only the probable effectiveness of the puny efforts toward
subversion. In Abrams, they wrote,
"I do not doubt for a moment that, by the same reasoning that
would justify punishing persuasion to murder, the United States
constitutionally may punish speech that produces or is intended to
produce a clear and imminent danger that it will bring about
forthwith certain substantive evils that the United States
constitutionally may seek to prevent."
250 U.S. at 250 U. S. 627 .
And in Schaefer the test was said to be one of "degree,"
251 U.S. at 251 U. S. 482 ,
although it is not clear whether "degree" refers to clear and
present danger or evil. Perhaps both were meant.
The rule we deduce from these cases is that, where an offense is
specified by a statute in nonspeech or nonpress terms, a conviction
relying upon speech or press as evidence of violation may be
sustained only when the speech or publication created a "clear and
present danger" of attempting or accomplishing the prohibited
crime, e.g., interference with enlistment. The dissents,
we repeat, in emphasizing the value of speech, were addressed to
the argument of the sufficiency of the evidence.
The next important case [ Footnote 4 ] before the Court in which free speech was the
crux of the conflict was Gitlow v. New York, 268 U.
S. 652 (1925). There, New York had Page 341 U. S. 506 made it a crime to advocate "the necessity or propriety of
overthrowing . . . organized government by force. . . ." The
evidence of violation of the statute was that the defendant had
published a Manifesto attacking the Government and capitalism. The
convictions were sustained, Justices Holmes and Brandeis
dissenting. The majority refused to apply the "clear and present
danger" test to the specific utterance. Its reasoning was as
follows: the "clear and present danger" test was applied to the
utterance itself in Schenck because the question was
merely one of sufficiency of evidence under an admittedly
constitutional statute. Gitlow however, presented a
different question. There a legislature had found that a certain
kind of speech was, itself, harmful and unlawful. The
constitutionality of such a state statute had to be adjudged by
this Court just as it determined the constitutionality of any state
statute, namely, whether the statute was "reasonable." Since it was
entirely reasonable for a state to attempt to protect itself from
violent overthrow, the statute was perforce reasonable. The only
question remaining in the case became whether there was evidence to
support the conviction, a question which gave the majority no
difficulty. Justices Holmes and Brandeis refused to accept this
approach, but insisted that, wherever speech was the evidence of
the violation, it was necessary to show that the speech created the
"clear and present danger" of the substantive evil which the
legislature had the right to prevent. Justices Holmes and Brandeis,
then, made no distinction between a federal statute which made
certain acts unlawful, the evidence to support the conviction being
speech, and a statute which made speech itself the crime. This
approach was emphasized in Whitney v. California, 274 U. S. 357 (1927), where the Court was confronted with a conviction under the
California Criminal Syndicalist statute. The Court sustained the
conviction, Justices Brandeis and Holmes Page 341 U. S. 507 concurring in the result. In their concurrence they repeated
that, even though the legislature had designated certain speech as
criminal, this could not prevent the defendant from showing that
there was no danger that the substantive evil would be brought
about.
Although no case subsequent to Whitney and Gitlow has expressly overruled the majority opinions in
those cases, there is little doubt that subsequent opinions have
inclined toward the Holmes-Brandeis rationale. [ Footnote 5 ] And in American Communications
Assn. v. Douds, supra, we were called upon to decide the
validity of § 9(h) of the Labor Management Relations Act of 1947.
That section required officials of unions which desired to avail
themselves of the facilities of the National Labor Relations Board
to take oaths that they did not belong to the Communist Party and
that they did not believe in the overthrow of the Government by
force and violence. We pointed out that Congress did not intend to
punish belief, but rather intended to regulate the conduct of union
affairs. We therefore held that any indirect sanction on speech
which might arise from the oath requirement did not present a
proper case for the "clear and present danger" test, for the
regulation was aimed at conduct, rather than speech. In discussing
the proper measure of evaluation of this kind of legislation, we
suggested that the Homes-Brandeis philosophy insisted that,
where Page 341 U. S. 508 there was a direct restriction upon speech, a "clear and present
danger" that the substantive evil would be caused was necessary
before the statute in question could be constitutionally applied.
And we stated,
"[The First] Amendment requires that one be permitted to believe
what he will. It requires that one be permitted to advocate what he
will unless there is a clear and present danger that a substantial
public evil will result therefrom."
339 U.S. at 339 U. S. 412 .
But we further suggested that neither Justice Holmes nor Justice
Brandeis ever envisioned that a shorthand phrase should be
crystallized into a rigid rule to be applied inflexibly without
regard to the circumstances of each case. Speech is not an
absolute, above and beyond control by the legislature when its
judgment, subject to review here, is that certain kinds of speech
are so undesirable as to warrant criminal sanction. Nothing is more
certain in modern society than the principle that there are no
absolutes, that a name, a phrase, a standard has meaning only when
associated with the considerations which gave birth to the
nomenclature. See American Communications Assn. v. Douds, 339 U.S. at 339 U. S. 397 .
To those who would paralyze our Government in the face of impending
threat by encasing it in a semantic straitjacket we must reply that
all concepts are relative.
In this case, we are squarely presented with the application of
the "clear and present danger" test, and must decide what that
phrase imports. We first note that many of the cases in which this
Court has reversed convictions by use of this or similar tests have
been based on the fact that the interest which the State was
attempting to protect was itself too insubstantial to warrant
restriction of speech. In this category we may put such cases as Schneider v. State, 308 U. S. 147 (1939); Cantwell v. Connecticut, 310 U.
S. 296 (1940); Martin v. Struthers, 319 U. S. 141 (1943); West Virginia Board of
Education Page 341 U. S. 509 v. Barnette, 319 U. S. 624 (1943); Thomas v. Collins, 323 U.
S. 516 (1945); Marsh v. Alabama, 326 U.
S. 501 (1946); but cf. Prince v. Massachusetts, 321 U. S. 158 (1944); Cox v. New Hampshire, 312 U.
S. 569 (1941). Overthrow of the Government by force and
violence is certainly a substantial enough interest for the
Government to limit speech. Indeed, this is the ultimate value of
any society, for if a society cannot protect its very structure
from armed internal attack, it must follow that no subordinate
value can be protected. If, then, this interest may be protected,
the literal problem which is presented is what has been meant by
the use of the phrase "clear and present danger" of the utterances
bringing about the evil within the power of Congress to punish.
Obviously, the words cannot mean that, before the Government may
act, it must wait until the putsch is about to be executed, the
plans have been laid and the signal is awaited. If Government is
aware that a group aiming at its overthrow is attempting to
indoctrinate its members and to commit them to a course whereby
they will strike when the leaders feel the circumstances permit,
action by the Government is required. The argument that there is no
need for Government to concern itself, for Government is strong, it
possesses ample powers to put down a rebellion, it may defeat the
revolution with ease needs no answer. For that is not the question.
Certainly an attempt to overthrow the Government by force, even
though doomed from the outset because of inadequate numbers or
power of the revolutionists, is a sufficient evil for Congress to
prevent. The damage which such attempts create both physically and
politically to a nation makes it impossible to measure the validity
in terms of the probability of success, or the immediacy of a
successful attempt. In the instant case, the trial judge charged
the jury that they could not convict unless they found that
petitioners intended to overthrow the Government Page 341 U. S. 510 "as speedily as circumstances would permit." This does not mean,
and could not properly mean, that they would not strike until there
was certainty of success. What was meant was that the
revolutionists would strike when they thought the time was ripe. We
must therefore reject the contention that success or probability of
success is the criterion.
The situation with which Justices Holmes and Brandeis were
concerned in Gitlow was a comparatively isolated event,
bearing little relation in their minds to any substantial threat to
the safety of the community. Such also is true of cases like Fiske v. Kansas, 274 U. S. 380 (1927), and De Jonge v. Oregon, 299 U.
S. 353 (1937); but cf. Lazar v. Pennsylvania, 286 U.S. 532 (1932). They were not confronted with any situation
comparable to the instant one -- the development of an apparatus
designed and dedicated to the overthrow of the Government, in the
context of world crisis after crisis.
Chief Judge Learned Hand, writing for the majority below,
interpreted the phrase as follows:
"In each case, [courts] must ask whether the gravity of the
'evil,' discounted by its improbability, justifies such invasion of
free speech as is necessary to avoid the danger."
183 F.2d at 212. We adopt this statement of the rule. As
articulated by Chief Judge Hand, it is as succinct and inclusive as
any other we might devise at this time. It takes into consideration
those factors which we deem relevant, and relates their
significances. More we cannot expect from words.
Likewise, we are in accord with the court below, which affirmed
the trial court's finding that the requisite danger existed. The
mere fact that, from the period 1945 to 1948, petitioners'
activities did not result in an attempt to overthrow the Government
by force and violence is, of course, no answer to the fact that
there was a group that was ready to make the attempt. The
formation Page 341 U. S. 511 by petitioners of such a highly organized conspiracy, with
rigidly disciplined members subject to call when the leaders, these
petitioners, felt that the time had come for action, coupled with
the inflammable nature of world conditions, similar uprisings in
other countries, and the touch-and-go nature of our relations with
countries with whom petitioners were in the very least
ideologically attuned, convince us that their convictions were
justified on this score. And this analysis disposes of the
contention that a conspiracy to advocate, as distinguished from the
advocacy itself, cannot be constitutionally restrained, because it
comprises only the preparation. It is the existence of the
conspiracy which creates the danger. Cf. Pinkerton v. United
States, 328 U. S. 640 (1946); Goldman v. United States, 245 U.
S. 474 (1918); United States v. Rabinowich, 238 U. S. 78 (1915). If the ingredients of the reaction are present, we cannot
bind the Government to wait until the catalyst is added. IV Although we have concluded that the finding that there was a
sufficient danger to warrant the application of the statute was
justified on the merits, there remains the problem of whether the
trial judge's treatment of the issue was correct. He charged the
jury, in relevant part, as follows:
"In further construction and interpretation of the statute, I
charge you that it is not the abstract doctrine of overthrowing or
destroying organized government by unlawful means which is
denounced by this law, but the teaching and advocacy of action for
the accomplishment of that purpose, by language reasonably and
ordinarily calculated to incite persons to such action.
Accordingly, you cannot find the defendants or any of them guilty
of the crime charged Page 341 U. S. 512 unless you are satisfied beyond a reasonable doubt that they
conspired to organize a society, group and assembly of persons who
teach and advocate the overthrow or destruction of the Government
of the United States by force and violence and to advocate and
teach the duty and necessity of overthrowing or destroying the
Government of the United States by force and violence, with the
intent that such teaching and advocacy be of a rule or principle of
action and by language reasonably and ordinarily calculated to
incite persons to such action, all with the intent to cause the
overthrow or destruction of the Government of the United States by
force and violence as speedily as circumstances would permit."
" * * * *" "If you are satisfied that the evidence establishes beyond a
reasonable doubt that the defendants, or any of them, are guilty of
a violation of the statute, as I have interpreted it to you, I find
as matter of law that there is sufficient danger of a substantive
evil that the Congress has a right to prevent to justify the
application of the statute under the First Amendment of the
Constitution."
"This is matter of law about which you have no concern. It is a
finding on a matter of law which I deem essential to support my
ruling that the case should be submitted to you to pass upon the
guilt or innocence of the defendants. . . ."
It is thus clear that he reserved the question of the existence
of the danger for his own determination, and the question becomes
whether the issue is of such a nature that it should have been
submitted to the jury.
The first paragraph of the quoted instructions calls for the
jury to find the facts essential to establish the substantive
crime, violation of §§ 2(a)(1) and 2(a)(3) of Page 341 U. S. 513 the Smith Act, involved in the conspiracy charge. There can be
no doubt that, if the jury found those facts against the
petitioners, violation of the Act would be established. The
argument that the action of the trial court is erroneous in
declaring as a matter of law that such violation shows sufficient
danger to justify the punishment despite the First Amendment rests
on the theory that a jury must decide a question of the application
of the First Amendment. We do not agree.
When facts are found that establish the violation of a statute,
the protection against conviction afforded by the First Amendment
is a matter of law. The doctrine that there must be a clear and
present danger of a substantive evil that Congress has a right to
prevent is a judicial rule to be applied as a matter of law by the
courts. The guilt is established by proof of facts. Whether the
First Amendment protects the activity which constitutes the
violation of the statute must depend upon a judicial determination
of the scope of the First Amendment applied to the circumstances of
the case.
Petitioners' reliance upon Justice Brandeis' language in his
concurrence in Whitney, supra, is misplaced. In that case,
Justice Brandeis pointed out that the defendant could have made the
existence of the requisite danger the important issue at her trial,
but that she had not done so. In discussing this failure, he stated
that the defendant could have had the issue determined by the court
or the jury. [ Footnote 6 ] No
realistic construction of this disjunctive language Page 341 U. S. 514 could arrive at the conclusion that he intended to state that
the question was only determinable by a jury. Nor is the incidental
statement of the majority in Pierce, supra, of any more
persuasive effect. [ Footnote 7 ]
There, the issue of the probable effect of the publication had been
submitted to the jury, and the majority was apparently addressing
its remarks to the contention of the dissenters that the jury could
not reasonably have returned a verdict of guilty on the evidence.
[ Footnote 8 ] Indeed, in the
very case in which the phrase was born, Schenck, this
Court itself examined the record to find whether the requisite
danger appeared, and the issue was not submitted to a jury. And in
every later case in which the Court has measured the validity of a
statute by the "clear and present danger" test, that determination
has been by the court, the question of the danger not being
submitted to the jury.
The question in this case is whether the statute which the
legislature has enacted may be constitutionally applied. In other
words, the Court must examine judicially Page 341 U. S. 515 the application of the statute to the particular situation, to
ascertain if the Constitution prohibits the conviction. We hold
that the statute may be applied where there is a "clear and present
danger" of the substantive evil which the legislature had the right
to prevent. Bearing, as it does, the marks of a "question of law,"
the issue is properly one for the judge to decide. V There remains to be discussed the question of vagueness --
whether the statute as we have interpreted it is too vague, not
sufficiently advising those who would speak of the limitations upon
their activity. It is urged that such vagueness contravenes the
First and Fifth Amendments. This argument is particularly
nonpersuasive when presented by petitioners, who, the jury found,
intended to overthrow the Government as speedily as circumstances
would permit. See Abrams v. United States, 250 U.
S. 616 , 250 U. S.
627 -629 (1919) (dissenting opinion); Whitney v.
California, 274 U. S. 357 , 274 U. S. 373 (1927) (concurring opinion); Taylor v. Mississippi, 319 U. S. 583 , 319 U. S. 589 (1943). A claim of guilelessness ill becomes those with evil
intent. Williams v. United States, 341 U. S.
97 , 341 U. S.
101 -102 (1951); Jordan v. De George, 341 U. S. 223 , 341 U. S.
230 -232 (1951); American Communications Assn. v.
Douds, 339 U.S. at 339 U. S. 413 ; Screws v. United States, 325 U. S. 91 , 325 U. S. 101 (1945).
We agree that the standard as defined is not a neat,
mathematical formulary. Like all verbalizations it is subject to
criticism on the score of indefiniteness. But petitioners
themselves contend that the verbalization "clear and present
danger" is the proper standard. We see no difference, from the
standpoint of vagueness, whether the standard of "clear and present
danger" is one contained in haec verba within the statute,
or whether it is the judicial measure of constitutional
applicability. We Page 341 U. S. 516 have shown the indeterminate standard the phrase necessarily
connotes. We do not think we have rendered that standard any more
indefinite by our attempt to sum up the factors which are included
within its scope. We think it well serves to indicate to those who
would advocate constitutionally prohibited conduct that there is a
line beyond which they may not go -- a line which they, in full
knowledge of what they intend and the circumstances in which their
activity takes place, will well appreciate and understand. Williams, supra, at 341 U. S.
101 -102; Jordan, supra, at 341 U. S.
230 -232; United States v. Petrillo, 332 U. S. 1 , 332 U. S. 7 (1948); United States v. Wurzbach, 280 U.
S. 396 , 280 U. S. 399 (1930); Nash v. United States, 229 U.
S. 373 , 229 U. S.
376 -377 (1913). Where there is doubt as to the intent of
the defendants, the nature of their activities, or their power to
bring about the evil, this Court will review the convictions with
the scrupulous care demanded by our Constitution. But we are not
convinced that, because there may be borderline cases at some time
in the future, these convictions should be reversed because of the
argument that these petitioners could not know that their
activities were constitutionally proscribed by the statute.
We have not discussed many of the questions which could be
extracted from the record, although they were treated in detail by
the court below. Our limited grant of the writ of certiorari has
withdrawn from our consideration at this date those questions,
which include, inter alia, sufficiency of the evidence,
composition of jury, and conduct of the trial.
We hold that §§ 2(a)(1), 2(a)(3) and 3 of the Smith Act do not
inherently, or as construed or applied in the instant case, violate
the First Amendment and other provisions of the Bill of Rights, or
the First and Fifth Amendments because of indefiniteness.
Petitioners intended to overthrow the Government of the United
States as speedily as the circumstances would permit. Their
conspiracy Page 341 U. S. 517 to organize the Communist Party and to teach and advocate the
overthrow of the Government of the United States by force and
violence created a "clear and present danger" of an attempt to
overthrow the Government by force and violence. They were properly
and constitutionally convicted for violation of the Smith Act. The
judgments of conviction are Affirmed. MR. JUSTICE CLARK took no part in the consideration or decision
of this case.
[ Footnote 1 ]
Following the dissolution of the Communist International in
1943, the Communist Party of the United States dissolved and was
reconstituted as the Communist Political Association. The program
of this Association was one of cooperation between labor and
management, and, in general, one designed to achieve national unity
and peace and prosperity in the post-war period.
[ Footnote 2 ]
We have treated this point because of the discussion accorded it
by the Court of Appeals and its importance to the administration of
this statute, compare Johnson v. United States, 318 U. S. 189 (1943), although petitioners themselves requested a charge similar
to the one given, and under Rule 30 of the Federal Rules of
Criminal Procedure would appear to be barred from raising this
point on appeal. Cf. Boyd v. United States, 271 U.
S. 104 (1926).
[ Footnote 3 ] Toledo Newspaper Co. v. United States, 247 U.
S. 402 (1918); Fox v. Washington, 236 U.
S. 273 (1915); Davis v. Massachusetts, 167 U. S. 43 (1897); see Gompers v. Bucks Stove & Range Co., 221 U. S. 418 , 221 U. S. 439 (1911); Robertson v. Baldwin, 165 U.
S. 275 , 165 U. S. 281 (1897).
[ Footnote 4 ] Cf. Gilbert v. Minnesota, 254 U.
S. 325 (1920).
[ Footnote 5 ]
Contempt of court: Craig v. Harney, 331 U.
S. 367 , 331 U. S. 373 (1947); Pennecamp v. Florida, 328 U.
S. 331 , 328 U. S.
333 -336 (1946); Bridges v. California, 314 U. S. 252 , 314 U. S.
260 -263 (1941).
Validity of state statute: Thomas v. Collins, 323 U. S. 516 , 323 U. S. 530 (1945); Taylor v. Mississippi, 319 U.
S. 583 , 319 U. S.
589 -590 (1943); Thornhill v. Alabama, 310 U. S. 88 , 310 U. S.
104 -106 (1940).
Validity of local ordinance or regulation: West Virginia
Board of Education v. Barnette, 319 U.
S. 624 , 319 U. S. 639 (1943); Carlson v. California, 310 U.
S. 106 , 310 U. S. 113 (1940).
Common law offense: Cantwell v. Connecticut, 310 U. S. 296 , 310 U. S. 308 , 310 U. S. 311 (1940).
[ Footnote 6 ]
"Whether, in 1919, when Miss Whitney did the things complained
of, there was in California such clear and present danger of
serious evil might have been made the important issue in the case.
She might have required that the issue be determined either by the
court or the jury. She claimed below that the statute, as applied
to her, violated the Federal Constitution, but she did not claim
that it was void because there was no clear and present danger of
serious evil, nor did she request that the existence of these
conditions of a valid measure thus restricting the rights of free
speech and assembly be passed upon by the court or a jury. On the other hand, there was evidence on which the court or
jury might have found that such danger existed."
(Emphasis added.) 274 U.S. at 274 U. S.
379 .
[ Footnote 7 ]
"Whether the printed words would, in fact, produce as a
proximate result a material interference with the recruiting or
enlistment service, or the operation or success of the forces of
the United States, was a question for the jury to decide in view of
all the circumstances of the time and considering the place and
manner of distribution." 252 U.S.
239 , 252 U. S. 250 (1920).
[ Footnote 8 ]
A similarly worded expression is found in that part of the
majority opinion sustaining the overruling of the defendants'
general demurrer to the indictment. 252 U.S. at 252 U. S. 244 .
Since the defendants had not raised the issue of "clear and present
danger" at the trial, it is clear that the Court was not faced with
the question whether the trial judge erred in not determining, as a
conclusive matter, the existence or nonexistence of a "clear and
present danger." The only issue to which the remarks were addressed
was whether the indictment sufficiently alleged the violation.
MR. JUSTICE FRANKFURTER, concurring in affirmance of the
judgment.
The defendants were convicted under § 3 of the Smith Act for
conspiring to violate § 2 of that Act, which makes it unlawful
"to organize or help to organize any society, group, or assembly
of persons who teach, advocate, or encourage the overthrow or
destruction of any government in the United States by force or
violence."
Act of June 28, 1940, § 2(a)(3), 54 Stat. 670, 671, 18 U.S.C. §
10, now 18 U.S.C. § 2385. The substance of the indictment is that
the defendants between April 1, 1945, and July 20, 1948, agreed to
bring about the dissolution of a body known as the Communist
Political Association and to organize in its place the Communist
Party of the United States; that the aim of the new party was "the
overthrow and destruction of the Government of the United States by
force and violence"; that the defendants were to assume leadership
of the Party and to recruit members for it and that the Party was
to publish books and conduct classes, teaching the duty and the
necessity of forceful overthrow. The jury found all the defendants
guilty. With one exception, each was sentenced to imprisonment for
five years and to a fine of $10,000. The convictions were affirmed
by the Court of Appeals for the Second Page 341 U. S. 518 Circuit. 183 F.2d 201. We were asked to review this affirmance
on all the grounds considered by the Court of Appeals. These
included not only the scope of the freedom of speech guaranteed by
the Constitution, but also serious questions regarding the legal
composition of the jury and the fair conduct of the trial. We
granted certiorari, strictly limited, however, to the contention
that §§ 2 and 3 of the Smith Act, inherently and as applied,
violated the First and Fifth Amendments. 340 U.S. 863. No attempt
was made to seek an enlargement of the range of questions thus
defined, and these alone are now open for our consideration. All
others are foreclosed by the decision of the Court of Appeals.
As thus limited, the controversy in this Court turns essentially
on the instructions given to the jury for determining guilt or
innocence. 9 F.R.D. 367. The first question is whether -- wholly
apart from constitutional matters -- the judge's charge properly
explained to the jury what it is that the Smith Act condemns. The
conclusion that he did so requires no labored argument. On the
basis of the instructions, the jury found, for the purpose of our
review, that the advocacy which the defendants conspired to promote
was to be a rule of action, by language reasonably calculated to
incite persons to such action, and was intended to cause the
overthrow of the Government by force and violence as soon as
circumstances permit. This brings us to the ultimate issue. In
enacting a statute which makes it a crime for the defendants to
conspire to do what they have been found to have conspired to do,
did Congress exceed its constitutional power?
Few questions of comparable import have come before this Court
in recent years. The appellants maintain that they have a right to
advocate a political theory, so long, at least, as their advocacy
does not create an immediate danger of obvious magnitude to the
very existence of Page 341 U. S. 519 our present scheme of society. On the other hand, the Government
asserts the right to safeguard the security of the Nation by such a
measure as the Smith Act. Our judgment is thus solicited on a
conflict of interests of the utmost concern to the wellbeing of the
country. This conflict of interests cannot be resolved by a
dogmatic preference for one or the other, nor by a sonorous formula
which is, in fact, only a euphemistic disguise for an unresolved
conflict. If adjudication is to be a rational process, we cannot
escape a candid examination of the conflicting claims with full
recognition that both are supported by weighty title-deeds. I There come occasions in law, as elsewhere, when the familiar
needs to be recalled. Our whole history proves even more decisively
than the course of decisions in this Court that the United States
has the powers inseparable from a sovereign nation.
"America has chosen to be, in many respects, and to many
purposes, a nation, and for all these purposes, her government is
complete; to all these objects, it is competent."
Chief Justice Marshall in Cohens v.
Virginia , 6 Wheat. 264, 19 U. S. 414 .
The right of a government to maintain its existence --
self-preservation -- is the most pervasive aspect of sovereignty.
"Security against foreign danger," wrote Madison, "is one of the
primitive objects of civil society." The Federalist, No. 41. The
constitutional power to act upon this basic principle has been
recognized by this Court at different periods and under diverse
circumstances.
"To preserve its independence, and give security against foreign
aggression and encroachment, is the highest duty of every nation,
and to attain these ends nearly all other considerations are to be
subordinated. It matters not in what form such aggression and
encroachment come. . . . The government, possessing the powers
which are to be exercised Page 341 U. S. 520 for protection and security, is clothed with authority to
determine the occasion on which the powers shall be called forth. .
. ." Chinese Exclusion Case, 130 U.
S. 581 , 130 U. S. 606 . See also De Lima v. Bidwell, 182 U. S.
1 ; Mackenzie v. Hare, 239 U.
S. 299 ; Missouri v. Holland, 252 U.
S. 416 ; United States v. Curtiss-Wright Corp., 299 U. S. 304 . The
most tragic experience in our history is a poignant reminder that
the Nation's continued existence may be threatened from within. To
protect itself from such threats, the Federal Government
"is invested with all those inherent and implied powers which,
at the time of adopting the Constitution, were generally considered
to belong to every government as such, and as being essential to
the exercise of its functions."
Mr. Justice Bradley, concurring in Legal
Tender Cases , 12 Wall. 457, 79 U. S. 554 , 79 U. S. 556 , and see In re Debs, 158 U. S. 564 , 158 U. S.
582 .
But even the all-embracing power and duty of self-preservation
are not absolute. Like the war power, which is indeed an aspect of
the power of self-preservation, it is subject to applicable
constitutional limitations. See Hamilton v. Kentucky
Distilleries Co., 251 U. S. 146 , 251 U. S. 156 .
Our Constitution has no provision lifting restrictions upon
governmental authority during periods of emergency, although the
scope of a restriction may depend on the circumstances in which it
is invoked.
The First Amendment is such a restriction. It exacts obedience
even during periods of war; it is applicable when war clouds are
not figments of the imagination no less than when they are. The
First Amendment categorically demands that
"Congress shall make no law respecting an establishment of
religion, or prohibiting the free exercise thereof; or abridging
the freedom of speech, or of the press; or the right of the people
peaceably to assemble, and to petition the Government for a redress
of grievances."
The right of a man to think what he Page 341 U. S. 521 pleases, to write what he thinks, and to have his thoughts made
available for others to hear or read has an engaging ring of
universality. The Smith Act and this conviction under it no doubt
restrict the exercise of free speech and assembly. Does that,
without more, dispose of the matter?
Just as there are those who regard as invulnerable every measure
for which the claim of national survival is invoked, there are
those who find in the Constitution a wholly unfettered right of
expression. Such literalness treats the words of the Constitution
as though they were found on a piece of outworn parchment instead
of being words that have called into being a nation with a past to
be preserved for the future. The soil in which the Bill of Rights
grew was not a soil of arid pedantry. The historic antecedents of
the First Amendment preclude the notion that its purpose was to
give unqualified immunity to every expression that touched on
matters within the range of political interest. The Massachusetts
Constitution of 1780 guaranteed free speech; yet there are records
of at least three convictions for political libels obtained between
1799 and 1803. [ Footnote 2/1 ] The
Pennsylvania Constitution of 1790 and the Delaware Constitution of
1792 expressly imposed liability for abuse of the right of free
speech. [ Footnote 2/2 ] Madison's
own State put on its books in 1792 a statute confining the abusive
exercise of the right of utterance. [ Footnote 2/3 ] And it deserves to be noted that, in
writing to John Adams' wife, Jefferson did not rest his
condemnation of the Sedition Act of 1798 on his belief in Page 341 U. S. 522 unrestrained utterance as to political matter. The First
Amendment, he argued, reflected a limitation upon Federal power,
leaving the right to enforce restrictions on speech to the States.
[ Footnote 2/4 ] Page 341 U. S. 523 The language of the First Amendment is to be read not as barren
words found in a dictionary but as symbols of historic experience
illumined by the presuppositions of those who employed them. Not
what words did Madison and Hamilton use, but what was it in their
minds which they conveyed? Free speech is subject to prohibition of
those abuses of expression which a civilized society may forbid. As
in the case of every other provision of the Constitution that is
not crystallized by the nature of its technical concepts, the fact
that the First Amendment is not self-defining and self-enforcing
neither impairs its usefulness nor compels its paralysis as a
living instrument. Page 341 U. S. 524 "The law is perfectly well settled," this Court said over fifty
years ago,
"that the first ten amendments to the Constitution, commonly
known as the Bill of Rights, were not intended to lay down any
novel principles of government, but simply to embody certain
guaranties and immunities which we had inherited from our English
ancestors, and which had from time immemorial been subject to
certain well recognized exceptions arising from the necessities of
the case. In incorporating these principles into the fundamental
law, there was no intention of disregarding the exceptions, which
continued to be recognized as if they had been formally
expressed." Robertson v. Baldwin, 165 U. S. 275 , 165 U. S. 281 .
That this represents the authentic view of the Bill of Rights and
the spirit in which it must be construed has been recognized again
and again in cases that have come here within the last fifty years. See, e.g., Gompers v. United States, 233 U.
S. 604 , 233 U. S. 610 .
Absolute rules would inevitably lead to absolute exceptions, and
such exceptions would eventually corrode the rules. [ Footnote 2/5 ] The demands of free speech in
a democratic society, as well as the interest Page 341 U. S. 525 in national security are better served by candid and informed
weighing of the competing interests, within the confines of the
judicial process, than by announcing dogmas too inflexible for the
non-Euclidian problems to be solved.
But how are competing interests to be assessed? Since they are
not subject to quantitative ascertainment, the issue necessarily
resolves itself into asking, who is to make the adjustment? -- who
is to balance the relevant factors and ascertain which interest is
in the circumstances to prevail? Full responsibility for the choice
cannot be given to the courts. Courts are not representative
bodies. They are not designed to be a good reflex of a democratic
society. Their judgment is best informed, and therefore most
dependable, within narrow limits. Their essential quality is
detachment, founded on independence. History teaches that the
independence of the judiciary is jeopardized when courts become
embroiled in the passions of the day and assume primary
responsibility in choosing between competing political, economic
and social pressures.
Primary responsibility for adjusting the interests which compete
in the situation before us of necessity belongs to the Congress.
The nature of the power to be exercised by this Court has been
delineated in decisions not charged with the emotional appeal of
situations such as that now before us. We are to set aside the
judgment of those whose duty it is to legislate only if there is no
reasonable basis for it. Sinking-Fund Cases, 99 U. S.
700 , 99 U. S. 718 ; Mugler v. Kansas, 123 U. S. 623 , 123 U. S.
660 -661; United States v. Carolene Products
Co., 304 U. S. 144 . We
are to determine whether a statute is sufficiently definite to meet
the constitutional requirements of due process, and whether it
respects the safeguards against undue concentration of authority
secured by separation of power. United States v. Cohen Grocery
Co., 255 U. S. 81 . Page 341 U. S. 526 We must assure fairness of procedure, allowing full scope to
governmental discretion but mindful of its impact on individuals in
the context of the problem involved. Joint Anti-Fascist Refugee
Comm. v. McGrath, 341 U. S. 123 .
And, of course, the proceedings in a particular case before us must
have the warrant of substantial proof. Beyond these powers we must
not go; we must scrupulously observe the narrow limits of judicial
authority even though self-restraint is alone set over us. Above
all, we must remember that this Court's power of judicial review is
not "an exercise of the powers of a super-legislature." Mr. Justice
Brandeis and Mr. Justice Holmes, dissenting in Burns Baking Co.
v. Bryan, 264 U. S. 504 , 264 U. S.
534 .
A generation ago, this distribution of responsibility would not
have been questioned. See Fox v. Washington, 236 U.
S. 273 ; Meyer v. Nebraska, 262 U.
S. 390 ; Bartels v. Iowa, 262 U.
S. 404 ; cf. New York ex rel. Bryant v.
Zimmerman, 278 U. S. 63 . But,
in recent decisions, we have made explicit what has long been
implicitly recognized. In reviewing statutes which restrict
freedoms protected by the First Amendment, we have emphasized the
close relation which those freedoms bear to maintenance of a free
society. See Kovacs v. Cooper, 336 U. S.
77 , 336 U. S. 89 , 336 U. S. 95 (concurring). Some members of the Court -- and at times a majority
-- have done more. They have suggested that our function in
reviewing statutes restricting freedom of expression differs
sharply from our normal duty in sitting in judgment on legislation.
It has been said that such statutes
"must be justified by clear public interest, threatened not
doubtfully or remotely, but by clear and present danger. The
rational connection between the remedy provided and the evil to be
curbed, which in other contexts might support legislation against
attack on due process grounds, will not suffice." Thomas v. Collins, 323 U. S. 516 , 323 U. S. 530 .
It has been suggested, with the casualness of a footnote, that such
legislation is not Page 341 U. S. 527 presumptively valid, see United States v. Carolene Products
Co., 304 U. S. 144 , 304 U. S. 152 ,
n. 4, and it has been weightily reiterated that freedom of speech
has a "preferred position" among constitutional safeguards. Kovacs v. Cooper, 336 U. S. 77 , 336 U. S.
88 .
The precise meaning intended to be conveyed by these phrases
need not now be pursued. It is enough to note that they have
recurred in the Court's opinions, and their cumulative force has,
not without justification, engendered belief that there is a
constitutional principle, expressed by those attractive but
imprecise words, prohibiting restriction upon utterance unless it
creates a situation of "imminent" peril against which legislation
may guard. [ Footnote 2/6 ] It is on
this body of the Court's pronouncements that the defendants'
argument here is based.
In all fairness, the argument cannot be met by reinterpreting
the Court's frequent use of "clear" and "present" to mean an
entertainable "probability." In giving this meaning to the phrase
"clear and present danger," the Court of Appeals was fastidiously
confining the rhetoric of opinions to the exact scope of what was
decided by them. We have greater responsibility for having given
constitutional support, over repeated protests, to uncritical
libertarian generalities. Page 341 U. S. 528 Nor is the argument of the defendants adequately met by citing
isolated cases. Adjustment of clash of interests which are at once
subtle and fundamental is not likely to reveal entire consistency
in a series of instances presenting the clash. It is not too
difficult to find what one seeks in the language of decisions
reporting the effort to reconcile free speech with the interests
with which it conflicts. The case for the defendants requires that
their conviction be tested against the entire body of our relevant
decisions. Since the significance of every expression of thought
derives from the circumstances evoking it, results reached, rather
than language employed give the vital meaning. See Cohens v.
Virginia , 6 Wheat. 264, 19 U. S. 442 ;
Wambaugh, The Study of Cases, 10.
There is an added reason why we must turn to the decisions.
"Great cases," it is appropriate to remember,
"like hard cases, make bad law. For great cases are called great
not by reason of their real importance in shaping the law of the
future, but because of some accident of immediate overwhelming
interest which appeals to the feelings and distorts the judgment.
These immediate interests exercise a kind of hydraulic pressure
which makes what previously was clear seem doubtful, and before
which even well settled principles of law will bend."
Mr. Justice Holmes, dissenting in Northern Securities Co. v.
United States, 193 U. S. 197 , 193 U. S.
400 -401.
This is such a case. Unless we are to compromise judicial
impartiality and subject these defendants to the risk of an ad
hoc judgment influenced by the impregnating atmosphere of the
times, the constitutionality of their conviction must be determined
by principles established in cases decided in more tranquil
periods. If those decisions are to be used as a guide, and not as
an argument, it is important to view them as a whole, and to
distrust the easy generalizations to which some of them lend
themselves. Page 341 U. S. 529 II We have recognized and resolved conflicts between speech and
competing interests in six different types of cases. [ Footnote 2/7 ]
1. The cases involving a conflict between the interest in
allowing free expression of ideas in public places and the interest
in protection of the public peace and the primary uses of streets
and parks, were too recently considered to be rehearsed here. Niemotko v. Maryland, 340 U. S. 268 , 340 U. S. 273 .
It suffices to recall that the result in each case was found to
turn on the character of the interest with which the speech
clashed, the method used to impose the restriction, and the nature
and circumstances of the utterance prohibited. While the decisions
recognized the importance of free speech and carefully scrutinized
the justification for its regulation, they rejected the notion that
vindication of the deep public interest in freedom of expression
requires subordination of all conflicting values.
2. A critique of the cases testing restrictions on picketing is
made more difficult by the inadequate recognition by the Court from
the outset that the loyalties and responses evoked and exacted by
picket lines differentiate this form of expression from other modes
of communication. See Thornhill v. Alabama, 310 U. S.
88 . But the Page 341 U. S. 530 crux of the decision in the Thornhill case was that a
State could not constitutionally punish peaceful picketing when
neither the aim of the picketing nor the manner in which it was
carried out conflicted with a substantial interest. In subsequent
decisions, we sustained restrictions designed to prevent recurrence
of violence, Milk Wagon Drivers Union v. Meadowmoor
Dairies, 312 U. S. 287 , or
reasonably to limit the area of industrial strife, Carpenters
& Joiners Union v. Ritter's Cafe, 315 U.
S. 722 ; cf. Bakery & Pastry Drivers Local v.
Wohl, 315 U. S. 769 . We
held that a State's policy against restraints of trade justified it
in prohibiting picketing which violated that policy, Giboney v.
Empire Storage Co., 336 U. S. 490 ; we
sustained restrictions designed to encourage self-employed persons, International Brotherhood of Teamsters Union v. Hanke, 339 U. S. 470 , and
to prevent racial discrimination, Hughes v. Superior
Court, 339 U. S. 460 . The
Fourteenth Amendment bars a State from prohibiting picketing when
there is no fair justification for the breadth of the restriction
imposed. American Federation of Labor v. Swing, 312 U. S. 321 ; Cafeteria Employees Union v. Angelos, 320 U.
S. 293 . But it does not prevent a State from denying the
means of communication that picketing affords in a fair balance
between the interests of trade unionism and other interests of the
community.
3. In three cases, we have considered the scope and application
of the power of the Government to exclude, deport, or denaturalize
aliens because of their advocacy or their beliefs. In United
States ex rel. Turner v. Williams, 194 U.
S. 279 , we held that the First Amendment did not disable
Congress from directing the exclusion of an alien found in an
administrative proceeding to be an anarchist. "[A]s long as human
governments endure," we said, "they cannot be denied the power of
self-preservation, as that question is presented here." Page 341 U. S. 531 194 U.S. at 194 U. S. 294 .
In Schneiderman v. United States, 320 U.
S. 118 , and Bridges v. Wixon, 326 U.
S. 135 , we did not consider the extent of the power of
Congress. In each case, by a closely divided Court, we interpreted
a statute authorizing denaturalization or deportation to impose on
the Government the strictest standards of proof.
4. History regards "freedom of the press" as indispensable for a
free society and for its government. We have, therefore,
invalidated discriminatory taxation against the press and prior
restraints on publication of defamatory matter. Grosjean v.
American Press Co., 297 U. S. 233 ; Near v. Minnesota, 283 U. S. 697 .
We have also given clear indication of the importance we attach
to dissemination of ideas in reviewing the attempts of States to
reconcile freedom of the press with protection of the integrity of
the judicial process. In Pennekamp v. Florida, 328 U. S. 331 , the
Court agreed that the Fourteenth Amendment barred a State from
adjudging in contempt of court the publisher of critical and
inaccurate comment about portions of a litigation that, for all
practical purposes, were no longer pending. We likewise agreed, in
a minor phase of our decision in Bridges v. California, 314 U. S. 252 ,
that even when statements in the press relate to matters still
pending before a court, convictions for their publication cannot be
sustained if their utterance is too trivial to be deemed a
substantial threat to the impartial administration of justice.
The Court has, however, sharply divided on what constitutes a
sufficient interference with the course of justice. In the first
decision, Patterson v. Colorado, 205 U.
S. 454 , the Court affirmed a judgment for contempt
imposed by a State supreme court for publication of articles
reflecting on the conduct of the court in cases still before it
on Page 341 U. S. 532 motions for rehearing. In the Bridges case, however, a
majority held that a State court could not protect itself from the
implied threat of a powerful newspaper that failure of an elected
judge to impose a severe sentence would be a "serious mistake." The
same case also placed beyond a State's power to punish the
publication of a telegram from the president of an important union
who threatened a damaging strike in the event of an adverse
decision. The majority in Craig v. Harney, 331 U.
S. 367 , 331 U. S. 376 ,
held that the Fourteenth Amendment protected "strong,"
"intemperate," "unfair" criticism of the way an elected lay judge
was conducting a pending civil case. None of the cases establishes
that the public interest in a free press must in all instances
prevail over the public interest in dispassionate adjudication. But
the Bridges and Craig decisions, if they survive,
tend to require a showing that interference be so imminent and so
demonstrable that the power theoretically possessed by the State is
largely paralyzed.
5. Our decision in American Communications Assn. v.
Douds, 339 U. S. 382 ,
recognized that the exercise of political rights protected by the
First Amendment was necessarily discouraged by the requirement of
the Taft-Hartley Act that officers of unions employing the services
of the National Labor Relations Board sign affidavits that they are
not Communists. But we held that the statute was not for this
reason presumptively invalid. The problem, we said, was
"one of weighing the probable effects of the statute upon the
free exercise of the right of speech and assembly against the
congressional determination that political strikes are evils of
conduct which cause substantial harm to interstate commerce and
that Communists and others identified by § 9(h) pose continuing
threats to that public interest when in positions of union
leadership. " Page 341 U. S. 533 339 U.S. at 339 U. S. 400 .
On balance, we decided that the legislative judgment was a
permissible one. [ Footnote 2/8 ]
6. Statutes prohibiting speech because of its tendency to lead
to crime present a conflict of interests which bears directly on
the problem now before us. The first case in which we considered
this conflict was Fox v. Washington, supra. The statute
there challenged had been interpreted to prohibit publication of
matter "encouraging an actual breach of law." We held that the
Fourteenth Amendment did not prohibit application of the statute to
an article which we concluded incited a breach of laws against
indecent exposure. We said that the statute
"lays hold of encouragements that, apart from statute, if
directed to a particular person's conduct, generally would make him
who uttered them guilty of a misdemeanor, if not an accomplice or a
principal in the crime encouraged, and deals with the publication
of them to a wider and less selected audience."
236 U.S. at 236 U. S.
277 -278. To be sure, the Fox case preceded the
explicit absorption of the substance of the First Amendment in the
Fourteenth. But subsequent decisions extended the Fox principle to free speech situations. They are so important to the
problem before us that we must consider them in detail.
(a) The first important application of the principle was made in
six cases arising under the Espionage Act of 1917. That Act
prohibits conspiracies and attempts Page 341 U. S. 534 to "obstruct the recruiting or enlistment service." In each of
the first three cases, Mr. Justice Holmes wrote for a unanimous
Court, affirming the convictions. The evidence in Schenck v.
United States, 249 U. S. 47 ,
showed that the defendant had conspired to circulate among men
called for the draft 15,000 copies of a circular which asserted a
"right" to oppose the draft. The defendant in Frohwerk v.
United States, 249 U. S. 204 , was
shown to have conspired to publish in a newspaper twelve articles
describing the sufferings of American troops and the futility of
our war aims. The record was inadequate, and we said that it was
therefore
"impossible to say that it might not have been found that the
circulation of the paper was in quarters where a little breath
would be enough to kindle a flame and that the fact was known and
relied upon by those who sent the paper out."
249 U.S. at 249 U. S. 209 .
In Debs v. United States, 249 U.
S. 211 , the indictment charged that the defendant had
delivered a public speech expounding socialism and praising
Socialists who had been convicted of abetting violation of the
draft laws.
The ground of decision in each case was the same. The First
Amendment
"cannot have been, and obviously was not, intended to give
immunity for every possible use of language. Robertson v.
Baldwin, 165 U. S. 275 , 165 U. S.
281 ." Frohwerk v. United States, supra, at 249 U. S.
206 .
"The question in every case is whether the words used are used
in such circumstances and are of such a nature as to create a clear
and present danger that they will bring about the substantive evils
that Congress has a right to prevent. It is a question of proximity
and degree." Schenck v. United States, supra, at 249 U. S. 52 .
When "the words used had as their natural tendency and reasonably
probable effect to obstruct the recruiting service," and "the
defendant had the specific intent to do so in his mind," conviction
in wartime is not prohibited by the Constitution. Debs v.
United States, supra, at 249 U. S.
216 . Page 341 U. S. 535 In the three succeeding cases, Holmes and Brandeis, JJ.,
dissented from judgments of the Court affirming convictions. The
indictment in Abrams v. United States, 250 U.
S. 616 , was laid under an amendment to the Espionage Act
which prohibited conspiracies to advocate curtailment of production
of material necessary to prosecution of the war, with the intent
thereby to hinder the United States in the prosecution of the war.
It appeared that the defendants were anarchists who had printed
circulars and distributed them in New York City. The leaflets
repeated standard Marxist slogans, condemned American intervention
in Russia, and called for a general strike in protest. In Schaefer v. United States, 251 U.
S. 466 , the editors of a German language newspaper in
Philadelphia were charged with obstructing the recruiting service
and with willfully publishing false reports with the intent to
promote the success of the enemies of the United States. The
evidence showed publication of articles which accused American
troops of weakness and mendacity, and in one instance misquoted or
mistranslated two words of a Senator's speech. The indictment in Pierce v. United States, 252 U. S. 239 ,
charged that the defendants had attempted to cause insubordination
in the armed forces and had conveyed false reports with intent to
interfere with military operations. Conviction was based on
circulation of a pamphlet which belittled Allied war aims and
criticized conscription in strong terms.
In each case, both the majority and the dissenting opinions
relied on Schenck v. United States. The Court divided on
its view of the evidence. The majority held that the jury could
infer the required intent and the probable effect of the articles
from their content. Holmes and Brandeis, JJ., thought that only
"expressions of opinion and exhortations," 250 U.S. at 250 U. S. 631 ,
were involved, that they were "puny anonymities," 250 U.S. at 250 U. S. 629 ,
"impotent to produce the evil against which the statute aimed," 251 U. S.
251 Page 341 U. S. 536 U.S. 493, and that, from them, the specific intent required by
the statute could not reasonably be inferred. The Court agreed that
an incitement to disobey the draft statute could constitutionally
be punished. It disagreed over the proof required to show such an
incitement.
(b) In the eyes of a majority of the Court, Gitlow v. New
York, 268 U. S. 652 ,
presented a very different problem. There, the defendant had been
convicted under a New York statute nearly identical with the Smith
Act now before us. The evidence showed that the defendant was an
official of the Left Wing Section of the Socialist Party, and that
he was responsible for publication of a Left Wing Manifesto. This
document repudiated "moderate Socialism," and urged the necessity
of a militant "revolutionary Socialism," based on class struggle
and revolutionary mass action. No evidence of the effect of the
Manifesto was introduced, but the jury were instructed that they
could not convict unless they found that the document advocated
employing unlawful acts for the purpose of overthrowing organized
government.
The conviction was affirmed. The question, the Court held, was
entirely different from that involved in Schenck v. United
States, where the statute prohibited acts without reference to
language. Here, where
"the legislative body has determined generally, in the
constitutional exercise of its discretion, that utterances of a
certain kind involve such danger of substantive evil that they may
be punished, the question whether any specific utterance coming
within the prohibited class is likely, in and of itself, to bring
about the substantive evil is not open to consideration."
268 U.S. at 268 U. S. 670 .
It is sufficient that the defendant's conduct falls within the
statute, and that the statute is a reasonable exercise of
legislative judgment.
This principle was also applied in Whitney v.
California, 274 U. S. 357 , to
sustain a conviction under a State criminal syndicalism statute.
That statute made it a Page 341 U. S. 537 felony to assist in organizing a group assembled to advocate the
commission of crime, sabotage, or unlawful acts of violence as a
means of effecting political or industrial change. The defendant
was found to have assisted in organizing the Communist Labor Party
of California, an organization found to have the specified
character. It was held that the legislature was not unreasonable in
believing organization of such a party
"involves such danger to the public peace and the security of
the State, that these acts should be penalized in the exercise of
its police power."
274 U.S. at 274 U. S.
371 .
In neither of these cases did Mr. Justice Holmes and Mr. Justice
Brandeis accept the reasoning of the Court. " The question,'"
they said, quoting from Schenck v. United States, "'in every case is whether the words used are used in such
circumstances and are of such a nature as to create a clear and
present danger that they will bring about the substantive evils
that [the State] has a right to prevent.'"
268 U.S. at 268 U. S.
672 -673. Since the Manifesto circulated by Gitlow "had
no chance of starting a present conflagration," 268 U.S. at 268 U. S. 673 ,
they dissented from the affirmance of his conviction. In Whitney v. California, they concurred in the result
reached by the Court, but only because the record contained some
evidence that organization of the Communist Labor Party might
further a conspiracy to commit immediate serious crimes, and the
credibility of the evidence was not put in issue by the defendant.
[ Footnote 2/9 ]
(c) Subsequent decisions have added little to the principles
established in these two groups of cases. In the only case arising
under the Espionage Act decided by this Court during the last war,
the substantiality of the evidence was the crucial issue. The
defendant in Hartzel 322 U. S. S.
538� v. United States,@ 322 U. S. 680 , was
an educated man and a citizen, not actively affiliated with any
political group. In 1942, he wrote three articles condemning our
wartime allies and urging that the war be converted into a racial
conflict. He mailed the tracts to 600 people, including
high-ranking military officers. According to his testimony, his
intention was to "create sentiment against war amongst the white
races." The majority of this Court held that a jury could not
reasonably infer from these facts that the defendant had acted with
a specific intent to cause insubordination or disloyalty in the
armed forces.
Of greater importance is the fact that the issue of law which
divided the Court in the Gitlow and Whitney cases
has not again been clearly raised, although in four additional
instances we have reviewed convictions under comparable statutes. Fiske v. Kansas, 274 U. S. 380 ,
involved a criminal syndicalism statute similar to that before us
in Whitney v. California. We reversed a conviction based
on evidence that the defendant exhibited an innocuous preamble to
the constitution of the Industrial Workers of the World in
soliciting members for that organization. In Herndon v.
Lowry, 301 U. S. 242 , the
defendant had solicited members for the Communist Party, but there
was no proof that he had urged or even approved those of the
Party's aims which were unlawful. We reversed a conviction obtained
under a statute prohibiting an attempt to incite to insurrection by
violence on the ground that the Fourteenth Amendment prohibited
conviction where, on the evidence, a jury could not reasonably
infer that the defendant had violated the statute the State sought
to apply. [ Footnote 2/10 ] Page 341 U. S. 539 The other two decisions go no further than to hold that the
statute, as construed by the State courts, exceeded the bounds of a
legislative judgment founded in reason. The statute presented in De Jonge v. Oregon, 299 U. S. 353 , had
been construed to apply to anyone who merely assisted in the
conduct of a meeting held under the auspices of the Communist
Party. In Taylor v. Mississippi, 319 U.
S. 583 , the statute prohibited dissemination of printed
matter "designed and calculated to encourage violence, sabotage, or
disloyalty to the government of the United States, or the state of
Mississippi." We reversed a conviction for what we concluded was
mere criticism and prophesy, without indicating whether we thought
the statute could in any circumstances validly be applied. What the
defendants communicated, we said,
"is not claimed or shown to have been done with an evil or
sinister purpose, to have advocated or incited subversive action
against the nation or state, or to have threatened any clear and
present danger to our institutions or our Government."
319 U.S. at 319 U. S.
589 -590.
I must leave to others the ungrateful task of trying to
reconcile all these decisions. In some instances, we have too
readily permitted juries to infer deception from error, or
intention from argumentative or critical statements. Abrams v.
United States, supra; Schaefer v. United States, supra; Pierce v.
United States, supra; Gilbert v. Minnesota, 254 U.
S. 325 . In other instances, we weighted the interest in
free speech so heavily that we permitted essential conflicting
values to be destroyed. Bridges v. California, supra; Craig v.
Harney, supra. Viewed as a whole, however, the decisions
express an attitude toward the judicial function and a standard of
values which, for me, are decisive of the case before us. First. -- Free-speech cases are not an exception to the
principle that we are not legislators, that direct policymaking is
not our province. How best to reconcile competing Page 341 U. S. 540 interests is the business of legislatures, and the balance they
strike is a judgment not to be displaced by ours, but to be
respected unless outside the pale of fair judgment.
On occasion, we have strained to interpret legislation in order
to limit its effect on interests protected by the First Amendment. Schneiderman v. United States, supra; Bridges v. Wixon,
supra. In some instances, we have denied to States the
deference to which I think they are entitled. Bridges v.
California, supra; Craig v. Harney, supra. Once in this recent
course of decisions the Court refused to permit a jury to draw
inferences which seemed to me to be obviously reasonable. Hartzel v. United States, supra. But in no case has a majority of this Court held that a
legislative judgment, even as to freedom of utterance, may be
overturned merely because the Court would have made a different
choice between the competing interests had the initial legislative
judgment been for it to make. In the cases in which the opinions go
farthest towards indicating a total rejection of respect for
legislative determinations, the interests between which choice was
actually made were such that decision might well have been
expressed in the familiar terms of want of reason in the
legislative judgment. In Thomas v. Collins, 323 U.
S. 516 , for example, decision could not unreasonably
have been placed on the ground that no substantial interest
justified a State in requiring an out-of-State labor leader to
register before speaking in advocacy of the cause of trade
unionism. In Martin v. City of Struthers, 319 U.
S. 141 , it was broadly held that a municipality was not
justified in prohibiting knocking on doors and ringing doorbells
for the purpose of delivering handbills. But since the good faith
and reasonableness of the regulation were placed in doubt by the
fact that the city did not think it necessary also to prohibit
door-to-door commercial Page 341 U. S. 541 sales, decision could be sustained on narrower ground. And
compare Breard v. Alexandria, post, p. 341 U. S. 622 ,
decided this day.
In other cases, moreover, we have given clear indication that
even when free speech is involved, we attach great significance to
the determination of the legislature. Gitlow v. New York,
supra; Whitney v. California, supra; American Communications Assn.
v. Douds, supra; cf. Bridges v. California, 314 U.S. at 314 U. S. 260 . And see Hughes v. Superior Court, supra; International
Brotherhood of Teamsters Union v. Hanke, supra. In Gitlow v. New York, we put our respect for the
legislative judgment in terms which, if they were accepted here,
would make decision easy. For that case held that, when the
legislature has determined that advocacy of forceful overthrow
should be forbidden, a conviction may be sustained without a
finding that, in the particular case, the advocacy had a close
relation to a serious attempt at overthrow. We held that it was
enough that the statute be a reasonable exercise of the legislative
judgment, and that the defendant's conduct fall within the
statute.
One of the judges below rested his affirmance on the Gitlow decision, and the defendants do not attempt to
distinguish the case. They place their argument squarely on the
ground that the case has been overruled by subsequent decisions. It
has not been explicitly overruled. But it would be disingenuous to
deny that the dissent in Gitlow has been treated with the
respect usually accorded to a decision.
The result of the Gitlow decision was to send a
left-wing Socialist to jail for publishing a Manifesto expressing
Marxist exhortations. It requires excessive tolerance of the
legislative judgment to suppose that the Gitlow publication in the circumstances could justify serious concern. Page 341 U. S. 542 In contrast, there is ample justification for a legislative
judgment that the conspiracy now before us is a substantial threat
to national order and security. If the Smith Act is justified at
all, it is justified precisely because it may serve to prohibit the
type of conspiracy for which these defendants were convicted. The
court below properly held that, as a matter of separability, the
Smith Act may be limited to those situations to which it can
constitutionally be applied. See 183 F.2d at 214-215. Our
decision today certainly does not mean that the Smith Act can
constitutionally be applied to facts like those in Gitlow v.
New York. While reliance may properly be placed on the
attitude of judicial self-restraint which the Gitlow decision reflects, it is not necessary to depend on the facts or
the full extent of the theory of that case in order to find that
the judgment of Congress, as applied to the facts of the case now
before us, is not in conflict with the First Amendment. Second. -- A survey of the relevant decisions indicates
that the results which we have reached are on the whole those that
would ensue from careful weighing of conflicting interests. The
complex issues presented by regulation of speech in public places,
by picketing, and by legislation prohibiting advocacy of crime have
been resolved by scrutiny of many factors besides the imminence and
gravity of the evil threatened. The matter has been well summarized
by a reflective student of the Court's work.
"The truth is that the 'clear and present danger' test is an
oversimplified judgment unless it takes account also of a number of
other factors: the relative seriousness of the danger in comparison
with the value of the occasion for speech or political activity;
the availability of more moderate controls than those which the
state has imposed, and perhaps the specific intent with which the
speech or activity is launched. No matter how rapidly we utter the
phrase 'clear and present danger,' or how Page 341 U. S. 543 closely we hyphenate the words, they are not a substitute for
the weighing of values. They tend to convey a delusion of certitude
when what is most certain is the complexity of the strands in the
web of freedoms which the judge must dissentangle."
Freund, On Understanding the Supreme Court, 27-28.
It is a familiar experience in the law that new situations do
not fit neatly into legal conceptions that arose under different
circumstances to satisfy different needs. So it was when the
injunction was tortured into an instrument of oppression against
labor in industrial conflicts. So it is with the attempt to use the
direction of thought lying behind the criterion of "clear and
present danger" wholly out of the context in which it originated,
and to make of it an absolute dogma and definitive measuring rod
for the power of Congress to deal with assaults against security
through devices other than overt physical attempts.
Bearing in mind that Mr. Justice Holmes regarded questions under
the First Amendment as questions of "proximity and degree," Schenck v. United States, 249 U.S. at 249 U. S. 52 , it
would be a distortion, indeed a mockery, of his reasoning to
compare the "puny anonymities," 250 U.S. at 250 U. S. 629 ,
to which he was addressing himself in the Abrams case in
1919 or the publication that was "futile and too remote from
possible consequences," 268 U.S. at 268 U. S. 673 ,
in the Gitlow case in 1925 with the setting of events in
this case in 1950.
"It does an ill service to the author of the most quoted
judicial phrases regarding freedom of speech, to make him the
victim of a tendency which he fought all his life, whereby phrases
are made to do service for critical analysis by being turned into
dogma."
"It is one of the misfortunes of the law that ideas become
encysted in phrases, and thereafter for a long time cease to
provoke further analysis."
"Holmes, J., dissenting, in Hyde v. United Page 341 U. S. 544 States, 225 U. S. 347 , 225 U. S.
384 , at 225 U. S. 391 ."
The phrase "clear and present danger," in its origin,
"served to indicate the importance of freedom of speech to a
free society, but also to emphasize that its exercise must be
compatible with the preservation of other freedoms essential to a
democracy and guaranteed by our Constitution." Pennekamp v. Florida, 328 U. S. 331 , 328 U. S. 350 , 328 U. S.
352 -353 (concurring). It were far better that the phrase
be abandoned than that it be sounded once more to hide from the
believers in an absolute right of free speech the plain fact that
the interest in speech, profoundly important as it is, is no more
conclusive in judicial review than other attributes of democracy or
than a determination of the people's representatives that a measure
is necessary to assure the safety of government itself. Third. -- Not every type of speech occupies the same
position on the scale of values. There is no substantial public
interest in permitting certain kinds of utterances:
"the lewd and obscene, the profane, the libelous, and the
insulting or 'fighting' words -- those which, by their very
utterance, inflict injury or tend to incite an immediate breach of
the peace." Chaplinsky v. New Hampshire, 315 U.
S. 568 , 315 U. S. 572 .
We have frequently indicated that the interest in protecting speech
depends on the circumstances of the occasion. See cases
collected in Niemotko v. Maryland, 340 U.S. at 340 U. S.
275 -283. It is pertinent to the decision before us to
consider where on the scale of values we have in the past placed
the type of speech now claiming constitutional immunity.
The defendants have been convicted of conspiring to organize a
party of persons who advocate the overthrow of the Government by
force and violence. The jury has found that the object of the
conspiracy is advocacy as "a rule or principle of action," "by
language reasonably and ordinarily calculated to incite persons to
such action," Page 341 U. S. 545 and with the intent to cause the overthrow "as speedily as
circumstances would permit."
On any scale of values which we have hitherto recognized, speech
of this sort ranks low.
Throughout our decisions, there has recurred a distinction
between the statement of an idea which may prompt its hearers to
take unlawful action and advocacy that such action be taken. The
distinction has its root in the conception of the common law,
supported by principles of morality, that a person who procures
another to do an act is responsible for that act as though he had
done it himself. This principle was extended in Fox v.
Washington, supra, to words directed to the public generally
which would constitute an incitement were they directed to an
individual. It was adapted in Schenck v. United States,
supra, into a rule of evidence designed to restrict
application of the Espionage Act. It was relied on by the Court in Gitlow v. New York, supra. The distinction has been
repeated in many of the decisions in which we have upheld the
claims of speech. We frequently have distinguished protected forms
of expression from statements which "incite to violence and crime
and threaten the overthrow of organized government by unlawful
means." Stromberg v. California, 283 U.S. at 283 U. S. 369 . See also Near v. Minnesota, 283 U.S. at 283 U. S. 716 ; De Jonge v. Oregon, 299 U.S. at 299 U. S. 365 ; Cantwell v. Connecticut, 310 U. S. 296 , 310 U. S. 308 ; Taylor v. Mississippi, 319 U.S. at 319 U. S.
589 .
It is true that there is no divining rod by which we may locate
"advocacy." Exposition of ideas readily merges into advocacy. The
same Justice who gave currency to application of the incitement
doctrine in this field dissented four times from what he thought
was its misapplication. As he said in the Gitlow dissent,
"Every idea is an incitement." 268 U.S. at 268 U. S. 673 .
Even though advocacy of overthrow deserves little protection, we
should hesitate to prohibit it if we thereby inhibit the Page 341 U. S. 546 interchange of rational ideas so essential to representative
government and free society.
But there is underlying validity in the distinction between
advocacy and the interchange of ideas, and we do not discard a
useful tool because it may be misused. That such a distinction
could be used unreasonably by those in power against hostile or
unorthodox views does not negate the fact that it may be used
reasonably against an organization wielding the power of the
centrally controlled international Communist movement. The object
of the conspiracy before us is so clear that the chance of error in
saying that the defendants conspired to advocate, rather than to
express ideas is slight. MR. JUSTICE DOUGLAS quite properly points
out that the conspiracy before us is not a conspiracy to overthrow
the Government. But it would be equally wrong to treat it as a
seminar in political theory. III These general considerations underlie decision of the case
before us.
On the one hand is the interest in security. The Communist Party
was not designed by these defendants as an ordinary political
party. For the circumstances of its organization, its aims and
methods, and the relation of the defendants to its organization and
aims, we are concluded by the jury's verdict. The jury found that
the Party rejects the basic premise of our political system -- that
change is to be brought about by nonviolent constitutional process.
The jury found that the Party advocates the theory that there is a
duty and necessity to overthrow the Government by force and
violence. It found that the Party entertains and promotes this view
not as a prophetic insight or as a bit of unworldly
speculation, Page 341 U. S. 547 but as a program for winning adherents and as a policy to be
translated into action.
In finding that the defendants violated the statute, we may not
treat as established fact that the Communist Party in this country
is of significant size, well organized, well disciplined,
conditioned to embark on unlawful activity when given the command.
But, in determining whether application of the statute to the
defendants is within the constitutional powers of Congress, we are
not limited to the facts found by the jury. We must view such a
question in the light of whatever is relevant to a legislative
judgment. We may take judicial notice that the Communist doctrines
which these defendants have conspired to advocate are in the
ascendency in powerful nations who cannot be acquitted of
unfriendliness to the institutions of this country. We may take
account of evidence brought forward at this trial and elsewhere,
much of which has long been common knowledge. In sum, it would
amply justify a legislature in concluding that recruitment of
additional members for the Party would create a substantial danger
to national security.
In 1947, it has been reliably reported, at least 60,000 members
were enrolled in the Party. [ Footnote
2/11 ] Evidence was introduced in this case that the membership
was organized in small units, linked by an intricate chain of
command, and protected by elaborate precautions designed to prevent
disclosure of individual identity. There are no reliable data
tracing acts of sabotage or espionage directly to these defendants.
But a Canadian Royal Commission appointed in 1946 to investigate
espionage reported that it was "overwhelmingly established"
that Page 341 U. S. 548 "the Communist movement was the principal base within which the
espionage network was recruited." [ Footnote 2/12 ] The most notorious spy in recent history
was led into the service of the Soviet Union through Communist
indoctrination. [ Footnote 2/13 ]
Evidence supports the conclusion that members of the Party seek and
occupy positions of importance in political and labor
organizations. [ Footnote 2/14 ]
Congress was not barred by the Constitution from believing that
indifference to such experience would be an exercise not of
freedom, but of irresponsibility.
On the other hand is the interest in free speech. The right to
exert all governmental powers in aid of maintaining our
institutions and resisting their physical overthrow does not
include intolerance of opinions and speech that cannot do harm
although opposed and perhaps alien to dominant, traditional
opinion. The treatment of its Page 341 U. S. 549 minorities, especially their legal position, is among the most
searching tests of the level of civilization attained by a society.
It is better for those who have almost unlimited power of
government in their hands to err on the side of freedom. We have
enjoyed so much freedom for so long that we are perhaps in danger
of forgetting how much blood it cost to establish the Bill of
Rights.
Of course, no government can recognize a "right" of revolution,
or a "right" to incite revolution if the incitement has no other
purpose or effect. But speech is seldom restricted to a single
purpose, and its effects may be manifold. A public interest is not
wanting in granting freedom to speak their minds even to those who
advocate the overthrow of the Government by force. For, as the
evidence in this case abundantly illustrates, coupled with such
advocacy is criticism of defects in our society. Criticism is the
spur to reform, and Burke's admonition that a healthy society must
reform in order to conserve has not lost its force. Astute
observers have remarked that one of the characteristics of the
American Republic is indifference to fundamental criticism. Bryce,
The American Commonwealth, c. 84. It is a commonplace that there
may be a grain of truth in the most uncouth doctrine, however false
and repellent the balance may be. Suppressing advocates of
overthrow inevitably will also silence critics who do not advocate
overthrow but fear that their criticism may be so construed. No
matter how clear we may be that the defendants now before us are
preparing to overthrow our Government at the propitious moment, it
is self-delusion to think that we can punish them for their
advocacy without adding to the risks run by loyal citizens who
honestly believe in some of the reforms these defendants advance.
It is a sobering fact that, in sustaining the convictions before
us, we can hardly escape restriction on the interchange of
ideas. Page 341 U. S. 550 We must not overlook the value of that interchange. Freedom of
expression is the well spring of our civilization -- the
civilization we seek to maintain and further by recognizing the
right of Congress to put some limitation upon expression. Such are
the paradoxes of life. For social development of trial and error,
the fullest possible opportunity for the free play of the human
mind is an indispensable prerequisite. The history of civilization
is in considerable measure the displacement of error which once
held sway as official truth by beliefs which in turn have yielded
to other truths. Therefore, the liberty of man to search for truth
ought not to be fettered, no matter what orthodoxies he may
challenge. Liberty of thought soon shrivels without freedom of
expression. Nor can truth be pursued in an atmosphere hostile to
the endeavor or under dangers which are hazarded only by
heroes.
"The interest, which [the First Amendment] guards, and which
gives it its importance, presupposes that there are no orthodoxies
-- religious, political, economic, or scientific -- which are
immune from debate and dispute. Back of that is the assumption --
itself an orthodoxy, and the one permissible exception -- that
truth will be most likely to emerge, if no limitations are imposed
upon utterances that can with any plausibility be regarded as
efforts to present grounds for accepting or rejecting propositions
whose truth the utterer asserts, or denies." International Brotherhood of Electrical Workers v. Labor
Board, 181 F.2d 34, 40. In the last analysis, it is on the
validity of this faith that our national security is staked.
It is not for us to decide how we would adjust the clash of
interests which this case presents were the primary responsibility
for reconciling it ours. Congress has determined that the danger
created by advocacy of overthrow justifies the ensuing restriction
on freedom of speech. The determination was made after due
deliberation, and Page 341 U. S. 551 the seriousness of the congressional purpose is attested by the
volume of legislation passed to effectuate the same ends. [ Footnote 2/15 ]
Can we then say that the judgment Congress exercised was denied
it by the Constitution? Can we establish a constitutional doctrine
which forbids the elected representatives of the people to make
this choice? Can we hold that the First Amendment deprives Congress
of what it deemed necessary for the Government's protection?
To make validity of legislation depend on judicial reading of
events still in the womb of time a forecast, that is, of the
outcome of forces, at best, appreciated only with knowledge of the
topmost secrets of nations -- is to charge the judiciary with
duties beyond its equipment. We do not expect courts to pronounce
historic verdicts on bygone events. Even historians have
conflicting views to this day on the origins and conduct of the
French Revolution, or, for that matter, varying interpretations of
"the glorious Revolution" of 1688. It is as absurd to be confident
that we can measure the present clash of forces and Page 341 U. S. 552 their outcome as to ask us to read history still enveloped in
clouds of controversy.
In the light of their experience, the Framers of the
Constitution chose to keep the judiciary dissociated from direct
participation in the legislative process. In asserting the power to
pass on the constitutionality of legislation, Marshall and his
Court expressed the purposes of the Founders. See Charles
A. Beard, The Supreme Court and the Constitution. But the extent to
which the exercise of this power would interpenetrate matters of
policy could hardly have been foreseen by the most prescient. The
distinction which the Founders drew between the Court's duty to
pass on the power of Congress and its complementary duty not to
enter directly the domain of policy is fundamental. But, in its
actual operation, it is rather subtle, certainly to the common
understanding. Our duty to abstain from confounding policy with
constitutionality demands perceptive humility as well as
self-restraint in not declaring unconstitutional what in a judge's
private judgment is deemed unwise and even dangerous.
Even when moving strictly within the limits of constitutional
adjudication, judges are concerned with issues that may be said to
involve vital finalities. The too easy transition from disapproval
of what is undesirable to condemnation as unconstitutional has led
some of the wisest judges to question the wisdom of our scheme in
lodging such authority in courts. But it is relevant to remind
that, in sustaining the power of Congress in a case like this,
nothing irrevocable is done. The democratic process, at all events,
is not impaired or restricted. Power and responsibility remain with
the people, and, immediately, with their representatives. All the
Court says is that Congress was not forbidden by the Constitution
to pass this enactment and that a prosecution under it may be
brought against a conspiracy such as the one before us. Page 341 U. S. 553 IV The wisdom of the assumptions underlying the legislation and
prosecution is another matter. In finding that Congress has acted
within its power, a judge does not remotely imply that he favors
the implications that lie beneath the legal issues. Considerations
there enter which go beyond the criteria that are binding upon
judges within the narrow confines of their legitimate authority.
The legislation we are here considering is but a truncated aspect
of a deeper issue. For me, it has been most illuminatingly
expressed by one in whom responsibility and experience have
fructified native insight, the Director-General of the British
Broadcasting Corporation:
"We have to face up to the fact that there are powerful forces
in the world today misusing the privileges of liberty in order to
destroy her. The question must be asked, however, whether
suppression of information or opinion is the true defense. We may
have come a long way from Mill's famous dictum that: "
"If all mankind minus one were of one opinion, and only one
person were of the contrary opinion, mankind would be no more
justified in silencing that one person than he, if he had the
power, would be justified in silencing mankind,"
"but Mill's reminders from history as to what has happened when
suppression was most virulently exercised ought to warn us that no
debate is ever permanently won by shutting one's ears or by even
the most Draconian policy of silencing opponents. The debate must be won . And it must be won with full
information. Where there are lies, they must be shown for what they
are. Where there are errors, they must be refuted. It would be a
major defeat if the enemies of democracy forced us to abandon our
faith in the power of informed discussion, and so brought us
down Page 341 U. S. 554 to their own level. Mankind is so constituted, moreover, that,
if, where expression and discussion are concerned, the enemies of
liberty are met with a denial of liberty, many men of goodwill will
come to suspect there is something in the proscribed doctrine after
all. Erroneous doctrines thrive on being expunged. They die if
exposed."
Sir William Haley, What Standards for Broadcasting? Measure,
Vol. I, No. 3, Summer 1950, pp. 211-212.
In the context of this deeper struggle, another voice has
indicated the limitations of what we decide today. No one is better
equipped than George F. Kennan to speak on the meaning of the
menace of Communism and the spirit in which we should meet it.
"If our handling of the problem of Communist influence in our
midst is not carefully moderated -- if we permit it, that is, to
become an emotional preoccupation and to blind us to the more
important positive tasks before us -- we can do a damage to our
national purpose beyond comparison greater than anything that
threatens us today from the Communist side. The American Communist
party is today, by and large, an external danger. It represents a
tiny minority in our country, it has no real contact with the
feelings of the mass of our people, and its position as the agency
of a hostile foreign power is clearly recognized by the
overwhelming mass of our citizens."
"But the subjective emotional stresses and temptations to which
we are exposed in our attempt to deal with this domestic problem
are not an external danger: they represent a danger within
ourselves -- a danger that something may occur in our own minds and
souls which will make us no longer like the persons by whose
efforts this republic was founded and held together, but rather
like the representatives Page 341 U. S. 555 of that very power we are trying to combat: intolerant,
secretive, suspicious, cruel, and terrified of internal dissension
because we have lost our own belief in ourselves and in the power
of our ideals. The worst thing that our Communists could do to us,
and the thing we have most to fear from their activities, is that
we should become like them."
"That our country is beset with external dangers I readily
concede. But these dangers, at their worst, are ones of physical
destruction, of the disruption of our world security, of expense
and inconvenience and sacrifice. These are serious, and sometimes
terrible things, but they are all things that we can take and still
remain Americans."
"The internal danger is of a different order. America is not
just territory and people. There is lots of territory elsewhere,
and there are lots of people; but it does not add up to America.
America is something in our minds and our habits of outlook which
causes us to believe in certain things and to behave in certain
ways, and by which, in its totality, we hold ourselves
distinguished from others. If that, once goes there will be no
America to defend. And that can go too easily if we yield to the
primitive human instinct to escape from our frustrations into the
realms of mass emotion and hatred and to find scapegoats for our
difficulties in individual fellow-citizens who are, or have at one
time been, disoriented or confused."
George F. Kennan, Where Do You Stand on Communism? New York
Times Magazine, May 27, 1951, pp. 7, 53, 55.
Civil liberties draw, at best, only limited strength from legal
guaranties. Preoccupation by our people with the constitutionality,
instead of with the wisdom, of legislation or of executive action
is preoccupation with a false value. Even those who would most
freely use the judicial Page 341 U. S. 556 brake on the democratic process by invalidating legislation that
goes deeply against their grain, acknowledge, at least by paying
lip service, that constitutionality does not exact a sense of
proportion or the sanity of humor or an absence of fear. Focusing
attention on constitutionality tends to make constitutionality
synonymous with wisdom. When legislation touches freedom of thought
and freedom of speech, such a tendency is a formidable enemy of the
free spirit. Much that should be rejected as illiberal, because
repressive and envenoming, may well be not unconstitutional. The
ultimate reliance for the deepest needs of civilization must be
found outside their vindication in courts of law; apart from all
else, judges, howsoever they may conscientiously seek to discipline
themselves against it, unconsciously are too apt to be moved by the
deep undercurrents of public feeling. A persistent, positive
translation of the liberating faith into the feelings and thoughts
and actions of men and women is the real protection against
attempts to strait-jacket the human mind. Such temptations will
have their way, if fear and hatred are not exorcized. The mark of a
truly civilized man is confidence in the strength and security
derived from the inquiring mind. We may be grateful for such honest
comforts as it supports, but we must be unafraid of its
incertitudes. Without open minds, there can be no open society. And
if society be not open, the spirit of man is mutilated, and becomes
enslaved.
| 341
U.S. 494 app| APPENDIX TO OPINION OF MR. JUSTICE FRANKFURTER. Opinions responsible for the view that speech could not
constitutionally be restricted unless there would result from it an
imminent -- i.e., close at hand -- substantive evil.
1. Thornhill v. Alabama, 310 U. S.
88 , 310 U. S.
104 -105 (State statute prohibiting picketing held
invalid):
". . . Every Page 341 U. S. 557 expression of opinion on matters that are important has the
potentiality of inducing action in the interests of one rather than
another group in society. But the group in power at any moment may
not impose penal sanctions on peaceful and truthful discussion of
matters of public interest merely on a showing that others may
thereby be persuaded to take action inconsistent with its
interests. Abridgment of the liberty of such discussion can be
justified only where the clear danger of substantive evils arises
under circumstances affording no opportunity to test the merits of
ideas by competition for acceptance in the market of public
opinion. . . ."
". . . [N]o clear and present danger of destruction of life or
property, or invasion of the right of privacy, or breach of the
peace can be thought to be inherent in the activities of every
person who approaches the premises of an employer and publicizes
the facts of a labor dispute involving the latter."
2. Bridges v. California, 314 U.
S. 252 , 314 U. S.
262 -263 (convictions for contempt of court
reversed):
". . . [T]he 'clear and present danger' language of the Schenck case has afforded practical guidance in a great
variety of cases in which the scope of constitutional protections
of freedom of expression was in issue. It has been utilized by
either a majority or minority of this Court in passing upon the
constitutionality of convictions under espionage acts, Schenck
v. United States, supra , [ 249 U.S.
47 ]; Abrams v. United States, 250 U. S.
616 ; under a criminal syndicalism act, Whitney v. California,
supra , [ 274 U.S.
357 ]; under an 'anti-insurrection' act, Herndon v. Lowry,
supra , [ 301 U.S.
242 ], and for breach of the peace at common law, Cantwell v. Connecticut,
supra , [ 310 U.S.
296 ]. And, very recently, we have also suggested that 'clear
and present danger' is an appropriate guide in determining the
constitutionality of restrictions upon expression where the
substantive evil sought to be prevented Page 341 U. S. 558 by the restriction is 'destruction of life or property, or
invasion of the right of privacy.' Thornhill v. Alabama, 310 U. S.
88 , 310 U. S. 105 ."
" * * * *" "What finally emerges from the 'clear and present danger' cases
is a working principle that the substantive evil must be extremely
serious and the degree of imminence extremely high before
utterances can be punished. Those cases do not purport to mark the
furthermost constitutional boundaries of protected expression, nor
do we here. They do no more than recognize a minimum compulsion of
the Bill of Rights. For the First Amendment does not speak
equivocally. It prohibits any law 'abridging the freedom of speech,
or of the press.' It must be taken as a command of the broadest
scope that explicit language, read in the context of a
liberty-loving society, will allow."
3. West Virginia Board of Education v. Barnette, 319 U. S. 624 , 319 U. S. 639 (flag salute requirement for school children held invalid):
"In weighing arguments of the parties, it is important to
distinguish between the due process clause of the Fourteenth
Amendment as an instrument for transmitting the principles of the
First Amendment and those cases in which it is applied for its own
sake. The test of legislation which collides with the Fourteenth
Amendment, because it also collides with the principles of the
First, is much more definite than the test when only the Fourteenth
is involved. Much of the vagueness of the due process clause
disappears when the specific prohibitions of the First become its
standard. The right of a State to regulate, for example, a public
utility may well include, so far as the due process test is
concerned, power to impose all of the restrictions which a
legislature may have a 'rational basis' for adopting. But freedoms
of speech and of press, of assembly, and of worship may not be
infringed on such slender grounds. They are susceptible Page 341 U. S. 559 of restriction only to prevent grave and immediate danger to
interests which the State may lawfully protect. It is important to
note that, while it is the Fourteenth Amendment which bears
directly upon the State, it is the more specific limiting
principles of the First Amendment that finally govern this
case."
4. Thomas v. Collins, 323 U. S. 516 , 323 U. S.
529 -530 (State statute requiring registration of labor
organizers held invalid as applied):
"The case confronts us again with the duty our system places on
this Court to say where the individual's freedom ends and the
State's power begins. Choice on that border, now as always
delicate, is perhaps more so where the usual presumption supporting
legislation is balanced by the preferred place given in our scheme
to the great, the indispensable democratic freedoms secured by the
First Amendment. Cf. Schneider v. State, 308 U. S.
147 ; Cantwell v. Connecticut, 310 U. S.
296 ; Prince v. Massachusetts, 321 U. S.
158 . That priority gives these liberties a sanctity and
a sanction not permitting dubious intrusions. And it is the
character of the right, not of the limitation, which determines
what standard governs the choice. Compare United States v.
Carolene Products Co., 304 U. S. 144 , 304 U. S.
152 -153."
"For these reasons, any attempt to restrict those liberties must
be justified by clear public interest, threatened not doubtfully or
remotely, but by clear and present danger. The rational connection
between the remedy provided and the evil to be curbed, which in
other contexts might support legislation against attack on due
process grounds, will not suffice. These rights rest on firmer
foundation. Accordingly, whatever occasion would restrain orderly
discussion and persuasion, at appropriate time and place, must have
clear support in public danger, actual or impending. Only the
gravest abuses, endangering paramount interests, give occasion for
permissible limitation. " Page 341 U. S. 560 5. Craig v. Harney, 331 U. S. 367 , 331 U. S. 376 (conviction for contempt of court reversed):
"The fires which [the language] kindles must constitute an
imminent, not merely a likely, threat to the administration of
justice. The danger must not be remote or even probable; it must
immediately imperil."
6. Giboney v. Empire Storage Co., 336 U.
S. 490 , 336 U. S. 503 (injunction against picketing upheld):
". . . There was clear danger, imminent and immediate, that,
unless restrained, appellants would succeed in making [the State's
policy against restraints of trade] a dead letter insofar as
purchases by nonunion men were concerned. . . ."
7. Terminiello v. Chicago, 337 U. S.
1 , 337 U. S. 4 -5
(conviction for disorderly conduct reversed):
"Speech is often provocative and challenging. It may strike at
prejudices and preconceptions and have profound unsettling effects
as it presses for acceptance of an idea. That is why freedom of
speech, though not absolute, Chaplinsky v. New Hampshire,
supra , [ 315 U.S.
568 ,] 315 U. S. 571 -572, is
nevertheless protected against censorship or punishment unless
shown likely to produce a clear and present danger of a serious
substantive evil that rises far above public inconvenience,
annoyance, or unrest. See Bridges v. California, 314 U. S.
252 , 314 U. S. 262 ; Craig v.
Harney, 331 U. S. 367 , 331 U. S.
373 . There is no room under our Constitution for a more
restrictive view. For the alternative would lead to standardization
of ideas either by legislatures, courts, or dominant political or
community groups."
8. American Communications Assn. v. Douds, 339 U.
S. 382 , 339 U. S. 396 , 339 U. S. 412 ("Non-Communist affidavit" provision of Taft-Hartley Act
upheld):
"Speech may be fought with speech. Falsehoods and fallacies must
be exposed, not suppressed, unless there is not sufficient time to
avert the evil consequences of noxious doctrine by argument and
education. That is the command of the First Amendment."
And again,
"[The First] Amendment requires Page 341 U. S. 561 that one be permitted to believe what he will. It requires that
one be permitted to advocate what he will unless there is a clear
and present danger that a substantial public evil will result
therefrom."
[ Footnote 2/1 ]
Mass.Const., 1780, Part I, Art. XVI. See Duniway,
Freedom of the Press in Massachusetts, 144-146.
[ Footnote 2/2 ]
Pa.Const., 1790, Art. IX, § 7; Del.Const., 1792, Art. I, §
5.
[ Footnote 2/3 ]
The General Assembly of Virginia passed a statute on December
26, 1792, directed at establishment of
"any government separate from, or independent of the government
of Virginia, within the limits thereof, unless by act of the
legislature of this commonwealth for that purpose first
obtained."
The statute provided that
"EVERY person . . . who shall by writing or advised speaking,
endeavour to instigate the people of this commonwealth to erect or
establish such government without such assent as aforesaid, shall
be adjudged guilty of a high crime and misdemeanor. . . ."
Va.Code, 1803, c. CXXXVI.
[ Footnote 2/4 ]
In a letter to Abigail Adams, dated September 11, 1804,
Jefferson said with reference to the Sedition Act:
"Nor does the opinion of the unconstitutionality and consequent
nullity of that law remove all restraint from the overwhelming
torrent of slander which is confounding all vice and virtue, all
truth and falsehood in the US. The power to do that is fully
possessed by the several state legislatures. It was reserved to
them, and was denied to the general government, by the constitution
according to our construction of it. While we deny that Congress
have a right to controul the freedom of the press, we have ever
asserted the right of the states, and their exclusive right, to do
so."
The letter will be published in a forthcoming volume of The
Papers of Thomas Jefferson (Boyd ed.), to which I am indebted for
its reproduction here in its exact form.
The Sedition Act of July 14, 1798, was directed at two types of
conduct. Section 1 made it a criminal offense to conspire "to
impede the operation of any law of the United States," and to
"counsel, advise or attempt to procure any insurrection, riot,
unlawful assembly, or combination." Section 2 provided:
"That if any person shall write, print, utter or publish, or
shall cause or procure to be written, printed, uttered or
published, or shall knowingly and willingly assist or aid in
writing, printing, uttering or publishing any false, scandalous and
malicious writing or writings against the government of the United
States, or either house of the Congress of the United States, or
the President of the United States, with intent to defame the said
government, or either house of the said Congress, or the said
President, or to bring them, or either of them, into contempt or
disrepute; or to excite against them, or either or any of them, the
hatred of the good people of the United States, or to stir up
sedition within the United States, or to excite any unlawful
combinations therein, for opposing or resisting any law of the
United States, or any act of the President of the United States,
done in pursuance of any such law, or of the powers in him vested
by the constitution of the United States, or to resist, oppose, or
defeat any such law or act, or to aid, encourage or abet any
hostile designs of any foreign nation against the United States,
their people or government, then such person, being thereof
convicted before any court of the United States having jurisdiction
thereof, shall be punished by a fine not exceeding two thousand
dollars, and by imprisonment not exceeding two years."
1 Stat. 596-597.
No substantial objection was raised to § 1 of the Act. The
argument against the validity of § 2 is stated most fully in the
Virginia Report of 1799-1800. That Report, prepared for the House
of Delegates by a committee of which Madison was chairman,
attempted to establish that the power to regulate speech was not
delegated to the Federal Government by the Constitution, and that
the First Amendment had prohibited the National Government from
exercising the power. In reply, it was urged that power to restrict
seditious writing was implicit in the acknowledged power of the
Federal Government to prohibit seditious acts, and that the liberty
of the press did not extend to the sort of speech restricted by the
Act. See the Report of the Committee of the House of
Representatives to which were referred memorials from the States,
H.R.Rep. No. 110, 5th Cong., 3d Sess., published in American State
Papers, Misc. Vol. 1, p. 181. For an extensive contemporary account
of the controversy, see St. George Tucker's 1803 edition
of Blackstone's Commentaries, Appendix to Vol. First, Part Second,
Note G.
[ Footnote 2/5 ]
Professor Alexander Meiklejohn is a leading exponent of the
absolutist interpretation of the First Amendment. Recognizing that
certain forms of speech require regulation, he excludes those forms
of expression entirely from the protection accorded by the
Amendment.
"The constitutional status of a merchant advertising his wares,
of a paid lobbyist fighting for the advantage of his client, is
utterly different from that of a citizen who is planning for the
general welfare."
Meiklejohn, Free Speech, 39.
"The radio as it now operates among us is not free. Nor is it
entitled to the protection of the First Amendment. It is not
engaged in the task of enlarging and enriching human communication.
It is engaged in making money." Id. at 104. Professor Meiklejohn even suggests that
scholarship may now require such subvention and control that it no
longer is entitled to protection by the First Amendment. See
id. at 99-100. Professor Chafee, in his review of the
Meiklejohn book, 62 Harv.L.Rev. 891, has subjected this position to
trenchant comment.
[ Footnote 2/6 ]
In Hartzel v. United States, 322 U.
S. 680 , 322 U. S. 687 ,
the Court reversed a conviction for willfully causing
insubordination in the military forces on the ground that the
intent required by the statute was not shown. It added that there
was a second element necessary to conviction,
"consisting of a clear and present danger that the activities in
question will bring about the substantive evils which Congress has
a right to prevent. Schenck v. United States, 249 U. S.
47 . Both elements must be proved by the Government
beyond a reasonable doubt."
Other passages responsible for attributing to the Court the
principle that imminence of the apprehended evil is necessary to
conviction in free speech cases are collected in an Appendix to
this opinion, post, p. 341 U. S.
556 .
[ Footnote 2/7 ]
No useful purpose would be served by considering here decisions
in which the Court treated the challenged regulation as though it
imposed no real restraint on speech or on the press. E.g.,
Associated Press v. Labor Board, 301 U.
S. 103 ; Valentine v. Chrestensen, 316 U. S.
52 ; Railway Express Agency v. New York, 336 U. S. 106 ; Lewis Publishing Co. v. Morgan, 229 U.
S. 288 . We recognized that restrictions on speech were
involved in United States ex rel. Milwaukee Publishing Co. v.
Burleson, 255 U. S. 407 , and Gilbert v. Minnesota, 254 U. S. 325 ; but
the decisions raised issues so different from those presented here
that they too need not be considered in detail. Our decisions in Stromberg v. California, 283 U. S. 359 , and Winters v. New York, 333 U. S. 507 ,
turned on the indefiniteness of the statutes.
[ Footnote 2/8 ]
The Taft-Hartley Act also requires that an officer of a union
using the services of the National Labor Relations Board take oath
that he
"does not believe in, and is not a member of or supports any
organization that believes in or teaches, the overthrow of the
United States Government by force or by any illegal or
unconstitutional methods."
The Court divided on the validity of this requirement. Test
oaths raise such special problems that decisions on their validity
are not directly helpful here. See West Virginia Board of
Education v. Barnette, 319 U. S. 624 .
[ Footnote 2/9 ] Burns v. United States, 274 U.
S. 328 , adds nothing to the decision in Whitney v.
California. [ Footnote 2/10 ]
In Herndon v. Georgia, 295 U.
S. 441 , the opinion of the Court was concerned solely
with a question of procedure. Mr. Justice Brandeis, Mr. Justice
Stone, and Mr. Justice Cardozo, however, thought that the problem
of Gitlow v. New York was raised. See 295 U.S. at 295 U. S.
446 .
[ Footnote 2/11 ] See the testimony of the Director of the Federal Bureau
of Investigation. Hearings before the House Committee on
Un-American Activities, on H.R. 1884 and H.R. 2122, 80th Cong., 1st
Sess., Part 2, p. 37.
[ Footnote 2/12 ]
Report of the Royal Commission to Investigate Communication of
Secret and Confidential Information to Agents of a Foreign Power,
June 27, 1946, p. 44. There appears to be little reliable evidence
demonstrating directly that the Communist Party in this country has
recruited persons willing to engage in espionage or other unlawful
activity on behalf of the Soviet Union. The defection of a Soviet
diplomatic employee, however, led to a careful investigation of an
espionage network in Canada, and has disclosed the effectiveness of
the Canadian Communist Party in conditioning its members to
disclose to Soviet agents vital information of a secret character.
According to the Report of the Royal Commission investigating the
network, conspiratorial characteristics of the Party similar to
those shown in the evidence now before us were instrumental in
developing the necessary motivation to cooperate in the espionage. See pp. 43-83 of the Report.
[ Footnote 2/13 ]
The Communist background of Dr. Klaus Fuchs was brought out in
the proceedings against him. See The [London] Times, Mar.
2, 1950, p.2, col. 6.
[ Footnote 2/14 ] See American Communications Assn. v. Douds, 339 U. S. 382 .
Former Senator Robert M. La Follette, Jr., has reported his
experience with infiltration of Communist sympathizers into
congressional committee staffs. Collier's, Feb. 8, 1947, p. 22.
[ Footnote 2/15 ]
Immigration laws require, for instance, exclusion and
deportation of aliens who advocate the overthrow of the Government
by force and violence, and declare ineligible for naturalization
aliens who are members of organizations so advocating. Act of Feb.
5, 1917, § 19, 39 Stat. 889, 8 U.S.C. § 155; Act of Oct. 16, 1918,
40 Stat. 1012, 8 U.S.C. § 137; Act of Oct. 14, 1940, § 305, 54
Stat. 1141, 8 U.S.C. § 705. The Hatch Act prohibits employment by
any Government agency of members of organizations advocating
overthrow of "our constitutional form of government." Act of Aug.
2, 1939, § 9A, 53 Stat. 1148, 5 U.S.C. (Supp. III) § 118j. The
Voorhis Act of Oct. 17, 1940, was passed to require registration of
organizations subject to foreign control which engage in political
activity. 54 Stat. 1201, 18 U.S.C. § 2386. The Taft-Hartley Act
contains a section designed to exclude Communists from positions of
leadership in labor organizations. Act of June 23, 1947, § 9(h), 61
Stat. 146, 29 U.S.C. (Supp. III) § 159(h). And, most recently, the
McCarran Act requires registration of "Communist action" and
"Communist front" organizations. Act of Sept. 23, 1950, § 7, 64
Stat. 987, 993.
MR. JUSTICE JACKSON, concurring.
This prosecution is the latest of never-ending, because never
successful, quests for some legal formula that will secure an
existing order against revolutionary radicalism. It requires us to
reappraise, in the light of our own times and conditions,
constitutional doctrines devised under other circumstances to
strike a balance between authority and liberty.
Activity here charged to be criminal is conspiracy -- that
defendants conspired to teach and advocate, and to organize the
Communist Party to teach and advocate, overthrow and destruction of
the Government by force and violence. There is no charge of actual
violence or attempt at overthrow. [ Footnote 3/1 ]
The principal reliance of the defense in this Court is that the
conviction cannot stand under the Constitution because the
conspiracy of these defendants presents no "clear and present
danger" of imminent or foreseeable overthrow. Page 341 U. S. 562 I The statute before us repeats a pattern, originally devised to
combat the wave of anarchistic terrorism that plagued this country
about the turn of the century, [ Footnote 3/2 ] which lags at least two generations behind
Communist Party techniques.
Anarchism taught a philosophy of extreme individualism and
hostility to government and property. Its avowed aim was a more
just order, to be achieved by violent destruction of all
government. [ Footnote 3/3 ]
Anarchism's sporadic and uncoordinated acts of terror were not
integrated with an effective revolutionary machine, but the Chicago
Haymarket riots of 1886, [ Footnote
3/4 ] attempted murder of the industrialist Frick, attacks on
state officials, and Page 341 U. S. 563 assassination of President McKinley in 1901, were fruits of its
preaching.
However, extreme individualism was not educive to cohesive and
disciplined organization. Anarchism fell into disfavor among
incendiary radicals, many of whom shifted their allegiance to the
rising Communist Party. Meanwhile, in Europe, anarchism had been
displaced by Bolshevism as the doctrine and strategy of social and
political upheaval. Led by intellectuals hardened by revolutionary
experience, it was a more sophistic&ted, dynamic and realistic
movement. Establishing a base in the Soviet Union, it founded an
aggressive international Communist apparatus which has modeled and
directed a revolutionary movement able only to harass our own
country. But it has seized control of a dozen other countries.
Communism, the antithesis of anarchism, [ Footnote 3/5 ] appears today as a closed system of
thought representing Stalin's Page 341 U. S. 564 version of Lenin's version of Marxism. As an ideology, it is not
one of spontaneous protest arising from American working-class
experience. It is a complicated system of assumptions, based on
European history and conditions, shrouded in an obscure and
ambiguous vocabulary, which allures our ultrasophisticated
intelligentsia more than our hard-headed working people. From time
to time it champions all manner of causes and grievances and makes
alliances that may add to its foothold in government or embarrass
the authorities.
The Communist Party, nevertheless, does not seek its strength
primarily in numbers. Its aim is a relatively small party whose
strength is in selected, dedicated, indoctrinated, and rigidly
disciplined members. From established policy it tolerates no
deviation and no debate. It seeks members that are, or may be,
secreted in strategic posts in transportation, communications,
industry, government, and especially in labor unions where it can
compel employers to accept and retain its members. [ Footnote 3/6 ] It also seeks to infiltrate and
control organizations of professional and other groups. Through
these placements in positions of power, it seeks a leverage over
society that will make up in power of coercion what it lacks in
power of persuasion.
The Communists have no scruples against sabotage, terrorism,
assassination, or mob disorder, but violence is not with them, as
with the anarchists, an end in itself. The Communist Party
advocates force only when prudent and profitable. Their strategy of
stealth precludes premature or uncoordinated outbursts of violence,
except, of course, when the blame will be placed on shoulders other
than their own. They resort to violence as to truth, not Page 341 U. S. 565 as a principle but as an expedient. Force or violence, as they
would resort to it, may never be necessary, because infiltration
and deception may be enough.
Force would be utilized by the Communist Party not to destroy
government, but for its capture. The Communist recognizes that an
established government in control of modern technology cannot be
overthrown by force until it is about ready to fall of its own
weight. Concerted uprising, therefore, is to await that
contingency, and revolution is seen not as a sudden episode, but as
the consummation of a long process.
The United States, fortunately, has experienced Communism only
in its preparatory stages, and, for its pattern of final action,
must look abroad. Russia, of course, was the pilot Communist
revolution which, to the Marxist, confirms the Party's assumptions
and points its destiny. [ Footnote
3/7 ] Page 341 U. S. 566 But Communist technique in the overturn of a free government was
disclosed by the coup d'etat in which they seized power in
Czechoslovakia. [ Footnote 3/8 ]
There, the Communist Party, during its preparatory stage, claimed
and received protection for its freedoms of speech, press, and
assembly. Pretending to be but another political party, it
eventually was conceded participation in government, where it
entrenched reliable members chiefly in control of police and
information services. When the government faced a foreign and
domestic crisis, the Communist Party had established a leverage
strong enough to threaten civil war. In a period of confusion, the
Communist plan unfolded, and the underground organization came to
the surface throughout the country in the form chiefly of labor
"action committees." Communist officers of the unions took over
transportation, and allowed only persons with party permits to
travel. Communist printers took over the newspapers and radio, and
put out only party-approved versions of events. Possession was
taken of telegraph and telephone systems, and communications were
cut off wherever directed by party heads. Communist unions took
over the factories, and in the cities, a partisan distribution of
food was managed by the Communist organization. A virtually
bloodless abdication by the elected government admitted the
Communists to power, whereupon they instituted a reign of
oppression and terror, and ruthlessly denied to all others the
freedoms which had sheltered their conspiracy. Page 341 U. S. 567 II The foregoing is enough to indicate that,.either by accident or
design, the Communist stratagem outwits the anti-anarchist pattern
of statute aimed against "overthrow by force and violence" if
qualified by the doctrine that only "clear and present danger" of
accomplishing that result will sustain the prosecution.
The "clear and present danger" test was an innovation by Mr.
Justice Holmes in the Schenck case, [ Footnote 3/9 ] reiterated and refined by him and Mr.
Justice Brandeis in later cases, [ Footnote 3/10 ] all arising before the era of World War
II revealed the subtlety and efficacy of modernized revolutionary
techniques used by totalitarian parties. In those cases, they were
faced with convictions under so-called criminal syndicalism
statutes aimed at anarchists but which, loosely construed, had been
applied to punish socialism, pacifism, and left-wing ideologies,
the charges often resting on far-fetched Page 341 U. S. 568 inferences which, if true, would establish only technical or
trivial violations. They proposed "clear and present danger" as a
test for the sufficiency of evidence in particular cases.
I would save it, unmodified, for application as a "rule of
reason" [ Footnote 3/11 ] in the
kind of case for which it was devised. When the issue is
criminality of a hot-headed speech on a street corner, or
circulation of a few incendiary pamphlets, or parading by some
zealots behind a red flag, or refusal of a handful of school
children to salute our flag, it is not beyond the capacity of the
judicial process to gather, comprehend, and weigh the necessary
materials for decision whether it is a clear and present danger of
substantive evil or a harmless letting off of steam. It is not a
prophecy, for the danger in such cases has matured by the time of
trial or it was never present. The test applies and has meaning
where a conviction is sought to be based on a speech or writing
which does not directly or explicitly advocate a crime, but to
which such tendency is sought to be attributed by construction or
by implication from external circumstances. The formula in such
cases favors freedoms that are vital to our society, and even if
sometimes applied too generously, the consequences cannot be grave.
But its recent expansion has extended, in particular to Communists,
unprecedented immunities. [ Footnote
3/12 ] Unless we are to hold our Government captive in a
judge-made verbal trap, we must approach the problem of a well
organized, nationwide conspiracy, such as I have Page 341 U. S. 569 described, as realistically as our predecessors faced the
trivialities that were being prosecuted until they were checked
with a rule of reason.
I think reason is lacking for applying that test to this
case. Page 341 U. S. 570 If we must decide that this Act and its application are
constitutional only if we are convinced that petitioner's conduct
creates a "clear and present danger" of violent overthrow, we must
appraise imponderables, including international and national
phenomena which baffle the best informed foreign offices and our
most experienced politicians. We would have to foresee and predict
the effectiveness of Communist propaganda, opportunities for
infiltration, whether, and when, a time will come that they
consider propitious for action, and whether and how fast our
existing government will deteriorate. And we would have to
speculate as to whether an approaching Communist coup would not be
anticipated by a nationalistic fascist movement. No doctrine can be
sound whose application requires us to make a prophecy of that sort
in the guise of a legal decision. The judicial process simply is
not adequate to a trial of such far-flung issues. The answers given
would reflect our own political predilections, and nothing
more.
The authors of the clear and present danger test never applied
it to a case like this, nor would I. If applied as it is proposed
here, it means that the Communist plotting is protected during its
period of incubation; its preliminary stages of organization and
preparation are immune from the law; the Government can move only
after imminent action is manifest, when it would, of course, be too
late. III The highest degree of constitutional protection is due to the
individual acting without conspiracy. But even an individual cannot
claim that the Constitution protects him in advocating or teaching
overthrow of government by force or violence. I should suppose no
one would doubt that Congress has power to make such attempted Page 341 U. S. 571 overthrow a crime. But the contention is that one has the
constitutional right to work up a public desire, and will to do
what it is a crime to attempt. I think direct incitement by speech
or writing can be made a crime, and I think there can be a
conviction without also proving that the odds favored its success
by 99 to 1, or some other extremely high ratio.
The names of Mr. Justice Holmes and Mr. Justice Brandeis cannot
be associated with such a doctrine of governmental disability.
After the Schenck case, in which they set forth the clear
and present danger test, they joined in these words of Mr. Justice
Holmes, spoken for a unanimous Court:
". . . [T]he First Amendment, while prohibiting legislation
against free speech as such, cannot have been, and obviously was
not, intended to give immunity for every possible use of language. Robertson v. Baldwin, 165 U. S. 275 , 165 U. S.
281 . We venture to believe that neither Hamilton nor
Madison, nor any other competent person then or later, ever
supposed that to make criminal the counseling of a murder within
the jurisdiction of Congress would be an unconstitutional
interference with free speech." Frohwerk v. United States, 249 U.
S. 204 , 249 U. S.
206 .
The same doctrine was earlier stated in Fox v.
Washington, 236 U. S. 273 , 236 U. S. 277 ,
and that case was recently and with approval cited in Giboney
v. Empire Storage & Ice Co., 336 U.
S. 490 , 336 U. S.
502 .
As aptly stated by Judge Learned Hand in Masses Publishing
Co. v. Patten, 244 F. 535, 540:
"One may not counsel or advise others to violate the law as it
stands. Words are not only the keys of persuasion, but the triggers
of action, and those which have no purport but to counsel the
violation of law cannot by any latitude of interpretation be a part
of that public opinion which is the final source of government in a
democratic state. " Page 341 U. S. 572 Of course, it is not always easy to distinguish teaching or
advocacy in the sense of incitement from teaching or advocacy in
the sense of exposition or explanation. It is a question of fact in
each case. IV What really is under review here is a conviction of conspiracy,
after a trial for conspiracy, on an indictment charging conspiracy,
brought under a statute outlawing conspiracy. With due respect to
my colleagues, they seem to me to discuss anything under the sun
except the law of conspiracy. One of the dissenting opinions even
appears to chide me for "invoking the law of conspiracy." As that
is the case before us, it may be more amazing that its reversal can
be proposed without even considering the law of conspiracy.
The Constitution does not make conspiracy a civil right. The
Court has never before done so, and I think it should not do so
now. Conspiracies of labor unions, trade associations, and news
agencies have been condemned, although accomplished, evidenced and
carried out, like the conspiracy here, chiefly by letter-writing,
meetings, speeches and organization. Indeed, this Court seems,
particularly in cases where the conspiracy has economic ends, to be
applying its doctrines with increasing severity. While I consider
criminal conspiracy a dragnet device capable of perversion into an
instrument of injustice in the hands of a partisan or complacent
judiciary, it has an established place in our system of law, and no
reason appears for applying it only to concerted action claimed to
disturb interstate commerce and withholding it from those claimed
to undermine our whole Government. [ Footnote 3/13 ] Page 341 U. S. 573 The basic rationale of the law of conspiracy is that a
conspiracy may be an evil in itself, independently of any other
evil it seeks to accomplish. Thus, we recently held in Pinkerton v. United States, 328 U.
S. 640 , 328 U. S.
643 -644,
"It has been long and consistently recognized by the Court that
the commission of the substantive offense and a conspiracy to
commit it are separate and distinct offenses. The power of Congress
to separate the two and to affix to each a different penalty is
well established. . . . And the plea of double jeopardy is no
defense to a conviction for both offenses. . . ."
So far does this doctrine reach that it is well settled that
Congress may make it a crime to conspire with others to do what an
individual may lawfully do on his own. This principle is
illustrated in conspiracies that violate the antitrust laws as
sustained and applied by this Court. Although one may raise the
prices of his own products, and many, acting without concert, may
do so, the moment they conspire to that end, they are punishable.
The same principle is applied to organized labor. Any workman may
quit his work for any reason, but concerted actions to the same end
are in some circumstances forbidden. National Labor Relations Act,
as amended, 61 Stat. 136, § 8(b), 29 U.S.C. § 158(b).
The reasons underlying the doctrine that conspiracy may be a
substantive evil in itself, apart from any evil it may threaten,
attempt, or accomplish, are peculiarly appropriate to
conspiratorial Communism.
"The reason for finding criminal liability in case of a
combination to effect an unlawful end or to use unlawful means,
where none would exist, even though the act contemplated were
actually committed by an individual, is that a combination of
persons to commit a wrong, either as an end or as a means to an
end, is so much more dangerous, because of its increased power to
do wrong, because it is more difficult Page 341 U. S. 574 to guard against and prevent the evil designs of a group of
persons than of a single person, and because of the terror which
fear of such a combination tends to create in the minds of people.
[ Footnote 3/14 ]"
There is lamentation in the dissents about the injustice of
conviction in the absence of some overt act. Of course, there has
been no general uprising against the Government, but the record is
replete with acts to carry out the conspiracy alleged, acts such as
always are held sufficient to consummate the crime where the
statute requires an overt act.
But the shorter answer is that no overt act is or need be
required. The Court, in antitrust cases, early upheld the power of
Congress to adopt the ancient common law that makes conspiracy
itself a crime. Through Mr. Justice Holmes, it said:
"Coming next to the objection that no overt act is laid, the
answer is that the Sherman Act punishes the conspiracies at which
it is aimed on the common law footing -- that is to say, it does
not make the doing of any act other than the act of conspiring a
condition of liability." Nash v. United States, 229 U.
S. 373 , 229 U. S. 378 .
Reiterated, United States v. Socony-Vacuum Oil Co., 310 U. S. 150 , 310 U. S. 252 .
It is not to be supposed that the power of Congress to protect the
Nation's existence is more limited than its power to protect
interstate commerce.
Also, it is urged that, since the conviction is for conspiracy
to teach and advocate, and to organize the Communist Party to teach
and advocate, the First Amendment is violated because freedoms of
speech and press protect teaching and advocacy regardless of what
is taught or advocated. I have never thought that to be the
law. Page 341 U. S. 575 I do not suggest that Congress could punish conspiracy to
advocate something, the doing of which it may not punish. Advocacy
or exposition of the doctrine of communal property ownership, or
any political philosophy unassociated with advocacy of its
imposition by force or seizure of government by unlawful means
could not be reached through conspiracy prosecution. But it is not
forbidden to put down force or violence, it is not forbidden to
punish its teaching or advocacy, and the end being punishable,
there is no doubt of the power to punish conspiracy for the
purpose.
The defense of freedom of speech or press has often been raised
in conspiracy cases, because, whether committed by Communists, by
businessmen, or by common criminals, it usually consists of words
written or spoken, evidenced by letters, conversations, speeches or
documents. Communication is the essence of every conspiracy, for
only by it can common purpose and concert of action be brought
about or be proved. However, when labor unions raised the defense
of free speech against a conspiracy charge, we unanimously
said:
"It rarely has been suggested that the constitutional freedom
for speech and press extends its immunity to speech or writing used
as an integral part of conduct in violation of a valid criminal
statute. We reject the contention now. . . ."
". . . It is true that the agreements and course of conduct here
were as in most instances brought about through speaking or
writing. But it has never been deemed an abridgment of freedom of
speech or press to make a course of conduct illegal merely because
the conduct was in part initiated, evidenced, or carried out by
means of language, either spoken, written, or printed. . . . Such
an expansive interpretation Page 341 U. S. 576 of the constitutional guaranties of speech and press would make
it practically impossible ever to enforce laws against agreements
in restraint of trade, as well as many other agreements and
conspiracies deemed injurious to society." Giboney v. Empire Storage & Ice Co., 336 U.
S. 490 , 336 U. S. 498 , 336 U. S.
502 .
A contention by the press itself, in a conspiracy case, that it
was entitled to the benefits of the "clear and present danger"
test, was curtly rebuffed by this Court, saying:
"Nor is a publisher who engages in business practices made
unlawful by the Sherman Act entitled to a partial immunity by
reason of the 'clear and present danger' doctrine. . . . Formulated
as it was to protect liberty of thought and of expression, it would
degrade the clear and present danger doctrine to fashion from it a
shield for business publishers who engage in business practices
condemned by the Sherman Act. . . ." Associated Press v. United States, 326 U. S.
1 , 326 U. S. 7 . I
should think it at least as "degrading" to fashion of it a shield
for conspirators whose ultimate purpose is to capture or overthrow
the Government.
In conspiracy cases, the Court not only has dispensed with proof
of clear and present danger, but even of power to create a
danger:
"It long has been settled, however, that a 'conspiracy to commit
a crime is a different offense from the crime that is the object of
the conspiracy.' . . . Petitioners, for example, might have been
convicted here of a conspiracy to monopolize without ever having
acquired the power to carry out the object of the conspiracy. . .
." American Tobacco Co. v. United States, 328 U.
S. 781 , 328 U. S.
789 .
Having held that a conspiracy alone is a crime and its
consummation is another, it would be weird legal reasoning to hold
that Congress could punish the one only if there was "clear and
present danger" of the second. This Page 341 U. S. 577 would compel the Government to prove two crimes in order to
convict for one.
When our constitutional provisions were written, the chief
forces recognized as antagonists in the struggle between authority
and liberty were the Government, on the one hand, and the
individual citizen, on the other. It was thought that, if the state
could be kept in its place, the individual could take care of
himself.
In more recent times, these problems have been complicated by
the intervention between the state and the citizen of permanently
organized, well financed, semi-secret and highly disciplined
political organizations. Totalitarian groups here and abroad
perfected the technique of creating private paramilitary
organizations to coerce both the public government and its
citizens. These organizations assert as against our Government all
of the constitutional rights and immunities of individuals, and at
the same time exercise over their followers much of the authority
which they deny to the Government. The Communist Party
realistically is a state within a state, an authoritarian
dictatorship within a republic. It demands these freedoms not for
its members, but for the organized party. It denies to its own
members at the same time the freedom to dissent, to debate, to
deviate from the party line, and enforces its authoritarian rule by
crude purges, if nothing more violent.
The law of conspiracy has been the chief means at the
Government's disposal to deal with the growing problems created by
such organizations. I happen to think it is an awkward and inept
remedy, but I find no constitutional authority for taking this
weapon from the Government. There is no constitutional right to
"gang up" on the Government.
While I think there was power in Congress to enact this statute
and that, as applied in this case, it cannot be Page 341 U. S. 578 held unconstitutional, [ Footnote
3/15 ] I add that I have little faith in the long-range
effectiveness of this conviction to stop the rise of the Communist
movement. Communism will not go to jail with these Communists. No
decision by this Court can forestall revolution whenever the
existing government fails to command the respect and loyalty of the
people and sufficient distress and discontent is allowed to grow up
among the masses. Many failures by fallen governments attest that
no government can long prevent revolution by outlawry. [ Footnote 3/16 ] Corruption, ineptitude,
inflation, oppressive taxation, militarization, injustice, and loss
of leadership capable of intellectual initiative in domestic or
foreign affairs are allies on which the Communists Page 341 U. S. 579 count to bring opportunity knocking to their door. Sometimes I
think they may be mistaken. But the Communists are not building
just for today -- the rest of us might profit by their example.
[ Footnote 3/1 ]
The Government's own summary of its charge is:
"The indictment charged that from, April 1, 1945, to the date of
the indictment, petitioners unlawfully, willfully, and knowingly
conspired with each other and with other persons unknown to the
grand jury (1) to organize as the Communist Party of the United
States of America a society, group and assembly of persons who
teach and advocate the overthrow and destruction of the Government
of the United States by force and violence, and (2) knowingly and
willfully to advocate and teach the duty and necessity of
overthrowing and destroying the Government of the United States by
force and violence. The indictment alleged that Section 2 of the
Smith Act proscribes these acts, and that the conspiracy to take
such action is a violation of Section 3 of the act (18 U.S.C. 10,
11 (1946 ed.))."
[ Footnote 3/2 ]
The Government says this Act before us was modeled after the New
York Act of 1909, sustained by this Court in Gitlow v. New
York, 268 U. S. 652 .
That, in turn, as the Court pointed out, followed an earlier New
York Act of 1902. Shortly after the assassination of President
McKinley by an anarchist, Congress adopted the same concepts in the
Immigration Act of March 3, 1903. 32 Stat. 1213, § 2. Some germs of
the same concept can be found in some reconstruction legislation,
such as the Enforcement Act of 1871, 17 Stat. 13. The Espionage Act
of 1917, 40 Stat. 217, tit. 1, § 3, which gave rise to a series of
civil rights decisions, applied only during war and defined as
criminal "false statements with intent" to interfere with our war
effort or cause insubordination in the armed forces or obstruct
recruiting. However, a wave of "criminal syndicalism statutes" were
enacted by the States. They were generally upheld, Whitney v.
California, 274 U. S. 357 , and
prosecutions under them were active from 1919 to 1924. In
California alone, 531 indictments were returned and 164 persons
convicted. 4 Encyc.Soc.Sci. 582, 583. The Smith Act followed
closely the terminology designed to incriminate the methods of
terroristic anarchism.
[ Footnote 3/3 ]
Elementary texts amplify the theory and practice of these
movements which must be greatly oversimplified in this opinion. See Anarchism, 2 Encyc.Soc.Sci. 46; Nihilism, 11
Encyc.Soc.Sci. 377.
[ Footnote 3/4 ] Spies v. Illinois, 122 Ill. 1, 12 N.E. 865, 17 N.E.
898.
[ Footnote 3/5 ]
Prof. Beard demonstrates this antithesis by quoting the Russian
anarchist leader Bakunin, as follows:
"'Marx is an authoritarian and centralizing communist. He wishes
what we wish: the complete triumph of economic and social equality,
however, within the state and through the power of the state,
through the dictatorship of a very strong and, so to speak,
despotic provisional government, that is, by the negation of
liberty. His economic ideal is the state as the sole owner of land
and capital, tilling the soil by means of agricultural
associations, under the management of its engineers, and directing
through the agency of capital all industrial and commercial
associations."
"'We demand the same triumph of economic and social equality
through the abolition of the state and everything called juridical
right, which is according to our view the permanent negation of
human right. We wish the reconstruction of society and the
establishment of the unity of mankind not from above downward
through authority, through socialistic officials, engineers and
public technicians, but from below upward through the voluntary
federation of labor associations of all kinds emancipated entirely
from the yoke of the state.'"
Beard, Individualism and Capitalism, 1 Encyc.Soc.Sci. 145,
158.
[ Footnote 3/6 ]
For methods and objects of infiltration of labor unions, see
American Communications Assn. v. Douds, 339 U.
S. 382 , 339 U. S.
422 .
[ Footnote 3/7 ]
The Czar's government, in February, 1917, literally gave up,
almost without violence, to the Provisional Government because it
was ready to fall apart from its corruption, ineptitude,
superstition, oppression and defeat. The revolutionary parties had
little to do with this, and regarded it as a bourgeoisie triumph.
Lenin was an exile in Switzerland, Trotsky in the United States,
and Stalin was in Siberia. The Provisional Government attempted to
continue the war against Germany, but it, too, was unable to solve
internal problems, and its Galician campaign failed with heavy
losses. By October, its prestige and influence sank so low that it
could not continue. Meanwhile, Lenin and Trotsky had returned and
consolidated the Bolshevik position around the Soviets, or trade
unions. They simply took over power in an almost bloodless
revolution between October 25 and November 7, 1917. That Lenin and
Trotsky represented only a minority was demonstrated in November
elections, in which the Bolsheviks secured less than a quarter of
the seats. Then began the series of opportunistic movements to
entrench themselves in power. Faced by invasion of the allies, by
counterrevolution, and the attempted assassination of Lenin,
terrorism was resorted to on a large scale, and all the devices of
the Czar's police state were reestablished. See 1 Carr,
The Bolshevik Revolution 1917-1923, 99-110, and Moore, Soviet
Politics -- The Dilemma of Power, 117-139.
[ Footnote 3/8 ]
Duchacek, The Strategy of Communist Infiltration:
Czechoslovakia, 1944-1948, World Politics, Vol. II, No. 3 (April
1950) 345-372, and The February Coup in Czechoslovakia, id., July, 1950, 511-532; see also Kertesz, The
Methods of Communist Conquest: Hungary, 1944-1947, id., October 1950, 20-54; Lasswell, The Strategy of Soviet Propaganda,
24 Acad.Pol.Sci.Proc. 214, 221. See also Friedman, The
Break-up of Czech Democracy.
[ Footnote 3/9 ] Schenck v. United States, 249 U. S.
47 . This doctrine has been attacked as one which "annuls
the most significant purpose of the First Amendment. It destroys
the intellectual basis of our plan of self-government." Meiklejohn,
Free Speech And Its Relation to Self-Government, 29. It has been
praised:
"The concept of freedom of speech received for the first time an
authoritative judicial interpretation in accord with the purpose of
the framers of the Constitution."
Chafee, Free Speech in the United States, 82. In either event,
it is the only original judicial thought on the subject, all later
cases having made only extensions of its application. All agree
that it means something very important, but no two seem to agree on
what it is. See concurring opinion, MR. JUSTICE
FRANKFURTER, Kovacs v. Cooper, 336 U. S.
77 , 336 U. S.
89 .
[ Footnote 3/10 ] Gitlow v. New York, 268 U. S. 652 ; Whitney v. California, 274 U. S. 357 .
Holmes' comment on the former, in his letters to Sir Frederick
Pollock of June 2 and 18, 1925, as "a case in which conscience and
judgment are a little in doubt," and description of his dissent as
one "in favor of the rights of an anarchist (so-called) to talk
drool in favor of the proletarian dictatorship" show the tentative
nature of his test, even as applied to a trivial case.
Holmes-Pollock Letters (Howe ed.1946).
[ Footnote 3/11 ]
So characterized by Mr. Justice Brandeis in Schaefer v.
United States, 251 U. S. 466 , 251 U. S.
482 .
[ Footnote 3/12 ]
Recent cases have pushed the "clear and present danger" doctrine
to greater extremes. While Mr. Justice Brandeis said only that the
evil to be feared must be "imminent" and "relatively serious," Whitney v. California, 274 U. S. 357 , 274 U. S. 376 and 274 U. S. 377 ,
more recently it was required
"that the substantive evil must be extremely serious
and the degree of imminence extremely high before
utterances can be punished." Bridges v. California, 314 U.
S. 252 , 314 U. S. 263 .
(Italics supplied.) Schneiderman v. United States, 320 U.
S. 118 , overruled earlier holdings that the courts could
take judicial notice that the Communist Party does advocate
overthrow of the Government by force and violence. This Court
reviewed much of the basic Communist literature that is before us
now, and held that it was within "the area of allowable thought," id. at 320 U. S. 139 ,
that it does not show lack of attachment to the Constitution, and
that success of the Communist Party would not necessarily mean the
end of representative government. The Court declared further
that
"[a] tenable conclusion from the foregoing is that the Party, in
1927, desired to achieve its purpose by peaceful and democratic
means, and, as a theoretical matter, justified the use of force and
violence only as a method of preventing an attempted forcible
counter-overthrow once the Party had obtained control in a peaceful
manner, or as a method of last resort to enforce the majority will
if at some indefinite future time because of peculiar circumstances
constitutional or peaceful channels were no longer open." Id. at 320 U. S. 157 .
Moreover, the Court considered that this
"mere doctrinal justification or prediction of the use of force
under hypothetical conditions at some indefinite future time --
prediction that is not calculated or intended to be presently acted
upon. . . ." ibid., was within the realm of free speech. A dissent
by Mr. Chief Justice Stone, for himself and Justices Roberts and
Frankfurter, challenged these naive conclusions, as they did again
in Bridges v. Wixon, 326 U. S. 135 , in
which the Court again set aside an Attorney General's deportation
order. Here, Mr. Justice Murphy, without whom there would not have
been a majority for the decision, speaking for himself in a
concurring opinion, pronounced the whole deportation statute
unconstitutional, as applied to Communists, under the "clear and
present danger test," because
"Not the slightest evidence was introduced to show that either
Bridges or the Communist Party seriously and imminently threatens
to uproot the Government by force or violence."
326 U.S. at 326 U. S.
165 .
[ Footnote 3/13 ]
These dangers were more fully set out in Krulewitch v.
United States, 336 U. S. 440 , 336 U. S.
445 .
[ Footnote 3/14 ]
Miller on Criminal Law, 110. Similar reasons have been
reiterated by this Court. United States v. Rabinowich, 238 U. S. 78 , 238 U. S. 88 ; Pinkerton v. United States, 328 U.
S. 640 , 328 U. S.
643 -644.
[ Footnote 3/15 ]
The defendants have had the benefit so far in this case of all
the doubts and confusions afforded by attempts to apply the "clear
and present danger" doctrine. While I think it has no proper
application to the case, these efforts have been in response to
their own contentions and favored, rather than prejudiced, them.
There is no call for reversal on account of it.
[ Footnote 3/16 ]
The pathetically ineffective efforts of free European states to
overcome feebleness of the Executive and decomposition of the
Legislative branches of government by legal proscriptions are
reviewed in Loewenstein, Legislative Control of Political Extremism
in European Democracies, 38 Col.L.Rev. 591, 725 (1938). The Nazi
Party seizure of power in Germany occurred while both it and its
Communist counterpart were under sentence of illegality from the
courts of the Weimar Republic. The German Criminal Code struck
directly at the disciplinary system of totalitarian parties. It
provided:
"The participation in an organization the existence,
constitution, or purposes of which are to be kept secret from the
Government, or in which obedience to unknown superiors or
unconditional obedience to known superiors is pledged, is
punishable by imprisonment up to six months for the members and
from one month to one year for the founders and officers. Public
officials may be deprived of the right to hold public office for a
period of from one to five years."
2 Nazi Conspiracy and Aggression (GPO 1946) 11. The Czar's
government of Russia fell while the Communist leaders were in
exile. See 341
U.S. 494 fn3/7|>n. 7. Instances of similar failures could be
multiplied indefinitely.
MR. JUSTICE BLACK, dissenting.
Here again, as in Breard v. Alexandria, post, p. 341 U. S. 622 ,
decided this day, my basic disagreement with the Court is not as to
how we should explain or reconcile what was said in prior
decisions, but springs from a fundamental difference in
constitutional approach. Consequently, it would serve no useful
purpose to state my position at length.
At the outset, I want to emphasize what the crime involved in
this case is, and what it is not. These petitioners were not
charged with an attempt to overthrow the Government. They were not
charged with overt acts of any kind designed to overthrow the
Government. They were not even charged with saying anything or
writing anything designed to overthrow the Government. The charge
was that they agreed to assemble and to talk and publish certain
ideas at a later date: the indictment is that they conspired to
organize the Communist Party and to use speech or newspapers and
other publications in the future to teach and advocate the forcible
overthrow of the Government. No matter how it is worded, this is a
virulent form of prior censorship of speech and press, which I
believe the First Amendment forbids. I would hold § 3 of the Smith
Act authorizing this prior restraint unconstitutional on its face
and as applied.
But let us assume, contrary to all constitutional ideas of fair
criminal procedure, that petitioners, although not indicted for the
crime of actual advocacy, may be punished for it. Even on this
radical assumption, the other opinions in this case show that the
only way to affirm Page 341 U. S. 580 these convictions is to repudiate directly or indirectly the
established "clear and present danger" rule. This the Court does in
a way which greatly restricts the protections afforded by the First
Amendment. The opinions for affirmance indicate that the chief
reason for jettisoning the rule is the expressed fear that advocacy
of Communist doctrine endangers the safety of the Republic.
Undoubtedly a governmental policy of unfettered communication of
ideas does entail dangers. To the Founders of this Nation, however,
the benefits derived from free expression were worth the risk. They
embodied this philosophy in the First Amendment's command that
"Congress shall make no law . . . abridging the freedom of speech,
or of the press. . . ." I have always believed that the First
Amendment is the keystone of our Government, that the freedoms it
guarantees provide the best insurance against destruction of all
freedom. At least as to speech in the realm of public matters, I
believe that the "clear and present danger" test does not "mark the
furthermost constitutional boundaries of protected expression," but
does "no more than recognize a minimum compulsion of the Bill of
Rights." Bridges v. California, 314 U.
S. 252 , 314 U. S.
263 .
So long as this Court exercises the power of judicial review of
legislation, I cannot agree that the First Amendment permits us to
sustain laws suppressing freedom of speech and press on the basis
of Congress' or our own notions of mere "reasonableness." Such a
doctrine waters down the First Amendment so that it amounts to
little more than an admonition to Congress. The Amendment as so
construed is not likely to protect any but those "safe" or orthodox
views which rarely need its protection. I must also express my
objection to the holding because, as MR. JUSTICE DOUGLAS dissent
shows, it sanctions the determination of a crucial issue of fact by
the judge, rather than by the jury. Nor can I let this
opportunity Page 341 U. S. 581 pass without expressing my objection to the severely limited
grant of certiorari in this case which precluded consideration here
of at least two other reasons for reversing these convictions: (1)
the record shows a discriminatory selection of the jury panel which
prevented trial before a representative cross-section of the
community; (2) the record shows that one member of the trial jury
was violently hostile to petitioners before and during the
trial.
Public opinion being what it now is, few will protest the
conviction of these Communist petitioners. There is hope, however,
that, in calmer times, when present pressures, passions and fears
subside, this or some later Court will restore the First Amendment
liberties to the high preferred place where they belong in a free
society.
MR. JUSTICE DOUGLAS, dissenting.
If this were a case where those who claimed protection under the
First Amendment were teaching the techniques of sabotage, the
assassination of the President, the filching of documents from
public files, the planting of bombs, the art of street warfare, and
the like, I would have no doubts. The freedom to speak is not
absolute; the teaching of methods of terror and other seditious
conduct should be beyond the pale along with obscenity and
immorality. This case was argued as if those were the facts. The
argument imported much seditious conduct into the record. That is
easy, and it has popular appeal, for the activities of Communists
in plotting and scheming against the free world are common
knowledge. But the fact is that no such evidence was introduced at
the trial. There is a statute which makes a seditious conspiracy
unlawful. [ Footnote 4/1 ]
Petitioners, however, were not Page 341 U. S. 582 charged with a "conspiracy to overthrow" the Government. They
were charged with a conspiracy to form a party and groups and
assemblies of people who teach and advocate the overthrow of our
Government by force or violence and with a conspiracy to advocate
and teach its overthrow by force and violence. [ Footnote 4/2 ] It may well be that indoctrination in
the techniques of terror to destroy the Government would be
indictable under either statute. But the teaching which is
condemned here is of a different character.
So far as the present record is concerned, what petitioners did
was to organize people to teach and themselves teach the
Marxist-Leninist doctrine contained chiefly in four books:
[ Footnote 4/3 ] Stalin, Foundations
of Leninism (1924); Marx and Engels, Manifesto of the Communist
Party (1848); Lenin, The State and Revolution (1917); History of
the Communist Party of the Soviet Union (B.) (1939).
Those books are to Soviet Communism what Mein Kampf was to
Nazism. If they are understood, the ugliness of Communism is
revealed, its deceit and cunning are exposed, the nature of its
activities becomes apparent, and the chances of its success less
likely. That is not, of course, the reason why petitioners chose
these books for their classrooms. They are fervent Communists to
whom these volumes are gospel. They preached the creed with the
hope that some day it would be acted upon. Page 341 U. S. 583 The opinion of the Court does not outlaw these texts nor condemn
them to the fire, as the Communists do literature offensive to
their creed. But if the books themselves are not outlawed, if they
can lawfully remain on library shelves, by what reasoning does
their use in a classroom become a crime? It would not be a crime
under the Act to introduce these books to a class, though that
would be teaching what the creed of violent overthrow of the
Government is. The Act, as construed, requires the element of
intent -- that those who teach the creed believe in it. The crime
then depends not on what is taught, but on who the teacher is. That
is to make freedom of speech turn not on what is said, but
on the intent with which it is said. Once we start down that road,
we enter territory dangerous to the liberties of every citizen.
There was a time in England when the concept of constructive
treason flourished. Men were punished not for raising a hand
against the king, but for thinking murderous thoughts about him.
The Framers of the Constitution were alive to that abuse, and took
steps to see that the practice would not flourish here. Treason was
defined to require overt acts -- the evolution of a plot against
the country into an actual project. The present case is not one of
treason. But the analogy is close when the illegality is made to
turn on intent, not on the nature of the act. We then start probing
men's minds for motive and purpose; they become entangled in the
law not for what they did, but for what they thought; they
get convicted not for what they said, but for the purpose with
which they said it.
Intent, of course, often makes the difference in the law. An act
otherwise excusable or carrying minor penalties may grow to an
abhorrent thing if the evil intent is present. We deal here,
however, not with ordinary acts, but with speech, to which the
Constitution has given a special sanction. Page 341 U. S. 584 The vice of treating speech as the equivalent of overt acts of a
treasonable or seditious character is emphasized by a concurring
opinion, which, by invoking the law of conspiracy, makes speech do
service for deeds which are dangerous to society. The doctrine of
conspiracy has served divers and oppressive purposes, and, in its
broad reach, can be made to do great evil. But never until today
has anyone seriously thought that the ancient law of conspiracy
could constitutionally be used to turn speech into seditious
conduct. Yet that is precisely what is suggested. I repeat that we
deal here with speech alone, not with speech plus acts of sabotage
or unlawful conduct. Not a single seditious act is charged in the
indictment. To make a lawful speech unlawful because two men
conceive it is to raise the law of conspiracy to appalling
proportions. That course is to make a radical break with the past
and to violate one of the cardinal principles of our constitutional
scheme.
Free speech has occupied an exalted position because of the high
service it has given our society. Its protection is essential to
the very existence of a democracy. The airing of ideas releases
pressures which otherwise might become destructive. When ideas
compete in the market for acceptance, full and free discussion
exposes the false, and they gain few adherents. Full and free
discussion even of ideas we hate encourages the testing of our own
prejudices and preconceptions. Full and free discussion keeps a
society from becoming stagnant and unprepared for the stresses and
strains that work to tear all civilizations apart.
Full and free discussion has indeed been the first article of
our faith. We have founded our political system on it. It has been
the safeguard of every religious, political, philosophical,
economic, and racial group amongst us. We have counted on it to
keep us from embracing what is cheap and false; we have trusted the
common sense of our Page 341 U. S. 585 people to choose the doctrine true to our genius and to reject
the rest. This has been the one single outstanding tenet that has
made our institutions the symbol of freedom and equality. We have
deemed it more costly to liberty to suppress a despised minority
than to let them vent their spleen. We have above all else feared
the political censor. We have wanted a land where our people can be
exposed to all the diverse creeds and cultures of the world.
There comes a time when even speech loses its constitutional
immunity. Speech innocuous one year may at another time fan such
destructive flames that it must be halted in the interests of the
safety of the Republic. That is the meaning of the clear and
present danger test. When conditions are so critical that there
will be no time to avoid the evil that the speech threatens, it is
time to call a halt. Otherwise, free speech which is the strength
of the Nation will be the cause of its destruction.
Yet free speech is the rule, not the exception. The restraint to
be constitutional must be based on more than fear, on more than
passionate opposition against the speech, on more than a revolted
dislike for its contents. There must be some immediate injury to
society that is likely if speech is allowed. The classic statement
of these conditions was made by Mr. Justice Brandeis in his
concurring opinion in Whitney v. California, 274 U.
S. 357 , 274 U. S.
376 -377,
"Fear of serious injury cannot alone justify suppression of free
speech and assembly. Men feared witches and burnt women. It is the
function of speech to free men from the bondage of irrational
fears. To justify suppression of free speech, there must be
reasonable ground to fear that serious evil will result if free
speech is practiced. There must be reasonable ground to believe
that the danger apprehended Page 341 U. S. 586 is imminent. There must be reasonable ground to believe that the
evil to be prevented is a serious one. Every denunciation of
existing law tends in some measure to increase the probability that
there will be violation of it. Condonation of a breach enhances the
probability. Expressions of approval add to the probability.
Propagation of the criminal state of mind by teaching syndicalism
increases it. Advocacy of law-breaking heightens it still further.
But even advocacy of violation, however reprehensible morally, is
not a justification for denying free speech where the advocacy
falls short of incitement and there is nothing to indicate that the
advocacy would be immediately acted on. The wide difference between
advocacy and incitement, between preparation and attempt, between
assembling and conspiracy, must be borne in mind. In order to
support a finding of clear and present danger, it must be shown
either that immediate serious violence was to be expected or was
advocated, or that the past conduct furnished reason to believe
that such advocacy was then contemplated."
"Those who won our independence by revolution were not cowards.
They did not fear political change. They did not exalt order at the
cost of liberty. To courageous, self-reliant men, with confidence
in the power of free and fearless reasoning applied through the
processes of popular government, no danger flowing from speech can
be deemed clear and present unless the incidence of the evil
apprehended is so imminent that it may befall before there is
opportunity for full discussion. If there be time to expose
through discussion the falsehood and fallacies, to avert the evil
by the processes of education, the remedy to be applied is more
speech, not enforced silence. "
(Italics added.) Page 341 U. S. 587 I had assumed that the question of the clear and present danger,
being so critical an issue in the case, would be a matter for
submission to the jury. It was squarely held in Pierce v.
United States, 252 U. S. 239 , 252 U. S. 244 ,
to be a jury question. Mr. Justice Pitney, speaking for the Court,
said,
"Whether the statement contained in the pamphlet had a natural
tendency to produce the forbidden consequences, as alleged, was a
question to be determined not upon demurrer, but by the jury at the
trial."
That is the only time the Court has passed on the issue. None of
our other decisions is contrary. Nothing said in any of the nonjury
cases has detracted from that ruling. [ Footnote 4/4 ] The statement in Pierce v. United
States, supra, states the law as it has been, and as it should
be. The Court, I think, errs when it treats the question as one of
law.
Yet, whether the question is one for the Court or the jury,
there should be evidence of record on the issue. This record,
however, contains no evidence whatsoever showing that the acts
charged, viz., the teaching of the Soviet theory of
revolution with the hope that it will be realized, have created any
clear and present danger to the Nation. The Court, however, rules
to the contrary. It says,
"The formation by petitioners of such a highly organized
conspiracy, with rigidly disciplined members subject to call when
the leaders, these petitioners, felt that the time had come for
action, coupled with the inflammable nature of world conditions,
similar uprisings in other countries, and the touch-and-go nature
of our relations with countries with whom petitioners were in the
very least ideologically attuned, convince us that their
convictions were justified on this score."
That ruling is, in my view, not responsive to the issue in the
case. We might as well say that the speech of Page 341 U. S. 588 petitioners is outlawed because Soviet Russia and her Red Army
are a threat to world peace.
The nature of Communism as a force on the world scene would, of
course, be relevant to the issue of clear and present danger of
petitioners' advocacy within the United States. But the primary
consideration is the strength and tactical position of petitioners
and their converts in this country. On that, there is no evidence
in the record. If we are to take judicial notice of the threat of
Communists within the nation, it should not be difficult to
conclude that, as a political party, they are of little
consequence. Communists in this country have never made a
respectable or serious showing in any election. I would doubt that
there is a village, let alone a city or county or state, which the
Communists could carry. Communism in the world scene is no
bogeyman; but Communism as a political faction or party in this
country plainly is. Communism has been so thoroughly exposed in
this country that it has been crippled as a political force. Free
speech has destroyed it as an effective political party. It is
inconceivable that those who went up and down this country
preaching the doctrine of revolution which petitioners espouse
would have any success. In days of trouble and confusion, when
bread lines were long, when the unemployed walked the streets, when
people were starving, the advocates of a short-cut by revolution
might have a chance to gain adherents. But today there are no such
conditions. The country is not in despair; the people know Soviet
Communism; the doctrine of Soviet revolution is exposed in all of
its ugliness, and the American people want none of it.
How it can be said that there is a clear and present danger that
this advocacy will succeed is, therefore, a mystery. Some nations
less resilient than the United States, where illiteracy is high and
where democratic traditions are only budding, might have to take
drastic Page 341 U. S. 589 steps and jail these men for merely speaking their creed. But in
America, they are miserable merchants of unwanted ideas; their
wares remain unsold. The fact that their ideas are abhorrent does
not make them powerful.
The political impotence of the Communists in this country does
not, of course, dispose of the problem. Their numbers; their
positions in industry and government; the extent to which they
have, in fact, infiltrated the police, the armed services,
transportation, stevedoring, power plants, munitions works, and
other critical places -- these facts all bear on the likelihood
that their advocacy of the Soviet theory of revolution will
endanger the Republic. But the record is silent on these facts. If
we are to proceed on the basis of judicial notice, it is impossible
for me to say that the Communists in this country are so potent or
so strategically deployed that they must be suppressed for their
speech. I could not so hold unless I were willing to conclude that
the activities in recent years of committees of Congress, of the
Attorney General, of labor unions, of state legislatures, and of
Loyalty Boards were so futile as to leave the country on the edge
of grave peril. To believe that petitioners and their following are
placed in such critical positions as to endanger the Nation is to
believe the incredible. It is safe to say that the followers of the
creed of Soviet Communism are known to the FBI; that, in case of
war with Russia, they will be picked up overnight, as were all
prospective saboteurs at the commencement of World War II; that the
invisible army of petitioners is the best known, the most beset,
and the least thriving of any fifth column in history. Only those
held by fear and panic could think otherwise.
This is my view if we are to act on the basis of judicial
notice. But the mere statement of the opposing views indicates how
important it is that we know the facts before we act. Neither
prejudice nor hate nor senseless Page 341 U. S. 590 fear should be the basis of this solemn act. Free speech -- the
glory of our system of government -- should not be sacrificed on
anything less that plain and objective proof of danger that the
evil advocated is imminent. On this record, no one can say that
petitioners and their converts are in such a strategic position as
to have even the slightest chance of achieving their aims.
The First Amendment provides that "Congress shall make no law .
. . abridging the freedom of speech." The Constitution provides no
exception. This does not mean, however, that the Nation need hold
its hand until it is in such weakened condition that there is no
time to protect itself from incitement to revolution. Seditious
conduct can always be punished. But the command of the First
Amendment is so clear that we should not allow Congress to call a
halt to free speech except in the extreme case of peril from the
speech itself. The First Amendment makes confidence in the common
sense of our people and in their maturity of judgment the great
postulate of our democracy. Its philosophy is that violence is
rarely, if ever, stopped by denying civil liberties to those
advocating resort to force. The First Amendment reflects the
philosophy of Jefferson
"that it is time enough for the rightful purposes of civil
government for its officers to interfere when principles break out
into overt acts against peace and good order. [ Footnote 4/5 ]"
The political censor has no place in our public debates. Unless
and until extreme and necessitous circumstances are shown, our aim
should be to keep speech unfettered and to allow the processes Page 341 U. S. 591 of law to be invoked only when the provocateurs among us move
from speech to action.
Vishinsky wrote in 1938 in The Law of the Soviet State, "In our
state, naturally, there is and can be no place for freedom of
speech, press, and so on for the foes of socialism."
Our concern should be that we accept no such standard for the
United States. Our faith should be that our people will never give
support to these advocates of revolution, so long as we remain
loyal to the purposes for which our Nation was founded.
| 341
U.S. 494 app2| APPENDIX TO OPINION OF MR. JUSTICE DOUGLAS. There have been numerous First Amendment cases before the Court
raising the issue of clear and present danger since Mr. Justice
Holmes first formulated the test in Schenck v. United
States, 249 U. S. 47 , 249 U. S. 52 .
Most of them, however, have not involved jury trials.
The cases which may be deemed at all relevant to our problem can
be classified as follows:
CONVICTIONS FOR CONTEMPT OF COURT (NON-JURY): Near v.
Minnesota, 283 U. S. 697 ; Bridges v. California, 314 U. S. 252 ; Thomas v. Collins, 323 U. S. 516 ; Pennekamp v. Florida, 328 U. S. 331 ; Craig v. Harney, 331 U. S. 367 .
CONVICTIONS BY STATE COURTS SITTING WITHOUT JURIES, GENERALLY
FOR VIOLATIONS OF LOCAL ORDINANCES: Lovell v. Griffin, 303 U. S. 444 ; Schneider v. State, 308 U. S. 147 ; Cantwell v. Connecticut, 310 U. S. 296 ; Marsh v. Alabama, 326 U. S. 501 ; Tucker v. Texas, 326 U. S. 517 ; Winters v. New York, 333 U. S. 507 ; Saia v. New York, 334 U. S. 558 ; Kovacs v. Cooper, 336 U. S. 77 ; Kunz v. New York, 340 U. S. 290 ; Feiner v. New York, 340 U. S. 315 .
INJUNCTIONS AGAINST ENFORCEMENT OF STATE OR LOCAL LAWS
(NON-JURY): Grosjean v. American Press
Co. , 297 Page 341 U. S. 592 U.S. 233; Hague v. CIO, 307 U.
S. 496 ; Minersville School District v. Gobitis, 310 U. S. 586 ; West Virginia Board of Education v. Barnette, 319 U.
S. 624 .
ADMINISTRATIVE PROCEEDINGS (NON-JURY): Bridges v.
Wixon, 326 U. S. 135 ; Schneiderman v. United States, 320 U.
S. 118 ; American Communications Association v.
Douds, 339 U. S. 382 .
CASES TRIED BEFORE JURIES FOR VIOLATIONS OF STATE LAWS DIRECTED
AGAINST ADVOCACY OF ANARCHY, CRIMINAL SYNDICALISM, ETC.: Gilbert v. Minnesota, 254 U. S. 325 ; Gitlow v. New York, 268 U. S. 652 ; Whitney v. California, 274 U. S. 357 ; Fiske v. Kansas, 274 U. S. 380 ; Stromberg v. California, 283 U. S. 359 ; De Jonge v. Oregon, 299 U. S. 353 ; Herndon v. Lowry, 301 U. S. 242 ; Taylor v. Mississippi, 319 U. S. 583 ; or
for minor local offenses: Cox v. New Hampshire, 312 U. S. 569 ; Chaplinsky v. New Hampshire, 315 U.
S. 568 ; Terminiello v. Chicago, 337 U. S.
1 ; Niemotko v. Maryland, 340 U.
S. 268 .
FEDERAL PROSECUTIONS BEFORE JURIES UNDER THE ESPIONAGE ACT OF
1917 FOLLOWING WORLD WAR I: Schenck v. United States, 249 U. S. 47 ; Frohwerk v. United States, 249 U.
S. 204 ; Debs v. United States, 249 U.
S. 211 ; Abrams v. United States, 250 U.
S. 616 ; Schaefer v. United States, 251 U.
S. 466 ; Pierce v. United States, 252 U.
S. 239 . Pierce v. United States ruled that the
question of clear and present danger was for the jury. In the other
cases in this group the question whether the issue was for the
court or the jury was not raised or passed upon.
FEDERAL PROSECUTION BEFORE A JURY UNDER THE ESPIONAGE ACT OF 117
FOLLOWING WORLD WAR II: Hartzel v. United States, 322 U. S. 680 . The
jury was instructed on clear and present danger in terms drawn from
the language of Mr. Justice Holmes in Schenck v. United States,
supra, p. 249 U. S. 52 .
The Court reversed the conviction on the ground that there had not
been sufficient evidence for submission of the case to the
jury.
[ Footnote 4/1 ]
18 U.S.C. § 2384 provides:
"If two or more persons in any State or Territory, or in any
place subject to the jurisdiction of the United States, conspire to
overthrow, put down, or to destroy by force the Government of the
United States, or to levy war against them, or to oppose by force
the authority thereof, or by force to prevent, hinder, or delay the
execution of any law of the United States, or by force to seize,
take, or possess any property of the United States contrary to the
authority thereof, they shall each be fined not more than $5,000 or
imprisoned not more than six years, or both."
[ Footnote 4/2 ]
54 Stat. 671, 18 U.S.C. §§ 10, 11.
[ Footnote 4/3 ]
Other books taught were Stalin, Problems of Leninism, Strategy
and Tactics of World Communism (H.R.Doc. No. 619, 80th Cong., 2d
Sess.), and Program of the Communist International.
[ Footnote 4/4 ]
The cases which reached the Court are analyzed in the Appendix
attached to this opinion, post, p. 341 U. S.
591 .
[ Footnote 4/5 ]
12 Hening's Stat. (Virginia 1823), c. 34, p. 84. Whipple, Our
Ancient Liberties (1927), p. 95, states:
"This idea that the limit on freedom of speech or press should
be set only by an actual overt act was not new. It had been
asserted by a long line of distinguished thinkers, including John
Locke, Montesquieu in his The Spirit of the Laws ('Words
do not constitute an overt act'), the Rev. Phillip Furneaux, James
Madison, and Thomas Jefferson." | In Dennis v. United States (1951), the Supreme Court upheld the constitutionality of the Smith Act, which criminalized advocating for the overthrow of the US government. The Court found that the First Amendment doesn't protect speech that presents a "clear and present danger," and that the Smith Act's prohibition on advocating for violent revolution fell within this category. The Court also rejected vagueness challenges to the Act, stating that its terms were sufficiently clear. This case set a precedent for restricting speech that poses a potential threat to national security. |
Free Speech | Red Lion Broadcasting Co., Inc. v. FCC | https://supreme.justia.com/cases/federal/us/395/367/ | U.S. Supreme Court Red Lion Broadcasting Co., Inc. v.
FCC, 395
U.S. 367 (1969) Red Lion Broadcasting Co., Inc.
v. Federal Communications
Commission No. 2 Argued April 2-3,
1969 Decided June 9, 1969 395
U.S. 367 ast|>* 395
U.S. 367 CERTIORARI TO THE UNITED STATES
COURT OF APPEALS FOR THE DISTRICT OF COLUMBIA
CIRCUIT Syllabus The Federal Communications Commission (FCC) has for many years
imposed on broadcasters a "fairness doctrine," requiring that
public issues be presented by broadcasters and that each side of
those issues be given fair coverage. In No. 2, the FCC declared
that petitioner Red Lion Broadcasting Co. had failed to meet its
obligation under the fairness doctrine when it carried a program
which constituted a personal attack on one Cook, and ordered it to
send a transcript of the broadcast to Cook and provide reply time,
whether or not Cook would pay for it. The Court of Appeals upheld
the FCC's position. After the commencement of the Red Lion litigation, the FCC began a rulemaking proceeding to make the
personal attack aspect of the fairness doctrine more precise and
more readily enforceable, and to specify its rules relating to
political editorials. The rules, as adopted and amended, were held
unconstitutional by the Court of Appeals in RTNDA (No.
717) as abridging the freedoms of speech and press. Held: 1. The history of the fairness doctrine and of related
legislation shows that the FCC's action in the Red Lion case did not exceed its authority, and that, in adopting the new
regulations, the FCC was implementing congressional policy. Pp. 395 U. S.
375 -386.
(a) The fairness doctrine began shortly after the Federal Radio
Commission was established to allocate frequencies among competing
applicants in the public interest, and insofar as there is an
affirmative obligation of the broadcaster to see that both sides
are presented, the personal attack doctrine and regulations do not
differ from the fairness doctrine. Pp. 395 U. S.
375 -379.
(b) The FCC's statutory mandate to see that broadcasters operate
in the public interest and Congress' reaffirmation, in the Page 395 U. S. 368 1959 amendment to § 315 of the Communications Act, of the FCC's
view that the fairness doctrine inhered in the public interest
standard, support the conclusion that the doctrine and its
component personal attack and political editorializing' regulations
are a legitimate exercise of congressionally delegated authority.
Pp. 395 U. S.
379 -386.
2. The fairness doctrine and its specific manifestations in the
personal attack and political editorial rules do not violate the
First Amendment. Pp. 395 U. S.
386 -401.
(a) The First Amendment is relevant to public broadcasting, but
it is the right of the viewing and listening public, and not the
right of the broadcasters, which is paramount. Pp. 395 U. S.
386 -390.
(b) The First Amendment does not protect private censorship by
broadcasters who are licensed by the Government to use a scarce
resource which is denied to others. Pp. 395 U. S.
390 -392.
(c) The danger that licensees will eliminate coverage of
controversial issues as a result of the personal attack and
political editorial rules is, at best, speculative, and, in any
event, the FCC has authority to guard against this danger. Pp. 395 U. S.
392 -395.
(d) There was nothing vague about the FCC's specific ruling in
the Red Lion case, and the regulations at issue in No. 717
could be employed in precisely the same way as the fairness
doctrine in Red Lion. It is not necessary to decide every
aspect of the fairness doctrine to decide these cases. Problems
involving more extreme applications or more difficult
constitutional questions will be dealt with if and when they arise.
Pp. 395 U. S.
395 -396.
(e) It has not been shown that the scarcity of broadcast
frequencies, which impelled governmental regulation, is entirely a
thing of the past, as new uses for the frequency spectrum have kept
pace with improved technology and more efficient utilization of
that spectrum. Pp. 395 U. S.
396 -400.
No. 2, 127 U.S.App.D.C. 129, 381 F.2d 908, affirmed; No. 717,
400 F.2d 1002, reversed and remanded. Page 395 U. S. 369 MR. JUSTICE WHITE delivered the opinion of the Court
The Federal Communications Commission has for many years imposed
on radio and television broadcasters the requirement that
discussion of public issues be presented on broadcast stations, and
that each side of those issues must be given fair coverage. This is
known as the fairness doctrine, which originated very early in the
history of broadcasting and has maintained its present outlines for
some time. It is an obligation whose content has been defined in a
long series of FCC rulings in particular cases, and which is
distinct from the statutory Page 395 U. S. 370 requirement of § 315 of the Communications Act [ Footnote 1 ] that equal time be allotted all
qualified candidates for public office. Two aspects of the fairness
doctrine, relating to personal attacks in the context of
controversial public issues and to political editorializing, were
codified more precisely in the form of FCC regulations in 1967. The
two cases before us now, which were decided separately below,
challenge the constitutional and statutory bases of the doctrine
and component rules. Red Lion Page 395 U. S. 371 involves the application of the fairness doctrine to a
particular broadcast, and RTNDA arises as an action to
review the FCC's 1967 promulgation of the personal attack and
political editorializing regulations, which were laid down after
the Red Lion litigation had begun. I A The Red Lion Broadcasting Company is licensed to operate a
Pennsylvania radio station, WGCB. On November 27, 1964, WGCB
carried a 15-minute broadcast by the Reverend Billy James Hargis as
part of a "Christian Crusade" series. A book by Fred J. Cook
entitled "Goldwater -- Extremist on the Right" was discussed by
Hargis, who said that Cook had been fired by a newspaper for making
false charges against city officials; that Cook had then worked for
a Communist-affiliated publication; that he had defended Alger Hiss
and attacked J. Edgar Hoover and the Central Intelligence Agency,
and that he had now written a "book to smear and destroy Barry
Goldwater." [ Footnote 2 ] When
Cook heard of the broadcast, he Page 395 U. S. 372 concluded that he had been personally attacked and demanded free
reply time, which the station refused. After an exchange of letters
among Cook, Red Lion, and the FCC, the FCC declared that the Hargis
broadcast constituted a personal attack on Cook; that Red Lion had
failed to meet its obligation under the fairness doctrine as
expressed in Times-Mirror Broadcasting Co., 24 P & F
Radio Reg. 404 (1962), to send a tape, transcript, or summary of
the broadcast to Cook and offer him reply time, and that the
station must provide reply time whether or not Cook would pay for
it. On review in the Court of Appeals for the District of Columbia
Circuit, [ Footnote 3 ] the Page 395 U. S. 373 FCC's position was upheld as constitutional and otherwise
proper. 127 U.S.App.D.C. 129, 381 F.2d 908 (1967). B Not long after the Red Lion litigation was begun, the
FCC issued a Notice of Proposed Rule Making, 31 Fed.Reg. 5710, with
an eye to making the personal attack aspect of the fairness
doctrine more precise and more readily enforceable, and to
specifying its rules relating to political editorials. After
considering written comments supporting and opposing the rules, the
FCC adopted them substantially as proposed, 32 Fed.Reg. 10303.
Twice amended, 32 Fed.Reg. 11531, 33 Fed.Reg. 5362, the rules were
held unconstitutional in the RTNDA litigation by the Court
of Appeals for the Seventh Circuit, on review of the rulemaking
proceeding, as abridging the freedoms of speech and press. 400 F.2d
1002 (1968).
As they now stand amended, the regulations read as follows:
"Personal attacks; political editorials."
"(a) When, during the presentation of views on a controversial
issue of public importance, an attack is made upon the honesty,
character, integrity or like personal qualities of an identified
person or group, the licensee shall, within a reasonable time and
in no event later than 1 week after the attack, transmit to the
person or group attacked(1) notification of the date, time and
identification of the broadcast; (2) a script or tape (or an
accurate summary if a script or tape is not available) of the Page 395 U. S. 374 attack, and (3) an offer of a reasonable opportunity to respond
over the licensee's facilities."
"(b) The provisions of paragraph (a) of this section shall not
be applicable (1) to attacks on foreign groups or foreign public
figures; (2) to personal attacks which are made by legally
qualified candidates, their authorized spokesmen, or those
associated with them in the campaign, on other such candidates,
their authorized spokesmen, or persons associated with the
candidates in the campaign, and (3) to bona fide newscasts, bona
fide news interviews, and on-the-spot coverage of a bona fide news
event (including commentary or analysis contained in the foregoing
programs, but the provisions of paragraph (a) of this section shall
be applicable to editorials of the licensee)."
"NOTE: The fairness doctrine is applicable to situations coming
within [(3)], above, and, in a specific factual situation, may be
applicable in the general area of political broadcasts [(2)],
above. See section 315(a) of the Act, 47 U.S.C. 315(a); Public
Notice: Applicability of the Fairness Doctrine in the Handling of
Controversial Issues of Public Importance. 29 F. R. 10415. The
categories listed in [(3)] are the same as those specified in
section 315(a) of the Act."
"(c) Where a licensee, in an editorial, (i) endorses or (ii)
opposes a legally qualified candidate or candidates, the licensee
shall, within 24 hours after the editorial, transmit to
respectively (i) the other qualified candidate or candidates for
the same office or (ii) the candidate opposed in the editorial (1)
notification of the date and the time of the editorial; (2) a
script or tape of the editorial, and (3) an offer of a reasonable
opportunity for a candidate or a spokesman of the candidate to
respond over the Page 395 U. S. 375 licensee's facilities: Provided, however, That where
such editorials are broadcast within 72 hours prior to the day of
the election, the licensee shall comply with the provisions of this
paragraph sufficiently far in advance of the broadcast to enable
the candidate or candidates to have a reasonable opportunity to
prepare a response and to present it in a timely fashion."
47 CFR §§ 73.123, 73.300, 73.598, 73.679 (all identical). C Believing that the specific application of the fairness doctrine
in Red Lion, and the promulgation of the regulations in RTNDA, are both authorized by Congress and enhance, rather
than abridge, the freedoms of speech and press protected by the
First Amendment, we hold them valid and constitutional, reversing
the judgment below in RTNDA and affirming the judgment
below in Red Lion. II The history of the emergence of the fairness doctrine and of the
related legislation shows that the Commission's action in the Red Lion case did not exceed its authority, and that, in
adopting the new regulations, the Commission was implementing
congressional policy, rather than embarking on a frolic of its
own. A Before 1927, the allocation of frequencies was left entirely to
the private sector, and the result was chaos. [ Footnote 4 ] Page 395 U. S. 376 It quickly became apparent that broadcast frequencies
constituted a scarce resource whose use could be regulated and
rationalized only by the Government. Without government control,
the medium would be of little use because of the cacaphony of
competing voices, none of which could be clearly and predictably
heard. [ Footnote 5 ]
Consequently, the Federal Radio Commission was established Page 395 U. S. 377 to allocate frequencies among competing applicants in a manner
responsive to the public "convenience, interest, or necessity."
[ Footnote 6 ]
Very shortly thereafter, the Commission expressed its view that
the
"public interest requires ample play for the free and fair
competition of opposing views, and the commission believes that the
principle applies . . . to all discussions of issues of importance
to the public." Great Lakes Broadcasting Co., 3 F.R.C.Ann.Rep. 32, 33
(1929), rev'd on other grounds, 59 App.D.C.197, 37 F.2d
993, cert. dismissed, 281 U.S. 706 (1930). This doctrine
was applied through denial of license renewals or construction
permits, both by the FRC, Trinity Methodist Church, South v.
FRC, 61 App.D.C. 311, 62 F.2d 850 (1932), cert.
denied, 288 U.S. 599 (1933), and its successor FCC, Young
People's Association for the Propagation of the Gospel, 6
F.C.C. 178 (1938). After an extended period during which the
licensee was obliged not only to cover and to cover fairly the
views of others but also to refrain from expressing his own
personal views, Mayflower Broadcasting Corp., 8 F.C.C. 333
(1940), the latter limitation on the licensee was abandoned, and
the doctrine developed into its present form.
There is a twofold duty laid down by the FCC's decisions and
described by the 1949 Report on Editorializing by Broadcast
Licensees, 13 F.C.C. 1246 (1949). The broadcaster must give
adequate coverage to public issues, United Broadcasting
Co., 10 F.C.C. 515 (1945), and coverage must be fair in that
it accurately reflects the opposing views. New Broadcasting
Co., 6 P & F Radio Reg. 258 (1950). This must be done at
the broadcaster's own expense if sponsorship is unavailable. Cullman Broadcasting Co., 25 P & F Radio Reg. 895
(1963). Page 395 U. S. 378 Moreover, the duty must be met by programming obtained at the
licensee's own initiative if available from no other source. John J. Dempsey, 6 P & F Radio Reg. 615 (1950); see Metropolitan Broadcasting Corp., 19 P & F Radio
Reg. 602 (1960); The Evening News Assn., 6 P & F Radio
Reg. 283 (1950). The Federal Radio Commission had imposed these two
basic duties on broadcasters since the outset, Great Lakes
Broadcasting Co., 3 F.R.C.Ann.Rep. 32 (1929), rev'd on
other grounds, 59 App.D.C.197, 37 F.2d 993, cert.
dismissed, 281 U.S. 706 (1930); Chicago Federation of
Labor v. FRC, 3 F.R.C.Ann.Rep. 36 (1029), aff'd, 59
App.D.C. 333, 41 F.2d 422 (1930); KFKB Broadcasting Assn. v.
FRC, 60 App.D.C. 79, 47 F.2d 670 (1931), and in particular
respects the personal attack rules and regulations at issue here
have spelled them out in greater detail.
When a personal attack has been made on a figure involved in a
public issue, both the doctrine of cases such as Red Lion and Times-Mirror Broadcasting Co., 24 P & F Radio Reg.
404 (1962), and also the 1967 regulations at issue in RTNDA, require that the individual attacked himself be
offered an opportunity to respond. Likewise, where one candidate is
endorsed in a political editorial, the other candidates must
themselves be offered reply time to use personally or through a
spokesman. These obligations differ from the general fairness
requirement that issues be presented, and presented with coverage
of competing views, in that the broadcaster does not have the
option of presenting the attacked party's side himself or choosing
a third party to represent that side. But insofar as there is an
obligation of the broadcaster to see that both sides are presented,
and insofar as that is an affirmative obligation, the personal
attack doctrine and regulations do not differ from the preceding
fairness doctrine. The simple fact that the attacked men or
unendorsed candidates may respond themselves or through Page 395 U. S. 379 agents is not a critical distinction, and, indeed, it is not
unreasonable for the FCC to conclude that the objective of adequate
presentation of all sides may best be served by allowing those most
closely affected to make the response, rather than leaving the
response in the hands of the station which has attacked their
candidacies, endorsed their opponents, or carried a personal attack
upon them. B The statutory authority of the FCC to promulgate these
regulations derives from the mandate to the "Commission from time
to time, as public convenience, interest, or necessity requires" to
promulgate
"such rules and regulations and prescribe such restrictions and
conditions . . . as may be necessary to carry out the provisions of
this chapter. . . ."
47 U.S.C. § 303 and § 303(r). [ Footnote 7 ] The Commission is specifically directed to
consider the demands of the public interest in the course of
granting licenses, 47 U.S.C. §§ 307(a), 309(a); Page 395 U. S. 380 renewing them, 47 U.S.C. § 307, and modifying them. Ibid. Moreover, the FCC has included among the conditions
of the Red Lion license itself the requirement that operation of
the station be carried out in the public interest, 47 U.S.C. §
309(h). This mandate to the FCC to assure that broadcasters operate
in the public interest is a broad one, a power "not niggardly but
expansive," National Broadcasting Co. v. United States, 319 U. S. 190 , 319 U. S. 219 (1943), whose validity we have long upheld. FCC v. Pottsville
Broadcasting Co., 309 U. S. 134 , 309 U. S. 138 (1940); FCC v. RCA Communications, Inc., 346 U. S.
86 , 346 U. S. 90 (1953); FRC v. Nelson Bros. Bond & Mortgage Co., 289 U. S. 266 , 289 U. S. 285 (1933). It is broad enough to encompass these regulations.
The fairness doctrine finds specific recognition in statutory
form, is in part modeled on explicit statutory provisions relating
to political candidates, and is approvingly reflected in
legislative history.
In 1959, the Congress amended the statutory requirement of § 315
that equal time be accorded each political candidate to except
certain appearances on news programs, but added that this
constituted no exception
" from the obligation imposed upon them under this Act to
operate in the public interest and to afford reasonable opportunity
for the discussion of conflicting views on issues of public
importance. "
Act of September 14, 1959, § 1, 73 Stat. 557, amending 47 U.S.C.
§ 315(a) (emphasis added). This language makes it very plain that
Congress, in 1959, announced that the phrase "public interest,"
which had been in the Act since 1927, imposed a duty on
broadcasters to discuss both sides of controversial public issues.
In other words, the amendment vindicated the FCC's general view
that the fairness doctrine inhered in the public interest standard.
Subsequent legislation declaring the intent of an earlier
statute Page 395 U. S. 381 is entitled to great weight in statutory construction. [ Footnote 8 ] And here this principle is
given special force by the equally venerable principle that the
construction of a statute by those charged with its execution
should be followed unless there are compelling indications that it
is wrong, [ Footnote 9 ]
especially when Congress has refused to alter the administrative
construction. [ Footnote 10 ]
Here, the Congress has not just kept its silence by refusing to
overturn the administrative construction, [ Footnote 11 ] but has ratified it with Page 395 U. S. 382 positive legislation. Thirty years of consistent administrative
construction left undisturbed by Congress until 1959, when that
construction was expressly accepted, reinforce the natural
conclusion that the public interest language of the Act authorized
the Commission to require licensees to use their stations for
discussion of public issues, and that the FCC is free to implement
this requirement by reasonable rules and regulations which fall
short of abridgment of the freedom of speech and press, and of the
censorship proscribed by § 326 of the Act. [ Footnote 12 ]
The objectives of § 315 themselves could readily be circumvented
but for the complementary fairness doctrine ratified by § 315. The
section applies only to campaign appearances by candidates, and not
by family, friends, campaign managers, or other supporters. Without
the fairness doctrine, then, a licensee could ban all campaign
appearances by candidates themselves from the air [ Footnote 13 ] and Page 395 U. S. 383 proceed to deliver over his station entirely to the supporters
of one slate of candidates, to the exclusion of all others. In this
way, the broadcaster could have a far greater impact on the favored
candidacy than he could by simply allowing a spot appearance by the
candidate himself. It is the fairness doctrine as an aspect of the
obligation to operate in the public interest, rather than § 315,
which prohibits the broadcaster from taking such a step.
The legislative history reinforces this view of the effect of
the 1959 amendment. Even before the language relevant here was
added, the Senate report on amending § 315 noted that
"broadcast frequencies are limited, and, therefore, they have
been necessarily considered a public trust. Every licensee who is
fortunate in obtaining a license is mandated to operate in the
public interest, and has assumed the obligation of presenting
important public questions fairly and without bias."
S.Rep. No. 562, 86th Cong., 1st Sess., 8-9 (1959). See
also, specifically adverting to Federal Communications
Commission doctrine, id. at 13.
Rather than leave this approval solely in the legislative
history, Senator Proxmire suggested an amendment to make it part of
the Act. 105 Cong.Rec. 14457. This amendment, which Senator
Pastore, a manager of the bill and a ranking member of the Senate
Committee, considered "rather surplusage," 105 Cong.Rec. 14462,
constituted a positive statement of doctrine, [ Footnote 14 ] and was altered Page 395 U. S. 384 to the present merely approving language in the conference
committee. In explaining the language to the Senate after the
committee changes, Senator Pastore said:
"We insisted that that provision remain in the bill, to be a
continuing reminder and admonition to the Federal Communications
Commission and to the broadcasters alike that we were not
abandoning the philosophy that gave birth to section 316, in giving
the people the right to have a full and complete disclosure of
conflicting views on news of interest to the people of the
country."
105 Cong.Rec. 17830. Senator Scott, another Senate manager,
added that: "It is intended to encompass all legitimate areas of
public importance which are controversial," not just politics. 105
Cong.Rec. 17831.
It is true that the personal attack aspect of the fairness
doctrine was not actually adjudicated until after 1959, so that
Congress then did not have those rules specifically before it.
However, the obligation to offer time to reply to a personal attack
was presaged by the FCC's 1949 Report on Editorializing, which the
FCC views as the principal summary of its ratio decidendi in cases in this area:
"In determining whether to honor specific requests for time, the
station will inevitably be confronted with such questions as . . .
whether there may not be other available groups or individuals who
might be more appropriate spokesmen for the particular point of
view than the person making the request. The latter's personal
involvement in the controversy may also be a factor which must be
considered, for elementary considerations of fairness may dictate
that time be allocated to a person or group which has been
specifically attacked over the station, where otherwise no such
obligation would exist."
13 F.C.C. at 1251-1252. Page 395 U. S. 385 When the Congress ratified the FCC's implication of a fairness
doctrine in 1959, it did not, of course, approve every past
decision or pronouncement by the Commission on this subject, or
give it a completely free hand for the future. The statutory
authority does not go so far. But we cannot say that, when a
station publishes personal attacks or endorses political
candidates, it is a misconstruction of the public interest standard
to require the station to offer time for a response, rather than to
leave the response entirely within the control of the station which
has attacked either the candidacies or the men who wish to reply in
their own defense. When a broadcaster grants time to a political
candidate, Congress itself requires that equal time be offered to
his opponents. It would exceed our competence to hold that the
Commission is unauthorized by the statute to employ a similar
device where personal attacks or political editorials are broadcast
by a radio or television station.
In light of the fact that the "public interest" in broadcasting
clearly encompasses the presentation of vigorous debate of
controversial issues of importance and concern to the public, the
fact that the FCC has rested upon that language from its very
inception a doctrine that these issues must be discussed, and
fairly, and the fact that Congress has acknowledged that the
analogous provisions of § 315 are not preclusive in this area, and
knowingly preserved the FCC's complementary efforts, we think the
fairness doctrine and its component personal attack and political
editorializing regulations are a legitimate exercise of
congressionally delegated authority. The Communications Act is not
notable for the precision of its substantive standards, and, in
this respect the explicit provisions of § 315, and the doctrine and
rules at issue here which are closely modeled upon that section,
are far more explicit than the generalized "public interest"
standard in which the Commission ordinarily finds its Page 395 U. S. 386 sole guidance, and which we have held a broad but adequate
standard before. FCC v. RCA Communications, Inc., 346 U. S. 86 , 346 U. S. 90 (1953); National Broadcasting Co. v. United States, 319 U. S. 190 , 319 U. S.
216 -217 (1943); FCC v. Pottsville Broadcasting
Co., 309 U. S. 134 , 309 U. S. 138 (1940); FRC v. Nelson Bros. Bond & Mortgage Co., 289 U. S. 266 , 289 U. S. 285 (1933). We cannot say that the FCC's declaratory ruling in Red
Lion, or the regulations at issue in RTNDA, are
beyond the scope of the congressionally conferred power to assure
that stations are operated by those whose possession of a license
serves "the public interest." III The broadcasters challenge the fairness doctrine and its
specific manifestations in the personal attack and political
editorial rules on conventional First Amendment grounds, alleging
that the rules abridge their freedom of speech and press. Their
contention is that the First Amendment protects their desire to use
their allotted frequencies continuously to broadcast whatever they
choose, and to exclude whomever they choose from ever using that
frequency. No man may be prevented from saying or publishing what
he thinks, or from refusing in his speech or other utterances to
give equal weight to the views of his opponents. This right, they
say, applies equally to broadcasters. A Although broadcasting is clearly a medium affected by a First
Amendment interest, United States v. Paramount Pictures,
Inc., 334 U. S. 131 , 334 U. S. 166 (1948), differences in the characteristics of new media justify
differences in the First Amendment standards applied to them.
[ Footnote 15 ] Joseph Page 395 U. S. 387 Burstyn, Inc. v. Wilson, 343 U.
S. 495 , 343 U. S. 503 (1352). For example, the ability of new technology to produce
sounds more raucous than those of the human voice justifies
restrictions on the sound level, and on the hours and places of
use, of sound trucks so long as the restrictions are reasonable and
applied without discrimination. Kovacs v. Cooper, 336 U. S. 77 (1949).
Just as the Government may limit the use of sound-amplifying
equipment potentially so noisy that it drowns out civilized private
speech, so may the Government limit the use of broadcast equipment.
The right of free speech of a broadcaster, the user of a sound
truck, or any other individual does not embrace a right to snuff
out the free speech of others. Associated Press v. United
States, 326 U. S. 1 , 326 U. S. 20 (1945).
When two people converse face to face, both should not speak at
once if either is to be clearly understood. But the range of the
human voice is so limited that there could be meaningful
communications if half the people in the United States were talking
and the other half listening. Just as clearly, half the people
might publish and the other half read. But the reach of radio
signals is Page 395 U. S. 388 incomparably greater than the range of the human voice, and the
problem of interference is a massive reality. The lack of know-how
and equipment may keep many from the air, but only a tiny fraction
of those with resources and intelligence can hope to communicate by
radio at the same time if intelligible communication is to be had,
even if the entire radio spectrum is utilized in the present state
of commercially acceptable technology.
It was this fact, and the chaos which ensued from permitting
anyone to use any frequency at whatever power level he wished,
which made necessary the enactment of the Radio Act of 1927 and the
Communications Act of 1934, [ Footnote 16 ] as the Court has noted at length before. National Broadcasting Co. v. United States, 319 U.
S. 190 , 319 U. S.
210 -214 (1943). It was this reality which, at the very
least, necessitated first the division of the radio spectrum into
portions reserved respectively for public broadcasting and for
other important radio uses such as amateur operation, aircraft,
police, defense, and navigation, and then the subdivision of each
portion, and assignment of specific frequencies to individual users
or groups of users. Beyond this, however, because the frequencies
reserved for public broadcasting were limited in number, it was
essential for the Government to tell some applicants that they
could not broadcast at all, because there was room for only a
few.
Where there are substantially more individuals who want to
broadcast than there are frequencies to allocate, it is idle to
posit an unabridgeable First Amendment right to broadcast
comparable to the right of every individual to speak, write, or
publish. If 100 persons want broadcast Page 395 U. S. 389 licenses, but there are only 10 frequencies to allocate, all of
them may have the same "right" to a license, but, if there is to be
any effective communication by radio, only a few can be licensed,
and the rest must be barred from the airwaves. It would be strange
if the First Amendment, aimed at protecting and furthering
communications, prevented the Government from making radio
communication possible by requiring licenses to broadcast and by
limiting the number of licenses so as not to overcrowd the
spectrum.
This has been the consistent view of the Court. Congress
unquestionably has the power to grant and deny licenses and to
eliminate existing stations. FRC v. Nelson Bros. Bond &
Mortgage Co., 289 U. S. 266 (1933). No one has a First Amendment right to a license or to
monopolize a radio frequency; to deny a station license because
"the public interest" requires it "is not a denial of free speech." National Broadcasting Co. v. United States, 319 U.
S. 190 , 319 U. S. 227 (1943).
By the same token, as far as the First Amendment is concerned,
those who are licensed stand no better than those to whom licenses
are refused. A license permits broadcasting, but the licensee has
no constitutional right to be the one who holds the license or to
monopolize a radio frequency to the exclusion of his fellow
citizens. There is nothing in the First Amendment which prevents
the Government from requiring a licensee to share his frequency
with others and to conduct himself as a proxy or fiduciary with
obligations to present those views and voices which are
representative of his community and which would otherwise, by
necessity, be barred from the airwaves.
This is not to say that the First Amendment is irrelevant to
public broadcasting. On the contrary, it has a major role to play,
as the Congress itself recognized in § 326, which forbids FCC
interference with "the right Page 395 U. S. 390 of free speech by means of radio communication." Because of the
scarcity of radio frequencies, the Government is permitted to put
restraints on licensees in favor of others whose views should be
expressed on this unique medium. But the people as a whole retain
their interest in free speech by radio and their collective right
to have the medium function consistently with the ends and purposes
of the First Amendment. It is the right of the viewers and
listeners, not the right of the broadcasters, which is paramount. See FCC v. Sanders Bros. Radio Station, 309 U.
S. 470 , 309 U. S. 475 (1940); FCC v. Allentown Broadcasting Corp., 349 U.
S. 358 , 349 U. S.
361 -362 (1955); 2 Z. Chafee, Government and Mass
Communications 546 (1947). It is the purpose of the First Amendment
to preserve an uninhibited marketplace of ideas in which truth will
ultimately prevail, rather than to countenance monopolization of
that market, whether it be by the Government itself or a private
licensee. Associated Press v. United States, 326 U. S.
1 , 326 U. S. 20 (1945); New York Times Co. v. Sullivan, 376 U.
S. 254 , 376 U. S. 270 (1964); Abrams v. United States, 250 U.
S. 616 , 250 U. S. 630 (1919) (Holmes, J., dissenting). "[S]peech concerning public
affairs is more than self-expression; it is the essence of
self-government." Garrison v. Louisiana, 379 U. S.
64 , 379 U. S. 74 -75
(1964). See Brennan, The Supreme Court and the Meiklejohn
Interpretation of the First Amendment, 79 Harv.L.Rev. 1 (1965). It
is the right of the public to receive suitable access to social,
political, esthetic, moral, and other ideas and experiences which
is crucial here. That right may not constitutionally be abridged
either by Congress or by the FCC. B Rather than confer frequency monopolies on a relatively small
number of licensees, in a Nation of 200,000,000, the Government
could surely have decreed that Page 395 U. S. 391 each frequency should be shared among all or some of those who
wish to use it, each being assigned a portion of the broadcast day
or the broadcast week. The ruling and regulations at issue here do
not go quite so far. They assert that, under specified
circumstances, a licensee must offer to make available a reasonable
amount of broadcast time to those who have a view different from
that which has already been expressed on his station. The
expression of a political endorsement, or of a personal attack
while dealing with a controversial public issue, simply triggers
this time-sharing. As we have said, the First Amendment confers no
right on licensees to prevent others from broadcasting on "their"
frequencies, and no right to an unconditional monopoly of a scarce
resource which the Government has denied others the right to
use.
In terms of constitutional principle, and as enforced sharing of
a scarce resource, the personal attack and political editorial
rules are indistinguishable from the equal time provision of § 315,
a specific enactment of Congress requiring stations to set aside
reply time under specified circumstances and to which the fairness
doctrine and these constituent regulations are important
complements. That provision, which has been part of the law since
1927, Radio Act of 1927, § 18, 44 Stat. 1170, has been held valid
by this Court as an obligation of the licensee relieving him of any
power in any way to prevent or censor the broadcast, and thus
insulating him from liability for defamation. The constitutionality
of the statute under the First Amendment was unquestioned.
[ Footnote 17 ] Farmers
Educ. & Coop. Union v. WDAY, 360 U.
S. 525 (1959). Page 395 U. S. 392 Nor can we say that it is inconsistent with the First Amendment
goal of producing an informed public capable of conducting its own
affairs to require a broadcaster to permit answers to personal
attacks occurring in the course of discussing controversial issues,
or to require that the political opponents of those endorsed by the
station be given a chance to communicate with the public. [ Footnote 18 ] Otherwise, station
owners and a few networks would have unfettered power to make time
available only to the highest bidders, to communicate only their
own views on public issues, people and candidates, and to permit on
the air only those with whom they agreed. There is no sanctuary in
the First Amendment for unlimited private censorship operating in a
medium not open to all.
"Freedom of the press from governmental interference under the
First Amendment does not sanction repression of that freedom by
private interests."
" Associated Press v. United States, 326 U. S. 1 , 326 U. S. 20 (1945)." C It is strenuously argued, however, that, if political editorials
or personal attacks will trigger an obligation in broadcasters to
afford the opportunity for expression Page 395 U. S. 393 to speakers who need not pay for time and whose views are
unpalatable to the licensees, then broadcasters will be
irresistibly forced to self-censorship, and their coverage of
controversial public issues will be eliminated, or at least
rendered wholly ineffective. Such a result would indeed be a
serious matter, for, should licensees actually eliminate their
coverage of controversial issues, the purposes of the doctrine
would be stifled.
At this point, however, as the Federal Communications Commission
has indicated, that possibility is, at best, speculative. The
communications industry, and, in particular, the networks, have
taken pains to present controversial issues in the past, and even
now they do not assert that they intend to abandon their efforts in
this regard. [ Footnote 19 ]
It would be better if the FCC's encouragement were never necessary
to induce the broadcasters to meet their responsibility. And if
experience with the administration of these doctrines indicates
that they have the net effect of reducing, rather than enhancing,
the volume and quality of coverage, there will be time enough to
reconsider the constitutional implications. The fairness doctrine
in the past has had no such overall effect.
That this will occur now seems unlikely, however, since, if
present licensees should suddenly prove timorous, the Commission is
not powerless to insist that they give adequate and fair attention
to public issues. Page 395 U. S. 394 It does not violate the First Amendment to treat licensees given
the privilege of using scarce radio frequencies as proxies for the
entire community, obligated to give suitable time and attention to
matters of great public concern. To condition the granting or
renewal of licenses on a willingness to present representative
community views on controversial issues is consistent with the ends
and purposes of those constitutional provisions forbidding the
abridgment of freedom of speech and freedom of the press. Congress
need not stand idly by and permit those with licenses to ignore the
problems which beset the people or to exclude from the airways
anything but their own views of fundamental questions. The statute,
long administrative practice, and cases are to this effect.
Licenses to broadcast do not confer ownership of designated
frequencies, but only the temporary privilege of using them. 47
U.S.C. § 301. Unless renewed, they expire within three years. 47
U.S.C. § 307(d). The statute mandates the issuance of licenses if
the "public convenience, interest, or necessity will be served
thereby." 47 U.S.C. § 307(a). In applying this standard, the
Commission for 40 years has been choosing licensees based in part
on their program proposals. In FRC v. Nelson Bros. Bond &
Mortgage Co., 289 U. S. 266 , 289 U. S. 279 (1933), the Court noted that, in "view of the limited number of
available broadcasting frequencies, the Congress has authorized
allocation and licenses." In determining how best to allocate
frequencies, the Federal Radio Commission considered the needs of
competing communities and the programs offered by competing
stations to meet those needs; moreover, if needs or programs
shifted, the Commission could alter its allocations to reflect
those shifts. Id. at 289 U. S. 285 .
In the same vein, in FCC v. Pottsville Broadcasting Co., 309 U. S. 134 , 309 U. S.
137 -138 (1940), the Court noted that Page 395 U. S. 395 the statutory standard was a supple instrument to effect
congressional desires "to maintain . . . a grip on the dynamic
aspects of radio transmission" and allay fears that, "in the
absence of governmental control, the public interest might be
subordinated to monopolistic domination in the broadcasting field."
Three years later, the Court considered the validity of the
Commission's chain broadcasting regulations, which, among other
things, forbade stations from devoting too much time to network
programs in order that there be suitable opportunity for local
programs serving local needs. The Court upheld the regulations,
unequivocally recognizing that the Commission was more than a
traffic policeman concerned with the technical aspects of
broadcasting and that it neither exceeded its powers under the
statute nor transgressed the First Amendment in interesting itself
in general program format and the kinds of programs broadcast by
licensees. National Broadcasting Co. v. United States, 319 U. S. 190 (1943). D The litigants embellish their First Amendment arguments with the
contention that the regulations are so vague that their duties are
impossible to discern. Of this point it is enough to say that,
judging the validity of the regulations on their face as they are
presented here, we cannot conclude that the FCC has been left a
free hand to vindicate its own idiosyncratic conception of the
public interest or of the requirements of free speech. Past
adjudications by the FCC give added precision to the regulations;
there was nothing vague about the FCC's specific ruling in Red
Lion that Fred Cook should be provided an opportunity to
reply. The regulations at issue in RTNDA could be employed
in precisely the same way as the fairness doctrine was in Red
Lion. Moreover, the FCC itself has recognized that Page 395 U. S. 396 the applicability of its regulations to situations beyond the
scope of past cases may be questionable, 32 Fed.Reg. 10303, 10304
and n. 6, and will not impose sanctions in such cases without
warning. We need not approve every aspect of the fairness doctrine
to decide these cases, and we will not now pass upon the
constitutionality of these regulations by envisioning the most
extreme applications conceivable, United States v.
Sullivan, 332 U. S. 689 , 332 U. S. 694 (1948), but will deal with those problems if and when they
arise.
We need not and do not now ratify every past and future decision
by the FCC with regard to programming. There is no question here of
the Commission's refusal to permit the broadcaster to carry a
particular program or to publish his own views; of a discriminatory
refusal to require the licensee to broadcast certain views which
have been denied access to the airwaves; of government censorship
of a particular program contrary to § 326; or of the official
government view dominating public broadcasting. Such questions
would raise more serious First Amendment issues. But we do hold
that the Congress and the Commission do not violate the First
Amendment when they require a radio or television station to give
reply time to answer personal attacks and political editorials. E It is argued that, even if, at one time, the lack of available
frequencies for all who wished to use them justified the
Government's choice of those who would best serve the public
interest by acting as proxy for those who would present differing
views, or by giving the latter access directly to broadcast
facilities, this condition no longer prevails, so that continuing
control is not justified. To this there are several answers.
Scarcity is not entirely a thing of the past. Advances Page 395 U. S. 397 in technology, such as microwave transmission, have led to more
efficient utilization of the frequency spectrum, but uses for that
spectrum have also gown apace. [ Footnote 20 ] Portions of the spectrum must be reserved
for vital uses unconnected with human communication, such as
radionavigational aids used by aircraft and vessels. Conflicts have
even emerged between such vital functions as defense preparedness
and experimentation in methods of averting mid-air collisions
through radio warning devices. [ Footnote 21 ] "Land mobile services" such as police,
ambulance, fire department, public utility, and other
communications systems have been occupying an increasingly crowded
portion of the frequency spectrum, [ Footnote 22 ] and there are, apart from licensed amateur
radio operators' equipment, 5,000,000 transmitters operated on the
"citizens' band," which is also increasingly congested. [ Footnote 23 ] Among the various uses
for radio frequency space, including marine, Page 395 U. S. 398 aviation, amateur, military, and common carrier users, there are
easily enough claimants to permit use of the whole with an even
smaller allocation to broadcast radio and television uses than now
exists.
Comparative hearings between competing applicants for broadcast
spectrum space are by no means a thing of the past. The radio
spectrum has become so congested that, at times, it has been
necessary to suspend new applications. [ Footnote 24 ] The very high frequency television
spectrum is, in the country's major markets, almost entirely
occupied, although space reserved for ultra high frequency
television transmission, which is a relatively recent development
as a commercially viable alternative, has not yet been completely
filled. [ Footnote 25 ] Page 395 U. S. 399 The rapidity with which technological advances succeed one
another to create more efficient use of spectrum space, on the one
hand, and to create new uses for that space by ever-growing numbers
of people, on the other, makes it unwise to speculate on the future
allocation of that space. It is enough to say that the resource is
one of considerable and growing importance whose scarcity impelled
its regulation by an agency authorized by Congress. Nothing in this
record, or in our own researches, convinces us that the resource is
no longer one for which there are more immediate and potential uses
than can be accommodated, and for which wise planning is essential.
[ Footnote 26 ] This does not
mean, of course, that every possible wavelength must be occupied at
every hour by some vital use in order to sustain the congressional
judgment. The Page 395 U. S. 400 substantial capital investment required for many uses, in
addition to the potentiality for confusion and interference
inherent in any scheme for continuous kaleidoscopic reallocation of
all available space may make this unfeasible. The allocation need
not be made at such a breakneck pace that the objectives of the
allocation are themselves imperiled. [ Footnote 27 ]
Even where there are gaps in spectrum utilization, the fact
remains that existing broadcasters have often attained their
present position because of their initial government selection in
competition with others before new technological advances opened
new opportunities for further uses. Long experience in
broadcasting, confirmed habits of listeners and viewers, network
affiliation, and other advantages in program procurement give
existing broadcasters a substantial advantage over new entrants,
even where new entry is technologically possible. These advantages
are the fruit of a preferred position conferred by the Government.
Some present possibility for new entry by competing stations is not
enough, in itself, to render unconstitutional the Government's
effort to assure that a broadcaster's programming ranges widely
enough to serve the public interest.
In view of the scarcity of broadcast frequencies, the
Government's role in allocating those frequencies, and the
legitimate claims of those unable without governmental assistance
to gain access to those frequencies for expression of their views,
we hold the regulations and Page 395 U. S. 401 ruling at issue here are both authorized by statute and
constitutional. [ Footnote
28 ] The judgment of the Court of Appeals in Red Lion is affirmed and that in RTNDA reversed, and the causes
remanded for proceedings consistent with this opinion. It is so ordered. Not having heard oral argument in these cases, MR. JUSTICE
DOUGLAS took no part in the Court's decision.
* Together with No. 717, United States et al. v. Radio
Television News Directors Assn. et al., on certiorari to the
United States Court of Appeals for the Seventh Circuit, argued
April 3, 1969.
[ Footnote 1 ]
Communications Act of 1934, Tit. III, 48 Stat. 1081, as amended,
47 U.S.C. § 301 et seq. Section 315 now reads:
"315. Candidates for public office; facilities; rules."
"(a) If any licensee shall permit any person who is a legally
qualified candidate for any public office to use a broadcasting
station, he shall afford equal opportunities to all other such
candidates for that office in the use of such broadcasting station: Provided, That such licensee shall have no power of
censorship over the material broadcast under the provisions of this
section. No obligation is imposed upon any licensee to allow the
use of its station by any such candidate. Appearance by a legally
qualified candidate on any --"
"(1) bona fide newscast,"
"(2) bona fide news interview,"
"(3) bona fide news documentary (if the appearance of the
candidate is incidental to the presentation of the subject or
subjects covered by the news documentary), or"
"(4) on-the-spot coverage of bona fide news events (including
but not limited to political conventions and activities incidental
thereto),"
"shall not be deemed to be use of a broadcasting station within
the meaning of this subsection. Nothing in the foregoing sentence
shall be construed as relieving broadcasters, in connection with
the presentation of newscasts, news interviews, news documentaries,
and on-the-spot coverage of news events, from the obligation
imposed upon them under this chapter to operate in the public
interest and to afford reasonable opportunity for the discussion of
conflicting views on issues of public importance."
"(b) The charges made for the use of any broadcasting station
for any of the purposes set forth in this section shall not exceed
the charges made for comparable use of such station for other
purposes."
"(c) The Commission shall prescribe appropriate rules and
regulations to carry out the provisions of this section."
[ Footnote 2 ]
According to the record, Hargis asserted that his broadcast
included the following statement:
"Now, this paperback book by Fred J. Cook is entitled,
'GOLDWATER -- EXTREMIST ON THE RIGHT.' Who is Cook? Cook was fired
from the New York World Telegram after he made a false charge
publicly on television against an unnamed official of the New York
City government. New York publishers and NEWSWEEK Magazine for
December 7, 1959, showed that Fred Cook and his pal, Eugene
Gleason, had made up the whole story, and this confession was made
to New York District Attorney, Frank Hogan. After losing his job,
Cook went to work for the left-wing publication THE NATION, one of
the most scurrilous publications of the left which has championed
many communist causes over many years. Its editor, Carry
McWilliams, has been affiliated with many communist enterprises,
scores of which have been cited as subversive by the Attorney
General of the U.S. or by other government agencies. . . . Now,
among other things Fred Cook wrote for THE NATION was an article
absolving Alger Hiss of any wrongdoing . . . ; there was a 208-page
attack on the FBI and J. Edgar Hoover; another attack by Mr. Cook
was on the Central Intelligence Agency . . . ; now this is the man
who wrote the book to smear and destroy Barry Goldwater called
'Barry Goldwater -- Extremist Of The Right.'"
[ Footnote 3 ]
The Court of Appeals initially dismissed the petition for want
of a reviewable order, later reversing itself en banc upon argument
by the Government that the FCC rule used here, which permits it to
issue "a declaratory ruling terminating a controversy or removing
uncertainty," 47 CFR § 312, was, in fact, justified by the
Administrative Procedure Act. That Act permits an adjudicating
agency, "in its sound discretion, with like effect as in the case
of other orders, to issue a declaratory order to terminate a
controversy or remove uncertainty." § 5, 60 Stat. 239, 5 U.S.C. §
1004(d). In this case, the FCC could have determined the question
of Red Lion's liability to a cease and desist order or license
revocation, 47 U.S.C. § 312, for failure to comply with the
license's condition that the station be operated "in the public
interest," or for failure to obey a requirement of operation in the
public interest implicit in the ability of the FCC to revoke
licenses for conditions justifying the denial of an initial
license, 47 U.S.C. § 312(a)(2), and the statutory requirement that
the public interest be served in granting and renewing licenses, 47
U.S.C. §§ 307(a), (d). Since the FCC could have adjudicated these
questions it could, under the Administrative Procedure Act, have
issued a declaratory order in the course of its adjudication which
would have been subject to judicial review. Although the FCC did
not comply with all of the formalities for an adjudicative
proceeding in this case, the petitioner itself adopted as its own
the Government's position that this was a reviewable order, waiving
any objection it might have had to the procedure of the
adjudication.
[ Footnote 4 ]
Because of this chaos, a series of National Radio Conferences
was held between 1922 and 1925, at which it was resolved that
regulation of the radio spectrum by the Federal Government was
essential, and that regulatory power should be utilized to ensure
that allocation of this limited resource would be made only to
those who would serve the public interest. The 1923 Conference
expressed the opinion that the Radio Communications Act of 1912, 37
Stat. 302, conferred upon the Secretary of Commerce the power to
regulate frequencies and hours of operation, but when Secretary
Hoover sought to implement this claimed power by penalizing the
Zenith Radio Corporation for operating on an unauthorized
frequency, the 1912 Act was held not to permit enforcement. United States v. Zenith Radio Corporation, 12 F.2d 614 (D.C.N.D.Ill.1926). Cf. Hoover v. Intercity Radio Co., 52
App.D.C. 339, 286 F. 1003 (1923) (Secretary had no power to deny
licenses, but was empowered to assign frequencies). An opinion
issued by the Attorney General at Hoover's request confirmed the
impotence of the Secretary under the 1912 Act. 35 Op.Atty.Gen. 126
(1926). Hoover thereafter appealed to the radio industry to
regulate itself, but his appeal went largely unheeded. See
generally L. Schmeckebier, The Federal Radio Commission 1-14
(1932).
[ Footnote 5 ]
Congressman White, a sponsor of the bill enacted as the Radio
Act of 1927, commented upon the need for new legislation:
"We have reached the definite conclusion that the right of all
our people to enjoy this means of communication can be preserved
only by the repudiation of the idea underlying the 1912 law that
anyone who will may transmit and by the assertion in its stead of
the doctrine that the right of the public to service is superior to
the right of any individual. . . . The recent radio conference met
this issue squarely. It recognized that, in the present state of
scientific development, there must be a limitation upon the number
of broadcasting stations, and it recommended that licenses should
be issued only to those stations whose operation would render a
benefit to the public, are necessary in the public interest, or
would contribute to the development of the art. This principle was
approved by every witness before your committee. We have written it
into the bill. If enacted into law, the broadcasting privilege will
not be a right of selfishness. It will rest upon an assurance of
public interest to be served."
67 Cong.Rec. 5479.
[ Footnote 6 ]
Radio Act of 1927, § 4, 44 Stat. 1163. See generally Davis, The Radio Act of 1927, 13 Va.L.Rev. 611 (1927).
[ Footnote 7 ]
As early as 1930, Senator Dill expressed the view that the
Federal Radio Commission had the power to make regulations
requiring a licensee to afford an opportunity for presentation of
the other side on "public questions." Hearings before the Senate
Committee on Interstate Commerce on S. 6, 71st Cong., 2d Sess.,
1616 (1930):
"Senator DILL. Then you are suggesting that the provision of the
statute that now requires a station to give equal opportunity to
candidates for office shall be applied to all public
questions?"
"Commissioner ROBINSON. Of course, I think, in the legal
concept, the law requires it now. I do not see that there is any
need to legislate about it. It will evolve one of these days.
Somebody will go into court and say, 'I am entitled to this
opportunity,' and he will get it."
"Senator DILL. Has the Commission considered the question of
making regulations requiring the stations to do that?"
"Commissioner ROBINSON. Oh, no."
"Senator DILL. It would be within the power of the commission, I
think, to make regulations on that subject."
[ Footnote 8 ] Federal Housing Administration v. Darlington, Inc., 358 U. S. 84 , 358 U. S. 90 (1958); Glidden Co. v. Zdanok, 370 U.
S. 530 , 370 U. S. 541 (1962) (opinion of MR. JUSTICE HARLAN, joined by MR. JUSTICE
BRENNAN and MR. JUSTICE STEWART). This principle is a venerable
one. Alexander v.
Alexandria , 5 Cranch 1 (1809); United
States v. Freeman , 3 How. 556 (1845); Stockdale v. The Insurance
Companies , 20 Wall. 323 (1874).
[ Footnote 9 ] Zemel v. Rusk, 381 U. S. 1 , 381 U. S. 11 -12
(1965); Udall v. Tallman, 380 U. S.
1 , 380 U. S. 16 -18
(1965); Commissioner v. Sternberger's Estate, 348 U.
S. 187 , 348 U. S. 199 (1955); Hastings & D. R. Co. v. Whitney, 132 U.
S. 357 , 132 U. S. 366 (1889); United States v. Burlington & Missouri River R.
Co., 98 U. S. 334 , 98 U. S. 341 (1879); United States v.
Alexander , 12 Wall. 177, 79 U. S.
179 -181 (1871); Surgett v.
Lapice , 8 How. 48, 49 U. S. 68 (1850).
[ Footnote 10 ] Zemel v. Rusk, 381 U. S. 1 , 381 U. S. 11 -12
(1965); United States v. Bergh, 352 U. S.
40 , 352 U. S. 46 -47
(1956); Alstate Construction Co. v. Durkin, 345 U. S.
13 , 345 U. S. 16 -17
(1953); Costanzo v. Tillinghast, 287 U.
S. 341 , 287 U. S. 345 (1932).
[ Footnote 11 ]
An attempt to limit sharply the FCC's power to interfere with
programming practices failed to emerge from Committee in 1943. S.
814, 78th Cong., 1st Sess. (1943). See Hearings on S. 814
before the Senate Committee on Interstate Commerce, 78th Cong., 1st
Sess. (1943). Also, attempts specifically to enact the doctrine
failed in the Radio Act of 1927, 67 Cong.Rec. 12505 (1926)
(agreeing to amendment proposed by Senator Dill eliminating
coverage of "question affecting the public"), and a similar
proposal in the Communications Act of 1934 was accepted by the
Senate, 78 Cong.Rec. 8854 (1934); see S.Rep. No. 781, 73d
Cong., 2d Sess., 8 (1934), but was not included in the bill
reported by the House Committee, see H.R.Rep. No. 1850,
73d Cong., 2d Sess. (1934). The attempt which came nearest success
was a bill, H.R. 7716, 72d Cong., 1st Sess. (1932), passed by
Congress but pocket-vetoed by the President in 1933, which would
have extended "equal opportunities" whenever a public question was
to be voted on at an election or by a government agency. H.R.Rep.
No. 2106, 72d Cong., 2d Sess., 6 (1933). In any event, unsuccessful
attempts at legislation are not the best of guides to legislative
intent. Fogarty v. United States, 340 U. S.
8 , 340 U. S. 13 -14
(1950); United States v. United Mine Workers, 330 U.
S. 258 , 330 U. S.
281 -282 (1947). A review of some of the legislative
history over the years, drawing a somewhat different conclusion, is
found in Staff Study of the House Committee on Interstate and
Foreign Commerce, Legislative History of the Fairness Doctrine,
90th Cong., 2d Sess. (Comm.Print.1968). This inconclusive history
was, of course, superseded by the specific statutory language added
in 1959.
[ Footnote 12 ]
"§ 326. Censorship."
"Nothing in this chapter shall be understood or construed to
give the Commission the power of censorship over the radio
communications or signals transmitted by any radio station, and no
regulation or condition shall be promulgated or fixed by the
Commission which shall interfere with the right of free speech by
means of radio communication."
[ Footnote 13 ]
John P. Crommelin, 19 P & F Radio Reg. 1392 (1960).
[ Footnote 14 ]
The Proxmire amendment read:
"[B]ut nothing in this sentence shall be construed as changing
the basic intent of Congress with respect to the provisions of this
act, which recognizes that television and radio frequencies are in
the public domain, that the license to operate in such frequencies
requires operation in the public interest, and that, in newscasts,
news interviews, news documentaries, on-the-spot coverage of news
events, and panel discussions, all sides of public controversies
shall be given as equal an opportunity to be heard as is
practically possible."
105 Cong.Rec. 14457.
[ Footnote 15 ]
The general problems raised by a technology which supplants
atomized, relatively informal communication with mass media as a
prime source of national cohesion and news were discussed at
considerable length by Zechariah Chafee in Government and Mass
Communications (1947). Debate on the particular implications of
this view for the broadcasting industry has continued unabated. A
compendium of views appears in Freedom and Responsibility in
Broadcasting (J. Coons ed.) (1961). See also Kalven,
Broadcasting, Public Policy and the First Amendment, 10 J.Law &
Econ. 15 (1967); M. Ernst, The First Freedom 125-180 (1946); T.
Robinson, Radio Networks and the Federal Government, especially at
75-87 (1943). The considerations which the newest technology brings
to bear on the particular problem of this litigation are concisely
explored by Louis Jaffe in The Fairness Doctrine, Equal Time, Reply
to Personal Attacks, and the Local Service Obligation; Implications
of Technological Change, Printed for Special Subcommittee on
Investigations of the House Committee on Interstate and Foreign
Commerce (1968).
[ Footnote 16 ]
The range of controls which have in fact, been imposed over the
last 40 years, without giving rise to successful constitutional
challenge in this Court, is discussed in W. Emery, Broadcasting and
Government: Responsibilities and Regulations (1961); Note,
Regulation of Program Content by the FCC, 77 Harv.L.Rev. 701
(1964).
[ Footnote 17 ]
This has not prevented vigorous argument from developing on the
constitutionality of the ancillary FCC doctrines. Compare Barrow, The Equal Opportunities and Fairness Doctrines in
Broadcasting: Pillars in the Forum of Democracy, 37 U.Cin.L.Rev.
447 (1968), with Rohinson, The FCC and the First
Amendment: Observations on 40 Years of Radio and Television
Regulation, 52 Minn.L.Rev. 67 (1967), and Sullivan, Editorials and
Controversy: The Broadcaster's Dilemma, 32 Geo.Wash.L.Rev. 719
(1964).
[ Footnote 18 ]
The expression of views opposing those which broadcasters permit
to be aired in the first place need not be confined solely to the
broadcasters themselves as proxies.
"Nor is it enough that he should hear the arguments of
adversaries from his own teachers, presented as they state them,
and accompanied by what they offer as refutations. That is not the
way to do justice to the arguments, or bring them into real contact
with his own mind. He must be able to hear them from persons who
actually believe them; who defend them in earnest, and do their
very utmost for them."
J. Mill, On Liberty 32 (R. McCallum ed.1947).
[ Footnote 19 ]
The President of the Columbia Broadcasting System has recently
declared that, despite the Government,
"we are determined to continue covering controversial issues as
a public service, and exercising our own independent news judgment
and enterprise. I, for one, refuse to allow that judgment and
enterprise to be affected by official intimidation."
F. Stanton, Keynote Address, Sigma Delta Chi National
Convention, Atlanta, Georgia, November 21, 1968. Problems of news
coverage from the broadcaster's viewpoint are surveyed in W. Wood,
Electronic Journalism (1967).
[ Footnote 20 ]
Current discussions of the frequency allocation problem appear
in Telecommunication Science Panel, Commerce Technical Advisory
Board, U.S. Dept. of Commerce, Electromagnetic Spectrum Utilization
-- The Silent Crisis (1966); Joint Technical Advisory Committee,
Institute of Electrical and Electronics Engineers and Electronic
Industries Assn., Report on Radio Spectrum Utilization (1964);
Note, The Crisis in Electromagnetic Frequency Spectrum Allocation,
53 Iowa L.Rev. 437 (1967). A recently released study is the Final
Report of the President's Task Force on Communications Policy
(1968).
[ Footnote 21 ] Bendix Aviation Corp. v. FCC, 106 U.S.App.D.C. 304, 272
F.2d 533 (1959), cert. denied, 361 U.S. 965 (1960).
[ Footnote 22 ]
1968 FCC Annual Report 65-69.
[ Footnote 23 ]
New limitations on these users, who can also lay claim to First
Amendment protection, were sustained against First Amendment attack
with the comment, "Here is truly a situation where, if everybody
could say anything, many could say nothing." Lafayette Radio
Electronics Corp. v. United States, 345 F.2d 278, 281 (1965). Accord, California Citizens Band Assn. v. United States, 375 F.2d 43 (C.A. 9th Cir.), cert. denied, 389 U.S. 844
(1967).
[ Footnote 24 ] Kessler v. FCC, 117 U.S. App.D.C. 130, 326 F.2d 673
(1963).
[ Footnote 25 ]
In a table prepared by the FCC on the basis of statistics
current as of August 31, 1968, VHF and UHF channels allocated to
and those available in the top 100 market areas for television are
set forth:
COMMERCIAL
Channels
On the Air,
Channels Authorized, or Available
Market Areas Allocated Applied for Channels
VHF UHF VHF UHF VHF UHF
Top 10. . . . . . 40 45 40 44 0 1
Top 50. . . . . . 157 163 157 136 0 27
Top 100 . . . . . 264 297 264 213 0 84
NONCOMMERCIAL
Channels
On the Air,
Channels Authorized, or Available
Market Areas Allocated Applied for Channels
VHF UHF VHF UHF VHF UHF
Top 10. . . . . . 7 17 7 16 0 1
Top 50. . . . . . 21 79 20 47 1 32
Top 100 . . . . . 35 138 34 69 1 69
1968 FCC Annual Report 132-135.
[ Footnote 26 ] RTNDA argues that these regulations should be held
invalid for failure of the FCC to make specific findings in the
rulemaking proceeding relating to these factual questions.
Presumably the fairness doctrine and the personal attack decisions
themselves, such as Red Lion, should fall for the same
reason. But this argument ignores the fact that these regulations
are no more than the detailed specification of certain consequences
of longstanding rules, the need for which was recognized by the
Congress on the factual predicate of scarcity made plain in 1927,
recognized by this Court in the 1943 National Broadcasting
Co. case, and reaffirmed by the Congress as recently as
1959.
"If the number of radio and television stations were not limited
by available frequencies, the committee would have no hesitation in
removing completely the present provision regarding equal time and
urge the right of each broadcaster to follow his own conscience. .
. . However, broadcast frequencies are limited, and, therefore,
they have been necessarily considered a public trust."
S.Rep. No. 562, 86th Cong., 1st Sess., 8-9 (1959). In light of
this history; the opportunity which the broadcasters have had to
address the FCC and show that somehow the situation had radically
changed, undercutting the validity of the congressional judgment,
and their failure to adduce any convincing evidence of that, in the
record here, we cannot consider the absence of more detailed
findings below to be determinative.
[ Footnote 27 ]
The "airwaves [need not] be filled at the earliest possible
moment in all circumstances without due regard for these important
factors." Community Broadcasting Co. v. FCC, 107
U.S.App.D.C. 95, 105, 274 F.2d 753, 763 (1960). Accord, enforcing the fairness doctrine, Office of Communication of the
United Church of Christ v. FCC, 123 U.S.App.D.C. 328, 343, 359
F.2d 994, 1009 (1966).
[ Footnote 28 ]
We need not deal with the argument that, even if there is no
longer a technological scarcity of frequencies limiting the number
of broadcasters, there nevertheless is an economic scarcity in the
sense that the Commission could or does limit entry to the
broadcasting market on economic grounds and license no more
stations than the market will support. Hence, it is said, the
fairness doctrine or its equivalent is essential to satisfy the
claims of those excluded and of the public generally. A related
argument, which we also put aside, is that, quite apart from
scarcity of frequencies, technological or economic, Congress does
not abridge freedom of speech or press by legislation directly or
indirectly multiplying the voices and views presented to the public
through time sharing, fairness doctrines, or other devices which
limit or dissipate the power of those who sit astride the channels
of communication with the general public. Cf. Citizen
Publishing Co. v. United States, 394 U.
S. 131 (1969). | In Red Lion Broadcasting Co., Inc. v. FCC, the Supreme Court upheld the Federal Communications Commission's (FCC) "fairness doctrine," which required broadcasters to present public issues fairly and give airtime to opposing views. The case centered around a broadcaster's obligation under the doctrine when they aired a personal attack. The Court ruled that the FCC's actions were within its authority and implemented congressional policy. The Court also rejected First Amendment challenges to the doctrine, prioritizing the public's right to diverse viewpoints over broadcasters' rights. The scarcity of broadcast frequencies was cited as a key factor in the decision. |
Free Speech | Cohen v. California | https://supreme.justia.com/cases/federal/us/403/15/ | U.S. Supreme Court Cohen v. California, 403 U.S.
15 (1971) Cohen v. California No. 299 Argued February 22,
1971 Decided June 7, 1971 403 U.S.
15 APPEAL FROM THE COURT OF APPEAL OF
CALIFORNIA, SECOND APPELLATE
DISTRICT Syllabus Appellant was convicted of violating that part of Cal.Penal Code
§ 415 which prohibits "maliciously and willfully disturb[ing] the
peace or quiet of any neighborhood or person . . . by . . .
offensive conduct," for wearing a jacket bearing the words "Fuck
the Draft" in a corridor of the Los Angeles Courthouse. The Court
of Appeal held that "offensive conduct" means "behavior which has a
tendency to provoke others to acts of violence or to in
turn disturb the peace," and affirmed the conviction. Held: Absent a more particularized and compelling
reason for its actions, the State may not, consistently with the
First and Fourteenth Amendments, make the simple public display of
this single four-letter expletive a criminal offense. Pp. 403 U. S.
22 -26. 1 Cal. App. 3d
94 , 81 Cal. Rptr.
503 , reversed.
HARLAN, J., delivered the opinion of the Court, in which
DOUGLAS, BRENNAN, STEWART, and MARSHALL, JJ., joined. BLACKMUN, J.,
filed a dissenting opinion, in which BURGER, C.J., and BLACK, J.,
joined, and in which WHITE, J., joined in part, post, p. 403 U. S.
27 .
MR. JUSTICE HARLAN delivered the opinion of the Court.
This case may seem at first blush too inconsequential to find
its way into our books, but the issue it presents is of no small
constitutional significance. Page 403 U. S. 16 Appellant Paul Robert Cohen was convicted in the Los Angeles
Municipal Court of violating that part of California Penal Code §
415 which prohibits "maliciously and willfully disturb[ing] the
peace or quiet of any neighborhood or person . . . by . . .
offensive conduct. . . ." [ Footnote
1 ] He was given 30 days' imprisonment. The facts upon which his
conviction rests are detailed in the opinion of the Court of Appeal
of California, Second Appellate District, as follows:
"On April 26, 1968, the defendant was observed in the Los
Angeles County Courthouse in the corridor outside of division 20 of
the municipal court wearing a jacket bearing the words 'Fuck the
Draft' which were plainly visible. There were women and children
present in the corridor. The defendant was arrested. The defendant
testified that he wore the jacket knowing that the words were on
the jacket as a means of informing the public of the depth of his
feelings against the Vietnam War and the draft."
"The defendant did not engage in, nor threaten to engage in, nor
did anyone as the result of his conduct Page 403 U. S. 17 in fact commit or threaten to commit any act of violence. The
defendant did not make any loud or unusual noise, nor was there any
evidence that he uttered any sound prior to his arrest." 1 Cal. App. 3d
94 , 97-98, 81 Cal. Rptr.
503 , 505 (1969).
In affirming the conviction, the Court of Appeal held that
"offensive conduct" means "behavior which has a tendency to provoke others to acts of violence or to in turn disturb the
peace," and that the State had proved this element because, on the
facts of this case,
"[i]t was certainly reasonably foreseeable that such conduct
might cause others to rise up to commit a violent act against the
person of the defendant or attempt to forcibly remove his
jacket."
1 Cal. App. 3d at 99-100, 81 Cal. Rptr. at 506. The California
Supreme Court declined review by a divided vote. [ Footnote 2 ] We brought the case here,
postponing the consideration of the question of our jurisdiction
over this appeal to a hearing of the case on the merits. 399 U.S.
904. We now reverse.
The question of our jurisdiction need not detain us long.
Throughout the proceedings below, Cohen consistently Page 403 U. S. 18 claimed that, as construed to apply to the facts of this case,
the statute infringed his rights to freedom of expression
guaranteed by the First and Fourteenth Amendments of the Federal
Constitution. That contention has been rejected by the highest
California state court in which review could be had. Accordingly,
we are fully satisfied that Cohen has properly invoked our
jurisdiction by this appeal. 28 U.S.C. § 1257(2); Dahnke-Walker
Milling Co. v. Bondurant, 257 U. S. 282 (1921). I In order to lay hands on the precise issue which this case
involves, it is useful first to canvass various matters which this
record does not present.
The conviction quite clearly rests upon the asserted
offensiveness of the words Cohen used to convey his message to the
public. The only "conduct" which the State sought to punish is the
fact of communication. Thus, we deal here with a conviction resting
solely upon "speech," cf. Stromberg v. California, 283 U. S. 359 (1931), not upon any separately identifiable conduct which
allegedly was intended by Cohen to be perceived by others as
expressive of particular views but which, on its face, does not
necessarily convey any message, and hence arguably could be
regulated without effectively repressing Cohen's ability to express
himself. Cf. United States v. O'Brien, 391 U.
S. 367 (1968). Further, the State certainly lacks power
to punish Cohen for the underlying content of the message the
inscription conveyed. At least so long as there is no showing of an
intent to incite disobedience to or disruption of the draft, Cohen
could not, consistently with the First and Fourteenth Amendments,
be punished for asserting the evident position on the inutility or
immorality of the draft his jacket reflected. Yates v. United
States, 354 U. S. 298 (1957). Page 403 U. S. 19 Appellant's conviction, then, rests squarely upon his exercise
of the "freedom of speech" protected from arbitrary governmental
interference by the Constitution, and can be justified, if at all,
only as a valid regulation of the manner in which he exercised that
freedom, not as a permissible prohibition on the substantive
message it conveys. This does not end the inquiry, of course, for
the First and Fourteenth Amendments have never been thought to give
absolute protection to every individual to speak whenever or
wherever he pleases, or to use any form of address in any
circumstances that he chooses. In this vein, too, however, we think
it important to note that several issues typically associated with
such problems are not presented here.
In the first place, Cohen was tried under a statute applicable
throughout the entire State. Any attempt to support this conviction
on the ground that the statute seeks to preserve an appropriately
decorous atmosphere in the courthouse where Cohen was arrested must
fail in the absence of any language in the statute that would have
put appellant on notice that certain kinds of otherwise permissible
speech or conduct would nevertheless, under California law, not be
tolerated in certain places. See Edwards v. South
Carolina, 372 U. S. 229 , 372 U. S.
236 -237, and n. 11 (1963). Cf. Adderley v.
Florida, 385 U. S. 39 (1966). No fair reading of the phrase "offensive conduct" can be
said sufficiently to inform the ordinary person that distinctions
between certain locations are thereby created. [ Footnote 3 ]
In the second place, as it comes to us, this case cannot be said
to fall within those relatively few categories of Page 403 U. S. 20 instances where prior decisions have established the power of
government to deal more comprehensively with certain forms of
individual expression simply upon a showing that such a form was
employed. This is not, for example, an obscenity case. Whatever
else may be necessary to give rise to the States' broader power to
prohibit obscene expression, such expression must be, in some
significant way, erotic. Roth v. United States, 354 U. S. 476 (1957). It cannot plausibly be maintained that this vulgar allusion
to the Selective Service System would conjure up such psychic
stimulation in anyone likely to be confronted with Cohen's crudely
defaced jacket.
This Court has also held that the States are free to ban the
simple use, without a demonstration of additional justifying
circumstances, of so-called "fighting words," those personally
abusive epithets which, when addressed to the ordinary citizen,
are, as a matter of common knowledge, inherently likely to provoke
violent reaction. Chaplinsky v. New Hampshire, 315 U. S. 568 (1942). While the four-letter word displayed by Cohen in relation
to the draft is not uncommonly employed in a personally provocative
fashion, in this instance it was clearly not "directed to the
person of the hearer." Cantwell v. Connecticut, 310 U. S. 296 , 310 U. S. 309 (1940). No individual actually or likely to be present could
reasonably have regarded the words on appellant's jacket as a
direct personal insult. Nor do we have here an instance of the
exercise of the State's police power to prevent a speaker from
intentionally provoking a given group to hostile reaction. Cf.
Feiner v. New York, 340 U. S. 315 (1951); Termniello v. Chicago, 337 U. S.
1 (1949). There is, as noted above, no showing that
anyone who saw Cohen was, in fact, violently aroused, or that
appellant intended such a result. Page 403 U. S. 21 Finally, in arguments before this Court, much has been made of
the claim that Cohen's distasteful mode of expression was thrust
upon unwilling or unsuspecting viewers, and that the State might
therefore legitimately act as it did in order to protect the
sensitive from otherwise unavoidable exposure to appellant's crude
form of protest. Of course, the mere presumed presence of unwitting
listeners or viewers does not serve automatically to justify
curtailing all speech capable of giving offense. See, e.g.,
Organization for a Better Austin v. Keefe, 402 U.
S. 415 (1971). While this Court has recognized that
government may properly act in many situations to prohibit
intrusion into the privacy of the home of unwelcome views and ideas
which cannot be totally banned from the public dialogue, e.g.,
Rowan v. Post Office Dept., 397 U. S. 728 (1970), we have at the same time consistently stressed that "we are
often captives' outside the sanctuary of the home and subject
to objectionable speech." Id. at 397 U. S. 738 .
The ability of government, consonant with the Constitution, to shut
off discourse solely to protect others from hearing it is, in other
words, dependent upon a showing that substantial privacy interests
are being invaded in an essentially intolerable manner. Any broader
view of this authority would effectively empower a majority to
silence dissidents simply as a matter of personal
predilections. In this regard, persons confronted with Cohen's jacket were in a
quite different posture than, say, those subjected to the raucous
emissions of sound trucks blaring outside their residences. Those
in the Los Angeles courthouse could effectively avoid further
bombardment of their sensibilities simply by averting their eyes.
And, while it may be that one has a more substantial claim to a
recognizable privacy interest when walking through a courthouse
corridor than, for example, strolling through Central Park, surely
it is nothing like the interest in Page 403 U. S. 22 being free from unwanted expression in the confines of one's own
home. Cf. Keefe, supra. Given the subtlety and complexity
of the factors involved, if Cohen's "speech" was otherwise entitled
to constitutional protection, we do not think the fact that some
unwilling "listeners" in a public building may have been briefly
exposed to it can serve to justify this breach of the peace
conviction where, as here, there was no evidence that persons
powerless to avoid appellant's conduct did in fact, object to it,
and where that portion of the statute upon which Cohen's conviction
rests evinces no concern, either on its face or as construed by the
California courts, with the special plight of the captive auditor,
but, instead, indiscriminately sweeps within its prohibitions all
"offensive conduct" that disturbs "any neighborhood or person." Cf. Edwards v. South Carolina, supra. [ Footnote 4 ] II Against this background, the issue flushed by this case stands
out in bold relief. It is whether California can excise, as
"offensive conduct," one particular scurrilous epithet from the
public discourse, either upon the theory of the court below that
its use is inherently likely to cause violent reaction or upon a
more general assertion that the States, acting as guardians of
public morality, Page 403 U. S. 23 may properly remove this offensive word from the public
vocabulary.
The rationale of the California court is plainly untenable. At
most, it reflects an "undifferentiated fear or apprehension of
disturbance [which] is not enough to overcome the right to freedom
of expression." Tinker v. Des Moines Indep. Community School
Dist., 393 U. S. 503 , 393 U. S. 508 (1969). We have been shown no evidence that substantial numbers of
citizens are standing ready to strike out physically at whoever may
assault their sensibilities with execrations like that uttered by
Cohen. There may be some persons about with such lawless and
violent proclivities, but that is an insufficient base upon which
to erect, consistently with constitutional values, a governmental
power to force persons who wish to ventilate their dissident views
into avoiding particular forms of expression. The argument amounts
to little more than the self-defeating proposition that, to avoid
physical censorship of one who has not sought to provoke such a
response by a hypothetical coterie of the violent and lawless, the
States may more appropriately effectuate that censorship
themselves. Cf. Ashton v. Kentucky, 384 U.
S. 195 , 384 U. S. 200 (1966); Cox v. Louisiana, 379 U.
S. 536 , 379 U. S.
550 -551 (1965).
Admittedly, it is not so obvious that the First and Fourteenth
Amendments must be taken to disable the States from punishing
public utterance of this unseemly expletive in order to maintain
what they regard as a suitable level of discourse within the body
politic. [ Footnote 5 ] We Page 403 U. S. 24 think, however, that examination and reflection will reveal the
shortcomings of a contrary viewpoint.
At the outset, we cannot overemphasize that, in our judgment,
most situations where the State has a justifiable interest in
regulating speech will fall within one or more of the various
established exceptions, discussed above but not applicable here, to
the usual rule that governmental bodies may not prescribe the form
or content of individual expression. Equally important to our
conclusion is the constitutional backdrop against which our
decision must be made. The constitutional right of free expression
is powerful medicine in a society as diverse and populous a ours.
It is designed and intended to remove governmental restraints from
the arena of public discussion, putting the decision as to what
views shall be voiced largely into the hands of each of us, in the
hope that use of such freedom will ultimately produce a more
capable citizenry and more perfect polity and in the belief that no
other approach would comport with the premise of individual dignity
and choice upon which our political system rests. See Whitney
v. California, 274 U. S. 357 , 274 U. S.
375 -377 (1927) (Brandeis, J., concurring).
To many, the immediate consequence of this freedom may often
appear to be only verbal tumult, discord, and Page 403 U. S. 25 even offensive utterance. These are, however, within established
limits, in truth necessary side effects of the broader enduring
values which the process of open debate permits us to achieve. That
the air may at times seem filled with verbal cacophony is, in this
sense not a sign of weakness but of strength. We cannot lose sight
of the fact that, in what otherwise might seem a trifling and
annoying instance of individual distasteful abuse of a privilege,
these fundamental societal values are truly implicated. That is why
"[w]holly neutral futilities . . . come under the protection of
free speech as fully as do Keats' poems or Donne's sermons," Winters v. New York, 333 U. S. 507 , 333 U. S. 528 (1948) (Frankfurter, J., dissenting), and why, "so long as the
means are peaceful, the communication need not meet standards of
acceptability," Organization for a Better Austin v. Keefe, 402 U. S. 415 , 402 U. S. 419 (1971).
Against this perception of the constitutional policies involved,
we discern certain more particularized considerations that
peculiarly call for reversal of this conviction. First, the
principle contended for by the State seems inherently boundless.
How is one to distinguish this from any other offensive word?
Surely the State has no right to cleanse public debate to the point
where it is grammatically palatable to the most squeamish among us.
Yet no readily ascertainable general principle exists for stopping
short of that result were we to affirm the judgment below. For,
while the particular four-letter word being litigated here is
perhaps more distasteful than most others of its genre, it is
nevertheless often true that one man's vulgarity is another's
lyric. Indeed, we think it is largely because governmental
officials cannot make principled distinctions in this area that the
Constitution leaves matters of taste and style so largely to the
individual.
Additionally, we cannot overlook the fact, because it Page 403 U. S. 26 is well illustrated by the episode involved here, that much
linguistic expression serves a dual communicative function: it
conveys not only ideas capable of relatively precise, detached
explication, but otherwise inexpressible emotions as well. In fact,
words are often chosen as much for their emotive as their cognitive
force. We cannot sanction the view that the Constitution, while
solicitous of the cognitive content of individual speech, has
little or no regard for that emotive function which, practically
speaking, may often be the more important element of the overall
message sought to be communicated. Indeed, as Mr. Justice
Frankfurter has said,
"[o]ne of the prerogatives of American citizenship is the right
to criticize public men and measures -- and that means not only
informed and responsible criticism, but the freedom to speak
foolishly and without moderation." Baumgartner v. United States, 322 U.
S. 665 , 322 U. S.
673 -674 (1944).
Finally, and in the same vein, we cannot indulge the facile
assumption that one can forbid particular words without also
running a substantial risk of suppressing ideas in the process.
Indeed, governments might soon seize upon the censorship of
particular words as a convenient guise for banning the expression
of unpopular views. We have been able, as noted above, to discern
little social benefit that might result from running the risk of
opening the door to such grave results.
It is, in sum, our judgment that, absent a more particularized
and compelling reason for its actions, the State may not,
consistently with the First and Fourteenth Amendments, make the
simple public display here involved of this single four-letter
expletive a criminal offense. Because that is the only arguably
sustainable rationale for the conviction here at issue, the
judgment below must be Reversed. Page 403 U. S. 27 [ Footnote 1 ]
The statute provides in full:
"Every person who maliciously and willfully disturbs the peace
or quiet of any neighborhood or person, by loud or unusual noise,
or by tumultuous or offensive conduct, or threatening, traducing,
quarreling, challenging to fight, or fighting, or who, on the
public streets of any unincorporated town, or upon the public
highways in such unincorporated town, run any horse race, either
for a wager or for amusement, or fire any gun or pistol in such
unincorporated town, or use any vulgar, profane, or indecent
language within the presence or hearing of women or children, in a
loud and boisterous manner, is guilty of a misdemeanor, and upon
conviction by any Court of competent jurisdiction shall be punished
by fine not exceeding two hundred dollars, or by imprisonment in
the County Jail for not more than ninety days, or by both fine and
imprisonment, or either, at the discretion of the Court."
[ Footnote 2 ]
The suggestion has been made that, in light of the supervening
opinion of the California Supreme Court in In re
Bushman, 1 Cal. 3d 767 ,
463 P.2d 727 (1970), it is "not at all certain that the California
Court of Appeal's construction of § 415 is now the authoritative
California construction." Post at 403 U. S. 27 (BLACKMUN, J., dissenting). In the course of the Bushman opinion, Chief Justice Traynor stated:
"[One] may . . . be guilty of disturbing the peace through
'offensive' conduct [within the meaning of § 415] if, by his
actions, he willfully and maliciously incites others to violence or
engages in conduct likely to incite others to violence. ( People
v. Cohen (1969) 1 Cal. App. 3d
94 , 101, [ 81 Cal. Rptr.
503 ].)"
1 Cal. 3d at 773, 463 P.2d at 730.
We perceive no difference of substance between the Bushman construction and that of the Court of Appeal,
particularly in light of the Bushman court's approving
citation of Cohen. [ Footnote 3 ]
It is illuminating to note what transpired when Cohen entered a
courtroom in the building. He removed his jacket and stood with it
folded over his arm. Meanwhile, a policeman sent the presiding
judge a note suggesting that Cohen be held in contempt of court.
The judge declined to do so, and Cohen was arrested by the officer
only after he emerged from the courtroom. App. 119.
[ Footnote 4 ]
In fact, other portions of the same statute do make some such
distinctions. For example, the statute also prohibits disturbing
"the peace or quiet . . . by loud or unusual noise" and using
"vulgar, profane, or indecent language within the presence or
hearing of women or children, in a loud and boisterous manner." See n 1, supra. This second-quoted provision in particular serves
to put the actor on much fairer notice as to what is prohibited. It
also buttresses our view that the "offensive conduct" portion, as
construed and applied in this case, cannot legitimately be
justified in this Court as designed or intended to make fine
distinctions between differently situated recipients.
[ Footnote 5 ]
The amicus urges, with some force, that this issue is
not properly before us, since the statute, as construed, punishes
only conduct that might cause others to react violently. However,
because the opinion below appears to erect a virtually irrebuttable
presumption that use of this word will produce such results, the
statute, as thus construed, appears to impose, in effect, a flat
ban on the public utterance of this word. With the case in this
posture, it does not seem inappropriate to inquire whether any
other rationale might properly support this result. While we think
it clear, for the reasons expressed above, that no statute which
merely proscribes "offensive conduct" and has been construed as
broadly as this one was below can subsequently be justified in this
Court as discriminating between conduct that occurs in different
places or that offends only certain persons, it is not so
unreasonable to seek to justify its full broad sweep on an
alternate rationale such as this. Because it is not so patently
clear that acceptance of the justification presently under
consideration would render the statute overbroad or
unconstitutionally vague, and be cause the answer to appellee's
argument seems quite clear, we do not pass on the contention that
this claim is not presented on this record.
MR. JUSTICE BLACKMUN, with whom THE CHIEF JUSTICE and MR.
JUSTICE BLACK join.
I dissent, and I do so for two reasons:
1. Cohen's absurd and immature antic, in my view, was mainly
conduct, and little speech. See Street v. New York, 394 U. S. 576 (1969); Cox v. Louisiana, 379 U.
S. 536 , 379 U. S. 555 (1965); Giboney v. Empire Storage Co., 336 U.
S. 490 , 336 U. S. 502 (1949). The California Court of Appeal appears so to have described
it, 1 Cal. App. 3d
94 , 100, 81 Cal. Rptr.
503 , 507, and I cannot characterize it otherwise. Further, the
case appears to me to be well within the sphere of Chaplinsky
v. New Hampshire, 315 U. S. 568 (1942), where Mr. Justice Murphy, a known champion of First
Amendment freedoms, wrote for a unanimous bench. As a consequence,
this Court's agonizing over First Amendment values seems misplaced
and unnecessary.
2. I am not at all certain that the California Court of Appeal's
construction of § 415 is now the authoritative California
construction. The Court of Appeal filed its opinion on October 22,
1969. The Supreme Court of California declined review by a
four-to-three vote on December 17. See 1 Cal. App. 3d at
104. A month later, on January 27, 1970, the State Supreme Court,
in another case, construed § 415, evidently for the first time. In re Bushman, 1 Cal. 3d 767 ,
463 P.2d 727. Chief Justice Traynor, who was among the dissenters
to his court's refusal to take Cohen's case, wrote the majority
opinion. He held that § 415 "is not unconstitutionally vague and
overbroad," and further said:
"[T]hat part of Penal Code section 415 in question here makes
punishable only willful and malicious conduct that is violent and
endangers public safety and order or that creates a clear and
present danger that others will engage in violence of that nature.
" Page 403 U. S. 28 ". . . [It] does not make criminal any nonviolent act unless the
act incites or threatens to incite others to violence. . . ."
1 Cal. 3d at 773-774, 463 P.2d at 731. Cohen was cited
in Bushman, 1 Cal. 3d at 773, 463 P.2d at 730, but I am
not convinced that its description there and Cohen itself
are completely consistent with the "clear and present danger"
standard enunciated in Bushman. Inasmuch as this Court
does not dismiss this case, it ought to be remanded to the
California Court of Appeal for reconsideration in the light of the
subsequently rendered decision by the State's highest tribunal in Bushman. MR. JUSTICE WHITE concurs in Paragraph 2 of MR. JUSTICE
BLACKMUN's dissenting opinion. | The Supreme Court ruled in favor of Cohen, arguing that the state could not criminalize the public display of a jacket with the phrase "Fuck the Draft" without violating the First and Fourteenth Amendments. Justice Harlan, delivering the opinion of the Court, acknowledged the case's seemingly trivial nature but emphasized its significant constitutional implications. Cohen's conviction under the California Penal Code for disturbing the peace with offensive conduct was overturned, as his actions did not incite violence or pose a clear and present danger. Justice Blackmun, in dissent, viewed Cohen's actions as primarily conduct rather than speech and believed the case fell within the scope of Chaplinsky v. New Hampshire, upholding similar laws. He also questioned the consistency between the Court of Appeal's interpretation of the law and the subsequent ruling by the California Supreme Court in In re Bushman. |
Free Speech | New York v. Ferber | https://supreme.justia.com/cases/federal/us/458/747/ | U.S. Supreme Court New York v. Ferber, 458
U.S. 747 (1982) New York v. Ferber No. 81-55 Argued April 27, 1982 Decided July 2, 1982 458
U.S. 747 CERTIORARI TO THE COURT OF APPEALS
OF NEW YORK Syllabus A New York statute prohibits persons from knowingly promoting a
sexual performance by a child under the age of 16 by distributing
material which depicts such a performance. The statute defines
"sexual performance" as any performance that includes sexual
conduct by such a child, and "sexual conduct" is in turn defined as
actual or simulated sexual intercourse, deviate sexual intercourse,
sexual bestiality, masturbation, sado-masochistic abuse, or lewd
exhibition of the genitals. Respondent bookstore proprietor was
convicted under the statute for selling films depicting young boys
masturbating, and the Appellate Division of the New York Supreme
Court affirmed. The New York Court of Appeals reversed, holding
that the statute violated the First Amendment as being both
underinclusive and overbroad. The court reasoned that, in light of
the explicit inclusion of an obscenity standard in a companion
statute banning the knowing dissemination of similarly defined
material, the statute in question could not be construed to include
an obscenity standard, and therefore would prohibit the promotion
of materials traditionally entitled to protection under the First
Amendment. Held: As applied to respondent and others who
distribute similar material, the statute in question does not
violate the First Amendment as applied to the States through the
Fourteenth Amendment. Pp. 458 U. S.
753 -774.
(a) The States are entitled to greater leeway in the regulation
of pornographic depictions of children for the following reasons:
(1) the legislative judgment that the use of children as subjects
of pornographic materials is harmful to the physiological,
emotional, and mental health of the child easily passes muster
under the First Amendment; (2) the standard of Miller v.
California, 413 U. S. 15 , for
determining what is legally obscene is not a satisfactory solution
to the child pornography problem; (3) the advertising and selling
of child pornography provide an economic motive for, and are thus
an integral part of, the production of such materials, an activity
illegal throughout the Nation; (4) the value of permitting live
performances and photographic reproductions of children engaged in
lewd exhibitions is exceedingly modest, if not de minimis; and (5) recognizing and classifying child pornography as a category
of material outside the First Amendment's protection is not
incompatible with this Court's decisions dealing with what speech
is unprotected. When a definable class of material, such as that
covered by the New Page 458 U. S. 748 York statute, bears so heavily and pervasively on the welfare of
children engaged in its production, the balance of competing
interests is clearly struck, and it is permissible to consider
these materials as without the First Amendment's protection. Pp. 458 U. S.
756 -764.
(b) The New York statute describes a category of material the
production and distribution of which is not entitled to First
Amendment protection. Accordingly, there is nothing
unconstitutionally "underinclusive" about the statute, and the
State is not barred by the First Amendment from prohibiting the
distribution of such unprotected materials produced outside the
State. Pp. 458 U. S.
764 -766.
(c) Nor is the New York statute unconstitutionally overbroad as
forbidding the distribution of material with serious literary,
scientific, or educational value. The substantial overbreadth rule
of Broadrick v. Oklahoma, 413 U.
S. 601 , applies. This is the paradigmatic case of a
state statute whose legitimate reach dwarfs its arguably
impermissible applications.
"[W]hatever overbreadth may exist should be cured through
case-by-case analysis of the fact situations to which [the
statute's] sanctions, assertedly, may not be applied." Broadrick v. Oklahoma, supra, at 413 U. S.
615 -616. Pp. 458 U. S.
766 -774.
52 N.Y.2d 674, 422 N.E.2d 523, reversed and remanded.
WHITE, J., delivered the opinion of the Court, in which BURGER,
C.J., and POWELL, REHNQUIST, and O'CONNOR, JJ., joined. O'CONNOR,
J., filed a concurring opinion, post, p. 458 U. S. 774 .
BRENNAN, J., filed an opinion concurring in the judgment, in which
MARSHALL, J., joined, post, p. 458 U. S. 775 .
BLACKMUN, J., concurred in the result. STEVENS, J., filed an
opinion concurring in the judgment, post, p. 458 U. S.
777 . Page 458 U. S. 749 JUSTICE WHITE delivered the opinion of the Court.
At issue in this case is the constitutionality of a New York
criminal statute which prohibits persons from knowingly promoting
sexual performances by children under the age of 16 by distributing
material which depicts such performances. I In recent years, the exploitive use of children in the
production of pornography has become a serious national problem.
[ Footnote 1 ] The Federal
Government and 47 States have sought to combat the problem with
statutes specifically directed at the production of child
pornography. At least half of such statutes do not require that the
materials produced be legally obscene. Thirty-five States and the
United States Congress have also passed legislation prohibiting the
distribution of such materials; 20 States prohibit the distribution
of material depicting children engaged in sexual conduct without
requiring that the material be legally obscene. [ Footnote 2 ] Page 458 U. S. 750 New York is one of the 20. In 1977, the New York Legislature
enacted Article 263 of its Penal Law. N.Y.Penal Law, Art. 263
(McKinney 1980). Section 263.05 criminalizes as a class C felony
the use of a child in a sexual performance:
"A person is guilty of the use of a child in a sexual
performance if knowing the character and content thereof he
employs, authorizes or induces a child less than sixteen years of
age to engage in a sexual performance or being a parent, legal
guardian or custodian of such child, Page 458 U. S. 751 he consents to the participation by such child in a sexual
performance."
A "[s]exual performance" is defined as "any performance or part
thereof which includes sexual conduct by a child less than sixteen
years of age." § 263.00(1). "Sexual conduct" is in turn defined in
§ 263.00(3):
"'Sexual conduct' means actual or simulated sexual intercourse,
deviate sexual intercourse, sexual bestiality, masturbation,
sado-masochistic abuse, or lewd exhibition of the genitals."
A performance is defined as "any play, motion picture,
photograph or dance" or "any other visual representation exhibited
before an audience." § 263.00(4).
At issue in this case is § 263.15, defining a class D felony:
[ Footnote 3 ]
"A person is guilty of promoting a sexual performance by a child
when, knowing the character and content thereof, he produces,
directs or promotes any performance which includes sexual conduct
by a child less than sixteen years of age."
To "promote" is also defined:
"'Promote' means to procure, manufacture, issue, sell, give,
provide, lend, mail, deliver, transfer, transmute, publish,
distribute, circulate, disseminate, present, exhibit or advertise,
or to offer or agree to do the same."
§ 263.00(5). A companion provision bans only the knowing
dissemination of obscene material. § 263.10.
This case arose when Paul Ferber, the proprietor of a
Manhattan Page 458 U. S. 752 bookstore specializing in sexually oriented products, sold two
films to an undercover police officer. The films are devoted almost
exclusively to depicting young boys masturbating. Ferber was
indicted on two counts of violating § 263.10 and two counts of
violating § 263.15, the two New York laws controlling dissemination
of child pornography. [ Footnote
4 ] After a jury trial, Ferber was acquitted of the two counts
of promoting an obscene sexual performance, but found guilty of the
two counts under § 263.15, which did not require proof that the
films were obscene. Ferber's convictions were affirmed without
opinion by the Appellate Division of the New York State Supreme
Court. 74 App.Div.2d 558, 424 N.Y.S.2d 967 (1980).
The New York Court of Appeals reversed, holding that § 263.15
violated the First Amendment. 52 N.Y.2d 674, 422 N.E.2d 523 (1981).
The court began by noting that, in light of § 263.10's explicit
inclusion of an obscenity standard, § 263.15 could not be construed
to include such a standard. Therefore,
"the statute would . . . prohibit the promotion of materials
which are traditionally entitled to constitutional protection from
government interference under the First Amendment."
52 N.Y.2d at 678, 422 N.E.2d at 525. Although the court
recognized the State's "legitimate interest in protecting the
welfare of minors" and noted that this "interest may transcend
First Amendment concerns," id. at 679, 422 N.E.2d at
525-526, it nevertheless found two fatal defects in the New York
statute. Section 263.15 was underinclusive because it discriminated
against visual portrayals of children engaged in sexual activity by
not also prohibiting the distribution of films of other dangerous
activity. It was also overbroad because it prohibited the
distribution of materials produced outside the State, as well as
materials, such as medical books and educational sources, which Page 458 U. S. 753 "deal with adolescent sex in a realistic but nonobscene manner."
52 N.Y.2d at 681, 422 N.E.2d at 526. Two judges dissented. We
granted the State's petition for certiorari, 454 U.S. 1052 (1981),
presenting the single question:
"To prevent the abuse of children who are made to engage in
sexual conduct for commercial purposes, could the New York State
Legislature, consistent with the First Amendment, prohibit the
dissemination of material which shows children engaged in sexual
conduct, regardless of whether such material is obscene?" II The Court of Appeals proceeded on the assumption that the
standard of obscenity incorporated in § 263.10, which follows the
guidelines enunciated in Miller v. California, 413 U. S. 15 (1973), [ Footnote 5 ]
constitutes the appropriate line dividing protected from
unprotected expression by which to measure a regulation directed at
child pornography. It was on the premise that "nonobscene
adolescent sex" could not be singled out for special treatment that
the court found § 263.15 "strikingly underinclusive." Moreover, the
assumption that the constitutionally permissible regulation of
pornography could not be more extensive with respect to the
distribution of material depicting children may also have led the
court to conclude that a narrowing construction of § 263.15 was
unavailable.
The Court of Appeals' assumption was not unreasonable in light
of our decisions. This case, however, constitutes our first
examination of a statute directed at and limited to depictions of
sexual activity involving children. We believe our inquiry should
begin with the question of whether a State has somewhat more
freedom in proscribing works which portray sexual acts or lewd
exhibitions of genitalia by children. Page 458 U. S. 754 A In Chaplinsky v. New Hampshire, 315 U.
S. 568 (1942), the Court laid the foundation for the
excision of obscenity from the realm of constitutionally protected
expression:
"There are certain well-defined and narrowly limited classes of
speech, the prevention and punishment of which have never been
thought to raise any Constitutional problem. These include the lewd
and obscene. . . . It has been well observed that such utterances
are no essential part of any exposition of ideas, and are of such
slight social value as a step to truth that any benefit that may be
derived from them is clearly outweighed by the social interest in
order and morality." Id. at 315 U. S.
571 -572 (footnotes omitted).
Embracing this judgment, the Court squarely held in Roth v.
United States, 354 U. S. 476 (1957), that "obscenity is not within the area of constitutionally
protected speech or press." Id. at 354 U. S. 485 .
The Court recognized that "rejection of obscenity as utterly
without redeeming social importance" was implicit in the history of
the First Amendment: the original States provided for the
prosecution of libel, blasphemy, and profanity, and the
"universal judgment that obscenity should be restrained [is]
reflected in the international agreement of over 50 nations, in the
obscenity laws of all of the 48 states, and in the 20 obscenity
laws enacted by Congress from 1842 to 1956." Id. at 354 U. S.
484 -485 (footnotes omitted). Roth was followed by 15 years during which this Court
struggled with "the intractable obscenity problem." Interstate
Circuit, Inc. v. Dallas, 390 U. S. 676 , 390 U. S. 704 (1968) (opinion of Harlan, J.). See, e.g., Redrup v. New
York, 386 U. S. 767 (1967). Despite considerable vacillation over the proper definition
of obscenity, a majority of the Members of the Court remained firm
in the position that
"the States have a legitimate interest in prohibiting
dissemination or exhibition of obscene material when the mode of
dissemination carries with it a significant danger of offending the
sensibilities of Page 458 U. S. 755 unwilling recipients or of exposure to juveniles." Miller v. California, supra, at 413 U. S. 119 (footnote omitted); Stanley v. Georgia, 394 U.
S. 557 , 394 U. S. 567 (1969); Ginsberg v. New York, 390 U.
S. 629 , 390 U. S.
637 -643 (1968); Interstate Circuit, Inc. v. Dallas,
supra, at 390 U. S. 690 ; Redrup v. New York, supra, at 386 U. S. 769 ; Jacobellis v. Ohio, 378 U. S. 184 , 378 U. S. 195 (1964).
Throughout this period, we recognized "the inherent dangers of
undertaking to regulate any form of expression." Miller v.
California, supra, at 413 U. S. 23 . Consequently, our difficulty was not only
to assure that statutes designed to regulate obscene materials
sufficiently defined what was prohibited, but also to devise
substantive limits on what fell within the permissible scope of
regulation. In Miller v. California, supra, a majority of
the Court agreed that a
"state offense must also be limited to works which, taken as a
whole, appeal to the prurient interest in sex, which portray sexual
conduct in a patently offensive way, and which, taken as a whole,
do not have serious literary, artistic, political, or scientific
value." Id. at 413 U. S. 24 .
Over the past decade, we have adhered to the guidelines expressed
in Miller, [ Footnote 6 ] which
subsequently has been followed in the regulatory schemes of most
States. [ Footnote 7 ] Page 458 U. S. 756 B The Miller standard, like its predecessors, was an
accommodation between the State's interests in protecting the
"sensibilities of unwilling recipients" from exposure to
pornographic material and the dangers of censorship inherent in
unabashedly content-based laws. Like obscenity statutes, laws
directed at the dissemination of child pornography run the risk of
suppressing protected expression by allowing the hand of the censor
to become unduly heavy. For the following reasons, however, we are
persuaded that the States are entitled to greater leeway in the
regulation of pornographic depictions of children. First. It is evident beyond the need for elaboration
that a State's interest in "safeguarding the physical and
psychological Page 458 U. S. 757 wellbeing of a minor" is "compelling." Globe Newspaper Co.
v. Superior Court, 457 U. S. 596 , 457 U. S. 607 (1982). "A democratic society rests, for its continuance, upon the
healthy, well-rounded growth of young people into full maturity as
citizens." Prince v. Massachusetts, 321 U.
S. 158 , 321 U. S. 168 (1944). Accordingly, we have sustained legislation aimed at
protecting the physical and emotional wellbeing of youth even when
the laws have operated in the sensitive area of constitutionally
protected rights. In Prince v. Massachusetts, supra, the
Court held that a statute prohibiting use of a child to distribute
literature on the street was valid notwithstanding the statute's
effect on a First Amendment activity. In Ginsberg v. New York,
supra, we sustained a New York law protecting children from
exposure to nonobscene literature. Most recently, we held that the
Government's interest in the "wellbeing of its youth" justified
special treatment of indecent broadcasting received by adults as
well as children. FCC v. Pacifica Foundation, 438 U.
S. 726 (1978).
The prevention of sexual exploitation and abuse of children
constitutes a government objective of surpassing importance. The
legislative findings accompanying passage of the New York laws
reflect this concern:
"[T]here has been a proliferation of exploitation of children as
subjects in sexual performances. The care of children is a sacred
trust and should not be abused by those who seek to profit through
a commercial network based upon the exploitation of children. The
public policy of the state demands the protection of children from
exploitation through sexual performances."
1977 N.Y.Laws, ch. 910, § 1. [ Footnote 8 ] Page 458 U. S. 758 We shall not second-guess this legislative judgment. Respondent
has not intimated that we do so. Suffice it to say that virtually
all of the States and the United States have passed legislation
proscribing the production of or otherwise combating "child
pornography." The legislative judgment, as well as the judgment
found in the relevant literature, is that the use of children as
subjects of pornographic materials is harmful to the physiological,
emotional, and mental health of the child. [ Footnote 9 ] That judgment, we think, easily passes
muster under the First Amendment. Page 458 U. S. 759 Second. The distribution of photographs and films
depicting sexual activity by juveniles is intrinsically related to
the sexual abuse of children in at least two ways. First, the
materials produced are a permanent record of the children's
participation and the harm to the child is exacerbated by their
circulation. [ Footnote 10 ]
Second, the distribution network for child pornography must be
closed if the production of material which requires the sexual
exploitation of children is to be effectively controlled. Indeed,
there is no serious contention that the legislature was unjustified
in believing that it is difficult, if Page 458 U. S. 760 not impossible, to halt the exploitation of children by pursuing
only those who produce the photographs and movies. While the
production of pornographic materials is a low profile, clandestine
industry, the need to market the resulting products requires a
visible apparatus of distribution. The most expeditious, if not the
only practical, method of law enforcement may be to dry up the
market for this material by imposing severe criminal penalties on
persons selling, advertising, or otherwise promoting the product.
Thirty-five States and Congress have concluded that restraints on
the distribution of pornographic materials are required in order to
effectively combat the problem, and there is a body of literature
and testimony to support these legislative conclusions. [ Footnote 11 ] Cf. United States
v. Darby, 312 U. S. 100 (1941) (upholding federal restrictions on sale of goods
manufactured in violation of Fair Labor Standards Act).
Respondent does not contend that the State is unjustified in
pursuing those who distribute child pornography. Rather, he argues
that it is enough for the State to prohibit the distribution of
materials that are legally obscene under the Miller test.
While some States may find that this approach properly accommodates
its interests, it does not follow Page 458 U. S. 761 that the First Amendment prohibits a State from going further.
The Miller standard, like all general definitions of what
may be banned as obscene, does not reflect the State's particular
and more compelling interest in prosecuting those who promote the
sexual exploitation of children. Thus, the question under the Miller test of whether a work, taken as a whole, appeals
to the prurient interest of the average person bears no connection
to the issue of whether a child has been physically or
psychologically harmed in the production of the work. Similarly, a
sexually explicit depiction need not be "patently offensive" in
order to have required the sexual exploitation of a child for its
production. In addition, a work which, taken on the whole, contains
serious literary, artistic, political, or scientific value may
nevertheless embody the hardest core of child pornography. "It is
irrelevant to the child [who has been abused] whether or not the
material . . . has a literary, artistic, political or social
value." Memorandum of Assemblyman Lasher in Support of § 263.15. We
therefore cannot conclude that the Miller standard is a
satisfactory solution to the child pornography problem. [ Footnote 12 ] Third. The advertising and selling of child pornography
provide an economic motive for, and are thus an integral part of,
the production of such materials, an activity illegal throughout
the Nation. [ Footnote
13 ]
"It rarely has been suggested that Page 458 U. S. 762 the constitutional freedom for speech and press extends its
immunity to speech or writing used as an integral part of conduct
in violation of a valid criminal statute." Giboney v. Empire Storage & Ice Co., 336 U.
S. 490 , 336 U. S. 498 (1949). [ Footnote 14 ] We
note that, were the statutes outlawing the employment of children
in these films and photographs fully effective, and the
constitutionality of these laws has not been questioned, the First
Amendment implications would be no greater than that presented by
laws against distribution: enforceable production laws would leave
no child pornography to be marketed. [ Footnote 15 ] Fourth. The value of permitting live performances and
photographic reproductions of children engaged in lewd sexual
conduct is exceedingly modest, if not de minimis. We
consider it unlikely that visual depictions of children performing
sexual acts or lewdly exhibiting their genitals would often
constitute an important and necessary part of a literary
performance Page 458 U. S. 763 or scientific or educational work. As a state judge in this case
observed, if it were necessary for literary or artistic value, a
person over the statutory age who perhaps looked younger could be
utilized. [ Footnote 16 ]
Simulation outside of the prohibition of the statute could provide
another alternative. Nor is there any question here of censoring a
particular literary theme or portrayal of sexual activity. The
First Amendment interest is limited to that of rendering the
portrayal somewhat more "realistic" by utilizing or photographing
children. Fifth. Recognizing and classifying child pornography as
a category of material outside the protection of the First
Amendment is not incompatible with our earlier decisions. "The
question whether speech is, or is not, protected by the First
Amendment often depends on the content of the speech." Young v.
American Mini Theatres, Inc., 427 U. S.
50 , 427 U. S. 66 (1976) (opinion of STEVENS, J., joined by BURGER, C.J., and WHITE
and REHNQUIST JJ.). See also FCC v. Pacifica Foundation, 438 U. S. 726 , 438 U. S.
742 -748 (1978) (opinion of STEVENS, J., joined by
BURGER, C.J., and REHNQUIST, J.). "[I]t is the content of [an]
utterance that determines whether it is a protected epithet or an
unprotected fighting comment.'" Young v. American Mini
Theatres, Inc., supra, at 427 U. S. 66 . See Chaplinsky v. New Hampshire, 315 U.
S. 568 (1942). Leaving aside the special considerations
when public officials are the target, New York Times Co. v.
Sullivan, 376 U. S. 254 (1964), a libelous publication is not protected by the
Constitution. Beauharnais v. Illinois, 343 U.
S. 250 (1952). Thus, it is not rare that a content-based
classification of speech has been accepted because it may be
appropriately generalized that within the confines of the given
classification, the evil to be restricted so overwhelmingly
outweighs Page 458 U. S. 764 the expressive interests, if any, at stake, that no process of
case-by-case adjudication is required. When a definable class of
material, such as that covered by § 263.15, bears so heavily and
pervasively on the welfare of children engaged in its production,
we think the balance of competing interests is clearly struck, and
that it is permissible to consider these materials as without the
protection of the First Amendment. C There are, of course, limits on the category of child
pornography which, like obscenity, is unprotected by the First
Amendment. As with all legislation in this sensitive area, the
conduct to be prohibited must be adequately defined by the
applicable state law, as written or authoritatively construed. Here
the nature of the harm to be combated requires that the state
offense be limited to works that visually depict sexual conduct by
children below a specified age. [ Footnote 17 ] The category of "sexual conduct" proscribed
must also be suitably limited and described.
The test for child pornography is separate from the obscenity
standard enunciated in Miller, but may be compared to it
for the purpose of clarity. The Miller formulation is
adjusted in the following respects: a trier of fact need not find
that the material appeals to the prurient interest of the average
person; it is not required that sexual conduct portrayed be done so
in a patently offensive manner; and the material at issue need not
be considered as a whole. We note that the distribution Page 458 U. S. 765 of descriptions or other depictions of sexual conduct, not
otherwise obscene, which do not involve live performance or
photographic or other visual reproduction of live performances,
retains First Amendment protection. As with obscenity laws,
criminal responsibility may not be imposed without some element of
scienter on the part of the defendant. Smith v.
California, 361 U. S. 147 (1959); Hamling v. United States, 418 U. S.
87 (1974). D Section 263.15's prohibition incorporates a definition of sexual
conduct that comports with the above-stated principles. The
forbidden acts to be depicted are listed with sufficient precision
and represent the kind of conduct that, if it were the theme of a
work, could render it legally obscene:
"actual or simulated sexual intercourse, deviate sexual
intercourse, sexual bestiality, masturbation, sado-masochistic
abuse, or lewd exhibition of the genitals."
§ 263.00(3). The term "lewd exhibition of the genitals" is not
unknown in this area and, indeed, was given in Miller as
an example of a permissible regulation. 413 U.S. at 413 U. S. 25 . A
performance is defined only to include live or visual depictions:
"any play, motion picture, photograph or dance . . . [or] other
visual representation exhibited before an audience." § 263.00(4).
Section 263.15 expressly includes a scienter requirement.
We hold that § 263.15 sufficiently describes a category of
material the production and distribution of which is not entitled
to First Amendment protection. It is therefore clear that there is
nothing unconstitutionally "underinclusive" about a statute that
singles out this category of material for proscription. [ Footnote 18 ] It also follows that
the State is not barred by Page 458 U. S. 766 the First Amendment from prohibiting the distribution of
unprotected materials produced outside the State. [ Footnote 19 ] III It remains to address the claim that the New York statute is
unconstitutionally overbroad because it would forbid the
distribution of material with serious literary, scientific, or
educational value or material which does not threaten the harms
sought to be combated by the State. Respondent prevailed on that
ground below, and it is to that issue that we now turn.
The New York Court of Appeals recognized that overbreadth
scrutiny has been limited with respect to conduct-related
regulation, Broadrick v. Oklahoma, 413 U.
S. 601 (1973), but it did not apply the test enunciated
in Broadrick because the challenged statute, in its view,
was directed at "pure speech." The court went on to find that §
263.15 was fatally overbroad:
"[T]he statute would prohibit the showing of any play or movie
in which a child portrays a defined sexual act, real or simulated,
in a nonobscene manner. It would also prohibit the sale, showing,
or distributing of medical or educational materials containing
photographs of such acts. Page 458 U. S. 767 Indeed, by its terms, the statute would prohibit those who
oppose such portrayals from providing illustrations of what they
oppose."
52 N.Y.2d at 678, 422 N.E.2d at 525.
While the construction that a state court gives a state statute
is not a matter subject to our review, Wainwright v.
Stone, 414 U. S. 21 , 414 U. S. 22 -23
(1973); Gooding v. Wilson, 405 U.
S. 518 , 405 U. S. 520 (1972), this Court is the final arbiter of whether the Federal
Constitution necessitated the invalidation of a state law. It is
only through this process of review that we may correct erroneous
applications of the Constitution that err on the side of an overly
broad reading of our doctrines and precedents, as well as state
court decisions giving the Constitution too little shrift. A state
court is not free to avoid a proper facial attack on federal
constitutional grounds. Bigelow v. Virginia, 421 U.
S. 809 , 421 U. S. 817 (1975). By the same token, it should not be compelled to entertain
an overbreadth attack when not required to do so by the
Constitution. A The traditional rule is that a person to whom a statute may
constitutionally be applied may not challenge that statute on the
ground that it may conceivably be applied unconstitutionally to
others in situations not before the Court. Broadrick v.
Oklahoma, supra, at 413 U. S. 610 ; United States v. Raines, 362 U. S. 17 , 362 U. S. 21 (1960); Carmichael v. Southern Coal & Coke Co., 301 U. S. 495 , 301 U. S. 513 (1937); Yazoo & M. V. R. Co. v. Jackson Vinegar Co., 226 U. S. 217 , 226 U. S.
219 -220 (1912). In Broadrick, we recognized
that this rule reflects two cardinal principles of our
constitutional order: the personal nature of constitutional rights, McGowan v. Maryland, 366 U. S. 420 , 366 U. S. 429 (1961), and prudential limitations on constitutional adjudication.
[ Footnote 20 ] In United
States v. Raines, supra, at 362 U. S. 21 ,
we Page 458 U. S. 768 noted the "incontrovertible proposition" that it
"'would indeed be undesirable for this Court to consider every
conceivable situation which might possibly arise in the application
of complex and comprehensive legislation,'"
(quoting Barrows v. Jackson, 346 U.
S. 249 , 346 U. S. 256 (1953)). By focusing on the factual situation before us, and
similar cases necessary for development of a constitutional rule,
[ Footnote 21 ] we face
"flesh-and-blood" [ Footnote
22 ] legal problems with data "relevant and adequate to an
informed judgment." [ Footnote
23 ] This practice also fulfills a valuable institutional
purpose: it allows state courts the opportunity to construe a law
to avoid constitutional infirmities.
What has come to be known as the First Amendment overbreadth
doctrine is one of the few exceptions to this principle, and must
be justified by "weighty countervailing policies." United
States v. Raines, supra, at 362 U. S. 223 .
The doctrine is predicated on the sensitive nature of protected
expression:
"persons whose expression is constitutionally protected may well
refrain from exercising their rights for fear of criminal sanctions
by a statute susceptible of application to protected
expression." Village of Schaumburg
v. Page 458 U. S. 769 Citizens for a Better Environment, 444 U.
S. 620 , 444 U. S. 634 (1980); Gooding v. Wilson, supra, at 405 U. S. 521 .
It is for this reason that we have allowed persons to attack overly
broad statutes even though the conduct of the person making the
attack is clearly unprotected, and could be proscribed by a law
drawn with the requisite specificity. Dombrowski v.
Pfister, 380 U. S. 479 , 380 U. S. 486 (1965); Thornhill v. Alabama, 310 U. S.
88 , 310 U. S. 97 -98
(1940); United States v. Raines, supra, at 362 U. S. 21 -22; Gooding v. Wilson, supra, at 405 U. S.
521 .
The scope of the First Amendment overbreadth doctrine, like most
exceptions to established principles, must be carefully tied to the
circumstances in which facial invalidation of a statute is truly
warranted. Because of the wide-reaching effects of striking down a
statute on its face at the request of one whose own conduct may be
punished despite the First Amendment, we have recognized that the
overbreadth doctrine is "strong medicine," and have employed it
with hesitation, and then "only as a last resort." Broadrick, 413 U.S. at 413 U. S. 613 .
We have, in consequence, insisted that the overbreadth involved be
"substantial" before the statute involved will be invalidated on
its face. [ Footnote 24 ] Page 458 U. S. 770 In Broadrick, we explained the basis for this
requirement:
"[T]he plain import of our cases is, at the very least, that
facial overbreadth adjudication is an exception to our traditional
rules of practice, and that its function, a limited one at the
outset, attenuates as the otherwise unprotected behavior that it
forbids the State to sanction moves from 'pure speech' toward
conduct, and that conduct -- even if expressive -- falls within the
scope of otherwise valid criminal laws that reflect legitimate
state interests in maintaining comprehensive controls over harmful,
constitutionally unprotected conduct. Although such laws, if too
broadly worded, may deter protected speech to some unknown extent,
there comes a point where that effect -- at best a prediction --
cannot, with confidence, justify invalidating a statute on its
face, and so prohibiting a State from enforcing the statute against
conduct that is admittedly within its power to proscribe. Cf.
Aldelman v. United States, 394 U. S. 165 , 394 U. S.
174 -175 (1969)." Id. at 413 U. S. 615 .
We accordingly held that,
"particularly where conduct, and not merely speech, is involved,
we believe that the overbreadth of a statute must not only be real,
but substantial as well, judged in relation to the statute's
plainly legitimate sweep." Ibid. [ Footnote
25 ] Page 458 U. S. 771 Broadrick examined a regulation involving restrictions
on political campaign activity, an area not considered "pure
speech," and thus it was unnecessary to consider the proper
overbreadth test when a law arguably reaches traditional forms of
expression such as books and films. As we intimated in Broadrick, the requirement of substantial overbreadth
extended "at the very least" to cases involving conduct plus
speech. This case, which poses the question squarely, convinces us
that the rationale of Broadrick is sound, and should be
applied in the present context involving the harmful employment of
children to make sexually explicit materials for distribution.
The premise that a law should not be invalidated for overbreadth
unless it reaches a substantial number of impermissible
applications is hardly novel. On most occasions involving facial
invalidation, the Court has stressed the embracing sweep of the
statute over protected expression. [ Footnote 26 ] Page 458 U. S. 772 Indeed, JUSTICE BRENNAN observed in his dissenting opinion in Broadrick: "We have never held that a statute should be held invalid on its
face merely because it is possible to conceive of a single
impermissible application, and in that sense, a requirement of
substantial overbreadth is already implicit in the doctrine." Id. at 413 U. S. 630 .
The requirement of substantial overbreadth is directly derived from
the purpose and nature of the doctrine. While a sweeping statute,
or one incapable of limitation, has the potential to repeatedly
chill the exercise of expressive activity by many individuals, the
extent of deterrence of protected speech can be expected to
decrease with the declining reach of the regulation. [ Footnote 27 ] This observation
appears equally applicable to the publication of books and films as
it is to activities, such as picketing or participation in election
campaigns, which have previously been categorized as involving
conduct plus speech. We see no appreciable difference between the
position of a publisher or bookseller in doubt as to the reach of
New York's child pornography law and the situation faced by the
Oklahoma state employees with respect to that State's restriction
on partisan political activity. Indeed, it could reasonably be
argued that the bookseller, with an economic incentive to sell
materials that may fall within the statute's scope, may be less
likely to be deterred than the employee who wishes to engage in
political campaign activity. Cf. Bates v. State Bar of
Arizona, 433 U. S. 350 , 433 U. S.
380 -381 (1977) (overbreadth analysis inapplicable to
commercial speech).
This requirement of substantial overbreadth may justifiably be
applied to statutory challenges which arise in defense Page 458 U. S. 773 of a criminal prosecution as well as civil enforcement or
actions seeking a declaratory judgment. Cf. Parker v.
Levy, 417 U. S. 733 , 417 U. S. 760 (1974). Indeed, the Court's practice when confronted with ordinary
criminal laws that are sought to be applied against protected
conduct is not to invalidate the law in toto, but rather
to reverse the particular conviction. Cantwell v.
Connecticut, 310 U. S. 296 (1940); Edwards v. South Carolina, 372 U.
S. 229 (1973). We recognize, however, that the penalty
to be imposed is relevant in determining whether demonstrable
overbreadth is substantial. We simply hold that the fact that a
criminal prohibition is involved does not obviate the need for the
inquiry or a priori warrant a finding of substantial
overbreadth.
Applying these principles, we hold that § 263.15 is not
substantially overbroad. We consider this the paradigmatic case of
a state statute whose legitimate reach dwarfs its arguably
impermissible applications. New York, as we have held, may
constitutionally prohibit dissemination of material specified in §
263.15. While the reach of the statute is directed at the hard core
of child pornography, the Court of Appeals was understandably
concerned that some protected expression, ranging from medical
textbooks to pictorials in the National Geographic would fall prey
to the statute. How often, if ever, it may be necessary to employ
children to engage in conduct clearly within the reach of § 263.15
in order to produce educational, medical, or artistic works cannot
be known with certainty. Yet we seriously doubt, and it has not
been suggested, that these arguably impermissible applications of
the statute amount to more than a tiny fraction of the materials
within the statute's reach. Nor will we assume that the New York
courts will widen the possibly invalid reach of the statute by
giving an expansive construction to the proscription on "lewd
exhibition[s] of the genitals." Under these circumstances, § 263.15
is
"not substantially overbroad, and . . . whatever overbreadth may
exist Page 458 U. S. 774 should be cured through case-by-case analysis of the fact
situations to which its sanctions, assertedly, may not be
applied." Broadrick v. Oklahoma, 413 U.S. at 413 U. S.
615 -616. IV Because § 263.15 is not substantially overbroad, it is
unnecessary to consider its application to material that does not
depict sexual conduct of a type that New York may restrict
consistent with the First Amendment. As applied to Paul Ferber and
to others who distribute similar material, the statute does not
violate the First Amendment as applied to the States through the
Fourteenth. [ Footnote 28 ]
The judgment of the New York Court of Appeals is reversed, and the
case is remanded to that court for further proceedings not
inconsistent with this opinion. So ordered. JUSTICE BLACKMUN concurs in the result.
[ Footnote 1 ]
"[C]hild pornography and child prostitution have become highly
organized, multimillion dollar industries that operate on a
nationwide scale." S.Rep. No. 95-438, p. 5 (1977). One researcher
has documented the existence of over 260 different magazines which
depict children engaging in sexually explicit conduct. Ibid. "Such magazines depict children, some as young as three to five
years of age. . . . The activities featured range from lewd poses
to intercourse, fellatio, cunnilingus, masturbation, rape, incest
and sado-masochism." Id. at 6. In Los Angeles alone, police reported that
30,000 children have been sexually exploited. Sexual Exploitation
of Children, Hearings before the Subcommittee on Select Education
of the House Committee on Education and Labor, 95th Cong., 1st
Sess., 41-42 (1977).
[ Footnote 2 ]
In addition to New York, 19 States have prohibited the
dissemination of material depicting children engaged in sexual
conduct regardless of whether the material is obscene.
Ariz.Rev.Stat.Ann. § 13-3553 (Supp.1981-1982); Colo.Rev.Stat. §
18403 (Supp.1981); Del. Code Ann., Tit. 11, §§ 1108, 1109 (1979);
Fla.Stat. § 847.014 (1981); Haw. Rev.Stat. § 707-751 (Supp.1981);
Ky.Rev.Stat. §§ 531.320, 531.340-531.360 (Supp.1980);
La.Rev.Stat.Ann. § 14:81.1(A)(3) (West Supp.1982); Mass.Gen.Laws
Ann., ch. 272, § 29A (West Supp.1982-1983); Mich.Comp.Laws Ann. §
750.145c(3) (1982-1983); Miss.Code Ann. § 97-5-33(4) (Supp.1981);
Mont.Code Ann. § 45625 (1981); N.J.Stat.Ann. § 2C:24-4(b)(5) (West
1981); Okla.Stat., Tit. 21, § 1021.2 (1981); Pa.Stat.Ann., Tit. 18,
§ 6312(c) (Purdon 1982-1983); R.I.Gen.Laws § 11-9-1.1 (1981);
Tex.Penal Code Ann. § 43.25 (1982); Utah Code Ann. §
76-10-1206.5(3) (Supp.1981); W.Va.Code § 61-8C3 (Supp.1981);
Wis.Stat. § 940.203(4) (1979-1980).
Fifteen States prohibit the dissemination of such material only
if it is obscene. Ala.Code §§ 13-7-231, 13-7-232 (Supp.1981);
Ark.Stat.Ann. § 41-4204 (Supp.1981); Cal.Penal Code Ann. § 311.2(b)
(West Supp.1982) (general obscenity statute); Ill.Rev.Stat., ch.
38, � 11-20a(b)(1) (1979); Ind.Code § 35-30-10.1-2 (1979);
Me.Rev.Stat.Ann., Tit. 17, § 2923(1) (Supp.1981-1982); Minn.Stat.
§§ 617.246(3) and (4) (1980); Neb.Rev.Stat. § 28-1463(2) (1979);
N.H.Rev.Stat.Ann. § 650:2(II) (Supp.1981); N.D.Cent.Code §
12.1-27.1-01 (1976) (general obscenity statute); Ohio Rev.Code Ann.
§ 2907.321(A) (1982); Ore.Rev.Stat. § 163.485 (1981); S.D.Codified
Laws §§ 22-22-24, 22-22-25 (1979); Tenn.Code Ann. § 39-1020
(Supp.1981); Wash.Rev.Code § 9.68 A. 030 (1981). The federal
statute also prohibits dissemination only if the material is
obscene. 18 U.S.C. § 2252(a) (1976 ed., Supp. IV). Two States
prohibit dissemination only if the material is obscene as to
minors. Conn.Gen.Stat. § 53a-196b (1981); Va.Code § 18.2-374.1
(1982).
Twelve States prohibit only the use of minors in the production
of the material. Alaska Stat.Ann. § 11.41.455 (1978); Ga.Code §
26-9943a(b) (1978); Idaho Code § 44-1306 (1977); Iowa Code § 728.12
(1981); Kan.Stat.Ann. § 21516 (1981); Md.Ann.Code, Art. 27, § 419A
(Supp.1981); Mo.Rev.Stat. § 568.060(1)(b) (1978); Nev.Rev.Stat. §
200.509 (1981); N.M.Stat.Ann. § 301 (Supp.1982); N.C.Gen.Stat. §
14-190.6 (1981); S.C.Code § 115-380 (Supp.1981); Wyo.Stat. §
14102(a)(v)(E) (1978).
[ Footnote 3 ]
Class D felonies carry a maximum punishment of imprisonment for
up to seven years as to individuals, and as to corporations a fine
of up to $10,000. N.Y. Penal Law §§ 70.00, 80.10 (McKinney 1975).
Respondent Ferber was sentenced to 45 days in prison.
[ Footnote 4 ]
A state judge rejected Ferber's First Amendment attack on the
two sections in denying a motion to dismiss the indictment. 96
Misc.2d 669, 409 N.Y.S.2d 632 (1978).
[ Footnote 5 ]
N.Y. Penal Law § 235.00(1) (McKinney 1980); People v.
Illardo, 48 N.Y.2d 408, 415, and n. 3, 399 N.E.2d 59, 62-63,
and n. 3 (1979).
[ Footnote 6 ] Hamling v. United States, 418 U. S.
87 (1974); Jenkins v. Georgia, 418 U.
S. 153 (1974); Ward v. Illinois, 431 U.
S. 767 (1977); Marks v. United States, 430 U. S. 188 (1977); Pinkus v. United States, 436 U.
S. 293 (1978).
[ Footnote 7 ]
Thirty-seven States and the District of Columbia have either
legislatively adopted or judicially incorporated the Miller test for obscenity. Ala.Code § 13A-12-150
(Supp.1981); Ariz.Rev.Stat.Ann. § 13-3501(2) (1978); Ark.Stat.Ann.
§ 41-3502(6) (Supp.1981); Colo.Rev.Stat. § 18-7-101(2) (Supp.1981);
Del. Code Ann., Tit. 11, § 1364 (1979); Larkin v. United
States, 363
A.2d 990 (D.C.1976); Ga.Code § 26-2101(b) (1978); Haw.
Rev.Stat. § 712-1210(6) (Supp.1981); Idaho Code § 184101(A) (1979);
Iowa Code § 728.4 (1981) (only child pornography covered); Ind.Code
§ 35-30-10.1-1(c) (1979); Kan.Stat.Ann. § 21-4301 (2)(a) (1981);
Ky.Rev.Stat. § 531.010(3) (1975); La.Rev.Stat.Ann. §§ 14:106(A)(2)
and (A)(3) (West Supp.1982); Ebert v. Maryland State Bd. of
Censors, 19 Md.App. 300, 313 A.2d 536 (1973); Mass.Gen.Laws Ann., ch. 272, § 31 (West
Supp.1982-1983); People v. Neumayer, 405 Mich. 341, 275 N.W.2d
230 (1979), State v. Welke, 298 Minn. 402, 216 N.W.2d
641 (1974); Mo.Rev.Stat. § 573.010(1) (1978); Neb.Rev.Stat. §
28-807(9) (1979); Nev.Rev.Stat. § 201.235 (1981); N.H.Rev.Stat.Ann.
§ 650:1(IV) (Supp.1981); N.J.Stat.Ann. § 2C:32 (West 1981); N.Y.
Penal Law § 235.00(1) (McKinney 1980); N.C.Gen.Stat. § 14-190.1(b)
(1981); N.D.Cent.Code § 12.1-27.1-01(4) (1976); State v.
Burgun, 56 Ohio St.2d 354, 384 N.E.2d 255 (1978); McCrary
v. State, 533 P.2d
629 (Okla.Crim.App.1974); Ore.Rev.Stat. § 167.087(2) (1981);
Pa.Stat.Ann., Tit. 18, § 5903(b) (Purdon Supp.1982-1983);
R.I.Gen.Laws § 11-31-1198(1); S.C.Code § 16-15-260(a) (Supp.1981);
S.D.Codified Laws § 22-24-27(10) (1979); Tenn.Code Ann. §
39-3001(1) (Supp.1981); Tex.Penal Code Ann. § 43.21(a) (1982); Utah
Code Ann. § 76-10-1203(1) (1978); Va.Code § 18.2-372 (1982); 1982
Wash.Laws., ch. 184, § 1(2).
Four States continue to follow the test approved in Memoirs
v. Massachusetts, 383 U. S. 413 (1966). Cal.Penal Code Ann. § 311(a) (West Supp.1982);
Conn.Gen.Stat. § 53a-193 (1981); Fla.Stat. § 847.07 (1981);
Ill.Rev.Stat., ch. 38, � 11-20(b) (1979). Five States regulate only
the distribution of pornographic material to minors.
Me.Rev.Stat.Ann., Tit. 17, § 2911 (Supp.1981-1982); Mont.Code Ann.
§ 45201 (1981); N.M.Stat.Ann. § 30-37-2 (Supp.1982); Vt.Stat.Ann.,
Tit. 13, § 2802 (1974); W.Va.Code § 61-8A-2 (1977). Three state
obscenity laws do not fall into any of the above categories.
Miss.Code Ann. § 97-29-33 (1973), declared invalid in ABC
Interstate Theatres, Inc. v. State, 325 So. 2d
123 (Miss.1976); Wis.Stat. § 944.21(1)(a) (1979-1980), declared
invalid in State v. Princess Cinema of Milwaukee, Inc., 96
Wis.2d 646, 292 N.W.2d
807 (1980); Wyo.Stat. § 6-5-303 (1977). Alaska has no current
state obscenity law.
A number of States employ a different obscenity standard with
respect to material distributed to children. See, e.g., Fla.Stat. § 847.0125 (1981).
[ Footnote 8 ]
In addition, the legislature found
"the sale of these movies, magazines and photographs depicting
the sexual conduct of children to be so abhorrent to the fabric of
our society that it urge[d] law enforcement officers to
aggressively seek out and prosecute . . . the peddlers . . . of
this filth by vigorously applying the sanctions contained in this
act."
1977 N.Y. Laws, ch. 910, § 1.
[ Footnote 9 ]
"[T]he use of children as . . . subjects of pornographic
materials is very harmful to both the children and the society as a
whole." S.Rep. No. 95-438, p. 5 (1977). It has been found that
sexually exploited children are unable to develop healthy
affectionate relationships in later life, have sexual dysfunctions,
and have a tendency to become sexual abusers as adults. Schoettle,
Child Exploitation: A Study of Child Pornography, 19
J.Am.Acad.Child Psychiatry 289, 296 (1980) (hereafter cited as
Child Exploitation); Schoettle, Treatment of the Child Pornography
Patient, 137 Am.J.Psychiatry 1109, 1110 (1980); Densen-Gerner,
Child Prostitution and Child Pornography: Medical, Legal, and
Societal Aspects of the Commercial Exploitation of Children,
reprinted in U.S. Dept. of Health and Human Services, Sexual Abuse
of Children: Selected Readings 77, 80 (1980) (hereafter cited as
Commercial Exploitation) (sexually exploited children predisposed
to self-destructive behavior such as drug and alcohol abuse or
prostitution). See generally Burgess & Holmstrom,
Accessory-to-Sex: Pressure, Sex, and Secrecy, in A. Burgess, A.
Groth, L. Holmstrom, & S. Sgroi, Sexual Assault of Children and
Adolescents 85, 94 (1978); V. De Francis, Protecting the Child
Victim of Sex Crimes Committed by Adults 169 (1969); Ellerstein
& Canavan, Sexual Abuse of Boys, 134 Am. J. Diseases of
Children 255, 256-257 (1980); Finch, Adult Seduction of the Child:
Effects on the Child, Medical Aspects of Human Sexuality 170, 185
(Mar.1973); Groth, Sexual Trauma in the Life Histories of Rapists
and Child Molesters, 4 Victimology 10 (1979). Sexual molestation by
adults is often involved in the production of child sexual
performances. Sexual Exploitation of Children, A Report to the
Illinois General Assembly by the Illinois Legislative Investigating
Commission 30-31 (1980). When such performances are recorded and
distributed, the child's privacy interests are also invaded. See n 10, infra. [ Footnote 10 ]
As one authority has explained:
"[P]ornography poses an even greater threat to the child victim
than does sexual abuse or prostitution. Because the child's actions
are reduced to a recording, the pornography may haunt him in future
years, long after the original misdeed took place. A child who has
posed for a camera must go through life knowing that the recording
is circulating within the mass distribution system for child
pornography."
Shouvlin, Preventing the Sexual Exploitation of Children: A
Model Act, 17 Wake Forest L.Rev. 535, 545 (1981). See also Child Exploitation 292 ("[I]t is the fear of exposure and the
tension of keeping the act secret that seem to have the most
profound emotional repercussions"); Note, Protection of Children
from Use in Pornography: Toward Constitutional and Enforceable
Legislation, 12 U. Mich.J.Law Reform 295, 301 (1979) (hereafter
cited as Use in Pornography) (interview with child psychiatrist)
("The victim's knowledge of publication of the visual material
increases the emotional and psychic harm suffered by the
child").
Thus, distribution of the material violates "the individual
interest in avoiding disclosure of personal matters." Whalen v.
Roe, 429 U. S. 589 , 429 U. S. 599 (1977). Respondent cannot undermine the force of the privacy
interests involved here by looking to Cox Broadcasting Corp. v.
Cohn, 420 U. S. 469 (1975), and Smith v. Daily Mail Publishing Co., 443 U. S. 97 (1979), cases protecting the right of newspapers to publish,
respectively, the identity of a rape victim and a youth charged as
a juvenile offender. Those cases only stand for the proposition
that,
"if a newspaper lawfully obtains truthful information about a
matter of public significance, then state officials may not
constitutionally punish publication of the information, absent a
need . . . of the highest order." Id. at 443 U. S.
103 .
[ Footnote 11 ] See Sexual Exploitation of Children, Hearings before
the Subcommittee on Crime of the House Judiciary Committee, 95th
Cong., 1st Sess., 34 (1977) (statement of Charles Rembar) ("It is
an impossible prosecutorial job to try to get at the acts
themselves"); id. at 11 (statement of Frank Osanka,
Professor of Social Justice and Sociology) ("[W]e have to be very
careful . . . that we don't take comfort in the existence of
statutes that are on the books in the connection with the use of
children in pornography. . . . There are usually no witnesses to
these acts of producing pornography"); id. at 69
(statement of Investigator Lloyd Martin, Los Angeles Police
Department) (producers of child pornography use false names making
difficult the tracing of material back from distributor). See
also L. Tribe, American Constitutional Law 666, n. 62 (1978);
Note, Child Pornography: A New Role for the Obscenity Doctrine,
1978 U.Ill.Law Forum 711, 716, n. 29; Use in Pornography 315
("passage of criminal laws aimed at producers without similar
regulation of distributors will arguably shift the production
process further underground").
[ Footnote 12 ]
In addition, legal obscenity under Miller is a function
of "contemporary community standards." 413 U.S. at 413 U. S.
24 .
"It is neither realistic nor constitutionally sound to read the
First Amendment as requiring that the people of Maine or
Mississippi accept public depiction of conduct found tolerable in
Las Vegas, or New York City." Id. at 413 U. S. 32 . It
would be equally unrealistic to equate a community's toleration for
sexually oriented material with the permissible scope of
legislation aimed at protecting children from sexual exploitation.
Furthermore, a number of States rely on stricter obscenity tests, see n 7, supra, under which successful prosecution for child
pornography may be even more difficult.
[ Footnote 13 ]
One state committee studying the problem declared: "The act of
selling these materials is guaranteeing that there will be
additional abuse of children." Texas House Select Committee on
Child Pornography: Its Related Causes and Control 132 (1978). See also Commercial Exploitation 80 ("Printed materials
cannot be isolated or removed from the process involved in
developing them").
[ Footnote 14 ]
In Giboney, a unanimous Court held that labor unions
could be restrained from picketing a firm in support of a secondary
boycott which a State had validly outlawed. In Pittsburgh Press
Co. v. Pittsburgh Comm'n on Human Relations, 413 U.
S. 376 (1973), the Court allowed an injunction against a
newspaper's furtherance of illegal sex discrimination by placing of
job advertisements in gender-designated columns. The Court
stated:
"Any First Amendment interest which might be served by
advertising an ordinary commercial proposal and which might
arguably outweigh the governmental interest supporting the
regulation is altogether absent when the commercial activity itself
is illegal and the restriction on advertising is incidental to a
valid limitation on economic activity." Id. at 389.
[ Footnote 15 ]
In this connection, we note that 18 U.S.C. § 2251 (1976 ed.,
Supp. IV), making it a federal offense for anyone to use children
under the age of 16 in the production of pornographic materials,
embraces all "sexually explicit conduct" without imposing an
obscenity test. In addition, half of the state laws imposing
criminal liability on the producer do not require the visual
material to be legally obscene. Use in Pornography 307-308.
[ Footnote 16 ]
96 Misc.2d at 676, 409 N.Y.S.2d at 637. This is not merely a
hypothetical possibility. See Brief for Petitioner 25 and
examples cited therein.
[ Footnote 17 ]
Sixteen States define a child as a person under age 18. Four
States define a child as under 17 years old. The federal law and 16
States, including New York, define a child as under 16. Illinois
and Nebraska define a child as a person under age 16 or who appears
as a prepubescent. Ill.Rev.Stat., ch. 38, � 11-20a(a)(1)(A) (1979);
Neb.Rev.Stat. § 28-1463 (1979). Indiana defines a child as one who
is or appears to be under 16. Ind.Code. §§ 35-30-10.1-2,
35-30-10.1-3 (1979). Kentucky provides for two age classifications
(16 and 18) and varies punishment according to the victim's age.
Ky.Rev.Stat. §§ 531.300-531.370 (Supp.1980). See Use in
Pornography 307, n. 71 (collecting statutes).
[ Footnote 18 ] Erznoznik v. City of Jacksonville, 422 U.
S. 205 (1975), relied upon by the Court of Appeals,
struck down a law against drive-in theaters showing nude scenes if
movies could be seen from a public place. Since nudity, without
more is protected expression, id. at 422 U. S. 213 ,
we proceeded to consider the underinclusiveness of the ordinance.
The Jacksonville ordinance impermissibly singled out movies with
nudity for special treatment while failing to regulate other
protected speech which created the same alleged risk to traffic.
Today, we hold that child pornography as defined in § 263.15 is
unprotected speech subject to content-based regulation. Hence, it
cannot be underinclusive or unconstitutional for a State to do
precisely that.
[ Footnote 19 ]
It is often impossible to determine where such material is
produced. The Senate Report accompanying federal child pornography
legislation stressed that
"it is quite common for photographs or films made in the United
States to be sent to foreign countries to be reproduced and then
returned to this country in order to give the impression of foreign
origin."
S.Rep. No. 95-438, p. 6 (1977). In addition, States have not
limited their distribution laws to material produced within their
own borders because the maintenance of the market itself
"leaves open the financial conduit by which the production of
such material is funded and materially increases the risk that
[local] children will be injured."
52 N.Y.2d 674, 688, 422 N.E.2d 523, 531 (1981) (Jasen, J.,
dissenting).
[ Footnote 20 ]
In addition to prudential restraints, the traditional rule is
grounded in Art. III limits on the jurisdiction of federal courts
to actual cases and controversies.
"This Court, as is the case with all federal courts, 'has no
jurisdiction to pronounce any statute, either of a State or of the
United States, void, because irreconcilable with the Constitution,
except as it is called upon to adjudge the legal rights of
litigants in actual controversies. In the exercise of that
jurisdiction, it is bound by two rules, to which it has rigidly
adhered, one, never to anticipate a question of constitutional law
in advance of the necessity of deciding it; the other, never to
formulate a rule of constitutional law broader than is required by
the precise facts to which it is to be applied.' Liverpool, New
York & Philadelphia S.S. Co. v. Commissioners of
Emigration, 113 U. S. 33 , 113 U. S.
39 ." United States v. Raines, 362 U. S.
17 , 362 U. S. 21 (1960).
[ Footnote 21 ]
Overbreadth challenges are only one type of facial attack. A
person whose activity may be constitutionally regulated
nevertheless may argue that the statute under which he is convicted
or regulated is invalid on its face. See, e.g., Terminiello v.
City of Chicago, 337 U. S. 1 , 337 U. S. 5 (1949). See generally Monaghan, Overbreadth, 1981
S.Ct.Rev. 1, 10-14.
[ Footnote 22 ]
A. Bickel, The Least Dangerous Branch 115-116 (1962).
[ Footnote 23 ]
Frankfurter & Hart, The Business of the Supreme Court at
October Term, 1934, 49 Harv.L.Rev. 68, 95-96 (1935).
[ Footnote 24 ]
When a federal court is dealing with a federal statute
challenged as overbroad, it should, of course, construe the statute
to avoid constitutional problems, if the statute is subject to such
a limiting construction. Crowell v. Benson, 285 U. S.
22 , 285 U. S. 62 (1932). Accord, e.g., Haynes v. United States, 390 U. S. 85 , 390 U. S. 92 (1968) (dictum); Schneider v. Smith, 390 U. S.
17 , 390 U. S. 27 (1968); United States v. Rumely, 345 U. S.
41 , 345 U. S. 45 (1953); Ashwander v. TVA, 297 U.
S. 288 , 297 U. S. 348 (1936) (Brandeis, J., concurring). Furthermore, if the federal
statute is not subject to a narrowing construction and is
impermissibly overbroad, it nevertheless should not be stricken
down on its face; if it is severable, only the unconstitutional
portion is to be invalidated. United States v. Thirty-seven
Photographs, 402 U. S. 363 (1971).
A state court is also free to deal with a state statute in the
same way. If the invalid reach of the law is cured, there is no
longer reason for proscribing the statute's application to
unprotected conduct. Here, of course, we are dealing with a state
statute on direct review of a state court decision that has
construed the statute. Such a construction is binding on us.
[ Footnote 25 ] Parker v. Levy, 417 U. S. 733 , 417 U. S. 760 (1974) ("This Court has . . . repeatedly expressed its reluctance
to strike down a statute on its face where there were a substantial
number of situations to which it might be validly applied. Thus,
even if there are marginal applications in which a statute would
infringe on First Amendment values, facial invalidation is
inappropriate if the remainder of the statute . . . covers a
whole range of easily identifiable and constitutionally
proscribable . . . conduct. . . .' CSC v. Letter Carriers, 413 U. S. 548 , 413 U. S.
580 -581 (1973)"). See Bogen, First Amendment
Ancillary Doctrines, 37 Md.L.Rev. 679, 712-714 (1978); Note, The
First Amendment Overbreadth Doctrine, 83 Harv.L.Rev. 844, 860-861
(1970). [ Footnote 26 ]
In Gooding v. Wilson, 405 U. S. 518 , 405 U. S. 519 , 405 U. S. 527 (1972), the Court's invalidation of a Georgia statute making it a
misdemeanor to use " opprobrious words or abusive language,
tending to cause a breach of the peace'" followed from state
judicial decisions indicating that "merely to speak words offensive
to some who hear them" could constitute a "breach of the peace."
Cases invalidating laws requiring members of a "subversive
organization" to take a loyalty oath, Baggett v. Bullitt, 377 U. S. 360 (1964), or register with the government, Domorowski v.
Pfister, 380 U. S. 479 (1965), can be explained on the basis that the laws involved,
unlike § 263.15, defined no central core of constitutionally
regulable conduct; the entire scope of the laws was subject to the
uncertainties and vagaries of prosecutorial discretion. See
also Bigelow v. Virginia, 421 U. S. 809 , 421 U. S. 817 (1975) ("the facts of this case well illustrate `the statute's
potential for sweeping and improper applications'") (citation
omitted); NAACP v. Button, 371 U.
S. 415 , 371 U. S. 433 (1963) ("We read the decree of the Virginia Supreme Court of
Appeals . . . as proscribing any arrangement by which prospective
litigants are advised to seek the assistance of particular
attorneys"); Thornhill v. Alabama, 310 U. S.
88 , 310 U. S. 97 (1940) (the statute "does not aim specifically at evils within the
allowable area of state control but, on the contrary, sweeps within
its ambit other activities that in ordinary circumstances
constitute an exercise of freedom of speech or of the
press"). [ Footnote 27 ]
"A substantial overbreadth rule is implicit in the chilling
effect rationale. . . . [T]he presumption must be that only
substantially overbroad laws set up the kind and degree of chill
that is judicially cognizable."
Moreover,
"[w]ithout a substantial overbreadth limitation, review for
overbreadth would be draconian indeed. It is difficult to think of
a law that is utterly devoid of potential for unconstitutionality
in some conceivable application."
Note, 83 Harv.L.Rev. supra, n 25, at 859, and n. 61.
[ Footnote 28 ]
There is no argument that the films sold by respondent do not
fall squarely within the category of activity we have defined as
unprotected. Therefore, no independent examination of the material
is necessary to assure ourselves that the judgment here "does not
constitute a forbidden intrusion on the field of free expression." New York Times Co. v. Sullivan, 376 U.
S. 254 , 376 U. S. 285 (1964).
JUSTICE O'CONNOR, concurring.
Although I join the Court's opinion, I write separately to
stress that the Court does not hold that New York must except
"material with serious literary, scientific, or educational value," ante at 458 U. S. 766 ,
from its statute. The Court merely holds that, even if the First
Amendment shelters such material, New York's current statute is not
sufficiently overbroad to support respondent's facial attack. The
compelling interests identified in today's opinion, see
ante at 458 U. S.
756 -764, suggest that the Constitution might, in fact,
permit New York to ban knowing distribution of works depicting
minors engaged in explicit sexual conduct, regardless of the social
value of the depictions. For example, a 12-year-old child
photographed while Page 458 U. S. 775 masturbating surely suffers the same psychological harm whether
the community labels the photograph "edifying" or "tasteless." The
audience's appreciation of the depiction is simply irrelevant to
New York's asserted interest in protecting children from
psychological, emotional, and mental harm.
An exception for depictions of serious social value, moreover,
would actually increase opportunities for the content-based
censorship disfavored by the First Amendment. As drafted, New
York's statute does not attempt to suppress the communication of
particular ideas. The statute permits discussion of child
sexuality, forbidding only attempts to render the "portrayal[s]
somewhat more realistic' by utilizing or photographing
children." Ante at 458 U. S. 763 .
Thus, the statute attempts to protect minors from abuse without
attempting to restrict the expression of ideas by those who might
use children as live models. On the other hand, it is quite possible that New York's statute
is overbroad because it bans depictions that do not actually
threaten the harms identified by the Court. For example, clinical
pictures of adolescent sexuality, such as those that might appear
in medical textbooks, might not involve the type of sexual
exploitation and abuse targeted by New York's statute. Nor might
such depictions feed the poisonous "kiddie porn" market that New
York and other States have attempted to regulate. Similarly,
pictures of children engaged in rites widely approved by their
cultures, such as those that might appear in issues of the National
Geographic, might not trigger the compelling interests identified
by the Court. It is not necessary to address these possibilities
further today, however, because this potential overbreadth is not
sufficiently substantial to warrant facial invalidation of New
York's statute.
JUSTICE BRENNAN, with whom JUSTICE MARSHALL joins, concurring in
the judgment.
I agree with much of what is said in the Court's opinion. As I
made clear in the opinion I delivered for the Court in Page 458 U. S. 776 Ginsburg v. New York, 390 U. S. 629 (1968), the State has a special interest in protecting the
wellbeing of its youth. Id. at 390 U. S.
638 -641. See also Globe Newspaper Co. v. Superior
Court, 457 U. S. 596 , 457 U. S. 607 (1982). This special and compelling interest, and the particular
vulnerability of children, afford the State the leeway to regulate
pornographic material, the promotion of which is harmful to
children, even though the State does not have such leeway when it
seeks only to protect consenting adults from exposure to such
material. Ginsburg v. New York, supra, at 390 U. S. 637 , 390 U. S. 638 ,
n. 6, 390 U. S.
642 -643, n. 10. See also Jacobellis v. Ohio, 378 U. S. 184 , 378 U. S. 195 (1964) (opinion of BRENNAN, J.). I also agree with the Court that
the "tiny fraction," ante at 458 U. S. 773 ,
of material of serious artistic, scientific, or educational value
that could conceivably fall within the reach of the statute is
insufficient to justify striking the statute on the grounds of
overbreadth. See Broadrick v. Oklahoma, 413 U.
S. 601 , 413 U. S. 630 (1973) (BRENNAN, J., dissenting).
But, in my view, application of § 263.15 or any similar statute
to depictions of children that, in themselves, do have serious
literary, artistic, scientific, or medical value would violate the
First Amendment. As the Court recognizes, the limited classes of
speech the suppression of which does not raise serious First
Amendment concerns have two attributes. They are of exceedingly
"slight social value," and the State has a compelling interest in
their regulation. See Chaplinsky v. New Hampshire, 315 U. S. 568 , 315 U. S.
571 -572 (1942). The First Amendment value of depictions
of children that are, in themselves, serious contributions to art,
literature, or science is, by definition, simply not " de
minimis. " See ante at 458 U. S. 761 .
At the same time, the State's interest in suppression of such
materials is likely to be far less compelling. For the Court's
assumption of harm to the child resulting from the "permanent
record" and "circulation" of the child's "participation," ante at 458 U. S. 759 ,
lacks much of its force where the depiction is a serious
contribution to art or science. The production of materials of
serious value is not the "low Page 458 U. S. 777 profile, clandestine industry" that, according to the Court,
produces purely pornographic materials. See ante at 458 U. S. 760 .
In short, it is inconceivable how a depiction of a child that is
itself a serious contribution to the world of art or literature or
science can be deemed "material outside the protection of the First
Amendment." See ante at 458 U. S.
763 .
I, of course, adhere to my view that, in the absence of
exposure, or particular harm, to juveniles or unconsenting adults,
the State lacks power to suppress sexually oriented materials. See, e.g., Paris Adult Theatre I v. Slaton, 413 U. S.
49 , 413 U. S. 73 (1973) (BRENNAN, J., dissenting). With this understanding, I concur
in the Court's judgment in this case.
JUSTICE STEVENS, concurring in the judgment.
Two propositions seem perfectly clear to me. First, the specific
conduct that gave rise to this criminal prosecution is not
protected by the Federal Constitution; second, the state statute
that respondent violated prohibits some conduct that is protected
by the First Amendment. The critical question, then, is whether
this respondent, to whom the statute may be applied without
violating the Constitution, may challenge the statute on the ground
that it conceivably may be applied unconstitutionally to others in
situations not before the Court. I agree with the Court's answer to
this question, but not with its method of analyzing the issue.
Before addressing that issue, I shall explain why respondent's
conviction does not violate the Constitution. The two films that
respondent sold contained nothing more than lewd exhibition; there
is no claim that the films included any material that had literary,
artistic, scientific, or educational value. [ Footnote 2/1 ] Respondent was a willing participant in a
commercial market that the State of New York has a legitimate
interest in suppressing. The character of the State's interest in
protecting children from sexual abuse justifies the imposition Page 458 U. S. 778 of criminal sanctions against those who profit, directly or
indirectly, from the promotion of such films. In this respect, my
evaluation of this case is different from the opinion I have
expressed concerning the imposition of criminal sanctions for the
promotion of obscenity in other contexts. [ Footnote 2/2 ]
A holding that respondent may be punished for selling these two
films does not require us to conclude that other users of these
very films, or that other motion pictures containing similar
scenes, are beyond the pale of constitutional protection. Thus, the
exhibition of these films before a legislative committee studying a
proposed amendment to a state law, or before a group of research
scientists studying human behavior, could not, in my opinion, be
made a crime. Moreover, it is at least conceivable that a serious
work of art, a documentary on behavioral problems, or a medical or
psychiatric teaching device, might include a scene from one of
these films and, when viewed as a whole in a proper setting, be
entitled to constitutional protection. The question whether a
specific act of communication is protected by the First Amendment
always requires some consideration of both its content and its
context.
The Court's holding that this respondent may not challenge New
York's statute as overbroad follows its discussion of the contours
of the category of nonobscene child pornography that New York may
legitimately prohibit. Having defined that category in an abstract
setting, [ Footnote 2/3 ] the Court
makes the Page 458 U. S. 779 empirical judgment that the arguably impermissible application
of the New York statute amounts to only a "tiny fraction of the
materials within the statute's reach." Ante at 458 U. S. 773 .
Even assuming that the Court's empirical analysis is sound,
[ Footnote 2/4 ] I believe a more
conservative approach to the issue would adequately vindicate the
State's interest in protecting its children and cause less harm to
the federal interest in free expression.
A hypothetical example will illustrate my concern. Assume that
the operator of a New York motion picture theater specializing in
the exhibition of foreign feature films is offered a full-length
movie containing one scene that is plainly lewd if viewed in
isolation, but that nevertheless is part of a serious work of art.
If the child actor resided abroad, New York's interest in
protecting its young from sexual exploitation would be far less
compelling than in the case before us. The federal interest in free
expression would, however, be just as strong as if an adult actor
had been used. There are at least three different ways to deal with
the statute's potential application to that sort of case.
First, at one extreme and as the Court appears to hold, the
First Amendment inquiry might be limited to determining Page 458 U. S. 780 whether the offensive scene, viewed in isolation, is lewd. When
the constitutional protection is narrowed in this drastic fashion,
the Court is probably safe in concluding that only a tiny fraction
of the materials covered by the New York statute is protected. And
with respect to my hypothetical exhibitor of foreign films, he need
have no uncertainty about the permissible application of the
statute; for the one lewd scene would deprive the entire film of
any constitutional protection.
Second, at the other extreme and as the New York Court of
Appeals correctly perceived, the application of this Court's cases
requiring that an obscenity determination be based on the artistic
value of a production, taken as a whole, would afford the exhibitor
constitutional protection, and result in a holding that the statute
is invalid because of its overbreadth. Under that approach, the
rationale for invalidating the entire statute is premised on the
concern that the exhibitor's understanding about its potential
reach could cause him to engage in self-censorship. This Court's
approach today substitutes broad, unambiguous, state-imposed
censorship for the self-censorship that an overbroad statute might
produce.
Third, as an intermediate position, I would refuse to apply
overbreadth analysis for reasons unrelated to any prediction
concerning the relative number of protected communications that the
statute may prohibit. Specifically, I would postpone decision of my
hypothetical case until it actually arises. Advocates of a liberal
use of overbreadth analysis could object to such postponement on
the ground that it creates the risk that the exhibitor's
uncertainty may produce self-censorship. But that risk obviously
interferes less with the interest in free expression than does an
abstract, advance ruling that the film is simply unprotected
whenever it contains a lewd scene, no matter how brief.
My reasons for avoiding overbreadth analysis in this case are
more qualitative than quantitative. When we follow our Page 458 U. S. 781 traditional practice of adjudicating difficult and novel
constitutional questions only in concrete factual situations, the
adjudications tend to be crafted with greater wisdom. Hypothetical
rulings are inherently treacherous, and prone to lead us into
unforeseen errors; they are qualitatively less reliable than the
products of case-by-case adjudication.
Moreover, it is probably safe to assume that the category of
speech that is covered by the New York statute generally is of a
lower quality than most other types of communication. On a number
of occasions, I have expressed the view that the First Amendment
affords some forms of speech more protection from governmental
regulation than other forms of speech. [ Footnote 2/5 ] Today the Court accepts this view, putting
the category of speech described in the New York statute in its
rightful place near the bottom of this hierarchy. Ante at 458 U. S.
761 -763. Although I disagree with the Court's position
that such speech is totally without First Amendment protection, I
agree that, generally, marginal speech does not warrant the
extraordinary protection afforded by the overbreadth doctrine.
[ Footnote 2/6 ]
Because I have no difficulty with the statute's application in
this case, I concur in the Court's judgment.
[ Footnote 2/1 ]
Respondent's counsel conceded at oral argument that a finding
that the films are obscene would have been consistent with the Miller definition. Tr. of Oral Arg. 41.
[ Footnote 2/2 ] See Burch v. Louisiana, 441 U.
S. 130 , 441 U. S. 139 (STEVENS, J., concurring); Pinkus v. United States, 436 U. S. 293 , 436 U. S. 305 (STEVENS, J., concurring); Ballew v. Georgia, 435 U.
S. 223 , 435 U. S. 245 (STEVENS, J., concurring); Smith v. United States, 431 U. S. 291 , 431 U. S.
311 -321 (STEVENS, J., dissenting); Marks v. United
States, 430 U. S. 188 , 430 U. S. 198 (STEVENS, J., concurring in part and dissenting in part); see
also Schad v. Borough of Mount Ephraim, 452 U. S.
61 , 452 U. S. 84 (STEVENS, J., concurring in judgment); FCC v. Pacifica
Foundation, 438 U. S. 726 , 438 U. S. 750 (opinion of STEVENS, J.).
[ Footnote 2/3 ]
"The test for child pornography is separate from the obscenity
standard enunciated in Miller, but may be compared to it
for the purpose of clarity. The Miller formulation is
adjusted in the following respects: a trier of fact need not find
that the material appeals to the prurient interest of the average
person; it is not required that sexual conduct portrayed be done so
in a patently offensive manner; and the material at issue need not
be considered as a whole." Ante at 458 U. S.
764 .
[ Footnote 2/4 ]
The Court's analysis is directed entirely at the permissibility
of the statute's coverage of nonobscene material. Its empirical
evidence, however, is drawn substantially from congressional
Committee Reports that ultimately reached the conclusion that a
prohibition against obscene child pornography -- coupled with
sufficiently stiff sanctions -- is an adequate response to this
social problem. The Senate Committee on the Judiciary concluded
that "virtually all of the materials that are normally considered
child pornography are obscene under the current standards," and
that,
"[i]n comparison with this blatant pornography, non-obscene
materials that depict children are very few and very
inconsequential."
S.Rep. No. 95-438, p. 13 (1977); see also H.R.Rep. No.
95-696, pp. 7-8 (1977). The coverage of the federal statute is
limited to obscene material. See 18 U.S.C. § 2252(a) (1976
ed., Supp. IV).
[ Footnote 2/5 ] See, e.g., Schad v. Borough of Mount Ephraim, 452 U.S.
at 452 U. S. 80 , 452 U. S. 83 (STEVENS, J., concurring in judgment); Consolidated Edison Co.
v. Public Service Comm'n, 447 U. S. 530 , 447 U. S.
544 -548 (STEVENS, J., concurring in judgment); FCC
v. Pacifica Foundation, 438 U.S. at 438 U. S.
744 -748 (opinion of STEVENS, J.); Carey v.
Population Services International, 431 U.
S. 678 , 431 U. S.
716 -717 (STEVENS, J., concurring in part and concurring
in judgment); Smith v. United States, 431 U.S. at 431 U. S.
317 -319 (STEVENS, J., dissenting); Young v. American
Mini Theatres, Inc., 427 U. S. 50 , 427 U. S. 66 -71
(opinion of STEVENS,J.).
[ Footnote 2/6 ] See FCC v. Pacifica Foundation, supra, at 438 U. S.
742 -743 (opinion of STEVENS, J.); Young v. American
Mini Theatres, Inc., supra, at 427 U. S. 59 -61; see also Metromedia, Inc. v. City of San Diego, 453 U. S. 490 , 453 U. S.
544 -548 (STEVENS, J., dissenting in part); Schad v.
Borough of Mount Ephraim, supra, at 452 U. S. 85 (STEVENS, J., concurring in judgment). | In New York v. Ferber (1982), the U.S. Supreme Court upheld a New York statute prohibiting the distribution of material depicting children engaged in sexual conduct, even if the material was not obscene. The Court recognized the harmful nature of child pornography and granted states greater leeway in regulating it. The Court balanced First Amendment rights with the welfare of children, concluding that the statute's focus on the distribution of such material was permissible due to the severe harm inflicted on children during its production. This decision established child pornography as a category of speech unprotected by the First Amendment. |
Free Speech | Miller v. California | https://supreme.justia.com/cases/federal/us/413/15/ | U.S. Supreme Court Miller v. California, 413 U.S.
15 (1973) Miller v. California No. 70-73 Argued January 18-19,
1972 Reargued November 7,
1972 Decided June 21, 1973 413 U.S.
15 APPEAL FROM THE APPELLATE
DEPARTMENT, SUPERIOR COURT OF CALIFORNIA, COUNTY OF
ORANGE Syllabus Appellant was convicted of mailing unsolicited sexually explicit
material in violation of a California statute that approximately
incorporated the obscenity test formulated in Memoirs v.
Massachusetts, 383 U. S. 413 , 383 U. S. 418 (plurality opinion). The trial court instructed the jury to
evaluate the materials by the contemporary community standards of
California. Appellant's conviction was affirmed on appeal. In lieu
of the obscenity criteria enunciated by the Memoirs plurality, it is held: 1. Obscene material is not protected by the First Amendment. Roth v. United States, 354 U. S. 476 ,
reaffirmed. A work may be subject to state regulation where that
work, taken as a whole, appeals to the prurient interest in sex;
portrays, in a patently offensive way, sexual conduct specifically
defined by the applicable state law; and, taken as a whole, does
not have serious literary, artistic, political, or scientific
value. Pp. 413 U. S.
23 -24.
2. The basic guidelines for the trier of fact must be: (a)
whether "the average person, applying contemporary community
standards" would find that the work, taken as a whole, appeals to
the prurient interest, Roth, supra, at 354 U. S. 489 ,
(b) whether the work depicts or describes, in a patently offensive
way, sexual conduct specifically defined by the applicable state
law, and (c) whether the work, taken as a whole, lacks serious
literary, artistic, political, or scientific value. If a state
obscenity law is thus limited, First Amendment values are
adequately protected by ultimate independent appellate review of
constitutional claims when necessary. Pp. 413 U. S.
24 -25.
3. The test of "utterly without redeeming social value"
articulated in Memoirs, supra, is rejected as a
constitutional standard. Pp. 413 U. S.
24 -25.
4. The jury may measure the essentially factual issues of
prurient appeal and patent offensiveness by the standard that
prevails in the forum community, and need not employ a "national
standard." Pp. 413 U. S.
30 -34.
Vacated and remanded. Page 413 U. S. 16 BURGER, C.J., delivered the opinion of the Court, in which
WHITE, BLACKMUN, POWELL, and REHNQUIST, JJ., joined. DOUGLAS, J.,
filed a dissenting opinion, post, p. 413 U. S. 37 .
BRENNAN, J., filed a dissenting opinion, in which STEWART and
MARSHALL, JJ., joined, post, p. 413 U. S.
47 .
MR. CHIEF JUSTICE BURGER delivered the opinion of the Court.
This is one of a group of "obscenity-pornography" cases being
reviewed by the Court in a reexamination of standards enunciated in
earlier cases involving what Mr. Justice Harlan called "the
intractable obscenity problem." Interstate Circuit, Inc. v.
Dallas, 390 U. S. 676 , 390 U. S. 704 (1968) (concurring and dissenting).
Appellant conducted a mass mailing campaign to advertise the
sale of illustrated books, euphemistically called "adult" material.
After a jury trial, he was convicted of violating California Penal
Code § 311.2(a), a misdemeanor, by knowingly distributing obscene
matter, [ Footnote 1 ] Page 413 U. S. 17 and the Appellate Department, Superior Court of California,
County of Orange, summarily affirmed the judgment without opinion.
Appellant's conviction was specifically Page 413 U. S. 18 based on his conduct in causing five unsolicited advertising
brochures to be sent through the mail in an envelope addressed to a
restaurant in Newport Beach, California. The envelope was opened by
the manager of the restaurant and his mother. They had not
requested the brochures; they complained to the police.
The brochures advertise four books entitled "Intercourse,"
"Man-Woman," "Sex Orgies Illustrated," and "An Illustrated History
of Pornography," and a film entitled "Marital Intercourse." While
the brochures contain some descriptive printed material, primarily
they consist of pictures and drawings very explicitly depicting men
and women in groups of two or more engaging in a variety of sexual
activities, with genitals often prominently displayed. I This case involves the application of a State's criminal
obscenity statute to a situation in which sexually explicit
materials have been thrust by aggressive sales action upon
unwilling recipients who had in no way indicated any desire to
receive such materials. This Court has recognized that the States
have a legitimate interest in prohibiting dissemination or
exhibition of obscene material [ Footnote 2 ] Page 413 U. S. 19 when the mode of dissemination carries with it a significant
danger of offending the sensibilities of unwilling recipients or of
exposure to juveniles. Stanley v. Georgia, 394 U.
S. 557 , 394 U. S. 567 (1969); Ginsberg v. New York, 390 U.
S. 629 , 390 U. S.
637 -643 (1968); Interstate Circuit, Inc. v. Dallas,
supra, at 390 U. S. 690 ; Redrup v. New York, 386 U. S. 767 , 386 U. S. 769 (1967); Jacobellis v. Ohio, 378 U.
S. 184 , 378 U. S. 195 (1964). See Rabe v. Washington, 405 U.
S. 313 , 405 U. S. 317 (1972) (BURGER, C.J., concurring); United States v.
Reidel, 402 U. S. 351 , 402 U. S.
360 -362 (1971) (opinion of MARSHALL, J.); Joseph
Burstyn, Inc. v. Wilson, 343 U. S. 495 , 343 U. S. 502 (1952); Breard v. Alexandria, 341 U.
S. 622 , 341 U. S. 644 645 (1951); Kovacs v. Cooper, 336 U. S.
77 , 336 U. S. 88 -89
(1949); Prince v. Massachusetts, 321 U.
S. 158 , 321 U. S.
169 -170 (1944). Cf. Butler v. Michigan, 352 U. S. 380 , 352 U. S.
382 -383 (1957); Public Utilities Comm'n v.
Pollak, 343 U. S. 451 , 343 U. S.
464 -465 (1952) It is in this context that we are
called Page 413 U. S. 20 on to define the standards which must be used to identify
obscene material that a State may regulate without infringing on
the First Amendment as applicable to the States through the
Fourteenth Amendment.
The dissent of MR. JUSTICE BRENNAN reviews the background of the
obscenity problem, but since the Court now undertakes to formulate
standards more concrete than those in the past, it is useful for us
to focus on two of the landmark cases in the somewhat tortured
history of the Court's obscenity decisions. In Roth v. United
States, 354 U. S. 476 (1957), the Court sustained a conviction under a federal statute
punishing the mailing of "obscene, lewd, lascivious or filthy . .
." materials. The key to that holding was the Court's rejection of
the claim that obscene materials were protected by the First
Amendment. Five Justices joined in the opinion stating:
"All ideas having even the slightest redeeming social importance
-- unorthodox ideas, controversial ideas, even ideas hateful to the
prevailing climate of opinion -- have the full protection of the
[First Amendment] guaranties, unless excludable because they
encroach upon the limited area of more important interests. But
implicit in the history of the First Amendment is the rejection of
obscenity as utterly without redeeming social importance. . . .
This is the same judgment expressed by this Court in Chaplinsky
v. New Hampshire, 315 U. S. 568 , 315 U. S.
571 -572: "
". . . There are certain well defined and narrowly limited
classes of speech, the prevention and punishment of which have
never been thought to raise any Constitutional problem. These
include the lewd and obscene. . . . It has been well observed that
such utterances are no essential part of any exposition of ideas,
and are of such slight social Page 413 U. S. 21 value as a step to truth that any benefit that may be
derived from them is clearly outweighed by the social interest in
order and morality. . . ."
[Emphasis by Court in Roth opinion.]
"We hold that obscenity is not within the area of
constitutionally protected speech or press."
354 U.S. at 354 U. S. 48 85
(footnotes omitted).
Nine years later, in Memoirs v. Massachusetts, 383 U. S. 413 (1966), the Court veered sharply away from the Roth concept and, with only three Justices in the plurality opinion,
articulated a new test of obscenity. The plurality held that, under
the Roth definition,
"as elaborated in subsequent cases, three elements must
coalesce: it must be established that (a) the dominant theme of the
material, taken as a whole, appeals to a prurient interest in sex;
(b) the material is patently offensive because it affronts
contemporary community standards relating to the description or
representation of sexual matters; and (c) the material is utterly
without redeeming social value." Id. at 383 U. S. 418 .
The sharpness of the break with Roth, represented by the
third element of the Memoirs test and emphasized by MR.
JUSTICE WHITE's dissent, id. at 383 U. S.
460 -462, was further underscored when the Memoirs plurality went on to state:
"The Supreme Judicial Court erred in holding that a book need
not be 'unqualifiedly worthless before it can be deemed obscene.' A
book cannot be proscribed unless it is found to be utterly without redeeming social value." Id. at 383 U. S. 419 (emphasis in original).
While Roth presumed "obscenity" to be "utterly without
redeeming social importance," Memoirs required Page 413 U. S. 22 that to prove obscenity it must be affirmatively established
that the material is " utterly without redeeming social
value." Thus, even as they repeated the words of Roth, the Memoirs plurality produced a drastically altered test that
called on the prosecution to prove a negative, i.e., that
the material was " utterly without redeeming social value"
-- a burden virtually impossible to discharge under our criminal
standards of proof. Such considerations caused Mr. Justice Harlan
to wonder if the " utterly without redeeming social value"
test had any meaning at all. See Memoirs v. Massachusetts,
id. at 383 U. S. 459 (Harlan, J., dissenting). See also id. at 383 U. S. 461 (WHITE, J., dissenting); United States v. Groner, 479 F.2d
577, 579581 (CA5 1973).
Apart from the initial formulation in the Roth case, no
majority of the Court has at any given time been able to agree on a
standard to determine what constitutes obscene, pornographic
material subject to regulation under the States' police power. See, e.g., Redrup v. New York, 386 U.S. at 386 U. S.
770 -771. We have seen "a variety of views among the
members of the Court unmatched in any other course of
constitutional adjudication." Interstate Circuit, Inc. v.
Dallas, 390 U.S. at 390 U. S.
704 -705 (Harlan, J., concurring and dissenting)
(footnote omitted). [ Footnote
3 ] This is not remarkable, for in the area Page 413 U. S. 23 of freedom of speech and press the courts must always remain
sensitive to any infringement on genuinely serious literary,
artistic, political, or scientific expression. This is an area in
which there are few eternal verities.
The case we now review was tried on the theory that the
California Penal Code § 311 approximately incorporates the
three-stage Memoirs test, supra. But now the Memoirs test has been abandoned as unworkable by its
author, [ Footnote 4 ] and no
Member of the Court today supports the Memoirs formulation. II This much has been categorically settled by the Court, that
obscene material is unprotected by the First Amendment. Kois v.
Wisconsin, 408 U. S. 229 (1972); United States v. Reidel, 402 U.S. at 402 U. S. 354 ; Roth v. United States, supra, at 354 U. S. 485 .
[ Footnote 5 ] "The First and
Fourteenth Amendments have never been treated as absolutes
[footnote omitted]." Breard v. Alexandria, 341 U.S. at 341 U. S. 642 ,
and cases cited. See Times Film Corp. v. Chicago, 365 U. S. 43 , 365 U. S. 47 -50
(1961); Joseph Burstyn, Inc. v. Wilson, 343 U.S. at 343 U. S. 502 .
We acknowledge, however, the inherent dangers of undertaking to
regulate any form of expression. State statutes designed to
regulate obscene materials must be Page 413 U. S. 24 carefully limited. See Interstate Circuit, Inc. v. Dallas,
supra, at 390 U. S.
682 -685. As a result, we now confine the permissible
scope of such regulation to works which depict or describe sexual
conduct. That conduct must be specifically defined by the
applicable state law, as written or authoritatively construed.
[ Footnote 6 ] A state offense
must also be limited to works which, taken as a whole, appeal to
the prurient interest in sex, which portray sexual conduct in a
patently offensive way, and which, taken as a whole, do not have
serious literary, artistic, political, or scientific value.
The basic guidelines for the trier of fact must be: (a) whether
"the average person, applying contemporary community standards"
would find that the work, taken as a whole, appeals to the prurient
interest, Kois v. Wisconsin, supra, at 408 U. S. 230 ,
quoting Roth v. United States, supra, at 354 U. S. 489 ;
(b) whether the work depicts or describes, in a patently offensive
way, sexual conduct specifically defined by the applicable state
law; and (c) whether the work, taken as a whole, lacks serious
literary, artistic, political, or scientific value. We do not adopt
as a constitutional standard the "utterly without redeeming social
value" test of Memoirs v. Massachusetts, Page 413 U. S. 25 383 U.S. at 383 U. S. 419 ;
that concept has never commanded the adherence of more than three
Justices at one time. [ Footnote
7 ] See supra at 413 U. S. 21 . If
a state law that regulates obscene material is thus limited, as
written or construed, the First Amendment values applicable to the
States through the Fourteenth Amendment are adequately protected by
the ultimate power of appellate courts to conduct an independent
review of constitutional claims when necessary. See Kois v.
Wisconsin, supra, at 408 U. S. 232 ; Memoirs v. Massachusetts, supra, at 383 U. S.
459 -460 (Harlan, J., dissenting); Jacobellis v.
Ohio, 378 U.S. at 204 (Harlan, J., dissenting); New York
Times Co. v. Sullivan, 376 U. S. 254 , 376 U. S.
284 -285 (1964); Roth v. United States, supra, at 354 U. S.
497 -498 (Harlan, J., concurring and dissenting).
We emphasize that it is not our function to propose regulatory
schemes for the States. That must await their concrete legislative
efforts. It is possible, however, to give a few plain examples of
what a state statute could define for regulation under part (b) of
the standard announced in this opinion, supra: (a) Patently offensive representations or descriptions of
ultimate sexual acts, normal or perverted, actual or simulated.
(b) Patently offensive representations or descriptions of
masturbation, excretory functions, and lewd exhibition of the
genitals.
Sex and nudity may not be exploited without limit by films or
pictures exhibited or sold in places of public accommodation any
more than live sex and nudity can Page 413 U. S. 26 be exhibited or sold without limit in such public places.
[ Footnote 8 ] At a minimum,
prurient, patently offensive depiction or description of sexual
conduct must have serious literary, artistic, political, or
scientific value to merit First Amendment protection. See Kois
v. Wisconsin, supra, at 408 U. S.
230 -232; Roth v. United States, supra, at 354 U. S. 487 ; Thornhill v. Alabama, 310 U. S. 88 , 310 U. S.
101 -102 (1940). For example, medical books for the
education of physicians and related personnel necessarily use
graphic illustrations and descriptions of human anatomy. In
resolving the inevitably sensitive questions of fact and law, we
must continue to rely on the jury system, accompanied by the
safeguards that judges, rules of evidence, presumption of
innocence, and other protective features provide, as we do with
rape, murder, and a host of other offenses against society and its
individual members. [ Footnote
9 ]
MR. JUSTICE BRENNAN, author of the opinions of the Court, or the
plurality opinions, in Roth v. United States, supra; Jacobellis
v. Ohio, supra; Ginzburg v. United Page 413 U. S. 27 States, 383 U. S. 463 (1966), Mishkin v. New York, 383 U.
S. 502 (1966); and Memoirs v. Massachusetts,
supra, has abandoned his former position and now maintains
that no formulation of this Court, the Congress, or the States can
adequately distinguish obscene material unprotected by the First
Amendment from protected expression, Paris Adult Theatre I v.
Slaton, post, p. 413 U. S. 73 (BRENNAN, J., dissenting). Paradoxically, MR. JUSTICE BRENNAN
indicates that suppression of unprotected obscene material is
permissible to avoid exposure to unconsenting adults, as in this
case, and to juveniles, although he gives no indication of how the
division between protected and nonprotected materials may be drawn
with greater precision for these purposes than for regulation of
commercial exposure to consenting adults only. Nor does he indicate
where in the Constitution he finds the authority to distinguish
between a willing "adult" one month past the state law age of
majority and a willing "juvenile" one month younger.
Under the holdings announced today, no one will be subject to
prosecution for the sale or exposure of obscene materials unless
these materials depict or describe patently offensive "hard core"
sexual conduct specifically defined by the regulating state law, as
written or construed. We are satisfied that these specific
prerequisites will provide fair notice to a dealer in such
materials that his public and commercial activities may bring
prosecution. See Roth v. United States, supra, at 354 U. S.
491 -492. Cf. Ginsberg v. New York, 390 U.S. at 390 U. S. 643 .
[ Footnote 10 ] If Page 413 U. S. 28 the inability to define regulated materials with ultimate,
god-like precision altogether removes the power of the States or
the Congress to regulate, then "hard core" pornography may be
exposed without limit to the juvenile, the passerby, and the
consenting adult alike, as, indeed, MR. JUSTICE DOUGLAS contends.
As to MR. JUSTICE DOUGLAS' position, see United States v.
Thirty-seven Photographs, 402 U. S. 363 , 402 U. S.
379 -380 (1971) (Black, J., joined by DOUGLAS, J.,
dissenting); Ginzburg v. United States, supra, at 383 U. S. 476 , 383 U. S.
491 -492 (Black, J., and DOUGLAS, J., dissenting); Jacobellis v. Ohio, supra, at 378 U. S. 196 (Black, J., joined by DOUGLAS, J., concurring); Roth,
supra, at 354 U. S.
508 -514 (DOUGLAS, J., dissenting). In this belief,
however, MR. JUSTICE DOUGLAS now stands alone.
MR. JUSTICE BRENNAN also emphasizes "institutional stress" in
justification of his change of view. Noting that "[t]he number of
obscenity cases on our docket gives ample testimony to the burden
that has been placed upon this Court," he quite rightly remarks
that the examination of contested materials "is hardly a source of
edification to the members of this Court." Paris Adult Page 413 U. S. 29 Theatre I v. Slaton, post, at 413 U. S. 92 , 413 U. S. 93 . He
also notes, and we agree, that "uncertainty of the standards
creates a continuing source of tension between state and federal
courts. . . ."
"The problem is . . . that one cannot say with certainty that
material is obscene until at least five members of this Court,
applying inevitably obscure standards, have pronounced it so." Id. at 413 U. S. 93 , 413 U. S.
92 .
It is certainly true that the absence, since Roth, of a
single majority view of this Court as to proper standards for
testing obscenity has placed a strain on both state and federal
courts. But today, for the first time since Roth was
decided in 1957, a majority of this Court has agreed on concrete
guidelines to isolate "hard core" pornography from expression
protected by the First Amendment. Now we may abandon the casual
practice of Redrup v. New York, 386 U.
S. 767 (1967), and attempt to provide positive guidance
to federal and state courts alike.
This may not be an easy road, free from difficulty. But no
amount of "fatigue" should lead us to adopt a convenient
"institutional" rationale -- an absolutist, "anything goes" view of
the First Amendment -- because it will lighten our burdens.
[ Footnote 11 ] "Such an
abnegation of judicial supervision in this field would be
inconsistent with our duty to uphold the constitutional
guarantees." Jacobellis v. Ohio, supra, at 378 U. S.
187 -188 (opinion of BRENNAN, J.). Nor should we remedy
"tension between state and federal courts" by arbitrarily depriving
the States of a power reserved to them under the Constitution, a
power which they have enjoyed and exercised continuously from
before the adoption of the First Amendment to this day. See
Roth v. United States, supra, at 354 U. S.
482 -485.
"Our duty admits of no 'substitute for facing up Page 413 U. S. 30 to the tough individual problems of constitutional judgment
involved in every obscenity case.' [ Roth v. United States,
supra, at 354 U. S. 498 ]; see
Manual Enterprises, Inc. v. Day, 370 U. S.
478 , 370 U. S. 488 (opinion of
Harlan, J.) [footnote omitted]." Jacobellis v. Ohio, supra, at 378 U. S. 188 (opinion of BRENNAN, J.). III Under a National Constitution, fundamental First Amendment
limitations on the powers of the States do not vary from community
to community, but this does not mean that there are, or should or
can be, fixed, uniform national standards of precisely what appeals
to the "prurient interest" or is "patently offensive." These are
essentially questions of fact, and our Nation is simply too big and
too diverse for this Court to reasonably expect that such standards
could be articulated for all 50 States in a single formulation,
even assuming the prerequisite consensus exists. When triers of
fact are asked to decide whether "the average person, applying
contemporary community standards" would consider certain materials
"prurient," it would be unrealistic to require that the answer be
based on some abstract formulation. The adversary system, with lay
jurors as the usual ultimate factfinders in criminal prosecutions,
has historically permitted triers of fact to draw on the standards
of their community, guided always by limiting instructions on the
law. To require a State to structure obscenity proceedings around
evidence of a national "community standard" would be an
exercise in futility.
As noted before, this case was tried on the theory that the
California obscenity statute sought to incorporate the tripartite
test of Memoirs. This, a "national" standard of First
Amendment protection enumerated by a plurality of this Court, was
correctly regarded at the time of trial as limiting state
prosecution under the controlling case Page 413 U. S. 31 law. The jury, however, was explicitly instructed that, in
determining whether the "dominant theme of the material as a whole
. . . appeals to the prurient interest," and, in determining
whether the material "goes substantially beyond customary limits of
candor and affronts contemporary community standards of decency,"
it was to apply "contemporary community standards of the State of
California."
During the trial, both the prosecution and the defense assumed
that the relevant "community standards" in making the factual
determination of obscenity were those of the State of California,
not some hypothetical standard of the entire United States of
America. Defense counsel at trial never objected to the testimony
of the State's expert on community standards [ Footnote 12 ] or to the instructions of the trial
judge on "state-wide" standards. On appeal to the Appellate
Department, Superior Court of California, County of Orange,
appellant for the first time contended that application of state,
rather than national, standards violated the First and Fourteenth
Amendments.
We conclude that neither the State's alleged failure to offer
evidence of "national standards," nor the trial court's charge that
the jury consider state community standards, were constitutional
errors. Nothing in the First Amendment requires that a jury must
consider hypothetical and unascertainable "national standards" when
attempting to determine whether certain materials are obscene as a
matter Page 413 U. S. 32 of fact. Mr. Chief Justice Warren pointedly commented in his
dissent in Jacobellis v. Ohio, supra, at 378 U. S.
200 :
"It is my belief that, when the Court said in Roth that
obscenity is to be defined by reference to 'community standards,'
it meant community standards -- not a national standard, as is
sometimes argued. I believe that there is no provable 'national
standard.' . . . At all events, this Court has not been able to
enunciate one, and it would be unreasonable to expect local courts
to divine one."
It is neither realistic nor constitutionally sound to read the
First Amendment as requiring that the people of Maine or
Mississippi accept public depiction of conduct found tolerable in
Las Vegas, or New York City. [ Footnote 13 ] Page 413 U. S. 33 See Hoyt v. Minnesota, 399
U.S. at 524 -525 (1970) (BLACKMUN, J., dissenting); Walker
v. Ohio, 398 U.S. at
434 (1970) (BURGER, C.J., dissenting); id. at 434-435
(Harlan, J., dissenting); Cain v. Kentucky, 397 U.
S. 319 (1970) (BURGER, C.J., dissenting); id. at 397 U. S. 319 -320
(Harlan, J., dissenting); United States v. Groner, 479
F.2d at 581-583; O'Meara & Shaffer, Obscenity in The Supreme
Court: A Note on Jacobellis v. Ohio, 40 Notre Dame Law. 1,
6-7 (1964). See also Memoirs v. Massachusetts, 383 U.S. at 383 U. S. 458 (Harlan, J., dissenting); Jacobellis v. Ohio, supra, at 378 U. S.
203 -204 (Harlan, J., dissenting); Roth v. United
States, supra, at 354 U. S.
505 -506 (Harlan, J., concurring and dissenting). People
in different States vary in their tastes and attitudes, and this
diversity is not to be strangled by the absolutism of imposed
uniformity. As the Court made clear in Mishkin v. New
York, 383 U.S. at 383 U. S.
508 -509, the primary concern with requiring a jury to
apply the standard of "the average person, applying contemporary
community standards" is to be certain that, so far as material is
not aimed at a deviant group, it will be judged by its impact on an
average person, rather than a particularly susceptible or sensitive
person -- or indeed a totally insensitive one. See Roth v.
United States, supra, at 354 U. S. 489 . Cf. the now discredited test in Regina v.
Hicklin, [1868] L.R. 3 Q.B. 360. We hold that the requirement
that the jury evaluate the materials with reference to
"contemporary Page 413 U. S. 34 standards of the State of California" serves this protective
purpose and is constitutionally adequate. [ Footnote 14 ] IV The dissenting Justices sound the alarm of repression. But, in
our view, to equate the free and robust exchange of ideas and
political debate with commercial exploitation of obscene material
demeans the grand conception of the First Amendment and its high
purposes in the historic struggle for freedom. It is a "misuse of
the great guarantees of free speech and free press. . . ." Breard v. Alexandria, 341 U.S. at 341 U. S. 645 .
The First Amendment protects works which, taken as a whole, have
serious literary, artistic, political, or scientific value,
regardless of whether the government or a majority of the people
approve of the ideas these works represent.
"The protection given speech and press was fashioned to assure
unfettered interchange of ideas for the bringing about
of Page 413 U. S. 35 political and social changes desired by the people," Roth v. United States, supra, at 354 U. S. 484 (emphasis added). See Kois v. Wisconsin, 408 U.S. at 408 U. S.
230 -232; Thornhill v. Alabama, 310 U.S. at 310 U. S.
101 -102. But the public portrayal of hard-core sexual
conduct for its own sake, and for the ensuing commercial gain, is a
different matter. [ Footnote
15 ]
There is no evidence, empirical or historical, that the stern
19th century American censorship of public distribution and display
of material relating to sex, see Roth v. United States,
supra, at 354 U. S.
482 -485, in any way limited or affected expression of
serious literary, artistic, political, or scientific ideas. On the
contrary, it is beyond any question that the era following Thomas
Jefferson to Theodore Roosevelt was an "extraordinarily vigorous
period" not just in economics and politics, but in belles
lettres and in "the outlying fields of social and political
philosophies." [ Footnote 16 ]
We do not see the harsh hand Page 413 U. S. 36 of censorship of ideas -- good or bad, sound or unsound -- and
"repression" of political liberty lurking in every state regulation
of commercial exploitation of human interest in sex.
MR. JUSTICE BRENNAN finds "it is hard to see how state-ordered
regimentation of our minds can ever be forestalled." Paris
Adult Theatre I v. Slaton, post, at 413 U. S. 110 (BRENNAN, J., dissenting). These doleful anticipations assume that
courts cannot distinguish commerce in ideas, protected by the First
Amendment, from commercial exploitation of obscene material.
Moreover, state regulation of hard-core pornography so as to make
it unavailable to nonadults, a regulation which MR. JUSTICE BRENNAN
finds constitutionally permissible, has all the elements of
"censorship" for adults; indeed even more rigid enforcement
techniques may be called for with such dichotomy of regulation. See Interstate Circuit, Inc. v. Dallas, 390 U.S. at 390 U. S. 690 .
[ Footnote 17 ] One can
concede that the "sexual revolution" of recent years may have had
useful byproducts in striking layers of prudery from a subject long
irrationally kept from needed ventilation. But it does not follow
that no regulation of patently offensive "hard core" materials is
needed or permissible; civilized people do not allow unregulated
access to heroin because it is a derivative of medicinal
morphlne.
In sum, we (a) reaffirm the Roth holding that obscene
material is not protected by the First Amendment; (b) hold that
such material can be regulated by the States, subject to the
specific safeguards enunciated Page 413 U. S. 37 above, without a showing that the material is "utterly without
redeeming social value"; and (c) hold that obscenity is to be
determined by applying "contemporary community standards," see
Kois v. Wisconsin, supra, at 408 U. S. 230 ,
and Roth v. United States, supra, at 354 U. S. 489 ,
not "national standards." The judgment of the Appellate Department
of the Superior Court, Orange County, California, is vacated and
the case remanded to that court for further proceedings not
inconsistent with the First Amendment standards established by this
opinion. See United States v. 12 200-ft. Reels of Film,
post at 413 U. S. 130 n. 7. Vacated and remanded. [ Footnote 1 ]
At the time of the commission of the alleged offense, which was
prior to June 25, 1969, §§ 311.2(a) and 311 of the California Penal
Code read in relevant part:
"§ 311.2 Sending or bringing into state for sale or
distribution; printing, exhibiting, distributing or possessing
within state"
"(a) Every person who knowingly: sends or causes to be sent, or
brings or causes to be brought, into this state for sale or
distribution, or in this state prepares, publishes, prints,
exhibits, distributes, or offers to distribute, or has in his
possession with intent to distribute or to exhibit or offer to
distribute, any obscene matter is guilty of a misdemeanor. . .
."
"§ 311. Definitions"
"As used in this chapter: "
"(a) 'Obscene' means that to the average person, applying
contemporary standards, the predominant appeal of the matter, taken
as a whole, is to prurient interest, i.e., a shameful or morbid
interest in nudity, sex, or excretion, which goes substantially
beyond customary limits of candor in description or representation
of such matters and is matter which is utterly without redeeming
social importance."
"(b) 'Matter' means any book, magazine, newspaper, or other
printed or written material or any picture, drawing, photograph,
motion picture, or other pictorial representation or any statue or
other figure, or any recording, transcription or mechanical,
chemical or electrical reproduction or any other articles,
equipment, machines or materials."
"(c) 'Person' means any individual, partnership, firm,
association, corporation, or other legal entity."
"(d) 'Distribute' means to transfer possession of, whether with
or without consideration."
"(e) 'Knowingly' means having knowledge that the matter is
obscene."
Section 311(e) of the California Penal Code, supra, was
amended on June 25, 1969, to read as follows:
"(e) 'Knowingly' means being aware of the character of the
matter."
Cal. Amended Stats.1969, c. 249, § 1, p. 598. Despite
appellant's contentions to the contrary, the record indicates that
the new § 311(e) was not applied ex post facto to his
case, but only the old § 311(e) as construed by state decisions
prior to the commission of the alleged offense. See People v.
Pinkus, 256 Cal. App. 2d 941, 948-950, 63 Cal. Rptr. 680,
685-686 (App. Dept., Superior Ct., Los Angeles, 1967); People
v. Campise, 242 Cal. App. 2d 905, 914, 51 Cal. Rptr. 815, 821
(App.Dept., Superior Ct., San Diego, 1966). Cf. Bouie v. City
of Columbia, 378 U. S. 347 (1964). Nor did § 311.2, supra, as applied, create any
"direct, immediate burden on the performance of the postal
functions," or infringe on congressional commerce powers under Art.
I, § 8, cl. 3. Roth v. United States, 354 U.
S. 476 , 354 U. S. 494 (1957), quoting Railway Mail Assn. v. Corsi, 326 U. S.
88 , 326 U. S. 96 (1945). See also Mishkin v. New York, 383 U.
S. 502 , 383 U. S. 506 (1966); Smith v. California, 361 U.
S. 147 , 361 U. S.
150 -152 (1959).
[ Footnote 2 ]
This Court has defined "obscene material" as "material which
deals with sex in a manner appealing to prurient interest," Roth v. United States, supra, at 354 U. S. 487 ,
but the Roth definition does not reflect the precise
meaning of "obscene" as traditionally used in the English language.
Derived from the Latin obscaenus ob, to, plus caenum, filth, "obscene" is defined in the Webster's Third
New International Dictionary (Unabridged 1969) as
"1a: disgusting to the senses . . . b: grossly repugnant to the
generally accepted notions of what is appropriate . . . 2:
offensive or revolting as countering or violating some ideal or
principle."
The Oxford English Dictionary (1933 ed.) gives a similar
definition, "[o]ffensive to the senses, or to taste or refinement;
disgusting, repulsive, filthy, foul, abominable, loathsome."
The material we are discussing in this case is more accurately
defined as "pornography" or "pornographic material." "Pornography"
derives from the Greek (porne, harlot, and graphos, writing). The
word now means
"1: a description of prostitutes or prostitution 2: a depiction
(as in writing or painting) of licentiousness or lewdness: a
portrayal of erotic behavior designed to cause sexual
excitement."
Webster's Third New International Dictionary, supra. Pornographic material which is obscene forms a sub-group of all
"obscene" expression, but not the whole, at least as the word
"obscene" is now used in our language. We note, therefore, that the
words "obscene material," as used in this case, have a specific
judicial meaning which derives from the Roth case, i.e., obscene material "which deals with sex." Roth,
supra, at 354 U. S. 487 . See also ALI Model Penal Code § 251.4(1) "Obscene
Defined." (Official Draft 1962.)
[ Footnote 3 ]
In the absence of a majority view, this Court was compelled to
embark on the practice of summarily reversing convictions for the
dissemination of materials that, at least five members of the
Court, applying their separate tests, found to be protected by the
First Amendment. Redrup v. New York, 386 U.
S. 767 (1967). Thirty-one cases have been decided in
this manner. Beyond the necessity of circumstances, however, no
justification has ever been offered in support of the Redrup "policy." See Walker v. Ohio, 398 U.S. at 398 U. S. 434 -435
(1970) (dissenting opinions of BURGER, C.J., and Harlan, J.). The Redrup procedure has cast us in the role of an
unreviewable board of censorship for the 50 States, subjectively
judging each piece of material brought before us.
[ Footnote 4 ] See the dissenting opinion of MR. JUSTICE BRENNAN in Paris Adult Theatre I v. Slaton, post, p. 413 U. S.
73 .
[ Footnote 5 ]
As Mr. Chief Justice Warren stated, dissenting, in Jacobellis v. Ohio, 378 U. S. 184 , 378 U. S. 200 (1964):
"For all the sound and fury that the Roth test has
generated, it has not been proved unsound, and I believe that we
should try to live with it -- at least until a more satisfactory
definition is evolved. No government -- be it federal, state, or
local -- should be forced to choose between repressing all
material, including that within the realm of decency, and allowing
unrestrained license to publish any material, no matter how vile.
There must be a rule of reason in this as in other areas of the
law, and we have attempted in the Roth case to provide
such a rule."
[ Footnote 6 ] See, e.g., Oregon Laws 1971, c. 743, Art. 29, §§
255-262, and Hawaii Penal Code, Tit. 37, §§ 1210-1216, 1972 Hawaii
Session Laws, Act 9, c. 12, pt.. II, pp. 126-129, as examples of
state laws directed at depiction of defined physical conduct, as
opposed to expression. Other state formulations could be equally
valid in this respect. In giving the Oregon and Hawaii statutes as
examples, we do not wish to be understood as approving of them in
all other respects nor as establishing their limits as the extent
of state power.
We do not hold, as MR. JUSTICE BRENNAN intimates, that all
States other than Oregon must now enact new obscenity statutes.
Other existing state statutes, as construed heretofore or
hereafter, may well be adequate. See United States v. 12
200-ft. Reel of Film, post, at 413 U. S. 130 n. 7.
[ Footnote 7 ]
"A quotation from Voltaire in the flyleaf of a book will not
constitutionally redeem an otherwise obscene publication. . . ." Kois v. Wisconsin, 408 U. S. 229 , 408 U. S. 231 (1972). See Memoirs v. Massachusetts, 383 U.
S. 413 , 383 U. S. 461 (1966) (WHITE, J., dissenting). We also reject, as a constitutional
standard, the ambiguous concept of "social importance." See
id. at 383 U. S. 462 (WHITE, J., dissenting).
[ Footnote 8 ]
Although we are not presented here with the problem of
regulating lewd public conduct itself, the States have greater
power to regulate nonverbal, physical conduct than to suppress
depictions or descriptions of the same behavior. In United
States v. O'Brien, 391 U. S. 367 , 391 U. S. 377 (1968), a case not dealing with obscenity, the Court held a State
regulation of conduct which itself embodied both speech and
nonspeech elements to be
"sufficiently justified if . . . it furthers an important or
substantial governmental interest; if the governmental interest is
unrelated to the suppression of free expression; and if the
incidental restriction on alleged First Amendment freedoms is no
greater than is essential to the furtherance of that interest." See California v. LaRue, 409 U.
S. 109 , 409 U. S.
117 -118 (1972).
[ Footnote 9 ]
The mere fact juries may reach different conclusions as to the
same material does not mean that constitutional rights are
abridged. As this Court observed in Roth v. United States, 354 U.S. at 354 U. S. 492 n. 30,
"it is common experience that different juries may reach
different results under any criminal statute. That is one of the
consequences we accept under our jury system. Cf. Dunlop v.
United States, 165 U. S. 486 , 165 U. S.
499 -500."
[ Footnote 10 ]
As MR. JUSTICE BRENNAN stated for the Court in Roth v.
United States, supra at 354 U. S.
491 -492:
"Many decisions have recognized that these terms of obscenity
statutes are not precise. [Footnote omitted.] This Court, however,
has consistently held that lack of precision is not itself
offensive to the requirements of due process. '. . . [T]he
Constitution does not require impossible standards;' all that is
required is that the language 'conveys sufficiently definite
warning as to the proscribed conduct when measured by common
understanding and practices. . . .' United States v.
Petrillo, 332 U. S. 1 , 332 U. S.
7 -8. These words, applied according to the proper
standard for judging obscenity, already discussed, give adequate
warning of the conduct proscribed and mark"
". . . boundaries sufficiently distinct for judges and juries
fairly to administer the law. . . . That there may be marginal
cases in which it is difficult to determine the side of the line on
which a particular fact situation falls is no sufficient reason to
hold the language too ambiguous to define a criminal offense. . .
."
" Id. at 332 U. S. 7 . See also United
States v. Harriss, 347 U. S. 612 , 347 U. S.
624 , n. 15; Boyce Motor Lines, Inc. v. United
States, 342 U. S. 337 , 342 U. S.
340 ; United States v. Ragen, 314 U. S.
513 , 314 U. S. 523 -524; United States v. Wurzbach, 280 U. S.
396 ; Hygrade Provision Co. v. Sherman, 266 U. S.
497 ; Fox v. Washington, 236 U. S.
273 ; Nash v. United States, 229 U. S.
373 ."
[ Footnote 11 ]
We must note, in addition, that any assumption concerning the
relative burdens of the past and the probable burden under the
standards now adopted is pure speculation.
[ Footnote 12 ]
The record simply does not support appellant's contention,
belatedly raised on appeal, that the State's expert was unqualified
to give evidence on California "community standards." The expert, a
police officer with many years of specialization in obscenity
offenses, had conducted an extensive state-wide survey and had
given expert evidence on 26 occasions in the year prior to this
trial. Allowing such expert testimony was certainly not
constitutional error. Cf. United States v. Augenblick, 393 U. S. 348 , 393 U. S. 356 (1969).
[ Footnote 13 ]
In Jacobellis v. Ohio, 378 U.
S. 184 (1964), two Justices argued that application of
"local" community standards would run the risk of preventing
dissemination of materials in some places because sellers would be
unwilling to risk criminal conviction by testing variations in
standards from place to place. Id. at 378 U. S.
193 -195 (opinion of BRENNAN, J., joined by Goldberg,
J.). The use of "national" standards, however, necessarily implies
that materials found tolerable in some places, but not under the
"national" criteria, will nevertheless be unavailable where they
are acceptable. Thus, in terms of danger to free expression, the
potential for suppression seems at least as great in the
application of a single nationwide standard as in allowing
distribution in accordance with local tastes, a point which Mr.
Justice Harlan often emphasized. See Roth v. United
States, 354 U.S. at 354 U. S.
506 .
Appellant also argues that adherence to a "national standard" is
necessary "in order to avoid unconscionable burdens on the free
flow of interstate commerce." As noted supra at 413 U. S. 18 n.
1, the application of domestic state police powers in this case did
not intrude on any congressional powers under Art. I, § 8, cl. 3,
for there is no indication that appellant's materials were ever
distributed interstate. Appellant's argument would appear without
substance in any event. Obscene material may be validly regulated
by a State in the exercise of its traditional local power to
protect the general welfare of its population despite some possible
incidental effect on the flow of such materials across state lines. See, e.g., Head v. New Mexico Board, 374 U.
S. 424 (1963); Huron Portland Cement Co. v.
Detroit, 362 U. S. 440 (1960); Breard v. Alexandria, 341 U.
S. 622 (1951); H. P. Hood & Sons v. Du
Mond, 336 U. S. 525 (1949); Southern Pacific Co. v. Arizona, 325 U.
S. 761 (1945); Baldwin v. G.A.F. Seelig, Inc., 294 U. S. 511 (1935); Sligh v. Kirkwood, 237 U. S.
52 (1915).
[ Footnote 14 ]
Appellant's jurisdictional statement contends that he was
subjected to "double jeopardy" because a Los Angeles County trial
judge dismissed, before trial, a prior prosecution based on the
same brochures, but apparently alleging exposures at a different
time in a different setting. Appellant argues that, once material
has been found not to be obscene in one proceeding, the State is
"collaterally estopped" from ever alleging it to be obscene in a
different proceeding. It is not clear from the record that
appellant properly raised this issue, better regarded as a question
of procedural due process than a "double jeopardy" claim, in the
state courts below. Appellant failed to address any portion of his
brief on the merits to this issue, and appellee contends that the
question was waived under California law because it was improperly
pleaded at trial. Nor is it totally clear from the record before us
what collateral effect the pretrial dismissal might have under
state law. The dismissal was based, at least in part, on a failure
of the prosecution to present affirmative evidence required by
state law, evidence which was apparently presented in this case.
Appellant's contention, therefore, is best left to the California
courts for further consideration on remand. The issue is not, in
any event, a proper subject for appeal. See Mishkin v. New
York, 383 U. S. 502 , 383 U. S.
512 -514 (1966).
[ Footnote 15 ]
In the apt words of Mr. Chief Justice Warren, appellant in this
case was
"plainly engaged in the commercial exploitation of the morbid
and shameful craving for materials with prurient effect. I believe
that the State and Federal Governments can constitutionally punish
such conduct. That is all that these cases present to us, and that
is all we need to decide." Roth v. United States, supra, at 354 U. S. 496 (concurring opinion).
[ Footnote 16 ] See 2 V. Parrington, Main Currents in American Thought ix et seq. (1930). As to the latter part of the 19th
century, Parrington observed
"A new age had come and other dreams -- the age and the dreams
of a middle-class sovereignty. . . . From the crude and vast
romanticisms of that vigorous sovereignty emerged eventually a
spirit of realistic criticism, seeking to evaluate the worth of
this new America, and discover if possible other philosophies to
take the place of those which had gone down in the fierce battles
of the Civil War." Id. at 474. Cf. 2 S. Morison, H. Commager
& W. Leuchtenburg, The Growth of the American Republic 197-233
(6th ed.1969); Paths of American Thought 123-166, 203-290 (A.
Schlesinger & M. White ed.1963) (articles of Fleming, Lerner,
Morton & Lucia White, E. Rostow, Samuelson, Kazin, Hofstadter);
and H. Wish, Society and Thought in Modern America 337-386
(1952).
[ Footnote 17 ]
"[W]e have indicated . . . that, because of its strong and
abiding interest in youth, a State may regulate the dissemination
to juveniles of, and their access to, material objectionable as to
them, but which a State clearly could not regulate as to adults. Ginsberg v. New York , . . .
[ 390 U.S.
629 (1968)]." Interstate Circuit, Inc. v. Dallas, 390 U.
S. 676 , 390 U. S. 690 (1968) (footnote omitted).
MR. JUSTICE DOUGLAS, dissenting. I Today we leave open the way for California [ Footnote 2/1 ] to send a man to prison for
distributing brochures that advertise books and a movie under
freshly written standards defining obscenity which until today is
decision were never the part of any law.
The Court has worked hard to define obscenity and concededly has
failed. In Roth v. United States, 354 U.
S. 476 , it ruled that "[o]bscene material is material
which deals with sex in a manner appealing to prurient interest." Id. at 354 U. S. 487 .
Obscenity, it was said, was rejected by the First Amendment because
it is "utterly without redeeming Page 413 U. S. 38 social importance." Id. at 354 U. S. 484 .
The presence of a "prurient interest" was to be determined by
"contemporary community standards." Id. at 354 U. S. 489 .
That test, it has been said, could not be determined by one
standard here and another standard there, Jacobellis v.
Ohio, 378 U. S. 184 , 378 U. S. 194 ,
but "on the basis of a national standard." Id. at 378 U. S. 195 .
My Brother STEWART, in Jacobellis, commented that the
difficulty of the Court in giving content to obscenity was that it
was "faced with the task of trying to define what may be
indefinable." Id. at 378 U. S.
197 .
In Memoirs v. Massachusetts, 383 U.
S. 413 , 383 U. S. 418 ,
the Roth test was elaborated to read as follows:
"[T]hree elements must coalesce: it must be established that (a)
the dominant theme of the material taken as a whole appeals to a
prurient interest in sex; (b) the material is patently offensive
because it affronts contemporary community standards relating to
the description or representation of sexual matters; and (c) the
material is utterly without redeeming social value."
In Ginzburg v. United States, 383 U.
S. 463 , a publisher was sent to prison, not for the kind
of books and periodicals he sold, but for the manner in which the
publications were advertised. The "leer of the sensualist" was said
to permeate the advertisements. Id. at 383 U. S. 468 .
The Court said,
"Where the purveyor's sole emphasis is on the sexually
provocative aspects of his publications, that fact may be decisive
in the determination of obscenity." Id. at 383 U. S. 470 .
As Mr. Justice Black said in dissent,
". . . Ginzburg . . . is now finally and authoritatively
condemned to serve five years in prison for distributing printed
matter about sex which neither Ginzburg nor anyone else could
possibly have known to be criminal." Id. at 383 U. S. 476 .
That observation by Mr. Justice Black is underlined by the fact
that the Ginzburg decision was five to four. Page 413 U. S. 39 A further refinement was added by Ginsberg v. New York, 390 U. S. 629 , 390 U. S. 641 ,
where the Court held that "it was not irrational for the
legislature to find that exposure to material condemned by the
statute is harmful to minors."
But even those members of this Court who had created the new and
changing standards of "obscenity" could not agree on their
application. And so we adopted a per curiam treatment of so-called
obscene publications that seemed to pass constitutional muster
under the several constitutional tests which had been formulated. See Redrup v. New York, 386 U. S. 767 .
Some condemn it if its "dominant tendency might be to deprave
or corrupt' a reader." [ Footnote
2/2 ] Others look not to the content of the book, but to whether
it is advertised "`to appeal to the erotic interests of
customers.'" [ Footnote 2/3 ] Some
condemn only "hard-core pornography," but even then a true
definition is lacking. It has indeed been said of that definition,
"I could never succeed in [defining it] intelligibly," but "I know
it when I see it." [ Footnote
2/4 ] Today we would add a new three-pronged test:
"(a) whether 'the average person, applying contemporary
community standards,' would find that the work, taken as a whole,
appeals to the prurient interest, . . . (b) whether the work
depicts or describes, in a patently offensive way, sexual conduct
specifically defined by the applicable state law, and (c) whether
the work, taken as a whole, lacks serious literary, artistic,
political, or scientific value."
Those are the standards we ourselves have written into the
Constitution. [ Footnote 2/5 ] Yet
how under these vague tests can Page 413 U. S. 40 we sustain convictions for the sale of an article prior to the
time when some court has declared it to be obscene?
Today the Court retreats from the earlier formulations of the
constitutional test and undertakes to make new definitions. This
effort, like the earlier ones, is earnest and well intentioned. The
difficulty is that we do not deal with constitutional terms, since
"obscenity" is not mentioned in the Constitution or Bill of Rights.
And the First Amendment makes no such exception from "the press"
which it undertakes to protect nor, as I have said on other
occasions, is an exception necessarily implied, for there was no
recognized exception to the free press at the time the Bill of
Rights was adopted which treated "obscene" publications differently
from other types of papers, magazines, and books. So there are no
constitutional guidelines for deciding what is and what is not
"obscene." The Court is at large because we deal with tastes and
standards of literature. What shocks me may Page 413 U. S. 41 be sustenance for my neighbor. What causes one person to boil up
in rage over one pamphlet or movie may reflect only his neurosis,
not shared by others. We deal here with a regime of censorship
which, if adopted, should be done by constitutional amendment after
full debate by the people.
Obscenity cases usually generate tremendous emotional outbursts.
They have no business being in the courts. If a constitutional
amendment authorized censorship, the censor would probably be an
administrative agency. Then criminal prosecutions could follow as,
if, and when publishers defied the censor and sold their
literature. Under that regime, a publisher would know when he was
on dangerous ground. Under the present regime -- whether the old
standards or the new ones are used -- the criminal law becomes a
trap. A brand new test would put a publisher behind bars under a
new law improvised by the courts after the publication. That was
done in Ginzburg, and has all the evils of an ex post
facto law.
My contention is that, until a civil proceeding has placed a
tract beyond the pale, no criminal prosecution should be sustained.
For no more vivid illustration of vague and uncertain laws could be
designed than those we have fashioned. As Mr. Justice Harlan has
said:
"The upshot of all this divergence in viewpoint is that anyone
who undertakes to examine the Court's decisions since Roth which have held particular material obscene or not obscene would
find himself in utter bewilderment." Interstate Circuit, Inc. v. Dallas, 390 U.
S. 676 , 390 U. S.
707 .
In Bouie v. City of Columbia, 378 U.
S. 347 , we upset a conviction for remaining on property
after being asked to leave, while the only unlawful act charged by
the statute was entering. We held that the defendants had received
no "fair warning, at the time of their conduct" Page 413 U. S. 42 while on the property "that the act for which they now stand
convicted was rendered criminal" by the state statute. Id. at 378 U. S. 355 .
The same requirement of "fair warning" is due here, as much as in Bouie. The latter involved racial discrimination; the
present case involves rights earnestly urged as being protected by
the First Amendment. In any case -- certainly when constitutional
rights are concerned -- we should not allow men to go to prison or
be fined when they had no "fair warning" that what they did was
criminal conduct. II If a specific book, play, paper, or motion picture has in a
civil proceeding been condemned as obscene and review of that
finding has been completed, and thereafter a person publishes,
shows, or displays that particular book or film, then a vague law
has been made specific. There would remain the underlying question
whether the First Amendment allows an implied exception in the case
of obscenity. I do not think it does, [ Footnote 2/6 ] and my views Page 413 U. S. 43 on the issue have been stated over and over again. [ Footnote 2/7 ] But at least a criminal
prosecution brought at that juncture would not violate the
time-honored "void for vagueness" test. [ Footnote 2/8 ]
No such protective procedure has been designed by California in
this case. Obscenity -- which even we cannot define with precision
-- is a hodge-podge. To send Page 413 U. S. 44 men to jail for violating standards they cannot understand,
construe, and apply is a monstrous thing to do in a Nation
dedicated to fair trials and due process. III While the right to know is the corollary of the right to speak
or publish, no one can be forced by government to listen to
disclosure that he finds offensive. That was the basis of my
dissent in Public Utilities Comm'n v. Pollak, 343 U.
S. 451 , 343 U. S. 467 ,
where I protested against making streetcar passengers a "captive"
audience. There is no "captive audience" problem in these obscenity
cases. No one is being compelled to look or to listen. Those who
enter newsstands or bookstalls may be offended by what they see.
But they are not compelled by the State to frequent those places;
and it is only state or governmental action against which the First
Amendment, applicable to the States by virtue of the Fourteenth,
raises a ban.
The idea that the First Amendment permits government to ban
publications that are "offensive" to some people puts an ominous
gloss on freedom of the press. That test would make it possible to
ban any paper or any journal or magazine in some benighted place.
The First Amendment was designed "to invite dispute," to induce "a
condition of unrest," to "create dissatisfaction with conditions as
they are," and even to stir "people to anger." Terminiello v.
Chicago, 337 U. S. 1 , 337 U. S. 4 . The
idea that the First Amendment permits punishment for ideas that are
"offensive" to the particular judge or jury sitting in judgment is
astounding. No greater leveler of speech or literature has ever
been designed. To give the power to the censor, as we do today, is
to make a sharp and radical break with the traditions of a free
society. The First Amendment was not fashioned as a vehicle for Page 413 U. S. 45 dispensing tranquilizers to the people. Its prime function was
to keep debate open to "offensive" as well as to "staid" people.
The tendency throughout history has been to subdue the individual
and to exalt the power of government. The use of the standard
"offensive" gives authority to government that cuts the very vitals
out of the First Amendment. [ Footnote
2/9 ] As is intimated by the Court's opinion, the materials
before us may be garbage. But so is much of what is said in
political campaigns, in the daily press, on TV, or over the radio.
By reason of the First Amendment -- and solely because of it --
speakers and publishers have not been threatened or subdued because
their thoughts and ideas may be "offensive" to some.
The standard "offensive" is unconstitutional in yet another way.
In Coates v. City of Cincinnati, 402 U.
S. 611 , we had before us a municipal ordinance that made
it a crime for three or more persons to assemble on a street and
conduct themselves "in a manner annoying to persons Page 413 U. S. 46 passing by." We struck it down, saying:
"If three or more people meet together on a sidewalk or street
corner, they must conduct themselves so as not to annoy any police
officer or other person who should happen to pass by. In our
opinion, this ordinance is unconstitutionally vague because it
subjects the exercise of the right of assembly to an
unascertainable standard, and unconstitutionally broad because it
authorizes the punishment of constitutionally protected
conduct."
"Conduct that annoys some people does not annoy others. Thus,
the ordinance is vague not in the sense that it requires a person
to conform his conduct to an imprecise but comprehensive normative
standard, but rather in the sense that no standard of conduct is
specified at all." Id. at 402 U. S.
614 .
How we can deny Ohio the convenience of punishing people who
"annoy" others and allow California power to punish people who
publish materials "offensive" to some people is difficult to square
with constitutional requirements.
If there are to be restraints on what is obscene, then a
constitutional amendment should be the way of achieving the end.
There are societies where religion and mathematics are the only
free segments. It would be a dark day for America if that were our
destiny. But the people can make it such if they choose to write
obscenity into the Constitution and define it.
We deal with highly emotional, not rational, questions. To many,
the Song of Solomon is obscene. I do not think we, the judges, were
ever given the constitutional power to make definitions of
obscenity. If it is to be defined, let the people debate and decide
by a constitutional amendment what they want to ban as obscene and
what standards they want the legislatures and the courts to apply.
Perhaps the people will decide that the path towards a mature,
integrated society requires Page 413 U. S. 47 that all ideas competing for acceptance must have no censor.
Perhaps they will decide otherwise. Whatever the choice, the courts
will have some guidelines. Now we have none except our own
predilections.
[ Footnote 2/1 ]
California defines "obscene matter" as
"matter, taken as a whole, the predominant appeal of which to
the average person, applying contemporary standards, is to prurient
interest, i.e., a shameful or morbid interest in nudity,
sex, or excretion; and is matter which taken as a whole goes
substantially beyond customary limits of candor in description or
representation of such matters; and is matter which taken as a
whole is utterly without redeeming social importance."
Calif. Penal Code § 311(a).
[ Footnote 2/2 ] Roth v. United States, 354 U.
S. 476 , 354 U. S. 502 (opinion of Harlan, J.).
[ Footnote 2/3 ] Ginzburg v. United States, 383 U.
S. 463 , 383 U. S.
467 .
[ Footnote 2/4 ] Jacobellis v. Ohio, 378 U. S. 184 , 378 U. S. 197 (STEWART, J., concurring).
[ Footnote 2/5 ]
At the conclusion of a two-year study, the U.S. Commission on
Obscenity and Pornography determined that the standards we have
written interfere with constitutionally protected materials:
"Society's attempts to legislate for adults in the area of
obscenity have not been successful. Present laws prohibiting the
consensual sale or distribution of explicit sexual materials to
adults are extremely unsatisfactory in their practical application.
The Constitution permits material to be deemed 'obscene' for adults
only if, as a whole, it appeals to the 'prurient' interest of the
average person, is 'patently offensive' in light of 'community
standards,' and lacks 'redeeming social value.' These vague and
highly subjective aesthetic, psychological and moral tests do not
provide meaningful guidance for law enforcement officials, juries
or courts. As a result, law is inconsistently and sometimes
erroneously applied, and the distinctions made by courts between
prohibited and permissible materials often appear indefensible.
Errors in the application of the law and uncertainty about its
scope also cause interference with the communication of
constitutionally protected materials."
Report of the Commission on Obscenity and Pornography 53
(1970).
[ Footnote 2/6 ]
It is said that "obscene" publications can be banned on
authority of restraints on communications incident to decrees
restraining unlawful business monopolies or unlawful restraints of
trade, Sugar Institute v. United States, 297 U.
S. 553 , 297 U. S. 597 ,
or communications respecting the sale of spurious or fraudulent
securities. Hall v. Geier-Jones Co., 242 U.
S. 539 , 242 U. S. 549 ; Caldwell v. Sioux Falls Stock Yards Co., 242 U.
S. 559 , 242 U. S. 567 ; Merrick v. Halsey & Co., 242 U.
S. 568 , 242 U. S. 584 .
The First Amendment answer is that, whenever speech and conduct are
brigaded -- as they are when one shouts "Fire" in a crowded theater
-- speech can be outlawed. Mr. Justice Black, writing for a
unanimous Court in Giboney v. Empire Storage Co., 336 U. S. 490 ,
stated that labor unions could be restrained from picketing a firm
in support of a secondary boycott which a State had validly
outlawed. Mr. Justice Black said:
"It rarely has been suggested that the constitutional freedom
for speech and press extends its immunity to speech or writing used
as an integral part of conduct in violation of a valid criminal
statute. We reject the contention now." Id. at 336 U. S.
498 .
[ Footnote 2/7 ] See United States v. 12 200-ft. Reels of Film, post, p. 413 U. S. 123 ; United States v. Orito, post, p. 413 U. S. 139 ; Kois v. Wisconsin, 408 U. S. 229 ; Byrne v. Karalexis, 396 U. S. 976 ,
977; Ginsberg v. New York, 390 U.
S. 629 , 390 U. S. 650 ; Jacobs v. New York, 388 U. S. 431 , 388 U. S. 436 ; Ginzburg v. United States, 383 U.
S. 463 , 383 U. S. 482 ; Memoirs v. Massachusetts, 383 U.
S. 413 , 383 U. S. 424 ; Bantam Books, Inc. v. Sullivan, 372 U. S.
58 , 372 U. S. 72 ; Times Film Corp. v. Chicago, 365 U. S.
43 , 365 U. S. 78 ; Smith v. California, 361 U. S. 147 , 361 U. S. 167 ; Kingsley Pictures Corp. v. Regents, 360 U.
S. 684 , 360 U. S. 697 ; Roth v. United States, 354 U. S. 476 , 354 U. S. 508 ; Kingsley Books, Inc. v. Brown, 354 U.
S. 436 , 354 U. S. 446 ; Superior Films, Inc. v. Department of Education, 346 U. S. 587 , 346 U. S. 588 ; Gelling v. Texas, 343 U. S. 60 .
[ Footnote 2/8 ]
The Commission on Obscenity and Pornography has advocated such a
procedure:
" The Commission recommends the enactment, in all
jurisdictions which enact or retain provisions prohibiting the
dissemination of sexual materials to adults or young persons, of
legislation authorizing prosecutors to obtain declaratory judgments
as to whether particular materials fall within existing legal
prohibitions. . . . "
"A declaratory judgment procedure . . . would permit prosecutors
to proceed civilly, rather than through the criminal process,
against suspected violations of obscenity prohibition. If such
civil procedures are utilized, penalties would be imposed for
violation of the law only with respect to conduct occurring after a
civil declaration is obtained. The Commission believes this course
of action to be appropriate whenever there is any existing doubt
regarding the legal status of materials; where other alternatives
are available, the criminal process should not ordinarily be
invoked against persons who might have reasonably believed, in good
faith, that the books or films they distributed were entitled to
constitutional protection, for the threat of criminal sanctions
might otherwise deter the free distribution of constitutionally
protected material."
Report of the Commission on Obscenity and Pornography 63
(1970).
[ Footnote 2/9 ]
Obscenity law has had a capricious history:
"The white slave traffic was first exposed by W. T. Stead in a
magazine article, 'The Maiden Tribute.' The English law did
absolutely nothing to the profiteers in vice, but put Stead in
prison for a year for writing about an indecent subject. When the
law supplies no definite standard of criminality, a judge, in
deciding what is indecent or profane, may consciously disregard the
sound test of present injury, and proceeding upon an entirely
different theory may condemn the defendant because his words
express ideas which are thought liable to cause bad future
consequences. Thus, musical comedies enjoy almost unbridled
license, while a problem play is often forbidden because opposed to
our views of marriage. In the same way, the law of blasphemy has
been used against Shelley's Queen Mab and the decorous promulgation
of pantheistic ideas on the ground that to attack religion is to
loosen the bonds of society and endanger the state. This is simply
a round-about modern method to make heterodoxy in sex matters and
even in religion a crime."
Z. Chafee, Free Speech in the United States 151 (1942).
MR. JUSTICE BRENNAN, with whom MR. JUSTICE STEWART and MR.
JUSTICE MARSHALL join, dissenting.
In my dissent in Paris Adult Theatre I v. Slaton, post, p. 413 U. S. 73 ,
decided this date, I noted that I had no occasion to consider the
extent of state power to regulate the distribution of sexually
oriented material to juveniles or the offensive exposure of such
material to unconsenting adults. In the case before us, appellant
was convicted of distributing obscene matter in violation of
California Penal Code § 311.2, on the basis of evidence that he had
caused to be mailed unsolicited brochures advertising various books
and a movie. I need not now decide whether a statute might be drawn
to impose, within the requirements of the First Amendment, criminal
penalties for the precise conduct at issue here. For it is clear
that, under my dissent in Paris Adult Theatre I, the
statute under which the prosecution was brought is
unconstitutionally overbroad, and therefore invalid on its face. * "[T]he transcendent value to all society of constitutionally
protected expression is deemed to justify allowing 'attacks on
overly broad statutes with no requirement that the person making
the attack demonstrate that his own conduct could not be regulated
by a statute drawn with the requisite narrow specificity." Gooding v. Wilson, 405 U. S. 518 , 405 U. S. 521 (1972), quoting Page 413 U. S. 48 from Dombrowski v. Pfister, 380 U.
S. 479 , 380 U. S. 486 (1965). See also Baggett v. Bullitt, 377 U.
S. 360 , 377 U. S. 366 (1964); Coates v. City of Cincinnati, 402 U.
S. 611 , 402 U. S. 616 (1971); id. at 402 U. S.
619 -620 (WHITE, J., dissenting); United States v.
Raines, 362 U. S. 17 , 362 U. S. 21 -22
(1960); NAACP v. Button, 371 U. S. 415 , 371 U. S. 433 (1963). Since my view in Paris Adult Theatre I represents
a substantial departure from the course of our prior decisions, and
since the state courts have as yet had no opportunity to consider
whether a "readily apparent construction suggests itself as a
vehicle for rehabilitating the [statute] in a single prosecution," Dombrowski v. Pfister, supra, at 380 U. S. 491 ,
I would reverse the judgment of the Appellate Department of the
Superior Court and remand the case for proceedings not inconsistent
with this opinion. See Coates v. City of Cincinnati,
supra, at 402 U. S.
616 .
* Cal. Penal Code § 311.2(a) provides that
"Every person who knowingly: sends or causes to be sent, or
brings or causes to be brought, into this state for sale or
distribution, or in this state prepares, publishes, prints,
exhibits, distributes, or offers to distribute, or has in his
possession with intent to distribute or to exhibit or offer to
distribute, any obscene matter is guilty of a misdemeanor." | In Miller v. California, the Supreme Court of the United States addressed the issue of state regulation of obscene material and provided guidelines for determining what constitutes obscene material that is not protected by the First Amendment.
The Court held that obscene material is not protected by the First Amendment and outlined a three-part test for determining obscenity:
1. The work, taken as a whole, must appeal to the prurient interest in sex;
2. The work must portray sexual conduct in a patently offensive way as specifically defined by applicable state law;
3. The work, taken as a whole, must lack serious literary, artistic, political, or scientific value.
The Court also held that the trier of fact must apply contemporary community standards in evaluating the material and rejected the "utterly without redeeming social value" test from an earlier case, Memoirs v. Massachusetts.
In this case, the Court reviewed the conviction of the appellant, who was found guilty of mailing unsolicited sexually explicit material in violation of a California statute. The Court vacated the conviction and remanded the case for further consideration in light of the new obscenity standards set forth in this decision. |
Government Agencies | Perez v. Mortgage Bankers Ass'n | https://supreme.justia.com/cases/federal/us/575/13-1041/ | NOTICE: This opinion is subject to formal revision before
publication in the preliminary print of the United States
Reports. Readers are requested to notify the Reporter of Decisions,
Supreme Court of the United States, Washington, D. C. 20543,
of any typographical or other formal errors, in order that
corrections may be made before the preliminary print goes to
press.
SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES
_________________
Nos. 13–1041 and 13–1052
_________________
THOMAS E. PEREZ, SECRETARY OF LABOR, et al.,
PETITIONERS
13–1041 v. MORTGAGE BANKERS ASSOCIATION et al.
JEROME NICKOLS, et al., PETITIONERS
13–1052 v. MORTGAGE BANKERS ASSOCIATION
on writs of certiorari to the united states court of appeals for
the district of columbia circuit
[March 9, 2015]
Justice Sotomayor delivered the opinion of the Court.
When a federal administrative agency first issues a rule
interpreting one of its regulations, it is generally not required
to follow the notice-and-comment rulemaking procedures of the
Administrative Procedure Act (APA or Act). See5 U. S. C.
§553(b)(A). The United States Court of Appeals for the District of
Columbia Circuit has nevertheless held, in a line of cases
beginning with Paralyzed Veterans of Am. v. D. C.
Arena L. P. , 117 F. 3d 579 (1997), that an agency must use
the APA’s notice-and-comment procedures when it wishes to issue a
new interpretation of a regulation that deviates significantly from
one the agency has previously adopted. The question in these cases
is whether the rule announced in Paralyzed Veterans is
consistent with the APA. We hold that it is not.
I
A
The APA establishes the procedures federal administrative
agencies use for “rule making,” defined as the process of
“formulating, amending, or repealing a rule.” §551(5). “Rule,” in
turn, is defined broadly to include “statement[s] of general or
particular applicability and future effect” that are designed to
“implement, interpret, or prescribe law or policy.” §551(4).
Section 4 of the APA,5 U. S. C. §553, prescribes a
three-step procedure for so-called “notice-and-comment rulemaking.”
First, the agency must issue a “[g]eneral notice of proposed rule
making,” ordinarily by publication in the Federal Register . §553(b). Second, if “notice [is] required,” the agency must “give
interested persons an opportunity to participate in the rule making
through submission of written data, views, or arguments.” §553(c).
An agency must consider and respond to significant comments
received during the period for public comment. See Citizens to
Preserve Overton Park, Inc. v. Volpe ,401 U. S.
402,416 (1971); Thompson v. Clark , 741 F. 2d
401, 408 (CADC 1984). Third, when the agency promulgates the final
rule, it must include in the rule’s text “a concise general
statement of [its] basis and purpose.” §553(c). Rules issued
through the notice-and-comment process are often referred to as
“legislative rules” because they have the “force and effect of
law.” Chrysler Corp. v. Brown ,441 U. S. 281–303
(1979) (internal quotation marks omitted).
Not all “rules” must be issued through the notice-and-comment
process. Section 4(b)(A) of the APA provides that, unless another
statute states otherwise, the notice-and-comment requirement “does
not apply” to “interpretative rules, general statements of policy,
or rules of agency organization, procedure, or practice.”5
U. S. C. §553(b)(A). The term “interpretative rule,” or
“interpretive rule,”[ 1 ] is not further defined by
the APA, and its precise meaning is the source of much scholarly
and judicial debate. See generally Pierce, Distinguishing
Legislative Rules From Interpretative Rules, 52 Admin. L. Rev.
547 (2000); Manning, Nonlegislative Rules, 72 Geo. Wash.
L. Rev. 893 (2004). We need not, and do not, wade into that
debate here. For our purposes, it suffices to say that the critical
feature of interpretive rules is that they are “issued by an agency
to advise the public of the agency’s construction of the statutes
and rules which it administers.” Shalala v. Guernsey
Memorial Hospital ,514 U. S. 87,99 (1995) (internal
quotation marks omitted). The absence of a notice-and-comment
obligation makes the process of issuing interpretive rules
comparatively easier for agencies than issuing legislative rules.
But that convenience comes at a price: Interpretive rules “do not
have the force and effect of law and are not accorded that weight
in the adjudicatory process.” Ibid. B
These cases began as a dispute over efforts by the Department of
Labor to determine whether mortgage-loan officers are covered by
the Fair Labor Standards Act of 1938 (FLSA),52Stat.1060, as
amended,29 U. S. C. §201 et seq. The FLSA
“establishe[s] a minimum wage and overtime compensation for each
hour worked in excess of 40 hours in each workweek” for many
employees. Integ-rity Staffing Solutions, Inc. v. Busk , 574 U. S. ___, ___ (2014) (slip op., at 3).
Certain classes of employees, however, are exempt from these
provisions. Among these exempt individuals are those “employed in a
bona fide executive, administrative, or professional capacity
. . . or in the capacity of outside salesman
. . . .” §213(a)(1). The exemption for such employees is
known as the “administrative” exemption.
The FLSA grants the Secretary of Labor authority to “defin[e]”
and “delimi[t]” the categories of exempt admin-istrative employees. Ibid. The Secretary’s current regu-lations regarding the
administrative exemption were promulgated in 2004 through a
notice-and-commentrulemaking. As relevant here, the 2004
regulations differed from the previous regulations in that they
contained a new section providing several examples of exempt
administrative employees. See 29 CFR §541.203. One of the examples
is “[e]mployees in the financial services industry,” who, depending
on the nature of their day-to-day work, “generally meet the duties
requirements for the administrative exception.” §541.203(b). The
financial services example ends with a caveat, noting that “an
employee whose primary duty is selling financial products does not
qualify for the administrative exemption.” Ibid. In 1999 and again in 2001, the Department’s Wage and Hour
Division issued letters opining that mortgage-loan officers do not
qualify for the administrative exemption. See Opinion Letter, Loan
Officers/Exempt Status, 6A LRR, Wages and Hours Manual 99:8351
(Feb. 16, 2001); Opinion Letter, Mortgage Loan Officers/Exempt
Status, id., at 99:8249. (May 17, 1999). In other words, the
Department concluded that the FLSA’s minimum wage and maximum hour
requirements applied to mortgage-loan officers. When the Department
promulgated its current FLSA regulations in 2004, respondent
Mortgage Bankers Association (MBA), a national trade association
representing real estate finance companies, requested a new opinion
interpreting the revised regulations. In 2006, the Department
issued an opinion letter finding that mortgage-loan officers fell
within the administrative exemption under the 2004 regulations. See
App. to Pet. for Cert. in No. 13–1041, pp. 70a–84a. Four years
later, however, the Wage and Hour Division again altered its
interpretation of the FLSA’s administrative exemption as it applied
to mortgage-loan officers. Id., at 49a–69a. Reviewing the
provisions of the 2004 regulations and judicial decisions
addressing the administrative exemption, the Department’s 2010
Administrator’s Interpretation concluded that mortgage-loan
officers “have a primary duty of making sales for their employers,
and, therefore, do not qualify” for the administrative exemption. Id., at 49a, 69a. The Department accordingly withdrew its
2006 opinion letter, which it now viewed as relying on “misleading
assumption[s] and selective and narrow analysis” of the exemption
example in §541.203(b). Id., at 68a. Like the 1999, 2001,
and 2006 opinion letters, the 2010 Administrator’s Interpretation
was issued without notice or an opportunity for comment.
C
MBA filed a complaint in Federal District Court challenging the
Administrator’s Interpretation. MBA contended that the document was
inconsistent with the 2004 regulation it purported to interpret,
and thus arbitrary and capricious in violation of §10 of the APA,5
U. S. C. §706. More pertinent to this case, MBA also
argued that the Administrator’s Interpretation was procedurally
in-valid in light of the D. C. Circuit’s decision in Paralyzed Veterans , 117 F. 3d 579. Under the Paralyzed
Veterans doctrine, if “an agency has given its regulation a
definitive interpretation, and later significantly revises that
interpretation, the agency has in effect amended its rule,
something it may not accomplish” under the APA “without notice and
comment.” Alaska Professional Hunters Assn., Inc. v. FAA , 177 F. 3d 1030, 1034 (CADC 1999). Three former
mortgage-loan officers—Beverly Buck, Ryan Henry, and Jerome
Nickols—subsequently intervened in thecase to defend the
Administrator’s Interpretation.[ 2 ]
The District Court granted summary judgment to the Department. Mortgage Bankers Assn. v. Solis , 864 F. Supp. 2d
193 (DC 2012). Though it accepted the parties’ characterization of
the Administrator’s Interpretation as an interpretive rule, id., at 203, n. 7, the District Court determined that
the Paralyzed Veterans doctrine was inapplicable because MBA
had failed to establish its reliance on the contrary interpretation
expressed in the Department’s 2006 opinion letter. The
Administrator’s Interpretation, the District Court further
determined, was fully supported by the text of the 2004 FLSA
regulations. The court accordingly held that the 2010
interpretation was not arbitrary or capricious.[ 3 ]
The D. C. Circuit reversed. Mortgage Bankers Assn. v. Harris , 720 F. 3d 966 (2013). Bound to the rule of Paralyzed Veterans by precedent, the Court of Appeals
rejected the Government’s call to abandon the doctrine. 720
F. 3d., at 967, n. 1. In the court’s view, “[t]he only
question” properly before it was whether the District Court had
erred in requiring MBA to prove that it relied on the Department’s
prior interpretation. Id., at 967. Explaining that reliance
was not a required element of the Paralyzed Veterans doctrine, and noting the Department’s concession that a prior,
conflicting interpretation of the 2004 regulations existed, the
D. C. Circuit concluded that the 2010 Administrator’s
Interpretation had to be vacated.
We granted certiorari, 573 U. S. __ (2014), and now
reverse.
II
The Paralyzed Veterans doctrine is contrary to the clear
text of the APA’s rulemaking provisions, and it improperly imposes
on agencies an obligation beyond the “maximum procedural
requirements” specified in the APA, Vermont Yankee Nuclear Power
Corp. v. Natural Resources Defense Council, Inc. ,435
U. S. 519,524 (1978).
A
The text of the APA answers the question presented. Section 4 of
the APA provides that “notice of proposed rule making shall be
published in the Federal Register.”5 U. S. C. §553(b).
When such notice is required by the APA, “the agency shall give
interested persons an opportunity to participate in the rule
making.” §553(c). But §4 further states that unless “notice or
hearing is required by statute,” the Act’s notice-and-comment
requirement “does not apply . . . to interpretative
rules.” §553(b)(A). This exemption of interpretive rules from the
notice-and-comment process is categorical, and it is fatal to the
rule announced in Paralyzed Veterans .
Rather than examining the exemption for interpretive rules
contained in §4(b)(A) of the APA, the D. C. Circuit in Paralyzed Veterans focused its attention on §1 of the Act.
That section defines “rule making” to include not only the initial
issuance of new rules, but also “repeal[s]” or “amend[ments]” of
existing rules. See §551(5). Because notice-and-comment
requirements may apply even to these later agency actions, the
court reasoned, “allow[ing] an agency to make a fundamental change
in its interpretation of a substantive regulation without notice
and comment” would undermine the APA’s procedural framework. 117
F. 3d, at 586.
This reading of the APA conflates the differing purposes of §§1
and 4 of the Act. Section 1 defines what a rule-making is. It does
not, however, say what procedures an agency must use when it
engages in rulemaking. That is the purpose of §4. And §4
specifically exempts interpretive rules from the notice-and-comment
requirements that apply to legislative rules. So, the D. C.
Circuit correctly read §1 of the APA to mandate that agencies use
the same procedures when they amend or repeal a rule as they used
to issue the rule in the first instance. See FCC v. Fox
Television Stations, Inc. ,556 U. S. 502,515 (2009) (the
APA “make[s] no distinction . . . between initial agency
action and subsequent agency action undoing or revising that
action”). Where the court went wrong was in failing to apply that
accurate understanding of §1 to the exemption for interpretive
rules contained in §4: Because an agency is not required to use
notice-and-comment procedures to issue an initial interpretive
rule, it is also not required to use those procedures when it
amends or repeals that interpretive rule.
B
The straightforward reading of the APA we now adopt harmonizes
with longstanding principles of our administrative law
jurisprudence. Time and again, we have reiterated that the APA
“sets forth the full extent of judicial authority to review
executive agency action for procedural correctness.” Fox
Television Stations, Inc. , 556 U. S., at 513. Beyond the APA’s
minimum requirements, courts lack authority “to impose upon [an]
agency its own notion of which procedures are ‘best’ or most likely
to further some vague, undefined public good.” Vermont
Yankee , 435 U. S., at 549. To do otherwise would violate
“the very basic tenet of administrative law that agencies should be
free to fashion their own rules of procedure.” Id., at
544.
These foundational principles apply with equal force to the
APA’s procedures for rulemaking. We explained in Vermont
Yankee that §4 of the Act “established the maximum procedural
requirements which Congress was willing to have the courts impose
upon agencies in conducting rulemaking procedures.” Id., at
524. “Agencies are free to grant additional procedural rights in
the exercise of their discretion, but reviewing courts are
generally not free to impose them if the agencies have not chosen
to grant them.” Ibid. The Paralyzed Veterans doctrine creates just such a
judge-made procedural right: the right to notice and an opportunity
to comment when an agency changes its interpretation of one of the
regulations it enforces. That requirement may be wise policy. Or it
may not. Regardless, imposing such an obligation is the
responsibility of Congress or the administrative agencies, not the
courts. We trust that Congress weighed the costs and benefits of
placing more rigorous procedural restrictions on the issuance of
interpretive rules. See id., at 523 (when Congress enacted
the APA, it “settled long-continued and hard-fought contentions,
and enact[ed] a formula upon which opposing social and political
forces have come to rest” (internal quotation marks omitted)). In
the end, Congress decided to adopt standards that permit agencies
to promulgate freely such rules—whether or not they are consistent
with earlier interpretations. That the D. C. Circuit would
have struck the balance differently does not permit that court or
this one to overturn Congress’ contrary judgment. Cf. Law v. Siegel , 571 U. S. ___, ___ (2014) (slip op., at
11).
III
MBA offers several reasons why the Paralyzed Veterans doctrine should be upheld. They are not persuasive.
A
MBA begins its defense of the Paralyzed Veterans doctrine
by attempting to bolster the D. C. Circuit’s reading of the
APA. “ Paralyzed Veterans ,” MBA contends, “simply
acknowledges the reality that where an agency significantly alters
a prior, definitive interpretation of a regulation, it has
effectively amended the regulation itself,” something that under
the APA requires use of notice-and-comment procedures. Brief for
Respondent 20–21.
The act of “amending,” however, in both ordinary parlance and
legal usage, has its own meaning separate and apart from the act of
“interpreting.” Compare Black’s Law Dictionary 98 (10th ed. 2014)
(defining “amend” as “[t]o change the wording of” or “formally
alter . . . by striking out, inserting, or substituting
words”), with id., at 943 (defining “interpret” as “[t]o
ascertain the meaning and significance of thoughts expressed in
words”). One would not normally say that a court “amends” a statute
when it interprets its text. So too can an agency “interpret” a
regulation without “effectively amend[ing]” the underlying source
of law. MBA does not explain how , precisely, an interpretive
rule changes the regulation it interprets, and its assertion is
impossible to reconcile with the longstanding recognition that
interpretive rules do not have the force and effect of law. See Chrysler Corp. , 441 U. S., at 302, n. 31 (citing
Attorney General’s Manual on the Administrative Procedure Act 30,
n. 3 (1947)); Skidmore v. Swift & Co. ,323
U. S. 134,140 (1944).
MBA’s “interpretation-as-amendment” theory is particularly odd
in light of the limitations of the Paralyzed Veterans doctrine. Recall that the rule of Paralyzed Veterans applies
only when an agency has previously adopted an interpretation of its
regulation. Yet in that initial interpretation as much as all that
come after, the agency is giving a definite meaning to an ambiguous
text—the very act MBA insists requires notice and comment. MBA is
unable to say why its arguments regarding revised interpretations
should not also extend to the agency’s first
interpretation.[ 4 ]
Next, MBA argues that the Paralyzed Veterans doctrine is
more consistent with this Court’s “functional” approach to
interpreting the APA. Relying on Christensen v. Harris
County ,529 U. S. 576 (2000), and Shalala v. Guernsey Memorial Hospital ,514 U. S. 87, MBA contends
that we have already recognized that an agency may not “avoid
notice-and-comment procedures by cloaking its actions in the mantle
of mere ‘interpretation.’ ” Brief for Respondent 23–24.
Neither of the cases MBA cites supports its argument. Our
decision in Christensen did not address a change in agency
interpretation. Instead, we there refused to give deference to an
agency’s interpretation of an unambiguous regulation, observing
that to defer in such a case would allow the agency “to create de facto a new regulation.” 529 U. S., at 588. Put
differently, Christensen held that the agency interpretation
at issue was substantively invalid because it conflicted with the
text of the regulation the agency purported to interpret. That
holding is irrelevant to this suit and to the Paralyzed
Veterans rule, which assesses whether an agency interpretation
is procedurally invalid.
As for Guernsey , that case is fully consistent
with—indeed, confirms—what the text of the APA makes plain:
“Interpretive rules do not require notice and comment.” 514
U. S., at 99. Sidestepping this inconvenient language, MBA
instead quotes a portion of the Court’s opinion stating that “APA
rulemaking would still be required if [an agency] adopted a new
position inconsistent with . . . existing regulations.” Id., at 100. But the statement on which MBA relies is
dictum. Worse, it is dictum taken out of context. The “regulations”
to which the Court referred were two provisions of the Medicare
reimbursement scheme. And it is apparent from the Court’s
description of these regulations in Part II of the opinion that
they were legislative rules, issued through the notice-and-comment
process. See id., at 91–92 (noting that the disputed
regulations were codified in the Code of Federal Regulations). Read
properly, then, the cited passage from Guernsey merely means
that “an agency may only change its interpretation if the revised
interpretation is consistent with the underlying regulations.”
Brief for Petitioners in No. 13–1052, p. 44.
B
In the main, MBA attempts to justify the Paralyzed
Veterans doctrine on practical and policy grounds. MBA contends
that the doctrine reinforces the APA’s goal of “procedural
fairness” by preventing agencies from unilaterally and unexpectedly
altering their interpretation of important regulations. Brief for
Respondent 16.
There may be times when an agency’s decision to issue an
interpretive rule, rather than a legislative rule, is driven
primarily by a desire to skirt notice-and-comment provisions. But
regulated entities are not without recourse in such situations.
Quite the opposite. The APA contains a variety of constraints on
agency decisionmaking—the arbitrary and capricious standard being
among the most notable. As we held in Fox Television
Stations , and underscore again today, the APA requires an
agency to provide more substantial justification when “its new
policy rests upon factual findings that contradict those which
underlay its prior policy; or when its prior policy has engendered
serious reliance interests that must be taken into account. It
would be arbitrary and capricious to ignore such matters.” 556
U. S., at 515 (citation omitted); see also id., at 535
(Kennedy, J., concurring in part and concurring in judgment).
In addition, Congress is aware that agencies sometimes alter
their views in ways that upset settled reliance interests. For that
reason, Congress sometimes includes in the statutes it drafts
safe-harbor provisions that shelter regulated entities from
liability when they act in conformance with previous agency
interpretations. The FLSA includes one such provision: As amended
by the Portal-to-Portal Act of 1947,29 U. S. C. §251 et seq., the FLSA provides that “no employer shall be
subject to any liability” for failing “to pay minimum wages or
overtime compensation” if it demonstrates that the “act or omission
complained of was in good faith in conformity with and in reliance
on any written administrative regulation, order, ruling, approval,
or interpretation” of the Administrator of the Department’s Wage
and Hour Division, even when the guidance is later “modified or
rescinded.” §§259(a), (b)(1). These safe harbors will often protect
parties from liability when an agency adopts an interpretation that
conflicts with its previous position.[ 5 ]
C
MBA changes direction in the second half of its brief,
contending that if the Court overturns the Paralyzed
Veterans rule, the D. C. Circuit’s judgment should
nonetheless be affirmed. That is so, MBA says, because the agency
interpretation at issue—the 2010 Administrator’s
Interpretation—should in fact be classified as a legislative
rule.
We will not address this argument. From the beginning, the
parties litigated this suit on the understanding that the
Administrator’s Interpretation was—as its name suggests—an
interpretive rule. Indeed, if MBA did not think the Administrator’s
Interpretation was an interpretive rule, then its decision to
invoke the Paralyzed Veterans doctrine in attacking the rule
is passing strange. After all, Paralyzed Veterans applied
only to interpretive rules. Consequently, neither the District
Court nor the D. C. Circuit considered MBA’s current claim
that the Administrator’s Interpretation is actually a legislative
rule. Beyond that, and more important still, MBA’s brief in
opposition to certiorari did not dispute petitioners’ assertions—in
their framing of the question presented and in the substance of
their petitions—that the Administrator’s Interpretation is an
interpretive rule. Thus, even assuming MBA did not waive the
argument below, it has done so in this Court. See this Court’s Rule
15.2; Carcieri v. Salazar ,555 U. S. 379–396
(2009).
* * *
For the foregoing reasons, the judgment of the United States
Court of Appeals for the District of Columbia Circuit is
reversed.
It is so ordered. Notes 1 The latter is the more common
phrasing today, and the one we use throughout this
opinion. 2 Buck, Henry, and Nickols are
petitioners in No. 13–1052 and respondents in No.
13–1041. 3 MBA did not challenge this aspect of
the District Court’s decision on appeal. 4 MBA alternatively suggests that
interpretive rules have the force of law because an agency’s
interpretation of its own regulations may be entitled to deference
under Auer v. Robbins ,519 U. S. 452 (1997), and Bowles v. Seminole Rock & Sand Co. ,325 U. S.
410 (1945). Even in cases where an agency’s interpretation receives Auer deference, how-ever, it is the court that ultimately
decides whether a given regulation means what the agency says.
Moreover, Auer deference is not an inexorable command in all
cases. See Christopher v. SmithKline Beecham Corp. ,
567 U. S. ___, ___ (2012) (slip op., at 10) ( Auer deference is inappropriate “when the agency’s interpretation is
plainly erroneous or inconsistent with the regulation” or “when
there is reason to suspect that the agency’s interpretation does
not reflect the agency’s fair and considered judgment” (internal
quotation marks omitted)); Thomas Jefferson Univ. v. Shalala ,512 U. S. 504,515 (1994) (“[A]n agency’s
interpretation of a . . . regulation that conflicts with
a prior interpretation is entitled to considerably less deference
than a consistently held agency view” (internal quotation marks
omitted)). 5 The United States acknowledged at
argument that even in situations where a statute does not contain a
safe-harbor provision similar to the one included in the FLSA, an
agency’s ability to pursue enforcement actions against regulated
entities for conduct in conformance with prior agency
interpretations may be limited by principles of retroactiv-ity. See
Tr. of Oral Arg. 44–45. We have no occasion to consider how such
principles might apply here. SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES
_________________
Nos. 13–1041 and 13–1052
_________________
THOMAS E. PEREZ, SECRETARY OF LABOR, et al.,
PETITIONERS
13–1041 v. MORTGAGE BANKERS ASSOCIATION et al.
JEROME NICKOLS, et al., PETITIONERS
13–1052 v. MORTGAGE BANKERS ASSOCIATION
on writs of certiorari to the united states court of appeals for
the district of columbia circuit
[March 9, 2015]
Justice Alito, concurring in part and concurring in the
judgment.
I join the opinion of the Court except for Part III–B. I agree
that the doctrine of Paralyzed Veterans of America v. D.
C. Arena L. P. , 117 F. 3d 579 (CADC 1997), is incompatible with
the Administrative Procedure Act. The creation of that doctrine may
have been prompted by an understandable concern about the
aggrandizement of the power of administrative agencies as a result
of the combined effect of (1) the effective delegation to
agencies by Congress of huge swaths of lawmaking authority,
(2) the exploitation by agencies of the uncertain boundary
between legislative and interpretive rules, and (3) this
Court’s cases holding that courts must ordinarily defer to an
agency’s interpretation of its own ambiguous regulations. See Bowles v. Seminole Rock & Sand Co. ,325 U. S.
410 (1945). I do not dismiss these concerns, but the Paralyzed
Veterans doctrine is not a viable cure for these problems. At
least one of the three factors noted above, however, concerns a
matter that can be addressed by this Court. The opinions of Justice
Scalia and Justice Thomas offer substantial reasons why the Seminole Rock doctrine may be incorrect. See also Christopher v. SmithKline Beecham Corp. , 567
U. S. ___, ___–___ (2012) (slip op., at 13–14) (citing, inter alia , Manning, Constitutional Structure and Judicial
Deference to Agency Interpretations of Agency Rules, 96 Colum.
L. Rev. 612 (1996)). I await a case in which the validity of Seminole Rock may be explored through full briefing and
argument. SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES
_________________
Nos. 13–1041 and 13–1052
_________________
THOMAS E. PEREZ, SECRETARY OF LABOR, et al.,
PETITIONERS
13–1041 v. MORTGAGE BANKERS ASSOCIATION et al.
JEROME NICKOLS, et al., PETITIONERS
13–1052 v. MORTGAGE BANKERS ASSOCIATION
on writs of certiorari to the united states court of appeals for
the district of columbia circuit
[March 9, 2015]
Justice Scalia, concurring in the judgment.
I agree with the Court’s decision, and all of its reasoning
demonstrating the incompatibility of the D. C. Circuit’s Paralyzed Veterans holding with the Administrative Procedure
Act. Paralyzed Veterans of Am. v. D. C. Arena
L.P. , 117 F. 3d 579 (CADC 1997). I do not agree, however,
with the Court’s portrayal of the result it produces as a
vindication of the balance Congress struck when it “weighed the
costs and benefits of placing more rigorous . . .
restrictions on the issuance of interpretive rules.” Ante, at 9. That depiction is accurate enough if one looks at this case
in isolation. Considered alongside our law of deference to
administrative determinations, however, today’s decision produces a
balance between power and procedure quite different from the one
Congress chose when it enacted the APA.
“The [APA] was framed against a background of rapid expansion of
the administrative process as a check upon administrators whose
zeal might otherwise have carried them to excesses not contemplated
in legislation creating their offices.” United States v. Morton Salt Co. ,338 U. S. 632,644 (1950). The Act
guards against excesses in rulemaking by requiring notice and
comment. Before an agency makes a rule, it normally must notify the
public of the proposal, invite them to comment on its shortcomings,
consider and respond to their arguments, and explain its final
decision in a statement of the rule’s basis and purpose.5
U. S. C. §553(b)–(c); ante, at 2.
The APA exempts interpretive rules from these requirements.
§553(b)(A). But this concession to agencies was meant to be more
modest in its effects than it is today. For despite exempting
interpretive rules from notice and comment, the Act provides that
“the reviewing court shall . . . interpret
constitutional and statutory provisions, and determine the meaning
or applicability of the terms of an agency action.” §706 (emphasis
added). The Act thus contemplates that courts, not agencies, will
authoritatively resolve ambiguities in statutes and regulations. In
sucha regime, the exemption for interpretive rules does not add
much to agency power. An agency may use interpretive rules to advise the public by explaining its interpretation of the
law. But an agency may not use interpretive rules to bind the public by making law, because it remains the responsibility of
the court to decide whether the law means what the agency says it
means.
Heedless of the original design of the APA, we have developed an
elaborate law of deference to agencies’ interpretations of statutes
and regulations. Never mentioning §706’s directive that the
“reviewing court . . . interpret . . .
statutory provisions,” we have held that agencies may
authoritatively resolve ambiguities in statutes. Chevron
U. S. A. Inc. v. Natural Resources Defense
Council, Inc. ,467 U. S. 837–843 (1984). And never
mentioning §706’s directive that the “reviewing court
. . . determine the meaning or applicability of the terms
of an agency action,” we have—relying on a case decided before the
APA, Bowles v. Seminole Rock & Sand Co. ,325
U. S. 410 (1945)—held that agencies may authoritatively
resolve ambiguities in regulations. Auer v. Robbins ,519 U. S. 452,461 (1997).
By supplementing the APA with judge-made doctrines of deference,
we have revolutionized the import of interpretive rules’ exemption
from notice-and-comment rulemaking. Agencies may now use these
rules not just to advise the public, but also to bind them. After
all, if an interpretive rule gets deference, the people are bound
to obey it on pain of sanction, no less surely than they are bound
to obey substantive rules, which are accorded similar deference.
Interpretive rules that command deference do have the force
of law.
The Court’s reasons for resisting this obvious point would not
withstand a gentle breeze. Even when an agency’s interpretation
gets deference, the Court argues, “it is the court that ultimately
decides whether [the text] means what the agency says.” Ante, at 10–11, n. 4. That is not quite so. So long as
the agency does not stray beyond the ambiguity in the text being
interpreted, deference compels the reviewing court to
“decide” that the text means what the agency says. The Court
continues that “deference is not an inexorable command in all
cases,” because (for example) it does not apply to plainly
erroneous interpretations. Ibid. True, but beside the point.
Saying all interpretive rules lack force of law because
plainly erroneous interpretations do not bind courts is like saying all substantive rules lack force of law because arbitrary
and capricious rules do not bind courts. Of course an interpretive
rule must meet certain conditions before it gets deference—the
interpretation must, for instance, be reason-able—but once it does
so it is every bit as binding as a substantive rule. So the point
stands: By deferring to interpretive rules, we have allowed
agencies to make binding rules unhampered by
notice-and-commentprocedures.
The problem is bad enough, and perhaps insoluble if Chevron is not to be uprooted, with respect to interpretive
rules setting forth agency interpretation of statutes. But an
agency’s interpretation of its own regulations is an-other matter.
By giving that category of interpretive rules Auer deference, we do more than allow the agency to make binding
regulations without notice and comment. Because the agency (not
Congress) drafts the substantive rules that are the object of those
interpretations, giving them deference allows the agency to control
the extent of its notice-and-comment-free domain. To expand this
domain, the agency need only write substantive rules morebroadly
and vaguely, leaving plenty of gaps to be filled in later, using
interpretive rules unchecked by notice and comment. The APA does
not remotely contemplate this regime.
Still and all, what are we to do about the problem? The Paralyzed Veterans doctrine is a courageous (indeed, brazen)
attempt to limit the mischief by requiring an interpretive rule to
go through notice and comment if it revises an earlier definitive
interpretation of a regulation. That solution is unlawful for the
reasons set forth in the Court’s opinion: It contradicts the APA’s
unqualified exemption of interpretive rules from notice-and-comment
rulemaking.
But I think there is another solution—one unavailable to the
D. C. Circuit since it involves the overruling of one this
Court’s decisions (that being even a greater fault than merely
ignoring the APA). As I have described elsewhere, the rule of Chevron , if it did not comport with the APA, at least was in
conformity with the long history of judicial review of executive
action, where “[s]tatutory ambiguities . . . were left to
reasonable resolution by the Executive.” United States v. Mead Corp. ,533 U. S. 218,243 (2001) (Scalia, J.,
dissenting). I am unaware of any such history justifying deference
to agency interpretations of its own regulations. And there are
weighty reasons to deny a lawgiver the power to write ambiguous
laws and then be the judge of what the ambiguity means. See Decker v. Northwest Environmental Defense Center , 568
U. S. ___, ___–___ (2013) (Scalia, J., concurring in part and
dissenting in part) (slip op., at 1–7). I would therefore restore
the balance originally struck by the APA with respect to an
agency’s interpretation of its own regulations, not by rewriting
the Act in order to make up for Auer , but by abandoning Auer and applying the Act as written. The agency is free to
interpret its own regulations with or without notice and comment;
but courts will decide—with no deference to the agency—whether that
interpretation is correct. SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES
_________________
Nos. 13–1041 and 13–1052
_________________
THOMAS E. PEREZ, SECRETARY OF LABOR, et al.,
PETITIONERS
13–1041 v. MORTGAGE BANKERS ASSOCIATION et al.
JEROME NICKOLS, et al., PETITIONERS
13–1052 v. MORTGAGE BANKERS ASSOCIATION
on writs of certiorari to the united states court of appeals for
the district of columbia circuit
[March 9, 2015]
Justice Thomas, concurring in the judgment.
I concur in the Court’s holding that the doctrine first
announced in Paralyzed Veterans of America v. D. C.
Arena L. P. , 117 F. 3d 579 (CADC 1997), is inconsistent
with the Administrative Procedure Act (APA),5 U. S. C.
§551 et seq. , and must be rejected. An agency’s
substantial revision of its interpretation of a regulation does not
amount to an “amendment” of the regulation as that word is used in
the statute.
I write separately because these cases call into question the
legitimacy of our precedents requiring deference to administrative
interpretations of regulations. That line of precedents, beginning
with Bowles v. Seminole Rock & Sand Co. ,325
U. S. 410 (1945), requires judges to defer to agency
interpretations of regulations, thus, as happened in these cases,
giving legal effect to the interpretations rather than the
regulations themselves. Because this doctrine effects a transfer of
the judicial power to an executive agency, it raises constitutional
concerns. This line of precedents undermines our obligation to
provide a judicial check on the other branches, and it subjects
regulated parties to precisely the abuses that the Framers sought
to prevent.
I
The doctrine of deference to an agency’s interpretation of
regulations is usually traced back to this Court’s decision in Seminole Rock, supra , which involved the interpretation of a
war-time price control regulation, id., at 411. Along with a
general price freeze, the Administrator of the Office of Price
Administration had promulgated specialized regulations governing
the maximum price for different commodities. Id., at 413.
When the Administrator brought an enforcement action against a
manufacturer of crushed stone, the manufacturer challenged the
Administrator’s interpretation of his regulations.
The lower courts agreed with the manufacturer’s interpretation, id., at 412–413, but this Court reversed. In setting out the
approach it would apply to the case, the Court announced—without
citation or explanation—that an administrative interpretation of an
ambiguous regulation was entitled to “controlling weight”:
“Since this involves an interpretation of an administrative
regulation a court must necessarily look to the administrative
construction of the regulation if the meaning of the words used is
in doubt. The intention of Congress or the principles of the
Constitution in some situations may be relevant in the first
instance in choosing between various constructions. But the
ultimate criterion is the administrative interpretation, which
becomes of controlling weight unless it is plainly erroneous or
inconsistent with the regulation.” Id., at 413–414.
The Court then concluded that the rule “clearly” favored the
Administrator’s interpretation, rendering this discussion dictum. Id., at 415–417.
From this unsupported rule developed a doctrine of deference
that has taken on a life of its own.[ 1 ] It has
been broadly applied to regulations issued by agencies across a
broad spectrum of subjects. See, e.g., Robertson v. Methow Valley Citizens Council ,490 U. S. 332–359 (1989)
(forests); Ehlert v. United States ,402 U. S.
99–105 (1971) (Selective Service); INS v. Stanisic ,395 U. S. 62,72 (1969) (deportation); Udall v. Tallman ,380 U. S. 1–17 (1965) (oil and
gas leases). It has even been applied to an agency’s interpretation
of another agency’s regulations. See Pauley v. BethEnergy
Mines, Inc. ,501 U. S. 680–699 (1991). And, it has been
applied to an agency interpretation that was inconsistent with a
previous interpretation of the same regulation. See Long Island
Care at Home, Ltd. v. Coke ,551 U. S. 158–171
(2007). It has been applied to formal and informal interpretations
alike, including those taken during litigation. See Auer v. Robbins ,519 U. S. 452,462 (1997). Its reasoning has
also been extended outside the context of traditional agency
regulations into the realm of criminal sentencing. See Stinson v. United States ,508 U. S. 36–45 (1993)
(concluding that the Sentencing Commission’s commentary on its
Guidelines is analogous to an agency interpretation of its own
regulations, entitled to Seminole Rock deference).
The Court has even applied the doctrine to an agency
interpretation of a regulation cast in such vague aspirational
terms as to have no substantive content. See Thomas Jefferson
Univ. v. Shalala ,512 U. S. 504–513 (1994); see also id., at 518 (Thomas, J., dissenting).
On this steady march toward deference, the Court only once
expressly declined to apply Seminole Rock deference on the
ground that the agency’s interpretation was plainly
erroneous.[ 2 ] In that case, we were faced with
the predict-able consequence of this line of precedents: An agency
sought deference to an opinion letter that interpreted a permissive
regulation as mandatory. See Christensen v. Harris
County ,529 U. S. 576,588 (2000). We rejected that request
for deference as an effort, “under the guise of interpreting a
regulation, to create de facto a new regulation.” Ibid. This narrow limit on the broad deference given the
agency interpretations, though sound, could not save a doctrine
that was constitutionally infirm from the start. Seminole
Rock was constitutionally suspect from the start, and this
Court’s repeated extensions of it have only magnified the effects
and the attendant concerns.
II
We have not always been vigilant about protecting the structure
of our Constitution. Although this Court has repeatedly invoked the
“separation of powers” and “the constitutional system of checks and
balances” as core principles of our constitutional design,
essential to the protection of individual liberty, see, e.g., Stern v. Marshall , 564 U. S. ___,
___–___ (2011) (slip op., at 16–17) (internal quotation marks
omitted), it has also endorsed a “more pragmatic, flexible
approach” to that design when it has seemed more convenient to
permit the powers to be mixed, see, e.g., Nixon v. Administrator of General Services ,433 U. S. 425,442
(1977). As the history shows, that approach runs the risk of
compromising our constitutionalstructure.
A
The Constitution’s particular blend of separated powers and
checks and balances was informed by centuries of political thought
and experiences. See M. Vile, Constitutionalism and the Separation
of Powers 38, 168–169 (2d ed. 1998) (Vile). Though the theories of
the separation of powers and checks and balances have roots in the
ancient world, events of the 17th and 18th centuries played a
crucial role in their development and informed the men who crafted
and ratified the Constitution.
Over a century before our War of Independence, the English Civil
War catapulted the theory of the separation of powers to
prominence. As political theorists of the day witnessed the
conflict between the King and Parliament, and the dangers of
tyrannical government posed by each, they began to call for a clear
division of authority between the two. Id. , at 44–45, 48–49.
A 1648 work titled The Royalist’s Defence offered perhaps the first
extended account of the theory of the separation of powers:
“[W]hilst the Supreamacy , the Power to Judge the Law,
and Authority to make new Lawes, are kept in severall
hands , the known Law is preserved , but united, it
is vanished , instantly thereupon, and Arbytrary and Tyrannicall power is introduced.” The Royalist’s Defence 80
(1648) (italics in original).
John Locke and Baron de Montesquieu endorsed and expanded on
this concept. See Vile 63–64. They agreed with the general theory
set forth in The Royalist’s Defence, emphasizing the need for a
separation of powers to protect individual liberty. J. Locke,
Second Treatise of Civil Government §§143–144, p. 72 (J. Gough ed.
1947); Montesquieu, Spirit of the Laws bk. XI, ch. 6, pp. 151–152
(O. Piest ed., T. Nugent transl. 1949). But they also advocated a
system of checks and balances to reinforce that separation. Vile
72–73, 102. For instance, they agreed that the executive should
have the power to assemble and dismiss the legislature and to
consent to laws passed by it. See Locke, supra , §§151, 156,
at 75, 77–78; Montesquieu, Spirit of the Laws, at 157, 159.
Montesquieu warned that “power should be a check to power” lest the
legislature “arrogate to itself what authority it pleased
. . . [and] soon destroy all the other powers.” Id. , at 150, 157.
The experience of the States during the period between the War
of Independence and the ratification of the Constitution confirmed
the wisdom of combining these theories. Although many State
Constitutions of the time included language unequivocally endorsing
the separation of powers, they did not secure that separation with
checks and balances, Vile 147, and actively placed traditional
executive and judicial functions in the legislature, G. Wood,
The Creation of the American Republic 1776–1787, pp. 155–156
(1969). Under these arrangements, state legislatures arrogated
power to themselves and began to confiscate property, approve the
printing of paper money, and suspend the ordinary means for the
recovery of debts. Id. , at 403–409.[ 3 ]
When the Framers met for the Constitutional Convention, they
understood the need for greater checks and balances to reinforce
the separation of powers. As Madison remarked, “experience has
taught us a distrust” of the separation of powers alone as “a
sufficient security to each [branch] [against] encroachments of the
others.” 2 Re-cords of the Federal Convention of 1787, p. 77 (M.
Farrand rev. 1966). “[I]t is necessary to introduce such a balance
of powers and interests, as will guarantee the provisions on
paper.” Ibid. The Framers thus separated the three main
powers of Government—legislative, executive, and judicial—into the
three branches created by Articles I, II, and III. But they also
created checks and balances to reinforce that separation. For
example, they gave Congress specific enumerated powers to enact
legislation, Art. I, §8, but gave the President the power to
veto that legislation, subject to congressional override by a
supermajority vote, Art. I, §7, cls. 2, 3. They gave the
President the power to appoint principal officers of the United
States, but gave the Senate the power to give advice and consent to
those appointments. Art. II, §2, cl. 2. They gave the
House and Senate the power to agree to adjourn for more than three
days, Art. I, §5, cl. 4, but gave the President the
power, “in Case of Disagreement between them,” to adjourn the
Congress “to such Time as he shall think proper.” Art. II, §3,
cl. 3. During the ratification debates, Madison argued that
this structure represented “the great security” for liberty in the
Constitution. The Federalist No. 51, p. 321 (C. Rossiter ed. 1961)
(J. Madison).
To the Framers, the separation of powers and checks and balances
were more than just theories. They were practical and real
protections for individual liberty in the new Constitution. See Mistretta v. United States ,488 U. S. 361,426
(1989) (Scalia, J., dissenting) (“[The Constitution] is a
prescribed structure, a framework, for the conduct of government.
In designing that structure, the Framers themselves considered how much commingling [of governmental powers] was, in
the generality of things, acceptable, and set forth their
conclusions in the document”). The Judiciary—no less than the other
two branches—has an obligation to guard against deviations from
those principles. The Seminole Rock line of precedent is one
such deviation.
B Seminole Rock raises two related constitutional concerns.
It represents a transfer of judicial power to the Executive Branch,
and it amounts to an erosion of the judicial obligation to serve as
a “check” on the political branches.
1
When a party properly brings a case or controversy to an Article
III court, that court is called upon to exercise the “judicial
Power of the United States.” Art. III, §1. For the reasons I
explain in this section, the judicial power, as originally
understood, requires a court to exercise its independent judgment
in interpreting and expounding upon the laws.
Those who ratified the Constitution knew that legal texts would
often contain ambiguities. See generally Molot, The Judicial
Perspective in the Administrative State: Reconciling Modern
Doctrines of Deference with the Judiciary’s Structural Role, 53
Stan. L. Rev. 1, 20–21, and n. 66 (2000); Nelson, Originalism
and Interpretive Conventions, 70 U. Chi. L. Rev. 519, 525–526
(2003). As James Madison explained, “All new laws, though penned
with the greatest technical skill and passed on the fullest and
most mature deliberation, are considered as more or less obscure
and equivocal . . . .” The Federalist No. 37,at
229.
The judicial power was understood to include the power to
resolve these ambiguities over time. See ibid. Alexander
Hamilton lauded this power, arguing that “[t]he interpretation of
the laws is the proper and peculiar province of the courts.” Id. , No. 78, at 467. It is undoubtedly true that the other
branches of Government have the authority and obligation to
interpret the law, but only the judicial interpretation would be
considered authoritative in a judicial proceeding. Vile 360.
Although the Federalists and Anti-Federalists engaged in a
public debate about this interpretive power, that debate centered
on the dangers inherent in the power, not on its allocation under
the Constitution. See, e.g., Letters from The Federal Farmer
XV (Jan. 18, 1788), in 2 The Complete Anti-Federalist 315–316 (H.
Storing ed. 1981) (arguing that the interpretive power made the
Judiciary the most dangerous branch). Writing as “Brutus,” one
leading anti-Federalist argued that judges “w[ould] not confine
themselves to any fixed or established rules, but w[ould]
determine, according to what appears to them, the reason and spirit
of the constitution.” Essays of Brutus (Jan. 31, 1788), in 2 id. , at 420. The Federalists rejected these arguments,
assuring the public that judges would be guided “by strict rules
and precedents which serve to define and point out their duty in
every particular case that comes before them.” The Federalist No.
78, at 471 (A. Hamilton). Those rules included principles of
interpretation that had been set out by jurists for centuries. See, e.g. , 2 S. von Pufendorf, De Officio Hominis Et Civis Juxta
Legem Naturalem Libri Duo 83–86 (1682) (F. Moore transl. 1927); see
also 1 W. Blackstone, Commentaries on the Laws of England 59–61
(1765).
One of the key elements of the Federalists’ arguments in support
of the allocation of power to make binding interpretations of the
law was that Article III judges would exercise independent
judgment. Although “judicial independence” is often discussed in
terms of independence from external threats, the Framers understood
the concept to also require independence from the “internal threat”
of “human will.” P. Hamburger, Law and Judicial Duty 507, 508
(2008); see also The Federalist No. 78, at 465 (A. Hamilton) (“The
judiciary . . . may truly be said to have neither FORCE nor WILL
but merely judgment . . . ”). Independent judgment
required judges to decide cases in accordance with the law of the
land, not in accordance with pressures placed upon them through
either internal or external sources. Internal sources might include
personal biases, while external sources might include pressure from
the political branches, the public, or otherinterested parties. See
Hamburger, supra, at 508–521.
The Framers made several key decisions at the Convention with
these pressures in mind. For example, they rejected proposals to
include a federal council of revision after several participants at
the Convention expressed concern that judicial involvement in such
a council would foster internal biases. Rufus King of Maryland, for
example, asserted that “the Judges ought to be able to expound the
law as it should come before them, free from the bias of having
participated in its formation.” 1 Records of the Federal Convention
of 1787, at 98. Alexander Hamilton repeated these concerns in The
Federalist, arguing that “the judges, who are to be interpreters of
the law, might receive an improper bias from having given a
previous opinion in their revisionary capacities” or “be induced to
embark too far in the political views of [the Executive]” from too
much association with him. The Federalist No. 73, at 446; see also
Hamburger, supra, at 508–512.
The Framers also created structural protections in the
Constitution to free judges from external influences. They
provided, for example, that judges should “hold their Offices
during good Behaviour” and receive “a Compensation, which shall not
be diminished during their Continuance in Office.” Art. III,
§1. Hamilton noted that such unequivocal language had been shown
necessary by the experience of the States, where similar state
constitutional protections for judges had not been “sufficiently
definiteto preclude legislative evasions” of the separation of the
judicial power. The Federalist No. 79, at 472. Because “power over
a man’s subsistence amounts to a power over his will,” he argued
that Article III’s structural protections would help ensure that
judges fulfilled their constitutional role. Ibid. (emphasis
deleted).
The Framers made the opposite choice for legislators and the
Executive. Instead of insulating them from external pressures, the
Constitution tied them to those pressures. It provided for election
of Members of the House of Representatives every two years,
Art. I, §2, cl. 1; and selection of Members of the Senate
every six years, Art. I, §3, cl. 1. It also provided for
the President to be subject to election every four years.
Art. II, §1, cl. 1. “The President is [thus] directly
dependent on the people, and since there is only one President, he is responsible. The people know whom to blame
. . . .” See Morrison v. Olson ,487
U. S. 654,729 (1988) (Scalia, J., dissenting). To preserve
that accountability, we have held that executive officers must be subject to removal by the President to ensure
account-ability within the Executive Branch. See Free Enterprise
Fund v. Public Company Accounting Oversight Bd. ,561
U. S. 477,495 (2010); see also Morrison , supra ,
at 709 (opinion of Scalia, J.) (“It is not for us to determine, and
we have never presumed to determine, how much of the purely
executive powers of government must be within the full control of
the President. The Constitution prescribes that they all are”).
Given these structural distinctions between the branches, it is
no surprise that judicial interpretations are defini-tive in cases
and controversies before the courts. Courts act as “an intermediate
body between the people and the legislature, in order, among other
things, to keep the latter within the limits assigned to their
authority.” Federalist No. 78, at 467 (A. Hamilton). The
Legislature and Executive may be swayed by popular sentiment to
abandon the strictures of the Constitution or other rules of law.
But the Judiciary, insulated from both internal and external
sources of bias, is duty bound to exercise independent judgment in
applying the law.
Interpreting agency regulations calls for that exercise of
independent judgment. Substantive regulations have the force and
effect of law. See, e.g., United States v. Mead
Corp. ,533 U. S. 218–232 (2001).[ 4 ]
Agencies and private parties alike can use these regulations in
proceedings against regulated parties. See, e.g. , Christopher v. SmithKline Beecham Corp. , 567
U. S. ___, ___–___ (2012) (slip op., at 6–7) (private party
relying on Department of Labor regulations); FCC v. Fox
Television Stations, Inc. , 567 U. S. ___, ___ (2012) (slip
op., at 6) (agency issuing notices of liability under regulations).
Just as it is critical for judges to exercise independent judgment
in applying statutes, it is critical for judges to exercise
independent judgment in determining that a regulation properly
covers the conduct of regulated parties. Defining the legal meaning
of the regulation is one aspect of that determination. Seminole Rock deference, however, precludes judges from
independently determining that meaning. Rather than judges’
applying recognized tools of interpretation to determine the best
meaning of a regulation, this doctrine demands that courts accord
“controlling weight” to the agency interpretation of a regulation,
subject only to the narrow exception for interpretations that are
plainly erroneous or inconsistent with the regulation. That
deference amounts to a transfer of the judge’s exercise of
interpretive judgment to the agency. See 1 S. Johnson, Dictionary
of the English Language 499 (4th ed. 1773) (defining “[d]efer” as
“to leave to another’s judgment”). But the agency, as part of the
Executive Branch, lacks the structural protections for independent
judgment adopted by the Framers, including the life tenure and
salary protections of Article III. Because the agency is thus not
properly constituted to exercise the judicial power under the
Constitution, the transfer of interpretive judgment raises serious
separation-of-powers concerns.
2 Seminole Rock is constitutionally questionable for an
additional reason: It undermines the judicial “check” on the
political branches. Unlike the Legislative and Executive Branches,
each of which possesses several political checks on the other, the
Judiciary has one primary check on the excesses of political
branches. That check is the enforcement of the rule of law through
the exercise of judicial power.
Judges have long recognized their responsibility to apply the
law, even if they did not conceive of it as a “check” on political
power. During the 17th century, for example, King James I sought to
pressure Chief Justice Coke to affirm the lawfulness of his efforts
to raise revenue without the participation of Parliament.
Hamburger, Law and Judicial Duty, at 200–201. Coke sought time to
confer with his fellow jurists to “make an advised answer according
to law and reason.” Case of Proclamations , 12 Co. Rep. 74,
75, 77 Eng. Rep. 1352, 1353 (K. B. 1611). But the King’s
representative, Lord Chancellor Ellesmere, responded that “he would
advise the Judges to maintain the power and prerogative of the
King” and suggested that, “in cases in which there is no authority
and precedent,” the judiciary should “leave it to the King to order
in it according to his wisdom.” Ibid . Coke famously
responded, “[T]he King cannot change any part of the common law,
nor create any offence by his proclamation, which was not an
offence before, without Parliament.” Ibid. When James I
later attempted to do just that, Coke declared the proclamations
“ ‘utterly against Law and reason, and for that void.’ ”
Hamburger, supra , at 202.
The Framers expected Article III judges to engage in similar
efforts, by applying the law as a “check” on the excesses of both
the Legislative and Executive Branches. See, e.g., 3 J.
Elliot, Debates in the Several Conventions on the Adoption of the
Federal Constitution 553 (1863) (J. Marshall) (“If [the Government
of the United States] make a law not warranted by any of the powers
enumerated, it would be considered by the judges as an infringement
of the Constitution which they are to guard. . . . They
would declare it void”); see also Vile 174. The Framers
“contemplated [the Constitution], as a rule for the government of courts , as well as of the legislature.” Marbury v. Madison , 1 Cranch 137, 179–180 (1803). Thus, if a case
involved a conflict between a law and the Constitution, judges
would have a duty “to adhere to the latter and disregard the
former.” The Federalist No. 78, at 468 (A. Hamilton); see also Marbury , 1 Cranch, at 178. Similarly, if a case involved an
executive effort to extend a law beyond its meaning, judges would
have a duty to adhere to the law that had been properly promulgated
under the Constitution. Cf. id. , at 157–158 (considering the
scope of the President’s constitutional power of appointment). As
this Court said long ago, “[T]he particular phraseology of the
constitution of the United States confirms and strengthens the
principle, supposed to be essential to all written constitutions,
that a law repugnant to the constitution is void; and that courts , as well as other departments, are bound by that
instrument.” Id., at 180.
Article III judges cannot opt out of exercising their check. As
we have long recognized, “[t]he Judiciary has a responsibility to
decide cases properly before it, even those it ‘would gladly
avoid.’ ” Zivotofsky v. Clinton , 566 U. S.
___, ___ (2012) (slip op., at 5) (quoting Cohens v. Virginia , 6 Wheat. 264, 404 (1821)). This responsibility
applies not only to constitutional challenges to particular
statutes, see, e.g., Shelby County v. Holder , 570
U. S. ___, ___ (2013) (slip op., at 2), including those based
on the separation of powers, Free Enterprise Fund , 561
U. S., at 501–502, but also to more routine questions about
the best interpretation of statutes, see, e.g., Whitfield v. United States , 574 U. S. ___, ___–___ (2015) (slip op.,
at 2–3), or the compatibility of agency actions with enabling
statutes, Utility Air Regulatory Group v. EPA , 573
U. S. ___, ___ (2014) (slip op., at 10). In each case, the
Judiciary is called upon to exercise its independent judgment and
apply the law.
But we have not consistently exercised the judicial check with
respect to administrative agencies. Even though regulated parties
have repeatedly challenged agency interpretations as inconsistent
with existing regulations, we have just as repeatedly declined to
exercise independent judgment as to those claims. Instead, we have
deferred to the executive agency that both promulgated the
regulations and enforced them. Although an agency’s interpretation
of a regulation might be the best interpretation, it also might
not. When courts refuse even to decide what the best interpretation
is under the law, they abandon the judicial check. That abandonment
permits precisely the accumulation of governmental powers that the
Framers warned against. See The Federalist No. 47, at 302 (J.
Madison).
C
This accumulation of governmental powers allows agencies to
change the meaning of regulations at their discretion and without
any advance notice to the parties. It is precisely this problem
that the United States Court of Appeals for the D. C. Circuit
attempted to address by requiring agencies to undertake notice and
comment procedures before substantially revising definitive
interpretations of regulations. Paralyzed Veterans, supra .
Though legally erroneous, the Court of Appeals’ reasoning was
practically sound. When courts give “controlling weight” to an
administrative interpretation of a regulation—instead of to the best interpretation of it—they effectively give the
interpretation—and not the regulation—the force and effect of law.
To regulated parties, the new interpretation might as well be a new
regulation.
These cases provide a classic example of the problem. The Fair
Labor Standards Act of 1938 establishes federal minimum wage and
overtime requirements, but exempts from these requirements “any
employee engaged in a bona fide executive, administrative, or
professional capac-ity . . . , or in the
capacity of outside salesman (as such terms are defined and
delimited from time to time by regulations of the Secretary).”29
U. S. C. §213(a)(1). The Department of Labor has
accordingly promulgated regulations providing that “an employee
whose primary duty is selling financial products does not qualify
for the administrative exemption.” 29 CFR §541.203(b) (2015).
Unsure whether certain mortgage-loan officers qualified as
employees whose primary duty is selling financial products, the
Mortgage Bankers Association asked the Department of Labor for
advice. In 2006, the Department concluded that the officers are not
employees whose primary duty is selling financial products. But in
2010, the Department reversed course, concluding exactly the
opposite. If courts accord “controlling weight” to both the 2006
and 2010 interpretations, the regulated entities are subject to two
opposite legal rules imposed under the same regulation.
This practice turns on its head the principle that the United
States is “a government of laws, and not of men.” Marbury , supra , at 163. Regulations provide notice to regulated
parties in only a limited sense because their meaning will
ultimately be determined by agencies rather than by the “strict
rules and precedents” to which Alexander Hamilton once
referred.[ 5 ]
III
Although this Court offered no theoretical justifica-tion for Seminole Rock deference when announcing it, sev-eral
justifications have been proposed since. None is persuasive.
A
Probably the most oft-recited justification for Seminole
Rock deference is that of agency expertise in administering
technical statutory schemes. Under this justification, deference to
administrative agencies is necessary when a “regulation concerns ‘a
complex and highly technical regulatory program’ in which the
identification and classification of relevant ‘criteria necessarily
require significant expertise and entail the exercise of judgment
grounded in policy concerns.’ ” Thomas Jefferson Univ., 512 U. S., at 512.
This defense of Seminole Rock deference misidentifies the
relevant inquiry. The proper question faced by courts in
interpreting a regulation is not what the best policy choice might
be, but what the regulation means. Because this Court has concluded
that “substantive agency regulations have the ‘force and effect of
law,’ ” Chrysler Corp. v. Brown ,441 U. S.
281,295 (1979), such regulations should be interpreted like any
other law. Thus, we should “assum[e] that the ordinary meaning of
the regulation’s language expresses” its purpose and enforce it
“according to its terms.” See Hardt v. Reliance Standard
Life Ins. Co. ,560 U. S. 242,251 (2010) (internal quotation
marks omitted). Judges are at least as well suited as
administrative agencies to engage in this task. Cf. Marbury ,
1 Cranch, at 177 (“It is emphatically the province and duty of the
judicial department to say what the law is”). Indeed, judges are
frequently called upon to interpret the meaning of legal texts and
are able to do so even when those texts involve technical language.
See, e.g., Barber v. Gonzales ,347 U. S. 637–643
(1954) (interpreting deportation statute according to technical
meaning).
Fundamentally, the argument about agency expertise is less about
the expertise of agencies in interpreting language than it is about
the wisdom of according agencies broad flexibility to administer
statutory schemes.[ 6 ] “But policy arguments
supporting even useful ‘political inventions’ are subject to the
demands of the Constitution which defines powers and . . . sets out
. . . how those powers are to be exercised.” INS v. Chadha ,462 U. S. 919,945 (1983). Even in the face of
a perceived necessity, the Constitution protects us from ourselves. New York v. United States ,505 U. S. 144–188
(1992).
B
Another oft-recited justification for Seminole Rock deference is that agencies are better situated to define the
original intent behind their regulations. See Martin v. Occupational Safety and Health Review Comm’n ,499 U. S.
144–153 (1991). Under this justification, “[b]ecause the Secretary
[of Labor] promulgates th[e] standards, the Secretary is in a
better position . . . to reconstruct the purpose of the
regulations in question.” Id. , at 152.
This justification rings hollow. This Court has afforded Seminole Rock deference to agency interpretations even when
the agency was not the original drafter. See Pauley , 501
U. S., at 696–698 (applying Seminole Rock deference to
one agency’s interpretation of another agency’s regulations because
Congress had delegated authority to both to administer the
program). It has likewise granted Seminole Rock deference to
agency interpretations that are inconsistent with interpretations
adopted closer in time to the promulgation of the regulations. See, e.g., Long Island Care at Home , 551 U. S., at
170–171.
Even if the scope of Seminole Rock deference more closely
matched the original-drafter justification, it would still fail. It
is the text of the regulations that have the force and effect of
law, not the agency’s intent. “Citizens arrange their affairs not
on the basis of their legislators’ unexpressed intent, but on the
basis of the law as it is written and promulgated.” Zuni Public
School Dist. No. 89 v. Department of Education ,550
U. S. 81,119 (2007) (Scalia, J., dissenting). Cf. Wyeth v. Levine ,555 U. S. 555–587 (2009) (Thomas, J.,
concurring in judgment) (noting that only “federal standards
. . . that are set forth in, or necessarily follow from,
the statutory text that was produced through the constitutionally
required bicameral and presentment procedures”—not Congress’
“purposes and objectives”—can become the “law of the land”). “To be
governed by legislated text rather than legislators’ intentions is
what it means to be ‘a Government of laws, not of men.’ ” Zuni Public School Dist. No. 89 , supra , at 119
(Scalia, J., dissenting). Only the text of a regulation goes
through the procedures established by Congress for agency
rulemaking. And it is that text on which the public is entitled to
rely. For the same reasons that we should not accord controlling
weight to postenactment expressions of intent by individual Members
of Congress, see Sullivan v. Finkelstein ,496
U. S. 617–632 (1990) (Scalia, J., concurring in part), we
should not accord controlling weight to expressions of intent by
administrators ofagencies.
C
A third asserted justification for Seminole Rock deference is that Congress has delegated to agencies the authority
to interpret their own regulations. See, e.g., Martin , 499
U. S., at 151. The theory is that, “[b]ecause applying an
agency’s regulation to complex or changing circumstances calls upon
the agency’s unique expertise and policymaking prerogatives,
. . . the power authoritatively to interpret its own
regulations is a component of the agency’s delegated lawmaking
powers.” Ibid. This justification fails because Congress lacks authority to
delegate the power. As we have explained in an analogous context,
“[t]he structure of the Constitution does not permit Congress to
execute the laws; it follows that Congress cannot grant to an
officer under its control what it does not possess.” Bowsher v. Synar ,478 U. S. 714,726 (1986). Similarly, the
Constitution does not empower Congress to issue a judicially
binding interpretation of the Constitution or its laws. Lacking the
power itself, it cannot delegate that power to an agency.
To hold otherwise would be to vitiate the separation of powers
and ignore the “sense of a sharp necessity to separate the
legislative from the judicial power . . . [that]
triumphed among the Framers of the new Federal Constitution.” Plaut v. Spendthrift Farm, Inc. ,514 U. S.
211,221 (1995). As this Court has explained, the “essential
balance” of the Constitution is that the Legislature is “possessed
of power to ‘prescrib[e] the rules by which the duties and rights
of every citizen are to be regulated,’ but the power of ‘[t]he
interpretation of the laws’ [is] ‘the proper and peculiar province
of the courts.’ ” Id., at 222 (citation omitted; third
brackets added). Although the Constitution imposes a duty on all
three branches to interpret the laws within their own spheres, the
power to create legally binding interpretations rests with the
Judiciary. See Marbury , 1 Cranch, at 177, 179–180.
D
A final proposed justification for Seminole Rock deference is that too much oversight of administrative matters
would imperil the “independence and esteem” of judges. See, e.g., Charles Evans Hughes, Speech before the Elmira Chamber
of Commerce, May 3, 1907, in Addresses of Charles Evans Hughes,
1906–1916, p. 185 (2d ed. 1916). The argument goes that questions
of administration are those which “lie close to the public
impatience,” id., at 186, and thus the courts’ resolution of
such questions could “expose them to the fire of public criticism,” id., at 187.
But this argument, which boils down to a policy judgment of
questionable validity, cannot vitiate the constitutional allocation
of powers. The Judicial Branch is separate from the political
branches for a reason: It has the obligation to apply the law to
cases and controversies that come before it, and concerns about the
popular esteem of individual judges—or even the Judiciary as a
whole—have no place in that analysis. Our system of Government
could not long survive absent adherence to the written Constitution
that formed it.
* * *
Although on the surface these cases require only a
straightforward application of the APA, closer scrutiny reveals
serious constitutional questions lurking beneath. I have
“acknowledge[d] the importance of stare decisis to the
stability of our Nation’s legal system.” “But stare decisis is only an ‘adjunct’ of our duty as judges to decide by our best
lights what the Constitution means.” McDonald v. Chicago ,561 U. S. 742,812 (2010) (Thomas, J.,
concurring inpart and concurring in judgment) (citation omitted).
By my best lights, the entire line of precedent beginning with Seminole Rock raises serious constitutional questions and
should be reconsidered in an appropriate case. Notes 1 Although the Court has appeared to
treat our agency deference regimes as precedents entitled to stare decisis effect, some scholars have noted that they
might instead be classified as interpretive tools. See, e.g., C. Nelson, Statutory Interpretation 701 (2011). Such
tools might not be entitled to such effect. Because resolution of
that issue is not necessary to my conclusion here, I leave it for
another day. 2 The Court has also twice expressly
found Seminole Rock deference inapplicable for other
reasons. Christopher v. SmithKline Beecham Corp. , 567
U. S. ___, ___–___ (2012) (slip op., at 13–14) (“[W]here, as
here, an agency’s announcement of its interpretation is preceded by
a very lengthy period of conspicuous inaction, the potential for
unfair surprise is acute. . . . [W]hatever the general
merits of Auer deference, it is unwarranted here”); Gonzales v. Oregon ,546 U. S. 243–257 (2006) (“In
our view Auer and the standard of deference it accords to an
agency are inapplicable here. . . . The language the
Interpretive Rule addresses comes from Congress, not the Attorney
General, and the near equivalence of the statute and regulation
belies the Government’s argument for Auer deference”). 3 The practices of the time can perhaps
best be summarized by the following commentary from a
contemporaneous magazine: “[S]o many legal infractions of
sacred right—so many public invasions of private property—so many
wanton abuses of legislative powers!” Giles Hickory (Noah Webster),
Government, The American Magazine, Mar. 1788, p. 206. 4 These cases also raise constitutional
questions about the distinction in administrative law between
“substantive” (or “legislative”) and interpretative rules. The
United States Court of Appeals for the D. C. Circuit has defined a
legislative rule as “[a]n agency action that purports to impose
legally binding obligations or prohibitions on regulated parties”
and an interpretative rule as “[a]n agency action that merely
interprets a prior statute or regulation, and does not itself
purport to impose new obligations or prohibitions or requirements
on regulated parties.” National Mining Assn. v. McCarthy , 758 F. 3d 243, 251–252 (2014). And our
precedents make clear that administrative agencies must exercise
only executive power in promulgating these rules. Arlington v. FCC , 569 U. S. ___, ___, n. 4 (2013) (slip op.,
at 13, n. 4). But while it is easy to see the promulgation of
interpretative rules as an “executive” function—executive officials
necessarily interpret the laws they enforce—it is difficult to see
what authority the President has “to impose legally binding
obligations or prohibitions on regulated parties.” That definition
suggests something much closer to the legislative power, which our
Constitution does not permit the Executive to exercise in this
manner. Because these troubling questions are not directly
implicated here, I leave them for another case. See Department
of Transportation v. Association of American Railroads , ante, at 19–22 (Thomas, J., concurring in
judgment). 5 The notice problem is exacerbated by
agency departures from the procedures established for rulemaking in
the APA. Although almost all rulemaking is today accomplished
through informal notice and comment, the APA actually contemplated
a much more formal process for most rulemaking. To that end, it
provided for elaborate trial-like hearings in which proponents of
particular rules would introduce evidence and bear the burden of
proof in support of those proposed rules. See5 U. S. C.
§556. 6 Many decisions of this Court invoke
agency expertise as a justification for deference. This argument
has its root in the support for administrative agencies that
developed during the Progressive Era in this country. The Era was
marked by a move from the individualism that had long characterized
American society to the concept of a society organized for
collective action. See A. Link, Woodrow Wilson and the Progressive
Era 1910–1917, p. 1 (1954). That move also reflected a deep disdain
for the theory of popular sovereignty. As Woodrow Wilson wrote
before he attained the presidency, “Our peculiar American
difficulty in organizing administration is not the danger of losing
liberty, but the danger of not being able or willing to separate
its essentials from its accidents. Our success is made doubtful by
that besetting error of ours, the error of trying to do too much by
vote.” Wilson, The Study of Administration, 2 Pol. Sci. Q. 197, 214
(1887). In President Wilson’s view, public criticism would be
beneficial in the formation of overall policy, but “a clumsy
nuisance” in the daily life of Government—“a rustic handling
delicate machinery.” Id., at 215. Reflecting this belief
that bureaucrats might more effectively govern the country than the
American people, the progressives ushered in significant expansions
of the administrative state, ultimately culminating in the New
Deal. See generally M. Keller, Regulating a New Economy: Public
Policy and Economic Change in America, 1900–1933
(1990). | The Supreme Court ruled that federal agencies do not need to follow notice-and-comment rulemaking procedures when issuing a new interpretation of a regulation, departing from the D.C. Circuit's previous ruling in Paralyzed Veterans of Am. v. D.C. Arena L.P. |
Free Speech | Paris Adult Theatre I v. Slaton | https://supreme.justia.com/cases/federal/us/413/49/ | U.S. Supreme Court Paris Adult Theatre I v. Slaton, 413 U.S.
49 (1973) Paris Adult Theatre I v.
Slaton No. 71-1051 Argued October 19,
1972 Decided June 21, 1973 413 U.S.
49 CERTIORARI TO THE SUPREME COURT OF
GEORGIA Syllabus Respondents sued under Georgia civil law to enjoin the
exhibiting by petitioners of two allegedly obscene films. There was
no prior restraint. In a jury-waived trial, the trial court (which
did not require "expert" affirmative evidence of obscenity) viewed
the films and thereafter dismissed the complaints on the ground
that the display of the films in commercial theaters to consenting
adult audiences (reasonable precautions having been taken to
exclude minors) was "constitutionally permissible." The Georgia
Supreme Court reversed, holding that the films constituted "hard
core" pornography not within the protection of the First
Amendment. Held: 1. Obscene material is not speech entitled to First Amendment
protection. Miller v. California, ante p. 413 U. S. 15 ; Roth v. United States, 354 U. S. 476 . P. 413 U. S.
54 .
2. The Georgia civil procedure followed here (assuming use of a
constitutionally acceptable standard for determining what is
unprotected by the First Amendment) comported with the standards of Teitel Film Corp. v. Cusack, 390 U.
S. 139 ; Freedman v. Maryland, 380 U. S.
51 ; and Kingsley Books, Inc. v. Brown, 354 U. S. 436 . Pp. 413 U. S.
54 -55.
3. It was not error to fail to require expert affirmative
evidence of the films' obscenity, since the films (which were the
best evidence of what they depicted) were themselves placed in
evidence. P. 413 U. S.
56 .
4. States have a legitimate interest in regulating commerce in
obscene material and its exhibition in places of public
accommodation, including "adult" theaters. Pp. 413 U. S.
57 -69.
(a) There is a proper state concern with safeguarding against
crime and the other arguably ill effects of obscenity by
prohibiting the public or commercial exhibition of obscene
material. Though conclusive proof is lacking, the States may
reasonably determine that a nexus does or might exist between
antisocial behavior and obscene material, just as States have acted
on unprovable assumptions in other areas of public control. Pp. 413 U. S.
57 -63.
(b) Though States are free to adopt a laissez-faire policy toward commercialized obscenity, they are not
constitutionally obliged to do so. P. 413 U. S.
64 . Page 413 U. S. 50 (c) Exhibition of obscene material in places of public
accommodation is not protected by any constitutional doctrine of
privacy. A commercial theater cannot be equated with a private
home; nor is there here a privacy right arising from a special
relationship, such as marriage. Stanley v. Georgia, 394 U. S. 557 ; Griswold v. Connecticut, 381 U. S. 479 ,
distinguished. Nor can the privacy of the home be equated with a
"one" of "privacy" that follows a consumer of obscene materials
wherever he goes. United States v. Orito, post, p. 413 U. S. 139 ; United States v. 12 200-ft. Reels of Film, post, p. 123.
Pp. 413 U. S.
65 -67.
(d) Preventing the unlimited display of obscene material is not
thought control. Pp. 413 U. S.
67 -68.
(e) Not all conduct directly involving "consenting adults" only
has a claim to constitutional protection. Pp. 413 U. S.
68 -69.
5. The Georgia obscenity laws involved herein should now be
reevaluated in the light of the First Amendment standards newly
enunciated by the Court in Miller v. California, ante, p.
15. Pp. 413 U. S.
69 -70.
228 Ga. 343, 185 S.E.2d
768 , vacated and remanded.
BURGER, C.J., delivered the opinion of the Court, in which
WHITE, BLACKMUN, POWELL, and REHNQUIST, JJ., joined. DOUGLAS, J.,
filed a dissenting opinion, post, p. 413 U. S. 70 .
BRENNAN, J., filed a dissenting opinion, in which STEWART and
MARSHALL, JJ., joined, post, p. 413 U. S.
73 .
MR. CHIEF JUSTICE BURGER delivered the opinion of the Court.
Petitioners are two Atlanta, Georgia, movie theaters and their
owners and managers, operating in the Page 413 U. S. 51 style of "adult" theaters. On December 28, 1970, respondents,
the local state district attorney and the solicitor for the local
state trial court, filed civil complaints in that court alleging
that petitioners were exhibiting to the public for paid admission
two allegedly obscene films, contrary to Georgia Code Ann. §
26-2101. [ Footnote 1 ] The two
films in question, "Magic Mirror" and "It All Comes Out in the
End," depict sexual conduct characterized Page 413 U. S. 52 by the Georgia Supreme Court as "hard core pornography" leaving
"little to the imagination."
Respondents' complaints, made on behalf of the State of Georgia,
demanded that the two films be declared obscene and that
petitioners be enjoined from exhibiting the films. The exhibition
of the films was not enjoined, but a temporary injunction was
granted ex parte by the local trial court, restraining
petitioners from destroying the films or removing them from the
jurisdiction. Petitioners were further ordered to have one print
each of the films in court on January 13, 1971, together with the
proper viewing equipment.
On January 13, 1971, 15 days after the proceedings began, the
films were produced by petitioners at a jury-waived trial. Certain
photographs, also produced at trial, were stipulated to portray the
single entrance to both Paris Adult Theatre I and Paris Adult
Theatre II as it appeared at the time of the complaints. These
photographs show a conventional, inoffensive theater entrance,
without any pictures, but with signs indicating that the theaters
exhibit "Atlanta's Finest Mature Feature Films." On the door itself
is a sign saying: "Adult Theatre -- You must be 21 and able to
prove it. If viewing the nude body offends you, Please Do Not
Enter."
The two films were exhibited to the trial court. The only other
state evidence was testimony by criminal investigators that they
had paid admission to see the films and that nothing on the outside
of the theater indicated the full nature of what was shown. In
particular, nothing indicated that the films depicted -- as they
did -- scenes of simulated fellatio, cunnilingus, and group sex
intercourse. There was no evidence presented that minors had ever
entered the theaters. Nor was there evidence presented that
petitioners had a systematic policy of barring minors, apart from
posting signs at the entrance. On April 12, 1971, the trial judge
dismissed Page 413 U. S. 53 respondents' complaints. He assumed "that obscenity is
established," but stated:
"It appears to the Court that the display of these films in a
commercial theatre, when surrounded by requisite notice to the
public of their nature and by reasonable protection against the
exposure of these films to minors, is constitutionally
permissible."
On appeal, the Georgia Supreme Court unanimously reversed. It
assumed that the adult theaters in question barred minors and gave
a full warning to the general public of the nature of the films
shown, but held that the films were without protection under the
First Amendment. Citing the opinion of this Court in United
States v. Reidel, 402 U. S. 351 (1971), the Georgia court stated that "the sale and delivery of
obscene material to willing adults is not protected under the first
amendment." The Georgia court also held Stanley v.
Georgia, 394 U. S. 557 (1969), to be inapposite, since it did not deal with "the
commercial distribution of pornography, but with the right of
Stanley to possess, in the privacy of his home, pornographic
films." 228 Ga. 343, 345, 185 S.E.2d
768 , 769 (1971). After viewing the films, the Georgia Supreme
Court held that their exhibition should have been enjoined,
stating:
"The films in this case leave little to the imagination. It is
plain what they purport to depict, that is, conduct of the most
salacious character. We hold that these films are also hard core
pornography, and the showing of such films should have been
enjoined, since their exhibition is not protected by the first
amendment." Id. at 347, 185 S.E.2d at 770. I It should be clear from the outset that we do not undertake to
tell the States what they must do, but Page 413 U. S. 54 rather to define the area in which they may chart their own
course in dealing with obscene material. This Court has
consistently held that obscene material is not protected by the
First Amendment as a limitation on the state police power by virtue
of the Fourteenth Amendment. Miller v. California, ante at 413 U. S. 225 ; Kois v. Wisconsin, 408 U. S. 229 , 408 U. S. 230 (1972); United States v. Reidel, supra, at 402 U. S. 354 ; Roth v. United States, 354 U. S. 476 , 354 U. S. 485 (1957).
Georgia case law permits a civil injunction of the exhibition of
obscene materials. See 1024 Peachtree Corp. v. Slaton, 228
Ga. 102, 184 S.E.2d 144 (1971); Walter v. Slaton, 227 Ga.
676, 182 S.E.2d 464 (1971); Evans Theatre Corp. v. Slaton, 227 Ga. 377, 180 S.E.2d 712 (1971). While this procedure is civil in nature, and does not
directly involve the state criminal statute proscribing exhibition
of obscene material, [ Footnote
2 ] the Georgia case law permitting civil injunction does adopt
the definition of "obscene materials" used by the criminal statute.
[ Footnote 3 ] Today, in Miller v. California, supra, we have Page 413 U. S. 55 sought to clarify the constitutional definition of obscene
material subject to regulation by the States, and we vacate and
remand this case for reconsideration in light of Miller. This is not to be read as disapproval of the Georgia civil
procedure employed in this case, assuming the use of a
constitutionally acceptable standard for determining what is
unprotected by the First Amendment. On the contrary, such a
procedure provides an exhibitor or purveyor of materials the best
possible notice, prior to any criminal indictments, as to whether
the materials are unprotected by the First Amendment and subject to
state regulation. [ Footnote 4 ] See Kingsley Books, Inc. v. Brown, 354 U.
S. 436 , 354 U. S.
441 -444 (1957). Here, Georgia imposed no restraint on
the exhibition of the films involved in this case until after a
full adversary proceeding and a final judicial determination by the
Georgia Supreme Court that the materials were constitutionally
unprotected. [ Footnote 5 ] Thus,
the standards of Blount v. Rizzi, 400 U.
S. 410 , 400 U. S. 417 (1971); Teitel Film Corp. v. Cusack, 390 U.
S. 139 , 390 U. S.
141 -142 (1968); Freedman v. Maryland, 380 U. S. 51 , 380 U. S. 559 (1965), and Kingsley Books, Inc. v. Brown, supra, at 354 U. S.
443 -445, were met. Cf. United States v. Thirty-seven
Photographs, 402 U. S. 363 , 402 U. S.
367 -369 (1971) (opinion of WHITE, J.). Page 413 U. S. 56 Nor was it error to fail to require "expert" affirmative
evidence that the materials were obscene when the materials
themselves were actually placed in evidence. United States v.
Groner, 479 F.2d 577, 579-586 (CA5 1973); id. at
586-588 (Ainsworth, J., concurring); id. at 586-589
(Clark, J., concurring); United States v. Wild, 422 1.2d
34, 35-36 (CA2 1969), cert. denied, 402 U.S. 986 (1971); Kahm v. United States, 300 F.2d 78, 84 (CA5), cert.
denied, 369 U.S. 859 (1962); State v. Amato, 49
Wis.2d 638, 645, 183 N.W.2d
29 , 32 (1971), cert. denied sub nom. Amato v.
Wisconsin, 404 U.S. 1063 (1972). See Smith v.
California, 361 U. S. 147 , 361 U. S. 172 (1959) (Harlan, J., concurring and dissenting); United States
v. Brown, 328 F.
Supp. 196 , 199 (ED Va.1971). The films, obviously, are the best
evidence of what they represent. [ Footnote 6 ]
"In the cases in which this Court has decided obscenity
questions since Roth, it has regarded the materials as
sufficient in themselves for the determination of the
question." Ginzburg v. United States, 383 U.
S. 463 , 383 U. S. 465 (1966). Page 413 U. S. 57 II We categorically disapprove the theory, apparently adopted by
the trial judge, that obscene, pornographic films acquire
constitutional immunity from state regulation simply because they
are exhibited for consenting adults only. This holding was properly
rejected by the Georgia Supreme Court. Although we have often
pointedly recognized the high importance of the state interest in
regulating the exposure of obscene materials to juveniles and
unconsenting adults, see Miller v. California, ante at 413 U. S. 18 -20; Stanley v. Georgia, 394 U.S. at 394 U. S. 567 ; Redrup v. New York, 386 U. S. 767 , 386 U. S. 769 (1967), this Court has never declared these to be the only
legitimate state interests permitting regulation of obscene
material. The States have a long-recognized legitimate interest in
regulating the use of obscene material in local commerce and in all
places of public accommodation, as long as these regulations do not
run afoul of specific constitutional prohibitions. See United
States v. Thirty-seven Photographs, supra, at 402 U. S.
376 -377 (opinion of WHITE, J.); United States v.
Reidel, 402 U.S. at 402 U. S.
354 -356. Cf. United States v. Thirty-seven
Photographs, supra, at 402 U. S. 378 (STEWART, J., concurring).
"In an unbroken series of cases extending over a long stretch of
this Court's history, it has been accepted as a postulate that 'the
primary requirements of decency may be enforced against obscene
publications.' [ Near v. Minnesota, 283 U. S.
697 , 283 U. S. 716 (1931)]." Kingsley Books, Inc. v. Brown, supra, at 354 U. S.
440 .
In particular, we hold that there are legitimate state interests
at stake in stemming the tide of commercialized obscenity, even
assuming it is feasible to enforce effective safeguards against
exposure to juveniles and to passersby. [ Footnote 7 ] Page 413 U. S. 58 Rights and interests "other than those of the advocates are
involved." Breard v. Alexandria, 341 U.
S. 622 , 341 U. S. 642 (1951). These include the interest of the public in the quality of
life and the total community environment, the tone of commerce in
the great city centers, and, possibly, the public safety itself.
The Hill-Link Minority Report of the Commission on Obscenity and
Pornography indicates that there is at least an arguable
correlation between obscene material and crime. [ Footnote 8 ] Quite Page 413 U. S. 59 apart from sex crimes, however, there remains one problem of
large proportions aptly described by Professor Bickel:
"It concerns the tone of the society, the mode, or to use terms
that have perhaps greater currency, the style and quality of life,
now and in the future. A man may be entitled to read an obscene
book in his room, or expose himself indecently there. . . . We
should protect his privacy. But if he demands a right to obtain the
books and pictures he wants in the market, and to foregather in
public places -- discreet, if you will, but accessible to all --
with others who share his tastes, then to grant him his right
is to affect the world about the rest of us, and to impinge on
other privacies. Even supposing that each of us can, if he
wishes, effectively avert the eye and stop the ear (which, in
truth, we cannot), what is commonly read and seen and heard and
done intrudes upon us all, want it or not."
22 The Public Interest 25-26 (Winter 1971). [ Footnote 9 ] (Emphasis added.) As Mr. Chief Justice
Warren stated, there is a "right of the Nation and of the States to
maintain a decent society . . . ," Page 413 U. S. 60 Jacobellis v. Ohio, 378 U. S. 184 , 378 U. S. 199 (1964) (dissenting opinion). [ Footnote 10 ] See Memoirs v. Massachusetts, 383 U. S. 413 , 383 U. S. 457 (1966) (Harlan, J., dissenting); Beauharnais v. Illinois, 343 U. S. 250 , 343 U. S.
256 -257 (1952); Kovacs v. Cooper, 336 U. S.
77 , 336 U. S. 86 -88
(1949).
But, it is argued, there are no scientific data which
conclusively demonstrate that exposure to obscene material
adversely affects men and women or their society. It is urged on
behalf of the petitioners that, absent such a demonstration, any
kind of state regulation is "impermissible." We reject this
argument. It is not for us to resolve empirical uncertainties
underlying state legislation, save in the exceptional case where
that legislation plainly impinges upon rights protected by the
Constitution itself. [ Footnote
11 ] MR. JUSTICE BRENNAN, speaking for the Court in Ginsberg
v. New York, 390 U. S. 629 , 390 U. S.
642 -643 (1968), said: "We do not demand of legislatures scientifically certain criteria of legislation.' Noble
State Bank v. Haskell, 219 U. S. 104 , 219 U. S.
110 ." Although there is no conclusive proof of a
connection between antisocial behavior Page 413 U. S. 61 and obscene material, the legislature of Georgia could quite
reasonably determine that such a connection does or might exist. In
deciding Roth, this Court implicitly accepted that a legislature
could legitimately act on such a conclusion to protect "the social
interest in order and morality." Roth v. United States, 354 U.S. at 354 U. S. 485 ,
quoting Chaplinsky v. New Hampshire, 315 U.
S. 568 , 315 U. S. 572 (1942) (emphasis added in Roth ). [ Footnote 12 ]
From the beginning of civilized societies, legislators and
judges have acted on various unprovable assumptions. Such
assumptions underlie much lawful state regulation of commercial and
business affairs. See Ferguson v. Skrupa, 372 U.
S. 726 , 372 U. S. 730 (1963); Breard v. Alexandria, 341 U.S. at 341 U. S.
632 -633, 341 U. S.
641 -645; Lincoln Federal Labor Union v. Northwestern
Iron Metal Co., 335 U. S. 525 , 335 U. S.
536 -537 (1949). The same is true of the federal
securities and antitrust laws and a host of federal regulations. See SEC v. Capital Gains Research Bureau, Inc., 375 U. S. 180 , 375 U. S.
186 -195 (1963); American Power & Light Co. v.
SEC, 329 U. S. 90 , 329 U. S. 99 -103
(1946); North American Co. v. SEC, 327 U.
S. 686 , 327 U. S.
705 -707 (1946), and cases cited. See also Brooks v.
United States, 267 U. S. 432 , 267 U. S.
436 -437 (1925), and Hoke v. United States, 227 U. S. 308 , 227 U. S. 322 (1913). On the basis of these assumptions both Congress and state
legislatures have, for example, drastically restricted
associational rights by adopting antitrust laws, and have strictly
regulated public expression by issuers of and dealers in
securities, profit sharing "coupons," and "trading stamps," Page 413 U. S. 62 commanding what they must and must not publish and announce. See Sugar Institute, Inc. v. United States, 297 U.
S. 553 , 297 U. S.
597 -602 (1936); Merrick v. N.W. Halsey &
Co., 242 U. S. 568 , 242 U. S.
584 -589 (1917); Caldwell v. Sioux Falls Stock Yards
Co., 242 U. S. 559 , 242 U. S.
567 -568 (1917); Hall v. Geiger-Jones Co., 242 U. S. 539 , 242 U. S.
548 -552 (1917); Tanner v. Little, 240 U.
S. 369 , 240 U. S.
383 -386 (1916); Rast v. Van Deman Lewis Co., 240 U. S. 342 , 240 U. S.
363 -368 (1916). Understandably those who entertain an
absolutist view of the First Amendment find it uncomfortable to
explain why rights of association, speech, and press should be
severely restrained in the marketplace of goods and money, but not
in the marketplace of pornography.
Likewise, when legislatures and administrators act to protect
the physical environment from pollution and to preserve our
resources of forests, streams, and parks, they must act on such
imponderables as the impact of a new highway near or through an
existing park or wilderness area. See Citizens to Preserve
Overton Park v. Volpe, 401 U. S. 402 , 401 U. S.
417 -420 (1971). Thus, § 18(a) of the Federal-Aid Highway
Act of 1968, 23 U.S.C. § 138, and the Department of Transportation
Act of 1966, as amended, 82 Stat. 824, 49 U.S.C. § 1653(f), have
been described by Mr. Justice Black as
"a solemn determination of the highest law-making body of this
Nation that the beauty and health-giving facilities of our parks
are not to be taken away for public roads without hearings,
factfindings, and policy determinations under the supervision of a
Cabinet officer. . . ." Citizens to Preserve Overton Park, supra, at 401 U. S. 421 (separate opinion joined by BRENNAN, J.). The fact that a
congressional directive reflects unprovable assumptions about what
is good for the people, including imponderable aesthetic
assumptions, is not a sufficient reason to find that statute
unconstitutional. Page 413 U. S. 63 If we accept the unprovable assumption that a complete education
requires the reading of certain books, see Board of Education
v. Allen, 392 U. S. 236 , 392 U. S. 245 (1968), and Johnson v. New York State Education Dept., 449
F.2d 871, 882-883 (CA2 1971) (dissenting opinion), vacated and
remanded to consider mootness, 409 U. S.
75 (1972), id. at 777 (MARSHALL, J.,
concurring), and the well nigh universal belief that good books,
plays, and art lift the spirit, improve the mind, enrich the human
personality, and develop character, can we then say that a state
legislature may not act on the corollary assumption that commerce
in obscene books, or public exhibitions focused on obscene conduct,
have a tendency to exert a corrupting and debasing impact leading
to antisocial behavior? "Many of these effects may be intangible
and indistinct, but they are nonetheless real." American Power
& Light Co. v. SEC, supra, at 329 U. S. 103 .
Mr. Justice Cardozo said that all laws in Western civilization are
"guided by a robust common sense. . . ." Steward Machine Co. v.
Davis, 301 U. S. 548 , 301 U. S. 590 (1937). The sum of experience, including that of the past two
decades, affords an ample basis for legislatures to conclude that a
sensitive, key relationship of human existence, central to family
life, community welfare, and the development of human personality,
can be debased and distorted by crass commercial exploitation of
sex. Nothing in the Constitution prohibits a State from reaching
such a conclusion and acting on it legislatively simply because
there is no conclusive evidence or empirical data.
It is argued that individual "free will" must govern, even in
activities beyond the protection of the First Amendment and other
constitutional guarantees of privacy, and that government cannot
legitimately impede an individual's desire to see or acquire
obscene plays, movies, and books. We do indeed base our society
on Page 413 U. S. 64 certain assumptions that people have the capacity for free
choice. Most exercises of individual free choice -- those in
politics, religion, and expression of idea are explicitly protected
by the Constitution. Totally unlimited play for free will, however,
is not allowed in our or any other society. We have just noted, for
example, that neither the First Amendment nor "free will" precludes
States from having "blue sky" laws to regulate what sellers of
securities may write or publish about their wares. See
supra at 413 U. S. 61 -62.
Such laws are to protect the weak, the uninformed, the
unsuspecting, and the gullible from the exercise of their own
volition. Nor do modern societies leave disposal of garbage and
sewage up to the individual "free will," but impose regulation to
protect both public health and the appearance of public places.
States are told by some that they must await a
" laissez-faire " market solution to the
obscenity-pornography problem, paradoxically "by people who have
never otherwise had a kind word to say for laissez-faire, "
particularly in solving urban, commercial, and environmental
pollution problems. See I. Kristol, On the Democratic Idea
in America 37 (1972).
The States, of course, may follow such a
" laissez-faire " policy and drop all controls on
commercialized obscenity, if that is what they prefer, just as they
can ignore consumer protection in the marketplace, but nothing in
the Constitution compels the States to do so with regard
to matters falling within state jurisdiction. See United States
v. Reidel, 402 U.S. at 402 U. S. 357 ; Memoirs v. Massachusetts, 383 U.S. at 383 U. S. 462 (WHITE, J., dissenting).
"We do not sit as a super-legislature to determine the wisdom,
need, and propriety of laws that touch economic problems, business
affairs, or social conditions." Griswold v. Connecticut, 381 U.
S. 479 , 381 U. S. 482 (1965). See Ferguson v. Skrupa, 372 U.S. at 372 U. S. 731 ; Day-Brite Lighting, Inc. v. Missouri, 342 U.
S. 421 , 342 U. S. 423 (1952). Page 413 U. S. 65 It is asserted, however, that standards for evaluating state
commercial regulations are inapposite in the present context, as
state regulation of access by consenting adults to obscene material
violates the constitutionally protected right to privacy enjoyed by
petitioners' customers. Even assuming that petitioners have
vicarious standing to assert potential customers' rights, it is
unavailing to compare a theater open to the public for a fee, with
the private home of Stanley v. Georgia, 394 U.S. at 394 U. S. 568 ,
and the marital bedroom of Griswold v. Connecticut, supra, at 381 U. S.
485 -486. This Court, has, on numerous occasions, refused
to hold that commercial ventures such as a motion-picture house are
"private" for the purpose of civil rights litigation and civil
rights statutes. See Sullivan v. Little Hunting Park,
Inc., 396 U. S. 229 , 396 U. S. 236 (1969); Daniel v. Paul, 395 U. S. 298 , 395 U. S.
305 -308 (1969); Blow v. North Carolina, 379 U. S. 684 , 379 U. S.
685 -686 (1965); Hamm v. Rock Hill, 379 U.
S. 306 , 379 U. S.
307 -308 (1964); Heart of Atlanta Motel, Inc. v.
United States, 379 U. S. 241 , 379 U. S. 247 , 379 U. S.
260 -261 (1964). The Civil Rights Act of 1964
specifically defines motion picture houses and theaters as places
of "public accommodation" covered by the Act as operations
affecting commerce. 78 Stat. 243, 42 U.S.C. § § 2000a(b)(3),
(c).
Our prior decisions recognizing a right to privacy guaranteed by
the Fourteenth Amendment included
"only personal rights that can be deemed 'fundamental' or
'implicit in the concept of ordered liberty.' Palko v.
Connecticut, 302 U. S. 319 , 302 U. S.
325 (1937)." Roe v. Wade, 410 U. S. 113 , 410 U. S. 152 (1973). This privacy right encompasses and protects the personal
intimacies of the home, the family, marriage, motherhood,
procreation, and childrearing. Cf. Eisenstadt v. Baird, 405 U. S. 438 , 405 U. S.
453 -454 (1972); id. at 405 U. S. 460 , 405 U. S.
463 -465 (WHITE, J., concurring); Stanley v. Georgia,
supra, at 394 U. S. 568 ; Loving v.
Virginia , 388 Page 413 U. S. 66 U.S. 1, 388 U. S. 12 (1967); Griswold v. Connecticut, supra, at 381 U. S. 486 ; Prince v. Massachusetts, 321 U. S. 158 , 321 U. S. 166 (1944); Skinner v. Oklahoma, 316 U.
S. 535 , 316 U. S. 541 (1942); Pierce v. Society of Sisters, 268 U.
S. 510 , 268 U. S. 535 (1925); Meyer v. Nebraska, 262 U.
S. 390 , 262 U. S. 399 (1923). Nothing, however, in this Court's decisions intimates that
there is any "fundamental" privacy right "implicit in the concept
of ordered liberty" to watch obscene movies in places of public
accommodation.
If obscene material unprotected by the First Amendment, in
itself, carried with it a "penumbra" of constitutionally protected
privacy, this Court would not have found it necessary to decide Stanley on the narrow basis of the "privacy of the home,"
which was hardly more than a reaffirmation that "a man's home is
his castle." Cf. Stanley v. Georgia, supra, at 394 U. S. 564 .
[ Footnote 13 ] Moreover, we
have declined to equate the privacy of the home relied on in Stanley with a "zone" of "privacy" that follows a
distributor or a consumer of obscene materials wherever he goes. See United States v. Orito, post at 413 U. S.
141 -143; United States v. 12 200-ft. Reels of Film,
post at 413 U. S.
126 -129; United States v. Thirty-seven
Photographs, 42 U.S. at 43 U. S. 376 -377
(opinion of WHITE, J.); United States v. Reidel, supra, at 402 U. S. 355 .
The idea of a "privacy" right and a place of public accommodation
are, in this context, Page 413 U. S. 67 mutually exclusive. Conduct or depictions of conduct that the
state police power can prohibit on a public street do not become
automatically protected by the Constitution merely because the
conduct is moved to a bar or a "live" theater stage, any more than
a "live" performance of a man and woman locked in a sexual embrace
at high noon in Times Square is protected by the Constitution
because they simultaneously engage in a valid political
dialogue.
It is also argued that the State has no legitimate interest in
"control [of] the moral content of a person's thoughts," Stanley v. Georgia, supra, at 394 U. S. 565 ,
and we need not quarrel with this. But we reject the claim that the
State of Georgia is here attempting to control the minds or
thoughts of those who patronize theaters. Preventing unlimited
display or distribution of obscene material, which by definition
lacks any serious literary, artistic, political, or scientific
value as communication, Miller v. California, ante at 413 U. S. 24 , 413 U. S. 34 , is
distinct from a control of reason and the intellect. Cf. Kois
v. Wisconsin, 408 U. S. 229 (1972); Roth v. United States, supra, at 354 U. S.
485 -487; Thornhill v. Alabama, 310 U. S.
88 , 310 U. S.
101 -102 (1940); Finnis, "Reason and Passion": The
Constitutional Dialectic of Free Speech and Obscenity, 116
U.Pa.L.Rev. 222, 229-230, 241-243 (1967). Where communication of
ideas, protected by the First Amendment, is not involved, or the
particular privacy of the home protected by Stanley, or any of the
other "areas or zones" of constitutionally protected privacy, the
mere fact that, as a consequence, some human "utterances" or.
"thoughts" may be incidentally affected does not bar the State from
acting to protect legitimate state interests. Cf. Roth v.
United States, supra, at 354 U. S. 483 ,
485-487; Beauharnais v. Illinois, 343 U.S. at 343 U. S.
256 -257. The fantasies of a drug addict are his own and
beyond the reach of government, but government regulation of drug
sales is not Page 413 U. S. 68 prohibited by the Constitution. Cf. United States v. Reidel,
supra, at 402 U. S.
359 -360 (Harlan, J., concurring).
Finally, petitioners argue that conduct which directly involves
"consenting adults" only has, for that sole reason, a special claim
to constitutional protection. Our Constitution establishes a broad
range of conditions on the exercise of power by the States, but for
us to say that our Constitution incorporates the proposition that
conduct involving consenting adults only is always beyond state
regulation, [ Footnote 14 ] is
a step we are unable to take. [ Footnote 15 ] Commercial exploitation of depictions,
descriptions, or exhibitions of obscene conduct on commercial
premises open to the adult public falls within a State's broad
power to regulate commerce and protect the public Page 413 U. S. 69 environment. The issue in this context goes beyond whether
someone, or even the majority, considers the conduct depicted as
"wrong" or "sinful." The States have the power to make a morally
neutral judgment that public exhibition of obscene material, or
commerce in such material, has a tendency to injure the community
as a whole, to endanger the public safety, or to jeopardize, in Mr.
Chief Justice Warren's words, the States' "right . . . to maintain
a decent society." Jacobellis v. Ohio, 378 U.S. at 378 U. S. 199 (dissenting opinion).
To summarize, we have today reaffirmed the basic holding of Roth v. United States, supra, that obscene material has no
protection under the First Amendment. See Miller v. California,
supra, and Kaplan v. California, post, p. 413 U. S. 115 . We
have directed our holdings, not at thoughts or speech, but at
depiction and description of specifically defined sexual conduct
that States may regulate within limits designed to prevent
infringement of First Amendment rights. We have also reaffirmed the
holdings of United States v. Reidel, supra, and United
States v. Thirty-seven Photographs, supra, that commerce in
obscene material is unprotected by any constitutional doctrine of
privacy. United States v. Orito, post at 413 U. S.
141 -143; United States v. 12 200-ft. Reels of Film,
post at 413 U. S.
126 -129. In this case, we hold that the States have a
legitimate interest in regulating commerce in obscene material and
in regulating exhibition of obscene material in places of public
accommodation, including so-called "adult" theaters from which
minors are excluded. In light of these holdings, nothing precludes
the State of Georgia from the regulation of the allegedly obscene
material exhibited in Paris Adult Theatre I or II, provided that
the applicable Georgia law, as written or authoritatively
interpreted by the Georgia courts, meets the First Amendment
standards set forth in Miller v. California, ante at 413 U. S. 23 -25.
The Page 413 U. S. 70 judgment is vacated and the case remanded to the Georgia Supreme
Court for further proceedings not inconsistent with this opinion
and Miller v. California, supra. See United States v.
12 200-ft. Reels of Film, post at 413 U. S. 130 n. 7. Vacated and remanded. [ Footnote 1 ]
This is a civil proceeding. Georgia Code Ann. § 26-2101 defines
a criminal offense, but the exhibition of materials found to be
"obscene" as defined by that statute may be enjoined in a civil
proceeding under Georgia case law. 1024 Peachtree Corp. v.
Slaton, 228 Ga. 102, 184 S.E.2d 144 (1971); Walter v.
Slaton, 227 Ga. 676, 182 S.E.2d 464 (1971); Evans Theatre Corp. v. Slaton, 227 Ga. 377, 180 S.E.2d 712 (1971). See infra at 413 U. S. 54 .
Georgia Code Ann. § 26-2101 reads in relevant part:
"Distributing obscene materials."
"(a) A person commits the offense of distributing obscene
materials when he sells, lends, rents, leases, gives, advertises,
publishes, exhibits or otherwise disseminates to any person any
obscene material of any description, knowing the obscene nature
thereof, or who offers to do so, or who possesses such material
with the intent so to do. . . ."
"(b) Material is obscene if considered as a whole, applying
community standards, its predominant appeal is to prurient
interest, that is, a shameful or morbid interest in nudity, sex or
excretion, and utterly without redeeming social value and if, in
addition, it goes substantially beyond customary limits of candor
in describing or representing such matters. . ."
"(d) A person convicted of distributing obscene material shall
for the first offense be punished as for a misdemeanor, and for any
subsequent offense shall be punished by imprisonment for not less
than one nor more than five years, or by a fine not to exceed
$5,000, or both."
The constitutionality of Georgia Code Ann. § 26-2101 was upheld
against First Amendment and due process challenges in Gable v.
Jenkins, 309 F.
Supp. 998 (ND Ga.1969), aff'd per curiam, 397 U.
S. 592 (1970).
[ Footnote 2 ] See Georgia Code Ann. § 26-2101, set out supra at 51 n. 1.
[ Footnote 3 ]
In Walter v. Slaton, 227 Ga. 676, 182 S.E.2d 464 (1971), the Georgia Supreme Court described the cases before it as
follows:
"Each case was commenced as a civil action by the District
Attorney of the Superior Court of Fulton County jointly with the
Solicitor of the Criminal Court of Fulton County. In each case, the
plaintiffs alleged that the defendants named therein were
conducting a business of exhibiting motion picture films to members
of the public; that they were in control and possession of the
described motion picture film, which they were exhibiting to the
public on a fee basis; that said film"
"constitutes a flagrant violation of Ga.Code § 22101 in that the
sole and dominant theme of the motion picture film . . . considered
as a whole, and applying contemporary standards, appeals to the
prurient interest in sex and nudity, and that said motion picture
film is utterly and absolutely without any redeeming social value
whatsoever and transgresses beyond the customary limits of candor
in describing and discussing sexual matters." Id. at 676-677, 182 S.E.2d at 465.
[ Footnote 4 ]
This procedure would have even more merit if the exhibitor or
purveyor could also test the issue of obscenity in a similar civil
action, prior to any exposure to criminal penalty. We are not here
presented with the problem of whether a holding that materials were
not obscene could be circumvented in a later proceeding by evidence
of pandering. See Memoirs v. Massachusetts, 383 U.
S. 413 , 383 U. S. 458 n. 3 (1966) (Harlan, J., dissenting); Ginzburg v. United
States, 383 U. S. 463 , 383 U. S. 496 (1966) (Harlan, J., dissenting).
[ Footnote 5 ]
At the specific request of petitioners' counsel, the copies of
the films produced for the trial court were placed in the
"administrative custody" of that court pending the outcome of this
litigation.
[ Footnote 6 ]
This is not a subject that lends itself to the traditional use
of expert testimony. Such testimony is usually admitted for the
purpose of explaining to lay jurors what they otherwise could not
understand. Cf. 2 J. Wigmore, Evidence §§ 556, 559 (3d
ed.1940). No such assistance is needed by jurors in obscenity
cases; indeed, the "expert witness" practices employed in these
cases have often made a mockery out of the otherwise sound concept
of expert testimony. See United States v. Groner, 479 F.2d
577, 585-586 (CA5 1973); id. at 587-588 (Ainsworth, J.,
concurring). "Simply stated, hard core pornography . . . can and
does speak for itself." United States v. Wild, 422 F.2d
34, 36 (CA2 1970), cert. denied, 402 U.S. 986 (1971). We
reserve judgment, however, on the extreme case, not presented here,
where contested materials are directed at such a bizarre deviant
group that the experience of the trier of fact would be plainly
inadequate to judge whether the material appeals to the prurient
interest. See Mishkin v. New York, 383 U.
S. 502 , 383 U. S.
508 -510 (1966); United States v. Klaw, 350 F.2d
155, 167-168 (CA2 1965).
[ Footnote 7 ]
It is conceivable that an "adult" theater can -- if it really
insists -- prevent the exposure of its obscene wares to juveniles.
An "adult" bookstore, dealing in obscene books, magazines, and
pictures cannot realistically make this claim. The Hill-Link
Minority Report of the Commission on Obscenity and Pornography
emphasizes evidence (the Abelson National Survey of Youth and
Adults) that, although most pornography may be bought by
elders,
"the heavy users and most highly exposed people to pornography
are adolescent females (among women) and adolescent and young adult
males (among men)."
The Report of the Commission on Obscenity and Pornography 401
(1970). The legitimate interest in preventing exposure of juveniles
to obscene material cannot be fully served by simply barring
juveniles from the immediate physical premises of "adult"
bookstores, when there is a flourishing "outside business" in these
materials.
[ Footnote 8 ]
The Report of the Commission on Obscenity and Pornography
390-412 (1970). For a discussion of earlier studies indicating "a
division of thought [among behavioral scientists] on the
correlation between obscenity and socially deleterious behavior," Memoirs v. Massachusetts, supra, at 383 U. S. 451 ,
and references to expert opinions that obscene material may induce
crime and antisocial conduct, see id. at 383 U. S.
451 -453 (Clark, J., dissenting). Mr. Justice Clark
emphasized:
"While erotic stimulation caused by pornography may be legally
insignificant in itself, there are medical experts who believe that
such stimulation frequently manifests itself in criminal sexual
behavior or other antisocial conduct. For example, Dr. George W.
Henry of Cornell University has expressed the opinion that
obscenity, with its exaggerated and morbid emphasis on sex,
particularly abnormal and perverted practices, and its unrealistic
presentation of sexual behavior and attitudes, may induce
antisocial conduct by the average person. A number of sociologists
think that this material may have adverse effects upon individual
mental health, with potentially disruptive consequences for the
community."
" * * * *" "Congress and the legislatures of every State have enacted
measures to restrict the distribution of erotic and pornographic
material, justifying these controls by reference to evidence that
antisocial behavior may result in part from reading obscenity." Id. at 383 U. S.
452 -453 (footnotes omitted).
[ Footnote 9 ] See also Berns, Pornography vs. Democracy: The Case for
Censorship, in 22 The Public Interest 3 (Winter 1971); van den
Haag, in Censorship: For & Against 156-157 (H. Hart
ed.1971).
[ Footnote 10 ]
"In this and other cases in this area of the law, which are
coming to us in ever-increasing numbers, we are faced with the
resolution of rights basic both to individuals and to society as a
whole. Specifically, we are called upon to reconcile the right of
the Nation and of the States to maintain a decent society and, on
the other hand, the right of individuals to express themselves
freely in accordance with the guarantees of the First and
Fourteenth Amendments." Jacobellis v. Ohio, supra, at 378 U. S. 199 (Warren, C.J., dissenting).
[ Footnote 11 ]
Mr. Justice Holmes stated in another context, that:
"[T]he proper course is to recognize that a state legislature
can do whatever it sees fit to do unless it is restrained by some
express prohibition in the Constitution of the United States or of
the State, and that Courts should be careful not to extend such
prohibitions beyond their obvious meaning by reading into them
conceptions of public policy that the particular Court may happen
to entertain." Tyson & Brother v. Banton, 273 U.
S. 418 , 273 U. S. 446 (1927) (dissenting opinion joined by Brandeis, J.).
[ Footnote 12 ]
" It has been well observed that such [lewd and obscene]
utterances are no essential part of any exposition of ideas, and
are of such slight social value as a step to truth that any benefit
that may be derived from them is clearly outweighed by the social
interest in order and morality. " Roth v. United States, 354 U.
S. 476 , 354 U. S. 485 (1957), quoting Chaplinsky v. New Hampshire, 315 U.
S. 568 , 315 U. S. 572 (1942) (emphasis added in Roth ).
[ Footnote 13 ]
The protection afforded by Stanley v. Georgia, 394 U. S. 557 (1969), is restricted to a place, the home. In contrast, the
constitutionally protected privacy of family, marriage, motherhood,
procreation, and childrearing is not just concerned with a
particular place, but with a protected intimate relationship. Such
protected privacy extends to the doctor's office, the hospital, the
hotel room, or as otherwise required to safeguard the right to
intimacy involved. Cf. Roe v. Wade, 410 U.
S. 113 , 410 U. S.
152 -154 (1973); Griswold v. Connecticut, 381 U. S. 479 , 381 U. S.
485 -486 (1965). Obviously, there is no necessary or
legitimate expectation of privacy which would extend to marital
intercourse on a street corner or a theater stage.
[ Footnote 14 ] Cf. J. Mill, On Liberty 13 (1955 ed.).
[ Footnote 15 ]
The state statute books are replete with constitutionally
unchallenged laws against prostitution, suicide, voluntary
self-mutilation, brutalizing "bare fist" prize fights, and duels,
although these crimes may only directly involve "consenting
adults." Statutes making bigamy a crime surely cut into an
individual's freedom to associate, but few today seriously claim
such statutes violate the First Amendment or any other
constitutional provision. See Davis v. Beason, 133 U. S. 333 , 133 U. S.
344 -345 (1890). Consider also the language of this Court
in McLaughlin v. Florida, 379 U.
S. 184 , 379 U. S. 196 (1964), as to adultery; Southern Surety Co. v. Oklahoma, 241 U. S. 582 , 241 U. S. 586 (1916), as to fornication; Hoke v. United States, 227 U. S. 308 , 227 U. S.
320 -322 (1913), and Caminetti v. United States, 242 U. S. 470 , 242 U. S.
484 -487, 242 U. S.
491 -492 (1917), as to "white slavery"; Murphy v.
California, 225 U. S. 623 , 225 U. S. 629 (1912), as to billiard halls; and the Lottery Case, 188 U. S. 321 , 188 U. S.
355 -356 (1903), as to gambling. See also the
summary of state statutes prohibiting bearbaiting, cockfighting,
and other brutalizing animal "sports," in Stevens, Fighting and
Baiting, in Animals and Their Legal Rights 112-127 (Leavitt
ed.1970). As Professor Irving Kristol has observed:
"Bearbaiting and cockfighting are prohibited only in part out of
compassion for the suffering animals; the main reason they were
abolished was because it was felt that they debased and brutalized
the citizenry who flocked to witness such spectacles."
On the Democratic Idea in America 33 (1972).
MR. JUSTICE DOUGLAS, dissenting.
My Brother BRENNAN is to be commended for seeking a new path
through the thicket which the Court entered when it undertook to
sustain the constitutionality of obscenity laws and to place limits
on their application. I have expressed on numerous occasions my
disagreement with the basic decision that held that "obscenity" was
not protected by the First Amendment. I disagreed also with the
definitions that evolved. Art and literature reflect tastes; and
tastes, like musical appreciation, are hardly reducible to precise
definitions. That is one reason I have always felt that "obscenity"
was not an exception to the First Amendment. For matters of taste,
like matters of belief, turn on the idiosyncrasies of individuals.
They are too personal to define and too emotional and vague to
apply, as witness the prison term for Ralph Ginzburg, Ginzburg
v. United States, 383 U. S. 463 , not
for what he printed but for the sexy manner in which he advertised
his creations.
The other reason I could not bring myself to conclude that
"obscenity" was not covered by the First Amendment was that, prior
to the adoption of our Constitution and Bill of Rights the Colonies
had no law excluding "obscenity" from the regime of freedom of
expression and press that then existed. I could find no such laws;
and more important, our leading colonial expert, Julius Goebel,
could find none, J. Goebel, Development of Legal Institutions
(1946); J. Goebel, Felony and Misdemeanor (1937). So I became
convinced that the Page 413 U. S. 71 creation of the "obscenity" exception to the First Amendment was
a legislative and judicial tour de force; that, if we were
to have such a regime of censorship and punishment, it should be
done by constitutional amendment.
People are, of course, offended by many offerings made by
merchants in this area. They are also offended by political
pronouncements, sociological themes, and by stories of official
misconduct. The list of activities and publications and
pronouncements that offend someone is endless. Some of it goes on
in private; some of it is inescapably public, as when a government
official generates crime, becomes a blatant offender of the moral
sensibilities of the people, engages in burglary, or breaches the
privacy of the telephone, the conference room, or the home. Life in
this crowded modern technological world creates many offensive
statements and many offensive deeds. There is no protection against
offensive ideas, only against offensive conduct.
"Obscenity" at most is the expression of offensive ideas. There
are regimes in the world where ideas "offensive" to the majority
(or at least to those who control the majority) are suppressed.
There life proceeds at a monotonous pace. Most of us would find
that world offensive. One of the most offensive experiences in my
life was a visit to a nation where bookstalls were filled only with
books on mathematics and books on religion.
I am sure I would find offensive most of the books and movies
charged with being obscene. But in a life that has not been short,
I have yet to be trapped into seeing or reading something that
would offend me. I never read or see the materials coming to the
Court under charges of "obscenity," because I have thought the
First Amendment made it unconstitutional for me to act as a censor.
I see ads in bookstores and neon lights over theaters that resemble
bait for those who Page 413 U. S. 72 seek vicarious exhilaration. As a parent or a priest or as a
teacher I would have no compunction in edging my children or wards
away from the books and movies that did no more than excite man's
base instincts. But I never supposed that government was permitted
to sit in judgment on one's tastes or belief save as they involved
action within the reach of the police power of government.
I applaud the effort of my Brother BRENNAN to forsake the low
road which the Court has followed in this field. The new regime he
would inaugurate is much closer than the old to the policy of
abstention which the First Amendment proclaims. But since we do not
have here the unique series of problems raised by
government-imposed or government-approved captive audiences, cf. Public Utilities Comm'n v. Pollak, 343 U.
S. 451 , I see no constitutional basis for fashioning a
rule that makes a publisher, producer, bookseller, librarian, or
movie house operator criminally responsible, when he fails to take
affirmative steps to protect the consumer against literature,
books, or movies offensive * to those who
temporarily occupy the seats of the mighty. Page 413 U. S. 73 When man was first in the jungle, he took care of himself. When
he entered a societal group, controls were necessarily imposed. But
our society -- unlike most in the world -- presupposes that freedom
and liberty are in a frame of reference that makes the individual,
not government, the keeper of his tastes, beliefs, and ideas. That
is the philosophy of the First Amendment; and it is the article of
faith that sets us apart from most nations in the world.
* What we do today is rather ominous as respects librarians. The
net now designed by the Court is so finely meshed that, taken
literally, it could result in raids on libraries. Libraries, I had
always assumed, were sacrosanct, representing every part of the
spectrum. If what is offensive to the most influential person or
group in a community can be purged from a library, the library
system would be destroyed.
A few States exempt librarians from laws curbing distribution of
"obscene" literature. California's law, however, provides:
"Every person who, with knowledge that a person is a minor, or
who fails to exercise reasonable care in ascertaining the true age
of a minor, knowingly distributes to or sends or causes to be sent
to, or exhibits to, or offers to distribute or exhibit any harmful
matter to a minor, is guilty of a misdemeanor."
Calif.Penal Code § 313.1.
A "minor" is one under 18 years of age; the word "distribute"
means "to transfer possession"; "matter" includes "any book,
magazine, newspaper, or other printed or written material." Id. §§ 313(b), (d), (g).
"Harmful matter" is defined in § 313(a) to mean
"matter, taken as a whole, the predominant appeal of which to
the average person, applying contemporary standards, is to prurient
interest, i.e., a shameful or morbid interest in nudity, sex, or
excretion; and is matter which taken as a whole goes substantially
beyond customary limits of candor in description or representation
of such matters; and is matter which taken as a whole is utterly
without redeeming social importance for minors."
MR. JUSTICE BRENNAN, with whom MR. JUSTICE STEWART and MR.
JUSTICE MARSHALL join, dissenting.
This case requires the Court to confront once again the vexing
problem of reconciling state efforts to suppress sexually oriented
expression with the protections of the First Amendment, as applied
to the States through the Fourteenth Amendment. No other aspect of
the First Amendment has, in recent years, demanded so substantial a
commitment of our time, generated such disharmony of views, and
remained so resistant to the formulation of stable and manageable
standards. I am convinced that the approach initiated 16 years ago
in Roth v. United States, 354 U.
S. 476 (1957), and culminating in the Court's decision
today, cannot bring stability to this area of the law without
jeopardizing fundamental First Amendment values, and I have
concluded that the Page 413 U. S. 74 time has come to make a significant departure from that
approach.
In this civil action in the Superior Court of Fulton County, the
State of Georgia sought to enjoin the showing of two motion
pictures, It All Comes Out In The End, and Magic Mirror, at the
Paris Adult Theatres (I and II) in Atlanta, Georgia. The State
alleged that the films were obscene under the standards set forth
in Georgia Code Ann. § 26-2101. [ Footnote 2/1 ] The trial court denied injunctive relief,
holding that, even though the films could be considered obscene,
their commercial presentation could not constitutionally be barred
in the absence of proof that they were shown to minors or
unconsenting adults. Reversing, the Supreme Court of Georgia found
the films obscene, and held that the care taken to avoid exposure
to minors and unconsenting adults was without constitutional
significance. I The Paris Adult Theatres are two commercial cinemas, linked by a
common box office and lobby, on Peachtree Street in Atlanta,
Georgia. On December 28, 1970, investigators employed by the
Criminal Court of Fulton County entered the theaters as paying
customers and viewed each of the films which are the subject of
this action. Thereafter, two separate complaints, one for Page 413 U. S. 75 each of the two films, were filed in the Superior Court seeking
a declaration that the films were obscene and an injunction against
their continued presentation to the public. The complaints alleged
that the films were
"a flagrant violation of Georgia Code Section 26-2101 in that
the sole and dominant theme[s] of the said motion picture film[s]
considered as a whole and applying contemporary community standards
[appeal] to the prurient interest in sex, nudity and excretion, and
that the said motion picture film[s are] utterly and absolutely
without any redeeming social value whatsoever, and [transgress]
beyond the customary limits of candor in describing and discussing
sexual matters."
App. 20, 39.
Although the language of the complaints roughly tracked the
language of § 26-2101, which imposes criminal penalties on persons
who knowingly distribute obscene materials, [ Footnote 2/2 ] this proceeding was not brought pursuant
to that statute. Instead, the State initiated a nonstatutory civil
proceeding to determine the obscenity of the films and to enjoin
their exhibition. While the parties waived jury trial and
stipulated that the decision of the trial court would be final on
the issue of obscenity, the State has not indicated whether it
intends to bring a criminal action under the statute in the event
that it succeeds in proving the films obscene.
Upon the filing of the complaints, the trial court scheduled a
hearing for January 13, 1971, and entered an order temporarily
restraining the defendants from concealing, destroying, altering,
or removing the films Page 413 U. S. 76 from the jurisdiction, but not from exhibiting the films to the
public pendente lite. In addition to viewing the films at
the hearing, the trial court heard the testimony of witnesses and
admitted into evidence photographs that were stipulated to depict
accurately the facade of the theater. The witnesses testified that
the exterior of the theater was adorned with prominent signs
reading "Adults Only," "You Must Be 21 and Able to Prove It," and
"If the Nude Body Offends You, Do Not Enter." Nothing on the
outside of the theater described the films with specificity. Nor
were pictures displayed on the outside of the theater to draw the
attention of passersby to the contents of the films. The admission
charge to the theaters was $3. The trial court heard no evidence
that minors had ever entered the theater, but also heard no
evidence that petitioners had enforced a systematic policy of
screening out minors (apart from the posting of the notices
referred to above).
On the basis of the evidence submitted, the trial court
concluded that the films could fairly be considered obscene,
"[a]ssuming that obscenity is established by a finding that the
actors cavorted about in the nude indiscriminately," but held,
nonetheless, that
"the display of these films in a commercial theatre, when
surrounded by requisite notice to the public of their nature and by
reasonable protection against the exposure of these films to
minors, is constitutionally permissible. [ Footnote 2/3 ] Page 413 U. S. 77 Since the issue did not arise in a statutory proceeding, the
trial court was not required to pass upon the constitutionality of
any state statute, on its face or as applied, in denying the
injunction sought by the State."
The Supreme Court of Georgia unanimously reversed, reasoning
that the lower court's reliance on Stanley v. Georgia, 394 U. S. 557 (1969), was misplaced in view of our subsequent decision in United States v. Reidel, 402 U. S. 351 (1971):
"In [ Reidel ], the Supreme Court expressly held that the
government could constitutionally prohibit the distribution of
obscene materials through the mails, even though the distribution
be limited to willing recipients who state that they are adults,
and, further, that the constitutional right of a person to possess
obscene material in the privacy of his own home, as expressed in
the Stanley case, does not carry with it the right to sell
and deliver such material. . . . Those who choose to pass through
the front door of the defendant's theater and purchase a ticket to
view the films and who certify thereby that they are more than 21
years of age are willing recipients of the material in the same
legal sense as were those in the Reidel case, who, after
reading the newspaper advertisements of the material, mailed an
order to the defendant accepting his solicitation to sell them the
obscene booklet there. That case clearly establishes once and for
all that the sale and delivery of obscene material to willing
adults is not Page 413 U. S. 78 protected under the first amendment."
228 Ga. 343, 346, 185 S.E.2d
768 , 769-770 (1971). The decision of the Georgia Supreme Court
rested squarely on its conclusion that the State could
constitutionally suppress these films even if they were displayed
only to persons over the age of 21 who were aware of the nature of
their contents and who had consented to viewing them. For the
reasons set forth in this opinion, I am convinced of the invalidity
of that conclusion of law, and I would therefore vacate the
judgment of the Georgia Supreme Court. I have no occasion to
consider the extent of state power to regulate the distribution of
sexually oriented materials to juveniles or to unconsenting adults.
Nor am I required, for the purposes of this review, to consider
whether or not these petitioners had, in fact, taken precautions to
avoid exposure of films to minors or unconsenting adults. II In Roth v. United States, 354 U.
S. 476 (1957), the Court held that obscenity, although
expression, falls outside the area of speech or press
constitutionally protected under the First and Fourteenth
Amendments against state or federal infringement. But at the same
time we emphasized in Roth that "sex and obscenity are not
synonymous," id. at 354 U. S. 487 ,
and that matter which is sexually oriented but not obscene is fully
protected by the Constitution. For we recognized that
"[s]ex, a great and mysterious motive force in human life, has
indisputably been a subject of absorbing interest to mankind
through the ages; it is one of the vital problems of human interest
and public concern." Ibid. [ Footnote 2/4 ] Roth rested, in Page 413 U. S. 79 other words, on what has been termed a two-level approach to the
question of obscenity. [ Footnote
2/5 ] While much criticized, [ Footnote 2/6 ] that approach has been endorsed by all but
two members of this Court who have addressed the question since Roth. Yet our efforts to implement that approach
demonstrate that agreement on the existence of something called
"obscenity" is still a long and painful step from agreement on a
workable definition of the term.
Recognizing that "the freedoms of expression . . . are
vulnerable to gravely damaging yet barely visible encroachments," Bantam Books, Inc. v. Sullivan, 372 U. S.
58 , 372 U. S. 66 (1963), we have demanded that "sensitive tools" be used to carry
out the "separation of legitimate from illegitimate speech." Speiser v. Randall, 357 U. S. 513 , 357 U. S. 525 (1958). The essence of our problem in the obscenity area is that we
have been unable to provide "sensitive tools" to separate obscenity
from other sexually oriented but constitutionally protected
speech, Page 413 U. S. 80 so that efforts to suppress the former do not spill over into
the suppression of the latter. The attempt, as the late Mr. Justice
Harlan observed, has only "produced a variety of views among the
members of the Court unmatched in any other course of
constitutional adjudication." Interstate Circuit, Inc. v.
Dallas, 390 U. S. 676 , 390 U. S.
704 -705 (1968) (separate opinion).
To be sure, five members of the Court did agree in Roth that obscenity could be determined by asking
"whether to the average person, applying contemporary community
standards, the dominant theme of the material taken as a whole
appeals to prurient interest."
354 U.S. at 354 U. S. 489 .
But agreement on that test -- achieved in the abstract and without
reference to the particular material before the Court, see
id. at 354 U. S. 481 n. 8 -- was, to say the least, short-lived. By 1967, the following
views had emerged: Mr. Justice Black and MR. JUSTICE DOUGLAS
consistently maintained that government is wholly powerless to
regulate any sexually oriented matter on the ground of its
obscenity. See, e.g., Ginzburg v. United States, 383 U. S. 463 , 383 U. S. 476 , 383 U. S. 482 (1966) (dissenting opinions); Jacobellis v. Ohio, 378 U. S. 184 , 378 U. S. 196 (1964) (concurring opinion); Roth v. United States, supra, at 354 U. S. 508 (dissenting opinion). Mr. Justice Harlan, on the other hand,
believed that the Federal Government in the exercise of its
enumerated powers could control the distribution of "hard core"
pornography, while the States were afforded more latitude to
"[ban] any material which, taken as a whole, has been reasonably
found in state judicial proceedings to treat with sex in a
fundamentally offensive manner, under rationally established
criteria for judging such material." Jacobellis v. Ohio, supra, at 378 U. S. 204 (dissenting opinion). See also, e.g., Ginzburg v. United
States, supra, at 383 U. S. 493 (dissenting opinion); A Quantity of Books v. Kansas, 378 U. S. 205 , 378 U. S. 215 (1964) (dissenting opinion joined by Clark, J.); Roth,
supra, at 354 U. S.
496 Page 413 U. S. 81 (separate opinion). MR. JUSTICE STEWART regarded "hard core"
pornography as the limit of both federal and state power. See,
e.g., Ginzburg v. United States, supra, at 383 U. S. 497 (dissenting opinion); Jacobellis v. Ohio, supra, at 378 U. S. 197 (concurring opinion).
The view that, until today, enjoyed the most, but not majority,
support was an interpretation of Roth (and not, as the
Court suggests, a veering "sharply away from the Roth concept" and the articulation of "a new test of obscenity," Miller v. California, ante at 413 U. S. 21 )
adopted by Mr. Chief Justice Warren, Mr. Justice Fortas, and the
author of this opinion in Memoirs v. Massachusetts, 383 U. S. 413 (1966). We expressed the view that Federal or State Governments
could control the distribution of material where
"three elements . . . coalesce: it must be established that (a)
the dominant theme of the material taken as a whole appeals to a
prurient interest in sex; (b) the material is patently offensive
because it affronts contemporary community standards relating to
the description or representation of sexual matters; and (c) the
material is utterly without redeeming social value." Id. at 383 U. S. 418 .
Even this formulation, however, concealed differences of opinion. Compare Jacobellis v. Ohio, supra, at 378 U. S.
192 -195 (BRENNAN, J., joined by Goldberg, J.) (community
standards national), with id. at 378 U. S.
200 -201 (Warren, C.J., joined by Clark, J., dissenting)
(community standards local). [ Footnote
2/7 ] Moreover, it did not provide a definition covering all
situations. See Mishkin v. New York, 383 U.
S. 502 (1966) Page 413 U. S. 82 (prurient appeal defined in terms of a deviant sexual group); Ginzburg v. United States, supra, ("pandering" probative
evidence of obscenity in close cases). See also Ginsberg v. New
York, 390 U. S. 629 (1968) (obscenity for juveniles). Nor, finally, did it ever command
a majority of the Court. Aside from the other views described
above, Mr. Justice Clark believed that "social importance" could
only "be considered together with evidence that the material in
question appeals to prurient interest and is patently offensive." Memoirs v. Massachusetts, supra, at 383 U. S. 445 (dissenting opinion). Similarly, MR. JUSTICE WHITE regarded "a
publication to be obscene if its predominant theme appeals to the
prurient interest in a manner exceeding customary limits of
candor," id. at 383 U. S.
460 -461 (dissenting opinion), and regarded
"'social importance' . . . not [as] an independent test of
obscenity, but [as] relevant only to determining the predominant
prurient interest of the material. . . ." Id. at 383 U. S.
462 .
In the face of this divergence of opinion the Court began the
practice in Redrup v. New York, 386 U.
S. 767 (1967), of per curiam reversals of convictions
for the dissemination of materials that, at least five members of
the Court, applying their separate tests, deemed not to be obscene.
[ Footnote 2/8 ] This approach capped
the attempt in Page 413 U. S. 83 Roth to separate all forms of sexually oriented
expression into two categories -- the one subject to full
governmental suppression and the other beyond the reach of
governmental regulation to the same extent as any other protected
form of speech or press. Today a majority of the Court offers a
slightly altered formulation of the basic Roth test, while
leaving entirely unchanged the underlying approach. III Our experience with the Roth approach has certainly
taught us that the outright suppression of obscenity cannot be
reconciled with the fundamental principles of the First and
Fourteenth Amendments. For we have failed to formulate a standard
that sharply distinguishes protected from unprotected speech, and
out of necessity, we have resorted to the Redrup approach,
which resolves cases as between the parties, but offers only the
most obscure guidance to legislation, adjudication by other courts,
and primary conduct. By disposing of cases through summary reversal
or denial of certiorari, we have deliberately and effectively
obscured the rationale underlying the decisions. It comes as no
surprise that judicial attempts to follow our lead conscientiously
have often ended in hopeless confusion.
Of course, the vagueness problem would be largely of our own
creation if it stemmed primarily from our Page 413 U. S. 84 failure to reach a consensus on any one standard. But, after 16
years of experimentation and debate, I am reluctantly forced to the
conclusion that none of the available formulas, including the one
announced today, can reduce the vagueness to a tolerable level
while at the same time striking an acceptable balance between the
protections of the First and Fourteenth Amendments, on the one
hand, and, on the other, the asserted state interest in regulating
the dissemination of certain sexually oriented materials. Any
effort to draw a constitutionally acceptable boundary on state
power must resort to such indefinite concepts as "prurient
interest," "patent offensiveness," "serious literary value," and
the like. The meaning of these concepts necessarily varies with the
experience, outlook, and even idiosyncrasies of the person defining
them. Although we have assumed that obscenity does exist and that
we "know it when [we] see it," Jacobellis v. Ohio, supra, at 378 U. S. 197 (STEWART, J., concurring), we are manifestly unable to describe it
in advance except by reference to concepts so elusive that they
fail to distinguish clearly between protected and unprotected
speech.
We have more than once previously acknowledged that
"constitutionally protected expression . . . is often separated
from obscenity only by a dim and uncertain line." Bantam Books,
Inc. v. Sullivan, 372 U.S. at 372 U. S. 66 . See also, e.g., Mishkin v. New York, supra, at 383 U. S. 511 .
Added to the "perhaps inherent residual vagueness" of each of the
current multitude of standards, Ginzburg v. United States,
supra, at 383 U. S. 475 n.19, is the further complication that the obscenity of any
particular item may depend upon nuances of presentation and the
context of its dissemination. See ibid. Redrup itself suggested that obtrusive exposure to unwilling individuals,
distribution to juveniles, and "pandering" may also bear upon the
determination of Page 413 U. S. 85 obscenity. See Redrup v. New York, supra, at 386 U. S. 769 .
As Mr. Chief Justice Warren stated in a related vein, obscenity is
a function of the circumstances of its dissemination:
"It is not the book that is on trial; it is a person. The
conduct of the defendant is the central issue, not the obscenity of
a book or picture. The nature of the materials is, of course,
relevant as an attribute of the defendant's conduct, but the
materials are thus placed in context from which they draw color and
character." Roth, 354 U.S. at 354 U. S. 495 (concurring opinion). See also, e.g., Jacobellis v. Ohio,
supra, at 378 U. S. 201 (dissenting opinion); Kingsley Books, Inc. v. Brown, 354 U. S. 436 , 354 U. S.
445 -446 (1957) (dissenting opinion). I need hardly point
out that the factors which must be taken into account are
judgmental and can only be applied on "a case-by-case,
sight-by-sight" basis. Mishkin v. New York, supra, at 383 U. S. 516 (Black, J., dissenting). These considerations suggest that no one
definition, no matter how precisely or narrowly drawn, can possibly
suffice for all situations, or carve out fully suppressible
expression from all media without also creating a substantial risk
of encroachment upon the guarantees of the Due Process Clause and
the First Amendment. [ Footnote
2/9 ] Page 413 U. S. 86 The vagueness of the standards in the obscenity area produces a
number of separate problems, and any improvement must rest on an
understanding that the problems are to some extent distinct. First,
a vague statute fails to provide adequate notice to persons who are
engaged in the type of conduct that the statute could be thought to
proscribe. The Due Process Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment
requires that all criminal laws provide fair notice of "what the
State commands or forbids." Lanzetta v. New Jersey, 30 U. S. 451 , 30 U. S. 453 (1939); Connally v. General Construction Co., 269 U.
S. 385 (1926). In the service of this general principle,
we have repeatedly held that the definition of obscenity must
provide adequate notice of exactly what Page 413 U. S. 87 is prohibited from dissemination. See, e.g., Rabe v.
Washington, 405 U. S. 313 (1972); Interstate Circuit, Inc. v. Dallas, 390 U.
S. 676 (1968); Winters v. New York, 333 U. S. 507 (1948). While various tests have been upheld under the Due Process
Clause, see Ginsberg v. New York, 390 U.S. at 390 U. S. 643 ; Mishkin v. New York, 383 U.S. at 383 U. S.
506 -507; Roth v. United States, 354 U.S. at 354 U. S.
491 -492, I have grave doubts that any of those test
could be sustained today. For I know of no satisfactory answer to
the assertion by Mr. Justice Black, "after the fourteen separate
opinions handed down" in the trilogy of cases decided in 1966,
that
"no person, not even the most learned judge, much less a layman,
is capable of knowing in advance of an ultimate decision in his
particular case by this Court whether certain material comes within
the area of 'obscenity.' . . ." Ginzburg v. United States, 383 U.S. at 383 U. S.
480 -481 (dissenting opinion). See also the
statement of Mr. Justice Harlan in Interstate Circuit, Inc. v.
Dallas, supra, at 390 U. S. 707 (separate opinion). As Mr. Chief Justice Warren pointed out,
"[t]he constitutional requirement of definiteness is violated by
a criminal statute that fails to give a person of ordinary
intelligence fair notice that his contemplated conduct is forbidden
by the statute. The underlying principle is that no man shall be
held criminally responsible for conduct which he could not
reasonably understand to be proscribed." United States v. Harriss, 347 U.
S. 612 , 347 U. S. 617 (1954). In this context, even the most painstaking efforts to
determine in advance whether certain sexually oriented expression
is obscene must inevitably prove unavailing. For the insufficiency
of the notice compels persons to guess not only whether their
conduct is covered by a criminal statute, but also whether their
conduct falls within the constitutionally permissible reach of the
statute. The resulting level of uncertainty is utterly intolerable,
not alone because it makes Page 413 U. S. 88 "[b]ookselling . . . a hazardous profession," Ginsberg v.
New York, supra, at 390 U. S. 674 (Fortas, J., dissenting), but as well because it invites arbitrary
and erratic enforcement of the law. See, e.g., Papachristou v.
City of Jacksonville, 405 U. S. 156 (1972); Gregory v. City of Chicago, 394 U.
S. 111 , 394 U. S. 120 (1969) (Black, J., concurring); Niemotko v. Maryland, 340 U. S. 268 (1951); Cantwell v. Connecticut, 310 U.
S. 296 , 310 U. S. 308 (1940); Thornhill v. Alabama, 310 U. S.
88 (1940).
In addition to problems that arise when any criminal statute
fails to afford fair notice of what it forbids, a vague statute in
the areas of speech and press creates a second level of difficulty.
We have indicated that
"stricter standards of permissible statutory vagueness may be
applied to a statute having a potentially inhibiting effect on
speech; a man may the less be required to act at his peril here,
because the free dissemination of ideas may be the loser. [ Footnote 2/10 ]" Smith v. California, 361 U. S. 147 , 361 U. S. 151 (1959). That proposition draws its strength from our recognition
that
"[t]he fundamental freedoms of speech and press have contributed
greatly to the development and wellbeing of our free society, and
are indispensable to its continued growth. Ceaseless vigilance is
the watchword to prevent their erosion by Congress or by the
States. The door barring federal and state intrusion into this area
cannot be left ajar. . . ." Roth, supra, at 354 U. S. 488 .
[ Footnote 2/11 ] Page 413 U. S. 89 To implement this general principle, and recognizing the
inherent vagueness of any definition of obscenity, we have held
that the definition of obscenity must be drawn as narrowly as
possible, so as to minimize the interference with protected
expression. Thus, in Roth, we rejected the test of Regina v. Hicklin, [1868] L.R. 3 Q.B. 360, that "[judged]
obscenity by the effect of isolated passages upon the most
susceptible persons." 354 U.S. at 354 U. S. 489 .
That test, we held in Roth, "might well encompass material
legitimately treating with sex. . . ." Ibid. Cf.
Mishkin v. New York, supra, at 383 U. S. 509 .
And we have supplemented the Roth standard with additional
tests in an effort to hold in check the corrosive effect of
vagueness on the guarantees of the First Amendment. [ Footnote 2/12 ] We have held, for example,
that "a State is not free to adopt whatever procedures it
pleases Page 413 U. S. 90 for dealing with obscenity. . . ." Marcus v. Search
Warrant, 367 U. S. 717 , 367 U. S. 731 (1961).
"Rather, the First Amendment requires that procedures be
incorporated that 'ensure against the curtailment of
constitutionally protected expression. . . .'" Blount v. Rizzi, 400 U. S. 410 , 400 U. S. 416 (1971), quoting from Bantam Books, Inc., v. Sullivan, 372
U.S. at 372 U. S. 66 . See generally Rizzi, supra, at 400 U. S. 417 ; United States v. Thirty-seven Photographs, 402 U.
S. 363 , 402 U. S.
367 -375 (1971); Lee Art Theatre, Inc. v.
Virginia, 392 U. S. 636 (1968); Freedman v. Maryland, 380 U. S.
51 , 380 U. S. 58 -60
(1965); A Quantity of Books v. Kansas, 378 U.
S. 205 (1964) (plurality opinion).
Similarly, we have held that a State cannot impose criminal
sanctions for the possession of obscene material absent proof that
the possessor had knowledge of the contents of the material. Smith v. California, supra. "Proof of scienter "
is necessary
"to avoid the hazard of self-censorship of constitutionally
protected material and to compensate for the ambiguities inherent
in the definition of obscenity." Mishkin v. New York, supra, at 383 U. S. 511 ; Ginsberg v. New York, supra, at 390 U. S.
644 -645. In short,
"[t]he objectionable quality of vagueness and overbreadth . . .
[is] the danger of tolerating, in the area of First Amendment
freedoms, the existence of a penal statute susceptible of sweeping
and improper application. Cf. Marcus v. Search Warrant, 367 U. S.
717 , 367 U. S. 733 . These
freedoms are delicate and vulnerable, as well as supremely precious
in our society. The threat of sanctions may deter their exercise
almost as potently as the actual application of sanctions. Cf.
Smith v. California, [361 U.S.], at 361 U. S.
151 -154; Speiser v. Randall, 357 U. S.
513 , 357 U. S. 526 . Because First
Amendment freedoms need breathing space to survive, government Page 413 U. S. 91 may regulate in the area only with narrow specificity. Cantwell v. Connecticut, 310 U. S. 296 , 310 U. S.
311 ." NAACP v. Button, 371 U. S. 415 , 371 U. S. 432 433 (1963).
The problems of fair notice and chilling protected speech are
very grave standing alone. But it does not detract from their
importance to recognize that a vague statute in this area creates a
third, although admittedly more subtle, set of problems. These
problems concern the institutional stress that inevitably results
where the line separating protected from unprotected speech is
excessively vague. In Roth, we conceded that "there may be
marginal cases in which it is difficult to determine the side of
the line on which a particular fact situation falls. . . ." 354
U.S. at 354 U. S.
491 -492. Our subsequent experience demonstrates that
almost every case is "marginal." And since the "margin" marks the
point of separation between protected and unprotected speech, we
are left with a system in which almost every obscenity case
presents a constitutional question of exceptional difficulty.
"The suppression of a particular writing or other tangible form
of expression is . . . an individual matter, and in the nature of
things every such suppression raises an individual constitutional
problem, in which a reviewing court must determine for itself
whether the attacked expression is suppressable within
constitutional standards." Roth, supra, at 354 U. S. 497 (separate opinion of Harlan, J.).
Examining the rationale, both explicit and implicit, of our
vagueness decisions, one commentator has viewed these decisions as
an attempt by the Court to establish an "insulating buffer zone of
added protection at the peripheries of several of the Bill of
Rights freedoms." Note, The Void-for-Vagueness Doctrine in the
Supreme Court, 109 U.Pa.L.Rev. 67, 75 (1960). The buffer zone
enables the Court to fend off legislative attempts Page 413 U. S. 92 "to pass to the courts -- and ultimately to the Supreme Court --
the awesome task of making case by case at once the criminal and
the constitutional law." Id. at 81. Thus,
[b]ecause of the Court's limited power to reexamine fact on a
cold record, what appears to be going on in the administration of
the law must be forced, by restrictive procedures, to reflect what
is really going on; and because of the impossibility, through sheer
volume of cases, of the Court's effectively policing law
administration case by case, those procedures must be framed to
assure, as well as procedures can assure, a certain overall probability of regularity. Id. at 89 (emphasis in original).
As a result of our failure to define standards with predictable
application to any given piece of material, there is no probability
of regularity in obscenity decisions by state and lower federal
courts. That is not to say that these courts have performed badly
in this area or paid insufficient attention to the principles we
have established. The problem is, rather, that one cannot say with
certainty that material is obscene until at least five members of
this Court, applying inevitably obscure standards, have pronounced
it so. The number of obscenity cases on our docket gives ample
testimony to the burden that has been placed upon this Court.
But the sheer number of the cases does not define the full
extent of the institutional problem. For, quite apart from the
number of cases involved and the need to make a fresh
constitutional determination in each case, we are tied to the
"absurd business of perusing and viewing the miserable stuff that
pours into the Court. . . ." Interstate Circuit, Inc. v.
Dallas, 390 U.S. at 390 U. S. 707 (separate opinion of Harlan, J.). While the material may have
varying degrees of social importance, Page 413 U. S. 93 it is hardly a source of edification to the members of this
Court who are compelled to view it before passing on its obscenity. Cf. Mishkin v. New York, 383 U.S. at 383 U. S.
516 -517 (Black, J., dissenting).
Moreover, we have managed the burden of deciding scores of
obscenity cases by relying on per curiam reversals or denials of
certiorari -- a practice which conceals the rationale of decision
and gives at least the appearance of arbitrary action by this
Court. See Bloss v. Dykema, 398 U.
S. 278 (1970) (Harlan, J., dissenting). More important,
no less than the procedural schemes struck down in such cases as Blount v. Rizzi, supra, and Freedman v. Maryland,
supra, the practice effectively censors protected expression
by leaving lower court determinations of obscenity intact even
though the status of the allegedly obscene material is entirely
unsettled until final review here. In addition, the uncertainty of
the standards creates a continuing source of tension between state
and federal courts, since the need for an independent determination
by this Court seems to render superfluous even the most
conscientious analysis by state tribunals. And our inability to
justify our decisions with a persuasive rationale -- or indeed, any
rationale at all -- necessarily creates the impression that we are
merely second-guessing state court judges.
The severe problems arising from the lack of fair notice, from
the chill on protected expression, and from the stress imposed on
the state and federal judicial machinery persuade me that a
significant change in direction is urgently required. I turn,
therefore, to the alternatives that are now open. IV 1. The approach requiring the smallest deviation from our
present course would be to draw a new line between protected and
unprotected speech, still permitting Page 413 U. S. 94 the States to suppress all material on the unprotected side of
the line. In my view, clarity cannot be obtained pursuant to this
approach except by drawing a line that resolves all doubt in favor
of state power and against the guarantees of the First Amendment.
We could hold, for example, that any depiction or description of
human sexual organs, irrespective of the manner or purpose of the
portrayal, is outside the protection of the First Amendment, and
therefore open to suppression by the States. That formula would, no
doubt, offer much fairer notice of the reach of any state statute
drawn at the boundary of the State's constitutional power. And it
would also, in all likelihood, give rise to a substantial
probability of regularity in most judicial determinations under the
standard. But such a standard would be appallingly overbroad,
permitting the suppression of a vast range of literary, scientific,
and artistic masterpieces. Neither the First Amendment nor any free
community could possibly tolerate such a standard. Yet, short of
that extreme, it is hard to see how any choice of words could
reduce the vagueness problem to tolerable proportions, so long as
we remain committed to the view that some class of materials is
subject to outright suppression by the State.
2. The alternative adopted by the Court today recognizes that a
prohibition against any depiction or description of human sexual
organs could not be reconciled with the guarantees of the First
Amendment. But the Court does retain the view that certain sexually
oriented material can be considered obscene, and therefore
unprotected by the First and Fourteenth Amendments. To describe
that unprotected class of expression, the Court adopts a
restatement of the Roth-Memoirs definition of
obscenity:
"The basic guidelines for the trier of fact must be: (a) whether
'the average person, applying contemporary community standards,'
would find that the Page 413 U. S. 95 work, taken as a whole, appeals to the prurient interest . . .
(b) whether the work depicts or describes, in a patently offensive
way, sexual conduct specifically defined by the applicable state
law, and (c) whether the work, taken as a whole, lacks serious
literary, artistic, political, or scientific value." Miller v. California, ante at 413 U. S. 24 . In
apparent illustration of "sexual conduct," as that term is used in
the test's second element, the Court identifies "(a) Patently
offensive representations or descriptions of ultimate sexual acts,
normal or perverted, actual or simulated," and "(b) Patently
offensive representations or descriptions of masturbation,
excretory functions, and lewd exhibition of the genitals." Id. at 413 U. S.
25 .
The differences between this formulation and the three-pronged Memoirs test are, for the most part, academic. [ Footnote 2/13 ] The first element of the
Court's test is virtually identical to the Memoirs requirement that "the dominant theme of the material taken as a
whole [must appeal] to a prurient interest in sex." 383 U.S. at 383 U. S. 418 .
Whereas the second prong of the Memoirs test demanded that
the material be Page 413 U. S. 96 "patently offensive because it affronts contemporary community
standards relating to the description or representation of sexual
matters," ibid., the test adopted today requires that the
material describe, "in a patently offensive way, sexual conduct
specifically defined by the applicable state law." Miller v.
California, ante at 413 U. S. 24 .
The third component of the Memoirs test is that the
material must be "utterly without redeeming social value." 383 U.S.
at 383 U. S. 418 .
The Court's rephrasing requires that the work, taken as a whole,
must be proved to lack "serious literary, artistic, political, or
scientific value." Miller, ante at 413 U. S.
24 .
The Court evidently recognizes that difficulties with the Roth approach necessitate a significant change of
direction. But the Court does not describe its understanding of
those difficulties, nor does it indicate how the restatement of the Memoirs test is in any way responsive to the problems that
have arisen. In my view, the restatement leaves unresolved the very
difficulties that compel our rejection of the underlying Roth approach, while at the same time contributing
substantial difficulties of its own. The modification of the Memoirs test may prove sufficient to jeopardize the
analytic underpinnings of the entire scheme. And today's
restatement will likely have the effect, whether or not intended,
of permitting far more sweeping suppression of sexually oriented
expression, including expression that would almost surely be held
protected under our current formulation.
Although the Court's restatement substantially tracks the
three-part test announced in Memoirs v. Massachusetts,
supra, it does purport to modify the "social value" component
of the test. Instead of requiring, as did Roth and Memoirs, that state suppression be limited to materials
utterly lacking in social value, the Court today Page 413 U. S. 97 permits suppression if the government can prove that the
materials lack " serious literary, artistic, political or
scientific value." But the definition of "obscenity" as expression
utterly lacking in social importance is the key to the conceptual
basis of Roth and our subsequent opinions. In Roth, we held that certain expression is obscene, and thus
outside the protection of the First Amendment, precisely because it lacks even the slightest redeeming social
value. See Roth v. United States, 354 U.S. at 354 U. S.
484 -485; [ Footnote
2/14 ] Jacobellis v. Ohio, 378 U.S. at 378 U. S. 191 ; Zeitlin v. Arnebergh, 59 Cal. 2d
901 , 920, 383 P.2d 152, 165; cf. New York Times Co. v.
Sullivan, 376 U. S. 254 (1964); Garrison v. Louisiana, 379 U. S.
64 , 379 U. S. 75 (1964); Chaplinsky v. New Hampshire, 315 U.
S. 568 , 315 U. S. 572 (1942); Kalven, The Metaphysics of the Law of Obscenity, 1960
Sup.Ct.Rev. 1. The Court's approach necessarily assumes that some
works will be deemed obscene -- even though they clearly have some social value -- because the State was able to prove
that the value, measured by some unspecified standard, was not
sufficiently "serious" to warrant constitutional protection. That
result is not merely inconsistent with our holding in Roth; it is nothing less than a rejection of the
fundamental First Amendment premises and rationale of the Roth opinion and an invitation to widespread suppression
of sexually oriented speech. Before today, the protections of the
First Amendment have never been thought limited to expressions of serious literary or political value. See Gooding v.
Wilson, 405 U. S. 518 Page 413 U. S. 98 (1972); Cohen v. California, 403 U. S.
15 , 403 U. S. 25 -26
(1971); Terminiello v. Chicago, 337 U. S.
1 , 337 U. S. 4 -5
(1949).
Although the Court concedes that " Roth presumed obscenity' to be `utterly without redeeming social
importance,'" it argues that Memoirs produced "a drastically altered test that called on the prosecution to
prove a negative, i.e., that the material was 'utterly
without redeeming social value' -- a burden virtually impossible to
discharge under our criminal standards of proof. [ Footnote 2/15 ]"
One should hardly need to point out that under the third
component of the Court's test the prosecution is still required to
"prove a negative" -- i.e., that the material lacks
serious literary, artistic, political, or scientific value. Whether
it will be easier to prove that material lacks "serious" value than
to prove that it lacks any value at all remains, of course, to be
seen.
In any case, even if the Court's approach left undamaged the
conceptual framework of Roth, and even if it clearly
barred the suppression of works with at least some social value, I
would nevertheless be compelled to reject it. For it is beyond
dispute that the approach can have no ameliorative impact on the
cluster of problems that grow out of the vagueness of our current
standards. Indeed, even the Court makes no argument that the
reformulation will provide fairer notice to booksellers, theater
owners, and the reading and viewing public. Nor does the Court
contend that the approach will provide clearer guidance to law
enforcement officials or reduce the chill on protected expression.
Nor, finally, does the Court suggest that the approach will
mitigate to the slightest degree the institutional problems that
have plagued this Court and the state and federal judiciary as a
direct result of the uncertainty inherent in any definition of
obscenity. Page 413 U. S. 99 Of course, the Court's restated Roth test does limit
the definition of obscenity to depictions of physical conduct and
explicit sexual acts. And that limitation may seem, at first
glance, a welcome and clarifying addition to the Roth-Memoirs formula. But just as the agreement in Roth on an abstract definition of obscenity gave little
hint of the extreme difficulty that was to follow in attempting to
apply that definition to specific material, the mere formulation of
a "physical conduct" test is no assurance that it can be applied
with any greater facility. The Court does not indicate how it would
apply its test to the materials involved in Miller v.
California, supra, and we can only speculate as to its
application. But even a confirmed optimist could find little
realistic comfort in the adoption of such a test. Indeed, the
valiant attempt of one lower federal court to draw the
constitutional line at depictions of explicit sexual conduct seems
to belie any suggestion that this approach marks the road to
clarity. [ Footnote 2/16 ] The
Court surely demonstrates little sensitivity to our own
institutional problems, much less the other vagueness-related
difficulties, in establishing a system that requires us to consider
whether a description of human genitals is sufficiently "lewd" to
deprive it of constitutional protection; whether a sexual act is
"ultimate"; whether the conduct depicted in materials before us
fits within one of the categories of conduct whose depiction the
State and Federal Governments have attempted to suppress; and a
host of equally pointless inquiries. In addition, adoption of such
a test does not, presumably, obviate the need for consideration of
the Page 413 U. S. 100 nuances of presentation of sexually oriented material, yet it
hardly clarifies the application of those opaque but important
factors.
If the application of the "physical conduct" test to pictorial
material is fraught with difficulty, its application to textual
material carries the potential for extraordinary abuse. Surely we
have passed the point where the mere written description of sexual
conduct is deprived of First Amendment protection. Yet the test
offers no guidance to us, or anyone else, in determining which
written descriptions of sexual conduct are protected, and which are
not.
Ultimately, the reformulation must fail because it still leaves
in this Court the responsibility of determining in each case
whether the materials are protected by the First Amendment. The
Court concedes that, even under its restated formulation, the First
Amendment interests at stake require "appellate courts to conduct
an independent review of constitutional claims when necessary," Miller v. California, ante at 413 U. S. 25 ,
citing Mr. Justice Harlan's opinion in Roth, where he
stated,
"I do not understand how the Court can resolve the
constitutional problems now before it without making its own
independent judgment upon the character of the material upon which
these convictions were based."
354 U.S. at 354 U. S. 498 .
Thus, the Court's new formulation will not relieve us of "the
awesome task of making case by case at once the criminal and the
constitutional law." [ Footnote
2/17 ] And the careful efforts of state and lower federal courts
to apply the standard will remain an essentially pointless
exercise, in view of the need for an ultimate decision by this
Court. In addition, since the status of sexually oriented material
will necessarily remain in doubt until final Page 413 U. S. 101 decision by this Court, the new approach will not diminish the
chill on protected expression that derives from the uncertainty of
the underlying standard. I am convinced that a definition of
obscenity in terms of physical conduct cannot provide sufficient
clarity to afford fair notice, to avoid a chill on protected
expression, and to minimize the institutional stress, so long as
that definition is used to justify the outright suppression of any
material that is asserted to fall within its terms.
3. I have also considered the possibility of reducing our own
role, and the role of appellate courts generally, in determining
whether particular matter is obscene. Thus, we might conclude that
juries are best suited to determine obscenity vel non, and
that jury verdicts in this area should not be set aside except in
cases of extreme departure from prevailing standards. Or, more
generally, we might adopt the position that, where a lower federal
or state court has conscientiously applied the constitutional
standard, its finding of obscenity will be no more vulnerable to
reversal by this Court than any finding of fact. Cf. Interstate
Circuit, Inc. v. Dallas, 390 U.S. at 390 U. S.
706 -707 (separate opinion of Harlan, J.). While the
point was not clearly resolved prior to our decision in Redrup
v. New York, 386 U. S. 767 (1967), [ Footnote 2/18 ] it is
implicit in that decision that the First Amendment requires Page 413 U. S. 102 an independent review by appellate courts of the constitutional
fact of obscenity. [ Footnote
2/19 ] That result is required by principles applicable to the
obscenity issue no less than to any other area involving free
expression, see, e.g., New York Times Co. v. Sullivan, 376
U.S. at 376 U. S.
284 -285, or other constitutional right. [ Footnote 2/20 ] In any event, even if the
Constitution would permit us to refrain from judging for ourselves
the alleged obscenity of particular materials, that approach would
solve at best only a small part of our problem. For while it would
mitigate the institutional stress produced by the Roth approach, it
would neither offer nor produce any cure for the other vices of
vagueness. Far from providing a clearer guide to permissible
primary conduct, the approach would inevitably lead to even greater
uncertainty and the consequent due process problems of fair notice.
And the approach would expose much protected, sexually oriented
expression to the vagaries of jury determinations. Cf. Herndon
v. Lowry, 301 U. S. 242 , 301 U. S. 263 (1937). Plainly, the institutional gain would be more than offset
by the unprecedented infringement of First Amendment rights.
4. Finally, I have considered the view, urged so forcefully
since 1957 by our Brothers Black and DOUGLAS, that the First
Amendment bars the suppression of any sexually oriented expression.
That position would effect a sharp reduction, although perhaps not
a total elimination, of the uncertainty that surrounds our
current Page 413 U. S. 103 approach. Nevertheless, I am convinced that it would achieve
that desirable goal only by stripping the States of power to an
extent that cannot be justified by the commands of the
Constitution, at least so long as there is available an alternative
approach that strikes a better balance between the guarantee of
free expression and the States' legitimate interests. V Our experience since Roth requires us not only to
abandon the effort to pick out obscene materials on a case-by-case
basis, but also to reconsider a fundamental postulate of Roth: that there exists a definable class of sexually
oriented expression that may be totally suppressed by the Federal
and State Governments. Assuming that such a class of expression
does in fact, exist, [ Footnote
2/21 ] I am forced to conclude that the concept of "obscenity"
cannot be defined with sufficient specificity and clarity to
provide fair notice to persons who create and distribute sexually
oriented materials, to prevent substantial erosion of protected
speech as a byproduct of the attempt to suppress unprotected
speech, and to avoid very costly institutional harms. Given these
inevitable side effects of state efforts to suppress what is
assumed to be unprotected speech, we must scrutinize with
care the state interest that is asserted to justify the
suppression. For, in the absence of some very substantial interest
in suppressing such speech, we can hardly condone the ill effects
that seem to flow inevitably from the effort. [ Footnote 2/22 ] Page 413 U. S. 104 Obscenity laws have a long history in this country. Most of the
States that had ratified the Constitution by 1792 punished the
related crime of blasphemy or profanity despite the guarantees of
free expression in their constitutions, and Massachusetts expressly
prohibited the
"Composing, Writing, Printing or Publishing, of any Filthy
Obscene or Prophane Song, Pamphlet, Libel or Mock-Sermon, in
Imitation or in Mimicking of Preaching, or any other part of Divine
Worship."
Acts and Laws of Massachusetts Bay Colony (1726), Acts of
1711-1712, c. 1, p. 218. In 1815, the first reported obscenity
conviction was obtained under the common law of Pennsylvania. See Commonwealth v. Sharpless, 2 S. & R. 91. A
conviction in Massachusetts under its common law and colonial
statute followed six years later. See Commonwealth v.
Holmes, 17 Mass. 336 (1821). In 1821, Vermont passed the first
state law proscribing the publication or sale of "lewd or obscene"
material, Laws of Vermont, 1824, c. XXXII, No. 1, § 23, and federal
legislation barring the importation of similar matter appeared in
1842. See Tariff Act of 1842, § 28, 5 Stat. 566. Although
the number of early obscenity laws was small and their enforcement
exceedingly lax, the situation significantly changed after about
1870, when Federal and State Governments, mainly as a result of the
efforts Page 413 U. S. 105 of Anthony Comstock, took an active interest in the suppression
of obscenity. By the end of the 19th century, at least 30 States
had some type of General prohibition on the dissemination of
obscene materials, and by the time of our decision in Roth, no State was without some provision on the subject.
The Federal Government meanwhile had enacted no fewer than 20
obscenity laws between 1842 and 1956. See Roth v. United
States, 354 U.S. at 354 U. S.
482 -483, 354 U. S. 485 ;
Report of the Commission on Obscenity and Pornography 300-301
(1970).
This history caused us to conclude in Roth "that the unconditional phrasing of the First Amendment [that
'Congress shall make no law . . . abridging the freedom of speech,
or of the press . . .'] was not intended to protect every
utterance."
354 U.S. at 354 U. S. 483 .
It also caused us to hold, as numerous prior decisions of this
Court had assumed, see id. at 354 U. S. 481 ,
that obscenity could be denied the protection of the First
Amendment, and hence suppressed because it is a form of expression
"utterly without redeeming social importance," id. at 354 U. S. 484 ,
as "mirrored in the universal judgment that [it] should be
restrained. . . ." Id. at 354 U. S.
485 .
Because we assumed -- incorrectly, as experience has proved --
that obscenity could be separated from other sexually oriented
expression without significant costs either to the First Amendment
or to the judicial machinery charged with the task of safeguarding
First Amendment freedoms, we had no occasion in Roth to
probe the asserted state interest in curtailing unprotected,
sexually oriented speech. Yet, as we have increasingly come to
appreciate the vagueness of the concept of obscenity, we have begun
to recognize and articulate the state interests at stake.
Significantly, in Redrup v. New York, 386 U.
S. 767 (1967), where we set aside findings Page 413 U. S. 106 of obscenity with regard to three sets of material, we pointed
out that
"[i]n none of the cases was there a claim that the statute in
question reflected a specific and limited state concern for
juveniles. See Prince v. Massachusetts, 321 U. S.
158 ; cf. Butler v. Michigan, 352 U. S.
380 . In none was there any suggestion of an assault upon
individual privacy by publication in a manner so obtrusive as to
make it impossible for an unwilling individual to avoid exposure to
it. Cf. Breard v. Alexandria, 341 U. S.
622 ; Public Utilities Comm'n v. Pollak, 343 U. S.
451 . And in none was there evidence of the sort of
'pandering' which the Court found significant in Ginzburg v.
United States, 383 U. S. 463 ."
386 U.S. at 386 U. S. 769 . See Rowan v. Post Office Dept., 397 U.
S. 728 (1970); Stanley v. Georgia, 394 U.S. at 394 U. S. 567 .
[ Footnote 2/23 ]
The opinions in Redrup and Stanley reflected
our emerging view that the state interests in protecting children
and in protecting unconsenting adults may stand on a different
footing from the other asserted state interests. It may well be, as
one commentator has argued, that
"exposure to [erotic material] is for some persons an intense
emotional experience. A communication of this nature, imposed upon
a person contrary to his wishes, Page 413 U. S. 107 has all the characteristics of a physical assault. . . . [And
it] constitutes an invasion of his privacy. . . . [ Footnote 2/24 ]" But cf. Cohen v. California, 403 U.S. at 403 U. S. 21 -22.
Similarly, if children are "not possessed of that full capacity for
individual choice which is the presupposition of the First
Amendment guarantees," Ginsberg v. New York, 390 U.S. at 390 U. S.
649 -650 (STEWART, J., concurring), then the State may
have a substantial interest in precluding the flow of obscene
materials even to consenting juveniles. [ Footnote 2/25 ] But cf. id. at 390 U. S.
673 -674 (Fortas, J., dissenting).
But, whatever the strength of the state interests in protecting
juveniles and unconsenting adults from exposure to sexually
oriented materials, those interests cannot be asserted in defense
of the holding of the Georgia Supreme Court in this case. That
court assumed for the purposes of its decision that the films in
issue were exhibited only to persons over the age of 21 who viewed
them willingly and with prior knowledge of the nature of their
contents. And on that assumption, the state court held that the
films could still be suppressed. The justification for the
suppression must be found, therefore, in some independent interest
in regulating the reading and viewing habits of consenting
adults.
At the outset, it should be noted that virtually all of the
interests that might be asserted in defense of suppression, laying
aside the special interests associated with distribution to
juveniles and unconsenting adults, were also posited in Stanley
v. Georgia, supra, where we held that the State could not make
the "mere private possession of obscene material a crime." Id. at 394 U. S. 568 .
That decision presages the conclusions I reach here today.
In Stanley, we pointed out that "[t]here appears to
be Page 413 U. S. 108 little empirical basis for" the assertion that "exposure to
obscene materials may lead to deviant sexual behavior or crimes of
sexual violence." Id. at 394 U. S. 566 and n. 9. [ Footnote 2/26 ] In any
event, we added that
"if the State is only concerned about printed or filmed
materials inducing antisocial conduct, we believe that in the
context of private consumption of ideas and information we should
adhere to the view that '[a]mong free men, the deterrents
ordinarily to be applied to prevent crime are education and
punishment for violations of the law. . . .' Whitney v.
California, 274 U. S. 357 , 274 U. S.
378 (1927) (Brandeis, J., concurring)." Id. at 394 U. S.
566 -567.
Moreover, in Stanley, we rejected as "wholly
inconsistent with the philosophy of the First Amendment," id. at 394 U. S. 566 ,
the notion that there is a legitimate state concern in the "control
[of] the moral content of a person's thoughts," id. at 394 U. S. 565 ,
and we held that a State "cannot constitutionally premise
legislation on the desirability of controlling a person's private
thoughts." Id. at 394 U. S. 566 . That is not to say, of course, that a
State must remain utterly indifferent to -- and take no action
bearing on -- the morality of the community. The traditional
description Page 413 U. S. 109 of state police power does embrace the regulation of morals as
well as the health, safety, and general welfare of the citizenry. See, e.g., Village of Euclid v. Ambler Realty Co., 272 U. S. 365 , 272 U. S. 395 (1926). And much legislation -- compulsory public education laws,
civil rights laws, even the abolition of capital punishment -- is
grounded, at least in part, on a concern with the morality of the
community. But the State's interest in regulating morality by
suppressing obscenity, while often asserted, remains essentially
unfocused and ill-defined. And, since the attempt to curtail
unprotected speech necessarily spills over into the area of
protected speech, the effort to serve this speculative interest
through the suppression of obscene material must tread heavily on
rights protected by the First Amendment.
In Roe v. Wade, 410 U. S. 113 (1973), we held constitutionally invalid a state abortion law, even
though we were aware of
"the sensitive and emotional nature of the abortion controversy,
of the vigorous opposing views, even among physicians, and of the
deep and seemingly absolute convictions that the subject inspires.
One's philosophy, one's experiences, one's exposure to the raw
edges of human existence, one's religious training, one's attitudes
toward life and family and their values, and the moral standards
one establishes and seeks to observe, are all likely to influence
and to color one's thinking and conclusions about abortion." Id. at 116. Like the proscription of abortions, the
effort to suppress obscenity is predicated on unprovable, although
strongly held, assumptions about human behavior, morality, sex, and
religion. [ Footnote 2/27 ] The
existence of these assumptions cannot Page 413 U. S. 110 validate a statute that substantially undermines the guarantees
of the First Amendment, any more than the existence of similar
assumptions on the issue of abortion can validate a statute that
infringes the constitutionally protected privacy interests of a
pregnant woman.
If, as the Court today assumes, "a state legislature may . . .
act on the . . . assumption that commerce in obscene books, or
public exhibitions focused on obscene conduct, have a tendency to
exert a corrupting and debasing impact leading to antisocial
behavior," ante at 413 U. S. 63 ,
then it is hard to see how state-ordered regimentation of our minds
can ever be forestalled. For if a State, in an effort to maintain
or create a particular moral tone, may prescribe what its citizens
cannot read or cannot see, then it would seem to follow that in
pursuit of that same objective a State could decree that its
citizens must read certain books or must view certain films. Cf. United States v. Roth, 237 F.2d 796, 823 (CA2 1956)
(Frank, J., concurring). However laudable its goal -- and that is
obviously a question on which reasonable minds may differ -- the
State cannot proceed by means that violate the Constitution. The
precise point was established a half century ago in Meyer v.
Nebraska, 262 U. S. 390 (1923).
"That the State may do much, go very far, indeed, in order to
improve the quality of its citizens, physically, mentally and
morally, is clear; but the individual has certain fundamental
rights which must be respected. The protection of the Constitution
extends to all, to those who speak other languages as well as to
those born with English on the tongue. Perhaps it would be highly
advantageous if all had ready understanding of our ordinary speech,
but this cannot be coerced by methods which conflict with the
Constitution -- a desirable end cannot be promoted by prohibited
means. " Page 413 U. S. 111 "For the welfare of his Ideal Commonwealth, Plato suggested a
law which should provide:"
"That the wives of our guardians are to be common, and their
children are to be common, and no parent is to know his own child,
nor any child his parent. . . . The proper officers will take the
offspring of the good parents to the pen or fold, and there they
will deposit them with certain nurses who dwell in a separate
quarter; but the offspring of the inferior, or of the better when
they chance to be deformed, will be put away in some mysterious,
unknown place, as they should be."
"In order to submerge the individual and develop ideal citizens,
Sparta assembled the males at seven into barracks and intrusted
their subsequent education and training to official guardians.
Although such measures have been deliberately approved by men of
great genius, their ideas touching the relation between individual
and State were wholly different from those upon which our
institutions rest; and it hardly will be affirmed that any
legislature could impose such restrictions upon the people of a
State without doing violence to both letter and spirit of the
Constitution." Id. at 401-402.
Recognizing these principles, we have held that so-called
thematic obscenity -- obscenity which might persuade the viewer or
reader to engage in "obscene" conduct -- is not outside the
protection of the First Amendment:
"It is contended that the State's action was justified because
the motion picture attractively portrays a relationship which is
contrary to the moral standards, the religious precepts, and the
legal code of its citizenry. This argument misconceives what it is
that the Constitution protects. Its guarantee is Page 413 U. S. 112 not confined to the expression of ideas that are conventional or
shared by a majority. It protects advocacy of the opinion that
adultery may sometimes be proper, no less than advocacy of
socialism or the single tax. And, in the realm of ideas, it
protects expression which is eloquent no less than that which is
unconvincing." Kingsley Pictures Corp. v. Regents, 360 U.
S. 684 , 360 U. S.
688 -689 (1959). Even a legitimate, sharply focused state
concern for the morality of the community cannot, in other words,
justify an assault on the protections of the First Amendment. Cf. Griswold v. Connecticut, 381 U.
S. 479 (1965); Eisenstadt v. Baird, 405 U. S. 438 (1972); Loving v. Virginia, 388 U. S.
1 (1967). Where the state interest in regulation of
morality is vague and ill-defined, interference with the guarantees
of the First Amendment is even more difficult to justify. [ Footnote 2/28 ]
In short, while I cannot say that the interests of the State
apart from the question of juveniles and unconsenting adults -- are
trivial or nonexistent, I am compelled to conclude that these
interests cannot justify the substantial damage to constitutional
rights and to this Nation's judicial machinery that inevitably
results Page 413 U. S. 113 from state efforts to bar the distribution even of unprotected
material to consenting adults. NAACP v. Alabama, 377 U. S. 288 , 377 U. S. 307 (1964); Cantwell v. Connecticut, 310 U.S. at 310 U. S. 304 .
I would hold, therefore, that, at least in the absence of
distribution to juveniles or obtrusive exposure to unconsenting
adults, the First and Fourteenth Amendments prohibit the State and
Federal Governments from attempting wholly to suppress sexually
oriented materials on the basis of their allegedly "obscene"
contents. Nothing in this approach precludes those governments from
taking action to serve what may be strong and legitimate interests
through regulation of the manner of distribution of sexually
oriented material. VI Two Terms ago we noted that
"there is developing sentiment that adults should have complete
freedom to produce, deal in, possess and consume whatever
communicative materials may appeal to them and that the law's
involvement with obscenity should be limited to those situations
where children are involved or where it is necessary to prevent
imposition on unwilling recipients of whatever age. The concepts
involved are said to be so elusive and the laws so inherently
unenforceable without extravagant expenditures of time and effort
by enforcement officers and the courts that basic reassessment is
not only wise but essential." United States v. Reidel, 402 U.S. at 402 U. S. 357 .
Nevertheless, we concluded that "the task of restructuring the
obscenity laws lies with those who pass, repeal, and amend statutes
and ordinances." Ibid. But the law of obscenity has been
fashioned by this Court -- and necessarily so under our duty to
enforce the Constitution. Page 413 U. S. 114 It is surely the duty of this Court, as expounder of the
Constitution, to provide a remedy for the present unsatisfactory
state of affairs. I do not pretend to have found a complete and
infallible answer to what Mr. Justice Harlan called "the
intractable obscenity problem." Interstate Circuit, Inc. v.
Dallas, 390 U.S. at 390 U. S. 704 (separate opinion). See also Memoirs v. Massachusetts, 383
U.S. at 383 U. S. 456 (dissenting opinion). Difficult questions must still be faced,
notably in the areas of distribution to juveniles and offensive
exposure to unconsenting adults. Whatever the extent of state power
to regulate in those areas, [ Footnote
2/29 ] it should be clear that the view I espouse today would
introduce a large measure of clarity to this troubled area, would
reduce the institutional pressure on this Court and the rest of the
State and Federal Judiciary, and would guarantee fuller freedom of
expression while leaving room for the protection of legitimate
governmental interests. Since the Supreme Court of Georgia
erroneously concluded that the State has power to suppress sexually
oriented material even in the absence of distribution to juveniles
or exposure to unconsenting adults, I would reverse that judgment
and remand the case to that court for further proceedings not
inconsistent with this opinion.
[ Footnote 2/1 ]
Ga.Code Ann. § 22101 provides in pertinent part that
"(b) Material is obscene if considered as a whole, applying
community standards, its predominant appeal is to prurient
interest, that is, a shameful or morbid interest in nudity, sex or
excretion, and utterly without redeeming social value and if, in
addition, it goes substantially beyond customary limits of candor
in describing or representing such matters. Undeveloped
photographs, molds, printing plates and the like shall be deemed
obscene notwithstanding that processing or other acts may be
required to make the obscenity patent or to disseminate it."
[ Footnote 2/2 ]
Ga.Code § 22101(a):
"A person commits the offense of distributing obscene materials
[as described in subsection (b), 413 U.S.
49 fn2/1|>n. 1, supra ] when he sells, lends, rents,
leases, gives, advertises, publishes, exhibits or otherwise
disseminates to any person any obscene material of any description,
knowing the obscene nature thereof, or who offers to do so, or who
possesses such material with the intent so to do. . . ."
[ Footnote 2/3 ]
The precise holding of the trial court is not free from
ambiguity. After pointing out that the films could be considered
obscene, and that they still could not be suppressed in the absence
of exposure to juveniles or unconsenting adults, the trial court
concluded that
"[i]t is the judgment of this court that the films, even though
they display the human body and the human personality in a most
degrading fashion, are not obscene."
It is not clear whether the trial court found that the films
were not obscene in the sense that they were protected expression
under the standards of Roth v. United States, 354 U.
S. 476 (1957), and Redrup v. New York, 386 U. S. 767 (1967), or whether it used the expression "not obscene" as a term
of art to indicate that the films could not be suppressed even
though they were not protected under the Roth-Redrup standards. In any case, the Georgia Supreme Court viewed the trial
court's opinion as holding that the films could not be suppressed,
even if they were unprotected expression, provided that they were
not exhibited to juveniles or unconsenting adults.
[ Footnote 2/4 ]
"As to all such problems, this Court said in Thornhill v.
Alabama, 310 U. S. 88 , 310 U. S.
101 -102 (1940): "
"'The freedom of speech and of the press guaranteed by the
Constitution embraces at the least the liberty to discuss publicly
and truthfully all matters of public concern without
previous restraint or fear of subsequent punishment. The exigencies
of the colonial period and the efforts to secure freedom from
oppressive administration developed a broadened conception of these
liberties as adequate to supply the public need for information
and education with respect to the significant issues of the
times. . . . Freedom of discussion, if it would fulfill its
historic function in this nation, must embrace all issues about
which information is needed or appropriate to enable the members of
society to cope with the exigencies of their period. '
(Emphasis added.)" Roth, 354 U.S. at 354 U. S.
487 -488. See also, e.g., Thomas v. Collins, 323 U. S. 516 , 323 U. S. 531 (1945) ("the rights of free speech and a free press are not
confined to any field of human interest").
[ Footnote 2/5 ] See, e.g., Kalven, The Metaphysics of the Law of
Obscenity, 1960 Sup.Ct.Rev. 1, 10-11; cf. Beauharnais v.
Illinois, 343 U. S. 250 (1952).
[ Footnote 2/6 ] See, e.g., T. Emerson, The System of Freedom of
Expression 487 (1970); Kalven, supra, 413 U.S.
49 fn2/5|>n. 5; Comment, More Ado About Dirty Books, 75 Yale
L.J. 1364 (1966).
[ Footnote 2/7 ]
On the question of community standards see also Hoyt v.
Minnesota, 399 U. S. 524 (1970) (BLACKMUN, J., joined by BURGER, C.J., and Harlan, J.,
dissenting) (flexibility for state standards); Cain v.
Kentucky, 397 U. S. 319 (1970) (BURGER, C.J., dissenting) (same); Manual Enterprises v.
Day, 370 U. S. 478 , 370 U. S. 488 (1962) (Harlan, J., joined by STEWART, J.) (national standards in
context of federal prosecution).
[ Footnote 2/8 ]
No fewer than 31 cases have been disposed of in this fashion.
Aside from the three cases reversed in Redrup, they are: Keney v. New York, 388 U. S. 440 (1967); Friedman v. New York, 388 U.
S. 441 (1967); Ratner v. California, 388 U. S. 442 (1967); Cobert v. New York, 388 U.
S. 443 (1967); Sheperd v. New York, 388 U. S. 444 (1967); Avansino v. New York, 388 U.
S. 446 (1967); Aday v. New York, 388 U.
S. 447 (1967); Books, Inc. v. United States, 388 U. S. 449 (1967); A Quantity of Books v. Kansas, 388 U.
S. 452 (1967); Mazes v. Ohio, 388 U.
S. 453 (1967); Schackman v. California, 388 U. S. 454 (1967); Potomac News Co. v. United States, 389 U. S.
47 (1967); Conner v. City of Hammond, 389 U. S. 48 (1967); Central Magazine Sales, Ltd. v. United States, 389 U. S. 50 (1967); Chance v. California, 389 U. S.
89 (1967); I. M. Amusement Corp. v. Ohio, 389 U. S. 573 (1968); Robert Arthur Management Corp. v. Tennessee, 389 U. S. 578 (1968); Felton v. City of Pensacola, 390 U.
S. 340 (1968); Henry v. Louisiana, 392 U.
S. 655 (1968); Cain v. Kentucky, supra; Bloss v.
Dykema, 398 U. S. 278 (1970); Walker v. Ohio, 398 U. S. 434 (1970); Hoyt v. Minnesota, supra; Childs v. Oregon, 401
U.S. 1006 (1971); Bloss v. Michigan, 402 U.S. 938 (1971); Burgin v. South Carolina, 404 U.
S. 809 (1971); Hartstein v. Missouri, 404 U.S.
988 (1971); Wiener v. California, 404 U.S. 988 (1971).
[ Footnote 2/9 ]
Although I did not join the opinion of the Court in Stanley
v. Georgia, 394 U. S. 557 (1969), I am now inclined to agree that "the Constitution protects
the right to receive information and ideas," and that "[t]his right
to receive information and ideas, regardless of their social worth
. . . is fundamental to our free society." Id. at 394 U. S. 564 . See Martin v. City of Struthers, 319 U.
S. 141 , 319 U. S. 143 (1943); Winters v. New York, 333 U.
S. 507 , 333 U. S. 510 (1948); Lamont v. Postmaster General, 381 U.
S. 301 , 381 U. S.
307 -308 (1965) (concurring opinion). This right is
closely tied, as Stanley recognized, to "the right to be
free, except in very limited circumstances, from unwarranted
governmental intrusions into one's privacy." 394 U.S. at 394 U. S. 564 . See Griswold v. Connecticut, 381 U.
S. 479 (1965); Olmstead v. United States, 277 U. S. 438 , 277 U. S. 478 (1928) (Brandeis, J., dissenting). It is similarly related to
"the right of the individual, married or single, to be free from
unwarranted governmental intrusion into matters so fundamentally
affecting a person as the decision whether to bear or beget a
child"
(italics omitted), Eisenstadt v. Baird, 405 U.
S. 438 , 405 U. S. 453 (1972), and the right to exercise "autonomous control over the
development and expression of one's intellect, interests, tastes,
and personality." (Italics omitted.) Doe v. Bolton, 410 U. S. 179 , 410 U. S. 211 (1973) (DOUGLAS, J., concurring). It seems to me that the
recognition of these intertwining rights calls in question the
validity of the two-level approach recognized in Roth. After all, if a person has the right to receive information without
regard to its social worth -- that is, without regard to its
obscenity -- then it would seem to follow that a State could not
constitutionally punish one who undertakes to provide this
information to a willing adult recipient. See
Eisenstadt v. Baird, supra, at 405 U. S.
443 -446. In any event, I need not rely on this line of
analysis or explore all of its possible ramifications, for there is
available a narrower basis on which to rest this decision. Whether
or not a class of "obscene" and thus entirely unprotected speech
does exist, I am forced to conclude that the class is incapable of
definition with sufficient clarity to withstand attack on vagueness
grounds. Accordingly, it is on principles of the "void for
vagueness" doctrine that this opinion exclusively relies.
[ Footnote 2/10 ]
In this regard, the problems of vagueness and overbreadth are,
plainly, closely intertwined. See NAACP v. Button, 371 U. S. 415 , 371 U. S.
432 -433 (1963); Note, The First Amendment Overbreadth
Doctrine, 83 Harv.L.Rev. 844, 845 (1970). Cf. infra at 413 U. S.
93 -94.
[ Footnote 2/11 ] See also Speiser v. Randall, 357 U.
S. 513 (1958); cf. Barenblatt v. United States, 360 U. S. 109 , 360 U. S.
137 -138 (1959) (Black, J., dissenting):
"This Court . . . has emphasized that the 'vice of vagueness' is
especially pernicious where legislative power over an area
involving speech, press, petition and assembly is involved. . . .
For a statute broad enough to support infringement of speech,
writings, thoughts and public assemblies, against the unequivocal
command of the First Amendment necessarily leaves all persons to
guess just what the law really means to cover, and fear of a wrong
guess inevitably leads people to forego the very rights the
Constitution sought to protect above all others. Vagueness becomes
even more intolerable in this area if one accepts, as the Court
today does, a balancing test to decide if First Amendment rights
shall be protected. It is difficult, at best, to make a man guess
-- at the penalty of imprisonment -- whether a court will consider
the State's need for certain information superior to society's
interest in unfettered freedom. It is unconscionable to make him
choose between the right to keep silent and the need to speak when
the statute supposedly establishing the state's interest' is too
vague to give him guidance."
(Citations omitted.)
[ Footnote 2/12 ]
Note, The First Amendment Overbreadth Doctrine, 83 Harv.L.Rev.
844, 885-886 and n. 158 (1970) ("Thus, in the area of obscenity the
overbreadth doctrine operates interstitially, when no line of
privilege is apposite or yet to be found, to control the impact of
schemes designed to curb distribution of unprotected
material").
[ Footnote 2/13 ]
While the Court's modification of the Memoirs test is
small, it should still prove sufficient to invalidate virtually
every state law relating to the suppression of obscenity. For,
under the Court's restatement, a statute must specifically
enumerate certain forms of sexual conduct, the depiction of which
is to be prohibited. It seems highly doubtful to me that state
courts will be able to construe state statutes so as to incorporate
a carefully itemized list of various forms of sexual conduct, and
thus to bring them into conformity with the Court's requirements. Cf. Blount v. Rizzi, 400 U. S. 410 , 400 U. S. 419 (1971). The statutes of at least one State should, however, escape
the wholesale invalidation. Oregon has recently revised its statute
to prohibit only the distribution of obscene materials to juveniles
or unconsenting adults. The enactment of this principle is, of
course, a choice constitutionally open to every State, even under
the Court's decision. See Oregon Laws 1971, c. 743, Art.
29, §§ 255-262.
[ Footnote 2/14 ]
"All ideas having even the slightest redeeming social importance
-- unorthodox ideas, controversial ideas, even ideas hateful to the
prevailing climate of opinion -- have the full protection of the
guaranties, unless excludable because they encroach upon the
limited area of more important interests. But implicit in the
history of the First Amendment is the rejection of obscenity as
utterly without redeeming social importance." Roth v. United States, supra, at 354 U. S.
484 .
[ Footnote 2/15 ] Miller v. California, ante at 413 U. S.
22 .
[ Footnote 2/16 ] Huffman v. United States, 152 U.S. App. D.C. 238, 470
F.2d 386 (1971). The test apparently requires an effort to
distinguish between "singles" and "duals," between "erect penises"
and "semi-erect penises," and between "ongoing sexual activity" and
"imminent sexual activity."
[ Footnote 2/17 ]
Note, The "Void for Vagueness" Doctrine in the Supreme Court,
109 U.Pa.L.Rev. 67, 81 (1960).
[ Footnote 2/18 ] Compare Ginsberg v. New York, 390 U.
S. 629 , 390 U. S. 672 (1968) (Fortas, J., dissenting); Jacobellis v. Ohio, 378 U. S. 184 , 378 U. S.
187 -190 (1964) (BRENNAN, J., joined by Goldberg, J.); Manual Enterprises v. Day, 370 U.S. at 370 U. S. 488 (Harlan, J., joined by STEWART, J.); and Kingsley Pictures
Corp. v. Regents, 360 U. S. 684 , 360 U. S.
696 -697 (1959) (Frankfurter, J., concurring); id. at 360 U. S. 708 (Harlan, J., joined by Frankfurter, J., and Whittaker, J.,
concurring), with Jacobellis v. Ohio, supra, at 378 U. S.
202 -203 (Warren, C.J., joined by Clark, J., dissenting); Roth v. United States, 354 U.S. at 354 U. S. 492 n. 30; and Kingsley Books, Inc. v. Brown, 354 U.
S. 436 , 354 U. S. 448 (1957) (BRENNAN, J., dissenting). See also Walker v. Ohio, 398 U. S. 434 (1970) (BURGER, C.J., dissenting).
[ Footnote 2/19 ]
Mr. Justice Harlan, it bears noting, considered this requirement
critical for review of not only federal but state convictions,
despite his view that the States were accorded more latitude than
the Federal Government in defining obscenity. See, e.g., Roth
supra, at 354 U. S.
502 -503 (separate opinion).
[ Footnote 2/20 ] See generally Culombe v. Connecticut, 367 U.
S. 568 , 367 U. S.
603 -606 (1961) (opinion of Frankfurter, J.); cf.
Crowell v. Benson, 285 U. S. 22 , 285 U. S. 55 -65
(1932); Ng Fung Ho v. White, 259 U.
S. 276 , 259 U. S.
284 -285 (1922).
[ Footnote 2/21 ] See 413 U.S.
49 fn2/9|>n. 9, supra. [ Footnote 2/22 ] Cf. United States v. O'Brien, 391 U.
S. 367 , 391 U. S.
376 -377 (1968):
"This Court has held that, when 'speech' and 'nonspeech'
elements are combined in the same course of conduct, a sufficiently
important governmental interest in regulating the nonspeech element
can justify incidental limitations on First Amendment freedoms. To
characterize the quality of the governmental interest which must
appear, the Court has employed a variety of descriptive terms:
compelling; substantial; subordinating; paramount; cogent; strong.
Whatever imprecision inheres in these terms, we think it clear that
a government regulation is sufficiently justified if it is within
the constitutional power of the Government; if it furthers an
important or substantial governmental interest; if the governmental
interest is unrelated to the suppression of free expression; and if
the incidental restriction on alleged First Amendment freedoms is
no greater than is essential to the furtherance of that
interest."
(Footnotes omitted.) See also Speiser v. Randall, 357 U. S. 513 (1958).
[ Footnote 2/23 ] See also Rabe v. Washington, 405 U.
S. 313 , 405 U. S. 317 (1972) (concurring opinion); United States v. Reidel, 402 U. S. 351 , 402 U. S.
360 -362 (1971) (separate opinion); Ginsberg v. New
York, 390 U. S. 629 (1968); id. at 390 U. S.
674 -675 (dissenting opinion); Redmond v. United
States, 384 U. S. 264 , 384 U. S. 265 (1966); Ginzburg v. United States, 383 U.
S. 463 (1966); id. at 383 U. S. 498 n. 1 (dissenting opinion); Memoirs v. Massachusetts, 383 U. S. 413 , 383 U. S. 421 n. 8 (1966); Jacobellis v. Ohio, 378 U.S. at 378 U. S. 195 (1964) (opinion of BRENNAN, J., joined by Goldberg, J.); id. at 378 U. S. 201 (dissenting opinion). See also Report of the Commission on
Obscenity and Pornography 300-301 (1970) (focus of early obscenity
laws on protection of youth).
[ Footnote 2/24 ]
T. Emerson, The System of Freedom of Expression 496 (1970).
[ Footnote 2/25 ] See ibid. [ Footnote 2/26 ]
Indeed, since Stanley was decided, the President's
Commission on Obscenity and Pornography has concluded:
"In sum, empirical research designed to clarify the question has
found no evidence to date that exposure to explicit sexual
materials plays a significant role in the causation of delinquent
or criminal behavior among youth or adults. The Commission cannot
conclude that exposure to erotic materials is a factor in the
causation of sex crime or sex delinquency."
Report of the Commission on Obscenity and Pornography 27 (1970)
(footnote omitted). To the contrary, the Commission found that,
"[o]n the positive side, explicit sexual materials are sought as
a source of entertainment and information by substantial numbers of
American adults. At times, these materials also appear to serve to
increase and facilitate constructive communication about sexual
matters within marriage." Id. at 53.
[ Footnote 2/27 ] See Henkin, Morals and the Constitution: The Sin of
Obscenity, 63 Col.L.Rev. 391, 395 (1963).
[ Footnote 2/28 ]
"[I]n our system, undifferentiated fear or apprehension of
disturbance is not enough to overcome the right to freedom of
expression. Any departure from absolute regimentation may cause
trouble. Any variation from the majority's opinion may inspire
fear. Any word spoken, in class, in the lunchroom, or on the
campus, that deviates from the views of another person may start an
argument or cause a disturbance. But our Constitution says we must
take this risk, Terminiello v. Chicago, 337 U. S. 1 (1949); and our history says that it is this sort of hazardous
freedom -- this kind of openness -- that is the basis of our
national strength and of the independence and vigor of Americans
who grow up and live in this relatively permissive, often
disputatious, society." Tinker v. Des Moines School District, 393 U.
S. 503 , 393 U. S.
508 -509 (1969). See also Cohen v. California, 403 U. S. 15 , 403 U. S. 23 (1971).
[ Footnote 2/29 ]
The Court erroneously states, Miller v. California,
ante at 413 U. S. 27 ,
that the author of this opinion "indicates that suppression of
unprotected obscene material is permissible to avoid exposure to
unconsenting adults . . . and to juveniles. . . ." I defer
expression of my views as to the scope of state power in these
areas until cases squarely presenting these questions are before
the Court. See 413 U.S.
49 fn2/9|>n. 9, supra; Miller v. California, supra, (dissenting opinion). | In Paris Adult Theatre I v. Slaton, the U.S. Supreme Court held that obscene material is not protected by the First Amendment and that states have a legitimate interest in regulating its exhibition in public places, including adult theaters. The Court also upheld the Georgia civil procedure used in this case and found that expert evidence of obscenity was not necessary when the films themselves were placed into evidence. The Court distinguished between the privacy of the home and public places, concluding that a commercial theater does not enjoy the same privacy protections as a private home. |
Free Speech | FCC v. League of Women Voters | https://supreme.justia.com/cases/federal/us/468/364/ | U.S. Supreme Court FCC v. League of Women Voters, 468
U.S. 364 (1984) Federal Communications Commission
v. League of Women Voters of
California No. 82-912 Argued January 16,
1984 Decided July 2, 1984 468
U.S. 364 APPEAL FROM THE UNITED STATES
DISTRICT COURT FOR THE CENTRAL DISTRICT OF
CALIFORNIA Syllabus The Public Broadcasting Act of 1967 (Act) established the
Corporation for Public Broadcasting (CPB), a nonprofit corporation,
to disburse federal funds to noncommercial television and radio
stations in support of station operations and educational
programming. Section 399 of the Act forbids any noncommercial
educational station that receives a grant from the CPB to "engage
in editorializing." Appellees (Pacifica Foundation, a nonprofit
corporation that owns and operates several noncommercial
educational broadcasting stations that receive grants from the CPB,
the League of Women Voters of California, and an individual
listener and viewer of public broadcasting) brought an action in
Federal District Court challenging the constitutionality of § 399.
The District Court granted summary judgment in appellees' favor,
holding that § 399 violates the First Amendment. Held: Section 399's ban on editorializing violates the
First Amendment. Pp. 468 U. S.
374 -402.
(a) Congress, acting pursuant to the Commerce Clause, has power
to regulate the use of the broadcast medium. In the exercise of
this power, Congress may seek to assure that the public receives
through this medium a balanced presentation of information and
views on issues of public importance that otherwise might not be
addressed if control of the medium were left entirely in the hands
of the owners and operators of broadcasting stations. At the same
time, since broadcasters are engaged in a vital and independent
form of communicative activity, the First Amendment must inform and
give shape to the manner in which Congress exercises its regulatory
power. Thus, although the broadcasting industry operates under
restrictions not imposed upon other media, the thrust of these
restrictions has generally been to secure the public's First
Amendment interest in receiving a balanced presentation of views on
diverse matters of public concern. As a result, the absolute
freedom to advocate one's own positions without also presenting
opposing viewpoints -- a freedom enjoyed, for example, by newspaper
publishers -- is denied to broadcasters. Such restrictions have
been upheld Page 468 U. S. 365 by this Court only when they were narrowly tailored to further a
substantial governmental interest, such as ensuring adequate and
balanced coverage of public issues. Pp. 468 U. S.
374 -381.
(b) The restriction imposed by § 399 is specifically directed at
a form of speech -- the expression of editorial opinions -- that
lies at the heart of First Amendment protection, and is defined
solely on the basis of the content of the suppressed speech.
Section 399 singles out noncommercial broadcasters and denies them
the right to address their chosen audience on matters of public
importance. Pp. 468 U. S.
381 -384.
(c) Section 399's broad ban on all editorializing by every
station that receives CPB funds far exceeds what is necessary to
protect against the risk of governmental interference or to prevent
the public from assuming that editorials by public broadcasting
stations represent the official view of government. The ban
impermissibly sweeps within it a wide range of speech by wholly
private stations on topics that do not take a directly partisan
stand or that have nothing whatever to do with federal, state, or
local government. Pp. 468 U. S.
386 -395.
(d) The patent overinclusiveness and underinclusiveness of §
399's ban also undermines the likelihood of a genuine governmental
interest in preventing private groups from propagating their own
views via public broadcasting. Section 399 does not prevent the use
of noncommercial stations for the presentation of partisan views on
controversial matters; instead, it merely bars a station from
specifically labeling such issues as its own or those of its
management. Pp. 468 U. S.
396 -399.
(e) Section 399 cannot be justified on the basis of Congress'
spending power as simply determining that Congress will not
subsidize public broadcasting station editorials. Regan v.
Taxation With Representation of Washington, 461 U.
S. 540 , distinguished. Since a noncommercial educational
station that receives only 1% of its income from CPB grants is
barred absolutely from editorializing, such a station has no way of
limiting the use of its federal funds to noneditorial activities,
and, more importantly, it is barred from using even private funds
to finance its editorial activity. Pp. 468 U. S.
399 -401. 547 F.
Supp. 379 , affirmed.
BRENNAN, J., delivered the opinion of the Court, in which
MARSHALL, BLACKMUN, POWELL, and O'CONNOR, JJ., joined. WHITE, J.,
filed a dissenting statement, post, p. 468 U. S. 402 .
REHNQUIST, J., filed a dissenting opinion, in which BURGER, C.J.,
and WHITE, J., joined, post, p. 468 U. S. 402 .
STEVENS, J., filed a dissenting opinion, post, p. 468 U. S.
408 . Page 468 U. S. 366 JUSTICE BRENNAN delivered the opinion of the Court.
Moved to action by a widely felt need to sponsor independent
sources of broadcast programming as an alternative to commercial
broadcasting, Congress set out in 1967 to support and promote the
development of noncommercial, educational broadcasting stations. A
keystone of Congress' program was the Public Broadcasting Act of
1967, Pub.L. 90-129, 81 Stat. 365, 47 U.S.C. § 390 et
seq., which established the Corporation for Public
Broadcasting, a nonprofit corporation authorized to disburse
federal funds to noncommercial television and radio stations in
support of station operations and educational programming. Section
399 of that Act, as amended by the Public Broadcasting Amendments
Act of 1981, Pub.L. 97-35, 95 Stat. 730, forbids any "noncommercial
educational broadcasting station which receives a grant from the
Corporation" to "engage in editorializing." 47 U.S.C. § 399. In
this case, we are called upon to decide whether Congress, by
imposing that restriction, has passed a "law . . . abridging the
freedom of speech, or of the press" in violation of the First
Amendment of the Constitution. Page 468 U. S. 367 I A The history of noncommercial educational broadcasting in the
United States is as old as broadcasting itself. [ Footnote 1 ] In its first efforts to regulate
broadcasting, Congress made no special provision for noncommercial,
educational broadcasting stations. Under the Radio Act of 1927 and
the Communications Act of 1934, such stations were subject to the
same licensing requirements as their commercial counterparts. As
commercial broadcasting rapidly expanded during the 1930's,
however, the percentage of broadcast licenses held by noncommercial
stations began to shrink. In 1939, recognizing the potential effect
of these commercial pressures on educational stations, the Federal
Communications Commission (FCC or Commission) decided to reserve
certain frequencies for educational radio, 47 CFR §§ 4.131-4.133
(1939), and in 1945, the Commission allocated 20 frequencies on the
new FM spectrum exclusively for educational use, FCC, Report of
Proposed Allocations 77 (1945). Similarly, in 1952, with the advent
of television, the FCC reserved certain television channels solely
for educational stations. Television Assignments, 41
F.C.C. 148 (1952). Helped in part by these allocations, a wide
variety of noncommercial stations, some funded by state and local
governments and others by private donations and foundation grants,
developed during this period. [ Footnote 2 ]
It was not until 1962, however, that Congress provided any
direct financial assistance to noncommercial, educational
broadcasting. This first step was taken with the passage of Page 468 U. S. 368 the Educational Television Act of 1962, Pub.L. 87-447, 76 Stat.
64, which authorized the former Department of Health, Education,
and Welfare (HEW) to distribute $32 million in matching grants over
a 5-year period for the construction of noncommercial television
facilities.
Impetus for expanded federal involvement came in 1967 when the
Carnegie Corporation sponsored a special commission to review the
state of educational broadcasting. Finding that the prospects for
an expanded public broadcasting system rested on "the vigor of its
local stations," but that these stations were hobbled by chronic
underfinancing, the Carnegie Commission called upon the Federal
Government to supplement existing state, local, and private
financing so that educational broadcasting could realize its full
potential as a true alternative to commercial broadcasting. Carnegie I, at 33-34, 36-37. [ Footnote 3 ] In fashioning a legislative proposal to carry
out this vision, the Commission recommended the creation of a
nonprofit, nongovernmental "Corporation for Public Television" to
provide support for noncommercial broadcasting, including funding
for new program production, local station operations, and the
establishment of satellite interconnection facilities to permit
nationwide distribution of educational programs to all local
stations that wished to receive and use them. Id. at
37-38.
The Commission's report met with widespread approval, and its
proposals became the blueprint for the Public Broadcasting Act of
1967, which established the basic framework of the public
broadcasting system of today. Titles I and III of Page 468 U. S. 369 the Act authorized over $38 million for continued HEW
construction grants and for the study of instructional television.
Title II created the Corporation for Public Broadcasting (CPB or
Corporation), a nonprofit, private corporation governed by a
15-person, bipartisan Board of Directors appointed by the President
with the advice and consent of the Senate. [ Footnote 4 ] The Corporation was given power to fund
"the production of . . . educational television or radio programs
for national or regional distribution," 47 U.S.C. § 396(g)(2)(B)
(1976 ed.), to make grants to local broadcasting stations that
would "aid in financing local educational . . . programming costs
of such stations," § 396(g)(2)(C), and to assist in the
establishment and development of national interconnection
facilities. § 396(g)(2)(E). [ Footnote 5 ] Aside from conferring these powers on the
Corporation, Congress also adopted other measures designed both to
ensure the autonomy of the Corporation and to protect the local
stations from governmental interference and control. For example,
all federal agencies, officers, and employees were prohibited from
"exercis[ing] any direction, supervision or control" over the
Corporation or local stations, § 398, and the Corporation itself
was forbidden to "own or operate any television or radio broadcast
station," § 396(g)(3), and was further required to
"carry out its purposes and functions . . . in ways that will
most effectively assure the maximum freedom . . . from Page 468 U. S. 370 interference with or control of program content"
of the local stations. § 396(g)(1)(D). B Appellee Pacifica Foundation is a nonprofit corporation that
owns and operates several noncommercial educational broadcasting
stations in five major metropolitan areas. [ Footnote 6 ] Its licensees have received and are
presently receiving grants from the Corporation, and are therefore
prohibited from editorializing by the terms of § 399, as originally
enacted and as recently amended. [ Footnote 7 ] In April, 1979, appellees brought this suit in
the United States District Court for the Central District of
California challenging the constitutionality of former § 399. In
October, 1979, the Department of Justice informed Page 468 U. S. 371 both Houses of Congress and the District Court that it had
decided not to defend the constitutionality of the statute.
[ Footnote 8 ] The Senate then
adopted a resolution directing its counsel to intervene as amicus curiae in support of § 399. Counsel appeared and
subsequently obtained dismissal of the lawsuit for want of a
justiciable controversy because the Government had decided not to
enforce the statute. While appellees' appeal from this disposition
was pending before the Court of Appeals for the Ninth Circuit,
however, the Department of Justice, under a new administration,
announced that it would defend the statute. The Court of Appeals
then remanded the case to the District Court; the District Court
permitted the Senate counsel to withdraw from the litigation, and,
finding that a concrete controversy was now presented, vacated its
earlier order of dismissal. While the suit was pending before the
District Court, Congress, as already mentioned, see n 7, supra, amended §
399 by confining the ban on editorializing to noncommercial
stations that receive Corporation grants and by separately
prohibiting all noncommercial stations from making political
endorsements, irrespective of whether they receive federal funds.
Subsequently, appellees amended their complaint to reflect this
change, challenging only the ban on editorializing. [ Footnote 9 ] Page 468 U. S. 372 The District Court granted summary judgment in favor of
appellees, holding that § 399's ban on editorializing violated the
First Amendment. 547 F.
Supp. 379 (1982). The court rejected the Federal Communication
Commission's contention that
"§ 399 serves a compelling government interest in ensuring that
funded noncommercial broadcasters do not become propaganda organs
for the government." Id. at 384-385. Noting the diverse sources of funding
for noncommercial stations, the protections built into the Public
Broadcasting Act to ensure that noncommercial broadcasters remain
free of governmental influence, and the requirements of the FCC's
fairness doctrine which are designed to guard against one-sided
presentation of controversial issues, the District Court concluded
that the asserted fear of Government control was not sufficiently
compelling to warrant § 399's restriction on speech. Id. at 386. The court also rejected the contention that the restriction
on editorializing as necessary to ensure that Government funding of
noncommercial broadcast stations does not interfere with the
balanced presentation of opinion on those stations. Id. at
387. The FCC appealed from the District Court judgment Page 468 U. S. 373 directly to this Court pursuant to 28 U.S.C. § 1252. We
postponed consideration of the question of our jurisdiction to the
merits, 460 U.S. 1010 (1983), [ Footnote 10 ] and we now affirm. Page 468 U. S. 374 II We begin by considering the appropriate standard of review. The
District Court acknowledged that our decisions Page 468 U. S. 375 have generally applied a different First Amendment standard for
broadcast regulation than in other areas, but after finding that no
special characteristic of the broadcast media justified application
of a less stringent standard in this case, it held that § 399 could
survive constitutional scrutiny only if it served a "compelling"
governmental interest. 547 F. Supp. at 384. Claiming that the court
drew the wrong lessons from our prior decisions concerning
broadcast regulation, the Government contends that a less demanding
standard is required. It argues that Congress may, consistently
with the First Amendment, exercise broad power to regulate
broadcast speech because the medium of broadcasting is subject to
the "special characteristic" of spectrum scarcity -- a
characteristic not shared by other media -- which calls for more
exacting regulation. This power, in the Government's view, includes
authority to restrict the ability of all broadcasters, both
commercial and noncommercial, to editorialize. Brief for Appellant
31. Moreover, given the unique role of noncommercial broadcasting
as a source of "programming excellence and diversity that the
commercial sector could not or would not produce," id. at
33, Congress was entitled to impose special restrictions such as §
399 upon these stations. The Government concludes by urging that §
399 is an appropriate and essential means of furthering "important"
governmental interests, id. at 34, 35, 39, which leaves
open the possibility that a wide variety of views on matters of
public importance can be expressed through the medium of
noncommercial educational broadcasting.
At first glance, of course, it would appear that the District
Court applied the correct standard. Section 399 plainly operates to
restrict the expression of editorial opinion on matters of public
importance, and, as we have repeatedly explained, communication of
this kind is entitled to the most Page 468 U. S. 376 exacting degree of First Amendment protection. E.g.,
Minneapolis Star & Tribune Co. v. Minnesota Commissioner of
Revenue, 460 U. S. 575 , 460 U. S. 585 (1983); First National Bank of Boston v. Bellotti, 435 U. S. 765 , 435 U. S.
776 -777 (1978); Buckley v. Valeo, 424 U. S.
1 , 424 U. S. 14 (1976); Thornhill v. Alabama, 310 U. S.
88 , 310 U. S.
101 -102 (1940). Were a similar ban on editorializing
applied to newspapers and magazines, we would not hesitate to
strike it down as violative of the First Amendment. E.g., Mills
v. Alabama, 384 U. S. 214 (1966). But, as the Government correctly notes, because broadcast
regulation involves unique considerations, our cases have not
followed precisely the same approach that we have applied to other
media, and have never gone so far as to demand that such
regulations serve "compelling" governmental interests. At the same
time, we think the Government's argument loses sight of concerns
that are important in this area, and thus misapprehends the
essential meaning of our prior decisions concerning the reach of
Congress' authority to regulate broadcast communication.
The fundamental principles that guide our evaluation of
broadcast regulation are by now well established. First, we have
long recognized that Congress, acting pursuant to the Commerce
Clause, has power to regulate the use of this scarce and valuable
national resource. The distinctive feature of Congress' efforts in
this area has been to ensure through the regulatory oversight of
the FCC that only those who satisfy the "public interest,
convenience, and necessity" are granted a license to use radio and
television broadcast frequencies. 47 U.S.C. § 309(a). [ Footnote 11 ] Page 468 U. S. 377 Second, Congress may, in the exercise of this power, seek to
assure that the public receives through this medium a balanced
presentation of information on issues of public importance that
otherwise might not be addressed if control of the medium were left
entirely in the hands of those who own and operate broadcasting
stations. Although such governmental regulation has never been
allowed with respect to the print media, Miami Herald
Publishing Co. v. Tornillo, 418 U. S. 241 (1974), we have recognized that "differences in the characteristics
of new media justify differences in the First Amendment standards
applied to them." Red Lion Broadcasting Co. v. FCC,d 395 U. S. 367 , 395 U. S. 386 (1969). The fundamental distinguishing characteristic of the new
medium of broadcasting that, in our view, has required some
adjustment in First Amendment analysis is that "[b]roadcast
frequencies are a scarce resource [that] must be portioned out
among applicants." Columbia Broadcasting System, Inc. v.
Democratic National Committee, 412 U. S.
94 , 412 U. S. 101 (1973). Thus, our cases have taught that, given spectrum scarcity,
those who are granted a license to broadcast must serve in a sense
as fiduciaries for the public by presenting
"those views and voices which are representative of [their]
community and which would otherwise, by necessity, be barred from
the airwaves." Red Lion, supra, at 395 U. S. 389 .
As we observed in that case, because
"[i]t is the purpose of the First Amendment to preserve an
uninhibited marketplace of ideas in which truth will ultimately
prevail, . . . the right of the public to receive suitable access
to social, political, esthetic, moral, and other ideas and
experiences [through the medium of broadcasting] Page 468 U. S. 378 is crucial here [and it] may not constitutionally be abridged
either by Congress or by the FCC."
395 U.S. at 395 U. S. 390 .
Finally, although the Government's interest in ensuring balanced
coverage of public issues is plainly both important and
substantial, we have, at the same time, made clear that
broadcasters are engaged in a vital and independent form of
communicative activity. As a result, the First Amendment must
inform and give shape to the manner in which Congress exercises its
regulatory power in this area. Unlike common carriers, broadcasters
are "entitled under the First Amendment to exercise the widest
journalistic freedom consistent with their public [duties].'" CBS, Inc. v. FCC, 453 U. S. 367 , 453 U. S. 395 (1981) (quoting Columbia Broadcasting System, Inc. v.
Democratic National Committee, supra, at 412 U. S. 110 ). See also FCC v. Midwest Video Corp., 440 U.
S. 689 , 440 U. S. 703 (1979). Indeed, if the public's interest in receiving a balanced
presentation of views is to be fully served, we must necessarily
rely in large part upon the editorial initiative and judgment of
the broadcasters who bear the public trust. See Columbia
Broadcasting System, Inc. v. Democratic National Committee,
supra, at 412 U. S.
124 -127. Our prior cases illustrate these principles. In Red
Lion, for example, we upheld the FCC's "fairness doctrine" --
which requires broadcasters to provide adequate coverage of public
issues and to ensure that this coverage fairly and accurately
reflects the opposing views -- because the doctrine advanced the
substantial governmental interest in ensuring balanced
presentations of views in this limited medium, and yet posed no
threat that a "broadcaster [would be denied permission] to carry a
particular program or to publish his own views." 395 U.S. at 395 U. S. 396 .
[ Footnote 12 ] Similarly, in CBS, Inc. v. FCC, supra, the Page 468 U. S. 379 Court upheld the right of access for federal candidates imposed
by § 312(a)(7) of the Communications Act both because that
provision
"makes a significant contribution to freedom of expression by
enhancing the ability of candidates to present, and the public to
receive, information necessary for the effective operation of the
democratic process," id. at 453 U. S. 396 ,
and because it defined a sufficiently " limited right of reasonable' access" so that "the discretion of broadcasters to
present their views on any issue or to carry any particular type of
programming" was not impaired. Id. at 453 U. S.
396 -397 (emphasis in original). Finally, in Columbia
Broadcasting System, Inc. v. Democratic National Committee,
supra, the Court affirmed the FCC's refusal to require
broadcast licensees to accept all paid political advertisements.
Although it was argued that such a requirement would serve the
public's First Amendment interest in receiving additional views on
public issues, the Court rejected this approach, finding that such
a requirement would tend to transform broadcasters into common
carriers, and would intrude unnecessarily upon the editorial
discretion of broadcasters. Id. at 412 U. S.
123 -125. The FCC's ruling, therefore, helped to advance
the important purposes of the Communications Act, grounded in the
First Amendment, of preserving the right of broadcasters to
exercise "the widest journalistic freedom consistent with [their]
public obligations," and of guarding against "the risk of an
enlargement Page 468 U. S. 380 of Government control over the content of broadcast discussion
of public issues." Id. at 412 U. S. 110 , 412 U. S. 126 .
[ Footnote 13 ]
Thus, although the broadcasting industry plainly operates under
restraints not imposed upon other media, the thrust of these
restrictions has generally been to secure the public's First
Amendment interest in receiving a balanced presentation of views on
diverse matters of public concern. As a result of these
restrictions, of course, the absolute freedom to advocate one's own
positions without also presenting opposing viewpoints -- a freedom
enjoyed, for example, by newspaper publishers and soapbox orators
-- is denied to broadcasters. But, as our cases attest, these
restrictions have been upheld only when we were satisfied that the
restriction is narrowly tailored to further a substantial
governmental interest, such as ensuring adequate and balanced
coverage of public issues, e.g., Red Lion, 395 U.S. at 395 U. S. 377 . See also CBS, Inc. v. FCC, supra, at 453 U. S.
396 -397; Columbia Broadcasting System, Inc. v.
Democratic National Committee, 412 U.S. at 412 U. S.
110 -111; Red Lion, supra, at 395 U. S. 396 .
Making that Page 468 U. S. 381 judgment requires a critical examination of the interests of the
public and broadcasters in light of the particular circumstances of
each case. E.g., FCC v. Pacifica Foundation, 438 U.
S. 726 (1978). III We turn now to consider whether the restraint imposed by § 399
satisfies the requirements established by our prior cases for
permissible broadcast regulation. Before assessing the Government's
proffered justifications for the statute, however, two central
features of the ban against editorializing must be examined, since
they help to illuminate the importance of the First Amendment
interests at stake in this case. A First, the restriction imposed by § 399 is specifically directed
at a form of speech -- namely, the expression of editorial opinion
-- that lies at the heart of First Amendment protection. In
construing the reach of the statute, the FCC has explained
that,
"although the use of noncommercial educational broadcast
facilities by licensees, their management or those speaking on
their behalf for the propagation of the licensee's own views on
public issues is therefore not to be permitted, such prohibition
should not be construed to inhibit any other presentations
on controversial issues of public importance." Accuracy in Media, Inc., 45 F.C.C.2d 297, 302 (1973)
(emphasis added). The Commission's interpretation of § 399 simply
highlights the fact that what the statute forecloses is the
expression of editorial opinion on "controversial issues of public
importance." As we recently reiterated in NAACP v. Claiborne
Hardware Co., 458 U. S. 886 (1982), "expression on public issues has always rested on the
highest rung of the hierarchy of First Amendment values.'" Id. at 458 U. S. 913 (quoting Carey v. Brown, 447 U. S. 455 , 447 U. S. 467 (1980)). And we have emphasized: "The freedom of speech and of the press guaranteed by the
Constitution embraces at the least the liberty to Page 468 U. S. 382 discuss publicly and truthfully all matters of public concern
without previous restraint or fear of subsequent punishment. . . .
Freedom of discussion, if it would fulfill its historic function in
this nation, must embrace all issues about which information is
needed or appropriate to enable the members of society to cope with
the exigencies of their period." Thornhill v. Alabama, 310 U.S. at 310 U. S.
101 -102.
The editorial has traditionally played precisely this role by
informing and arousing the public, and by criticizing and cajoling
those who hold government office in order to help launch new
solutions to the problems of the time. Preserving the free
expression of editorial opinion, therefore, is part and parcel of
"a profound national commitment . . . that debate on public issues
should be uninhibited, robust, and wide-open." New York Times
Co. v. Sullivan, 376 U. S. 254 , 376 U. S. 270 (1964). As we recognized in Mills v. Alabama, 384 U.
S. 214 (1966), the special place of the editorial in our
First Amendment jurisprudence simply reflects the fact that the
press, of which the broadcasting industry is indisputably a part, United States v. Paramount Pictures, Inc., 334 U.
S. 131 , 334 U. S. 166 (1948), carries out a historic, dual responsibility in our society
of reporting information and of bringing critical judgment to bear
on public affairs. Indeed, the pivotal importance of editorializing
as a means of satisfying the public's interest in receiving a wide
variety of ideas and views through the medium of broadcasting has
long been recognized by the FCC; the Commission has, for the past
35 years, actively encouraged commercial broadcast licensees to
include editorials on public affairs in their programming.
[ Footnote 14 ] Page 468 U. S. 383 Because § 399 appears to restrict precisely that form of speech
which the Framers of the Bill of Rights were most anxious to
protect -- speech that is "indispensable to the discovery and
spread of political truth" -- we must be especially careful in
weighing the interests that are asserted in support of this
restriction and in assessing the precision with which the ban is
crafted. Whitney v. California, 274 U.
S. 357 , 274 U. S. 375 (1927) (Brandeis, J., concurring).
Second, the scope of § 399's ban is defined solely on the basis
of the content of the suppressed speech. A wide variety of
noneditorial speech "by licensees, their management or those
speaking on their behalf," Accuracy in Media, Inc., 45
F.C.C.2d at 302, is plainly not prohibited by § 399. Examples of
such permissible forms of speech include daily announcements of the
station's program schedule or over-the-air appeals for
contributions from listeners. Consequently, in order to determine
whether a particular statement by station management constitutes an
"editorial" proscribed by § 399, enforcement authorities must
necessarily examine the content of the message that is conveyed to
determine whether the views expressed concern "controversial issues
of public importance." Ibid. AS JUSTICE STEVENS observed in Consolidated Edison Co. v.
Public Service Comm'n of N.Y., 447 U.
S. 530 (1980), however:
"A regulation of speech that is motivated by nothing Page 468 U. S. 384 more than a desire to curtail expression of a particular point
of view on controversial issues of general interest is the purest
example of a 'law . . . abridging the freedom of speech, or of the
press.' A regulation that denies one group of persons the right to
address a selected audience on 'controversial issues of public
policy' is plainly such a regulation." Id. at 447 U. S. 546 (opinion concurring in judgment); accord, id. at 447 U. S.
537 -540 (majority opinion). Section 399 is just such a
regulation, for it singles out noncommercial broadcasters and
denies them the right to address their chosen audience on matters
of public importance. Thus, in enacting § 399, Congress appears to
have sought, in much the same way that the New York Public Service
Commission had attempted through the regulation of utility company
bill inserts struck down in Consolidated Edison, to limit
discussion of controversial topics, and thus to shape the agenda
for public debate. Since, as we observed in Consolidated
Edison, "[t]he First Amendment's hostility to content-based regulation
extends not only to restrictions on particular viewpoints, but also
to prohibition of public discussion of an entire topic," id. at 447 U. S. 537 ,
we must be particularly wary in assessing § 399 to determine
whether it reflects an impermissible attempt "to allow a government
[to] control . . . the search for political truth." Id. at 447 U. S. 538 .
[ Footnote 15 ] B In seeking to defend the prohibition on editorializing imposed
by § 399, the Government urges that the statute was aimed at
preventing two principal threats to the overall success of the
Public Broadcasting Act of 1967. According to this argument, the
ban was necessary, first, to protect noncommercial educational
broadcasting stations from being coerced, as a result of federal
financing, into becoming vehicles Page 468 U. S. 385 for Government propagandizing or the objects of governmental
influence; and, second, to keep these stations from becoming
convenient targets for capture by private interest groups wishing
to express their own partisan viewpoints. [ Footnote 16 ] By seeking to safeguard the
public's right to a balanced presentation of public issues through
the prevention of either governmental or private bias, these
objectives are, of course, broadly consistent with the goals
identified in our earlier broadcast regulation cases. But, in sharp
contrast to the restrictions upheld in Red Lion or in CBS, Inc.
v. FCC, which left room for editorial discretion and simply
required broadcast editors to grant others access to the
microphone, § 399 directly prohibits the broadcaster from speaking
out on public issues even in a balanced and fair manner. The
Government insists, however, that the hazards posed in the
"special" circumstances of noncommercial Page 468 U. S. 386 educational broadcasting are so great that § 399 is an
indispensable means of preserving the public's First Amendment
interests. We disagree. (1) When Congress first decided to provide financial support for the
expansion and development of noncommercial educational stations,
all concerned agreed that this step posed some risk that these
traditionally independent stations might be pressured into becoming
forums devoted solely to programming and views that were acceptable
to the Federal Government. That Congress was alert to these dangers
cannot be doubted. It sought through the Public Broadcasting Act to
fashion a system that would provide local stations with sufficient
funds to foster their growth and development while preserving their
tradition of autonomy and community-orientation. [ Footnote 17 ] A cardinal objective of the
Act was the establishment Page 468 U. S. 387 of a private corporation that would
"facilitate the development of educational radio and television
broadcasting and . . . afford maximum protection to such
broadcasting from extraneous interference and control."
47 U.S.C. § 396(a)(6) (1976 ed.).
The intended role of § 399 in achieving these purposes, however,
is not as clear. The provision finds no antecedent in the Carnegie
report, which generally provided the model for most other aspects
of the Act. It was not part of the administration's original
legislative proposal. And it was not included in the original
version of the Act passed by the Senate. The provision found its
way into the Act only as a result of an amendment in the House.
Indeed, it appears that, as the House Committee Report frankly
admits, § 399 was added not because Congress thought it was
essential to preserving the autonomy and vitality of local
stations, but rather "[o]ut of an abundance of caution." H.R.Rep.
No. 572, 90th Cong., 1st Sess., 20 (1967). [ Footnote 18 ] Page 468 U. S. 388 More importantly, an examination of both the overall legislative
scheme established by the 1967 Act and the character of public
broadcasting demonstrates that the interest asserted by the
Government is not substantially advanced by § 399. First, to the
extent that federal financial support creates a risk that stations
will lose their independence through the bewitching power of
governmental largesse, the elaborate structure established by the
Public Broadcasting Act Page 468 U. S. 389 already operates to insulate local stations from governmental
interference. Congress not only mandated that the new Corporation
for Public Broadcasting would have a private, bipartisan structure, see §§ 396(c)-(f), but also imposed a variety of important
limitations on its powers. The Corporation was prohibited from
owning or operating any station, § 396(g)(3), it was required to
adhere strictly to a standard of "objectivity and balance" in
disbursing federal funds to local stations, § 396(g)(1)(A), and it
was prohibited from contributing to or otherwise supporting any
candidate for office, § 396(f)(3).
The Act also established a second layer of protections which
serve to protect the stations from governmental coercion and
interference. Thus, in addition to requiring the Corporation to
operate so as to "assure the maximum freedom [of local stations]
from interference with or control of program content or other
activities," § 396(g)(1)(D), the Act expressly forbids
"any department, agency, officer, or employee of the United
States to exercise any direction, supervision, or control over
educational television or radio broadcasting, or over the
Corporation or any of its grantees or contractors. . . ,"
§ 398(a) (1976 ed.). Subsequent amendments to the Act have
confirmed Congress' commitment to the principle that, because local
stations are the "bedrock of the system," their independence from
governmental interference and control must be fully guaranteed.
These amendments have provided long-term appropriations authority
for public broadcasting, rather than allowing funding to depend
upon yearly appropriations, see § 396(k)(1)(C), as
amended, Pub.L. 97-35, Title XII, § 1227, 95 Stat. 727; have
strictly defined the percentage of appropriated funds that must be
disbursed by the Corporation to local stations, § 396(k)(3)
(A)-(B); and have defined objective criteria under which local
television and radio stations receive basic grants from the
Corporation to be used at the discretion of the station. §§
396(k)(6)(A)-(B), 396(k)(7). The principal thrust of the
amendments, therefore, has been to assure long-term Page 468 U. S. 390 appropriations for the Corporation and, more importantly, to
insist that it pass specified portions of these funds directly
through to local stations to give them greater autonomy in defining
the uses to which those funds should be put. Thus, in sharp
contrast to § 399, the unifying theme of these various statutory
provisions is that they substantially reduce the risk of
governmental interference with the editorial judgments of local
stations without restricting those stations' ability to speak on
matters of public concern. [ Footnote 19 ]
Even if these statutory protections were thought insufficient to
the task, however, suppressing the particular category of speech
restricted by § 399 is simply not likely, given the character of
the public broadcasting system, to reduce substantially the risk
that the Federal Government will seek to influence or put pressure
on local stations. An underlying supposition of the Government's
argument in this regard is that individual noncommercial stations
are likely to speak so forcefully on particular issues that
Congress, the ultimate source of the stations' federal funding,
will be tempted to retaliate against these individual stations by
restricting appropriations for all of public broadcasting. But, as
the District Court recognized, the character of public
broadcasting Page 468 U. S. 391 suggests that such a risk is speculative, at best. There are
literally hundreds of public radio and television stations in
communities scattered throughout the United States and its
territories, see CPB, 1983-84 Public Broadcasting
Directory 20-50, 66-86 (Sept.1983). Given that central fact, it
seems reasonable to infer that the editorial voices of these
stations will prove to be as distinctive, varied, and idiosyncratic
as the various communities they represent. More importantly, the
editorial focus of any particular station can fairly be expected to
focus largely on issues affecting only its community. [ Footnote 20 ] Accordingly, absent
some showing by the Government to the contrary, the risk that local
editorializing will place all of public broadcasting in jeopardy is
not sufficiently pressing to warrant § 399's broad suppression of
speech.
Indeed, what is far more likely than local station editorials to
pose the kinds of dangers hypothesized by the Government are the
wide variety of programs addressing controversial issues produced,
often with substantial CPB funding, for national distribution to
local stations. Such programs truly have the potential to reach a
large audience and, because of the critical commentary they
contain, to have the kind of genuine national impact that might
trigger a congressional response or kindle governmental resentment.
The ban imposed by § 399, however, is plainly not directed at the
potentially controversial content of such programs; it is, instead,
leveled solely at the expression of editorial opinion by local
station management, a form of expression that is far more likely to
be aimed at a smaller local audience, to have less Page 468 U. S. 392 national impact, and to be confined to local issues. In
contrast, the Act imposes no substantive restrictions, other than
normal requirements of balance and fairness, on those who produce
nationally distributed programs. Indeed, the Act is designed in
part to encourage and sponsor the production of such programs, and
to allow each station to decide for itself whether to accept such
programs for local broadcast. [ Footnote 21 ]
Furthermore, the manifest imprecision of the ban imposed by §
399 reveals that its proscription is not sufficiently tailored to
the harms it seeks to prevent to justify its substantial
interference with broadcasters' speech. Section Page 468 U. S. 393 399 includes within its grip a potentially infinite variety of
speech, most of which would not be related in any way to
governmental affairs, political candidacies, or elections. Indeed,
the breadth of editorial commentary is as wide as human imagination
permits. But the Government never explains how, say, an editorial
by local station management urging improvements in a town's parks
or museums will so infuriate Congress or other federal officials
that the future of public broadcasting will be imperiled unless
such editorials are suppressed. Nor is it explained how the
suppression of editorials alone serves to reduce the risk of
governmental retaliation and interference when it is clear that
station management is fully able to broadcast controversial views
so long as such views are not labeled as its own. See
infra, at 468 U. S. 396 ,
and n. 25.
The Government appears to recognize these flaws in § 399,
because it focuses instead on the suggestion that the source of
governmental influence may well be state and local governments,
many of which have established public broadcasting commissions that
own and operate local noncommercial educational stations. [ Footnote 22 ] The ban on
editorializing is all the more necessary with respect to these
stations, the argument runs, because the management of such
stations will be especially likely to broadcast only editorials
that are favorable to the state or local authorities that hold the
purse strings. The Government's argument, however, proves too much.
First, § 399's ban applies to the many private noncommercial
community organizations that own and operate stations that Page 468 U. S. 394 are not controlled in any way by state or local government.
Second, the legislative history of the Public Broadcasting Act
clearly indicates that Congress was concerned with "assur[ing]
complete freedom from any Federal Government influence. "
The Public Television Act of 1967: Hearings on S. 1160 before the
Subcommittee on Communications of the Senate Committee on Commerce,
90th Cong., 1st Sess., 9 (1967) (remarks of Sen. Pastore) (emphasis
added). [ Footnote 23 ]
Consistently with this concern, Congress refused to create any
federally owned stations, and it expressly forbade the CPB to own
or operate any television or radio stations, § 396(g)(3). By
contrast, although Congress was clearly aware in 1967 that many
noncommercial educational stations were owned by state and local
governments, it did not hesitate to extend federal assistance to
such stations, it imposed no special requirements to restrict state
or local control over these stations, and, indeed, it ensured
through the structure of the Act that these stations would be as
insulated from federal interference as the wholly private stations.
[ Footnote 24 ] Page 468 U. S. 395 Finally, although the Government certainly has a substantial
interest in ensuring that the audiences of noncommercial stations
will not be led to think that the broadcaster's editorials reflect
the official view of the Government, this interest can be fully
satisfied by less restrictive means that are readily available. To
address this important concern, Congress could simply require
public broadcasting stations to broadcast a disclaimer every time
they editorialize which would state that the editorial represents
only the view of the station's management, and does not in any way
represent the views of the Federal Government or any of the
station's other sources of funding. Such a disclaimer -- similar to
those often used in commercial and noncommercial programming of a
controversial nature -- would effectively and directly communicate
to the audience that the editorial reflected only the views of the
station, rather than those of the Government. Furthermore, such
disclaimers would have the virtue of clarifying the responses that
might be made under the fairness doctrine by opponents of the
station's position, since those opponents would know with certainty
that they were responding only to the station's views, and not in
any sense to the Government's position.
In sum, § 399's broad ban on all editorializing by every station
that receives CPB funds far exceeds what is necessary to protect
against the risk of governmental interference or to prevent the
public from assuming that editorials by public broadcasting
stations represent the official view of government. The regulation
impermissibly sweeps within its prohibition a wide range of speech
by wholly private stations on topics that do not take a directly
partisan stand or that have nothing whatever to do with federal,
state, or local government. Page 468 U. S. 396 (2) Assuming that the Government's second asserted interest in
preventing noncommercial stations from becoming a "privileged
outlet for the political and ideological opinions of station owners
and managers," Brief for Appellant 34, is legitimate, the
substantiality of this asserted interest is dubious. The patent
overinclusiveness and underinclusiveness of § 399's ban "undermines
the likelihood of a genuine [governmental] interest" in preventing
private groups from propagating their own views via public
broadcasting. First National Bank of Boston v. Bellotti, 435 U.S. at 435 U. S. 793 .
If it is true, as the Government contends, that noncommercial
stations remain free, despite § 399, to broadcast a wide variety of
controversial views through their power to control program
selection, to select which persons will be interviewed, and to
determine how news reports will be presented, Brief for Appellant
41, then it seems doubtful that § 399 can fairly be said to advance
any genuinely substantial governmental interest in keeping
controversial or partisan opinions from being aired by
noncommercial stations. Indeed, since the very same opinions that
cannot be expressed by the station's management may be aired so
long as they are communicated by a commentator or by a guest
appearing at the invitation of the station during an interview, ibid.; see also Accuracy in Media, 45 F.C.C.2d at 302, §
399 clearly "provides only ineffective or remote support for the
government's purpose." Central Hudson Gas & Electric Corp.
v. Public Service Comm'n of N.Y., 447 U.
S. 557 , 447 U. S. 564 (1980). Cf. Buckley v. Valeo, 424 U.S. at 424 U. S. 45 ; First National Bank of Boston v. Bellotti, supra, at 435 U. S. 793 .
[ Footnote 25 ] Page 468 U. S. 397 In short, § 399 does not prevent the use of noncommercial
stations for the presentation of partisan views on controversial
matters; instead, it merely bars a station from specifically
communicating such views on its own behalf or on behalf of its
management. If the vigorous expression of controversial opinions
is, as the Government assures us, affirmatively encouraged by the
Act, and if local licensees are permitted under the Act to exercise
editorial control over the selection of programs, controversial or
otherwise, that are aired on their stations, then § 399
accomplishes only one thing -- the suppression of editorial speech
by station management. It does virtually nothing, however, to
reduce the risk that public stations will serve solely as outlets
for expression of narrow partisan views. What we said in Columbia Broadcasting System, Inc. v. Democratic National
Committee applies, therefore, with equal force here: the
"sacrifice [of] First Amendment protections for so speculative a
gain is not warranted. . . ." 412 U.S. at 412 U. S.
127 .
Finally, the public's interest in preventing public broadcasting
stations from becoming forums for lopsided presentations of narrow
partisan positions is already secured by Page 468 U. S. 398 a variety of other regulatory means that intrude far less
drastically upon the "journalistic freedom" of noncommercial
broadcasters. Columbia Broadcasting System, Inc. v. Democratic
National Committee, 412 U.S. at 412 U. S. 110 .
The requirements of the FCC's fairness doctrine, for instance,
which apply to commercial and noncommercial stations alike, ensure
that such editorializing would maintain a reasonably balanced and
fair presentation of controversial issues. Thus, even if the
management of a noncommercial educational station were inclined to
seek to further only its own partisan views when editorializing, it
simply could not do so. Indeed, in considering the
constitutionality of the FCC's fairness doctrine, the Court in Red Lion considered precisely the same justification
invoked by the Government today in support of § 399: that without
some requirement of fairness and balance,
"station owners . . . would have unfettered power . . . to
communicate only their own views on public issues . . . and to
permit on the air only those with whom they agreed."
395 U.S. at 395 U. S. 392 .
The solution to this problem offered by § 399, however, is
precisely the opposite of the remedy prescribed by the FCC and
endorsed by the Court in Red Lion. Rather than requiring
noncommercial broadcasters who express editorial opinions on
controversial subjects to permit more speech on such
subjects to ensure that the public's First Amendment interest in
receiving a balanced account of the issue is met, § 399 simply
silences all editorial speech by such broadcasters. Since the
breadth of § 399 extends so far beyond what is necessary to
accomplish the goals identified by the Government, it fails to
satisfy the First Amendment standards that we have applied in this
area.
We therefore hold that, even if some of the hazards at which §
399 was aimed are sufficiently substantial, the restriction is not
crafted with sufficient precision to remedy those dangers that may
exist to justify the significant abridgment of speech worked by the
provision's broad ban on editorializing. The Page 468 U. S. 399 statute is not narrowly tailored to address any of the
Government's suggested goals. Moreover, the public's "paramount
right" to be fully and broadly informed on matters of public
importance through the medium of noncommercial educational
broadcasting is not well served by the restriction, for its effect
is plainly to diminish, rather than augment, "the volume and
quality of coverage" of controversial issues. Red Lion, 395 U.S. at 395 U. S. 393 .
Nor do we see any reason to deny noncommercial broadcasters the
right to address matters of public concern on the basis of merely
speculative fears of adverse public or governmental reactions to
such speech. IV Although the Government did not present the argument in any form
to the District Court, [ Footnote
26 ] it now seeks belatedly to justify § 399 on the basis of
Congress' spending power. Relying upon our recent decision in Regan v. Taxation With Representation of Washington, 461 U. S. 540 (1983), the Government argues that, by prohibiting noncommercial
educational stations that receive CPB grants from editorializing,
Congress has, in the proper exercise of its spending power, simply
determined that it "will not subsidize public broadcasting station
editorials." Brief for Appellant 42. In Taxation With
Representation, the Court found that Congress could, in the
exercise of its spending power, reasonably refuse to subsidize the
lobbying activities of tax-exempt charitable organizations by
prohibiting such organizations from using tax-deductible
contributions to support their lobbying efforts. In so holding,
however, we explained that such organizations remained free "to
receive [tax-]deductible Page 468 U. S. 400 contributions to support nonlobbying activit[ies]." 461 U.S. at 461 U. S. 545 .
Thus, a charitable organization could create, under § 501(C)(3) of
the Internal Revenue Code, 26 U.S.C. § 501(C)(3), an affiliate to
conduct its nonlobbying activities using tax-deductible
contributions, and, at the same time, establish, under § 501(C)(4),
a separate affiliate to pursue its lobbying efforts without such
contributions. 461 U.S. at 461 U. S. 544 ; see also id. at 461 U. S.
552 -553 (BLACKMUN, J., concurring). Given that statutory
alternative, the Court concluded that
"Congress has not infringed any First Amendment rights or
regulated any First Amendment activity; [it] has simply chosen not
to pay or TWR's lobbying." Id. at 461 U. S.
546 .
In this case, however, unlike the situation faced by the
charitable organization in Taxation With Representation, a
noncommercial educational station that receives only 1% of its
overall income from CPB grants is barred absolutely from all
editorializing. Therefore, in contrast to the appellee in Taxation With Representation, such a station is not able
to segregate its activities according to the source of its funding.
The station has no way of limiting the use of its federal funds to
all noneditorializing activities, and, more importantly, it is
barred from using even wholly private funds to finance its
editorial activity.
Of course, if Congress were to adopt a revised version of § 399
that permitted noncommercial educational broadcasting stations to
establish "affiliate" organizations which could then use the
station's facilities to editorialize with nonfederal funds, such a
statutory mechanism would plainly be valid under the reasoning of Taxation With Representation. Under such a statute, public
broadcasting stations would be free, in the same way that the
charitable organization in Taxation With Representation was free, to make known its views on matters of public importance
through its nonfederally funded, editorializing affiliate without
losing federal grants for its noneditorializing broadcast
activities. Cf. id. Page 468 U. S. 401 at 461 U. S. 544 .
But in the absence of such authority, we must reject the
Government's contention that our decision in Taxation With
Representation is controlling here. [ Footnote 27 ] Page 468 U. S. 402 V In conclusion, we emphasize that our disposition of this case
rests upon a narrow proposition. We do not hold that the Congress
or the FCC is without power to regulate the content, timing, or
character of speech by noncommercial educational broadcasting
stations. Rather, we hold only that the specific interests sought
to be advanced by § 399's ban on editorializing are either not
sufficiently substantial or are not served in a sufficiently
limited manner to justify the substantial abridgment of important
journalistic freedoms which the First Amendment jealously protects.
Accordingly, the judgment of the District Court is Affirmed. [ Footnote 1 ] See S. Frost, Education's Own Stations 464 (1937).
[ Footnote 2 ]
For a review of the history of public broadcasting, see Carnegie Commission on Educational Television, Public Television: A
Program for Action 21-29 (1967) ( Carnegie I ); Carnegie
Commission on the Future of Public Broadcasting, A Public Trust
33-34 (1979) ( Carnegie II ). See also S.Rep. No.
93-123, pp. 2-6 (1973).
[ Footnote 3 ]
Although its recommendations were later applied by Congress to
noncommercial educational radio as well, the Commission's report
addressed solely the problems and prospects of what it called
"public television." This term was coined by the authors of the
report not to distinguish noncommercial, educational broadcasting
from "private" commercial broadcasting, but rather to identify a
larger view of the potential of noncommercial broadcasting
comprising not only "instructional" programming but also
educational, political, and cultural programming broadly defined. See Carnegie I at 1.
[ Footnote 4 ]
The structure of the Board was modified in 1981 to provide for
10, rather than 15 members. 47 U.S.C. § 396(c), as amended by
Pub.L. 97-35, Title XII, § 1225(a)(1), 95 Stat. 726.
[ Footnote 5 ]
In accordance with the Act, an interconnection system was
formally developed in 1969 when the Public Broadcasting Service
(PBS) was created. Today, PBS is a private, nonprofit membership
corporation governed by a Board of Directors elected by its
membership, which consists of the licensees of noncommercial,
educational television stations located throughout the United
States. See Brief for PBS et al. as Amici
Curiae 1. National Public Radio (NPR) was established in 1970,
and performs an analogous service for public radio stations.
[ Footnote 6 ]
In addition to Pacifica Foundation, appellees include the League
of Women Voters of California, and Congressman Henry Waxman, who is
a regular listener and viewer of public broadcasting.
[ Footnote 7 ]
As first enacted in 1967, § 399 provided:
"No noncommercial educational broadcasting station may engage in
editorializing or may support or oppose any candidate for political
office."
Pub.L. 90-129, Title II, § 201(8), 81 Stat. 368.
Although the statutory language remained the same, this
provision was redesignated as § 399(a) in 1973, when subsection
(b), requiring public stations to "retain an audio recording of
each of its broadcasts of any program in which any issue of public
importance is discussed," was added. Pub.L. 93-84, § 2, 87 Stat.
219. Because appellees filed their complaint in 1979, their suit
was initially directed at § 399(a). Subsection (b) was found
unconstitutional by the Court of Appeals for the District of
Columbia Circuit, Community Service Broadcasting of
Mid-America, Inc. v. FCC, 192 U.S.App.D.C. 448, 593 F.2d 1102
(1978), and was deleted by Congress in 1981. Pub.L. 97-35, Title
XII, § 1229, 95 Stat. 730.
Also as part of those 1981 amendments, Congress revised and
redesignated former § 399(a) by confining the ban on editorializing
to stations receiving CPB grants and by separately prohibiting
political endorsements by all stations; § 399 in its current form
provides in full:
"No noncommercial educational broadcasting station which
receives a grant from the Corporation under subpart C of this part
may engage in editorializing. No noncommercial educational
broadcasting station may support or oppose any candidate for public
office."
47 U.S.C. § 399.
[ Footnote 8 ]
As then Attorney General Civiletti explained:
"After careful consideration, we have concluded that Section
[399] violates the First Amendment guarantees of freedom of speech
and freedom of the press by restricting the ability of public
broadcasting stations to comment on matters of public interest. . .
."
"The Department of Justice is, of course, fully mindful of its
duty to support the laws enacted by Congress. Here, however, the
Department has determined, after careful study and deliberation,
that reasonable arguments cannot be advanced to defend the
challenged statute."
Letter from Attorney General Benjamin R. Civiletti to Senate
Majority Leader Robert C. Byrd (Oct. 11, 1979), App. 13-14.
[ Footnote 9 ]
In their amended complaint, appellees did not challenge the
provision in § 399 prohibiting all noncommercial educational
broadcasting stations from "support[ing] or oppos[ing] any
candidate for public office." Neither party suggests that the two
sentences of § 399 are so inseverable that we may not consider the
constitutionality of one without also reviewing the other. Indeed,
as the Federal Communications Commission explained before the
District Court,
"[n]ew section 399 does more than reinforce the severability of
the two provisions by setting them forth in separate
sentences,"
it also confines the ban on editorializing to stations that
receive CPB grants while extending a separate ban on political
endorsements to all public stations. Defendant's Supplemental
Memorandum on Amendment of Section 399, p. 4 (Sept. 15, 1981). We
therefore express no view of the constitutionality of the second
sentence in § 399. Cf. First National Bank of Boston v.
Bellotti, 435 U. S. 765 , 435 U. S. 788 ,
n. 26 (1978) (noting that "our consideration of a corporation's
right to speak on issues of general public interest implies no
comparable right in the quite different context of participation in
a political campaign for election to public office" -- a separate
restriction not challenged in that case).
[ Footnote 10 ]
Relying on our recent decision in Griggs v. Provident
Consumer Discount Co., 459 U. S. 56 (1982)
(per curiam), appellees contend that we lack jurisdiction because
the FCC filed its notice of appeal while a motion to amend the
District Court's judgment was still pending. Our decision in Griggs, however, rested squarely on the plain language of
new Federal Rule of Appellate Procedure 4(a)(4), which specifically
provides:
"A notice of appeal filed before the disposition of [a Rule
59(e) motion] shall have no effect. A new notice of appeal must be
filed within the prescribed time measured from the entry of the
order disposing of the motion. . . ." See 459 U.S. at 459 U. S. 61 .
Because this case comes to us directly from the District Court via
28 U.S.C. § 1252, the question whether the FCC's notice of appeal
was effective to vest this Court with appellate jurisdiction turns
not on Rule 4(a)(4), but rather on our own Rule 11.3. The express
language of Rule 4(a)(4) found dispositive in Griggs has
no direct equivalent in our Rule 11.3, which simply provides
that,
"if a petition for rehearing is timely filed by any party . . .
, the time for filing the notice of appeal . . . runs from the date
of the denial of rehearing or the entry of a subsequent
judgment."
By its terms, therefore, our Rule does not determine whether a
notice of appeal filed during the pendency of a motion to amend is
ineffective to vest appellate jurisdiction in this Court. We have
observed, however, that the filing of a petition for rehearing or a
motion to amend or alter the judgment "suspend[s] the finality of
the [original] judgment," thereby extending the time for filing a
notice of appeal "until [the lower court's] denial of the motion .
. . restores" that finality. Communist Party of Indiana v.
Whitcomb, 414 U. S. 441 , 414 U. S. 445 (1974). At the same time, we have emphasized that the rule
requiring suspension of a judgment's finality for purposes of
appeal during the pendency of a postjudgment motion for
reconsideration applies only when such a motion actually seeks an
"alteration of the rights adjudicated" in the court's first
judgment. Department of Banking of Nebraska v. Pink, 317 U. S. 264 , 317 U. S. 266 (1942) (per curiam); see also FTC v. Minneapolis-Honeywell
Regulator Co., 344 U. S. 206 , 211
(1952) ("mere fact that a judgment previously entered is reentered
or revised in an immaterial way does not toll the time within which
review must be sought").
The FCC has brought this appeal pursuant to § 1252, which
permits direct appeal to this Court from "an interlocutory or a
final judgment . . . holding an Act of Congress unconstitutional."
Section 1252 departs significantly from the general congressional
policy of minimizing the mandatory docket of this Court and
reflects instead Congress' "unambiguou[s] mandat[e]" that we afford
immediate direct review of all decisions that call into doubt the
constitutionality of Acts of Congress. McLucas v.
DeChamplain, 421 U. S. 21 , 421 U. S. 31 (1975). It is clear that the motion filed by the FCC following the
entry of the District Court's August 6 order was directed not at
the court's judgment holding § 399 unconstitutional, but rather at
the wholly collateral issue of whether appellees were entitled to
recover attorney's fees and costs. Prior to the court's decision,
the question of attorney's fees had never been briefed or discussed
by the parties; nevertheless, the court, acting sua
sponte, included in its August 6 order an award of"reasonable
attorneys' fees and costs" to appellees. Recognizing that the
court's order had been entered in the absence of any application
for fees and without benefit of briefing, the FCC sought, through
its postjudgment motion, to restore the status quo ante with respect to the question of fees in order to allow time for
full briefing. The District Court, in an order entered November 1,
did precisely that by striking the award of attorney's fees from
the August 6 order, and taking the question of fees under
advisement.
As we recognized in White v. New Hampshire Dept. of
Employment Security, 455 U. S. 445 (1982), an "award [of attorney's fees] is uniquely separable from
the cause of action" that is settled by a court's judgment on the
merits, and therefore a postjudgment request for attorney's fees is
not considered a motion to amend or alter the judgment under Rule
59(e) of the Federal Rules of Civil Procedure. Id. at 455 U. S. 452 .
Since, as appellees concede, the FCC's motion in this case related
solely to the "uniquely separable" question of attorney's fees and
was in no way directed at the District Court's judgment "holding an
Act of Congress unconstitutional," 28 U.S.C. § 1252, it is true
here, as it was in Department of Banking v. Pink, supra, that the District Court was not asked to "alter its adjudication of
the rights of the parties," and consequently the finality of the
judgment which the FCC seeks to have reviewed "was never
suspended." Id. at 317 U. S. 266 .
Accordingly, we think the time for filing the FCC's notice of
appeal was properly calculated from the date the District Court's
initial judgment was rendered, and its notice is therefore timely
within 28 U.S.C. § 2101(a). A different result would frustrate the
clear purpose of § 1252 to permit "prompt determination by the
court of last resort of disputed questions of the constitutionality
of acts of the Congress." H.R.Rep. No. 212, 75th Cong., 1st Sess.,
2 (1937), since an appeal from a judgment "holding an Act of
Congress unconstitutional" would be delayed by collateral issues
having no bearing whatever on the judgment from which the appeal is
taken.
[ Footnote 11 ] See FCC v. National Citizens Committee for
Broadcasting, 436 U. S. 775 , 436 U. S.
799 -800 (1978); Columbia Broadcasting System, Inc.
v. Democratic National Committee, 412 U. S.
94 , 412 U. S.
101 -102 (1973); Red Lion Broadcasting Co. v.
FCC, 395 U. S. 367 , 395 U. S.
387 -390 (1969); National Broadcasting Co. v. United
States, 319 U. S. 190 , 319 U. S. 216 (1943); Federal Radio Comm'n v. Nelson Bros. Bond &
Mortgage Co., 289 U. S. 266 , 289 U. S. 282 (1933).
The prevailing rationale for broadcast regulation based on
spectrum scarcity has come under increasing criticism in recent
years. Critics, including the incumbent Chairman of the FCC, charge
that, with the advent of cable and satellite television technology,
communities now have access to such a wide variety of stations that
the scarcity doctrine is obsolete. See, e.g., Fowler &
Brenner, A Marketplace Approach to Broadcast Regulation, 60 Texas
L.Rev. 207, 221-226 (1982). We are not prepared, however, to
reconsider out longstanding approach without some signal from
Congress or the FCC that technological developments have advanced
so far that some revision of the system of broadcast regulation may
be required.
[ Footnote 12 ]
We note that the FCC, observing that
"[i]f any substantial possibility exists that the [fairness
doctrine] rules have impeded, rather than furthered, First
Amendment objectives, repeal may be warranted on that ground
alone,"
has tentatively concluded that the rules, by effectively
chilling speech, do not serve the public interest, and has
therefore proposed to repeal them. Notice of Proposed Rulemaking In
re Repeal or Modification of the Personal Attack and Political
Editorial Rules, 48 Fed.Reg. 28298, 28301 (1983). Of course, the
Commission may, in the exercise of its discretion, decide to modify
or abandon these rules, and we express no view on the legality of
either course. As we recognized in Red Lion, however, were
it to be shown by the Commission that the fairness doctrine "[has]
the net effect of reducing, rather than enhancing," speech, we
would then be forced to reconsider the constitutional basis of our
decision in that case. 395 U.S. at 395 U. S.
393 .
[ Footnote 13 ]
This Court's decision in FCC v. Pacifica Foundation, 438 U. S. 726 (1978), upholding an exercise of the Commission's authority to
regulate broadcasts containing "indecent" language as applied to a
particular afternoon broadcast of a George Carlin monologue, is
consistent with the approach taken in our other broadcast cases.
There, the Court focused on certain physical characteristics of
broadcasting -- specifically, that the medium's uniquely pervasive
presence renders impossible any prior warning for those listeners
who may be offended by indecent language, and, second, that the
ease with which children may gain access to the medium, especially
during daytime hours, creates a substantial risk that they may be
exposed to such offensive expression without parental supervision. Id. at 438 U. S.
748 -749. The governmental interest in reduction of those
risks through Commission regulation of the timing and character of
such "indecent broadcasting" was thought sufficiently substantial
to outweigh the broadcaster's First Amendment interest in
controlling the presentation of its programming. Id. at 438 U. S. 750 .
In this case, by contrast, we are faced not with indecent
expression, but rather with expression that is at the core of First
Amendment protections, and no claim is made by the Government that
the expression of editorial opinion by noncommercial stations will
create a substantial "nuisance" of the kind addressed in FCC v.
Pacifica Foundation. [ Footnote 14 ]
In 1949, finding that
"programs in which the licensee's personal opinions are
expressed are [not] intrinsically more or less subject to abuse
than any other program devoted to public issues,"
the FCC concluded that overt licensee editorializing, so long
as
"it is exercised in conformity with the paramount right of the
public to hear a reasonably balanced presentation of all
responsible viewpoints,"
is "consistent with the licensee's duty to operate in the public
interest." Editorializing by Broadcast Licensees, 13
F.C.C. 1246, 1253, 1258 (1949). At the time, of course, this
decision applied with equal force to both noncommercial educational
licensees and commercial stations. The FCC has since underscored
its view that editorializing by broadcast licensees serves the
public interest by identifying editorial programming as one of 14
"major elements usually necessary to meet the public interest,
needs and desires of the community." FCC Programming Statement, 25
Fed.Reg. 7295 (1960). The Commission has regularly enforced this
policy by considering a licensee's editorializing practices in
license renewal proceedings. See, e.g., Greater Boston
Television Corp. v. FCC, 143 U.S.App.D.C. 383, 402, 444 F.2d
841, 860 (1970); Evening Star Broadcasting Co., 27
F.C.C.2d 316, 332 (1971); RKO General, Inc., 44 F.C.C.2d
149, 219 (1969).
[ Footnote 15 ] See also Bolger v. Youngs Drug Products Corp., 463 U. S. 60 , 463 U. S. 65 (1983); Carey v. Brown, 447 U. S. 455 , 447 U. S.
462 -463 (1980); First National Bank of Boston v.
Bellotti, 435 U.S. at 435 U. S. 784 -785; Police Department of Chicago v.
Mosley, 408 U. S. 92 , 408 U. S. 95 -96
(1972).
[ Footnote 16 ]
The Government also contends that § 399 is intended to prevent
the use of taxpayer moneys to promote private views with which
taxpayers may disagree. This argument is readily answered by our
decision in Buckley v. Valeo, 424 U. S.
1 , 424 U. S. 90 -93
(1976) (per curiam). As we explained in that case, virtually every
congressional appropriation will, to some extent, involve a use of
public money as to which some taxpayers may object. Id. at 424 U. S. 91 -92.
Nevertheless, this does not mean that those taxpayers have a
constitutionally protected right to enjoin such expenditures. Nor
can this interest be invoked to justify a congressional decision to
suppress speech. And, unlike Wooley v. Maynard, 430 U. S. 705 (1977), this is not a case in which an individual taxpayer is
forced in his daily life to identify with particular views
expressed by educational broadcasting stations. Even if this were a
serious interest, it is belied by the underinclusiveness of § 399.
The Government concedes -- indeed it insists -- that all sorts of
controversial speech are subsidized by the 1967 Act, and yet, out
of all of this potentially objectionable speech, only the
expression of editorial opinion by local stations is selected for
suppression. If angry taxpayers were really the central, animating
concern of Congress when it passed the 1967 Act, then § 399 does
not go far enough in suppressing controversial speech in this
medium. That the provision is so unrelated to this asserted purpose
suggests that the Government's interest is not substantial. Cf.
Buckley v. Valeo, supra, at 424 U. S. 45 ; First National Bank of Boston v. Bellotti, supra, at 435 U. S.
793 .
[ Footnote 17 ]
The Senate Report concerning the Act, for example,
explained:
"There is general agreement that, for the time being, Federal
financial assistance is required to provide the resources necessary
for quality programs. It is also recognized that this assistance
should in no way involve the Government in programming or program
judgments. An independent entity supported by Federal funds is
required to provide programs free of political pressures. The
Corporation for Public Broadcasting, a nonprofit private
corporation, . . . provides such an entity."
S.Rep. No. 222, 90th Cong., 1st Sess., 4 (1967).
"Your committee has heard considerable discussion about the fear
of Government control or interference in programming if [the Act]
is enacted. We wish to state in the strongest terms possible that
it is our intention that local stations be absolutely free to
determine for themselves what they should or should not
broadcast." Id. at 11. See also The Public Television Act
of 1967: Hearings on S. 1160 before the Subcommittee on
Communications of the Senate Committee on Commerce, 90th Cong., 1st
Sess., 9 (1967) (remarks of Sen. Pastore).
The House Report echoed the same concerns:
"Every witness who discussed the operation of the Corporation
agreed that funds for programs should not be provided directly by
the Federal Government. It was generally agreed that a nonprofit
Corporation, directed by a Board of Directors, none of whom will be
Government employees, will provide the most effective insulation
from Government control or influence over the expenditure of
funds."
H.R.Rep. No. 572, 90th Cong., 1st Sess., 15 (1967).
"[L]ocal stations shall retain both the opportunity and
responsibility for broadcasting programs they feel best serve their
communities. Similarly, the local station alone will make the
decision whether or not to participate in any interconnection
arrangements. . . ." Id. at 18.
[ Footnote 18 ]
The legislative history surrounding § 399 also suggests that a
variety of reasons lay behind the decision to include it as part of
the Act. Although some supporters of § 399 plainly were concerned
that permitting editorializing might create a risk that
noncommercial stations would be subjected to undue governmental
influence, and thereby become vehicles for governmental propaganda, see 113 Cong.Rec. 26383 (1967) (remarks of Rep. Staggers),
other supporters of the provision appear to have been more
concerned with preventing the possibility that these stations would
criticize Government officials. Representative Springer, the
provision's chief sponsor and the ranking minority member of the
House Committee that reported out the bill containing § 399,
explained that his concerns were due at least in part to the fact
that "[t]here are some of us who have very strong feelings because
they have been editorialized against." Hearings on H.R. 6736 and S.
1160 before the House Committee on Interstate and Foreign Commerce,
90th Cong., 1st Sess., 641 (1967) (House Hearings). See
also 113 Cong.Rec. 26391 (1967) (remarks of Rep. Joelson).
Indeed, during hearings on the bill, the Committee heard a variety
of views on the question of editorializing by noncommercial
educational stations. Some witnesses felt that editorials of any
kind would be inappropriate, see, e.g., House Hearings at
513-514 (remarks of William Harley, President, National Association
of Educational Broadcasters), while others took a different view,
explaining that, although specific endorsements of political
candidates would be inappropriate, editorials concerning civic
affairs and other matters of public concern would be an important
part of responsible educational broadcasting, see, e.g.,
id. at 391-392 (remarks of McGeorge Bundy, President, Ford
Foundation); id. at 640-642 (remarks of Dr. Samuel Gould,
Joint Council on Educational Telecommunications). After the House
passed H.R. 6736, the Senate, disagreeing with the addition of §
399, requested a Conference and only receded from its
disagreement
"when it was explained that the prohibition . . . was limited to
providing that no noncommercial educational broadcast station may
broadcast editorials representing the opinion of the management of
such station . . . [and that] these provisions are not intended to
preclude balanced, fair, and objective presentations of
controversial issues. . . ."
H.R.Conf.Rep. No. 794, 90th Cong., 1st Sess., 12 (1967).
Of course, as the Government points out, Congress has
consistently retained the basic proscription on editorializing in §
399, despite periodic reconsiderations and modifications of the Act
in 1973, 1978, and 1981. Brief for Appellant 25-27; see
also n 7, supra. A reviewing court may not easily set aside such a considered
congressional judgment. At the same time,
"[d]eference to a legislative finding cannot limit judicial
inquiry when First Amendment rights are at stake. . . . Were it
otherwise, the scope of freedom of speech and of the press would be
subject to legislative definition and the function of the First
Amendment as a check on legislative power would be nullified." Landmark Communications, Inc. v. Virginia, 435 U.
S. 829 , 435 U. S.
843 -844 (1978).
[ Footnote 19 ]
Furthermore, the risk that federal coercion or influence will be
brought to bear against local stations as a result of federal
financing is considerably attenuated by the fact that CPB grants
account for only a portion of total public broadcasting income.
CPB, Public Broadcasting Income: Fiscal Year 1982, Table 2 (Final
Report, Dec.1983) (noting that federal funds account for 23.4% of
total income for all public broadcasting stations). The vast
majority of financial support comes instead from state and local
governments, as well as a wide variety of private sources,
including foundations, businesses, and individual contributions;
indeed, as the CPB recently noted, "[t]he diversity of support in
America for public broadcasting is remarkable," CPB, 1982 Annual
Report 2 (1982). Given this diversity of funding sources and the
decentralized manner in which funds are secured, the threat that
improper federal influence will be exerted over local stations is
not so pressing as to require the total suppression of editorial
speech by these stations.
[ Footnote 20 ]
This likelihood is enhanced with respect to public stations
because they are required to establish community advisory boards
which must reasonably reflect the "diverse needs and interests of
the communities served by such station[s]." § 396(k)(9)(A). For a
review of sample topics of broadcast editorializing, see Fang & Whelan, Survey of Television Editorials and Ombudsman
Segments, 17 J. Broadcasting 363 (1973); see also E.
Routt, Dimensions of Broadcast Editorializing (1974).
[ Footnote 21 ]
Congressional experience with the Act following its passage in
1967 has reaffirmed its commitment to preserving broad editorial
discretion for local stations in determining the content of their
schedules and programming. This experience also suggests that those
critical reactions to public broadcasting that have occurred have
focused not on the exercise of such editorial judgments by local
stations, but rather on controversial programming produced for
national distribution, which has included critical commentary on
public affairs. In 1972, claiming that the centralization of
program production was usurping the role of local stations,
then-President Nixon vetoed a bill establishing 2-year
appropriations authority for CPB funding. See Carnegie II,
at 41-43. In addition, the administration was critical of certain
of the best known nationally distributed public affairs programs,
such as "Bill Moyer's Journal" and "Washington Week in Review,"
which were regarded by some as too controversial. See Canby, The First Amendment and the State as Editor: Implications
for Public Broadcasting, 52 Texas L.Rev. 1123, 1156-1157 (1974).
These events prompted Congress to undertake its first thorough
review of the public broadcasting system since the enactment of the
Public Broadcasting Act. See S.Rep. No. 93-123, p. 12
(1973). The result of that review was a firm congressional
commitment to developing long-range financing for public
broadcasting to "provide adequate insulation against Government
interference," id. at 14, and to ensuring an
"increase [in] both the percentage and amount of unrestricted
support available to public television stations . . . [in order to
ensure] strong local programming made possible by a predictable
level of community service [ i.e., unrestricted]
grants."
H.R.Rep. No. 93-324, pp. 7, 9 (1973). These themes have been
carried forward in subsequent amendments to the Act, see Pub.L. 95-567, § 307, 92 Stat. 2415, and Pub.L. 97-35, § 1227, 95
Stat. 727.
[ Footnote 22 ]
As the Government points out in its brief, at least two-thirds
of the public television broadcasting stations in operation are
licensed to (a) state public broadcasting authorities or
commissions, in which commission members are often appointed by the
governor with the advice and consent of the state legislature, (b)
state universities or educational commissions, or (c) local school
boards or municipal authorities. Brief for Appellant 20, nn. 43,
44; see also CPB, 1983-84 CPB Public Broadcasting
Directory 5-8, 66-86 (Sept.1983).
[ Footnote 23 ] See also Hearings on S. 1160, at 93 (remarks of FCC
Chairman Hyde); Special Message to the Congress: "Education and
Health in America," 1 Public Papers of the Presidents, Lyndon B.
Johnson, Feb. 28, 1967, p. 250 (1967) ("Noncommercial television
and radio in America, even though supported by federal funds, must
be absolutely free from any federal government interference over
programming"); see also 113 Cong.Rec. 26384 (1967)
(remarks of Rep. Staggers); H.R.Rep. No. 572, 90th Cong., 1st
Sess., 18-19 (1967); S.Rep. No. 222, 90th Cong., 1st Sess., 7-8, 11
(1967).
[ Footnote 24 ]
We note in this regard that, in 1977, the administration,
observing that § 399's ban appeared to "mak[e] sense for stations
licensed to a State or local government instrumentalit[ies]" but
not for nongovernmental licensees, proposed that the statute be
amended to permit editorializing by all stations not licensed to
governmental entities. President's Message on Public Broadcasting
(Oct. 6, 1977), reprinted in H.R.Rep. No. 95-1178, p. 9 (1978). The
House, however, went further and passed H.R. 12605, which, among
other things, amended § 399 by deleting entirely the ban on
editorializing, while retaining the ban on political endorsements.
124 Cong.Rec.19937 (1978); see also H.R.Rep. No. 95-1178, supra, at 31. The Senate then passed an amended version of
H.R. 12605, which retained § 399 in its original form. 124
Cong.Rec. 30081 (1978). At conference, the House receded from its
disagreement, and § 399 was retained. H.R.Conf.Rep. No. 95-1774, p.
35 (1978). Whether a prohibition on editorializing restricted to
the licensees of state and local governmental entities would pass
constitutional muster is a question we need not decide.
[ Footnote 25 ]
When it determined in 1949 that broadcast editorializing served
the public interest, the FCC recognized precisely this fact:
"It is clear that the licensee's authority to determine the
specific programs to be broadcast over his station gives him an
opportunity . . . to insure that his personal viewpoint on any
particular issue is presented in his station's broadcasts, whether
or not these views are expressly identified with the licensee." Editorializing by Broadcast Licensees, 13 F.C.C. at
1252. The Commission nonetheless rejected the contention that overt
advocacy by licensees would be contrary to the public interest.
Instead, the FCC found that
"these fears are largely misdirected . . . ; they stem from a
confusion of the question of overt advocacy in the name of the
licensee, with the broader issue of insuring that the station's
broadcasts devoted to the consideration of public issues will
provide the listening public with a fair and balanced presentation
of differing viewpoints on such issues. . . . If it be true that
station good will and licensee prestige, where it exists, may give
added weight to opinion expressed by the licensee, it does not
follow that such opinion should be excluded from the air. . . . Assurance off-airness must, in the final analysis, be achieved
not by the exclusion of particular views because of the source of
the views, . . . but by making the microphone available, for
the presentation of contrary views. . . ." Id. at 1253-1254 (emphasis added).
[ Footnote 26 ] See Defendant's Memorandum of Points and Authorities in
Opposition to Plaintiff's Motion for Summary Judgment (July 22,
1981); Defendant's Supplemental Memorandum on Amendment of Section
399 (Sept. 15, 1981); Defendant's Memorandum in Support of Its
Motion to Dismiss the Second Amended Complaint (Oct. 13, 1981).
[ Footnote 27 ]
JUSTICE REHNQUIST's effort to prop up his position by relying on
our decisions upholding certain provisions of the Hatch Act, 5
U.S.C. § 7324 et seq., only reveals his misunderstanding
of what is at issue in this case. For example, in both United
Public Workers v. Mitchell, 330 U. S. 75 (1947), and CSC v. Letter Carriers, 413 U.
S. 548 (1973), the Court has upheld § 9(a) of the Hatch
Act -- a provision that differs from § 399 in three fundamental
respects: first, the statute only prohibits Government employees
from "active participation in political management and political
campaigns," and, accordingly, "[e]xpressions, public or private, on
public affairs, personalities and matters of public interest" are
not proscribed, id. at 413 U. S. 556 ;
second, the constitutionality of that restriction is grounded in
the Government's substantial and important interest in ensuring
effective job performance by its own employees, id. at 413 U. S.
564 -565; and, finally, these restrictions evolved over a
century of governmental experience with less restrictive
alternatives that proved to be inadequate to maintain the effective
operation of government, id. at 413 U. S.
557 -563. Here, by contrast, the editorializing ban in §
399 directly suppresses not only political endorsements, but all
editorial expression on matters of public importance; it applies to
independent, nongovernmental entities rather than to the
Government's own employees; and, it is not grounded in any prior
governmental experience with less restrictive means.
More importantly, in neither of those cases did the Court even
consider that the restrictions could be justified simply because
these employees were receiving Government funds, nor did it find
that a lesser degree of judicial scrutiny was required simply
because Government funds were involved.
JUSTICE REHNQUIST's reliance upon Oklahoma v. CSC, 330 U. S. 127 (1947), see post at 468 U. S.
405 -406, is also misplaced. There, a principal issue
addressed by the Court was Oklahoma's claim that § 12 of the Hatch
Act invaded the State's sovereignty in violation of the Tenth
Amendment, because it authorized the Civil Service Commission to
withhold federal funds from States whose officers violated the Act.
As the Court noted,
"[t]he coercive effect of the authorization to withhold sums
allocated to a state is relied upon as an interference with the
reserved powers of the state." Id. at 468 U. S. 142 .
After citing Mitchell, supra, for the proposition that the
Act did not impermissibly interfere with an employee's freedom of
expression in political matters, 330 U.S. at 330 U. S. 142 ,
the Court explained:
"While the United States is not concerned with, and has no power
to regulate, local political activities as such of state officials,
it does have power to fix the terms upon which its money allotments
to states shall be disbursed. The Tenth Amendment does not
forbid the exercise of this power in the way that Congress has
proceeded in this case. " Id. at 330 U. S. 143 (emphasis added). Thus, it was only in the context of rejecting
Oklahoma's Tenth Amendment claim that the Court used the language
cited by the dissent. Just as in Mitchell and Letter
Carriers, therefore, the Court never intimated in Oklahoma
v. CSC that the mere presence of Government funds was a
sufficient reason to uphold the Hatch Act's restrictions on
employee freedoms on the basis of relaxed First Amendment
standards.
JUSTICE WHITE: Believing that the editorializing and candidate
endorsement proscription stand or fall together, and being
confident that Congress may condition use of its funds on
abstaining from political endorsements, I join JUSTICE REHNQUIST's
dissenting opinion.
JUSTICE REHNQUIST, with whom THE CHIEF JUSTICE and JUSTICE WHITE
join, dissenting.
All but three paragraphs of the Court's lengthy opinion in this
case are devoted to the development of a scenario in which the
Government appears as the "Big Bad Wolf," and appellee Pacifica as
"Little Red Riding Hood." In the Court's scenario the Big Bad Wolf
cruelly forbids Little Red Page 468 U. S. 403 Riding Hood to take to her grandmother some of the food that she
is carrying in her basket. Only three paragraphs are used to
delineate a truer picture of the litigants, wherein it appears that
some of the food in the basket was given to Little Red Riding Hood
by the Big Bad Wolf himself, and that the Big Bad Wolf had told
Little Red Riding Hood in advance that, if she accepted his food,
she would have to abide by his conditions. Congress, in enacting §
399 of the Public Broadcasting Act, 47 U.S.C. § 399, has simply
determined that public funds shall not be used to subsidize
noncommercial, educational broadcasting stations which engage in
"editorializing" or which support or oppose any political
candidate. I do not believe that anything in the First Amendment to
the United States Constitution prevents Congress from choosing to
spend public moneys in that manner. Perhaps a more appropriate
analogy than that of Little Red Riding Hood and the Big Bad Wolf is
that of Faust and Mephistopheles; Pacifica, well aware of § 399's
condition on its receipt of public money, nonetheless accepted the
public money, and now seeks to avoid the conditions which Congress
legitimately has attached to receipt of that funding.
While noncommercial, educational broadcasting has a long history
in this country, its success was spotty at best until the Federal
Government came to its assistance some 45 years ago. Beginning in
the late 1930's, the Federal Communications Commission (FCC)
reserved certain frequencies, first for educational radio, 47 CFR
§§ 4.131-4.133 (1939), and then for educational television, Television Assignments, 41 F.C.C. 148 (1952). But even
with that assistance, by 1962 there were only 50 educational
television stations on the air, and two-thirds of the population
had no access to educational television. S.Rep. No. 67, 87th Cong.,
1st Sess., 3 (1961). In that year, Congress passed the Educational
Television Act of 1962, Pub.L. 87-447, 76 Stat. 64, which
appropriated $32 million over a period of five years to aid the
construction of educational stations, and by 1967, 126 such
stations were operating. Page 468 U. S. 404 Congress' vision was that public broadcasting would be a forum
for the educational, cultural, and public affairs broadcasting
which commercial stations had been unable or unwilling to furnish.
In order to further that vision, in 1967, Congress passed the
Public Broadcasting Act of 1967, Pub.L. 90-129, 81 Stat. 365, 47
U.S.C. § 390 et seq., of which § 399 is a part, which
created the Corporation for Public Broadcasting (CPB), a nonprofit,
Government-chartered corporation governed by a Board of Directors
appointed by the President. Although Congress could have chosen to
create a federally owned broadcasting network, instead it chose a
Government funding program whereby CPB would make grants to
stations owned by others, fund the production of programs, and
assist in the establishment and development of interconnection
systems.
Congress' intent was that CPB's subsidies would ensure that
"programs of high quality, diversity, creativity, excellence,
and innovation, which are obtained from diverse sources, will be
made available to public telecommunications entities, with strict
adherence to objectivity and balance in all programs or series of
programs of a controversial nature."
47 U.S.C. § 396(g)(1)(A). Understandably Congress did not leave
its creature CPB free to roam at large in the broadcasting world,
but instead imposed certain restrictions, in keeping with Congress'
purposes in passing the Act, on CPB's authorization to grant funds.
For example, Congress required that stations receiving CPB grants
be government entities or nonprofit organizations, 47 U.S.C. §§
397(6), (7), and it prohibited them from selling air time for any
purpose whatever -- including selling time for political or public
affairs presentations. §§ 397(7), 399a; see 47 CFR §§
73.503(d), 73.621(e) (1983). Furthermore, in order to prevent
recipient stations from serving as outlets for the political and
ideological views of station owners and managers, Congress also
insisted in § 399 that subsidized educational stations not engage
in editorializing or endorsing or opposing political
candidates. Page 468 U. S. 405 The Court's three-paragraph discussion of why § 399, repeatedly
reexamined and retained by Congress, violates the First Amendment
is to me utterly unpersuasive. Congress has rationally determined
that the bulk of the taxpayers whose moneys provide the funds for
grants by the CPB would prefer not to see the management of local
educational stations promulgate its own private views on the air at
taxpayer expense. Accordingly Congress simply has decided not to
subsidize stations which engage in that activity.
Last Term, in Regan v. Taxation With Representation of
Washington, 461 U. S. 540 (1983), we upheld a provision of the Internal Revenue Code which
deprives an otherwise eligible organization of its tax-exempt
status and its right to receive tax-deductible contributions if it
engages in lobbying. We squarely rejected the contention that
Congress' decision not to subsidize lobbying violates the First
Amendment, even though we recognized that the right to lobby is
constitutionally protected. In so holding, we reiterated that "a
legislature's decision not to subsidize the exercise of a
fundamental right does not infringe the right." Id. at 461 U. S. 549 .
We also rejected the notion that, because Congress chooses to
subsidize some speech but not other speech, its exercise of its
spending powers is subject to strict judicial scrutiny. Id. at 461 U. S.
547 -548.
Relying primarily on the reasoning of the concurrence, rather
than of the majority, opinion in Taxation with
Representation, the Court today seeks to avoid the thrust of
that opinion by pointing out that a public broadcasting station is
barred from editorializing with its nonfederal funds even though it
may receive only a minor fraction of its income from CPB grants.
The Court reasons that § 399 does not operate simply to restrict
the use of federal funds to purposes defined by Congress; instead,
it goes further by prohibiting any station that receives "only 1%
of its overall income from CPB grants" from using "even wholly
private funds to finance its editorial activity." Ante at 468 U. S.
400 . Page 468 U. S. 406 But to me, there is no distinction between § 399 and the statute
which we upheld in Oklahoma v. CSC, 330 U.
S. 127 (1947). Section 12(a) of the Hatch Act totally
prohibits any local or state employee who is employed in any
activity which receives partial or total financing from the United
States from taking part in any political activities. One might just
as readily denounce such congressional action as prohibiting
employees of a state or local government receiving even a minor
fraction of that government's income from federal assistance from
exercising their First Amendment right to speak. But, not
surprisingly, this Court upheld the Hatch Act provision in Oklahoma v. CSC, supra, succinctly stating:
"While the United States is not concerned with, and has no power
to regulate, local political activities, as such, of state
officials, it does have power to fix the terms upon which its money
allotments to states shall be disbursed." Id. at 143. * See also CSC
v. Letter Carriers, 413 U. S. 548 (1973); United Public Workers v. Mitchell, 330 U. S.
75 (1947) (rejecting a First Amendment attack on the
Hatch Act provisions applicable to federal employees).
The Court seems to believe that Congress actually subsidizes
editorializing only if a station uses federal money specifically to
cover the expenses that the Court believes can be isolated as
editorializing expenses. But to me, the Court's approach ignores
economic reality. CPB's unrestricted grants are used for salaries,
training, equipment, promotion, etc. -- financial expenditures
which benefit all aspects of a station's programming, including
management's editorials. Page 468 U. S. 407 Given the impossibility of compartmentalizing programming
expenses in any meaningful way, it seems clear to me that the only
effective means for preventing the use of public moneys to
subsidize the airing of management's views is for Congress to ban a
subsidized station from all on-the-air editorializing. Under the
Court's view, if Congress decided to withhold a 100% subsidy from a
station which editorializes, that decision would be constitutional
under the principle affirmed in our Taxation With
Representation decision. Surely, on these facts, the
distinction between the Government's power to withhold a 100%
subsidy, on the one hand, and the 20-30% subsidy involved here, 547 F.
Supp. 379 , 385 (CD Cal.1982), on the other hand, is simply
trivialization.
This is not to say that the Government may attach any condition
to its largess; it is only to say that, when the Government is
simply exercising its power to allocate its own public funds, we
need only find that the condition imposed has a rational
relationship to Congress' purpose in providing the subsidy, and
that it is not primarily " "aimed at the suppression of
dangerous ideas."'" Cammarano v. United States, 358 U. S. 498 , 358 U. S. 513 (1959), quoting Speiser v. Randall, 357 U.
S. 513 , 357 U. S. 519 (1958), in turn quoting American Communications Assn. v.
Douds, 339 U. S. 382 , 339 U. S. 402 (1950). In this case, Congress' prohibition is directly related to
its purpose in providing subsidies for public broadcasting, and it
is plainly rational for Congress to have determined that taxpayer
moneys should not be used to subsidize management's views or to pay
for management's exercise of partisan politics. Indeed, it is
entirely rational for Congress to have wished to avoid the
appearance of Government sponsorship of a particular view or a
particular political candidate. Furthermore, Congress' prohibition
is strictly neutral. In no sense can it be said that Congress has
prohibited only editorial views of one particular ideological bent.
Nor has it prevented public stations from airing programs,
documentaries, interviews, etc. dealing with controversial
subjects, so long as management Page 468 U. S. 408 itself does not expressly endorse a particular viewpoint. And
Congress has not prevented station management from communicating
its own views on those subjects through any medium other than
subsidized public broadcasting.
For the foregoing reasons I find this case entirely different
from the so-called "unconstitutional condition" cases, wherein the
Court has stated that the government
"may not deny a benefit to a person on a basis that infringes
his constitutionally protected interests -- especially his interest
in freedom of speech." Perry v. Sindermann, 408 U. S. 593 , 408 U. S. 597 (1972). In those cases, the suppressed speech was not
content-neutral in the same sense as here, and in those cases,
there is, at best, only a strained argument that the legislative
purpose of the condition imposed was to avoid subsidizing the
prohibited speech. Speiser v. Randall, supra, is
illustrative of the difference. In that case, California's decision
to deny its property tax exemption to veterans who would not
declare that they would not work to overthrow the government was
plainly directed at suppressing what California regarded as speech
of a dangerous content. And the condition imposed was so unrelated
to the benefit to be conferred that it is difficult to argue that
California's property tax exemption actually subsidized the
dangerous speech.
Here, in my view, Congress has rationally concluded that the
bulk of taxpayers whose moneys provide the funds for grants by the
CPB would prefer not to see the management of public stations
engage in editorializing or the endorsing or opposing of political
candidates. Because Congress' decision to enact § 399 is a rational
exercise of its spending powers, and strictly neutral, I would hold
that nothing in the First Amendment makes it unconstitutional.
Accordingly, I would reverse the judgment of the District
Court.
* The Court takes pains to show that the argument rejected in Oklahoma v. CSC was a Tenth Amendment argument. Ante at 468 U. S.
401 -402, n. 27. Without belaboring the point, in my view
a fair reading of the opinion is that the Court used the quoted
language in that case to refer to a First Amendment argument
similar to this one, as well as to a Tenth Amendment argument.
JUSTICE STEVENS, dissenting.
The court jester who mocks the King must choose his words with
great care. An artist is likely to paint a flattering portrait of
his patron. The child who wants a new toy Page 468 U. S. 409 does not preface his request with a comment on how fat his
mother is. Newspaper publishers have been known to listen to their
advertising managers. Elected officials may remember how their
elections were financed. By enacting the statutory provision that
the Court invalidates today, a sophisticated group of legislators
expressed a concern about the potential impact of Government funds
on pervasive and powerful organs of mass communication. One need
not have heard the raucous voice of Adolf Hitler over Radio Berlin
to appreciate the importance of that concern.
AS JUSTICE WHITE correctly notes, the statutory prohibitions
against editorializing and candidate endorsements rest on the same
foundation. In my opinion, that foundation is far stronger than
merely "a rational basis," and it is not weakened by the fact that
it is buttressed by other provisions that are also designed to
avoid the insidious evils of government propaganda favoring
particular points of view. The quality of the interest in
maintaining government neutrality in the free market of ideas -- of
avoiding subtle forms of censorship and propaganda -- outweigh the
impact on expression that results from this statute. Indeed, by
simply terminating or reducing funding, Congress could curtail much
more expression with no risk whatever of a constitutional
transgression.
In order to explain my assessment of the case, it is necessary
first to supplement the majority's description of the impact of the
statute on free expression, and then to comment on the
justification for that impact. I The relevant facts may be briefly stated. Appellee League of
Women Voters of California, a nonprofit organization, wants to
enlist the "editorial support" of educational broadcasters in
support of its causes. App. 8. Appellee Henry Waxman, a regular
listener and viewer of educational stations, desires to hear the
"editorial opinions" of educational Page 468 U. S. 410 stations. Id. at 9. Appellee Pacifica, a nonprofit
educational corporation which operates five educational radio
stations -- the broadcasts from which reach 20 percent of the
Nation's population -- wants to
"broadcast its views on various important public issues, and . .
. clearly label those views as being editorials broadcast on behalf
of the Pacifica management." Id. at 9-10.
In short, Pacifica wants to broadcast its views to Waxman via
its radio stations; Waxman wants to listen to those views on his
radio; and the League of Women Voters wants a chance to convince
Pacifica to take positions its members favor in its radio
broadcasts.
All of these wants could be realized but for the fact that
Pacifica receives public funds to finance its broadcasts. Because
the Government subsidizes its broadcasts, a federal statute
prohibits Pacifica from broadcasting its views -- labeled as such
-- via the radio stations it operates. That statute now
provides:
"No noncommercial educational broadcasting station which
receives a grant from the Corporation under subpart C of this part
may engage in editorializing. No noncommercial educational
broadcasting station may support or oppose any candidate for public
office."
47 U.S.C. § 399. [ Footnote
2/1 ]
Although appellees originally challenged the validity of the
entire statute, in their amended complaint, they limited their
attack to the prohibition against editorializing. [ Footnote 2/2 ] In its analysis Page 468 U. S. 411 of the case, the Court assumes that the ban on political
endorsements is severable from the first section, and that it may
be constitutional. [ Footnote 2/3 ]
In view of the fact that the major Page 468 U. S. 412 difference between the ban on political endorsements is based on
the content of the speech, it is apparent that the entire rationale
of the Court's opinion rests on the premise that it may be
permissible to predicate a statutory restriction on candidate
endorsements on the difference between the content of that kind of
speech and the content of other expressions of editorial
opinion.
The Court does not tell us whether speech that endorses
political candidates is more or less worthy of protection than
other forms of editorializing, but it does iterate and reiterate
the point that "the expression of editorial opinion" is a special
kind of communication that "is entitled to the most exacting degree
of First Amendment protection." Ante at 468 U. S.
375 -376; see also ante at 468 U. S. 380 n. 13, 468 U. S. 381 , 468 U. S. 382 , 468 U. S. 383 ,
and 468 U. S. 384 .
[ Footnote 2/4 ]
Neither the fact that the statute regulates only one kind of
speech nor the fact that editorial opinion has traditionally been
an important kind of speech is sufficient to identify the character
or the significance of the statute's impact on speech. Three
additional points are relevant. First, the statute does not
prohibit Pacifica from expressing its opinion through any avenue
except the radio stations for which it receives federal financial
support. It eliminates the subsidized channel of communication as a
forum for Pacifica itself, and thereby deprives Pacifica of an
advantage it would otherwise have over other speakers, but it does
not exclude Pacifica from the marketplace for ideas. Second, the
statute does not curtail the expression of opinion by individual
commentators Page 468 U. S. 413 who participate in Pacifica's programs. The only comment that is
prohibited is a statement that Pacifica agrees or disagrees with
the opinions that others may express on its programs. Third, and of
greatest significance for me, the statutory restriction is
completely neutral in its operation -- it prohibits all editorials
without any distinction's being drawn concerning the subject matter
or the point of view that might be expressed. [ Footnote 2/5 ] Page 468 U. S. 414 II The statute does not violate the fundamental principle that the
citizen's right to speak may not be conditioned upon the
sovereign's agreement with what the speaker intends to say.
[ Footnote 2/6 ] On the contrary, the
statute was enacted in order to protect that very principle -- to
avoid the risk that some speakers will be rewarded or penalized for
saying things that appeal to -- or are offensive to -- the
sovereign. [ Footnote 2/7 ] The
interests the statute Page 468 U. S. 415 is designed to protect are interests that underlie the First
Amendment itself.
In my judgment, the interest in keeping the Federal Government
out of the propaganda arena is of overriding importance. That
interest is of special importance in the field of electronic
communication, not only because that medium is so powerful and
persuasive, but also because it is the one form of communication
that is licensed by the Federal Government. [ Footnote 2/8 ] When the Government already has great
potential Page 468 U. S. 416 power over the electronic media, it is surely legitimate to
enact statutory safeguards to make sure that it does not cross the
threshold that separates neutral regulation from the subsidy of
partisan opinion.
The Court does not question the validity of the basic interests
served by § 399. See ante at 468 U. S. 386 .
Instead, it suggests that the statute does not substantially serve
those interests, because the Public Broadcasting Act operates in
many other respects to insulate local stations from governmental
interference. See ante at 468 U. S.
388 -390. In my view, that is an indication of nothing
more than the strength of the governmental interest involved here
-- Congress enacted many safeguards because the evil to be avoided
was so grave. Organs of official propaganda are antithetical to
this Nation's heritage, and Congress understandably acted with
great caution in this area. [ Footnote
2/9 ] It is no answer to say that the other statutory
provisions
"substantially reduce the risk of governmental interference with
the editorial judgments of local stations without restricting those
stations' ability to speak on matters of public concern." Ante at 468 U. S. 390 .
The other safeguards protect the stations from interference with
judgments that they will necessarily make in selecting programming,
but those judgments are relatively amorphous. No safeguard is
foolproof, and the fact that funds are dispensed according to
largely "objective" criteria certainly is no guarantee. Individuals
must always make judgments in allocating funds, and pressure can be
exerted in subtle ways, as well as through outright
fund-cutoffs.
Members of Congress, not members of the Judiciary, live in the
world of politics. When they conclude that there is a real danger
of political considerations' influencing the dispensing of this
money, and that this provision is necessary to insulate grantees
from political pressures in addition to the other safeguards, that
judgment is entitled to our respect. Page 468 U. S. 417 The magnitude of the present danger that the statute is designed
to avoid is admittedly a matter about which reasonable judges may
disagree. [ Footnote 2/10 ]
Moreover, I would agree that the risk would be greater if other
statutory safeguards were removed. It remains true, however, that
Congress has the power to prevent the use of public funds to
subsidize the expression of partisan points of view, or to suppress
the propagation of dissenting opinions. No matter how great or how
small the immediate risk may be, there surely is more than a
theoretical possibility that future grantees might be influenced by
the ever present tie of the political purse strings, even if those
strings are never actually pulled. "[O]ne who knows that he may
dissent knows also that he somehow consents when he does not
dissent." H. Arendt, Crises of the Republic 88 (1972), citing 1 A.
de Tocqueville, Democracy in America 419 (1945). [ Footnote 2/11 ] Page 468 U. S. 418 III The Court describes the scope of § 399's ban as being "defined
solely on the basis of the content of the suppressed speech," ante at 468 U. S. 383 ,
and analogizes this case to the regulation of speech we condemned
in Consolidated Edison Co. v. Public Service Comm'n of
N.Y., 447 U. S. 530 (1980). This description reveals how the Court manipulates labels
without perceiving the critical differences behind the two
cases.
In Consolidated Edison, the class of speakers that was
affected by New York's prohibition consisted of regulated public
utilities that had been expressing their opinion on the issue of
nuclear power by means of written statements inserted in their
customers' monthly bills. Although the scope of the prohibition was
phrased in general terms and applied to a selected group of
speakers, it was obviously directed at spokesmen for a particular
point of view. The justification for the restriction was phrased in
terms of the potential offensiveness of the utilities' messages to
their audiences. It was a classic case of a viewpoint-based
prohibition.
In this case, however, although the regulation applies only to a
defined class of noncommercial broadcast licensees, it is common
ground that these licensees represent heterogenous points of view.
[ Footnote 2/12 ] There is simply
no sensible basis for considering this regulation a viewpoint
restriction -- or, to use the Court's favorite phrase, to condemn
it as "content-based" -- because it applies equally to station
owners of all shades of opinion. Moreover, the justification for
the prohibition is not based on the "offensiveness" of the messages
in the sense that that term was used in Consolidated
Edison. Here, it is true that taxpayers might find it
offensive if their tax moneys were being used to subsidize the
expression of editorial Page 468 U. S. 419 opinion with which they disagree, but it is the fact of the
subsidy -- not just the expression of the opinion -- that
legitimates this justification. Furthermore, and of greater
importance, the principal justification for this prohibition is the
overriding interest in forestalling the creation of propaganda
organs for the Government. I respectfully dissent.
[ Footnote 2/1 ]
As originally enacted in 1967, the statute provided:
"No noncommercial educational broadcasting station may engage in
editorializing or may support or oppose any candidate for political
office."
Pub.L. 90-129, Title II, § 201(8), 81 Stat. 368.
[ Footnote 2/2 ]
Appellees' abandonment of their attack on the ban on political
endorsements merits some comment. At one level, it is perplexing,
given that we have stated that such political expression is at the
very core of the First Amendment's protection, see, e.g., Brown
v. Hartlage, 456 U. S. 45 (1982); Monitor Patriot Co. v. Roy, 401 U.
S. 265 , 401 U. S. 272 (1971), and given that Pacifica cannot escape the ban on political
endorsements simply by declining to accept Government funds. Viewed
solely from the perspective of the First Amendment interests at
stake, therefore, it would appear that the ban on candidate
endorsements is more suspect than the ban on editorializing.
In New York Times Co. v. Sullivan, 376 U.
S. 254 (1964), we expressly recognized the
"profound national commitment to the principle that debate on
public issues should be uninhibited, robust, and wide-open, and
that it may well include vehement, caustic, and sometimes
unpleasantly sharp attacks on government and public officials. . .
." Id. at 376 U. S. 270 .
Appellee Pacifica, which originally asserted a desire to endorse
political candidates, apparently has now decided that it does not
want to engage in a "wide-open" debate on public issues -- it no
longer asserts the right to make "vehement, caustic, and sometimes
unpleasantly sharp attacks on government and public officials" over
its radio stations which are, in fact, funded by Government
officials.
In any event, if these particular litigants abandoned their
attack on the seemingly more suspect political endorsement ban for
tactical reasons, that fact is an indication of the strength of the
same basic governmental interest which forms the foundation of the
provision which they continue to challenge.
[ Footnote 2/3 ]
The Court actually raises the wrong severability issue. The
serious question in this regard is whether the entire public
funding scheme is severable from the prohibition on editorializing
and political endorsements. The legislative history of the statute
indicates the strength of the congressional aversion to these
practices. The basic notion of providing Government subsidies to
these domestic organs for the dissemination of information --
"educational" stations -- was viewed as extremely troubling. The
line between education and indoctrination is a subtle one, and it
is one Congress did not want these publicly funded stations to
cross. The fact that the House Committee Report stated in passing
that the provision was added out of "an abundance of caution,"
merely shows that Congress deemed an abundance of caution
necessary. The majority may view the congressional concerns --
potential governmental censorship, giving louder voices to a
privileged few station owners, and the use of taxpayer funds to
subsidize expression of viewpoints with which the taxpayers may not
agree -- as insufficiently weighty to justify the statute, but
Congress clearly thought they were weighty enough.
[ Footnote 2/4 ]
Thus, once again the Court embraces the obvious proposition that
some speech is more worthy of protection than other speech -- that
the right to express editorial opinion may be worth fighting to
preserve even though the right to hear less worthy speech may not
-- a proposition that several Members of today's majority could
only interpret "as an aberration" in Young v. American Mini
Theatres, Inc., 427 U. S. 50 , 427 U. S. 87 (1976) (dissenting opinion) ("The fact that the offensive'
speech here may not address `important' topics -- `ideas of social
and political significance,' in the Court's terminology, [427 U.S.
at 427 U. S. 61 ] --
does not mean that it is less worthy of constitutional
protection"). [ Footnote 2/5 ]
Section 399's ban on editorializing is a content-based
restriction on speech, but not in the sense that the majority
implies. The majority speaks of "editorial opinion" as if it were
some sort of special species of opinion, limited to issues of
public importance. See, e.g., ante at 468 U. S.
375 -376. The majority confuses the typical content of
editorials with the meaning of editorial itself. An editorial is,
of course, a statement of the management's opinion on any topic
imaginable. The Court asserts that what the statute "forecloses is
the expression of editorial opinion on controversial issues of
public importance.'" Ante at 468 U. S. 381 .
The statute is not so limited. The content which is prohibited is
that the station is not permitted to state its opinion with respect
to any matter. In short, it may not be an on-the-air advocate if it
accepts Government funds for its broadcasts. The prohibition on
editorializing is not directed at any particular message a station
might wish to convey, cf. Linmark Associates, Inc. v.
Willingboro, 431 U. S. 85 , 431 U. S. 96 -97
(1977); see generally Whitney v. California, 274 U.
S. 357 , 274 U. S. 377 (1927) (Brandeis, J., concurring). Unlike the Court, I am not
troubled by the fact that the stations are allowed to make "daily
announcements of the station's program schedule or over-the-air
appeals for contributions from listeners " ante at 468 U. S. 383 ,
for it is quite plain that this statute is not directed at
curtailing expression of particular points of view on controversial
issues; it is designed to assure to the extent possible that the
station does not become a vehicle for Government
propaganda. Paradoxically, § 399 is later attacked by the majority as
essentially being underinclusive because it does not prohibit
"controversial" national programming that is often aired with
substantial federal funding. Here the Court recognizes that the ban
imposed by § 399 "is plainly not directed at the potentially
controversial content of such programs," ante at 468 U. S. 391 ,
which only demonstrates that it is not directed at the substance of
communication at all. Next, § 399's ban on editorializing is
attacked by the majority on overinclusive grounds -- because it is
content-neutral -- since it prohibits a
"potentially infinite variety of speech, most of which would not
be related in any way to governmental affairs, political
candidacies, or elections." Ante at 468 U. S. 393 .
Hence, while earlier the majority attacked § 399 as being
content-based, it is now attacked as being non-content-based,
applying to expressions of opinion -- such as "urging improvements
in a town's parks or museums," ibid. -- which does not
pose, in the Court's view at least, a realistic danger of
governmental interference because of its content.
[ Footnote 2/6 ]
"The general principle that has emerged from this line of cases
is that the First Amendment forbids the government to regulate
speech in ways that favor some viewpoints or ideas at the expense
of others. See Bolger v. Youngs Drug Products Corp., 463 U. S.
60 , 463 U. S. 65 , 463 U. S.
72 (1983); Consolidated Edison Co. v. Public Service
Comm'n of N.Y., 447 U. S. 530 , 447 U. S.
535 -536 (1980); Carey v. Brown, 447 U. S.
455 , 447 U. S. 462 -463 (1980); Young v. American Mini Theatres, Inc., 427 U. S.
50 , 427 U. S. 63 -65, 427 U. S.
67 -68 (1976) (plurality opinion); Police Department
of Chicago v. Mosley, 408 U. S. 92 , 408 U. S.
95 -96 (1972)." City Council of Los Angeles v. Taxpayers for Vincent, 466 U. S. 789 , 466 U. S. 804 (1984).
[ Footnote 2/7 ]
It is ironic indeed that the majority states that it must be
particularly wary in assessing § 399 "to determine whether it
reflects an impermissible attempt to allow a government [to]
control . . . the search for political truth,'" ante at 468 U. S. 384 (citation omitted), given that the very object of § 399 is to
prevent the Government from controlling the search for political
truth. Indeed, the Court recognizes that, when Congress decided to
provide financial support to educational stations, "all concerned agreed that this step posed some risk that these
traditionally independent stations might be pressured into becoming
forums devoted solely to programming and views that were acceptable
to the Federal Government." Ante at 468 U. S.
386 .
Moreover, the statute will also protect the listener's interest
in not having his tax payments used to finance the advocacy of
causes he opposes. The majority gives extremely short shrift to the
Government's interest in minimizing the use of taxpayer moneys to
promote private views with which the taxpayers may disagree. The
Court briefly observes that the taxpayers do not have a
constitutionally protected right to enjoin such expenditures, and
then leaps to the conclusion that, given the fact the funding
scheme itself is not unconstitutional, this interest cannot be used
to support the statute at issue here. Ante at 468 U. S. 385 ,
n. 16. The conclusion manifestly does not follow from the premise,
and this interest is plainly legitimate and significant.
[ Footnote 2/8 ]
We have consistently adhered to the following guiding principles
applicable to First Amendment claims in the area of broadcasting,
and they bear repeating at some length:
"Where there are substantially more individuals who want to
broadcast than there are frequencies to allocate, it is idle to
posit an unabridgeable First Amendment right to broadcast
comparable to the right of every individual to speak, write, or
publish. . . ."
". . . No one has a First Amendment right to a license or to
monopolize a radio frequency. . . . "
"By the same token, as far as the First Amendment is concerned,
those who are licensed stand no better than those to whom licenses
are refused. A license permits broadcasting, but the licensee has
no constitutional right to be the one who holds the license or to
monopolize a radio frequency to the exclusion of his fellow
citizens. There is nothing in the First Amendment which prevents
the Government from requiring a licensee to share his frequency
with others and to conduct himself as a proxy or fiduciary with
obligations to present those views and voices which are
representative of his community and which would otherwise, by
necessity, be barred from the airwaves."
"[T]he people as a whole retain their interest in free speech by
radio and their collective right to have the medium function
consistently with the ends and purposes of the First Amendment. It
is the right of the viewers and listeners, not the right of the
broadcasters, which is paramount. . . . It is the purpose of the
First Amendment to preserve an uninhibited marketplace of ideas in
which truth will ultimately prevail, rather than to countenance
monopolization of that market, whether it be by the Government
itself or a private licensee. . . . It is the right of the public
to receive . . . ideas . . . which is crucial here." Red Lion Broadcasting Co. v. FCC, 395 U.
S. 367 , 395 U. S.
388 -390 (1969).
[ Footnote 2/9 ] Cf. 22 U.S.C. § 1461 (prohibiting the International
Communication Agency -- successor to the United States Information
Agency -- from disseminating information in the United States).
[ Footnote 2/10 ]
The majority argues that the Government's concededly substantial
interest in ensuring that audiences of educational stations will
not perceive the station to be a Government propaganda organ can be
fully satisfied by requiring such stations to broadcast a
disclaimer each time they editorialize, stating that the editorial
"does not in any way represent the views of the Federal Government.
. . ." Ante at 468 U. S. 395 .
This solution would be laughable were it not so Orwellian: the
answer to the fact that there is a real danger that the editorials
are really Government propaganda is for the Government to require
the station to tell the audience that it is not propaganda at
all!
[ Footnote 2/11 ]
The "fairness doctrine" is no answer to the concern that
Government-funded organs of mass communication will, overall, take
a pro-Government slant in editorializing, and thereby create a
distortion in the marketplace of ideas. First, the "fairness
doctrine" is itself enforced by the Government. Second, that
doctrine does not guarantee other speakers access to the microphone
if they disagree with editorial opinion expressed by the station on
public policy issues. No other voice need be heard if the
Government determines that the station's editorial "fairly"
presented the substance of "the" opposing view. Moreover, as
appellees argue, editorials from an institution which the public
may hold in high regard may carry added weight in the marketplace
of ideas. See Brief for Appellees 15. That fact, however,
magnifies the evil sought to be avoided, for the danger is that
pro-Government views that are not actually shared by that
institution will be parroted to curry favor with its
benefactor.
[ Footnote 2/12 ]
That does not necessarily mean, however,
"that the editorial voices of these stations will prove to be as
distinctive, varied, and idiosyncratic as the various communities
they represent," ante at 468 U. S. 391 ,
given the potential effects of Government funding, see
supra at 468 U. S.
416 -417, and 468
U.S. 364 fn2/11|>n. 11. | The Supreme Court ruled that a ban on non-commercial educational stations receiving federal funds from editorializing violates the First Amendment. The Court found that while Congress has the power to regulate broadcasting under the Commerce Clause, the First Amendment protects the freedom of speech for broadcasters. The Court also noted that the restriction on editorializing was content-based and singled out non-commercial broadcasters, which raised concerns about government interference in the marketplace of ideas. The Court prioritized the right of viewers and listeners to receive a balanced presentation of views over the government's interest in preventing stations from becoming government propaganda organs. |
Free Speech | Branzburg v. Hayes | https://supreme.justia.com/cases/federal/us/408/665/ | U.S. Supreme Court Branzburg v. Hayes, 408
U.S. 665 (1972) Branzburg v. Hayes No. 70-85 Argued February 23,
1972 Decided June 29,
1972* 408
U.S. 665 CERTIORARI TO THE COURT OF APPEALS
OF KENTUCKY Syllabus The First Amendment does not relieve a newspaper reporter of the
obligation that all citizens have to respond to a grand jury
subpoena and answer questions relevant to a criminal investigation,
and therefore the Amendment does not afford him a constitutional
testimonial privilege for an agreement he makes to conceal facts
relevant to a grand jury's investigation of a crime or to conceal
the criminal conduct of his source or evidence thereof. Pp. 408 U. S.
679 -709.
No. 705, 461
S.W.2d 345 , and Kentucky Court of Appeals judgment in
unreported case of Branzburg v. Meigs, and No. 70-94, 358
Mass. 604, 266
N.E.2d 297 , affirmed; No. 70-57, 434 F.2d 1081, reversed.
WHITE, J., wrote the opinion of the Court, in which BURGER,
C.J., and BLACKMUN, POWELL, and REHNQUIST, JJ., joined. POWELL, J.,
filed a concurring opinion, post, p. 408 U. S. 709 .
DOUGLAS, J., filed a dissenting opinion, post, p. 408 U. S. 711 .
STEWART, J., filed a dissenting opinion, in which BRENNAN and
MARSHALL, JJ., joined, post, p. 408 U. S.
725 . Page 408 U. S. 667 Opinion of the Court by MR. JUSTICE WHITE, announced by THE
CHIEF JUSTICE.
The issue in these cases is whether requiring newsmen to appear
and testify before state or federal grand juries abridges the
freedom of speech and press guaranteed by the First Amendment. We
hold that it does not. I The writ of certiorari in No. 70-85, Branzburg v. Hayes and Meigs, brings before us two judgments of the Kentucky Court of
Appeals, both involving petitioner Branzburg, a staff reporter for
the Courier-Journal, a daily newspaper published in Louisville,
Kentucky.
On November 15, 1969, the Courier-Journal carried a story under
petitioner's by-line describing in detail his observations of two
young residents of Jefferson County synthesizing hashish from
marihuana, an activity which, they asserted, earned them about
$5,000 in three weeks. The article included a photograph of a pair
of hands working above a laboratory table on which was a substance
identified by the caption as hashish. The article stated that
petitioner had promised not to Page 408 U. S. 668 reveal the identity of the two hashish makers. [ Footnote 1 ] Petitioner was shortly subpoenaed
by the Jefferson County grand jury; he appeared, but refused to
identify the individuals he had seen possessing marihuana or the
persons he had seen making hashish from marihuana. [ Footnote 2 ] A state trial court judge
[ Footnote 3 ] ordered petitioner
to answer these questions and rejected his contention that the
Kentucky reporters' privilege statute, Ky.Rev.Stat. § 421.100
(1962) [ Footnote 4 ] the First
Amendment of the United States Constitution, or §§ 1, 2, and 8 of
the Kentucky Constitution authorized his refusal to answer.
Petitioner then sought prohibition and mandamus in the Kentucky
Court of Appeals on the same ground, but the Court of Appeals
denied the petition. Branzburg v. Page 408 U. S. 669 Pound, 461
S.W.2d 345 (1970), as modified on denial of rehearing, Jan. 22, 1971. It held that petitioner had abandoned his First
Amendment argument in a supplemental memorandum he had filed and
tacitly rejected his argument based on the Kentucky Constitution.
It also construed Ky.Rev.Stat. § 421.100 as affording a newsman the
privilege of refusing to divulge the identity of an informant who
supplied him with information, but held that the statute did not
permit a reporter to refuse to testify about events he had observed
personally, including the identities of those persons he had
observed.
The second case involving petitioner Branzburg arose out of his
later story published on January 10, 1971, which described in
detail the use of drugs in Frankfort, Kentucky. The article
reported that, in order to provide a comprehensive survey of the
"drug scene" in Frankfort, petitioner had "spent two weeks
interviewing several dozen drug users in the capital city," and had
seen some of them smoking marihuana. A number of conversations with
and observations of several unnamed drug users were recounted.
Subpoenaed to appear before a Franklin County grand jury "to
testify in the matter of violation of statutes concerning use and
sale of drugs," petitioner Branzburg moved to quash the summons;
[ Footnote 5 ] the motion was
denied, although Page 408 U. S. 670 an order was issued protecting Branzburg from revealing
"confidential associations, sources or information" but requiring
that he "answer any questions which concern or pertain to any
criminal act, the commission of which was actually observed by
[him]." Prior to the time he was slated to appear before the grand
jury, petitioner sought mandamus and prohibition from the Kentucky
Court of Appeals, arguing that, if he were forced to go before the
grand jury or to answer questions regarding the identity of
informants or disclose information given to him in confidence, his
effectiveness as a reporter would be greatly damaged. The Court of
Appeals once again denied the requested writs, reaffirming its
construction of Ky.Rev.Stat. § 421.100, and rejecting petitioner's
claim of a First Amendment privilege. It distinguished Caldwell
v. United States, 434 F.2d 1081 (CA9 1970), and it also
announced its "misgivings" about that decision, asserting that it
represented "a drastic departure from the generally recognized rule
that the sources of information of a newspaper reporter are not
privileged under the First Amendment." It characterized
petitioner's fear that his ability to obtain Page 408 U. S. 671 news would be destroyed as
"so tenuous that it does not, in the opinion of this court,
present an issue of abridgement of the freedom of the press within
the meaning of that term as used in the Constitution of the United
States."
Petitioner sought a writ of certiorari to review both judgments
of the Kentucky Court of Appeals, and we granted the writ.
[ Footnote 6 ] 402 U.S. 942
(1971). Page 408 U. S. 672 In re Pappas, No. 70-94, originated when petitioner
Pappas, a television newsman-photographer working out of the
Providence, Rhode Island, office of a New Bedford, Massachusetts,
television station, was called to New Bedford on July 30, 1970, to
report on civil disorders there which involved fires and other
turmoil. He intended to cover a Black Panther news conference at
that group's headquarters in a boarded-up store. Petitioner found
the streets around the store barricaded, but he ultimately gained
entrance to the area and recorded and photographed a prepared
statement read by one of the Black Panther leaders at about 3 p.m.
[ Footnote 7 ] He then asked for
and received permission to reenter the area. Returning at about 9
o'clock, he was allowed to enter and remain inside Panther
headquarters. As a condition of entry, Pappas agreed not to
disclose anything he saw or heard inside the store except an
anticipated police raid, which Pappas, "on his own," was free to
photograph and report as he wished. Pappas stayed inside the
headquarters for about three hours, but there was no police raid,
and petitioner wrote no story and did not otherwise reveal what had
occurred in the store while he was there. Two months later,
petitioner was summoned before the Bristol Page 408 U. S. 673 County Grand Jury and appeared, answered questions as to his
name, address, employment, and what he had seen and heard outside
Panther headquarters, but refused to answer any questions about
what had taken place inside headquarters while he was there,
claiming that the First Amendment afforded him a privilege to
protect confidential informants and their information. A second
summons was then served upon him, again directing him to appear
before the grand jury and "to give such evidence as he knows
relating to any matters which may be inquired of on behalf of the
Commonwealth before . . . the Grand Jury." His motion to quash on
First Amendment and other grounds was denied by the trial judge
who, noting the absence of a statutory newsman's privilege in
Massachusetts, ruled that petitioner had no constitutional
privilege to refuse to divulge to the grand jury what he had seen
and heard, including the identity of persons he had observed. The
case was reported for decision to the Supreme Judicial Court of
Massachusetts. [ Footnote 8 ] The
record there did not include a transcript of the hearing on the
motion to quash, nor did it reveal the specific questions
petitioner had refused to answer, the expected nature of his
testimony, the nature of the grand jury investigation, or the
likelihood of the grand jury's securing the information it sought
from petitioner by other means. [ Footnote 9 ] The Page 408 U. S. 674 Supreme Judicial Court, however, took
"judicial notice that, in July, 1970, there were serious civil
disorders in New Bedford, which involved street barricades,
exclusion of the public from certain streets, fires, and similar
turmoil. We were told at the arguments that there was gunfire in
certain streets. We assume that the grand jury investigation was an
appropriate effort to discover and indict those responsible for
criminal acts."
358 Mass. 604, 607, 266
N.E.2d 297 , 299 (1971). The court then reaffirmed prior
Massachusetts holdings that testimonial privileges were
"exceptional" and "limited," stating that "[t]he principle that the
public has a right to every man's evidence'" had usually been
preferred, in the Commonwealth, to countervailing interests. Ibid. The court rejected the holding of the Ninth Circuit
in Caldwell v. United States, supra, and "adhere[d] to the view that there exists no constitutional
newsman's privilege, either qualified or absolute, to refuse to
appear and testify before a court or grand jury. [ Footnote 10 ]"
358 Mass. at 612, 266 N.E.2d at 302-303. Any adverse effect upon
the free dissemination of news by virtue of petitioner's being
called to testify was deemed to be only "indirect, theoretical, and
uncertain." Id. at 612, 266 N.E.2d at 302. The court
concluded that
"[t]he obligation of newsmen . . . is that of every citizen . .
. to appear when summoned, with relevant written or other material
when required, and to answer relevant and reasonable
inquiries." Id. at 612, 266 N.E.2d at 303. The court nevertheless
noted that grand juries were subject to supervision by the
presiding Page 408 U. S. 675 judge, who had the duty "to prevent oppressive, unnecessary,
irrelevant, and other improper inquiry and investigation," ibid., to insure that a witness' Fifth Amendment rights
were not infringed, and to assess the propriety, necessity, and
pertinence of the probable testimony to the investigation in
progress. [ Footnote 11 ] The
burden was deemed to be on the witness to establish the impropriety
of the summons or the questions asked. The denial of the motion to
quash was affirmed, and we granted a writ of certiorari to
petitioner Pappas. 402 U.S. 942 (1971). United States v. Caldwell, No. 70-57, arose from
subpoenas issued by a federal grand jury in the Northern District
of California to respondent Earl Caldwell, a reporter for the New
York Times assigned to cover the Black Panther Party and other
black militant groups. A subpoena duces tecum was served
on respondent on February 2, 1970, ordering him to appear before
the grand jury to testify and to bring with him notes and tape
recordings of interviews given him for publication by officers and
spokesmen of the Black Panther Party concerning the aims, purposes,
and activities of that organization. [ Footnote 12 ] Respondent objected to the scope Page 408 U. S. 676 of this subpoena, and an agreement between his counsel and the
Government attorneys resulted in a continuance. A second subpoena,
served on March 16, omitted the documentary requirement and simply
ordered Caldwell "to appear . . . to testify before the Grand
Jury." Respondent and his employer, the New York Times, [ Footnote 13 ] moved to quash on the
ground that the unlimited breadth of the subpoenas and the fact
that Caldwell would have to appear in secret before the grand jury
would destroy his working relationship with the Black Panther Party
and "suppress vital First Amendment freedoms . . . by driving a
wedge of distrust and silence between the news media and the
militants." App. 7. Respondent argued that "so drastic an incursion
upon First Amendment freedoms" should not be permitted "in the
absence of a compelling governmental interest -- not shown here --
in requiring Mr. Caldwell's appearance before the grand jury." Ibid. The motion was supported by amicus curiae memoranda from other publishing concerns and by affidavits from
newsmen asserting the unfavorable impact on news sources of
requiring reporters to appear before grand juries. The Government
filed three memoranda in opposition to the motion to quash, each
supported by affidavits. These documents stated that the grand jury
was investigating, among other things, possible violations of a
number of criminal statutes, including 18 U.S.C. § 871 (threats
against the President), 18 U.S.C. Page 408 U. S. 677 § 1751 (assassination, attempts to assassinate, conspiracy to
assassinate the President), 18 U.S.C. § 231 (civil disorders), 18
U.S.C. § 2101 (interstate travel to incite a riot), and 18 U.S.C. §
1341 (mail frauds and swindles). It was recited that, on November
15, 1969, an officer of the Black Panther Party made a publicly
televised speech in which he had declared that "[w]e will kill
Richard Nixon" and that this threat had been repeated in three
subsequent issues of the Party newspaper. App. 66, 77. Also
referred to were various writings by Caldwell about the Black
Panther Party, including an article published in the New York Times
on December 14, 1969, stating that "[i]n their role as the vanguard
in a revolutionary struggle, the Panthers have picked up guns," and
quoting the Chief of Staff of the Party as declaring:
"We advocate the very direct overthrow of the Government by way
of force and violence. By picking up guns and moving against it
because we recognize it as being oppressive and, in recognizing
that, we know that the only solution to it is armed struggle
[ sic ]."
App. 62. The Government also stated that the Chief of Staff of
the Party had been indicted by the grand jury on December 3, 1969,
for uttering threats against the life of the President in violation
of 18 U.S.C. § 871, and that various efforts had been made to
secure evidence of crimes under investigation through the
immunization of persons allegedly associated with the Black Panther
Party.
On April 6, the District Court denied the motion to quash, Application of Caldwell, 311 F.
Supp. 358 (ND Cal.1970), on the ground that " every
person within the jurisdiction of the government" is bound to
testify upon being properly summoned. Id. at 360 (emphasis
in original). Nevertheless, the court accepted respondent's First
Amendment arguments to the extent of issuing a protective order
providing that, although respondent had to divulge Page 408 U. S. 678 whatever information had been given to him for publication,
he
"shall not be required to reveal confidential associations,
sources or information received, developed or maintained by him as
a professional journalist in the course of his efforts to gather
news for dissemination to the public through the press or other
news media."
The court held that the First Amendment afforded respondent a
privilege to refuse disclosure of such confidential information
until there had been
"a showing by the Government of a compelling and overriding
national interest in requiring Mr. Caldwell's testimony which
cannot be served by any alternative means." Id. at 362.
Subsequently, [ Footnote
14 ] the term of the grand jury expired, a new grand jury was
convened, and a new subpoena ad testificandum was issued
and served on May 22, 1970. A new motion to quash by respondent and
memorandum in opposition by the Government were filed, and, by
stipulation of the parties, the motion was submitted on the prior
record. The court denied the motion to quash, repeating the
protective provisions in its prior order but this time directing
Caldwell to appear before the grand jury pursuant to the May 22
subpoena. Respondent refused to appear before the grand jury, and
the court issued an order to show cause why he should not be held
in contempt. Upon his further refusal to go before the grand jury,
respondent was ordered committed for contempt until such time as he
complied with the court's order or until the expiration of the term
of the grand jury. Page 408 U. S. 679 Respondent Caldwell appealed the contempt order, [ Footnote 15 ] and the Court of Appeals
reversed. Caldwell v. United States, 434 F.2d 1081 (CA9
1970). Viewing the issue before it as whether Caldwell was required
to appear before the grand jury at all, rather than the scope of
permissible interrogation, the court first determined that the
First Amendment provided a qualified testimonial privilege to
newsmen; in its view, requiring a reporter like Caldwell to testify
would deter his informants from communicating with him in the
future and would cause him to censor his writings in an effort to
avoid being subpoenaed. Absent compelling reasons for requiring his
testimony, he was held privileged to withhold it. The court also
held, for similar First Amendment reasons, that, absent some
special showing of necessity by the Government, attendance by
Caldwell at a secret meeting of the grand jury was something he was
privileged to refuse because of the potential impact of such an
appearance on the flow of news to the public. We granted the United
States' petition for certiorari. [ Footnote 16 ] 402 U.S. 942 (1971). II Petitioners Branzburg and Pappas and respondent Caldwell press
First Amendment claims that may be simply put: that, to gather
news, it is often necessary to agree either not to identify the
source of information published or to publish only part of the
facts revealed, or both; that, if the reporter is nevertheless Page 408 U. S. 680 forced to reveal these confidences to a grand jury, the source
so identified and other confidential sources of other reporters
will be measurably deterred from furnishing publishable
information, all to the detriment of the free flow of information
protected by the First Amendment. Although the newsmen in these
cases do not claim an absolute privilege against official
interrogation in all circumstances, they assert that the reporter
should not be forced either to appear or to testify before a grand
jury or at trial until and unless sufficient grounds are shown for
believing that the reporter possesses information relevant to a
crime the grand jury is investigating, that the information the
reporter has is unavailable from other sources, and that the need
for the information is sufficiently compelling to override the
claimed invasion of First Amendment interests occasioned by the
disclosure. Principally relied upon are prior cases emphasizing the
importance of the First Amendment guarantees to individual
development and to our system of representative government,
[ Footnote 17 ] decisions
requiring that official action with adverse impact on First
Amendment rights be justified by a public interest that is
"compelling" or "paramount," [ Footnote 18 ] and those precedents establishing the
principle that justifiable governmental goals may not be achieved
by unduly broad means having an unnecessary impact Page 408 U. S. 681 on protected rights of speech, press, or association. [ Footnote 19 ] The heart of the claim
is that the burden on news gathering resulting from compelling
reporters to disclose confidential information outweighs any public
interest in obtaining the information. [ Footnote 20 ]
We do not question the significance of free speech, press, or
assembly to the country's welfare. Nor is it suggested that news
gathering does not qualify for First Amendment protection; without
some protection for seeking out the news, freedom of the press
could be eviscerated. But these cases involve no intrusions upon
speech or assembly, no prior restraint or restriction on what the
press may publish, and no express or implied command that the press
publish what it prefers to withhold. No exaction or tax for the
privilege of publishing, and no penalty, civil or criminal, related
to the content of published material is at issue here. The use of
confidential sources by the press is not forbidden or restricted;
reporters remain free to seek news from Page 408 U. S. 682 any source by means within the law. No attempt is made to
require the press to publish its sources of information or
indiscriminately to disclose them on request.
The sole issue before us is the obligation of reporters to
respond to grand jury subpoenas as other citizens do, and to answer
questions relevant to an investigation into the commission of
crime. Citizens generally are not constitutionally immune from
grand jury subpoenas, and neither the First Amendment nor any other
constitutional provision protects the average citizen from
disclosing to a grand jury information that he has received in
confidence. [ Footnote 21 ]
The claim is, however, that reporters are exempt from these
obligations because, if forced to respond to subpoenas and identify
their sources or disclose other confidences, their informants will
refuse or be reluctant to furnish newsworthy information in the
future. This asserted burden on news gathering is said to make
compelled testimony from newsmen constitutionally suspect, and to
require a privileged position for them.
It is clear that the First Amendment does not invalidate every
incidental burdening of the press that may result from the
enforcement of civil or criminal statutes of general applicability.
Under prior cases, otherwise valid laws serving substantial public
interests may be enforced against the press as against others,
despite Page 408 U. S. 683 the possible burden that may be imposed. The Court has
emphasized that
"[t]he publisher of a newspaper has no special immunity from the
application of general laws. He has no special privilege to invade
the rights and liberties of others." Associated Press v. NLRB, 301 U.
S. 103 , 301 U. S.
132 -133 (1937). It was there held that the Associated
Press, a news-gathering and disseminating organization, was not
exempt from the requirements of the National Labor Relations Act.
The holding was reaffirmed in Oklahoma Press Publishing Co. v.
Walling, 327 U. S. 186 , 327 U. S.
192 -193 (1946), where the Court rejected the claim that
applying the Fair Labor Standards Act to a newspaper publishing
business would abridge the freedom of press guaranteed by the First
Amendment. See also Mabee v. White Plains Publishing Co., 327 U. S. 178 (1946). Associated Press v. United States, 326 U. S.
1 (1945), similarly overruled assertions that the First
Amendment precluded application of the Sherman Act to a
newsgathering and disseminating organization. Cf. Indiana
Farmer's Guide Publishing Co. v. Prairie Farmer Publishing
Co., 293 U. S. 268 , 293 U. S. 276 (1934); Citizen Publish in Co. v. United States, 394 U. S. 131 , 394 U. S. 139 (1969); Lorain Journal Co. v. United States, 342 U.
S. 143 , 342 U. S.
155 -156 (1951). Likewise, a newspaper may be subjected
to nondiscriminatory forms of general taxation. Grosjean v.
American Press Co., 297 U. S. 233 , 297 U. S. 250 (1936); Murdock v. Pennsylvania, 319 U.
S. 105 , 319 U. S. 112 (1943).
The prevailing view is that the press is not free to publish
with impunity everything and anything it desires to publish.
Although it may deter or regulate what is said or published, the
press may not circulate knowing or reckless falsehoods damaging to
private reputation without subjecting itself to liability for
damages, including punitive damages, or even criminal prosecution. See New York Times Co. v. Sullivan, 376 U.
S. 254 , Page 408 U. S. 684 376 U. S.
279 -280 (1964); Garrison v. Louisiana, 379 U. S. 64 , 379 U. S. 74 (1964); Curtis Publishing Co. v. Butts, 388 U.
S. 130 , 388 U. S. 147 (1967) (opinion of Harlan, J.,); Monitor Patriot Co. v.
Roy, 401 U. S. 265 , 401 U. S. 277 (1971). A newspaper or a journalist may also be punished for
contempt of court, in appropriate circumstances. Craig v.
Harney, 331 U. S. 367 , 331 U. S.
377 -378 (1947).
It has generally been held that the First Amendment does not
guarantee the press a constitutional right of special access to
information not available to the public generally. Zemel v.
Rusk, 381 U. S. 1 , 381 U. S. 16 -17
(1965); New York Times Co. v. United States, 403 U.
S. 713 , 403 U. S.
728 -730 (1971), (STEWART, J., concurring); Tribune
Review Publishing Co. v. Thomas, 254 F.2d 883, 885 (CA3 1958); In the Matter of United Press Assns. v.
Valente, 308 N.Y.
71 , 77, 123 N.E.2d 777, 778 (1954). In Zemel v. Rusk,
supra, for example, the Court sustained the Government's
refusal to validate passports to Cuba even though that restriction
"render[ed] less than wholly free the flow of information
concerning that country." Id. at 381 U. S. 16 . The
ban on travel was held constitutional, for "[t]he right to speak
and publish does not carry with it the unrestrained right to gather
information." Id. at 381 U. S. 17 .
[ Footnote 22 ]
Despite the fact that news gathering may be hampered, the press
is regularly excluded from grand jury proceedings, our own
conferences, the meetings of other official bodies gathered in
executive session, and the meetings of private organizations.
Newsmen have no constitutional right of access to the scenes of
crime or Page 408 U. S. 685 disaster when the general public is excluded, and they may be
prohibited from attending or publishing information about trials if
such restrictions re necessary to assure a defendant a fair trial
before an impartial tribunal. In Sheppard v. Maxwell, 384 U. S. 333 (1966), for example, the Court reversed a state court conviction
where the trial court failed to adopt "stricter rules governing the
use of the courtroom by newsmen, as Sheppard's counsel requested,"
neglected to insulate witnesses from the press, and made no "effort
to control the release of leads, information, and gossip to the
press by police officers, witnesses, and the counsel for both
sides." Id. at 384 U. S. 358 , 384 U. S.
359 .
"[T]he trial court might well have proscribed extrajudicial
statements by any lawyer, party, witness, or court official which
divulged prejudicial matters." Id. at 384 U. S. 361 . See also Estes v. Texas, 381 U. S. 532 , 381 U. S.
539 -540 (1965); Rideau v. Louisiana, 373 U. S. 723 , 373 U. S. 726 (1963).
It is thus not surprising that the great weight of authority is
that newsmen are not exempt from the normal duty of appearing
before a grand jury and answering questions relevant to a criminal
investigation. At common law, courts consistently refused to
recognize the existence of any privilege authorizing a newsman to
refuse to reveal confidential information to a grand jury. See,
e.g., Ex Parte Lawrence, 116 Cal. 298, 48 P. 124 (1897); Plunkett v. Hamilton, 136 Ga. 72, 70 S.E. 781 (1911); Clein v. State, 52 So. 2d
117 (Fla.1950); In re Grunow, 84 N.J.L. 235, 85 A.
1011 (1913); People ex rel. Mooney v. Sheriff, 269 N.Y.
291, 199 N.E. 415 (1936); Joslyn v. People, 67 Colo. 297,
184 P. 375 (1919); Adams v. Associated Press, 46 F.R.D.
439 (SD Tex.1969); Brewster v. Boston Herald-Traveler
Corp., 20 F.R.D. 416 (Mass.1957). See generally Annot., 7 A.L.R.3d 591 (1966). In 1958, a news gatherer asserted
for the first time that the First Amendment Page 408 U. S. 686 exempted confidential information from public disclosure
pursuant to a subpoena issued in a civil suit, Garland v.
Torre, 259 F.2d 545 (CA2), cert. denied, 358 U.S. 910
(1958), but the claim was denied, and this argument has been almost
uniformly rejected since then, although there are occasional dicta
that, in circumstances not presented here, a newsman might be
excused. In re Goodfader, 45 Haw. 317, 367 P.2d 472 (1961); In re Taylor, 412 Pa. 32, 193 A.2d 181 (1963); State v. Buchanan, 250 Ore. 244, 436
P.2d 729 , cert. denied, 392 U.S. 905 (1968); Murphy v. Colorado (No.19604, Sup.Ct.Colo.), cert.
denied, 365 U.S. 843 (1961) (unreported, discussed in In
re Goodfader, supra, at 366, 367 P.2d at 498 (Mizuha, J.,
dissenting)). These courts have applied the presumption against the
existence of an asserted testimonial privilege, United States
v. Bryan, 339 U. S. 323 , 339 U. S. 331 (1950), and have concluded that the First Amendment interest
asserted by the newsman was outweighed by the general obligation of
a citizen to appear before a grand jury or at trial, pursuant to a
subpoena, and give what information he possesses. The opinions of
the state courts in Branzburg and Pappas are
typical of the prevailing view, although a few recent cases, such
as Caldwell, have recognized and given effect to some form
of constitutional newsman's privilege. See State v. Knops, 49 Wis.2d 647, 183 N.W.2d
93 (1971) (dictum); Alioto v. Cowles Communications,
Inc., C.A. No. 52150 (ND Cal.1969); In re Grand Jury
Witnesses, 322 F.
Supp. 573 (ND Cal.1970); People v. Dohrn, Crim. No.
69-3808 (Cook County, Ill., Cir. Ct.1970).
The prevailing constitutional view of the newsman's privilege is
very much rooted in the ancient role of the grand jury that has the
dual function of determining if there is probable cause to believe
that a crime has been committed and of protecting citizens against
unfounded Page 408 U. S. 687 criminal prosecutions. [ Footnote 23 ] Grand jury proceedings are constitutionally
mandated for the institution of federal criminal prosecutions for
capital or other serious crimes, and "its constitutional
prerogatives are rooted in long centuries of Anglo-American
history." Hannah v. Larche, 363 U.
S. 420 , 363 U. S.
489 -490 (1960) (Frankfurter, J., concurring in result).
The Fifth Amendment provides that "[n]o person shall be held to
answer for a capital, or otherwise infamous crime, unless on a
presentment or indictment of a Grand Jury." [ Footnote 24 ] The adoption of the grand jury "in
our Constitution as the sole method for preferring charges in
serious criminal cases shows the high place it held as an
instrument of justice." Costello v. United States, 350 U. S. 359 , 350 U. S. 362 (1956). Although state systems of criminal procedure differ greatly
among themselves, the grand jury is similarly guaranteed by many
state constitutions and plays an important role in fair and
effective law enforcement in the overwhelming Page 408 U. S. 688 majority of the States. [ Footnote 25 ] Because its task is to inquire into the
existence of possible criminal conduct and to return only well
founded indictments, its investigative powers are necessarily
broad.
"It is a grand inquest, a body with powers of investigation and
inquisition, the scope of whose inquiries is not to be limited
narrowly by questions of propriety or forecasts of the probable
result of the investigation, or by doubts whether any particular
individual will be found properly subject to an accusation of
crime." Blair v. United States, 250 U.
S. 273 , 250 U. S. 282 (1919). Hence, the grand jury's authority to subpoena witnesses is
not only historic, id. at 250 U. S.
279 -281, but essential to its task. Although the powers
of the grand jury are not unlimited and are subject to the
supervision of a judge, the longstanding principle that "the public
. . . has a right to every man's evidence," except for those
persons protected by a constitutional, common law, or statutory
privilege, United States v. Bryan, 339 U.S. at 339 U. S. 331 ; Blackmer v. United States, 284 U.
S. 421 , 284 U. S. 438 (1932); 8 J. Wigmore, Evidence § 2192 (McNaughton rev.1961), is
particularly applicable to grand jury proceedings. [ Footnote 26 ] Page 408 U. S. 689 A number of States have provided newsmen a statutory privilege
of varying breadth, [ Footnote
27 ] but the majority have not done so, and none has been
provided by federal statute. [ Footnote 28 ] Until now, the only testimonial privilege
for unofficial witnesses that is rooted in the Federal
Constitution Page 408 U. S. 690 is the Fifth Amendment privilege against compelled
self-incrimination. We are asked to create another by interpreting
the First Amendment to grant newsmen a testimonial privilege that
other citizens do not enjoy. This we decline to do. [ Footnote 29 ] Fair and effective law
enforcement aimed at providing security for the person and property
of the individual is a fundamental function of government, and the
grand jury plays an important, constitutionally mandated role in
this process. On the records now before us, we perceive no basis
for holding hat the public interest in law enforcement and in
ensuring effective grand jury proceedings if insufficient to
override the consequential, but uncertain, burden on news gathering
that is said to result from insisting that reporters, like other
citizens, respond to relevant Page 408 U. S. 691 questions put to them in the course of a valid grand jury
investigation or criminal trial.
This conclusion itself involves no restraint on what newspapers
may publish or on the type or quality of information reporters may
seek to acquire, nor does it threaten the vast bulk of confidential
relationships between reporters and their sources. Grand juries
address themselves to the issues of whether crimes have been
committed and who committed them. Only where news sources
themselves are implicated in crime or possess information relevant
to the grand jury's task need they or the reporter be concerned
about grand jury subpoenas. Nothing before us indicates that a
large number or percentage of all confidential news sources falls
into either category and would in any way be deterred by our
holding that the Constitution does not, as it never has, exempt the
newsman from performing the citizen's normal duty of appearing and
furnishing information relevant to the grand jury's task.
The preference for anonymity of those confidential informants
involved in actual criminal conduct is presumably a product of
their desire to escape criminal prosecution, and this preference,
while understandable, is hardly deserving of constitutional
protection. It would be frivolous to assert -- and no one does in
these cases -- that the First Amendment, in the interest of
securing news or otherwise, confers a license on either the
reporter or his news sources to violate valid criminal laws.
Although stealing documents or private wiretapping could provide
newsworthy information, neither reporter nor source is immune from
conviction for such conduct, whatever the impact on the flow of
news. Neither is immune, on First Amendment grounds, from
testifying against the other, before the grand jury or at a
criminal trial. The Amendment does not reach so far as to override
the interest of the public in ensuring Page 408 U. S. 692 that neither reporter nor source is invading the rights of other
citizens through reprehensible conduct forbidden to all other
persons. To assert the contrary proposition
"is to answer it, since it involves in its very statement the
contention that the freedom of the press is the freedom to do wrong
with impunity and implies the right to frustrate and defeat the
discharge of those governmental duties upon the performance of
which the freedom of all, including that of the press, depends. . .
. It suffices to say that, however complete is the right of the
press to state public things and discuss them, that right, as every
other right enjoyed in human society, is subject to the restraints
which separate right from wrongdoing." Toledo Newspaper Co. v. United States, 247 U.
S. 402 , 247 U. S.
419 -420 (1918). [ Footnote 30 ]
Thus, we cannot seriously entertain the notion that the First
Amendment protects a newsman's agreement to conceal the criminal
conduct of his source, or evidence thereof, on the theory that it
is better to write about crime than to do something about it.
Insofar as any reporter in these cases undertook not to reveal or
testify about the crime he witnessed, his claim of privilege under
the First Amendment presents no substantial question. The crimes of
news sources are no less reprehensible and threatening to the
public interest when witnessed by a reporter than when they are
not. Page 408 U. S. 693 There remain those situations where a source is not engaged in
criminal conduct but has information suggesting illegal conduct by
others. Newsmen frequently receive information from such sources
pursuant to a tacit or express agreement to withhold the source's
name and suppress any information that the source wishes not
published. Such informants presumably desire anonymity in order to
avoid being entangled as a witness in a criminal trial or grand
jury investigation. They may fear that disclosure will threaten
their job security or personal safety, or that it will simply
result in dishonor or embarrassment.
The argument that the flow of news will be diminished by
compelling reporters to aid the grand jury in a criminal
investigation is not irrational, nor are the records before us
silent on the matter. But we remain unclear how often and to what
extent informers are actually deterred from furnishing information
when newsmen are forced to testify before a grand jury. The
available data indicate that some newsmen rely a great deal on
confidential sources, and that some informants are particularly
sensitive to the threat of exposure, and may be silenced if it is
held by this Court that, ordinarily, newsmen must testify pursuant
to subpoenas, [ Footnote 31 ]
but the evidence fails to demonstrate that there would be a
significant constriction of the flow of news to the public if this
Court reaffirms the prior common law and constitutional rule
regarding the testimonial obligations of newsmen. Estimates of the
inhibiting effect of such subpoenas on the willingness of
informants to make disclosures to newsmen are widely divergent
and Page 408 U. S. 694 to a great extent speculative. [ Footnote 32 ] It would be difficult to canvass the views
of the informants themselves; surveys of reporters on this topic
are chiefly opinions of predicted informant behavior and must be
viewed in the light of the professional self-interest of the
interviewees. [ Footnote 33 ]
Reliance by the press on confidential informants does not mean that
all such sources will, in fact, dry up because of the later
possible appearance of the newsman before a grand jury. The
reporter may never be called, and, if he objects to testifying, the
prosecution may not insist. Also, the relationship of many
informants to the press is a symbiotic one which is unlikely to be
greatly inhibited by the threat of subpoena: quite often, such
informants are members of a minority political or cultural group
that Page 408 U. S. 695 relies heavily on the media to propagate its views, publicize
its aims, and magnify its exposure to the public. Moreover, grand
juries characteristically conduct secret proceedings, and law
enforcement officers are themselves experienced in dealing with
informers, and have their own methods for protecting them without
interference with the effective administration of justice. There is
little before us indicating that informants whose interest in
avoiding exposure is that it may threaten job security, personal
safety, or peace of mind, would in fact, be in a worse position, or
would think they would be, if they risked placing their trust in
public officials as well as reporters. We doubt if the informer who
prefers anonymity but is sincerely interested in furnishing
evidence of crime will always or very often be deterred by the
prospect of dealing with those public authorities
characteristically charged with the duty to protect the public
interest as well as his.
Accepting the fact, however, that an undetermined number of
informants not themselves implicated in crime will nevertheless,
for whatever reason, refuse to talk to newsmen if they fear
identification by a reporter in an official investigation, we
cannot accept the argument that the public interest in possible
future news about crime from undisclosed, unverified sources must
take precedence over the public interest in pursuing and
prosecuting those crimes reported to the press by informants and in
thus deterring the commission of such crimes in the future.
We note first that the privilege claimed is that of the
reporter, not the informant, and that, if the authorities
independently identify the informant, neither his own reluctance to
testify nor the objection of the newsman would shield him from
grand jury inquiry, whatever the impact on the flow of news or on
his future usefulness as a secret source of information. More
important, Page 408 U. S. 696 it is obvious that agreements to conceal information relevant to
commission of crime have very little to recommend them from the
standpoint of public policy. Historically, the common law
recognized a duty to raise the "hue and cry" and report felonies to
the authorities. [ Footnote
34 ] Misprision of a felony -- that is, the concealment of a
felony "which a man knows, but never assented to . . . [so as to
become] either principal or accessory," 4 W. Blackstone,
Commentaries *121, was often said to be a common law crime.
[ Footnote 35 ] The first
Congress passed a statute, 1 Stat. 113, § 6, as amended, 35 Stat.
1114, § 146, 62 Stat. 884, which is still in effect, defining a
federal crime of misprision:
"Whoever, having knowledge of the actual commission of a felony
cognizable by a court of the United States, conceals and does not
as soon as possible make known the same to some judge or other
person in civil or military authority under the United States,
shall be [guilty of misprision]."
18 U.S.C. § 4. [ Footnote
36 ] Page 408 U. S. 697 It is apparent from this statute, as well as from our history
and that of England, that concealment of crime and agreements to do
so are not looked upon with favor. Such conduct deserves no
encomium, and we decline now to afford it First Amendment
protection by denigrating the duty of a citizen, whether reporter
or informer, to respond to grand jury subpoena and answer relevant
questions put to him.
Of course, the press has the right to abide by its agreement not
to publish all the information it has, but the right to withhold
news is not equivalent to a First Amendment exemption from the
ordinary duty of all other citizens to furnish relevant information
to a grand jury performing an important public function. Private
restraints on the flow of information are not so favored by the
First Amendment that they override all other public interests. As
Mr. Justice Black declared in another context,
"[f]reedom of the press from governmental interference under the
First Amendment does not sanction repression of that freedom by
private interests." Associated Press v. United States, 326 U.S. at 326 U. S. 20 .
Neither are we now convinced that a virtually impenetrable
constitutional shield, beyond legislative or judicial control,
should be forged to protect a private system of informers operated
by the press to report on criminal conduct, a system that would be
unaccountable to the public, would pose a threat to the citizen's
justifiable expectations of privacy, and would equally protect well
intentioned informants and those who for pay or otherwise betray
their trust to their employer or associates. The public, through
its elected and appointed Page 408 U. S. 698 law enforcement officers regularly utilizes informers, and in
proper circumstances may assert a privilege against disclosing the
identity of these informers. But
"[t]he purpose of the privilege is the furtherance and
protection of the public interest in effective law enforcement. The
privilege recognizes the obligation of citizens to communicate
their knowledge of the commission of crimes to law enforcement
officials and, by preserving their anonymity, encourages them to
perform that obligation." Roviaro v. United States, 353 U. S.
53 , 353 U. S. 59 (1957). Such informers enjoy no constitutional protection. Their
testimony is available to the public when desired by grand juries
or at criminal trials; their identity cannot be concealed from the
defendant when it is critical to his case. Id. at 353 U. S. 60 -61,
62; McCray v. Illinois, 386 U. S. 300 , 386 U. S. 310 (1967); Smith v. Illinois, 390 U.
S. 129 , 390 U. S. 131 (1968); Alford v. United States, 282 U.
S. 687 , 282 U. S. 693 (1931). Clearly, this system is not impervious to control by the
judiciary and the decision whether to unmask an informer or to
continue to profit by his anonymity is in public, not private,
hands. We think that it should remain there and that public
authorities should retain the options of either insisting on the
informer's testimony relevant to the prosecution of crime or of
seeking the benefit of further information that his exposure might
prevent.
We are admonished that refusal to provide a First Amendment
reporter's privilege will undermine the freedom of the press to
collect and disseminate news. But this is not the lesson history
teaches us. As noted previously, the common law recognized no such
privilege, and the constitutional argument was not even asserted
until 1958. From the beginning of our country the press has
operated without constitutional protection Page 408 U. S. 699 for press informants, and the press has flourished. The existing
constitutional rules have not been a serious obstacle to either the
development or retention of confidential news sources by the press.
[ Footnote 37 ]
It is said that currently press subpoenas have multiplied,
[ Footnote 38 ] that mutual
distrust and tension between press and officialdom have increased,
that reporting styles have changed, and that there is now more need
for confidential sources, particularly where the press seeks news
about minority cultural and political groups or dissident
organizations suspicious of the law and public officials. These
developments, even if true, are treacherous grounds for a
far-reaching interpretation of the First Amendment fastening a
nationwide rule on courts, grand juries, and prosecuting officials
everywhere. The obligation to testify in response to grand jury
subpoenas will not threaten these sources not involved with
criminal conduct and without information relevant to grand jury
investigations, and we cannot hold that the Constitution places the
sources in these two categories either above the law or beyond its
reach.
The argument for such a constitutional privilege rests heavily
on those cases holding that the infringement of protected First
Amendment rights must be no broader than necessary to achieve a
permissible governmental purpose, see cases cited at n 19, supra. We do
not deal, however, with a governmental institution that has
abused Page 408 U. S. 700 its proper function, as a legislative committee does when it
"expose[s] for the sake of exposure." Watkins v. United
States, 354 U. S. 178 , 354 U. S. 200 (157). Nothing in the record indicates that these grand juries were
"prob[ing] at will and without relation to existing need." DeGregory v. Attorney General of New Hampshire, 383 U. S. 825 , 383 U. S. 829 (1966). Nor did the grand juries attempt to invade protected First
Amendment rights by forcing wholesale disclosure of names and
organizational affiliations for a purpose that was not germane to
the determination of whether crime has been committed, cf.
NAACP v. Alabama, 357 U. S. 449 (1958); NAACP v. Button, 371 U. S. 415 (1963); Bates v. Little Rock, 361 U.
S. 516 (1960), and the characteristic secrecy of grand
jury proceedings is a further protection against the undue invasion
of such rights. See Fed.Rule Crim.Proc. 6(e). The
investigative power of the grand jury is necessarily broad if its
public responsibility is to be adequately discharged. Costello
v. United States, 350 U.S. at 350 U. S.
364 .
The requirements of those cases, see n 18, supra, which hold that a
State's interest must be "compelling" or "paramount" to justify
even an indirect burden on First Amendment rights, are also met
here. As we have indicated, the investigation of crime by the grand
jury implements a fundamental governmental role of securing the
safety of the person and property of the citizen, and it appears to
us that calling reporters to give testimony in the manner and for
the reasons that other citizens are called "bears a reasonable
relationship to the achievement of the governmental purpose
asserted as its justification." Bates v. Little Rock,
supra, at 361 U. S. 525 .
If the test is that the government "convincingly show a substantial
relation between the information sought and a subject of overriding
and compelling state interest," Gibson v.
Florida Legislative Investigation Committee , Page 408 U. S. 701 372 U. S. 539 , 372 U. S. 546 (1963), it is quite apparent (1) that the State has the necessary
interest in extirpating the traffic in illegal drugs, in
forestalling assassination attempts on the President, and in
preventing the community from being disrupted by violent disorders
endangering both persons and property; and (2) that, based on the
stories Branzburg and Caldwell wrote and Pappas' admitted conduct,
the grand jury called these reporters as they would others --
because it was likely that they could supply information to help
the government determine whether illegal conduct had occurred and,
if it had, whether there was sufficient evidence to return an
indictment.
Similar considerations dispose of the reporters' claims that
preliminary to requiring their grand jury appearance, the State
must show that a crime has been committed and that they possess
relevant information not available from other sources, for only the
grand jury itself can make this determination. The role of the
grand jury as an important instrument of effective law enforcement
necessarily includes an investigatory function with respect to
determining whether a crime has been committed and who committed
it. To this end it must call witnesses, in the manner best suited
to perform its task.
"When the grand jury is performing its investigatory function
into a general problem area . . . society's interest is best served
by a thorough and extensive investigation." Wood v. Georgia, 370 U. S. 375 , 370 U. S. 392 (1962). A grand jury investigation
"is not fully carried out until every available clue has been
run down and all witnesses examined in every proper way to find if
a crime has been committed." United States v. Stone, 429 F.2d 138, 140 (CA2 1970).
Such an investigation may be triggered by tips, rumors, evidence
proffered by the prosecutor, or the personal knowledge of the grand
jurors. Costello v. United States, 350 U.S. at 350 U. S. 362 .
It is Page 408 U. S. 702 only after the grand jury has examined the evidence that a
determination of whether the proceeding will result in an
indictment can be made.
"It is impossible to conceive that in such cases the examination
of witnesses must be stopped until a basis is laid by an indictment
formally preferred, when the very object of the examination is to
ascertain who shall be indicted." Hale v. Henkel, 201 U. S. 43 , 201 U. S. 65 (1906). See also Hendricks v. United States, 223 U.
S. 178 (1912); Blair v. United States, 250 U.S.
at 250 U. S.
282 -283. We see no reason to hold that these reporters,
any more than other citizens, should be excused from furnishing
information that may help the grand jury in arriving at its initial
determinations.
The privilege claimed here is conditional, not absolute; given
the suggested preliminary showings and compelling need, the
reporter would be required to testify. Presumably, such a rule
would reduce the instances in which reporters could be required to
appear, but predicting in advance when and in what circumstances
they could be compelled to do so would be difficult. Such a rule
would also have implications for the issuance of compulsory process
to reporters at civil and criminal trials and at legislative
hearings. If newsmen's confidential sources are as sensitive as
they are claimed to be, the prospect of being unmasked whenever a
judge determines the situation justifies it is hardly a
satisfactory solution to the problem. [ Footnote 39 ] For them, it would appear that only an
absolute privilege would suffice. Page 408 U. S. 703 We are unwilling to embark the judiciary on a long and difficult
journey to such an uncertain destination. The administration of a
constitutional newsman's privilege Page 408 U. S. 704 would present practical and conceptual difficulties of a high
order. Sooner or later, it would be necessary to define those
categories of newsmen who qualified for the privilege, a
questionable procedure in light of the traditional doctrine that
liberty of the press is the right of the lonely pamphleteer who
uses carbon paper or a mimeograph just as much as of the large
metropolitan publisher who utilizes the latest photocomposition
methods. Cf. In re Grand Jury Witnesses, 322 F.
Supp. 573 , 574 (ND Cal.1970). Freedom of the press is a
"fundamental personal right" which
"is not confined to newspapers and periodicals. It necessarily
embraces pamphlets and leaflets. . . . The press in its historic
connotation comprehends every sort of publication which affords a
vehicle of information and opinion." Lovell v. Griffin, 303 U. S. 444 , 303 U. S. 450 , 303 U. S. 452 (138). See also Mills Page 408 U. S. 705 v. Alabama, 34 U.S. 214, 34 U. S. 219 (1966); Murdock v. Pennsylvania, 319 U.
S. 105 , 319 U. S. 111 (1943). The informative function asserted by representatives of the
organized press in the present cases is also performed by
lecturers, political pollsters, novelists, academic researchers,
and dramatists. Almost any author may quite accurately assert that
he is contributing to the flow of information to the public, that
he relies on confidential sources of information, and that these
sources will be silenced if he is forced to make disclosures before
a grand jury. [ Footnote
40 ]
In each instance where a reporter is subpoenaed to testify, the
courts would also be embroiled in preliminary factual and legal
determinations with respect to whether the proper predicate had
been laid for the reporter's appearance: Is there probable cause to
believe a crime has been committed? Is it likely that the reporter
has useful information gained in confidence? Could the grand jury
obtain the information elsewhere? Is the official interest
sufficient to outweigh the claimed privilege?
Thus, in the end, by considering whether enforcement of a
particular law served a "compelling" governmental interest, the
courts would be inextricably involved in Page 408 U. S. 706 distinguishing between the value of enforcing different criminal
laws. By requiring testimony from a reporter in investigations
involving some crimes but not in others, they would be making a
value judgment that a legislature had declined to make, since, in
each case, the criminal law involved would represent a considered
legislative judgment, not constitutionally suspect, of what conduct
is liable to criminal prosecution. The task of judges, like other
officials outside the legislative branch, is not to make the law,
but to uphold it in accordance with their oaths.
At the federal level, Congress has freedom to determine whether
a statutory newsman's privilege is necessary and desirable and to
fashion standards and rules as narrow or broad as deemed necessary
to deal with the evil discerned and, equally important, to
refashion those rules as experience from time to time may dictate.
There is also merit in leaving state legislatures free, within
First Amendment limits, to fashion their own standards in light of
the conditions and problems with respect to the relations between
law enforcement officials and press in their own areas. It goes
without saying, of course, that we are powerless to bar state
courts from responding in their own way and construing their own
constitutions so as to recognize a newsman's privilege, either
qualified or absolute.
In addition, there is much force in the pragmatic view that the
press has at its disposal powerful mechanisms of communication, and
is far from helpless to protect itself from harassment or
substantial harm. Furthermore, if what the newsmen urged in these
cases is true -- that law enforcement cannot hope to gain, and may
suffer from subpoenaing newsmen before grand juries -- prosecutors
will be loath to risk so much for so little. Thus, at the federal
level, the Attorney General has already fashioned a set of rules
for federal officials in connection Page 408 U. S. 707 with subpoenaing members of the press to testify before grand
juries or at criminal trials. [ Footnote 41 ] These rules are a major step in the
direction the reporters herein desire to move. They may prove
wholly sufficient to resolve the bulk of disagreements and
controversies between press and federal officials.
Finally, as we have earlier indicated, news gathering is not
without its First Amendment protections, and grand jury
investigations, if instituted or conducted other than in good
faith, would pose wholly different issues for resolution under the
First Amendment. [ Footnote
42 ] Official harassment of the press undertaken not for
purposes of law enforcement, but to disrupt a reporter's
relationship Page 408 U. S. 708 with his news sources would have no justification. Grand juries
are subject to judicial control and subpoenas to motions to quash.
We do not expect courts will forget that grand juries must operate
within the limits of the First Amendment as well as the Fifth. III We turn, therefore, to the disposition of the cases before us.
From what we have said, it necessarily follows that the decision in United States v. Caldwell, No. 70-57, must be reversed. If
there is no First Amendment privilege to refuse to answer the
relevant and material questions asked during a good faith grand
jury investigation, then it is a fortiori true that there
is no privilege to refuse to appear before such a grand jury until
the Government demonstrates some "compelling need" for a newsman's
testimony. Other issues were urged upon us, but since they were not
passed upon by the Court of Appeals, we decline to address them in
the first instance.
The decisions in No. 70-85, Branzburg v. Hayes and Branzburg v. Meigs, must be affirmed. Here, petitioner
refused to answer question that directly related to criminal
conduct that he had observed and written about. The Kentucky Court
of Appeals noted that marihuana is defined as a narcotic drug by
statute, Ky.Rev.Stat. § 218.010(14) (1962), and that unlicensed
possession or compounding of it is a felony punishable by both fine
and imprisonment. Ky.Rev.Stat. § 218.210 (1962). It held that
petitioner "saw the commission of the statutory felonies of
unlawful possession of marijuana and the unlawful conversion of it
into hashish," in Branzburg v. Pound, 461 S.W.2d at 346.
Petitioner may be presumed to have observed similar violations of
the state narcotics laws during the research he did for the story
that forms the basis of the subpoena in Branzburg v.
Meigs. In both cases, if what petitioner wrote was true, Page 408 U. S. 709 he had direct information to provide the grand jury concerning
the commission of serious crimes.
The only question presented at the present time in In re
Pappas, No. 70-94, is whether petitioner Pappas must appear
before the grand jury to testify pursuant to subpoena. The
Massachusetts Supreme Judicial Court characterized the record in
this case as "meager," and it is not clear what petitioner will be
asked by the grand jury. It is not even clear that he will be asked
to divulge information received in confidence. We affirm the
decision of the Massachusetts Supreme Judicial Court and hold that
petitioner must appear before the grand jury to answer the
questions put to him, subject, of course, to the supervision of the
presiding judge as to "the propriety, purposes, and scope of the
grand jury inquiry and the pertinence of the probable testimony."
358 Mass. at 614, 266 N.E.2d at 303-304. So ordered. [ Footnote 1 ]
he article contained the following paragraph:
"'I don't know why I'm letting you do this story,' [one
informant] said quietly. 'To make the narcs (narcotics detectives)
mad, I guess. That's the main reason.' However, Larry and his
partner asked for and received a promise that their names would be
changed."
App. 3-4.
[ Footnote 2 ]
The Foreman of the grand jury reported that petitioner Branzburg
had refused to answer the following two questions:
"#1. On November 12, or 13, 1969, who was the person or persons
you observed in possession of Marijuana, about which you wrote an
article in the Courier-Journal on November 15, 1969?"
"#2. On November 12, or 13, 1969, who was the person or persons
you observed compounding Marijuana, producing same to a compound
known as Hashish?"
App. 6.
[ Footnote 3 ]
Judge J. Miles Pound. The respondent in this case, Hon. John P.
Hayes, is the successor of Judge Pound.
[ Footnote 4 ]
Ky.Rev.Stat. § 421.100 provides:
"No person shall be compelled to disclose in any legal
proceeding or trial before any court, or before any grand or petit
jury, or before the presiding officer of any tribunal, or his agent
or agents, or before the General Assembly, or any committee
thereof, or before any city or county legislative body, or any
committee thereof, or elsewhere, the source of any information
procured or obtained by him, and published in a newspaper or by a
radio or television broadcasting station by which he is engaged or
employed, or with which he is connected."
[ Footnote 5 ]
Petitioner's Motion to Quash argued:
"If Mr. Branzburg were required to disclose these confidences to
the Grand Jury, or any other person, he would thereby destroy the
relationship of trust which he presently enjoys with those in the
drug culture. They would refuse to speak to him; they would become
even more reluctant than they are now to speak to any newsman; and
the news media would thereby be vitally hampered in their ability
to cover that views and activities of those involved in the drug
culture."
"The inevitable effect of the subpoena issued to Mr. Branzburg,
if it not be quashed by this Court, will be to suppress vital First
Amendment freedoms of Mr. Branzburg, of the Courier Journal, of the
news media, and of those involved in the drug culture by driving a
wedge of distrust and silence between the news media and the drug
culture. This Court should not sanction a use of its process
entailing so drastic an incursion upon First Amendment freedoms in
the absence of compelling Commonwealth interest in requiring Mr.
Branzburg's appearance before the Grand Jury. It is insufficient
merely to protect Mr. Branzburg's right to silence after he appears
before the Grand Jury. This Court should totally excuse Mr.
Branzburg from responding to the subpoena and even entering the
Grand Jury room. Once Mr. Branzburg is required to go behind the
closed doors of the Grand Jury room, his effectiveness as a
reporter in these areas is totally destroyed. The secrecy that
surrounds Grand Jury testimony necessarily introduces uncertainties
in the minds of those who fear a betrayal of their
confidences."
App. 43-44.
[ Footnote 6 ]
After the Kentucky Court of Appeals' decision in Branzburg
v. Meigs was announced, petitioner filed a rehearing motion in Branzburg v. Pound suggesting that the court had not
passed upon his First Amendment argument and calling to the court's
attention the recent Ninth Circuit decision in Caldwell v.
United States, 434 F.2d 1081 (1970). On Jan. 22, 1971, the
court denied petitioner's motion and filed an amended opinion in
the case, adding a footnote, 461
S.W.2d 345 , 346 n. 1, to indicate that petitioner had abandoned
his First Amendment argument and elected to rely wholly on
Ky.Rev.Stat. § 421.100 when he filed a Supplemental Memorandum
before oral argument. In his Petition for Prohibition and Mandamus,
petitioner had clearly relied on the First Amendment, and he had
filed his Supplemental Memorandum in response to the State's
Memorandum in Opposition to the granting of the writs. As its title
indicates, this Memorandum was complementary to petitioner's
earlier Petition, and it dealt primarily with the State's
construction of the phrase "source of any information" in
Ky.Rev.Stat. § 421.100. The passage that the Kentucky Court of
Appeals cited to indicate abandonment of petitioner's First
Amendment claim is as follows:
"Thus, the controversy continues as to whether a newsman's
source of information should be privileged. However, that question
is not before the Court in this case. The Legislature of Kentucky
has settled the issue, having decided that a newsman's source of
information is to be privileged. Because of this, there is no point
in citing Professor Wigmore and other authorities who speak against
the grant of such a privilege. The question has been many times
debated, and the Legislature has spoken. The only question before
the Court is the construction of the term 'source of information'
as it was intended by the Legislature."
Though the passage itself is somewhat unclear, the surrounding
discussion indicates that petitioner was asserting here that the
question of whether a common law privilege should be recognized was
irrelevant, since the legislature had already enacted a statute. In
his earlier discussion, petitioner had analyzed certain cases in
which the First Amendment argument was made, but indicated that it
was not necessary to reach this question if the statutory phrase
"source of any information" were interpreted expansively. We do not
interpret this discussion as indicating that petitioner was
abandoning his First Amendment claim if the Kentucky Court of
Appeals did not agree with his statutory interpretation argument,
and we hold that the constitutional question in Branzburg v.
Pound was properly preserved for review.
[ Footnote 7 ]
Petitioner's news films of this event were made available to the
Bristol County District Attorney. App. 4.
[ Footnote 8 ]
The case was reported by the superior court directly to the
Supreme Judicial Court for an interlocutory ruling under
Mass.Gen.Laws, c. 278, § 30A and Mass.Gen.Laws, c. 231, § 111
(1959). The Supreme Judicial Court's decision appears at 358 Mass.
604, 266
N.E.2d 297 (1971).
[ Footnote 9 ]
"We do not have before us the text of any specific questions
which Pappas has refused to answer before the grand jury, or any
petition to hold him for contempt for his refusal. We have only
general statements concerning (a) the inquiries of the grand jury,
and (b) the materiality of the testimony sought from Pappas. The
record does not show the expected nature of his testimony or what
likelihood there is of being able to obtain that testimony from
persons other than news gatherers."
358 Mass. at 606-607, 266 N.E.2d at 299 (footnote omitted).
[ Footnote 10 ]
The court expressly declined to consider, however, appearances
of newsmen before legislative or administrative bodies. Id. at 612 n. 10, 266 N.E.2d at 303 n. 10.
[ Footnote 11 ]
The court noted that "a presiding judge may consider in his
discretion" the argument that the use of newsmen as witnesses is
likely to result in unnecessary or burdensome use of their work
product, id. at 614 n. 13, 266 N.E.2d at 304 n. 13, and
cautioned that:
"We do not suggest that a general investigation of mere
political or group association of persons, without substantial
relation to criminal events, may not be viewed by a judge in a
somewhat different manner from an investigation of particular
criminal events concerning which a newsman may have knowledge." Id. at 614 n. 14, 266 N.E.2d at 304 n. 14.
[ Footnote 12 ]
The subpoena ordered production of
"[n]otes and tape recordings of interviews covering the period
from January 1, 1969, to date, reflecting statements made for
publication by officers and spokesmen for the Black Panther Party
concerning the aims and purposes of said organization and the
activities of said organization, its officers, staff, personnel,
and members, including specifically but not limited to interviews
given by David Hilliard and Raymond 'Masai' Hewitt."
App. 20.
[ Footnote 13 ]
The New York Times was granted standing to intervene as a party
on the motion to quash the subpoenas. Application of
Caldwell, 311 F.
Supp. 358 , 359 (ND Cal, 1970). It did not file an appeal from
the District Court's contempt citation, and it did not seek
certiorari here. It has filed an amicus curiae brief,
however.
[ Footnote 14 ]
Respondent appealed from the District Court's April 6 denial of
his motion to quash on April 17, 1970, and the Government moved to
dismiss that appeal on the ground that the order was interlocutory.
On May 12, 1970, the Ninth Circuit dismissed the appeal without
opinion.
[ Footnote 15 ]
The Government did not file a cross-appeal, and did not
challenge the validity of the District Court protective order in
the Court of Appeals.
[ Footnote 16 ]
The petition presented a single question:
"Whether a newspaper reporter who has published articles about
an organization can, under the First Amendment, properly refuse to
appear before a grand jury investigating possible crimes by members
of that organization who have been quoted in the published
articles."
[ Footnote 17 ] Curtis Publishing Co. v. Butts, 388 U.
S. 130 , 388 U. S. 145 (1967) (opinion of Harlan, J.); New York Times Co. v.
Sullivan, 376 U. S. 254 , 376 U. S. 270 (1964); Talley v. California, 362 U. S.
60 , 362 U. S. 64 -65
(1960); Bridges v. California, 314 U.
S. 252 , 314 U. S. 263 (1941); Grosjean v. American Press Co., 297 U.
S. 233 , 297 U. S. 250 (1936); Near v. Minnesota, 283 U.
S. 697 , 283 U. S. 722 (1931).
[ Footnote 18 ] NAACP v. Button, 371 U. S. 415 , 371 U. S. 439 (1963); Thomas v. Collins, 323 U.
S. 516 , 323 U. S. 530 (1945); DeGregory v. Attorney General of New Hampshire, 383 U. S. 825 , 383 U. S. 829 (1966); Bates v. Little Rock, 361 U.
S. 516 , 361 U. S. 524 (1960); Schneider v. State, 308 U.
S. 147 , 308 U. S. 161 (1939); NAACP v. Alabama, 357 U.
S. 449 , 357 U. S. 464 (1958).
[ Footnote 19 ] Freedman v. Maryland, 380 U. S. 51 , 380 U. S. 56 (1965); NAACP v. Alabama, 377 U.
S. 288 , 377 U. S. 307 (1964); Martin v. City of Struthers, 319 U.
S. 141 , 319 U. S. 147 (1943); Elfbrandt v. Russell, 384 U. S.
11 , 384 U. S. 18 (1966).
[ Footnote 20 ]
There has been a great deal of writing in recent years on the
existence of a newsman's constitutional right of nondisclosure of
confidential information. See, e.g., Beaver, The Newsman's
Code, The Claim of Privilege and Everyman's Right to Evidence, 47
Ore.L.Rev. 243 (1968); Guest & Stanzler, The Constitutional
Argument for Newsmen Concealing Their Sources, 64 Nw.U.L.Rev. 18
(1969); Note, Reporters and Their Sources: The Constitutional Right
to a Confidential Relationship, 80 Yale L.J. 317 (1970); Comment,
The Newsman's Privilege: Government Investigations, Criminal
Prosecutions and Private Litigation, 58 Calif.L.Rev. 1198 (1970);
Note, The Right of the Press to Gather Information, 71 Col.L.Rev.
838 (1971); Nelson, The Newsmen's Privilege Against Disclosure of
Confidential Sources and Information, 24 Vand.L.Rev. 667
(1971).
[ Footnote 21 ]
"In general, then, the mere fact that a communication was made
in express confidence, or in the implied confidence of a
confidential relation, does not create a privilege."
". . . No pledge of privacy nor oath of secrecy can avail
against demand for the truth in a court of justice."
8 J. Wigmore, Evidence § 2286 (McNaughton rev.1961). This was
not always the rule at common law, however . In 17th century
England, the obligations of honor among gentlemen were occasionally
recognized as privileging from compulsory disclosure information
obtained in exchange for a promise of confidence. See Bulstrod
v. Letchmere, 2 Freem. 6, 22 Eng.Rep. 1019 (1676); Lord
Grey's Trial, 9 How.St.Tr. 127 (1682).
[ Footnote 22 ]
"There are few restrictions on action which could not be clothed
by ingenious argument in the garb of decreased data flow. For
example, the prohibition of unauthorized entry into the White House
diminishes the citizen's opportunities to gather information he
might find relevant to his opinion of the way the country is being
run, but that does not make entry into the White House a First
Amendment right."
381 U.S. at 381 U. S.
117 .
[ Footnote 23 ]
"Historically, [the grand jury] has been regarded as a primary
security to the innocent against hasty, malicious and oppressive
persecution; it serves the invaluable function in our society of
standing between the accuser and the accused . . . to determine
whether a charge is founded upon reason or was dictated by an
intimidating power or by malice and personal ill will." Wood v. Georgia, 370 U. S. 375 , 370 U. S. 390 (1962) (footnote omitted).
[ Footnote 24 ]
It has been held that "infamous" punishments include confinement
at hard labor, United States v. Moreland, 258 U.
S. 433 (1922); incarceration in a penitentiary, Macking v. United States, 117 U.
S. 348 (1886); and imprisonment for more than a year, Barkman v. Sanford, 162 F.2d 592 (CA5), cert.
denied, 332 U.S. 816 (1947). Fed.Rule Crim.Proc. 7(a) has
codified these holdings:
"An offense which may be punished by death shall be prosecuted
by indictment. An offense which may be punished by imprisonment for
a term exceeding one year or at hard labor shall be prosecuted by
indictment or, if indictment is waived, it may be prosecuted by
information. Any other offense may be prosecuted by indictment or
by information."
[ Footnote 25 ]
Although indictment by grand jury is not part of the due process
of law guaranteed to state criminal defendants by the Fourteenth
Amendment, Hurtado v. California, 110 U.
S. 516 (1884), a recent study reveals that 32 States
require that certain kinds of criminal prosecutions be initiated by
indictment. Spain, The Grand Jury, Past and Present: A Survey, 2
Am.Crim. L.Q. 119, 126-142 (1964). In the 18 States in which the
prosecutor may proceed by information, the grand jury is retained
as an alternative means of invoking the criminal process and as an
investigative tool. Ibid. [ Footnote 26 ]
Jeremy Bentham vividly illustrated this maxim:
"Are men of the first rank and consideration -- are men high in
office -- men whose time is not less valuable to the public than to
themselves -- are such men to be forced to quit their business,
their functions, and what is more than all, their pleasure, at the
beck of every idle or malicious adversary, to dance attendance upon
every petty cause? Yes, as far as it is necessary, they and
everybody. Were the Prince of Wales, the Archbishop of Canterbury,
and the Lord High Chancellor, to be passing by in the same coach,
while a chimney-sweeper and a barrow-woman were in dispute about a
halfpennyworth of apples, and the chimney-sweeper or the
barrowwoman were to think proper to call upon them for their
evidence, could they refuse it? No, most certainly."
4 The Works of Jeremy Bentham 320-321 (J. Bowring ed. 1843). In United States v. Burr, 25 F. Cas. 30, 34 (No. 14,692d) (CC
Va. 1807), Chief Justice Marshall, sitting on Circuit, opined that,
in proper circumstances, a subpoena could be issued to the
President of the United States.
[ Footnote 27 ]
Thus, far, 17 States have provided some type of statutory
protection to a newsman's confidential sources:
Ala.Code, Tit. 7, § 370 (1960); Alaska Stat. §09.25.150 (Supp.
1971); Ariz.Rev.Stat.Ann. § 12-2237 (Supp. 1971-1972);
Ark.Stat.Ann. § 43-917 (1964); Cal. Evid.Code § 1070 (Supp. 1972);
Ind.Ann.Stat. § 2-1733 (1968); Ky.Rev.Stat. § 421.100 (1962);
La.Rev.Stat.Ann. §§ 45:1451-45:1454 (Supp. 1972); Md.Ann.Code, Art.
35, § 2 (1971); Mich.Comp.Laws § 767.5a (Supp. 1956),
Mich.Stat.Ann. § 28.945(1) (1954); Mont.Rev.Codes Ann. § 93-601-2
(1964); Nev.Rev.Stat. § 49.275 (1971); N.J.Rev.Stat. §§ 2A:84A-21,
2A:84A-29 (Supp. 1972-1973); N.M.Stat.Ann. § 20-1-12.1 (1970); N.Y.
Civ. Rights Law § 79-h (Supp 1971-1972); Ohio Rev.Code Ann. §
2739.12 (1954); Pa.Stat.Ann., Tit. 28, § 330 (Supp. 1972-1973).
[ Footnote 28 ]
Such legislation has been introduced, however. See,
e.g., S. 1311, 92d Cong., 1st Sess. (1971); S. 3552, 91st
Cong., 2d Sess. (1970); H.R. 16328, H R. 16704, 91st Cong., 2d
Sess. (1970); S. 1851, 88th Cong., 1st Sess. (1963); H.R. 8519,
H.R. 7787, 88th Cong., 1st Sess. (1963); S. 965, 86th Cong., 1st
Sess. (1959); H.R. 355, 86th Cong., 1st Sess. (1959). For a general
analysis of proposed congressional legislation, see Staff
of Senate Committee on the Judiciary, 89th Cong., 2d Sess., The
Newsman's Privilege (Comm.Print 1966).
[ Footnote 29 ]
The creation of new testimonial privileges has been met with
disfavor by commentators, since such privileges obstruct the search
for truth. Wigmore condemns such privileges as "so many derogations
from a positive general rule [that everyone is obligated to testify
when properly summoned]" and as "obstacle[s] to the administration
of justice." 8 J. Wigmore, Evidence § 2192 (McNaughton rev.1961).
His criticism that " all privileges of exemption from this duty
are exceptional, and are therefore to be discountenanced," id. at § 2192, p. 73 (emphasis in original) has been
frequently echoed. Morgan, Foreword, Model Code of Evidence 22-30
(1942); 2 Z. Chafee, Government and Mass Communications 496-497
(1947); Report of ABA Committee on Improvements in the Law of
Evidence, 63 A.B.A. Reports 595 (1938); C. McCormick, Evidence 159
(2d ed.1972); Chafee, Privileged Communications: Is Justice Served
or Obstructed by Closing the Doctor's Mouth on the Witness Stand?,
52 Yale L.J. 607 (1943); Ladd, Privileges, 1969 Law & the
Social Order 555, 556; 58 Am.Jur., Witnesses § 546 (1948); 97
C.J.S., Witnesses § 259 (1957); McMann v. Securities and Exchange
Commission, 87 F.2d 377, 378 (CA2 1937) (L. Hand, J.). Neither the
ALI's Model Code of Evidence (1942), the Uniform Rules of Evidence
of the National Conference of Commissioners on Uniform State Laws
(1953), nor the Proposed Rules of Evidence for the United States
Courts and Magistrates (rev. ed.1971) has included a newsman's
privilege.
[ Footnote 30 ]
The holding in this case involved a construction of the Contempt
of Court Act of 1831, 4 Stat. 487, which permitted summary trial of
contempts "so near [to the court] as to obstruct the administration
of justice." The Court held that the Act required only that the
conduct have a "direct tendency to prevent and obstruct the
discharge of judicial duty." 247 U.S. at 247 U. S. 419 .
This view was overruled and the Act given a much narrower reading
in Nye v. United States, 313 U. S. 33 , 313 U. S. 47 -52
(1941). See Bloom v. Illinois, 391 U.
S. 194 , 391 U. S.
205 -206 (1968).
[ Footnote 31 ]
Respondent Caldwell attached a number of affidavits from
prominent newsmen to his initial motion to quash, which detail the
experiences of such journalists after they have been subpoenaed.
Appendix to No. 757, pp. 221.
[ Footnote 32 ] Cf., e.g., the results of a study conducted by Guest
& Stanzler, which appears as an appendix to their article, supra, n 20. A
number of editors of daily newspapers of varying circulation were
asked the question,
"Excluding one- or two-sentence gossip items, on the average,
how many stories based on information received in confidence are
published in your paper each year? Very rough estimate."
Answers varied significantly, e.g., "Virtually
innumerable," Tucson Daily Citizen (41,969 daily circ.), "Too many
to remember," Los Angeles Herald-Examiner (718,221 daily circ.),
"Occasionally," Denver Post (252,084 daily circ.), "Rarely,"
Cleveland Plain Dealer (370,499 daily circ.), "Very rare, some
politics," Oregon Journal (146,403 daily circ.). This study did not
purport to measure the extent of deterrence of informants caused by
subpoenas to the press.
[ Footnote 33 ]
In his Press Subpoenas: An Empirical and Legal Analysis, Study
Report of the Reporters' Committee on Freedom of the Press 12,
Prof. Vince Blasi discusses these methodological problems. Prof.
Blasi's survey found that slightly more than half of the 975
reporters questioned said that they relied on regular confidential
sources for at least 10% of their stories. Id. at 21. Of
this group of reporters, only 8% were able to say with some
certainty that their professional functioning had been adversely
affected by the threat of subpoena; another 11% were not certain
whether or not they had been adversely affected. Id. at
53.
[ Footnote 34 ] See Statute of Westminster First, 3 Edw. 1, c. 9, p. 43
(1275); Statute of Westminster Second, 13 Edw. 1, c. 6, pp. 114-115
(1285); Sheriffs Act of 1887, 50 & 51 Vict., c. 55, § 8(1); 4
W. Blackstone, Commentaries *293-295; 2 W. Holdsworth, History of
English Law 80-81, 101-102 (3d ed.1927); 4 id. at
521-522.
[ Footnote 35 ] See, e.g., Scope's Case, referred to in 3 Coke's
Institute 36; Rex v. Cowper, 5 Mod. 206, 87 Eng.Rep. 611
(1696); Proceedings under a Special Commission for the County of
York, 31 How.St.Tr. 965, 969 (1813); Sykes v. Director of
Public Prosecutions, [1961] 3 W.L.R. 371. But see Glazebrook, Misprision of Felony -- Shadow or Phantom?, 8
Am.J.Legal Hist. 189 (1964). See also Act 5 & 6 Edw.
6, c. 11 (1552).
[ Footnote 36 ]
This statute has been construed, however, to require both
knowledge of a crime and some affirmative act of concealment or
participation. Bratton v. United States, 73 F.2d 795 (CA10
1934); United States v. Farrar, 38 F.2d
515 , 516 (Mass.), aff'd on other grounds, 281 U.
S. 624 (1930); United States v. Norman, 391
F.2d 212 (CA6), cert. denied, 390 U.S. 1014 (1968); Lancey v. United States, 356 F.2d 407 (CA9), cert.
denied, 385 U.S. 922 (1966). Cf. 20 U.
S. Brooks, 7 Wheat. 556, 20 U. S. 575 (1822) (Marshall, C.J.).
[ Footnote 37 ]
Though the constitutional argument for a newsman's privilege has
been put forward very recently, newsmen have contended for a number
of years that such a privilege was desirable. See, e.g., Siebert & Ryniker, Press Winning Fight to Guard Sources, Editor
& Publisher, Sept. 1, 1934, pp. 9, 36-37; G. Bird & F.
Merwin, The Press and Society 592 (1971). The first newsman's
privilege statute was enacted by Maryland in 1896, and currently is
codified as Md.Ann.Code, Art. 35, § 2 (1971).
[ Footnote 38 ]
A list of recent subpoenas to the news media is contained in the
appendix to the brief of amicus New York Times in No.
757.
[ Footnote 39 ]
"Under the case-by-case method of developing rules, it will be
difficult for potential informants and reporters to predict whether
testimony will be compelled, since the decision will turn on the
judge's ad hoc assessment in different fact settings of
'importance' or 'relevance' in relation to the free press interest.
A 'general' deterrent effect is likely to result. This type of
effect stems from the vagueness of the tests and from the
uncertainty attending their application. For example, if a
reporter's information goes to the 'heart of the matter' in
Situation X, another reporter and informant who subsequently are in
Situation Y will not know if 'heart of the matter rule X' will be
extended to them, and deterrence will thereby result. Leaving
substantial discretion with judges to delineate those 'situations'
in which rules of 'relevance' or 'importance' apply would therefore
seem to undermine significantly the effectiveness of a
reporter-informer privilege."
Note, Reporters and Their Sources: The Constitutional Right to a
Confidential Relationship, 80 Yale L.J. 317, 341 (1970). In re Grand Jury Witnesses, 322 F.
Supp. 573 (ND Cal.1970), illustrates the impact of this ad
hoc approach. Here, the grand jury was, as in Caldwell, investigating the Black Panther Party, and
was
"inquiring into matters which involve possible violations of
Congressional acts passed to protect the person of the President
(18 U.S.C. § 1751), to free him from threats (18 U.S.C. § 871), to
protect our armed forces from unlawful interference (18 U.S.C. §
2387), conspiracy to commit the foregoing offenses (18 U.S.C. §
371), and related statutes prohibiting acts directed against the
security of the government." Id. at 577. The two witnesses, reporters for a Black
Panther Party newspaper, were subpoenaed and given Fifth Amendment
immunity against criminal prosecution, and they claimed a First
Amendment journalist's privilege. The District Court entered a
protective order, allowing them to refuse to divulge confidential
information until the Government demonstrated "a compelling and
overriding national interest in requiring the testimony of [the
witnesses] which cannot be served by any alternative means." Id. at 574. The Government claimed that it had information
that the witnesses had associated with persons who had conspired to
perform some of the criminal acts that the grand jury was
investigating. The court held the Government had met its burden and
ordered the witnesses to testify:
"The whole point of the investigation is to identify persons
known to the [witnesses] who may have engaged in activities
violative of the above indicated statutes, and also to ascertain
the details of their alleged unlawful activities. All questions
directed to such objectives of the investigation are unquestionably
relevant, and any other evaluation thereof by the Court without
knowledge of the facts before the Grand Jury would clearly
constitute 'undue interference of the Court.'" Id. at 577.
Another illustration is provided by State v. Knops, 49
Wis.2d 647, 183 N.W.2d
93 (1971), in which a grand jury was investigating the August
24, 1970, bombing of Sterling Hall on the University of Wisconsin
Madison campus. On August 26, 1970, an "underground" newspaper, the
Madison Kaleidoscope, printed a front-page story entitled "The
Bombers Tell Why and What Next -- Exclusive to Kaleidoscope." An
editor of the Kaleidoscope was subpoenaed, appeared, asserted his
Fifth Amendment right against self-incrimination, was given
immunity, and then pleaded that he had a First Amendment privilege
against disclosing his confidential informants. The Wisconsin
Supreme Court rejected his claim and upheld his contempt
sentence:
"[Appellant] faces five very narrow and specific questions, all
of which are founded on information which he himself has already
volunteered. The purpose of these questions is very clear. The need
for answers to them is 'overriding,' to say the least. The need for
these answers is nothing short of the public's need (and right) to
protect itself from physical attack by apprehending the
perpetrators of such attacks."
49 Wis.2d at 658, 183 N.W.2d at 98-99.
[ Footnote 40 ]
Such a privilege might be claimed by group that set up
newspapers in order to engage in criminal activity and to therefore
be insulated from grand jury inquiry, regardless of Fifth Amendment
grants of immunity. It might appear that such "ham" newspaper would
be easily distinguishable, yet the First Amendment ordinarily
prohibits courts from inquiring into the content of expression,
except in cases of obscenity or libel, and protects speech and
publication regardless of their motivation, orthodoxy,
truthfulness, timeliness, or taste. New York Times Co. v.
Sullivan, 376 U.S. at 376 U. S. 269 -270; Kingsley Pictures Corp. v.
Regents, 360 U. S. 684 , 360 U. S. 689 (1959); Winters v. New York, 333 U.
S. 507 , 333 U. S. 510 (1948); Thomas v. Collins, 323 U.S. at 323 U. S. 537 .
By affording a privilege to some organs of communication but not to
others, court would inevitably be discriminating on the basis of
content.
[ Footnote 41 ]
The Guidelines for Subpoenas to the News Media were first
announced in a speech by the Attorney General on August 10, 1970,
and then were expressed in Department of Justice Memo. No. 692
(Sept. 2, 1970), which was sent to all United States Attorneys by
the Assistant Attorney General in charge of the Criminal Division.
The Guidelines state that:
"The Department of Justice recognizes that compulsory process in
some circumstances may have a limiting effect on the exercise of
First Amendment rights. In determining whether to request issuance
of a subpoena to the press, the approach in every case must be to
weigh that limiting effect against the public interest to be served
in the fair administration of justice,"
and that:
"The Department of Justice does not consider the press 'an
investigative arm of the government.' Therefore, all reasonable
attempts should be made to obtain information from non-press
sources before there is any consideration of subpoenaing the
press."
The Guidelines provide for negotiations with the press, and
require the express authorization of the Attorney General for such
subpoenas. The principles to be applied in authorizing such
subpoenas are stated to be whether there is "sufficient reason to
believe that the information sought [from the journalist] is
essential to a successful investigation" and whether the Government
has unsuccessfully attempted to obtain the information from
alternative non-press sources. The Guidelines provide, however,
that, in "emergencies and other unusual situations," subpoenas may
be issued which do not exactly conform to the Guidelines.
[ Footnote 42 ] Cf. Younger v. Harris, 401 U. S.
37 , 401 U. S. 49 , 401 U. S. 53 -54
(1971).
MR. JUSTICE POWELL, concurring.
I add this brief statement to emphasize what seems to me to be
the limited nature of the Court's holding. The Court does not hold
that newsmen, subpoenaed to testify before a grand jury, are
without constitutional rights with respect to the gathering of news
or in safeguarding their sources. Certainly, we do not hold, as
suggested in MR. JUSTICE STEWART's dissenting opinion, that state
and federal authorities are free to "annex" the news media as "an
investigative arm of government." The solicitude repeatedly shown
by this Court for First Amendment freedoms should be sufficient
assurance against any such effort, even if one seriously believed
that the media -- properly free and untrammeled in the fullest
sense of these terms -- were not able to protect themselves.
As indicated in the concluding portion of the opinion, the Court
states that no harassment of newsmen will Page 408 U. S. 710 be tolerated. If a newsman believes that the grand jury
investigation is not being conducted in good faith, he is not
without remedy. Indeed, if the newsman is called upon to give
information bearing only a remote and tenuous relationship to the
subject of the investigation, or if he has some other reason to
believe that his testimony implicates confidential source
relationships without a legitimate need of law enforcement, he will
have access to the court on a motion to quash, and an appropriate
protective order may be entered. The asserted claim to privilege
should be judged on its facts by the striking of a proper balance
between freedom of the press and the obligation of all citizens to
give relevant testimony with respect to criminal conduct. The
balance of these vital constitutional and societal interests on a
case-by-case basis accords with the tried and traditional way of
adjudicating such questions. * In short, the courts will be available to newsmen under
circumstances where legitimate First Amendment interests require
protection. Page 408 U. S. 711 * It is to be remembered that Caldwell asserts a constitutional
privilege not even to appear before the grand jury unless a court
decides that the Government has made a showing that meets the three
preconditions specified in the dissenting opinion of MR. JUSTICE
STEWART. To be sure, this would require a "balancing" of interests
by the court, but under circumstances and constraints significantly
different from the balancing that will be appropriate under the
court's decision. The newsman witness, like all other witnesses,
will have to appear; he will not be in a position to litigate at
the threshold the State's very authority to subpoena him. Moreover,
absent the constitutional preconditions that Caldwell and that
dissenting opinion would impose as heavy burdens of proof to be
carried by the State, the court -- when called upon to protect a
newsman from improper or prejudicial questioning -- would be free
to balance the competing interests on their merits in the
particular case. The new constitutional rule endorsed by that
dissenting opinion would, as a practical matter, defeat such a fair
balancing and the essential societal interest in the detection and
prosecution of crime would be heavily subordinated.
MR. JUSTICE DOUGLAS, dissenting in No. 757, United States v.
Caldwell. Caldwell, a black, is a reporter for the New York Times and was
assigned to San Francisco with the hope that he could report on the
activities and attitudes of the Black Panther Party. Caldwell in
time gained the complete confidence of its members, and wrote
in-depth articles about them.
He was subpoenaed to appear and testify before a federal grand
jury and to bring with him notes and tapes covering interviews with
its members. A hearing on a motion to quash was held. The District
Court ruled that, while Caldwell had to appear before the grand
jury, he did not have to reveal confidential communications unless
the court was satisfied that there was a "compelling and overriding
national interest." See 311 F.
Supp. 358 , 362. Caldwell filed a notice of appeal and the Court
of Appeals dismissed the appeal without opinion.
Shortly thereafter, a new grand jury was impaneled and it issued
a new subpoena for Caldwell to testify. On a motion to quash, the
District Court issued an order substantially identical to its
earlier one.
Caldwell refused to appear, and was held in contempt. On appeal,
the Court of Appeals vacated the judgment of contempt. It said that
the revealing of confidential sources of information jeopardized a
First Amendment freedom and that Caldwell did not have to appear
before the grand jury absent a showing that there was a "compelling
and overriding national interest" in pursuing such an
interrogation.
The District Court had found that Caldwell's knowledge of the
activities of the Black Panthers "derived in substantial part" from
information obtained "within the scope of a relationship of trust
and confidence." Id. at 361. It also found that
confidential relationships of this sort are commonly developed and
maintained by Page 408 U. S. 712 professional journalists, and are indispensable to their work of
gathering, analyzing, and publishing the news.
The District Court further had found that compelled disclosure
of information received by a journalist within the scope of such
confidential relationships jeopardized those relationships, and
thereby impaired the journalist's ability to gather, analyze, and
publish the news.
The District Court, finally, had found that, without a
protective order delimiting the scope of interrogation of Earl
Caldwell by the grand jury, his appearance and examination before
the jury would severely impair and damage his confidential
relationships with members of the Black Panther Party and other
militants, and thereby severely impair and damage his ability to
gather, analyze, and publish news concerning them; and that it
would also damage and impair the abilities of all reporters to
gather, analyze, and publish news concerning them.
The Court of Appeals agreed with the findings of the District
Court, but held that Caldwell did not have to appear at all before
the grand jury absent a "compelling need" shown by the Government.
434 F.2d 1081.
It is my view that there is no "compelling need" that can be
shown which qualifies the reporter's immunity from appearing or
testifying before a grand jury, unless the reporter himself is
implicated in a crime. His immunity, in my view, is therefore quite
complete, for, absent his involvement in a crime, the First
Amendment protects him against an appearance before a grand jury,
and, if he is involved in a crime, the Fifth Amendment stands as a
barrier. Since, in my view, there is no area of inquiry not
protected by a privilege, the reporter need not appear for the
futile purpose of invoking one to each question. And since, in my
view, a newsman has an absolute right not to appear before a grand
jury, it follows for me that a journalist who voluntarily appears
before that body may invoke his First Amendment privilege to
specific questions. Page 408 U. S. 713 The basic issue is the extent to which the First Amendment
(which is applicable to investigating committees, Watkins v.
United States, 354 U. S. 178 ; NAACP v. Alabama, 357 U. S. 449 , 357 U. S. 463 ; Gibson v. Florida Legislative Investigation Committee, 372 U. S. 539 ; Baird v. State Bar of Arizona, 401 U. S.
1 , 401 U. S. 6 -7; In re Stolar, 401 U. S. 23 ) must
yield to the Government's asserted need to know a reporter's
unprinted information.
The starting point for decision pretty well marks the range
within which the end result lies. The New York Times, whose
reporting functions are at issue here, takes the amazing position
that First Amendment rights are to be balanced against other needs
or conveniences of government. [ Footnote 2/1 ] My belief is that all of the "balancing"
was done by those who wrote the Bill of Rights. By casting the
First Amendment in absolute terms, they repudiated the timid,
watered-down, emasculated versions of the First Amendment which
both the Government and the New York Times advance in the case.
My view is close to that of the late Alexander Meiklejohn:
[ Footnote 2/2 ]
"For the understanding of these principles, it is essential to
keep clear the crucial difference between 'the rights' of the
governed and 'the powers' of the governors. And at this point, the
title 'Bill of Rights' is lamentably inaccurate as a
designation Page 408 U. S. 714 of the first ten amendments. They are not a 'Bill of Rights,'
but a 'Bill of Powers and Rights.' The Second through the Ninth
Amendments limit the powers of the subordinate agencies in order
that due regard shall be paid to the private 'rights of the
governed.' The First and Tenth Amendments protect the governing
'powers' of the people from abridgment by the agencies which are
established as their servants. In the field of our 'rights,' each
one of us can claim 'due process of law.' In the field of our
governing 'powers,' the notion of 'due process' is irrelevant."
He also believed that
"[s]elf-government can exist only insofar as the voters acquire
the intelligence, integrity, sensitivity, and generous devotion to
the general welfare that, in theory, casting a ballot is assumed to
express,' [ Footnote 2/3 ]"
and that
"[p]ublic discussions of public issues, together with the
spreading of information and opinion bearing on those issues, must
have a freedom unabridged by our agents. Though they govern us, we,
in a deeper sense, govern them. Over our governing, they have no
power. Over their governing, we have sovereign power. [ Footnote 2/4 ]"
Two principles which follow from this understanding of the First
Amendment are at stake here. One is that the people, the ultimate
governors, must have absolute freedom of, and therefore privacy of,
their individual opinions and beliefs regardless of how suspect or
strange they may appear to others. Ancillary to that principle is
the conclusion that an individual must also have absolute privacy
over whatever information he may generate in the course of testing
his opinions and beliefs. In this regard, Caldwell's status as a
reporter is less relevant than is his status as a student who
affirmatively pursued empirical research to enlarge his own
intellectual viewpoint. Page 408 U. S. 715 The second principle is that effective self-government cannot
succeed unless the people are immersed in a steady, robust,
unimpeded, and uncensored flow of opinion and reporting which are
continuously subjected to critique, rebuttal, and reexamination. In
this respect, Caldwell's status as a news gatherer and an integral
part of that process becomes critical. I Government has many interests that compete with the First
Amendment. Congressional investigations determine how existing laws
actually operate or whether new laws are needed. While
congressional committees have broad powers, they are subject to the
restraints of the First Amendment. As we said in Watkins v.
United States, 354 U.S. at 354 U. S.
197 :
"Clearly, an investigation is subject to the command that the
Congress shall make no law abridging freedom of speech or press or
assembly. While it is true that there is no statute to be reviewed,
and that an investigation is not a law, nevertheless an
investigation is part of lawmaking. It is justified solely as an
adjunct to the legislative process. The First Amendment may be
invoked against infringement of the protected freedoms by law or by
lawmaking."
Hence, matters of belief, ideology, religious practices, social
philosophy, and the like are beyond the pale and of no rightful
concern of government, unless the belief or the speech, or other
expression has been translated into action. West Virginia State
Board of Education v. Barnette, 319 U.
S. 624 , 319 U. S. 642 ; Baird v. State Bar of Arizona, 401 U.S. at 401 U. S. 6 -7; In re Stolar, 401 U. S. 23 .
Also at stake here is Caldwell's privacy of association. We have
held that
"[i]nviolability of privacy in group association may in many
circumstances be indispensable to preservation of freedom of
association, particularly where a group espouses dissident
beliefs." NAACP v. Page 408 U. S. 716 Alabama, 357 U.S. at 357 U. S. 462 ; NAACP v. Button, 371 U. S. 415 .
As I said in Gibson v. Florida Legislative Investigation
Committee, 372 U.S. at 372 U. S.
565 :
"the associational rights protected by the First Amendment . . .
cover the entire spectrum in political ideology as well as in art,
in journalism, in teaching, and in religion. . . . [G]overnment is
. . . precluded from probing the intimacies of spiritual and
intellectual relationships in the myriad of such societies and
groups that exist in this country, regardless of the
legislative purpose sought to be served. . . . If that is not
true, I see no barrier to investigation of newspapers, churches,
political parties, clubs, societies, unions, and any other
association for their political, economic, social, philosophical,
or religious views."
(Concurring opinion.) (Emphasis added.)
The Court has not always been consistent in its protection of
these First Amendment rights, and has sometimes allowed a
government interest to override the absolutes of the First
Amendment. For example, under the banner of the "clear and present
danger" test, [ Footnote 2/5 ] and
later under the influence of the "balancing" formula, [ Footnote 2/6 ] the Page 408 U. S. 717 Court has permitted men to be penalized not for any harmful
conduct, but solely for holding unpopular beliefs.
In recent years, we have said over and over again that, where
First Amendment rights are concerned, any regulation "narrowly
drawn," [ Footnote 2/7 ] must be
"compelling," and not Page 408 U. S. 718 merely "rational" as is the case where other activities are
concerned. [ Footnote 2/8 ] But the
"compelling" interest in regulation neither includes paring down or
diluting the right nor Page 408 U. S. 719 embraces penalizing one solely for his intellectual viewpoint;
it concerns the State's interest, for example, in regulating the
time and place or perhaps manner of exercising First Amendment
rights. Thus, one has an undoubted right to read and proclaim the
First Amendment in the classroom or in a park. But he would not
have the right to blare it forth from a sound truck rolling through
the village or city at 2 a.m. The distinction drawn in Cantwell
v. Connecticut, 310 U. S. 296 , 310 U. S.
303 -304, should still stand:
"[T]he Amendment embraces two concepts, -- freedom to believe
and freedom to act. The first is absolute, but, in the nature of
things, the second cannot be. [ Footnote
2/9 ]"
Under these precedents, there is no doubt that Caldwell could
not be brought before the grand jury for the sole purpose of
exposing his political beliefs. Yet today the Court effectively
permits that result under the guise of allowing an attempt to
elicit from him "factual information." To be sure, the inquiry will
be couched only in terms of extracting Caldwell's recollection of
what was said to him during the interviews, but the fact remains
that his questions to the Panthers, and therefore the respective
answers, were guided by Caldwell's own preconceptions and views
about the Black Panthers. His Page 408 U. S. 720 entire experience was shaped by his intellectual viewpoint.
Unlike the random bystander, those who affirmatively set out to
test a hypothesis, as here, have no tidy means of segregating
subjective opinion from objective facts.
Sooner or later, any test which provides less than blanket
protection to beliefs and associations will be twisted and relaxed
so as to provide virtually no protection at all. As Justice Holmes
noted in Abrams v. United States, 250 U.
S. 616 , 250 U. S. 624 ,
such was the fate of the "clear and present danger" test which he
had coined in Schenck v. United States, 249 U. S.
47 . Eventually, that formula was 80 watered down that
the danger had to be neither clear nor present, but merely "not
improbable." Dennis v. United States, 341 U.
S. 494 , 341 U. S. 510 . See my concurring opinion in Brandenburg v. Ohio, 395 U. S. 444 , 395 U. S. 450 .
A compelling interest test may prove as pliable as did the "clear
and present danger" test. Perceptions of the worth of state
objectives will change with the composition of the Court and with
the intensity of the politics of the times. For example, in Uphaus v. Wyman, 360 U. S. 72 ,
sustaining an attempt to compel a witness to divulge the names of
participants in a summer political camp, JUSTICE BRENNAN dissented
on the ground that "it is patent that there is really no
subordinating interest . . . demonstrated on the part of the
State." Id. at 360 U. S. 106 .
The majority, however, found that "the governmental interest in
self-preservation is sufficiently compelling to subordinate the
interest in associational privacy. . . ." Id. at 360 U. S. 81 .
That is to enter the world of "make believe," for New Hampshire,
the State involved in Uphaus, was never in fear of being
overthrown. II Today's decision will impede the wide-open and robust
dissemination of ideas and counterthought which Page 408 U. S. 721 a free press both fosters and protects and which is essential to
the success of intelligent self-government. Forcing a reporter
before a grand jury will have two retarding effects upon the ear
and the pen of the press. Fear of exposure will cause dissidents to
communicate less openly to trusted reporters. And fear of
accountability will cause editors and critics to write with more
restrained pens.
I see no way of making mandatory the disclosure of a reporter's
confidential source of the information on which he bases his news
story.
The press has a preferred position in our constitutional scheme
not to enable it to make money, not to set newsmen apart as a
favored class, but to bring fulfillment to the public's right to
know. The right to know is crucial to the governing powers of the
people, to paraphrase Alexander Meiklejohn. Knowledge is essential
to informed decisions.
As Mr. Justice Black said in New York Times Co. v. United
States, 403 U. S. 713 , 403 U. S. 717 (concurring opinion),
"The press was to serve the governed, not the governors. . . .
The press was protected so that it could bare the secrets of
government and inform the people."
Government has an interest in law and order, and history shows
that the trend of rulers -- the bureaucracy and the police -- is to
suppress the radical and his ideas and to arrest him, rather than
the hostile audience. See Feiner v. New York, 340 U.
S. 315 . Yet, as held in Terminiello v. Chicago, 337 U. S. 1 , 337 U. S. 4 , one
"function of free speech under our system of government is to
invite dispute." We went on to say,
"It may indeed best serve its high purpose when it induces a
condition of unrest, creates dissatisfaction with conditions as
they are, or even stirs people to anger. Speech is often
provocative and challenging. It may strike at prejudices and
preconceptions Page 408 U. S. 722 and have profound unsettling effects as it presses for
acceptance of an idea."
The people who govern are often far removed from the cabals that
threaten the regime; the people are often remote from the sources
of truth even though they live in the city where the forces that
would undermine society operate. The function of the press is to
explore and investigate events, inform the people what is going on,
and to expose the harmful as well as the good influences at work.
There is no higher function performed under our constitutional
regime. Its performance means that the press is often engaged in
projects that bring anxiety or even fear to the bureaucracies,
departments, or officials of government. The whole weight of
government is therefore often brought to bear against a paper or a
reporter.
A reporter is no better than his source of information. Unless
he has a privilege to withhold the identity of his source, he will
be the victim of governmental intrigue or aggression. If he can be
summoned to testify in secret before a grand jury, his sources will
dry up and the attempted exposure, the effort to enlighten the
public, will be ended. If what the Court sanctions today becomes
settled law, then the reporter's main function in American society
will be to pass on to the public the press releases which the
various departments of government issue.
It is no answer to reply that the risk that a newsman will
divulge one's secrets to the grand jury is no greater than the
threat that he will, in any event, inform to the police. Even the
most trustworthy reporter may not be able to withstand relentless
badgering before a grand jury. [ Footnote 2/10 ] Page 408 U. S. 723 The record in this case is replete with weighty affidavits from
responsible newsmen, telling how important is the sanctity of their
sources of information. [ Footnote
2/11 ] When we deny newsmen that protection, we deprive the
people of the information needed to run the affairs of the Nation
in an intelligent way.
Madison said:
"A popular Government, without popular information or the means
of acquiring it, is but a Prologue to a Farce or a Tragedy, or
perhaps both. Knowledge will forever govern ignorance, and a people
who mean to be their own Governors, must arm themselves with the
power which knowledge gives."
(To W. T. Barry, Aug. 4, 1822.) 9 Writings of James Madison 103
(G. Hunt ed.1910). Page 408 U. S. 724 Today's decision is more than a clog upon news gathering. It is
a signal to publishers and editors that they should exercise
caution in how they use whatever information they can obtain.
Without immunity, they may be summoned to account for their
criticism. Entrenched officers have been quick to crash their
powers down upon unfriendly commentators. [ Footnote 2/12 ] E.g., New York Times Co. v.
Sullivan, 376 U. S. 254 ; Garrison v. Louisiana, 379 U. S. 64 ; Pickering v. Board of Education, 391 U.
S. 563 ; Gravel v. United States, ante, p. 408 U. S. 606 .
The intrusion of government into this domain is symptomatic of
the disease of this society. As the years pass, the power of
government becomes more and more pervasive. It is a power to
suffocate both people and causes. Those in power, whatever their
politics, want only to perpetuate Page 408 U. S. 725 it. Now that the fences of the law and the tradition that has
protected the press are broken down, the people are the victims.
The First Amendment, as I read it, was designed precisely to
prevent that tragedy. I would also reverse the judgments in No.
785, Branzburg v. Hayes, and No. 794, In re
Pappas, for the reasons stated in the above dissent in No.
757, United States v. Caldwell. [ Footnote 2/1 ]
"The three minimal tests we contend must be met before testimony
divulging confidences may be compelled from a reporter are these:
1. The government must clearly show that there is probable cause to
believe that the reporter possesses information which is
specifically relevant to a specific probable violation of law. 2.
The government must clearly show that the information it seeks
cannot be obtained by alternative means, which is to say, from
sources other than the reporter. 3. The government must clearly
demonstrate a compelling and overriding interest in the
information."
Brief for New York Times as Amicus Curiae 29.
[ Footnote 2/2 ]
The First Amendment Is An Absolute, 191 Sup.Ct.Rev. 245,
254.
[ Footnote 2/3 ] Id. at 255.
[ Footnote 2/4 ] Id. at 257.
[ Footnote 2/5 ] E.g., Schenck v. United States, 249 U. S.
47 (wartime anti-draft "leafleting"); Debs v. United
States, 249 U. S. 211 (wartime anti-draft speech); Abrams v. United States, 250 U. S. 616 (wartime leafleting calling for general strike); Feiner v. New
York, 340 U. S. 315 (arrest of radical speaker without attempt to protect him from
hostile audience); Dennis v. United States, 341 U.
S. 494 (reformulation of test as "not improbable" rule
to sustain conviction of knowing advocacy of overthrow); Scales
v. United States, 367 U. S. 203 (knowing membership in group which espouses forbidden advocacy is
punishable). For a more detailed account of the infamy of the
"clear and present danger" test, see my concurring opinion
in Brandenburg v. Ohio, 395 U. S. 444 , 395 U. S.
450 .
[ Footnote 2/6 ] E.g., Adler v. Board of Education, 342 U.
S. 485 (protection of schools from "pollution" outweighs
public teachers' freedom to advocate violent overthrow); Uphaus
v. Wyman, 360 U. S. 72 , 360 U. S. 79 , 81
(preserving security of New Hampshire from subversives outweighs
privacy of list of participants in suspect summer camp); Barenblatt v. United States, 360 U.
S. 109 (legislative inquiry more important than
protecting HUAC witness' refusal to answer whether a third person
had been a Communist); Wilkinson v. United States, 365 U. S. 399 (legislative inquiry more important than protecting HUAC witness'
refusal to state whether he was currently a member of the Communist
Party); Braden v. United States, 365 U.
S. 431 , 365 U. S. 435 (legislative inquiry more important than protecting HUAC witness'
refusal to state whether he had once been a member of the Communist
Party); Konigsberg v. State Bar, 366 U. S.
36 (regulating membership of bar outweighs interest of
applicants in refusing to answer question concerning Communist
affiliations); In re Anastaplo, 366 U. S.
82 (regulating membership of bar outweighs protection of
applicant's belief in Declaration of Independence that citizens
should revolt against an oppressive government); Communist
Party v. Subversive Activities Control Board, 367 U. S.
1 (national security outweighs privacy of association of
leaders of suspect groups); Law Students Research Council v.
Wadmond, 401 U. S. 154 (regulating membership of bar outweighs privacy of applicants'
views on the soundness of the Constitution).
[ Footnote 2/7 ]
Thus, we have held "overbroad" measures which unduly restricted
the time, place, and manner of expression. Schneider v.
State, 308 U. S. 147 , 308 U. S. 161 (anti-leafleting law); Thornhill v. Alabama, 310 U. S.
88 , 310 U. S. 102 (anti-boycott statute); Cantwell v. Connecticut, 310 U. S. 296 (breach-of-peace measure); Cox v. Louisiana, 379 U.
S. 536 (breach-of-peace measure); Edwards v. South
Carolina, 372 U. S. 229 (breach-of-peace statute); Cohen v. California, 403 U. S. 15 , 403 U. S. 22 (breach-of-peace statute); Gooding v. Wilson, 405 U.
S. 518 (breach-of-peace statute). But insofar as
penalizing the content of thought and opinion is concerned, the
Court has not in recent Terms permitted any interest to override
the absolute privacy of one's philosophy. To be sure, opinions have
often adverted to the absence of a compelling justification for
attempted intrusions into philosophical or associational privacy. Bates v. Little Rock, 361 U. S. 516 , 361 U. S. 523 (disclosure of NAACP membership lists to city officials); Gibson v. Florida Legislative Investigation Committee, 372 U. S. 539 , 372 U. S. 546 (disclosure of NAACP membership list to state legislature); DeGregory v. Attorney General of New Hampshire, 383 U. S. 825 , 383 U. S. 829 (witness' refusal to state whether he had been a member of the
Communist Party three years earlier); Baird v. State Bar of
Arizona, 401 U. S. 1 , 401 U. S. 6 -7
(refusal of bar applicant to state whether she had been a member of
the Communist Party); In re Stolar, 401 U. S.
23 (refusal of bar applicant to state whether he was
"loyal" to the Government); see also Street v. New York, 394 U. S. 576 (expression of disgust for nag). Yet, while the rhetoric of these
opinions did not expressly embrace an absolute privilege for the
privacy of opinions and philosophy, the trend of those results was
not inconsistent with and in their totality appeared to be
approaching such a doctrine. Moreover, in another group of opinions
invalidating for overbreadth intrusions into the realm of belief
and association, there was no specification of whether a danger
test, a balancing process, an absolute doctrine, or a compelling
justification inquiry had been used to detect invalid applications
comprehended by the challenged measures. E.g., Wieman v.
Updegraff, 344 U. S. 183 (loyalty test which condemned mere unknowing membership in a
suspect group); Shelton v. Tucker, 364 U.
S. 479 (requirement that public teachers disclose all
affiliations); Louisiana ex rel. Gremillion v. NAACP, 366 U. S. 293 , 366 U. S. 296 (disclosure of NAACP membership lists); Whitehill v.
Elkins, 389 U. S. 54 , 389 U. S. 59 (nonactive membership in a suspect group a predicate for refusing
employment as a public teacher); United States v. Robel, 389 U. S. 258 (mere membership in Communist Party a sole ground for exclusion
from employment in defense facility). Regrettably, the vitality of
the overdue trend toward a complete privilege in this area has been
drawn into question by quite recent decisions of the Court, Law
Students Research Council v. Wadmond, 401 U. S.
1 54, holding that bar applicants may be turned away for
refusing to disclose their opinions on the soundness of the
Constitution; Cole v. Richardson, 405 U.
S. 676 , sustaining an oath required of public employees
that they will "oppose" a violent overthrow; and, of course, by
today's decision.
[ Footnote 2/8 ]
Where no more than economic interests were affected, this Court
has upheld legislation only upon a showing that it was "rationally
connected" to some permissible state objective. E.g., United
States v. Carolene Products Co., 304 U.
S. 144 , 304 U. S. 152 ; Goesaert v. Cleary, 335 U. S. 464 ; Williamson v. Lee Optical Co., 348 U.
S. 483 ; McGowan v. Maryland, 366 U.
S. 420 ; McDonald v. Board of Election Comm'rs, 394 U. S. 802 ; United States v. Maryland Savings-Share Ins. Corp., 400 U. S. 4 ; Richardson v. Belcher, 404 U. S. 78 ; Schilb v. Kuebel, 404 U. S. 357 .
[ Footnote 2/9 ]
The majority cites several cases which held that certain burdens
on the press were permissible despite incidental burdens on its
news-gathering ability. For example, see Sheppard v.
Maxwell, 384 U. S. 333 , 384 U. S. 358 .
Even assuming that those cases were rightly decided, the fact
remains that in none of them was the Government attempting to
extract personal belief from a witness, and the privacy of a
citizen's personal intellectual viewpoint was not implicated.
[ Footnote 2/10 ]
"The secrecy of the [grand jury's] proceedings and the
possibility of a jail sentence for contempt so intimidate the
witness that he may be led into answering questions which pry into
his personal life and associations and which, in the bargain, are
frequently immaterial and vague. Alone and faced by either hostile
or apathetic grand juries, the witness is frequently undone by his
experience. Life in a relatively open society makes him especially
vulnerable to a secret appearance before a body that is considering
criminal charges. And the very body toward which he could once look
for protection has become a weapon of the prosecution. When he
seeks protective guidance from his lawyer, he learns that the
judicial broadening of due process which has occurred in the past
two decades has largely ignored grand jury matters precisely
because it was assumed that the grand jury still functioned as a
guardian of the rights of potential defendants."
Donner & Cerruti, The Grand Jury Network: How the Nixon
Administration Has Secretly Perverted A Traditional Safeguard of
Individual Rights, 214 The Nation 5, 6 (1972).
[ Footnote 2/11 ]
It is said that
"we remain unclear how often and to what extent informers are
actually deterred from furnishing information when newsmen are
forced to testify before a grand jury." Ante at 408 U. S. 693 .
But the majority need look no further than its holdings that
prosecutors need not disclose informers' names because disclosure
would (a) terminate the usefulness of an exposed informant inasmuch
as others would no longer confide in him, and (b) it would
generally inhibit persons from becoming confidential informers. McCray v. Illinois, 386 U. S. 300 ; Scher v. United States, 305 U. S. 251 ; cf. Roviaro v. United States, 353 U. S.
53 .
[ Footnote 2/12 ]
For a summary of early reprisals against the press, such as the
John Peter Zenger trial, the Alien and Sedition Acts prosecutions,
and Civil War suppression of newspapers, see Press
Freedoms Under Pressure, Report of the Twentieth Century Fund Task
Force on the Government and the Press 3-5 (1972). We have not
outlived the tendency of officials to retaliate against critics.
For recent examples see J. Wiggins, Freedom or Secrecy 87
(1956) ("New Mexico, in 1954, furnished a striking example of
government reprisal against . . . a teacher in the state reform
school [who] wrote a letter to the New Mexican, confirming stories
it had printed about mistreatment of inmates by guards. [Two days
later, he] was notified of his dismissal."); Note, The Right of
Government Employees to Furnish Information to Congress: Statutory
and Constitutional Aspects, 57 Va.L.Rev. 885-886 (1971) (dismissal
of an Air Force employee who testified before a Senate committee
with respect to C-5A cargo plane cost overruns and firing of an FBI
agent who wrote Senators complaining of the Bureau's personnel
practices); N.Y. Times, Nov. 8, 1967, p. 1, col. 2; id. Nov. 9, 1967, p. 2, col. 4 (Selective Service directive to local
draft boards requiring conscription of those who protested war);
N.Y. Times, Nov. 11, 1971, p. 95, col. 4; id. Nov. 12,
1971, p. 13, col. 1; id. Nov. 14, 1971, pt. 4, p. 13, col.
1 (FBI investigation of a television commentator who criticized
administration policies); id. Nov. 14, 1971, p. 75, col. 3
(denial of White House press pass to underground journalist).
MR. JUSTICE STEWART, with whom MR. JUSTICE BRENNAN and MR.
JUSTICE MARSHALL join, dissenting.
The Court's crabbed view of the First Amendment reflect a
disturbing insensitivity to the critical role of an independent
press in our society. The question whether a reporter has a
constitutional right to a confidential relationship with his source
is of first impression here, but the principles that should guide
our decision are as basic as any to be found in the Constitution.
While MR. JUSTICE POWELL's enigmatic concurring opinion gives some
hope of a more flexible view in the future, the Court in these
cases holds that a newsman has no First Amendment right to protect
his sources when called before a grand jury. The Court thus invites
state and federal authorities to undermine the historic
independence of the press by attempting to annex the journalistic
profession as an investigative arm of government. Not only will
this decision impair performance of the press' constitutionally
protected functions, but it will, I am convinced, in the long run
harm, rather than help, the administration of justice.
I respectfully dissent. I The reporter's constitutional right to a confidential
relationship with his source stem from the broad societal interest
in a full and free flow of information to the public. It is this
basic concern that underlie the Constitution's Page 408 U. S. 726 protection of a free press, Grosjean v. American Press
Co., 297 U. S. 233 , 297 U. S. 250 ; New York Times Co. v. Sullivan, 376 U.
S. 254 , 376 U. S. 269 ,
[ Footnote 3/1 ] because the
guarantee is "not for the benefit of the press so much as for the
benefit of all of us." Time, Inc. v. Hill, 385 U.
S. 374 , 385 U. S. 389 .
[ Footnote 3/2 ] Enlightened choice
by an informed citizenry is the basic ideal upon which an open
society is premised, [ Footnote 3/3 ]
and a free press is thus indispensable to a free society. Not only
does the press enhance personal self-fulfillment Page 408 U. S. 727 by providing the people with the widest possible range of fact
and opinion, but it also is an incontestable precondition of
self-government. The press
"has been a mighty catalyst in awakening public interest in
governmental affairs, exposing corruption among public officers and
employees and generally informing the citizenry of public events
and occurrences. . . ." Estes v. Texas, 381 U. S. 532 , 381 U. S. 539 ; Mills v. Alabama, 384 U. S. 214 , 384 U. S. 219 ; Grosjean, supra, at 297 U. S. 250 .
As private and public aggregations of power burgeon in size and the
pressures for conformity necessarily mount, there is obviously a
continuing need for an independent press to disseminate a robust
variety of information and opinion through reportage,
investigation, and criticism, if we are to preserve our
constitutional tradition of maximizing freedom of choice by
encouraging diversity of expression. A In keeping with this tradition, we have held that the right to
publish is central to the First Amendment and basic to the
existence of constitutional democracy. Grosjean, supra, at 297 U. S. 250 ; New York Times, supra, at 403 U. S.
270 .
A corollary of the right to publish must be the right to gather
news. The full flow of information to the public protected by the
free press guarantee would be severely curtailed if no protection
whatever were afforded to the process by which news is assembled
and disseminated. We have, therefore, recognized that there is a
right to publish without prior governmental approval, Near v.
Minnesota, 283 U. S. 697 ; New York Times Co. v. United States, 403 U.
S. 713 , a right to distribute information, see,
e.g., Lovell v. Griffin, 303 U. S. 444 , 303 U. S. 452 ; Marsh v. Alabama, 326 U. S. 501 ; Martin v. City of Struthers, 319 U.
S. 141 ; Grosjean, supra, and a right to receive
printed matter, Lamont v. Postmaster General, 381 U.
S. 301 . Page 408 U. S. 728 No less important to the news dissemination process is the
gathering of information. News must not be unnecessarily cut off at
its source, for without freedom to acquire information, the right
to publish would be impermissibly compromised. Accordingly, a right
to gather news, of some dimensions, must exist. Zemel v.
Rusk, 381 U. S. 1 .
[ Footnote 3/4 ] Note, The Right of
the Press to Gather Information, 71 Col.L.Rev. 838 (1971). As
Madison wrote: "A popular Government without popular information or
the means of acquiring it is but a Prologue to a Farce or a
Tragedy, or perhaps both." 9 Writings of James Madison 103 (G. Hunt
ed.1910). B The right to gather news implies, in turn, a right to a
confidential relationship between a reporter and his source. This
proposition follows as a matter of simple logic once three factual
predicates are recognized: (1) newsmen require informants to gather
news; (2) confidentiality -- the promise or understanding that
names or certain aspects of communications will be kept off the
record -- is essential to the creation and maintenance of a
newsgathering relationship with informants; and (3) an unbridled
subpoena power -- the absence of a constitutional right protecting,
in any way, a confidential relationship from compulsory process --
will either deter source from divulging information or deter
reporters from gathering and publishing information. Page 408 U. S. 729 It is obvious that informants are necessary to the
news-gathering process as we know it today. If it is to perform its
constitutional mission, the press must do far more than merely
print public statements or publish prepared handouts. Familiarity
with the people and circumstances involved in the myriad background
activities that result in the final product called "news" is vital
to complete and responsible journalism, unless the press is to be a
captive mouthpiece of "newsmakers." [ Footnote 3/5 ]
It is equally obvious that the promise of confidentiality may be
a necessary prerequisite to a productive relationship between a
newsman and his informants. An officeholder may fear his superior;
a member of the bureaucracy, his associates; a dissident, the scorn
of majority opinion. All may have information valuable to the
public discourse, yet each may be willing to relate that
information only in confidence to a reporter whom he trusts, either
because of excessive caution or because of a reasonable fear of
reprisals or censure for unorthodox Page 408 U. S. 730 views. The First Amendment concern must not be with the motives
of any particular news source, but rather with the conditions in
which informants of all shades of the spectrum may make information
available through the press to the public. Cf. Talley v.
California, 362 U. S. 60 , 362 U. S. 65 ; Bates v. Little Rock, 361 U. S. 516 ; NAACP v. Alabama, 357 U. S. 449 .
[ Footnote 3/6 ]
In Caldwell, the District Court found that
"confidential relationships . . . are commonly developed and
maintained by professional journalists, and are indispensable to
their work of gathering, analyzing and publishing the news.
[ Footnote 3/7 ]"
Commentators and individual reporters have repeatedly noted the
importance of confidentiality. [ Footnote 3/8 ] Page 408 U. S. 731 And surveys among reporters and editors indicate that the
promise of nondisclosure is necessary for many types of news
gathering. [ Footnote 3/9 ]
Finally, and most important, when governmental officials possess
an unchecked power to compel newsmen to disclose information
received in confidence, sources will clearly be deterred from
giving information, and reporters will clearly be deterred from
publishing it, because uncertainty about exercise of the power will
lead to "self-censorship." Smith v. California, 361 U. S. 147 , 361 U. S.
149 -154; New York Times Co. v. Sullivan, 376
U.S. at 376 U. S. 279 .
The uncertainty arises, of course, because the judiciary has
traditionally imposed virtually no limitations on the grand jury's
broad investigatory powers. See Antell, The Modern Grand
Jury: Benighted Supergovernment, 51 A.B.A.J. 153 (1965). See
also 408 U. S. infra. After today's decision, the potential informant can never be
sure that his identity or off-the-record communications will not
subsequently be revealed through the compelled testimony of a
newsman. A public-spirited person inside government, who is not
implicated in any crime, will now be fearful of revealing
corruption or other governmental wrongdoing, because he will now
know he can subsequently be identified by use of compulsory
process. The potential source must, therefore, choose between
risking exposure by giving information or avoiding the risk by
remaining silent.
The reporter must speculate about whether contact with a
controversial source or publication of controversial material will
lead to a subpoena. In the event of a Page 408 U. S. 732 subpoena, under today's decision, the newsman will know that he
must choose between being punished for contempt if he refuses to
testify or violating his profession's ethic [ Footnote 3/10 ] and impairing his resourcefulness as a
reporter if he discloses confidential information. [ Footnote 3/11 ]
Again, the common sense understanding that such deterrence will
occur is buttressed by concrete evidence. The existence of
deterrent effects through fear and self-censorship was impressively
developed in the District Court in Caldwell. [ Footnote 3/12 ] Individual reporters
[ Footnote 3/13 ] and commentators
[ Footnote 3/14 ] have noted such
effects. Surveys have verified that an unbridled subpoena power
will substantially Page 408 U. S. 733 impair the flow of news to the public, especially in sensitive
areas involving governmental officials, financial affairs,
political figures, dissidents, or minority groups that require
in-depth, investigative reporting. [ Footnote 3/15 ] And the Justice Department has
recognized that "compulsory process in some circumstances may have
a limiting effect on the exercise of First Amendment rights."
[ Footnote 3/16 ] No evidence
contradicting the existence of such deterrent effects was offered
at the trials or in the briefs here by the petitioner in Caldwell
or by the respondents in Branzburg and Pappas. The impairment of the flow of news cannot, of course, be proved
with scientific precision, as the Court seems to demand. Obviously,
not every news gathering relationship requires confidentiality. And
it is difficult to pinpoint precisely how many relationships do
require a promise or understanding of nondisclosure. But we have
never before demanded that First Amendment rights rest on elaborate
empirical studies demonstrating beyond any conceivable doubt that
deterrent effects exist; we have never before required proof of the
exact number of people potentially affected by governmental action
who would actually be dissuaded from engaging in First Amendment
activity.
Rather, on the basis of common sense and available information,
we have asked, often implicitly, (1) whether there was a rational
connection between the cause (the governmental action) and the
effect (the deterrence or Page 408 U. S. 734 impairment of First Amendment activity), and (2) whether the
effect would occur with some regularity, i.e., would not
be de minimis. See, e.g., Grosjean v. American Press
Co., 297 U.S. at 297 U. S.
244 -245; Burstyn, Inc. v. Wilson, 343 U.
S. 495 , 343 U. S. 503 ; Sweezy v. New Hampshire, 354 U. S. 234 , 354 U. S. 248 (plurality opinion); NAACP v. Alabama, 357 U.S. at 357 U. S.
461 -466; Smith v. California, 361 U.S. at 361 U. S.
150 -154; Bates v. Little Rock, 361 U.S. at 361 U. S.
523 -524; Talley v. California, 362 U.S. at 362 U. S. 64 -65; Shelton v. Tucker, 364 U. S. 479 , 364 U. S.
485 -486; Cramp v. Board of Public Instruction, 368 U. S. 278 , 368 U. S. 286 ; NAACP v. Button, 371 U. S. 415 , 371 U. S.
431 -438; Gibson v. Florida Legislative Investigation
Committee, 372 U. S. 539 , 372 U. S.
555 -557; New York Times Co. v. Sullivan, 376
U.S. at 376 U. S.
277 -278; Freedman v. Maryland, 380 U. S.
51 , 380 U. S. 59 ; DeGregory v. New Hampshire Attorney General, 383 U.
S. 825 ; Elfbrandt v. Russell, 384 U. S.
11 , 16-19. And, in making this determination, we have
shown a special solicitude toward the "indispensable liberties"
protected by the First Amendment, NAACP v. Alabama, supra, at 357 U. S. 461 ; Bantam Books, Inc. v. Sullivan, 372 U. S.
58 , 372 U. S. 66 ,
for
"[f]reedoms such as these are protected not only against
heavy-handed frontal attack, but also from being stifled by more
subtle governmental interference." Bates, supra, at 361 U. S. 523 .
[ Footnote 3/17 ] Once this
threshold inquiry has been satisfied, we have then examined the
competing interests in determining whether Page 408 U. S. 735 there is an unconstitutional infringement of First Amendment
freedoms.
For example, in NAACP v. Alabama, supra, we found that
compelled disclosure of the names of those in Alabama who belonged
to the NAACP
"is likely to affect adversely the ability [of the NAACP] and
its members to pursue their . . . beliefs which they admittedly
have the right to advocate, in that it may induce members to
withdraw from the Association and dissuade others from joining it
because of fear of exposure of their beliefs shown through their
associations and of the consequences of this exposure." Id. at 357 U. S.
462 -463. In Talley, supra, we held invalid a
city ordinance that forbade circulation of any handbill that did
not have the distributor's name on it, for there was
"no doubt that such an identification requirement would tend to
restrict freedom to distribute information, and thereby freedom of
expression." Id. at 362 U. S. 64 .
And in Burstyn, Inc., supra, we found deterrence of First
Amendment activity inherent in a censor's power to exercise
unbridled discretion under an overbroad statute. Id. at 343 U. S.
503 .
Surely the analogous claim of deterrence here is as securely
grounded in evidence and common sense as the claims in the cases
cited above, although the Court calls the claim "speculative." See ante at 408 U. S. 694 .
The deterrence may not occur in every confidential relationship
between a reporter and his source. [ Footnote 3/18 ] But it will certainly Page 408 U. S. 736 occur in certain types of relationships involving sensitive and
controversial matters. And such relationships are vital to the free
flow of information.
To require any greater burden of proof is to shirk our duty to
protect values securely embedded in the Constitution. We cannot
await an unequivocal -- and therefore unattainable -- imprimatur
from empirical studies. [ Footnote
3/19 ] We can and must accept the evidence developed in the
record, and elsewhere, that overwhelmingly supports the premise
that deterrence will occur with regularity in important types of
news-gathering relationships. [ Footnote 3/20 ]
Thus, we cannot escape the conclusion that, when neither the
reporter nor his source can rely on the shield of confidentiality
against unrestrained use of the grand jury's subpoena power,
valuable information will not be published and the public dialogue
will inevitably be impoverished. II Posed against the First Amendment's protection of the newsman's
confidential relationships in these cases is society's interest in
the use of the grand jury to administer Page 408 U. S. 737 justice fairly and effectively. The grand jury serves two
important functions: "to examine into the commission of crimes"
and
"to stand between the prosecutor and the accused, and to
determine whether the charge was founded upon credible testimony or
was dictated by malice or personal ill will." Hale v. Henkel, 201 U. S. 43 , 201 U. S. 59 .
And to perform these functions, the grand jury must have available
to it every man's relevant evidence. See Blair v. United
States, 250 U. S. 273 , 250 U. S. 281 ; Blackmer v. United States, 284 U.
S. 421 , 284 U. S.
438 .
Yet the longstanding rule making every person's evidence
available to the grand jury is not absolute. The rule has been
limited by the Fifth Amendment, [ Footnote 3/21 ] the Fourth Amendment, [ Footnote 3/22 ] and the evidentiary privileges of
the common law. [ Footnote 3/23 ]
So it was that, in Blair, supra, after recognizing that
the right against compulsory self-incrimination prohibited certain
inquiries, the Court noted that
"some confidential matters are shielded from considerations of
policy, and perhaps in other cases, for special reasons, a
witness may be excused from telling all that he knows." Id. at 250 U. S. 281 (emphasis supplied). And in United States v. Bryan, 339 U. S. 323 , the
Court observed that any exemption from the duty to testify before
the grand jury "presupposes a very real interest to be protected." Id. at 339 U. S.
332 .
Such an interest must surely be the First Amendment protection
of a confidential relationship that I have discussed above in Part
I. As noted there, this protection does not exist for the purely
private interests of the Page 408 U. S. 738 newsman or his informant, nor even, at bottom, for the First
Amendment interests of either partner in the newsgathering
relationship. [ Footnote 3/24 ]
Rather, it functions to insure nothing less than democratic
decisionmaking through the free flow of information to the public,
and it serves, thereby, to honor the "profound national commitment
to the principle that debate on public issues should be
uninhibited, robust, and wide-open." New York Times Co. v.
Sullivan, 376 U.S. at 376 U. S. 270 .
In striking the proper balance between the public interest in
the efficient administration of justice and the First Amendment
guarantee of the fullest flow of information, we must begin with
the basic proposition that, because of their "delicate and
vulnerable" nature, NAACP v. Button, 371 U.S. at 371 U. S. 433 ,
and their transcendent importance for the just functioning of our
society, First Amendment rights require special safeguards. A This Court has erected such safeguards when government, by
legislative investigation or other investigative means, has
attempted to pierce the shield of privacy inherent in freedom of
association. [ Footnote 3/25 ] In
no previous case have we considered the extent to which the First
Amendment limits the grand jury subpoena power. But the Page 408 U. S. 739 Court has said that
"[t]he Bill of Rights is applicable to investigations, as to all
forms of governmental action. Witnesses cannot be compelled to give
evidence against themselves. They cannot be subjected to
unreasonable search and seizure. Nor can the First Amendment
freedoms of speech, press . . . or political belief and association
be abridged." Watkins v. United States, 354 U.
S. 178 , 354 U. S. 188 .
And, in Sweezy v. New Hampshire, it was stated:
"It is particularly important that the exercise of the power of
compulsory process be carefully circumscribed when the
investigative process tends to impinge upon such highly sensitive
areas as freedom of speech or press, freedom of political
association, and freedom of communication of ideas."
354 U.S. at 354 U. S. 245 (plurality opinion).
The established method of "carefully" circumscribing
investigative powers is to place a heavy burden of justification on
government officials when First Amendment rights are impaired. The
decisions of this Court have
"consistently held that only a compelling state interest in the
regulation of a subject within the State's constitutional power to
regulate can justify limiting First Amendment freedoms." NAACP v. Button, 371 U.S. at 371 U. S. 438 .
And
"it is an essential prerequisite to the validity of an
investigation which intrudes into the area of constitutionally
protected rights of speech, press, association and petition that
the State convincingly show a substantial relation between the
information sought and a subject of overriding and compelling state
interest. " Gibson v. Florida Legislative Investigation Committee, 372 U.S. at 372 U. S. 546 (emphasis supplied). See also DeGregory v. Attorney General of
New Hampshire, 383 U. S. 825 ; NAACP v. Alabama, 357 U. S. 449 ; Sweezy, supra; Watkins, supra. Thus, when an investigation impinges on First Amendment rights,
the government must not only show that Page 408 U. S. 740 the inquiry is of "compelling and overriding importance," but it
must also "convincingly" demonstrate that the investigation is
"substantially related"to the information sought.
Governmental officials must, therefore, demonstrate that the
information sought is clearly relevant to a precisely defined subject of governmental inquiry. Watkins, supra;
Sweezy, supra. [ Footnote
3/26 ] They must demonstrate that it is reasonable to think the
witness in question has that information. Sweezy, supra;
Gibson, supra. [ Footnote
3/27 ] And they must show that there is not any means of
obtaining the information less destructive of First Amendment
liberties. Sheldon v. Tucker, 364 U.S. at 364 U. S. 488 ; Louisiana ex rel. Gremillion v. NAACP, 366 U.
S. 293 , 366 U. S. 297 .
[ Footnote 3/28 ]
These requirements, which we have recognized in decisions
involving legislative and executive investigations, serve
established policies reflected in numerous First Page 408 U. S. 741 Amendment decisions arising in other contexts. The requirements
militate against vague investigations that, like vague laws, create
uncertainty and needlessly discourage First Amendment activity.
[ Footnote 3/29 ] They also insure
that a legitimate governmental purpose will not be pursued by means
that "broadly stifle fundamental personal liberties when the end
can be more narrowly achieved." Shelton, supra, at 364 U. S. 488 .
[ Footnote 3/30 ] As we said in Gibson, supra, "Of course, a legislative investigation -- as any investigation
-- must proceed 'step by step,' . . . but step by step or in
totality, an adequate foundation for inquiry must be laid before
proceeding in such a manner as will substantially intrude upon and
severely curtail or inhibit constitutionally protected activities
or seriously interfere with similarly protected associational
rights."
372 U.S. at 372 U. S.
557 .
I believe the safeguards developed in our decisions involving
governmental investigations must apply to the grand jury inquiries
in these cases. Surely the function of the grand jury to aid in the
enforcement of the law is no more important than the function of
the legislature, and its committees, to make the law. We have long
recognized the value of the role played by legislative
investigations, see, e.g., 345 U. S. Rumely, Page 408 U. S. 742 345 U. S. 41 , 345 U. S. 43 ; Barenblatt v. United States, 360 U.
S. 109 , 360 U. S.
111 -112, for the
"power of the Congress to conduct investigations is inherent . .
. [encompassing] surveys of defects in our social, economic or
political system for the purpose of enabling the Congress to remedy
them." Watkins, supra, at 354 U. S. 187 .
Similarly, the associational rights of private individuals, which
have been the prime focus of our First Amendment decisions in the
investigative sphere, are hardly more important than the First
Amendment rights of mass circulation newspapers and electronic
media to disseminate idea and information, and of the general
public to receive them. Moreover, the vices of vagueness and
overbreadth that legislative investigations may manifest are also
exhibited by grand jury inquiries, since grand jury investigations
are not limited in scope to specific criminal acts, see, e.g.,
Wilson v. United States, 221 U. S. 361 , Hendricks v. United States, 223 U.
S. 178 , 223 U. S. 184 , United States v. Johnson, 319 U.
S. 503 , and since standards of materiality and relevance
are greatly relaxed. Holt v. United States, 218 U.
S. 245 ; Costello v. United States, 350 U.
S. 359 . See generally Note, The Grand Jury as
an Investigatory Body, 74 Harv.L.Rev. 590, 591-592 (1961).
[ Footnote 3/31 ] For, as the
United States notes in its brief in Caldwell, the Page 408 U. S. 743 grand jury
"need establish no factual basis for commencing an
investigation, and can pursue rumors which further investigation
may prove groundless."
Accordingly, when a reporter is asked to appear before a grand
jury and reveal confidences, I would hold that the government must
(1) show that there is probable cause to believe that the newsman
has information that is clearly relevant to a specific probable
violation of law; [ Footnote 3/32 ]
(2) demonstrate that the information sought cannot be obtained by
alternative means less destructive of First Amendment rights; and
(3) demonstrate a compelling and overriding interest in the
information. [ Footnote 3/33 ]
This is not to say that a grand jury could not issue a subpoena
until such a showing were made, and it is not to say that a newsman
would be in any way privileged to ignore any subpoena that was
issued. Obviously, before the government's burden to make such a
showing were triggered, the reporter would have to move to quash
the subpoena, asserting the basis on which he considered the
particular relationship a confidential one. Page 408 U. S. 744 B The crux of the Court's rejection of any newsman's privilege is
its observation that only
"where news sources themselves are implicated in crime or
possess information relevant to the grand jury's task need
they or the reporter be concerned about grand jury subpoenas." See ante at 408 U. S. 691 (emphasis supplied). But this is a most misleading construct. For
it is obviously not true that the only persons about whom reporters
will be forced to testify will be those "confidential informants
involved in actual criminal conduct" and those having "information
suggesting illegal conduct by others." See ante at 408 U. S. 691 , 408 U. S. 693 .
As noted above, given the grand jury's extraordinarily broad
investigative powers and the weak standards of relevance and
materiality that apply during such inquiries, reporters, if they
have no testimonial privilege, will be called to give information
about informants who have neither committed crimes nor have
information about crime. It is to avoid deterrence of such sources,
and thus to prevent needless injury to First Amendment values that
I think the government must be required to show probable cause that
the newsman has information that is clearly relevant to a specific
probable violation of criminal law. [ Footnote 3/34 ] Page 408 U. S. 745 Similarly, a reporter may have information from a confidential
source that is "related" to the commission of crime, but the
government may be able tax obtain an indictment or otherwise
achieve its purposes by subpoenaing persons other than the
reporter. It is an obvious but important truism that, when
government aims have been fully served, there can be no legitimate
reason to disrupt a confidential relationship between a reporter
and his source. To do so would not aid the administration of
justice ,and would only impair the flow of information to the
public. Thus, it is to avoid deterrence of such sources that I
think the government must show that there are no alternative means
for the grand jury to obtain the information sought.
Both the "probable cause" and "alternative means" requirements
would thus serve the vital function of mediating between the public
interest in the administration of justice and the constitutional
protection of the full flow of information. These requirements
would avoid a direct conflict between these competing concerns, and
they would generally provide adequate protection for newsmen. See 408 U. S. infra. [ Footnote 3/35 ]
No doubt the courts would be required to make some delicate
judgments in working out this accommodation. But that, after
all, Page 408 U. S. 746 is the function of court of law. Better such judgments, however
difficult, than the simplistic and stultifying absolutism adopted
by the Court in denying any force to the First Amendment in these
cases. [ Footnote 3/36 ]
The error in the Court's absolute rejection of First Amendment
interests in these cases seems to me to be most profound. For in
the name of advancing the administration of justice, the Court's
decision, I think, will only impair the achievement of that goal.
People entrusted with law enforcement responsibility, no less than
private citizens, need general information relating to
controversial social problems. Obviously, press reports have great
value to government, even when the newsman cannot be compelled to
testify before a grand jury. The sad paradox of the Court's
position is that, when a grand jury may exercise an unbridled
subpoena power, and sources involved in sensitive matters become
fearful of disclosing information, the newsman will not only cease
to be a useful grand jury witness; he will cease to investigate and
publish information about issues of public import. I cannot
subscribe to such an anomalous result, for, in my view, the
interests protected by the First Amendment are not antagonistic to
the administration of justice. Rather, they can, in the long run,
only be complementary, and for that reason must be given great
"breathing space." NAACP v. Button, 371 U.S. at 371 U. S.
433 . III In deciding what protection should be given to information a
reporter receives in confidence from a news source, the Court of
Appeals for the Ninth Circuit affirmed the holding of the District
Court that the grand Page 408 U. S. 747 jury power of testimonial compulsion must not be exercised in a
manner likely to impair First Amendment interests "until there has
been a clear showing of a compelling and overriding national
interest that cannot be served by any alternative means." Caldwell v. United States, 434 F.2d 1081, 1086. It
approved the request of respondent Caldwell for specification by
the government of the "subject, direction or scope of the Grand
Jury inquiry." Id. at 1085. And it held that, in the
circumstances of this case, Caldwell need not divulge confidential
information.
I think this decision was correct. On the record before us, the
United States has not met the burden that I think the appropriate
newsman's privilege should require.
In affidavits before the District Court, the United States said
it was investigating possible violations of 18 U.S.C. § 871
(threats against the President), 18 U.S.C. § 1751 (assassination,
attempts to assassinate, conspiracy to assassinate the President),
18 U.S.C. § 231 (civil disorders), 18 U.S.C. § 2101 (interstate
travel to incite a riot), 18 U.S.C. § 1341 (mail fraud and
swindles) and other crimes that were not specified. But, with one
exception, there has been no factual showing in this case of the
probable commission of, or of attempts to commit, any crimes.
[ Footnote 3/37 ] The single
exception relates to the allegation that a Black Panther Party
leader, David Hilliard, violated 18 U.S.C. § 871 during the course
of a speech in November, 1969. But Caldwell was subpoenaed two
months after an indictment was returned against Hilliard, and that
charge could not, subsequent to the indictment, be investigated by
a grand jury. See In re National Window Glass Workers, 287
F. 219; United Page 408 U. S. 748 States v. Dardi, 330 F.2d 316, 336. [ Footnote 3/38 ] Furthermore, the record before us
does not show that Caldwell probably had any information about the
violation of any other federal criminal laws, [ Footnote 3/39 ] or that alternative Page 408 U. S. 749 means of obtaining the desired information were pursued.
[ Footnote 3/40 ]
In the Caldwell case, the Court of Appeal further found
that Caldwell's confidential relationship with the leaders of the
Black Panther Party would be impaired if he appeared before the
grand jury at all to answer questions, even though not privileged. Caldwell v. United States, 434 F.2d at 1088. On the
particular facts before it, [ Footnote
3/41 ] the court concluded that the very Page 408 U. S. 750 appearance by Caldwell before the grand jury would jeopardize
his relationship with his sources, leading to a severance of the
news-gathering relationship and impairment of the flow of news to
the public: [ Footnote 3/42 ]
"Appellant asserted in affidavit that there is nothing to which
he could testify (beyond that which he has already made public and
for which, therefore, his appearance is unnecessary) that is not
protected by the District Court's order. If this is true -- and the
Government apparently has not believed it necessary to dispute it
-- appellant's response to the subpoena would be a barren
performance Page 408 U. S. 751 -- one of no benefit to the Grand Jury. To destroy appellant's
capacity as news gatherer for such a return hardly makes sense.
Since the cost to the public of excusing his attendance is so
slight, it may be said that there is here no public interest of
real substance in competition with the First Amendment freedoms
that are jeopardized."
"If any competing public interest is ever to arise in a case
such as this (where First Amendment liberties are threatened by
mere appearance at a Grand Jury investigation) it will be on an
occasion in which the witness, armed with his privilege, can still
serve a useful purpose before the Grand Jury. Considering the scope
of the privilege embodied in the protective order, these occasions
would seem to be unusual. It is not asking too much of the
Government to show that such an occasion is presented here." Id. at 1089.
I think this ruling was also correct in light of the
particularized circumstances of the Caldwell case.
Obviously, only in very rare circumstances would a confidential
relationship between a reporter and his source be so sensitive that
mere appearance before the grand jury by the newsman would
substantially impair his newsgathering function. But in this case,
the reporter made out a prima facie case that the flow of
news to the public would be curtailed. And he stated, without
contradiction, that the only nonconfidential material about which
he could testify was already printed in his newspaper articles.
[ Footnote 3/43 ] Since the United
States has not attempted to Page 408 U. S. 752 refute this assertion, the appearance of Caldwell would, on
these facts, indeed be a "barren performance." But this aspect of
the Caldwell judgment I would confine to its own facts. As
the Court of Appeals appropriately observed: "[T]he rule of this
case is a narrow one. . . ." Caldwell, supra, at 1090.
Accordingly, I would affirm the judgment of the Court of Appeals
in No. 70-57, United States v. Caldwell. [ Footnote 3/44 ] In the other two cases before us,
No. 70-85, Branzburg v. Hayes and Meigs, and No.
70-94, In re Pappas, I would vacate the judgments and
remand the cases for further proceedings not inconsistent with the
views I have expressed in this opinion.
[ Footnote 3/1 ]
We have often described the process of informing the public as
the core purpose of the constitutional guarantee of free speech and
a free press. See, e.g., Stromberg v. California, 283 U. S. 359 , 283 U. S. 369 ; De Jonge v. Oregon, 299 U. S. 353 , 299 U. S. 365 ; Smith v. California, 361 U. S. 147 , 361 U. S.
153 .
[ Footnote 3/2 ]
As I see it, a reporter's right to protect his source is
bottomed on the constitutional guarantee of a full flow of
information to the public. A newsman's personal First Amendment
rights or the associational rights of the newsman and the source
are subsumed under that broad societal interest protected by the
First Amendment. Obviously, we are not here concerned with the
parochial personal concerns of particular newsmen or
informants.
"The newsman-informer relationship is different from . . . other
relationships whose confidentiality is protected by statute, such
as the attorney-client and physician-patient relationships. In the
case of other statutory privileges, the right of nondisclosure is
granted to the person making the communication in order that he
will be encouraged by strong assurances of confidentiality to seek
such relationships which contribute to his personal wellbeing. The
judgment is made that the interests of society will be served when
individuals consult physicians and lawyers; the public interest is
thus advanced by creating a zone of privacy that the individual can
control. However, in the case of the reporter-informer
relationship, society's interest is not in the welfare of the
informant per se, but rather in creating conditions in
which information possessed by news sources can reach public
attention."
Note, 80 Yale L.J. 317, 343 (1970) (footnotes omitted)
(hereinafter Yale Note).
[ Footnote 3/3 ] See generally Z. Chafee, Free Speech in the United
States (1941); A. Meikeljohn, Free Speech and Its Relation to
Self-Government (1948); T. Emerson, Toward a General Theory of the
First Amendment (1963).
[ Footnote 3/4 ]
In Zemel v. Rusk, 381 U. S. 1 , we held
that the Secretary of State's denial of a passport for travel to
Cuba did not violate a citizen's First Amendment rights. The rule
was justified by the "weightiest considerations of national
security," and we concluded that the "right to speak and publish
does not carry with it the unrestrained right to gather
information." Id. at 381 U. S. 16 -17
(emphasis supplied). The necessary implication is that some right
to gather information does exist.
[ Footnote 3/5 ]
In Caldwell v. United States, 434 F.2d 1081, the
Government claimed that Caldwell did not have to maintain a
confidential relationship with members of the Black Panther Party
and provide independent reporting of their activities, since the
Party and its leaders could issue statements on their own. But, as
the Court of Appeals for the Ninth Circuit correctly observed:
"[I]t is not enough that Black Panther press releases and public
addresses by Panther leaders may continue unabated in the wake of
subpoenas such as the one here in question. It is not enough that
the public's knowledge of groups such as the Black Panthers should
be confined to their deliberate public pronouncements or distant
news accounts of their occasional dramatic forays into the public
view."
"The need for an untrammeled press takes on special urgency in
times of widespread protest and dissent. In such times, the First
Amendment protections exist to maintain communication with
dissenting groups and to provide the public with a wide range of
information about the nature of protest and heterodoxy."
Citing Associated Press v. United States, 326 U. S.
1 , 326 U. S. 20 ; Thornill v. Alabama, 310 U. S. 88 , 310 U. S. 102 . Id. at 1084-1085.
[ Footnote 3/6 ]
As we observed in Talley v. California, 362 U. S.
60 ,
"Anonymous pamphlets, leaflets, brochures and even books have
played al important role in the progress of mankind. . . . Before
the Revolutionary War, colonial patriots frequently had to conceal
their authorship or distribution of literature that easily could
have brought down on them prosecutions by English controlled
courts. . . . Even the Federalist Papers, written in favor of the
adoption of our Constitution, were published under fictitious
names. It is plain that anonymity has sometimes been assumed for
the most constructive purposes." Id. at 362 U. S. 64 -65.
And in Lamont v. Postmaster General, 381 U.
S. 301 , we recognized the importance to First Amendment
values of the right to receive information anonymously.
[ Footnote 3/7 ] Application of Caldwell, 311 F.
Supp. 358 , 361.
[ Footnote 3/8 ] See, e.g., F. Chalmers, A Gentleman of the Press: The
Biography of Colonel John Bayne MacLean 775 (1969); H. Klurfeld,
Behind the Lines: The World of Drew Pearson 50, 52-55 (1968); A.
Krock, Memoirs: Sixty Years on the Firing Line 181, 184-185 (1968);
E. Larsen, First with the Truth 22-23 (1968); R. Ottley, The Lonely
Warrior -- The Life and Times of Robert S. Abbott 143-145 (1955);
C. Sulzberger, A Long Row of Candles; Memoirs and Diaries 241
(1969).
As Walter Cronkite, a network television reporter, said in an
affidavit in Caldwell:
"In doing my work, I (and those who assist me) depend constantly
on information, ideas, leads and opinions received in confidence.
Such material is essential in digging out news worthy facts and,
equally important, in assessing the importance and analyzing the
significance of public events."
App. 52.
[ Footnote 3/9 ] See Guest & Stanzler, The Constitutional Argument
for Newsmen Concealing Their Sources, 64 Nw.U.L.Rev. 18 (1969); V.
Blasi, Press Subpoenas: An Empirical and Legal Analysis, Study
Report of the Reporters' Committee on Freedom of the Press 229
(hereinafter Blasi).
[ Footnote 3/10 ]
The American Newspaper Guild has adopted the following rule as
part of the newsman's code of ethics:
"[N]ewspapermen shall refuse to reveal confidences or disclose
sources of confidential information in court or before other
judicial or investigating bodies."
G. Bird & F. Merwin, The Press and Society 592 (1971).
[ Footnote 3/11 ]
Obviously, if a newsman does not honor a confidence, he will
have difficulty establishing other confidential relationships
necessary for obtaining information in the future. See Siebert & Ryniker, Press Winning Fight to Guard Sources, Editor
& Publisher, Sept. 1, 1934, pp. 9, 36-37.
[ Footnote 3/12 ]
The court found that
"compelled disclosure of information received by a journalist
within the scope of . . . confidential relationships jeopardizes
those relationships, and thereby impairs the journalist's ability
to gather, analyze and publish the news." Application of Caldwell, 311 F. Supp. at 361.
[ Footnote 3/13 ] See 408
U.S. 665 fn3/8|>n. 8, supra. [ Footnote 3/14 ]
Recent commentary is nearly unanimous in urging either an
absolute or qualified newsman's privilege. See, e.g., Goldstein, Newsmen and Their Confidential Sources, New Republic,
Mar. 21, 1970, pp. 13-14; Yale Note, supra, 408
U.S. 665 fn3/2|>n. 2; Comment, 46 N.Y.U.L.Rev. 617 (1971);
Nelson, The Newsmen's Privilege Against Disclosure of Confidential
Sources and Information, 24 Vand.L.Rev. 667 (1971); Note, The Right
of the Press to Gather Information, 71 Col.L.Rev. 838 (1971);
Comment, 4 U.Mich.J.L.Ref. 85 (1970); Comment, 6
Harv.Civ.Rights-Civ.Lib.L.Rev. 119 (1970); Comment, The Newsman's
Privilege: Government Investigations, Criminal Prosecutions and
Private Litigation, 58 Calif.L.Rev. 1198 (1970). But see the Court's opinion, ante at 408 U. S. 690 n. 29. And see generally articles collected in Yale Note, supra, 408
U.S. 665 fn3/2|>n. 2.
Recent decisions are in conflict both as to the importance of
the deterrent effects and, a fortiori, as to the existence
of a constitutional right to a confidential reporter-source
relationship. See the Court's opinion, ante at 408 U. S. 686 ,
and cases collected in Yale Note, at 318 nn. 6-7.
[ Footnote 3/15 ] See Blasi 6-71; Guest & Stanzler, supra, 408
U.S. 665 fn3/9|>n. 9, at 450.
[ Footnote 3/16 ]
Department of Justice Memo. No. 692 (Sept. 2, 1970).
[ Footnote 3/17 ]
Although, as the Court points out, we have held that the press
is not free from the requirements of the National Labor Relations
Act, the Fair Labor Standards Act, the antitrust laws, or
nondiscriminatory taxation, ante at 408 U. S. 683 ,
these decisions were concerned "only with restraints on certain
business or commercial practices" of the press. Citizen
Publishing Co. v. United States, 394 U.
S. 131 , 394 U. S. 139 .
And due weight was given to First Amendment interests. For
example,
"The First Amendment, far from providing an argument against
application of the Sherman Act . . . provides powerful reasons to
the contrary." Associated Press v. United States, 326 U.S. at 326 U. S. 20 .
[ Footnote 3/18 ]
The fact that some informants will not be deterred from giving
information by the prospect of the unbridled exercise of the
subpoena power only means that there will not always be a
conflict between the grand jury's inquiry and the protection of
First Amendment activities. But even if the percentage of such
informants is relatively large compared to the total "universe" of
potential informants, there will remain a large number of people in
"absolute" terms who will be deterred, and the flow of
news through mass circulation newspapers and electronic media will
inevitably be impaired.
[ Footnote 3/19 ]
Empirical studies, after all, can only provide facts. It is the
duty of courts to give legal significance to facts; and it is the
special duty of this Court to understand the constitutional
significance of facts. We must often proceed in a state of less
than perfect knowledge, either because the facts are murky or the
methodology used in obtaining the facts is open to question. It is
then that we must look to the Constitution for the values that
inform our presumptions. And the importance to our society of the
full flow of information to the public has buttressed this Court's
historic presumption in favor of First Amendment values.
[ Footnote 3/20 ] See, e.g., the uncontradicted evidence presented in
affidavits from newsmen in Caldwell, Appendix to No.
70-57, pp. 22-61 (statements from Gerald Fraser, Thomas Johnson,
John Kifner, Timothy Knight, Nicholas Proffitt, Anthony Ripley,
Wallace Turner, Gilbert Noble, Anthony Lukas, Martin Arnold, David
Burnham, Jon Lowell, Frank Morgan, Min Yee, Walter Cronkite, Eric
Severeid, Mike Wallace, Dan Rather, Marvin Kalb).
[ Footnote 3/21 ] See Blau v. United States, 340 U.
S. 159 ; Quinn v. United States, 349 U.
S. 155 ; Curcio v. United States, 354 U.
S. 118 ; Malloy v. Hogan, 378 U. S.
1 .
[ Footnote 3/22 ] See Silverthorne Lumber Co. v. United States, 251 U. S. 385 .
[ Footnote 3/23 ] See Committee on Rules of Practice and Procedure of
Judicial Conference of the United States, Revised Draft of Proposed
Rules of Evidence for the United States Court and Magistrates
(1971); 8 J. Wigmore, Evidence §§ 2292391 (McNaughton
rev.1961).
[ Footnote 3/24 ]
Although there is a longstanding presumption against creation of
common law testimonial privileges, United States v. Bryan, 339 U. S. 323 ,
these privileges are rounded in an "individual interest which has
been found . . . to outweigh the public interest in the search for
truth," rather than in the broad public concerns that inform the
First Amendment. Id. at 339 U. S.
331 .
[ Footnote 3/25 ]
The protection of information from compelled disclosure for
broad purposes of public policy has been recognized in decisions
involving police informers, see Roviaro v. United States, 353 U. S. 53 , United States v. Ventresca, 380 U.
S. 102 , 380 U. S. 108 , Aguilar v. Texas, 378 U. S. 108 , 378 U. S. 114 , McCray v. Illinois, 386 U. S. 300 , and
military and state secrets, United States v. Reynolds, 345 U. S. 1 .
[ Footnote 3/26 ]
As we said in Watkins v. United States, 354 U.
S. 178 ,
"[W]hen First Amendment rights are threatened, the delegation of
power to the [legislative] committee must be clearly revealed in
its charter. . . . It is the responsibility of the Congress . . .
to insure that compulsory process is used only in furtherance of a
legislative purpose. That requires that the instructions to an
investigating committee spell out the group's jurisdiction and
purpose with sufficient particularity. . . . The more vague the
committee's charter is, the greater becomes the possibility that
the committee's specific actions are not in conformity with the
will of the parent House of Congress." Id. at 354 U. S. 198 , 354 U. S.
201 .
[ Footnote 3/27 ]
We noted in Sweezy v. New Hampshire, 354 U.
S. 234 :
"The State Supreme Court itself recognized that there was a
weakness in its conclusion that the menace of forcible overthrow of
the government justified sacrificing constitutional rights. There
was a missing link in the chain of reasoning. The syllogism was not
complete. There was nothing to connect the question of
petitioner with this fundamental interest of the State. " Id. at 354 U. S. 251 (emphasis supplied).
[ Footnote 3/28 ] See generally Note, Less Drastic Means and the First
Amendment, 78 Yale L.J. 464 (1969).
[ Footnote 3/29 ] See Watkins, supra, at 354 U. S.
208 -209. See generally Baggett v. Bullitt, 377 U. S. 360 , 377 U. S. 372 ; Speiser v. Randall, 357 U. S. 513 , 357 U. S. 526 ; Ashton v. Kentucky, 384 U. S. 195 , 384 U. S.
200 -201; Dombrowski v. Pfister, 380 U.
S. 479 , 380 U. S. 486 ; Smith v. California, 361 U.S. at 361 U. S.
150 -152; Winters v. New York, 333 U.
S. 507 ; Stromberg v. California, 283 U.S. at 283 U. S. 369 . See also Note, The Chilling Effect in Constitutional Law,
69 Col.L.Rev. 808 (1969).
[ Footnote 3/30 ] See generally Zwickler v. Koota, 389 U.
S. 241 , 389 U. S.
249 -250, and cases cited therein; Coates v.
Cincinnati, 402 U. S. 611 , 402 U. S. 616 ; Cantwell v. Connecticut, 310 U. S. 296 , 310 U. S. 307 ; De Jonge v. Oregon, 299 U.S. at 299 U. S.
364 -365; Schneider v. State, 308 U.
S. 147 , 308 U. S. 164 ; Cox v. Louisiana, 379 U. S. 559 , 379 U. S.
562 -664. Cf. NAACP v. Button, 371 U.
S. 415 , 371 U. S. 438 . See also Note, The First Amendment Overbreadth Doctrine,
83 Harv.L.Rev. 844 (1970).
[ Footnote 3/31 ]
In addition, witnesses customarily are not allowed to object to
questions on the grounds of materiality or relevance, since the
scope of the grand jury inquiry is deemed to be of no concern to
the witness. Carter v. United States, 417 F.2d 384, cert. denied, 399 U.S. 935. Nor is counsel permitted to be
present to aid a witness. See In re Groban, 352 U.
S. 330 . See generally Younger, The Grand Jury Under Attack, pt.
3, 46 J.Crim.L.C. & P.S. 214 (1955); Recent Cases, 104
U.Pa.L.Rev. 429 (1955); Watts, Grand Jury: Sleeping Watchdog or
Expensive Antique, 37 N.C.L.Rev. 290 (1959); Whyte, Is the Grand
Jury Necessary?, 45 Va.L.Rev. 461 (1959); Note, 2 Col. J.Law &
Soc.Prob. 47, 58 (1966); Antell, The Modern Grand Jury: Benighted
Supergovernment, 51 A.B.A.J. 153 (1965); Orfield, The Federal Grand
Jury, 22 F.R.D. 343.
[ Footnote 3/32 ]
The standard of proof employed by most grand juries, federal and
State, is simply "probable cause" to believe that the accused has
committed a crime. See Note, 1963 Wash.U.L.Q.102; L. Hall et al., Modern Criminal Procedure 793-794 (1969).
Generally speaking, it is extremely difficult to challenge
indictments on the ground that they are not supported by adequate
or competent evidence. Cf. Costello v. United States, 350 U. S. 359 ; Beck v. Washington, 369 U. S. 541 .
[ Footnote 3/33 ] Cf. Garland v. Torre, 259 F.2d 545. The Court of
Appeals for the Second Circuit declined to provide a testimonial
privilege to a newsman called to testify at a civil trial. But the
court recognized a newsman's First Amendment right to a
confidential relationship with his source, and concluded:
"It is to be noted that we are not dealing here with the use of
the judicial process to force a wholesale disclosure of a
newspaper's confidential sources of news, nor with a case where the
identity of the news source is of doubtful relevance or
materiality. . . . The question asked . . . went to the heart of
the plaintiff's claim." Id. at 549-550 (citations omitted).
[ Footnote 3/34 ]
If this requirement is not met, then the government will
basically be allowed to undertake a "fishing expedition" at the
expense of the press. Such general, exploratory investigations will
be most damaging to confidential news-gathering relationships,
since they will create great uncertainty in both reporters and
their sources. The Court sanctions such explorations by refusing to
apply a meaningful "probable cause" requirement. See ante at 408 U.S. 701 -702. As the
Court states, a grand jury investigation "may be triggered by tips,
rumors, evidence proffered by the prosecutor, or the personal
knowledge of the grand jurors." Ante at 408 U.S. 701 . It thereby invites
government to try to annex the press as an investigative arm, since
any time government wants to probe the relationships between the
newsman and his source, it can, on virtually any pretext, convene a
grand jury and compel the journalist to testify.
The Court fails to recognize that, under the guise of
"investigating crime," vindictive prosecutors can, using the broad
powers of the grand jury which are, in effect, immune from judicial
supervision, explore the newsman's sources at will, with no serious
law enforcement purpose. The secrecy of grand jury proceedings
affords little consolation to a news source; the prosecutor
obviously will, in most cases, have knowledge of testimony given by
grand jury witnesses.
[ Footnote 3/35 ]
We need not, therefore, reach the question of whether
government's interest in these cases is "overriding and
compelling." I do not, however, believe, as the Court does, that
all grand jury investigations automatically would override the
newsman's testimonial privilege.
[ Footnote 3/36 ]
The disclaimers in MR. JUSTICE POWELL's concurring opinion leave
room for the hope that, in some future case, the Court may take a
less absolute position in this area.
[ Footnote 3/37 ] See Blasi 61 et seq. [ Footnote 3/38 ]
After Caldwell was first subpoenaed to appear before the grand
jury, the Government did undertake, by affidavits, to
"set forth facts indicating the general nature of the grand
jury's investigation [and] witness Earl Caldwell's possession of
information relevant to this general inquiry."
In detailing the basis for the belief that a crime had probably
been committed, the Government simply asserted that certain actions
had previously been taken by other grand juries, and by
Government counsel, with respect to certain members of the
Black Panther Party ( i.e., immunity grants for certain
Black Panthers were sought; the Government moved to compel party
members to testify before grand juries; and contempt citations were
sought when party members refused to testify). No facts were
asserted suggesting the actual commission of crime. The exception,
as noted, involved David Hilliard's speech and its republication in
the party newspaper, the Black Panther, for which Hilliard had been
indicted before Caldwell was subpoenaed.
[ Footnote 3/39 ]
In its affidavits, the Government placed primary reliance on
certain articles published by Caldwell in the New York Times during
1969 (on June 15, July 20, July 22, July 27, and Dec. 14). On Dec.
14, 1969, Caldwell wrote:
"'We are special,' Mr. Hilliard said recently. 'We advocate the
very direct overthrow of the Government by way of force and
violence. By picking up guns and moving against it because we
recognize it as being oppressive and, in recognizing that, we know
that the only solution to it is armed struggle.'"
"In their role as the vanguard in a revolutionary struggle, the
Panthers have picked up guns."
"Last week, two of their leaders were killed during the police
raid on one of their offices in Chicago. And in Los Angeles a few
days earlier, three officers and three Panthers were wounded in a
similar shooting incident. In these and in some other raids, the
police have found caches of weapons, including high-powered
rifles."
App. in No. 70-57, p. 13. In my view, this should be read as
indicating that Caldwell had interviewed Panther leaders. It does
not indicate that he probably had knowledge of the crimes being
investigated by the Government. And, to repeat, to the extent it
does relate to Hilliard's threat, an indictment had already been
brought in that matter. The other articles merely demonstrate that
Black Panther Party leaders had told Caldwell their ideological
beliefs -- beliefs that were readily available to the Government
through other sources, like the party newspaper.
[ Footnote 3/40 ]
The Government did not attempt to show that means less impinging
upon First Amendment interests had been pursued.
[ Footnote 3/41 ]
In an affidavit filed with the District Court, Caldwell
stated:
"I began covering and writing articles about the Black Panthers
almost from the time of their inception, and I myself found that,
in those first months . . . , they were very brief and reluctant to
discuss any substantive matter with me. However, as they realized I
could be trusted and that my sole purpose was to collect my
information and present it objectively in the newspaper, and that I
had no other motive, I found that not only were the party leaders
available for in-depth interviews, but also the rank and file
members were cooperative in aiding me in the newspaper stories that
I wanted to do. During the time that I have been covering the
party, I have noticed other newspapermen representing legitimate
organizations in the news media being turned away because they were
not known and trusted by the party leadership."
"As a result of the relationship that I have developed, I have
been able to write lengthy stories about the Panthers that have
appeared in The New York Times and have been of such a nature that
other reporters who have not known the Panthers have not been able
to write. Many of these stories have appeared in up to 50 or 60
other newspapers around the country."
"The Black Panther Party's method of operation with regard to
members of the press is significantly different from that of other
organizations. For instance, press credentials are not recognized
as being of any significance. In addition, interviews are not
normally designated as being 'backgrounders' or 'off the record' or
'for publication' or 'on the record.' Because no substantive
interviews are given until a relationship of trust and confidence
is developed between the Black Panther Party members and a
reporter, statements are rarely made to such reporters on an
expressed 'on' or 'off' the record basis. Instead, an understanding
is developed over a period of time between the Black Panther Party
members and the reporter as to matters which the Black Panther
Party wishes to disclose for publications and those matters which
are given in confidence. . . . Indeed, if I am forced to appear in
secret grand jury proceedings, my appearance alone would be
interpreted by the Black Panthers and other dissident groups as a
possible disclosure of confidences and trusts and would similarly
destroy my effectiveness as a newspaperman."
The Government did not contradict this affidavit.
[ Footnote 3/42 ]
"Militant groups might very understandably fear that, under the
pressure of examination before a Grand Jury, the witness may fail
to protect their confidences. . . . The Government characterizes
this anticipated loss of communication as Black Panther reprisal. .
. . But it is not an extortionate threat we face. It is human
reaction as reasonable to expect as that a client will leave his
lawyer when his confidence is shaken. . . . As the Government
points out, loss of such a sensitive news source can also result
from its reaction to indiscreet or unfavorable reporting or from a
reporter's association with Government agents or persons
disapproved of by the news source. Loss in such a case, however,
results from an exercise of the choice and prerogative of a free
press. It is not the result of Government compulsion." Caldwell v. United States, 434 F.2d at 1088.
[ Footnote 3/43 ]
Caldwell stated in his affidavit filed with the District Court, see 408
U.S. 665 fn3/40|>n. 40, supra: "It would be virtually impossible for me to recall whether any
particular matter disclosed to me by members of the Black Panther
Party since January l, 1969, was based on an understanding that it
would or would not be confidential. Generally, those matters which
were made on a nonconfidential or 'for publication' basis have been
published in articles I have written in The New York Times;
conversely, any matters which I have not thus far disclosed in
published articles would have been given to me based on the
understanding that they were confidential and would not be
published."
[ Footnote 3/44 ]
The District Court reserved jurisdiction to modify its order on
a showing of a governmental interest which cannot be served by
means other than Caldwell's grand jury testimony. The Government
would thus have further opportunity in that court to meet the
burden that, I think, protection of First Amendment rights
requires. | In the case of *Branzburg v. Hayes*, the U.S. Supreme Court ruled that the First Amendment does not grant journalists immunity from testifying before a grand jury or revealing confidential sources. The Court held that journalists, like all citizens, are legally obligated to respond to grand jury subpoenas and provide relevant information in criminal investigations. This decision affirmed the lower court rulings in two Kentucky cases and one Massachusetts case, while reversing a District Court ruling in a fourth case. |
Free Speech | Gertz v. Robert Welch, Inc. | https://supreme.justia.com/cases/federal/us/418/323/ | U.S. Supreme Court Gertz v. Robert Welch, Inc., 418
U.S. 323 (1974) Gertz v. Robert Welch,
Inc. No. 72-617 Argued November 14,
1973 Decided June 25, 1974 418
U.S. 323 CERTIORARI TO THE UNITED STATES
COURT OF APPEALS FOR THE SEVENTH
CIRCUIT Syllabus A Chicago policeman named Nuccio was convicted of murder. The
victim's family retained petitioner, a reputable attorney, to
represent them in civil litigation against Nuccio. An article
appearing in respondent's magazine alleged that Nuccio's murder
trial was part of a Communist conspiracy to discredit the local
police, and it falsely stated that petitioner had arranged Nuccio's
"frameup," implied that petitioner had a criminal record, and
labeled him a "Communist-fronter." Petitioner brought this
diversity libel action against respondent. After the jury returned
a verdict for petitioner, the District Court decided that the
standard enunciated in New York Times Co. v. Sullivan, 376 U. S. 254 ,
which bars media liability for defamation of a public official
absent proof that the defamatory statements were published with
knowledge of their falsity or in reckless disregard of the truth,
should apply to this suit. The court concluded that that standard
protects media discussion of a public issue without regard to
whether the person defamed is a public official as in New York
Times Co. v. Sullivan, supra, or a public figure, as in Curtis Publishing Co. v. Butts, 388 U.
S. 130 . The court found that petitioner had failed to
prove knowledge of falsity or reckless disregard for the truth, and
therefore entered judgment n.o.v. for respondent. The
Court of Appeals affirmed. Held: 1. A publisher or broadcaster of defamatory falsehoods about an
individual who is neither a public official nor a public figure may
not claim the New York Times protection against liability
for defamation on the ground that the defamatory statements concern
an issue of public or general interest. Pp. 418 U. S.
339 -348.
(a) Because private individuals characteristically have less
effective opportunities for rebuttal than do public officials and
public figures, they are more vulnerable to injury from defamation.
Because they have not voluntarily exposed themselves to increased
risk of injury from defamatory falsehoods, they are also more
deserving of recovery. The state interest in compensating Page 418 U. S. 324 injury to the reputation of private individuals is therefore
greater than for public officials and public figures. Pp. 418 U. S.
343 -345.
(b) To extend the New York Times standard to media
defamation of private persons whenever an issue of general or
public interest is involved would abridge to an unacceptable degree
the legitimate state interest in compensating private individuals
for injury to reputation and would occasion the additional
difficulty of forcing courts to decide on an ad hoc basis
which publications and broadcasts address issues of general or
public interest and which do not. Pp. 418 U. S.
345 -346.
(c) So long as they do not impose liability without fault, the
States may define for themselves the appropriate standard of
liability for a publisher or broadcaster of defamatory falsehood
which injures a private individual and whose substance makes
substantial danger to reputation apparent. Pp. 418 U. S.
347 -348.
2. The States, however, may not permit recovery of presumed or
punitive damages when liability is not based on knowledge of
falsity or reckless disregard for the truth, and the private
defamation plaintiff who establishes liability under a less
demanding standard than the New York Times test may
recover compensation only for actual injury. Pp. 418 U. S.
348 -350.
3. Petitioner was neither a public official nor a public figure.
Pp. 418 U. S.
351 -352.
(a) Neither petitioner's past service on certain city committees
nor his appearance as an attorney at the coroner's inquest into the
death of the murder victim made him a public official. P. 418 U. S.
351 .
(b) Petitioner was also not a public figure. Absent clear
evidence of general fame or notoriety in the community and
pervasive involvement in ordering the affairs of society, an
individual should not be deemed a public figure for all aspects of
his life. Rather, the public figure question should be determined
by reference to the individual's participation in the particular
controversy giving rise to the defamation. Petitioner's role in the
Nuccio affair did not make him a public figure. Pp. 418 U. S.
351 -352.
471 F.2d 801, reversed and remanded.
POWELL, J., delivered the opinion of the Court, in which WHITE,
MARSHALL, BLACKMUN, and REHNQUIST, JJ., joined. BLACKMUN, J., filed
a concurring opinion, post, p. 418 U. S. 353 .
BURGER, C.J., post, p. 418 U. S. 354 ,
DOUGLAS, J., post, p. 418 U. S. 355 ,
BRENNAN, J., post, p. 418 U. S. 361 ,
and WHITE, J., post, p. 418 U. S. 369 ,
filed dissenting opinions. Page 418 U. S. 325 MR. JUSTICE POWELL delivered the opinion of the Court.
This Court has struggled for nearly a decade to define the
proper accommodation between the law of defamation and the freedoms
of speech and press protected by the First Amendment. With this
decision we return to that effort. We granted certiorari to
reconsider the extent of a publisher's constitutional privilege
against liability for defamation of a private citizen. 410 U.S. 925
(1973). I In 1968, a Chicago policeman named Nuccio shot and killed a
youth named Nelson. The state authorities prosecuted Nuccio for the
homicide and ultimately obtained a conviction for murder in the
second degree. The Nelson family retained petitioner Elmer Gertz, a
reputable attorney, to represent them in civil litigation against
Nuccio.
Respondent publishes American Opinion, a monthly outlet for the
views of the John Birch Society. Early in the 1960's, the magazine
began to warn of a nationwide conspiracy to discredit local law
enforcement agencies and create in their stead a national police
force capable of supporting a Communist dictatorship. As part of
the continuing effort to alert the public to this assumed danger,
the managing editor of American Opinion commissioned an article on
the murder trial of Officer Nuccio. For this purpose, he engaged a
regular contributor to the magazine. In March, 1969, respondent
published the resulting article under the title "FRAME-UP:
Richard Page 418 U. S. 326 Nuccio And The War On Police." The article purports to
demonstrate that the testimony against Nuccio at his criminal trial
was false, and that his prosecution was part of the Communist
campaign against the police.
In his capacity as counsel for the Nelson family in the civil
litigation, petitioner attended the coroner's inquest into the
boy's death and initiated actions for damages, but he neither
discussed Officer Nuccio with the press nor played any part in the
criminal proceeding. Notwithstanding petitioner's remote connection
with the prosecution of Nuccio, respondent's magazine portrayed him
as an architect of the "frame-up." According to the article, the
police file on petitioner took "a big, Irish cop to lift." The
article stated that petitioner had been an official of the
"Marxist League for Industrial Democracy, originally known as
the Intercollegiate Socialist Society, which has advocated the
violent seizure of our government."
It labeled Gertz a "Leninist" and a "Communist-fronter." It also
stated that Gertz had been an officer of the National Lawyers
Guild, described as a Communist organization that "probably did
more than any other outfit to plan the Communist attack on the
Chicago police during the 1968 Democratic Convention."
These statements contained serious inaccuracies. The implication
that petitioner had a criminal record was false. Petitioner had
been a member and officer of the National Lawyers Guild some 15
years earlier, but there was no evidence that he or that
organization had taken any part in planning the 1968 demonstrations
in Chicago. There was also no basis for the charge that petitioner
was a "Leninist" or a "Communist-fronter." And he had never been a
member of the "Marxist League for Industrial Democracy" or the
"Intercollegiate Socialist Society." Page 418 U. S. 327 The managing editor of American Opinion made no effort to verify
or substantiate the charges against petitioner. Instead, he
appended an editorial introduction stating that the author had
"conducted extensive research into the Richard Nuccio Case." And he
included in the article a photograph of petitioner and wrote the
caption that appeared under it: "Elmer Gertz of Red Guild harasses
Nuccio." Respondent placed the issue of American Opinion containing
the article on sale at newsstands throughout the country and
distributed reprints of the article on the streets of Chicago.
Petitioner filed a diversity action for libel in the United
States District Court for the Northern District of Illinois. He
claimed that the falsehoods published by respondent injured his
reputation as a lawyer and a citizen. Before filing an answer,
respondent moved to dismiss the complaint for failure to state a
claim upon which relief could be granted, apparently on the ground
that petitioner failed to allege special damages. But the court
ruled that statements contained in the article constituted libel per se under Illinois law, and that, consequently,
petitioner need not plead special damages. 306 F.
Supp. 310 (1969).
After answering the complaint, respondent filed a pretrial
motion for summary judgment, claiming a constitutional privilege
against liability for defamation. [ Footnote 1 ] It asserted that petitioner was a public
official or a public figure, and that the article concerned an
issue of public interest and concern. For these reasons, respondent
argued, it was entitled to invoke the privilege enunciated in New York Times Co. v. Sullivan, 376 U.
S. 254 (1964). Under this rule, respondent would escape
liability unless Page 418 U. S. 328 petitioner could prove publication of defamatory falsehood "with actual malice' -- that is, with knowledge that it was false or
with reckless disregard of whether it was false or not." Id. at 376 U. S. 280 .
Respondent claimed that petitioner could not make such a showing,
and submitted a supporting affidavit by the magazine's managing
editor. The editor denied any knowledge of the falsity of the
statements concerning petitioner, and stated that he had relied on
the author's reputation and on his prior experience with the
accuracy and authenticity of the author's contributions to American
Opinion. The District Court denied respondent's motion for summary
judgment in a memorandum opinion of September 16, 1970. The court
did not dispute respondent's claim to the protection of the New
York Times standard. Rather, it concluded that petitioner
might overcome the constitutional privilege by making a factual
showing sufficient to prove publication of defamatory falsehood in
reckless disregard of the truth. During the course of the trial,
however, it became clear that the trial court had not accepted all
of respondent's asserted grounds for applying the New York
Times rule to this case. It thought that respondent's claim to
the protection of the constitutional privilege depended on the
contention that petitioner was either a public official under the New York Times decision or a public figure under Curtis Publishing Co. v. Butts, 388 U.
S. 130 (1967), apparently discounting the argument that
a privilege would arise from the presence of a public issue. After
all the evidence had been presented but before submission of the
case to the jury, the court ruled, in effect, that petitioner was
neither a public official nor a public figure. It added that, if he
were, the resulting application of the New York Times standard would require a directed verdict for respondent. Because
some statements in the article constituted libel per
se Page 418 U. S. 329 under Illinois law, the court submitted the case to the jury
under instructions that withdrew from its consideration all issues
save the measure of damages. The jury awarded $50,000 to
petitioner.
Following the jury verdict and on further reflection, the
District Court concluded that the New York Times standard
should govern this case even though petitioner was not a public
official or public figure. It accepted respondent's contention that
that privilege protected discussion of any public issue without
regard to the status of a person defamed therein. Accordingly, the
court entered judgment for respondent notwithstanding the jury's
verdict. [ Footnote 2 ] This
conclusion anticipated the reasoning Page 418 U. S. 330 of a plurality of this Court in Rosenbloom v. Metromedia,
Inc., 403 U. S. 29 (1971).
Petitioner appealed to contest the applicability of the New
York Times standard to this case. Although the Court of
Appeals for the Seventh Circuit doubted the correctness of the
District Court's determination that petitioner was not a public
figure, it did not overturn that finding. [ Footnote 3 ] It agreed with the District Court that
respondent could assert the constitutional privilege because the
article concerned a matter of public interest, citing this Court's
intervening decision in Rosenbloom v. Metromedia, Inc.,
supra. The Court of Appeals read Rosenbloom to require
application of the New York Times standard to any
publication or broadcast about an issue of significant public
interest, without regard to the position, fame, or anonymity of the
person defamed, and it concluded that respondent's statements Page 418 U. S. 331 concerned such an issue. [ Footnote 4 ] After reviewing the record, the Court of
Appeals endorsed the District Court's conclusion that petitioner
had failed to show by clear and Page 418 U. S. 332 convincing evidence that respondent had acted with "actual
malice" as defined by New York Times. There was no
evidence that the managing editor of American Opinion knew of the
falsity of the accusations made in the article. In fact, he knew
nothing about petitioner except what he learned from the article.
The court correctly noted that mere proof of failure to
investigate, without more, cannot establish reckless disregard for
the truth. Rather, the publisher must act with a " high degree
of awareness of . . . probable falsity.'" St. Amant v.
Thompson, 390 U. S. 727 , 390 U. S. 731 (1968); accord, Beckley Newspapers Corp. v. Hanks, 389 U. S. 81 , 389 U. S. 84 -85
(1967); Garrison v. Louisiana, 379 U. S.
64 , 379 U. S. 75 -76
(1964). The evidence in this case did not reveal that respondent
had cause for such an awareness. The Court of Appeals therefore
affirmed, 471 F.2d 801 (1972). For the reasons stated below, we
reverse. II The principal issue in this case is whether a newspaper or
broadcaster that publishes defamatory falsehoods about an
individual who is neither a public official nor a public figure may
claim a constitutional privilege against liability for the injury
inflicted by those statements. The Court considered this question
on the rather different set of facts presented in Rosenbloom v.
Metromedia, Inc., 403 U. S. 29 (1971). Rosenbloom, a distributor of nudist magazines, was arrested
for selling allegedly obscene material while making Page 418 U. S. 333 a delivery to a retail dealer. The police obtained a warrant and
seized his entire inventory of 3,000 books and magazines. He sought
and obtained an injunction prohibiting further police interference
with his business. He then sued a local radio station for failing
to note in two of its newscasts that the 3,000 items seized were
only "reportedly" or "allegedly" obscene and for broadcasting
references to "the smut literature racket" and to "girlie book
peddlers" in its coverage of the court proceeding for injunctive
relief. He obtained a judgment against the radio station, but the
Court of Appeals for the Third Circuit held the New York
Times privilege applicable to the broadcast, and reversed. 415
F.2d 892 (1969).
This Court affirmed the decision below, but no majority could
agree on a controlling rationale. The eight Justices [ Footnote 5 ] who participated in Rosenbloom announced their views in five separate
opinions, none of which commanded more than three votes. The
several statements not only reveal disagreement about the
appropriate result in that case, they also reflect divergent
traditions of thought about the general problem of reconciling the
law of defamation with the First Amendment. One approach has been
to extend the New York Times test to an expanding variety
of situations. Another has been to vary the level of constitutional
privilege for defamatory falsehood with the status of the person
defamed. And a third view would grant to the press and broadcast
media absolute immunity from liability for defamation. To place our
holding in the proper context, we preface our discussion of this
case with a review of the several Rosenbloom opinions and
their antecedents.
In affirming the trial court's judgment in the instant case, the
Court of Appeals relied on MR. JUSTICE BRENNAN's Page 418 U. S. 334 conclusion for the Rosenbloom plurality that "all
discussion and communication involving matters of public or general
concern," 403 U.S. at 403 U. S. 44 ,
warrant the protection from liability for defamation accorded by
the rule originally enunciated in New York Times Co. v.
Sullivan, 376 U. S. 254 (1964). There, this Court defined a constitutional privilege
intended to free criticism of public officials from the restraints
imposed by the common law of defamation. The Times ran a political
advertisement endorsing civil rights demonstrations by black
students in Alabama and impliedly condemning the performance of
local law enforcement officials. A police commissioner established
in state court that certain misstatements in the advertisement
referred to him, and that they constituted libel per se under Alabama law. This showing left the Times with the single
defense of truth, for, under Alabama law, neither good faith nor
reasonable care would protect the newspaper from liability. This
Court concluded that a "rule compelling the critic of official
conduct to guarantee the truth of all his factual assertions" would
deter protected speech, id. at 376 U. S. 279 ,
and announced the constitutional privilege designed to counter that
effect:
"The constitutional guarantees require, we think, a federal rule
that prohibits a public official from recovering damages for a
defamatory falsehood relating to his official conduct unless he
proves that the statement was made with 'actual malice' -- that is,
with knowledge that it was false or with reckless disregard of
whether it was false or not. " Id. at 376 U. S.
279 -280. [ Footnote
6 ] Page 418 U. S. 335 Three years after New York Times, a majority of the
Court agreed to extend the constitutional privilege to defamatory
criticism of "public figures." This extension Page 418 U. S. 336 was announced in Curtis Publishing Co. v. Butts and its
companion, Associated Press v. Walker, 388 U.
S. 130 , 388 U. S. 162 (1967). The first case involved the Saturday Evening Post's charge
that Coach Wally Butts of the University of Georgia had conspired
with Coach "Bear" Bryant of the University of Alabama to fix a
football game between their respective schools. Walker involved an erroneous Associated Pres account of former Major
General Edwin Waler's participation in a University of Mississippi
campus riot. Because Butts was paid by a private alumni association
and Walker had resigned from the Army, neither could be classified
as a "public official" under New York Times. Although Mr.
Justice Harlan announced the result in both cases, a majority of
the Court agreed with Mr. Chief Justice Warren's conclusion that
the New York Times test should apply to criticism of
"public figures" as well as "public officials." [ Footnote 7 ] The Court extended the
constitutional Page 418 U. S. 337 privilege announced in that case to protect defamatory criticism
of nonpublic persons who
"are nevertheless intimately involved in the resolution of
important public questions or, by reason of their fame, shape
events in areas of concern to society at large." Id. at 388 U. S. 164 (Warren, C.J., concurring in result).
In his opinion for the plurality in Rosenbloom v.
Metromedia, Inc., 403 U. S. 29 (1971), MR. JUSTICE BRENNAN took the New York Times privilege one step further. He concluded that its protection should
extend to defamatory falsehoods relating to private persons if the
statements concerned matters of general or public interest. He
abjured the suggested distinction between public officials and
public figures, on the one hand, and private individuals, on the
other. He focused instead on society's interest in learning about
certain issues:
"If a matter is a subject of public or general interest, it
cannot suddenly become less so merely because a private individual
is involved, or because in some sense the individual did not
'voluntarily' choose to become involved." Id. at 403 U. S. 43 .
Thus, under the plurality opinion, a private citizen involuntarily
associated with a matter of general interest has no recourse for
injury to his reputation unless he can satisfy the demanding
requirements of the New York Times test.
Two Members of the Court concurred in the result in Rosenbloom, but departed from the reasoning of the
plurality. Mr. Justice Black restated his view, long shared by MR.
JUSTICE DOUGLAS, that the First Amendment cloaks the news media
with an absolute and indefeasible immunity from liability for
defamation. Id. at 403 U. S. 57 . MR
JUSTICE WHITE concurred on a narrower ground. Ibid. He
concluded that
"the First Amendment gives the press and the broadcast media a
privilege to report and comment upon the official actions of
public Page 418 U. S. 338 servants in full detail, with no requirement that the reputation
or the privacy of an individual involved in or affected by the
official action be spared from public view." Id. at 403 U. S. 62 . He
therefore declined to reach the broader questions addressed by the
other Justices.
Mr. Justice Harlan dissented. Although he had joined the opinion
of the Court in New York Times, in Curtis Publishing
Co., he had contested the extension of the privilege to public
figures. There, he had argued that a public figure who held no
governmental office should be allowed to recover damages for
defamation
"on a showing of highly unreasonable conduct constituting an
extreme departure from the standards of investigation and reporting
ordinarily adhered to by responsible publishers."
388 U.S. at 388 U. S. 155 .
In his Curtis Publishing Co. opinion, Mr. Justice Harlan
had distinguished New York Times primarily on the ground
that defamation actions by public officials "lay close to seditious
libel. . . ." Id. at 388 U. S. 153 .
Recovery of damages by one who held no public office, however,
could not "be viewed as a vindication of governmental policy." Id. at 388 U. S. 154 .
Additionally, he had intimated that, because most public officials
enjoyed absolute immunity from liability for their own defamatory
utterances under Barr v. Matteo, 360 U.
S. 564 (1959,), they lacked a strong claim to the
protection of the courts.
In Rosenbloom, Mr. Justice Harlan modified these views.
He acquiesced in the application of the privilege to defamation of
public figures, but argued that a different rule should obtain
where defamatory falsehood harmed a private individual. He noted
that a private person has less likelihood "of securing access to
channels of communication sufficient to rebut falsehoods concerning
him" than do public officials and public figures, 403 U.S. at 403 U. S. 70 ,
and has not voluntarily placed himself in the Page 418 U. S. 339 public spotlight. Mr. Justice Harlan concluded that the States
could constitutionally allow private individuals to recover damages
for defamation on the basis of any standard of care except
liability without fault.
MR. JUSTICE MARSHALL dissented in Rosenbloom in an
opinion joined by MR. JUSTICE STEWART. Id. at 403 U. S. 78 . He
thought that the plurality's "public or general interest" test for
determining the applicability of the New York Times privilege would involve the courts in the dangerous business of
deciding "what information is relevant to self-government." Id. at 403 U. S. 79 . He
also contended that the plurality's position inadequately served
"society's interest in protecting private individuals from being
thrust into the public eye by the distorting light of defamation." Ibid. MR. JUSTICE MARSHALL therefore reached the
conclusion, also reached by Mr. Justice Harlan, that the States
should be "essentially free to continue the evolution of the common
law of defamation and to articulate whatever fault standard best
suits the State's need," so long as the States did not impose
liability without fault. Id. at 403 U. S. 86 .
The principal point of disagreement among the three dissenters
concerned punitive damages. Whereas Mr. Justice Harlan thought that
the States could allow punitive damages in amounts bearing "a
reasonable and purposeful relationship to the actual harm done . .
. ," id. at 403 U. S. 75 ,
MR. JUSTICE MARSHALL concluded that the size and unpredictability
of jury awards of exemplary damages unnecessarily exacerbated the
problems of media self-censorship, and that such damages should
therefore be forbidden. III We begin with the common ground. Under the First Amendment,
there is no such thing as a false idea. However pernicious an
opinion may seem, we depend for its correction not on the
conscience of judges and juries, but Page 418 U. S. 340 on the competition of other ideas. [ Footnote 8 ] But there is no constitutional value in false
statements of fact. Neither the intentional lie nor the careless
error materially advances society's interest in "uninhibited,
robust? and wide-open" debate on public issues. New York Times
Co. v. Sullivan, 376 U.S. at 376 U. S. 270 .
They belong to that category of utterances which
"are no essential part of any exposition of ideas, and are of
such slight social value as a step to truth that any benefit that
may be derived from them is clearly outweighed by the social
interest in order and morality." Chaplinsky v. New Hampshire, 315 U.
S. 568 , 315 U. S. 572 (1942).
Although the erroneous statement of fact is not worthy of
constitutional protection, it is nevertheless inevitable in free
debate. As James Madison pointed out in the Report on the Virginia
Resolutions of 1798: "Some degree of abuse is inseparable from the
proper use of every thing; and in no instance is this more true
than in that of the press." 4 J. Elliot, Debates on the Federal
Constitution of 1787, p. 571 (1876). And punishment of error runs
the risk of inducing a cautious and restrictive exercise of the
constitutionally guaranteed freedoms of speech and press. Our
decisions recognize that a rule of strict liability that compels a
publisher or broadcaster to guarantee the accuracy of his factual
assertions may lead to intolerable self-censorship. Allowing the
media to avoid liability only by proving the truth of all injurious
statements does not accord adequate protection to First Amendment
liberties. As the Court stated in New York Times Co. v.
Sullivan, supra, at 376 U. S.
279 :
"Allowance of the defense of truth, Page 418 U. S. 341 with the burden of proving it on the defendant, does not mean
that only false speech will be deterred."
The First Amendment requires that we protect some falsehood in
order to protect speech that matters.
The need to avoid self-censorship by the news media is, however,
not the only societal value at issue. If it were, this Court would
have embraced long ago the view that publishers and broadcasters
enjoy an unconditional and indefeasible immunity from liability for
defamation. See New York Times Co. v. Sullivan, supra, at 376 U. S. 293 (Black, J., concurring); Garrison v. Louisiana, 379 U.S.
at 379 U. S. 80 (DOUGLAS, J., concurring); Curtis Publishing Co. v. Butts, 388 U.S. at 388 U. S. 170 (opinion of Black, J.). Such a rule would, indeed, obviate the fear
that the prospect of civil liability for injurious falsehood might
dissuade a timorous press from the effective exercise of First
Amendment freedoms. Yet absolute protection for the communications
media requires a total sacrifice of the competing value served by
the law of defamation.
The legitimate state interest underlying the law of libel is the
compensation of individuals for the harm inflicted on them by
defamatory falsehood. We would not lightly require the State to
abandon this purpose, for, as MR. JUSTICE STEWART has reminded us,
the individual's right to the protection of his own good name
"reflects no more than our basic concept of the essential
dignity and worth of every human being -- a concept at the root of
any decent system of ordered liberty. The protection of private
personality, like the protection of life itself, is left primarily
to the individual States under the Ninth and Tenth Amendments. But
this does not mean that the right is entitled to any less
recognition by this Court as a basic of our constitutional
system." Rosenblatt v. Baer, 383 U. S. 75 , 383 U. S. 92 (1966) (concurring opinion). Page 418 U. S. 342 Some tension necessarily exists between the need for a vigorous
and uninhibited press and the legitimate interest in redressing
wrongful injury. As Mr. Justice Harlan stated,
"some antithesis between freedom of speech and press and libel
actions persists, for libel remains premised on the content of
speech and limits the freedom of the publisher to express certain
sentiments, at least without guaranteeing legal proof of their
substantial accuracy." Curtis Publishing Co. v. Butts, supra, at 388 U. S. 152 .
In our continuing effort to define the proper accommodation between
these competing concerns, we have been especially anxious to assure
to the freedoms of speech and press that "breathing space"
essential to their fruitful exercise. NAACP v. Button, 371 U. S. 415 , 371 U. S. 433 (1963). To that end, this Court has extended a measure of strategic
protection to defamatory falsehood.
The New York Times standard defines the level of
constitutional protection appropriate to the context of defamation
of a public person. Those who, by reason of the notoriety of their
achievements or the vigor and success with which they seek the
public's attention, are properly classed as public figures and
those who hold governmental office may recover for injury to
reputation only on clear and convincing proof that the defamatory
falsehood was made with knowledge of its falsity or with reckless
disregard for the truth. This standard administers an extremely
powerful antidote to the inducement to media self-censorship of the
common law rule of strict liability for libel and slander. And it
exacts a correspondingly high price from the victims of defamatory
falsehood. Plainly, many deserving plaintiffs, including some
intentionally subjected to injury, will be unable to surmount the
barrier of the New York Times test. Despite this Page 418 U. S. 343 substantial abridgment of the state law right to compensation
for wrongful hurt to one's reputation, the Court has concluded that
the protection of the New York Times privilege should be
available to publishers and broadcasters of defamatory falsehood
concerning public officials and public figures. New York Times
Co. v. Sullivan, supra; Curtis Publishing Co. v. Butts, supra. We think that these decisions are correct, but we do not find their
holdings justified solely by reference to the interest of the press
and broadcast media in immunity from liability. Rather, we believe
that the New York Times rule states an accommodation
between this concern and the limited state interest present in the
context of libel actions brought by public persons. For the reasons
stated below, we conclude that the state interest in compensating
injury to the reputation of private individuals requires that a
different rule should obtain with respect to them.
Theoretically, of course, the balance between the needs of the
press and the individual's claim to compensation for wrongful
injury might be struck on a case-by-case basis. As Mr. Justice
Harlan hypothesized,
"it might seem, purely as an abstract matter, that the most
utilitarian approach would be to scrutinize carefully every jury
verdict in every libel case, in order to ascertain whether the
final judgment leaves fully protected whatever First Amendment
values transcend the legitimate state interest in protecting the
particular plaintiff who prevailed." Rosenbloom v. Metromedia, Inc., 403 U.S. at 403 U. S. 63 (footnote omitted). But this approach would lead to unpredictable
results and uncertain expectations, and it could render our duty to
supervise the lower courts unmanageable. Because an ad hoc resolution of the competing interests at stake in each particular
case is not feasible, we must lay down broad rules of general Page 418 U. S. 344 application: such rules necessarily treat alike various cases
involving differences as well as similarities. Thus, it is often
true that not all of the considerations which justify adoption of a
given rule will obtain in each particular case decided under its
authority.
With that caveat, we have no difficulty in distinguishing among
defamation plaintiffs. The first remedy of any victim of defamation
is self-help -- using available opportunities to contradict the lie
or correct the error, and thereby to minimize its adverse impact on
reputation. Public officials and public figures usually enjoy
significantly greater access to the channels of effective
communication, and hence have a more realistic opportunity to
counteract false statements than private individuals normally
enjoy. [ Footnote 9 ] Private
individuals are therefore more vulnerable to injury, and the state
interest in protecting them is correspondingly greater.
More important than the likelihood that private individuals will
lack effective opportunities for rebuttal, there is a compelling
normative consideration underlying the distinction between public
and private defamation plaintiffs. An individual who decides to
seek governmental office must accept certain necessary consequences
of that involvement in public affairs. He runs the risk of closer
public scrutiny than might otherwise be the case. And society's
interest in the officers of government is not strictly limited to
the formal discharge of official duties. As the Court pointed out
in Garrison v. Louisiana, 379 U.S. at 379 U. S. 77 ,
the public's interest extends to
"anything Page 418 U. S. 345 which might touch on an official's fitness for office. . . . Few
personal attributes are more germane to fitness for office than
dishonesty, malfeasance, or improper motivation, even though these
characteristics may also affect the official's private
character."
Those classed as public figures stand in a similar position.
Hypothetically, it may be possible for someone to become a public
figure through no purposeful action of his own, but the instances
of truly involuntary public figures must be exceedingly rare. For
the most part, those who attain this status have assumed roles of
especial prominence in the affairs of society. Some occupy
positions of such persuasive power and influence that they are
deemed public figures for all purposes. More commonly, those
classed as public figures have thrust themselves to the forefront
of particular public controversies in order to influence the
resolution of the issues involved. In either event, they invite
attention and comment.
Even if the foregoing generalities do not obtain in every
instance, the communications media are entitled to act on the
assumption that public officials and public figures have
voluntarily exposed themselves to increased risk of injury from
defamatory falsehood concerning them. No such assumption is
justified with respect to a private individual. He has not accepted
public office or assumed an "influential role in ordering society." Curtis Publishing Co. v. Butts, 388 U.S. at 388 U. S. 164 (Warren, C.J., concurring in result). He has relinquished no part
of his interest in the protection of his own good name, and
consequently he has a more compelling call on the courts for
redress of injury inflicted by defamatory falsehood. Thus, private
individuals are not only more vulnerable to injury than public
officials and public figures; they are also more deserving of
recovery.
For these reasons, we conclude that the States should retain
substantial latitude in their efforts to enforce a Page 418 U. S. 346 legal remedy for defamatory falsehood injurious to the
reputation of a private individual. The extension of the New
York Times test proposed by the Rosenbloom plurality
would abridge this legitimate state interest to a degree that we
find unacceptable. And it would occasion the additional difficulty
of forcing state and federal judges to decide on an ad hoc basis which publications address issues of "general or public
interest" and which do not -- to determine, in the words of MR.
JUSTICE MARSHALL, "what information is relevant to
self-government." Rosenbloom v. Metromedia, Inc., 403 U.S.
at 403 U. S. 79 . We
doubt the wisdom of committing this task to the conscience of
judges. Nor does the Constitution require us to draw so thin a line
between the drastic alternatives of the New York Times privilege and the common law of strict liability for defamatory
error. The "public or general interest" test for determining the
applicability of the New York Times standard to private
defamation actions inadequately serves both of the competing values
at stake. On the one hand, a private individual whose reputation is
injured by defamatory falsehood that does concern an issue of
public or general interest has no recourse unless he can meet the
rigorous requirements of New York Times. This is true
despite the factors that distinguish the state interest in
compensating private individuals from the analogous interest
involved in the context of public persons. On the other hand, a
publisher or broadcaster of a defamatory error which a court deems
unrelated to an issue of public or general interest may be held
liable in damages even if it took every reasonable precaution to
ensure the accuracy of its assertions. And liability may far exceed
compensation for any actual injury to the plaintiff, for the jury
may be permitted to presume damages without proof of loss and even
to award punitive damages. Page 418 U. S. 347 We hold that, so long as they do not impose liability without
fault, the States may define for themselves the appropriate
standard of liability for a publisher or broadcaster of defamatory
falsehood injurious to a private individual. [ Footnote 10 ] This approach provides a more
equitable Page 418 U. S. 348 boundary between the competing concerns involved here. It
recognizes the strength of the legitimate state interest in
compensating private individuals for wrongful injury to reputation,
yet shields the press and broadcast media from the rigors of strict
liability for defamation. At least this conclusion obtains where,
as here, the substance of the defamatory statement "makes
substantial danger to reputation apparent." [ Footnote 11 ] This phrase places in perspective
the conclusion we announce today. Our inquiry would involve
considerations somewhat different from those discussed above if a
State purported to condition civil liability on a factual
misstatement whose content did not warn a reasonably prudent editor
or broadcaster of its defamatory potential. Cf. Time, Inc. v.
Hill, 385 U. S. 374 (1967). Such a case is not now before us, and we intimate no view
as to its proper resolution. IV Our accommodation of the competing values at stake in defamation
suits by private individuals allows the States to impose liability
on the publisher or broadcaster of defamatory falsehood on a less
demanding showing than that required by New York Times. This conclusion is not based on a belief that the considerations
which prompted the adoption of the New York Times privilege for defamation of public officials and its extension to
public figures are wholly inapplicable to the context of private
individuals. Rather, we endorse this approach in recognition of the
strong and legitimate state interest in compensating private
individuals for injury to reputation. Page 418 U. S. 349 But this countervailing state interest extends no further than
compensation for actual injury. For the reasons stated below, we
hold that the States may not permit recovery of presumed or
punitive damages, at least when liability is not based on a showing
of knowledge of falsity or reckless disregard for the truth.
The common law of defamation is an oddity of tort law, for it
allows recovery of purportedly compensatory damages without
evidence of actual loss. Under the traditional rules pertaining to
actions for libel, the existence of injury is presumed from the
fact of publication. Juries may award substantial sums as
compensation for supposed damage to reputation without any proof
that such harm actually occurred. The largely uncontrolled
discretion of juries to award damages where there is no loss
unnecessarily compounds the potential of any system of liability
for defamatory falsehood to inhibit the vigorous exercise of First
Amendment freedoms. Additionally, the doctrine of presumed damages
invites juries to punish unpopular opinion, rather than to
compensate individuals for injury sustained by the publication of a
false fact. More to the point, the States have no substantial
interest in securing for plaintiffs such as this petitioner
gratuitous awards of money damages far in excess of any actual
injury.
We would not, of course, invalidate state law simply because we
doubt its wisdom, but here we are attempting to reconcile state law
with a competing interest grounded in the constitutional command of
the First Amendment. It is therefore appropriate to require that
state remedies for defamatory falsehood reach no farther than is
necessary to protect the legitimate interest involved. It is
necessary to restrict defamation plaintiffs who do not prove
knowledge of falsity or reckless disregard for the truth to
compensation for actual injury. We Page 418 U. S. 350 need not define "actual injury," as trial courts have wide
experience in framing appropriate jury instructions in tort
actions. Suffice it to say that actual injury is not limited to
out-of-pocket loss. Indeed, the more customary types of actual harm
inflicted by defamatory falsehood include impairment of reputation
and standing in the community, personal humiliation, and mental
anguish and suffering. Of course, juries must be limited by
appropriate instructions, and all awards must be supported by
competent evidence concerning the injury, although there need be no
evidence which assigns an actual dollar value to the injury.
We also find no justification for allowing awards of punitive
damages against publishers and broadcasters held liable under
state-defined standards of liability for defamation. In most
jurisdictions jury discretion over the amounts awarded is limited
only by the gentle rule that they not be excessive. Consequently,
juries assess punitive damages in wholly unpredictable amounts
bearing no necessary relation to the actual harm caused. And they
remain free to use their discretion selectively to punish
expressions of unpopular views. Like the doctrine of presumed
damages, jury discretion to award punitive damages unnecessarily
exacerbates the danger of media self-censorship, but, unlike the
former rule, punitive damages are wholly irrelevant to the state
interest that justifies a negligence standard for private
defamation actions. They are not compensation for injury. Instead,
they are private fines levied by civil juries to punish
reprehensible conduct and to deter its future occurrence. In short,
the private defamation plaintiff who establishes liability under a
less demanding standard than that stated by New York Times may recover only such damages as are sufficient to compensate him
for actual injury. Page 418 U. S. 351 V Notwithstanding our refusal to extend the New York
Times privilege to defamation of private individuals,
respondent contends that we should affirm the judgment below on the
ground that petitioner is either a public official or a public
figure. There is little basis for the former assertion. Several
years prior to the present incident, petitioner had served briefly
on housing committees appointed by the mayor of Chicago, but, at
the time of publication, he had never held any remunerative
governmental position. Respondent admits this, but argues that
petitioner's appearance at the coroner's inquest rendered him a
" de facto public official." Our cases recognize no such
concept. Respondent's suggestion would sweep all lawyers under the New York Times rule as officers of the court, and distort
the plain meaning of the "public official" category beyond all
recognition. We decline to follow it.
Respondent's characterization of petitioner as a public figure
raises a different question. That designation may rest on either of
two alternative bases. In some instances an individual may achieve
such pervasive fame or notoriety that he becomes a public figure
for all purposes and in all contexts. More commonly, an individual
voluntarily injects himself or is drawn into a particular public
controversy, and thereby becomes a public figure for a limited
range of issues. In either case, such persons assume special
prominence in the resolution of public questions.
Petitioner has long been active in community and professional
affairs. He has served as an officer of local civic groups and of
various professional organizations, and he has published several
books and articles on legal subjects. Although petitioner was
consequently well known in some circles, he had achieved no general
fame Page 418 U. S. 352 or notoriety in the community. None of the prospective jurors
called at the trial had ever heard of petitioner prior to this
litigation, and respondent offered no proof that this response was
atypical of the local population. We would not lightly assume that
a citizen's participation in community and professional affairs
rendered him a public figure for all purposes. Absent clear
evidence of general fame or notoriety in the community, and
pervasive involvement in the affairs of society, an individual
should not be deemed a public personality for all aspects of his
life. It is preferable to reduce the public figure question to a
more meaningful context by looking to the nature and extent of an
individual's participation in the particular controversy giving
rise to the defamation.
In this context, it is plain that petitioner was not a public
figure. He played a minimal role at the coroner's inquest, and his
participation related solely to his representation of a private
client. He took no part in the criminal prosecution of Officer
Nuccio. Moreover, he never discussed either the criminal or civil
litigation with the press, and was never quoted as having done so.
He plainly did not thrust himself into the vortex of this public
issue, nor did he engage the public's attention in an attempt to
influence its outcome. We are persuaded that the trial court did
not err in refusing to characterize petitioner as a public figure
for the purpose of this litigation.
We therefore conclude that the New York Times standard
is inapplicable to this case, and that the trial court erred in
entering judgment for respondent. Because the jury was allowed to
impose liability without fault and was permitted to presume damages
without proof of injury, a new trial is necessary. We reverse and
remand for further proceedings in accord with this opinion. It is so ordered. Page 418 U. S. 353 [ Footnote 1 ]
Petitioner filed a cross-motion for summary judgment on grounds
not specified in the record. The court denied petitioner's
cross-motion without discussion in a memorandum opinion of
September 16, 1970.
[ Footnote 2 ] 322 F.
Supp. 997 (1970). Petitioner asserts that the entry of judgment n.o.v. on the basis of his failure to show knowledge of
falsity or reckless disregard for the truth constituted unfair
surprise and deprived him of a full and fair opportunity to prove
"actual malice" on the part of respondent. This contention is not
supported by the record. It is clear that the trial court gave
petitioner no reason to assume that the New York Times privilege would not be available to respondent. The court's
memorandum opinion denying respondent's pretrial motion for summary
judgment does not state that the New York Times standard
was inapplicable to this case. Rather, it reveals that the trial
judge thought it possible for petitioner to make a factual showing
sufficient to overcome respondent's claim of constitutional
privilege. It states in part:
"When there is a factual dispute as to the existence of actual
malice, summary judgment is improper."
" * * * *" "In the instant case, a jury might infer from the evidence that
[respondent's] failure to investigate the truth of the allegations,
coupled with its receipt of communications challenging the factual
accuracy of this author in the past, amounted to actual malice,
that is, 'reckless disregard' of whether the allegations were true
or not. New York Times \[Co.\] v.
Sullivan , [ 376 U.S.
254 ,] 376 U. S. 279 -280
[(1964)]."
Mem.Op., Sept. 16, 1970. Thus, petitioner knew or should have
known that the outcome of the trial might hinge on his ability to
show by clear and convincing evidence that respondent acted with
reckless disregard for the truth. And this question remained open
throughout the trial. Although the court initially concluded that
the applicability of the New York Times rule depended on
petitioner's status as a public figure, the court did not decide
that petitioner was not a public figure until all the evidence had
been presented. Thus, petitioner had every opportunity, indeed
incentive, to prove "reckless disregard" if he could, and he, in
fact, attempted to do so. The record supports the observation by
the Court of Appeals that petitioner
"did present evidence of malice (both the 'constitutional' and
the 'ill will' type) to support his damage claim and no such
evidence was excluded. . . ."
471 F.2d 801, 807 n. 15 (1972).
[ Footnote 3 ]
The court stated:
"[Petitioner's] considerable stature as a lawyer, author,
lecturer, and participant in matters of public import undermine[s]
the validity of the assumption that he is not a 'public figure' as
that term has been used by the progeny of New York Times. Nevertheless, for purposes of decision, we make that assumption and
test the availability of the claim of privilege by the subject
matter of the article." Id. at 805.
[ Footnote 4 ]
In the Court of Appeals petitioner made an ingenious but
unavailing attempt to show that respondent's defamatory charge
against him concerned no issue of public or general interest. He
asserted that the subject matter of the article was the murder
trial of Officer Nuccio, and that he did not participate in that
proceeding. Therefore, he argued, even if the subject matter of the
article generally were protected by the New York Times privilege, under the opinion of the Rosenbloom plurality,
the defamatory statements about him were not. The Court of Appeals
rejected this argument. It noted that the accusations against
petitioner played an integral part in respondent's general thesis
of a nationwide conspiracy to harass the police:
"[W]e may also assume that the article's basic thesis is false.
Nevertheless, under the reasoning of New York Times Co. v.
Sullivan, even a false statement of fact made in support of a
false thesis is protected unless made with knowledge of its falsity
or with reckless disregard of its truth or falsity. It would
undermine the rule of that case to permit the actual falsity of a
statement to determine whether or not its publisher is entitled to
the benefit of the rule."
"If, therefore, we put to one side the false character of the
article and treat it as though its contents were entirely true, it
cannot be denied that the comments about [petitioner] were integral
to its central thesis. They must be tested under the New York
Times standard."
471 F.2d at 806.
We think that the Court of Appeals correctly rejected
petitioner's argument. Its acceptance might lead to arbitrary
imposition of liability on the basis of an unwise differentiation
among kinds of factual misstatements. The present case illustrates
the point. Respondent falsely portrayed petitioner as an architect
of the criminal prosecution against Nuccio. On its face, this
inaccuracy does not appear defamatory. Respondent also falsely
labeled petitioner a "Leninist" and a "Communist-fronter." These
accusations are generally considered defamatory. Under petitioner's
interpretation of the "public or general interest" test, respondent
would have enjoyed a constitutional privilege to publish defamatory
falsehood if petitioner had, in fact, been associated with the
criminal prosecution. But this would mean that the seemingly
innocuous mistake of confusing petitioner's role in the litigation
against Officer Nuccio would destroy the privilege otherwise
available for calling petitioner a Communist-fronter. Thus,
respondent's privilege to publish statements whose content should
have alerted it to the danger of injury to reputation would hinge
on the accuracy of statements that carried with them no such
warning. Assuming that none of these statements was published with
knowledge of falsity or with reckless disregard for the truth, we
see no reason to distinguish among the inaccuracies.
[ Footnote 5 ]
MR. JUSTICE DOUGLAS did not participate in the consideration or
decision of Rosenbloom. [ Footnote 6 ] New York Times and later cases explicated the meaning
of the new standard. In New York Times, the Court held
that, under the circumstances, the newspaper's failure to check the
accuracy of the advertisement against news stories in its own files
did not establish reckless disregard for the truth. 376 U.S. at 376 U. S.
287 -288. In St. Amant v. Thompson, 390 U.
S. 727 , 390 U. S. 731 (1968), the Court equated reckless disregard of the truth with
subjective awareness of probable falsity: "There must be sufficient
evidence to permit the conclusion that the defendant, in fact,
entertained serious doubts as to the truth of his publication." In Beckley Newspapers Corp. v. Hanks, 389 U. S.
81 (1967), the Court emphasized the distinction between
the New York Times test of knowledge of falsity or
reckless disregard of the truth and "actual malice" in the
traditional sense of ill will. Garrison v. Louisiana, 379 U. S. 64 (1964), made plain that the new standard applied to criminal libel
laws as well as to civil actions, and that it governed criticism
directed at "anything which might touch on an official's fitness
for office." Id. at 379 U. S. 77 .
Finally, in Rosenblatt v. Baer, 383 U. S.
75 , 383 U. S. 85 (1966), the Court stated that
"the 'public official' designation applies at the very least to
those among the hierarchy of government employees who have, or
appear to the public to have, substantial responsibility for or
control over the conduct of governmental affairs."
In Time, Inc. v. Hill, 385 U.
S. 374 (1967), the Court applied the New York
Times standard to actions under an unusual state statute. The
statute did not create a cause of action for libel. Rather, it
provided a remedy for unwanted publicity. Although the law allowed
recovery of damages for harm caused by exposure to public
attention, rather than by factual inaccuracies, it recognized truth
as a complete defense. Thus, nondefamatory factual errors could
render a publisher liable for something akin to invasion of
privacy. The Court ruled that the defendant in such an action could
invoke the New York Times privilege regardless of the fame
or anonymity of the plaintiff. Speaking for the Court, MR. JUSTICE
BRENNAN declared that this holding was not an extension of New
York Times, but rather a parallel line of reasoning applying
that standard to this discrete context:
"This is neither a libel action by a private individual nor a
statutory action by a public official. Therefore, although the
First Amendment principles pronounced in New York Times guide our conclusion, we reach that conclusion only by applying
these principles in this discrete context. It therefore serves no
purpose to distinguish the facts here from those in New York
Times. Were this a libel action, the distinction which has
been suggested between the relative opportunities of the public
official and the private individual to rebut defamatory charges
might be germane. And the additional state interest in the
protection of the individual against damage to his reputation would
be involved. Cf. Rosenblatt v. Baer, 383 U. S.
75 , 383 U. S. 91 (STEWART, J.,
concurring)."
385 U.S. at 385 U. S.
390 -391.
[ Footnote 7 ]
Professor Kalven once introduced a discussion of these cases
with the apt heading, "You Can't Tell the Players without a Score
Card." Kalven, The Reasonable Man and the First Amendment: Hill, Butts, and Walker, 1967 Sup.Ct.Rev. 267,
275. Only three other Justices joined Mr. Justice Harlan's analysis
of the issues involved. In his concurring opinion, Mr. Chief
Justice Warren stated the principle for which these cases stand --
that the New York Times test reaches both public figures
and public officials. MR. JUSTICE BRENNAN and MR. JUSTICE WHITE
agreed with the Chief Justice on that question. Mr. Justice Black
and MR. JUSTICE DOUGLAS reiterated their view that publishers
should have an absolute immunity from liability for defamation, but
they acquiesced in the Chief Justice's reasoning in order to enable
a majority of the Justices to agree on the question of the
appropriate constitutional privilege for defamation of public
figures.
[ Footnote 8 ]
As Thomas Jefferson made the point in his first Inaugural
address:
"If there be any among us who would wish to dissolve this Union
or change its republican form, let them stand undisturbed as
monuments of the safety with which error of opinion may be
tolerated where reason is left free to combat it."
[ Footnote 9 ]
Of course, an opportunity for rebuttal seldom suffices to undo
harm of defamatory falsehood. Indeed, the law of defamation is
rooted in our experience that the truth rarely catches up with a
lie. But the fact that the self-help remedy of rebuttal, standing
alone, is inadequate to its task does not mean that it is
irrelevant to our inquiry.
[ Footnote 10 ]
Our caveat against strict liability is the prime target of MR.
JUSTICE WHITE's dissent. He would hold that a publisher or
broadcaster may be required to prove the truth of a defamatory
statement concerning a private individual and, failing such proof,
that the publisher or broadcaster may be held liable for defamation
even though he took every conceivable precaution to ensure the
accuracy of the offending statement prior to its dissemination. Post at 418 U. S.
388 -392. In MR. JUSTICE WHITE's view, one who publishes
a statement that later turns out to be inaccurate can never be
"without fault" in any meaningful sense, for "[i]t is he who
circulated a falsehood that he was not required to
publish. " Post at 418 U. S. 392 (emphasis added).
MR. JUSTICE WHITE characterizes New York Times Co. v.
Sullivan, 376 U. S. 254 (1964), as simply a case of seditious libel. Post at 418 U. S. 387 .
But that rationale is certainly inapplicable to Curtis
Publishing Co. v. Butts, 388 U. S. 130 (1967), where MR. JUSTICE WHITE joined four other Members of the
Court to extend the "knowing or reckless falsity" standard to media
defamation of persons identified as public figures but not
connected with the Government. MR. JUSTICE WHITE now suggests that
he would abide by that vote, post at 418 U. S. 398 ,
but the full thrust of his dissent -- as we read it -- contradicts
that suggestion. Finally, in Rosenbloom v. Metromedia,
Inc., 403 U. S. 29 , 403 U. S. 57 (1971), MR. JUSTICE WHITE voted to apply the New York
Times privilege to media defamation of an individual who was
neither a public official nor a public figure. His opinion states
that the "knowing or reckless falsity" standard should apply to
media "comment upon the official actions of public servants," id. at 403 U. S. 62 ,
including defamatory falsehood about a person arrested by the
police. If adopted by the Court, this conclusion would
significantly extend the New York Times privilege.
MR. JUSTICE WHITE asserts that our decision today "trivializes
and denigrates the interest in reputation," Miami Herald
Publishing Co. v. Tornillo, ante, at 418 U. S. 262 (concurring opinion), that it "scuttle[s] the libel laws of the
States in . . . wholesale fashion" and renders ordinary citizens
"powerless to protect themselves." Post at 418 U. S. 370 .
In light of the progressive extension of the "knowing or reckless
falsity" requirement detailed in the preceding paragraph, one might
have viewed today's decision allowing recovery under any standard
save strict liability as a more generous accommodation of the state
interest in comprehensive reputational injury to private
individuals than the law presently affords.
[ Footnote 11 ] Curtis Publishing Co. v. Butts, supra, at 388 U. S.
155 .
MR. JUSTICE BLACKMUN, concurring.
I joined MR. JUSTICE BRENNAN's opinion for the plurality in Rosenbloom v. Metromedia, Inc., 403 U. S.
29 (1971). I did so because I concluded that, given New York Times Co. v. Sullivan, 376 U.
S. 254 (1964), and its progeny (noted by the Court, ante at 418 U. S.
334 -336, n. 6), as well as Curtis Publishing Co. v.
Butts and Associated Press v. Walker, 388 U.
S. 130 (1967), the step taken in Rosenbloom, extending the New York Times doctrine to an event of
public or general interest, was logical and inevitable. A majority
of the Court evidently thought otherwise, as is particularly
evidenced by MR. JUSTICE WHITE's separate concurring opinion there
and by the respective dissenting opinions of Mr. Justice Harlan and
of MR. JUSTICE MARSHALL joined by MR. JUSTICE STEWART.
The Court today refuses to apply New York Times to the
private individual, as contrasted with the public official and the
public figure. It thus withdraws to the factual limits of the
pre- Rosenbloom cases. It thereby fixes the outer boundary
of the New York Times doctrine, and says that, beyond that
boundary, a State is free to define for itself the appropriate
standard of media liability so long as it does not impose liability
without fault. As my joinder in Rosenbloom's plurality
opinion would intimate, I sense some illogic in this.
The Court, however, seeks today to strike a balance between
competing values where necessarily uncertain assumptions about
human behavior color the result. Although the Court's opinion in
the present case departs from the rationale of the Rosenbloom plurality, in that the Court now conditions a
libel action by a private person upon a showing of negligence, as
contrasted with a showing of willful or reckless disregard, I am
willing to Page 418 U. S. 354 join, and do join, the Court's opinion and its judgment for two
reasons:
1. By removing the specters of presumed and punitive damages in
the absence of New York Times malice, the Court eliminates
significant and powerful motives for self-censorship that otherwise
are present in the traditional libel action. By so doing, the Court
leaves what should prove to be sufficient and adequate breathing
space for a vigorous press. What the Court has done, I believe,
will have little, if any, practical effect on the functioning of
responsible journalism.
2. The Court was sadly fractionated in Rosenbloom. A
result of that kind inevitably leads to uncertainty. I feel that it
is of profound importance for the Court to come to rest in the
defamation area and to have a clearly defined majority position
that eliminates the unsureness engendered by Rosenbloom's diversity. If my vote were not needed to create a majority, I would
adhere to my prior view. A definitive ruling, however, is
paramount. See Curtis Publishing Co. v. Butts, 388 U.S. at 388 U. S. 170 (Black, J., concurring); Time, Inc. v. Hill, 385 U.
S. 374 , 385 U. S. 398 (1967) (Black, J., concurring); United States v. Vuitch, 402 U. S. 62 , 402 U. S. 97 (1971) (separate statement).
For these reasons, I join the opinion and the judgment of the
Court.
MR. CHIEF JUSTICE BURGER, dissenting.
The doctrines of the law of defamation have had a gradual
evolution primarily in the state courts. In New York Times Co.
v. Sullivan, 376 U. S. 254 (1964), and its progeny this Court entered this field.
Agreement or disagreement with the law as it has evolved to this
time does not alter the fact that it has been orderly development
with a consistent basic rationale. In today's opinion, the Court
abandons the traditional Page 418 U. S. 355 thread so far as the ordinary private citizen is concerned, and
introduces the concept that the media will be liable for negligence
in publishing defamatory statements with respect to such persons.
Although I agree with much of what MR. JUSTICE WHITE states, I do
not read the Court's new doctrinal approach in quite the way he
does. I am frank to say I do not know the parameters of a
"negligence" doctrine as applied to the news media. Conceivably
this new doctrine could inhibit some editors, as the dissents of
MR. JUSTICE DOUGLAS and MR. JUSTICE BRENNAN suggest. But I would
prefer to allow this area of law to continue to evolve as it has up
to now with respect to private citizens, rather than embark on a
new doctrinal theory which has no jurisprudential ancestry.
The petitioner here was performing a professional representative
role as an advocate in the highest tradition of the law, and, under
that tradition, the advocate is not to be invidiously identified
with his client. The important public policy which underlies this
tradition -- the right to counsel -- would be gravely jeopardized
if every lawyer who takes an "unpopular" case, civil or criminal,
would automatically become fair game for irresponsible reporters
and editors who might, for example, describe the lawyer as a "mob
mouthpiece" for representing a client with a serious prior criminal
record, or as an "ambulance chaser" for representing a claimant in
a personal injury action.
I would reverse the judgment of the Court of Appeals and remand
for reinstatement of the verdict of the jury and the entry of an
appropriate judgment on that verdict.
MR. JUSTICE DOUGLAS, dissenting.
The Court describes this case as a return to the struggle of
"defin[ing] the proper accommodation between the law of defamation
and the freedoms of speech and press protected by the First
Amendment." It is indeed a struggle, once described by Mr. Justice
Black as "the same Page 418 U. S. 356 quagmire" in which the Court "is now helplessly struggling in
the field of obscenity." Curtis Publishing Co. v. Butts, 388 U. S. 130 , 388 U. S. 171 (concurring opinion). I would suggest that the struggle is a quite
hopeless one, for, in light of the command of the First Amendment,
no "accommodation" of its freedoms can be "proper" except those
made by the Framers themselves.
Unlike the right of privacy which, by the terms of the Fourth
Amendment, must be accommodated with reasonable searches and
seizures and warrants issued by magistrates, the rights of free
speech and of a free press were protected by the Framers in
verbiage whose proscription seems clear. I have stated before my
view that the First Amendment would bar Congress from passing any
libel law. [ Footnote 2/1 ] This was
the view held by Thomas Jefferson, [ Footnote 2/2 ] and it is one Congress has never
challenged through enactment of a civil libel statute. The sole
congressional attempt at this variety of First Amendment muzzle was
in the Sedition Act of 1798 -- criminal libel act never tested in
this Court and one which expired, by its terms, three years after
enactment. As President, Thomas Jefferson pardoned those who were
convicted under the Act, and fines levied in its prosecution were
repaid by Act of Congress. [ Footnote
2/3 ] The general Page 418 U. S. 357 consensus was that the Act constituted a regrettable legislative
exercise plainly in violation of the First Amendment. [ Footnote 2/4 ]
With the First Amendment made applicable to the States through
the Fourteenth, [ Footnote 2/5 ] I do
not see how States have any more ability to "accommodate" freedoms
of speech or of the press than does Congress. This is true whether
the form of the accommodation is civil or criminal, since "[w]hat a
State may not constitutionally bring about by means of a criminal
statute is likewise beyond the reach of its civil law of libel." New York Times Co. v. Sullivan, 376 U.
S. 254 , 376 U. S. 277 .
Like Congress, States are without power "to use a civil libel law
or any other law to impose damages for merely discussing public
affairs." Id. at 376 U. S. 295 (Black, J., concurring). [ Footnote
2/6 ] Page 418 U. S. 358 Continued recognition of the possibility of state libel suits
for public discussion of public issues leaves the freedom of speech
honored by the Fourteenth Amendment a diluted version of First
Amendment protection. This view is only possible if one accepts the
position that the First Amendment is applicable to the States only
through the Due Process Clause of the Fourteenth, due process
freedom of speech being only that freedom which this Court might
deem to be "implicit in the concept of ordered liberty." [ Footnote 2/7 ] But the Court frequently has
rested Page 418 U. S. 359 state free speech and free press decisions on the Fourteenth
Amendment generally, [ Footnote 2/8 ]
rather than on the Due Process Clause alone. The Fourteenth
Amendment speaks not only of due process, but also of "privileges
and immunities" of United States citizenship. I can conceive of no
privilege or immunity with a higher claim to recognition against
state abridgment than the freedoms of speech and of the press. In
our federal system, we are all subject to two governmental regimes,
and freedoms of speech and of the press protected against the
infringement of only one are quite illusory. The identity of the
oppressor is, I would think, a matter of relative indifference to
the oppressed.
There can be no doubt that a State impinges upon free and open
discussion when it sanctions the imposition of damages for such
discussion through its civil libel laws. Discussion of public
affairs is often marked by highly charged emotions, and jurymen,
not unlike us all, are subject to those emotions. It is indeed this
very type of speech which is the reason for the First Amendment,
since speech which arouses little emotion is little in need of
protection. The vehicle for publication in this case was the
American Opinion, a most controversial periodical which
disseminates the views of the John Birch Society, an organization
which many deem to be Page 418 U. S. 360 quite offensive. The subject matter involved "Communist plots,"
"conspiracies against law enforcement agencies," and the killing of
a private citizen by the police. With any such amalgam of
controversial elements pressing upon the jury, a jury
determination, unpredictable in the most neutral circumstances,
becomes for those who venture to discuss heated issues, a virtual
roll of the dice separating them from liability for often massive
claims of damage.
It is only the hardy publisher who will engage in discussion in
the face of such risk, and the Court's preoccupation with
proliferating standards in the area of libel increases the risks.
It matters little whether the standard be articulated as "malice"
or "reckless disregard of the truth" or "negligence," for jury
determinations by any of those criteria are virtually unreviewable.
This Court, in its continuing delineation of variegated mantles of
First Amendment protection, is, like the potential publisher, left
with only speculation on how jury findings were influenced by the
effect the subject matter of the publication had upon the minds and
viscera of the jury. The standard announced today leaves the States
free to "define for themselves the appropriate standard of
liability for a publisher or broadcaster" in the circumstances of
this case. This, of course, leaves the simple negligence standard
as an option, with the jury free to impose damages upon a finding
that the publisher failed to act as "a reasonable man." With such
continued erosion of First Amendment protection, I fear that it may
well be the reasonable man who refrains from speaking.
Since, in my view, the First and Fourteenth Amendments prohibit
the imposition of damages upon respondent for this discussion of
public affairs, I would affirm the judgment below. Page 418 U. S. 361 [ Footnote 2/1 ] See, e.g., Rosenblatt v. Baer, 383 U. S.
75 , 383 U. S. 90 (concurring).
[ Footnote 2/2 ]
In 1798, Jefferson stated:
"[The First Amendment] thereby guard[s] in the same sentence,
and under the same words, the freedom of religion, of speech, and
of the press insomuch, that whatever violates either throws down
the sanctuary which covers the others, and that libels,
falsehood, and defamation, equally with heresy and false religion,
are withheld from the cognizance of federal tribunals. . .
."
8 The Works of Thomas Jefferson 464-465 (Ford ed.1904) (emphasis
added).
[ Footnote 2/3 ] See, e.g., Act of July 4, 1840, c. 45, 6 Stat. 802,
accompanied by H.R.Rep. No. 86, 26th Cong., 1st Sess. (1840).
[ Footnote 2/4 ]
Senator Calhoun, in reporting to Congress, assumed the
invalidity of the Act to be a matter "which no one now doubts."
Report with Senate Bill No. 122, S.Doc. No. 118, 24th Cong., 1st
Sess., 3 (1836).
[ Footnote 2/5 ] See Stromberg v. California, 283 U.
S. 359 , 283 U. S.
368 -369.
[ Footnote 2/6 ]
Since this case involves a discussion of public affairs, I need
not decide at this point whether the First Amendment prohibits all
libel actions. "An unconditional right to say what one pleases
about public affairs is what I consider to be the minimum guarantee
of the First Amendment." New York Times Co. v. Sullivan, 376 U. S. 254 , 376 U. S. 297 (Black, J., concurring) (emphasis added). But "public affairs"
includes a great deal more than merely political affairs. Matters
of science, economics, business, art, literature, etc., are all
matters of interest to the general public. Indeed, any matter of
sufficient general interest to prompt media coverage may be said to
be a public affair. Certainly police killings, "Communist
conspiracies," and the like qualify.
A more regressive view of free speech has surfaced, but it has
thus far gained no judicial acceptance. Solicitor General Bork has
stated:
"Constitutional protection should be accorded only to speech
that is explicitly political. There is no basis for judicial
intervention to protect any other form of expression, be it
scientific, literary or that variety of expression we call obscene
or pornographic. Moreover, within that category of speech we
ordinarily call political, there should be no constitutional
obstruction to laws making criminal any speech that advocates
forcible overthrow of the government or the violation of any
law."
Bork, Neutral Principles and Some First Amendment Problems, 47
Ind.L.J. 1, 20 (1971).
According to this view, Congress, upon finding a painting
aesthetically displeasing or a novel poorly written or a
revolutionary new scientific theory unsound could constitutionally
prohibit exhibition of the painting, distribution of the book or
discussion of the theory. Congress might also proscribe the
advocacy of the violation of any law, apparently without regard to
the law's constitutionality. Thus, were Congress to pass a
blatantly invalid law such as one prohibiting newspaper editorials
critical of the Government, a publisher might be punished for
advocating its violation. Similarly, the late Dr. Martin Luther
King, Jr., could have been punished for advising blacks to
peacefully sit in the front of buses or to ask for service in
restaurants segregated by law.
[ Footnote 2/7 ] See Palko v. Connecticut, 302 U.
S. 319 , 302 U. S. 325 .
As Mr. Justice Black has noted, by this view, the test becomes
"whether the government has an interest in abridging the right
involved, and, if so, whether that interest is of sufficient
importance, in the opinion of a majority of the Supreme
Court, to justify the government's action in doing so. Such a
doctrine can be used to justify almost any government suppression
of First Amendment freedoms. As I have stated many times before, I
cannot subscribe to this doctrine, because I believe that the First
Amendment's unequivocal command that there shall be no abridgement
of the rights of free speech shows that the men who drafted our
Bill of Rights did all the 'balancing' that was to be done in this
field."
H. Black, A Constitutional Faith 52 (1969).
[ Footnote 2/8 ] See, e.g., Bridges v. California, 314 U.
S. 252 , 314 U. S. 263 n. 6 (Black, J.); Murdock v. Pennsylvania, 319 U.
S. 105 , 319 U. S. 108 (DOUGLAS, J.); Saia v. New York, 334 U.
S. 558 , 334 U. S. 560 (DOUGLAS, J.); Talley v. California, 362 U. S.
60 , 362 U. S. 62 (Black, J.); DeGregory v. Attorney General of New
Hampshire, 383 U. S. 825 , 383 U. S. 828 (DOUGIAS, J.); Elfbrant v. Russell, 384 U. S.
11 , 384 U. S. 18 (DOUGLAS, J.); Mills v. Alabama, 384 U.
S. 214 , 384 U. S. 218 (Black, J.); Mine Workers v. Illinois Bar Assn., 389 U. S. 217 , 389 U. S.
221 -222, and n. 4 (Black, J.).
MR. JUSTICE BRENNAN, dissenting.
I agree with the conclusion, expressed in 418 U.
S. that, at the time of publication of respondent's
article, petitioner could not properly have been viewed as either a
"public official" or "public figure"; instead, respondent's
article, dealing with an alleged conspiracy to discredit local
police forces, concerned petitioner's purported involvement in "an
event of public or general interest." Roosenbloom v.
Metromedia, Inc., 403 U. S. 29 , 403 U. S. 31 -32
(1971); see ante at 418 U. S.
331 -332, n. 4. I cannot agree, however, that free and
robust debate-- so essential to the proper functioning of our
system of government -- is permitted adequate "breathing space," NAACP v. Button, 371 U. S. 415 , 371 U. S. 433 (1963), when, as the Court holds, the States may impose all but
strict liability for defamation if the defamed party is a private
person and "the substance of the defamatory statement makes
substantial danger to reputation apparent.'" Ante at 418 U. S. 348 .
[ Footnote 3/1 ] I adhere to my view
expressed in Rosenbloom v. Metromedia, Inc., supra, that
we strike the proper accommodation between avoidance of media
self-censorship and protection of individual reputations only when
we require States to apply the New York Times Co. v.
Sullivan, 376 U. S. 254 (1964), "knowing or reckless falsity" standard in civil libel
actions concerning media reports of the involvement of private
individuals in events of public or general interest. The Court does not hold that First Amendment guarantees do not
extend to speech concerning private persons' involvement in events
of public or general interest. It recognizes that self-governance
in this country perseveres because of our "profound national
commitment Page 418 U. S. 362 to the principle that debate on public issues should be
uninhibited, robust, and wide-open." Id. at 376 U. S. 270 (emphasis added). Thus, guarantees of free speech and press
necessarily reach "far more than knowledge and debate about the
strictly official activities of various levels of government," Rosenbloom v. Metromedia, Inc., supra, at 403 U. S. 41 ;
for
"[f]reedom of discussion, if it would fulfill its historic
function in this nation, must embrace all issues about which
information is needed or appropriate to enable the members of
society to cope with the exigencies of their period." Thornhill v. Alabama, 310 U. S. 88 , 310 U. S. 102 (1940).
The teaching to be distilled from our prior cases is that, while
public interest in events may at times be influenced by the
notoriety of the individuals involved, "[t]he public's primary
interest is, in the event[,] . . . the conduct of the participant
and the content, effect, and significance of the conduct. . . ." Rosenbloom, supra, at 403 U. S. 43 .
Matters of public or general interest do not "suddenly become less
so merely because a private individual is involved, or because, in
some sense, the individual did not voluntarily' choose to
become involved." Ibid. See Time, Inc. v. Hill, 385 U. S. 374 , 385 U. S. 388 (1967). Although acknowledging that First Amendment values are of no
less significance when media reports concern private persons'
involvement in matters of public concern, the Court refuses to
provide, in such cases, the same level of constitutional protection
that has been afforded the media in the context of defamation of
public persons. The accommodation that this Court has established
between free speech and libel laws in cases involving public
officials and public figures -- that defamatory falsehood be shown
by clear and convincing evidence to have been published with
knowledge of falsity or with reckless disregard of truth -- is not
apt, the Court holds because Page 418 U. S. 363 the private individual does not have the same degree of access
to the media to rebut defamatory comments as does the public
person, and he has not voluntarily exposed himself to public
scrutiny.
While these arguments are forcefully and eloquently presented, I
cannot accept them, for the reasons I stated in Rosenbloom: "The New York Times standard was applied to libel of a
public official or public figure to give effect to the [First]
Amendment's function to encourage ventilation of public issues, not
because the public official has any less interest in protecting his
reputation than an individual in private life. While the argument
that public figures need less protection because they can command
media attention to counter criticism may be true for some very
prominent people, even then it is the rare case where the denial
overtakes the original charge. Denials, retractions, and
corrections are not 'hot' news, and rarely receive the prominence
of the original story. When the public official or public figure is
a minor functionary, or has left the position that put him in the
public eye . . . , the argument loses all of its force. In the vast
majority of libels involving public officials or public figures,
the ability to respond through the media will depend on the same
complex factor on which the ability of a private individual
depends: the unpredictable event of the media's continuing interest
in the story. Thus, the unproved, and highly improbable,
generalization that an as-yet [not fully defined] class of 'public
figures' involved in matters of public concern will be better able
to respond through the media than private individuals also involved
in such matters seems too insubstantial Page 418 U. S. 364 a reed on which to rest a constitutional distinction."
403 U.S. at 403 U. S. 46 -47.
Moreover, the argument that private persons should not be required
to prove New York Times "knowing or reckless falsity"
because they do not assume the risk of defamation by freely
entering the public arena "bears little relationship either to the
values protected by the First Amendment or to the nature of our
society." Id. at 403 U. S. 47 .
Social interaction exposes all of us to some degree of public view.
This Court has observed that "[t]he risk of this exposure is an
essential incident of life in a society which places a primary
value on freedom of speech and of press." Time, Inc. v.
Hill, 385 U.S. at 385 U. S. 388 .
Therefore,
"[v]oluntarily or not, we are all 'public' men to some degree.
Conversely, some aspects of the lives of even the most public men
fall outside the area of matters of public or general concern. See . . . Griswold v. Connecticut, 381 U. S.
479 (1965). Thus, the idea that certain 'public' figures
have voluntarily exposed their entire lives to public inspection,
while private individuals have kept theirs carefully shrouded from
public view is, at best, a legal fiction. In any event, such a
distinction could easily produce the paradoxical result of
dampening discussion of issues of public or general concern because
they happen to involve private citizens while extending
constitutional encouragement to discussion of aspects of the lives
of 'public figures' that are not in the area of public or general
concern." Rosenbloom, supra, at 403 U. S. 48 (footnote omitted).
To be sure, no one commends publications which defame the good
name and reputation of any person: "In an ideal world, the
responsibility of the press would match the freedom and public
trust given it." Id. at Page 418 U. S. 365 403 U. S. 51 .
[ Footnote 3/2 ] Rather, as the Court
agrees, some abuse of First Amendment freedoms is tolerated only to
insure that would-be commentators on events of public or general
interest are not
"deterred from voicing their criticism, even though it is
believed to be true and even though it is, in fact, true, because
of doubt whether it can be proved in court or fear of the expense
of having to do so." New York Times Co. v. Sullivan, 376 U.S. at 376 U. S. 279 .
The Court's holding and a fortiori my Brother WHITE's
views, see 418
U.S. 323 fn3/1|>n. 1, supra, simply deny free
expression its needed "breathing space." Today's decision will
exacerbate the rule of self-censorship of legitimate utterance as
publishers "steer far wider of the unlawful zone," Speiser v.
Randall, 357 U. S. 513 , 357 U. S. 526 (1958).
We recognized in New York Times Co. v. Sullivan, supra, at 376 U. S. 279 ,
that a rule requiring a critic of official conduct to guarantee the
truth of all of his factual contentions would inevitably lead to
self-censorship when Page 418 U. S. 366 publishers, fearful of being unable to prove truth or unable to
bear the expense of attempting to do so, simply eschewed printing
controversial articles. Adoption, by many States, of a reasonable
care standard in cases where private individuals are involved in
matters of public interest -- the probable result of today's
decision -- will likewise lead to self-censorship, since publishers
will be required carefully to weigh a myriad of uncertain factors
before publication. The reasonable care standard is "elusive," Time, Inc. v. Hill, supra, at 385 U. S. 389 ;
it saddles the press with
"the intolerable burden of guessing how a jury might assess the
reasonableness of steps taken by it to verify the accuracy of every
reference to a name, picture or portrait." Ibid. Under a reasonable care regime, publishers and
broadcasters will have to make pre-publication judgments about
juror assessment of such diverse considerations as the size,
operating procedures, and financial condition of the newsgathering
system, as well as the relative costs and benefits of instituting
less frequent and more costly reporting at a higher level of
accuracy. See The Supreme Court, 1970 Term, 85 Harv.L.Rev.
3, 228 (1971). Moreover, in contrast to proof by clear and
convincing evidence required under the New York Times test, the burden of proof for reasonable care will doubtless be the
preponderance of the evidence.
"In the normal civil suit, where [the preponderance of the
evidence] standard is employed, 'we view it as no more serious in
general for there to be an erroneous verdict in the defendant's
favor than for there to be an erroneous verdict in the plaintiff's
favor.' In re Winship, 397 U. S. 358 , 397 U. S.
371 (1970) (HARLAN, J., concurring). In libel cases,
however, we view an erroneous verdict for the plaintiff as most
serious. Not only does it mulct the defendant for an innocent
misstatement . . . but the Page 418 U. S. 367 possibility of such error, even beyond the vagueness of the
negligence standard itself, would create a strong impetus toward
self-censorship, which the First Amendment cannot tolerate." Rosenbloom, 403 U.S. at 403 U. S. 50 .
And, most hazardous, the flexibility which inheres in the
reasonable care standard will create the danger that a jury will
convert it into
"an instrument for the suppression of those 'vehement, caustic,
and sometimes unpleasantly sharp attacks' . . . which must be
protected if the guarantees of the First and Fourteenth Amendments
are to prevail." Monitor Patriot Co. v. Roy, 401 U.
S. 265 , 401 U. S. 277 (1971).
The Court does not discount altogether the danger that jurors
will punish for the expression of unpopular opinions. This
probability accounts for the Court's limitation that
"the States may not permit recovery of presumed or punitive
damages, at least when liability is not based on a showing of
knowledge of falsity or reckless disregard for the truth." Ante at 418 U. S. 349 .
But plainly a jury's latitude to impose liability for want of due
care poses a far greater threat of suppressing unpopular views than
does a possible recovery of presumed or punitive damages. Moreover,
the Court's broad-ranging examples of "actual injury," including
impairment of reputation and standing in the community, as well as
personal humiliation, and mental anguish and suffering, inevitably
allow a jury bent on punishing expression of unpopular views a
formidable weapon for doing so. Finally, even a limitation of
recovery to "actual injury" -- however much it reduces the size or
frequency of recoveries -- will not provide the necessary elbowroom
for First Amendment expression.
"It is not simply the possibility of a judgment for damages that
results in self-censorship. The very Page 418 U. S. 368 possibility of having to engage in litigation, an expensive and
protracted process, is threat enough to cause discussion and debate
to 'steer far wider of the unlawful zone,' thereby keeping
protected discussion from public cognizance. . . . Too, a small
newspaper suffers equally from a substantial damage award, whether
the label of the award be 'actual' or 'punitive.'" Rosenbloom, supra, at 403 U. S.
52 -53.
On the other hand, the uncertainties which the media face under
today's decision are largely avoided by the New York Times standard. I reject the argument that my Rosenbloom view
improperly commits to judges the task of determining what is and
what is not an issue of "general or public interest." [ Footnote 3/3 ] I noted in Rosenbloom Page 418 U. S. 369 that performance of this task would not always be easy. Id. at 403 U. S. 49 n.
17. But surely the courts, the ultimate arbiters of all disputes
concerning clashes of constitutional values, would only be
performing one of their traditional functions in undertaking this
duty. Also, the difficulty of this task has been substantially
lessened by that
"sizable body of cases, decided both before and after Rosenbloom, that have employed the concept of a matter of
public concern to reach decisions in . . . cases dealing with an
alleged libel of a private individual that employed a public
interest standard . . . and . . . cases that applied Butts to the alleged libel of a public figure."
Comment, The Expanding Constitutional Protection for the News
Media from Liability for Defamation: Predictability and the New
Synthesis, 70 Mich.L.Rev. 1547, 1560 (1972). The public interest is
necessarily broad; any residual self-censorship that may result
from the uncertain contours of the "general or public interest"
concept should be of far less concern to publishers and
broadcasters than that occasioned by state laws imposing liability
for negligent falsehood.
Since petitioner failed, after having been given a full and fair
opportunity, to prove that respondent published the disputed
article with knowledge of its falsity or with reckless disregard of
the truth, see ante at 418 U. S.
329 -330, n. 2, I would affirm the judgment of the Court
of Appeals.
[ Footnote 3/1 ] A fortiori, I disagree with in Brother WHITE's view
that the States should have free rein to impose strict liability
for defamation in cases not involving public persons.
[ Footnote 3/2 ]
A respected commentator has observed that factors other than
purely legal constraints operate to control the press:
"Traditions, attitudes, and general rules of political conduct
are far more important controls. The fear of opening a credibility
gap, and thereby lessening one's influence, holds some participants
in check. Institutional pressures in large organizations, including
some of the press, have a similar effect; it is difficult for an
organization to have an open policy of making intentionally false
accusations."
T. Emerson, The System of Freedom of Expression 538 (1970).
Typical of the press' own ongoing self-evaluation is a proposal to
establish a national news council, composed of members drawn from
the public and the journalism profession, to examine and report on
complaints concerning the accuracy and fairness of news reporting
by the largest newsgathering sources. Twentieth Century Fund Task
Force Report for a National News Council, A Free and Responsive
Press (1973). See also Comment, The Expanding
Constitutional Protection for the News Media from Liability for
Defamation: Predictability and the New Synthesis, 70 Mich.L.Rev.
1547, 1569-1570 (1972).
[ Footnote 3/3 ]
The Court, taking a novel step, would not limit application of
First Amendment protection to private libels involving issues of
general or public interest, but would forbid the States from
imposing liability without fault in any case where the substance of
the defamatory statement made substantial danger to reputation
apparent. As in Rosenbloom v. Metromedia, Inc., 403 U. S. 29 , 403 U. S. 44 n.
12, 403 U. S. 48 -49,
n. 17 (1971), I would leave open the question of what
constitutional standard, if any, applies when defamatory falsehoods
are published or broadcast concerning either a private or public
person's activities not within the scope of the general or public
interest.
Parenthetically, my Brother WHITE argues that the Court's view
and mine will prevent a plaintiff -- unable to demonstrate some
degree of fault -- from vindicating his reputation by securing a
judgment that the publication was false. This argument overlooks
the possible enactment of statutes, not requiring proof of fault,
which provide for an action for retraction or for publication of a
court's determination of falsity if the plaintiff is able to
demonstrate that false statements have been published concerning
his activities. Cf. Note, Vindication of the Reputation of
a Public Official, 80 Harv.L.Rev. 1730, 1739-1747 (1967). Although
it may be that questions could be raised concerning the
constitutionality of such statutes, certainly nothing I have said
today (and, as I read the Court's opinion, nothing said there)
should be read to imply that a private plaintiff, unable to prove
fault, must inevitably be denied the opportunity to secure a
judgment upon the truth or falsity of statements published about
him. Cf. Rosenbloom v. Metromedia, Inc., supra, at 403 U. S. 47 ,
and n. 15.
MR. JUSTICE WHITE, dissenting.
For some 200 years -- from the very founding of the Nation --
the law of defamation and right of the ordinary citizen to recover
for false publication injurious to his reputation have been almost
exclusively the business of Page 418 U. S. 370 state courts and legislatures. Under typical state defamation
law, the defamed private citizen had to prove only a false
publication that would subject him to hatred, contempt, or
ridicule. Given such publication, general damage to reputation was
presumed, while punitive damages required proof of additional
facts. The law governing the defamation of private citizens
remained untouched by the First Amendment, because, until
relatively recently, the consistent view of the Court was that
libelous words constitute a class of speech wholly unprotected by
the First Amendment, subject only to limited exceptions carved out
since 1964.
But now, using that Amendment as the chosen instrument, the
Court, in a few printed pages, has federalized major aspects of
libel law by declaring unconstitutional in important respects the
prevailing defamation law in all or most of the 50 States. That
result is accomplished by requiring the plaintiff in each and every
defamation action to prove not only the defendant's culpability
beyond his act of publishing defamatory material, but also actual
damage to reputation resulting from the publication. Moreover,
punitive damages may not be recovered by showing malice in the
traditional sense of ill will; knowing falsehood or reckless
disregard of the truth will now be required.
I assume these sweeping changes will be popular with the press,
but this is not the road to salvation for a court of law. As I see
it, there are wholly insufficient grounds for scuttling the libel
laws of the States in such wholesale fashion, to say nothing of
deprecating the reputation interest of ordinary citizens and
rendering them powerless to protect themselves. I do not suggest
that the decision is illegitimate or beyond the bounds of judicial
review, but it is an ill-considered exercise of the power entrusted
to this Court, particularly when the Page 418 U. S. 371 Court has not had the benefit of briefs and argument addressed
to most of the major issues which the Court now decides. I
respectfully dissent. I Lest there be any mistake about it, the changes wrought by the
Court's decision cut very deeply. In 1938, the Restatement of Torts
reflected the historic rule that publication in written form of
defamatory material -- material tending
"so to harm the reputation of another as to lower him in the
estimation of the community or to deter third persons from
associating or dealing with him [ Footnote 4/1 ]"
-- subjected the publisher to liability although no special harm
to reputation was actually proved. [ Footnote 4/2 ] Restatement Page 418 U. S. 372 of Torts § 569 (1938). [ Footnote
4/3 ] Truth was a defense, and some libels were privileged; but,
given a false circulation, general damage to reputation was
presumed, and damages could be awarded by the jury, along with any
special damages such as pecuniary loss and emotional distress. At
the very least, the rule allowed the recovery of nominal damages
for any defamatory publication actionable per se, and thus
performed
"a vindicatory function by enabling the plaintiff publicly to
brand the defamatory publication as false. The salutary social
value of this rule is preventive in character, since it often
permit a defamed person to expose the groundless character of a
defamatory rumor before harm to the reputation has resulted
therefrom." Id. § 569, comment b, p. 166.
If the defamation was not libel, but slander, it was actionable per se only if it imputed a criminal offense; a venereal
or loathsome and communicable disease; improper conduct of a lawful
business; or unchastity by a woman. Id. § 570. To be
actionable, all other types of slanderous statements required proof
of special damage other than actual loss of reputation or emotional
distress, that special damage almost always being in the form of
material or pecuniary loss of some kind. Id. § 575 and
comment b, pp. 185-187.
Damages for libel or slander per se included
"harm caused thereby to the reputation of the person defamed or,
in the absence of proof of such harm, for the harm which normally
results from such a defamation." Id., § 621. At the heart of the libel and slander per se Page 418 U. S. 373 damage scheme lay the award of general damages for loss of
reputation. They were granted without special proof because the
judgment of history was that the content of the publication itself
was so likely to cause injury and because,
"in many cases, the effect of defamatory statements is so subtle
and indirect that it is impossible directly to trace the effects
thereof in loss to the person defamed." Id. § 621, comment a, p. 314. [ Footnote 4/4 ] Proof of actual injury to reputation was
itself insufficient proof of that special damage necessary to
support liability for slander not actionable per se. But
if special damage in the form of material or pecuniary loss were
proved, general damages for injury to reputation could be had
without further proof. "The plaintiff may recover not only for the
special harm so caused, but also for general loss of reputation." Id. § 575, comment a, p. 185. [ Footnote 4/5 ] The right to recover for emotional
distress depended upon the defendant's otherwise being liable for
either libel or slander. Id. § 623. Punitive damages were
recoverable upon proof of special facts amounting to express
malice. Id. § 908 and comment b, p. 555. Page 418 U. S. 374 Preparations in the mid-1960's for Restatement (Second) of Torts
reflected what were deemed to be substantial changes in the law of
defamation, primarily a trend toward limiting per se libels to those where the defamatory nature of the publication is
apparent on its face, i.e., where the "defamatory innuendo
is apparent from the publication itself, without reference to
extrinsic facts by way of inducement." Restatement (Second) of
Torts § 569, p. 29 (Tent.Draft No. 12, Apr. 27, 1966). Libels of
this sort and slanders per se continued to be recognized
as actionable without proof of special damage or injury to
reputation. [ Footnote 4/6 ] All
other defamations would require proof of special injury in the form
of material or pecuniary loss. Whether this asserted change
reflected the prevailing law was heavily debated, [ Footnote 4/7 ] but it was unquestioned at the time
that there are recurring situations in which libel and slander are
and should be actionable per se. In surveying the current state of the law, the proposed
Restatement (Second) observed that "[a]ll courts except Virginia
agree that any libel which is defamatory upon its face is
actionable without proof of damage. . . ." Restatement (Second) of
Torts § 569, p. 84 (Tent.Draft No. 11, Apr. 15, 1965). Ten
jurisdictions continued to support the old rule that libel not
defamatory on its face and whose innuendo depends on extrinsic
facts is actionable without proof of damage, although slander would
not be. Twenty-four jurisdictions were said to hold that libel not
defamatory on its face is to be treated like slander, and thus not
actionable without proof of damage where Page 418 U. S. 375 slander would not be. Id. § 569, p. 86. The law in six
jurisdictions was found to be in an unsettled state, but most
likely consistent with the Restatement (Second). Id. §
569, p. 88. The law in Virginia was thought to consider libel
actionable without proof of special damage only where slander would
be, regardless of whether the libel is defamatory on its face. Id. § 569, p. 89. All States, therefore, were at that time
thought to recognize important categories of defamation that were
actionable per se. [ Footnote
4/8 ] Nor was any question apparently raised at that time that,
upon proof of special damage in the form of material or pecuniary
loss, general damages to reputation could be recovered without
further proof.
Unquestionably, state law continued to recognize some absolute,
as well as some conditional, privileges to publish defamatory
materials, including the privilege of fair comment in defined
situations. But it remained true that, in a wide range of
situations, the ordinary citizen could make out a prima
facie case without proving more than a defamatory publication,
and could recover general damages for injury to his reputation
unless defeated by the defense of truth. [ Footnote 4/9 ]
The impact of today's decision on the traditional law of libel
is immediately obvious and indisputable. No longer will the
plaintiff be able to rest his case with proof of a libel defamatory
on its face or proof of a slander historically actionable per
se. In addition, he must prove some further degree of culpable
conduct on the part of the Page 418 U. S. 376 publisher, such as intentional or reckless falsehood or
negligence. And if he succeeds in this respect, he faces still
another obstacle: recovery for loss of reputation will be
conditioned upon "competent" proof of actual injury to his standing
in the community. This will be true regardless of the nature of the
defamation, and even though it is one of those particularly
reprehensible statements that have traditionally made slanderous
words actionable without proof of fault by the publisher or of the
damaging impact of his publication. The Court rejects the judgment
of experience that some publications are so inherently capable of
injury, and actual injury so difficult to prove, that the risk of
falsehood should be borne by the publisher, not the victim.
Plainly, with the additional burden on the plaintiff of proving
negligence or other fault, it will be exceedingly difficult,
perhaps impossible, for him to vindicate his reputation interest by
securing a judgment for nominal damages, the practical effect of
such a judgment being a judicial declaration that the publication
was indeed false. Under the new rule, the plaintiff can lose not
because the statement is true, but because it was not negligently
made.
So too, the requirement of proving special injury to reputation
before general damages may be awarded will clearly eliminate the
prevailing rule, worked out over a very long period of time, that,
in the case of defamations not actionable per se, the
recovery of general damages for injury to reputation may also be
had if some form of material or pecuniary loss is proved. Finally,
an inflexible federal standard is imposed for the award of punitive
damages. No longer will it be enough to prove ill will and an
attempt to injure.
These are radical changes in the law and severe invasions of the
prerogatives of the States. They should Page 418 U. S. 377 at least be shown to be required by the First Amendment or
necessitated by our present circumstances. Neither has been
demonstrated.
Of course, New York Times Co. v. Sullivan, 376 U.
S. 254 (1964); Rosenblatt v. Baer, 383 U. S.
75 (1966), and Curtis Publishing Co. v. Butts and Associated Press v. Walker, 388 U.
S. 130 (1967), have themselves worked major changes in
defamation law. Public officials and public figures, if they are to
recover general damages for injury to reputation, must prove
knowing falsehood or reckless disregard for the truth. The States
were required to conform to these decisions. Thereafter in Rosenbloom v. Metromedia, Inc., 403 U. S.
29 (1971), three Members of the Court urged that the
same standard be applied whenever the publication concerned an
event of public or general concern. But none of these cases
purported to foreclose in all circumstances recovery by the
ordinary citizen on traditional standards of liability, and, until
today, a majority of the Court had not supported the proposition
that, given liability, a court or jury may not award general
damages in a reasonable amount without further proof of injury.
In the brief period since Rosenbloom was decided, at
least 17 States and several federal courts of appeals have felt
obliged to consider the New York Times constitutional
privilege for liability as extending to, in the words of the Rosenbloom plurality, "all discussion and communication
involving matters of public or general concern." Id. at 403 U. S. 44 .
[ Footnote 4/10 ] Apparently,
however, general Page 418 U. S. 378 damages still remain recoverable once that standard of liability
is satisfied. Except where public officials and public figures are
concerned, the Court now repudiates Page 418 U. S. 379 the plurality opinion in Rosenbloom and appears to
espouse the liability standard set forth by three other Justices in
that case. The States must now struggle to Page 418 U. S. 380 discern the meaning of such ill-defined concepts as "liability
without fault" and to fashion novel rules for the recovery of
damages. These matters have not been briefed or argued by the
parties, and their workability has not been seriously explored.
Nevertheless, yielding to the apparently irresistible impulse to
announce a new and different interpretation of the First Amendment,
the Court discards history and precedent in its rush to refashion
defamation law in accordance with the inclinations of a perhaps
evanescent majority of the Justices. II The Court does not contend, and it could hardly do so, that
those who wrote the First Amendment intended to prohibit the
Federal Government, within its sphere of influence in the
Territories and the District of Columbia, from providing the
private citizen a peaceful remedy for damaging falsehood. At the
time of the adoption of the First Amendment, many of the
consequences of libel law already described had developed,
particularly the rule that libels and some slanders were so
inherently injurious that they were actionable without special
proof of damage to reputation. As the Court pointed out in Roth
v. United States, 354 U. S. 476 , 354 U. S. 482 (1957), 10 of the 14 States that had ratified the Constitution by
1792 had themselves provided constitutional guarantees for free Page 418 U. S. 381 expression, and 13 of the 14 nevertheless provided for the
prosecution of libels. Prior to the Revolution, the American
Colonies had adopted the common law of libel. [ Footnote 4/11 ] Contrary to some popular notions,
freedom of the press was sharply curtailed in colonial America.
[ Footnote 4/12 ] Seditious libel
was punished as a contempt by the colonial legislatures and as a
criminal offense in the colonial courts. [ Footnote 4/13 ]
Scant, if any, evidence exists that the First Amendment was
intended to abolish the common law of libel, at least to the extent
of depriving ordinary citizens of meaningful redress against their
defamers. On the contrary,
"[i]t is conceded on all sides that the common law rules that
subjected the libeler to responsibility for the private injury, or
the public scandal or disorder occasioned by his conduct, are not
abolished by the protection extended to the press in our
constitutions."
2 T. Cooley, Constitutional Limitations 883 (8th ed.1927).
Moreover, consistent with the Blackstone formula, [ Footnote 4/14 ] these Page 418 U. S. 382 common law actions did not abridge freedom of the press. See
generally L. Levy, Legacy of Suppression: Freedom of Speech
and Press in Early American History 247-248 (1960); Merin, Libel
and the Supreme Court, 11 Wm. & Mary L.Rev. 371, 376 (1969);
Hallen, Fair Comment, 8 Tex.L.Rev. 41, 56 (1929). Alexander
Meiklejohn, who accorded generous reach to the First Amendment,
nevertheless acknowledged:
"No one can doubt that, in any well governed society, the
legislature has both the right and the duty to prohibit certain
forms of speech. Libelous assertions may be, and must be, forbidden
and punished. So too must slander. . . . All these necessities that
speech be limited are recognized and provided for under the
Constitution. They were not unknown to the writers of the First
Amendment. That amendment, then, we may take it for granted, does not forbid the abridging of speech. But, at the same
time, it does forbid the abridging of the freedom of
speech. It is to the solving of that paradox, that apparent
self-contradiction, that we are summoned if, as free men, we wish
to know what the right of freedom of speech is."
Political Freedom, The Constitutional Powers of the People 21
(1965). See also Leflar, The Free-ness of Free Speech, 15
Vand.L.Rev. 1073, 1080-1081 (1962).
Professor Zechariah Chafee, a noted First Amendment scholar, has
persuasively argued that conditions in 1791 "do not arbitrarily fix
the division between lawful and unlawful speech for all time." Free
Speech in the United States 14 (1954). [ Footnote 4/15 ] At the same time, however, Page 418 U. S. 383 he notes that, while the Framers may have intended to abolish
seditious libels and to prevent any prosecutions by the Federal
Government for criticism of the Government, [ Footnote 4/16 ] "the free speech clauses do not wipe out
the common law as to obscenity, profanity, and defamation of
individuals." [ Footnote 4/17 ]
The debates in Congress and the States over the Bill of Rights
are unclear and inconclusive on any articulated intention of the
Framers as to the free press guarantee. [ Footnote 4/18 ] We know that Benjamin Franklin, John
Adams, and William Cushing favored limiting freedom of the press to
truthful statements, while others such as James Wilson suggested a
restatement of the Blackstone standard. [ Footnote 4/19 ] Page 418 U. S. 384 Jefferson endorsed Madison's formula that "Congress shall make
no law . . . abridging the freedom of speech or the press" only
after he suggested:
"The people shall not be deprived of their right to speak, to
write, or otherwise to publish anything but false facts affecting
injuriously the life, liberty, or reputation of others. . . ."
F. Mott, Jefferson and the Press 14 (1943). [ Footnote 4/20 ] Doubt has been expressed that the
Members of Congress envisioned the First Amendment as reaching even
this far. Merin, Libel and the Supreme Court, 11 Wm. & Mary
L.Rev. 371, § 379-380 (1969).
This Court, in bygone years, has repeatedly dealt with libel and
slander actions from the District of Columbia and from the
Territories. Although in these cases First Amendment considerations
were not expressly discussed, the opinions of the Court
unmistakably revealed that the classic law of libel was firmly in
place in those areas where federal law controlled. See, e.g.,
Washington Post Co. v. Chaloner, 250 U.
S. 290 (1919); Baker v. Warner, 231 U.
S. 588 (1913); Nalle v. Oyster, 230 U.
S. 165 (1913); Dorr v. United States, 195 U. S. 138 (1904); Pollard v. Lyon, 91 U. S. 225 (1876); White v.
Nicholls , 3 How. 266 (1845).
The Court's consistent view prior to New York Times Co. v.
Sullivan, 376 U. S. 254 (1964), was that defamatory Page 418 U. S. 385 utterances were wholly unprotected by the First Amendment. In Patterson v. Colorado ex rel. Attorney General, 205 U. S. 454 , 205 U. S. 462 (1907), for example, the Court said that, although freedom of
speech and press is protected from abridgment by the Constitution,
these provisions "do not prevent the subsequent punishment of such
as may be deemed contrary to the public welfare." This statement
was repeated in Near v. Minnesota ex rel. Olson, 283 U. S. 697 , 283 U. S. 714 (1931), the Court adding:
"But it is recognized that punishment for the abuse of the
liberty accorded to the press is essential to the protection of the
public, and that the common law rules that subject the libeler to
responsibility for the public offense, as well as for the private
injury, are not abolished by the protection extended in our
constitutions." Id. at 283 U. S. 715 . Chaplinsky v. New Hampshire, 315 U.
S. 568 , 315 U. S.
571 -572 (1942) (footnotes omitted), reflected the same
view:
"There are certain well defined and narrowly limited classes of
speech, the prevention and punishment of which have never been
thought to raise any Constitutional problem. These include the lewd
and obscene, the profane, the libelous, and the insulting or
'fighting' words -- those which by their very utterance, inflict
injury or tend to incite an immediate breach of the peace. It has
been well observed that such utterances are no essential part of
any exposition of ideas, and are of such slight social value as a
step to truth that any benefit that may be derived from them is
clearly outweighed by the social interest in order and
morality." Beauharnais v. Illinois, 343 U.
S. 250 , 343 U. S.
254 -257 (1952) (footnotes omitted), repeated the Chaplinski statement, noting also that nowhere at the time
of the adoption of Page 418 U. S. 386 the Constitution "was there any suggestion that the crime of
libel be abolished." And in Roth v. United States, 354
U.S. at 354 U. S. 483 (footnote omitted), the Court further examined the meaning of the
First Amendment:
"In light of this history, it is apparent that the unconditional
phrasing of the First Amendment was not intended to protect every
utterance. This phrasing did not prevent this Court from concluding
that libelous utterances are not within the area of
constitutionally protected speech. Beauharnais v.
Illinois, 343 U. S. 250 , 343 U. S.
266 . At the time of the adoption of the First Amendment,
obscenity law was not as fully developed as libel law, but there is
sufficiently contemporaneous evidence to show that obscenity, too,
was outside the protection intended for speech and press. [ Footnote 4/21 ]"
The Court could not accept the generality of this historic view
in New York Times Co. v. Sullivan, supra. There, the Court
held that the First Amendment was intended to forbid actions for
seditious libel and that defamation actions by public officials
were therefore not subject to the traditional law of libel and
slander. If these officials (and, later, public figures occupying
semiofficial or influential, although private, positions) were to
recover, they were required to prove not only that the publication
was false, but also that it was knowingly false or published with
reckless disregard for its truth or falsity. This view that the
First Amendment was written to forbid Page 418 U. S. 387 seditious libel reflected one side of the dispute that raged at
the turn of the nineteenth century [ Footnote 4/22 ] and also mirrored the views of some
later scholars. [ Footnote
4/23 ]
The central meaning of New York Times, and, for me, the
First Amendment as it relates to libel laws, is that seditious
libel -- criticism of government and public officials -- falls
beyond the police power of the State. 376 U.S. at 376 U. S.
273 -276. [ Footnote
4/24 ] In a democratic society such as ours, the citizen has the
privilege of criticizing his government and its officials. But
neither New York Times nor its progeny suggest that the First
Amendment intended in all circumstances to deprive the private
citizen of his historic recourse to redress published falsehoods
damaging to reputation or that, contrary to history and precedent,
the Amendment should now be so interpreted. Simply put, the First
Amendment did not confer a "license to defame the citizen." W.
Douglas, The Right of the People 36 (1958).
I do not labor the foregoing matters to contend that the Court
is foreclosed from reconsidering prior interpretations of the First
Amendment. [ Footnote 4/25 ] But
the Court apparently finds a clean slate where, in fact, we have
instructive historical experience dating from long before Page 418 U. S. 388 the first settlers, with their notions of democratic government
and human freedom, journeyed to this land. Given this rich
background of history and precedent, and because we deal with
fundamentals when we construe the First Amendment, we should
proceed with care, and be presented with more compelling reasons
before we jettison the settled law of the States to an even more
radical extent. [ Footnote
4/26 ] III The Court concedes that the dangers of self-censorship are
insufficient to override the state interest in protecting the
reputation of private individuals who are both more helpless and
more deserving of state concern than public persons with more
access to the media to defend themselves. It therefore refuses to
condition the private plaintiff's recovery on a showing of
intentional or reckless falsehood as required by New York
Times. But the Court nevertheless extends the reach of the
First Amendment to all defamation actions by requiring that the
ordinary Page 418 U. S. 389 citizen, when libeled by a publication defamatory on its face,
must prove some degree of culpability on the part of the publisher
beyond the circulation to the public of a damaging falsehood. A
rule at least as strict would be called for where the defamatory
character of the publication is not apparent from its face. Ante at 418 U. S. 348 .
[ Footnote 4/27 ] Furthermore, if
this major hurdle to establish liability is surmounted, the Court
requires proof of actual injury to reputation before any damages
for such injury may be awarded.
The Court proceeds as though it were writing on tabula
rasa, and suggests that it must mediate between two
unacceptable choices -- on the one hand, the rigors of the New
York Times rule, which the Court thinks would give
insufficient recognition to the interest of the private plaintiff,
and, on the other hand, the prospect of imposing "liability without
fault" on the press and others who are charged with defamatory
utterances. Totally ignoring history and settled First Amendment
law, the Court purports to arrive at an "equitable compromise,"
rejecting both what it considers faultless liability and New
York Times malice, but insisting on some intermediate degree
of fault. Of course, the Court necessarily discards the contrary
judgment arrived at in the 50 States that the reputation interest
of the private citizen is deserving of considerably more
protection.
The Court evinces a deep-seated antipathy to "liability without
fault." But this catch-phrase has no talismanic significance, and
is almost meaningless in this context, where the Court appears to
be addressing those libels and slanders that are defamatory on
their face and where Page 418 U. S. 390 the publisher is no doubt aware from the nature of the material
that it would be inherently damaging to reputation. He publishes
notwithstanding, knowing that he will inflict injury. With this
knowledge, he must intend to inflict that injury, his excuse being
that he is privileged to do so -- that he has published the truth.
But, as it turns out, what he has circulated to the public is a
very damaging falsehood. Is he nevertheless "faultless"? Perhaps it
can be said that the mistake about his defense was made in good
faith, but the fact remains that it is he who launched the
publication knowing that it could ruin a reputation.
In these circumstances, the law has heretofore put the risk of
falsehood on the publisher where the victim is a private citizen
and no grounds of special privilege are invoked. The Court would
now shift this risk to the victim, even though he has done nothing
to invite the calumny, is wholly innocent of fault, and is helpless
to avoid his injury. I doubt that jurisprudential resistance to
liability without fault is sufficient ground for employing the
First Amendment to revolutionize the law of libel, and, in my view,
that body of legal rules poses no realistic threat to the press and
its service to the public. The press today is vigorous and robust.
To me, it is quite incredible to suggest that threats of libel
suits from private citizens are causing the press to refrain from
publishing the truth. I know of no hard facts to support that
proposition, and the Court furnishes none.
The communications industry has increasingly become concentrated
in a few powerful hands operating very lucrative businesses
reaching across the Nation and into almost every home. [ Footnote 4/28 ] Neither the industry as a
whole nor Page 418 U. S. 391 its individual components are easily intimidated, and we are
fortunate that they are not. Requiring them to pay for the
occasional damage they do to private reputation will play no
substantial part in their future performance or their
existence.
In any event, if the Court's principal concern is to protect the
communications industry from large libel judgments, it would appear
that its new requirements with respect to general and punitive
damages would be ample protection. Why it also feels compelled to
escalate the threshold standard of liability I cannot fathom, Page 418 U. S. 392 particularly when this will eliminate, in many instances, the
plaintiff's possibility of securing a judicial determination that
the damaging publication was indeed false, whether or not he is
entitled to recover money damages. Under the Court's new rules, the
plaintiff must prove not only the defamatory statement, but also
some degree of fault accompanying it. The publication may be wholly
false, and the wrong to him unjustified, but his case will
nevertheless be dismissed for failure to prove negligence or other
fault on the part of the publisher. I find it unacceptable to
distribute the risk in this manner and force the wholly innocent
victim to bear the injury; for, as between the two, the defamer is
the only culpable party. It is he who circulated a falsehood that
he was not required to publish.
It is difficult for me to understand why the ordinary citizen
should himself carry the risk of damage and suffer the injury in
order to vindicate First Amendment values by protecting the press
and others from liability for circulating false information. T his
is particularly true because such statements serve no purpose
whatsoever in furthering the public interest or the search for
truth, but, on the contrary, may frustrate that search, and, at the
same time, inflict great injury on the defenseless individual. The
owners of the press and the stockholders of the communications
enterprises can much better bear the burden. And if they cannot,
the public at large should somehow pay for what is essentially a
public benefit derived at private expense. IV A Not content with escalating the threshold requirements of
establishing liability, the Court abolishes the ordinary damages
rule, undisturbed by New York Times Page 418 U. S. 393 and later cases, that, as to libels or slanders defamatory on
their face, injury to reputation is presumed, and general damages
may be awarded along with whatever special damages may be sought.
Apparently because the Court feels that, in some unspecified and
unknown number of cases, plaintiffs recover where they have
suffered no injury or recover more than they deserve, it dismisses
this rule as an "oddity of tort law." The Court thereby refuses in
any case to accept the fact of wide dissemination of a per
se libel as prima facie proof of injury sufficient to
survive a motion to dismiss at the close of plaintiff's case.
I have said before, but it bears repeating, that, even if the
plaintiff should recover no monetary damages, he should be able to
prevail and have a judgment that the publication is false. But
beyond that, courts and legislatures literally for centuries have
thought that, in the generality of cases, libeled plaintiffs will
be seriously shortchanged if they must prove the extent of the
injury to their reputations. Even where libels or slanders are not,
on their face, defamatory, and special damage must be shown, when
that showing is made, general damages for reputation injury are
recoverable without specific proof. [ Footnote 4/29 ] Page 418 U. S. 394 The Court is clearly right when at one point it states that "the
law of defamation is rooted in our experience that the truth rarely
catches up with a lie." Ante at 418 U. S. 344 n. 9. But it ignores what that experience teaches, viz., that damage to reputation is recurringly difficult to prove, and
that requiring actual proof would repeatedly destroy any chance for
adequate compensation. Eminent authority has warned that
"it is clear that proof of actual damage will be impossible in a
great many cases where, from the character of the defamatory words
and the circumstances of publication, it is all but certain that
serious harm has resulted in fact."
W. Prosser, Law of Torts § 112, p. 765 (4th ed.1971). [ Footnote 4/30 ]
The Court fears uncontrolled awards of damages by juries, but
that not only denigrates the good sense of most jurors -- it fails
to consider the role of trial and appellate courts in limiting
excessive jury verdicts where no reasonable relationship exists
between the amount awarded and the injury sustained. [ Footnote 4/31 ] Available information Page 418 U. S. 395 tends to confirm that American courts have ably discharged this
responsibility. [ Footnote
4/32 ]
The new rule with respect to general damages appears to apply to
all libels or slanders, whether defamatory on their face or not,
except, I gather, when the plaintiff proves intentional falsehood
or reckless disregard. Although the impact of the publication on
the victim is the same, in such circumstances, the injury to
reputation may apparently be presumed in accordance with the
traditional rule. Why a defamatory statement is more apt to cause
injury if the lie is intentional than when it is only negligent, I
fail to understand. I suggest that judges and juries who must live
by these rules will find them equally incomprehensible. B With a flourish of the pen, the Court also discards the
prevailing rule in libel and slander actions that punitive damages
may be awarded on the classic grounds of common law malice, that
is, "'[a]ctual malice' in the sense of ill will or fraud or
reckless indifference to consequences." Page 418 U. S. 396 C. McCormick, Law of Damages § 118, p. 431 (1935); see
also W. Prosser, supra, § 113, p. 772; 1 A. Hanson,
Libel and Related Torts � 163, p. 133 (1969); Note, Developments in
the Law -- Defamation, 69 Harv.L.Rev. 875, 938 (1956); Cal.Civ.Code
§ 48a(4)(d) (1954). In its stead, the Court requires defamation
plaintiffs to show intentional falsehood or reckless disregard for
the truth or falsity of the publication. The Court again complains
about substantial verdicts and the possibility of press
self-censorship, saying that punitive damages are merely "private
fines levied by civil juries to punish reprehensible conduct and to
deter its future occurrence." Ante at 418 U. S. 350 .
But I see no constitutional difference between publishing with
reckless disregard for the truth, where punitive damages will be
permitted, and negligent publication, where they will not be
allowed. It is difficult to understand what is constitutionally
wrong with assessing punitive damages to deter a publisher from
departing from those standards of care ordinarily followed in the
publishing industry, particularly if common law malice is also
shown.
I note also the questionable premise that "juries assess
punitive damages in wholly unpredictable amounts bearing no
necessary relation to the actual harm caused." Ibid. This
represents an inaccurate view of established practice,
"another of those situations in which judges, largely unfamiliar
with the relatively rare actions for defamation, rely on words
without really going behind them. . . . [ Footnote 4/33 ]"
While a jury award in any type of civil case may certainly be
unpredictable, trial and appellate courts have been increasingly
vigilant in ensuring that the jury's result is "based upon a
rational consideration of the evidence and the proper application
of the Page 418 U. S. 397 law." Reynolds v. Pegler, 123 F.
Supp. 36 , 39 (SDNY 1954), aff'd, 223 F.2d 429 (CA2), cert. denied, 350 U.S. 846 (1955). See supra, nn. 418
U.S. 323 fn4/31|>31-32. Moreover, some courts require that
punitive damages bear a reasonable relation to the compensatory
damages award. [ Footnote 4/34 ]
Still others bar common law punitive damages or condition their
award on a refusal to print a retraction. [ Footnote 4/35 ]
"The danger . . . of immoderate verdicts is certainly a real
one, and the criterion to be applied by the judge in setting or
reducing the amount is concededly a vague and subjective one.
Nevertheless, the verdict may be twice submitted by the complaining
defendant to the common sense of trained judicial minds, once on
motion for new trial and again on appeal, and it must be a rare
instance when an unjustifiable award escapes correction."
C. McCormick, supra, § 77, p. 278.
The Court points to absolutely no empirical evidence to
substantiate its premise. For my part, I would require something
more substantial than an undifferentiated fear of unduly burdensome
punitive damages awards before retooling the established common law
rule and depriving the States of the opportunity to experiment with
different methods for guarding against abuses.
Even assuming the possibility that some verdicts will be
"excessive," I cannot subscribe to the Court's remedy. On its face,
it is a classic example of judicial overkill. Apparently abandoning
the salutary New York Times policy of case-by-case
"'independent examination of the whole record' . . . so as to
assure ourselves that the judgment does not constitute a forbidden
intrusion on Page 418 U. S. 398 the field of free expression, [ Footnote 4/36 ]"
the Court substitutes an inflexible rule barring recovery of
punitive damages absent proof of constitutional malice. The First
Amendment is a majestic statement of a free people's dedication to
"uninhibited, robust, and wide-open" debate on public issues,
[ Footnote 4/37 ] but we do it a
grave disservice when we needlessly spend its force. [ Footnote 4/38 ] For almost 200 years,
punitive damages and the First Amendment have peacefully coexisted.
There has been no demonstration that state libel laws as they
relate to punitive damages necessitate the majority's extreme
response. I fear that those who read the Court's decision will find
its words inaudible, for the Court speaks "only [with] a voice of
power, not of reason." Mapp v. Ohio, 367 U.
S. 643 , 367 U. S. 686 (1961) (Harlan, J., dissenting). V In disagreeing with the Court on the First Amendment's reach in
the area of state libel laws protecting nonpublic persons, I do not
repudiate the principle that the First Amendment
"rests on the assumption that the widest possible dissemination
of information from diverse and antagonistic sources is essential
to the welfare of the public, that a free press is a condition of a
free society." Associated Press v. United States, 326 U. S.
1 , 326 U. S. 20 (1945); see also Miami Herald Publishing Co. v. Tornillo,
ante at 418 U. S. 260 (WHITE, J., concurring). I continue to subscribe to the New
York Times decision and those decisions extending its
protection to defamatory falsehoods about public persons. My
quarrel with the Court stems Page 418 U. S. 399 from its willingness "to sacrifice good sense to a syllogism"
[ Footnote 4/39 ] -- to find in the New York Times doctrine an infinite elasticity.
Unfortunately, this expansion is the latest manifestation of the
destructive potential of any good idea carried out to its logical
extreme.
Recovery under common law standards for defamatory falsehoods
about a private individual, who enjoys no "general fame or
notoriety in the community," who is not "pervasive[ly] involve[d]
in the affairs of society," and who does not "thrust himself into
the vortex of [a given] public issue . . . in an attempt to
influence its outcome," [ Footnote
4/40 ] is simply not forbidden by the First Amendment. A
distinguished private study group put it this way:
"Accountability, like subjection to law, is not necessarily a
net subtraction from liberty. . . . The First Amendment was
intended to guarantee free expression, not to create a privileged
industry."
Commission on Freedom of the Press, A Free and Responsible Press
130, 81 (1947).
I fail to see how the quality or quantity of public debate will
be promoted by further emasculation of state libel laws for the
benefit of the news media. [ Footnote
4/41 ] If anything, Page 418 U. S. 400 this trend may provoke a new and radical imbalance in the
communications process. Cf. Barron, Access to the Pres --
A New First Amendment Right, 80 Harv.L.Rev. 1641, 1657 (1967). It
is not at all inconceivable that virtually unrestrained defamatory
remarks about private citizens will discourage them from speaking
out and concerning themselves with social problems. This would turn
the First Amendment on its head. Note, The Scope of First Amendment
Protection for Good-Faith Defamatory Error, 75 Yale L.J. 642, 649
(1966); Merin, 11 Wm. & Mary L.Rev. at 418. David Riesman,
writing in the midst of World War II on the fascists' effective use
of defamatory attacks on their opponents, commented:
"Thus it is that the law of libel, with its ecclesiastic
background and domestic character, its aura of heart-balm suits and
crusading nineteenth-century editors, becomes suddenly important
for modern democratic survival."
Democracy and Defamation: Fair Game and Fair Comment I, 42
Col.L.Rev. 1085, 1088 (1942).
This case ultimately comes down to the importance the Court
attaches to society's "pervasive and strong interest in preventing
and redressing attacks upon reputation." Rosenblatt v.
Baer, 383 U.S. at 383 U. S. 86 .
From all that I have seen, the Court has miscalculated and
denigrates that interest at a time when escalating assaults on
individuality and personal dignity counsel otherwise. [ Footnote 4/42 ] Page 418 U. S. 401 At the very least, the issue is highly debatable, and the Court
has not carried its heavy burden of proof to justify tampering with
state libel laws. [ Footnote
4/43 ] Page 418 U. S. 402 While some risk of exposure "is a concomitant of life in a
civilized community," Time, Inc. v. Hill, 385 U.
S. 374 , 385 U. S. 388 (1967), the private citizen does not bargain for defamatory
falsehoods. Nor is society powerless to vindicate unfair injury to
his reputation.
"It is a fallacy . . . to assume that the First Amendment is the
only guidepost in the area of state defamation laws. It is not. . .
."
"The right of a man to the protection of his own reputation from
unjustified invasion and wrongful hurt reflects no more than our
basic concept of the essential dignity and worth of every human
being -- a concept at the root of any decent system of ordered
liberty. The protection of private personality, like the protection
of life itself, is left primarily to the individual States under
the Ninth and Tenth Amendments. But this does not mean that the
right is entitled to any less recognition by this Court as a basic
of our constitutional system." Rosenblatt v. Baer, supra, at 383 U. S. 92 (STEWART, J., concurring).
The case against razing state libel laws is compelling when
considered in light of the increasingly prominent role of mass
media in our society and the awesome power it has placed in the
hands of a select few. [ Footnote
4/44 ] Surely, our political "system cannot flourish if
regimentation takes hold." Public Utilities Comm'n v.
Pollak, 343 U. S. 451 , 343 U. S. 469 (1952) (DOUGLAS, J., dissenting). Nor can it survive if our people
are deprived of an effective method Page 418 U. S. 403 of vindicating . their legitimate interest in their good names.
[ Footnote 4/45 ]
Freedom and human dignity and decency are not antithetical.
Indeed, they cannot survive without each other. Both exist
side-by-side in precarious balance, one always threatening to
overwhelm the other. Our experience as a Nation testifies to the
ability of our democratic institutions to harness this dynamic
tension. One of the mechanisms seized upon by the common law to
accommodate these forces was the civil libel action tried before a
jury of average citizens. And it has essentially fulfilled its
role. Not because it is necessarily the best or only answer, but
because
"the juristic philosophy of the common law is, at bottom, the
philosophy of pragmatism. Its truth is relative, not absolute. The
rule that functions well produces a title deed to recognition."
B. Cardozo, Selected Writings 149 (Hall ed.1947).
In our federal system, there must be room for allowing the
States to take diverse approaches to these vexing questions. We
should
"continue to forbear from fettering the States with an adamant
rule which may embarrass them in coping with their own peculiar
problems. . . ." Mapp v. Ohio, 367 U.S. at 367 U. S. 681 (Harlan, J., dissenting); see also Murnaghan, From Figment
to Fiction to Philosophy -- The Requirement of Proof of Damages in
Libel Actions, 22 Cath.U.L.Rev. 1, 38 (1972). Page 418 U. S. 404 Cf. Younger v. Harris, 401 U. S.
37 , 401 U. S. 44 -45
(1971). Whether or not the course followed by the majority is wise,
and I have indicated my doubts that it is, our constitutional
scheme compels a proper respect for the role of the States in
acquitting their duty to obey the Constitution. Finding no evidence
that they have shirked this responsibility, particularly when the
law of defamation is even now in transition, I would await some
demonstration of the diminution of freedom of expression before
acting.
For the foregoing reasons, I would reverse the judgment of the
Court of Appeals and reinstate the jury's verdict.
[ Footnote 4/1 ]
Restatement of Torts § 559 (1938); see also W. Prosser,
Law of Torts § 111, p. 739 (4th ed.1971); 1 A. Hanson, Libel and
Related Torts 14, pp. 21-22 (1969); 1 F. Harper & F. James, The
Law of Torts § 5.1, pp. 349-350 (1956).
[ Footnote 4/2 ]
The observations in 418 U. S. first published in 1938, and Tentative Drafts Nos. 11 and 12 of
Restatement of Torts (Second), released in 1965 and 1966,
respectively. The recent transmittal of Tentative Draft No. 20,
dated April 25, 1974, to the American Law Institute for its
consideration has resulted in the elimination of much of the
discussion of the prevailing defamation rules and the suggested
changes in many of the rules themselves previously found in the
earlier Tentative Drafts. This development appears to have been
largely influenced by the draftsmen's "sense for where the law of
this important subject should be thought to stand." Restatement
(Second) of Torts, p. vii (Tent.Draft No. 20, Apr. 25, 1974). It is
evident that, to a large extent, these latest views are colored by
the plurality opinion in Rosenbloom v. Metromedia, Inc., 403 U. S. 29 (1971). See, e.g., Restatement (Second) of Torts, supra at xiii, §§ 569, 580, 581A, 581B, 621. There is no
indication in the latest draft, however, that the conclusions
reached in Tentative Drafts Nos. 11 and 12 are not an accurate
reflection of the case law in the States in the mid-1960's, prior
to the developments occasioned by the plurality opinion in
Rosenbloom. See infra at 418 U. S.
374 -375.
[ Footnote 4/3 ] See also W. Prosser, supra, 418
U.S. 323 fn4/1|>n. 1, § 112, p. 752 and n. 85; Murnaghan,
From Figment to Fiction to Philosophy -- The Requirement of Proof
of Damages in Libel Actions, 22 Cath.U.L.Rev. 1, 11-13 (1972).
[ Footnote 4/4 ]
Proof of the defamation itself established the fact of injury
and the existence of some damage to the right of reputation, and
the jury was permitted, even without any other evidence, to assess
damages that were considered to be the natural or probable
consequences of the defamatory words. Restatement of Torts § 621,
comment a, p. 314 (1938); see also C. Gatley, Libel and
Slander 1004 (6th ed.1967); M. Newell, Slander and Libel § 721, p.
810 (4th ed.1924); see generally C. McCormick, Law of
Damages § 116, pp. 422-430 (1935). In this respect, therefore, the
damages were presumed because of the impossibility of affixing an
exact monetary amount for present and future injury to the
plaintiff's reputation, wounded feelings and humiliation, loss of
business, and any consequential physical illness or pain. Ibid. [ Footnote 4/5 ] See also Prosser, supra, 418
U.S. 323 fn4/1|>n. 1, § 112, p. 761; Harper & James, supra, 418
U.S. 323 fn4/1|>n. 1, § 5.14, p. 388; Note, Developments in
the Law -- Defamation, 69 Harv.L.Rev. 875, 939-940 (1956).
[ Footnote 4/6 ]
Also actionable per se were those libels where the
imputation, although not apparent from the material itself, would
have been slander per se if spoken, rather than
written.
[ Footnote 4/7 ]
Restatement (Second) of Torts § 569, pp. 29-45, 47-48
(Tent.Draft No. 12, Apr. 27, 1966); see also Murnaghan, supra, 418
U.S. 323 fn4/3|>n. 3.
[ Footnote 4/8 ]
Applying settled Illinois law, the District Court in this case
held that it is libel per se to label someone a Communist. 306 F.
Supp. 310 (ND Ill.1969).
[ Footnote 4/9 ]
This appears to have been the law in Illinois at the time Gertz
brought his libel suit. See, e.g., Brewer v. Hearst Publishing
Co., 185 F.2d 846 (CA7 1950); Hotz v. Alton Telegraph
Printing Co., 324 Ill.App. 1, 57 N.E.2d 137 (1944); Cooper
v. Illinois Publishing & Printing Co., 218 Ill.App. 95
(1920).
[ Footnote 4/10 ] See, e.g., West v. Northern Publishing
Co., 487 P.2d 1304 ,
1305-1306 (Alaska 1971) (article linking owners of taxicab
companies to illegal liquor sales to minors); Gallman v.
Carnes, 254 Ark. 987, 992, 497 S.W.2d
47 , 50 (1973) (matter concerning state law school professor and
assistant dean); Belli v. Curtis Publishing
Co., 25 Cal. App. 3d
384 , 102 Cal. Rptr. 122 (1972) (article concerning attorney
with national reputation); Moriarty v. Lippe, 162
Conn.371, 378379, 294 A.2d 326, 330-331 (1972) (publication about
certain police officers); Firestone v. Time,
Inc., 271 So. 2d
745 , 750-751 (Fla.1972) (divorce of prominent citizen not a
matter of legitimate public concern); State v.
Snyder, 277 So.
2d 660 , 666-668 (La.1973) (criminal defamation prosecution of a
defeated mayoral candidate for statements made about another
candidate); Twohi v. Boston Herald-Traveler Corp., ___
Mass. ___, 291
N.E.2d 398 , 400-401 (1973) (article concerning a candidate's
votes in the legislature); Priestley v. Hastings & Sons
Publishing Co. of Lynn, 360 Mass. 118, 271
N.E.2d 628 (1971) (article about an architect commissioned by a
town to build a school); Harnish v. Herald-Mail Co., Inc., 264 Md. 326, 334-336, 286 A.2d 146, 151 (1972) (article concerning
substandard rental property owned by a member of a city housing
authority); Standke v. B. E. Darby & Sons, Inc., 291
Minn. 468, 476-477, 193 N.W.2d
139 , 145 (1971) (newspaper editorial concerning performance of
grand jurors); Whitmore v. Kansas City Star
Co., 499 S.W.2d
45 , 49 (Mo.Ct.App. 1973) (article
brk:
concerning a juvenile officer, the operation of a detention
home, and a grand jury investigation); Trails West, Inc. v.
Wolff, 32
N.Y.2d 207 , 214-218, 298 N.E.2d 52, 55-58 (1973) (suit against
a Congressman for an investigation into the death of schoolchildren
in a bus accident); Twenty-five East 40th Street Restaurant
Corp. v. Forbes, Inc., 30 N.Y.2d 595, 282 N.E.2d 118 (1972)
(magazine article concerning a restaurant's food); Kent v. City
of Buffalo, 29 N.Y.2d 818, 277 N.E.2d 669 (1971) (television
station film of plaintiff as a captured robber); Frink v.
McEldowney, 29 N.Y.2d 720, 275 N.E.2d 337 (1971) (article
concerning an attorney representing a town); Mead v. Horvitz
Publishing Co. (9th Dist. Ohio Ct.App. June 13, 1973)
(unpublished), cert. denied, 416 U.S. 985 (1974)
(financial condition of participants in the development of a large
apartment complex involving numerous local contractors); Washington v. World Publishing Co., 506 P.2d 913 (Okla.1973) (article about contract dispute between a candidate for
United States Senate and his party's county chairman); Matus v.
Triangle Publications, Inc., 445 Pa. 384, 395-399, 286 A.2d
357, 363-365 (1971) (radio "talk show" host's discussion of gross
overcharging for snowplowing a driveway not considered an event of
public or general concern); Autobuses Internacionales S. De
R.L., Ltd. v. El Continental Publishing Co., 483 S.W.2d 506
(Tex.Ct. Civ.App. 1972) (newspaper article concerning a bus
company's raising of fares without notice and in violation of law); Sanders v. Harris, 213 Va. 369, 372-373, 192 S.E.2d
754 , 757-758 (1972) (article concerning English professor at a
community college); Old Dominion Branch No. 496 v. Austin, 213 Va. 377, 192 S.E.2d
737 (1972), rev'd, ante, p. 418 U. S. 264 (plaintiff's failure to join a labor union considered not an issue
of public or general concern); Chase v. Daily Record,
Inc., 83 Wash. 2d
37 , 41, 515 P.2d
154 , 156 (1973) (article concerning port district
commissioner); Miller v. .Argus Publishing
Co., 79 Wash. 2d
816 , 827, 490 P.2d
101 , 109 (1971) (article concerning the backer of political
candidates); Polzing v. Helmbrecht, 54 Wis.2d 578, 586, 196 N.W.2d
685 , 690 (1972) (letter to editor of newspaper concerning a
reporter and the financing of pollution control measures).
The following United States Courts of Appeals have adopted the
plurality opinion in Rosenbloom: Cantrell v. Forest City
Publishing Co., 484 F.2d 150 (CA6 1973), cert.
pending, No. 73-5520 (article concerning family members of the
victim of a highly publicized bridge disaster not actionable absent
proof of actual malice); Porter v. Guam Publications,
Inc., 475 F.2d 744, 745 (CA9 1973) (article concerning
citizen's arrest for theft of a cash box considered an event of
general or public interest); Cervantes v. Time, Inc., 464
F.2d 986, 991 (CA8 1972) (article concerning mayor and alleged
organized crime connections conceded to be a matter of public or
general concern); Firestone v. Time, Inc., 460 F.2d 712
(CA5 1972) (magazine article concerning prominent citizen's use of
detectives and electronic surveillance in connection with a
divorce); Davis v. National Broadcasting Co., 447 F.2d 981
(CA5 1971), aff'g 320 F.
Supp. 1070 (ED La.1970) (television report about a person
caught up in the events surrounding the assassination of President
Kennedy considered a matter of public interest). However, at least
one Court of Appeals, faced with an appeal from summary judgment in
favor of a publisher in a diversity libel suit brought by a
Philadelphia retailer, has expressed "discomfort in accepting the Rosenbloom plurality opinion as a definitive statement of
the appropriate law. . . ." Gordon v. Random House, Inc., 486 F.2d 1356, 1359 (CA3 1973).
As previously discussed in 418
U.S. 323 fn4/2|>n. 2, supra, the latest proposed
draft of Restatement (Second) of Torts substantially reflects the
views of the Rosenbloom plurality. It also anticipates
"that the Supreme Court will hold that strict liability for
defamation is inconsistent with the free speech provision of the
First Amendment . . . ," Restatement (Second) of Torts § 569, p. 59
(Tent.Draft No. 20, Apr. 25, 1974), as well as the demise of
pre- Rosenbloom damages rules. See id. § 621, pp.
285-288.
[ Footnote 4/11 ]
Merin, Libel and the Supreme Court, 11 Wm. & Mary L.Rev.
371, 373 (1969).
[ Footnote 4/12 ]
A. Sutherland, Constitutionalism in America: Origin and
Evolution of Its Fundamental Ideas 118-119 (1965).
[ Footnote 4/13 ] See generally L. Levy, Legacy of Suppression: Freedom
of Speech and Press in Early American History (1960).
[ Footnote 4/14 ]
The men who wrote and adopted the First Amendment were steeped
in the common law tradition of England. They read Blackstone, "a
classic tradition of the bar in the United States" and "the oracle
of the common law in the minds of the American Framers. . . ." J.
Hurst, The Growth of American Law: The Law Makers 257 (1950); Levy, supra, 418
U.S. 323 fn4/13|>n. 13, at 13; see also Sutherland, supra, 418
U.S. 323 fn4/12|>n. 12, at 124-125; Schick v. United
States, 195 U. S. 65 , 195 U. S. 69 (1904). From him they learned that the major means of accomplishing
free speech and press was to prevent prior restraints, the
publisher later being subject to legal action if his publication
was injurious. 4 W. Blackstone, Commentaries *150-153.
[ Footnote 4/15 ] See also Meiklejohn, The First Amendment Is An
Absolute, 1961 Sup.Ct.Rev. 245, 264:
"First, the Framers initiated a political revolution whose
develop ment is still in process throughout the world. Second, like
most revolutionaries, the Framers could not foresee the specific
issues which would arise as their 'novel idea' exercised its
domination over the governing activities of a rapidly developing
nation in a rapidly and fundamentally changing world. In that
sense, the Framers did not know what they were doing. And in the
same sense, it is still true that, after two centuries of
experience, we do not know what they were doing, or what we
ourselves are now doing."
"In a more abstract and more significant sense, however, both
they and we have been aware that the adoption of the principle of
self-government by 'The People' of this nation set loose upon us
and upon the world at large an idea which is still transforming
men's conceptions of what they are and how they may best be
governed."
[ Footnote 4/16 ] See Beauharnais v. Illinois, 343 U.
S. 250 , 343 U. S. 272 (1952) (Black, J., dissenting). Brant, who interprets the Framers'
intention more liberally than Chafee, nevertheless saw the free
speech protection as bearing upon criticism of government and other
political speech. I. Brant, The Bill of Rights 236 (1965).
[ Footnote 4/17 ]
Z. Chafee, Free Speech in the United States 14 (1954).
[ Footnote 4/18 ] See 1 Annals of Cong. 729-789 (1789). See also Brant, supra, 418
U.S. 323 fn4/16|>n. 16, at 224; Levy, supra, 418
U.S. 323 fn4/13|>n. 13, at 214, 224.
[ Footnote 4/19 ]
Merin, supra, 418
U.S. 323 fn4/11|>n. 11, at 377. Franklin, for example,
observed:
"If by the Liberty of the Press were understood merely
the Liberty of discussing the Propriety of Public Measures and
political opinions, let us have as much of it as you please; but if
it means the Liberty of affronting, calumniating, and defaming one
another, I, for my part, own myself willing to part with my Share
of it when our Legislators shall please so to alter the Law, and
shall cheerfully consent to exchange my Liberty of Abusing
others for the Privilege of not being abused myself."
10 B. Franklin, Writings 38 (Smyth ed.1907).
[ Footnote 4/20 ]
Jefferson's noted opposition to public prosecutions for libel of
government figures did not extend to depriving them of private
libel actions. Mott, supra, at 43. There is even a strong
suggestion that he favored state prosecutions. E.g., Hudon, Freedom of Speech and Press in America 47-48 (1963).
[ Footnote 4/21 ]
For further expressions of the general proposition that libels
are not protected by the First Amendment, see Konigsberg v.
State Bar of California, 366 U. S. 36 , 366 U. S. 49 -50
and n. 10 (1961); Time Film Corp. v. City of Chicago, 365 U. S. 43 , 365 U. S. 48 (1961); Pennekamp v. Florida, 328 U.
S. 331 , 328 U. S.
348 -349 (1946); cf. Paris Adult Theatre I v.
Slaton, 413 U. S. 49 , 413 U. S. 67 (1973); Stanley v. Georgia, 394 U.
S. 557 , 394 U. S. 561 in 5 (1969)
[ Footnote 4/22 ] See Levy, supra, 418
U.S. 323 fn4/13|>n. 13, at 247-248.
[ Footnote 4/23 ] See, e.g., Abrams v. United States, 250 U.
S. 616 , 250 U. S. 630 (1919) (Holmes, J., dissenting).
[ Footnote 4/24 ]
Kalven, The New York Times Case: A Note on "The Central
Meaning of the First Amendment," 1964 Sup.Ct.Rev.191, 208-209.
[ Footnote 4/25 ]
"The language of the First Amendment is to be read not as barren
words found in a dictionary, but as symbols of historic experience
illumined by the presuppositions of those who employed them. . . .
As in the case of every other provision of the Constitution that is
not crystallized by the nature of its technical concepts, the fact
that the First Amendment is not self-defining and self-enforcing
neither impairs its usefulness nor compels its paralysis as a
living instrument." Dennis v. United States, 341 U.
S. 494 , 341 U. S. 523 (1951) (Frankfurter, J., concurring).
[ Footnote 4/26 ]
"[T]he law of defamation has been an integral part of the laws
of England, the colonies and the states since time immemorial. So
many actions have been maintained and judgments recovered under the
various laws of libel that the Constitutional validity of libel
actions could be denied only by a Court willing to hold all of its
predecessors were wrong in their interpretation of the First
Amendment, and that two hundred years of precedents should be
overruled."
Rutledge, The Law of Defamation: Recent Developments, 32 Alabama
Lawyer 409, 410 (1971).
The prevailing common law libel rules in this country have
remained in England and the Commonwealth nations. Pedrick, Freedom
of the Press and the Law of Libel: The Modern Revised Translation,
49 Cornell L.Q. 581, 583-584 (1964). After many years of reviewing
the English law of defamation, the Porter Committee concluded that,
"though the law as to defamation requires some modification, the
basic principles upon which it is founded are not amiss." Report of
the Committee on the Law of Defamation, Cmd. No. 7536, � 222, p. 48
(1948).
[ Footnote 4/27 ]
If I read the Court correctly, it clearly implies that, for
those publications that do not make "substantial danger to
reputation apparent," the New York Times actual malice
standard will apply. Apparently this would be true even where the
imputation concerned conduct or a condition that would be per
se slander.
[ Footnote 4/28 ]
A recent study has comprehensively detailed the role and impact
of mass communications in this Nation. See Note, Media and
the First Amendment in a Free Society, 60 Geo.L.J. 867 (1972). For
example, 99% of the American households have a radio, and 77% hear
at least one radio newscast daily. In 1970, the yearly average home
television viewing time was almost six hours per day. Id. at 883 n. 53.
"Sixty years ago, 2,442 newspapers were published daily
nationwide, and 689 cities had competing dailies. Today, in only 42
of the cities served by one of the 1,748 American daily papers is
there a competing newspaper under separate ownership. Total daily
circulation has passed 62 million copies, but over 40 percent of
this circulation is controlled by only 25 ownership groups."
"Newspaper owners have profited greatly from the consolidation
of the journalism industry. Several of them report yearly profits
in the tens of millions of dollars, with after-tax profits ranging
from seven to 14 percent of gross revenues. Unfortunately, the
owners have made their profits at the expense of the public
interest in free expression. As the broad base of newspaper
ownership narrows, the variation of facts and opinions received by
the public from antagonistic sources is increasingly limited.
Newspaper publication is indeed a leading American industry.
Through its evolution in this direction, the press has come to be
dominated by a select group whose prime interest is economic."
"The effect of consolidation within the newspaper industry is
magnified by the degree of intermediate ownership. Sixty-eight
cities have a radio station owned by the only local daily
newspaper, and 160 television stations have newspaper affiliations.
In 11 cities, diversity of ownership is completely lacking, with
the only television station and newspaper under the same
control." Id. at 892-893 (footnotes omitted). See also Congress, FCC Consider Newspaper Control of Local TV, 32 Cong.Q.
659-663 (1974).
[ Footnote 4/29 ]
Having held that the defamation plaintiff is limited to
recovering for "actual injury," the Court hastens to add:
"Suffice it to say that actual injury is not limited to
out-of-pocket loss. Indeed, the more customary types of actual harm
inflicted by defamatory falsehood include impairment of reputation
and standing in the community, personal humiliation, and mental
anguish and suffering." Ante at 418 U. S. 350 .
It should be pointed out that, under the prevailing law, where the
defamation is not actionable per se and proof of "special
damage" is required, a showing of actual injury to reputation is
insufficient; but if pecuniary loss is shown, general reputation
damages are recoverable. The Court changes the latter, but not the
former, rule. Also under present law, pain and suffering, although
shown, do not warrant damages in any defamation action unless the
plaintiff is otherwise entitled to at least nominal damages. By
imposing a more difficult standard of liability and requiring proof
of actual damage to reputation, recovery for pain and suffering,
though real, becomes a much more remote possibility.
[ Footnote 4/30 ]
"The harm resulting from an injury to reputation is difficult to
demonstrate both because it may involve subtle differences in the
conduct of the recipients toward the plaintiff and because the
recipients, the only witnesses able to establish the necessary
causal connection, may be reluctant to testify that the publication
affected their relationships with the plaintiff. Thus, some
presumptions are necessary if the plaintiff is to be adequately
compensated."
Note, Developments in the Law -- Defamation, 69 Harv.L.Rev. 875,
891-892 (1956).
[ Footnote 4/31 ]
"On questions of damages, the judge plays an important role. It
is, of course, for him to determine and instruct the jury as to
what matters may be taken into consideration by them in arriving at
a verdict, since such questions are clearly matters of substantive
law. But the judge also may and frequently does exercise a judgment
as to the amount of damages the plaintiff may recover. His function
here is primarily to keep the jury within bounds of reason and
common sense, to guard against excessive verdicts dictated by
passion and prejudice and to see to it that the amount of the
verdict has some reasonable relation to the plaintiff's evidence as
to his loss or the probability of loss. Thus, the trial judge may
grant a new trial, or the appellate court may reverse and remand
the case for a new trial, because of excessive damages or, as is
more frequently the case, a remittitur may be ordered, the effect
of which is that the plaintiff must accept a specified reduction of
his damages or submit to a new trial on the issue of liability as
well as damages."
1 F. Harper & F. James, The Law of Torts § 5.29, p. 467
(1956) (footnote omitted).
[ Footnote 4/32 ] See Pedrick, supra, 418
U.S. 323 fn4/26|>n. 26, at 587 n. 23.
[ Footnote 4/33 ]
Murnaghan, supra, 418
U.S. 323 fn4/3|>n. 3, at 29.
[ Footnote 4/34 ]
Note, Developments in the Law -- Defamation, 69 Harv.L.Rev., supra, at 875, 938 and n. 443.
[ Footnote 4/35 ] Id. at 939, 941-942. See, e.g., Cal.Civ.Code §
48a(2) (1954).
[ Footnote 4/36 ]
376 U.S. at 376 U. S.
285 .
[ Footnote 4/37 ] Id. at 376 U. S.
270 .
[ Footnote 4/38 ]
Judicial review of jury libel awards for excessiveness should be
influenced by First Amendment considerations, but it makes little
sense to discard an otherwise useful and time-tested rule because
it might be misapplied in a few cases.
[ Footnote 4/39 ]
O. Holmes, The Common Law 36 (1881).
[ Footnote 4/40 ] Ante at 418 U. S. 351 , 418 U. S.
352 .
[ Footnote 4/41 ] Cf. Pedrick, supra, 418
U.S. 323 fn4/26|>n. 26, at 601-602:
"A great many forces in our society operate to determine the
extent to which men are free, in fact, to express their ideas.
Whether there is a privilege for good faith defamatory
misstatements on matters of public concern or whether there is
strict liability for such statements may not greatly affect the
course of public discussion. How different has life been in those
states which heretofore followed the majority rule imposing strict
liability for misstatements of fact defaming public figures from
life in the minority states where the good faith privilege held
sway?" See also T. Emerson, The System of Freedom of
Expression 519 (1970) (footnote omitted):
"[O]n the whole the role of libel law in the system of freedom
of expression has been relatively minor and essentially
erratic."
[ Footnote 4/42 ]
"The man who is compelled to live every minute of his life among
others, and whose every need, thought, desire, fancy or
gratification is subject to public scrutiny, has been deprived of
his individuality and human dignity. Such an individual merges with
the mass. His opinions, being public, tend never to be different;
his aspirations, being known, tend always to be conventionally
accepted ones; his feelings, being openly exhibited, tend to lose
their quality of unique personal warmth and to become the feelings
of every man. Such a being, although sentient, is fungible; he is
not an individual."
Bloustein, Privacy as an Aspect of Human Dignity: An Answer to
Dean Prosser, 39 N.Y.U.L.Rev. 962, 1003 (1964).
[ Footnote 4/43 ]
With the evisceration of the common law libel remedy for the
private citizen, the Court removes from his legal arsenal the most
effective weapon to combat assault on personal reputation by the
press establishment. The David and Goliath nature of this
relationship is all the more accentuated by the Court's holding
today in Miami Herald Publishing Co. v. Tornillo, ante p. 418 U. S. 241 ,
which I have joined, that an individual criticized by a newspaper's
editorial is precluded by the First Amendment from requiring that
newspaper to print his reply to that attack. While that case
involves an announced candidate for public office, the Court's
finding of a First Amendment barrier to government "intrusion into
the function of editors," ante at 418 U. S. 258 ,
does not rest on any distinction between private citizens or public
officials. In fact, the Court observes that the First Amendment
clearly protects from governmental restraint "the exercise of
editorial control and judgment," i.e., "[t]he choice of material to go into a newspaper, and the
decisions made as to limitations on the size and content of the
paper, and treatment of public issues and public officials -- whether fair or unfair. . . ." Ibid. (Emphasis added.)
We must, therefore, assume that the hapless ordinary citizen
libeled by the press (a) may not enjoin in advance of publication a
story about him, regardless of how libelous it may be, Near v.
Minnesota ex rel. Olson, 283 U. S. 697 (1931); (b) may not compel the newspaper to print his reply; and
(c) may not force the newspaper to print a retraction, because a
judicially compelled retraction, like a "remedy such as an
enforceable right of access," entails "governmental coercion" as to
content, which
"at once brings about a confrontation with the express
provisions of the First Amendment and the judicial gloss on that
Amendment developed over the years." Miami Herald Publishing Co. v. Tornillo, ante at 418 U. S. 254 ; but cf. this case, ante at 418 U. S. 368 n. 3 (BRENNAN, J., dissenting).
My Brother BRENNAN also suggests that there may constitutionally
be room for
"the possible enactment of statutes, not requiring proof of
fault, which provide . . . for publication of a court's
determination of falsity if the plaintiff is able to demonstrate
that false statements have been published concerning his
activities." Ibid. The Court, however, does not even consider this
less drastic alternative to its new "some fault" libel
standards.
[ Footnote 4/44 ] See 418
U.S. 323 fn4/28|>n. 28, supra. [ Footnote 4/45 ]
"No democracy, . . . certainly not the American democracy, will
indefinitely tolerate concentrations of private power irresponsible
and strong enough to thwart the aspirations of the people.
Eventually governmental power will be used to break up private
power, or governmental power will be used to regulate private power
-- if private power is at once great and irresponsible."
Commission on Freedom of the Press, A Free and Responsible Press
80 (1947). | In Gertz v. Robert Welch, Inc., the US Supreme Court held that the media cannot claim protection against defamation lawsuits from private individuals if the statements made are false and concern issues of public interest. The Court distinguished between public officials, public figures, and private individuals, arguing that the latter are more vulnerable to defamation and deserve greater protection. The Court also recognized the state's interest in compensating private individuals for reputational harm. This case established that media organizations can be held liable for defaming private citizens, even when discussing matters of public concern. |
Free Speech | Bethel School District v. Fraser | https://supreme.justia.com/cases/federal/us/478/675/ | U.S. Supreme Court Bethel Sch. Dist. v. Fraser, 478
U.S. 675 (1986) Bethel School District No. 403 v.
Fraser No. 84-1667 Argued March 3, 1986 Decided July 7, 1986 478
U.S. 675 CERTIORARI TO THE UNITED STATES
COURT OF APPEALS FOR THE NINTH CIRCUIT Syllabus Respondent public high school student (hereafter respondent)
delivered a speech nominating a fellow student for a student
elective office at a voluntary assembly that was held during school
hours as part of a school-sponsored educational program in
self-government, and that was attended by approximately 600
students, many of whom were 14-year-olds. During the entire speech,
respondent referred to his candidate in terms of an elaborate,
graphic, and explicit sexual metaphor. Some of the students at the
assembly hooted and yelled during the speech, some mimicked the
sexual activities alluded to in the speech, and others appeared to
be bewildered and embarrassed. Prior to delivering the speech,
respondent discussed it with several teachers, two of whom advised
him that it was inappropriate and should not be given. The morning
after the assembly, the Assistant Principal called respondent into
her office and notified him that the school considered his speech
to have been a violation of the school's "disruptive conduct rule,"
which prohibited conduct that substantially interfered with the
educational process, including the use of obscene, profane language
or gestures. Respondent was given copies of teacher reports of his
conduct, and was given a chance to explain his conduct. After he
admitted that he deliberately used sexual innuendo in the speech,
he was informed that he would be suspended for three days, and that
his name would be removed from the list of candidates for
graduation speaker at the school's commencement exercises. Review
of the disciplinary action through petitioner School District's
grievance procedures resulted in affirmance of the discipline, but
respondent was allowed to return to school after serving only two
days of his suspension. Respondent, by his father (also a
respondent) as guardian ad litem, then filed suit in
Federal District Court, alleging a violation of his First Amendment
right to freedom of speech and seeking injunctive relief and
damages under 42 U.S.C. § 1983. The court held that the school's
sanctions violated the First Amendment, that the school's
disruptive conduct rule was unconstitutionally vague and overbroad,
and that the removal of respondent's name from the graduation
speaker's list violated the Due Process Clause of the Fourteenth
Amendment. The court awarded respondent monetary relief and
enjoined the Page 478 U. S. 676 School District from preventing him from speaking at the
commencement ceremonies. The Court of Appeals affirmed. Held: 1. The First Amendment did not prevent the School District from
disciplining respondent for giving the offensively lewd and
indecent speech at the assembly. Tinker v. Des Moines
Independent Community School Dist., 393 U.
S. 503 , distinguished. Under the First Amendment, the
use of an offensive form of expression may not be prohibited to
adults making what the speaker considers a political point, but it
does not follow that the same latitude must be permitted to
children in a public school. It is a highly appropriate function of
public school education to prohibit the use of vulgar and offensive
terms in public discourse. Nothing in the Constitution prohibits
the states from insisting that certain modes of expression are
inappropriate and subject to sanctions. The inculcation of these
values is truly the work of the school, and the determination of
what manner of speech is inappropriate properly rests with the
school board. First Amendment jurisprudence recognizes an interest
in protecting minors from exposure to vulgar and offensive spoken
language, FCC v. Pacifica Foundation, 438 U.
S. 726 , as well as limitations on the otherwise absolute
interest of the speaker in reaching an unlimited audience where the
speech is sexually explicit and the audience may include children. Ginsberg v. New York, 390 U. S. 629 .
Petitioner School District acted entirely within its permissible
authority in imposing sanctions upon respondent in response to his
offensively lewd and indecent speech, which had no claim to First
Amendment protection. Pp. 478 U. S.
680 -686.
2. There is no merit to respondent's contention that the
circumstances of his suspension violated due process because he had
no way of knowing that the delivery of the speech would subject him
to disciplinary sanctions. Given the school's need to be able to
impose disciplinary sanctions for a wide range of unanticipated
conduct disruptive of the educational process, the school
disciplinary rules need not be as detailed as a criminal code which
imposes criminal sanctions. The school disciplinary rule
proscribing "obscene" language and the prespeech admonitions of
teachers gave adequate warning to respondent that his lewd speech
could subject him to sanctions. P. 478 U. S.
686 .
755 F.2d 1356, reversed.
BURGER, C.J., delivered the opinion of the Court, in which
WHITE, POWELL, REHNQUIST, and O'CONNOR, JJ., joined. BRENNAN J.,
filed an opinion concurring in the judgment, post, p. 478 U. S. 687 .
BLACKMUN, J. concurred in the result. MARSHALL, J., post, p. 478 U. S. 690 ,
and STEVENS, J., post, p. 478 U. S. 691 ,
filed dissenting opinions. Page 478 U. S. 677 CHIEF JUSTICE BURGER delivered the opinion of the Court.
We granted certiorari to decide whether the First Amendment
prevents a school district from disciplining a high school student
for giving a lewd speech at a school assembly. I A On April 26, 1983, respondent Matthew N. Fraser, a student at
Bethel High School in Pierce County, Washington, delivered a speech
nominating a fellow student for student elective office.
Approximately 600 high school students, many of whom were
14-year-olds, attended the assembly. Students were required to
attend the assembly or to report to the study hall. The assembly
was part of a school-sponsored educational program in
self-government. Students who elected not to attend the assembly
were required to report to study hall. During the entire speech,
Fraser referred Page 478 U. S. 678 to his candidate in terms of an elaborate, graphic, and explicit
sexual metaphor.
Two of Fraser's teachers, with whom he discussed the contents of
his speech in advance, informed him that the speech was
"inappropriate and that he probably should not deliver it," App.
30, and that his delivery of the speech might have "severe
consequences." Id. at 61.
During Fraser's delivery of the speech, a school counselor
observed the reaction of students to the speech. Some students
hooted and yelled; some by gestures graphically simulated the
sexual activities pointedly alluded to in respondent's speech.
Other students appeared to be bewildered and embarrassed by the
speech. One teacher reported that, on the day following the speech,
she found it necessary to forgo a portion of the scheduled class
lesson in order to discuss the speech with the class. Id. at 41-44.
A Bethel High School disciplinary rule prohibiting the use of
obscene language in the school provides:
"Conduct which materially and substantially interferes with the
educational process is prohibited, including the use of obscene,
profane language or gestures."
The morning after the assembly, the Assistant Principal called
Fraser into her office and notified him that the school considered
his speech to have been a violation of this rule. Fraser was
presented with copies of five letters submitted by teachers,
describing his conduct at the assembly; he was given a chance to
explain his conduct and he admitted to having given the speech
described and that he deliberately used sexual innuendo in the
speech. Fraser was then informed that he would be suspended for
three days, and that his name would be removed from the list of
candidates for graduation speaker at the school's commencement
exercises.
Fraser sought review of this disciplinary action through the
School District's grievance procedures. The hearing officer
determined that the speech given by respondent was "indecent, lewd,
and offensive to the modesty and decency of Page 478 U. S. 679 many of the students and faculty in attendance at the assembly."
The examiner determined that the speech fell within the ordinary
meaning of "obscene," as used in the disruptive conduct rule, and
affirmed the discipline in its entirety. Fraser served two days of
his suspension, and was allowed to return to school on the third
day. B Respondent, by his father as guardian ad litem, then
brought this action in the United States District Court for the
Western District of Washington. Respondent alleged a violation of
his First Amendment right to freedom of speech, and sought both
injunctive relief and monetary damages under 42 U.S.C. § 1983. The
District Court held that the school's sanctions violated
respondent's right to freedom of speech under the First Amendment
to the United States Constitution, that the school's disruptive
conduct rule is unconstitutionally vague and overbroad, and that
the removal of respondent's name from the graduation speaker's list
violated the Due Process Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment because
the disciplinary rule makes no mention of such removal as a
possible sanction. The District Court awarded respondent $278 in
damages, $12,750 in litigation costs and attorney's fees, and
enjoined the School District from preventing respondent from
speaking at the commencement ceremonies. Respondent, who had been
elected graduation speaker by a write-in vote of his classmates,
delivered a speech at the commencement ceremonies on June 8,
1983.
The Court of Appeals for the Ninth Circuit affirmed the judgment
of the District Court, 755 F.2d 1356 (1985), holding that
respondent's speech was indistinguishable from the protest armband
in Tinker v. Des Moines Independent Community School
Dist., 393 U. S. 503 (1969). The court explicitly rejected the School District's
argument that the speech, unlike the passive conduct of wearing a
black armband, had a disruptive effect on the educational process.
The Court of Page 478 U. S. 680 Appeals also rejected the School District's argument that it had
an interest in protecting an essentially captive audience of minors
from lewd and indecent language in a setting sponsored by the
school, reasoning that the School District's "unbridled discretion"
to determine what discourse is "decent" would "increase the risk of
cementing white, middle-class standards for determining what is
acceptable and proper speech and behavior in our public schools."
755 F.2d at 1363. Finally, the Court of Appeals rejected the School
District's argument that, incident to its responsibility for the
school curriculum, it had the power to control the language used to
express ideas during a school-sponsored activity.
We granted certiorari, 474 U.S. 814 (1985). We reverse. II This Court acknowledged in Tinker v. Des Moines Independent
Community School Dist., supra, that students do not "shed
their constitutional rights to freedom of speech or expression at
the schoolhouse gate." Id. at 474 U. S. 506 .
The Court of Appeals read that case as precluding any discipline of
Fraser for indecent speech and lewd conduct in the school assembly.
That court appears to have proceeded on the theory that the use of
lewd and obscene speech in order to make what the speaker
considered to be a point in a nominating speech for a fellow
student was essentially the same as the wearing of an armband in Tinker as a form of protest or the expression of a
political position.
The marked distinction between the political "message" of the
armbands in Tinker and the sexual content of respondent's
speech in this case seems to have been given little weight by the
Court of Appeals. In upholding the students' right to engage in a
nondisruptive, passive expression of a political viewpoint in Tinker, this Court was careful to note that the case did
"not concern speech or action that intrudes upon the work of the
schools or the rights of other students." Id. at 393 U. S.
508 . Page 478 U. S. 681 It is against this background that we turn to consider the level
of First Amendment protection accorded to Fraser's utterances and
actions before an official high school assembly attended by 600
students. III The role and purpose of the American public school system were
well described by two historians, who stated:
"[P]ublic education must prepare pupils for citizenship in the
Republic. . . . It must inculcate the habits and manners of
civility as values in themselves conducive to happiness and as
indispensable to the practice of self-government in the community
and the nation."
C. Beard & M. Beard, New Basic History of the United States
228 (1968). In Ambach v. Norwick, 441 U. S.
68 , 441 U. S. 76 -77
(1979), we echoed the essence of this statement of the objectives
of public education as the "inculcat[ion of] fundamental values
necessary to the maintenance of a democratic political system."
These fundamental values of "habits and manners of civility"
essential to a democratic society must, of course, include
tolerance of divergent political and religious views, even when the
views expressed may be unpopular. But these "fundamental values"
must also take into account consideration of the sensibilities of
others, and, in the case of a school, the sensibilities of fellow
students. The undoubted freedom to advocate unpopular and
controversial views in schools and classrooms must be balanced
against the society's countervailing interest in teaching students
the boundaries of socially appropriate behavior. Even the most
heated political discourse in a democratic society requires
consideration for the personal sensibilities of the other
participants and audiences.
In our Nation's legislative halls, where some of the most
vigorous political debates in our society are carried on, there are
rules prohibiting the use of expressions offensive to other
participants in the debate. The Manual of Parliamentary Page 478 U. S. 682 Practice, drafted by Thomas Jefferson and adopted by the House
of Representatives to govern the proceedings in that body,
prohibits the use of "impertinent" speech during debate, and
likewise provides that "[n]o person is to use indecent language
against the proceedings of the House." Jefferson's Manual of
Parliamentary Practice §§ 359, 360, reprinted in Manual and Rules
of House of Representatives, H.R. Doc. No. 97-271, pp. 158-159
(1982); see id. at 111, n. a (Jefferson's Manual governs
the House in all cases to which it applies). The Rules of Debate
applicable in the Senate likewise provide that a Senator may be
called to order for imputing improper motives to another Senator or
for referring offensively to any state. See Senate
Procedure, S. Doc. No. 97-2, Rule XIX, pp. 568-569, 588-591 (1981).
Senators have been censured for abusive language directed at other
Senators. See Senate Election, Expulsion and Censure Cases
from 1793 to 1972, S.Doc. No. 92-7, pp. 95-98 (1972) (Sens.
McLaurin and Tillman); id. at 152-153 (Sen. McCarthy). Can
it be that what is proscribed in the halls of Congress is beyond
the reach of school officials to regulate?
The First Amendment guarantees wide freedom in matters of adult
public discourse. A sharply divided Court upheld the right to
express an antidraft viewpoint in a public place, albeit in terms
highly offensive to most citizens. See Cohen v.
California, 403 U. S. 15 (1971). It does not follow, however, that, simply because the use
of an offensive form of expression may not be prohibited to adults
making what the speaker considers a political point, the same
latitude must be permitted to children in a public school. In New Jersey v. T.L.O., 469 U. S. 325 , 469 U. S.
340 -342 (1985), we reaffirmed that the constitutional
rights of students in public school are not automatically
coextensive with the rights of adults in other settings. As
cogently expressed by Judge Newman, "the First Amendment gives a
high school student the classroom right to wear Tinker's armband,
but not Cohen's jacket." Thomas v. Board of Education,
Granville Central School Page 478 U. S. 683 Dist., 607 F.2d 1043, 1057 (CA2 1979) (opinion
concurring in result).
Surely it is a highly appropriate function of public school
education to prohibit the use of vulgar and offensive terms in
public discourse. Indeed, the "fundamental values necessary to the
maintenance of a democratic political system" disfavor the use of
terms of debate highly offensive or highly threatening to others.
Nothing in the Constitution prohibits the states from insisting
that certain modes of expression are inappropriate and subject to
sanctions. The inculcation of these values is truly the "work of
the schools." Tinker, 393 U.S. at 393 U. S. 508 ; see Ambach v. Norwick, supra. The determination of what
manner of speech in the classroom or in school assembly is
inappropriate properly rests with the school board.
The process of educating our youth for citizenship in public
schools is not confined to books, the curriculum, and the civics
class; schools must teach by example the shared values of a
civilized social order. Consciously or otherwise, teachers -- and
indeed the older students -- demonstrate the appropriate form of
civil discourse and political expression by their conduct and
deportment in and out of class. Inescapably, like parents, they are
role models. The schools, as instruments of the state, may
determine that the essential lessons of civil, mature conduct
cannot be conveyed in a school that tolerates lewd, indecent, or
offensive speech and conduct such as that indulged in by this
confused boy.
The pervasive sexual innuendo in Fraser's speech was plainly
offensive to both teachers and students -- indeed, to any mature
person. By glorifying male sexuality, and in its verbal content,
the speech was acutely insulting to teenage girl students. See App. 77-81. The speech could well be seriously
damaging to its less mature audience, many of whom were only 14
years old and on the threshold of awareness of human sexuality.
Some students were reported as Page 478 U. S. 684 bewildered by the speech and the reaction of mimicry it
provoked.
This Court's First Amendment jurisprudence has acknowledged
limitations on the otherwise absolute interest of the speaker in
reaching an unlimited audience where the speech is sexually
explicit and the audience may include children. In Ginsberg v.
New York, 390 U. S. 629 (1968), this Court upheld a New York statute banning the sale of
sexually oriented material to minors, even though the material in
question was entitled to First Amendment protection with respect to
adults. And in addressing the question whether the First Amendment
places any limit on the authority of public schools to remove books
from a public school library, all Members of the Court, otherwise
sharply divided, acknowledged that the school board has the
authority to remove books that are vulgar. Board of Education
v. Pico, 457 U. S. 853 , 457 U. S.
871 -872 (1982) (plurality opinion); id. at 457 U. S.
879 -881 (BLACKMUN, J., concurring in part and in
judgment); id. at 457 U. S. 918 -920 (REHNQUIST, J., dissenting). These
cases recognize the obvious concern on the part of parents, and
school authorities acting in loco parentis, to protect
children especially in a captive audience -- from exposure to
sexually explicit, indecent, or lewd speech.
We have also recognized an interest in protecting minors from
exposure to vulgar and offensive spoken language. In FCC v.
Pacifica Foundation, 438 U. S. 726 (1978), we dealt with the power of the Federal Communications
Commission to regulate a radio broadcast described as "indecent but
not obscene." There the Court reviewed an administrative
condemnation of the radio broadcast of a self-styled "humorist" who
described his own performance as being in "the words you couldn't
say on the public, ah, airwaves, um, the ones you definitely
wouldn't say ever." Id. at 438 U. S. 729 ; see also id. at 438 U. S.
751 -755 (Appendix to opinion of the Court). The
Commission concluded that "certain words depicted sexual and
excretory activities in a patently offensive manner, [and]
noted Page 478 U. S. 685 that they were broadcast at a time when children were
undoubtedly in the audience.'" The Commission issued an order
declaring that the radio station was guilty of broadcasting
indecent language in violation of 18 U.S.C. § 1464. 438 U.S. at 438 U. S. 732 .
The Court of Appeals set aside the Commission's determination, and
we reversed, reinstating the Commission's citation of the station.
We concluded that the broadcast was properly considered "obscene,
indecent, or profane" within the meaning of the statute. The
plurality opinion went on to reject the radio station's assertion
of a First Amendment right to broadcast vulgarity: "These words offend for the same reasons that obscenity offends.
Their place in the hierarchy of First Amendment values was aptly
sketched by Mr. Justice Murphy when he said:"
"[S]uch utterances are no essential part of any exposition of
ideas, and are of such slight social value as a step to truth that
any benefit that may be derived from them is clearly outweighed by
the social interest in order and morality."
" Chaplinsky v. New Hampshire, 315 U.S. at 315 U. S.
572 ." Id. at 438 U. S.
746 .
We hold that petitioner School District acted entirely within
its permissible authority in imposing sanctions upon Fraser in
response to his offensively lewd and indecent speech. Unlike the
sanctions imposed on the students wearing armbands in Tinker, the penalties imposed in this case were unrelated
to any political viewpoint. The First Amendment does not prevent
the school officials from determining that to permit a vulgar and
lewd speech such as respondent's would undermine the school's basic
educational mission. A high school assembly or classroom is no
place for a sexually explicit monologue directed towards an
unsuspecting audience of teenage students. Accordingly, it was
perfectly appropriate for the school to disassociate itself to make
the point to the pupils that vulgar speech and lewd conduct is
wholly inconsistent with the "fundamental values" of public Page 478 U. S. 686 school education. Justice Black, dissenting in Tinker, made a point that is especially relevant in this case:
"I wish therefore, . . . to disclaim any purpose . . . to hold
that the Federal Constitution compels the teachers, parents, and
elected school officials to surrender control of the American
public school system to public school students."
393 U.S. at 526. IV Respondent contends that the circumstances of his suspension
violated due process because he had no way of knowing that the
delivery of the speech in question would subject him to
disciplinary sanctions. This argument is wholly without merit. We
have recognized that
"maintaining security and order in the schools requires a
certain degree of flexibility in school disciplinary procedures,
and we have respected the value of preserving the informality of
the student-teacher relationship." New Jersey v. T.L.O., 469 U.S. at 469 U. S. 340 .
Given the school's need to be able to impose disciplinary sanctions
for a wide range of unanticipated conduct disruptive of the
educational process, the school disciplinary rules need not be as
detailed as a criminal code, which imposes criminal sanctions. Cf. Arnett v. Kennedy, 416 U. S. 134 , 416 U. S. 161 (1974) (REHNQUIST, J., concurring). Two days' suspension from
school does not rise to the level of a penal sanction calling for
the full panoply of procedural due process protections applicable
to a criminal prosecution. Cf. Goss v. Lopez, 419 U.
S. 565 (1975). The school disciplinary rule proscribing
"obscene" language and the prespeech admonitions of teachers gave
adequate warning to Fraser that his lewd speech could subject him
to sanctions. * Page 478 U. S. 687 The judgment of the Court of Appeals for the Ninth Circuit
is Reversed. JUSTICE BLACKMUN concurs in the result.
* Petitioners also challenge the ruling of the District Court
that the removal of Fraser's name from the ballot for graduation
speaker violated his due process rights because that sanction was
not indicated as a potential punishment in the school's
disciplinary rules. We agree with the Court of Appeals that this
issue has become moot, since the graduation ceremony has long since
passed and Fraser was permitted to speak in accordance with the
District Court's injunction. No part of the damages award was based
upon the removal of Fraser's name from the list, since damages were
based upon the loss of two days' schooling.
JUSTICE BRENNAN, concurring in the judgment.
Respondent gave the following speech at a high school assembly
in support of a candidate for student government office:
"I know a man who is firm -- he's firm in his pants, he's firm
in his shirt, his character is firm -- but most . . . of all, his
belief in you, the students of Bethel, is firm."
"Jeff Kuhlman is a man who takes his point and pounds it in. If
necessary, he'll take an issue and nail it to the wall. He doesn't
attack things in spurts -- he drives hard, pushing and pushing
until finally -- he succeeds."
"Jeff is a man who will go to the very end -- even the climax,
for each and every one of you."
"So vote for Jeff for A.S.B. vice-president -- he'll never come
between you and the best our high school can be."
App. 47. The Court, referring to these remarks as "obscene,"
"vulgar," "lewd," and "offensively lewd," concludes that school
officials properly punished respondent for uttering the speech.
Having read the full text of respondent's remarks, I find it
difficult to believe that it is the same speech the Court
describes. To my mind, the most that can be said about respondent's
speech -- and all that need be said -- is that, in light of the
discretion school officials have to teach high school students how
to conduct civil and effective public discourse, and to prevent
disruption of school educational activities, it was Page 478 U. S. 688 not unconstitutional for school officials to conclude, under the
circumstances of this case, that respondent's remarks exceeded
permissible limits. Thus, while I concur in the Court's judgment, I
write separately to express my understanding of the breadth of the
Court's holding.
The Court today reaffirms the unimpeachable proposition that
students do not " shed their constitutional rights to freedom of
speech or expression at the schoolhouse gate.'" Ante at 478 U. S. 680 (quoting Tinker v. Des Moines Independent Community School
Dist., 393 U. S. 503 , 393 U. S. 506 (1969)). If respondent had given the same speech outside of the
school environment, he could not have been penalized simply because
government officials considered his language to be inappropriate, see Cohen v. California, 403 U. S. 15 (1971); the Court's opinion does not suggest otherwise. [ Footnote 1 ] Moreover, despite the
Court's characterizations, the language respondent used is far
removed from the very narrow class of "obscene" speech which the
Court has held is not protected by the First Amendment. Ginsberg v. New York, 390 U. S. 629 , 390 U. S. 635 (1968); Roth v. United States, 354 U.
S. 476 , 354 U. S. 485 (1957). It is true, however, that the State has interests in
teaching high school students how to conduct civil and effective
public discourse and in avoiding disruption of educational school
activities. Thus, the Court holds that, under certain
circumstances, high school students may properly be reprimanded for
giving a speech at a high school assembly which school officials
conclude disrupted the school's educational Page 478 U. S. 689 mission. [ Footnote 2 ]
Respondent's speech may well have been protected had he given it in
school but under different circumstances, where the school's
legitimate interests in teaching and maintaining civil public
discourse were less weighty.
In the present case, school officials sought only to ensure that
a high school assembly proceed in an orderly manner. There is no
suggestion that school officials attempted to regulate respondent's
speech because they disagreed with the views he sought to express. Cf. Tinker, supra. Nor does this case involve an attempt
by school officials to ban written materials they consider
"inappropriate" for high school students, cf. Board of
Education v. Pico, 457 U. S. 853 (1982), or to limit what students should hear, read, or learn
about. Thus, the Court's holding concerns only the authority that
school officials have to restrict a high school student's use of
disruptive language in a speech given to a high school
assembly.
The authority school officials have to regulate such speech by
high school students is not limitless. See Thomas v. Board of
Education, Granville Central School Dist., 607 F.2d 1043, 1057
(CA2 1979) (Newman, J., concurring in result) ("[S]chool officials
. . . do [not] have limitless discretion to apply their own notions
of indecency. Courts have a First Page 478 U. S. 690 Amendment responsibility to insure that robust rhetoric . . . is
not suppressed by prudish failures to distinguish the vigorous from
the vulgar"). Under the circumstances of this case, however, I
believe that school officials did not violate the First Amendment
in determining that respondent should be disciplined for the
disruptive language he used while addressing a high school
assembly. [ Footnote 3 ] Thus, I
concur in the judgment reversing the decision of the Court of
Appeals.
[ Footnote 1 ]
In the course of its opinion, the Court makes certain remarks
concerning the authority of school officials to regulate student
language in public schools. For example, the Court notes that
"[n]othing in the Constitution prohibits the states from insisting
that certain modes of expression are inappropriate and subject to
sanctions." Ante at 478 U. S. 683 .
These statements obviously do not, and indeed, given our prior
precedents, could not, refer to the government's authority
generally to regulate the language used in public debate outside of
the school environment.
[ Footnote 2 ]
The Court speculates that the speech was "insulting" to female
students, and "seriously damaging" to 14-year-olds, so that school
officials could legitimately suppress such expression in order to
protect these groups. Ante at 478 U. S. 683 .
There is no evidence in the record that any students, male or
female, found the speech "insulting." And while it was not
unreasonable for school officials to conclude that respondent's
remarks were inappropriate for a school-sponsored assembly, the
language respondent used does not even approach the sexually
explicit speech regulated in Ginsberg v. New York, 390 U. S. 629 (1968), or the indecent speech banned in FCC v. Pacifica
Foundation, 438 U. S. 726 (1978). Indeed, to my mind, respondent's speech was no more
"obscene," "lewd," or "sexually explicit" than the bulk of programs
currently appearing on prime time television or in the local
cinema. Thus, I disagree with the Court's suggestion that school
officials could punish respondent's speech out of a need to protect
younger students.
[ Footnote 3 ]
Respondent served two days' suspension and had his name removed
from the list of candidates for graduation speaker at the school's
commencement exercises, although he was eventually permitted to
speak at the graduation. While I find this punishment somewhat
severe in light of the nature of respondent's transgression, I
cannot conclude that school officials exceeded the bounds of their
disciplinary authority.
JUSTICE MARSHALL, dissenting.
I agree with the principles that JUSTICE BRENNAN sets out in his
opinion concurring in the judgment. I dissent from the Court's
decision, however, because, in my view, the School District failed
to demonstrate that respondent's remarks were indeed disruptive.
The District Court and Court of Appeals conscientiously applied Tinker v. Des Moines Independent Community School Dist., 393 U. S. 503 (1969), and concluded that the School District had not demonstrated
any disruption of the educational process. I recognize that the
school administration must be given wide latitude to determine what
forms of conduct are inconsistent with the school's educational
mission; nevertheless, where speech is involved, we may not
unquestioningly accept a teacher's or administrator's assertion
that certain pure speech interfered with education. Here the School
District, despite a clear opportunity to do so, failed to bring in
evidence sufficient to convince either of the two lower courts that
education at Bethel School was disrupted by respondent's speech. I
therefore see no reason to disturb the Court of Appeals'
judgment. Page 478 U. S. 691 JUSTICE STEVENS, dissenting.
"Frankly, my dear, I don't give a damn."
When I was a high school student, the use of those words in a
public forum shocked the Nation. Today Clark Gable's four-letter
expletive is less offensive than it was then. Nevertheless, I
assume that high school administrators may prohibit the use of that
word in classroom discussion and even in extracurricular activities
that are sponsored by the school and held on school premises. For I
believe a school faculty must regulate the content as well as the
style of student speech in carrying out its educational mission.
[ Footnote 2/1 ] It does seem to me,
however, that, if a student is to be punished for using offensive
speech, he is entitled to fair notice of the scope of the
prohibition and the consequences of its violation. Page 478 U. S. 692 The interest in free speech protected by the First Amendment and
the interest in fair procedure protected by the Due Process Clause
of the Fourteenth Amendment combine to require this conclusion.
This respondent was an outstanding young man with a fine
academic record. The fact that he was chosen by the student body to
speak at the school's commencement exercises demonstrates that he
was respected by his peers. This fact is relevant for two reasons.
It confirms the conclusion that the discipline imposed on him -- a
3-day suspension and ineligibility to speak at the school's
graduation exercises-- was sufficiently serious to justify
invocation of the School District's grievance procedures. See
Goss v. Lopez, 419 U. S. 565 , 419 U. S.
574 -575 (1975). More importantly, it indicates that he
was probably in a better position to determine whether an audience
composed of 600 of his contemporaries would be offended by the use
of a four-letter word -- or a sexual metaphor -- than is a group of
judges who are at least two generations and 3,000 miles away from
the scene of the crime. [ Footnote
2/2 ]
The fact that the speech may not have been offensive to his
audience -- or that he honestly believed that it would be
inoffensive -- does not mean that he had a constitutional right to
deliver it. For the school -- not the student -- must prescribe the
rules of conduct in an educational institution. [ Footnote 2/3 ] But it Page 478 U. S. 693 does mean that he should not be disciplined for speaking frankly
in a school assembly if he had no reason to anticipate punitive
consequences.
One might conclude that respondent should have known that he
would be punished for giving this speech on three quite different
theories: (1) it violated the "Disruptive Conduct" rule published
in the student handbook; (2) he was specifically warned by his
teachers; or (3) the impropriety is so obvious that no specific
notice was required. I discuss each theory in turn. The Disciplinary Rule At the time the discipline was imposed, as well as in its
defense of this lawsuit, the school took the position that
respondent violated the following published rule:
"In addition to the criminal acts defined above, the commission
of, or participation in certain noncriminal activities or acts may
lead to disciplinary action. Generally, these are acts which
disrupt and interfere with the educational process."
" * * * *" " Disruptive Conduct. Conduct which materially and
substantially interferes with the educational process is
prohibited, including the use of obscene, profane language or
gestures."
755 F.2d 1356, 1357, n. 1 (CA9 1985).
Based on the findings of fact made by the District Court, the
Court of Appeals concluded that the evidence did not show "that the
speech had a materially disruptive effect on the educational
process." Id. at 1361. The Court of Appeals explained the
basis for this conclusion:
"[T]he record now before us yields no evidence that Fraser's use
of a sexual innuendo in his speech materially interfered with
activities at Bethel High School. While the students' reaction to
Fraser's speech may fairly be characterized as boisterous, it was
hardly disruptive Page 478 U. S. 694 of the educational process. In the words of Mr. McCutcheon, the
school counselor whose testimony the District relies upon, the
reaction of the student body 'was not atypical to a high school
auditorium assembly.' In our view, a noisy response to the speech
and sexually suggestive movements by three students in a crowd of
600 fail to rise to the level of a material interference with the
educational process that justifies impinging upon Fraser's First
Amendment right to express himself freely."
"We find it significant that, although four teachers delivered
written statements to an assistant principal commenting on Fraser's
speech, none of them suggested that the speech disrupted the
assembly or otherwise interfered with school activities. See Finding of Fact No. 8. Nor can a finding of material
disruption be based upon the evidence that the speech proved to be
a lively topic of conversation among students the following
day." Id. at 1360-1361.
Thus, the evidence in the record, as interpreted by the District
Court and the Court of Appeals, makes it perfectly clear that
respondent's speech was not "conduct" prohibited by the
disciplinary rule. [ Footnote 2/4 ]
Indeed, even if the language of the rule could be stretched to
encompass the nondisruptive use of obscene or profane language,
there is no such language in respondent's speech. What the speech
does contain is a sexual metaphor that may unquestionably be
offensive to some listeners in some settings. But if an impartial
judge puts his Page 478 U. S. 695 or her own views about the metaphor to one side, I simply cannot
understand how he or she could conclude that it is embraced by the
above-quoted rule. At best, the rule is sufficiently ambiguous
that, without a further explanation or construction, it could not
advise the reader of the student handbook that the speech would be
forbidden. [ Footnote 2/5 ] The Specific Warning by the Teachers Respondent read his speech to three different teachers before he
gave it. Mrs. Irene Hicks told him that she thought the speech "was
inappropriate, and that he probably should not deliver it." App.
30. Steven DeHart told respondent "that this would indeed cause
problems in that it would raise eyebrows." Id. at 61. The
third teacher, Shawn Madden, did not testify. None of the three
suggested that the speech might violate a school rule. Id. at 49-50.
The fact that respondent reviewed the text of his speech with
three different teachers before he gave it does indicate that he
must have been aware of the possibility that it would provoke an
adverse reaction, but the teachers' responses certainly did not
give him any better notice of the likelihood of discipline than did
the student handbook itself. In my opinion, therefore, the most
difficult question is whether the speech was so obviously offensive
that an intelligent high school student must be presumed to have
realized that he would be punished for giving it. Page 478 U. S. 696 Obvious Impropriety Justice Sutherland taught us that a "nuisance may be merely a
right thing in the wrong place, -- like a pig in the parlor instead
of the barnyard." Euclid v. Ambler Realty Co., 272 U. S. 365 , 272 U. S. 388 (1926). Vulgar language, like vulgar animals, may be acceptable in
some contexts and intolerable in others. See FCC v. Pacifica
Foundation, 438 U. S. 726 , 438 U. S. 750 (1978). Indeed, even ordinary, inoffensive speech may be wholly
unacceptable in some settings. See Schenck v. United
States, 249 U. S. 47 , 249 U. S. 52 (1919); Pacifica, supra, at 438 U. S.
744 -745.
It seems fairly obvious that respondent's speech would be
inappropriate in certain classroom and formal social settings. On
the other hand, in a locker room or perhaps in a school corridor,
the metaphor in the speech might be regarded as rather routine
comment. If this be true, and if respondent's audience consisted
almost entirely of young people with whom he conversed on a daily
basis, can we -- at this distance -- confidently assert that he
must have known that the school administration would punish him for
delivering it?
For three reasons, I think not. First, it seems highly unlikely
that he would have decided to deliver the speech if he had known
that it would result in his suspension and disqualification from
delivering the school commencement address. Second, I believe a
strong presumption in favor of free expression should apply
whenever an issue of this kind is arguable. Third, because the
Court has adopted the policy of applying contemporary community
standards in evaluating expression with sexual connotations, this
Court should defer to the views of the district and circuit judges
who are in a much better position to evaluate this speech than we
are.
I would affirm the judgment of the Court of Appeals.
[ Footnote 2/1 ]
"Because every university's resources are limited, an
educational institution must routinely make decisions concerning
the use of the time and space that is available for extracurricular
activities. In my judgment, it is both necessary and appropriate
for those decisions to evaluate the content of a proposed student
activity. I should think it obvious, for example, that, if two
groups of 25 students requested the use of a room at a particular
time -- one to view Mickey Mouse cartoons and the other to rehearse
an amateur performance of Hamlet -- the First Amendment would not
require that the room be reserved for the group that submitted its
application first. Nor do I see why a university should have to
establish a 'compelling state interest' to defend its decision to
permit one group to use the facility and not the other. In my
opinion, a university should be allowed to decide for itself
whether a program that illuminates the genius of Walt Disney should
be given precedence over one that may duplicate material adequately
covered in the classroom. Judgments of this kind should be made by
academicians, not by federal judges, and their standards for
decision should not be encumbered with ambiguous phrases like
'compelling state interest.'" Widmar v. Vincent, 454 U. S. 263 , 454 U. S.
278 -279 (1981) (STEVENS, J., concurring in judgment)
(footnotes omitted).
"Any student of history who has been reprimanded for talking
about the World Series during a class discussion of the First
Amendment knows that it is incorrect to state that a 'time, place,
or manner restriction may not be based upon either the content or
subject matter of speech.'" Consolidated Edison Co. v. Public Service Comm'n of
N.Y., 447 U. S. 530 , 447 U. S.
544 -545 (1980) (STEVENS, J, concurring in judgment)
[ Footnote 2/2 ]
As the Court of Appeals noted, there "is no evidence in the
record indicating that any students found the speech to be
offensive." 755 F.2d 1356, 1361, n. 4 (CA9 1985).
In its opinion today, the Court describes respondent as a
"confused boy," ante at 478 U. S. 683 ,
and repeatedly characterizes his audience of high school students
as "children," ante at 478 U. S. 682 ,
684. When a more orthodox message is being conveyed to a similar
audience, four Members of today's majority would treat high school
students like college students, rather than like children. See
Bender v. Williamsport Area School Dist., 475 U.
S. 534 (1986) (dissenting opinions).
[ Footnote 2/3 ] See Arnold v. Carpenter, 459 F.2d 939, 944 (CA7 1972)
(STEVENS, J., dissenting).
[ Footnote 2/4 ]
The Court's reliance on the school's authority to prohibit
"unanticipated conduct disruptive of the educational process," ante at 478 U. S. 686 ,
is misplaced. The findings of the District Court, which were upheld
by the Court of Appeals, established that the speech was not
"disruptive." Departing from our normal practice concerning factual
findings, the Court's decision rests on "utterly unproven,
subjective impressions of some hypothetical students." Bender
v. Williamsport Area School Dist., 475 U.S. at 475 U. S. 553 (BURGER, C.J., dissenting).
[ Footnote 2/5 ]
The school's disruptive conduct rule is entirely concerned with
"the educational process." It does not expressly refer to
extracurricular activities in general, or to student political
campaigns or student debates. In contrast,
"[i]n our Nation's legislative halls, where some of the most
vigorous political debates in our society are carried on, there are
rules prohibiting the use of expressions offensive to other
participants in the debate." See ante at 478 U. S. 681 .
If a written rule is needed to forewarn a United States Senator
that the use of offensive speech may give rise to discipline, a
high school student should be entitled to an equally unambiguous
warning. Unlike the Manual of Parliamentary Practice drafted by
Thomas Jefferson, this School District's rules of conduct contain
no unequivocal prohibition against the use of "impertinent" speech
or "indecent language." | The Supreme Court ruled that a public high school student's lewd and indecent speech at a school assembly was not protected by the First Amendment, upholding the school's disciplinary action. The Court emphasized that schools have a responsibility to teach students the boundaries of socially appropriate behavior and that the student's speech was disruptive and inappropriate. The Court also noted the young age of the audience and the school's disruptive conduct rule, which prohibited obscene language. This case sets a precedent for schools' authority to regulate student speech that is deemed offensive or disruptive. |
Free Speech | Texas v. Johnson | https://supreme.justia.com/cases/federal/us/491/397/ | U.S. Supreme Court Texas v. Johnson, 491
U.S. 397 (1989) Texas v. Johnson No. 88-155 Argued March 21, 1989 Decided June 21, 1989 491
U.S. 397 CERTIORARI TO THE COURT OF CRIMINAL
APPEALS OF TEXAS Syllabus During the 1984 Republican National Convention, respondent
Johnson participated in a political demonstration to protest the
policies of the Reagan administration and some Dallas-based
corporations. After a march through the city streets, Johnson
burned an American flag while protesters chanted. No one was
physically injured or threatened with injury, although several
witnesses were seriously offended by the flag burning. Johnson was
convicted of desecration of a venerated object in violation of a
Texas statute, and a state court of appeals affirmed. However, the
Texas Court of Criminal Appeals reversed, holding that the State,
consistent with the First Amendment, could not punish Johnson for
burning the flag in these circumstances. The court first found that
Johnson's burning of the flag was expressive conduct protected by
the First Amendment. The court concluded that the State could not
criminally sanction flag desecration in order to preserve the flag
as a symbol of national unity. It also held that the statute did
not meet the State's goal of preventing breaches of the peace,
since it was not drawn narrowly enough to encompass only those flag
burnings that would likely result in a serious disturbance, and
since the flag burning in this case did not threaten such a
reaction. Further, it stressed that another Texas statute
prohibited breaches of the peace and could be used to prevent
disturbances without punishing this flag desecration. Held: Johnson's conviction for flag desecration is
inconsistent with the First Amendment. Pp. 491 U. S.
402 -420.
(a) Under the circumstances, Johnson's burning of the flag
constituted expressive conduct, permitting him to invoke the First
Amendment. The State conceded that the conduct was expressive.
Occurring as it did at the end of a demonstration coinciding with
the Republican National Convention, the expressive, overtly
political nature of the conduct was both intentional and
overwhelmingly apparent. Pp. 491 U. S.
402 -406.
(b) Texas has not asserted an interest in support of Johnson's
conviction that is unrelated to the suppression of expression and
would therefore permit application of the test set forth in United States v. O'Brien, 391 U.
S. 367 , whereby an important governmental interest in
regulating nonspeech can justify incidental limitations on First
Amendment freedoms when speech and nonspeech elements are combined
in the same course of conduct. An interest in preventing breaches
of the peace is not implicated on this record. Expression may not
be prohibited Page 491 U. S. 398 on the basis that an audience that takes serious offense to the
expression may disturb the peace, since the Government cannot
assume that every expression of a provocative idea will incite a
riot, but must look to the actual circumstances surrounding the
expression. Johnson's expression of dissatisfaction with the
Federal Government's policies also does not fall within the class
of "fighting words" likely to be seen as a direct personal insult
or an invitation to exchange fisticuffs. This Court's holding does
not forbid a State to prevent "imminent lawless action" and, in
fact, Texas has a law specifically prohibiting breaches of the
peace. Texas' interest in preserving the flag as a symbol of
nationhood and national unity is related to expression in this case
and, thus, falls outside the O'Brien test. Pp. 491 U. S.
406 -410.
(c) The latter interest does not justify Johnson's conviction.
The restriction on Johnson's political expression is content based,
since the Texas statute is not aimed at protecting the physical
integrity of the flag in all circumstances, but is designed to
protect it from intentional and knowing abuse that causes serious
offense to others. It is therefore subject to "the most exacting
scrutiny." Boos v. Barry, 485 U.
S. 312 . The Government may not prohibit the verbal or
nonverbal expression of an idea merely because society finds the
idea offensive or disagreeable, even where our flag is involved.
Nor may a State foster its own view of the flag by prohibiting
expressive conduct relating to it, since the Government may not
permit designated symbols to be used to communicate a limited set
of messages. Moreover, this Court will not create an exception to
these principles protected by the First Amendment for the American
flag alone. Pp. 491 U. S.
410 -422. 755
S.W.2d 92 , affirmed.
BRENNAN, J., delivered the opinion of the Court, in which
MARSHALL, BLACKMUN, SCALIA, and KENNEDY, JJ., joined. KENNEDY, J.,
filed a concurring opinion, post, p. 491 U. S. 420 .
REHNQUIST, C.J., filed a dissenting opinion, in which WHITE and
O'CONNOR, JJ., joined, post, p. 491 U. S. 421 .
STEVENS, J., filed a dissenting opinion, post, p. 491 U. S.
436 . Page 491 U. S. 399 JUSTICE BRENNAN delivered the opinion of the Court.
After publicly burning an American flag as a means of political
protest, Gregory Lee Johnson was convicted of desecrating a flag in
violation of Texas law. This case presents the question whether his
conviction is consistent with the First Amendment. We hold that it
is not. I While the Republican National Convention was taking place in
Dallas in 1984, respondent Johnson participated in a political
demonstration dubbed the "Republican War Chest Tour." As explained
in literature distributed by the demonstrators and in speeches made
by them, the purpose of this event was to protest the policies of
the Reagan administration and of certain Dallas-based corporations.
The demonstrators marched through the Dallas streets, chanting
political slogans and stopping at several corporate locations to
stage "die-ins" intended to dramatize the consequences of nuclear
war. On several occasions they spray-painted the walls of buildings
and overturned potted plants, but Johnson himself took no part in
such activities. He did, however, accept an American flag handed to
him by a fellow protestor who had taken it from a flagpole outside
one of the targeted buildings.
The demonstration ended in front of Dallas City Hall, where
Johnson unfurled the American flag, doused it with kerosene, and
set it on fire. While the flag burned, the protestors chanted,
"America, the red, white, and blue, we spit on you." After the
demonstrators dispersed, a witness to the flag burning collected
the flag's remains and buried them in his backyard. No one was
physically injured or threatened with injury, though several
witnesses testified that they had been seriously offended by the
flag burning. Page 491 U. S. 400 Of the approximately 100 demonstrators, Johnson alone was
charged with a crime. The only criminal offense with which he was
charged was the desecration of a venerated object in violation of
Tex.Penal Code Ann. § 42.09(a)(3) (1989). [ Footnote 1 ] After a trial, he was convicted, sentenced
to one year in prison, and fined $2,000. The Court of Appeals for
the Fifth District of Texas at Dallas affirmed Johnson's
conviction, 706 S.W.2d 120 (1986), but the Texas Court of Criminal
Appeals reversed, 755
S.W.2d 92 (1988), holding that the State could not, consistent
with the First Amendment, punish Johnson for burning the flag in
these circumstances.
The Court of Criminal Appeals began by recognizing that
Johnson's conduct was symbolic speech protected by the First
Amendment:
"Given the context of an organized demonstration, speeches,
slogans, and the distribution of literature, anyone who observed
appellant's act would have understood the message that appellant
intended to convey. The act for which appellant was convicted was
clearly 'speech' contemplated by the First Amendment." Id. at 95. To justify Johnson's conviction for engaging
in symbolic speech, the State asserted two interests: preserving
the flag as a symbol of national unity and preventing breaches of
the peace. The Court of Criminal Appeals held that neither interest
supported his conviction. Page 491 U. S. 401 Acknowledging that this Court had not yet decided whether the
Government may criminally sanction flag desecration in order to
preserve the flag's symbolic value, the Texas court nevertheless
concluded that our decision in West Virginia Board of Education
v. Barnette, 319 U. S. 624 (1943), suggested that furthering this interest by curtailing
speech was impermissible. "Recognizing that the right to differ is
the centerpiece of our First Amendment freedoms," the court
explained,
"a government cannot mandate by fiat a feeling of unity in its
citizens. Therefore, that very same government cannot carve out a
symbol of unity and prescribe a set of approved messages to be
associated with that symbol when it cannot mandate the status or
feeling the symbol purports to represent."
755 S.W.2d at 97. Noting that the State had not shown that the
flag was in "grave and immediate danger," Barnette, supra, at 639, of being stripped of its symbolic value, the Texas court
also decided that the flag's special status was not endangered by
Johnson's conduct. 755 S.W.2d at 97.
As to the State's goal of preventing breaches of the peace, the
court concluded that the flag desecration statute was not drawn
narrowly enough to encompass only those flag burnings that were
likely to result in a serious disturbance of the peace. And in
fact, the court emphasized, the flag burning in this particular
case did not threaten such a reaction. " Serious offense'
occurred," the court admitted, "but there was no breach of peace, nor does the record reflect
that the situation was potentially explosive. One cannot equate
'serious offense' with incitement to breach the peace." Id. at 96. The court also stressed that another Texas
statute, Tex.Penal Code Ann. § 42.01 (1989), prohibited breaches of
the peace. Citing Boos v. Barry, 485 U.
S. 312 (1988), the court decided that § 42.01
demonstrated Texas' ability to prevent disturbances of the peace
without punishing this flag desecration. 755 S.W.2d at 96. Page 491 U. S. 402 Because it reversed Johnson's conviction on the ground that §
42.09 was unconstitutional as applied to him, the state court did
not address Johnson's argument that the statute was, on its face,
unconstitutionally vague and overbroad. We granted certiorari, 488
U.S. 907 (1988), and now affirm. II Johnson was convicted of flag desecration for burning the flag,
rather than for uttering insulting words. [ Footnote 2 ] This fact Page 491 U. S. 403 somewhat complicates our consideration of his conviction under
the First Amendment. We must first determine whether Johnson's
burning of the flag constituted expressive conduct, permitting him
to invoke the First Amendment in challenging his conviction. See, e.g., Spence v. Washington, 418 U.
S. 405 , 418 U. S.
409 -411 (1974). If his conduct was expressive, we next
decide whether the State's regulation is related to the suppression
of free expression. See, e.g., United States v. O'Brien , 391 U. S. 367 , 391 U. S. 377 (1968); Spence, supra, at 418 U. S. 414 ,
n. 8. If the State's regulation is not related to expression, then
the less stringent standard we announced in United States v.
O'Brien for regulations of noncommunicative conduct controls. See O'Brien, supra, at 391 U. S. 377 .
If it is, then we are outside of O'Brien 's test, and we
must ask whether this interest justifies Johnson's conviction under
a more demanding standard. [ Footnote 3 ] See Spence, supra, at 418 U. S. 411 .
A Page 491 U. S. 404 third possibility is that the State's asserted interest is
simply not implicated on these facts, and, in that event, the
interest drops out of the picture. See 418 U.S. at 418 U. S. 414 ,
n. 8.
The First Amendment literally forbids the abridgment only of
"speech," but we have long recognized that its protection does not
end at the spoken or written word. While we have rejected
"the view that an apparently limitless variety of conduct can be
labeled 'speech' whenever the person engaging in the conduct
intends thereby to express an idea," United States v. O'Brien, supra, at 391 U. S. 376 ,
we have acknowledged that conduct may be "sufficiently imbued with
elements of communication to fall within the scope of the First and
Fourteenth Amendments," Spence, supra, at 418 U. S.
409 .
In deciding whether particular conduct possesses sufficient
communicative elements to bring the First Amendment into play, we
have asked whether
"[a]n intent to convey a particularized message was present, and
[whether] the likelihood was great that the message would be
understood by those who viewed it."
418 U.S. at 418 U. S.
410 -411. Hence, we have recognized the expressive nature
of students' wearing of black armbands to protest American military
involvement in Vietnam, Tinker v. Des Moines Independent
Community School Dist., 393 U. S. 503 , 393 U. S. 505 (1969); of a sit-in by blacks in a "whites only" area to protest
segregation, Brown v. Louisiana, 383 U.
S. 131 , 383 U. S.
141 -142 (1966); of the wearing of American military
uniforms in a dramatic presentation criticizing American
involvement in Vietnam, Schacht v. United States, 398 U. S. 58 (1970); and of picketing about a wide variety of causes, see,
e.g., Food Employees v. Logan Valley Plaza, Inc., 391 U.
S. 308 , 391 U. S.
313 -314 (1968); United States v. Grace, 461 U. S. 171 , 461 U. S. 176 (1983).
Especially pertinent to this case are our decisions recognizing
the communicative nature of conduct relating to flags. Attaching a
peace sign to the flag, Spence, supra, at 418 U. S.
409 -410; refusing to salute the flag, Barnette, 319 U.S. at 319 U. S. 632 ;
and displaying a red flag, Stromberg v. California, 283 U. S. 359 , Page 491 U. S. 405 283 U. S.
368 -369 (1931), we have held, all may find shelter under
the First Amendment. See also Smith v. Goguen, 415 U. S. 566 , 415 U. S. 588 (1974) (WHITE, J., concurring in judgment) (treating flag
"contemptuously" by wearing pants with small flag sewn into their
seat is expressive conduct). That we have had little difficulty
identifying an expressive element in conduct relating to flags
should not be surprising. The very purpose of a national flag is to
serve as a symbol of our country; it is, one might say, "the one
visible manifestation of two hundred years of nationhood." Id. at 415 U. S. 603 (REHNQUIST, J., dissenting). Thus, we have observed:
"[T]he flag salute is a form of utterance. Symbolism is a
primitive but effective way of communicating ideas. The use of an
emblem or flag to symbolize some system, idea, institution, or
personality, is a shortcut from mind to mind. Causes and nations,
political parties, lodges and ecclesiastical groups seek to knit
the loyalty of their followings to a flag or banner, a color or
design." Barnette, supra, at 319 U. S. 632 .
Pregnant with expressive content, the flag as readily signifies
this Nation as does the combination of letters found in
"America."
We have not automatically concluded, however, that any action
taken with respect to our flag is expressive. Instead, in
characterizing such action for First Amendment purposes, we have
considered the context in which it occurred. In Spence, for example, we emphasized that Spence's taping of a peace sign to
his flag was "roughly simultaneous with and concededly triggered by
the Cambodian incursion and the Kent State tragedy." 418 U.S. at 418 U. S. 410 .
The State of Washington had conceded, in fact, that Spence's
conduct was a form of communication, and we stated that "the
State's concession is inevitable on this record." Id. at 418 U. S.
409 .
The State of Texas conceded for purposes of its oral argument in
this case that Johnson's conduct was expressive conduct, Tr. of
Oral Arg. 4, and this concession seems to us as Page 491 U. S. 406 prudent as was Washington's in Spence. Johnson burned
an American flag as part -- indeed, as the culmination -- of a
political demonstration that coincided with the convening of the
Republican Party and its renomination of Ronald Reagan for
President. The expressive, overtly political nature of this conduct
was both intentional and overwhelmingly apparent. At his trial,
Johnson explained his reasons for burning the flag as follows:
"The American Flag was burned as Ronald Reagan was being
renominated as President. And a more powerful statement of symbolic
speech, whether you agree with it or not, couldn't have been made
at that time. It's quite a just position [juxtaposition]. We had
new patriotism and no patriotism."
5 Record 656. In these circumstances, Johnson's burning of the
flag was conduct "sufficiently imbued with elements of
communication," Spence, 418 U.S. at 418 U. S. 409 ,
to implicate the First Amendment. III The government generally has a freer hand in restricting
expressive conduct than it has in restricting the written or spoken
word. See O'Brien, 391 U.S. at 391 U. S.
376 -377; Clark v. Community for Creative
Non-Violence, 468 U. S. 288 , 468 U. S. 293 (1984); Dallas v. Stanglin, 490 U. S.
19 , 490 U. S. 25 (1989). It may not, however, proscribe particular conduct because it has expressive elements.
"[W]hat might be termed the more generalized guarantee of
freedom of expression makes the communicative nature of conduct an
inadequate basis for singling out that conduct for proscription. A
law directed at the communicative nature of conduct must,
like a law directed at speech itself, be justified by the
substantial showing of need that the First Amendment requires." Community for Creative Non-Violence v. Watt, 227
U.S.App.D.C. 19, 55-56, 703 F.2d 586, 622-623 (1983) (Scalia, J.,
dissenting) (emphasis in original), rev'd sub nom. Clark v.
Community for Creative Non-Violence, supra. It is, in short,
not simply the verbal or nonverbal nature of the expression, but
the governmental Page 491 U. S. 407 interest at stake, that helps to determine whether a restriction
on that expression is valid.
Thus, although we have recognized that, where
"'speech' and 'nonspeech' elements are combined in the same
course of conduct, a sufficiently important governmental interest
in regulating the nonspeech element can justify incidental
limitations on First Amendment freedoms," O'Brien, supra, at 391 U. S. 376 ,
we have limited the applicability of O'Brien's relatively
lenient standard to those cases in which "the governmental interest
is unrelated to the suppression of free expression." Id. at 391 U. S. 377 ; see also Spence, 418 U.S. at 418 U. S. 414 ,
n. 8. In stating, moreover, that O'Brien's test "in the
last analysis is little, if any, different from the standard
applied to time, place, or manner restrictions," Clark,
supra, at 468 U. S. 298 ,
we have highlighted the requirement that the governmental interest
in question be unconnected to expression in order to come under O'Brien's less demanding rule.
In order to decide whether O'Brien's test applies here,
therefore, we must decide whether Texas has asserted an interest in
support of Johnson's conviction that is unrelated to the
suppression of expression. If we find that an interest asserted by
the State is simply not implicated on the facts before us, we need
not ask whether O'Brien's test applies. See Spence,
supra, at 418 U. S. 414 ,
n. 8. The State offers two separate interests to justify this
conviction: preventing breaches of the peace and preserving the
flag as a symbol of nationhood and national unity. We hold that the
first interest is not implicated on this record, and that the
second is related to the suppression of expression. A Texas claims that its interest in preventing breaches of the
peace justifies Johnson's conviction for flag desecration.
[ Footnote 4 ] Page 491 U. S. 408 However, no disturbance of the peace actually occurred or
threatened to occur because of Johnson's burning of the flag.
Although the State stresses the disruptive behavior of the
protestors during their march toward City Hall, Brief for
Petitioner 34-36, it admits that "no actual breach of the peace
occurred at the time of the flagburning or in response to the
flagburning." Id. at 34. The State's emphasis on the
protestors' disorderly actions prior to arriving at City Hall is
not only somewhat surprising, given that no charges were brought on
the basis of this conduct, but it also fails to show that a
disturbance of the peace was a likely reaction to Johnson's
conduct. The only evidence offered by the State at trial to show
the reaction to Johnson's actions was the testimony of several
persons who had been seriously offended by the flag burning. Id. at 6-7.
The State's position, therefore, amounts to a claim that an
audience that takes serious offense at particular expression is
necessarily likely to disturb the peace, and that the expression
may be prohibited on this basis. [ Footnote 5 ] Our precedents do not countenance such a
presumption. On the contrary, they recognize that a principal
"function of free speech under our system of government is to
invite dispute. It may indeed best serve its high purpose when it
induces a condition of unrest, creates dissatisfaction with
conditions as they are, or Page 491 U. S. 409 even stirs people to anger." Terminiello v. Chicago, 337 U. S.
1 , 337 U. S. 4 (1949). See also Cox v. Louisiana, 379 U.
S. 536 , 379 U. S. 551 (1965); Tinker v. Des Moines Independent Community School
Dist., 393 U.S. at 393 U. S.
508 -509; Coates v. Cincinnati, 402 U.
S. 611 , 402 U. S. 615 (1971); Hustler Magazine, Inc. v. Falwell, 485 U. S.
46 , 485 U. S. 55 -56
(1988). It would be odd indeed to conclude both that "if
it is the speaker's opinion that gives offense, that consequence is
a reason for according it constitutional protection," FCC v.
Pacifica Foundation, 438 U. S. 726 , 438 U. S. 745 (1978) (opinion of STEVENS, J.), and that the Government
may ban the expression of certain disagreeable ideas on the
unsupported presumption that their very disagreeableness will
provoke violence.
Thus, we have not permitted the government to assume that every
expression of a provocative idea will incite a riot, but have
instead required careful consideration of the actual circumstances
surrounding such expression, asking whether the expression "is
directed to inciting or producing imminent lawless action and is
likely to incite or produce such action." Brandenburg v.
Ohio, 395 U. S. 444 , 395 U. S. 447 (1969) (reviewing circumstances surrounding rally and speeches by
Ku Klux Klan). To accept Texas' arguments that it need only
demonstrate "the potential for a breach of the peace," Brief for
Petitioner 37, and that every flag burning necessarily possesses
that potential, would be to eviscerate our holding in Brandenburg. This we decline to do.
Nor does Johnson's expressive conduct fall within that small
class of "fighting words" that are "likely to provoke the average
person to retaliation, and thereby cause a breach of the peace." Chaplinsky v. New Hampshire, 315 U.
S. 568 , 315 U. S. 574 (1942). No reasonable onlooker would have regarded Johnson's
generalized expression of dissatisfaction with the policies of the
Federal Government as a direct personal insult or an invitation to
exchange fisticuffs. See id. at 315 U. S.
572 -573; Cantwell v. Connecticut, 310 U.
S. 296 , 310 U. S. 309 (1940); FCC v. Pacifica Foundation, supra, at 438 U. S. 745 (opinion of STEVENS, J.). Page 491 U. S. 410 We thus conclude that the State's interest in maintaining order
is not implicated on these facts. The State need not worry that our
holding will disable it from preserving the peace. We do not
suggest that the First Amendment forbids a State to prevent
"imminent lawless action." Brandenburg, supra, at 395 U. S. 447 .
And, in fact, Texas already has a statute specifically prohibiting
breaches of the peace, Tex.Penal Code Ann. § 42.01 (1989), which
tends to confirm that Texas need not punish this flag desecration
in order to keep the peace. See Boos v. Barry, 485 U.S. at 485 U. S.
327 -329. B The State also asserts an interest in preserving the flag as a
symbol of nationhood and national unity. In Spence, we
acknowledged that the government's interest in preserving the
flag's special symbolic value "is directly related to expression in
the context of activity" such as affixing a peace symbol to a flag.
418 U.S. at 418 U. S. 414 ,
n. 8. We are equally persuaded that this interest is related to
expression in the case of Johnson's burning of the flag. The State,
apparently, is concerned that such conduct will lead people to
believe either that the flag does not stand for nationhood and
national unity, but instead reflects other, less positive concepts,
or that the concepts reflected in the flag do not in fact exist,
that is, that we do not enjoy unity as a Nation. These concerns
blossom only when a person's treatment of the flag communicates
some message, and thus are related "to the suppression of free
expression" within the meaning of O'Brien. We are thus
outside of O'Brien's test altogether. IV It remains to consider whether the State's interest in
preserving the flag as a symbol of nationhood and national unity
justifies Johnson's conviction.
As in Spence, "[w]e are confronted with a case of
prosecution for the expression of an idea through activity," and
"[a]ccordingly, we must examine with particular care the
interests Page 491 U. S. 411 advanced by [petitioner] to support its prosecution." 418 U.S.
at 418 U. S. 411 .
Johnson was not, we add, prosecuted for the expression of just any
idea; he was prosecuted for his expression of dissatisfaction with
the policies of this country, expression situated at the core of
our First Amendment values. See, e.g., Boos v. Barry,
supra, at 485 U. S. 318 ; Frisby v. Schultz, 487 U. S. 474 , 487 U. S. 479 (1988).
Moreover, Johnson was prosecuted because he knew that his
politically charged expression would cause "serious offense." If he
had burned the flag as a means of disposing of it because it was
dirty or torn, he would not have been convicted of flag desecration
under this Texas law: federal law designates burning as the
preferred means of disposing of a flag "when it is in such
condition that it is no longer a fitting emblem for display," 36
U.S.C. § 176(k), and Texas has no quarrel with this means of
disposal. Brief for Petitioner 45. The Texas law is thus not aimed
at protecting the physical integrity of the flag in all
circumstances, but is designed instead to protect it only against
impairments that would cause serious offense to others. [ Footnote 6 ] Texas concedes as much:
"Section 42.09(b) reaches only those severe acts of physical
abuse of the flag carried out in a way likely to be offensive. The
statute mandates intentional or knowing abuse, that is, the kind of
mistreatment that is not innocent, but rather is intentionally
designed to seriously offend other individuals." Id. at 44.
Whether Johnson's treatment of the flag violated Texas law thus
depended on the likely communicative impact of his expressive
conduct. [ Footnote 7 ] Our
decision in Boos v. Barry, supra, Page 491 U. S. 412 tells us that this restriction on Johnson's expression is
content-based. In Boos, we considered the
constitutionality of a law prohibiting
"the display of any sign within 500 feet of a foreign embassy if
that sign tends to bring that foreign government into 'public
odium' or 'public disrepute.'" Id. at 485 U. S. 315 .
Rejecting the argument that the law was content-neutral because it
was justified by "our international law obligation to shield
diplomats from speech that offends their dignity," id. at 485 U. S. 320 ,
we held that "[t]he emotive impact of speech on its audience is not
a secondary effect'" unrelated to the content of the expression
itself. Id. at 485 U. S. 321 (plurality opinion); see also id. at 485 U. S. 334 (BRENNAN, J., concurring in part and concurring in
judgment). According to the principles announced in Boos, Johnson's political expression was restricted because of the
content of the message he conveyed. We must therefore subject the
State's asserted interest in preserving the special symbolic
character of the flag to "the most exacting scrutiny." Boos v.
Barry, 485 U.S. at 485 U. S. 321 .
[ Footnote 8 ] Page 491 U. S. 413 Texas argues that its interest in preserving the flag as a
symbol of nationhood and national unity survives this close
analysis. Quoting extensively from the writings of this Court
chronicling the flag's historic and symbolic role in our society,
the State emphasizes the " special place"' reserved for the flag
in our Nation. Brief for Petitioner 22, quoting Smith v.
Goguen, 415 U.S. at 415 U. S. 601 (REHNQUIST, J., dissenting). The State's argument is not that it
has an interest simply in maintaining the flag as a symbol of something, no matter what it symbolizes; indeed, if that
were the State's position, it would be difficult to see how that
interest is endangered by highly symbolic conduct such as
Johnson's. Rather, the State's claim is that it has an interest in
preserving the flag as a symbol of nationhood and national unity, a symbol with a determinate range of
meanings. Brief for Petitioner 20-24. According to Texas, if one
physically treats the flag in a way that would tend to cast doubt
on either the idea that nationhood and national unity are the
flag's referents or that national unity actually exists, the
message conveyed thereby is a harmful one, and therefore may be
prohibited. [ Footnote
9 ] Page 491 U. S. 414 If there is a bedrock principle underlying the First Amendment,
it is that the government may not prohibit the expression of an
idea simply because society finds the idea itself offensive or
disagreeable. See, e.g., Hustler Magazine v. Falwell, 485
U.S. at 485 U. S. 55 -56; City Council of Los Angeles v. Taxpayers for Vincent, 466 U. S. 789 , 466 U. S. 804 (1984); Bolger v. Youngs Drug Products Corp., 463 U. S.
60 , 463 U. S. 65 , 463 U. S. 72 (1983); Carey v. Brown, 447 U. S. 455 , 447 U. S.
462 -463 (1980); FCC v. Pacifica Foundation, 438
U.S. at 438 U. S.
745 -746; Young v. American Mini Theatres, Inc., 427 U. S. 50 , 427 U. S. 63 -65, 427 U. S. 67 -68
(1976) (plurality opinion); Buckley v. Valeo, 424 U. S.
1 , 424 U. S. 16 -17
(1976); Grayned v. Rockford, 408 U.
S. 104 , 408 U. S. 115 (1972); Police Dept. of Chicago v. Mosley, 408 U. S.
92 , 408 U. S. 95 (1972); Bachellar v. Maryland, 397 U.
S. 564 , 397 U. S. 567 (1970); O'Brien, 391 U.S. at 391 U. S. 382 ; Brown v. Louisiana, 383 U.S. at 383 U. S.
142 -143; Stromberg v. California, 283 U.S. at 283 U. S.
368 -369.
We have not recognized an exception to this principle even where
our flag has been involved. In Street v. New York, 394 U. S. 576 (1969), we held that a State may not criminally punish a person for
uttering words critical of the flag. Rejecting the argument that
the conviction could be sustained on the ground that Street had
"failed to show the respect for our national symbol which may
properly be demanded of every citizen," we concluded that
"the constitutionally guaranteed 'freedom to be intellectually .
. . diverse or even contrary,' and the 'right to differ as to
things that touch the heart of the existing order,' encompass the
freedom to express publicly one's opinions about our flag,
including those opinions which are defiant or contemptuous." Id. at 394 U. S. 593 ,
quoting Barnette, 319 U.S. at 319 U. S. 642 .
Nor may the government, we have held, compel conduct that would
evince respect for the flag.
"To sustain the compulsory flag salute, we are required to say
that a Bill of Rights which guards the individual's right to speak
his own mind left it open to public authorities to compel him to
utter what is not in his mind." Id. at 319 U. S.
634 . Page 491 U. S. 415 In holding in Barnette that the Constitution did not
leave this course open to the government, Justice Jackson described
one of our society's defining principles in words deserving of
their frequent repetition:
"If there is any fixed star in our constitutional constellation,
it is that no official, high or petty, can prescribe what shall be
orthodox in politics, nationalism, religion, or other matters of
opinion or force citizens to confess by word or act their faith
therein." Id. at 319 U. S. 642 .
In Spence, we held that the same interest asserted by
Texas here was insufficient to support a criminal conviction under
a flag-misuse statute for the taping of a peace sign to an American
flag.
"Given the protected character of [ Spence's ] expression
and in light of the fact that no interest the State may have in
preserving the physical integrity of a privately owned flag was
significantly impaired on these facts,"
we held, "the conviction must be invalidated." 418 U.S. at 418 U. S. 415 . See also Goguen, 415 U.S. at 415 U. S. 588 (WHITE, J., concurring in judgment) (to convict person who had sewn
a flag onto the seat of his pants for "contemptuous" treatment of
the flag would be "[t]o convict not to protect the physical
integrity or to protect against acts interfering with the proper
use of the flag, but to punish for communicating ideas unacceptable
to the controlling majority in the legislature").
In short, nothing in our precedents suggests that a State may
foster its own view of the flag by prohibiting expressive conduct
relating to it. [ Footnote
10 ] To bring its argument outside our Page 491 U. S. 416 precedents, Texas attempts to convince us that, even if its
interest in preserving the flag's symbolic role does not allow it
to prohibit words or some expressive conduct critical of the flag,
it does permit it to forbid the outright destruction of the flag.
The State's argument cannot depend here on the distinction between
written or spoken words and nonverbal conduct. That distinction, we
have shown, is of no moment where the nonverbal conduct is
expressive, as it is here, and where the regulation of that conduct
is related to expression, as it is here. See supra at 491 U. S.
402 -403. In addition, both Barnette and Spence involved expressive conduct, not only verbal
communication, and both found that conduct protected.
Texas' focus on the precise nature of Johnson's expression,
moreover, misses the point of our prior decisions: their enduring
lesson, that the government may not prohibit expression simply
because it disagrees with its message, is not dependent on the
particular mode in which one chooses to express an idea. [ Footnote 11 ] If we were to hold that
a State may forbid flag burning wherever it is likely to endanger
the flag's symbolic role, but allow it wherever burning a flag
promotes that role -- as where, for example, a person ceremoniously
burns a dirty flag -- we would be saying that when it comes to
impairing the flag's physical integrity, the flag itself may be
used as Page 491 U. S. 417 a symbol -- as a substitute for the written or spoken word or a
"short cut from mind to mind" -- only in one direction. We would be
permitting a State to "prescribe what shall be orthodox" by saying
that one may burn the flag to convey one's attitude toward it and
its referents only if one does not endanger the flag's
representation of nationhood and national unity.
We never before have held that the Government may ensure that a
symbol be used to express only one view of that symbol or its
referents. Indeed, in Schacht v. United States, we
invalidated a federal statute permitting an actor portraying a
member of one of our armed forces to " wear the uniform of that
armed force if the portrayal does not tend to discredit that armed
force.'" 398 U.S. at 398 U. S. 60 ,
quoting 10 U.S.C. § 772(f). This proviso, we held, "which leaves Americans free to praise the war in Vietnam but
can send persons like Schacht to prison for opposing it, cannot
survive in a country which has the First Amendment." Id. at 398 U. S.
63 .
We perceive no basis on which to hold that the principle
underlying our decision in Schacht does not apply to this
case. To conclude that the government may permit designated symbols
to be used to communicate only a limited set of messages would be
to enter territory having no discernible or defensible boundaries.
Could the government, on this theory, prohibit the burning of state
flags? Of copies of the Presidential seal? Of the Constitution? In
evaluating these choices under the First Amendment, how would we
decide which symbols were sufficiently special to warrant this
unique status? To do so, we would be forced to consult our own
political preferences, and impose them on the citizenry, in the
very way that the First Amendment forbids us to do. See Carey
v. Brown, 447 U.S. at 447 U. S. 466 -467.
There is, moreover, no indication -- either in the text of the
Constitution or in our cases interpreting it -- that a separate
juridical category exists for the American flag alone. Indeed, we
would not be surprised to learn that the persons Page 491 U. S. 418 who framed our Constitution and wrote the Amendment that we now
construe were not known for their reverence for the Union Jack. The
First Amendment does not guarantee that other concepts virtually
sacred to our Nation as a whole -- such as the principle that
discrimination on the basis of race is odious and destructive --
will go unquestioned in the marketplace of ideas. See
Brandenburg v. Ohio, 395 U. S. 444 (1969). We decline, therefore, to create for the flag an exception
to the joust of principles protected by the First Amendment.
It is not the State's ends, but its means, to which we object.
It cannot be gainsaid that there is a special place reserved for
the flag in this Nation, and thus we do not doubt that the
government has a legitimate interest in making efforts to
"preserv[e] the national flag as an unalloyed symbol of our
country." Spence, 418 U.S. at 418 U. S. 412 .
We reject the suggestion, urged at oral argument by counsel for
Johnson, that the government lacks "any state interest whatsoever"
in regulating the manner in which the flag may be displayed. Tr. of
Oral Arg. 38. Congress has, for example, enacted precatory
regulations describing the proper treatment of the flag, see 36 U.S.C. §§ 173-177, and we cast no doubt on the
legitimacy of its interest in making such recommendations. To say
that the government has an interest in encouraging proper treatment
of the flag, however, is not to say that it may criminally punish a
person for burning a flag as a means of political protest.
"National unity as an end which officials may foster by
persuasion and example is not in question. The problem is whether,
under our Constitution, compulsion as here employed is a
permissible means for its achievement." Barnette, 319 U.S. at 319 U. S.
640 .
We are fortified in today's conclusion by our conviction that
forbidding criminal punishment for conduct such as Johnson's will
not endanger the special role played by our flag or the feelings it
inspires. To paraphrase Justice Holmes, we submit that nobody can
suppose that this one gesture of an unknown Page 491 U. S. 419 man will change our Nation's attitude towards its flag. See
Abrams v. United States, 250 U. S. 616 , 250 U. S. 628 (1919) (Holmes, J., dissenting). Indeed, Texas' argument that the
burning of an American flag " is an act having a high likelihood
to cause a breach of the peace,'" Brief for Petitioner 31, quoting Sutherland v. DeWulf, 323 F.
Supp. 740 , 745 (SD Ill.1971) (citation omitted), and its
statute's implicit assumption that physical mistreatment of the
flag will lead to "serious offense," tend to confirm that the
flag's special role is not in danger; if it were, no one would riot
or take offense because a flag had been burned. We are tempted to say, in fact, that the flag's deservedly
cherished place in our community will be strengthened, not
weakened, by our holding today. Our decision is a reaffirmation of
the principles of freedom and inclusiveness that the flag best
reflects, and of the conviction that our toleration of criticism
such as Johnson's is a sign and source of our strength. Indeed, one
of the proudest images of our flag, the one immortalized in our own
national anthem, is of the bombardment it survived at Fort McHenry.
It is the Nation's resilience, not its rigidity, that Texas sees
reflected in the flag -- and it is that resilience that we reassert
today.
The way to preserve the flag's special role is not to punish
those who feel differently about these matters. It is to persuade
them that they are wrong.
"To courageous, self-reliant men, with confidence in the power
of free and fearless reasoning applied through the processes of
popular government, no danger flowing from speech can be deemed
clear and present unless the incidence of the evil apprehended is
so imminent that it may befall before there is opportunity for full
discussion. If there be time to expose through discussion the
falsehood and fallacies, to avert the evil by the processes of
education, the remedy to bee applied is more speech, not enforced
silence." Whitney v. California, 274 U.
S. 357 , 274 U. S. 377 (1927) (Brandeis, J., concurring). And, precisely because it is our
flag that is involved, one's response to the flag-burner Page 491 U. S. 420 may exploit the uniquely persuasive power of the flag itself. We
can imagine no more appropriate response to burning a flag than
waving one's own, no better way to counter a flag burner's message
than by saluting the flag that burns, no surer means of preserving
the dignity even of the flag that burned than by -- as one witness
here did -- according its remains a respectful burial. We do not
consecrate the flag by punishing its desecration, for in doing so
we dilute the freedom that this cherished emblem represents. V Johnson was convicted for engaging in expressive conduct. The
State's interest in preventing breaches of the peace does not
support his conviction, because Johnson's conduct did not threaten
to disturb the peace. Nor does the State's interest in preserving
the flag as a symbol of nationhood and national unity justify his
criminal conviction for engaging in political expression. The
judgment of the Texas Court of Criminal Appeals is therefore Affirmed. [ Footnote 1 ]
Tex.Penal Code Ann. § 42.09 (1989) provides in full:
"§ 42.09. Desecration of Venerated Object"
"(a) A person commits an offense if he intentionally or
knowingly desecrates:"
"(1) a public monument;"
"(2) a place of worship or burial; or"
"(3) a state or national flag."
"(b) For purposes of this section, 'desecrate' means deface,
damage, or otherwise physically mistreat in a way that the actor
knows will seriously offend one or more persons likely to observe
or discover his action."
"(c) An offense under this section is a Class A
misdemeanor."
[ Footnote 2 ]
Because the prosecutor's closing argument observed that Johnson
had led the protestors in chants denouncing the flag while it
burned, Johnson suggests that he may have been convicted for
uttering critical words, rather than for burning the flag. Brief
for Respondent 33-34. He relies on Street v. New York, 394 U. S. 576 , 394 U. S. 578 (1969), in which we reversed a conviction obtained under a New York
statute that prohibited publicly defying or casting contempt on the
flag "either by words or act" because we were persuaded that the
defendant may have been convicted for his words alone. Unlike the
law we faced in Street, however, the Texas flag
desecration statute does not on its face permit conviction for
remarks critical of the flag, as Johnson himself admits. See Brief for Respondent 34. Nor was the jury in this case
told that it could convict Johnson of flag desecration if it found
only that he had uttered words critical of the flag and its
referents.
Johnson emphasizes, though, that the jury was instructed --
according to Texas' law of parties -- that
"'a person is criminally responsible for an offense committed by
the conduct of another if acting with intent to promote or assist
the commission of the offense, he solicits, encourages, directs,
aids, or attempts to aid the other person to commit the
offense.'"
Brief for Respondent 2, n. 2, quoting 1 Record 49. The State
offered this instruction because Johnson's defense was that he was
not the person who had burned the flag. Johnson did not object to
this instruction at trial, and although he challenged it on direct
appeal, he did so only on the ground that there was insufficient
evidence to support it. 706 S.W.2d 120, 124 (Tex.App.1986). It is
only in this Court that Johnson has argued that the law-of-parties
instruction might have led the jury to convict him for his words
alone. Even if we were to find that this argument is properly
raised here, however, we would conclude that it has no merit in
these circumstances. The instruction would not have permitted a
conviction merely for the pejorative nature of Johnson's words, and
those words themselves did not encourage the burning of the flag,
as the instruction seems to require. Given the additional fact that
"the bulk of the State's argument was premised on Johnson's
culpability as a sole actor," ibid., we find it too
unlikely that the jury convicted Johnson on the basis of this
alternative theory to consider reversing his conviction on this
ground.
[ Footnote 3 ]
Although Johnson has raised a facial challenge to Texas' flag
desecration statute, we choose to resolve this case on the basis of
his claim that the statute, as applied to him, violates the First
Amendment. Section 42.09 regulates only physical conduct with
respect to the flag, not the written or spoken word, and although
one violates the statute only if one "knows" that one's physical
treatment of the flag "will seriously offend one or more persons
likely to observe or discover his action," Tex.Penal Code Ann. §
42.09(b) (1989), this fact does not necessarily mean that the
statute applies only to expressive conduct protected by the First
Amendment. Cf. Smith v. Goguen, 415 U.
S. 566 , 415 U. S. 588 (1974) (WHITE, J., concurring in judgment) (statute prohibiting
"contemptuous" treatment of flag encompasses only expressive
conduct). A tired person might, for example, drag a flag through
the mud, knowing that this conduct is likely to offend others, and
yet have no thought of expressing any idea; neither the language
nor the Texas courts' interpretations of the statute precludes the
possibility that such a person would be prosecuted for flag
desecration. Because the prosecution of a person who had not
engaged in expressive conduct would pose a different case, and
because this case may be disposed of on narrower grounds, we
address only Johnson's claim that § 42.09, as applied to political
expression like his, violates the First Amendment.
[ Footnote 4 ]
Relying on our decision in Boos v. Barry, 485 U.
S. 312 (1988), Johnson argues that this state interest
is related to the suppression of free expression within the meaning
of United States v. O'Brien, 391 U.
S. 367 (1968). He reasons that the violent reaction to
flag burnings feared by Texas would be the result of the message
conveyed by them, and that this fact connects the State's interest
to the suppression of expression. Brief for Respondent 12, n. 11.
This view has found some favor in the lower courts. See Monroe
v. State Court of Fulton County, 739 F.2d 568 574-575 (CA11
1984). Johnson's theory may overread Boos insofar as it
suggests that a desire to prevent a violent audience reaction is
"related to expression" in the same way that a desire to prevent an
audience from being offended is "related to expression." Because we
find that the State's interest in preventing breaches of the peace
is not implicated on these facts, however, we need not venture
further into this area.
[ Footnote 5 ]
There is, of course, a tension between this argument and the
State's claim that one need not actually cause serious offense in
order to violate § 42.09. See Brief for Petitioner 44.
[ Footnote 6 ] Cf. Smith v. Goguen, 415 U.S. at 415 U. S.
590 -591 (BLACKMUN, J., dissenting) (emphasizing that
lower court appeared to have construed state statute so as to
protect physical integrity of the flag in all circumstances); id. at 415 U. S.
597 -598 (REHNQUIST, J., dissenting) (same).
[ Footnote 7 ]
Texas suggests that Johnson's conviction did not depend on the
onlookers' reaction to the flag burning, because § 42.09 is
violated only when a person physically mistreats the flag in a way
that he " knows will seriously offend one or more persons
likely to observe or discover his action." Tex.Penal Code Ann. §
42.09(b) (1969) (emphasis added). "The serious offense'
language of the statute," Texas argues, "refers to an individual's
intent and to the manner in which the conduct is effectuated, not
to the reaction of the crowd." Brief for Petitioner 44. If the
statute were aimed only at the actor's intent, and not at the
communicative impact of his actions, however, there would be little
reason for the law to be triggered only when an audience is
"likely" to be present. At Johnson's trial, indeed, the State
itself seems not to have seen the distinction between knowledge and
actual communicative impact that it now stresses: it proved the
element of knowledge by offering the testimony of persons who had
in fact been seriously offended by Johnson's conduct. Id. at 6-7. In any event, we find the distinction between Texas'
statute and one dependent on actual audience reaction too precious
to be of constitutional significance. Both kinds of statutes
clearly are aimed at protecting onlookers from being offended by
the ideas expressed by the prohibited activity. [ Footnote 8 ]
Our inquiry is, of course, bounded by the particular facts of
this case and by the statute under which Johnson was convicted.
There was no evidence that Johnson himself stole the flag he
burned, Tr. of Oral Arg. 17, nor did the prosecution or the
arguments urged in support of it depend on the theory that the flag
was stolen. Ibid. Thus, our analysis does not rely on the
way in which the flag was acquired, and nothing in our opinion
should be taken to suggest that one is free to steal a flag so long
as one later uses it to communicate an idea. We also emphasize that
Johnson was prosecuted only for flag desecration -- not
for trespass, disorderly conduct, or arson.
[ Footnote 9 ]
Texas claims that "Texas is not endorsing, protecting, avowing
or prohibiting any particular philosophy." Brief for Petitioner 29.
If Texas means to suggest that its asserted interest does not
prefer Democrats over Socialists, or Republicans over Democrats,
for example, then it is beside the point, for Johnson does not rely
on such an argument. He argues instead that the State's desire to
maintain the flag as a symbol of nationhood and national unity
assumes that there is only one proper view of the flag. Thus, if
Texas means to argue that its interest does not prefer any viewpoint over another, it is mistaken; surely one's attitude
toward the flag and its referents is a viewpoint.
[ Footnote 10 ]
Our decision in Halter v. Nebraska, 205 U. S.
34 (1907), addressing the validity of a state law
prohibiting certain commercial uses of the flag, is not to the
contrary. That case was decided "nearly 20 years before the Court
concluded that the First Amendment applies to the States by virtue
of the Fourteenth Amendment." Spence v. Washington, 418 U. S. 405 , 418 U. S. 413 ,
n. 7 (1974). More important, as we continually emphasized in Halter itself, that case involved purely commercial,
rather than political, speech. 205 U.S. at 205 U. S. 38 , 205 U. S. 41 , 205 U. S. 42 , 205 U. S.
45 .
Nor does San Francisco Arts & Athletics, Inc. v. United
States Olympic Committee, 483 U. S. 522 , 483 U. S. 524 (1987), addressing the validity of Congress' decision to
"authoriz[e] the United States Olympic Committee to prohibit
certain commercial and promotional uses of the word Olympic,'"
relied upon by THE CHIEF JUSTICE's dissent, post at 491 U. S. 429 ,
even begin to tell us whether the government may criminally punish
physical conduct towards the flag engaged in as a means of
political protest. [ Footnote 11 ]
THE CHIEF JUSTlCE's dissent appears to believe that Johnson's
conduct may be prohibited and, indeed, criminally sanctioned,
because "his act . . . conveyed nothing that could not have been
conveyed and was not conveyed just as forcefully in a dozen
different ways." Post at 491 U. S. 431 .
Not only does this assertion sit uneasily next to the dissent's
quite correct reminder that the flag occupies a unique position in
our society -- which demonstrates that messages conveyed without
use of the flag are not "just as forcefu[l]" as those conveyed with
it -- but it also ignores the fact that, in Spence, supra, we "rejected summarily" this very claim. See 418 U.S. at 418 U. S. 411 ,
n. 4.
JUSTICE KENNEDY, concurring.
I write not to qualify the words JUSTICE BRENNAN chooses so
well, for he says with power all that is necessary to explain our
ruling. I join his opinion without reservation, but with a keen
sense that this case, like others before us from time to time,
exacts its personal toll. This prompts me to add to our pages these
few remarks.
The case before us illustrates better than most that the
judicial power is often difficult in its exercise. We cannot here
ask another Branch to share responsibility, as when the argument is
made that a statute is flawed or incomplete. For we are presented
with a clear and simple statute to be judged against a pure command
of the Constitution. The outcome can be laid at no door but
ours.
The hard fact is that sometimes we must make decisions we do not
like. We make them because they are right, right Page 491 U. S. 421 in the sense that the law and the Constitution, as we see them,
compel the result. And so great is our commitment to the process
that, except in the rare case, we do not pause to express distaste
for the result, perhaps for fear of undermining a valued principle
that dictates the decision. This is one of those rare cases.
Our colleagues in dissent advance powerful arguments why
respondent may be convicted for his expression, reminding us that
among those who will be dismayed by our holding will be some who
have had the singular honor of carrying the flag in battle. And I
agree that the flag holds a lonely place of honor in an age when
absolutes are distrusted and simple truths are burdened by unneeded
apologetics.
With all respect to those views, I do not believe the
Constitution gives us the right to rule as the dissenting Members
of the Court urge, however painful this judgment is to announce.
Though symbols often are what we ourselves make of them, the flag
is constant in expressing beliefs Americans share, beliefs in law
and peace and that freedom which sustains the human spirit. The
case here today forces recognition of the costs to which those
beliefs commit us. It is poignant but fundamental that the flag
protects those who hold it in contempt.
For all the record shows, this respondent was not a philosopher
and perhaps did not even possess the ability to comprehend how
repellent his statements must be to the Republic itself. But
whether or not he could appreciate the enormity of the offense he
gave, the fact remains that his acts were speech, in both the
technical and the fundamental meaning of the Constitution. So I
agree with the Court that he must go free.
CHIEF JUSTICE REHNQUIST, with whom JUSTICE WHITE and JUSTICE
O'CONNOR join, dissenting.
In holding this Texas statute unconstitutional, the Court
ignores Justice Holmes' familiar aphorism that "a page of history
is worth a volume of logic." New York Trust Co.
v. Page 491 U. S. 422 Eisner, 256 U. S. 345 , 256 U. S. 349 (1921). For more than 200 years, the American flag has occupied a
unique position as the symbol of our Nation, a uniqueness that
justifies a governmental prohibition against flag burning in the
way respondent Johnson did here.
At the time of the American Revolution, the flag served to unify
the Thirteen Colonies at home while obtaining recognition of
national sovereignty abroad. Ralph Waldo Emerson's Concord Hymn
describes the first skirmishes of the Revolutionary War in these
lines:
"By the rude bridge that arched the flood"
"Their flag to April's breeze unfurled,"
"Here once the embattled farmers stood"
"And fired the shot heard round the world."
During that time, there were many colonial and regimental flags,
adorned with such symbols as pine trees, beavers, anchors, and
rattlesnakes, bearing slogans such as "Liberty or Death," "Hope,"
"An Appeal to Heaven," and "Don't Tread on Me." The first
distinctive flag of the Colonies was the "Grand Union Flag" -- with
13 stripes and a British flag in the left corner -- which was flown
for the first time on January 2, 1776, by troops of the Continental
Army around Boston. By June 14, 1777, after we declared our
independence from England, the Continental Congress resolved:
"That the flag of the thirteen United States be thirteen
stripes, alternate red and white: that the union be thirteen stars,
white in a blue field, representing a new constellation."
8 Journal of the Continental Congress 1774-1789, p. 464 (W. Ford
ed.1907). One immediate result of the flag's adoption was that
American vessels harassing British shipping sailed under an
authorized national flag. Without such a flag, the British could
treat captured seamen as pirates and hang them summarily; with a
national flag, such seamen were treated as prisoners of war. Page 491 U. S. 423 During the War of 1812, British naval forces sailed up
Chesapeake Bay and marched overland to sack and burn the city of
Washington. They then sailed up the Patapsco River to invest the
city of Baltimore, but to do so it was first necessary to reduce
Fort McHenry in Baltimore Harbor. Francis Scott Key, a Washington
lawyer, had been granted permission by the British to board one of
their warships to negotiate the release of an American who had been
taken prisoner. That night, waiting anxiously on the British ship,
Key watched the British fleet firing on Fort McHenry. Finally, at
daybreak, he saw the fort's American flag still flying; the British
attack had failed. Intensely moved, he began to scribble on the
back of an envelope the poem that became our national anthem:
"O say can you see by the dawn's early light"
"What so proudly we hail'd at the twilight's last gleaming,"
"Whose broad stripes & bright stars through the perilous
fight"
"O'er the ramparts we watch'd, were so gallantly streaming?"
"And the rocket's red glare, the bomb bursting in air,"
"Gave proof through the night that our flag was still
there,"
"O say does that star-spangled banner yet wave"
"O'er the land of the free & the home of the brave?"
The American flag played a central role in our Nation's most
tragic conflict, when the North fought against the South. The
lowering of the American flag at Fort Sumter was viewed as the
start of the war. G. Preble, History of the Flag of the United
States of America 453 (1880). The Southern States, to formalize
their separation from the Union, adopted the "Stars and Bars" of
the Confederacy. The Union troops marched to the sound of "Yes
We'll Rally Round The Flag Boys, We'll Rally Once Again." President
Abraham Lincoln refused proposals to remove from the Page 491 U. S. 424 American flag the stars representing the rebel States, because
he considered the conflict not a war between two nations, but an
attack by 11 States against the National Government. Id. at 411. By war's end, the American flag again flew over "an
indestructible union, composed of indestructible states." TeXas v.
White , 7 Wall. 700, 74 U. S. 725 (1869).
One of the great stories of the Civil War is told in John
Greenleaf Whittier's poem, "Barbara Frietchie":
Up from the meadows rich with corn,
Clear in the cool September morn,
The clustered spires of Frederick stand
Green-walled by the hills of Maryland.
Round about them orchards sweep,
Apple- and peach-tree fruited deep,
Fair as a garden of the Lord
To the eyes of the famished rebel horde,
On that pleasant morn of the early fall
When Lee marched over the mountain wall, --
Over the mountains winding down,
Horse and foot, into Frederick town.
Forty flags with their silver stars,
Forty flags with their crimson bars,
Flapped in the morning wind: the sun
Of noon looked down, and saw not one.
Up rose old Barbara Frietchie then,
Bowed with her four-score years and ten;
Bravest of all in Frederick town,
She took up the flag the men hauled down;
In her attic-window the staff she set,
To show that one heart was loyal yet.
Up the street came the rebel tread,
Stonewall Jackson riding ahead.
Under his slouched hat left and right
He glanced: the old flag met his sight.
"Halt!" -- the dust-brown ranks stood fast.
"Fire!" -- out blazed the rifle-blast Page 491 U. S. 425 It shivered the window, pane and sash;
It rent the banner with seam and gash.
Quick, as it fell, from the broken staff
Dame Barbara snatched the silken scarf;
She leaned far out on the window-sill,
And shook it forth with a royal will.
"Shoot, if you must, this old gray head,
But spare your country's flag," she said.
A shade of sadness, a blush of shame,
Over the face of the leader came;
The nobler nature within him stirred
To life at that woman's deed and word:
"Who touches a hair of yon gray head
Dies like a dog! March on!" he said.
All day long through Frederick street
Sounded the tread of marching feet:
All day long that free flag tost
Over the heads of the rebel host.
Ever its torn folds rose and fell
On the loyal winds that loved it well;
And through the hill-gaps sunset light
Shone over it with a warm good-night.
Barbara Frietchie's work is o'er,
And the Rebel rides on his raids no more.
Honor to her! and let a tear
Fall, for her sake, on Stonewall's bier.
Over Barbara Frietchie's grave,
Flag of Freedom and Union, wave!
Peace and order and beauty draw
Round thy symbol of light and law;
And ever the stars above look down
On thy stars below in Frederick town!
In the First and Second World Wars, thousands of our countrymen
died on foreign soil fighting for the American cause. At Iwo Jima
in the Second World War, United States Marines fought hand to hand
against thousands of Page 491 U. S. 426 Japanese. By the time the Marines reached the top of Mount
Suribachi, they raised a piece of pipe upright and from one end
fluttered a flag. That ascent had cost nearly 6,000 American lives.
The Iwo Jima Memorial in Arlington National Cemetery memorializes
that event. President Franklin Roosevelt authorized the use of the
flag on labels, packages, cartons, and containers intended for
export as lend-lease aid, in order to inform people in other
countries of the United States' assistance. Presidential
Proclamation No. 2605, 58 Stat. 1126.
During the Korean War, the successful amphibious landing of
American troops at Inchon was marked by the raising of an American
flag within an hour of the event. Impetus for the enactment of the
Federal Flag Desecration Statute in 1967 came from the impact of
flag burnings in the United States on troop morale in Vietnam.
Representative L. Mendel Rivers, then Chairman of the House Armed
Services Committee, testified that
"The burning of the flag . . . has caused my mail to increase
100 percent from the boys in Vietnam, writing me and asking me what
is going on in America."
Desecration of the Flag, Hearings on H.R. 271 before
Subcommittee No. 4 of the House Committee on the Judiciary, 90th
Cong., 1st Sess., 189 (1967). Representative Charles Wiggins
stated:
"The public act of desecration of our flag tends to undermine
the morale of American troops. That this finding is true can be
attested by many Members who have received correspondence from
servicemen expressing their shock and disgust of such conduct."
113 Cong.Rec. 16459 (1967).
The flag symbolizes the Nation in peace as well as in war. It
signifies our national presence on battleships, airplanes, military
installations, and public buildings from the United States Capitol
to the thousands of county courthouses and city halls throughout
the country. Two flags are prominently placed in our courtroom.
Countless flags are placed by the graves of loved ones each year on
what was first called Page 491 U. S. 427 Decoration Day, and is now called Memorial Day. The flag is
traditionally placed on the casket of deceased members of the Armed
Forces, and it is later given to the deceased's family. 10 U.S.C.
§§ 1481, 1482. Congress has provided that the flag be flown at
half-staff upon the death of the President, Vice President, and
other government officials "as a mark of respect to their memory."
36 U.S.C. § 175(m). The flag identifies United States merchant
ships, 22 U.S.C. § 454, and "[t]he laws of the Union protect our
commerce wherever the flag of the country may float." United States v.
Guthrie , 17 How. 284, 309 (1855).
No other American symbol has been as universally honored as the
flag. In 1931, Congress declared "The Star-Spangled Banner" to be
our national anthem. 36 U.S.C. § 170. In 1949, Congress declared
June 14th to be Flag Day. § 157. In 1987, John Philip Sousa's "The
Stars and Stripes Forever" was designated as the national march.
Pub.L. 101-186, 101 Stat. 1286. Congress has also established "The
Pledge of Allegiance to the Flag" and the manner of its
deliverance. 36 U.S.C. § 172. The flag has appeared as the
principal symbol on approximately 33 United States postal stamps
and in the design of at least 43 more, more times than any other
symbol. United States Postal Service, Definitive Mint Set 15
(1988).
Both Congress and the States have enacted numerous laws
regulating misuse of the American flag. Until 1967, Congress left
the regulation of misuse of the flag up to the States. Now,
however, Title 18 U.S.C. § 700(a) provides that:
"Whoever knowingly casts contempt upon any flag of the United
States by publicly mutilating, defacing, defiling, burning, or
trampling upon it shall be fined not more than $1,000 or imprisoned
for not more than one year, or both."
Congress has also prescribed, inter alia, detailed
rules for the design of the flag, 4 U.S.C. § 1, the time and
occasion of flag's display, 36 U.S.C. § 174, the position and
manner of Page 491 U. S. 428 its display, § 175, respect for the flag, § 176, and conduct
during hoisting, lowering, and passing of the flag, § 177. With the
exception of Alaska and Wyoming, all of the States now have
statutes prohibiting the burning of the flag. [ Footnote 2/1 ] Most of the state statutes are
patterned after the Uniform Flag Act of 1917, which in § 3
provides:
"No person shall publicly mutilate, deface, defile, defy,
trample upon, or by word or act cast contempt upon any such flag,
standard, color, ensign or shield."
Proceedings of National Conference of Commissioners on Uniform
State Laws 323-324 (1917). Most were passed by the States at about
the time of World War I. Rosenblatt, Flag Desecration Statutes:
History and Analysis, 1972 Wash.U.L.Q.193, 197. Page 491 U. S. 429 The American flag, then, throughout more than 200 years of our
history, has come to be the visible symbol embodying our Nation. It
does not represent the views of any particular political party, and
it does not represent any particular political philosophy. The flag
is not simply another "idea" or "point of view" competing for
recognition in the marketplace of ideas. Millions and millions of
Americans regard it with an almost mystical reverence, regardless
of what sort of social, political, or philosophical beliefs they
may have. I cannot agree that the First Amendment invalidates the
Act of Congress, and the laws of 48 of the 50 States, which make
criminal the public burning of the flag.
More than 80 years ago, in Halter v. Nebraska, 205 U. S. 34 (1907), this Court upheld the constitutionality of a Nebraska
statute that forbade the use of representations of the American
flag for advertising purposes upon articles of merchandise. The
Court there said:
"For that flag every true American has not simply an
appreciation, but a deep affection. . . . Hence, it has often
occurred that insults to a flag have been the cause of war, and
indignities put upon it, in the presence of those who revere it,
have often been resented and sometimes punished on the spot." Id. at 41.
Only two Terms ago, in San Francisco Arts & Athletics,
Inc. v. United States Olympic Committee, 483 U.
S. 522 (1987), the Court held that Congress could grant
exclusive use of the word "Olympic" to the United States Olympic
Committee. The Court thought that this
"restrictio[n] on expressive speech properly [was] characterized
as incidental to the primary congressional purpose of encouraging
and rewarding the USOC's activities." Id. at 483 U. S. 536 .
As the Court stated,
"when a word [or symbol] acquires value 'as the result of
organization and the expenditure of labor, skill, and money' by an
entity, that entity constitutionally may obtain a limited property
right in the word [or symbol]." Id. at 483 U. S. 532 ,
quoting International News Service v.
Associated Press , 248 Page 491 U. S. 430 U.S. 215, 248 U. S. 239 (1918). Surely Congress or the States may recognize a similar
interest in the flag.
But the Court insists that the Texas statute prohibiting the
public burning of the American flag infringes on respondent
Johnson's freedom of expression. Such freedom, of course, is not
absolute. See Schenck v. United States, 249 U. S.
47 (1919). In Chaplinsky v. New Hampshire, 315 U. S. 568 (1942), a unanimous Court said:
"Allowing the broadest scope to the language and purpose of the
Fourteenth Amendment, it is well understood that the right of free
speech is not absolute at all times and under all circumstances.
There are certain well defined and narrowly limited classes of
speech, the prevention and punishment of which have never been
thought to raise any Constitutional problem. These include the lewd
and obscene, the profane, the libelous, and the insulting or
'fighting' words -- those which, by their very utterance, inflict
injury or tend to incite an immediate breach of the peace. It has
been well observed that such utterances are no essential part of
any exposition of ideas, and are of such slight social value as a
step to truth that any benefit that may be derived from them is
clearly outweighed by the social interest in order and
morality." Id. at 315 U. S.
571 -572 (footnotes omitted). The Court upheld
Chaplinsky's conviction under a state statute that made it unlawful
to "address any offensive, derisive or annoying word to any person
who is lawfully in any street or other public place." Id. at 315 U. S. 569 .
Chaplinsky had told a local marshal, "You are a God damned
racketeer" and a "damned Fascist and the whole government of
Rochester are Fascists or agents of Fascists." Ibid. Here it may equally well be said that the public burning of the
American flag by Johnson was no essential part of any exposition of
ideas, and at the same time it had a tendency to incite a breach of
the peace. Johnson was free to make any verbal denunciation of the
flag that he wished; indeed, he was Page 491 U. S. 431 free to burn the flag in private. He could publicly burn other
symbols of the Government or effigies of political leaders. He did
lead a march through the streets of Dallas, and conducted a rally
in front of the Dallas City Hall. He engaged in a "die-in" to
protest nuclear weapons. He shouted out various slogans during the
march, including: "Reagan, Mondale which will it be? Either one
means World War III"; "Ronald Reagan, killer of the hour, Perfect
example of U.S. power"; and "red, white and blue, we spit on you,
you stand for plunder, you will go under." Brief for Respondent 3.
For none of these acts was he arrested or prosecuted; it was only
when he proceeded to burn publicly an American flag stolen from its
rightful owner that he violated the Texas statute.
The Court could not, and did not, say that Chaplinsky's
utterances were not expressive phrases -- they clearly and
succinctly conveyed an extremely low opinion of the addressee. The
same may be said of Johnson's public burning of the flag in this
case; it obviously did convey Johnson's bitter dislike of his
country. But his act, like Chaplinsky's provocative words, conveyed
nothing that could not have been conveyed and was not conveyed just
as forcefully in a dozen different ways. As with "fighting words,"
so with flag burning, for purposes of the First Amendment: It
is
"no essential part of any exposition of ideas, and [is] of such
slight social value as a step to truth that any benefit that may be
derived from [it] is clearly outweighed"
by the public interest in avoiding a probable breach of the
peace. The highest courts of several States have upheld state
statutes prohibiting the public burning of the flag on the grounds
that it is so inherently inflammatory that it may cause a breach of
public order. See, e.g., State v. Royal, 113 N. H. 224,
229, 305 A.2d 676, 680 (1973); State v.
Waterman, 190 N.W.2d 809 ,
811-812 (Iowa 1971); see also State v. Mitchell, 32 Ohio
App.2d 16, 30, 288 N.E.2d 216, 226 (1972). Page 491 U. S. 432 The result of the Texas statute is obviously to deny one in
Johnson's frame of mind one of many means of "symbolic speech." Far
from being a case of "one picture being worth a thousand words,"
flag burning is the equivalent of an inarticulate grunt or roar
that, it seems fair to say, is most likely to be indulged in not to
express any particular idea, but to antagonize others. Only five
years ago we said in City Council of Los Angeles v. Taxpayers
for Vincent, 466 U. S. 789 , 466 U. S. 812 (1984), that "the First Amendment does not guarantee the right to
employ every conceivable method of communication at all times and
in all places." The Texas statute deprived Johnson of only one
rather inarticulate symbolic form of protest -- a form of protest
that was profoundly offensive to many -- and left him with a full
panoply of other symbols and every conceivable form of verbal
expression to express his deep disapproval of national policy.
Thus, in no way can it be said that Texas is punishing him because
his hearers -- or any other group of people -- were profoundly
opposed to the message that he sought to convey. Such opposition is
no proper basis for restricting speech or expression under the
First Amendment. It was Johnson's use of this particular symbol,
and not the idea that he sought to convey by it or by his many
other expressions, for which he was punished.
Our prior cases dealing with flag desecration statutes have left
open the question that the Court resolves today. In Street v.
New York, 394 U. S. 576 , 394 U. S. 579 (1969), the defendant burned a flag in the street, shouting "We
don't need no damned flag" and, "[i]f they let that happen to
Meredith, we don't need an American flag." The Court ruled that
since the defendant might have been convicted solely on the basis
of his words, the conviction could not stand, but it expressly
reserved the question whether a defendant could constitutionally be
convicted for burning the flag. Id. at 394 U. S.
581 .
Chief Justice Warren, in dissent, stated:
"I believe that the States and Federal Government do have the
power to protect the flag from acts of desecration and disgrace. .
. . [I]t is difficult Page 491 U. S. 433 for me to imagine that, had the Court faced this issue, it would
have concluded otherwise." Id. at 394 U. S. 605 .
Justices Black and Fortas also expressed their personal view that a
prohibition on flag burning did not violate the Constitution. See id. at 394 U. S. 610 (Black, J., dissenting) ("It passes my belief that anything in the
Federal Constitution bars a State from making the deliberate
burning of the American Flag an offense"); id. at 394 U. S.
615 -617 (Fortas, J., dissenting) ("[T]he States and the
Federal Government have the power to protect the flag from acts of
desecration committed in public. . . . [T]he flag is a special kind
of personality. Its use is traditionally and universally subject to
special rules and regulation. . . . A person may own' a flag,
but ownership is subject to special burdens and responsibilities. A
flag may be property, in a sense; but it is property burdened with
peculiar obligations and restrictions. Certainly . . . these
special conditions are not per se arbitrary or beyond
governmental power under our Constitution"). In Spence v. Washington, 418 U.
S. 405 (1974), the Court reversed the conviction of a
college student who displayed the flag with a peace symbol affixed
to it by means of removable black tape from the window of his
apartment. Unlike the instant case, there was no risk of a breach
of the peace, no one other than the arresting officers saw the
flag, and the defendant owned the flag in question. The Court
concluded that the student's conduct was protected under the First
Amendment, because
"no interest the State may have in preserving the physical
integrity of a privately owned flag was significantly impaired on
these facts." Id. at 418 U. S. 415 .
The Court was careful to note, however, that the defendant "was not
charged under the desecration statute, nor did he permanently
disfigure the flag or destroy it." Ibid. In another related case, Smith v. Goguen, 415 U.
S. 566 (1974), the appellee, who wore a small flag on
the seat of his trousers, was convicted under a Massachusetts flag
misuse statute that subjected to criminal liability anyone who Page 491 U. S. 434 publicly. . . treats contemptuously the flag of the United
States." Id. at 415 U. S.
568 -569. The Court affirmed the lower court's reversal
of appellee's conviction, because the phrase "treats
contemptuously" was unconstitutionally broad and vague. Id. at 415 U. S. 576 .
The Court was again careful to point out that
"[c]ertainly nothing prevents a legislature from defining with
substantial specificity what constitutes forbidden treatment of
United States flags." Id. at 415 U. S.
581 -582. See also id. at 415 U. S. 587 (WHITE, J., concurring in judgment) ("The flag is a national
property, and the Nation may regulate those who would make,
imitate, sell, possess, or use it. I would not question those
statutes which proscribe mutilation, defacement, or burning of the
flag or which otherwise protect its physical integrity, without
regard to whether such conduct might provoke violence. . . . There
would seem to be little question about the power of Congress to
forbid the mutilation of the Lincoln Memorial. . . . The flag is
itself a monument, subject to similar protection"); id. at 415 U. S. 591 (BLACKMUN, J., dissenting) ("Goguen's punishment was
constitutionally permissible for harming the physical integrity of
the flag by wearing it affixed to the seat of his pants").
But the Court today will have none of this. The uniquely deep
awe and respect for our flag felt by virtually all of us are
bundled off under the rubric of "designated symbols," ante at 491 U. S. 417 ,
that the First Amendment prohibits the government from
"establishing." But the government has not "established" this
feeling; 200 years of history have done that. The government is
simply recognizing as a fact the profound regard for the American
flag created by that history when it enacts statutes prohibiting
the disrespectful public burning of the flag.
The Court concludes its opinion with a regrettably patronizing
civics lecture, presumably addressed to the Members of both Houses
of Congress, the members of the 48 state legislatures that enacted
prohibitions against flag burning, and the troops fighting under
that flag in Vietnam who objected to its Page 491 U. S. 435 being burned:
"The way to preserve the flag's special role is not to punish
those who feel differently about these matters. It is to persuade
them that they are wrong." Ante at 491 U. S. 419 .
The Court's role as the final expositor of the Constitution is well
established, but its role as a platonic guardian admonishing those
responsible to public opinion as if they were truant schoolchildren
has no similar place in our system of government. The cry of "no
taxation without representation" animated those who revolted
against the English Crown to found our Nation -- the idea that
those who submitted to government should have some say as to what
kind of laws would be passed. Surely one of the high purposes of a
democratic society is to legislate against conduct that is regarded
as evil and profoundly offensive to the majority of people --
whether it be murder, embezzlement, pollution, or flagburning.
Our Constitution wisely places limits on powers of legislative
majorities to act, but the declaration of such limits by this Court
"is, at all times, a question of much delicacy, which ought seldom,
if ever, to be decided in the affirmative, in a doubtful case." Fletcher v.
Peck , 6 Cranch 87, 10 U. S. 128 (1810) (Marshall, C.J.). Uncritical extension of constitutional
protection to the burning of the flag risks the frustration of the
very purpose for which organized governments are instituted. The
Court decides that the American flag is just another symbol, about
which not only must opinions pro and con be tolerated, but for
which the most minimal public respect may not be enjoined. The
government may conscript men into the Armed Forces where they must
fight and perhaps die for the flag, but the government may not
prohibit the public burning of the banner under which they fight. I
would uphold the Texas statute as applied in this case. [ Footnote 2/2 ] Page 491 U. S. 436 [ Footnote 2/1 ] See Ala.Code § 13A-11-12 (1982); Ariz.Rev.Stat.Ann. §
13-3703 (1978); Ark.Code Ann. § 5-51-207 (1987); Cal.Mil. &
Vet.Code Ann. § 614 (West 1988); Colo.Rev.Stat. § 18-11-204 (1986);
Conn.Gen.Stat. § 53-258a (1985); Del.Code Ann., Tit. 11, § 1331
(1987); Fla.Stat. §§ 256.05-256.051 (1987); Fla.Stat. § 876.52
(1987); Ga.Code Ann. § 50-3-9 (1986); Haw. Rev.Stat. § 711-1107
(1988); Idaho Code § 18-3401 (1987); Ill.Rev.Stat., ch. 1, �� 3307,
3351 (1980); Ind.Code § 35-45-1-4 (1986); Iowa Code § 32.1 (1978
and Supp.1989); Kan.Stat.Ann. § 21-4114 (1988); Ky.Rev.Stat.Ann. §
525.110 (Michie Supp.1988); La.Rev.Stat.Ann. § 14:116 (West 1986);
Me.Rev.Stat.Ann., Tit. 1, § 254 (1979); Md.Ann. Code, Art. 27, § 83
(1988); Mass.Gen.Laws §§ 264, 265 (1987); Mich.Comp.Laws § 750.246
(1968); Minn.Stat. § 609.40 (1987); Miss.Code Ann. § 97-7-39
(1973); Mo.Rev.Stat. § 578.095 (Supp.1989); Mont.Code Ann. §
45-8-215 (1987); Neb.Rev.Stat. § 28-928 (1985); Nev.Rev.Stat. §
201.290 (1986); N.H.Rev.Stat.Ann. § 646.1 (1986); N.J.Stat.Ann. §
2C:33-9 (West 1982); N.M.Stat.Ann. § 30-21-4 (1984);
N.Y.Gen.Bus.Law § 136 (McKinney 1988); N.C.Gen.Stat. § 14-381
(1986); N.D.Cent.Code § 12.1-07-02 (1985); Ohio Rev.Code Ann. §
2927.11 (1987); Okla.Stat., Tit. 21, § 372 (1983); Ore.Rev.Stat. §
166.075 (1987); 18 Pa.Cons.Stat. § 2102 (1983); R.I.Gen.Laws §
11-15-2 (1981); S.C.Code §§ 16-17-220, 16-17-230 (1985 and
Supp.1988); S.D.Codified Laws § 22-9-1 (1988); Tenn.Code Ann. §§
39-5-843, 39-5-847 (1982); Tex.Penal Code Ann. § 42.09 (1974); Utah
Code Ann. § 76-9-601 (1978); Vt.Stat.Ann., Tit. 13, § 1903 (1974);
Va.Code § 18.2-488 (1988); Wash.Rev.Code § 9.86.030 (1988); W.Va.
Code § 61-1-8 (1989); Wis.Stat. § 946.05 (1985-1986).
[ Footnote 2/2 ]
In holding that the Texas statute as applied to Johnson violates
the First Amendment, the Court does not consider Johnson's claims
that the statute is unconstitutionally vague or overbroad. Brief
for Respondent 24-30. I think those claims are without merit. In New York State Club Assn. v. City of New York, 487 U. S. 1 , 487 U. S. 11 (1988), we stated that a facial challenge is only proper under the
First Amendment when a statute can never be applied in a
permissible manner or when, even if it may be validly applied to a
particular defendant, it is so broad as to reach the protected
speech of third parties. While Tex.Penal Code Ann. § 42.09
(1989)
"may not satisfy those intent on finding fault at any cost, [it
is] set out in terms that the ordinary person exercising ordinary
common sense can sufficiently understand and comply with." CSC Letter Carriers, 413 U. S. 548 413 U. S. 579 (1973). By defining "desecrate" as "deface," "damage" or otherwise
"physically mistreat" in a manner that the actor knows will
"seriously offend" others, § 42.09 only prohibits flagrant acts of
physical abuse and destruction of the flag of the sort at issue
here -- soaking a flag with lighter fluid and igniting it in public
-- and not any of the examples of improper flag etiquette cited in
respondent's brief.
JUSTICE STEVENS, dissenting.
As the Court analyzes this case, it presents the question
whether the State of Texas, or indeed the Federal Government, has
the power to prohibit the public desecration of the American flag.
The question is unique. In my judgment, rules that apply to a host
of other symbols, such as state flags, armbands, or various
privately promoted emblems of political or commercial identity, are
not necessarily controlling. Even if flagburning could be
considered just another species of symbolic speech under the
logical application of the rules that the Court has developed in
its interpretation of the First Amendment in other contexts, this
case has an intangible dimension that makes those rules
inapplicable.
A country's flag is a symbol of more than "nationhood and
national unity." Ante at 491 U. S. 407 , 491 U. S. 410 , 491 U. S. 413 ,
and n. 9, 491 U. S. 417 , 491 U. S. 420 .
It also signifies the ideas that characterize the society that has
chosen that emblem as well as the special history that has animated
the growth and power of those ideas. The fleurs-de-lis and
the tricolor both symbolized "nationhood and national unity," but
they had vastly different meanings. The message conveyed by some
flags -- the swastika, for example -- may survive long after it has
outlived its usefulness as a symbol of regimented unity in a
particular nation. Page 491 U. S. 437 So it is with the American flag. It is more than a proud symbol
of the courage, the determination, and the gifts of nature that
transformed 13 fledgling Colonies into a world power. It is a
symbol of freedom, of equal opportunity, of religious tolerance,
and of goodwill for other peoples who share our aspirations. The
symbol carries its message to dissidents both at home and abroad
who may have no interest at all in our national unity or
survival.
The value of the flag as a symbol cannot be measured. Even so, I
have no doubt that the interest in preserving that value for the
future is both significant and legitimate. Conceivably, that value
will be enhanced by the Court's conclusion that our national
commitment to free expression is so strong that even the United
States, as ultimate guarantor of that freedom, is without power to
prohibit the desecration of its unique symbol. But I am
unpersuaded. The creation of a federal right to post bulletin
boards and graffiti on the Washington Monument might enlarge the
market for free expression, but at a cost I would not pay.
Similarly, in my considered judgment, sanctioning the public
desecration of the flag will tarnish its value -- both for those
who cherish the ideas for which it waves and for those who desire
to don the robes of martyrdom by burning it. That tarnish is not
justified by the trivial burden on free expression occasioned by
requiring that an available, alternative mode of expression --
including uttering words critical of the flag, see Street v.
New York, 394 U. S. 576 (1969) -- be employed.
It is appropriate to emphasize certain propositions that are not
implicated by this case. The statutory prohibition of flag
desecration does not
"prescribe what shall be orthodox in politics, nationalism,
religion, or other matters of opinion or force citizens to confess
by word or act their faith therein." West Virginia Board of Education v. Barnette, 319 U. S. 624 , 319 U. S. 642 (1943). The statute does not compel any conduct or any profession
of respect for any idea or any symbol. Page 491 U. S. 438 Nor does the statute violate "the government's paramount
obligation of neutrality in its regulation of protected
communication." Young v. American Mini Theatres, Inc., 427 U. S. 50 , 427 U. S. 70 (1976) (plurality opinion). The content of respondent's message has
no relevance whatsoever to the case. The concept of "desecration"
does not turn on the substance of the message the actor intends to
convey, but rather on whether those who view the act will
take serious offense. Accordingly, one intending to convey a
message of respect for the flag by burning it in a public square
might nonetheless be guilty of desecration if he knows that others
-- perhaps simply because they misperceive the intended message --
will be seriously offended. Indeed, even if the actor knows that
all possible witnesses will understand that he intends to send a
message of respect, he might still be guilty of desecration if he
also knows that this understanding does not lessen the offense
taken by some of those witnesses. Thus, this is not a case in which
the fact that "it is the speaker's opinion that gives offense"
provides a special "reason for according it constitutional
protection," FCC v. Pacifica Foundation, 438 U.
S. 726 , 438 U. S. 745 (1978) (plurality opinion). The case has nothing to do with
"disagreeable ideas," see ante at 491 U. S. 409 .
It involves disagreeable conduct that, in my opinion, diminishes
the value of an important national asset.
The Court is therefore quite wrong in blandly asserting that
respondent
"was prosecuted for his expression of dissatisfaction with the
policies of this country, expression situated at the core of our
First Amendment values." Ante at 491 U. S. 411 .
Respondent was prosecuted because of the method he chose to express
his dissatisfaction with those policies. Had he chosen to
spraypaint -- or perhaps convey with a motion picture projector --
his message of dissatisfaction on the facade of the Lincoln
Memorial, there would be no question about the power of the
Government to prohibit his means of expression. The prohibition
would be supported by the legitimate interest in preserving the
quality of an important Page 491 U. S. 439 national asset. Though the asset at stake in this case is
intangible, given its unique value, the same interest supports a
prohibition on the desecration of the American flag. * The ideas of liberty and equality have been an irresistible
force in motivating leaders like Patrick Henry, Susan B. Anthony,
and Abraham Lincoln, schoolteachers like Nathan Hale and Booker T.
Washington, the Philippine Scouts who fought at Bataan, and the
soldiers who scaled the bluff at Omaha Beach. If those ideas are
worth fighting for -- and our history demonstrates that they are --
it cannot be true that the flag that uniquely symbolizes their
power is not itself worthy of protection from unnecessary
desecration.
I respectfully dissent.
* The Court suggests that a prohibition against flag desecration
is not content-neutral, because this form of symbolic speech is
only used by persons who are critical of the flag or the ideas it
represents. In making this suggestion, the Court does not pause to
consider the far-reaching consequences of its introduction of
disparate-impact analysis into our First Amendment jurisprudence.
It seems obvious that a prohibition against the desecration of a
gravesite is content-neutral even if it denies some protesters the
right to make a symbolic statement by extinguishing the flame in
Arlington Cemetery where John F. Kennedy is buried while permitting
others to salute the flame by bowing their heads. Few would doubt
that a protester who extinguishes the flame has desecrated the
gravesite, regardless of whether he prefaces that act with a speech
explaining that his purpose is to express deep admiration or
unmitigated scorn for the late President. Likewise, few would claim
that the protester who bows his head has desecrated the gravesite,
even if he makes clear that his purpose is to show disrespect. In
such a case, as in a flag burning case, the prohibition against
desecration has absolutely nothing to do with the content of the
message that the symbolic speech is intended to convey. | Here is a summary of the case:
In *Texas v. Johnson*, the Supreme Court ruled that flag burning is a form of protected expression under the First Amendment. The case involved a political protest during the 1984 Republican National Convention, where the respondent, Gregory Lee Johnson, burned an American flag to express his dissatisfaction with the Reagan administration's policies. Johnson was initially convicted of desecrating a venerated object under Texas law. However, the Texas Court of Criminal Appeals reversed the conviction, holding that the state could not criminalize flag burning as a means of preserving national unity or preventing breaches of the peace.
The Supreme Court agreed with the Texas Court of Criminal Appeals and held that Johnson's conviction for flag desecration violated the First Amendment. The Court found that Johnson's act of flag burning was intentional political expression and that Texas's interest in preserving the flag as a symbol of national unity was insufficient to justify restricting such expression. The Court also rejected the argument that flag burning could be prohibited to prevent breaches of the peace, noting that the Texas statute was not narrowly tailored to achieve that goal and that another statute already prohibited such disturbances.
In his dissent, Justice Kennedy argued that the majority opinion failed to recognize the unique value of the American flag as a national asset and that its desecration could be prohibited to preserve its symbolic power. He compared flag burning to defacing a national monument, such as the Lincoln Memorial, which would also be considered a form of protected expression under the majority's reasoning. |
Free Speech | Hazelwood School District v. Kuhlmeier | https://supreme.justia.com/cases/federal/us/484/260/ | U.S. Supreme Court Hazelwood Sch. Dist. v. Kuhlmeier, 484
U.S. 260 (1988) Hazelwood School District v.
Kuhlmeier No. 86-836 Argued October 13,
1987 Decided January 13,
1988 484
U.S. 260 ON WRIT OF CERTIORARI TO THE UNITED
STATES COURT OF APPEALS FOR THE EIGHTH
CIRCUIT Syllabus Respondents, former high school students who were staff members
of the school's newspaper, filed suit in Federal District Court
against petitioners, the school district and school officials,
alleging that respondents' First Amendment rights were violated by
the deletion from a certain issue of the paper of two pages that
included an article describing school students' experiences with
pregnancy and another article discussing the impact of divorce on
students at the school. The newspaper was written and edited by a
journalism class, as part of the school's curriculum. Pursuant to
the school's practice, the teacher in charge of the paper submitted
page proofs to the school's principal, who objected to the
pregnancy story because the pregnant students, although not named,
might be identified from the text, and because he believed that the
article's references to sexual activity and birth control were
inappropriate for some of the younger students. The principal
objected to the divorce article because the page proofs he was
furnished identified by name (deleted by the teacher from the final
version) a student who complained of her father's conduct, and the
principal believed that the student's parents should have been
given an opportunity to respond to the remarks or to consent to
their publication. Believing that there was no time to make
necessary changes in the articles if the paper was to be issued
before the end of the school year, the principal directed that the
pages on which they appeared be withheld from publication even
though other, unobjectionable articles were included on such pages.
The District Court held that no First Amendment violation had
occurred. The Court of Appeals reversed. Held: Respondents' First Amendment rights were not
violated.
(a) First Amendment rights of students in the public schools are
not automatically coextensive with the rights of adults in other
settings, and must be applied in light of the special
characteristics of the school environment. A school need not
tolerate student speech that is inconsistent with its basic
educational mission, even though the government could not censor
similar speech outside the school.
(b) The school newspaper here cannot be characterized as a forum
for public expression. School facilities may be deemed to be public
forums Page 484 U. S. 261 only if school authorities have, by policy or by practice,
opened the facilities for indiscriminate use by the general public,
or by some segment of the public, such as student organizations. If
the facilities have instead been reserved for other intended
purposes, communicative or otherwise, then no public forum has been
created, and school officials may impose reasonable restrictions on
the speech of students, teachers, and other members of the school
community. The school officials in this case did not deviate from
their policy that the newspaper's production was to be part of the
educational curriculum and a regular classroom activity under the
journalism teacher's control as to almost every aspect of
publication. The officials did not evince any intent to open the
paper's pages to indiscriminate use by its student reporters and
editors, or by the student body generally. Accordingly, school
officials were entitled to regulate the paper's contents in any
reasonable manner.
(c) The standard for determining when a school may punish
student expression that happens to occur on school premises is not
the standard for determining when a school may refuse to lend its
name and resources to the dissemination of student expression. Tinker v. Des Moines Independent Community School Dist., 393 U. S. 503 ,
distinguished. Educators do not offend the First Amendment by
exercising editorial control over the style and content of student
speech in school-sponsored expressive activities, so long as their
actions are reasonably related to legitimate pedagogical
concerns.
(d) The school principal acted reasonably in this case in
requiring the deletion of the pregnancy article, the divorce
article, and the other articles that were to appear on the same
pages of the newspaper.
795 F.2d 1368, reversed.
WHITE, J., delivered the opinion of the Court, in which
REHNQUIST, C.J., and STEVENS, O'CONNOR, and SCALIA, JJ., joined.
BRENNAN, J., filed a dissenting opinion, in which MARSHALL and
BLACKMUN, JJ., joined, post, p. 484 U. S.
277 . Page 484 U. S. 262 JUSTICE WHITE delivered the opinion of the Court.
This case concerns the extent to which educators may exercise
editorial control over the contents of a high school newspaper
produced as part of the school's journalism curriculum. I Petitioners are the Hazelwood School District in St. Louis
County, Missouri; various school officials; Robert Eugene Reynolds,
the principal of Hazelwood East High School; and Howard Emerson, a
teacher in the school district. Respondents are three former
Hazelwood East students who were staff members of Spectrum, the
school newspaper. They contend that school officials violated their
First Amendment rights by deleting two pages of articles from the
May 13, 1983, issue of Spectrum.
Spectrum was written and edited by the Journalism II class at
Hazelwood East. The newspaper was published every three weeks or so
during the 1982-1983 school year. More than 4,500 copies of the
newspaper were distributed during that year to students, school
personnel, and members of the community.
The Board of Education allocated funds from its annual budget
for the printing of Spectrum. These funds were supplemented by
proceeds from sales of the newspaper. The printing expenses during
the 1982-1983 school year totaled $4,668.50; revenue from sales was
$1,166.84. The other costs associated with the newspaper -- such as
supplies, textbooks, Page 484 U. S. 263 and a portion of the journalism teacher's salary -- were borne
entirely by the Board.
The Journalism II course was taught by Robert Stergos for most
of the 1982-1983 academic year. Stergos left Hazelwood East to take
a job in private industry on April 29, 1983, when the May 13
edition of Spectrum was nearing completion, and petitioner Emerson
took his place as newspaper adviser for the remaining weeks of the
term.
The practice at Hazelwood East during the spring 1983 semester
was for the journalism teacher to submit page proofs of each
Spectrum issue to Principal Reynolds for his review prior to
publication. On May 10, Emerson delivered the proofs of the May 13
edition to Reynolds, who objected to two of the articles scheduled
to appear in that edition. One of the stories described three
Hazelwood East students' experiences with pregnancy; the other
discussed the impact of divorce on students at the school.
Reynolds was concerned that, although the pregnancy story used
false names "to keep the identity of these girls a secret," the
pregnant students still might be identifiable from the text. He
also believed that the article's references to sexual activity and
birth control were inappropriate for some of the younger students
at the school. In addition, Reynolds was concerned that a student
identified by name in the divorce story had complained that her
father "wasn't spending enough time with my mom, my sister and I"
prior to the divorce, "was always out of town on business or out
late playing cards with the guys," and "always argued about
everything" with her mother. App. to Pet. for Cert. 38. Reynolds
believed that the student's parents should have been given an
opportunity to respond to these remarks, or to consent to their
publication. He was unaware that Emerson had deleted the student's
name from the final version of the article.
Reynolds believed that there was no time to make the necessary
changes in the stories before the scheduled press run, Page 484 U. S. 264 and that the newspaper would not appear before the end of the
school year if printing were delayed to any significant extent. He
concluded that his only options under the circumstances were to
publish a four-page newspaper instead of the planned six-page
newspaper, eliminating the two pages on which the offending stories
appeared, or to publish no newspaper at all. Accordingly, he
directed Emerson to withhold from publication the two pages
containing the stories on pregnancy and divorce. [ Footnote 1 ] He informed his superiors of the
decision, and they concurred.
Respondents subsequently commenced this action in the United
States District Court for the Eastern District of Missouri, seeking
a declaration that their First Amendment rights had been violated,
injunctive relief, and monetary damages. After a bench trial, the
District Court denied an injunction, holding that no First
Amendment violation had occurred. 607 F.
Supp. 1450 (1985).
The District Court concluded that school officials may impose
restraints on students' speech in activities that are " an
integral part of the school's educational function'" -- including
the publication of a school-sponsored newspaper by a journalism
class -- so long as their decision has "`a substantial and
reasonable basis.'" Id. at 1466 (quoting Frasca v.
Andrews, 463
F. Supp. 1043 , 1052 (EDNY 1979)). The court found that
Principal Reynolds' concern that the pregnant students' anonymity
would be lost and their privacy invaded was "legitimate and
reasonable," given "the small number of pregnant students at
Hazelwood East and several identifying characteristics that were
disclosed in the article." 607 F. Supp. at 1466. The court held
that Reynolds' action was also justified "to avoid the impression
that [the school] endorses Page 484 U. S. 265 the sexual norms of the subjects" and to shield younger students
from exposure to unsuitable material. Ibid. The deletion
of the article on divorce was seen by the court as a reasonable
response to the invasion of privacy concerns raised by the named
student's remarks. Because the article did not indicate that the
student's parents had been offered an opportunity to respond to her
allegations, said the court, there was cause for
"serious doubt that the article complied with the rules of
fairness which are standard in the field of journalism and which
were covered in the textbook used in the Journalism II class." Id. at 1467. Furthermore, the court concluded that
Reynolds was justified in deleting two full pages of the newspaper,
instead of deleting only the pregnancy and divorce stories or
requiring that those stories be modified to address his concerns,
based on his
"reasonable belief that he had to make an immediate decision and
that there was no time to make modifications to the articles in
question." Id. at 1466.
The Court of Appeals for the Eighth Circuit reversed. 795 F.2d
1368 (1986). The court held at the outset that Spectrum was not
only "a part of the school adopted curriculum," id. at
1373, but also a public forum, because the newspaper was "intended
to be and operated as a conduit for student viewpoint." Id. at 1372. The court then concluded that Spectrum's
status as a public forum precluded school officials from censoring
its contents except when " necessary to avoid material and
substantial interference with school work or discipline . . . or
the rights of others.'" Id. at 1374 (quoting Tinker v.
Des Moines Independent Community School Dist., 393 U.
S. 503 , 393 U. S. 511 (1969)). The Court of Appeals found
"no evidence in the record that the principal could have
reasonably forecast that the censored articles or any materials in
the censored articles would have materially disrupted classwork or
given rise to substantial disorder in the school."
795 F.2d at 1375. School officials were entitled to censor the
articles on the ground that Page 484 U. S. 266 they invaded the rights of others, according to the court, only
if publication of the articles could have resulted in tort
liability to the school. The court concluded that no tort action
for libel or invasion of privacy could have been maintained against
the school by the subjects of the two articles or by their
families. Accordingly, the court held that school officials had
violated respondents' First Amendment rights by deleting the two
pages of the newspaper.
We granted certiorari, 479 U.S. 1053 (1987), and we now
reverse. II Students in the public schools do not "shed their constitutional
rights to freedom of speech or expression at the schoolhouse gate." Tinker, supra, at 393 U. S. 506 . They cannot be punished merely for
expressing their personal views on the school premises -- whether
"in the cafeteria, or on the playing field, or on the campus during
the authorized hours," 393 U.S. at 393 U. S.
512 -513 -- unless school authorities have reason to
believe that such expression will "substantially interfere with the
work of the school or impinge upon the rights of other students." Id. at 393 U. S.
509 .
We have nonetheless recognized that the First Amendment rights
of students in the public schools "are not automatically
coextensive with the rights of adults in other settings," Bethel School District No. 403 v. Fraser, 478 U.
S. 675 , 403 U. S. 682 (1986), and must be "applied in light of the special
characteristics of the school environment." Tinker, supra, at 393 U. S. 506 ; cf. New Jersey v. T.L.O., 469 U.
S. 325 , 469 U. S.
341 -343 (1985). A school need not tolerate student
speech that is inconsistent with its "basic educational mission," Fraser, supra, at 478 U. S. 685 , even though the government could not
censor similar speech outside the school. Accordingly, we held in Fraser that a student could be disciplined for having
delivered a speech that was "sexually explicit" but not legally
obscene at an official school assembly, because the school was
entitled to "disassociate itself " from the speech in a manner Page 484 U. S. 267 that would demonstrate to others that such vulgarity is "wholly
inconsistent with the fundamental values' of public school
education." 478 U.S. at 478 U. S.
685 -686. We thus recognized that "[t]he determination of
what manner of speech in the classroom or in school assembly is
inappropriate properly rests with the school board," id. at 478 U. S. 683 ,
rather than with the federal courts. It is in this context that
respondents' First Amendment claims must be considered. A We deal first with the question whether Spectrum may
appropriately be characterized as a forum for public expression.
The public schools do not possess all of the attributes of streets,
parks, and other traditional public forums that "time out of mind,
have been used for purposes of assembly, communicating thoughts
between citizens, and discussing public questions." Hague v.
CIO, 307 U. S. 496 , 307 U. S. 515 (1939). Cf. Widmar v. Vincent, 454 U.
S. 263 , 454 U. S.
267 -268, n. 5 (1981). Hence, school facilities may be
deemed to be public forums only if school authorities have "by
policy or by practice" opened those facilities "for indiscriminate
use by the general public," Perry Education Assn. v. Perry
Local Educators' Assn., 460 U. S. 37 , 460 U. S. 47 (1983), or by some segment of the public, such as student
organizations. Id. at 460 U. S. 46 , n.
7 (citing Widmar v. Vincent ). If the facilities have
instead been reserved for other intended purposes, "communicative
or otherwise," then no public forum has been created, and school
officials may impose reasonable restrictions on the speech of
students, teachers, and other members of the school community. 460
U.S. at 460 U. S. 46 , n.
7.
"The government does not create a public forum by inaction or by
permitting limited discourse, but only by intentionally opening a
nontraditional forum for public discourse." Cornelius v. NAACP Legal Defense & Educational Fund,
Inc., 473 U. S. 788 , 473 U. S. 802 (1985). Page 484 U. S. 268 The policy of school officials toward Spectrum was reflected in
Hazelwood School Board Policy 348.51 and the Hazelwood East
Curriculum Guide. Board Policy 348.51 provided that
"[s]chool sponsored publications are developed within the
adopted curriculum and its educational implications in regular
classroom activities."
App. 22. The Hazelwood East Curriculum Guide described the
Journalism II course as a "laboratory situation in which the
students publish the school newspaper applying skills they have
learned in Journalism I." Id. at 11. The lessons that were
to be learned from the Journalism II course, according to the
Curriculum Guide, included development of journalistic skills under
deadline pressure, "the legal, moral, and ethical restrictions
imposed upon journalists within the school community," and
"responsibility and acceptance of criticism for articles of
opinion." Ibid. Journalism II was taught by a faculty
member during regular class hours. Students received grades and
academic credit for their performance in the course.
School officials did not deviate in practice from their policy
that production of Spectrum was to be part of the educational
curriculum, and a "regular classroom activit[y]." The District
Court found that Robert Stergos, the journalism teacher during most
of the 1982-1983 school year, "both had the authority to exercise,
and in fact exercised, a great deal of control over Spectrum." 607
F. Supp. at 1453. For example, Stergos selected the editors of the
newspaper, scheduled publication dates, decided the number of pages
for each issue, assigned story ideas to class members, advised
students on the development of their stories, reviewed the use of
quotations, edited stories, selected and edited the letters to the
editor, and dealt with the printing company. Many of these
decisions were made without consultation with the Journalism II
students. The District Court thus found it
"clear that Mr. Stergos was the final authority with respect to
almost every aspect of the production and publication of Spectrum,
including its content." Ibid. Moreover, after Page 484 U. S. 269 each Spectrum issue had been finally approved by Stergos or his
successor, the issue still had to be reviewed by Principal Reynolds
prior to publication. Respondents' assertion that they had believed
that they could publish "practically anything" in Spectrum was
therefore dismissed by the District Court as simply "not credible." Id. at 1456. These factual findings are amply supported by
the record, and were not rejected as clearly erroneous by the Court
of Appeals.
The evidence relied upon by the Court of Appeals in finding
Spectrum to be a public forum, see 795 F.2d at 1372-1373,
is equivocal, at best. For example, Board Policy 348.51, which
stated in part that "[s]chool sponsored student publications will
not restrict free expression or diverse viewpoints within the rules
of responsible journalism," also stated that such publications were
"developed within the adopted curriculum and its educational
implications." App. 22. One might reasonably infer from the full
text of Policy 348.51 that school officials retained ultimate
control over what constituted "responsible journalism" in a
school-sponsored newspaper. Although the Statement of Policy
published in the September 14, 1982, issue of Spectrum declared
that "Spectrum, as a student-press publication, accepts all rights
implied by the First Amendment," this statement, understood in the
context of the paper's role in the school's curriculum, suggests,
at most, that the administration will not interfere with the
students' exercise of those First Amendment rights that attend the
publication of a school-sponsored newspaper. It does not reflect an
intent to expand those rights by converting a curricular newspaper
into a public forum. [ Footnote
2 ] Finally, Page 484 U. S. 270 that students were permitted to exercise some authority over the
contents of Spectrum was fully consistent with the Curriculum Guide
objective of teaching the Journalism II students "leadership
responsibilities as issue and page editors." App. 11. A decision to
teach leadership skills in the context of a classroom activity
hardly implies a decision to relinquish school control over that
activity. In sum, the evidence relied upon by the Court of Appeals
fails to demonstrate the "clear intent to create a public forum," Cornelius, 473 U.S. at 473 U. S. 802 ,
that existed in cases in which we found public forums to have been
created. See id. at 473 U. S.
802 -803 (citing Widmar v. Vincent, 454 U.S. at 454 U. S. 267 ; Madison School District v. Wisconsin Employment Relations
Comm'n, 429 U. S. 167 , 429 U. S. 174 ,
n. 6 (1976); Southeastern Promotions, Ltd. v. Conrad, 420 U. S. 546 , 420 U. S. 555 (1975)). School officials did not evince either "by policy or by
practice," Perry Education Assn., 460 U.S. at 460 U. S. 47 ,
any intent to open the pages of Spectrum to "indiscriminate use," ibid., by its student reporters and editors, or by the
student body generally. Instead, they "reserve[d] the forum for its
intended purpos[e]," id. at 460 U. S. 46 , as
a supervised learning experience for journalism students.
Accordingly, school officials were entitled to regulate the
contents of Spectrum in any reasonable manner. Ibid. It is
this standard, rather than our decision in Tinker, that
governs this case. B The question whether the First Amendment requires a school to
tolerate particular student speech -- the question that we
addressed in Tinker -- is different from the question
whether the First Amendment requires a school affirmatively Page 484 U. S. 271 to promote particular student speech. The former question
addresses educators' ability to silence a student's personal
expression that happens to occur on the school premises. The latter
question concerns educators' authority over school-sponsored
publications, theatrical productions, and other expressive
activities that students, parents, and members of the public might
reasonably perceive to bear the imprimatur of the school. These
activities may fairly be characterized as part of the school
curriculum, whether or not they occur in a traditional classroom
setting, so long as they are supervised by faculty members and
designed to impart particular knowledge or skills to student
participants and audiences. [ Footnote 3 ]
Educators are entitled to exercise greater control over this
second form of student expression to assure that participants learn
whatever lessons the activity is designed to teach, that readers or
listeners are not exposed to material that may be inappropriate for
their level of maturity, and that the views of the individual
speaker are not erroneously attributed to the school. Hence, a
school may, in its capacity as publisher of a school newspaper or
producer of a school play, "disassociate itself," Fraser, 478 U.S. at 478 U. S. 685 ,
not only from speech that would "substantially interfere with [its]
work . . . or impinge upon the rights of other students," Tinker, 393 U.S. at 393 U. S. 509 ,
but also from speech that is, for example, ungrammatical, poorly
written, inadequately researched, biased or prejudiced, vulgar or
profane, or unsuitable for immature audiences. [ Footnote 4 ] A school must be able to set high
standards for Page 484 U. S. 272 the student speech that is disseminated under its auspices --
standards that may be higher than those demanded by some newspaper
publishers or theatrical producers in the "real" world -- and may
refuse to disseminate student speech that does not meet those
standards. In addition, a school must be able to take into account
the emotional maturity of the intended audience in determining
whether to disseminate student speech on potentially sensitive
topics, which might range from the existence of Santa Claus in an
elementary school setting to the particulars of teenage sexual
activity in a high school setting. A school must also retain the
authority to refuse to sponsor student speech that might reasonably
be perceived to advocate drug or alcohol use, irresponsible sex, or
conduct otherwise inconsistent with "the shared values of a
civilized social order," Fraser, supra, at 478 U. S. 683 ,
or to associate the school with any position other than neutrality
on matters of political controversy. Otherwise, the schools would
be unduly constrained from fulfilling their role as
"a principal instrument in awakening the child to cultural
values, in preparing him for later professional training, and in
helping him to adjust normally to his environment." Brown v. Board of Education, 347 U.
S. 483 , 347 U. S. 493 (1954).
Accordingly, we conclude that the standard articulated in Tinker for determining when a school may punish student
expression need not also be the standard for determining when a
school may refuse to lend its name and resources to the
dissemination Page 484 U. S. 273 of student expression. [ Footnote
5 ] Instead, we hold that educators do not offend the First
Amendment by exercising editorial control over the style and
content of student speech in school-sponsored expressive
activities, so long as their actions are reasonably related to
legitimate pedagogical concerns. [ Footnote 6 ]
This standard is consistent with our oft-expressed view that the
education of the Nation's youth is primarily the responsibility of
parents, teachers, and state and local school officials, and not of
federal judges. See, e.g., Board of Education of Hendrick
Hudson Central School Dist. v. Rowley, 458 U.
S. 176 , 458 U. S. 208 (1982); Wood v. Strickland, 420 U.
S. 308 , 420 U. S. 326 (1975); Epperson v. Arkansas, 393 U. S.
97 , 393 U. S. 104 (1968). It is only when the decision to censor a school-sponsored
publication, theatrical production, or other vehicle of student
expression has no valid educational purpose that the First
Amendment is so "directly and sharply implicate[d]," ibid., as to require judicial intervention to protect
students' constitutional rights. [ Footnote 7 ] Page 484 U. S. 274 III We also conclude that Principal Reynolds acted reasonably in
requiring the deletion from the May 13 issue of Spectrum of the
pregnancy article, the divorce article, and the remaining articles
that were to appear on the same pages of the newspaper.
The initial paragraph of the pregnancy article declared that
"[a]ll names have been changed to keep the identity of these girls
a secret." The principal concluded that the students' anonymity was
not adequately protected, however, given the other identifying
information in the article and the small number of pregnant
students at the school. Indeed, a teacher at the school credibly
testified that she could positively identify at least one of the
girls, and possibly all three. It is likely that many students at
Hazelwood East would have been at least as successful in
identifying the girls. Reynolds therefore could reasonably have
feared that the article violated whatever pledge of anonymity had
been given to the pregnant students. In addition, he could
reasonably have been concerned that the article was not
sufficiently sensitive to the privacy interests of the students'
boyfriends and parents, who were discussed in the article but who
were given no opportunity to consent to its publication or to offer
a response. The article did not contain graphic accounts of sexual
activity. The girls did comment in the article, however, concerning
their sexual histories and their use or nonuse of birth control. It
was not unreasonable for the principal to have concluded that such
frank talk was inappropriate in a school-sponsored publication
distributed to 14-year-old freshmen Page 484 U. S. 275 and presumably taken home to be read by students' even younger
brothers and sisters.
The student who was quoted by name in the version of the divorce
article seen by Principal Reynolds made comments sharply critical
of her father. The principal could reasonably have concluded that
an individual publicly identified as an inattentive parent --
indeed, as one who chose "playing cards with the guys" over home
and family -- was entitled to an opportunity to defend himself as a
matter of journalistic fairness. These concerns were shared by both
of Spectrum's faculty advisers for the 1982-1983 school year, who
testified that they would not have allowed the article to be
printed without deletion of the student's name. [ Footnote 8 ]
Principal Reynolds testified credibly at trial that, at the time
that he reviewed the proofs of the May 13 issue during an extended
telephone conversation with Emerson, he believed that there was no
time to make any changes in the articles, and that the newspaper
had to be printed immediately or not at all. It is true that
Reynolds did not verify whether the necessary modifications could
still have been made in the articles, and that Emerson did not
volunteer the information that printing could be delayed until the
changes were made. We nonetheless agree with the District Court
that the decision to excise the two pages containing the
problematic articles was reasonable, given the particular
circumstances of this case. These circumstances included the very
recent Page 484 U. S. 276 replacement of Stergos by Emerson, who may not have been
entirely familiar with Spectrum editorial and production
procedures, and the pressure felt by Reynolds to make an immediate
decision so that students would not be deprived of the newspaper
altogether.
In sum, we cannot reject as unreasonable Principal Reynolds'
conclusion that neither the pregnancy article nor the divorce
article was suitable for publication in Spectrum. Reynolds could
reasonably have concluded that the students who had written and
edited these articles had not sufficiently mastered those portions
of the Journalism II curriculum that pertained to the treatment of
controversial issues and personal attacks, the need to protect the
privacy of individuals whose most intimate concerns are to be
revealed in the newspaper, and "the legal, moral, and ethical
restrictions imposed upon journalists within [a] school community"
that includes adolescent subjects and readers. Finally, we conclude
that the principal's decision to delete two pages of Spectrum,
rather than to delete only the offending articles or to require
that they be modified, was reasonable under the circumstances as he
understood them. Accordingly, no violation of First Amendment
rights occurred. [ Footnote
9 ]
The judgment of the Court of Appeals for the Eighth Circuit is
therefore Reversed. Page 484 U. S. 277 [ Footnote 1 ]
The two pages deleted from the newspaper also contained articles
on teenage marriage, runaways, and juvenile delinquents, as well as
a general article on teenage pregnancy. Reynolds testified that he
had no objection to these articles, and that they were deleted only
because they appeared on the same pages as the two objectionable
articles.
[ Footnote 2 ]
The Statement also cited Tinker v. Des Moines Independent
Community School Dist., 393 U. S. 503 (1969), for the proposition that
"[o]nly speech that 'materially and substantially interferes
with the requirements of appropriate discipline' can be found
unacceptable and therefore be prohibited."
App. 26. This portion of the Statement does not, of course, even
accurately reflect our holding in Tinker. Furthermore, the
Statement nowhere expressly extended the Tinker standard
to the news and feature articles contained in a school-sponsored
newspaper. The dissent apparently finds as a fact that the
Statement was published annually in Spectrum; however, the District
Court was unable to conclude that the Statement appeared on more
than one occasion. In any event, even if the Statement says what
the dissent believes that it says, the evidence that school
officials never intended to designate Spectrum as a public forum
remains overwhelming.
[ Footnote 3 ]
The distinction that we draw between speech that is sponsored by
the school and speech that is not is fully consistent with Papish v. University of Missouri Board of Curators, 410 U. S. 667 (1973) (per curiam), which involved an off-campus "underground"
newspaper that school officials merely had allowed to be sold on a
state university campus.
[ Footnote 4 ]
The dissent perceives no difference between the First Amendment
analysis applied in Tinker and that applied in Fraser. We disagree. The decision in Fraser rested on the "vulgar," "lewd," and "plainly offensive" character
of a speech delivered at an official school assembly, rather than
on any propensity of the speech to "materially disrup[t] classwork
or involv[e] substantial disorder or invasion of the rights of
others." 393 U.S. at 393 U. S. 513 .
Indeed, the Fraser Court cited as "especially relevant" a
portion of Justice Black's dissenting opinion in Tinker "'disclaim[ing] any purpose . . . to hold that the Federal
Constitution compels the teachers, parents, and elected school
officials to surrender control of the American public school system
to public school students.'"
478 U.S. at 478 U. S. 686 (quoting 393 U.S. at 393 U. S.
526 ). Of course, Justice Black's observations are
equally relevant to the instant case.
[ Footnote 5 ]
We therefore need not decide whether the Court of Appeals
correctly construed Tinker as precluding school officials
from censoring student speech to avoid "invasion of the rights of
others," 393 U.S. at 393 U. S. 513 ,
except where that speech could result in tort liability to the
school.
[ Footnote 6 ]
We reject respondents' suggestion that school officials be
permitted to exercise prepublication control over school-sponsored
publications only pursuant to specific written regulations. To
require such regulations in the context of a curricular activity
could unduly constrain the ability of educators to educate. We need
not now decide whether such regulations are required before school
officials may censor publications not sponsored by the school that
students seek to distribute on school grounds. See Baughman v.
Freienmuth, 478 F.2d 1345 (CA4 1973); Shanley v. Northeast
Independent School Dist., Bexar Cty., Tex., 462 F.2d 960 (CA5
1972); Eisner v. Stamford Board of Education, 440 F.2d 803
(CA2 1971).
[ Footnote 7 ]
A number of lower federal courts have similarly recognized that
educators' decisions with regard to the content of school-sponsored
newspapers, dramatic productions, and other expressive activities
are entitled to substantial deference. See, e.g., Nicholson v.
Board of Education, Torrance Unified School Dist., 682 F.2d
858 (CA9 1982); Seyfried v. Walton, 668 F.2d 214 (CA3
1981); Trachtman v. Anker, 563 F.2d 512 (CA2 1977), cert. denied, 435 U.S. 925 (1978); Frasca v.
Andrews, 463 F.
Supp. 1043 (EDNY 1979). We need not now decide whether the same
degree of deference is appropriate with respect to school-sponsored
expressive activities at the college and university level.
[ Footnote 8 ]
The reasonableness of Principal Reynolds' concerns about the two
articles was further substantiated by the trial testimony of Martin
Duggan, a former editorial page editor of the St. Louis Globe
Democrat and a former college journalism instructor and newspaper
adviser. Duggan testified that the divorce story did not meet
journalistic standards of fairness and balance because the father
was not given an opportunity to respond, and that the pregnancy
story was not appropriate for publication in a high school
newspaper because it was unduly intrusive into the privacy of the
girls, their parents, and their boyfriends. The District Court
found Duggan to be "an objective and independent witness" whose
testimony was entitled to significant weight. 607 F.
Supp. 1450 , 1461 (ED Mo.1985).
[ Footnote 9 ]
It is likely that the approach urged by the dissent would, as a
practical matter, have far more deleterious consequences for the
student press than does the approach that we adopt today. The
dissent correctly acknowledges "[t]he State's prerogative to
dissolve the student newspaper entirely." Post at 484 U. S. 287 .
It is likely that many public schools would do just that rather
than open their newspapers to all student expression that does not
threaten "materia[l] disrup[tion of] classwork" or violation of
"rights that are protected by law," post at 484 U. S. 289 ,
regardless of how sexually explicit, racially intemperate, or
personally insulting that expression otherwise might be.
JUSTICE BRENNAN, with whom JUSTICE MARSHALL and JUSTICE BLACKMUN
join, dissenting.
When the young men and women of Hazelwood East High School
registered for Journalism II, they expected a civics lesson.
Spectrum, the newspaper they were to publish,
"was not just a class exercise in which students learned to
prepare papers and hone writing skills, it was a . . . forum
established to give students an opportunity to express their views
while gaining an appreciation of their rights and responsibilities
under the First Amendment to the United States Constitution. . .
."
795 F.2d 1368, 1373 (CA8 1986). "[A]t the beginning of each
school year," id. at 1372, the student journalists
published a Statement of Policy -- tacitly approved each year by
school authorities -- announcing their expectation that
" Spectrum, as a student-press publication, accepts all
rights implied by the First Amendment. . . . Only speech that
'materially and substantially interferes with the requirements of
appropriate discipline' can be found unacceptable and therefore
prohibited."
App. 26 (quoting Tinker v. Des Moines Independent Community
School Dist., 393 U. S. 503 , 393 U. S. 513 (1969)). [ Footnote 2/1 ] The school
board itself affirmatively guaranteed the students of Journalism II
an atmosphere conducive to fostering such an appreciation and
exercising the full panoply of rights associated with a free
student press. "School-sponsored student publications," it vowed,
"will not restrict free expression or diverse viewpoints within the
rules of responsible journalism." App. 22 (Board Policy
348.51). Page 484 U. S. 278 This case arose when the Hazelwood East administration breached
its own promise, dashing its students' expectations. The school
principal, without prior consultation or explanation, excised six
articles -- comprising two full pages -- of the May 13, 1983, issue
of Spectrum. He did so not because any of the articles would
"materially and substantially interfere with the requirements of
appropriate discipline," but simply because he considered two of
the six "inappropriate, personal, sensitive, and unsuitable" for
student consumption. 795 F.2d at 1371.
In my view, the principal broke more than just a promise. He
violated the First Amendment's prohibitions against censorship of
any student expression that neither disrupts classwork nor invades
the rights of others, and against any censorship that is not
narrowly tailored to serve its purpose. I Public education serves vital national interests in preparing
the Nation's youth for life in our increasingly complex society and
for the duties of citizenship in our democratic Republic. See
Brown v. Board of Education, 347 U. S. 483 , 347 U. S. 493 (1954). The public school conveys to our young the information and
tools required not merely to survive in, but to contribute to,
civilized society. It also inculcates in tomorrow's leaders the
"fundamental values necessary to the maintenance of a democratic
political system. . . ." Ambach v. Norwick, 441 U. S.
68 , 441 U. S. 77 (1979). All the while, the public educator nurtures students'
social and moral development by transmitting to them an official
dogma of " community values.'" Board of Education v.
Pico, 457 U. S. 853 , 457 U. S. 864 (1982) (plurality opinion) (citation omitted). The public educator's task is weighty and delicate indeed. It
demands particularized and supremely subjective choices among
diverse curricula, moral values, and political stances to teach or
inculcate in students, and among various methodologies for doing
so. Accordingly, we have traditionally reserved Page 484 U. S. 279 the "daily operation of school systems" to the States and their
local school boards. Epperson v. Arkansas, 393 U. S.
97 , 393 U. S. 104 (1968); see Board of Education v. Pico, supra, at 457 U. S.
863 -864. We have not, however, hesitated to intervene
where their decisions run afoul of the Constitution. See e.g.,
Edwards v. Aguillard, 482 U. S. 578 (1987) (striking state statute that forbade teaching of evolution
in public school unless accompanied by instruction on theory of
"creation science"); Board of Education v. Pico, supra, (school board may not remove books from library shelves merely
because it disapproves of ideas they express); Epperson v.
Arkansas, supra, (striking state law prohibition against
teaching Darwinian theory of evolution in public school); West
Virginia Board of Education v. Barnette, 319 U.
S. 624 (1943) (public school may not compel student to
salute flag); Meyer v. Nebraska, 262 U.
S. 390 (1923) (state law prohibiting the teaching of
foreign languages in public or private schools is
unconstitutional).
Free student expression undoubtedly sometimes interferes with
the effectiveness of the school's pedagogical functions. Some
brands of student expression do so by directly preventing the
school from pursuing its pedagogical mission: the young polemic who
stands on a soapbox during calculus class to deliver an eloquent
political diatribe interferes with the legitimate teaching of
calculus. And the student who delivers a lewd endorsement of a
student government candidate might so extremely distract an
impressionable high school audience as to interfere with the
orderly operation of the school. See Bethel School Dist. No.
403 v. Fraser, 478 U. S. 675 (1986). Other student speech, however, frustrates the school's
legitimate pedagogical purposes merely by expressing a message that
conflicts with the school's, without directly interfering with the
school's expression of its message: a student who responds to a
political science teacher's question with the retort, "socialism is
good," subverts the school's inculcation of the message that
capitalism is better. Page 484 U. S. 280 Even the maverick who sits in class passively sporting a symbol
of protest against a government policy, cf. Tinker v. Des
Moines Independent Community School Dist., 393 U.
S. 503 (1969), or the gossip who sits in the student
commons swapping stories of sexual escapade could readily muddle a
clear official message condoning the government policy or
condemning teenage sex. Likewise, the student newspaper that, like
Spectrum, conveys a moral position at odds with the school's
official stance might subvert the administration's legitimate
inculcation of its own perception of community values.
If mere incompatibility with the school's pedagogical message
were a constitutionally sufficient justification for the
suppression of student speech, school officials could censor each
of the students or student organizations in the foregoing
hypotheticals, converting our public schools into "enclaves of
totalitarianism," id. at 393 U. S. 511 ,
that "strangle the free mind at its source," West Virginia
Board of Education v. Barnette, supra, at 319 U. S. 637 .
The First Amendment permits no such blanket censorship authority.
While the "constitutional rights of students in public school are
not automatically coextensive with the rights of adults in other
settings," Fraser, supra, at 478 U. S. 682 ,
students in the public schools do not "shed their constitutional
rights to freedom of speech or expression at the schoolhouse gate," Tinker, supra, at 393 U. S. 506 . Just as the public on the street corner
must, in the interest of fostering "enlightened opinion," Cantwell v. Connecticut, 310 U. S. 296 , 310 U. S. 310 (1940), tolerate speech that "tempt[s] [the listener] to throw [the
speaker] off the street," id. at 310 U. S. 309 ,
public educators must accommodate some student expression even if
it offends them or offers views or values that contradict those the
school wishes to inculcate.
In Tinker, this Court struck the balance. We held that
official censorship of student expression -- there the suspension
of several students until they removed their armbands protesting
the Vietnam war -- is unconstitutional unless the Page 484 U. S. 281 speech "materially disrupts classwork or involves substantial
disorder or invasion of the rights of others. . . . " 393 U.S. at 393 U. S. 513 .
School officials may not suppress "silent, passive expression of
opinion, unaccompanied by any disorder or disturbance on the part
of" the speaker. Id. at 393 U. S. 508 .
The "mere desire to avoid the discomfort and unpleasantness that
always accompany an unpopular viewpoint," id. at 393 U. S. 509 ,
or an unsavory subject, Fraser, supra, at 478 U. S.
688 -689 (BRENNAN, J., concurring in judgment), does not
justify official suppression of student speech in the high
school.
This Court applied the Tinker test just a Term ago in Fraser, supra, upholding an official decision to
discipline a student for delivering a lewd speech in support of a
student government candidate. The Court today casts no doubt on Tinker's vitality. Instead, it erects a taxonomy of school
censorship, concluding that Tinker applies to one
category, and not another. On the one hand is censorship "to
silence a student's personal expression that happens to occur on
the school premises." Ante at 484 U. S. 271 .
On the other hand is censorship of expression that arises in the
context of "school-sponsored . . . expressive activities that
students, parents, and members of the public might reasonably
perceive to bear the imprimatur of the school." Ibid. The Court does not, for it cannot, purport to discern from our
precedents the distinction it creates. One could, I suppose,
readily characterize the students' symbolic speech in Tinker as "personal expression that happens to [have]
occur[red] on school premises," although Tinker did not
even hint that the personal nature of the speech was of any (much
less dispositive) relevance. But that same description could not,
by any stretch of the imagination, fit Fraser's speech. He did not
just "happen" to deliver his lewd speech to an ad hoc gathering on the playground. As the second paragraph of Fraser evinces, if ever a forum for student expression was
"school-sponsored," Fraser's was: Page 484 U. S. 282 "Fraser . . . delivered a speech nominating a fellow student for
student elective office. Approximately 600 high school students . .
. attended the assembly. Students were required to attend the
assembly or to report to the study hall. The assembly was part of a school-sponsored educational program in
self-government." Fraser, 478 U.S. at 478 U. S. 677 (emphasis added). Yet, from the first sentence of its analysis, see id. at 478 U. S. 680 ,
Fraser faithfully applied Tinker. Nor has this Court ever intimated a distinction between personal
and school-sponsored speech in any other context. Particularly
telling is this Court's heavy reliance on Tinker in two
cases of First Amendment infringement on state college campuses. See Papish v. University of Missouri Board of Curators, 410 U. S. 667 , 410 U. S. 671 ,
n. 6 (1973) (per curiam); Healy v. James, 408 U.
S. 169 , 408 U. S. 180 , 408 U. S. 189 ,
and n. 18, 408 U. S. 191 (1972). One involved the expulsion of a student for lewd expression
in a newspaper that she sold on campus pursuant to university
authorization, see Papish, supra, at 410 U. S. 667 -668,
and the other involved the denial of university recognition and
concomitant benefits to a political student organization, see
Healy, supra, at 408 U. S. 174 , 408 U. S. 176 , 408 U. S.
181 -182. Tracking Tinker's analysis, the Court
found each act of suppression unconstitutional. In neither case did
this Court suggest the distinction, which the Court today finds
dispositive, between school-sponsored and incidental student
expression. II Even if we were writing on a clean slate, I would reject the
Court's rationale for abandoning Tinker in this case. The
Court offers no more than an obscure tangle of three excuses to
afford educators "greater control" over school-sponsored speech
than the Tinker test would permit: the public educator's
prerogative to control curriculum; the pedagogical interest in
shielding the high school audience from objectionable viewpoints
and sensitive topics; and the school's need Page 484 U. S. 283 to dissociate itself from student expression. Ante at 484 U. S. 271 .
None of the excuses, once disentangled, supports the distinction
that the Court draws. Tinker fully addresses the first
concern; the second is illegitimate; and the third is readily
achievable through less oppressive means. A The Court is certainly correct that the First Amendment permits
educators "to assure that participants learn whatever lessons the
activity is designed to teach. . . ." Ante at 484 U. S. 271 .
That is, however, the essence of the Tinker test, not an
excuse to abandon it. Under Tinker, school officials may
censor only such student speech as would "materially disrup[t]" a
legitimate curricular function. Manifestly, student speech is more
likely to disrupt a curricular function when it arises in the
context of a curricular activity -- one that "is designed to teach"
something -- than when it arises in the context of a noncurricular
activity. Thus, under Tinker, the school may
constitutionally punish the budding political orator if he disrupts
calculus class, but not if he holds his tongue for the cafeteria. See Consolidated Edison Co. v. Public Service Comm'n of New
York, 447 U. S. 530 , 447 U. S.
544 -545 (1980) (STEVENS, J., concurring in judgment).
That is not because some more stringent standard applies in the
curricular context. (After all, this Court applied the same
standard whether the students in Tinker wore their
armbands to the "classroom" or the "cafeteria." 393 U.S. at 393 U. S.
512 .) It is because student speech in the noncurricular
context is less likely to disrupt materially any legitimate
pedagogical purpose.
I fully agree with the Court that the First Amendment should
afford an educator the prerogative not to sponsor the publication
of a newspaper article that is "ungrammatical, poorly written,
inadequately researched, biased or prejudiced," or that falls short
of the "high standards for . . . student speech that is
disseminated under [the school's] auspices. . . ." Ante at 484 U. S.
271 -272. But we need not abandon Tinker Page 484 U. S. 284 to reach that conclusion; we need only apply it. The enumerated
criteria reflect the skills that the curricular newspaper "is
designed to teach." The educator may, under Tinker, constitutionally "censor" poor grammar, writing, or research,
because to reward such expression would "materially disrup[t]" the
newspaper's curricular purpose.
The same cannot be said of official censorship designed to
shield the audience or dissociate the sponsor from the expression. Censorship so motivated might well serve
(although, as I demonstrate infra at 484 U. S.
285 -289, cannot legitimately serve) some other school
purpose. But it in no way furthers the curricular purposes of a
student newspaper unless one believes that the purpose of
the school newspaper is to teach students that the press ought
never report bad news, express unpopular views, or print a thought
that might upset its sponsors. Unsurprisingly, Hazelwood East
claims no such pedagogical purpose.
The Court relies on bits of testimony to portray the principal's
conduct as a pedagogical lesson to Journalism II students who
"had not sufficiently mastered those portions of the . . .
curriculum that pertained to the treatment of controversial issues
and personal attacks, the need to protect the privacy of
individuals . . . and 'the legal, moral, and ethical restrictions
imposed upon journalists. . . .'" Ante at 484 U. S. 276 .
In that regard, the Court attempts to justify censorship of the
article on teenage pregnancy on the basis of the principal's
judgment that (1) "the [pregnant] students' anonymity was not
adequately protected," despite the article's use of aliases; and
(2) the judgment that "the article was not sufficiently sensitive
to the privacy interests of the students' boyfriends and parents. .
. ." Ante at 484 U. S. 274 .
Similarly, the Court finds in the principal's decision to censor
the divorce article a journalistic lesson that the author should
have given the father of one student an "opportunity to defend
himself" against her charge that (in the Court's words) he
"chose Page 484 U. S. 285 playing cards with the guys' over home and family. . . ." Ante at 484 U. S.
275 . But the principal never consulted the students before censoring
their work. "[T]hey learned of the deletions when the paper was
released. . . ." 795 F.2d at 1371. Further, he explained the
deletions only in the broadest of generalities. In one meeting
called at the behest of seven protesting Spectrum staff members
(presumably a fraction of the full class), he characterized the
articles as " too sensitive' for `our immature audience of
readers,'" 607 F.
Supp. 1450 , 1459 (ED Mo.1985), and in a later meeting he deemed
them simply "inappropriate, personal, sensitive and unsuitable for
the newspaper," ibid. The Court's supposition that the
principal intended (or the protesters understood) those
generalities as a lesson on the nuances of journalistic
responsibility is utterly incredible. If he did, a fact that
neither the District Court nor the Court of Appeals found, the
lesson was lost on all but the psychic Spectrum staffer. B The Court's second excuse for deviating from precedent is the
school's interest in shielding an impressionable high school
audience from material whose substance is "unsuitable for immature
audiences." Ante at 484 U. S. 271 (footnote omitted). Specifically, the majority decrees that we must
afford educators authority to shield high school students from
exposure to "potentially sensitive topics" (like "the particulars
of teenage sexual activity") or unacceptable social viewpoints
(like the advocacy of "irresponsible se[x] or conduct otherwise
inconsistent with the shared values of a civilized social
order'") through school-sponsored student activities. Ante at 484 U. S. 272 (citation omitted). Tinker teaches us that the state educator's undeniable,
and undeniably vital, mandate to inculcate moral and political
values is not a general warrant to act as "thought police" stifling
discussion of all but state-approved topics and advocacy of all Page 484 U. S. 286 but the official position. See also Epperson v.
Arkansas, 393 U. S. 97 (1968); Meyer v. Nebraska, 262 U.
S. 390 (1923). Otherwise, educators could transform
students into "closed-circuit recipients of only that which the
State chooses to communicate," Tinker, 393 U.S. at 393 U. S. 511 ,
and cast a perverse and impermissible "pall of orthodoxy over the
classroom," Keyishian v. Board of Regents, 385 U.
S. 589 , 385 U. S. 603 (1967). Thus, the State cannot constitutionally prohibit its high
school students from recounting in the locker room "the particulars
of [their] teen-age sexual activity," nor even from advocating
"irresponsible se[x]" or other presumed abominations of "the shared
values of a civilized social order." Even in its capacity as
educator, the State may not assume an Orwellian "guardianship of
the public mind," Thomas v. Collins, 323 U.
S. 516 , 323 U. S. 545 (1945) (Jackson, J., concurring).
The mere fact of school sponsorship does not, as the Court
suggests, license such thought control in the high school, whether
through school suppression of disfavored viewpoints or through
official assessment of topic sensitivity. [ Footnote 2/2 ] The former would constitute unabashed and
unconstitutional viewpoint Page 484 U. S. 287 discrimination, see Board of Education v. Pico, 457
U.S. at 457 U. S.
878 -879 (BLACKMUN, J., concurring in part and concurring
in judgment), as well as an impermissible infringement of the
students' " right to receive information and ideas,'" id. at 457 U. S. 867 (plurality opinion) (citations omitted); see First National
Bank v. Bellotti, 435 U. S. 765 , 435 U. S. 783 (1978). [ Footnote 2/3 ] Just as a
school board may not purge its state-funded library of all books
that "`offen[d] [its] social, political and moral tastes,'" 457
U.S. at 457 U. S.
858 -859 (plurality opinion) (citation omitted), school
officials may not, out of like motivation, discriminatorily excise
objectionable ideas from a student publication. The State's
prerogative to dissolve the student newspaper entirely (or to limit
its subject matter) no more entitles it to dictate which viewpoints
students may express on its pages than the State's prerogative to
close down the schoolhouse entitles it to prohibit the
nondisruptive expression of antiwar sentiment within its
gates. Official censorship of student speech on the ground that it
addresses "potentially sensitive topics" is, for related reasons,
equally impermissible. I would not begrudge an educator the
authority to limit the substantive scope of a school-sponsored
publication to a certain, objectively definable topic, such as
literary criticism, school sports, or an overview of the school
year. Unlike those determinate limitations, "potential topic
sensitivity" is a vaporous nonstandard -- like " public welfare,
peace, safety, health, decency, good order, morals or
convenience,'" Shuttlesworth v. Birmingham, 394 U.
S. 147 , 394 U. S. 150 (1969), or "`general welfare of citizens,'" Staub v.
Baxley, 355 U. S. 313 , 355 U. S. 322 (1958) -- that invites manipulation to achieve ends that cannot
permissibly be achieved through blatant viewpoint discrimination
and chills student speech to which school officials might
not Page 484 U. S. 288 object. In part because of those dangers, this Court has
consistently condemned any scheme allowing a state official
boundless discretion in licensing speech from a particular forum. See, e.g., Shuttlesworth v. Birmingham, supra, at 394 U. S.
150 -151, and n. 2; Cox v. Louisiana, 379 U. S. 536 , 379 U. S.
557 -558 (1965); Staub v. Baxley, supra, at 355 U. S.
322 -324.
The case before us aptly illustrates how readily school
officials (and courts) can camouflage viewpoint discrimination as
the "mere" protection of students from sensitive topics. Among the
grounds that the Court advances to uphold the principal's
censorship of one of the articles was the potential sensitivity of
"teenage sexual activity." Ante at 484 U. S. 272 .
Yet the District Court specifically found that the principal "did
not, as a matter of principle, oppose discussion of said topi[c] in
Spectrum." 607 F.
Supp. at 1467 . That much is also clear from the same
principal's approval of the "squeal law" article on the same page,
dealing forthrightly with "teenage sexuality," "the use of
contraceptives by teenagers," and "teenage pregnancy," App. 4-5. If
topic sensitivity were the true basis of the principal's decision,
the two articles should have been equally objectionable. It is much
more likely that the objectionable article was objectionable
because of the viewpoint it expressed: it might have been read (as
the majority apparently does) to advocate "irresponsible sex." See ante at 484 U. S.
272 . C The sole concomitant of school sponsorship that might
conceivably justify the distinction that the Court draws between
sponsored and nonsponsored student expression is the risk "that the
views of the individual speaker [might be] erroneously attributed
to the school." Ante at 484 U. S. 271 .
Of course, the risk of erroneous attribution inheres in any student
expression, including "personal expression" that, like the armbands
in Tinker, "happens to occur on the school premises," ante at 484 U. S. 271 .
Nevertheless, the majority is certainly correct that indicia of
school sponsorship increase the likelihood Page 484 U. S. 289 of such attribution, and that state educators may therefore have
a legitimate interest in dissociating themselves from student
speech.
But
"'[e]ven though the governmental purpose be legitimate and
substantial, that purpose cannot be pursued by means that broadly
stifle fundamental personal liberties when the end can be more
narrowly achieved.'" Keyishian v. Board of Regents, 385 U.S. at 385 U. S. 602 (quoting Shelton v. Tucker, 364 U.
S. 479 , 364 U. S. 488 (1960)). Dissociative means short of censorship are available to
the school. It could, for example, require the student activity to
publish a disclaimer, such as the "Statement of Policy" that
Spectrum published each school year announcing that
"[a]ll . . . editorials appearing in this newspaper reflect the
opinions of the Spectrum staff, which are not necessarily shared by
the administrators or faculty of Hazelwood East,"
App. 26; or it could simply issue its own response clarifying
the official position on the matter and explaining why the student
position is wrong. Yet, without so much as acknowledging the less
oppressive alternatives, the Court approves of brutal
censorship. III Since the censorship served no legitimate pedagogical purpose,
it cannot by any stretch of the imagination have been designed to
prevent "materia[l] disrup[tion of] classwork," Tinker, 393 U.S. at 393 U. S. 513 .
Nor did the censorship fall within the category that Tinker described as necessary to prevent student
expression from "inva[ding] the rights of others," ibid. If that term is to have any content, it must be limited to rights
that are protected by law. "Any yardstick less exacting than [that]
could result in school officials curtailing speech at the slightest
fear of disturbance," 795 F.2d at 1376, a prospect that would be
completely at odds with this Court's pronouncement that the
"undifferentiated fear or apprehension of disturbance is not
enough [even in the public school context] to overcome the right to
freedom of expression. " Page 484 U. S. 290 Tinker, supra, at 393 U. S. 508 .
And, as the Court of Appeals correctly reasoned, whatever
journalistic impropriety these articles may have contained, they
could not conceivably be tortious, much less criminal. See 795 F.2d at 1375-1376
Finally, even if the majority were correct that the principal
could constitutionally have censored the objectionable material, I
would emphatically object to the brutal manner in which he did so.
Where "[t]he separation of legitimate from illegitimate speech
calls for more sensitive tools," Speiser v. Randall, 357 U. S. 513 , 357 U. S. 525 (1958); see Keyishian v. Board of Regents, supra, at 385 U. S. 602 ,
the principal used a paper shredder. He objected to some material
in two articles, but excised six entire articles. He did not so
much as inquire into obvious alternatives, such as precise
deletions or additions (one of which had already been made),
rearranging the layout, or delaying publication. Such unthinking
contempt for individual rights is intolerable from any state
official. It is particularly insidious from one to whom the public
entrusts the task of inculcating in its youth an appreciation for
the cherished democratic liberties that our Constitution
guarantees. IV The Court opens its analysis in this case by purporting to
reaffirm Tinker's time-tested proposition that public
school students "do not shed their constitutional rights to
freedom of speech or expression at the schoolhouse gate.'" Ante at 484 U. S. 266 (quoting Tinker, supra, at 393 U. S.
506 ). That is an ironic introduction to an opinion that
denudes high school students of much of the First Amendment
protection that Tinker itself prescribed. Instead of
"teach[ing] children to respect the diversity of ideas that is
fundamental to the American system," Board of Education v.
Pico, 457 U.S. at 457 U. S. 880 (BLACKMUN, J., concurring in part and concurring in judgment), and
"that our Constitution is a living reality, not parchment preserved
under glass," Shanley v. Northeast Independent School Dist.,
Bexar Cty., Tex., 462 F.2d 960, 972 (CA5 Page 484 U. S. 291 1972), the Court today "teach[es] youth to discount important
principles of our government as mere platitudes." West Virginia
Board of Education v. Barnette, 319 U.S. at 319 U. S. 637 .
The young men and women of Hazelwood East expected a civics lesson,
but not the one the Court teaches them today.
I dissent.
[ Footnote 2/1 ]
The Court suggests that the passage quoted in the text did not
"exten[d] the Tinker standard to the news and feature
articles contained in a school-sponsored newspaper" because the
passage did not expressly mention them. Ante at 484 U. S. 269 , n 2. It is hard to imaging why
the Court (or anyone else) might expect a passage that applies
categorically to "a student-press publication," composed almost
exclusively of "news and feature articles," to mention those
categories expressly. Understandably, neither court below so
limited the passage.
[ Footnote 2/2 ]
The Court quotes language in Bethel School Dist. No. 403 v.
Fraser, 478 U. S. 675 (1986), for the proposition that
"'[t]he determination of what manner of speech in the classroom
or in school assembly is inappropriate properly rests with the
school board.'" Ante at 484 U. S. 267 (quoting 478 U.S. at 478 U. S.
683 ). As the discussion immediately preceding that
quotation makes clear, however, the Court was referring only to the
appropriateness of the manner in which the message is conveyed, not
of the message's content. See, e.g., Fraser, 478 U.S. at 478 U. S. 683 ("[T]he fundamental values necessary to the maintenance of a
democratic political system' disfavor the use of terms of debate
highly offensive or highly threatening to others"). In fact, the Fraser Court coupled its first mention of "society's . . .
interest in teaching students the boundaries of socially
appropriate behavior," with an acknowledgment of "[t]he undoubted
freedom to advocate unpopular and controversial views in schools
and classrooms," id. at 478 U. S. 681 (emphasis added). See also id. at 478 U. S. 689 (BRENNAN, J., concurring in judgment) ("Nor does this case involve
an attempt by school officials to ban written materials they
consider `inappropriate' for high school students" (citation
omitted)). [ Footnote 2/3 ]
Petitioners themselves concede that " [c]ontrol over access'"
to Spectrum is permissible only if "`the distinctions drawn . . .
are viewpoint-neutral.'" Brief for Petitioners 32 (quoting Cornelius v. NAACP Legal Defense & Educational Fund,
Inc., 473 U. S. 788 , 473 U. S. 806 (1985)). | In *Hazelwood School District v. Kuhlmeier*, the US Supreme Court ruled that a school district did not violate the First Amendment rights of student journalists by censoring articles in the school newspaper. The Court held that student speech rights in public schools are not absolute and must be balanced against the school's educational mission. As the newspaper was part of the school curriculum and not a public forum, the school could censor articles deemed inappropriate for younger students or that identified students without their consent. This decision emphasized the school's role in teaching appropriate behavior and respecting student privacy. |
Free Speech | Ward v. Rock Against Racism | https://supreme.justia.com/cases/federal/us/491/781/ | U.S. Supreme Court Ward v. Rock Against Racism, 491
U.S. 781 (1989) Ward v. Rock Against
Racism No. 88-226 Argued February 27,
1989 Decided June 22, 1989 491
U.S. 781 CERTIORARI TO THE UNITED STATES
COURT OF APPEALS FOR THE SECOND CIRCUIT Syllabus Respondent Rock Against Racism (RAR), furnishing its own sound
equipment and technicians, has sponsored yearly programs of rock
music at the Naumberg Acoustic Bandshell in New York City's Central
Park. The city received numerous complaints about excessive noise
at RAR's concerts from users of the nearby Sheep Meadow, an area
designated by the city for passive recreation, from other users of
the park, and from residents of areas adjacent to the park.
Moreover, when the city shut off the power after RAR ignored
repeated requests to lower the volume at one of its concerts, the
audience became abusive and disruptive. The city also experienced
problems at bandshell events put on by other sponsors, who, due to
their use of inadequate sound equipment or sound technicians
unskilled at mixing sound for the bandshell area, were unable to
provide sufficient amplification levels, resulting in disappointed
or unruly audiences. Rejecting various other solutions to the
excessive noise and inadequate amplification problems, the city
adopted a Use Guideline for the bandshell which specified that the
city would furnish high quality sound equipment and retain an
independent, experienced sound technician for all performances.
After the city implemented this guideline, RAR amended a
preexisting District Court complaint against the city to seek
damages and a declaratory judgment striking down the guideline as
facially invalid under the First Amendment. The court upheld the
guideline, finding, inter alia, that performers who had
used the city's sound system and technician had been uniformly
pleased; that, although the city's technician ultimately controlled
both sound volume and mix, the city's practice was to give the
sponsor autonomy as to mix and to confer with him before turning
the volume down; and that the city's amplification system was
sufficient for RAR's needs. Applying this Court's three-part test
for judging the constitutionality of governmental regulation of the
time, place, and manner of protected speech, the court found the
guideline valid. The Court of Appeals reversed on the ground that
such regulations' method and extent must be the least intrusive
upon the freedom of expression as is reasonably necessary to
achieve the regulations' purpose, finding that there were various
less restrictive means by which the city could control excessive
volume without also intruding on RAR's ability to control sound
mix. Page 491 U. S. 782 Held: The city's sound-amplification guideline is valid
under the First Amendment as a reasonable regulation of the place
and manner of protected speech. Pp. 491 U. S.
790 -803.
(a) The guideline is content-neutral, since it is justified
without reference to the content of the regulated speech. The
city's principal justification -- the desire to control noise in
order to retain the sedate character of the Sheep Meadow and other
areas of the park and to avoid intrusion into residential areas --
has nothing to do with content. The city's other justification, its
interest in ensuring sound quality, does not render the guideline
content-based as an attempt to impose subjective standards of
acceptable sound mix on performers, since the city has expressly
disavowed any such intent, and requires its technician to defer to
the sponsor's wishes as to mix. On the record below, the city's
sound quality concern extends only to the clearly content-neutral
goals of ensuring adequate amplification and avoiding volume
problems associated with inadequate mix. There is no merit to RAR's
argument that the guideline is nonetheless invalid on its face
because it places unbridled discretion in the hands of city
enforcement officials. Even granting the doubtful proposition that
this claim falls within the narrow class of permissible facial
challenges to allegedly unconstrained grants of regulatory
authority, the claim nevertheless fails, since the guideline's own
terms in effect forbid officials purposely to select an inadequate
system or to vary sound quality or volume based on the performer's
message. Moreover, the city has applied a narrowing construction to
the guideline by requiring officials to defer to sponsors on sound
quality and confer with them as to volume problems, and by
mandating that amplification be sufficient for the sound to reach
all concert-ground listeners. Pp. 491 U. S.
791 -796.
(b) The guideline is narrowly tailored to serve significant
governmental interests. That the city has a substantial interest in
protecting citizens from unwelcome and excessive noise, even in a
traditional public forum such as the park, cannot be doubted.
Moreover, it has a substantial interest in ensuring the sufficiency
of sound amplification at bandshell events in order to allow
citizens to enjoy the benefits of the park, in light of the
evidence that inadequate amplification had resulted in the
inability of some audiences to hear performances. The Court of
Appeals erred in requiring the city to prove that the guideline was
the least intrusive means of furthering these legitimate interests,
since a "less-restrictive-alternative analysis" has never been --
and is here, again, specifically rejected as -- a part of the
inquiry into the validity of a time, place, or manner regulation. See Clark v. Community for Creative Non-Violence, 468 U. S. 288 , 468 U. S. 293 ; Regan v. Time, Inc., 468 U. S. 641 . The
requirement of narrow tailoring is satisfied so long as the
regulation promotes a substantial governmental interest that would
be Page 491 U. S. 783 achieved less effectively absent the regulation, and the means
chosen are not substantially broader than necessary to achieve that
interest. If these standards are met, courts should defer to the
government's reasonable determination. Here, the city's substantial
interest in limiting sound volume is served in a direct and
effective way by the requirement that its technician control the
mixing board. Absent this requirement, the city's interest would
have been served less well, as is evidenced by the excessive noise
complaints generated by RAR's past concerts. The city also could
reasonably have determined that, overall, its interest in ensuring
that sound amplification was sufficient to reach all concert-ground
listeners would be served less effectively without the guideline
than with it, since, by providing competent technicians and
adequate equipment, the city eliminated inadequate amplification
problems that plagued some performers in the past. Furthermore, in
the absence of evidence that the guideline had a substantial
deleterious effect on the ability of performers to achieve the
quality of sound they desired, there is no merit to RAR's
contention that the guideline is substantially broader than
necessary to achieve the city's legitimate ends. Pp. 491 U. S.
796 -802.
(c) The guideline leaves open ample alternative channels of
communication, since it does not attempt to ban any particular
manner or type of expression at a given place and time. Rather, it
continues to permit expressive activity in the bandshell, and has
no effect on the quantity or content of that expression beyond
regulating the extent of amplification. That the city's volume
limitations may reduce to some degree the potential audience for
RAR's speech is of no consequence, since there has been no showing
that the remaining avenues of communication are inadequate. Pp. 491 U. S.
802 -803.
848 F.2d 367, reversed.
KENNEDY, J., delivered the opinion of the Court, in which
REHNQUIST, C.J., and WHITE, O'CONNOR, and SCALIA, JJ., joined.
BLACKMUN, J., concurred in the result. MARSHALL, J., filed a
dissenting opinion, in which BRENNAN and STEVENS, JJ., joined, post, p. 491 U. S.
803 . Page 491 U. S. 784 JUSTICE KENNEDY delivered the opinion of the Court.
In the southeast portion of New York City's Central Park, about
10 blocks upward from the park's beginning point at 59th Street,
there is an amphitheater and stage structure known as the Naumberg
Acoustic Bandshell. The bandshell faces west across the remaining
width of the park. In close proximity to the bandshell, and lying
within the directional path of its sound, is a grassy open area
called the Sheep Meadow. The city has designated the Sheep Meadow
as a quiet area for passive recreations like reclining, walking,
and reading. Just beyond the park, and also within the potential
sound range of the bandshell, are the apartments and residences of
Central Park West.
This case arises from the city's attempt to regulate the volume
of amplified music at the bandshell so the performances are
satisfactory to the audience without intruding upon those who use
the Sheep Meadow or live on Central Park West and in its
vicinity.
The city's regulation requires bandshell performers to use sound
amplification equipment and a sound technician provided by the
city. The challenge to this volume control technique comes from the
sponsor of a rock concert. The trial court sustained the noise
control measures, but the Court of Appeals for the Second Circuit
reversed. We granted certiorari to resolve the important First
Amendment issues presented by the case. I Rock Against Racism, respondent in this case, is an
unincorporated association which, in its own words, is "dedicated
to the espousal and promotion of antiracist views." App. to Pet.
for Cert. 3. Each year from 1979 through 1986, RAR has sponsored a
program of speeches and rock music at the Page 491 U. S. 785 bandshell. RAR has furnished the sound equipment and sound
technician used by the various performing groups at these annual
events.
Over the years, the city received numerous complaints about
excessive sound amplification at respondent's concerts from park
users and residents of areas adjacent to the park. On some
occasions, RAR was less than cooperative when city officials asked
that the volume be reduced; at one concert, police felt compelled
to cut off the power to the sound system, an action that caused the
audience to become unruly and hostile. App. 127-131, 140-141,
212-214, 345-347.
Before the 1984 concert, city officials met with RAR
representatives to discuss the problem of excessive noise. It was
decided that the city would monitor sound levels at the edge of the
concert-ground, and would revoke respondent's event permit if
specific volume limits were exceeded. Sound levels at the concert
did exceed acceptable levels for sustained periods of time, despite
repeated warnings and requests that the volume be lowered. Two
citations for excessive volume were issued to respondent during the
concert. When the power was eventually shut off, the audience
became abusive and disruptive.
The following year, when respondent sought permission to hold
its upcoming concert at the bandshell, the city declined to grant
an event permit, citing its problems with noise and crowd control
at RAR's previous concerts. The city suggested some other
city-owned facilities as alternative sites for the concert. RAR
declined the invitation, and filed suit in United States District
Court against the city, its mayor, and various police and parks
department officials, seeking an injunction directing issuance of
an event permit. After respondent agreed to abide by all applicable
regulations, the parties reached agreement and a permit was
issued.
The city then undertook to develop comprehensive New York City
Parks Department Use Guidelines for the Naumberg Bandshell. A
principal problem to be addressed by Page 491 U. S. 786 the guidelines was controlling the volume of amplified sound at
bandshell events. A major concern was that, at some bandshell
performances, the event sponsors had been unable to "provide the
amplification levels required and crowds unhappy with the sound
became disappointed or unruly.'" Brief for Petitioners 9. The city
found that this problem had several causes, including inadequate
sound equipment, sound technicians who were either unskilled at
mixing sound outdoors or unfamiliar with the acoustics of the
bandshell and its surroundings, and the like. Because some
performers compensated for poor sound mix by raising volume, these
factors tended to exacerbate the problem of excess noise. [ Footnote 1 ] App. 30, 189,
218-219. The city considered various solutions to the sound amplification
problem. The idea of a fixed decibel limit for all performers using
the bandshell was rejected because the impact on listeners of a
single decibel level is not constant, but varies in response to
changes in air temperature, foliage, audience size, and like
factors. Id. at 31, 220, 285-286. The city also rejected
the possibility of employing a sound technician to operate the
equipment provided by the various sponsors of bandshell events
because the city's technician might have had difficulty satisfying
the needs of sponsors while operating unfamiliar, and perhaps
inadequate, sound equipment. Id. Page 491 U. S. 787 at 220. Instead, the city concluded that the most effective way
to achieve adequate but not excessive sound amplification would be
for the city to furnish high quality sound equipment and retain an
independent, experienced sound technician for all performances at
the bandshell. After an extensive search, the city hired a private
sound company capable of meeting the needs of all the varied users
of the bandshell.
The Use Guidelines were promulgated on March 21, 1986. [ Footnote 2 ] After learning that it
would be expected to comply with the guidelines at its upcoming
annual concert in May, 1986, respondent returned to the District
Court and filed a motion for an injunction against the enforcement
of certain aspects of the guidelines. The District Court
preliminarily enjoined enforcement of the sound amplification rule
on May 1, 1986. See 636 F.
Supp. 178 (SDNY 1986). Under the protection of the injunction,
and alone among users of the bandshell in the 1986 season, RAR was
permitted to use its own sound equipment Page 491 U. S. 788 and technician, just as it had done in prior years. RAR's 1986
concert again generated complaints about excessive noise from park
users and nearby residents. App. 127, 138.
After the concert, respondent amended its complaint to seek
damages and a declaratory judgment striking down the guidelines as
facially invalid. After hearing five days of testimony about
various aspects of the guidelines, the District Court issued its
decision upholding the sound amplification guideline. [ Footnote 3 ] The court found that the
city had been "motivated by a desire to obtain top-flight sound
equipment and experienced operators" in selecting an independent
contractor to provide the equipment and technician for bandshell
events, and that the performers who did use the city's sound system
in the 1986 season, in performances "which ran the full cultural
gamut from grand opera to salsa to reggae," were uniformly pleased
with the quality of the sound provided. 658
F. Supp. 1346 , 1352 (SDNY 1987).
Although the city's sound technician controlled both sound
volume and sound mix by virtue of his position at the mixing board,
the court found that
"[t]he City's practice for events at the Bandshell is to give
the sponsor autonomy with respect to the sound mix: balancing
treble with bass, highlighting a particular instrument or voice,
and the like,"
and that the city's sound technician "does all he can to
accommodate the sponsor's desires in those regards." Ibid. Even with respect to volume control, the city's practice was to
confer with the sponsor before making any decision to turn the
volume down. Ibid. In some instances, as with a New York
Grand Opera performance, the sound technician accommodated the
performers' unique needs by integrating special microphones with
the city's equipment. The Court specifically found that
"[t]he City's implementation of the Bandshell guidelines
provides for a sound amplification system capable of meeting Page 491 U. S. 789 RAR's technical needs and leaves control of the sound 'mix' in
the hands of RAR." Id. at 1353. Applying this Court's three-part test for
judging the constitutionality of government regulation of the time,
place, or manner of protected speech, the court found the city's
regulation valid.
The Court of Appeals reversed. 848 F.2d 367 (CA2 1988). After
recognizing that
"[c]ontent-neutral time, place and manner regulations are
permissible so long as they are narrowly tailored to serve a
substantial government interest and do not unreasonably limit
alternative avenues of expression,"
the court added the proviso that
"the method and extent of such regulation must be reasonable,
that is, it must be the least intrusive upon the freedom of
expression as is reasonably necessary to achieve a legitimate
purpose of the regulation." Id. at 370 (citing United States v. O'Brien, 391 U. S. 367 , 377
(1968)). Applying this test, the court determined that the city's
guideline was valid only to the extent necessary to achieve the
city's legitimate interest in controlling excessive volume, but
found there were various alternative means of controlling volume
without also intruding on respondent's ability to control the sound
mix. For example, the city could have directed respondent's sound
technician to keep the volume below specified levels.
Alternatively, a volume-limiting device could have been installed;
and as a "last resort," the court suggested, "the plug can be
pulled on the sound to enforce the volume limit." 848 F.2d at 372,
n. 6. In view of the potential availability of these seemingly less
restrictive alternatives, the Court of Appeals concluded that the
sound amplification guideline was invalid because the city had
failed to prove that its regulation "was the least intrusive means
of regulating the volume." Id. at 371.
We granted certiorari, 488 U, S. 816 (1988), to clarify the
legal standard applicable to governmental regulation of the time,
place, or manner of protected speech. Because the Court of Appeals
erred in requiring the city to prove that its regulation was the
least intrusive means of furthering its legitimate Page 491 U. S. 790 governmental interests, and because the ordinance is valid on
its face, we now reverse. II Music is one of the oldest forms of human expression. From
Plato's discourse in the Republic to the totalitarian state in our
own times, rulers have known its capacity to appeal to the
intellect and to the emotions, and have censored musical
compositions to serve the needs of the state. See 2
Dialogues of Plato, Republic, bk. 3, pp. 231, 245-248 (B. Jowett
transl., 4th ed.1953) ("Our poets must sing in another and a nobler
strain"); Musical Freedom and Why Dictators Fear It, N.Y. Times,
Aug. 23, 1981, section 2, p. 1, col. 5; Soviet Schizophrenia toward
Stravinsky, N.Y. Times, June 26, 1982, section 1, p. 25, col. 2;
Symphonic Voice from China Is Heard Again, N.Y. Times, Oct. 11,
1987, section 2, p. 27, col. 1. The Constitution prohibits any like
attempts in our own legal order. Music, as a form of expression and
communication, is protected under the First Amendment. In the case
before us, the performances apparently consisted of remarks by
speakers, as well as rock music, but the case has been presented as
one in which the constitutional challenge is to the city's
regulation of the musical aspects of the concert; and, based on the
principle we have stated, the city's guideline must meet the
demands of the First Amendment. The parties do not appear to
dispute that proposition.
We need not here discuss whether a municipality which owns a
bandstand or stage facility may exercise, in some circumstances, a
proprietary right to select performances and control their quality. See Southeastern Promotions, Ltd. v. Conrad, 420 U.
S. 546 , 420 U. S.
570 -574 (1975) (REHNQUIST, J., dissenting). Though it
did demonstrate its own interest in the effort to insure high
quality performances by providing the equipment in question, the
city justifies its guideline as a regulatory measure to limit and
control noise. Here the bandshell was open, apparently, to all
performers; and we decide Page 491 U. S. 791 the case as one in which the bandshell is a public forum for
performances in which the government's right to regulate expression
is subject to the protections of the First Amendment. United
States v. Grace, 461 U. S. 171 , 461 U. S. 177 (1983); see Frisby v. Schultz, 487 U.
S. 474 , 487 U. S. 481 (1988); Perry Education Assn. v. Perry Local Educators'
Assn., 460 U. S. 37 , 460 U. S. 45 (1983). Our cases make clear, however, that even in a public forum,
the government may impose reasonable restrictions on the time,
place, or manner of protected speech, provided the restrictions
"are justified without reference to the content of the regulated
speech, that they are narrowly tailored to serve a significant
governmental interest, and that they leave open ample alternative
channels for communication of the information." Clark v. Community for Creative NonViolence, 468 U. S. 288 , 468 U. S. 293 (1984); see Heffron v. International Society for Krishna
Consciousness, Inc., 452 U. S. 640 , 452 U. S. 648 (1981) (quoting Virginia Pharmacy Bd. v. Virginia Citizens
Consumer Council, Inc., 425 U. S. 748 , 425 U. S. 771 (1976)). We consider these requirements in turn. A The principal inquiry in determining content-neutrality, in
speech cases generally and in time, place, or manner cases in
particular, is whether the government has adopted a regulation of
speech because of disagreement with the message it conveys. Community for Creative Non-Violence, supra, at 468 U. S. 295 .
The government's purpose is the controlling consideration. A
regulation that serves purposes unrelated to the content of
expression is deemed neutral, even if it has an incidental effect
on some speakers or messages, but not others. See Renton v.
Playtime Theatres, Inc., 475 U. S. 41 , 475 U. S. 47 -48
(1986). Government regulation of expressive activity is
content-neutral so long as it is " justified without
reference to the content of the regulated speech." Community
for Creative Non-Violence, supra, at 468 U. S. 293 (emphasis added); Heffron, supra, at 462 U. S. 648 (quoting Virginia Pharmacy Bd., supra, at Page 491 U. S. 792 425 U. S.
771 ); see Boos v. Barry, 485 U.
S. 312 , 485 U. S.
320 -321 (1988) (opinion of O'CONNOR, J.).
The principal justification for the sound amplification
guideline is the city's desire to control noise levels at bandshell
events, in order to retain the character of the Sheep Meadow and
its more sedate activities, and to avoid undue intrusion into
residential areas and other areas of the park. This justification
for the guideline "ha[s] nothing to do with content," Boos v.
Barry, supra, at 485 U. S. 320 ,
and it satisfies the requirement that time, place, or manner
regulations be content-neutral.
The only other justification offered below was the city's
interest in "ensur[ing] the quality of sound at Bandshell events."
658 F. Supp. at 1352; see 848 F.2d at 370, n. 3.
Respondent urges that this justification is not content-neutral,
because it is based upon the quality, and thus the content, of the
speech being regulated. In respondent's view, the city is seeking
to assert artistic control over performers at the bandshell by
enforcing a bureaucratically determined, value-laden conception of
good sound. That all performers who have used the city's sound
equipment have been completely satisfied is of no moment,
respondent argues, because
"[t]he First Amendment does not permit and cannot tolerate state
control of artistic expression merely because the State claims that
[its] efforts will lead to 'top-quality' results."
Brief for Respondent 19.
While respondent's arguments that the government may not
interfere with artistic judgment may have much force in other
contexts, they are inapplicable to the facts of this case. The city
has disclaimed in express terms any interest in imposing its own
view of appropriate sound mix on performers. To the contrary, as
the District Court found, the city requires its sound technician to
defer to the wishes of event sponsors concerning sound mix. 658 F.
Supp. at 1352-1353. On this record, the city's concern with sound
quality extends only to the clearly content-neutral goals of
ensuring adequate Page 491 U. S. 793 sound amplification and avoiding the volume problems associated
with inadequate sound mix. [ Footnote 4 ] Any governmental attempt to serve purely
aesthetic goals by imposing subjective standards of acceptable
sound mix on performers would raise serious First Amendment
concerns, but this case provides us with no opportunity to address
those questions. As related above, the District Court found that
the city's equipment and its sound technician could meet all of the
standards requested by the performers, including RAR.
Respondent argues further that the guideline, even if not
content-based in explicit terms, is nonetheless invalid on its face
because it places unbridled discretion in the hands of city
officials charged with enforcing it. See Lakewood v. Plain
Dealer Publishing Co., 486 U. S. 750 , 486 U. S.
769 -772 (1988) (4-to-3 decision); Heffron v.
International Society for Krishna Consciousness, Inc., supra, at 452 U. S. 649 ; Freedman v. Maryland, 380 U. S. 51 , 380 U. S. 56 (1965); Thornhill v. Alabama, 310 U. S.
88 , 310 U. S. 97 (1940). According to respondent, there is nothing in the language
of the guideline to prevent city officials from selecting wholly
inadequate sound equipment or technicians, or even from varying the
volume and quality of sound based on the message being conveyed by
the performers.
As a threshold matter, it is far from clear that respondent
should be permitted to bring a facial challenge to this aspect of
the regulation. Our cases permitting facial challenges to
regulations that allegedly grant officials unconstrained authority
to regulate speech have generally involved licensing schemes that
"ves[t] unbridled discretion in a government official over whether
to permit or deny expressive activity." Plain Dealer,
supra, at 486 U. S. 755 .
The grant of discretion that respondent Page 491 U. S. 794 seeks to challenge here is of an entirely different, and lesser,
order of magnitude, because respondent does not suggest that city
officials enjoy unfettered discretion to deny bandshell permits
altogether. Rather, respondent contends only that the city, by
exercising what is concededly its right to regulate amplified
sound, could choose to provide inadequate sound for performers
based on the content of their speech. Since respondent does not
claim that city officials enjoy unguided discretion to deny the
right to speak altogether, it is open to question whether
respondent's claim falls within the narrow class of permissible
facial challenges to allegedly unconstrained grants of regulatory
authority. Cf. 486 U.S. at 486 U. S. 787 (WHITE, J., dissenting) (arguing that facial challenges of this
type are permissible only where "the local law at issue require[s]
licenses -- not for a narrow category of expressive conduct that
could be prohibited -- but for a sweeping range of First Amendment
protected activity").
We need not decide, however, whether the "extraordinary
doctrine" that permits facial challenges to some regulations of
expression, see id. at 486 U. S. 772 (WHITE, J., dissenting), should be extended to the circumstances of
this case, for respondent's facial challenge fails on its merits.
The city's guideline states that its goals are to "provide the best
sound for all events" and to
"insure appropriate sound quality balanced with respect for
nearby residential neighbors and the mayorally decreed quiet zone
of [the] Sheep Meadow."
App. 375. While these standards are undoubtedly flexible, and
the officials implementing them will exercise considerable
discretion, perfect clarity and precise guidance have never been
required even of regulations that restrict expressive activity. See Grayned v. City of Rockford, 408 U.
S. 104 , 408 U. S. 110 (1972) ("Condemned to the use of words, we can never expect
mathematical certainty in our language"); see also Kovacs v.
Cooper, 336 U. S. 77 , 336 U. S. 79 (1949) (rejecting vagueness challenge to city ordinance forbidding
"loud and raucous" sound amplification) (opinion of Reed, J.). By
its own terms, the Page 491 U. S. 795 city's sound amplification guideline must be interpreted to
forbid city officials purposely to select inadequate sound systems
or to vary the sound quality or volume based on the message being
delivered by performers. The guideline is not vulnerable to
respondent's facial challenge. [ Footnote 5 ]
Even if the language of the guideline were not sufficient on its
face to withstand challenge, our ultimate conclusion would be the
same, for the city has interpreted the guideline in such a manner
as to provide additional guidance to the officials charged with its
enforcement. The District Court expressly found that the city's
policy is to defer to the sponsor's desires concerning sound
quality. 658 F. Supp. at 1352. With respect to sound volume, the
city retains ultimate control, but city officials "mak[e] it a
practice to confer with the sponsor if any questions of excessive
sound arise, before taking any corrective action." Ibid. The city's goal of ensuring that "the sound amplification [is]
sufficient to reach all listeners within the defined
concert-ground," ibid., serves to limit further the
discretion of the officials on the scene. Administrative
interpretation and implementation of a regulation is, of course,
highly relevant to our analysis, for,
"[i]n evaluating a facial Page 491 U. S. 796 challenge to a state law, a federal court must . . . consider
any limiting construction that a state court or enforcement agency
has proffered." Hoffman Estates v. The Flipside, Hoffman Estates, Inc., 455 U. S. 489 , 455 U. S. 494 ,
n. 5 (1982); see Plain Dealer, 486 U.S. at 486 U. S.
769 -770, and n. 11; United States v. Grace, 461
U.S. at 461 U. S. 181 ,
n. 10; Grayned v. City of Rockford, supra, at 408 U. S. 110 ; Poulos v. New Hampshire, 345 U. S. 395 (1953). Any inadequacy on the face of the guideline would have been
more than remedied by the city's narrowing construction. B The city's regulation is also "narrowly tailored to serve a
significant governmental interest." Community for Creative
Non-Violence, 468 U.S. at 468 U. S. 293 .
Despite respondent's protestations to the contrary, it can no
longer be doubted that government "ha[s] a substantial interest in
protecting its citizens from unwelcome noise." City Council of
Los Angeles v. Taxpayers for Vincent, 466 U.
S. 789 , 466 U. S. 806 (1984) (citing Kovacs v. Cooper, supra ); see Grayned,
supra, at 408 U. S. 116 .
This interest is perhaps at its greatest when government seeks to
protect " the wellbeing, tranquility, and privacy of the home,'" Frisby v. Schultz, 487 U.S. at 487 U. S. 484 (quoting Carey v. Brown, 447 U. S. 455 , 447 U. S. 471 (1980)), but it is by no means limited to that context, for the
government may act to protect even such traditional public forums
as city streets and parks from excessive noise. Kovacs v.
Cooper, 336 U.S. at 336 U. S. 86 -87
(opinion of Reed, J.); id. at 336 U. S. 96 -97
(Frankfurter, J., concurring); id. at 336 U. S. 97 (Jackson, J., concurring); see Community for Creative
Non-Violence, supra, at 468 U. S. 296 (recognizing the government's "substantial interest in maintaining
the parks . . . in an attractive and intact condition, readily
available to the millions of people who wish to see and enjoy
them"). We think it also apparent that the city's interest in ensuring
the sufficiency of sound amplification at bandshell events is a
substantial one. The record indicates that inadequate Page 491 U. S. 797 sound amplification has had an adverse affect on the ability of
some audiences to hear and enjoy performances at the bandshell. The
city enjoys a substantial interest in ensuring the ability of its
citizens to enjoy whatever benefits the city parks have to offer,
from amplified music to silent meditation. See Community for
Creative Non-Violence, supra, at 468 U. S.
296 .
The Court of Appeals recognized the city's substantial interest
in limiting the sound emanating from the bandshell. See 848 F.2d at 370. The court concluded, however, that the city's
sound amplification guideline was not narrowly tailored to further
this interest, because "it has not [been] shown . . . that the
requirement of the use of the city's sound system and technician
was the least intrusive means of regulating the volume." Id. at 371 (emphasis added). In the court's judgment,
there were several alternative methods of achieving the desired end
that would have been less restrictive of respondent's First
Amendment rights.
The Court of Appeals erred in sifting through all the available
or imagined alternative means of regulating sound volume in order
to determine whether the city's solution was "the least intrusive
means" of achieving the desired end. This
"less-restrictive-alternative analysis . . . has never been a
part of the inquiry into the validity of a time, place, and manner
regulation." Regan v. Time, Inc., 468 U. S. 641 , 468 U. S. 657 (1984) (opinion of WHITE, J.). Instead, our cases quite clearly
hold that restrictions on the time, place, or manner of protected
speech are not invalid "simply because there is some imaginable
alternative that might be less burdensome on speech." United
States v. Albertini, 472 U. S. 675 , 472 U. S. 689 (1985).
The Court of Appeals apparently drew its least-intrusive-means
requirement from United States v. O'Brien, 391 U.S. at 391 U. S. 377 ,
the case in which we established the standard for judging the
validity of restrictions on expressive conduct. See 848
F.2d at 370. The court's reliance was misplaced, Page 491 U. S. 798 however, for we have held that the O'Brien test, "in
the last analysis, is little, if any, different from the standard
applied to time, place, or manner restrictions." Community for
Creative Non-Violence, supra, at 468 U. S. 298 .
Indeed, in Community for Creative Non-Violence, we
squarely rejected reasoning identical to that of the court
below:
"We are unmoved by the Court of Appeals' view that the
challenged regulation is unnecessary, and hence invalid, because
there are less speech-restrictive alternatives that could have
satisfied the Government interest in preserving park lands. . . .
We do not believe . . . that either United States v.
O'Brien or the time, place, or manner decisions assign to the
judiciary the authority to replace the [parks department] as the
manager of the [city's] parks or endow the judiciary with the
competence to judge how much protection of park lands is wise and
how that level of conservation is to be attained."
468 U.S. 468 U. S.
299 .
Lest any confusion on the point remain, we reaffirm today that a
regulation of the time, place, or manner of protected speech must
be narrowly tailored to serve the government's legitimate,
content-neutral interests, but that it need not be the least
restrictive or least intrusive means of doing so. [ Footnote 6 ] Page 491 U. S. 799 Rather, the requirement of narrow tailoring is satisfied
"so long as the . . . regulation promotes a substantial
government interest that would be achieved less effectively absent
the regulation." United States v. Albertini, supra, at 472 U. S. 689 ; see also Community for Creative Non-Violence, supra, at 468 U. S. 297 .
To be sure, this standard does not mean that a time, place, or
manner regulation may burden substantially more speech than is
necessary to further the government's legitimate interests.
Government may not regulate expression in such a manner that a
substantial portion of the burden on speech does not serve to
advance its goals. [ Footnote 7 ] See Frisby Page 491 U. S. 800 v. Schultz, 487 U.S. at 487 U. S. 485 ("A complete ban can be narrowly tailored, but only if each
activity within the proscription's scope is an appropriately
targeted evil"). So long as the means chosen are not substantially
broader than necessary to achieve the government's interest,
however, the regulation will not be invalid simply because a court
concludes that the government's interest could be adequately served
by some less-speech-restrictive alternative.
"The validity of [time, place, or manner] regulations does not
turn on a judge's agreement with the responsible decisionmaker
concerning the most appropriate method for promoting significant
government interests"
or the degree to which those interests should be promoted. United States v. Albertini, supra, at 472 U. S. 689 ; see Community for Creative Non-Violence, supra, at 468 U. S.
299 .
It is undeniable that the city's substantial interest in
limiting sound volume is served in a direct and effective way by
the requirement that the city's sound technician control the mixing
board during performances. Absent this requirement, the city's
interest would have been served less well, as is evidenced by the
complaints about excessive volume generated by respondent's past
concerts. The alternative regulatory methods hypothesized by the
Court of Appeals reflect nothing more than a disagreement with the
city over how much control of volume is appropriate or how that
level of control is to be achieved. See Community for Creative
Non-Violence, 468 U.S. at 468 U. S. 299 .
The Court of Appeals erred in failing to defer to the city's
reasonable determination that its interest in controlling volume
would be best served by requiring bandshell performers to utilize
the city's sound technician.
The city's second content-neutral justification for the
guideline, that of ensuring "that the sound amplification [is]
sufficient to reach all listeners within the defined
concert-ground," Page 491 U. S. 801 658 F. Supp. at 1352, also supports the city's choice of
regulatory methods. By providing competent sound technicians and
adequate amplification equipment, the city eliminated the problems
of inexperienced technicians and insufficient sound volume that had
plagued some bandshell performers in the past. No doubt this
concern is not applicable to respondent's concerts, which
apparently were characterized by more-than-adequate sound
amplification. But that fact is beside the point, for the validity
of the regulation depends on the relation it bears to the overall
problem the government seeks to correct, not on the extent to which
it furthers the government's interests in an individual case. Here,
the regulation's effectiveness must be judged by considering all
the varied groups that use the bandshell, and it is valid so long
as the city could reasonably have determined that its interests
overall would be served less effectively without the sound
amplification guideline than with it. United States v.
Albertini, supra, at 472 U. S.
688 -689; Community for Creative Non-Violence,
supra, at 468 U. S.
296 -297. Considering these proffered justifications
together, therefore, it is apparent that the guideline directly
furthers the city's legitimate governmental interests, and that
those interests would have been less well served in the absence of
the sound amplification guideline.
Respondent nonetheless argues that the sound amplification
guideline is not narrowly tailored because, by placing control of
sound mix in the hands of the city's technician, the guideline
sweeps far more broadly than is necessary to further the city's
legitimate concern with sound volume. According to respondent, the
guideline "targets . . . more than the exact source of the evil' it seeks to remedy." Frisby v. Schultz, supra, at 487 U. S.
485 . If the city's regulatory scheme had a substantial deleterious
effect on the ability of bandshell performers to achieve the
quality of sound they desired, respondent's concerns would have
considerable force. The District Court found, Page 491 U. S. 802 however, that, pursuant to city policy, the city's sound
technician
"give[s] the sponsor autonomy with respect to the sound mix . .
. [and] does all that he can to accommodate the sponsor's desires
in those regards."
658 F. Supp. at 1352. The court squarely rejected respondent's
claim that the city's "technician is not able properly to implement
a sponsor's instructions as to sound quality or mix," finding that
"[n]o evidence to that effect was offered at trial; as noted, the
evidence is to the contrary." App. to Pet. for Cert. 89. In view of
these findings, which were not disturbed by the Court of Appeals,
we must conclude that the city's guideline has no material impact
on any performer's ability to exercise complete artistic control
over sound quality. Since the guideline allows the city to control
volume without interfering with the performer's desired sound mix,
it is not "substantially broader than necessary" to achieve the
city's legitimate ends, City Council of Los Angeles v.
Taxpayers Page 491 U. S. 803 for Vincent, 466 U.S. at 466 U. S. 808 ,
and thus it satisfies the requirement of narrow tailoring. C The final requirement, that the guideline leave open ample
alternative channels of communication, is easily met. Indeed, in
this respect the guideline is far less restrictive than regulations
we have upheld in other cases, for it does not attempt to ban any
particular manner or type of expression at a given place or time. Compare Frisby, supra, at 487 U. S.
482 -484; Community for Creative Non-Violence,
supra, at 468 U. S. 295 ; Renton v. Playtime Theatres, Inc., 475 U.S. at 475 U. S. 53 -54.
Rather, the guideline continues to permit expressive activity in
the bandshell, and has no effect on the quantity or content of that
expression beyond regulating the extent of amplification. That the
city's limitations on volume may reduce to some degree the
potential audience for respondent's speech is of no consequence,
for there has been no showing that the remaining avenues of
communication are inadequate. See Taxpayers for Vincent,
supra, at 466 U. S. 803 ,
and n. 23, 466 U. S. 812 ,
and n. 30; Kovacs, 336 U.S. at 336 U. S. 88 -89
(opinion of Reed, J.). III The city's sound amplification guideline is narrowly tailored to
serve the substantial and content-neutral governmental interests of
avoiding excessive sound volume and providing sufficient
amplification within the bandshell concert-ground, and the
guideline leaves open ample channels of communication. Accordingly,
it is valid under the First Amendment as a reasonable regulation of
the place and manner of expression. The judgment of the Court of
Appeals is Reversed. JUSTICE BLACKMUN concurs in the result.
[ Footnote 1 ]
The amplified sound heard at a rock concert consists of two
components, volume and mix. Sound produced by the various
instruments and performers on stage is picked up by microphones and
fed into a central mixing board, where it is combined into one
signal and then amplified through speakers to the audience. A sound
technician is at the mixing board to select the appropriate mix, or
balance, of the various sounds produced on stage, and to add other
effects as desired by the performers. In addition to controlling
the sound mix, the sound technician also controls the overall
volume of sound reaching the audience. During the course of a
performance, the sound technician is continually manipulating
various controls on the mixing board to provide the desired sound
mix and volume. The sound technician thus plays an important role
in determining the quality of the amplified sound that reaches the
audience.
[ Footnote 2 ]
In pertinent part, the Use Guidelines provide:
"SOUND AMPLIFICATION"
"To provide the best sound for all events, Department of Parks
and Recreation has leased a sound amplification system designed for
the specific demands of the Central Park Bandshell. To insure
appropriate sound quality balanced with respect for nearby
residential neighbors and the mayorally decreed quiet zone of Sheep
Meadow, all sponsors may use only the Department of Parks and
Recreation sound system. DEPARTMENT OF PARKS AND RECREATION IS TO
BE THE SOLE AND ONLY PROVIDER OF SOUND AMPLIFICATION, INCLUDING,
THOUGH NOT LIMITED TO, AMPLIFIERS, SPEAKERS, MONITORS, MICROPHONES,
AND PROCESSORS."
"Clarity of sound results from a combination of amplification
equipment and a sound technician's familiarity and proficiency with
that system. Department of Parks and Recreation will employ a
professional sound technician [who] will be fully versed in sound
bounce patterns, daily air currents, and sound skipping within the
Park. The sound technician must also consider the Bandshell's
proximity to Sheep Meadow, activities at Bethesda Terrace, and the
New York City Department of Environmental Protection
recommendations."
App. 375-376.
[ Footnote 3 ]
The court invalidated certain other aspects of the Use
Guidelines, but those provisions are not before us.
[ Footnote 4 ]
As noted above, there is evidence to suggest that volume control
and sound mix are interrelated to a degree, in that performers
unfamiliar with the acoustics of the Bandshell sometimes attempt to
compensate for poor sound mix by increasing volume. App. 218,
290-291. By providing adequate sound equipment and professional
sound mixing, the city avoids this problem.
[ Footnote 5 ]
The dissent's suggestion that the guideline constitutes a prior
restraint is not consistent with our cases. See post at 491 U. S.
808 -809. As we said in Southeastern Promotions, Ltd.
v. Conrad, 420 U. S. 546 (1975), the regulations we have found invalid as prior restraints
have "had this in common: they gave public officials the power to
deny use of a forum in advance of actual expression." Id. at 420 U. S. 553 .
The sound amplification guideline, by contrast, grants no authority
to forbid speech, but merely permits the city to regulate volume to
the extent necessary to avoid excessive noise. It is true that the
city's sound technician theoretically possesses the power to shut
off the volume for any particular performer, but that hardly
distinguishes this regulatory scheme from any other; government
will always possess the raw power to suppress speech
through force, and indeed it was in part to avoid the necessity of
exercising its power to "pull the plug" on the volume that the city
adopted the sound amplification guideline. The relevant question is
whether the challenged regulation authorizes suppression
of speech in advance of its expression, and the sound amplification
guideline does not.
[ Footnote 6 ]
Respondent contends that our decision last Term in Boos v.
Barry, 485 U. S. 312 (1988), supports the conclusion that "a regulation is neither
precisely drawn nor narrowly tailored' if less intrusive means
than those employed are available." Brief for Respondent 27. In Boos, we concluded that the government regulation at issue
was "not narrowly tailored; a less restrictive alternative is
readily available." 485 U.S. at 485 U. S. 329 (citing Wygant v. Jackson Bd. of Ed., 476 U.
S. 267 , 476 U. S. 280 ,
n. 6 (1986) (plurality opinion)). In placing reliance on Boos, however, respondent ignores a crucial difference
between that case and this. The regulation we invalidated in Boos was a content-based ban on displaying signs critical
of foreign governments; such content-based restrictions on
political speech "must be subjected to the most exacting scrutiny."
485 U.S. at 485 U. S. 321 .
While time, place, or manner regulations must also be "narrowly
tailored" in order to survive First Amendment challenge, we have
never applied strict scrutiny in this context. As a result, the
same degree of tailoring is not required of these regulations, and
least-restrictive-alternative analysis is wholly out of place. For
the same reason, the dissent's citation of Richmond v. J. A.
Croson Co., 488 U. S. 469 (1989), is beside the point. See post at 491 U. S. 806 ,
n. 4. Croson, like Boos, is a strict scrutiny
case; even the dissent does not argue that strict scrutiny is
applicable to time, place, or manner regulations. Our summary affirmance of Watseka v. Illinois Public Action
Council, 796 F.2d 1547 (CA7 1986), aff'd, 479 U.S.
1048 (1987), is not to the contrary. Although the Seventh Circuit
in that case did adopt the least-restrictive-alternative approach, see 796 F.2d at 1553-1554, its judgment was also supported
by the alternative grounds that the regulation at issue did not
serve to further the stated governmental interests, and did not
leave open alternative channels of communication. Id. at
1555-1558. As we have noted on more than one occasion:
"A summary disposition affirms only the judgment of the court
below, and no more may be read into our action than was essential
to sustain that judgment." Anderson v. Celebrezze, 460 U.
S. 780 , 460 U. S. 785 ,
n. 5 (1983).
[ Footnote 7 ]
The dissent's attempt to analogize the sound amplification
guideline to a total ban on distribution of handbills is
imaginative, but misguided. See post at 491 U. S.
806 -807. The guideline does not ban all concerts, or
even all rock concerts, but instead focuses on the source of the
evils the city seeks to eliminate -- excessive and inadequate sound
amplification -- and eliminates them without, at the same time,
banning or significantly restricting a substantial quantity of
speech that does not create the same evils. This is the essence of
narrow tailoring. A ban on handbilling, of course, would suppress a
great quantity of speech that does not cause the evils that it
seeks to eliminate, whether they be fraud, crime, litter, traffic
congestion, or noise. See Martin v. Struthers, 319 U. S. 141 , 319 U. S.
145 -146 (1943). For that reason, a complete ban on
handbilling would be substantially broader than necessary to
achieve the interests justifying it.
JUSTICE MARSHALL, with whom JUSTICE BRENNAN and JUSTICE STEVENS
join, dissenting.
No one can doubt that government has a substantial interest in
regulating the barrage of excessive sound that can plague urban
life. Unfortunately, the majority plays to our shared impatience
with loud noise to obscure the damage that it does to our First
Amendment rights. Until today, a key safeguard of free speech has
been government's obligation to adopt the least intrusive
restriction necessary to achieve its goals. By abandoning the
requirement that time, place, and manner regulations must be
narrowly tailored, the majority replaces constitutional scrutiny
with mandatory deference. The majority's willingness to give
government officials a free hand in achieving their policy ends
extends so far as to permit, in this case, government control of
speech in advance of its dissemination. Because New York City's Use
Guidelines (Guidelines) are not narrowly tailored to serve its
interest in regulating loud noise, and because they constitute an
impermissible prior restraint, I dissent. Page 491 U. S. 804 I The majority sets forth the appropriate standard for assessing
the constitutionality of the Guidelines. A time, place, and manner
regulation of expression must be content-neutral, serve a
significant government interest, be narrowly tailored to serve that
interest, and leave open ample alternative channels of
communication. See Frisby v. Schultz, 487 U.
S. 474 , 487 U. S.
481 -482 (1988); Perry Education Assn. v. Perry Local
Educators' Assn., 460 U. S. 37 , 460 U. S. 44 (1983). The Guidelines indisputably are content-neutral, as they
apply to all bandshell users irrespective of the message of their
music. App. 375; see Pacific Gas & Electric Co. v. Public
Utilities Comm'n of Cal., 475 U. S. 1 , 475 U. S. 20 (1985). [ Footnote 2/1 ] They also
serve government's significant interest in limiting loud noise in
public places, see Grayned v. Rockford, 408 U.
S. 104 , 408 U. S. 116 (1972), by giving the city exclusive control of all sound
equipment.
My complaint is with the majority's serious distortion of the
narrow tailoring requirement. Our cases have not, as the majority
asserts, "clearly" rejected a less-restrictive-alternative test. Ante at 491 U. S. 797 .
On the contrary, just last Term, we held that a statute is narrowly
tailored only "if it targets and eliminates no more than the exact
source of the evil' it seeks to remedy." Frisby v. Schultz,
supra, at 487 U. S. 485 .
While there is language in a few opinions which, taken out
of Page 491 U. S. 805 context, supports the majority's position, [ Footnote 2/2 ] in practice, the Court has
interpreted the narrow tailoring requirement to mandate an
examination of alternative methods of serving the asserted
governmental interest and a determination whether the greater
efficacy of the challenged regulation outweighs the increased
burden it places on protected speech. See, e.g., Martin v.
Struthers, 319 U. S. 141 , 319 U. S.
147 -148 (1943); Schneider v. State, 308 U. S. 147 , 308 U. S. 162 (1939). In Schneider, for example, the Court invalidated a
ban on handbill distribution on public streets, notwithstanding
that it was the most effective means of serving government's
legitimate interest in minimizing litter, noise, and traffic
congestion, and in preventing fraud. The Court concluded that
punishing those who actually litter or perpetrate frauds was a much
less intrusive, albeit not quite as effective, means to serve those
significant interests. Id. at 308 U. S. 162 , 308 U. S. 164 ; see also Martin, supra, at 148 (invalidating ban on
door-to-door distribution of handbills because directly punishing
fraudulent solicitation was a less intrusive, yet still effective,
means of serving government's interest in preventing fraud).
[ Footnote 2/3 ] Page 491 U. S. 806 The Court's past concern for the extent to which a regulation
burdens speech more than would a satisfactory alternative is
noticeably absent from today's decision. The majority requires only
that government show that its interest cannot be served as
effectively without the challenged restriction. Ante at 491 U. S. 799 .
It will be enough, therefore, that the challenged regulation
advances the government's interest only in the slightest, for any
differential burden on speech that results does not enter the
calculus. Despite its protestations to the contrary, the majority
thus has abandoned the requirement that restrictions on speech be
narrowly tailored in any ordinary use of the phrase. [ Footnote 2/4 ] Indeed, after today's
decision, a city could claim that bans on handbill distribution or
on door-to-door solicitation are the most effective means of
avoiding littering and fraud, or that a ban on loudspeakers and
radios in a public park is the most effective means of avoiding
loud noise. Logically extended, the majority's analysis would
permit such far reaching restrictions on speech.
True, the majority states that
"[g]overnment may not regulate expression in such a manner that
a substantial portion of the burden on speech does not serve to
advance its goals." Ibid. But this means that only those regulations that
"engage in the gratuitous inhibition of expression" will be
invalidated. Ely, Flag Desecration: A Case Study in the Roles of
Categorization and Balancing in First Amendment Analysis, 88
Harv.L.Rev. 1482, 1485 (1975). Moreover, the majority has robbed
courts of the necessary analytic tools to make even this limited
inquiry. The Court of Appeals examined "how much control of volume
is appropriate [and] how that level of control is to be achieved," ante at 491 U. S. 800 ,
but the majority admonishes that court for doing so, stating that
it should Page 491 U. S. 807 have "defer[red] to the city's reasonable determination." Ibid. The majority thus instructs courts to refrain from
examining how much speech may be restricted to serve an asserted
interest, and how that level of restriction is to be achieved. If a
court cannot engage in such inquiries, I am at a loss to understand
how a court can ascertain whether the government has adopted a
regulation that burdens substantially more speech than is
necessary.
Had the majority not abandoned the narrow tailoring requirement,
the Guidelines could not possibly survive constitutional scrutiny.
Government's interest in avoiding loud sounds cannot justify giving
government total control over sound equipment, any more than its
interest in avoiding litter could justify a ban on handbill
distribution. In both cases, government's legitimate goals can be
effectively and less intrusively served by directly punishing the
evil -- the persons responsible for excessive sounds and the
persons who litter. Indeed, the city concedes that it has an
ordinance generally limiting noise, but has chosen not to enforce
it. See Tr. of Oral. Arg. 5-6. [ Footnote 2/5 ]
By holding that the Guidelines are valid time, place, and manner
restrictions, notwithstanding the availability of less intrusive
but effective means of controlling volume, the majority deprives
the narrow tailoring requirement of all meaning. [ Footnote 2/6 ] Today, the majority enshrines
efficacy, but sacrifices free speech. Page 491 U. S. 808 II The majority's conclusion that the city's exclusive control of
sound equipment is constitutional is deeply troubling for another
reason. It places the Court's imprimatur on a
quintessential prior restraint, incompatible with fundamental First
Amendment values. See Near v. Minnesota ex rel. Olson, 283 U. S. 697 (1931). Indeed, just as "[m]usic is one of the oldest forms of
human expression," ante at 491 U. S. 790 ,
the city's regulation is one of the oldest forms of speech
repression. In 16th- and 17th-century England, government
controlled speech through its monopoly on printing presses. See L. Levy, Emergence of a Free Press 6 (1985). Here, the
city controls the volume and mix of sound through its monopoly on
sound equipment. In both situations, government's exclusive control
of the means of communication enables public officials to censor
speech in advance of its expression. See Southeastern
Promotions, Ltd. v. Conrad, 420 U. S. 546 , 420 U. S. 553 (1975). Under more familiar prior restraints, government officials
censor speech "by a simple stroke of the pen," Emerson, The
Doctrine of Prior Restraint, 20 Law & Contemp. Prob. 648, 657
(1955). Here, it is done by a single turn of a knob.
The majority's implication that government control of sound
equipment is not a prior restraint because city officials do not
"enjoy unguided discretion to deny the right to speak altogether," ante at 491 U. S. 794 ,
is startling. In the majority's view, this case involves a question
of "different and lesser" magnitude -- the discretion to provide
inadequate sound for performers. But whether the city denies a
performer a bandshell permit or grants the permit and then silences
or Page 491 U. S. 809 distorts the performer's music, the result is the same -- the
city censors speech. In the words of CHIEF JUSTICE REHNQUIST, the
First Amendment means little if it permits government to "allo[w] a
speaker in a public hall to express his views while denying him the
use of an amplifying system." FEC v. National Conservative
Political Action Committee, 470 U. S. 480 , 470 U. S. 493 (1985); see also Southeastern Promotions, supra, at 420 U. S. 556 ,
n. 8 ("A licensing system need not effect total suppression in
order to create a prior restraint").
As a system of prior restraint, the Guidelines are presumptively
invalid. See Southeastern Promotions, supra, at 420 U. S. 558 ; Bantam Books, Inc. v. Sullivan, 372 U. S.
58 , 372 U. S. 70 (1963). They may be constitutional only if accompanied by the
procedural safeguards necessary "to obviate the dangers of a
censorship system." Freedman v. Maryland, 380 U. S.
51 , 380 U. S. 58 (1965). The city must establish neutral criteria embodied in
"narrowly drawn, reasonable and definite standards," in order to
ensure that discretion is not exercised based on the content of
speech. Niemotko v. Maryland, 340 U.
S. 268 , 340 U. S. 271 (1951); see also Lakewood v. Plain Dealer Publishing Co., 486 U. S. 750 , 486 U. S. 758 (1988); Shuttlesworth v. Birmingham, 394 U.
S. 147 , 394 U. S.
150 -151 (1969). Moreover, there must be "an almost
immediate judicial determination" that the restricted material was
unprotected by the First Amendment. Bantam Books, supra, at 372 U. S. 70 ; see also Southeastern Promotions, supra, at 420 U. S.
560 .
The Guidelines contain neither of these procedural safeguards.
First, there are no "narrowly drawn, reasonable and definite
standards" guiding the hands of the city's sound technician as he
mixes the sound. The Guidelines state that the goals are "to
provide the best sound for all events" and to "insure appropriate
sound quality balanced with respect for nearby residential
neighbors and the mayorally decreed quiet zone." App. 375; see
also ante at 491 U. S. 794 .
But the city never defines "best sound" or "appropriate sound
quality." The bandshell program director-manager testified that
quality of Page 491 U. S. 810 sound refers to tone and to sound mix. App. 229, 230. Yet
questions of tone and mix cannot be separated from musical
expression as a whole. See The New Grove Dictionary of
Music and Musicians 51-55 (S. Sadie ed.1980) (tonality involves
relationship between pitches and harmony); F. Everest, Successful
Sound System Operation 173 (1985) ("The mixing console . . . must
be considered as a creative tool"). Because judgments that sounds
are too loud, noise-like, or discordant can mask disapproval of the
music itself, [ Footnote 2/7 ]
government control of the sound mixing equipment necessitates
detailed and neutral standards.
The majority concedes that the standards in the Guidelines are
"undoubtedly flexible," and that "the officials implementing them
will exercise considerable discretion." Ante at 491 U. S. 794 .
Nevertheless, it concludes that,
"[b]y its own terms, the city's sound amplification guideline
must be interpreted to forbid city officials purposefully to select
inadequate sound systems or to vary the sound quality or volume
based on the message being delivered by performers." Ante at 491 U. S.
794 -795. Although the majority wishes it were so, the
language of the Guidelines simply does not support such a
limitation on the city's discretion. Alternatively, the majority
finds a limitation in the city's practice of deferring to the
sponsor with respect to sound mix, and of conferring "with the
sponsor if any questions of excessive sound arise before taking any
corrective action." 658 F.
Supp. 1346 , 1352 (SDNY 1987). A promise to consult, however,
does not provide the detailed Page 491 U. S. 811 "neutral criteria" necessary to prevent future abuses of
discretion any more than did the city's promise in Lakewood to deny permit applications only for reasons
related to the health, safety, or welfare of Lakewood citizens.
Indeed, a presumption that city officials will act in good faith
and adhere to standards absent from a regulation's face is "the
very presumption that the doctrine forbidding unbridled discretion
disallows." Lakewood, 486 U.S. at 770. [ Footnote 2/8 ]
Second, even if there were narrowly drawn guidelines limiting
the city's discretion, the Guidelines would be fundamentally
flawed. For the requirement that there be detailed standards is of
value only so far as there is a judicial mechanism to enforce them.
Here, that necessary safeguard is absent. The city's sound
technician consults with the performers for several minutes before
the performance, and then decides how to present each song or piece
of music. During the performance itself, the technician makes
hundreds of decisions affecting the mix and volume of sound. Tr. of
Oral Arg. 13. The music is played immediately after each decision.
There is, of course, no time for appeal in the middle of a song. As
a result, no court ever determines that a particular restraint on
speech is necessary. The city's admission that it does not impose
sanctions on violations of its general sound ordinance because the
necessary litigation is too costly and time-consuming only
underscores its contempt for the need for judicial review of
restrictions on speech. Id. at 5. With neither prompt
judicial review nor detailed and neutral standards fettering the
city's discretion to restrict protected Page 491 U. S. 812 speech, the Guidelines constitute a quintessential, and
unconstitutional, prior restraint. III Today's decision has significance far beyond the world of rock
music. Government no longer need balance the effectiveness of
regulation with the burdens on free speech. After today, government
need only assert that it is most effective to control speech in
advance of its expression. Because such a result eviscerates the
First Amendment, I dissent.
[ Footnote 2/1 ]
The majority's reliance on Renton v. Playtime Theatres,
Inc., 475 U. S. 41 (1986)
is unnecessary and unwise. That decision dealt only with the unique
circumstances of "businesses that purvey sexually explicit
materials," id. at 475 U. S. 49 ,
and n. 2. Today, for the first time, a majority of the Court
applies Renton analysis to a category of speech far afield
from that decision's original limited focus. Given the serious
threat to free expression posed by Renton analysis, see Boos v. Barry, 485 U. S. 312 , 485 U. S.
335 -337 (1988) (BRENNAN, J., concurring in part and
concurring in judgment); Renton, supra, at 475 U. S. 55 (BRENNAN, J., concurring in part and concurring in judgment), I
fear that its broad application may encourage widespread official
censorship.
[ Footnote 2/2 ] United States v. Albertini, 472 U.
S. 675 (1985), for example, involved a person's right to
enter a military base, which, unlike a public park, is not a place
traditionally dedicated to free expression. Id. at 472 U. S. 687 (commanding officer's power to exclude civilians from a military
base cannot "be analyzed in the same manner as government
regulation of a traditional public forum"). Nor can isolated
language from JUSTICE WHITE's opinion in Regan v. Time,
Inc., 468 U. S. 641 , 468 U. S. 657 (1984), which commanded the votes of only three other Justices, be
construed as this Court's definitive explication of the narrow
tailoring requirement.
[ Footnote 2/3 ]
The majority relies heavily on Clark v. Community for
Creative Non-Violence, 468 U. S. 288 (1984), but, in that case, the Court engaged in an inquiry similar
to the one the majority now rejects; it considered whether the
increased efficacy of the challenged regulation warranted the
increased burden on speech. Id. at 468 U. S. 299 ("[P]reventing overnight sleeping will avoid a measure of actual or
threatened damage"; however, "minimiz[ing] the possible injury by
reducing the size, duration, or frequency of demonstrations would
still curtail the total allowable expression in which demonstrators
could engage").
[ Footnote 2/4 ]
In marked contrast, the majority recently adopted a far more
stringent narrow tailoring requirement in the affirmative action
context. See Richmond v. J. A. Croson Co., 488 U.
S. 469 , 488 U. S.
507 -508 (1989) (plurality opinion).
[ Footnote 2/5 ]
Significantly, the National Park Service relies on the very
methods of volume control rejected by the city -- monitoring sound
levels on the perimeter of an event, communicating with event
sponsors, and, if necessary, turning off the power. Brief for
United States as Amicus Curiae 21. In light of the Park
Service's "experienc[e] with thousands of events over the years," ibid., the city's claims that these methods of monitoring
excessive sound are ineffective and impracticable are hard to
accept.
[ Footnote 2/6 ]
Because I conclude that the Guidelines are not narrowly
tailored, there is no need to consider whether there are ample
alternative channels for communication. I note only that the
availability of alternative channels of communication outside a
public park does not magically validate a government restriction on
protected speech within it. See Southeastern Promotions, Ltd.
v. Conrad, 420 U. S. 546 , 420 U. S. 556 (1975) (" [O]ne is not to have the exercise of his liberty of
expression in appropriate places abridged on the plea that it may
be exercised in some other place,'" quoting Schneider v.
State, 308 U. S. 147 , 308 U. S. 163 (1939)). [ Footnote 2/7 ]
"New music always sounds loud to old ears. Beethoven seemed to
make more noise than Mozart; Liszt was noisier than Beethoven;
Schoenberg and Stravinsky noisier than any of their
predecessors."
N. Slonimsky, Lexicon of Musical Invective: Critical Assaults on
Composers Since Beethoven's Time 18 (1953). One music critic wrote
of Prokofiev:
"Those who do not believe that genius is evident in
superabundance of noise looked in vain for a new musical message in
Mr. Prokofiev's work. Nor in the Classical Symphony, which the
composer conducted, was there any cessation from the orgy of
discordant sounds." Id. at 5 (internal quotations omitted).
[ Footnote 2/8 ]
Of course, if the city always defers to a performer's wishes in
sound mixing, then it is difficult to understand the need for a
city technician to operate the mixing console. See Tr. of
Oral. Arg. 12 (city concedes that the possibilities for a
confrontation over volume are the same whether the city technician
directly controls the mixing console or sits next to a performer's
technician who operates the equipment). Conversely, if the city can
control sound only by using its own equipment and technician, then
it must not be heeding all the performer's wishes on sound
mixing. | The Supreme Court upheld a New York City guideline requiring the use of city-provided sound equipment and technicians for performances at the Naumberg Acoustic Bandshell in Central Park, finding it to be a reasonable and content-neutral regulation of the place and manner of protected speech. The city implemented this guideline to address excessive noise complaints and inadequate amplification issues. The Court rejected arguments that there were less restrictive means to control volume, finding that the city's method was narrowly tailored to achieve its purpose without unnecessarily intruding on performers' expression. |
Free Speech | Forsyth County v. Nationalist Movement | https://supreme.justia.com/cases/federal/us/505/123/ | OCTOBER TERM, 1991
Syllabus
FORSYTH COUNTY, GEORGIA v. NATIONALIST MOVEMENT
CERTIORARI TO THE UNITED STATES COURT OF APPEALS FOR THE
ELEVENTH CIRCUIT No. 91-538. Argued March 31, 1992-Decided June 19, 1992 Petitioner county's Ordinance 34 mandates permits for private
demonstrations and other uses of public property; declares that the
cost of protecting participants in such activities exceeds the
usual and normal cost of law enforcement and should be borne by the
participants; requires every permit applicant to pay a fee of not
more than $1,000; and empowers the county administrator to adjust
the fee's amount to meet the expense incident to the ordinance's
administration and to the maintenance of public order. After the
county attempted to impose such a fee for respondent's proposed
demonstration in opposition to the Martin Luther King, Jr., federal
holiday, respondent filed this suit, claiming that the ordinance
violates the free speech guarantees of the First and Fourteenth
Amendments. The District Court denied relief, ruling that the
ordinance was not unconstitutional as applied in this case. The
Court of Appeals reversed, holding that an ordinance which charges
more than a nominal fee for using public forums for public issue
speech is facially unconstitutional. Held: The ordinance is facially invalid. Pp. 129-137.
(a) In order to regulate competing uses of public forums,
government may impose a permit requirement on those wishing to hold
a march, parade, or rally, if, inter alia, the permit scheme
does not delegate overly broad licensing discretion to a government
official, Freedman v. Maryland, 380 U. S. 51 , 56, and is
not based on the content of the message, see United States v. Grace, 461
U. S. 171 , 177. Pp. 129-130.
(b) An examination of the county's implementation and
authoritative constructions of the ordinance demonstrates the
absence of the constitutionally required "narrowly drawn,
reasonable and definite standards," Niemotko v. Maryland, 340
U. S. 268 , 271, to guide the county administrator's hand when
he sets a permit fee. The decision how much to charge for police
protection or administrative time-or even whether to charge at
all-is left to the unbridled discretion of the administrator, who
is not required to rely on objective standards or provide any
explanation for his decision. Pp. 130-133.
(c) The ordinance is unconstitutionally content based because it
requires that the administrator, in order to assess accurately the
cost of 124 security for parade participants, must examine the content of
the message conveyed, estimate the public response to that content,
and judge the number of police necessary to meet that response. Cox v. New Hampshire, 312 U. S. 569 ,
distinguished. Pp. 133-136.
(d) Neither the $1,000 cap on the permit fee, nor even some
lower "nominal" cap, could save the ordinance. Murdock v. Pennsylvania, 319 U. S. 105 , 116,
distinguished. The level of the fee is irrelevant in this context,
because no limit on the fee's size can remedy the ordinance's
constitutional infirmities. pp. 136-137. 913 F.2d
885 and 934 F.2d
1482 , affirmed.
BLACKMUN, J., delivered the opinion of the Court, in which
STEVENS, O'CONNOR, KENNEDY, and SOUTER, JJ., joined. REHNQUIST, C.
J., filed a dissenting opinion, in which WHITE, SCALIA, and THOMAS,
JJ., joined, post, p. 137. Robert S. Stubbs III argued the cause for
petitioner.
With him on the briefs was Gordon A. Smith. Richard Barrett argued the cause and filed a brief for
respondent. *
JUSTICE BLACKMUN delivered the opinion of the Court. In this
case, with its emotional overtones, we must decide whether the free
speech guarantees of the First and Fourteenth Amendments are
violated by an assembly and parade ordinance that permits a
government administrator to vary the fee for assembling or parading
to reflect the estimated cost of maintaining public order.
I
Petitioner Forsyth County is a primarily rural Georgia county
approximately 30 miles northeast of Atlanta. It has * Jody M. Litchford filed a brief for the city of
Orlando et al. as amici curiae urging reversal.
Briefs of amici curiae urging affirmance were filed for
the American Civil Liberties Union et al. by Eric Neisser,
Steven R. Shapiro, John A. Powell, and Elliot M.
Mincberg; for the American Federation of Labor and Congress of
Industrial Organizations by Marsha S. Berzon and Laurence Gold; and for Public Citizen by David C. Vladeck and Alan B. Morrison. 125 had a troubled racial history. In 1912, in one month, its entire
African-American population, over 1,000 citizens, was driven
systematically from the county in the wake of the rape and murder
of a white woman and the lynching of her accused assailant.1
Seventy-five years later, in 1987, the county population remained
99% white.2
Spurred by this history, Hosea Williams, an Atlanta city
councilman and civil rights personality, proposed a Forsyth County
"March Against Fear and Intimidation" for J anuary 17, 1987.
Approximately 90 civil rights demonstrators attempted to parade in
Cumming, the county seat. The marchers were met by members of the
Forsyth County Defense League (an independent affiliate of
respondent, The Nationalist Movement), of the Ku Klux Klan, and
other Cumming residents. In all, some 400 counterdemonstrators
lined the parade route, shouting racial slurs. Eventually, the
counterdemonstrators, dramatically outnumbering police officers,
forced the parade to a premature halt by throwing rocks and beer
bottles.
Williams planned a return march the following weekend.
It developed into the largest civil rights demonstration in the
South since the 1960's. On January 24, approximately 20,000
marchers joined civil rights leaders, United States Senators,
Presidential candidates, and an Assistant United States Attorney
General in a parade and rally.3 The 1,000 counterdemonstrators on
the parade route were contained
1 The 1910 census counted 1,098 African-Americans in Forsyth
County.
U. S. Dept. of Commerce, Bureau of Census, Negro Population
1790-1915, p. 779 (1918). For a description of the 1912 events, see
generally Hackworth, "Completing the Job" in Forsyth County, 8
Southern Exposure 26 (1980).
2 See J. Clements, Georgia Facts 184 (1989); Hackworth, 8
Southern Exposure, at 26 ("[O]ther than an occasional delivery
truck driver or visiting government official, there are currently
no black faces anywhere in the county").
3See Chicago Tribune, Jan. 25,1987, p. 1; Los Angeles Times,
Jan. 25, 1987, p. 1, col. 2; App. to Pet. for Cert. 89-91. 126 by more than 3,000 state and local police and National
Guardsmen. Although there was sporadic rock throwing and 60
counterdemonstrators were arrested, the parade was not interrupted.
The demonstration cost over $670,000 in police protection, of which
Forsyth County apparently paid a small portion.4 See App. to Pet.
for Cert. 75-94; Los Angeles Times, Jan. 28, 1987, Metro section,
p. 5, col. 1.
"As a direct result" of these two demonstrations, the Forsyth
County Board of Commissioners enacted Ordinance 34 on January 27,
1987. See Brief for Petitioner 6. The ordinance recites that it is
"to provide for the issuance of permits for parades, assemblies,
demonstrations, road closings, and other uses of public property
and roads by private organizations and groups of private persons
for private purposes." See App. to Pet. for Cert. 98. The board of
commissioners justified the ordinance by explaining that "the cost
of necessary and reasonable protection of persons participating in
or observing said parades, assemblies, demonstrations, road
closings and other related activities exceeds the usual and normal
cost of law enforcement for which those participating should be
held accountable and responsible." Id., at 100. The
ordinance required the permit applicant to defray these costs by
paying a fee, the amount of which was to be fixed "from time to
time" by the Board. Id., at 105.
Ordinance 34 was amended on June 8, 1987, to provide that every
permit applicant "'shall pay in advance for such permit, for the
use of the County, a sum not more than $1,000.00 for each day such
parade, procession, or open air public meeting shall take place.'" Id., at 119.5 In addition, the county
4 Petitioner Forsyth County does not indicate what portion of
these costs it paid. Newspaper articles reported that the State of
Georgia paid an estimated $579,148. Other government entities paid
an additional $29,759. Figures were not available for the portion
paid by the city of Atlanta for the police it sent. See id., at 95-97.
5 The ordinance was amended at other times, too, but those
amendments are not under challenge here. 127 administrator was empowered to "'adjust the amount to be paid in
order to meet the expense incident to the administration of the
Ordinance and to the maintenance of public order in the matter
licensed.'" Ibid. In January 1989, respondent The Nationalist Movement proposed to
demonstrate in opposition to the federal holiday commemorating the
birthday of Martin Luther King, Jr. In Forsyth County, the Movement
sought to "conduct a rally and speeches for one and a half to two
hours" on the courthouse steps on a Saturday afternoon. Nationalist Movement v. City of Cumming, 913 F.2d
885 , 887 (CAll 1990).6 The county imposed a $100 fee. The fee
did not include any calculation for expenses incurred by law
enforcement authorities, but was based on 10 hours of the county
administrator's time in issuing the permit. The county
administrator testified that the cost of his time was deliberately
undervalued and that he did not charge for the clerical support
involved in processing the application. Tr. 135-139.
The Movement did not pay the fee and did not hold the rally.
Instead, it instituted this action on January 19, 1989, in the
United States District Court for the Northern District of Georgia,
requesting a temporary restraining order and permanent injunction
prohibiting Forsyth County from interfering with the Movement's
plans.
The District Court denied the temporary restraining order and
injunction. It found that, although "the instant ordinance vests
much discretion in the County Administrator in determining an
appropriate fee," the determination of the fee was "based solely
upon content-neutral criteria; namely,
6 The demonstration proposed was to consist of assembling at the
Forsyth County High School, marching down a public street in
Cumming to the courthouse square, and there conducting a rally.
Only the rally was to take place on property under the jurisdiction
of the county. The parade and assembly required permits from the
city of Cumming and the Forsyth County Board of Education. Their
permit schemes are not challenged here. 128 the actual costs incurred investigating and processing the
application." App. to Pet. for Cert. 13-14. Although it expressed
doubt about the constitutionality of that portion of the ordinance
that permits fees to be based upon the costs incident to
maintaining public order, the District Court found that "the county
ordinance, as applied in this case, is not unconstitutional." Id., at 14.
The United States Court of Appeals for the Eleventh Circuit
reversed this aspect of the District Court's judgment. Nationalist Movement v. City of Cumming, 913 F.2d
885 (1990). Relying on its prior opinion in Central Florida
Nuclear Freeze Campaign v. Walsh, 774
F.2d 1515 , 1521 (CAll 1985), cert. denied, 475 U. S. 1120
(1986), the Court of Appeals held: "An ordinance which charges more
than a nominal fee for using public forums for public issue speech,
violates the First Amendment." 913 F. 2d, at 891 (internal
quotation marks omitted). The court determined that a permit fee of
up to $1,000 a day exceeded this constitutional threshold. Ibid. One judge concurred specially, calling for Central
Florida to be overruled. 913 F. 2d, at 896.
The Court of Appeals then voted to vacate the panel's opinion
and to rehear the case en bane. 921 F.2d
1125 (1990). After further briefing, the court issued a per
curiam opinion reinstating the panel opinion in its entirety. 934 F.2d
1482 , 1483 (1991). Two judges, concurring in part and
dissenting in part, agreed that any fee imposed on the exercise of
First Amendment rights in a traditional public forum must be
nominal if it is to survive constitutional scrutiny. Those judges,
however, did not believe that the county ordinance swept so broadly
that it was facially invalid, and would have remanded the case for
the District Court to determine whether the fee was nominaP Ibid. Three judges
7 These judges also found that the ordinance contained
sufficiently tailored standards for the administrator to use in
reviewing permit applications. 934 F.2d
1482 , 1487-1489 (1991). This issue was raised by respondent,
but the panel did not reach it. 129 dissented, arguing that this Court's cases do not require that
fees be nominal. Id., at 1493.
We granted certiorari to resolve a conflict among the Courts of
Appeals concerning the constitutionality of charging a fee for a
speaker in a public forum.8 502 U. S. 1023 (1991).
II
Respondent mounts a facial challenge to the Forsyth County
ordinance. It is well established that in the area of freedom of
expression an overbroad regulation may be subject to facial review
and invalidation, even though its application in the case under
consideration may be constitutionally unobjectionable. See, e.
g., City Council of Los Angeles v. Taxpayers for
Vincent, 466 U.
S. 789 , 798-799, and n. 15 (1984); Board of Airport Comm'rs
of Los Angeles v. Jews for Jesus, Inc., 482 U. S. 569 , 574
(1987). This exception from general standing rules is based on an
appreciation that the very existence of some broadly written laws
has the potential to chill the expressive activity of others not
before the court. See, e. g., New York v. Ferber, 458 U. S. 747 ,
772 (1982); Brockett v. Spokane Arcades, Inc., 472 U. S. 491 ,
503 (1985). Thus, the Court has permitted a party to challenge an
ordinance under the overbreadth doctrine in cases where every
application creates an impermissible risk of suppression of ideas,
such as an ordinance that delegates overly broad discretion to the
decisionmaker, see Thornhill v. Ala- 8 Compare the Eleventh Circuit's opinions in this litigation, 913 F.2d
885 , 891 (1990), and 934 F.2d
1482 , 1483 (1991), with Stonewall Union v. Columbus, 931 F.2d
1130 , 1136 (CA6) (permitting greater than nominal fees
that are reasonably related to expenses incident to the
preservation of public safety and order), cert. denied, 502 U. S.
899 (1991); Eastern Conn. Citizens Action Group v. Powers, 723 F.2d
1050 , 1056 (CA2 1983) (licensing fees permissible only
to offset expenses associated with processing applications for
public property); Fernandes v. Limmer, 663 F.2d
619 , 632-633 (CA5 1981) ($6 flat fee for permit was
unconstitutional), cert. dism'd, 458 U. S. 1124 (1982). 130 bama, 310 U.
S. 88 , 97 (1940); Freedman v. Maryland, 380 U. S.
51, 56 (1965); Taxpayers for Vincent, 466 U. S., at 798, n.
15, and in cases where the ordinance sweeps too broadly, penalizing
a substantial amount of speech that is constitutionally protected,
see Broadrick v. Oklahoma, 413 U. S. 601 (1973);
Jews for Jesus, 482 U. S., at 574-575.
The Forsyth County ordinance requiring a permit and a fee before
authorizing public speaking, parades, or assemblies in "the
archetype of a traditional public forum," Frisby v. Schultz, 487
U. S. 474 , 480 (1988), is a prior restraint on speech, see Shuttlesworth v. Birmingham, 394 U. S. 147 , 150-151
(1969); Niemotko v. Maryland, 340 U. S. 268 , 271
(1951). Although there is a "heavy presumption" against the
validity of a prior restraint, Bantam Books, Inc. v. Sulli van, 372
U. S. 58 , 70 (1963), the Court has recognized that government,
in order to regulate competing uses of public forums, may impose a
permit requirement on those wishing to hold a march, parade, or
rally, see Cox v. New Hampshire, 312 U. S. 569 , 574-576
(1941). Such a scheme, however, must meet certain constitutional
requirements. It may not delegate overly broad licensing discretion
to a government official. See Freedman v. Maryland,
supra. Further, any permit scheme controlling the time, place,
and manner of speech must not be based on the content of the
message, must be narrowly tailored to serve a significant
governmental interest, and must leave open ample alternatives for
communication. See United States v. Grace, 461 U. S. 171 , 177
(1983).
A
Respondent contends that the county ordinance is facially
invalid because it does not prescribe adequate standards for the
administrator to apply when he sets a permit fee. A government
regulation that allows arbitrary application is "inherently
inconsistent with a valid time, place, and manner regulation
because such discretion has the potential for becoming a means of
suppressing a particular point of view." 131 Heffron v. International Society for Krishna
Consciousness, Inc., 452 U. S. 640 , 649
(1981). To curtail that risk, "a law subjecting the exercise of
First Amendment freedoms to the prior restraint of a license" must
contain "narrow, objective, and definite standards to guide the
licensing authority." Shuttlesworth, 394 U. S., at 150-151;
see also Niemotko, 340 U. S., at 271. The reasoning is
simple: If the permit scheme "involves appraisal of facts, the
exercise of judgment, and the formation of an opinion," Cantwell v. Connecticut, 310 U. S. 296, 305 (1940),
by the licensing authority, "the danger of censorship and of
abridgment of our precious First Amendment freedoms is too great"
to be permitted, Southeastern Promotions, Ltd. v. Conrad, 420 U.
S. 546 , 553 (1975).
In evaluating respondent's facial challenge, we must consider
the county's authoritative constructions of the ordinance,
including its own implementation and interpretation of it. See Ward v. Rock Against Racism, 491 U. S. 781 , 795796
(1989); Lakewood v. Plain Dealer Publishing Co., 486 U. S. 750, 770, n. 11 (1988); Gooding v. Wilson, 405 U. S. 518 ,
524-528 (1972). In the present litigation, the county has made
clear how it interprets and implements the ordinance. The ordinance
can apply to any activity on public propertyfrom parades, to street
corner speeches, to bike races-and the fee assessed may reflect the
county's police and administrative costs. Whether or not, in any
given instance, the fee would include any or all of the county's
administrative and security expenses is decided by the county
administrator.9
9 In pertinent part, the ordinance, as amended, states that the
administrator "shall adjust the amount to be paid in order
to meet the expense incident to the administration of the Ordinance
and to the maintenance of public order." § 3(6) (emphasis added),
App. to Pet. for Cert. 119. This could suggest that the
administrator has no authority to reduce or waive these expenses.
It has not been so understood, however, by the county. See 934 F.
2d, at 1488, n. 12 (opinion concurring in part and dissenting in
part). In its February 23, 1987, amendments to the ordinance, the
board of commissioners changed the permit form from "Have you paid the application fee?" to "Have you paid any application fee?," see App. to 132 In this case, according to testimony at the District Court
hearing, the administrator based the fee on his own judgment of
what would be reasonable. Although the county paid for clerical
support and staff as an "expense incident to the administration" of
the permit, the administrator testified that he chose in this
instance not to include that expense in the fee. The administrator
also attested that he had deliberately kept the fee low by
undervaluing the cost of the time he spent processing the
application. Even if he had spent more time on the project, he
claimed, he would not have charged more. He further testified that,
in this instance, he chose not to include any charge for expected
security expense. Tr. 135-139.
The administrator also explained that the county had imposed a
fee pursuant to a permit on two prior occasions. The year before,
the administrator had assessed a fee of $100 for a permit for the
Movement. The administrator testified that he charged the same fee
the following year (the year in question here), although he did not
state that the Movement was seeking the same use of county property
or that it required the same amount of administrative time to
process. Id., at 138. The administrator also once charged
bike-race organizers $25 to hold a race on county roads, but he did
not explain why processing a bike-race permit demanded less
administrative time than processing a parade permit or why he had
chosen to assess $25 in that instance. Id., at 143-144. At
oral argument in this Court, counsel for Forsyth County stated that
the administrator had levied a $5 fee on the Girl Scouts for an
activity on county property. Tr. of Oral Arg. 26. Finally, the
administrator testified that in other cases the county required
neither a permit nor a fee for activities in other county
facilities or on county land. Tr. 146.
Based on the county's implementation and construction of the
ordinance, it simply cannot be said that there are any
Pet. for Cert. 115 (emphasis added), thus acknowledging the
administrator's authority to charge no fee. 133 "narrowly drawn, reasonable and definite standards," Nie motko, 340 U. S., at 271, guiding the hand of the Forsyth
County administrator. The decision how much to charge for police
protection or administrative time-or even whether to charge at
all-is left to the whim of the administrator. There are no
articulated standards either in the ordinance or in the county's
established practice. The administrator is not required to rely on
any objective factors. He need not provide any explanation for his
decision, and that decision is unreviewable. Nothing in the law or
its application prevents the official from encouraging some views
and discouraging others through the arbitrary application of
fees.10 The First Amendment prohibits the vesting of such unbridled
discretion in a government official.ll
B
The Forsyth County ordinance contains more than the possibility
of censorship through uncontrolled discretion. As
10 The District Court's finding that in this instance the
Forsyth County administrator applied legitimate, content-neutral
criteria, even if correct, is irrelevant to this facial challenge.
Facial attacks on the discretion granted a decisionmaker are not
dependent on the facts surrounding any particular permit decision.
See Lakewood v. Plain Dealer Publishing Co., 486 U. S. 750 ,
770 (1988). "It is not merely the sporadic abuse of power by the
censor but the pervasive threat inherent in its very existence that
constitutes the danger to freedom of discussion." Thornhill v. Alabama, 310
U. S. 88 , 97 (1940). Accordingly, the success of a facial
challenge on the grounds that an ordinance delegates overly broad
discretion to the decisionmaker rests not on whether the
administrator has exercised his discretion in a content-based
manner, but whether there is anything in the ordinance preventing
him from doing so.
n Petitioner also claims that Cox v. New
Hampshire, 312 U.
S. 569 (1941), excuses the administrator's discretion in
setting the fee. Reliance on Cox is misplaced. Although the
discretion granted to the administrator under the language in this
ordinance is the same as in the statute at issue in Cox, the
interpretation and application of that language are different.
Unlike this case, there was in Cox no testimony or evidence
that the statute granted unfettered discretion to the licensing
authority. Id., at 576-577. 134 construed by the county, the ordinance often requires that the
fee be based on the content of the speech.
The county envisions that the administrator, in appropriate
instances, will assess a fee to cover "the cost of necessary and
reasonable protection of persons participating in or observing said
... activit[y]." See App. to Pet. for Cert. 100. In order to assess
accurately the cost of security for parade participants, the
administrator" 'must necessarily examine the content of the message
that is conveyed,'" Arkansas Writers' Project, Inc. v. Ragland, 481
U. S. 221 , 230 (1987), quoting FCC v. League of Women
Voters of Cal., 468 U. S. 364, 383 (1984), estimate the
response of others to that content, and judge the number of police
necessary to meet that response. The fee assessed will depend on
the administrator's measure of the amount of hostility likely to be
created by the speech based on its content. Those wishing to
express views unpopular with bottle throwers, for example, may have
to pay more for their permit.
Although petitioner agrees that the cost of policing relates to
content, see Tr. of Oral Arg. 15 and 24, it contends that the
ordinance is content neutral because it is aimed only at a
secondary effect-the cost of maintaining public order. It is clear,
however, that, in this case, it cannot be said that the fee's
justification "'ha[s] nothing to do with content.'" Ward, 491 U. S., at 792, quoting Boos v. Barry, 485 U. S. 312 , 320 (1988)
(opinion of O'CONNOR, J.).
The costs to which petitioner refers are those associated with
the public's reaction to the speech. Listeners' reaction to speech
is not a content-neutral basis for regulation. See id., at
321 (opinion of O'CONNOR, J.); id., at 334 (opinion of
Brennan, J.); Hustler Magazine, Inc. v. Falwell, 485 U. S. 46 ,
55-56 (1988); Murdock v. Pennsylvania, 319 U. S. 105 , 116
(1943); cf. Schneider v. State (Town of Irvington), 308 U. S. 147 ,
162 (1939) (fact that city is financially burdened when listeners
throw leaflets on the street does not justify restriction on
distribution of leaflets). Speech cannot be financially 135 burdened, any more than it can be punished or banned, simply
because it might offend a hostile mob.12 See Gooding v. Wilson, 405 U.
S. 518 (1972); Terminiello v. Chicago, 337 U. S.
1 (1949).
This Court has held time and again: "Regulations which permit
the Government to discriminate on the basis of the content of the
message cannot be tolerated under the First Amendment." Regan v. Time, Inc., 468 U. S. 641 , 648-649 (1984); Simon & Schuster, Inc. v. Member
of N. Y. State Crime Victims Bd., 502 U. S. 105 , 116
(1991); Arkansas Writers' Project, 481 U. S., at 230. The
county offers only one
12 The dissent prefers a remand because there are no lower court
findings on the question whether the county plans to base parade
fees on hostile crowds. See post, at 142. We disagree. A
remand is unnecessary because there is no question that petitioner
intends the ordinance to recoup costs that are related to
listeners' reaction to the speech. Petitioner readily admits it did
not charge for police protection for the 4th of July parades,
although they were substantial parades, which required the closing
of streets and drew large crowds. Petitioner imposed a fee only
when it became necessary to provide security for parade
participants from angry crowds opposing their message. Brief for
Petitioner 6. The ordinance itself makes plain that the costs at
issue are those needed for "necessary and reasonable protection of
persons participating in or observing" the speech. See App. to Pet.
for Cert. 100. Repayment for police protection is the "[m]ost
importan[t]" purpose underlying the ordinance. Brief for Petitioner
6-7.
In this Court, petitioner specifically urges reversal because
the lower court has "taken away the right of local government to
obtain reimbursement for administration and policing costs which
are incurred in protecting those using government property for
expression." Id., at 17 (emphasis added). When directly faced
with the Court of Appeals' concern about "the enhanced cost
associated with policing expressive activity which would generate
potentially violent reactions," id., at 36, petitioner
responded not by arguing that it did not intend to charge for
police protection, but that such a charge was permissible because
the ordinance provided a cap. See id., at 36-37; Tr. of Oral
Arg. 24. At no point, in any level of proceedings, has petitioner
intimated that it did not construe the ordinance consistent with
its language permitting fees to be charged for the cost of police
protection from hostile crowds. We find no disputed interpretation
of the ordinance necessitating a remand. 136 justification for this ordinance: raising revenue for police
services. While this undoubtedly is an important government
responsibility, it does not justify a content-based permit fee. See id., at 229-231.
Petitioner insists that its ordinance cannot be
unconstitutionally content based because it contains much of the
same language as did the state statute upheld in Cox v. New Hampshire, 312 U. S. 569 (1941).
Although the Supreme Court of New Hampshire had interpreted the
statute at issue in Cox to authorize the municipality to
charge a permit fee for the "maintenance of public order," no fee
was actually assessed. See id., at 577. Nothing in this
Court's opinion suggests that the statute, as interpreted by the
New Hampshire Supreme Court, called for charging a premium in the
case of a controversial political message delivered before a
hostile audience. In light of the Court's subsequent First
Amendment jurisprudence, we do not read Cox to permit such a
premium.
C
Petitioner, as well as the Court of Appeals and the District
Court, all rely on the maximum allowable fee as the touchstone of
constitutionality. Petitioner contends that the $1,000 cap on the
fee ensures that the ordinance will not result in content-based
discrimination. The ordinance was found unconstitutional by the
Court of Appeals because the $1,000 cap was not sufficiently low to
be "nominal." Neither the $1,000 cap on the fee charged, nor even
some lower nominal cap, could save the ordinance because in this
context, the level of the fee is irrelevant. A tax based on the
content of speech does not become more constitutional because it is
a small tax.
The lower courts derived their requirement that the permit fee
be "nominal" from a sentence in the opinion in Murdock v. Pennsylvania, 319 U. S. 105 (1943). In Murdock, the Court invalidated a fiat license fee levied on
distributors of religious literature. In distinguishing the case
from Cox, 137 where the Court upheld a permit fee, the Court stated: "And the
fee is not a nominal one, imposed as a regulatory measure and
calculated to defray the expense of protecting those on the streets
and at home against the abuses of solicitors." 319 U. S., at 116.
This sentence does not mean that an invalid fee can be saved if it
is nominal, or that only nominal charges are constitutionally
permissible. It reflects merely one distinction between the facts
in Murdock and those in Cox. The tax at issue in Murdock was invalid because it was
unrelated to any legitimate state interest, not because it was of a
particular size. Similarly, the provision of the Forsyth County
ordinance relating to fees is invalid because it unconstitutionally
ties the amount of the fee to the content of the speech and lacks
adequate procedural safeguards; no limit on such a fee can remedy
these constitutional violations.
The judgment of the Court of Appeals is affirmed.
It is so ordered.
CHIEF JUSTICE REHNQUIST, with whom JUSTICE WHITE, JUSTICE
SCALIA, and JUSTICE THOMAS join, dissenting.
We granted certiorari in this case to consider the following
question: "Whether the provisions of the First Amendment to the United
States Constitution limit the amount of a license fee assessed
pursuant to the provisions of a county parade ordinance to a
nominal sum or whether the amount of the license fee may take into
account the actual expense incident to the administration of the
ordinance and the maintenance of public order in the matter
licensed, up to the sum of $1,000.00 per day of the activity." Pet.
for Cert. i. The Court's discussion of this question is limited to an
ambiguous and noncommittal paragraph toward the very end of the
opinion. Supra this page. The rest of the opinion 138 takes up and decides other perceived unconstitutional defects in
the Forsyth County ordinance. None of these claims were passed upon
by the Court of Appeals; that court decided only that the First
Amendment forbade the charging of more than a nominal fee for a
permit to parade on public streets. Since that was the question
decided by the Court of Appeals below, the question which divides
the Courts of Appeals, and the question presented in the petition
for certiorari, one would have thought that the Court would at
least authoritatively decide, if not limit itself to, that
question.
I
The answer to this question seems to me quite simple, because it
was authoritatively decided by this Court more than half a century
ago in Cox v. New Hampshire, 312 U. S. 569 (1941).
There we confronted a state statute which required payment of a
license fee of up to $300 to local governments for the right to
parade in the public streets. The Supreme Court of New Hampshire
had construed the provision as requiring that the amount of the fee
be adjusted based on the size of the parade, as the fee "for a
circus parade or a celebration procession of length, each drawing
crowds of observers, would take into account the greater public
expense of policing the spectacle, compared with the slight expense
of a less expansive and attractive parade or procession." Id., at 577 (internal quotation marks omitted). Under the
state court's construction, the fee provision was "not a revenue
tax, but one to meet the expense incident to the administration of
the Act and to the maintenance of public order in the matter
licensed." Ibid. (internal quotation marks omitted). This
Court, in a unanimous opinion by Chief Justice Hughes, upheld the
statute, saying: "There is nothing contrary to the Constitution in the charge of
a fee limited to the purpose stated. The suggestion that a fiat fee
should have been charged fails to take account of the difficulty of
framing a fair schedule 139 to meet all circumstances, and we perceive no constitutional
ground for denying to local governments that flexibility of
adjustment of fees which in the light of varying conditions would
tend to conserve rather than impair the liberty sought. "There is no evidence that the statute has been administered
otherwise than in the fair and nondiscriminatory manner which the
state court has construed it to require." Ibid. Two years later, in Murdock v. Pennsylvania, 319 U. S. 105 (1943), this Court confronted a municipal ordinance that required
payment of a flat license fee for the privilege of canvassing
door-to-door to sell one's wares. Pursuant to that ordinance, the
city had levied the flat fee on a group of Jehovah's Witnesses who
sought to distribute religious literature door-to-door for a small
price. Id., at 106-107. The Court held that the flat license
tax, as applied against the hand distribution of religious tracts,
was unconstitutional on the ground that it was "a flat tax imposed
on the exercise of a privilege granted by the Bill of Rights." Id., at 113. In making this ruling, the Court distinguished Cox by stating that "the fee is not a nominal one, imposed
as a regulatory measure and calculated to defray the expense of
protecting those on the streets and at home against the abuses of
solicitors." 319 U. S., at 116. This language, which suggested that
the fee involved in Cox was only nominal, led the Court of
Appeals for the Eleventh Circuit in the present case to conclude
that a city is prohibited from charging any more than a nominal fee
for a parade permit. 913 F.2d
885 , 890891, and n. 6 (1990). But the clear holding of Cox is to the contrary. In that case, the Court expressly
recognized that the New Hampshire state statute allowed a city to
levy much more than a nominal parade fee, as it stated that the fee
provision "had a permissible range from $300 to a nominal amount." Cox v. New Hampshire, supra, at 576. The use of the
word "nominal" in Murdock was thus unfortunate, as 140 it represented a mistaken characterization of the fee statute in Cox. But a mistaken allusion in a later case to the facts of
an earlier case does not by itself undermine the holding of the
earlier case. The situations in Cox and Murdock were
clearly different; the first involved a sliding fee to account for
administrative and security costs incurred as a result of a parade
on public property, while the second involved a fiat tax on
protected religious expression. I believe that the decision in Cox squarely controls the disposition of the question
presented in this case, and I therefore would explicitly hold that
the Constitution does not limit a parade license fee to a nominal
amount.
II
Instead of deciding the particular question on which we granted
certiorari, the Court concludes that the county ordinance is
facially unconstitutional because it places too much discretion in
the hands of the county administrator and forces parade
participants to pay for the cost of controlling those who might
oppose their speech. Ante, at 130-137. But, because the
lower courts did not pass on these issues, the Court is forced to
rely on its own interpretation of the ordinance in making these
rulings. The Court unnecessarily reaches out to interpret the
ordinance on its own at this stage, even though there are no lower
court factual findings on the scope or administration of the
ordinance. Because there are no such factual findings, I would not
decide at this point whether the ordinance fails for lack of
adequate standards to guide discretion or for incorporation of a
"heckler's veto," but would instead remand the case to the lower
courts to initially consider these issues.
The Court first finds fault with the alleged standardless
discretion possessed by the county administrator. The ordinance
provides that the administrator "shall adjust the amount to be paid
in order to meet the expense incident to the administration of the
Ordinance and to the maintenance of public order in the matter
licensed." App. to Pet. for 141 Cert. 119. In this regard, the ordinance clearly parallels the
construction of the statute we upheld in Cox. 312 U. S., at
577 (statute did not impose "a revenue tax, but one to meet the
expense incident to the administration of the Act and to the
maintenance of public order in the matter licensed" (internal
quotation marks omitted)). The Court worries, however, about the
possibility that the administrator has the discretion to set fees
based upon his approval of the message sought to be conveyed, and
concludes that "the county's authoritative constructio[n] of the
ordinance" allows for such a possibility. Ante, at 131. The
Court apparently envisions a situation where the administrator
would impose a $1,000 parade fee on a group whose message he
opposed, but would waive the fee entirely for a similarly situated
group with whom he agreed. But the county has never rendered any
"authoritative construction" indicating that officials have
"unbridled discretion," ante, at 133, in setting parade
fees, nor has any lower court so found. In making its own factual
finding that the ordinance does allow for standardless fee setting,
this Court simply cites four situations in which the administrator
set permit fees-two fees of $100, one of $25, and one of $5. Ante, at 132. On the basis of this evidence, the Court finds
that the administrator has unbridled discretion to set permit fees.
The mere fact that the permit fees differed in amount does not
invalidate the ordinance, however, as our decision in Cox clearly allows a governmental entity to adopt an adjustable permit
fee scheme. See Cox v. New Hampshire, supra, at 577
("[W]e perceive no constitutional ground for denying to local
governments thee] flexibility of adjustment of fees"). It is true
that the Constitution does not permit a system in which the county
administrator may vary fees at his pleasure, but there has been no
lower court finding that that is what this fledgling ordinance
creates. And, given the opportunity, the District Court might find
that the county has a policy that precludes the administrator from
arbitrarily imposing fees. Of course, the District 142 Court might find that the administrator does possess too much
discretion. In either case, I believe findings by the District
Court on the issue would be preferable.
The Court relies on Ward v. Rock Against Racism, 491 U. S. 781 ,
795-796 (1989), for the proposition that the county's
interpretation of the ordinance must be considered. In that case,
however, we relied upon District Court findings concerning New York
City's limiting interpretation of a noise regulation. Id., at 795. I would prefer to remand this case so that the Court might
rely on such express findings here as well.
The Court's second reason for invalidating the ordinance is its
belief that any fee imposed will be based in part on the cost of
security necessary to control those who oppose the message
endorsed by those marching in a parade. Assuming 100 people march
in a parade and 10,000 line the route in protest, for example, the
Court worries that, under this ordinance, the county will charge a
premium to control the hostile crowd of 10,000, resulting in the
kind of "heckler's veto" we have previously condemned. Ante, at 133-136. But there have been no lower court findings on the
question whether or not the county plans to base parade fees on
anticipated hostile crowds. It has not done so in any of the
instances where it has so far imposed fees. Ante, at 132.
And it most certainly did not do so in this case. The District
Court below noted that: "[T]he instant ordinance alternatively permits fees to be
assessed based upon 'the expense incident to ... the maintenance of
public order.' If the county had applied this portion of the
statute, the phrase might run afoul of ... constitutional concerns
.... "However, in the instant case, plaintiff did not base their [sic] argument upon this phrase, but contended that the mere
fact that a $100 fee was imposed is unconstitutional, especially in
light of the organization's financial circumstances. The
evidence was clear that the 143 fee was based solely upon the costs of processing the
application and plaintiff produced no evidence to the contrary."
App. to Pet. for Cert. 14 (emphasis added). The Court's analysis on this issue rests on an assumption that
the county will interpret the phrase "maintenance of public order"
to support the imposition of fees based on opposition crowds. There
is nothing in the record to support this assumption, however, and I
would remand for a hearing on this question.
For the foregoing reasons, I dissent. | Forsyth County, Georgia, required permits for private demonstrations and other uses of public property, with fees of up to $1000 to cover administrative and security costs. The Supreme Court ruled that the ordinance was facially invalid as it gave too much discretion to the county administrator in setting fees without clear standards, and it was content-based as the administrator had to consider the content of the message, estimate public response, and determine security needs. The ordinance also potentially allowed fees to be influenced by hostile crowds, creating a "heckler's veto." |
Free Speech | Barnes v. Glen Theatre, Inc. | https://supreme.justia.com/cases/federal/us/501/560/ | U.S. Supreme Court Barnes v. Glen Theatre, Inc., 501
U.S. 560 (1991) Barnes v. Glen Theatre,
Inc. No. 90-26 Argued Jan. 8, 1991 Decided June 21, 1991 501
U.S. 560 CERTIORARI TO THE UNITED STATES
COURT OF APPEALS FOR THE SEVENTH
CIRCUIT Syllabus Respondents, two Indiana establishments wishing to provide
totally nude dancing as entertainment and individual dancers
employed at those establishments, brought suit in the District
Court to enjoin enforcement of the state public indecency law --
which requires respondent dancers to wear pasties and a G-string --
asserting that the law's prohibition against total nudity in public
places violates the First Amendment. The court held that the nude
dancing involved here was not expressive conduct. The Court of
Appeals reversed, ruling that nonobscene nude dancing performed for
entertainment is protected expression, and that the statute was an
improper infringement of that activity because its purpose was to
prevent the message of eroticism and sexuality conveyed by the
dancers. Held: The judgment is reversed.
904 F.2d 1081 (CA9 1990), reversed.
The CHIEF JUSTICE, joined by JUSTICE O'CONNOR and JUSTICE
KENNEDY, concluded that the enforcement of Indiana's public
indecency law to prevent totally nude dancing does not violate the
First Amendment's guarantee of freedom of expression. Pp. 501 U. S.
565 -572.
(a) Nude dancing of the kind sought to be performed here is
expressive conduct within the outer perimeters of the First
Amendment, although only marginally so. See, e.g., Doran v.
Salem Inn, Inc., 422 U. S. 922 , 422 U. S. 932 .
Pp. 501 U. S.
565 -566.
(b) Applying the four-part test of United States v.
O'Brien, 391 U. S. 367 , 391 U. S.
376 -377 -- which rejected the contention that symbolic
speech is entitled to full First Amendment protection -- the
statute is justified despite its incidental limitations on some
expressive activity. The law is clearly within the State's
constitutional power. And it furthers a substantial governmental
interest in protecting societal order and morality. Public
indecency statutes reflect moral disapproval of people appearing in
the nude among strangers in public places, and this particular law
follows a line of state laws, dating back to 1831, banning public
nudity. The States' traditional police power is defined as the
authority to provide for the public health, safety, and morals, and
such a basis for legislation Page 501 U. S. 561 has been upheld. See, e.g., Paris Adult Theatre I v.
Slaton, 413 U. S. 49 , 413 U. S. 61 .
This governmental interest is unrelated to the suppression of free
expression, since public nudity is the evil the State seeks to
prevent, whether or not it is combined with expressive activity.
The law does not proscribe nudity in these establishments because
the dancers are conveying an erotic message. To the contrary, an
erotic performance may be presented without any state interference,
so long as the performers wear a scant amount of clothing. Finally,
the incidental restriction on First Amendment freedom is no greater
than is essential to the furtherance of the governmental interest.
Since the statutory prohibition is not a means to some greater end,
but an end itself, it is without cavil that the statute is narrowly
tailored. Pp. 501 U. S.
566 -572.
JUSTICE SCALIA concluded that the statute -- as a general law
regulating conduct and not specifically directed at expression,
either in practice or on its face -- is not subject to normal First
Amendment scrutiny, and should be upheld on the ground that moral
opposition to nudity supplies a rational basis for its prohibition. Cf. Employment Division, Oregon Dept. of Human Resources v.
Smith, 494 U. S. 872 .
There is no intermediate level of scrutiny requiring that an
incidental restriction on expression, such as that involved here,
be justified by an important or substantial governmental interest.
Pp. 501 U. S.
572 -580.
JUSTICE SOUTER, agreeing that the nude dancing at issue here is
subject to a degree of First Amendment protection, and that the
test of United States v. O'Brien, 391 U.
S. 367 , is the appropriate analysis to determine the
actual protection required, concluded that the State's interest in
preventing the secondary effects of adult entertainment
establishments -- prostitution, sexual assaults, and other criminal
activity -- is sufficient under O'Brien to justify the
law's enforcement against nude dancing. The prevention of such
effects clearly falls within the State's constitutional power. In
addition, the asserted interest is plainly substantial, and the
State could have concluded that it is furthered by a prohibition on
nude dancing, even without localized proof of the harmful effects. See Renton v. Playtime Theatres, Inc., 475 U. S.
41 , 475 U. S. 50 .
Moreover, the interest is unrelated to the suppression of free
expression, since the pernicious effects are merely associated with
nude dancing establishments and are not the result of the
expression inherent in nude dancing. Id. at 475 U. S. 48 .
Finally, the restriction is no greater than is essential to further
the governmental interest, since pasties and a G-string moderate
expression to a minor degree when measured against the dancer's
remaining capacity and opportunity to express an erotic message.
Pp. 501 U. S.
581 -587. Page 501 U. S. 562 REHNQUIST, C.J., announced the judgment of the Court and
delivered an opinion in which O'CONNOR and KENNEDY, JJ., joined.
SCALIA, J., post, p. 501 U. S. 572 ,
and SOUTER, J., post, p. 501 U. S. 581 ,
filed opinions concurring in the judgment. WHITE, J., filed a
dissenting opinion, in which MARSHALL, BLACKMUN, and STEVENS, JJ.,
joined, post, p. 501 U. S.
587 .
CHIEF JUSTICE REHNQUIST delivered the opinion of the Court.
Respondents are two establishments in South Bend, Indiana, that
wish to provide totally nude dancing as entertainment, and
individual dancers who are employed at these Page 501 U. S. 563 establishments. They claim that the First Amendment's guarantee
of freedom of expression prevents the State of Indiana from
enforcing its public indecency law to prevent this form of dancing.
We reject their claim.
The facts appear from the pleadings and findings of the District
Court, and are uncontested here. The Kitty Kat Lounge, Inc. (Kitty
Kat) is located in the city of South Bend. It sells alcoholic
beverages and presents "go-go dancing." Its proprietor desires to
present "totally nude dancing," but an applicable Indiana statute
regulating public nudity requires that the dancers wear "pasties"
and a "G-string" when they dance. The dancers are not paid an
hourly wage, but work on commission. They receive a 100 percent
commission on the first $60 in drink sales during their
performances. Darlene Miller, one of the respondents in the action,
had worked at the Kitty Kat for about two years at the time this
action was brought. Miller wishes to dance nude because she
believes she would make more money doing so.
Respondent Glen Theatre, Inc., is an Indiana corporation with a
place of business in South Bend. Its primary business is supplying
so-called adult entertainment through written and printed
materials, movie showings, and live entertainment at an enclosed
"bookstore." The live entertainment at the "bookstore" consists of
nude and seminude performances and showings of the female body
through glass panels. Customers sit in a booth and insert coins
into a timing mechanism that permits them to observe the live nude
and seminude dancers for a period of time. One of Glen Theatre's
dancers, Gayle Ann Marie Sutro, has danced, modeled, and acted
professionally for more than 15 years, and in addition to her
performances at the Glen Theatre, can be seen in a pornographic
movie at a nearby theater. App. to Pet. for Cert. 131-133.
Respondents sued in the United States District Court for the
Northern District of Indiana to enjoin the enforcement of the
Indiana public indecency statute, Ind.Code § 35-45-4-1 Page 501 U. S. 564 (1988), asserting that its prohibition against complete nudity
in public places violated the First Amendment. The District Court
originally granted respondents' prayer for an injunction, finding
that the statute was facially overbroad. The Court of Appeals for
the Seventh Circuit reversed, deciding that previous litigation
with respect to the statute in the Supreme Court of Indiana and
this Court precluded the possibility of such a challenge, [ Footnote 1 ] and remanded to the
District Court in order for the plaintiffs to pursue their claim
that the statute violated the First Amendment as applied to their
dancing. Glen Theatre, Inc. v. Pearson, 802 F.2d 287,
288-290 (1986). On remand, the District Court concluded that Page 501 U. S. 565 "the type of dancing these plaintiffs wish to perform is not
expressive activity protected by the Constitution of the United
States," and rendered judgment in favor of the defendants. Glen
Theatre, Inc. v. Civil City of South Bend, 695 F.
Supp. 414 , 419 (ND Ind.1988). The case was again appealed to
the Seventh Circuit, and a panel of that court reversed the
District Court, holding that the nude dancing involved here was
expressive conduct protected by the First Amendment. Miller v.
Civil City of South Bend, 887 F.2d 826 (CA7 1989). The Court
of Appeals then heard the case en banc, and the court rendered a
series of comprehensive and thoughtful opinions. The majority
concluded that nonobscene nude dancing performed for entertainment
is expression protected by the First Amendment, and that the public
indecency statute was an improper infringement of that expressive
activity because its purpose was to prevent the message of
eroticism and sexuality conveyed by the dancers. Miller v.
Civil City of South Bend, 904 F.2d 1081 (CA7 1990). We granted
certiorari, 498 U.S. 807 (1990), and now hold that the Indiana
statutory requirement that the dancers in the establishments
involved in this case must wear pasties and a G-string does not
violate the First Amendment.
Several of our cases contain language suggesting that nude
dancing of the kind involved here is expressive conduct protected
by the First Amendment. In Doran v. Salem Inn, Inc., 422 U. S. 922 , 422 U. S. 932 (1975), we said:
"[A]lthough the customary 'barroom' type of nude dancing may
involve only the barest minimum of protected expression, we
recognized in California v. LaRue, 409 U. S.
109 , 409 U. S. 118 (1972), that
this form of entertainment might be entitled to First and
Fourteenth Amendment protection under some circumstances."
In Schad v. Borough of Mount Ephraim, 452 U. S.
61 , 452 U. S. 66 (1981), we said that "[f]urthermore, as the state courts in this
case recognized, nude dancing is not without its First Amendment
protections from official regulation" (citations omitted). These
statements support the conclusion of the Court of Appeals Page 501 U. S. 566 that nude dancing of the kind sought to be performed here is
expressive conduct within the outer perimeters of the First
Amendment, though we view it as only marginally so. This, of
course, does not end our inquiry. We must determine the level of
protection to be afforded to the expressive conduct at issue, and
must determine whether the Indiana statute is an impermissible
infringement of that protected activity.
Indiana, of course, has not banned nude dancing as such, but has
proscribed public nudity across the board. The Supreme Court of
Indiana has construed the Indiana statute to preclude nudity in
what are essentially places of public accommodation such as the
Glen Theatre and the Kitty Kat Lounge. In such places, respondents
point out, minors are excluded and there are no nonconsenting
viewers. Respondents contend that, while the state may license
establishments such as the ones involved here and limit the
geographical area in which they do business, it may not in any way
limit the performance of the dances within them without violating
the First Amendment. The petitioner contends, on the other hand,
that Indiana's restriction on nude dancing is a valid "time, place
or manner" restriction under cases such as Clark v. Community
for Creative Non-Violence, 468 U. S. 288 (1984).
The "time, place, or manner" test was developed for evaluating
restrictions on expression taking place on public property which
had been dedicated as a "public forum," Ward v. Rock Against
Racism, 491 U. S. 781 , 491 U. S. 791 (1989), although we have on at least one occasion applied it to
conduct occurring on private property. See Renton v. Playtime
Theatres, Inc., 475 U. S. 41 (1986). In Clark, we observed that this test has been
interpreted to embody much the same standards as those set forth in United States v. O'Brien, 391 U.
S. 367 (1968), and we turn, therefore, to the rule
enunciated in O'Brien. O'Brien burned his draft card on the steps of the South
Boston courthouse in the presence of a sizable crowd, and Page 501 U. S. 567 was convicted of violating a statute that prohibited the knowing
destruction or mutilation of such a card. He claimed that his
conviction was contrary to the First Amendment because his act was
"symbolic speech" -- expressive conduct. The court rejected his
contention that symbolic speech is entitled to full First Amendment
protection, saying:
"[E]ven on the assumption that the alleged communicative element
in O'Brien's conduct is sufficient to bring into play the First
Amendment, it does not necessarily follow that the destruction of a
registration certificate is constitutionally protected activity.
This Court has held that, when 'speech' and 'nonspeech' elements
are combined in the same course of conduct, a sufficiently
important governmental interest in regulating the nonspeech element
can justify incidental limitations on First Amendment freedoms. To
characterize the quality of the governmental interest which must
appear, the Court has employed a variety of descriptive terms:
compelling; substantial; subordinating; paramount; cogent; strong.
Whatever imprecision inheres in these terms, we think it clear that
a government regulation is sufficiently justified if it is within
the constitutional power of the Government; if it furthers an
important or substantial governmental interest; if the governmental
interest is unrelated to the suppression of free expression; and if
the incidental restriction on alleged First Amendment freedoms is
no greater than is essential to the furtherance of that
interest." Id. at 391 U. S.
376 -377 (footnotes omitted).
Applying the four-part O'Brien test enunciated above,
we find that Indiana's public indecency statute is justified
despite its incidental limitations on some expressive activity. The
public indecency statute is clearly within the constitutional power
of the State, and furthers substantial governmental interests. It
is impossible to discern, other than from the text of the statute,
exactly what governmental interest the Indiana legislators had in
mind when they enacted Page 501 U. S. 568 this statute, for Indiana does not record legislative history,
and the state's highest court has not shed additional light on the
statute's purpose. Nonetheless, the statute's purpose of protecting
societal order and morality is clear from its text and history.
Public indecency statutes of this sort are of ancient origin, and
presently exist in at least 47 States. Public indecency, including
nudity, was a criminal offense at common law, and this Court
recognized the common law roots of the offense of "gross and open
indecency" in Winters v. New York, 333 U.
S. 507 , 333 U. S. 515 (1948). Public nudity was considered an act malum en se. Le Roy v. Sidley, 1 Sid. 168, 82 Eng.Rep. 1036 (K.B.1664).
Public indecency statutes such as the one before us reflect moral
disapproval of people appearing in the nude among strangers in
public places.
This public indecency statute follows a long line of earlier
Indiana statutes banning all public nudity. The history of
Indiana's public indecency statute shows that it predates barroom
nude dancing, and was enacted as a general prohibition. At least as
early as 1831, Indiana had a statute punishing "open and notorious
lewdness, or . . . any grossly scandalous and public indecency."
Rev.Laws of Ind., ch. 26, § 60 (1831); Ind.Rev.Stat., ch. 53, § 81
(1834). A gap during which no statute was in effect was filled by
the Indiana Supreme Court in Ardery v. State, 56 Ind. 328
(1877), which held that the court could sustain a conviction for
exhibition of "privates" in the presence of others. The court
traced the offense to the Bible story of Adam and Eve. Id. at 329-330. In 1881, a statute was enacted that would remain
essentially unchanged for nearly a century:
"Whoever, being over fourteen years of age, makes an indecent
exposure of his person in a public place, or in any place where
there are other persons to be offended or annoyed thereby, . . . is
guilty of public indecency. . . ."
1881 Ind.Acts, ch. 37, § 90. Page 501 U. S. 569 The language quoted above remained unchanged until it was
simultaneously repealed and replaced with the present statute in
1976. 1976 Ind.Acts, Pub.L. 148, Art. 45, ch. 4, § 1. [ Footnote 2 ]
This and other public indecency statutes were designed to
protect morals and public order. The traditional police power of
the States is defined as the authority to provide for the public
health, safety, and morals, and we have upheld such a basis for
legislation. In Paris Adult Theatre I v. Slaton, 413 U. S. 49 , 413 U. S. 61 (1973), we said:
"In deciding Roth [v. United States, 354 U. S.
476 (1957)], this Court implicitly accepted that a
legislature could legitimately act on such a conclusion to protect
'the social interest in order and morality.' [ Id. ] at 354 U. S. 485 ."
(Emphasis omitted.) And in Bowers v. Hardwick, 478 U. S. 186 , 478 U. S. 196 (1986), we said:
"The law, however, is constantly based on notions of morality,
and if all laws representing essentially moral choices are to be
invalidated under the Due Process Clause, the courts will be very
busy indeed."
Thus, the public indecency statute furthers a substantial
government interest in protecting order and morality. Page 501 U. S. 570 This interest is unrelated to the suppression of free
expression. Some may view restricting nudity on moral grounds as
necessarily related to expression. We disagree. It can be argued,
of course, that almost limitless types of conduct -- including
appearing in the nude in public -- are "expressive," and in one
sense of the word this is true. People who go about in the nude in
public may be expressing something about themselves by so doing.
But the court rejected this expansive notion of "expressive
conduct" in O'Brien, saying:
"We cannot accept the view that an apparently limitless variety
of conduct can be labelled 'speech' whenever the person engaging in
the conduct intends thereby to express an idea."
391 U.S. at 391 U. S.
376 .
And in Dallas v. Stanglin, 490 U. S.
19 , we further observed:
"It is possible to find some kernel of expression in almost
every activity a person undertakes -- for example, walking down the
street or meeting one's friends at a shopping mall -- but such a
kernel is not sufficient to bring the activity within the
protection of the First Amendment. We think the activity of these
dance-hall patrons coming together to engage in recreational
dancing -- is not protected by the First Amendment." 490 U.S.
19 , 490 U. S.
25 .
Respondents contend that, even though prohibiting nudity in
public generally may not be related to suppressing expression,
prohibiting the performance of nude dancing is related to
expression because the state seeks to prevent its erotic message.
Therefore, they reason that the application of the Indiana statute
to the nude dancing in this case violates the First Amendment,
because it fails the third part of the O'Brien test, viz:
the governmental interest must be unrelated to the suppression of
free expression.
But we do not think that, when Indiana applies its statute to
the nude dancing in these nightclubs it is proscribing nudity
because of the erotic message conveyed by the dancers. Page 501 U. S. 571 Presumably numerous other erotic performances are presented at
these establishments and similar clubs without any interference
from the state, so long as the performers wear a scant amount of
clothing. Likewise, the requirement that the dancers don pasties
and a G-string does not deprive the dance of whatever erotic
message it conveys; it simply makes the message slightly less
graphic. The perceived evil that Indiana seeks to address is not
erotic dancing, but public nudity. The appearance of people of all
shapes, sizes and ages in the nude at a beach, for example, would
convey little if any erotic message, yet the state still seeks to
prevent it. Public nudity is the evil the state seeks to prevent,
whether or not it is combined with expressive activity.
This conclusion is buttressed by a reference to the facts of O'Brien. An act of Congress provided that anyone who
knowingly destroyed a selective service registration certificate
committed an offense. O'Brien burned his certificate on the steps
of the South Boston Courthouse to influence others to adopt his
anti-war beliefs. This Court upheld his conviction, reasoning that
the continued availability of issued certificates served a
legitimate and substantial purpose in the administration of the
selective service system. O'Brien's deliberate destruction of his
certificate frustrated this purpose and "for this noncommunicative
aspect of his conduct, and for nothing else, he was convicted." 391
U.S. at 391 U. S. 382 .
It was assumed that O'Brien's act in burning the certificate had a
communicative element in it sufficient to bring into play the First
Amendment, 391 U.S. at 391 U. S. 382 ,
but it was for the noncommunicative element that he was prosecuted.
So here with the Indiana statute; while the dancing to which it was
applied had a communicative element, it was not the dancing that
was prohibited, but simply its being done in the nude.
The fourth part of the O'Brien test requires that the
incidental restriction on First Amendment freedom be no greater
than is essential to the furtherance of the governmental interest.
As indicated in the discussion above, Page 501 U. S. 572 the governmental interest served by the text of the prohibition
is societal disapproval of nudity in public places and among
strangers. The statutory prohibition is not a means to some greater
end, but an end in itself. It is without cavil that the public
indecency statute is "narrowly tailored;" Indiana's requirement
that the dancers wear at least pasties and a G-string is modest,
and the bare minimum necessary to achieve the state's purpose.
The judgment of the Court of Appeals accordingly is Reversed. [ Footnote 1 ]
The Indiana Supreme Court appeared to give the public indecency
statute a limiting construction to save it from a facial
overbreadth attack:
"There is no right to appear nude in public. Rather, it may be constitutionally required to tolerate or to allow
some nudity as a part of some larger form of expression meriting
protection, when the communication of ideas is involved." State v. Baysinger, 272 Ind. 236, 247, 397 N.E.2d
580 , 587 (1979) (emphasis added), appeals dism'd sub nom.
Clark v. Indiana, 446 U.S. 931, and Dove v. Indiana, 449 U.S. 806 (1980).
Five years after Baysinger, however, the Indiana
Supreme Court reversed a decision of the Indiana Court of Appeals
holding that the statute did "not apply to activity such as the
theatrical appearances involved herein, which may not be prohibited
absent a finding of obscenity," in a case involving a partially
nude dance in the "Miss Erotica of Fort Wayne" contest. Erhardt
v. State, 468 N.E.2d
224 (Ind.1984). The Indiana Supreme Court did not discuss the
constitutional issues beyond a cursory comment that the statute had
been upheld against constitutional attack in Baysinger, and Erhardt's conduct fell within the statutory prohibition.
Justice Hunter dissented, arguing that
"a public indecency statute which prohibits nudity in any public
place is unconstitutionally overbroad. My reasons for so concluding
have already been articulated in State v. Baysinger, (1979) 272 Ind. 236, 397 N.E.2d
580 (Hunter and DeBruler, JJ., dissenting)." Id. at 225-226, 397 N.E.2d
580 . Justice DeBruler expressed similar views in his dissent in
Erhardt. Ibid. Therefore, the Indiana Supreme Court did
not affirmatively limit the reach of the statute in Baysinger, but merely said that, to the extent the First
Amendment would require it, the statute might be unconstitutional
as applied to some activities.
[ Footnote 2 ]
Indiana Code § 35-451 (1988) provides:
"Public Indecency"
"Sec. 1. (a) A person who knowingly or intentionally, in a
public place:"
"(1) engages in sexual intercourse;"
"(2) engages in deviate sexual conduct;"
"(3) appears in a state of nudity; or"
"(4) fondles the genitals of himself or another person;"
"commits public indecency, a Class A misdemeanor."
"(b) 'Nudity' means the showing of the human male or female
genitals, pubic area, or buttocks with less than a fully opaque
covering, the showing of the female breast with less than a fully
opaque covering of any part of the nipple, or the showing of the
covered male genitals in a discernibly turgid state."
JUSTICE SCALIA, concurring in the judgment.
I agree that the judgment of the Court of Appeals must be
reversed. In my view, however, the challenged regulation must be
upheld, not because it survives some lower level of First-Amendment
scrutiny, but because, as a general law regulating conduct and not
specifically directed at expression, it is not subject to
First-Amendment scrutiny at all. I Indiana's public indecency statute provides:
"(a) A person who knowingly or intentionally, in a public
place:"
"(1) engages in sexual intercourse;"
"(2) engages in deviate sexual conduct;"
"(3) appears in a state of nudity; or"
"(4) fondles the genitals of himself or another person;"
"commits public indecency, a Class A misdemeanor."
"(b) 'Nudity' means the showing of the human male or female
genitals, pubic area, or buttocks with less than a fully opaque
covering, the showing of the female breast with less than a fully
opaque covering of any part of the nipple, or the showing of
covered male genitals in a discernibly turgid state."
Ind.Code § 35-45-4-1 (1988). On its face, this law is not
directed at expression in particular. As Judge Easterbrook put it
in his dissent below:
"Indiana Page 501 U. S. 573 does not regulate dancing. It regulates public nudity. . . .
Almost the entire domain of Indiana's statute is unrelated to
expression, unless we view nude beaches and topless hot dog vendors
as speech." Miller v. Civil City of South Bend, 904 F.2d 1081, 1120
(CA7 1990) (Easterbrook, J., dissenting). The intent to convey a
"message of eroticism" (or any other message) is not a necessary
element of the statutory offense of public indecency; nor does one
commit that statutory offense by conveying the most explicit
"message of eroticism," so long as he does not commit any of the
four specified acts in the process. [ Footnote 2/1 ]
Indiana's statute is in the line of a long tradition of laws
against public nudity, which have never been thought to run afoul
of traditional understanding of "the freedom of speech." Public
indecency -- including public nudity -- has long been an offense at
common law. See 50 Am.Jur.2d 449, 472-474 (1970); 93
A.L.R. 996, 997-998 (1934); Winters v. New York, 333 U. S. 507 , 333 U. S. 515 (1948). Indiana's first public nudity statute, Rev.Laws of Indiana,
ch. 26, § 60 (1831), predated by many years the appearance of nude
barroom dancing. It was general in scope, directed at all public
nudity, and not just at public nude expression; and all succeeding
statutes, down to Page 501 U. S. 574 the present one, have been the same. Were it the case that
Indiana in practice targeted only expressive nudity, while
turning a blind eye to nude beaches and unclothed purveyors of hot
dogs and machine tools, see Miller, 904 F.2d at 1120,
1121, it might be said that what posed as a regulation of conduct
in general was in reality a regulation of only communicative
conduct. Respondents have adduced no evidence of that. Indiana
officials have brought many public indecency prosecutions for
activities having no communicative element. See Bond v.
State, 515
N.E.2d 856 , 857 (Ind.1987); In re
Levinson, 444 N.E.2d
1175 , 1176 (Ind.1983); Preston v. State, 259 Ind. 353,
354-355, 287 N.E.2d
347 , 348 (1972); Thomas v. State, 238 Ind. 658,
659-660, 154 N.E.2d
503 , 504-505 (1958); Blanton v. State, 533
N.E.2d 190 , 191 (Ind.App.1989); Sweeney v.
State, 486
N.E.2d 651 , 652 (Ind.App.1985); Thompson v.
State, 482 N.E.2d
1372 , 1373-1374 (Ind.App.1985); Adims v.
State, 461 N.E.2d
740 , 741-742 (Ind.App.1984); State v.
Elliott, 435 N.E.2d
302 , 304 (Ind.App.1982); Lasko v.
State, 409 N.E.2d
1124 , 1126 (Ind.App.1980). [ Footnote 2/2 ]
The dissent confidently asserts, post at 501 U. S.
590 -591, that the purpose of restricting nudity in
public places in general is to protect nonconsenting parties from
offense; and argues that, since only consenting, admission-paying
patrons see respondents dance, that purpose cannot apply, and the
only remaining purpose must relate to the communicative elements of
the performance. Perhaps the dissenters believe that "offense to
others" ought to be the only reason for restricting nudity in
public places generally, but there is no Page 501 U. S. 575 basis for thinking that our society has ever shared that
Thoreauvian "you may do what you like so long as it does not injure
someone else" beau ideal -- much less for thinking that it was
written into the Constitution. The purpose of Indiana's nudity law
would be violated, I think, if 60,000 fully consenting adults
crowded into the Hoosierdome to display their genitals to one
another, even if there were not an offended innocent in the crowd.
Our society prohibits, and all human societies have prohibited,
certain activities not because they harm others but because they
are considered, in the traditional phrase, " contra bonos
mores, " i.e., immoral. In American society, such
prohibitions have included, for example, sadomasochism,
cockfighting, bestiality, suicide, drug use, prostitution, and
sodomy. While there may be great diversity of view on whether
various of these prohibitions should exist (though I have found few
ready to abandon, in principle, all of them) there is no doubt
that, absent specific constitutional protection for the conduct
involved, the Constitution does not prohibit them simply because
they regulate "morality." See Bowers v. Hardwick, 478 U. S. 186 , 478 U. S. 196 (1986) (upholding prohibition of private homosexual sodomy enacted
solely on "the presumed belief of a majority of the electorate in
[the jurisdiction] that homosexual sodomy is immoral and
unacceptable"). See also Paris Adult Theatre I v. Slaton, 413 U. S. 49 , 413 U. S. 68 , n.
15 (1973); Dronenburg v. Zech, 239 U.S.App.D.C. 229, 238,
and n. 6, 741 F.2d 1388, 1397, and n. 6 (1984) (opinion of Bork,
J.). The purpose of the Indiana statute, as both its text and the
manner of its enforcement demonstrate, is to enforce the
traditional moral belief that people should not expose their
private parts indiscriminately, regardless of whether those who see
them are disedified. Since that is so, the dissent has no basis for
positing that, where only thoroughly edified adults are present,
the purpose must be repression of communication. [ Footnote 2/3 ] Page 501 U. S. 576 II Since the Indiana regulation is a general law not specifically
targeted at expressive conduct, its application to such conduct
does not, in my view, implicate the First Amendment.
The First Amendment explicitly protects "the freedom of speech
[and] of the press" -- oral and written speech -- not "expressive
conduct." When any law restricts speech, even for a purpose that
has nothing to do with the suppression of communication (for
instance, to reduce noise, see Saia v. New York, 334 U. S. 558 , 334 U. S. 561 (1948), to regulate election campaigns, see Buckley v.
Valeo, 424 U. S. 1 , 424 U. S. 16 (1976), or to prevent littering, see Schneider v. State, 308 U. S. 147 , 308 U. S. 163 (1939)), we insist that it meet the high First-Amendment standard
of justification. But virtually every law restricts conduct, and
virtually any prohibited conduct can be performed for an expressive
purpose -- if only expressive of the fact that the actor disagrees
with the prohibition. See, e.g., Florida Free Beaches, Inc. v.
Miami, 734 F.2d 608, 609 (1984) (nude sunbathers challenging
public indecency law claimed their "message" was that nudity is not
indecent). It cannot reasonably be demanded, therefore, that every
restriction of expression incidentally produced by a general law
regulating conduct pass normal First Amendment scrutiny, or even --
as some of our cases have suggested, see e.g., United States v.
O'Brien, 391 U. S. 367 , 391 U. S. 377 (1968) -- that it be justified by an "important or substantial" Page 501 U. S. 577 government interest. Nor do our holdings require such
justification: we have never invalidated the application of a
general law simply because the conduct that it reached was being
engaged in for expressive purposes and the government could not
demonstrate a sufficiently important state interest.
This is not to say that the First Amendment affords no
protection to expressive conduct. Where the government prohibits
conduct precisely because of its communicative attributes, we hold the regulation unconstitutional. See, e.g., United
States v. Eichman, 496 U. S. 310 (1990) (burning flag); Texas v. Johnson, 491 U.
S. 397 (1989) (same); Spence v. Washington, 418 U. S. 405 (1974) (defacing flag); Tinker v. Des Moines Independent
Community School District, 393 U. S. 503 (1969) (wearing black arm bands); Brown v. Louisiana, 383 U. S. 131 (1966) (participating in silent sit-in); Stromberg v.
California, 283 U. S. 359 (1931) (flying a red flag). [ Footnote
2/4 ] In each of the foregoing cases, we explicitly found that
suppressing communication was the object of the regulation of
conduct. Where that has not been the case, however -- where
suppression of communicative use of the conduct was merely the
incidental effect of forbidding the conduct for other reasons -- we
have allowed the regulation to stand. O'Brien, 391 U.S. at 391 U. S. 377 (law banning destruction of draft card upheld in application
against card-burning to protest Page 501 U. S. 578 war); FTC v. Superior Court Trial Lawyers Assn., 493 U. S. 411 (1990) (Sherman Act upheld in application against restraint of
trade to protest low pay); cf. United States v. Albertini, 472 U. S. 675 , 472 U. S.
687 -688 (1985) (rule barring petitioner from military
base upheld in application against entrance on base to protest
war); Clark v. Community for Creative Non-Violence, 468 U. S. 288 (1984) (rule barring sleeping in parks upheld in application
against persons engaging in such conduct to dramatize plight of
homeless). As we clearly expressed the point in Johnson: "The government generally has a freer hand in restricting
expressive conduct than it has in restricting the written or spoken
word. It may not, however, proscribe particular conduct because it has expressive elements. What might be termed
the more generalized guarantee of freedom of expression makes the
communicative nature of conduct an inadequate basis for
singling out that conduct for proscription."
491 U.S. at 491 U. S. 406 (internal quotations and citations omitted; emphasis in
original).
All our holdings (though admittedly not some of our discussion)
support the conclusion that
"the only First Amendment analysis applicable to laws that do
not directly or indirectly impede speech is the threshold inquiry
of whether the purpose of the law is to suppress communication. If
not, that is the end of the matter so far as First Amendment
guarantees are concerned; if so, the court then proceeds to
determine whether there is substantial justification for the
proscription." Community for Creative Non-Violence v. Watt, 227
U.S.App.D.C.19, 55-56, 703 F.2d 586, 622-623 (1983) (en banc)
(Scalia, J., dissenting) (footnote omitted; emphasis omitted), rev'd, 468 U. S. Community for Creative Non-Violence, 468 U.
S. 288 (1984). Such a regime ensures that the government
does not act to suppress communication, without requiring that all
conduct-restricting regulation Page 501 U. S. 579 (which means in effect all regulation) survive an enhanced level
of scrutiny.
We have explicitly adopted such a regime in another First
Amendment context: that of Free Exercise. In Employment
Division, Oregon Dept. of Human Resources v. Smith, 494 U. S. 872 (1990), we held that general laws not specifically targeted at
religious practices did not require heightened First Amendment
scrutiny even though they diminished some people's ability to
practice their religion.
"The government's ability to enforce generally applicable
prohibitions of socially harmful conduct, like its ability to carry
out other aspects of public policy, 'cannot depend on measuring the
effects of a governmental action on a religious objector's
spiritual development.'" Id. at 494 U. S. 885 ,
quoting Lyng v. Northwest Indian Cemetery Protective
Assn., 485 U. S. 439 , 485 U. S. 451 (1988); see also Minersville School District v. Gobitis, 310 U. S. 586 , 310 U. S.
594 -595 (1940) (Frankfurter, J.) ("Conscientious
scruples have not, in the course of the long struggle for religious
toleration, relieved the individual from obedience to a general law
not aimed at the promotion or restriction of religious beliefs.").
There is even greater reason to apply this approach to the
regulation of expressive conduct. Relatively few can plausibly
assert that their illegal conduct is being engaged in for religious
reasons; but almost anyone can violate almost any law as a means of
expression. In the one case, as in the other, if the law is not
directed against the protected value (religion or expression) the
law must be obeyed. III While I do not think the plurality's conclusions differ greatly
from my own, I cannot entirely endorse its reasoning. The plurality
purports to apply to this general law, insofar as it regulates this
allegedly expressive conduct, an intermediate level of First
Amendment scrutiny: the government interest in the regulation must
be " important or substantial,'" ante at 501 U. S. 567 ,
quoting O'Brien, 391 U.S. at 391 U. S. 377 .
As I have indicated, Page 501 U. S. 580 I do not believe such a heightened standard exists. I think we
should avoid wherever possible, moreover, a method of analysis that
requires judicial assessment of the "importance" of government
interests -- and especially of government interests in various
aspects of morality.
Neither of the cases that the plurality cites to support the
"importance" of the State's interest here, see ante at 501 U. S. 569 ,
is in point. Paris Adult Theatre I v. Slaton, 413 U.S. at 413 U. S. 61 ,
and Bowers v. Hardwick, 478 U.S. at 478 U. S. 196 ,
did uphold laws prohibiting private conduct based on concerns of
decency and morality; but neither opinion held that those concerns
were particularly "important" or "substantial," or amounted to
anything more than a rational basis for regulation. Slaton
involved an exhibition which, since it was obscene and at least to
some extent public, was unprotected by the First Amendment, see
Roth v. United States, 354 U. S. 476 (1957); the State's prohibition could therefore be invalidated only
if it had no rational basis. We found that the State's "right . . .
to maintain a decent society" provided a "legitimate" basis for
regulation -- even as to obscene material viewed by consenting
adults. 413 U.S. at 413 U. S. 59 -60.
In Bowers, we held that, since homosexual behavior is not
a fundamental right, a Georgia law prohibiting private homosexual
intercourse needed only a rational basis in order to comply with
the Due Process Clause. Moral opposition to homosexuality, we said,
provided that rational basis. 478 U.S. at 478 U. S. 196 .
I would uphold the Indiana statute on precisely the same ground:
moral opposition to nudity supplies a rational basis for its
prohibition, and since the First Amendment has no application to
this case, no more than that is needed. * * * * Indiana may constitutionally enforce its prohibition of public
nudity even against those who choose to use public nudity as a
means of communication. The State is regulating conduct, not
expression, and those who choose to employ conduct Page 501 U. S. 581 as a means of expression must make sure that the conduct they
select is not generally forbidden. For these reasons, I agree that
the judgment should be reversed.
[ Footnote 2/1 ]
Respondents assert that the statute cannot be characterized as a
general regulation of conduct, unrelated to suppression of
expression, because one defense put forward in oral argument below
by the attorney general referred to the "message of eroticism"
conveyed by respondents. But that argument seemed to go to whether
the statute could constitutionally be applied to the present
performances, rather than to what was the purpose of the
legislation. Moreover, the State's argument below was in the
alternative: (1) that the statute does not implicate the First
Amendment because it is a neutral rule not directed at expression,
and (2) that the statute in any event survives First Amendment
scrutiny because of the State's interest in suppressing nude
barroom dancing. The second argument can be claimed to contradict
the first (though I think it does not); but it certainly does not
waive or abandon it. In any case, the clear purpose shown by both
the text and historical use of the statute cannot be refuted by a
litigating statement in a single case.
[ Footnote 2/2 ]
Respondents also contend that the statute, as interpreted, is
not content-neutral in the expressive conduct to which it applies,
since it allegedly does not apply to nudity in theatrical
productions. See State v. Baysinger, 272 Ind. 236, 247, 397 N.E.2d
580 , 587 (1979). I am not sure that theater versus non-theater
represents a distinction based on content, rather than format, but
assuming that it does, the argument nonetheless fails for the
reason the plurality describes, ante at 501 U. S. 564 ,
n. 1.
[ Footnote 2/3 ]
The dissent, post at 501 U. S. 590 , 501 U. S.
595 -596 also misunderstands what is meant by the term
"general law." I do not mean that the law restricts the targeted
conduct in all places at all times. A law is "general" for the
present purposes if it regulates conduct without regard to whether
that conduct is expressive. Concededly, Indiana bans nudity in
public places, but not within the privacy of the home. (That is not
surprising, since the common law offense, and the traditional moral
prohibition, runs against public nudity, not against all
nudity. E.g., 50 Am.Jur.2d at 472-474.) But that confirms,
rather than refutes, the general nature of the law: one may not go
nude in public, whether or not one intends thereby to convey a
message, and similarly one may go nude in private, again
whether or not that nudity is expressive.
[ Footnote 2/4 ]
It is easy to conclude that conduct has been forbidden because
of its communicative attributes when the conduct in question is
what the Court has called "inherently expressive," and what I would
prefer to call "conventionally expressive" -- such as flying a red
flag. I mean by that phrase (as I assume the Court means by
"inherently expressive") conduct that is normally engaged in for
the purpose of communicating an idea, or perhaps an emotion, to
someone else. I am not sure whether dancing fits that description, see Dallas v. Stanglin, 490 U. S. 19 , 490 U. S. 24 (1989) (social dance group "do[es] not involve the sort of
expressive association that the First Amendment has been held to
protect"). But even if it does, this law is directed against
nudity, not dancing. Nudity is not normally engaged in for
the purpose of communicating an idea or an emotion.
JUSTICE SOUTER, concurring in the judgment.
Not all dancing is entitled to First Amendment protection as
expressive activity. This Court has previously categorized ballroom
dancing as beyond the Amendment's protection, Dallas v.
Stanglin, 490 U. S. 19 , 490 U. S. 24 -25
(1989), and dancing as aerobic exercise would likewise be outside
the First Amendment's concern. But dancing as a performance
directed to an actual or hypothetical audience gives expression at
least to generalized emotion or feeling, and where the dancer is
nude or nearly so, the feeling expressed, in the absence of some
contrary clue, is eroticism, carrying an endorsement of erotic
experience. Such is the expressive content of the dances described
in the record.
Although such performance dancing is inherently expressive,
nudity per se is not. It is a condition, not an activity,
and the voluntary assumption of that condition, without more,
apparently expresses nothing beyond the view that the condition is
somehow appropriate to the circumstances. But every voluntary act
implies some such idea, and the implication is thus so common and
minimal that calling all voluntary activity expressive would reduce
the concept of expression to the point of the meaningless. A search
for some expression beyond the minimal in the choice to go nude
will often yield nothing: a person may choose nudity, for example,
for maximum sunbathing. But when nudity is combined with expressive
activity, its stimulative and attractive value certainly can
enhance the force of expression, and a dancer's acts in going from
clothed to nude, as in a strip-tease, are integrated into the dance
and its expressive function. Thus, I agree with the plurality and
the dissent that an interest in freely engaging in the nude dancing
at issue here is subject to a degree of First Amendment
protection. Page 501 U. S. 582 I also agree with the plurality that the appropriate analysis to
determine the actual protection required by the First Amendment is
the four-part enquiry described in United States v.
O'Brien, 391 U. S. 367 (1968), for judging the limits of appropriate state action
burdening expressive acts as distinct from pure speech or
representation. I nonetheless write separately to rest my
concurrence in the judgment, not on the possible sufficiency of
society's moral views to justify the limitations at issue, but on
the State's substantial interest in combating the secondary effects
of adult entertainment establishments of the sort typified by
respondents' establishments.
It is, of course, true that this justification has not been
articulated by Indiana's legislature or by its courts. As the
plurality observes, "Indiana does not record legislative history,
and the state's highest court has not shed additional light on the
statute's purpose," ante at 501 U. S. 568 .
While it is certainly sound in such circumstances to infer general
purposes "of protecting societal order and morality . . . from [the
statute's] text and history," ibid., I think that we need
not so limit ourselves in identifying the justification for the
legislation at issue here, and may legitimately consider
petitioners' assertion that the statute is applied to nude dancing
because such dancing "encourag[es] prostitution, increas[es] sexual
assaults, and attract[s] other criminal activity." Brief for
Petitioners 37.
This asserted justification for the statute may not be ignored
merely because it is unclear to what extent this purpose motivated
the Indiana Legislature in enacting the statute. Our appropriate
focus is not an empirical enquiry into the actual intent of the
enacting legislature, but rather the existence or not of a current
governmental interest in the service of which the challenged
application of the statute may be constitutional. Cf. McGowan
v. Maryland, 366 U. S. 420 Page 501 U. S. 583 (1961). At least as to the regulation of expressive conduct,
[ Footnote 3/1 ]
"[w]e decline to void [a statute] essentially on the ground that
it is unwise legislation which [the legislature] had the undoubted
power to enact and which could be reenacted in its exact form if
the same or another legislator made a 'wiser' speech about it." O'Brien, supra, 391 U.S. at 391 U. S. 384 .
In my view, the interest asserted by petitioners in preventing
prostitution, sexual assault, and other criminal activity, although
presumably not a justification for all applications of the statute,
is sufficient under O'Brien to justify the State's
enforcement of the statute against the type of adult entertainment
at issue here.
At the outset, it is clear that the prevention of such evils
falls within the constitutional power of the State, which satisfies
the first O'Brien criterion. See id. at 391 U. S. 377 .
The second O'Brien prong asks whether the regulation "furthers an
important or substantial governmental interest." Ibid. The
asserted state interest is plainly a substantial one; the only
question is whether prohibiting nude dancing of the sort at issue
here "furthers" that interest. I believe that our cases have
addressed this question sufficiently to establish that it does.
In Renton v. Playtime Theatres, Inc., 475 U. S.
41 (1986), we upheld a city's zoning ordinance designed
to prevent the occurrence of harmful secondary effects, including
the crime associated with adult entertainment by protecting
approximately 95% of the city's area from the placement of motion
picture theaters emphasizing " matter depicting, describing or
relating to "specified sexual activities" or "specified anatomical
areas" . . . for observation by patrons therein.'" Id. at 475 U. S. 44 . Of
particular importance to the present enquiry, we held that the city
of Renton was not compelled to justify its restrictions by studies
specifically relating to the problems Page 501 U. S. 584 that would be caused by adult theaters in that city. Rather,
"Renton was entitled to rely on the experiences of Seattle and
other cities," id. at 475 U. S. 51 ,
which demonstrated the harmful secondary effects correlated with
the presence "of even one [adult] theater in a given neighborhood." Id. at 475 U. S. 50 ; cf. Young v. American Mini Theatres, Inc., 427 U. S.
50 , 427 U. S. 71 , n.
34 (1976) (legislative finding that "a concentration of `adult'
movie theaters causes the area to deteriorate and become a focus of
crime"); California v. LaRue, 409 U.
S. 109 , 409 U. S. 111 (1972) (administrative findings of criminal activity associated
with adult entertainment).
The type of entertainment respondents seek to provide is plainly
of the same character as that at issue in Renton, American Mini
Theatres, and LaRue. It therefore is no leap to say
that live nude dancing of the sort at issue here is likely to
produce the same pernicious secondary effects as the adult films
displaying "specified anatomical areas" at issue in Renton. Other reported cases from the Circuit in which
this litigation arose confirm the conclusion. See, e.g., United
States v. Marren, 890 F.2d 924, 926 (CA7 1989) (prostitution
associated with nude dancing establishment); United States v.
Doerr, 886 F.2d 944, 949 (CA7 1989) (same). In light of Renton's recognition that legislation seeking to combat
the secondary effects of adult entertainment need not await
localized proof of those effects, the State of Indiana could
reasonably conclude that forbidding nude entertainment of the type
offered at the Kitty Kat Lounge and the Glen Theatre's "bookstore"
furthers its interest in preventing prostitution, sexual assault,
and associated crimes. Given our recognition that
"society's interest in protecting this type of expression is of
a wholly different, and lesser, magnitude than the interest in
untrammeled political debate," American Mini Theatres, supra, 427 U.S. at 427 U. S. 70 , I
do not believe that a State is required affirmatively to undertake
to litigate this issue repeatedly in every Page 501 U. S. 585 case. The statute as applied to nudity of the sort at issue here
therefore satisfies the second prong of O'Brien. [ Footnote 3/2 ]
The third O'Brien condition is that the governmental
interest be "unrelated to the suppression of free expression," 391
U.S. at 391 U. S. 377 ,
and, on its face, the governmental interest in combating
prostitution and other criminal activity is not at all inherently
related to expression. The dissent contends, however, that Indiana
seeks to regulate nude dancing as its means of combating such
secondary effects
"because . . . creating or emphasizing [the] thoughts and ideas
[expressed by nude dancing] in the minds of the spectators may lead
to increased prostitution," post at 501 U. S. 592 ,
and that regulation of expressive conduct because of the fear that
the expression will prove persuasive is inherently related to the
suppression of free expression. Ibid. The major premise of the dissent's reasoning may be correct, but
its minor premise describing the causal theory of Indiana's
regulatory justification is not. To say that pernicious secondary
effects are associated with nude dancing establishments is not
necessarily to say that such effects result from the persuasive
effect of the expression inherent in nude dancing. It is to say,
rather, only that the effects are correlated with the existence of
establishments offering such dancing, without deciding what the
precise causes of the correlation Page 501 U. S. 586 actually are. It is possible, for example, that the higher
incidence of prostitution and sexual assault in the vicinity of
adult entertainment locations results from the concentration of
crowds of men predisposed to such activities, or from the simple
viewing of nude bodies, regardless of whether those bodies are
engaged in expression or not. In neither case would the chain of
causation run through the persuasive effect of the expressive
component of nude dancing.
Because the State's interest in banning nude dancing results
from a simple correlation of such dancing with other evils, rather
than from a relationship between the other evils and the expressive
component of the dancing, the interest is unrelated to the
suppression of free expression. Renton is again persuasive
in support of this conclusion. In Renton, we held that an
ordinance that regulated adult theaters because the presence of
such theaters was correlated with secondary effects that the local
government had an interest in regulating was content-neutral (a
determination similar to the "unrelated to the suppression of free
expression" determination here, see Clark v. Community for
Creative Non-Violence, 468 U. S. 288 , 468 U. S. 298 ,
and n. 8 (1984)) because it was " justified without
reference to the content of the regulated speech." 475 U.S. at 475 U. S. 48 (emphasis in original). We reached this conclusion without need to
decide whether the cause of the correlation might have been the
persuasive effect of the adult films that were being regulated.
Similarly here, the "secondary effects" justification means that
enforcement of the Indiana statute against nude dancing is
"justified without reference to the content of the regulated
[expression]," ibid. (emphasis omitted), which is
sufficient, at least in the context of sexually explicit
expression, [ Footnote 3/3 ] to
satisfy the third prong of the O'Brien test. Page 501 U. S. 587 The fourth O'Brien condition, that the restriction be
no greater than essential to further the governmental interest,
requires little discussion. Pasties and a G-string moderate the
expression to some degree, to be sure, but only to a degree.
Dropping the final stitch is prohibited, but the limitation is
minor when measured against the dancer's remaining capacity and
opportunity to express the erotic message. Nor, so far as we are
told, is the dancer or her employer limited by anything short of
obscenity laws from expressing an erotic message by articulate
speech or representational means; a pornographic movie featuring
one of respondents, for example, was playing nearby without any
interference from the authorities at the time these cases
arose.
Accordingly, I find O'Brien satisfied, and concur in
the judgment.
[ Footnote 3/1 ] Cf., e.g., Edwards v. Aguillard, 482 U.
S. 578 (1987) (striking down state statute on
Establishment Clause grounds due to impermissible legislative
intent).
[ Footnote 3/2 ]
Because there is no overbreadth challenge before us, we are not
called upon to decide whether the application of the statute would
be valid in other contexts. It is enough, then, to say that the
secondary effects rationale on which I rely here would be open to
question if the State were to seek to enforce the statute by
barring expressive nudity in classes of productions that could not
readily be analogized to the adult films at issue in Renton v.
Playtime Theatres, Inc., 475 U. S. 41 (1986). It is difficult to see, for example, how the enforcement of
Indiana's statute against nudity in a production of "Hair" or
"Equus" somewhere other than an "adult" theater would further the
State's interest in avoiding harmful secondary effects, in the
absence of evidence that expressive nudity outside the context of Renton -type adult entertainment was correlated with such
secondary effects.
[ Footnote 3/3 ]
I reach this conclusion again mindful, as was the Court in Renton, that the protection of sexually explicit
expression may be of lesser societal importance than the protection
of other forms of expression. See Renton, supra, at 475 U. S. 49 ,
and n. 2, citing Young v. American Mini Theatres, Inc., 427 U. S. 50 , 427 U. S. 70 (1976).
JUSTICE WHITE, with whom JUSTICE MARSHALL, JUSTICE BLACKMUN, and
JUSTICE STEVENS join, dissenting.
The first question presented to us in this case is whether
nonobscene nude dancing performed as entertainment is expressive
conduct protected by the First Amendment. The Court of Appeals held
that it is, observing that our prior decisions permit no other
conclusion. Not surprisingly, then, the Court now concedes that
"nude dancing of the kind sought to be performed here is expressive
conduct within the outer perimeters of the First Amendment. . . ." Ante at 501 U. S. 566 .
This is no more than recognizing, as the Seventh Circuit observed,
that dancing is an ancient art form and "inherently embodies the
expression and communication of ideas and emotions." Miller v.
Civil City of South Bend, 904 F.2d 1081, 1087 (1990) (en
banc). [ Footnote 4/1 ] Page 501 U. S. 588 Having arrived at the conclusion that nude dancing performed as
entertainment enjoys First Amendment protection, the Court states
that it must
"determine the level of protection to be afforded to the
expressive conduct at issue, and must determine whether the Indiana
statute is an impermissible infringement of that protected
activity." Ante at 501 U. S. 566 .
For guidance, the plurality turns to United States v.
O'Brien, 391 U. S. 367 (1968), which held that expressive conduct could be narrowly
regulated or forbidden in pursuit of an important or substantial
governmental interest that is unrelated to the content of the
expression. The plurality finds that the Indiana statute satisfies
the O'Brien test in all respects.
The plurality acknowledges that it is impossible to discern the
exact state interests which the Indiana legislature had in mind
when it enacted the Indiana statute, but the Court nonetheless
concludes that it is clear from the statute's text and history that
the law's purpose is to protect "societal order and morality." Ante at 501 U. S. 568 .
The plurality goes on to Page 501 U. S. 589 conclude that Indiana's statute "was enacted as a general
prohibition, " ante at 501 U. S. 568 (emphasis added), on people appearing in the nude among strangers
in public places. The plurality then points to cases in which we
upheld legislation based on the State's police power, and
ultimately concludes that the Indiana statute "furthers a
substantial government interest in protecting order and morality." Ante at 569. The plurality also holds that the basis for
banning nude dancing is unrelated to free expression, and that it
is narrowly drawn to serve the State's interest.
The plurality's analysis is erroneous in several respects. Both
the Court and JUSTICE SCALIA in his concurring opinion overlook a
fundamental and critical aspect of our cases upholding the States'
exercise of their police powers. None of the cases they rely upon,
including O'Brien and Bowers v. Hardwick, 478 U. S. 186 (1986), involved anything less than truly general proscriptions on individual conduct. In O'Brien, for
example, individuals were prohibited from destroying their draft
cards at any time and in any place, even in completely private
places such as the home. Likewise, in Bowers, the State
prohibited sodomy, regardless of where the conduct might occur,
including the home, as was true in that case. The same is true of
cases like Employment Division, Oregon Dept. of Human Resources
v. Smith, 494 U. S. 872 (1990), which, though not applicable here because it did not
involve any claim that the peyote users were engaged in expressive
activity, recognized that the State's interests in preventing the
use of illegal drugs extends even into the home. By contrast, in
this case, Indiana does not suggest that its statute applies to, or
could be applied to, nudity wherever it occurs, including the home.
We do not understand the Court or JUSTICE SCALIA to be suggesting
that Indiana could constitutionally enact such an intrusive
prohibition, nor do we think such a suggestion would be tenable in
light of our decision in Stanley v. Georgia, 394 U.
S. 557 , (1969), in which we held that States could not
punish the Page 501 U. S. 590 mere possession of obscenity in the privacy of one's own
home.
We are told by the Attorney General of Indiana that, in State v. Baysinger, 272 Ind. 236, 397 N.E.2d
580 (1979), the Indiana Supreme Court held that the statute at
issue here cannot and does not prohibit nudity as a part of some
larger form of expression meriting protection when the
communication of ideas is involved. Brief for Petitioners 25,
30-31; Reply Brief for Petitioners 9-11. Petitioners also state
that the evils sought to be avoided by applying the statute in this
case would not obtain in the case of theatrical productions, such
as Salome or Hair. Id. at 11-12. Neither
is there any evidence that the State has attempted to apply the
statute to nudity in performances such as plays, ballets or operas.
"No arrests have ever been made for nudity as part of a play or
ballet." App.19 (affidavit of Sgt. Timothy Corbett).
Thus, the Indiana statute is not a general prohibition
of the type we have upheld in prior cases. As a result, the Court's
and JUSTICE SCALIA's simple references to the State's general
interest in promoting societal order and morality is not sufficient
justification for a statute which concededly reaches a significant
amount of protected expressive activity. Instead, in applying the O'Brien test, we are obligated to carefully examine the
reasons the State has chosen to regulate this expressive conduct in
a less than general statute. In other words, when the State enacts
a law which draws a line between expressive conduct which is
regulated and nonexpressive conduct of the same type which is not
regulated, O'Brien places the burden on the State to
justify the distinctions it has made. Closer inquiry as to the
purpose of the statute is surely appropriate.
Legislators do not just randomly select certain conduct for
proscription; they have reasons for doing so, and those reasons
illuminate the purpose of the law that is passed. Indeed, a law may
have multiple purposes. The purpose of Page 501 U. S. 591 forbidding people from appearing nude in parks, beaches, hot dog
stands, and like public places is to protect others from offense.
But that could not possibly be the purpose of preventing nude
dancing in theaters and barrooms, since the viewers are exclusively
consenting adults who pay money to see these dances. The purpose of
the proscription in these contexts is to protect the viewers from
what the State believes is the harmful message that nude dancing
communicates. This is why Clark v. Community for Creative
Non-Violence, 468 U. S. 288 (1984), is of no help to the State:
"In Clark, . . . the damage to the parks was the same
whether the sleepers were camping out for fun, were in fact
homeless, or wished by sleeping in the park to make a symbolic
statement on behalf of the homeless."
904 F.2d at 1103 (Posner, J., concurring). That cannot be said
in this case: the perceived damage to the public interest caused by
appearing nude on the streets or in the parks, as I have said, is
not what the State seeks to avoid in preventing nude dancing in
theaters and taverns. There the perceived harm is the communicative
aspect of the erotic dance. As the State now tells us, and as
JUSTICE SOUTER agrees, the State's goal in applying what it
describes as its "content-neutral" statute to the nude dancing in
this case is "deterrence of prostitution, sexual assaults, criminal
activity, degradation of women, and other activities which break
down family structure." Reply Brief for Petitioners 11. The
attainment of these goals, however, depends on preventing an
expressive activity.
The plurality nevertheless holds that the third requirement of
the O'Brien test, that the governmental interest be
unrelated to the suppression of free expression, is satisfied,
because, in applying the statute to nude dancing, the State is not
"proscribing nudity because of the erotic message conveyed by the
dancers." Ante at 501 U. S. 570 . The plurality suggests that this is so
because the State does not ban dancing that sends an erotic
message; it is only nude erotic dancing that is forbidden. The
perceived evil is not erotic dancing, but public Page 501 U. S. 592 nudity, which may be prohibited despite any incidental impact on
expressive activity. This analysis is transparently erroneous.
In arriving at its conclusion, the Court concedes that nude
dancing conveys an erotic message, and concedes that the message
would be muted if the dancers wore pasties and G-strings. Indeed,
the emotional or erotic impact of the dance is intensified by the
nudity of the performers. As Judge Posner argued in his thoughtful
concurring opinion in the Court of Appeals, the nudity of the
dancer is an integral part of the emotions and thoughts that a nude
dancing performance evokes. Id. at 1090-1098. The sight of
a fully clothed, or even a partially clothed, dancer generally will
have a far different impact on a spectator than that of a nude
dancer, even if the same dance is performed. The nudity is itself
an expressive component of the dance, not merely incidental
"conduct." We have previously pointed out that " [n]udity alone'
does not place otherwise protected material outside the mantle of
the First Amendment." Schad v. Mt. Ephraim, 452 U. S.
61 , 452 U. S. 66 (1981). This being the case, it cannot be that the statutory prohibition
is unrelated to expressive conduct. Since the State permits the
dancers to perform if they wear pasties and G-strings, but forbids
nude dancing, it is precisely because of the distinctive,
expressive content of the nude dancing performances at issue in
this case that the State seeks to apply the statutory prohibition.
It is only because nude dancing performances may generate emotions
and feelings of eroticism and sensuality among the spectators that
the State seeks to regulate such expressive activity, apparently on
the assumption that creating or emphasizing such thoughts and ideas
in the minds of the spectators may lead to increased prostitution
and the degradation of women. But generating thoughts, ideas, and
emotions is the essence of communication. The nudity element of
nude dancing performances cannot Page 501 U. S. 593 be neatly pigeonholed as mere "conduct" independent of any
expressive component of the dance. [ Footnote 4/2 ]
That fact dictates the level of First Amendment protection to be
accorded the performances at issue here. In Texas v.
Johnson, 491 U. S. 397 , 491 U. S.
411 -412 (1989), the Court observed:
"Whether Johnson's treatment of the flag violated Texas law thus
depended on the likely communicative impact of his expressive
conduct. . . . We must therefore subject the State's asserted
interest in preserving the special symbolic character of the flag
to 'the most exacting scrutiny.' Boos v.
Barry , 485 U.S. [312], 485 U. S.
321 [(1988)]."
Content-based restrictions "will be upheld only if narrowly
drawn to accomplish a compelling governmental interest." United
States v. Grace, 461 U. S. 171 , 461 U. S. 177 (1983); Sable Communications of California, Inc. v. FCC, 492 U. S. 115 , 492 U. S. 126 (1989). Nothing could be clearer from our cases.
That the performances in the Kitty Kat Lounge may not be high
art, to say the least, and may not appeal to the Court, is hardly
an excuse for distorting and ignoring settled doctrine. The
plurality's assessment of the artistic merits of nude dancing
performances should not be the determining factor in deciding this
case. In the words of Justice Harlan,
"it is largely because governmental officials cannot make
principled decisions Page 501 U. S. 594 in this area that the Constitution leaves matters of taste and
style so largely to the individual." Cohen v. California, 403 U. S. 15 , 403 U. S. 25 (1971).
"[W]hile the entertainment afforded by a nude ballet at Lincoln
Center to those who can pay the price may differ vastly in content
(as viewed by judges) or in quality (as viewed by critics), it may
not differ in substance from the dance viewed by the person who . .
. wants some 'entertainment' with his beer or shot of rye." Salem Inn, Inc. v. Frank, 501 F.2d 18, 21, n. 3 (CA2
1974), aff'd in part, Doran v. Salem Inn, Inc., 422 U. S. 922 (1975).
The plurality and JUSTICE SOUTER do not go beyond saying that
the state interests asserted here are important and substantial.
But even if there were compelling interests, the Indiana statute is
not narrowly drawn. If the State is genuinely concerned with
prostitution and associated evils, as JUSTICE SOUTER seems to
think, or the type of conduct that was occurring in California
v. LaRue, 409 U. S. 109 (1972), it can adopt restrictions that do not interfere with the
expressiveness of nonobscene nude dancing performances. For
instance, the State could perhaps require that, while performing,
nude performers remain at all times a certain minimum distance from
spectators, that nude entertainment be limited to certain hours, or
even that establishments providing such entertainment be dispersed
throughout the city. Cf. Renton v. Playtime Theatres,
Inc., 475 U. S. 41 (1986). Likewise, the State clearly has the authority to
criminalize prostitution and obscene behavior. Banning an entire
category of expressive activity, however, generally does not
satisfy the narrow tailoring requirement of strict First Amendment
scrutiny. See Frisby v. Schultz, 487 U.
S. 474 , 487 U. S. 485 (1988). Furthermore, if nude dancing in barrooms as compared with
other establishments, is the most worrisome problem, the State
could invoke its Twenty-first Amendment powers and impose
appropriate regulation. New York State Liquor Authority v.
Bellanca, 452 U. S. 714 (1981) (per curiam); California v. LaRue, supra. Page 501 U. S. 595 As I see it, our cases require us to affirm, absent a compelling
state interest supporting the statute. Neither the Court nor the
State suggest that the statute could withstand scrutiny under that
standard.
JUSTICE SCALIA's views are similar to those of the Court, and
suffer from the same defects. The Justice asserts that a general
law barring specified conduct does not implicate the First
Amendment unless the purpose of the law is to suppress the
expressive quality of the forbidden conduct, and that, absent such
purpose, First Amendment protections are not triggered simply
because the incidental effect of the law is to proscribe conduct
that is unquestionably expressive. Cf. Community for Creative
Non-Violence v. Watt, 227 U.S.App.D.C. 19, 703 F.2d 586,
622-623 (1983) (SCALIA, J., dissenting). The application of the
Justice's proposition to this case is simple to state: the statute
at issue is a general law banning nude appearances in public
places, including barrooms and theaters. There is no showing that
the purpose of this general law was to regulate expressive conduct;
hence, the First Amendment is irrelevant, and nude dancing in
theaters and barrooms may be forbidden irrespective of the
expressiveness of the dancing.
As I have pointed out, however, the premise for the Justice's
position -- that the statute is a general law of the type
our cases contemplate -- is nonexistent in this case. Reference to
JUSTICE SCALIA's own hypothetical makes this clear. We agree with
JUSTICE SCALIA that the Indiana statute would not permit 60,000
consenting Hoosiers to expose themselves to each other in the
Hoosierdome. No one can doubt, however, that those same 60,000
Hoosiers would be perfectly free to drive to their respective homes
all across Indiana and, once there, to parade around, cavort, and
revel in the nude for hours in front of relatives and friends. It
is difficult to see why the State's interest in morality is any
less in that situation, especially if, as JUSTICE SCALIA seems to
suggest, nudity is inherently evil, but clearly the statute
does Page 501 U. S. 596 not reach such activity. As we pointed out earlier, the State's
failure to enact a truly general proscription requires closer
scrutiny of the reasons for the distinctions the State has drawn. See supra at 501 U. S.
590 .
As explained previously, the purpose of applying the law to the
nude dancing performances in respondents' establishments is to
prevent their customers from being exposed to the distinctive
communicative aspects of nude dancing. That being the case, JUSTICE
SCALIA's observation is fully applicable here: "Where government
prohibits conduct precisely because of its communicative
attributes, we hold the regulation unconstitutional." Ante at 501 U. S.
577 .
The O'Brien decision does not help JUSTICE SCALIA.
Indeed, his position, like the Court's, would eviscerate the O'Brien test. Employment Division, Oregon Dept. of
Human Resources v. Smith, 494 U. S. 872 (1990), is likewise not on point. The Indiana law, as applied to
nude dancing, targets the expressive activity itself; in Indiana,
nudity in a dancing performance is a crime because of the message
such dancing communicates. In Smith, the use of drugs was
not criminal because the use was part of or occurred within the
course of an otherwise protected religious ceremony, but because a
general law made it so, and was supported by the same interests in
the religious context as in others.
Accordingly, I would affirm the judgment of the Court of
Appeals, and dissent from this Court's judgment.
[ Footnote 4/1 ]
JUSTICE SCALIA suggests that performance dancing is not
inherently expressive activity, see ante at 501 U. S. 577 ,
n. 4, but the Court of Appeals has the better view:
"Dance has been defined as 'the art of moving the body in a
rhythmical way, usually to music, to express an emotion or idea, to
narrate a story, or simply to take delight in the movement itself.'
16 The New Encyclopedia Britannica 935 (1989). Inherently, it is
the communication of emotion or ideas. At the root of all"
"[t]he varied manifestations of dancing . . . lies the common
impulse to resort to movement to externalise states which we cannot
externalise by rational means. This is basic dance."
"Martin, J., Introduction to the Dance (1939).
Aristotle recognized in Poetics that the purpose of dance
is 'to represent men's character as well as what they do and
suffer.' The raw communicative power of dance was noted by the
French poet Stephane Mallarme, who declared that the dancer
'writing with her body . . . suggests things which the
written work could express only in several paragraphs of
dialogue or descriptive prose.'"
904 F.2d at 1085-1086. JUSTICE SCALIA cites Dallas v.
Stanglin, 490 U. S. 19 (1989), but that decision dealt with social dancing, not
performance dancing; and the submission in that case, which we
rejected, was not that social dancing was an expressive activity,
but that plaintiff's associational rights were violated by
restricting admission to dance halls on the basis of age. The
Justice also asserts that, even if dancing is inherently
expressive, nudity is not. The statement may be true, but it tells
us nothing about dancing in the nude.
[ Footnote 4/2 ]
JUSTICE SOUTER agrees with the Court that the third requirement
of the O'Brien test is satisfied, but only because he is
not certain that there is a causal connection between the message
conveyed by nude dancing and the evils which the State is seeking
to prevent. See ante at 501 U. S. 585 .
JUSTICE SOUTER's analysis is at least as flawed as that of the
Court. If JUSTICE SOUTER is correct that there is no causal
connection between the message conveyed by the nude dancing at
issue here and the negative secondary effects that the State
desires to regulate, the State does not have even a rational basis
for its absolute prohibition on nude dancing that is admittedly
expressive. Furthermore, if the real problem is the "concentration
of crowds of men predisposed to the" designated evils, ante at 501 U. S. 586 ,
then the First Amendment requires that the State address that
problem in a fashion that does not include banning an entire
category of expressive activity. See Renton v. Playtime
Theatres, Inc., 475 U. S. 41 (1986). | The Supreme Court ruled that enforcing Indiana's public indecency law to prevent totally nude dancing does not violate the First Amendment's freedom of expression. While nude dancing is considered expressive conduct within the First Amendment, it is only marginally protected. The Court applied the four-part test from United States v. O'Brien and concluded that the law is justified despite its limitations on expressive activity. The law is within the state's constitutional power, furthers a substantial government interest in protecting societal order and morality, and is unrelated to the suppression of free expression. |
Free Speech | Rust v. Sullivan | https://supreme.justia.com/cases/federal/us/500/173/ | U.S. Supreme Court Rust v. Sullivan, 500
U.S. 173 (1990) Rust v. Sullivan Nos. 89-1391, 89-1392 Argued Oct. 30, 1990 Decided May 23, 1991 500
U.S. 173 CERTIORARI TO THE UNITED STATES
COURT OF APPEALS FOR THE SECOND
CIRCUIT Syllabus Section 1008 of the Public Health Service Act specifies that
none of the federal funds appropriated under the Act's Title X for
family-planning services "shall be used in programs where abortion
is a method of family planning." In 1988, respondent Secretary of
Health and Human Services issued new regulations that, inter
alia, prohibit Title X projects from engaging in counseling
concerning, referrals for, and activities advocating abortion as a
method of family planning, and require such projects to maintain an
objective integrity and independence from the prohibited abortion
activities by the use of separate facilities, personnel, and
accounting records. Before the regulations could be applied,
petitioners -- Title X grantees and doctors who supervise Title X
funds -- filed suits, which were consolidated, challenging the
regulations' facial validity and seeking declaratory and injunctive
relief to prevent their implementation. In affirming the District
Court's grant of summary judgment to the Secretary, the Court of
Appeals held that the regulations were a permissible construction
of the statute and consistent with the First and Fifth
Amendments. Held: 1. The regulations are a permissible construction of Title X.
Pp. 500 U. S.
183 -191.
(a) Because § 1008 is ambiguous, in that it does not speak
directly to the issues of abortion counseling, referral, and
advocacy, or to "program integrity," the Secretary's construction
must be accorded substantial deference as the interpretation of the
agency charged with administering the statute, and may not be
disturbed as an abuse of discretion if it reflects a plausible
construction of the statute's plain language and does not otherwise
conflict with Congress' expressed intent. Chevron
U.S.A. Inc. v. Natural Resource Defense Council,
Inc. , 467 U. S. 837 , 467 U. S.
842 -844. P. 500 U. S.
184 .
(b) Title X's broad language plainly allows the abortion
counseling, referral, and advocacy regulations. Since the Title
neither defines Page 500 U. S. 174 § 1008's "method of family planning" phrase nor enumerates what
types of medical and counseling services are entitled to funding,
it cannot be said that the Secretary's construction of the § 1008
prohibition to require a ban on such activities within Title X
projects is impermissible. Moreover, since the legislative history
is ambiguous as to Congress' intent on these issues, this Court
will defer to the Secretary's expertise. Petitioners' contention,
that the regulations are entitled to little or no deference because
they reverse the Secretary's longstanding policy permitting
nondirective counseling and referral for abortion, is rejected.
Because an agency must be given ample latitude to adapt its rules
to changing circumstances, a revised interpretation may deserve
deference. The Secretary's change of interpretation is amply
supported by a "reasoned analysis" indicating that the new
regulations are more in keeping with the statute's original intent,
are justified by client experience under the prior policy, and
accord with a shift in attitude against the "elimination of unborn
children by abortion." Pp. 500 U. S. 184 -187.
(c) The regulations' "program integrity" requirements are not
inconsistent with Title X's plain language. The Secretary's view,
that the requirements are necessary to ensure that Title X grantees
apply federal funds only to authorized purposes and avoid creating
the appearance of governmental support for abortion-related
activities, is not unreasonable in light of § 1008's express
prohibitory language and is entltled to deference. Petitioners'
contention is unpersuasive that the requirements frustrate
Congress' intent, clearly expressed in the Act and the legislative
history, that Title X programs be an integral part of a broader,
comprehensive, health care system that envisions the efficient use
of non-Title X funds. The statements relied on are highly
generalized and do not directly address the scope of § 1008 and,
therefore, cannot form the basis for enjoining the regulations.
Indeed, the legislative history demonstrates that Congress intended
that Title X funds be kept separate and distinct from
abortion-related activities. Moreover, there is no need to
invalidate the regulations in order to save the statute from
unconstitutionality, since petitioners' constitutional arguments do
not carry the day. Pp. 500 U.S.
187 -191.
2. The regulations do not violate the First Amendment free
speech rights of private Title X fund recipients, their staffs, or
their patients by impermissibly imposing viewpoint-discriminatory
conditions on Government subsidies. There is no question but that §
1008's prohibition is constitutional, since the Government may make
a value judgment favoring childbirth over abortion, and implement
that judgment by the allocation of public funds. Maher v.
Roe, 432 U. S. 464 , 432 U. S. 474 .
In so doing, the Government has not discriminated on the basis of
viewpoint; it has merely chosen to fund one activity to the
exclusion of another. Similarly, Page 500 U. S. 175 in implementing the statutory prohibition by forbidding
counseling, referral, and the provision of information regarding
abortion as a method of family planning, the regulations simply
ensure that appropriated funds are not used for activities,
including speech, that are outside the federal program's scope. Arkansas Writers' Project, Inc. v. Ragland, 481 U.
S. 221 , distinguished. Petitioners' view that, if the
Government chooses to subsidize one protected right, it must
subsidize analogous counterpart rights, has been soundly rejected. See, e.g., Regan v. Taxation With Representation of Wash., 461 U. S. 540 . On
their face, the regulations cannot be read, as petitioners contend,
to bar abortion referral or counseling where a woman's life is
placed in imminent peril by her pregnancy, since it does not seem
that such counseling could be considered a "method of family
planning" under § 1008, and since provisions of the regulations
themselves contemplate that a Title X project could engage in
otherwise prohibited abortion-related activities in such
circumstances. Nor can the regulations' restrictions on the
subsidization of abortion-related speech be held to
unconstitutionally condition the receipt of a benefit, Title X
funding, on the relinquishment of a constitutional right, the right
to engage in abortion advocacy and counseling. The regulations do
not force the Title X grantee, or its employees, to give up
abortion-related speech; they merely require that such activities
be kept separate and distinct from the activities of the Title X
project. FCC v. League of Women Voters of Cal., 468 U. S. 364 , 468 U. S. 400 ; Regan, supra, 461 U.S. at 461 U. S. 546 ,
distinguished. Although it could be argued that the traditional
doctor-patient relationship should enjoy First Amendment protection
from Government regulation, even when subsidized by the Government, cf., e.g., United States v. Kokinda, 497 U.
S. 720 , 497 U. S. 726 ,
that question need not be resolved here, since the Title X program
regulations do not significantly impinge on the doctor-patient
relationship. Pp. 500 U. S.
192 -200.
3. The regulations do not violate a woman's Fifth Amendment
right to choose whether to terminate her pregnancy. The Government
has no constitutional duty to subsidize an activity merely because
it is constitutionally protected, and may validly choose to
allocate public funds for medical services relating to childbirth
but not to abortion. Webster v. Reproductive Health
Services, 492 U. S. 490 , 492 U. S. 510 .
That allocation places no governmental obstacle in the path of a
woman wishing to terminate her pregnancy, and leaves her with the
same choices as if the Government had chosen not to fund family
planning services at all. See, e.g., Harris v. McRae, 448 U. S. 297 , 448 U. S. 315 , 448 U. S. 317 ; Webster, supra, 492 U. S. 509 .
Nor do the regulations place restrictions on the patient/doctor
dialogue which violate a woman's right to make an informed and
voluntary choice under Akron v. Akron Center for
Reproductive Health, Inc. , 462 U.S. Page 500 U. S. 176 416, and Thornburg v. American College of Obstetricians and
Gynecologists, 476 U. S. 747 .
Unlike the laws invalidated in those cases, which required all
doctors to provide all pregnant patients contemplating abortion
with specific antiabortion information, here, a doctor's ability to
provide, and a woman's right to receive, abortion-related
information remains unfettered outside the context of the Title X
project. The fact that most Title X clients may be effectively
precluded by indigency from seeing a health care provider for
abortion-related services does not affect the outcome here, since
the financial constraints on such a woman's ability to enjoy the
full range of constitutionally protected freedom of choice are the
product not of governmental restrictions, but of her indigency. McRae, supra, 448 U.S. at 448 U. S. 316 .
Pp. 500 U. S.
201 -203.
889 F.2d 401 (C.A.2 1989), affirmed.
REHNQUIST, C.J., delivered the opinion of the Court, in which
WHITE, KENNEDY, SCALIA, and SOUTER, JJ., joined. BLACKMUN, J.,
filed a dissenting opinion, in which MARSHALL, J., joined; in Part
I of which O'CONNOR, J., joined; and in Parts II and III of which
STEVENS, J., joined, post, p. 500 U. S. 203 .
STEVENS, J., post, p. 500 U. S. 220 ,
and O'CONNOR, J., filed dissenting opinions, post, p. 500 U. S.
223 . Page 500 U. S. 177 CHIEF JUSTICE REHNQUIST delivered the opinion of the Court.
These cases concern a facial challenge to Department of Health
and Human Services (HHS) regulations which limit Page 500 U. S. 178 the ability of Title X fund recipients to engage in
abortion-related activities. The United States Court of Appeals for
the Second Circuit upheld the regulations, finding them to be a
permissible construction of the statute, as well as consistent with
the First and Fifth Amendments of the Constitution. We granted
certiorari to resolve a split among the Courts of Appeals.
[ Footnote 1 ] We affirm. I A In 1970, Congress enacted Title X of the Public Health Service
Act (Act), 84 stat. 1506, as amended, 42 U.S.C. §§ 300-300a6, which
provides federal funding for family planning services. The Act
authorizes the Secretary to
"make grants to and enter into contracts with public or
nonprofit private entities to assist in the establishment and
operation of voluntary family planning projects which shall offer a
broad range of acceptable and effective family Page 500 U. S. 179 planning methods and services."
42 U.S.C. § 300(a). Grants and contracts under Title X must "be
made in accordance with such regulations as the Secretary may
promulgate." 42 U.S.C. § 300a-4. Section 1008 of the Act, however,
provides that "[n]one of the funds appropriated under this
subchapter shall be used in programs where abortion is a method of
family planning." 42 U.S.C. § 300a-6. That restriction was intended
to ensure that Title X funds would
"be used only to support preventive family planning services,
population research, infertility services, and other related
medical, informational, and educational activities."
H.R. Conf.Rep. No. 91-1667, p. 8 (1970), U.S.Code Cong. &
Admin.News 1970, pp. 5068, 5081-82.
In 1988, the Secretary promulgated new regulations designed to
provide
"'clear and operational guidance' to grantees about how to
preserve the distinction between Title X programs and abortion as a
method of family planning."
53 Fed.Reg. 29232924 (1988). The regulations clarify, through
the definition of the term "family planning," that Congress
intended Title X funds "to be used only to support preventive family planning services." H.R.Conf. Rep. No.
91-1667, p. 8, U.S.Code Cong. & Admin.News 1970, p. 5081
(emphasis added). Accordingly, Title X services are limited to
"preconceptual counseling, education, and general reproductive
health care," and expressly exclude "pregnancy care (including
obstetric or prenatal care)." 42 CFR § 59.2 (1989). [ Footnote 2 ] The regulations
"focus the emphasis of the Title X program on its traditional
mission: the provision of preventive family planning services
specifically designed to enable individuals to determine the number
and spacing of their children, while clarifying that pregnant women
must be referred to appropriate prenatal care services."
53 Fed.Reg. 2925 (1988).
The regulations attach three principal conditions on the grant
of federal funds for Title X projects. First, the regulations
specify that a
"Title X project may not provide counseling concerning the use
of abortion as a method of family planning or provide referral for
abortion as a method of family planning."
42 CFR 59.8(a)(1) (1989). Because Title X is limited to
preconceptional services, the program does not furnish services
related to childbirth. Only in the context of a referral out of the
Title X program is a pregnant woman given transitional information.
§ 59.8(a)(2). Title X Page 500 U. S. 180 projects must refer every pregnant client
"for appropriate prenatal and/or social services by furnishing a
list of available providers that promote the welfare of the mother
and the unborn child." Ibid. The list may not be used indirectly to encourage
or promote abortion,
"such as by weighing the list of referrals in favor of health
care providers which perform abortions, by including on the list of
referral providers health care providers whose principal business
is the provision of abortions, by excluding available providers who
do not provide abortions, or by 'steering' clients to providers who
offer abortion as a method of family planning."
§ 59.8(a)(3). The Title X project is expressly prohibited from
referring a pregnant woman to an abortion provider, even upon
specific request. One permissible response to such an inquiry is
that
"the project does not consider abortion an appropriate method of
family planning, and therefore does not counsel or refer for
abortion."
§ 59.8(b)(5).
Second, the regulations broadly prohibit a Title X project from
engaging in activities that "encourage, promote or advocate
abortion as a method of family planning." § 59.10(a). Forbidden
activities include lobbying for legislation that would increase the
availability of abortion as a method of family planning, developing
or disseminating materials advocating abortion as a method of
family planning, providing speakers to promote abortion as a method
of family planning, using legal action to make abortion available
in any way as a method of family planning, and paying dues to any
group that advocates abortion as a method of family planning as a
substantial part of its activities. Ibid. B Third, the regulations require that Title X projects be
organized so that they are "physically and financially separate"
from prohibited abortion activities. § 59.9. To be deemed
physically and financially separate,
"a Title X project must have an objective integrity and
independence from prohibited activities. Mere bookkeeping
separation of Title X funds from other monies is not
sufficient." Ibid. The regulations Page 500 U. S. 181 provide a list of nonexclusive factors for the Secretary to
consider in conducting a case-by-case determination of objective
integrity and independence, such as the existence of separate
accounting records and separate personnel, and the degree of
physical separation of the project from facilities for prohibited
activities. Ibid. Petitioners are Title X grantees and doctors who supervise Title
X funds suing on behalf of themselves and their patients.
Respondent is the Secretary of the Department of Health and Human
Services. After the regulations had been promulgated, but before
they had been applied, petitioners filed two separate actions,
later consolidated, challenging the facial validity of the
regulations and seeking declaratory and injunctive relief to
prevent implementation of the regulations. Petitioners challenged
the regulations on the grounds that they were not authorized by
Title X and that they violate the First and Fifth Amendment rights
of Title X clients and the First Amendment rights of Title X health
providers. After initially granting the petitioners a preliminary
injunction, the District Court rejected petitioners' statutory and
constitutional challenges to the regulations and granted summary
judgment in favor of the Secretary. New York v.
Bowen, 690 F.
Supp. 1261 (SDNY 1988).
A panel of the Court of Appeals for the Second Circuit affirmed.
889 F.2d 401 (1989). Applying this Court's decision in Chevron U.S.A. Inc. v.
Natural Resources Defense Council, Inc. , 467 U. S. 837 , 467 U. S.
842 -843 (1984), the Court of Appeals determined that the
regulations were a permissible construction of the statute that
legitimately effectuated Congressional intent. The court rejected
as "highly strained," petitioners' contention that the plain
language of § 1008 forbids Title X projects only from performing
abortions. The court reasoned that
"it would be wholly anomalous to read Section 1008 to mean that
a program that merely counsels, but does not perform, abortions
does not include abortion as a 'method of family planning.'"
889 F.2d at 407. "[T]he natural Page 500 U. S. 182 construction of . . . the term method of family planning'
includes counseling concerning abortion." Ibid. The court
found this construction consistent with the legislative history,
and observed that "[a]ppellants' contrary view of the legislative history is based
entirely on highly generalized statements about the expansive scope
of the family planning services"
that "do not specifically mention counseling concerning abortion
as an intended service of Title X projects" and that "surely cannot
be read to trump a section of the statute that specifically
excludes it." Id. at 407-408.
Turning to petitioners' constitutional challenges to the
regulations, the Court of Appeals rejected petitioners' Fifth
Amendment challenge. It held that the regulations do not
impermissibly burden a woman's right to an abortion, because
the
"government may validly choose to favor childbirth over abortion
and to implement that choice by funding medical services relating
to childbirth but not those relating to abortion." Id. at 410. Finding that the prohibition on the
performance of abortions upheld by the Court in Webster v.
Reproductive Health Services, 492 U.
S. 490 (1989), was "substantially greater in impact than
the regulations challenged in the instant matter," 889 F.2d at 411,
the court concluded that the regulations "create[d] no affirmative
legal barriers to access to abortion." Ibid., citing Webster v. Reproductive Health Services. The court likewise found that the
"Secretary's implementation of Congress's decision not to fund
abortion counseling, referral or advocacy also does not, under
applicable Supreme Court precedent, constitute a facial violation
of the First Amendment rights of health care providers or of
women."
889 F.2d at 412. The court explained that, under Regan v.
Taxation With Representation of Wash., 461 U.
S. 540 (1983), the government has no obligation to
subsidize even the exercise of fundamental rights, including
"speech rights." The court also held that the regulations do not
violate the First Amendment by "condition[ing] receipt of a benefit
on the Page 500 U. S. 183 relinquishment of constitutional rights," because Title X
grantees and their employees "remain free to say whatever they wish
about abortion outside the Title X project." 889 F.2d at 412.
Finally, the court rejected petitioners' contention that the
regulations "facially discriminate on the basis of the viewpoint of
the speech involved." Id. at 414. II We begin by pointing out the posture of the cases before us.
Petitioners are challenging the facial validity of the regulations.
Thus, we are concerned only with the question whether, on their
face, the regulations are both authorized by the Act, and can be
construed in such a manner that they can be applied to a set of
individuals without infringing upon constitutionally protected
rights. Petitioners face a heavy burden in seeking to have the
regulations invalidated as facially unconstitutional.
"A facial challenge to a legislative Act is, of course, the most
difficult challenge to mount successfully, since the challenger
must establish that no set of circumstances exists under which the
Act would be valid. The fact that [the regulations] might operate
unconstitutionally under some conceivable set of circumstances is
insufficient to render [them] wholly invalid." United States v. Salerno, 481 U.
S. 739 , 481 U. S. 745 (1987).
We turn first to petitioners' contention that the regulations
exceed the Secretary's authority under Title X, and are arbitrary
and capricious. We begin with an examination of the regulations
concerning abortion counseling, referral, and advocacy, which every
Court of Appeals has found to be authorized by the statute, and
then turn to the "program integrity requirement," with respect to
which the courts below have adopted conflicting positions. We then
address petitioner's claim that the regulations must be struck down
because they raise a substantial constitutional question. Page 500 U. S. 184 A We need not dwell on the plain language of the statute, because
we agree with every court to have addressed the issue that the
language is ambiguous. The language of § 1008 -- that "[n]one of
the funds appropriated under this subchapter shall be used in
programs where abortion is a method of family planning" -- does not
speak directly to the issues of counseling, referral, advocacy, or
program integrity. If a statute is
"silent or ambiguous with respect to the specific issue, the
question for the court is whether the agency's answer is based on a
permissible construction of the statute." Chevron, 467 U.S. at 467 U. S.
842 -843.
The Secretary's construction of Title X may not be disturbed as
an abuse of discretion if it reflects a plausible construction of
the plain language of the statute and does not otherwise conflict
with Congress' expressed intent. Ibid. In determining
whether a construction is permissible,
"[t]he court need not conclude that the agency construction was
the only one it could permissibly have adopted . . . or even the
reading the court would have reached if the question initially had
arisen in a judicial proceeding." Id. at 467 U. S. 843 ,
n. 11. Rather, substantial deference is accorded to the
interpretation of the authorizing statute by the agency authorized
with administering it. Id. at 467 U. S.
844 .
The broad language of Title X plainly allows the Secretary's
construction of the statute. By its own terms, § 1008 prohibits the
use of Title X funds "in programs where abortion is a method of
family planning." Title X does not define the term "method of
family planning," nor does it enumerate what types of medical and
counseling services are entitled to Title X funding. Based on the
broad directives provided by Congress in Title X in general and §
1008 in particular, we are unable to say that the Secretary's
construction of the prohibition in § 1008 to require a ban on
counseling, referral, and advocacy within the Title X project is
impermissible. Page 500 U. S. 185 The District Courts and Courts of Appeals that have examined the
legislative history have all found, at least with regard to the
Act's counseling, referral, and advocacy provisions, that the
legislative history is ambiguous with respect to Congress' intent
in enacting Title X and the prohibition of § 1008. Massachusetts v. Sullivan, 899 F.2d 53, 62 (CA1 1990)
("Congress has not addressed specifically the question of the scope
of the abortion prohibition. The language of the statute and the
legislative history can support either of the litigants'
positions"); Planned Parenthood Federation of America v.
Sullivan, 913 F.2d 1492, 1497 (CA10 1990) ("[T]he
contemporaneous legislative history does not address whether
clinics receiving Title X funds can engage in nondirective
counseling including the abortion option and referrals"); New
York v. Sullivan, 889 F.2d 401, 407 (CA2 1989) (case below)
("Nothing in the legislative history of Title X detracts" from the
Secretary's construction of § 1008). We join these courts in
holding that the legislative history is ambiguous, and fails to
shed light on relevant congressional intent. At no time did
Congress directly address the issues of abortion counseling,
referral, or advocacy. The parties' attempts to characterize highly
generalized, conflicting statements in the legislative history into
accurate revelations of congressional intent are unavailing.
[ Footnote 3 ] Page 500 U. S. 186 When we find, as we do here, that the legislative history is
ambiguous and unenlightening on the matters with respect to which
the regulations deal, we customarily defer to the expertise of the
agency. Petitioners argue, however, that the regulations are
entitled to little or no deference, because they "reverse a
longstanding agency policy that permitted nondirective counseling
and referral for abortion," Brief for Petitioners in No. 89-1392,
p. 20, and thus represent a sharp beak from the Secretary's prior
construction of the statute. Petitioners argue that the agency's
prior consistent interpretation of Section 1008 to permit
nondirective counseling and to encourage coordination with local
and state family planning services is entitled to substantial
weight.
This Court has rejected the argument that an agency's
interpretation "is not entitled to deference because it represents
a sharp break with prior interpretations" of the statute in
question. Chevron, 467 U.S. at 467 U. S. 862 .
In Chevron, we held that a revised interpretation deserves
deference because "[a]n initial agency interpretation is not
instantly carved in stone," and "the agency, to engage in informed
rulemaking, must consider varying interpretations and the wisdom of
its policy on a continuing basis." Id. at 467 U. S.
863 -864. An agency is not required to " establish
rules of conduct to last forever,'" Motor
Vehicle Mfrs. Assn. of United States v.
State Page 500 U. S. 187 Farm Mutual Automobile Ins. Co., 463 U. S.
29 , 463 U. S. 42 (1983), quoting American Trucking Assns., Inc. v. Atchinson, T.
& S.F.R. Co., 387 U. S. 397 , 387 U. S. 416 (1967); NLRB v. Curtin Matheson Scientific, Inc., 494 U. S. 775 (1990), but rather "must be given ample latitude to `adapt [its]
rules and policies to the demands of changing circumstances.'" Motor Vehicle Mfrs., supra, 463 U.S. at 463 U. S. 42 ,
quoting Permian Basin Area Rate Cases, 390 U.
S. 747 , 390 U. S. 784 (1968).
We find that the Secretary amply justified his change of
interpretation with a "reasoned analysis." Motor Vehicle Mfrs.,
supra, 463 U.S. at 463 U. S. 42 .
The Secretary explained that the regulations are a result of his
determination, in the wake of the critical reports of the General
Accounting Office (GAO) and the Office of the Inspector General
(OIG), that prior policy failed to implement properly the statute
and that it was necessary to provide "clear and operational
guidance to grantees to preserve the distinction between Title X
programs and abortion as a method of family planning." 53 Fed.Reg.
2923-2924 (1988). He also determined that the new regulations are
more in keeping with the original intent of the statute, are
justified by client experience under the prior policy, and are
supported by a shift in attitude against the "elimination of unborn
children by abortion." We believe that these justifications are
sufficient to support the Secretary's revised approach. Having
concluded that the plain language and legislative history are
ambiguous as to Congress' intent in enacting Title X, we must defer
to the Secretary's permissible construction of the statute. B We turn next to the "program integrity" requirements embodied at
§ 59.9 of the regulations, mandating separate facilities,
personnel, and records. These requirements are not inconsistent
with the plain language of Title X. Petitioners contend, however,
that they are based on an impermissible construction of the statute
because they frustrate the clearly Page 500 U. S. 188 expressed intent of Congress that Title X programs be an
integral part of a broader, comprehensive, health care system. They
argue that this integration is impermissibly burdened because the
efficient use of nonTitle X funds by Title X grantees will be
adversely affected by the regulations.
The Secretary defends the separation requirements of § 59.9 on
the grounds that they are necessary to assure that Title X grantees
apply federal funds only to federally authorized purposes and that
grantees avoid creating the appearance that the government is
supporting abortion-related activities. The program integrity
regulations were promulgated in direct response to the observations
in the GAO and OIG reports that,
"[b]ecause the distinction between the recipient's title X and
other activities may not be easily recognized, the public can get
the impression that Federal funds are being improperly used for
abortion activities."
App. 85. The Secretary concluded that:
"[M]eeting the requirement of section 1008 mandates that Title X
programs be organized so that they are physically and financially
separate from other activities which are prohibited from inclusion
in a Title X program. Having a program that is separate from such
activities is a necessary predicate to any determination that
abortion is not being included as a method of family planning in
the Title X program."
53 Fed.Reg. 2940 (1988). The Secretary further argues that the
separation requirements do not represent a deviation from past
policy because the agency has consistently taken the position that
§ 1008 requires some degree of physical and financial separation
between Title X projects and abortion-related activities.
We agree that the program integrity requirements are based on a
permissible construction of the statute, and are not inconsistent
with Congressional intent. As noted, the legislative history is
clear about very little, and program integrity is no exception. The
statements relied upon by the petitioners Page 500 U. S. 189 to infer such an intent are highly generalized, and do not
directly address the scope of § 1008.
For example, the cornerstone of the conclusion that, in Title X,
Congress intended a comprehensive, integrated system of family
planning services is the statement in the statute requiring state
health authorities applying for Title X funds to submit "a state
plan for a coordinated and comprehensive program of family planning
services." § 1002. This statement is, on its face, ambiguous as to
Congress' intent in enacting Title X and the prohibition of § 1008.
Placed in context, the statement merely requires that a State
health authority submit a plan for a "coordinated and comprehensive
program of family planning services" in order to be eligible for
Title X funds. By its own terms, the language evinces Congress'
intent to place a duty on state entities seeking federal funds; it
does not speak either to an overall view of family planning
services or to the Secretary's responsibility for implementing the
statute. Likewise, the statement in the original House Report on
Title X that the Act was "not intended to interfere with or limit
programs conducted in accordance with State or local laws" and
supported through non-Title X funds is equally unclear. H.R.
Conf.Rep. No. 91-1667, pp. 8-9 (1970), U.S.Code Cong. &
Admin.News 1970, p. 5082. This language directly follows the
statement that it is the
"intent of both Houses that the funds authorized under this
legislation be used only to support preventive family planning
services. . . . The conferees have adopted the language contained
in section 1008, which prohibits the use of such funds for
abortion, in order to make this intent clear." Id. at 8, U.S.Code Cong. & Admin.News 1970, pp.
5081-82. When placed in context and read in light of the express
prohibition of § 1008, the statements fall short of evidencing a
congressional intent that would render the Secretary's
interpretation of the statute impermissible.
While the petitioners' interpretation of the legislative history
may be a permissible one, it is by no means the only one, and it is
certainly not the one found by the Secretary. It is well Page 500 U. S. 190 established that legislative history which does not demonstrate
a clear and certain congressional intent cannot form the basis for
enjoining the regulations. See Motor Vehicle Mfrs., 463
U.S. at 463 U. S. 42 .
The Secretary based the need for the separation requirements
"squarely on the congressional intent that abortion not be a part
of a Title X funded program." 52 Fed.Reg. 33212 (1987). Indeed, if
one thing is clear from the legislative history, it is that
Congress intended that Title X funds be kept separate and distinct
from abortion-related activities. It is undisputed that Title X was
intended to provide primarily prepregnancy preventive services.
Certainly the Secretary's interpretation of the statute that
separate facilities are necessary, especially in light of the
express prohibition of § 1008, cannot be judged unreasonable.
Accordingly, we defer to the Secretary's reasoned determination
that the program integrity requirements are necessary to implement
the prohibition.
Petitioners also contend that the regulations must be
invalidated because they raise serious questions of constitutional
law. They rely on Edward J. Debartolo Corp. v. Florida Gulf
Coast Building and Construction Trades Council, 485 U.
S. 568 (1988), and NLRB v. Catholic Bishop of
Chicago, 440 U. S. 490 (1979), which hold that "an Act of Congress ought not to be
construed to violate the Constitution if any other possible
construction remains available." Id. at 440 U. S. 500 .
Under this canon of statutory construction, "[t]he elementary rule
is that every reasonable construction must be resorted to in order
to save a statute from unconstitutionality." Debartolo Corp., supra, 485 U.S. at 485 U. S. 575 (emphasis added) quoting Hooper v. California, 155 U. S. 648 , 155 U. S. 657 (1895).
The principle enunciated in Hooper v. California,
supra, and subsequent cases is a categorical one:
"as between two possible interpretations of a statute, by one of
which it would be unconstitutional and by the other valid, our
plain duty is to adopt that which will save the Act." Blodgett v. Holden, 275 U. S. 142 , 275 U. S. 148 (1927) (opinion of Holmes, J.). This principle Page 500 U. S. 191 is based at least in part on the fact that a decision to declare
an act of Congress unconstitutional "is the gravest and most
delicate duty that this Court is called on to perform." Id. Following Hooper, supra, cases such as United States v. Delaware and Hudson Co., 213 U.
S. 366 , 213 U. S. 408 ,
and United States v. Jin Fuey Moy, 241 U.
S. 394 , 241 U. S. 401 ,
developed the corollary doctrine that
"[a] statute must be construed, if fairly possible, so as to
avoid not only the conclusion that it is unconstitutional but also
grave doubts upon that score." Jin Fuey Moy, supra, at 9241 U.S. 401401. This canon is
followed out of respect for Congress, which we assume legislates in
the light of constitutional limitations. FTC v. American
Tobacco Co., 264 U. S. 298 , 264 U. S.
305 -307 (1924). It is qualified by the proposition that
"avoidance of a difficulty will not be pressed to the point of
disingenuous evasion." Moore Ice Cream Co. v. Rose, 289 U. S. 373 , 289 U. S. 379 (1933).
Here Congress forbade the use of appropriated funds in programs
where abortion is a method of family planning. It authorized the
Secretary to promulgate regulations implementing this provision.
The extensive litigation regarding governmental restrictions on
abortion since our decision in Roe v. Wade, 410 U.
S. 113 (1973), suggests that it was likely that any set
of regulations promulgated by the Secretary -- other than the ones
in force prior to 1988 and found by him to be relatively toothless
and ineffectual -- would be challenged on constitutional grounds.
While we do not think that the constitutional arguments made by
petitioners in this case are without some force, in 500 U.
S. infra, we hold that they do not carry the
day. Applying the canon of construction under discussion as best we
can, we hold that the regulations promulgated by the Secretary do
not raise the sort of "grave and doubtful constitutional
questions," Delaware and Hudson Co., supra, 213 U.S. at 213 U. S. 408 ,
that would lead us to assume Congress did not intend to authorize
their issuance. Therefore, we need not invalidate the regulations
in order to save the statute from unconstitutionality. Page 500 U. S. 192 III Petitioners contend that the regulations violate the First
Amendment by impermissibly discriminating based on viewpoint
because they prohibit
"all discussion about abortion as a lawful option -- including
counseling, referral, and the provision of neutral and accurate
information about ending a pregnancy -- while compelling the clinic
or counselor to provide information that promotes continuing a
pregnancy to term."
Brief for Petitioners in No. 891391, p. 11. They assert that the
regulations violate the "free speech rights of private health care
organizations that receive Title X funds, of their staff, and of
their patients" by impermissibly imposing "viewpoint-discriminatory
conditions on government subsidies," and thus penaliz[e] speech
funded with non-Title X monies. Id. at 13, 14, 24.
Because
"Title X continues to fund speech ancillary to pregnancy testing
in a manner that is not evenhanded with respect to views and
information about abortion, it invidiously discriminates on the
basis of viewpoint." Id. at 18. Relying on Regan v. Taxation With
Representation of Wash. and Arkansas Writers Project, Inc.
v. Ragland, 481 U. S. 221 , 481 U. S. 234 (1987), petitioners also assert that, while the Government may
place certain conditions on the receipt of federal subsidies, it
may not "discriminate invidiously in its subsidies in such a way as
to ai[m] at the suppression of dangerous ideas.'" Regan,
supra, 461 U.S. at 461 U. S. 548 (quoting Cammarano v. United States, 358 U.
S. 498 , 358 U. S. 513 (1959)). There is no question but that the statutory prohibition
contained in § 1008 is constitutional. In Maher v. Roe,
supra, we upheld a state welfare regulation under which
Medicaid recipients received payments for services related to
childbirth, but not for nontherapeutic abortions. The Court
rejected the claim that this unequal subsidization worked a
violation of the Constitution. We held that the government may
"make a value judgment favoring childbirth over abortion, and . . .
implement that judgment by the allocation Page 500 U. S. 193 of public funds." Id. 432 U.S. at 432 U. S. 474 .
Here the Government is exercising the authority it possesses under Maher and McRae to subsidize family planning
services which will lead to conception and childbirth, and
declining to "promote or encourage abortion." The Government can,
without violating the Constitution, selectively fund a program to
encourage certain activities it believes to be in the public
interest, without at the same time funding an alternate program
which seeks to deal with the problem in another way. In so doing,
the Government has not discriminated on the basis of viewpoint; it
has merely chosen to fund one activity to the exclusion of the
other. "[A] legislature's decision not to subsidize the exercise of
a fundamental right does not infringe the right." Regan,
supra, 461 U.S. at 461 U. S. 549 . See also Buckley v. Valeo, 424 U. S.
1 (1976); Cammarano v. United States, supra. "A
refusal to fund protected activity, without more, cannot be equated
with the imposition of a penalty' on that activity." McRae, 448 U.S. at 448 U. S. 317 ,
n.19. "There is a basic difference between direct state interference
with a protected activity and state encouragement of an alternative
activity consonant with legislative policy." Maher, 432 U.S. at 432 U. S.
475 .
The challenged regulations implement the statutory prohibition
by prohibiting counseling, referral, and the provision of
information regarding abortion as a method of family planning. They
are designed to ensure that the limits of the federal program are
observed. The Title X program is designed not for prenatal care,
but to encourage family planning. A doctor who wished to offer
prenatal care to a project patient who became pregnant could
properly be prohibited from doing so because such service is
outside the scope of the federally funded program. The regulations
prohibiting abortion counseling and referral are of the same ilk;
"no funds appropriated for the project may be used in programs
where abortion is a method of family planning," and a doctor
employed by the project may be prohibited in Page 500 U. S. 194 the course of his project duties from counseling abortion or
referring for abortion. This is not a case of the Government
"suppressing a dangerous idea," but of a prohibition on a project
grantee or its employees from engaging in activities outside of its
scope.
To hold that the Government unconstitutionally discriminates on
the basis of viewpoint when it chooses to fund a program dedicated
to advance certain permissible goals because the program, in
advancing those goals, necessarily discourages alternate goals
would render numerous government programs constitutionally suspect.
When Congress established a National Endowment for Democracy to
encourage other countries to adopt democratic principles, 22 U.S.C.
§ 4411(b), it was not constitutionally required to fund a program
to encourage competing lines of political philosophy such as
Communism and Fascism. Petitioners' assertions ultimately boil down
to the position that, if the government chooses to subsidize one
protected right, it must subsidize analogous counterpart rights.
But the Court has soundly rejected that proposition. Regan v.
Taxation With Representation of Wash., supra; Maher v. Roe, supra;
Harris v. McRae, supra. Within far broader limits than
petitioners are willing to concede, when the government
appropriates public funds to establish a program, it is entitled to
define the limits of that program.
We believe that petitioners' reliance upon our decision in Arkansas Writers Project, supra, is misplaced. That case
involved a state sales tax which discriminated between magazines on
the basis of their content. Relying on this fact, and on the fact
that the tax "targets a small group within the press," contrary to
our decision in Minneapolis Star & Tribune Co. v. Minnesota
Comm'r of Revenue, 460 U. S. 575 (1983), the Court held the tax invalid. But we have here not the
case of a general law singling out a disfavored group on the basis
of speech content, but a case of the Government refusing Page 500 U. S. 195 to fund activities, including speech, which are specifically
excluded from the scope of the project funded.
Petitioners rely heavily on their claim that the regulations
would not, in the circumstance of a medical emergency, permit a
Title X project to refer a woman whose pregnancy places her life in
imminent peril to a provider of abortions or abortion-related
services. This case, of course, involves only a facial challenge to
the regulations, and we do not have before us any application by
the Secretary to a specific fact situation. On their face, we do
not read the regulations to bar abortion referral or counseling in
such circumstances. Abortion counseling as a "method of family
planning" is prohibited, and it does not seem that a medically
necessitated abortion in such circumstances would be the equivalent
of its use as a "method of family planning." Neither § 1008 nor the
specific restrictions of the regulations would apply. Moreover, the
regulations themselves contemplate that a Title X project would be
permitted to engage in otherwise prohibited abortion-related
activity in such circumstances. Section 59.8(a)(2) provides a
specific exemption for emergency care, and requires Title X
recipients "to refer the client immediately to an appropriate
provider of emergency medical services." 42 CFR 59.8(a)(2) (1989).
Section 59.5(b)(1) also requires Title X projects to provide
"necessary referral to other medical facilities when medically
indicated." [ Footnote 4 ] Page 500 U. S. 196 Petitioners also contend that the restrictions on the
subsidization of abortion-related speech contained in the
regulations are impermissible because they condition the receipt of
a benefit, in this case Title X funding, on the relinquishment of a
constitutional right, the right to engage in abortion advocacy and
counseling. Relying on Perry v. Sindermann, 408 U.
S. 593 , 408 U. S. 597 (1972), and FCC v. League of Women Voters of Cal., 468 U. S. 364 (1984), petitioners argue that,
"even though the government may deny [a] . . . benefit for any
number of reasons, there are some reasons upon which the government
may not rely. It may not deny a benefit to a person on a basis that
infringes his constitutionally protected interests -- especially,
his interest in freedom of speech." Perry, supra, 408 U.S. at 408 U. S.
597 .
Petitioners' reliance on these cases is unavailing, however,
because here the government is not denying a benefit to anyone, but
is instead simply insisting that public funds be spent for the
purposes for which they were authorized. The Secretary's
regulations do not force the Title X grantee to give up
abortion-related speech; they merely require that the grantee keep
such activities separate and distinct from Title X activities.
Title X expressly distinguishes between a Title X grantee and a Title X project. The grantee, which normally is a
health care organization, may receive funds from a variety of
sources for a variety of purposes. Brief for Petitioners in No.
89-1391, pp. 3, n. 5, 13. The grantee receives Title X funds,
however, for the specific and limited purpose of establishing and
operating a Title X project. 42 U.S.C. § 300(a). The regulations
govern the scope of the Title X project's activities, and
leave the grantee unfettered in its other activities. The Title X grantee can continue to perform abortions, provide
abortion-related services, and engage in abortion advocacy; it
simply is required to conduct those activities through programs
that are separate and independent from the project that receives
Title X funds. 42 CFR 59.9 (1989). Page 500 U. S. 197 In contrast, our "unconstitutional conditions" cases involve
situations in which the government has placed a condition on the recipient of the subsidy, rather that on a particular
program or service, thus effectively prohibiting the recipient from
engaging in the protected conduct outside the scope of the
federally funded program. In FCC v. League of Women Voters of
Cal., we invalidated a federal law providing that
noncommercial television and radio stations that receive federal
grants may not "engage in editorializing." Under that law, a
recipient of federal funds was "barred absolutely from all
editorializing," because it "is not able to segregate its
activities according to the source of its funding," and thus "has
no way of limiting the use of its federal funds to all
noneditorializing activities." The effect of the law was that
"a noncommercial educational station that receives only 1% of
its overall income from [federal] grants is barred absolutely from
all editorializing"
and "barred from using even wholly private funds to finance its
editorial activity." 468 U.S. at 468 U. S. 400 .
We expressly recognized, however, that were Congress to permit the
recipient stations to
"establish affiliate' organizations which could then use the
station's facilities to editorialize with nonfederal funds, such a
statutory mechanism would plainly be valid." Ibid. Such a scheme would permit the station
"to make known its views on matters of public importance through
its nonfederally funded, editorializing affiliate without losing
federal grants for its noneditorializing broadcast activities." Ibid. Similarly, in Regan, we held that Congress could, in
the exercise of its spending power, reasonably refuse to subsidize
the lobbying activities of tax-exempt charitable organizations by
prohibiting such organizations from using tax-deductible
contributions to support their lobbying efforts. In so holding, we
explained that such organizations remained free "to receive
deductible contributions to support . . . nonlobbying
activit[ies]." 461 U.S. at 461 U. S. 545 . Thus, a charitable organization could
create, under § 501(c)(3) of the Internal Page 500 U. S. 198 Revenue Code of 1954, 26 U.S.C. § 501(c)(3), an affiliate to
conduct its nonlobbying activities using tax-deductible
contributions, and at the same time establish, under § 501(c)(4), a
separate affiliate to pursue its lobbying efforts without such
contributions. Regan, supra, at 461 U. S. 544 .
Given that alternative, the Court concluded that
"Congress has not infringed any First Amendment rights or
regulated any First Amendment activity[; it] has simply chosen not
to pay for [appellee's] lobbying." Id. at 461 U. S. 546 .
We also noted that appellee
"would, of course, have to ensure that th § 501(c)(3)
organization did not subsidize the § 501(c)(4) organization;
otherwise, public funds might be spent on an activity Congress
chose not to subsidize." Ibid. The condition that federal funds will be used
only to further the purposes of a grant does not violate
constitutional rights.
"Congress could, for example, grant funds to an organization
dedicated to combating teenage drug abuse, but condition the grant
by providing that none of the money received from Congress should
be used to lobby state legislatures." See id. at 461 U. S.
548 .
By requiring that the Title X grantee engage in abortion-related
activity separately from activity receiving federal funding,
Congress has, consistent with our teachings in League of Women
Voters and Regan, not denied it the right to engage
in abortion-related activities. Congress has merely refused to fund
such activities out of the public fisc, and the Secretary has
simply required a certain degree of separation from the Title X
project in order to ensure the integrity of the federally funded
program.
The same principles apply to petitioners' claim that the
regulations abridge the free speech rights of the grantee's staff.
Individuals who are voluntarily employed for a Title X project must
perform their duties in accordance with the regulation's
restrictions on abortion counseling and referral. The employees
remain free, however, to pursue abortion-related activities when
they are not acting under the auspices of the Title X project. The
regulations, which govern solely Page 500 U. S. 199 the scope of the Title X project's activities, do not in any way
restrict the activities of those persons acting as private
individuals. The employees' freedom of expression is limited during
the time that they actually work for the project, but this
limitation is a consequence of their decision to accept employment
in a project, the scope of which is permissibly restricted by the
funding authority. [ Footnote
5 ]
This is not to suggest that funding by the Government, even when
coupled with the freedom of the fund recipients to speak outside
the scope of the Government-funded project, is invariably
sufficient to justify government control over the content of
expression. For example, this Court has recognized Page 500 U. S. 200 that the existence of a Government "subsidy," in the form of
Government-owned property, does not justify the restriction of
speech in areas that have "been traditionally open to the public
for expressive activity," United States v. Kokinda, 497 U. S. 720 , 497 U. S. 726 (1990); Hague v. CIO, 307 U. S. 496 , 307 U. S. 515 (1939) (opinion of Roberts, J.), or have been "expressly dedicated
to speech activity." Kokinda, supra, at 497 U. S. 726 ; Perry Education Assn. v. Perry Local Educators' Assn., 460 U. S. 37 , 460 U. S. 45 (1983). Similarly, we have recognized that the university is a
traditional sphere of free expression so fundamental to the
functioning of our society that the Government's ability to control
speech within that sphere by means of conditions attached to the
expenditure of Government funds is restricted by the vagueness and
overbreadth doctrines of the First Amendment, Keyishian v.
Board of Regents, 385 U. S. 589 , 385 U. S. 603 , 385 U. S.
605 -606 (1967). It could be argued by analogy that
traditional relationships such as that between doctor and patient
should enjoy protection under the First Amendment from government
regulation, even when subsidized by the Government. We need not
resolve that question here, however, because the Title X program
regulations do not significantly impinge upon the doctorpatient
relationship. Nothing in them requires a doctor to represent as his
own any opinion that he does not in fact hold. Nor is the
doctor-patient relationship established by the Title X program
sufficiently all-encompassing so as to justify an expectation on
the part of the patient of comprehensive medical advice. The
program does not provide post-conception medical care, and
therefore a doctor's silence with regard to abortion cannot
reasonably be thought to mislead a client into thinking that the
doctor does not consider abortion an appropriate option for her.
The doctor is always free to make clear that advice regarding
abortion is simply beyond the scope of the program. In these
circumstances, the general rule that the Government may choose not
to subsidize speech applies with full force. Page 500 U. S. 201 IV We turn now to petitioners' argument that the regulations
violate a woman's Fifth Amendment right to choose whether to
terminate her pregnancy. We recently reaffirmed the long-recognized
principle that
"'the Due Process Clauses generally confer no affirmative right
to governmental aid, even where such aid may be necessary to secure
life, liberty, or property interests of which the government itself
may not deprive the individual.'" Webster, 492 U.S. at 492 U. S. 507 ,
quoting DeShaney v. Winnebago County Dept. of Social
Services, 489 U. S. 189 , 489 U. S. 196 (1989). The Government has no constitutional duty to subsidize an
activity merely because the activity is constitutionally protected,
and may validly choose to fund childbirth over abortion and
" implement that judgment by the allocation of public funds'"
for medical services relating to childbirth, but not to those
relating to abortion. Webster, supra, 492 U.S. at 492 U. S. 510 (citation omitted). The Government has no affirmative duty to
"commit any resources to facilitating abortions," Webster, 492 U.S. at 492 U. S. 511 ,
and its decision to fund childbirth but not abortion "places no governmental obstacle in the path of a woman who
chooses to terminate her pregnancy, but rather, by means of unequal
subsidization of abortion and other medical services, encourages
alternative activity deemed in the public interest." McRae, 448 U.S. at 448 U. S.
315 .
That the regulations do not impermissibly burden a woman's Fifth
Amendment rights is evident from the line of cases beginning with Maher and McRae and culminating in our most
recent decision in Webster. Just as Congress' refusal to
fund abortions in McRae left "an indigent woman with at
least the same range of choice in deciding whether to obtain a
medically necessary abortion as she would have had if Congress had
chosen to subsidize no health care costs at all," 448 U.S. at 448 U. S. 317 ,
and
"Missouri's refusal to allow public employees to perform
abortions in public hospitals leaves a pregnant woman with the same
choices as if the State had chosen not Page 500 U. S. 202 to operate any public hospitals," Webster, supra, at 492 U. S. 509 ,
Congress' refusal to fund abortion counseling and advocacy leaves a
pregnant woman with the same choices as if the government had
chosen not to fund family planning services at all. The difficulty
that a woman encounters when a Title X project does not provide
abortion counseling or referral leaves her in no different position
than she would have been if the government had not enacted Title
X.
In Webster, we stated that,
"[h]aving held that the State's refusal [in Maher ] to
fund abortions does not violate Roe v. Wade, it strains
logic to reach a contrary result for the use of public facilities
and employees."
492 U.S. at 492 U. S.
509 -510. It similarly would strain logic, in light of
the more extreme restrictions in those cases, to find that the mere
decision to exclude abortion-related services from a federally
funded pre-conceptual family planning program, is
unconstitutional.
Petitioners also argue that by impermissibly infringing on the
doctor/patient relationship and depriving a Title X client of
information concerning abortion as a method of family planning, the
regulations violate a woman's Fifth Amendment right to medical
self-determination and to make informed medical decisions free of
government-imposed harm. They argue that, under our decisions in Akron v. Akron Center for Reproductive Health, Inc., 462 U. S. 416 (1983), and Thornburg v. American College of Obstetricians and
Gynecologists, 476 U. S. 747 (1986), the government cannot interfere with a woman's right to
make an informed and voluntary choice by placing restrictions on
the patient/doctor dialogue.
In Akron, we invalidated a city ordinance requiring all physicians to make specified statements to the patient
prior to performing an abortion in order to ensure that the woman's
consent was "truly informed." 462 U.S. at 462 U. S. 423 .
Similarly, in Thornburg, we struck down a state statute
mandating that a list of agencies offering alternatives to abortion
and a description of fetal development be provided to every woman considering terminating her pregnancy through
an Page 500 U. S. 203 abortion. Critical to our decisions in Akron and Thornburg to invalidate a governmental intrusion into the
patient/doctor dialogue was the fact that the laws in both cases
required all doctors within their respective jurisdictions
to provide all pregnant patients contemplating an abortion
a litany of information, regardless of whether the patient sought
the information or whether the doctor thought the information
necessary to the patient's decision. Under the Secretary's
regulations, however, a doctor's ability to provide, and a woman's
right to receive, information concerning abortion and
abortion-related services outside the context of the Title X
project remains unfettered. It would undoubtedly be easier for a
woman seeking an abortion if she could receive information about
abortion from a Title X project, but the Constitution does not
require that the Government distort the scope of its mandated
program in order to provide that information.
Petitioners contend, however, that most Title X clients are
effectively precluded by indigency and poverty from seeing a health
care provider who will provide abortion-related services. But once
again, even these Title X clients are in no worse position than if
Congress had never enacted Title X.
"The financial constraints that restrict an indigent woman's
ability to enjoy the full range of constitutionally protected
freedom of choice are the product not of governmental restrictions
on access to abortion, but rather of her indigency." McRae, supra, 448 U.S. at 448 U. S.
316 .
The Secretary's regulations are a permissible construction of
Title X, and do not violate either the First or Fifth Amendments to
the Constitution. Accordingly, the judgment of the Court of Appeals
is Affirmed. [ Footnote 1 ]
Both the First Circuit and the Tenth Circuit have invalidated
the regulations, primarily on constitutional grounds. See
Massachusetts v. Secretary of Health and Human Services, 899
F.2d 53 (CA1 1990); Planned Parenthood Federation of America v.
Sullivan, 913 F.2d 1492 (CA10 1990).
[ Footnote 2 ]
"Most clients of title X-sponsored clinics are not pregnant, and
generally receive only physical examinations, education on
contraceptive methods, and services related to birth control."
General Accounting Office Report, App. at 95.
[ Footnote 3 ]
For instance, the Secretary relies on the following passage of
the House Report as evidence that the regulations are consistent
with legislative intent:
"It is, and has been, the intent of both Houses that the funds
authorized under this legislation be used only to support
preventive family planning services, population research,
infertility services, and other related medical, informational, and
educational activities. The conferees have adopted the language
contained in section 1008, which prohibits the use of such funds
for abortion, in order to make this intent clear."
H.R.Conf.Rep. No. 91-1667, p. 8 (1970), U.S.Code Cong.Admin.News
1970, pp. 5081-82. Petitioners, however, point to language in the
statement of purpose in the House Report preceding the passage of
Title X stressing the importance of supplying both family planning
information and a full range of family planning information, and of
developing a comprehensive and coordinated program. Petitioners
also rely on the Senate Report which states:
"The committee does not view family planning as merely a
euphemism for birth control. It is properly a part of comprehensive
health care, and should consist of much more than the dispensation
of contraceptive devices. . . . [A] successful family planning
program must contain . . . [m]edical services, including
consultation examination, prescription, and continuing supervision,
supplies, instruction, and referral to other medical services as
needed."
S.Rep. No. 91-1004, p. 10 (1970).
These directly conflicting statements of legislative intent
demonstrate amply the inadequacies of the "traditional tools of
statutory construction," Immigration and
Naturalization Service v. Cardoza-Fonseca , 480 U.S.
[421] at 480 U. S.
446 -447, in resolving the issue before us.
[ Footnote 4 ]
We also find that, on their face, the regulations are narrowly
tailored to fit Congress' intent in Title X that federal funds not
be used to "promote or advocate" abortion as a "method of family
planning." The regulations are designed to ensure compliance with
the prohibition of § 1008 that none of the funds appropriated under
Title X be used in a program where abortion is a method of family
planning. We have recognized that Congress' power to allocate funds
for public purposes includes an ancillary power to ensure that
those funds are properly applied to the prescribed use. See
South Dakota v. Dole, 483 U. S. 203 , 483 U. S.
207 -209 (1987) (upholding against Tenth Amendment
challenge requirement that States raise drinking age as condition
to receipt of federal highway funds); Buckley v. Valeo, 424 U. S. 1 , 424 U. S. 99 (1976).
[ Footnote 5 ]
Petitioners also contend that the regulations violate the First
Amendment by penalizing speech funded with non-Title X monies. They
argue that, since Title X requires that grant recipients contribute
to the financing of Title X projects through the use of matching
funds and grant-related income, the regulation's restrictions on
abortion counseling and advocacy penalize privately funded
speech.
We find this argument flawed for several reasons. First, Title X
subsidies are just that, subsidies. The recipient is in no way
compelled to operate a Title X project; to avoid the force of the
regulations, it can simply decline the subsidy. See Grove City
College v. Bell, 465 U. S. 555 , 465 U. S. 575 (1984) (petitioner's First Amendment rights not violated, because
it "may terminate its participation in the [federal] program, and
thus avoid the requirements of [the federal program]"). By
accepting Title X funds, a recipient voluntarily consents to any
restrictions placed on any matching funds or grant-related income.
Potential grant recipients can choose between accepting Title X
funds -- subject to the Government's conditions that they provide
matching funds and forgo abortion counseling and referral in the
Title X project -- or declining the subsidy and financing their own
unsubsidized program. We have never held that the Government
violates the First Amendment simply by offering that choice.
Second, the Secretary's regulations apply only to Title X programs.
A recipient is therefore able to "limi[t] the use of its federal
funds to [Title X] activities." FCC v. League of Women Voters
of Cal., 468 U. S. 364 , at 468 U. S. 400 (1984). It is in no way "barred from using even wholly private
funds to finance" its pro-abortion activities outside the Title X
program. Ibid. The regulations are limited to Title X
funds; the recipient remains free to use private, non-Title X funds
to finance abortion-related activities.
JUSTICE BLACKMUN, with whom JUSTICE MARSHALL joins, with whom
JUSTICE STEVENS joins as to Parts II and Page 500 U. S. 204 III, and with whom JUSTICE O'CONNOR joins as to Part I,
dissenting.
Casting aside established principles of statutory construction
and administrative jurisprudence, the majority in these cases today
unnecessarily passes upon important questions of constitutional
law. In so doing, the Court, for the first time, upholds
viewpoint-based suppression of speech solely because it is imposed
on those dependent upon the Government for economic support. Under
essentially the same rationale, the majority upholds direct
regulation of dialogue between a pregnant woman and her physician
when that regulation has both the purpose and the effect of
manipulating her decision as to the continuance of her pregnancy. I
conclude that the Secretary's regulation of referral, advocacy, and
counseling activities exceeds his statutory authority, and also
that the Regulations violate the First and Fifth Amendments of our
Constitution. Accordingly, I dissent, and would reverse the
divided-vote judgment of the Court of Appeals. I The majority does not dispute that "[f]ederal statutes are to be
so construed as to avoid serious doubt of their constitutionality." Machinists v. Street, 367 U. S. 740 , 367 U. S. 749 (1961). See also Hooper v. California, 155 U.
S. 648 , 155 U. S. 657 (1895); Crowell v. Benson, 285 U. S.
22 , 285 U. S. 62 (1932); United States v. Security Industrial Bank, 459 U. S. 70 , 459 U. S. 78 (1982). Nor does the majority deny that this principle is fully
applicable to cases such as the instant one, in which a plausible
but constitutionally suspect statutory interpretation is embodied
in an administrative regulation. See Edward J. DeBartolo Corp.
v. Florida Gulf Coast Building & Construction Trades
Council, 485 U. S. 568 , 485 U. S. 575 (1988); NLRB v. Catholic Bishop of Chicago, 440 U.
S. 490 (1979); Kent v. Dulles, 357 U.
S. 116 , 357 U. S.
129 -130 (1958). Rather, in its zeal to address the
constitutional issues, the majority sidesteps this established
canon of construction with the feeble excuse that the
challenged Page 500 U. S. 205 Regulations
"do not raise the sort of 'grave and doubtful constitutional
questions,' . . . that would lead us to assume Congress did not
intend to authorize their issuance." Ante at 500 U. S. 191 ,
quoting United States v. Delaware and Hudson Co., 213 U. S. 366 , 213 U. S. 408 (1909).
This facile response to the intractable problem the Court
addresses today is disingenuous, at best. Whether or not one
believes that these Regulations are valid, it avoids reality to
contend that they do not give rise to serious constitutional
questions. The canon is applicable to this case not because "it was
likely that [the Regulations] . . . would be challenged on
constitutional grounds," ante at 500 U. S. 191 ,
but because the question squarely presented by the Regulations --
the extent to which the Government may attach an otherwise
unconstitutional condition to the receipt of a public benefit --
implicates a troubled area of our jurisprudence in which a court
ought not entangle itself unnecessarily. See, e.g., Epstein, Unconstitutional Conditions, State Power, and the Limits
of Consent, 102 Harv.L.Rev. 4, 6 (1988) (describing this problem as
"the basic structural issue that for over a hundred years has
bedeviled courts and commentators alike. . . ."); Sullivan,
Unconstitutional Conditions, 102 Harv.L.Rev. 1413, 1415-1416 (1989)
(observing that this Court's unconstitutional conditions cases
"seem a minefield to be traversed gingerly").
As is discussed in Parts II and III, infra, the
Regulations impose viewpoint-based restrictions upon protected
speech, and are aimed at a woman's decision whether to continue or
terminate her pregnancy. In both respects, they implicate core
constitutional values. This verity is evidenced by the fact that
two of the three Courts of Appeals that have entertained challenges
to the Regulations have invalidated them on constitutional grounds. See Massachusetts v. Secretary of Health and Human
Services, 899 F.2d 53 (CA1 1990); Planned Parenthood
Federation of America v. Sullivan, 913 F.2d 1492 (CA10
1990). Page 500 U. S. 206 A divided panel of the Tenth Circuit found the Regulations
"fal[l] squarely within the prohibition in Thornburgh v.
American College of Obstetricians and Gynecologists, 476 U. S.
747 (1986), and City of Akron v. Akron Center for
Reproductive Health, Inc., 462 U. S. 416 (1983), against
intrusion into the advice a woman requests from or is given by her
doctor."
913 F.2d at 1501. The First Circuit, en banc with one judge
dissenting, found the Regulations to violate both the privacy
rights of Title X patients and the First Amendment rights of Title
X grantees. See also New York v. Sullivan, 889 F.2d 401,
415 (CA2 1989) (Kearse, J., dissenting in part). That a bare
majority of this Court today reaches a different result does not
change the fact that the constitutional questions raised by the
Regulations are both grave and doubtful.
Nor is this a case in which the statutory language itself
requires us to address a constitutional question. Section 1008 of
the Public Health Service Act, 84 Stat. 1508, 42 U.S.C. § 300a-6,
provides simply: "None of the funds appropriated under this title
shall be used in programs where abortion is a method of family
planning." The majority concedes that this language "does not speak
directly to the issues of counseling, referral, advocacy, or
program integrity," ante at 500 U. S. 184 ,
and that "the legislative history is ambiguous" in this respect. Ante at 500 U. S. 186 .
Consequently, the language of § 1008 easily sustains a
constitutionally trouble-free interpretation. [ Footnote 2/1 ] Page 500 U. S. 207 Thus, this is not a situation in which "the intention of
Congress is revealed too distinctly to permit us to ignore it
because of mere misgivings as to power." Moore Ice Cream Co. v.
Rose, 289 U. S. 373 , 289 U. S. 379 (1933). Indeed, it would appear that our duty to avoid passing
unnecessarily upon important constitutional questions is strongest
where, as here, the language of the statute is decidedly ambiguous.
It is both logical and eminently prudent to assume that, when
Congress intends to press the limits of constitutionality in its
enactments, it will express that intent in explicit and unambiguous
terms. See Sunstein, Law and Administration After Chevron, 90 Colum.L.Rev. 2071, 2113 (1990) ("It is thus
implausible that, after Chevron, agency interpretations of
ambiguous statutes will prevail even if the consequence of those
interpretations is to produce invalidity or to raise serious
constitutional doubts").
Because I conclude that a plainly constitutional construction of
§ 1008 "is not only fairly possible' but entirely reasonable," Machinists, 367 U.S. at 367 U. S. 750 ,
I would reverse the judgment of the Court of Appeals on this ground
without deciding the constitutionality of the Secretary's
Regulations. II I also strongly disagree with the majority's disposition of
petitioners' constitutional claims, and because I feel that a
response thereto is indicated, I move on to that issue. A Until today, the Court never has upheld viewpoint-based
suppression of speech simply because that suppression was a
condition upon the acceptance of public funds. Whatever may be the
Government's power to condition the receipt of its largess upon the
relinquishment of constitutional rights, it surely does not extend
to a condition that suppresses the recipient's cherished freedom of
speech based solely upon the content or viewpoint of that speech. Speiser v. Randall, 357 U. S. 513 , 357 U. S.
518 -519 (1958) ("To deny an exemption to claimants Page 500 U. S. 208 who engage in certain forms of speech is in effect to penalize
them for such speech. . . . The denial is frankly aimed at the
suppression of dangerous ideas,'" quoting American
Communications Assn. v. Douds, 339 U.
S. 382 , 339 U. S. 402 (1950)). See Cammarano v. United States, 358 U.
S. 498 , 358 U. S. 513 (1959). See also League of Women Voters, 468 U.S. at 468 U. S. 407 (REHNQUIST, J., dissenting). Cf. Arkansas Writers' Project,
Inc. v. Ragland, 481 U. S. 221 , 481 U. S. 237 (1987) (SCALIA, J., dissenting). This rule is a sound one, for, as
the Court often has noted: ""A regulation of speech that is motivated by nothing more than
a desire to curtail expression of a particular point of view on
controversial issues of general interest is the purest example of a law . . . abridging the freedom of speech, or of the
press.'"" League of Women Voters, 468 U.S. at 468 U. S.
383 -384, quoting Consolidated Edison Co. v. Public
Service Comm'n of New York, 447 U. S. 530 , 447 U. S. 546 (1980) (STEVENS, J., concurring in judgment).
"[A]bove all else, the First Amendment means that government has
no power to restrict expression because of its message, its ideas,
its subject matter, or its content." Police Department of Chicago v. Mosley, 408 U. S.
92 , 408 U. S. 95 (1972).
Nothing in the Court's opinion in Regan v. Taxation With
Representation of Washington, 461 U.
S. 540 (1983), can be said to challenge this
long-settled understanding. In Regan, the Court upheld a
content-neutral provision of the Internal Revenue Code, 26 U.S.C. §
501(c)(3), that disallowed a particular tax-exempt status to
organizations that "attempt[ed] to influence legislation," while
affording such status to veterans' organizations irrespective of
their lobbying activities. Finding the case controlled by Cammarano, supra, the Court explained:
"The case would be different if Congress were to discriminate
invidiously in its subsidies in such a way as to " ai[m] at the
suppression of dangerous ideas.'" . . . We find no indication that
the statute was intended to suppress any ideas or any demonstration
that it has had that effect." 461 U.S. at 461 U. S. 548 ,
quoting Cammarano, 358 U.S. at Page 500 U. S. 209 358 U. S. 513 ,
in turn quoting Speiser, 357 U.S. at 357 U. S. 519 .
The separate concurrence in Regan joined the Court's
opinion precisely
"[b]ecause 26 U.S.C. § 501's discrimination between veterans'
organizations and charitable organizations is not based on the
content of their speech." Id. 461 U.S. at 461 U. S.
551 .
It cannot seriously be disputed that the counseling and referral
provisions at issue in the present cases constitute content-based
regulation of speech. Title X grantees may provide counseling and
referral regarding any of a wide range of family planning and other
topics, save abortion. Cf. Consolidated Edison Co., 447
U.S. at 447 U. S. 537 ("The First Amendment's hostility to content-based regulation
extends not only to restrictions on particular viewpoints, but also
to prohibition of public discussion of an entire topic"); Boos
v. Barry, 485 U. S. 312 , 485 U. S. 319 (1988) (opinion of O'CONNOR, J.) (same).
The Regulations are also clearly viewpoint-based. While
suppressing speech favorable to abortion with one hand, the
Secretary compels anti-abortion speech with the other. For example,
the Department of Health and Human Services' own description of the
Regulations makes plain that
"Title X projects are required to facilitate access to
prenatal care and social services, including adoption services,
that might be needed by the pregnant client to promote her
wellbeing and that of her child, while making it abundantly clear
that the project is not permitted to promote abortion by
facilitating access to abortion through the referral process."
53 Fed.Reg. 2927 (1988) (emphasis added).
Moreover, the Regulations command that a project refer for
prenatal care each woman diagnosed as pregnant, irrespective of the
woman's expressed desire to continue or terminate her pregnancy. 42
CFR § 59.8(a)(2) (1990). If a client asks directly about abortion,
a Title X physician or counselor is required to say, in essence,
that the project does not consider abortion to be an appropriate
method of family planning. § 59.8(b)(4). Both requirements are
antithetical to Page 500 U. S. 210 the First Amendment. See Wooley v. Maynard, 430 U. S. 705 , 430 U. S. 714 (1977).
The Regulations pertaining to "advocacy" are even more
explicitly viewpoint-based. These provide: "A Title X project may
not encourage, promote or advocate abortion as a method of
family planning." § 59.10 (emphasis added). They explain:
"This requirement prohibits actions to assist women to
obtain abortions or increase the availability or
accessibility of abortion for family planning purposes."
§ 59.10(a) (emphasis added). The Regulations do not, however,
proscribe or even regulate antiabortion advocacy. These are clearly
restrictions aimed at the suppression of "dangerous ideas."
Remarkably, the majority concludes that "the Government has not
discriminated on the basis of viewpoint; it has merely chosen to
fund one activity to the exclusion of another." Ante at 500 U. S. 193 .
But the majority's claim that the Regulations merely limit a Title
X project's speech to preventive or preconceptional services, ibid., rings hollow in light of the broad range of
non-preventive services that the Regulations authorize Title X
projects to provide. [ Footnote 2/2 ]
By refusing to fund those family planning projects that advocate
abortion because they advocate abortion, the Government plainly has
targeted a particular viewpoint. Cf. Ward v. Rock Against
Racism, 491 U. S. 781 (1989). The majority's reliance on the fact that the Regulations
pertain solely to funding decisions simply begs the question.
Clearly, there are some bases upon which government may not rest
its decision to fund or not to fund. For example, the Members of
the majority surely would agree that government may not base
its Page 500 U. S. 211 decision to support an activity upon considerations of race. See, e.g., Yick Wo v. Hopkins, 118 U.
S. 356 (1886). As demonstrated above, our cases make
clear that ideological viewpoint is a similarly repugnant ground
upon which to base funding decisions.
The majority's reliance upon Regan in this connection
is also misplaced. That case stands for the proposition that
government has no obligation to subsidize a private party's efforts
to petition the legislature regarding its views. Thus, if the
challenged Regulations were confined to nonideological limitations
upon the use of Title X funds for lobbying activities, there would
exist no violation of the First Amendment. The advocacy Regulations
at issue here, however, are not limited to lobbying, but extend to
all speech having the effect of encouraging, promoting, or
advocating abortion as a method of family planning. § 59.10(a).
Thus, in addition to their impermissible focus upon the viewpoint
of regulated speech, the provisions intrude upon a wide range of
communicative conduct, including the very words spoken to a woman
by her physician. By manipulating the content of the doctor/patient
dialogue, the Regulations upheld today force each of the
petitioners "to be an instrument for fostering public adherence to
an ideological point of view [he or she] finds unacceptable." Wooley v. Maynard, 430 U.S. at 430 U. S. 715 .
This type of intrusive, ideologically based regulation of speech
goes far beyond the narrow lobbying limitations approved in Regan, and cannot be justified simply because it is a
condition upon the receipt of a governmental benefit. [ Footnote 2/3 ] Page 500 U. S. 212 B The Court concludes that the challenged Regulations do not
violate the First Amendment rights of Title X staff members,
because any limitation of the employees' freedom of expression is
simply a consequence of their decision to accept employment at a
federally funded project. Ante at 500 U. S.
198 -199. But it has never been sufficient to justify an
otherwise unconstitutional condition upon public employment that
the employee may escape the condition by relinquishing his or her
job. It is beyond question
"that a government may not require an individual to relinquish
rights guaranteed him by the First Amendment as a condition of
public employment." Abood v. Detroit Board of Education, 431 U.
S. 209 , 431 U. S. 234 (1977), citing Elrod v. Burns, 427 U.
S. 347 , 427 U. S.
357 -360 (1976), and cases cited therein; Perry v.
Sindermann, 408 U. S. 593 (1972); Keyishian v. Board of Regents, 385 U.
S. 589 (1967). Nearly two decades ago, it was said:
"For at least a quarter-century, this Court has made clear that,
even though a person has no 'right' to a valuable governmental
benefit, and even though the government may deny him the benefit
for any number of reasons, there are some reasons upon which the
government may not rely. It may not deny a benefit to a Page 500 U. S. 213 person on a basis that infringes his constitutionally protected
interests -- especially, his interest in freedom of speech. For if
the government could deny a benefit to a person because of his
constitutionally protected speech or associations, his exercise of
those freedoms would, in effect, be penalized and inhibited. This
would allow the government to 'produce a result which [it] could
not command directly.'" Perry v. Sindermann, 408 U.S. at 408 U. S. 597 ,
quoting Speiser v. Randall, 357 U.
S. 513 , 357 U. S. 526 (1958).
The majority attempts to circumvent this principle by
emphasizing that Title X physicians and counselors "remain free . .
. to pursue abortion-related activities when they are not acting
under the auspices of the Title X project." Ante at 500 U. S. 198 .
"The regulations," the majority explains, "do not in any way
restrict the activities of those persons acting as private
individuals." Ibid. Under the majority's reasoning, the
First Amendment could be read to tolerate any governmental
restriction upon an employee's speech so long as that restriction
is limited to the funded workplace. This is a dangerous
proposition, and one the Court has rightly rejected in the
past.
In Abood, it was no answer to the petitioners' claim of
compelled speech as a condition upon public employment that their
speech outside the workplace remained unregulated by the State. Nor
was the public employee's First Amendment claim in Rankin v.
McPherson, 483 U. S. 378 (1987), derogated because the communication that her employer
sought to punish occurred during business hours. At the least, such
conditions require courts to balance the speaker's interest in the
message against those of government in preventing its
dissemination. Id. at 483 U. S. 384 ; Pickering v. Board of Education, 391 U.
S. 563 , 391 U. S. 568 (1968).
In the cases at bar, the speaker's interest in the communication
is both clear and vital. In addressing the family planning needs of
their clients, the physicians and counselors who staff Title X
projects seek to provide them with the full range of information
and options regarding their health and reproductive freedom.
Indeed, the legitimate expectations Page 500 U. S. 214 of the patient and the ethical responsibilities of the medical
profession demand no less.
"The patient's right of self-decision can be effectively
exercised only if the patient possesses enough information to
enable an intelligent choice. . . . The physician has an ethical
obligation to help the patient make choices from among the
therapeutic alternatives consistent with good medical
practice."
Current Opinions, the Council on Ethical and Judicial Affairs of
the American Medical Association � 8.08 (1989). See also President's Commission for the Study of Ethical Problems in
Medicine and Biomedical and Behavioral Research, Making Health Care
Decisions 70 (1982); American College of Obstetricians &
Gynecologists, Standards for Obstetric-Gynecologic Services 62 (7th
ed.1989). When a client becomes pregnant, the full range of
therapeutic alternatives includes the abortion option, and Title X
counselors' interest in providing this information is
compelling.
The Government's articulated interest in distorting the
doctor/patient dialogue -- ensuring that federal funds are not
spent for a purpose outside the scope of the program -- falls far
short of that necessary to justify the suppression of truthful
information and professional medical opinion regarding
constitutionally protected conduct. [ Footnote 2/4 ] Moreover, the offending Regulation is not
narrowly tailored to serve this interest. For example, the
governmental interest at stake could be served by imposing rigorous
bookkeeping standards to ensure financial separation or adopting
content-neutral rules for the balanced dissemination of family
planning and health information. See Massachusetts v. Secretary
of Health & Human Services, 899 F.2d 53, 74 (CA1 1990), cert. pending, No. 89-1929. By failing to balance or even
to consider the free speech interests claimed by Title X physicians
against the Government's asserted interest in suppressing the
speech, the Court falters in its duty to implement the
protection Page 500 U. S. 215 that the First Amendment clearly provides for this important
message. C Finally, it is of no small significance that the speech the
Secretary would suppress is truthful information regarding
constitutionally protected conduct of vital importance to the
listener. One can imagine no legitimate governmental interest that
might be served by suppressing such information. Concededly, the
abortion debate is among the most divisive and contentious issues
that our Nation has faced in recent years.
"But freedom to differ is not limited to things that do not
matter much. That would be a mere shadow of freedom. The test of
its substance is the right to differ as to things that touch the
heart of the existing order." West Virginia Board of Education v. Barnette, 319 U. S. 624 , 319 U. S. 642 (1943). III By far the most disturbing aspect of today's ruling is the
effect it will have on the Fifth Amendment rights of the women who,
supposedly, are beneficiaries of Title X programs. The majority
rejects petitioners' Fifth Amendment claims summarily. It relies
primarily upon the decisions in Harris v. McRae, 448 U. S. 297 (1980), and Webster v. Reproductive Health Services, 492 U. S. 490 (1989). There were dissents in those cases, and we continue to
believe that they were wrongly and unfortunately decided. Be that
as it may, even if one accepts as valid the Court's theorizing in
those cases, the majority's reasoning in the present cases is
flawed.
Until today, the Court has allowed to stand only those
restrictions upon reproductive freedom that, while limiting the
availability of abortion, have left intact a woman's ability to
decide without coercion whether she will continue her pregnancy to
term. Maher v. Roe, 432 U. S. 464 (1977), McRae, and Webster are all to this
effect. Today's decision abandons that principle, and with
disastrous results. Page 500 U. S. 216 Contrary to the majority's characterization, this is not a case
in which individuals seek government aid in exercising their
fundamental rights. The Fifth Amendment right asserted by
petitioners is the right of a pregnant woman to be free from
affirmative governmental interference in her decision. Roe v. Wade, 410 U. S. 113 (1973), and its progeny are not so much about a medical procedure
as they are about a woman's fundamental right to
self-determination. Those cases serve to vindicate the idea that
"liberty," if it means anything, must entail freedom from
governmental domination in making the most intimate and personal of
decisions. See, e.g., Akron v. Akron Center for Reproductive
Health, Inc., 462 U. S. 416 , 462 U. S. 444 (1983) (governmental interest in ensuring that pregnant women
receive medically relevant information "will not justify abortion
regulations designed to influence the woman's informed choice
between abortion or childbirth"); Maher v. Roe, 432 U.S.
at 432 U. S. 473 (noting that the Court's abortion cases "recognize a
constitutionally protected interest in making certain kinds of
important decisions' free from governmental compulsion," quoting Whalen v. Roe, 429 U. S. 589 , 429 U. S. 599 (1977)); see also Harris v. McRae, 448 U.S. at 448 U. S. 312 ; Thornburgh, 476 U.S. at 476 U. S. 759 ; Roe v. Wade, 410 U.S. at 410 U. S.
169 -170 (Stewart, J., concurring). By suppressing
medically pertinent information and injecting a restrictive
ideological message unrelated to considerations of maternal health,
the Government places formidable obstacles in the path of Title X
clients' freedom of choice and thereby violates their Fifth
Amendment rights. It is crystal clear that the aim of the challenged provisions --
an aim the majority cannot escape noticing -- is not simply to
ensure that federal funds are not used to perform abortions, but to
"reduce the incidence of abortion." 42 CFR § 59.2 (1990) (in
definition of "family planning"). As recounted above, the
Regulations require Title X physicians and counselors to provide
information pertaining only to childbirth, Page 500 U. S. 217 to refer a pregnant woman for prenatal care irrespective of her
medical situation, and, upon direct inquiry, to respond that
abortion is not an "appropriate method" of family planning.
The undeniable message conveyed by this forced speech, and the
one that the Title X client will draw from it, is that abortion
nearly always is an improper medical option. Although her
physician's words, in fact, are strictly controlled by the
Government, and wholly unrelated to her particular medical
situation, the Title X client will reasonably construe them as
professional advice to forgo her right to obtain an abortion. As
would most rational patients, many of these women will follow that
perceived advice and carry their pregnancy to term, despite their
needs to the contrary and despite the safety of the abortion
procedure for the vast majority of them. Others, delayed by the
Regulations' mandatory prenatal referral, will be prevented from
acquiring abortions during the period in which the process is
medically sound and constitutionally protected.
In view of the inevitable effect of the Regulations, the
majority's conclusion that
"[t]he difficulty that a woman encounters when a Title X project
does not provide abortion counseling or referral leaves her in no
different position than she would have been if the government had
not enacted Title X," ante at 500 U. S. 202 ,
is insensitive and contrary to common human experience. Both the
purpose and result of the challenged Regulations is to deny women
the ability voluntarily to decide their procreative destiny. For
these women, the Government will have obliterated the freedom to
choose as surely as if it had banned abortions outright. The denial
of this freedom is not a consequence of poverty, but of the
Government's ill-intentioned distortion of information it has
chosen to provide. [ Footnote
2/5 ] Page 500 U. S. 218 The substantial obstacles to bodily self-determination that the
Regulations impose are doubly offensive because they are effected
by manipulating the very words spoken by physicians and counselors
to their patients. In our society, the doctor/patient dialogue
embodies a unique relationship of trust. The specialized nature of
medical science and the emotional distress often attendant to
health-related decisions requires that patients place their
complete confidence, and often their very lives, in the hands of
medical professionals. One seeks a physician's aid not only for
medication or diagnosis, but also for guidance, professional
judgment, and vital emotional support. Accordingly, each of us
attaches profound importance and authority to the words of advice
spoken by the physician.
It is for this reason that we have guarded so jealously the
doctor/patient dialogue from governmental intrusion.
"[I]n Roe and subsequent cases, we have 'stressed
repeatedly the central role of the physician, both in consulting
with the woman about whether or not to have an abortion, and in
determining how any abortion was to be carried out.'" Akron, 462 U.S. at 462 U. S. 447 quoting Colautti v. Franklin, 439 U.
S. 379 , 439 U. S. 387 (1979). See also Thornburgh, 476 U.S. at 476 U. S. 763 .
The majority's approval of the Secretary's Regulations flies in the
face of our repeated warnings that regulations tending to "confine
the attending physician in an undesired and uncomfortable
straitjacket in the practice of his profession," cannot endure. Planned Parenthood of Central Mo. v. Danforth, 428 U. S. 52 , 428 U. S. 67 , n.
8 (1976).
The majority attempts to distinguish our holdings in Akron and Thornburgh on the post hoc basis that the governmental Page 500 U. S. 219 intrusions into the doctor/patient dialogue invalidated in those
cases applied to all physicians within a jurisdiction
while the Regulations now before the Court pertain to the narrow
class of healthcare professionals employed at Title X projects. Ante at 500 U. S. 202 .
But the rights protected by the Constitution are personal rights. Loving v. Virginia, 388 U. S.
1 , 388 U. S. 12 (1967); Shelley v. Kraemer, 334 U. S.
1 , 334 U. S. 22 (1948). And for the individual woman, the deprivation of liberty by
the Government is no less substantial because it affects few,
rather than many. It cannot be that an otherwise unconstitutional
infringement of choice is made lawful because it touches only some
of the Nation's pregnant women, and not all of them.
The manipulation of the doctor/patient dialogue achieved through
the Secretary's Regulations is clearly an effort "to deter a woman
from making a decision that, with her physician, is hers to make." Thornburgh, 476 U.S. at 476 U. S. 759 .
As such, it violates the Fifth Amendment. [ Footnote 2/6 ] IV In its haste further to restrict the right of every woman to
control her reproductive freedom and bodily integrity, the majority
disregards established principles of law and contorts this Court's
decided cases to arrive at its preordained result. The majority
professes to leave undisturbed the free speech protections upon
which our society has come to rely, but one must wonder what force
the First Amendment retains if it is read to countenance the
deliberate manipulation by the Government Page 500 U. S. 220 of the dialogue between a woman and her physician. While
technically leaving intact the fundamental right protected by Roe v. Wade, the Court, "through a relentlessly
formalistic catechism," McRae, 448 U.S. at 448 U. S. 341 (MARSHALL, J., dissenting), once again has rendered the right's
substance nugatory. See Webster v. Reproductive Health
Services, 492 U.S. at 492 U. S. 537 (opinions concurring in part and
dissenting in part). This is a course nearly as noxious as
overruling Roe directly, for if a right is found to be
unenforceable, even against flagrant attempts by government to
circumvent it, then it ceases to be a right at all. This, I fear,
may be the effect of today's decision.
[ Footnote 2/1 ]
The majority states: "There is no question but that the
statutory prohibition contained in § 1008 is constitutional." Ante at 500 U. S. 192 .
This statement simply begs the question. Were the Court to read §
1008 to prohibit only the actual performance of abortions with
Title X fund as, indeed, the Secretary did until February 2, 1988, see 53 Bed.Reg. 2923 (1988) -- the provision would fall
within the category of restrictions that the Court upheld in Harris v. McRae, 448 U. S. 297 (1980), and Maher v. Roe, 432 U.
S. 464 (1977). By interpreting the statute to authorize
the regulation of abortion-related speech between physician and
patient, however, the Secretary, and now the Court, have rejected a
constitutionally sound construction in favor of one that is by no
means clearly constitutional.
[ Footnote 2/2 ]
In addition to requiring referral for prenatal care and adoption
services, the Regulations permit general health services such as
physical examinations, screening for breast cancer, treatment of
gynecological problems, and treatment for sexually transmitted
diseases. 53 Fed.Reg. 2927 (1988). None of the latter are strictly
preventive, preconceptional services.
[ Footnote 2/3 ]
The majority attempts to obscure the breadth of its decision
through its curious contention that "the Title X program
regulations do not significantly impinge upon the doctor-patient
relationship." Ante at 500 U. S. 200 .
That the doctor-patient relationship is substantially burdened by a
rule prohibiting the dissemination by the physician of pertinent
medical information is beyond serious dispute. This burden is
undiminished by the fact that the relationship at issue here is not
an "all-encompassing" one. A woman seeking the services of a Title
X clinic has every reason to expect, as do we all, that her
physician will not withhold relevant information regarding the very
purpose of her visit. To suggest otherwise is to engage in
uninformed fantasy. Further, to hold that the doctor-patient
relationship is somehow incomplete where a patient lacks the
resources to seek comprehensive health care from a single provider
is to ignore the situation of a vast number of Americans. As
JUSTICE MARSHALL has noted in a different context:
"It is perfectly proper for judges to disagree about what the
Constitution requires. But it is disgraceful for an interpretation
of the Constitution to be premised upon unfounded assumptions about
how people live." United States v. Kras, 409 U.
S. 434 , 409 U. S. 460 (1973) (dissenting opinion).
[ Footnote 2/4 ]
It is to be noted that the Secretary has made no claim that the
Regulations at issue reflect any concern for the health or welfare
of Title X clients.
[ Footnote 2/5 ]
In the context of common law tort liability, commentators have
recognized:
"If there is no duty to go to the assistance of a person in
difficulty or peril, there is at least a duty to avoid any
affirmative acts which make his situation worse. . . . The same is
true, of course, of a physician who accepts a charity patient. Such
a defendant will then be liable for a failure to use reasonable
care for the protection of the plaintiffs interests."
P. Keeton et al., Prosser and Keeton on the Law of
Torts 378 (5th ed.1984) (footnotes omitted). This observation seems
equally appropriate to the cases at bar.
[ Footnote 2/6 ]
Significantly, the Court interprets the challenged regulations
to allow a Title X project to refer a woman whose health would be
seriously endangered by continued pregnancy to an abortion
provider. Ante at 500 U. S. 195 . To hold otherwise would be to adopt an
interpretation that would most certainly violate a patient's right
to substantive due process. See, e.g., Youngberg v. Romeo, 457 U. S. 307 (1982); Revere v. Massachusetts General Hospital, 463 U. S. 239 (1983). The Solicitor General at oral argument, however, afforded
the Regulations a far less charitable interpretation. See Tr. of Oral Arg. 44-47.
JUSTICE STEVENS, dissenting.
In my opinion, the Court has not paid sufficient attention to
the language of the controlling statute or to the consistent
interpretation accorded the statute by the responsible cabinet
officers during four different Presidencies and 18 years.
The relevant text of the "Family Planning Services and
Population Research Act of 1970" has remained unchanged since its
enactment. 84 Stat. 1504. The preamble to the Act states that it
was passed:
"To promote public health and welfare by expanding, improving,
and better coordinating the family planning services and population
research activities of the Federal Government, and for other
purposes." Ibid. The declaration of congressional purposes
emphasizes the importance of educating the public about family
planning services. Thus, § 2 of the Act states, in part, that the
purpose of the Act is:
"(1) to assist in making comprehensive voluntary family planning
services readily available to all persons desiring such
services;" * * * * "(5) to develop and make readily available information
(including educational materials) on family planning and Page 500 U. S. 221 population growth to all persons desiring such information."
42 U.S.C. § 300 (Congressional Declaration of Purpose).
In contrast to the statutory emphasis on making relevant
information readily available to the public, the statute contains
no suggestion that Congress intended to authorize the suppression
or censorship of any information by any Government employee or by
any grant recipient.
Section 6 of the Act authorizes the provision of federal funds
to support the establishment and operation of voluntary family
planning projects. The section also empowers the Secretary to
promulgate regulations imposing conditions on grant recipients to
ensure that "such grants will be effectively utilized for the
purposes for which made." § 300a-4(b). Not a word in the statute,
however, authorizes the Secretary to impose any restrictions on the
dissemination of truthful information or professional advice by
grant recipients.
The word "prohibition" is used only once in the Act. Section 6,
which adds to the Public Health Service Act the new Title X,
covering the subject of population research and voluntary planning
programs, includes the following provision:
"PROHIBITION OF ABORTION"
"SEC. 1008. None of the funds appropriated under this title
shall be used in programs where abortion is a method of family
planning."
84 Stat. 1508, 42 U.S.C. § 300a-6. Read in the context of the
entire statute, this prohibition is plainly directed at conduct,
rather than the dissemination of information or advice, by
potential grant recipients.
The original regulations promulgated in 1971 by the Secretary of
Health, Education and Welfare so interpreted the statute. This
" contemporaneous construction of [the] statute by the men
charged with the responsibility of setting its machinery in
motion'" is entitled to particular respect. See Power
Reactor Development Co. v. Electrical Workers , 367 Page 500 U. S. 222 U.S. 396, 367 U. S. 408 (1961) (citation omitted); Udall v. Tallman, 380 U. S.
1 , 380 U. S. 16 (1965); Aluminum Co. of America v. Central Lincoln Peoples'
Utility District, 467 U. S. 380 , 467 U. S. 390 (1984). The regulations described the kind of services that grant
recipients had to provide in order to be eligible for federal
funding, but they did not purport to regulate or restrict the kinds
of advice or information that recipients might make available to
their clients. Conforming to the language of the governing statute,
the regulations provided that "[t]he project will not provide abortions as a method of family planning." 42 CFR
§ 59.5(a)(9) (1972) (emphasis added). Like the statute itself, the
regulations prohibited conduct, not speech.
The same is true of the regulations promulgated in 1986 by the
Secretary of Health and Human Services. They also prohibited grant
recipients from performing abortions, but did not purport to censor
or mandate any kind of speech. See 42 CFR §§ 59.159.13
(1986).
The entirely new approach adopted by the Secretary in 1988 was
not, in my view, authorized by the statute. The new regulations did
not merely reflect a change in a policy determination that the
Secretary had been authorized by Congress to make. Cf. 467 U. S. S.A.
Inc. v. Natural Resources Defense Counsel, Inc., 467 U.
S. 837 , 467 U. S. 865 (1984). Rather, they represented an assumption of policymaking
responsibility that Congress had not delegated to the Secretary. See id. at 467 U. S.
842 -843 ("If the intent of Congress is clear, that is
the end of the matter; for the court, as well as the agency, must
give effect to the unambiguously expressed intent of Congress"). In
a society that abhors censorship and in which policymakers have
traditionally placed the highest value on the freedom to
communicate, it is unrealistic to conclude that statutory authority
to regulate conduct implicitly authorized the Executive to regulate
speech.
Because I am convinced that the 1970 Act did not authorize the
Secretary to censor the speech of grant recipients or their Page 500 U. S. 223 employees, I would hold the challenged regulations invalid and
reverse the judgment of the Court of Appeals.
Even if I thought the statute were ambiguous, however, I would
reach the same result for the reasons stated in JUSTICE O'CONNOR's
dissenting opinion. As she also explains, if a majority of the
Court had reached this result, it would be improper to comment on
the constitutional issues that the parties have debated. Because
the majority has reached out to decide the constitutional
questions, however, I am persuaded that JUSTICE BLACKMUN is correct
in concluding that the majority's arguments merit a response. I am
also persuaded that JUSTICE BLACKMUN has correctly analyzed these
issues. I have therefore joined Parts II and III of his
opinion.
JUSTICE O'CONNOR, dissenting.
"[W]here an otherwise acceptable construction of a statute would
raise serious constitutional problems, the Court will construe the
statute to avoid such problems unless such construction is plainly
contrary to the intent of Congress." Edward J. DeBartolo Corp. v. Florida Gulf Coast Building
& Construction Trades Council, 485 U.
S. 568 , 485 U. S. 575 (1988). JUSTICE BLACKMUN has explained well why this longstanding
canon of statutory construction applies in this case, and I join 500 U. S. 500 U. S. which constitute the Secretary's interpretation of § 1008 of the
Public Health Service Act, 84 Stat. 1508, 42 U.S.C. § 300a-6,
"raise serious constitutional problems": the regulations place
content-based restrictions on the speech of Title X fund
recipients, restrictions directed precisely at speech concerning
one of "the most divisive and contentious issues that our Nation
has faced in recent years." Ante at 500 U. S.
215 .
One may well conclude, as JUSTICE BLACKMUN does in 500 U.
S. that the regulations are unconstitutional for this
reason. I do not join Part II of the dissent, however, for the same
reason that I do not join 500 U. S. in
which JUSTICE Page 500 U. S. 224 BLACKMUN concludes that the regulations are unconstitutional
under the Fifth Amendment. The canon of construction that JUSTICE
BLACKMUN correctly applies here is grounded in large part upon our
time-honored practice of not reaching constitutional questions
unnecessarily. See DeBartolo, supra, at 485 U. S.
575 .
"It is a fundamental rule of judicial restraint . . . that this
Court will not reach constitutional questions in advance of the
necessity of deciding them." Three Affiliated Tribes of Fort Berthold Reservation v. Wold
Engineering, P.C., 467 U. S. 138 , 467 U. S. 157 (1984). See also Alexander v. Louisiana, 405 U.
S. 625 , 405 U. S. 633 (1972); Burton v. United States, 196 U.
S. 283 , 196 U. S. 295 (1905); Liverpool, New York and Philadelphia S.S. Co. v.
Commissioners of Emigration, 113 U. S. 33 , 113 U. S. 39 (1885) (In the exercise of its jurisdiction to pronounce
unconstitutional laws of the United States, this Court "has rigidly
adhered" to the rule "never to anticipate a question of
constitutional law in advance of the necessity of deciding
it").
This Court acts at the limits of its power when it invalidates a
law on constitutional grounds. In recognition of our place in the
constitutional scheme, we must act with "great gravity and
delicacy" when telling a coordinate branch that its actions are
absolutely prohibited absent constitutional amendment. Adkins
v. Children's Hospital of District of Columbia, 261 U.
S. 525 , 261 U. S. 544 (1923). See also Blodgett v. Holden, 275 U.
S. 142 , 275 U. S.
147 -148 (1927) (Holmes, J., concurring). In this case,
we need only tell the Secretary that his regulations are not a
reasonable interpretation of the statute; we need not tell Congress
that it cannot pass such legislation. If we rule solely on
statutory grounds, Congress retains the power to force the
constitutional question by legislating more explicitly. It may
instead choose to do nothing. That decision should be left to
Congress; we should not tell Congress what it cannot do before it
has chosen to do it. It is enough in this case to conclude that
neither the language nor the history of § 1008 compels the
Secretary's interpretation, Page 500 U. S. 225 and that the interpretation raises serious First Amendment
concerns. On this basis alone, I would reverse the judgment of the
Court of Appeals and invalidate the challenged regulations. | In *Rust v. Sullivan*, the U.S. Supreme Court upheld regulations prohibiting Title X family-planning projects from counseling, referring, or advocating for abortion as a method of family planning. The Court found that the regulations were a permissible interpretation of the Public Health Service Act, which states that federal funds under Title X cannot be used for programs where abortion is a method of family planning. The Court deferred to the Secretary of Health and Human Services' expertise and found that the regulations did not violate the First or Fifth Amendments. |
Free Speech | R.A.V. v. City of St. Paul | https://supreme.justia.com/cases/federal/us/505/377/ | OCTOBER TERM, 1991
Syllabus
R. A. V. v. CITY OF ST. PAUL, MINNESOTA
CERTIORARI TO THE SUPREME COURT OF MINNESOTA No. 90-7675. Argued
December 4, 1991-Decided June 22,1992
After allegedly burning a cross on a black family's lawn,
petitioner R. A. V. was charged under, inter alia, the St.
Paul, Minnesota, Bias-Motivated Crime Ordinance, which prohibits
the display of a symbol which one knows or has reason to know
"arouses anger, alarm or resentment in others on the basis of race,
color, creed, religion or gender." The trial court dismissed this
charge on the ground that the ordinance was substantially overbroad
and impermissibly content based, but the State Supreme Court
reversed. It rejected the overbreadth claim because the phrase
"arouses anger, alarm or resentment in others" had been construed
in earlier state cases to limit the ordinance's reach to "fighting
words" within the meaning of this Court's decision in Chaplinsky v. New Hampshire, 315 U. S. 568 , 572, a
category of expression unprotected by the First Amendment. The
court also concluded that the ordinance was not impermissibly
content based because it was narrowly tailored to serve a
compelling governmental interest in protecting the community
against bias-motivated threats to public safety and order. Held: The ordinance is facially invalid under the First
Amendment.
Pp.381-396.
(a) This Court is bound by the state court's construction of the
ordinance as reaching only expressions constituting "fighting
words." However, R. A. Vo's request that the scope of the Chaplinsky formulation be modified, thereby invalidating the
ordinance as substantially overbroad, need not be reached, since
the ordinance unconstitutionally prohibits speech on the basis of
the subjects the speech addresses. P.381.
(b) A few limited categories of speech, such as obscenity,
defamation, and fighting words, may be regulated because of
their constitutionally proscribable content. However, these
categories are not entirely invisible to the Constitution, and
government may not regulate them based on hostility, or favoritism,
towards a nonpros crib able message they contain. Thus the
regulation of "fighting words" may not be based on nonproscribable
content. It may, however, be underinclusive, addressing some
offensive instances and leaving other, equally offensive, ones
alone, so long as the selective proscription is not based on
content, or there is no realistic possibility that regulation of
ideas is afoot. Pp. 382-390. 378 Syllabus
(c) The ordinance, even as narrowly construed by the State
Supreme Court, is facially unconstitutional because it imposes
special prohibitions on those speakers who express views on the
disfavored subjects of "race, color, creed, religion or gender." At
the same time, it permits displays containing abusive invective if
they are not addressed to those topics. Moreover, in its practical
operation the ordinance goes beyond mere content, to actual
viewpoint, discrimination. Displays containing "fighting words"
that do not invoke the disfavored subjects would seemingly be
useable ad libitum by those arguing in favor of racial,
color, etc., tolerance and equality, but not by their opponents.
St. Paul's desire to communicate to minority groups that it does
not condone the "group hatred" of bias-motivated speech does not
justify selectively silencing speech on the basis of its content.
Pp. 391-393.
(d) The content-based discrimination reflected in the ordinance
does not rest upon the very reasons why the particular class of
speech at issue is pros crib able, it is not aimed only at the
"secondary effects" of speech within the meaning of Renton v. Playtime Theatres, Inc., 475 U. S. 41, and it is not for
any other reason the sort that does not threaten censorship of
ideas. In addition, the ordinance's content discrimination is not
justified on the ground that the ordinance is narrowly tailored to
serve a compelling state interest in ensuring the basic human
rights of groups historically discriminated against, since an
ordinance not limited to the favored topics would have precisely
the same beneficial effect. Pp. 393-396.
464 N. W. 2d 507, reversed and remanded.
SCALIA, J., delivered the opinion of the Court, in which
REHNQUIST, C. J., and KENNEDY, SOUTER, and THOMAS, JJ., joined.
WHITE, J., filed an opinion concurring in the judgment, in which
BLACKMUN and O'CONNOR, JJ., joined, and in which STEVENS, J.,
joined except as to Part I-A, post, p. 397. BLACKMUN, J.,
filed an opinion concurring in the judgment, post, p. 415.
STEVENS, J., filed an opinion concurring in the judgment, in Part I
of which WHITE and BLACKMUN, JJ., joined, post, p. 416. Edward J. Cleary argued the cause for
petitioner. With him on the briefs was Michael F.
Cromett. Tom Foley argued the cause for respondent. With him on
the brief was Steven C. DeCoster. * *Briefs of amici curiae urging reversal were filed for
the American Civil Liberties Union et al. by Steven R. Shapiro,
John A. Powell, and Mark R. Anfinson; for the
Association of American Publishers et al. by 379 JUSTICE SCALIA delivered the opinion of the Court.
In the predawn hours of June 21, 1990, petitioner and several
other teenagers allegedly assembled a crudely made cross by taping
together broken chair legs. They then allegedly burned the cross
inside the fenced yard of a black family that lived across the
street from the house where petitioner was staying. Although this
conduct could have been pun-
Bruce J. Ennis; and for the Center for Individual Rights
by Gary B. Born and Michael P. McDonald.
Briefs of amici curiae urging affirmance were filed for
the State of Minnesota et al. by Hubert H. Humphrey III, Attorney General of Minnesota, and Richard S. Slowes, Assistant Attorney General, Jimmy Evans, Attorney General of
Alabama, Grant Woods, Attorney General of Arizona, Richard Blumenthal, Attorney General of Connecticut, and John J. Kelly, Chief State's Attorney of
Connecticut, Larry EchoHawk, Attorney General of Idaho, Roland W Burris, Attorney General of Illinois, Robert T.
Stephan, Attorney General of Kansas, J. Joseph
Curran, Jr., Attorney General of Maryland, Scott
Harshbarger, Attorney General of Massachusetts, Frank J. Kelley, Attorney General of Michigan, Robert J. Del Tufo, Attorney General of New
Jersey, Lee I. Fisher, Attorney General of Ohio, Susan B.
Loving, Attorney General of Oklahoma, T. Travis Medlock, Attorney General of South Carolina, Charles W Burson, Attorney General of Tennessee, Mary Sue Terry, Attorney
General of Virginia, and Paul Van Dam, Attorney General of
Utah; for the Anti-Defamation League of B'nai B'rith by Allen I.
Saeks, Jeffrey P. Sinensky, Steven M. Freeman, and Michael
Lieberman; for the Asian American Legal Defense and Education
Fund et al. by Angelo N. Ancheta; for the Center for
Democratic Renewal et al. by Frank E. Deale; for the
Criminal Justice Legal Foundation by Kent S. Scheidegger and Charles L. Hobson; for the League of
Minnesota Cities et al. by Carla J. Heyl,
Robert J. Alfton, and Jerome J. Segal; for the National Association for the Advancement of
Colored People et al. by Ronald D. Maines, Dennis C. Hayes, Willie Abrams, and Kemp R. Harshman; for the
National Black Women's Health Project by Catharine A.
MacKinnon and Burke Marshall; for the National Institute
of Municipal Law Officers et al. by Richard Ruda, Michael J. Wahoske, and Mark B. Rotenberg; and for
People for the American Way by Richard S. Hoffman,
Kevin J. Hasson, and Elliot M.
Mincberg. Charles R. Sheppard filed a brief for the Patriot's
Defense Foundation, Inc., as amicus curiae. 380 ished under any of a number of laws,l one of the two provisions
under which respondent city of St. Paul chose to charge petitioner
(then a juvenile) was the St. Paul Bias-Motivated Crime Ordinance,
St. Paul, Minn., Legis. Code § 292.02 (1990), which provides: "Whoever places on public or private property a symbol, object,
appellation, characterization or graffiti, including, but not
limited to, a burning cross or Nazi swastika, which one knows or
has reasonable grounds to know arouses anger, alarm or resentment
in others on the basis of race, color, creed, religion or gender
commits disorderly conduct and shall be guilty of a
misdemeanor." Petitioner moved to dismiss this count on the ground that the
St. Paul ordinance was substantially overbroad and impermissibly
content based and therefore facially invalid under the First
Amendment.2 The trial court granted this motion, but the Minnesota
Supreme Court reversed. That court rejected petitioner's
overbreadth claim because, as construed in prior Minnesota cases,
see, e. g., In re Welfare of S. L. J., 263 N. W. 2d 412 (Minn. 1978), the modifying phrase
"arouses anger, alarm or resentment in others" limited the reach of
the ordinance to conduct that amounts to "fighting words," i. e., "conduct that itself inflicts injury or tends to incite
immediate violence ... ," In re Welfare of R. A. 17:,
464 N. W. 2d 507, 510 (Minn. 1991) (citing Chaplin- 1 The conduct might have violated Minnesota statutes carrying
significant penalties. See, e. g., Minn. Stat. §
609.713(1) (1987) (providing for up to five years in prison for
terroristic threats); § 609.563 (arson) (providing for up to five
years and a $10,000 fine, depending on the value of the property
intended to be damaged); § 609.595 (Supp. 1992) (criminal damage to
property) (providing for up to one year and a $3,000 fine,
depending upon the extent of the damage to the property).
2 Petitioner has also been charged, in Count I of the
delinquency petition, with a violation of Minn. Stat. § 609.2231(4)
(Supp. 1990) (racially motivated assaults). Petitioner did not
challenge this count. 381 sky v. New Hampshire, 315 U. S. 568 , 572
(1942)), and therefore the ordinance reached only expression "that
the first amendment does not protect," 464 N. W. 2d, at 511. The
court also concluded that the ordinance was not impermissibly
content based because, in its view, "the ordinance is a narrowly
tailored means toward accomplishing the compelling governmental
interest in protecting the community against bias-motivated threats
to public safety and order." Ibid. We granted certiorari,
501 U. S. 1204 (1991).
I
In construing the St. Paul ordinance, we are bound by the
construction given to it by the Minnesota court. Posadas de
Puerto Rico Associates v. Tourism Co. of Puerto Rico, 478 U. S. 328 ,
339 (1986); New York v. Ferber, 458 U. S. 747 , 769, n. 24
(1982); Terminiello v. Chicago, 337 U. S. 1 , 4 (1949).
Accordingly, we accept the Minnesota Supreme Court's authoritative
statement that the ordinance reaches only those expressions that
constitute "fighting words" within the meaning of Chaplinsky. 464 N. W. 2d, at 510-511. Petitioner and his amici urge us to modify the scope of the Chaplinsky formulation, thereby invalidating the ordinance as "substantially
overbroad," Broadrick v. Oklahoma, 413 U. S. 601, 610
(1973). We find it unnecessary to consider this issue. Assuming, arguendo, that all of the expression reached by the
ordinance is proscribable under the "fighting words" doctrine, we
nonetheless conclude that the ordinance is facially
unconstitutional in that it prohibits otherwise permitted speech
solely on the basis of the subjects the speech addresses.3
3 Contrary to JUSTICE WHITE'S suggestion, post, at
397-398, n. 1, petitioner's claim is "fairly included" within the
questions presented in the petition for certiorari, see this
Court's Rule 14.1(a). It was clear from the petition and from
petitioner's other filings in this Court (and in the courts below)
that his assertion that the St. Paul ordinance "violat[es]
overbreadth ... principles of the First Amendment," Pet. for Cert.
i, was not 382 The First Amendment generally prevents government from
proscribing speech, see, e. g., Cantwell v. Connecticut, 310 U. S. 296 , 309-311
(1940), or even expressive conduct, see, e. g., Texas v. Johnson, 491
U. S. 397 , 406 (1989), because of disapproval of the ideas
expressed. Content-based regulations are presumptively invalid. Simon & Schuster, Inc. v. Members of N. Y. State Crime Victims Bd., 502 U. S. 105 , 115
(1991); id., at 124 (KENNEDY, J., concurring in judgment); Consolidated Edison Co. of N. Y. v. Public Servo
Comm'n of N. Y., 447 U. S. 530 , 536
(1980); Police Dept. of Chicago v. Mosley, 408 U. S. 92 , 95 (1972).
From 1791 to the present, however, our society, like other free but
civilized societies, has permitted restrictions upon the content of
speech in a
just a technical "overbreadth" claim-i. e., a claim that
the ordinance violated the rights of too many third parties-but
included the contention that the ordinance was "overbroad" in the
sense of restricting more speech than the Constitution permits,
even in its application to him, because it is content based. An
important component of petitioner's argument is, and has been all
along, that narrowly construing the ordinance to cover only
"fighting words" cannot cure this fundamental defect. Id., at 12, 14, 1516. In his briefs in this Court, petitioner argued
that a narrowing construction was ineffective because (1) its
boundaries were vague, Brief for Petitioner 26, and because (2)
denominating particular expression a "fighting word" because of the
impact of its ideological content upon the audience is inconsistent
with the First Amendment, Reply Brief for Petitioner 5; id., at 13 ("[The ordinance] is overbroad, viewpoint
discriminatory and vague as 'narrowly construed''') (emphasis
added). At oral argument, counsel for petitioner reiterated this
second point: "It is ... one of my positions, that in [punishing
only some fighting words and not others], even though it is a
subcategory, technically, of unprotected conduct, [the ordinance]
still is picking out an opinion, a disfavored message, and making
that clear through the State." Tr. of Oral Arg. 8. In resting our
judgment upon this contention, we have not departed from our
criteria of what is "fairly included" within the petition. See Arkansas Electric Cooperative Corp. V. Arkansas Pub.
Servo Comm'n, 461
U. S. 375 , 382, n. 6 (1983); Brown V. Socialist
Workers '74 Campaign Comm., 459 U. S. 87 , 94, n. 9 (1982); Eddings V. Oklahoma, 455 U. S. 104 , 113, n. 9
(1982); see generally R. Stern, E. Gressman, & S. Shapiro,
Supreme Court Practice 361 (6th ed.1986). 383 few limited areas, which are "of such slight social value as a
step to truth that any benefit that may be derived from them is
clearly outweighed by the social interest in order and morality." Chaplinsky, supra, at 572. We have recognized that "the
freedom of speech" referred to by the First Amendment does not
include a freedom to disregard these traditional limitations. See, e. g., Roth v. United States, 354 U. S. 476 (1957)
(obscenity); Beauharnais v. Illinois, 343 U. S. 250 (1952)
(defamation); Chaplinsky v. New Hampshire, supra (" 'fighting' words"); see generally Simon & Schuster,
supra, at 124 (KENNEDY, J., concurring in judgment). Our
decisions since the 1960's have narrowed the scope of the
traditional categorical exceptions for defamation, see New York
Times Co. v. Sullivan, 376 U. S. 254 (1964); Gertz v. Robert Welch, Inc., 418 U. S. 323 (1974); see
generally Milkovich v. Lorain Journal Co., 497 U. S. 1 , 13-17 (1990),
and for obscenity, see Miller v. California, 413 U. S. 15 (1973), but a
limited categorical approach has remained an important part of our
First Amendment jurisprudence.
We have sometimes said that these categories of expression are
"not within the area of constitutionally protected speech," Roth, supra, at 483; Beauharnais, supra, at 266; Chap linsky, supra, at 571-572, or that the "protection of
the First Amendment does not extend" to them, Bose Corp. v. Consumers Union of United States, Inc., 466 U. S. 485 , 504
(1984); Sable Communications of Cal., Inc. v. FCC, 492 U. S. 115 ,
124 (1989). Such statements must be taken in context, however, and
are no more literally true than is the occasionally repeated
shorthand characterizing obscenity "as not being speech at all,"
Sunstein, Pornography and the First Amendment, 1986 Duke L. J. 589,
615, n. 46. What they mean is that these areas of speech can,
consistently with the First Amendment, be regulated because of
their constitutionally proscribable content (obscenity,
defamation, etc.)not that they are categories of speech entirely
invisible to the Constitution, so that they may be made the
vehicles for 384 content discrimination unrelated to their distinctively
proscribable content. Thus, the government may proscribe libel; but
it may not make the further content discrimination of proscribing only libel critical of the government. We recently
acknowledged this distinction in Ferber, 458 U. S., at 763,
where, in upholding New York's child pornography law, we expressly
recognized that there was no "question here of censoring a
particular literary theme .... " See also id., at 775
(O'CONNOR, J., concurring) ("As drafted, New York's statute does
not attempt to suppress the communication of particular
ideas").
Our cases surely do not establish the proposition that the First
Amendment imposes no obstacle whatsoever to regulation of
particular instances of such proscribable expression, so that the
government "may regulate [them] freely," post, at 400
(WHITE, J., concurring in judgment). That would mean that a city
council could enact an ordinance prohibiting only those legally
obscene works that contain criticism of the city government or,
indeed, that do not include endorsement of the city government.
Such a simplistic, all-or-nothing-atall approach to First Amendment
protection is at odds with common sense and with our jurisprudence
as wel1.4 It is
4JUSTICE WHITE concedes that a city council cannot prohibit only
those legally obscene works that contain criticism of the city
government, post, at 406, but asserts that to be the
consequence, not of the First Amendment, but of the Equal
Protection Clause. Such content-based discrimination would not, he
asserts, "be rationally related to a legitimate government
interest." Ibid. But of course the only reason that
government interest is not a "legitimate" one is that it violates
the First Amendment. This Court itself has occasionally fused the
First Amendment into the Equal Protection Clause in this fashion,
but at least with the acknowledgment (which JUSTICE WHITE cannot
afford to make) that the First Amendment underlies its analysis.
See Police Dept. of Chicago v. Mosley, 408 U. S. 92,
95 (1972) (ordinance prohibiting only nonlabor picketing violated
the Equal Protection Clause because there was no "appropriate
governmental interest" supporting the distinction inasmuch as "the
First Amendment means that government has no power to restrict
expression because of its message, its ideas, its subject matter,
or its content"); Carey v. 385 not true that "fighting words" have at most a "de
minimis" expressive content, ibid., or that their
content is in all respects "worthless and undeserving of
constitutional protection," post, at 401; sometimes they are
quite expressive indeed. We have not said that they constitute "no part of the expression of ideas," but only that they
constitute "no essential part of any exposition of ideas." Chap linsky, supra, at 572 (emphasis added).
The proposition that a particular instance of speech can be
proscribable on the basis of one feature (e. g., obscenity)
but not on the basis of another (e. g., opposition to the
city government) is commonplace and has found application in many
contexts. We have long held, for example, that nonverbal expressive
activity can be banned because of the action it entails, but not
because of the ideas it expresses-so that burning a flag in
violation of an ordinance against outdoor fires could be
punishable, whereas burning a flag in violation of an ordinance
against dishonoring the flag is not. See Johnson, 491 U. S.,
at 406-407. See also Barnes v. Glen Theatre, Inc., 501 U. S. 560 ,
569-570 (1991) (plurality opinion); id., at 573-574 (SCALIA,
J., concurring in judgment); id., at 581-582 (SOUTER, J.,
concurring in judgment); United Brown, 447
U. S. 455 (1980). See generally Simon & Schuster,
Inc. v. Members of N. Y. State Crime Victims Bd., 502 U. S. 105 ,
124 (1991) (KENNEDY, J., concurring in judgment).
JUSTICE STEVENS seeks to avoid the point by dismissing the
notion of obscene antigovernment speech as "fantastical," post, at 418, apparently believing that any reference to
politics prevents a finding of obscenity. Unfortunately for the
purveyors of obscenity, that is obviously false. A shockingly hard
core pornographic movie that contains a model sporting a political
tattoo can be found, "taken as a whole, [to] lac[k] serious
literary, artistic, political, or scientific value," Miller v. California, 413 U. S. 15 ,24 (1973)
(emphasis added). Anyway, it is easy enough to come up with other
illustrations of a content-based restriction upon "unprotected
speech" that is obviously invalid: the antigovernment libel
illustration mentioned earlier, for one. See supra, at 384.
And of course the concept of racist fighting words is,
unfortunately, anything but a "highly speculative hypothetica[l]," post, at 419. 386 States v. O'Brien, 391 U. S. 367 , 376-377
(1968). Similarly, we have upheld reasonable "time, place, or
manner" restrictions, but only if they are "justified without
reference to the content of the regulated speech." Ward v. Rock Against Racism, 491 U. S. 781 , 791 (1989)
(internal quotation marks omitted); see also Clark v. Community for Creative NonViolence, 468 U. S. 288 , 298 (1984)
(noting that the O'Brien test differs little from the
standard applied to time, place, or manner restrictions). And just
as the power to proscribe particular speech on the basis of a
noncontent element (e. g., noise) does not entail the power
to proscribe the same speech on the basis of a content element; so
also, the power to proscribe it on the basis of one content
element (e. g., obscenity) does not entail the power to
proscribe it on the basis of other content elements.
In other words, the exclusion of "fighting words" from the scope
of the First Amendment simply means that, for purposes of that
Amendment, the unprotected features of the words are, despite their
verbal character, essentially a "nonspeech" element of
communication. Fighting words are thus analogous to a noisy sound
truck: Each is, as Justice Frankfurter recognized, a "mode of
speech," Niemotko v. Maryland, 340 U. S. 268 , 282 (1951)
(opinion concurring in result); both can be used to convey an idea;
but neither has, in and of itself, a claim upon the First
Amendment. As with the sound truck, however, so also with fighting
words: The government may not regulate use based on hostility-or
favoritism-towards the underlying message expressed. Compare Frisby v. Schultz, 487 U. S. 474 (1988)
(upholding, against facial challenge, a content-neutral ban on
targeted residential picketing), with Carey v. Brown, 447 U. S. 455 (1980) (invalidating a ban on residential picketing that exempted
labor picketing). 5
5 Although JUSTICE WHITE asserts that our analysis disregards
"established principles of First Amendment law," post, at
415, he cites not a single case (and we are aware of none) that
even involved, much less con- 387 The concurrences describe us as setting forth a new First
Amendment principle that prohibition of constitutionally
proscribable speech cannot be "underinclusiv[e]," post, at
402 (WHITE, J., concurring in judgment)-a First Amendment
"absolutism" whereby "[w]ithin a particular 'proscribable' category
of expression, ... a government must either proscribe all speech or no speech at all," post, at 419 (STEVENS, J.,
concurring in judgment). That easy target is of the concurrences'
own invention. In our view, the First Amendment imposes not an
"underinclusiveness" limitation but a "content discrimination"
limitation upon a State's prohibition of proscribable speech. There
is no problem whatever, for example, with a State's prohibiting
obscenity (and other forms of proscribable expression) only in
certain media or markets, for although that prohibition would be
"underinclusive," it would not discriminate on the basis of
content. See, e. g., Sable Communications, 492 U. S., at
124-126 (upholding 47 U. S. C. § 223(b)(1), which prohibits obscene telephone communications).
Even the prohibition against content discrimination that we
assert the First Amendment requires is not absolute. It applies
differently in the context of proscribable speech than in the area
of fully protected speech. The rationale of the general
prohibition, after all, is that content discrimination "raises the
specter that the Government may effectively drive certain ideas or
viewpoints from the marketplace," Simon & Schuster, 502 U. S., at 116; Leathers v. Medlock, 499
U. S. 439 , 448 (1991); FCC v. League of Women Voters
of Cal., 468 U.
S. 364 , 383-384 (1984); Consolidated Edison Co., 447 U.
S., at 536; Police Dept. of Chicago v. Mosley, 408 U.
S.,
sidered and resolved, the issue of content discrimination
through regulation of "unprotected" speech-though we plainly recognized that as an issue in New York v. Ferber, 458 U.
S. 747 (1982). It is of course contrary to all traditions of
our jurisprudence to consider the law on this point conclusively
resolved by broad language in cases where the issue was not
presented or even envisioned. 388 at 95-98. But content discrimination among various instances of
a class of proscribable speech often does not pose this threat.
When the basis for the content discrimination consists entirely
of the very reason the entire class of speech at issue is
proscribable, no significant danger of idea or viewpoint
discrimination exists. Such a reason, having been adjudged neutral
enough to support exclusion of the entire class of speech from
First Amendment protection, is also neutral enough to form the
basis of distinction within the class. To illustrate: A State might
choose to prohibit only that obscenity which is the most patently
offensive in its prurience i. e., that which involves
the most lascivious displays of sexual activity. But it may not
prohibit, for example, only that obscenity which includes offensive political messages. See Kucharek v. Hanaway, 902 F.2d
513 , 517 (CA7 1990), cert. denied, 498 U. S. 1041 (1991). And
the Federal Government can criminalize only those threats of
violence that are directed against the President, see 18 U. S. C. §
871-since the reasons why threats of violence are outside the First
Amendment (protecting individuals from the fear of violence, from
the disruption that fear engenders, and from the possibility that
the threatened violence will occur) have special force when applied
to the person of the President. See Watts v. United
States, 394 U. S.
705 , 707 (1969) (upholding the facial validity of § 871 because
of the "overwhelmin[g] interest in protecting the safety of [the]
Chief Executive and in allowing him to perform his duties without
interference from threats of physical violence"). But the Federal
Government may not criminalize only those threats against the
President that mention his policy on aid to inner cities. And to
take a final example (one mentioned by JUSTICE STEVENS, post, at 421422), a State may choose to regulate price
advertising in one industry but not in others, because the risk of
fraud (one of the characteristics of commercial speech that
justifies depriving it of full First Amendment protection, see Virginia 389 State Bd. of Pharmacy v. Virginia Citizens Consumer
Council, Inc., 425 U. S. 748 , 771-772
(1976)) is in its view greater there. Cf. Morales v. Trans World Airlines, Inc., 504 U. S. 374 (1992)
(state regulation of airline advertising); Ohralik v. Ohio State Bar Assn., 436 U. S. 447 (1978)
(state regulation of lawyer advertising). But a State may not
prohibit only that commercial advertising that depicts men in a
demeaning fashion. See, e. g., Los Angeles Times,
Aug. 8, 1989, section 4, p. 6, col. 1.
Another valid basis for according differential treatment to even
a content-defined subclass of proscribable speech is that the
subclass happens to be associated with particular "secondary
effects" of the speech, so that the regulation is "justified without reference to the content of the ... speech," Renton v. Playtime Theatres, Inc., 475 U. S. 41 , 48 (1986)
(quoting, with emphasis, Virginia State Bd. of Pharmacy,
supra, at 771); see also Young v. American Mini
Theatres, Inc., 427 U. S. 50 , 71, n. 34
(1976) (plurality opinion); id., at 80-82 (Powell, J.,
concurring); Barnes, 501 U. S., at 586 (SOUTER, J.,
concurring in judgment). A State could, for example, permit all
obscene live performances except those involving minors. Moreover,
since words can in some circumstances violate laws directed not
against speech but against conduct (a law against treason, for
example, is violated by telling the enemy the Nation's defense
secrets), a particular content-based subcategory of a proscribable
class of speech can be swept up incidentally within the reach of a
statute directed at conduct rather than speech. See id., at
571 (plurality opinion); id., at 577 (SCALIA, J., concurring
in judgment); id., at 582 (SOUTER, J., concurring in
judgment); FTC v. Superior Court Trial Lawyers Assn., 493 U. S. 411 ,
425432 (1990); O'Brien, 391 U. S., at 376-377. Thus, for
example, sexually derogatory "fighting words," among other words,
may produce a violation of Title VII's general prohibition against
sexual discrimination in employment practices, 42 U. S. C. §
2000e-2; 29 CFR § 1604.11 (1991). See also 18 390 u. S. C. § 242; 42 U. S. C. §§ 1981, 1982. Where the government
does not target conduct on the basis of its expressive content,
acts are not shielded from regulation merely because they express a
discriminatory idea or philosophy.
These bases for distinction refute the proposition that the
selectivity of the restriction is "even arguably 'conditioned upon
the sovereign's agreement with what a speaker may intend to say.'" Metromedia, Inc. v. San Diego, 453 U. S. 490 , 555 (1981)
(STEVENS, J., dissenting in part) (citation omitted). There may be
other such bases as well. Indeed, to validate such selectivity
(where totally proscribable speech is at issue) it may not even be
necessary to identify any particular "neutral" basis, so long as
the nature of the content discrimination is such that there is no
realistic possibility that official suppression of ideas is afoot.
(We cannot think of any First Amendment interest that would stand
in the way of a State's prohibiting only those obscene motion
pictures with blue-eyed actresses.) Save for that limitation, the
regulation of "fighting words," like the regulation of noisy
speech, may address some offensive instances and leave other,
equally offensive, instances alone. See Posadas de Puerto
Rico, 478 U. S., at 342-343.6
6 JUSTICE STEVENS cites a string of opinions as supporting his
assertion that "selective regulation of speech based on content" is
not presumptively invalid. Post, at 421-422. Analysis
reveals, however, that they do not support it. To begin with, three
of them did not command a majority of the Court, Young v. American Mini Theatres, Inc., 427 U. S. 50 , 63-73 (1976)
(plurality opinion); FCC v. Pacifica Foundation, 438 U. S.
726 ,744748 (1978) (plurality opinion); Lehman v. Shaker Heights, 418 U. S. 298 (1974)
(plurality opinion), and two others did not even discuss the First
Amendment, Morales v. Trans World Airlines, Inc., 504 U. S. 374 (1992); Jacob Siegel Co. v. FTC, 327 U. S. 608 (1946). In
any event, all that their contents establish is what we readily
concede: that presumptive invalidity does not mean invariable
invalidity, leaving room for such exceptions as reasonable and
viewpoint-neutral content-based discrimination in nonpublie forums,
see Lehman, supra, at 301-304; see also Cornelius v. NAACP Legal Defense & Ed. Fund, Inc., 473 U. S. 788 ,806 (1985),
or with respect to certain speech by government employees, see Broadrick v. Oklahoma, 391 II
Applying these principles to the St. Paul ordinance, we conclude
that, even as narrowly construed by the Minnesota Supreme Court,
the ordinance is facially unconstitutional. Although the phrase in
the ordinance, "arouses anger, alarm or resentment in others," has
been limited by the Minnesota Supreme Court's construction to reach
only those symbols or displays that amount to "fighting words," the
remaining, unmodified terms make clear that the ordinance applies
only to "fighting words" that insult, or provoke violence, "on the
basis of race, color, creed, religion or gender." Displays
containing abusive invective, no matter how vicious or severe, are
permissible unless they are addressed to one of the specified
disfavored topics. Those who wish to use "fighting words" in
connection with other ideas-to express hostility, for example, on
the basis of political affiliation, union membership, or
homosexuality-are not covered. The First Amendment does not permit
St. Paul to impose special prohibitions on those speakers who
express views on disfavored subjects. See Simon & Schuster, 502 U. S., at 116; Arkansas Writers' Project,
Inc. v. Ragland, 481 U. S. 221 , 229230
(1987).
In its practical operation, moreover, the ordinance goes even
beyond mere content discrimination, to actual viewpoint
discrimination. Displays containing some wordsodious racial
epithets, for example-would be prohibited to proponents of all
views. But "fighting words" that do not themselves invoke race,
color, creed, religion, or genderaspersions upon a person's mother,
for example-would seemingly be usable ad libitum in the
placards of those arguing in favor of racial, color, etc.,
tolerance and equality, but could not be used by those speakers'
opponents. One could hold up a sign saying, for example, that all
"anti- 413 U. S. 601 (1973); see also Civil Service Comm'n v. Letter Carriers,
413 U. S. 548, 564-567 (1973). 392 Catholic bigots" are misbegotten; but not that all "papists"
are, for that would insult and provoke violence "on the basis of
religion." St. Paul has no such authority to license one side of a
debate to fight freestyle, while requiring the other to follow
Marquis of Queensberry rules.
What we have here, it must be emphasized, is not a prohibition
of fighting words that are directed at certain persons or groups
(which would be facially valid if it met the requirements of
the Equal Protection Clause); but rather, a prohibition of fighting
words that contain (as the Minnesota Supreme Court repeatedly
emphasized) messages of "biasmotivated" hatred and in particular,
as applied to this case, messages "based on virulent notions of
racial supremacy." 464 N. W. 2d, at 508, 511. One must
wholeheartedly agree with the Minnesota Supreme Court that "[i]t is
the responsibility, even the obligation, of diverse communities to
confront such notions in whatever form they appear," id., at
508, but the manner of that confrontation cannot consist of
selective limitations upon speech. St. Paul's brief asserts that a
general "fighting words" law would not meet the city's needs
because only a content-specific measure can communicate to minority
groups that the "group hatred" aspect of such speech "is not
condoned by the majority." Brief for Respondent 25. The point of
the First Amendment is that majority preferences must be expressed
in some fashion other than silencing speech on the basis of its
content.
Despite the fact that the Minnesota Supreme Court and St. Paul
acknowledge that the ordinance is directed at expression of group
hatred, JUSTICE STEVENS suggests that this "fundamentally misreads"
the ordinance. Post, at 433. I t is directed, he claims, not
to speech of a particular content, but to particular "injur[ies]"
that are "qualitatively different" from other injuries. Post, at 424. This is wordplay. What makes the anger, fear,
sense of dishonor, etc., produced by violation of this ordinance
distinct from the anger, fear, sense of dishonor, etc., produced by
other fighting words is 393 nothing other than the fact that it is caused by a distinctive
idea, conveyed by a distinctive message. The First Amendment cannot
be evaded that easily. It is obvious that the symbols which will
arouse "anger, alarm or resentment in others on the basis of race,
color, creed, religion or gender" are those symbols that
communicate a message of hostility based on one of these
characteristics. St. Paul concedes in its brief that the ordinance
applies only to "racial, religious, or gender-specific symbols"
such as "a burning cross, Nazi swastika or other instrumentality of
like import." Brief for Respondent 8. Indeed, St. Paul argued in
the Juvenile Court that "[t]he burning of a cross does express a
message and it is, in fact, the content of that message which the
St. Paul Ordinance attempts to legislate." Memorandum from the
Ramsey County Attorney to the Honorable Charles A. Flinn, Jr.,
dated July 13, 1990, in In re Welfare of R. A. V:, No.
89-D-1231 (Ramsey Cty. Juvenile Ct.), p. 1, reprinted in App. to
Brief for Petitioner C-l.
The content-based discrimination reflected in the St. Paul
ordinance comes within neither any of the specific exceptions to
the First Amendment prohibition we discussed earlier nor a more
general exception for content discrimination that does not threaten
censorship of ideas. It assuredly does not fall within the
exception for content discrimination based on the very reasons why
the particular class of speech at issue (here, fighting words) is
proscribable. As explained earlier, see supra, at 386, the
reason why fighting words are categorically excluded from the
protection of the First Amendment is not that their content
communicates any particular idea, but that their content embodies a
particularly intolerable (and socially unnecessary) mode of
expressing whatever idea the speaker wishes to convey. St.
Paul has not singled out an especially offensive mode of
expression-it has not, for example, selected for prohibition only
those fighting words that communicate ideas in a threatening (as
opposed to a merely obnoxious) manner. Rather, it has proscribed
fight- 394 ing words of whatever manner that communicate messages of
racial, gender, or religious intolerance. Selectivity of this sort
creates the possibility that the city is seeking to handicap the
expression of particular ideas. That possibility would alone be
enough to render the ordinance presumptively invalid, but St.
Paul's comments and concessions in this case elevate the
possibility to a certainty.
St. Paul argues that the ordinance comes within another of the
specific exceptions we mentioned, the one that allows content
discrimination aimed only at the "secondary effects" of the speech,
see Renton v. Playtime Theatres, Inc., 475 U. S. 41 (1986).
According to St. Paul, the ordinance is intended, "not to impact on [sic] the right of free expression of the accused," but
rather to "protect against the victimization of a person or persons
who are particularly vulnerable because of their membership in a
group that historically has been discriminated against." Brief for
Respondent 28. Even assuming that an ordinance that completely
proscribes, rather than merely regulates, a specified category of
speech can ever be considered to be directed only to the secondary
effects of such speech, it is clear that the St. Paul ordinance is
not directed to secondary effects within the meaning of Renton. As we said in Boos v. Barry, 485 U. S. 312 (1988),
"Listeners' reactions to speech are not the type of 'secondary
effects' we referred to in Renton." Id., at 321. "The
emotive impact of speech on its audience is not a 'secondary
effect.'" Ibid. See also id., at 334 (opinion of
Brennan, J.).7
7 St. Paul has not argued in this case that the ordinance merely
regulates that subclass of fighting words which is most likely to
provoke a violent response. But even if one assumes (as appears
unlikely) that the categories selected may be so described, that
would not justify selective regulation under a "secondary effects"
theory. The only reason why such expressive conduct would be
especially correlated with violence is that it conveys a
particularly odious message; because the "chain of causation" thus necessarily "run[s] through the persuasive effect of the
expressive component" of the conduct, Barnes v. Glen
Theatre, Inc., 501 U. S. 560 , 586 (1991)
(SOUTER, J., concurring in judgment), it is clear that the St.
Paul 395 It hardly needs discussion that the ordinance does not fall
within some more general exception permitting all selectivity that for any reason is beyond the suspicion of official
suppression of ideas. The statements of St. Paul in this very case
afford ample basis for, if not full confirmation of, that
suspicion.
Finally, St. Paul and its amici defend the conclusion of
the Minnesota Supreme Court that, even if the ordinance regulates
expression based on hostility towards its protected ideological
content, this discrimination is nonetheless justified because it is
narrowly tailored to serve compelling state interests.
Specifically, they assert that the ordinance helps to ensure the
basic human rights of members of groups that have historically been
subjected to discrimination, including the right of such group
members to live in peace where they wish. We do not doubt that
these interests are compelling, and that the ordinance can be said
to promote them. But the "danger of censorship" presented by a
facially contentbased statute, Leathers v. Medlock, 499 U. S., at 448, requires that that weapon be employed only where
it is "necessary to serve the asserted [compelling]
interest," Burson v. Freeman, 504 U. S. 191 , 199 (1992)
(plurality opinion) (emphasis added); Perry Ed. Assn. v. Perry Local Educators' Assn., 460 U. S. 37 , 45 (1983).
The existence of adequate contentneutral alternatives thus
"undercut[s] significantly" any defense of such a statute, Boos v. Barry, supra, at 329, casting considerable
doubt on the government's protestations that "the asserted
justification is in fact an accurate description of the purpose and
effect of the law," Burson, supra, at 213 (KENNEDY, J.,
concurring). See Boos, supra, at 324-329; cf. Minneapolis
Star & Tribune Co. v. Minnesota Comm'r of
Revenue, 460 U.
S. 575 , 586-587 (1983). The dispositive question in this case,
therefore, is whether content discrimination is reasonably
necessary to achieve St. Paul's compel-
ordinance regulates on the basis of the "primary" effect of the
speechi. e., its persuasive (or repellant) force. 396 ling interests; it plainly is not. An ordinance not limited to
the favored topics, for example, would have precisely the same
beneficial effect. In fact the only interest distinctively served
by the content limitation is that of displaying the city council's
special hostility towards the particular biases thus singled out.s
That is precisely what the First Amendment forbids. The politicians
of St. Paul are entitled to express that hostility-but not through
the means of imposing unique limitations upon speakers who (however
benightedly) disagree.
***
Let there be no mistake about our belief that burning a cross in
someone's front yard is reprehensible. But St. Paul has sufficient
means at its disposal to prevent such behavior without adding the
First Amendment to the fire.
The judgment of the Minnesota Supreme Court is reversed, and the
case is remanded for proceedings not inconsistent with this
opinion.
It is so ordered.
8 A plurality of the Court reached a different conclusion with
regard to the Tennessee antielectioneering statute considered
earlier this Term in Burson v. Freeman, 504 U. S. 191 (1992). In
light of the "logical connection" between electioneering and the
State's compelling interest in preventing voter intimidation and
election fraud-an inherent connection borne out by a "long history"
and a "widespread and time-tested consensus," id., at 206,
208, n. 10, 211-the plurality concluded that it was faced with one
of those "rare case[s]" in which the use of a facially
content-based restriction was justified by interests unrelated to
the suppression of ideas, id., at 211; see also id., at 213 (KENNEDY, J., concurring). JUSTICE WHITE and JUSTICE STEVENS
are therefore quite mistaken when they seek to convert the Burson plurality's passing comment that "[t]he First
Amendment does not require States to regulate for problems that do
not exist," id., at 207, into endorsement of the
revolutionary proposition that the suppression of particular ideas
can be justified when only those ideas have been a source of
trouble in the past. Post, at 405 (WHITE, J., concurring in
judgment); post, at 434 (STEVENS, J., concurring in
judgment). 397 JUSTICE WHITE, with whom JUSTICE BLACKMUN and JUSTICE O'CONNOR
join, and with whom JUSTICE STEVENS joins except as to Part I-A,
concurring in the judgment.
I agree with the majority that the judgment of the Minnesota
Supreme Court should be reversed. However, our agreement ends
there.
This case could easily be decided within the contours of
established First Amendment law by holding, as petitioner argues,
that the St. Paul ordinance is fatally overbroad because it
criminalizes not only unprotected expression but expression
protected by the First Amendment. See Part II, infra. Instead, "find[ing] it unnecessary" to consider the questions upon
which we granted review,l ante, at 381, the
1 The Court granted certiorari to review the following
questions:
"1. May a local government enact a content-based, 'hate-crime'
ordinance prohibiting the display of symbols, including a Nazi
swastika or a burning cross, on public or private property, which
one knows or has reason to know arouses anger, alarm, or resentment
in others on the basis of race, color, creed, religion, or gender
without violating overbreadth and vagueness principles of the First
Amendment to the United States Constitution?
"2. Can the constitutionality of such a vague and substantially
overbroad content-based restraint of expression be saved by a
limiting construction, like that used to save the vague and
overbroad content-neutral laws, restricting its application to
'fighting words' or 'imminent lawless action?'" Pet. for Cert.
i.
It has long been the rule of this Court that "[o]nly the
questions set forth in the petition, or fairly included therein,
will be considered by the Court." This Court's Rule 14.1(a). This
Rule has served to focus the issues presented for review. But the
majority reads the Rule so expansively that any First Amendment
theory would appear to be "fairly included" within the questions
quoted above.
Contrary to the impression the majority attempts to create
through its selective quotation of petitioner's briefs, see ante, at 381-382, n. 3, petitioner did not present to this
Court or the Minnesota Supreme Court anything approximating the
novel theory the majority adopts today. Most certainly petitioner
did not "reiterat[e]" such a claim at argument; he responded to a
question from the bench, Tr. of Oral Arg. 8. Previously, this Court
has shown the restraint to refrain from deciding cases on the
basis 398 WHITE, J., concurring in judgment
Court holds the ordinance facially unconstitutional on a ground
that was never presented to the Minnesota Supreme Court, a ground
that has not been briefed by the parties before this Court, a
ground that requires serious departures from the teaching of prior
cases and is inconsistent with the plurality opinion in Burson v. Freeman, 504 U. S. 191 (1992),
which was joined by two of the five Justices in the majority in the
present case.
This Court ordinarily is not so eager to abandon its precedents.
Twice within the past month, the Court has declined to overturn
longstanding but controversial decisions on questions of
constitutional law. See Allied-Signal, Inc. v. Director,
Division of Taxation, 504 U. S. 768 (1992); Quill Corp. v. North Dakota, 504 U. S. 298 (1992). In
each case, we had the benefit of full briefing on the critical
issue, so that the parties and amici had the opportunity to
apprise us of the impact of a change in the law. And in each case,
the Court declined to abandon its precedents, invoking the
principle of stare decisis. Allied-Signal, Inc., supra, at
783-786; Quill Corp., supra, at 317-318.
But in the present case, the majority casts aside
longestablished First Amendment doctrine without the benefit of
briefing and adopts an untried theory. This is hardly a judicious
way of proceeding, and the Court's reasoning in reaching its result
is transparently wrong.
of its own theories when they have not been pressed or passed
upon by a state court of last resort. See, e. g., Illinois v. Gates, 462
U. S. 213 , 217-224 (1983).
Given this threshold issue, it is my view that the Court lacks
jurisdiction to decide the case on the majority rationale. Cf. Arkansas Electric Cooperative Corp. v. Arkansas Pub.
Servo Comm'n, 461
U. S. 375 , 382, n. 6 (1983). Certainly the preliminary
jurisdictional and prudential concerns are sufficiently weighty
that we would never have granted certiorari had petitioner sought
review of a question based on the majority's decisional theory. 399 I A
This Court's decisions have plainly stated that expression
falling within certain limited categories so lacks the values the
First Amendment was designed to protect that the Constitution
affords no protection to that expression. Chaplinsky v. New Hampshire, 315 U. S. 568 (1942),
made the point in the clearest possible terms: "There are certain well-defined and narrowly limited classes of
speech, the prevention and punishment of which have never been
thought to raise any Constitutional problem .... It has been well
observed that such utterances are no essential part of any
exposition of ideas, and are of such slight social value as a step
to truth that any benefit that may be derived from them is clearly
outweighed by the social interest in order and morality." Id., at 571-572. See also Bose Corp. v. Consumers Union of United States, Inc., 466 U. S. 485 ,
504 (1984) (citing Chaplinsky).
Thus, as the majority concedes, see ante, at 383-384,
this Court has long held certain discrete categories of expression
to be proscribable on the basis of their content. For instance, the
Court has held that the individual who falsely shouts "fire" in a
crowded theater may not claim the protection of the First
Amendment. Schenck v. United States, 249 U. S. 47 , 52 (1919).
The Court has concluded that neither child pornography nor
obscenity is protected by the First Amendment. New York v. Ferber, 458 U.
S. 747 , 764 (1982); Miller v. California, 413 U. S. 15 , 20
(1973); Roth v. United States, 354 U. S. 476 , 484-485
(1957). And the Court has observed that, "[l]eaving aside the
special considerations when public officials [and public figures]
are the target, a libelous publication is not protected by the
Constitution." Ferber, supra, at 763 (citations
omitted). 400 WHITE, J., concurring in judgment
All of these categories are content based. But the Court has
held that the First Amendment does not apply to them because their
expressive content is worthless or of de minimis value to
society. Chaplinsky, supra, at 571-572. We have not departed
from this principle, emphasizing repeatedly that, "within the
confines of [these] given classification[s], the evil to be
restricted so overwhelmingly outweighs the expressive interests, if
any, at stake, that no process of case-by-case adjudication is
required." Ferber, supra, at 763-764; Bigelow v. Virginia, 421
U. S. 809 , 819 (1975). This categorical approach has provided a
principled and narrowly focused means for distinguishing between
expression that the government may regulate freely and that which
it may regulate on the basis of content only upon a showing of
compelling need.2
Today, however, the Court announces that earlier Courts did not
mean their repeated statements that certain categories of
expression are "not within the area of constitutionally protected
speech." Roth, supra, at 483. See ante, at 383,
citing Beauharnais v. Illinois, 343 U. S. 250 , 266
(1952); Chap linsky, supra, at 571-572; Bose Corp.,
supra, at 504; Sable Communications of Cal., Inc. v. FCC, 492 U. S.
115 , 124 (1989). The present Court submits that such clear
statements "must be taken in context" and are not "literally true." Ante, at 383.
To the contrary, those statements meant precisely what they
said: The categorical approach is a firmly entrenched part of our
First Amendment jurisprudence. Indeed, the Court in Roth reviewed the guarantees of freedom of expression in effect at the
time of the ratification of the Constitution and concluded, "In
light of this history, it is apparent that the unconditional
phrasing of the First Amendment was
2 "In each of these areas, the limits of the unprotected
category, as well as the unprotected character of particular
communications, have been determined by the judicial evaluation of
special facts that have been deemed to have constitutional
significance." Bose Corp. v. Consumers Union of United
States, Inc., 466
U. S. 485 , 504-505 (1984). 401 not intended to protect every utterance." 354 U. S., at
482-483.
In its decision today, the Court points to "[n]othing ... in
this Court's precedents warrant[ing] disregard of this longstanding
tradition." Burson, 504 U. S., at 216 (SCALIA, J.,
concurring in judgment); Allied-Signal, Inc., supra, at 783.
Nevertheless, the majority holds that the First Amendment protects
those narrow categories of expression long held to be undeserving
of First Amendment protection-at least to the extent that lawmakers
may not regulate some fighting words more strictly than others
because of their content. The Court announces that such
content-based distinctions violate the First Amendment because
"[t]he government may not regulate use based on hostility-or
favoritism-towards the underlying message expressed." Ante, at 386. Should the government want to criminalize certain fighting
words, the Court now requires it to criminalize all fighting
words.
To borrow a phrase: "Such a simplistic, all-or-nothing-atall
approach to First Amendment protection is at odds with common sense
and with our jurisprudence as well." Ante, at 384. It is
inconsistent to hold that the government may proscribe an entire
category of speech because the content of that speech is evil, Ferber, supra, at 763-764; but that the government may not
treat a subset of that category differently without violating the
First Amendment; the content of the subset is by definition
worthless and undeserving of constitutional protection.
The majority's observation that fighting words are "quite
expressive indeed," ante, at 385, is no answer. Fighting
words are not a means of exchanging views, rallying supporters, or
registering a protest; they are directed against individuals to
provoke violence or to inflict injury. Chaplin sky, 315 U.
S., at 572. Therefore, a ban on all fighting words or on a subset
of the fighting words category would restrict only the social evil
of hate speech, without creating the danger of driving viewpoints
from the marketplace. See ante, at 387. 402 WHITE, J., concurring in judgment
Therefore, the Court's insistence on inventing its brand of
First Amendment underinclusiveness puzzles me.3 The overbreadth
doctrine has the redeeming virtue of attempting to avoid the
chilling of protected expression, Broadrick v. Oklahoma, 413
U. S. 601 , 612 (1973); Osborne v. Ohio, 495 U. S. 103 , 112, n. 8
(1990); Brockett v. Spokane Arcades, Inc., 472 U. S. 491 , 503
(1985); Ferber, supra, at 772, but the Court's new
"underbreadth" creation serves no desirable function. Instead, it
permits, indeed invites, the continuation of expressive conduct
that in this case is evil and worthless in First Amendment terms,
see Ferber, supra, at 763 764; Chaplinsky, supra, at
571-572, until the city of St. Paul cures the underbreadth by
adding to its ordinance a catchall phrase such as "and all other
fighting words that may constitutionally be subject to this
ordinance."
Any contribution of this holding to First Amendment
jurisprudence is surely a negative one, since it necessarily
signals that expressions of violence, such as the message of
intimidation and racial hatred conveyed by burning a cross on
someone's lawn, are of sufficient value to outweigh the social
interest in order and morality that has traditionally placed such
fighting words outside the First Amendment.4 Indeed, by
characterizing fighting words as a form of "debate," ante, at 392, the majority legitimates hate speech as a form of public
discussion.
3 The assortment of exceptions the Court attaches to its rule
belies the majority's claim, see ante, at 387, that its new
theory is truly concerned with content discrimination. See Part
I-C, infra (discussing the exceptions).
4 This does not suggest, of course, that cross burning is always
unprotected. Burning a cross at a political rally would almost
certainly be protected expression. Cf. Brandenburg v. Ohio, 395 U.
S. 444 , 445 (1969). But in such a context, the cross burning
could not be characterized as a "direct personal insult or an
invitation to exchange fisticuffs," Texas v. Johnson, 491 U. S. 397 ,
409 (1989), to which the fighting words doctrine, see Part II, infra, applies. 403 Furthermore, the Court obscures the line between speech that
could be regulated freely on the basis of content (i. e., the narrow categories of expression falling outside the First
Amendment) and that which could be regulated on the basis of
content only upon a showing of a compelling state interest (i. e., all remaining expression). By placing fighting words,
which the Court has long held to be valueless, on at least equal
constitutional footing with political discourse and other forms of
speech that we have deemed to have the greatest social value, the
majority devalues the latter category. See Burson v. Freeman, supra, at 196; Eu v. San Francisco Cty.
Democratic Central Comm., 489 U. S. 214 , 222-223
(1989).
B
In a second break with precedent, the Court refuses to sustain
the ordinance even though it would survive under the strict
scrutiny applicable to other protected expression. Assuming, arguendo, that the St. Paul ordinance is a contentbased
regulation of protected expression, it nevertheless would pass
First Amendment review under settled law upon a showing that the
regulation "'is necessary to serve a compelling state interest and
is narrowly drawn to achieve that end.'" Simon & Schuster, Inc. v. Members of N. Y. State Crime
Victims Bd., 502
U. S. 105 , 118 (1991) (quoting Arkansas Writers' Project,
Inc. v. Ragland, 481 U. S. 221 , 231
(1987)). St. Paul has urged that its ordinance, in the words of the
majority, "helps to ensure the basic human rights of members of
groups that have historically been subjected to discrimination ....
" Ante, at 395. The Court expressly concedes that this
interest is compelling and is promoted by the ordinance. Ibid. Nevertheless, the Court treats strict scrutiny
analysis as irrelevant to the constitutionality of the
legislation: "The dispositive question ... is whether content discrimination
is reasonably necessary to achieve St. Paul's compelling interests;
it plainly is not. An ordinance not 404 WHITE, J., concurring in judgment limited to the favored topics, for example, would have precisely
the same beneficial effect." Ante, at 395-396. Under the majority's view, a narrowly drawn, content-based
ordinance could never pass constitutional muster if the object of
that legislation could be accomplished by banning a wider category
of speech. This appears to be a general renunciation of strict
scrutiny review, a fundamental tool of First Amendment
analysis.5
This abandonment of the doctrine is inexplicable in light of our
decision in Burson v. Freeman, 504 U. S. 191 (1992),
which was handed down just a month ago.6 In Burson, seven of
the eight participating Members of the Court agreed that the strict
scrutiny standard applied in a case involving a First Amendment
challenge to a content-based statute. See id., at 198
(plurality opinion); id., at 217 (STEVENS, J.,
5 The majority relies on Boos v. Barry, 485 U. S. 312 (1988), in
arguing that the availability of content-neutral alternatives
"'undercut[s] significantly'" a claim that content-based
legislation is "'necessary to serve the asserted
[compelling] interest.''' Ante, at 395 (quoting Boos,
supra, at 329, and Burson v. Freeman, 504 U. S. 191 , 199 (1992)
(plurality opinion)). Boos does not support the majority's
analysis. In Boos, Congress already had decided that the
challenged legislation was not necessary, and the Court pointedly
deferred to this choice. 485 U. S., at 329. St. Paul lawmakers have
made no such legislative choice.
Moreover, in Boos, the Court held that the challenged
statute was not narrowly tailored because a less restrictive
alternative was available. Ibid. But the Court's analysis
today turns Boos inside-out by substituting the majority's
policy judgment that a more restrictive alternative could
adequately serve the compelling need identified by St.
Paullawmakers. The result would be: (a) a statute that was not
tailored to fit the need identified by the government; and (b) a
greater restriction on fighting words, even though the Court
clearly believes that fighting words have protected expressive
content. Ante, at 384-385.
6 Earlier this Term, seven of the eight participating Members of
the Court agreed that strict scrutiny analysis applied in Simon & Schuster, Inc. v. Members of N. Y. State Crime Victims Bd., 502 U. S. 105 (1991), in
which we struck down New York's "Son of Sam" law, which required
"that an accused or convicted criminal's income from works
describing his crime be deposited in an escrow account." Id., at 108. 405 dissenting).7 The statute at issue prohibited the solicitation
of votes and the display or distribution of campaign materials
within 100 feet of the entrance to a polling place. The plurality
concluded that the legislation survived strict scrutiny because the
State had asserted a compelling interest in regulating
electioneering near polling places and because the statute at issue
was narrowly tailored to accomplish that goal. Id., at
208-210.
Significantly, the statute in Burson did not proscribe
all speech near polling places; it restricted only political
speech. Id., at 197. The Burson plurality, which
included THE CHIEF JUSTICE and JUSTICE KENNEDY, concluded that the
distinction between types of speech required application of strict
scrutiny, but it squarely rejected the proposition that the
legislation failed First Amendment review because it could have
been drafted in broader, content-neutral terms: "States adopt laws to address the problems that confront them.
The First Amendment does not require States to regulate for
problems that do not exist." Id., at 207 (emphasis added). This reasoning is in direct conflict with the majority's
analysis in the present case, which leaves two options to lawmakers
attempting to regulate expressions of violence: (1) enact a
sweeping prohibition on an entire class of speech (thereby
requiring "regulat[ion] for problems that do not exist"); or (2)
not legislate at all.
Had the analysis adopted by the majority in the present case
been applied in Burson, the challenged election law would
have failed constitutional review, for its content-based
distinction between political and nonpolitical speech could not
have been characterized as "reasonably necessary," ante, 7 The Burson dissenters did not complain that the
plurality erred in applying strict scrutiny; they objected that the
plurality was not sufficiently rigorous in its review. 504 U. S.,
at 225-226 (STEVENS, J., dissenting). 406 WHITE, J., concurring in judgment
at 395, to achieve the State's interest in regulating polling
place premises.8
As with its rejection of the Court's categorical analysis, the
majority offers no reasoned basis for discarding our firmly
established strict scrutiny analysis at this time. The majority
appears to believe that its doctrinal revisionism is necessary to
prevent our elected lawmakers from prohibiting libel against
members of one political party but not another and from enacting
similarly preposterous laws. Ante, at 384. The majority is
misguided.
Although the First Amendment does not apply to categories of
unprotected speech, such as fighting words, the Equal Protection
Clause requires that the regulation of unprotected speech be
rationally related to a legitimate government interest. A
defamation statute that drew distinctions on the basis of political
affiliation or "an ordinance prohibiting only those legally obscene
works that contain criticism of the city government," ibid., would unquestionably fail rational-basis review.9
8JU8TICE SCALIA concurred in the judgment in Burson, reasoning that the statute, "though content based, is
constitutional [as] a reasonable, viewpoint-neutral regulation of a
nonpublic forum." Id., at 214. However, nothing in his
reasoning in the present case suggests that a contentbased ban on
fighting words would be constitutional were that ban limited to
nonpublic fora. Taken together, the two opinions suggest that, in
some settings, political speech, to which "the First Amendment 'has
its fullest and most urgent application,'" is entitled to less
constitutional protection than fighting words. Eu v. San
Francisco Cty. Democratic Central Comm., 489 U. S. 214 , 223 (1989)
(quoting Monitor Patriot Co. v. Roy, 401 9 The majority is mistaken in stating that a ban on obscene
works critical of government would fail equal protection review
only because the ban would violate the First Amendment. Ante, at 384-385, n. 4. While decisions such as Police
Dept. of Chicago v. Mosley, 408 U. S. 92 (1972),
recognize that First Amendment principles may be relevant to an
equal protection claim challenging distinctions that impact on
protected expression, id., at 95-99, there is no basis for
linking First and Fourteenth Amendment analysis in a case involving
unprotected expression. Certainly, one 407 Turning to the St. Paul ordinance and assuming, arguendo, as the majority does, that the ordinance is not constitutionally
overbroad (but see Part II, infra), there is no question
that it would pass equal protection review. The ordinance
proscribes a subset of "fighting words," those that injure "on the
basis of race, color, creed, religion or gender." This selective
regulation reflects the city's judgment that harms based on race,
color, creed, religion, or gender are more pressing public concerns
than the harms caused by other fighting words. In light of our
Nation's long and painful experience with discrimination, this
determination is plainly reasonable. Indeed, as the majority
concedes, the interest is compelling. Ante, at 395.
C
The Court has patched up its argument with an apparently
nonexhaustive list of ad hoc exceptions, in what can be viewed
either as an attempt to confine the effects of its decision to the
facts of this case, see post, at 415 (BLACKMUN, J.,
concurring in judgment), or as an effort to anticipate some of the
questions that will arise from its radical revision of First
Amendment law.
For instance, if the majority were to give general application
to the rule on which it decides this case, today's decision would
call into question the constitutionality of the statute making it
illegal to threaten the life of the President. 18 U. S. C. §871.
See Watts v. United States, 394 U. S. 705 (1969) (per curiam). Surely, this statute, by
singling out certain threats, incorporates a content-based
distinction; it indicates that the Government especially disfavors
threats against the President as opposed to threats against all
oth-
need not resort to First Amendment principles to conclude that
the sort of improbable legislation the majority hypothesizes is
based on senseless distinctions. 408 WHITE, J., concurring in judgment
ers.10 See ante, at 391. But because the Government could
prohibit all threats and not just those directed against the
President, under the Court's theory, the compelling reasons
justifying the enactment of special legislation to safeguard the
President would be irrelevant, and the statute would fail First
Amendment review.
To save the statute, the majority has engrafted the following
exception onto its newly announced First Amendment rule:
Content-based distinctions may be drawn within an unprotected
category of speech if the basis for the distinctions is "the very
reason the entire class of speech at issue is proscribable." Ante, at 388. Thus, the argument goes, the statute making it
illegal to threaten the life of the President is constitutional,
"since the reasons why threats of violence are outside the First
Amendment (protecting individuals from the fear of violence, from
the disruption that fear engenders, and from the possibility that
the threatened violence will occur) have special force when applied
to the person of the President." Ibid. The exception swallows the majority's rule. Certainly, it should
apply to the St. Paul ordinance, since "the reasons why [fighting
words] are outside the First Amendment ... have special force when
applied to [groups that have historically been subjected to
discrimination]."
To avoid the result of its own analysis, the Court suggests that
fighting words are simply a mode of communication, rather than a
content-based category, and that the St. Paul ordinance has not
singled out a particularly objectionable mode of communication. Ante, at 386, 393. Again, the majority confuses the issue. A
prohibition on fighting words is not a time, place, or manner
restriction; it is a ban on a class of speech that conveys an
overriding message of personal injury and imminent violence, Chaplinsky, 315 U. S., at 572, a message that is at its
ugliest when directed against groups
10 Indeed, such a law is content based in and of itself because
it distinguishes between threatening and nonthreatening speech. 409 that have long been the targets of discrimination. Accordingly,
the ordinance falls within the first exception to the majority's
theory.
As its second exception, the Court posits that certain
content-based regulations will survive under the new regime if the
regulated subclass "happens to be associated with particular
'secondary effects' of the speech ... ," ante, at 389, which
the majority treats as encompassing instances in which "words can
... violate laws directed not against speech but against conduct
... ," ibidY Again, there is a simple explanation for the
Court's eagerness to craft an exception to its new First Amendment
rule: Under the general rule the Court applies in this case, Title
VII hostile work environment claims would suddenly be
unconstitutional.
Title VII of the Civil Rights Act of 1964 makes it unlawful to
discriminate "because of [an] individual's race, color, religion,
sex, or national origin," 42 U. S. C. § 2000e-2(a)(1), and the
regulations covering hostile workplace claims forbid "sexual
harassment," which includes "[u]nwelcome sexual advances, requests
for sexual favors, and other verbal or physical conduct of a sexual
nature" that create "an intimidating, hostile, or offensive working
environment," 29 CFR § 1604.11(a) (1991). The regulation does not
prohibit workplace harassment generally; it focuses on what the
majority would characterize as the "disfavored topi[c]" of sexual
harassment. Ante, at 391. In this way, Title VII is similar
to the St. Paul ordinance that the majority condemns because it
"impose[s] special prohibitions on those speakers who express views
on disfavored subjects." Ibid. Under the broad principle the
Court uses to decide the present case,
11 The consequences of the majority's conflation of the rarely
used secondary effects standard and the O'Brien test for
conduct incorporating "speech" and "nonspeech" elements, see
generally United States v. O'Brien, 391 U. S. 367 , 376-377
(1968), present another question that I fear will haunt us and the
lower courts in the aftermath of the majority's opinion. 410 WHITE, J., concurring in judgment
hostile work environment claims based on sexual harassment
should fail First Amendment review; because a general ban on
harassment in the workplace would cover the problem of sexual
harassment, any attempt to proscribe the subcategory of sexually
harassing expression would violate the First Amendment.
Hence, the majority's second exception, which the Court
indicates would insulate a Title VII hostile work environment claim
from an underinclusiveness challenge because "sexually derogatory
'fighting words' ... may produce a violation of Title VII's general
prohibition against sexual discrimination in employment practices." Ante, at 389. But application of this exception to a hostile
work environment claim does not hold up under close
examination.
First, the hostile work environment regulation is not keyed to
the presence or absence of an economic quid pro quo, Meritor
Savings Bank, F. S. B. v. Vinson, 477 U. S. 57 , 65 (1986),
but to the impact of the speech on the victimized worker.
Consequently, the regulation would no more fall within a secondary
effects exception than does the St. Paul ordinance. Ante, at
394. Second, the majority's focus on the statute's general
prohibition on discrimination glosses over the language of the
specific regulation governing hostile working environment, which
reaches beyond any "incidental" effect on speech. United
States v. O'Brien, 391 U. S. 367 , 376
(1968). If the relationship between the broader statute and
specific regulation is sufficent to bring the Title VII regulation
within O'Brien, then all St. Paul need do to bring its
ordinance within this exception is to add some prefatory language
concerning discrimination generally.
As to the third exception to the Court's theory for deciding
this case, the majority concocts a catchall exclusion to protect
against unforeseen problems, a concern that is heightened here
given the lack of briefing on the majority's decisional theory.
This final exception would apply in cases in which "there is no
realistic possibility that official suppression of ideas is afoot." Ante, at 390. As I have demon- 411 strated, this case does not concern the official suppression of
ideas. See supra, at 401. The majority discards this notion
out of hand. Ante, at 395.
As I see it, the Court's theory does not work and will do
nothing more than confuse the law. Its selection of this case to
rewrite First Amendment law is particularly inexplicable, because
the whole problem could have been avoided by deciding this case
under settled First Amendment principles.
II
Although I disagree with the Court's analysis, I do agree with
its conclusion: The St. Paul ordinance is unconstitutional.
However, I would decide the case on overbreadth grounds.
We have emphasized time and again that overbreadth doctrine is
an exception to the established principle that "a person to whom a
statute may constitutionally be applied will not be heard to
challenge that statute on the ground that it may conceivably be
applied unconstitutionally to others, in other situations not
before the Court." Broadrick v. Oklahoma, 413 U. S.,
at 610; Brockett v. Spokane Arcades, Inc., 472 U. S.,
at 503-504. A defendant being prosecuted for speech or expressive
conduct may challenge the law on its face if it reaches protected
expression, even when that person's activities are not protected by
the First Amendment. This is because "the possible harm to society
in permitting some unprotected speech to go unpunished is
outweighed by the possibility that protected speech of others may
be muted." Broadrick, supra, at 612; Osborne v. Ohio, 495 U. S., at 112, n. 8; New York v. Ferber, 458 U. S., at 768-769; Schaumburg v. Citizens for a Better Environment, 444 U. S. 620 , 634
(1980); Gooding v. Wilson, 405 U. S. 518 , 521
(1972).
However, we have consistently held that, because overbreadth
analysis is "strong medicine," it may be invoked to strike an
entire statute only when the overbreadth of the statute is not only
"real, but substantial as well, judged in relation to the statute's
plainly legitimate sweep," Broad- 412 WHITE, J., concurring in judgment rick, 413 U. S., at 615, and when the statute is not
susceptible to limitation or partial invalidation, id., at
613; Board of Airport Comm'rs of Los Angeles v. Jews for
Jesus, Inc., 482 U. S. 569, 574 (1987). "When a federal court
is dealing with a federal statute challenged as overbroad, it
should ... construe the statute to avoid constitutional problems,
if the statute is subject to a limiting construction." Ferber, 458 U. S., at 769, n. 24. Of course, "[a] state
court is also free to deal with a state statute in the same way." Ibid. See, e. g., Osborne, 495 U. S., at 113-114.
Petitioner contends that the St. Paul ordinance is not
susceptible to a narrowing construction and that the ordinance
therefore should be considered as written, and not as construed by
the Minnesota Supreme Court. Petitioner is wrong. Where a state
court has interpreted a provision of state law, we cannot ignore
that interpretation, even if it is not one that we would have
reached if we were construing the statute in the first instance. Ibid.; Kolender v. Lawson, 461 U. S. 352 , 355
(1983); Hoffman Estates v. Flipside, Hoffman Estates,
Inc., 455 U. S.
489 , 494, n. 5 (1982).12
Of course, the mere presence of a state court interpretation
does not insulate a statute from overbreadth review. We have
stricken legislation when the construction supplied by the state
court failed to cure the overbreadth problem.
12 Petitioner can derive no support from our statement in Virginia v. American Booksellers Assn., Inc., 484 U. S. 383 , 397
(1988), that "the statute must be 'readily susceptible' to the
limitation; we will not rewrite a state law to conform it to
constitutional requirements." In American Booksellers, no
state court had construed the language in dispute. In that
instance, we certified a question to the state court so that it
would have an opportunity to provide a narrowing interpretation. Ibid. In Erznoznik v. Jacksonville, 422 U. S. 205 , 216
(1975), the other case upon which petitioner principally relies, we
observed not only that the ordinance at issue was not "by its plain
terms ... easily susceptible of a narrowing construction," but that
the state courts had made no effort to restrict the scope of the
statute when it was challenged on overbreadth grounds. 413 See, e. g., Lewis v. New Orleans, 415 U. S. 130 , 132-133
(1974); Gooding, supra, at 524-525. But in such cases, we
have looked to the statute as construed in determining whether it
contravened the First Amendment. Here, the Minnesota Supreme Court
has provided an authoritative construction of the St. Paul antibias
ordinance. Consideration of petitioner's overbreadth claim must be
based on that interpretation.
I agree with petitioner that the ordinance is invalid on its
face. Although the ordinance as construed reaches categories of
speech that are constitutionally unprotected, it also criminalizes
a substantial amount of expression that-however repugnant-is
shielded by the First Amendment.
In attempting to narrow the scope of the St. Paul antibias
ordinance, the Minnesota Supreme Court relied upon two of the
categories of speech and expressive conduct that fall outside the
First Amendment's protective sphere: words that incite "imminent
lawless action," Brandenburg v. Ohio, 395 U. S. 444,
449 (1969), and "fighting" words, Chaplinsky v. New
Hampshire, 315 U. S., at 571-572. The Minnesota Supreme Court
erred in its application of the Chaplinsky fighting words
test and consequently interpreted the St. Paul ordinance in a
fashion that rendered the ordinance facially overbroad.
In construing the St. Paul ordinance, the Minnesota Supreme
Court drew upon the definition of fighting words that appears in Chaplinsky-words "which by their very utterance inflict
injury or tend to incite an immediate breach of the peace." Id., at 572. However, the Minnesota court was far from clear
in identifying the "injur[ies]" inflicted by the expression that
St. Paul sought to regulate. Indeed, the Minnesota court emphasized
(tracking the language of the ordinance) that "the ordinance
censors only those displays that one knows or should know will
create anger, alarm or resentment based on racial, ethnic, gender
or religious bias." In re Welfare of R. A. V:, 464 N. W. 2d
507, 510 (1991). I 414 WHITE, J., concurring in judgment
therefore understand the court to have ruled that St. Paul may
constitutionally prohibit expression that "by its very utterance"
causes "anger, alarm or resentment."
Our fighting words cases have made clear, however, that such
generalized reactions are not sufficient to strip expression of its
constitutional protection. The mere fact that expressive activity
causes hurt feelings, offense, or resentment does not render the
expression unprotected. See United States v. Eichman, 496 U. S. 310 ,
319 (1990); Texas v. Johnson, 491 U. S. 397 , 409, 414
(1989); Hustler Magazine, Inc. v. Falwell, 485 U. S. 46 , 55-56
(1988); FCC v. Pacifica Foundation, 438 U. S. 726 , 745
(1978); Hess v. Indiana, 414 U. S. 105 , 107-108
(1973); Cohen v. California, 403 U. S. 15 , 20 (1971); Street v. New York, 394 U. S. 576 , 592
(1969); Terminiello v. Chicago, 337 U. S. 1 (1949).
In the First Amendment context, "[c]riminal statutes must be
scrutinized with particular care; those that make unlawful a
substantial amount of constitutionally protected conduct may be
held facially invalid even if they also have legitimate
application." Houston v. Hill, 482 U. S. 451 , 459 (1987)
(citation omitted). The St. Paul antibias ordinance is such a law.
Although the ordinance reaches conduct that is unprotected, it also
makes criminal expressive conduct that causes only hurt feelings,
offense, or resentment, and is protected by the First Amendment.
Cf. Lewis, supra, at 132.13 The ordinance is therefore
fatally overbroad and invalid on its face.
13 Although the First Amendment protects offensive speech, Johnson v. Texas, 491 U. S., at 414, it does not require us to be
subjected to such expression at all times, in all settings. We have
held that such expression may be proscribed when it intrudes upon a
"captive audience." Frisby v. Schultz, 487 U. S. 474 , 484-485
(1988); FCC v. Pacifica Foundation, 438 U. S. 726,
748-749 (1978). And expression may be limited when it merges into
conduct. United States v. O'Brien, 391 U. S. 367 (1968); cf. Meritor Savings Bank, F. S. B. v. Vinson, 477 U. S. 57 ,65
(1986). However, because of the manner in which the Minnesota
Supreme Court construed the St. Paul ordinance, those issues are
not before us in this case. 415 III
Today, the Court has disregarded two established principles of
First Amendment law without providing a coherent replacement
theory. Its decision is an arid, doctrinaire interpretation, driven
by the frequently irresistible impulse of judges to tinker with the
First Amendment. The decision is mischievous at best and will
surely confuse the lower courts. I join the judgment, but not the
folly of the opinion.
JUSTICE BLACKMUN, concurring in the judgment.
I regret what the Court has done in this case. The majority
opinion signals one of two possibilities: It will serve as
precedent for future cases, or it will not. Either result is
disheartening.
In the first instance, by deciding that a State cannot regulate
speech that causes great harm unless it also regulates speech that
does not (setting law and logic on their heads), the Court seems to
abandon the categorical approach, and inevitably to relax the level
of scrutiny applicable to contentbased laws. As JUSTICE WHITE
points out, this weakens the traditional protections of speech. If
all expressive activity must be accorded the same protection, that
protection will be scant. The simple reality is that the Court will
never provide child pornography or cigarette advertising the level
of protection customarily granted political speech. If we are
forbidden to categorize, as the Court has done here, we shall
reduce protection across the board. It is sad that in its effort to
reach a satisfying result in this case, the Court is willing to
weaken First Amendment protections.
In the second instance is the possibility that this case will
not significantly alter First Amendment jurisprudence but, instead,
will be regarded as an aberration-a case where the Court
manipulated doctrine to strike down an ordinance whose premise it
opposed, namely, that racial threats and verbal assaults are of
greater harm than other fighting words. I fear that the Court has
been distracted from its 416 STEVENS, J., concurring in judgment
proper mission by the temptation to decide the issue over
"politically correct speech" and "cultural diversity," neither of
which is presented here. If this is the meaning of today's opinion,
it is perhaps even more regrettable.
I see no First Amendment values that are compromised by a law
that prohibits hoodlums from driving minorities out of their homes
by burning crosses on their lawns, but I see great harm in
preventing the people of Saint Paul from specifically punishing the
race-based fighting words that so prejudice their community.
I concur in the judgment, however, because I agree with JUSTICE
WHITE that this particular ordinance reaches beyond fighting words
to speech protected by the First Amendment.
JUSTICE STEVENS, with whom JUSTICE WHITE and JusTICE BLACKMUN
join as to Part I, concurring in the judgment.
Conduct that creates special risks or causes special harms may
be prohibited by special rules. Lighting a fire near an ammunition
dump or a gasoline storage tank is especially dangerous; such
behavior may be punished more severely than burning trash in a
vacant lot. Threatening someone because of her race or religious
beliefs may cause particularly severe trauma or touch off a riot,
and threatening a high public official may cause substantial social
disruption; such threats may be punished more severely than threats
against someone based on, say, his support of a particular athletic
team. There are legitimate, reasonable, and neutral justifications
for such special rules.
This case involves the constitutionality of one such ordinance.
Because the regulated conduct has some communicative content-a
message of racial, religious, or gender hostility-the ordinance
raises two quite different First Amendment questions. Is the
ordinance "overbroad" be- 417 cause it prohibits too much speech? If not, is it "underbroad"
because it does not prohibit enough speech?
In answering these questions, my colleagues today wrestle with
two broad principles: first, that certain "categories of expression
[including 'fighting words'] are 'not within the area of
constitutionally protected speech,'" ante, at 400 (WHITE,
J., concurring in judgment); and second, that "[c]ontent-based
regulations [of expression] are presumptively invalid," ante, at 382 (majority opinion). Although in past opinions
the Court has repeated both of these maxims, it has-quite
rightly-adhered to neither with the absolutism suggested by my
colleagues. Thus, while I agree that the St. Paul ordinance is
unconstitutionally overbroad for the reasons stated in Part II of
JUSTICE WHITE'S opinion, I write separately to suggest how the
allure of absolute principles has skewed the analysis of both the
majority and JUSTICE WHITE'S opinions.
I
Fifty years ago, the Court articulated a categorical ap-
proach to First Amendment jurisprudence. "There are certain well-defined and narrowly limited classes of
speech, the prevention and punishment of which have never been
thought to raise any Constitutional problem .... It has been well
observed that such utterances are no essential part of any
exposition of ideas, and are of such slight social value as a step
to truth that any benefit that may be derived from them is clearly
outweighed by the social interest in order and morality." Chaplinsky v. New Hampshire, 315 U. S. 568 , 571-572
(1942). We have, as JUSTICE WHITE observes, often described such
categories of expression as "not within the area of
constitutionally protected speech." Roth v. United
States, 354 U. S.
476 , 483 (1957). 418 STEVENS, J., concurring in judgment
The Court today revises this categorical approach. It is not,
the Court rules, that certain "categories" of expression are
"unprotected," but rather that certain "elements" of expression are
wholly "proscribable." To the Court, an expressive act, like a
chemical compound, consists of more than one element. Although the
act may be regulated because it contains a proscribable element, it
may not be regulated on the basis of another (nonproscribable)
element it also contains. Thus, obscene antigovernment speech may
be regulated because it is obscene, but not because it is
antigovernment. Ante, at 384. It is this revision of the
categorical approach that allows the Court to assume that the St.
Paul ordinance proscribes only fighting words, while at the
same time concluding that the ordinance is invalid because it
imposes a content-based regulation on expressive activity.
As an initial matter, the Court's revision of the categorical
approach seems to me something of an adventure in a doctrinal
wonderland, for the concept of "obscene antigovernment" speech is
fantastical. The category of the obscene is very narrow; to be
obscene, expression must be found by the trier of fact to "appea[l]
to the prurient interest, ... depic[t] or describ[e], in a patently
offensive way, sexual conduct, [and], taken as a whole, lac[k]
serious literary, artistic, political, or scientific value."
Miller v. California, 413 U. S. 15 , 24 (1973)
(emphasis added). "Obscene antigovernment" speech, then, is a
contradiction in terms: If expression is antigovernment, it does
not "lac[k] serious ... political ... value" and cannot be
obscene.
The Court attempts to bolster its argument by likening its novel
analysis to that applied to restrictions on the time, place, or
manner of expression or on expressive conduct. It is true that loud
speech in favor of the Republican Party can be regulated because it
is loud, but not because it is proRepublican; and it is true that
the public burning of the American flag can be regulated because it
involves public burning and not because it involves the flag. But
these anal- 419 ogies are inapposite. In each of these examples, the two
elements (e. g., loudness and pro-Republican orientation)
can coexist; in the case of "obscene antigovernment" speech,
however, the presence of one element ("obscenity") by definition
means the absence of the other. To my mind, it is unwise and
unsound to craft a new doctrine based on such highly speculative
hypotheticals.
I am, however, even more troubled by the second step of the
Court's analysis-namely, its conclusion that the St. Paul ordinance
is an unconstitutional content-based regulation of speech. Drawing
on broadly worded dicta, the Court establishes a near-absolute ban
on content-based regulations of expression and holds that the First
Amendment prohibits the regulation of fighting words by subject
matter. Thus, while the Court rejects the "all-or-nothing-at-all"
nature of the categorical approach, ante, at 384, it
promptly embraces an absolutism of its own: Within a particular
"proscribable" category of expression, the Court holds, a
government must either proscribe all speech or no speech at
all.1 This aspect of the Court's ruling fundamentally
misunderstands the role and constitutional status of content-based
regulations on speech, conflicts with the very nature of First
Amendment jurisprudence, and disrupts well-settled principles of
First Amendment law.
1 The Court disputes this characterization because it has
crafted two exceptions, one for "certain media or markets" and the
other for content discrimination based upon "the very reason that
the entire class of speech at issue is proscribable." Ante, at 388. These exceptions are, at best, ill defined. The Court does
not tell us whether, with respect to the former, fighting words
such as cross burning could be proscribed only in certain
neighborhoods where the threat of violence is particularly severe,
or whether, with respect to the second category, fighting words
that create a particular risk of harm (such as a race riot) would
be proscribable. The hypothetical and illusory category of these
two exceptions persuades me that either my description of the
Court's analysis is accurate or that the Court does not in fact
mean much of what it says in its opinion. 420 STEVENS, J., concurring in judgment
Although the Court has, on occasion, declared that content-based
regulations of speech are "never permitted," Police Dept. of
Chicago v. Mosley, 408 U. S. 92 , 99 (1972),
such claims are overstated. Indeed, in Mosley itself, the
Court indicated that Chicago's selective proscription of nonlabor
picketing was not per se unconstitutional, but rather could
be upheld if the city demonstrated that nonlabor picketing was
"clearly more disruptive than [labor] picketing." Id., at
100. Contrary to the broad dicta in Mosley and elsewhere,
our decisions demonstrate that content-based distinctions, far from
being presumptively invalid, are an inevitable and indispensable
aspect of a coherent understanding of the First Amendment.
This is true at every level of First Amendment law. In broadest
terms, our entire First Amendment jurisprudence creates a regime
based on the content of speech. The scope of the First Amendment is
determined by the content of expressive activity: Although the
First Amendment broadly protects "speech," it does not protect the
right to "fix prices, breach contracts, make false warranties,
place bets with bookies, threaten, [or] extort." Schauer,
Categories and the First Amendment: A Play in Three Acts, 34 Vand.
L. Rev. 265, 270 (1981). Whether an agreement among competitors is
a violation of the Sherman Act or protected activity under the Noerr-Pennington doctrine2 hinges upon the content of the
agreement. Similarly, "the line between permissible advocacy and
impermissible incitation to crime or violence depends, not merely
on the setting in which the speech occurs, but also on exactly what
the speaker had to say." Young v. American Mini Theatres,
Inc., 427 U. S.
50 , 66 (1976) (plurality opinion); see also Musser v. Utah, 333 U. S.
95 , 100-103 (1948) (Rutledge, J., dissenting).
2 See Mine Workers v. Pennington, 381 U. S. 657 (1965);
Eastern Railroad Presidents Conference v. Noerr Motor Freight,
Inc., 365 U. S.
127 (1961). 421 Likewise, whether speech falls within one of the categories of
"unprotected" or "proscribable" expression is determined, in part,
by its content. Whether a magazine is obscene, a gesture a fighting
word, or a photograph child pornography is determined, in part, by
its content. Even within categories of protected expression, the
First Amendment status of speech is fixed by its content. New
York Times Co. v. Sullivan, 376 U. S. 254 (1964), and Dun & Bradstreet, Inc. v. Greenmoss Builders,
Inc., 472 U. S.
749 (1985), establish that the level of protection given to
speech depends upon its subject matter: Speech about public
officials or matters of public concern receives greater protection
than speech about other topics. It can, therefore, scarcely be said
that the regulation of expressive activity cannot be predicated on
its content: Much of our First Amendment jurisprudence is premised
on the assumption that content makes a difference.
Consistent with this general premise, we have frequently upheld
content-based regulations of speech. For example, in Young v. American Mini Theatres, the Court upheld zoning
ordinances that regulated movie theaters based on the content of
the films shown. In FCC v. Pacifica Foundation, 438 U. S. 726 (1978) (plurality opinion), we upheld a restriction on the
broadcast of specific indecent words. In Lehman v. Shaker Heights, 418 U. S. 298 (1974)
(plurality opinion), we upheld a city law that permitted commercial
advertising, but prohibited political advertising, on city buses.
In Broadrick v. Oklahoma, 413 U. S. 601 (1973), we
upheld a state law that restricted the speech of state employees,
but only as concerned partisan political matters. We have long
recognized the power of the Federal Trade Commission to regulate
misleading advertising and labeling, see, e. g., Jacob Siegel
Co. v. FTC, 327 U. S. 608 (1946), and
the National Labor Relations Board's power to regulate an
employer's election-related speech on the basis of its content,
see, e. g., NLRB v. Gissel Packing Co., 395 U. S. 575 ,
616-618 (1969). 422 STEVENS, J., concurring in judgment
It is also beyond question that the Government may choose to
limit advertisements for cigarettes, see 15 U. S. C. §§ 13311340,3
but not for cigars; choose to regulate airline advertising, see Morales v. Trans World Airlines, Inc., 504 U. S. 374 (1992), but
not bus advertising; or choose to monitor solicitation by lawyers,
see Ohralik v. Ohio State Bar Assn., 436 U. S. 447
(1978), but not by doctors.
All of these cases involved the selective regulation of speech
based on content-precisely the sort of regulation the Court
invalidates today. Such selective regulations are unavoidably
content based, but they are not, in my opinion, "presumptively
invalid." As these many decisions and examples demonstrate, the
prohibition on content-based regulations is not nearly as total as
the Mosley dictum suggests.
Disregarding this vast body of case law, the Court today goes
beyond even the overstatement in Mosley and applies the
prohibition on content-based regulation to speech that the Court
had until today considered wholly "unprotected" by the First
Amendment-namely, fighting words. This new absolutism in the
prohibition of content-based regulations severely contorts the
fabric of settled First Amendment law.
Our First Amendment decisions have created a rough hierarchy in
the constitutional protection of speech. Core political speech
occupies the highest, most protected position; commercial speech
and nonobscene, sexually explicit speech are regarded as a sort of
second-class expression; obscenity and fighting words receive the
least protection of all. Assuming that the Court is correct that
this last class of speech is not wholly "unprotected," it certainly
does not follow that fighting words and obscenity receive the same sort of protection afforded core political speech. Yet
in ruling that proscribable speech cannot be regulated based on
subject
3 See also Packer Corp. v. Utah, 285 U. S. 105 (1932)
(Brandeis, J.) (upholding a statute that prohibited the
advertisement of cigarettes on billboards and streetcar
placards). 423 matter, the Court does just that.4 Perversely, this gives
fighting words greater protection than is afforded
commercial speech. If Congress can prohibit false advertising
directed at airline passengers without also prohibiting false
advertising directed at bus passengers and if a city can prohibit
political advertisements in its buses while allowing other
advertisements, it is ironic to hold that a city cannot regulate
fighting words based on "race, color, creed, religion or gender"
while leaving unregulated fighting words based on "union membership
... or homosexuality." Ante, at 391. The Court today turns
First Amendment law on its head:
Communication that was once entirely unprotected (and that still
can be wholly proscribed) is now entitled to greater protection
than commercial speech-and possibly greater protection than core
political speech. See Burson v. Freeman, 504 U. S. 191 , 195, 196
(1992).
Perhaps because the Court recognizes these perversities, it
quickly offers some ad hoc limitations on its newly extended
prohibition on content-based regulations. First, the Court states
that a content-based regulation is valid "[w]hen the basis for the
content discrimination consists entirely of the very reason the
entire class of speech ... is proscribable." Ante, at 388.
In a pivotal passage, the Court writes: "[T]he Federal Government can criminalize only those threats of
violence that are directed against the President, see 18 U. S. C. §
871-since the reasons why 4 The Court states that the prohibition on content-based
regulations "applies differently in the context of pros crib able
speech" than in the context of other speech, ante, at 387,
but its analysis belies that claim. The Court strikes down the St.
Paul ordinance because it regulates fighting words based on subject
matter, despite the fact that, as demonstrated above, we have long
upheld regulations of commercial speech based on subject matter.
The Court's self-description is inapt: By prohibiting the
regulation of fighting words based on its subject matter, the Court
provides the same protection to fighting words as is currently
provided to core political speech. 424 STEVENS, J., concurring in judgment threats of violence are outside the First Amendment (protecting
individuals from the fear of violence, from the disruption that
fear engenders, and from the possibility that the threatened
violence will occur) have special force when applied to the ...
President." Ibid. As I understand this opaque passage, Congress may choose from
the set of unprotected speech (all threats) to proscribe only a
subset (threats against the President) because those threats are
particularly likely to cause "fear of violence," "disruption," and
actual "violence."
Precisely this same reasoning, however, compels the conclusion
that St. Paul's ordinance is constitutional. Just as Congress may
determine that threats against the President entail more severe
consequences than other threats, so St. Paul's City Council may
determine that threats based on the target's race, religion, or
gender cause more severe harm to both the target and to society
than other threats. This latter judgment-that harms caused by
racial, religious, and gender-based invective are qualitatively
different from that caused by other fighting words-seems to me
eminently reasonable and realistic.
Next, the Court recognizes that a State may regulate advertising
in one industry but not another because "the risk of fraud (one of
the characteristics ... that justifies depriving [commercial
speech] of full First Amendment protection ... )" in the regulated
industry is "greater" than in other industries. Ibid. Again,
the same reasoning demonstrates the constitutionality of St. Paul's
ordinance. "[O]ne of the characteristics that justifies" the
constitutional status of fighting words is that such words "by
their very utterance inflict injury or tend to incite an immediate
breach of the peace." Chap linsky, 315 U. S., at 572.
Certainly a legislature that may determine that the risk of fraud
is greater in the legal 425 trade than in the medical trade may determine that the risk of
injury or breach of peace created by race-based threats is greater
than that created by other threats.
Similarly, it is impossible to reconcile the Court's analysis of
the St. Paul ordinance with its recognition that "a prohibition of
fighting words that are directed at certain persons or groups ...
would be facially valid." Ante, at 392 (emphasis deleted). A
selective proscription of unprotected expression designed to
protect "certain persons or groups" (for example, a law proscribing
threats directed at the elderly) would be constitutional if it were
based on a legitimate determination that the harm created by the
regulated expression differs from that created by the unregulated
expression (that is, if the elderly are more severely injured by
threats than are the nonelderly). Such selective protection is no
different from a law prohibiting minors (and only minors) from
obtaining obscene publications. See Ginsberg v. New
York, 390 U. S.
629 (1968). St. Paul has determined-reasonably in my
judgment-that fighting-word injuries "based on race, color, creed,
religion or gender" are qualitatively different and more severe
than fighting-word injuries based on other characteristics. Whether
the selective proscription of proscribable speech is defined by the
protected target ("certain persons or groups") or the basis of the
harm (injuries "based on race, color, creed, religion or gender")
makes no constitutional difference: What matters is whether the
legislature's selection is based on a legitimate, neutral, and
reasonable distinction.
In sum, the central premise of the Court's ruling-that
"[c]ontent-based regulations are presumptively invalid"has
simplistic appeal, but lacks support in our First Amendment
jurisprudence. To make matters worse, the Court today extends this
overstated claim to reach categories of hitherto unprotected speech
and, in doing so, wreaks havoc in an area of settled law. Finally,
although the Court recog- 426 STEVENS, J., concurring in judgment
nizes exceptions to its new principle, those exceptions
undermine its very conclusion that the St. Paul ordinance is
unconstitutional. Stated directly, the majority's position cannot
withstand scrutiny.
II
Although I agree with much of JUSTICE WHITE'S analysis, I do not
join Part I -A of his opinion because I have reservations about the
"categorical approach" to the First Amendment. These concerns,
which I have noted on other occasions, see, e. g., New York v. Ferber, 458
U. S. 747 , 778 (1982) (opinion concurring in judgment), lead me
to find JUSTICE WHITE'S response to the Court's analysis
unsatisfying.
Admittedly, the categorical approach to the First Amendment has
some appeal: Either expression is protected or it is not-the
categories create safe harbors for governments and speakers alike.
But this approach sacrifices subtlety for clarity and is, I am
convinced, ultimately unsound. As an initial matter, the concept of
"categories" fits poorly with the complex reality of expression.
Few dividing lines in First Amendment law are straight and
unwavering, and efforts at categorization inevitably give rise only
to fuzzy boundaries. Our definitions of "obscenity," see, e. g.,
Marks v. United States, 430 U. S. 188 , 198 (1977)
(STEVENS, J., concurring in part and dissenting in part), and
"public forum," see, e. g., United States Postal
Service v. Council of Greenburgh Civic Assns., 453 U. S. 114 , 126-131
(1981); id., at 136-140 (Brennan, J., concurring in
judgment); id., at 147-151 (Marshall, J., dissenting); id., at 152-154 (STEVENS, J., dissenting) (all debating the
definition of "public forum"), illustrate this all too well. The
quest for doctrinal certainty through the definition of categories
and subcategories is, in my opinion, destined to fail.
Moreover, the categorical approach does not take seriously the
importance of context. The meaning of any expression and the
legitimacy of its regulation can only be determined 427 in context.5 Whether, for example, a picture or a sentence is
obscene cannot be judged in the abstract, but rather only in the
context of its setting, its use, and its audience. Similarly,
although legislatures may freely regulate most nonobscene child
pornography, such pornography that is part of "a serious work of
art, a documentary on behavioral problems, or a medical or
psychiatric teaching device" may be entitled to constitutional
protection; the "question whether a specific act of communication
is protected by the First Amendment always requires some
consideration of both its content and its context." Ferber, 458 U. S., at 778 (STEVENS, J., concurring in judgment); see also Smith v. United States, 431 U. S. 291, 311-321 (1977)
(STEVENS, J., dissenting). The categorical approach sweeps too
broadly when it declares that all such expression is beyond the
protection of the First Amendment.
Perhaps sensing the limits of such an all-or-nothing approach,
the Court has applied its analysis less categorically than its
doctrinal statements suggest. The Court has recognized intermediate
categories of speech (for example, for indecent nonobscene speech
and commercial speech) and geographic categories of speech (public
fora, limited public fora, nonpublic fora) entitled to varying
levels of protection. The Court has also stringently delimited the
categories of unprotected speech. While we once declared that
"[l]ibelous utterances [are] not ... within the area of
constitutionally protected speech," Beauharnais v. Illinois, 343
U. S. 250 , 266 (1952), our rulings in New York Times Co. v. Sullivan, 376 U. S. 254 (1964); Gertz v. Robert
Welch, Inc., 418
U. S. 323 (1974), and Dun & Bradstreet, Inc. v. Greenmoss Builders, Inc., 472 U. S. 749 (1985),
have substantially qualified this
5 "A word," as Justice Holmes has noted, "is not a crystal,
transparent and unchanged, it is the skin of a living thought and
may vary greatly in color and content according to the
circumstances and the time in which it is used." Towne v. Eisner, 245 U.
S. 418 , 425 (1918); see also Jacobellis v. Ohio, 378 U. S. 184 ,
201 (1964) (Warren, C. J., dissenting). 428 STEVENS, J., concurring in judgment
broad claim. Similarly, we have consistently construed the
"fighting words" exception set forth in Chaplinsky narrowly.
See, e. g., Houston v. Hill, 482 U. S. 451 (1987); Lewis v. New Orleans, 415 U. S. 130 (1974); Cohen v. California, 403 U. S. 15 (1971). In
the case of commercial speech, our ruling that "the Constitution
imposes no ... restraint on government [regulation] as respects
purely commercial advertising," Valentine v. Chrestensen, 316 U. S. 52 , 54 (1942),
was expressly repudiated in Virginia Bd. of Pharmacy v. Virginia Citizens Consumer Council, Inc., 425 U. S. 748 (1976). In
short, the history of the categorical approach is largely the
history of narrowing the categories of unprotected speech.
This evolution, I believe, indicates that the categorical
approach is unworkable and the quest for absolute categories of
"protected" and "unprotected" speech ultimately futile. My analysis
of the faults and limits of this approach persuades me that the
categorical approach presented in Part I-A of JUSTICE WHITE'S
opinion is not an adequate response to the novel "underbreadth"
analysis the Court sets forth today.
III
As the foregoing suggests, I disagree with both the Court's and
part of JUSTICE WHITE'S analysis of the constitutionality of the
St. Paul ordinance. Unlike the Court, I do not believe that all
content-based regulations are equally infirm and presumptively
invalid; unlike JUSTICE WHITE, I do not believe that fighting words
are wholly unprotected by the First Amendment. To the contrary, I
believe our decisions establish a more complex and subtle analysis,
one that considers the content and context of the regulated speech,
and the nature and scope of the restriction on speech. Applying
this analysis and assuming, arguendo, (as the Court does)
that the St. Paul ordinance is not overbroad, I conclude
that such a selective, subject-matter regulation on proscribable
speech is constitutional. 429 Not all content-based regulations are alike; our decisions
clearly recognize that some content-based restrictions raise more
constitutional questions than others. Although the Court's analysis
of content-based regulations cannot be reduced to a simple formula,
we have considered a number of factors in determining the validity
of such regulations.
First, as suggested above, the scope of protection provided
expressive activity depends in part upon its content and character.
We have long recognized that when government regulates political
speech or "the expression of editorial opinion on matters of public
importance," FCC v. League of Women Voters of Cal., 468 U. S. 364 ,
375-376 (1984), "First Amendment protectio[n] is 'at its zenith,'" Meyer v. Grant, 486 U. S. 414 , 425
(1988). In comparison, we have recognized that "commercial speech
receives a limited form of First Amendment protection," Posadas
de Puerto Rico Associates v. Tourism Co. of Puerto Rico, 478 U. S. 328 ,
340 (1986), and that "society's interest in protecting [sexually
explicit films] is of a wholly different, and lesser, magnitude
than [its] interest in untrammeled political debate," Young v. American Mini Theatres, 427 U. S., at 70; see also FCC v. Pacifica Foundation, 438 U. S. 726 (1978). The
character of expressive activity also weighs in our consideration
of its constitutional status. As we have frequently noted, "[t]he
government generally has a freer hand in restricting expressive
conduct than it has in restricting the written or spoken word." Texas v. Johnson, 491 U. S. 397 , 406
(1989); see also United States v. O'Brien, 391 U. S. 367 (1968).
The protection afforded expression turns as well on the context
of the regulated speech. We have noted, for example, that "[a]ny
assessment of the precise scope of employer expression, of course,
must be made in the context of its labor relations setting ...
[and] must take into account the economic dependence of the
employees on their employers." NLRB v. Gissel Packing
Co., 395 U. S., at 617. Similarly, the distinctive character of
a university environment, see 430 STEVENS, J., concurring in judgment Widmar v. Vincent, 454 U. S. 263 , 277-280
(1981) (STEVENS, J., concurring in judgment), or a secondary school
environment, see Hazelwood School Dist. v. Kuhlmeier, 484 U. S. 260 (1988), influences our First Amendment analysis. The same is true
of the presence of a "'captive audience[, one] there as a matter of
necessity, not of choice.''' Lehman v. Shaker
Heights, 418 U. S., at 302 (citation omitted).6 Perhaps the
most familiar embodiment of the relevance of context is our "fora"
jurisprudence, differentiating the levels of protection afforded
speech in different locations.
The nature of a contested restriction of speech also informs our
evaluation of its constitutionality. Thus, for example, "[a]ny
system of prior restraints of expression comes to this Court
bearing a heavy presumption against its constitutional validity." Bantam Books, Inc. v. Sullivan, 372 U. S. 58 , 70 (1963).
More particularly to the matter of content-based regulations, we
have implicitly distinguished between restrictions on expression
based on subject matter and restrictions based on viewpoint, indicating that the latter are particularly
pernicious. "If there is a bedrock principle underlying the First
Amendment, it is that the Government may not prohibit the
expression of an idea simply because society finds the idea itself
offensive or disagreeable." Texas v. Johnson, 491 U.
S., at 414. "Viewpoint discrimination is censorship in its purest
form," Perry Ed. Assn. v. Perry Local Educators'
Assn., 460 U. S.
37 , 62 (1983) (Brennan, J., dissenting), and requires
particular scrutiny, in part because such regulation often
indicates a legislative effort to skew public debate on an issue,
see, e. g., Schacht v. United States, 398 U. S. 58 , 63 (1970).
"Especially where ... the legislature's suppression of speech
suggests an attempt
6 Cf. In re Chase, 468 F.2d
128 , 139-140 (CA7 1972) (Stevens, J., dissenting)
(arguing that defendant who, for reasons of religious belief,
refused to rise and stand as the trial judge entered the courtroom
was not subject to contempt proceedings because he was not present
in the courtroom "as a matter of choice"). 431 to give one side of a debatable public question an advantage in
expressing its views to the people, the First Amendment is plainly
offended." First Nat. Bank of Boston v. Bellotti, 435 U. S. 765 ,
785-786 (1978). Thus, although a regulation that on its face
regulates speech by subject matter may in some instances
effectively suppress particular viewpoints, see, e. g.,
Consolidated Edison Co. of N. Y. v. Public Servo
Comm'n of N. Y., 447 U. S. 530 , 546-547
(1980) (STEVENS, J., concurring in judgment), in general,
viewpoint-based restrictions on expression require greater scrutiny
than subjectmatter-based restrictions.7
Finally, in considering the validity of content-based
regulations we have also looked more broadly at the scope of the
restrictions. For example, in Young v. American Mini
Theatres, 427 U. S., at 71, we found significant the fact that
"what [was] ultimately at stake [was] nothing more than a
limitation on the place where adult films may be exhibited."
Similarly, in FCC v. Pacifica Foundation, the Court
emphasized two dimensions of the limited scope of the FCC ruling.
First, the ruling concerned only broadcast material which presents
particular problems because it "confronts the citizen ... in the
privacy of the home"; second, the ruling was not a complete ban on
the use of selected offensive words, but rather merely a limitation
on the times such speech could be broadcast. 438 U. S., at
748-750.
All of these factors play some role in our evaluation of
content-based regulations on expression. Such a multifaceted
analysis cannot be confiated into two dimensions. Whatever the
allure of absolute doctrines, it is just too simple to declare
expression "protected" or "unprotected" or to proclaim a regulation
"content based" or "content neutral."
7 Although the Court has sometimes suggested that
subject-matterbased and viewpoint-based regulations are equally
problematic, see, e. g., Consolidated Edison Co.
of N Y. V. Public Servo Comm'n of N Y., 447 U. S., at
537, our decisions belie such claims. 432 STEVENS, J., concurring in judgment
In applying this analysis to the St. Paul ordinance, I assume, arguendo-as the Court does-that the ordinance regulates only fighting words and therefore is not overbroad.
Looking to the content and character of the regulated activity, two
things are clear. First, by hypothesis the ordinance bars only
low-value speech, namely, fighting words. By definition such
expression constitutes "no essential part of any exposition of
ideas, and [is] of such slight social value as a step to truth that
any benefit that may be derived from [it] is clearly outweighed by
the social interest in order and morality." Chaplinsky, 315
U. S., at 572. Second, the ordinance regulates "expressive conduct
[rather] than ... the written or spoken word." Texas v. Johnson, 491 U. S., at 406.
Looking to the context of the regulated activity, it is again
significant that the ordinance (by hypothesis) regulates only fighting words. Whether words are fighting words is
determined in part by their context. Fighting words are not words
that merely cause offense; fighting words must be directed at
individuals so as to "by their very utterance inflict injury." By
hypothesis, then, the St. Paul ordinance restricts speech in
confrontational and potentially violent situations. The case at
hand is illustrative. The cross burning in this case-directed as it
was to a single African-American family trapped in their home-was
nothing more than a crude form of physical intimidation. That this
cross burning sends a message of racial hostility does not
automatically endow it with complete constitutional
protection.8
8 The Court makes much of St. Paul's description of the
ordinance as regulating "a message." Ante, at 393. As
always, however, St. Paul's argument must be read in context:
"Finally, we ask the Court to reflect on the 'content' of the
'expressive conduct' represented by a 'burning cross.' It is no
less than the first step in an act of racial violence. It was and
unfortunately still is the equivalent of [the] waving of a knife
before the thrust, the pointing of a gun before it is fired, the
lighting of the match before the arson, the hanging of the noose
before the lynching. It is not a political statement, or even 433 Significantly, the St. Paul ordinance regulates speech not on
the basis of its subject matter or the viewpoint expressed, but
rather on the basis of the harm the speech causes. In this
regard, the Court fundamentally misreads the St. Paul ordinance.
The Court describes the St. Paul ordinance as regulating expression
"addressed to one of [several] specified disfavored topics,"
ante, at 391 (emphasis supplied), as policing "disfavored subjects," ibid. (emphasis supplied), and as "prohibit[ing]
... speech solely on the basis of the subjects the speech
addresses," ante, at 381 (emphasis supplied). Contrary to
the Court's suggestion, the ordinance regulates only a subcategory
of expression that causes injuries based on "race, color,
creed, religion or gender," not a subcategory that involves discussions that concern those characteristics.9 The
ordinance, as construed by the Court, criminalizes expression that
"one knows ... [by its very utterance inflicts injury on] others on
the basis of race, color, creed, religion or
a cowardly statement of hatred. It is the first step in an act
of assault. It can be no more protected than holding a gun to a
victim['s] head. It is perhaps the ultimate expression of 'fighting
words.''' App. to Brief for Petitioner C-6. 9 The Court contends that this distinction is "wordplay,"
reasoning that "[w]hat makes [the harms caused by race-based
threats] distinct from [the harms] produced by other fighting words
is ... the fact that [the former are] caused by a distinctive
idea." Ante, at 392-393 (emphasis added). In this way, the
Court concludes that regulating speech based on the injury it
causes is no different from regulating speech based on its subject
matter. This analysis fundamentally miscomprehends the role of
"race, color, creed, religion [and] gender" in contemporary
American society. One need look no further than the recent social
unrest in the Nation's cities to see that race-based threats may
cause more harm to society and to individuals than other threats.
Just as the statute prohibiting threats against the President is
justifiable because of the place of the President in our social and
political order, so a statute prohibiting race-based threats is
justifiable because of the place of race in our social and
political order. Although it is regrettable that race occupies such
a place and is so incendiary an issue, until the Nation matures
beyond that condition, laws such as St. Paul's ordinance will
remain reasonable and justifiable. 434 STEVENS, J., concurring in judgment
gender." In this regard, the ordinance resembles the child
pornography law at issue in Ferber, which in effect singled
out child pornography because those publications caused far greater
harms than pornography involving adults.
Moreover, even if the St. Paul ordinance did regulate fighting
words based on its subject matter, such a regulation would, in my
opinion, be constitutional. As noted above, subject-matter-based
regulations on commercial speech are widespread and largely
unproblematic. As we have long recognized, subject-matter
regulations generally do not raise the same concerns of government
censorship and the distortion of public discourse presented by
viewpoint regulations. Thus, in upholding subject-matter
regulations we have carefully noted that viewpoint-based
discrimination was not implicated. See Young v. American
Mini Theatres, 427 U. S., at 67 (emphasizing "the need for
absolute neutrality by the government," and observing that the
contested statute was not animated by "hostility for the point of
view" of the theaters); FCC v. Pacifica Foundation, 438 U. S., at 745-746 (stressing that "government must remain
neutral in the marketplace of ideas"); see also FCC v. League of Women's Voters of Cal., 468 U. S., at 412-417
(STEVENS, J., dissenting); Metromedia, Inc. v. San
Diego, 453 U. S.
490 ,554-555 (1981) (STEVENS, J., dissenting in part). Indeed,
some subjectmatter restrictions are a functional necessity in
contemporary governance: "The First Amendment does not require
States to regulate for problems that do not exist." Burson Contrary to the suggestion of the majority, the St. Paul
ordinance does not regulate expression based on viewpoint.
The Court contends that the ordinance requires proponents of racial
intolerance to "follow the Marquis of Queensberry rules" while
allowing advocates of racial tolerance to "fight freestyle." The
law does no such thing. 435 The Court writes: "One could hold up a sign saying, for example, that all
'anti-Catholic bigots' are misbegotten; but not that all 'papists'
are, for that would insult and provoke violence 'on the basis of
religion.'" Ante, at 391-392. This may be true, but it hardly proves the Court's point. The
Court's reasoning is asymmetrical. The response to a sign saying
that "all [religious] bigots are misbegotten" is a sign saying that
"all advocates of religious tolerance are misbegotten." Assuming
such signs could be fighting words (which seems to me extremely
unlikely), neither sign would be banned by the ordinance for the
attacks were not "based on ... religion" but rather on one's
beliefs about tolerance. Conversely (and again assuming such signs
are fighting words), just as the ordinance would prohibit a Muslim
from hoisting a sign claiming that all Catholics were misbegotten,
so the ordinance would bar a Catholic from hoisting a similar sign
attacking Muslims.
The St. Paul ordinance is evenhanded. In a battle between
advocates of tolerance and advocates of intolerance, the ordinance
does not prevent either side from hurling fighting words at the
other on the basis of their conflicting ideas, but it does bar both sides from hurling such words on the basis of the
target's "race, color, creed, religion or gender." To extend the
Court's pugilistic metaphor, the St. Paul ordinance simply bans
punches "below the belt" by either party. It does not,
therefore, favor one side of any debate.10
10 Cf. FCC v. League of Women Voters of Cal., 468 U. S. 364 ,
418 (1984) (STEVENS, J., dissenting) ("In this case ... the
regulation applies ... to a defined class of ... licensees [who]
represent heterogenous points of view. There is simply no sensible
basis for considering this regulation a viewpoint restriction--or
... to condemn it as 'content-based'-because it applies equally to
station owners of all shades of opinion"). 436 STEVENS, J., concurring in judgment
Finally, it is noteworthy that the St. Paul ordinance is, as
construed by the Court today, quite narrow. The St. Paul ordinance
does not ban all "hate speech," nor does it ban, say, all cross
burnings or all swastika displays. Rather it only bans a
subcategory of the already narrow category of fighting words. Such
a limited ordinance leaves open and protected a vast range of
expression on the subjects of racial, religious, and gender
equality. As construed by the Court today, the ordinance certainly
does not" 'rais[e] the specter that the Government may effectively
drive certain ideas or viewpoints from the marketplace.'" Ante, at 387. Petitioner is free to burn a cross to announce
a rally or to express his views about racial supremacy, he may do
so on private property or public land, at day or at night, so long
as the burning is not so threatening and so directed at an
individual as to "by its very [execution] inflict injury." Such a
limited proscription scarcely offends the First Amendment.
In sum, the St. Paul ordinance (as construed by the Court)
regulates expressive activity that is wholly proscribable and does
so not on the basis of viewpoint, but rather in recognition of the
different harms caused by such activity. Taken together, these
several considerations persuade me that the St. Paul ordinance is
not an unconstitutional content-based regulation of speech. Thus,
were the ordinance not overbroad, I would vote to uphold it. | The Supreme Court ruled that a St. Paul, Minnesota ordinance prohibiting the display of symbols that arouse anger, alarm, or resentment on the basis of race, color, creed, religion, or gender is unconstitutional. The Court found that the ordinance violates the First Amendment by imposing special prohibitions on speech about certain subjects while allowing similar speech on other topics. The Court also rejected the argument that the ordinance was a valid regulation of "fighting words," a category of speech that is not protected by the First Amendment. |
Free Speech | Reno v. ACLU | https://supreme.justia.com/cases/federal/us/521/844/ | OCTOBER TERM, 1996
Syllabus
RENO, ATTORNEY GENERAL OF THE UNITED STATES, ET AL. v. AMERICAN CIVIL LIBERTIES UNION ET AL.
APPEAL FROM THE UNITED STATES DISTRICT COURT FOR THE EASTERN
DISTRICT OF PENNSYLVANIA No. 96-511. Argued March 19, 1997-Decided June 26, 1997 Two provisions of the Communications Decency Act of 1996 (CDA or
Act) seek to protect minors from harmful material on the Internet,
an international network of interconnected computers that enables
millions of people to communicate with one another in "cyberspace"
and to access vast amounts of information from around the world.
Title 47 U. S. C. § 223(a)(I)(B)(ii) (1994 ed., Supp. II)
criminalizes the "knowing" transmission of "obscene or indecent"
messages to any recipient under 18 years of age. Section 223(d)
prohibits the "knowin[g]" sending or displaying to a person under
18 of any message "that, in context, depicts or describes, in terms
patently offensive as measured by contemporary community standards,
sexual or excretory activities or organs." M firmative
defenses are provided for those who take "good faith, ... effective
... actions" to restrict access by minors to the prohibited
communications, § 223(e)(5)(A), and those who restrict such access
by requiring certain designated forms of age proof, such as a
verified credit card or an adult identification number,
§223(e)(5)(B). A number of plaintiffs filed suit challenging the
constitutionality of §§ 223(a)(I) and 223(d). After making
extensive findings of fact, a three-judge District Court convened
pursuant to the Act entered a preliminary injunction against
enforcement of both challenged provisions. The court's judgment
enjoins the Government from enforcing § 223(a)(I)(B)'s prohibitions
insofar as they relate to "indecent" communications, but expressly
preserves the Government's right to investigate and prosecute the
obscenity or child pornography activities prohibited therein. The
injunction against enforcement of § 223(d) is unqualified because
that section contains no separate reference to obscenity or child
pornography. The Government appealed to this Court under the Act's
special review provisions, arguing that the District Court erred in
holding that the CDA violated both the First Amendment because it
is overbroad and the Fifth Amendment because it is vague. Held: The CDA's "indecent transmission" and "patently
offensive display" provisions abridge "the freedom of speech"
protected by the First Amendment. Pp. 864-885. 845 (a) Although the CDA's vagueness is relevant to the First
Amendment overbreadth inquiry, the judgment should be affirmed
without reaching the Fifth Amendment issue. P. 864.
(b) A close look at the precedents relied on by the
Government Ginsberg v. New York, 390 U. S. 629 ; FCC v. Pacifica Foundation, 438 U. S. 726; and Renton v. Playtime Theatres, Inc., 475 U. S. 41 -raises,
rather than relieves, doubts about the CDA's constitutionality. The
CDA differs from the various laws and orders upheld in those cases
in many ways, including that it does not allow parents to consent
to their children's use of restricted materials; is not limited to
commercial transactions; fails to provide any definition of
"indecent" and omits any requirement that "patently offensive"
material lack socially redeeming value; neither limits its broad
categorical prohibitions to particular times nor bases them on an
evaluation by an agency familiar with the medium's unique
characteristics; is punitive; applies to a medium that, unlike
radio, receives full First Amendment protection; and cannot be
properly analyzed as a form of time, place, and manner regulation
because it is a content-based blanket restriction on speech. These
precedents, then, do not require the Court to uphold the CDA and
are fully consistent with the application of the most stringent
review of its provisions. Pp. 864-868.
(c) The special factors recognized in some of the Court's cases
as justifying regulation of the broadcast media-the history of
extensive Government regulation of broadcasting, see, e. g., Red
Lion Broadcasting Co. v. FCC, 395 U. S. 367 , 399-400;
the scarcity of available frequencies at its inception, see, e.
g., Turner Broadcasting System, Inc. v. FCC, 512 U. S.
622, 637-638; and its "invasive" nature, see Sable
Communications of Cal., Inc. v. FCC, 492 U. S. 115 , 128-are
not present in cyberspace. Thus, these cases provide no basis for
qualifying the level of First Amendment scrutiny that should be
applied to the Internet. Pp.868-870.
(d) Regardless of whether the CDA is so vague that it violates
the Fifth Amendment, the many ambiguities concerning the scope of
its coverage render it problematic for First Amendment purposes.
For instance, its use of the undefined terms "indecent" and
"patently offensive" will provoke uncertainty among speakers about
how the two standards relate to each other and just what they mean.
The vagueness of such a content-based regulation, see, e. g.,
Gentile v. State Bar of Nev., 501 U. S. 1030 , coupled
with its increased deterrent effect as a criminal statute, see, e. g., Dombrowski v. Pfister, 380 U. S. 479 , raise
special First Amendment concerns because of its obvious chilling
effect on free speech. Contrary to the Government's argument, the
CDA is not saved from vagueness by the fact that its "patently
offensive" stand- 846 ard repeats the second part of the three-prong obscenity test
set forth in Miller v. California, 413 U. S. 15 ,24. The
second Miller prong reduces the inherent vagueness of its
own "patently offensive" term by requiring that the proscribed
material be "specifically defined by the applicable state law." In
addition, the Miller definition applies only to "sexual
conduct," whereas the CDA prohibition extends also to "excretory
activities" and "organs" of both a sexual and excretory nature.
Each of Miller's other two prongs also critically limits the
uncertain sweep of the obscenity definition. Just because a
definition including three limitations is not vague, it does not
follow that one of those limitations, standing alone, is not vague.
The CDA's vagueness undermines the likelihood that it has been
carefully tailored to the congressional goal of protecting minors
from potentially harmful materials. Pp.870-874.
(e) The CDA lacks the precision that the First Amendment
requires when a statute regulates the content of speech. Although
the Government has an interest in protecting children from
potentially harmful materials, see, e. g., Ginsberg, 390 U.
S., at 639, the CDA pursues that interest by suppressing a large
amount of speech that adults have a constitutional right to send
and receive, see, e. g., Sable, 492 U. S., at 126. Its
breadth is wholly unprecedented. The CDA's burden on adult speech
is unacceptable if less restrictive alternatives would be at least
as effective in achieving the Act's legitimate purposes. See, e. g., id., at 126. The Government has not proved otherwise.
On the other hand, the District Court found that currently
available user-based software suggests that a reasonably
effective method by which parents can prevent their children
from accessing material which the parents believe is
inappropriate will soon be widely available. Moreover, the
arguments in this Court referred to possible alternatives such as
requiring that indecent material be "tagged" to facilitate parental
control, making exceptions for messages with artistic or
educational value, providing some tolerance for parental choice,
and regulating some portions of the Internet differently from
others. Particularly in the light of the absence of any detailed
congressional findings, or even hearings addressing the CDA's
special problems, the Court is persuaded that the CDA is not
narrowly tailored. Pp.874-879.
(f) The Government's three additional arguments for sustaining
the CDA's affirmative prohibitions are rejected. First, the
contention that the Act is constitutional because it leaves open
ample "alternative channels" of communication is unpersuasive
because the CDA regulates speech on the basis of its content, so
that a "time, place, and manner" analysis is inapplicable. See, e. g., Consolidated Edison Co. of N. Y. v. 847 Public Servo Comm'n of N. Y., 447 U. S. 530 , 536.
Second, the assertion that the CDA's "knowledge" and "specific
person" requirements significantly restrict its permissible
application to communications to persons the sender knows to be
under 18 is untenable, given that most Internet forums are open to
all comers and that even the strongest reading of the "specific
person" requirement would confer broad powers of censorship, in the
form of a "heckler's veto," upon any opponent of indecent speech.
Finally, there is no textual support for the submission that
material having scientific, educational, or other redeeming social
value will necessarily fall outside the CDA's prohibitions. Pp.
879-881.
(g) The § 223(e)(5) defenses do not constitute the sort of
"narrow tailoring" that would save the CDA. The Government's
argument that transmitters may take protective "good faith
actio[n]" by "tagging" their indecent communications in a way that
would indicate their contents, thus permitting recipients to block
their reception with appropriate software, is illusory, given the
requirement that such action be "effective": The proposed screening
software does not currently exist, but, even if it did, there would
be no way of knowing whether a potential recipient would actually
block the encoded material. The Government also failed to prove
that § 223(b)(5)'s verification defense would significantly reduce
the CDA's heavy burden on adult speech. Although such verification
is actually being used by some commercial providers of sexually
explicit material, the District Court's findings indicate that it
is not economically feasible for most noncommercial speakers.
Pp.881-882.
(h) The Government's argument that this Court should preserve
the CDA's constitutionality by honoring its severability clause, §
608, and by construing nonseverable terms narrowly, is acceptable
in only one respect. Because obscene speech may be banned totally,
see Miller, 413 U. S., at 18, and § 223(a)'s restriction of
"obscene" material enjoys a textual manifestation separate from
that for "indecent" material, the Court can sever the term "or
indecent" from the statute, leaving the rest of § 223(a) standing.
Pp. 882-885.
(i) The Government's argument that its "significant" interest in
fostering the Internet's growth provides an independent basis for
upholding the CDA's constitutionality is singularly unpersuasive.
The dramatic expansion of this new forum contradicts the factual
basis underlying this contention: that the unregulated availability
of "indecent" and "patently offensive" material is driving people
away from the Internet. P. 885.
929 F. Supp. 824, affirmed. 848 STEVENS, J., delivered the opinion of the Court, in which
SCALIA, KENNEDY, SOUTER, THOMAS, GINSBURG, and BREYER, JJ., joined.
O'CONNOR, J., filed an opinion concurring in the judgment in part
and dissenting in part, in which REHNQUIST, C. J., joined, post, p. 886.
Deputy Solicitor General Waxman argued the cause for appellants.
On the briefs were Acting Solicitor General Dellinger, Assistant
Attorney General Hunger, Deputy Solicitor General Kneedler, Irving
L. Gornstein, Barbara
Bruce J. Ennis, Jr., argued the cause for appellees. With him on
the brief for appellees American Library Association et al. were
Ann M. Kappler, Paul M. Smith, Donald B. Verrilli, Jr., John B.
Morris, Jr., Jill Lesser, Richard M. Schmidt, Jr., Bruce Rich,
James Wheaton, Jerry Berman, Elliot M. Mincberg, Lawrence S.
Ottinger, Andrew J. Schwartzman, Ronald L. Plesser, James J.
Halpert, Michael Traynor, Robert P. Taylor, Rene Milam, Marc
Jacobson, Bruce W Sanford, and Henry S. Hoberman. Christopher A.
Hansen, Steven R. Shapiro, Marjorie Heins, Catherine Weiss, Stefan
Presser, David L. Sobel, Marc Rotenberg, and Roger Evans filed a
brief for appellees American Civil Liberties Union Foundation et
al. *
*Briefs of amici curiae urging reversal were filed for
Member of Congress Dan Coats et al. by Bruce A. Taylor and Cathleen A. Cleaver; for Enough is Enough et al. by Ronald D. Maines; for the Family Life Project of the
American Center for Law and Justice by Jay Alan Sekulow, James
M. Henderson, Sr., Colby M. May, Keith A. Fournier, John G. Stepanovich, and Thomas P. Monaghan; for Morality in
Media, Inc., by Paul J. McGeady and Robert W
Peters; and for James J. Clancy by Mr. Clancy, pro se, and Carol A. Clancy. Briefs of amici curiae urging affirmance were filed for the
American Association of University Professors et al. by James D.
Crawford, Carl A. Solano, Theresa E. Loscalzo, Jennifer DuFault
James, and Joseph T. Lukens; for Apollomedia Corporation et al. by
William Bennett Turner; for the Association of National
Advertisers, Inc., by P. Cameron DeVore, John J. Walsh, Steven G.
Brody, Mary Elizabeth Taylor, Gilbert H. Weil, and Sol Schildhause;
for the Chamber of Commerce of the United States by Clifford M.
Sloan, Bert W Rein, Robert J. Butler, Stephen A. Bokat, and 849 JUSTICE STEVENS delivered the opinion of the Court.
At issue is the constitutionality of two statutory provisions
enacted to protect minors from "indecent" and "patently offensive"
communications on the Internet. Notwithstanding the legitimacy and
importance of the congressional goal of protecting children from
harmful materials, we agree with the three-judge District Court
that the statute abridges "the freedom of speech" protected by the
First Amendment.1
I
The District Court made extensive findings of fact, most of
which were based on a detailed stipulation prepared by the parties.
See 929 F. Supp. 824, 830-849 (ED Pa. 1996).2 The findings describe
the character and the dimensions of the Internet, the availability
of sexually explicit material in that medium, and the problems
confronting age verification for recipients of Internet
communications. Because those findings provide the underpinnings
for the legal issues, we begin with a summary of the undisputed
facts.
The Internet
The Internet is an international network of interconnected
computers. It is the outgrowth of what began in 1969 as a Robin S. Conrad; for Feminists for Free Expression
by Barbara M cDowell; for the National Association of
Broadcasters et al. by Floyd Abrams, Jack N. Goodman, and Susanna M. Lowy; for Playboy Enterprises, Inc., by Robert
Corn-Revere and Burton Joseph; for the Reporters
Committee for Freedom of the Press et al. by Jane E. Kirtley and S. Mark Goodman; for Site Specific, Inc., et al. by Jamie B. W Stecher; and for Volunteer Lawyers for the Arts
et al. by Daniel H. Weiner. Raphael Winick filed a brief of amicus curiae for
the Speech Communication Association.
1 "Congress shall make no law ... abridging the freedom of
speech."
2 The Court made 410 findings, including 356 paragraphs of the
parties' stipulation and 54 findings based on evidence received in
open court. See 929 F. Supp., at 830, n. 9, 842, n. 15. 850 military program called "ARPANET," 3 which was designed to
enable computers operated by the military, defense contractors, and
universities conducting defense-related research to communicate
with one another by redundant channels even if some portions of the
network were damaged in a war. While the ARPANET no longer exists,
it provided an example for the development of a number of civilian
networks that, eventually linking with each other, now enable tens
of millions of people to communicate with one another and to access
vast amounts of information from around the world. The Internet is
"a unique and wholly new medium of worldwide human
communication."4
The Internet has experienced "extraordinary growth." 5 The
number of "host" computers-those that store information and relay
communications-increased from about 300 in 1981 to approximately
9,400,000 by the time of the trial in 1996. Roughly 60% of these
hosts are located in the United States. About 40 million people
used the Internet at the time of trial, a number that is expected
to mushroom to 200 million by 1999.
Individuals can obtain access to the Internet from many
different sources, generally hosts themselves or entities with a
host affiliation. Most colleges and universities provide access for
their students and faculty; many corporations provide their
employees with access through an office network; many communities
and local libraries provide free access; and an increasing number
of storefront "computer coffee shops" provide access for a small
hourly fee. Several major national "online services" such as
America Online, CompuServe, the Microsoft Network, and Prodigy
offer access to their own extensive proprietary networks as well as
a link to the much larger resources of the Internet. These com-
3 An acronym for the network developed by the Advanced Research
Project Agency. 4Id., at 844 (finding 81). 5Id., at 831 (finding
3). 851 mercial online services had almost 12 million individual
subscribers at the time of trial.
Anyone with access to the Internet may take advantage of a wide
variety of communication and information retrieval methods. These
methods are constantly evolving and difficult to categorize
precisely. But, as presently constituted, those most relevant to
this case are electronic mail (e-mail), automatic mailing list
services ("mail exploders," sometimes referred to as "listservs"),
"newsgroups," "chat rooms," and the "World Wide Web." All of these
methods can be used to transmit text; most can transmit sound,
pictures, and moving video images. Taken together, these tools
constitute a unique medium-known to its users as "cyberspace"
-located in no particular geographical location but available to
anyone, anywhere in the world, with access to the Internet.
E-mail enables an individual to send an electronic
message-generally akin to a note or letter-to another individual or
to a group of addressees. The message is generally stored
electronically, sometimes waiting for the recipient to check her
"mailbox" and sometimes making its receipt known through some type
of prompt. A mail exploder is a sort of e-mail group. Subscribers
can send messages to a common e-mail address, which then forwards
the message to the group's other subscribers. Newsgroups also serve
groups of regular participants, but these po stings may be read by
others as well. There are thousands of such groups, each serving to
foster an exchange of information or opinion on a particular topic
running the gamut from, say, the music of Wagner to Balkan politics
to AIDS prevention to the Chicago Bulls. About 100,000 new messages
are posted every day. In most newsgroups, po stings are
automatically purged at regular intervals. In addition to posting a
message that can be read later, two or more individuals wishing to
communicate more immediately can enter a chat room to engage in
real-time dialogue-in other words, by typing messages to one
another that appear almost immediately on 852 the others' computer screens. The District Court found that at
any given time "tens of thousands of users are engaging in
conversations on a huge range of subjects." 6 It is "no
exaggeration to conclude that the content on the Internet is as
diverse as human thought."7
The best known category of communication over the Internet is
the World Wide Web, which allows users to search for and retrieve
information stored in remote computers, as well as, in some cases,
to communicate back to designated sites. In concrete terms, the Web
consists of a vast number of documents stored in different
computers all over the world. Some of these documents are simply
files containing information. However, more elaborate documents,
commonly known as Web "pages," are also prevalent. Each has its own
address-"rather like a telephone number."s Web pages frequently
contain information and sometimes allow the viewer to communicate
with the page's (or "site's") author. They generally also contain
"links" to other documents created by that site's author or to
other (generally) related sites. Typically, the links are either
blue or underlined text-sometimes images.
Navigating the Web is relatively straightforward. A user may
either type the address of a known page or enter one or more
keywords into a commercial "search engine" in an effort to locate
sites on a subject of interest. A particular Web page may contain
the information sought by the "surfer," or, through its links, it
may be an avenue to other documents located anywhere on the
Internet. Users generally explore a given Web page, or move to
another, by clicking a computer "mouse" on one of the page's icons
or links. Access to most Web pages is freely available, but some
allow access only to those who have purchased the right from a 6Id., at 835 (finding 27). 7Id., at 842 (finding
74). 8Id., at 836 (finding 36). 853 commercial provider. The Web is thus comparable, from the
readers' viewpoint, to both a vast library including millions of
readily available and indexed publications and a sprawling mall
offering goods and services.
From the publishers' point of view, it constitutes a vast
platform from which to address and hear from a worldwide audience
of millions of readers, viewers, researchers, and buyers. Any
person or organization with a computer connected to the Internet
can "publish" information. Publishers include government agencies,
educational institutions, commercial entities, advocacy groups, and
individuals.9 Publishers may either make their material available
to the entire pool of Internet users, or confine access to a
selected group, such as those willing to pay for the privilege. "No
single organization controls any membership in the Web, nor is
there any single centralized point from which individual Web sites
or services can be blocked from the Web." 10
Sexually Explicit Material
Sexually explicit material on the Internet includes text,
pictures, and chat and "extends from the modestly titillating to
the hardest-core." 11 These files are created, named, and posted in
the same manner as material that is not sexually explicit, and may
be accessed either deliberately or unintentionally during the
course of an imprecise search. "Once a provider posts its content
on the Internet, it cannot prevent that content from entering any
community." 12 Thus, for example,
9 "Web publishing is simple enough that thousands of individual
users and small community organizations are using the Web to
publish their own personal 'home pages,' the equivalent of
individualized newsletters about that person or organization, which
are available to everyone on the Web." Id., at 837 (finding
42). l°Id., at 838 (finding 46). 11 Id., at 844
(finding 82). 12 Ibid. (finding 86). 854 "when the UCR/California Museum of Photography posts to its Web
site nudes by Edward Weston and Robert Mapplethorpe to announce
that its new exhibit will travel to Baltimore and New York City,
those images are available not only in Los Angeles, Baltimore, and
New York City, but also in Cincinnati, Mobile, or Beijing-wherever
Internet users live. Similarly, the safer sex instructions that
Critical Path posts to its Web site, written in street language so
that the teenage receiver can understand them, are available not
just in Philadelphia, but also in Provo and Prague." 13 Some of the communications over the Internet that originate in
foreign countries are also sexually explicit.14
Though such material is widely available, users seldom encounter
such content accidentally. "A document's title or a description of
the document will usually appear before the document itself ... and
in many cases the user will receive detailed information about a
site's content before he or she need take the step to access the
document. Almost all sexually explicit images are preceded by
warnings as to the content." 15 For that reason, the "odds are
slim" that a user would enter a sexually explicit site by
accident.16 Unlike communications received by radio or television,
"the receipt of information on the Internet requires a series of
affirmative steps more deliberate and directed than merely turning
a dial. A child requires some sophistication and some ability to
read to retrieve material and thereby to use the Internet
unattended." 17
Systems have been developed to help parents control the material
that may be available on a home computer with In- 13 Ibid. (finding 85). 14Id., at 848 (finding 117). 15Id., at 844-845
(finding 88). 16 Ibid. 17Id., at 845 (finding 89). 855 ternet access. A system may either limit a computer's access to
an approved list of sources that have been identified as containing
no adult material, it may block designated inappropriate sites, or
it may attempt to block messages containing identifiable
objectionable features. "Although parental control software
currently can screen for certain suggestive words or for known
sexually explicit sites, it cannot now screen for sexually explicit
images."18 Nevertheless, the evidence indicates that "a reasonably
effective method by which parents can prevent their children from
accessing sexually explicit and other material which parents may
believe is inappropriate for their children will soon be widely
available." 19
Age Verification
The problem of age verification differs for different uses of
the Internet. The District Court categorically determined that
there "is no effective way to determine the identity or the age of
a user who is accessing material through e-mail, mail exploders,
newsgroups or chat rooms." 20 The Government offered no evidence
that there was a reliable way to screen recipients and participants
in such forums for 18Id., at 842 (finding 72). 19 Ibid. (finding
73). 2°Id., at 845 (finding 90): "An e-mail address provides
no authoritative information about the addressee, who may use an
e-mail .alias. or an anonymous remailer. There is also no universal
or reliable listing of e-mail addresses and corresponding names or
telephone numbers, and any such listing would be or rapidly become
incomplete. For these reasons, there is no reliable way in many
instances for a sender to know if the e-mail recipient is an adult
or a minor. The difficulty of e-mail age verification is compounded
for mail exploders such as listservs, which automatically send
information to all e-mail addresses on a sender's list. Government
expert Dr. Olsen agreed that no current technology could give a
speaker assurance that only adults were listed in a particular mail
exploder's mailing list." 856 age. Moreover, even if it were technologically feasible to block
minors' access to newsgroups and chat rooms containing discussions
of art, politics, or other subjects that potentially elicit
"indecent" or "patently offensive" contributions, it would not be
possible to block their access to that material and "still allow
them access to the remaining content, even if the overwhelming
majority of that content was not indecent." 21
Technology exists by which an operator of a Web site may
condition access on the verification of requested information such
as a credit card number or an adult password. Credit card
verification is only feasible, however, either in connection with a
commercial transaction in which the card is used, or by payment to
a verification agency. U sing credit card possession as a surrogate
for proof of age would impose costs on noncommercial Web sites that
would require many of them to shut down. For that reason, at the
time of the trial, credit card verification was "effectively
unavailable to a substantial number of Internet content providers."
929 F. Supp., at 846 (finding 102). Moreover, the imposition of
such a requirement "would completely bar adults who do not have a
credit card and lack the resources to obtain one from accessing any
blocked material." 22
Commercial pornographic sites that charge their users for access
have assigned them passwords as a method of age verification. The
record does not contain any evidence concerning the reliability of
these technologies. Even if passwords are effective for commercial
purveyors of indecent material, the District Court found that an
adult password requirement would impose significant burdens on
noncommercial sites, both because they would discourage users from
accessing their sites and because the cost of creating and 21 Ibid. (finding 93). 22Id., at 846 (finding 102). 857 maintaining such screening systems would be "beyond their
reach." 23
In sum, the District Court found: "Even if credit card verification or adult password verification
were implemented, the Government presented no testimony as to how
such systems could ensure that the user of the password or credit
card is in fact over 18. The burdens imposed by credit card
verification and adult password verification systems make them
effectively unavailable to a substantial number of Internet content
providers." Ibid. (finding 107). II
The Telecommunications Act of 1996, Pub. L. 104-104, 110 Stat.
56, was an unusually important legislative enactment. As stated on
the first of its 103 pages, its primary purpose was to reduce
regulation and encourage "the rapid deployment of new
telecommunications technologies." The major components of the
statute have nothing to do with the Internet; they were designed to
promote competition in the local telephone service market, the
multichannel video mar- 23Id., at 847 (findings 104-106):
"At least some, if not almost all, non-commercial organizations,
such as the ACLU, Stop Prisoner Rape or Critical Path AIDS Project,
regard charging listeners to access their speech as contrary to
their goals of making their materials available to a wide audience
free of charge.
"There is evidence suggesting that adult users, particularly
casual Web browsers, would be discouraged from retrieving
information that required use of a credit card or password. Andrew
Anker testified that HotWired has received many complaints from its
members about HotWired's registration system, which requires only
that a member supply a name, e-mail address and self-created
password. There is concern by commercial content providers that age
verification requirements would decrease advertising and revenue
because advertisers depend on a demonstration that the sites are
widely available and frequently visited." 858 ket, and the market for over-the-air broadcasting. The Act
includes seven Titles, six of which are the product of extensive
committee hearings and the subject of discussion in Reports
prepared by Committees of the Senate and the House of
Representatives. By contrast, Title V-known as the "Communications
Decency Act of 1996" (CDA)-contains provisions that were either
added in executive committee after the hearings were concluded or
as amendments offered during floor debate on the legislation. An
amendment offered in the Senate was the source of the two statutory
provisions challenged in this case.24 They are informally de-
24 See Exon Amendment No. 1268, 141 Congo Rec. 15536 (1995). See
also id., at 15505. This amendment, as revised, became § 502 of the
Telecommunications Act of 1996, 110 Stat. 133, 47 U. S. C. §§
223(a)-(e) (1994 ed., Supp. II). Some Members of the House of
Representatives opposed the Exon Amendment because they thought it
"possible for our parents now to child-proof the family computer
with these products available in the private sector." They also
thought the Senate's approach would "involve the Federal Government
spending vast sums of money trying to define elusive terms that are
going to lead to a flood of legal challenges while our kids are
unprotected." These Members offered an amendment intended as a
substitute for the Exon Amendment, but instead enacted as an
additional section of the Act entitled "Online Family Empowerment."
See 110 Stat. 137, 47 U. S. C. §230 (1994 ed., Supp. II); 141 Congo
Rec. 27881 (1995). No hearings were held on the provisions that
became law. See S. Rep. No. 104-23, p. 9 (1995). After the Senate
adopted the Exon Amendment, however, its Judiciary Committee did
conduct a one-day hearing on "Cyberporn and Children." In his
opening statement at that hearing, Senator Leahy observed:
"It really struck me in your opening statement when you
mentioned, Mr. Chairman, that it is the first ever hearing, and you
are absolutely right. And yet we had a major debate on the floor,
passed legislation overwhelmingly on a subject involving the
Internet, legislation that could dramatically change-some would say
even wreak havoc-on the Internet. The Senate went in willy-nilly,
passed legislation, and never once had a hearing, never once had a
discussion other than an hour or so on the floor." Cyberporn and
Children: The Scope of the Problem, The State of the Technology,
and the Need for Congressional Action, Hearing on S. 892 before the
Senate Committee on the Judiciary, 104th Cong., 1st Sess., 7-8
(1995). 859 scribed as the "indecent transmission" provision and the
"patently offensive display" provision.25
The first, 47 U. s. C. § 223(a) (1994 ed., Supp. II), prohibits
the knowing transmission of obscene or indecent messages to any
recipient under 18 years of age. It provides in pertinent part: "(a) Whoever- "(1) in interstate or foreign communications- "(B) by means of a telecommunications device knowingly- "(i) makes, creates, or solicits, and "(ii) initiates the
transmission of, "any comment, request, suggestion, proposal, image, or other
communication which is obscene or indecent, knowing that the
recipient of the communication is under 18 years of age, regardless
of whether the maker of such communication placed the call or
initiated the communication; "(2) knowingly permits any telecommunications facility under his
control to be used for any activity prohibited by paragraph (1)
with the intent that it be used for such activity, "shall be fined under Title 18, or imprisoned not more than two
years, or both." The second provision, § 223(d), prohibits the knowing sending or
displaying of patently offensive messages in a manner that is
available to a person under 18 years of age. It provides:
25 Although the Government and the dissent break § 223(d)(1)
into two separate "patently offensive" and "display" provisions, we
follow the convention of both parties below, as well as the
District Court's order and opinion, in describing § 223(d)(1) as
one provision. 860 "(d) Whoever- "(1) in interstate or foreign communications knowingly- "(A) uses an interactive computer service to send to a specific
person or persons under 18 years of age, or "(B) uses any interactive computer service to display in a
manner available to a person under 18 years of age, "any comment, request, suggestion, proposal, image, or other
communication that, in context, depicts or describes, in terms
patently offensive as measured by contemporary community standards,
sexual or excretory activities or organs, regardless of whether the
user of such service placed the call or initiated the
communication; or "(2) knowingly permits any telecommunications facility under
such person's control to be used for an activity prohibited by
paragraph (1) with the intent that it be used for such
activity, "shall be fined under Title 18, or imprisoned not more than two
years, or both." The breadth of these prohibitions is qualified by two
affirmative defenses. See § 223(e)(5).26 One covers those who take
"good faith, reasonable, effective, and appropriate actions" to
restrict access by minors to the prohibited communications. §
223(e)(5)(A). The other covers those who
26 In full, § 223(e)(5) provides:
"(5) It is a defense to a prosecution under subsection (a)(l)(B)
or (d) of this section, or under subsection (a)(2) of this section
with respect to the use of a facility for an activity under
subsection (a)(l)(B) of this section that a person-
"(A) has taken, in good faith, reasonable, effective, and
appropriate actions under the circumstances to restrict or prevent
access by minors to a communication specified in such subsections,
which may involve any appropriate measures to restrict minors from
such communications, including any method which is feasible under
available technology; or
"(B) has restricted access to such communication by requiring
use of a verified credit card, debit account, adult access code, or
adult personal identification number." 861 restrict access to covered material by requiring certain
designated forms of age proof, such as a verified credit card or an
adult identification number or code. § 223(e)(5)(B).
III
On February 8, 1996, immediately after the President signed the
statute, 20 plaintiffs 27 filed suit against the Attorney General
of the United States and the Department of Justice challenging the
constitutionality of §§ 223(a)(1) and 223(d). A week later, based
on his conclusion that the term "indecent" was too vague to provide
the basis for a criminal prosecution, District Judge Buckwalter
entered a temporary restraining order against enforcement of §
223(a)(1)(B)(ii) insofar as it applies to indecent communications.
A second suit was then filed by 27 additional plaintiffs,2S the two
cases
27 American Civil Liberties Union; Human Rights Watch;
Electronic Privacy Information Center; Electronic Frontier
Foundation; Journalism Education Association; Computer
Professionals for Social Responsibility; N ational Writers Union;
Clarinet Communications Corp.; Institute for Global Communications;
Stop Prisoner Rape; AIDS Education Global Information System;
Bibliobytes; Queer Resources Directory; Critical Path AIDS Project,
Inc.; Wildcat Press, Inc.; Declan McCullagh dba Justice on Campus;
Brock Meeks dba Cyberwire Dispatch; John Troyer dba The Safer Sex
Page; Jonathan Wallace dba The Ethical Spectacle; and Planned
Parenthood Federation of America, Inc.
28 American Library Association; America Online, Inc.; American
Booksellers Association, Inc.; American Booksellers Foundation for
Free Expression; American Society of Newspaper Editors; Apple
Computer, Inc.; Association of American Publishers, Inc.;
Association of Publishers, Editors and Writers; Citizens Internet
Empowerment Coalition; Commercial Internet Exchange Association;
CompuServe Incorporated; Families Against Internet Censorship;
Freedom to Read Foundation, Inc.; Health Sciences Libraries
Consortium; Hotwired Ventures LLC; Interactive Digital Software
Association; Interactive Services Association; Magazine Publishers
of America; Microsoft Corporation; The Microsoft Network, L. L. C.;
National Press Photographers Association; Netcom On-Line
Communication Services, Inc.; Newspaper Association of America;
Opnet, Inc.; Prodigy Services Company; Society of Professional
Journalists; and Wired Ventures, Ltd. 862 were consolidated, and a three-judge District Court was convened
pursuant to § 561 of the CDA.29 After an evidentiary hearing, that
court entered a preliminary injunction against enforcement of both
of the challenged provisions. Each of the three judges wrote a
separate opinion, but their judgment was unanimous.
Chief Judge Sloviter doubted the strength of the Government's
interest in regulating "the vast range of online material covered
or potentially covered by the CDA," but acknowledged that the
interest was "compelling" with respect to some of that material.
929 F. Supp., at 853. She concluded, nonetheless, that the statute
"sweeps more broadly than necessary and thereby chills the
expression of adults" and that the terms "patently offensive" and
"indecent" were "inherently vague." Id., at 854. She also
determined that the affirmative defenses were not "technologically
or economically feasible for most providers," specifically
considering and rejecting an argument that providers could avoid
liability by "tagging" their material in a manner that would allow
potential readers to screen out unwanted transmissions. Id., at
856. Chief Judge Sloviter also rejected the Government's suggestion
that the scope of the statute could be narrowed by construing it to
apply only to commercial pornographers. Id., at 854-855.
Judge Buckwalter concluded that the word "indecent" in §
223(a)(1)(B) and the terms "patently offensive" and "in context" in
§ 223(d)(1) were so vague that criminal enforcement of either
section would violate the "fundamental constitutional principle" of
"simple fairness," id., at 861, and the specific protections of the
First and Fifth Amendments, id., at 858. He found no statutory
basis for the Government's argument that the challenged provisions
would be applied only to "pornographic" materials, noting that,
unlike obscenity, "indecency has not been defined to exclude
works of serious literary, artistic, political or scientific
value." Id., at 863.
29110 Stat. 142-143, note following 47 U. S. C. §223 (1994 ed.,
Supp. II). 863 Moreover, the Government's claim that the work must be
considered patently offensive "in context" was itself vague because
the relevant context might "refer to, among other things, the
nature of the communication as a whole, the time of day it was
conveyed, the medium used, the identity of the speaker, or whether
or not it is accompanied by appropriate warnings." Id., at
864. He believed that the unique nature of the Internet aggravated
the vagueness of the statute. Id., at 865, n. 9.
Judge Dalzell's review of "the special attributes of Internet
communication" disclosed by the evidence convinced him that the
First Amendment denies Congress the power to regulate the content
of protected speech on the Internet. Id., at 867. His
opinion explained at length why he believed the CDA would abridge
significant protected speech, particularly by noncommercial
speakers, while "[p]erversely, commercial pornographers would
remain relatively unaffected." Id., at 879. He construed our
cases as requiring a "medium-specific" approach to the analysis of
the regulation of mass communication, id., at 873, and concluded
that the Internet-as "the most participatory form of mass speech
yet developed," id., at 883-is entitled to "the highest protection
from governmental intrusion," ibid. 30 30 See also 929 F. Supp., at 877: "Four related characteristics
of Internet communication have a transcendent importance to our
shared holding that the CDA is unconstitutional on its face. We
explain these characteristics in our Findings of fact above, and I
only rehearse them briefly here. First, the Internet presents very
low barriers to entry. Second, these barriers to entry are
identical for both speakers and listeners. Third, as a result of
these low barriers, astoundingly diverse content is available on
the Internet. Fourth, the Internet provides significant access to
all who wish to speak in the medium, and even creates a relative
parity among speakers." According to Judge Dalzell, these
characteristics and the rest of the District Court's findings "lead
to the conclusion that Congress may not regulate indecency on the
Internet at all." Ibid. Because appellees do not press this
argument before this Court, we do not consider it. Appellees also
do not dispute that the Government generally has a compelling
interest in protecting minors from "indecent" and "patently
offensive" speech. 864 The judgment of the District Court enjoins the Government from
enforcing the prohibitions in § 223(a)(1)(B) insofar as they relate
to "indecent" communications, but expressly preserves the
Government's right to investigate and prosecute the obscenity or
child pornography activities prohibited therein. The injunction
against enforcement of §§ 223(d)(1) and (2) is unqualified because
those provisions contain no separate reference to obscenity or
child pornography.
The Government appealed under the CDA's special review
provisions, § 561, 110 Stat. 142-143, and we noted probable
jurisdiction, see 519 U. S. 1025 (1996). In its appeal, the
Government argues that the District Court erred in holding that the
CDA violated both the First Amendment because it is overbroad and
the Fifth Amendment because it is vague. While we discuss the
vagueness of the CDA because of its relevance to the First
Amendment overbreadth inquiry, we conclude that the judgment should
be affirmed without reaching the Fifth Amendment issue. We begin
our analysis by reviewing the principal authorities on which the
Government relies. Then, after describing the overbreadth of the
CDA, we consider the Government's specific contentions, including
its submission that we save portions of the statute either by
severance or by fashioning judicial limitations on the scope of its
coverage.
IV
In arguing for reversal, the Government contends that the CDA is
plainly constitutional under three of our prior decisions: (1) Ginsberg v. New York, 390 U. S. 629 (1968); (2) FCC v. Pacifica Foundation, 438 U. S. 726 (1978); and
(3) Renton v. Playtime Theatres, Inc., 475 U. S. 41 (1986). A
close look at these cases, however, raises-rather than
relievesdoubts concerning the constitutionality of the CDA.
In Ginsberg, we upheld the constitutionality of a New
York statute that prohibited selling to minors under 17 years of
age material that was considered obscene as to them even if not
obscene as to adults. We rejected the defendant's broad 865 submission that "the scope of the constitutional freedom of
expression secured to a citizen to read or see material concerned
with sex cannot be made to depend on whether the citizen is an
adult or a minor." 390 U. S., at 636. In rejecting that contention,
we relied not only on the State's independent interest in the
well-being of its youth, but also on our consistent recognition of
the principle that "the parents' claim to authority in their own
household to direct the rearing of their children is basic in the
structure of our society." 31
In four important respects, the statute upheld in Ginsberg was narrower than the CDA. First, we noted in Ginsberg that "the prohibition against sales to minors does
not bar parents who so desire from purchasing the magazines for
their children." Id., at 639. Under the CDA, by contrast,
neither the parents' consent-nor even their participationin the
communication would avoid the application of the statute.32 Second,
the New York statute applied only to commercial transactions, id.,
at 647, whereas the CDA contains no such limitation. Third, the New
York statute cabined its definition of material that is harmful to
minors with the requirement that it be "utterly without redeeming
social importance for minors." Id., at 646. The CDA fails to
provide us with any definition of the term "indecent" as used in §
223(a)(1) and, importantly, omits any requirement that the
"patently offensive" material covered by § 223(d) lack serious
literary, artistic, political, or scientific value. Fourth, the New
York statute defined a minor as a person under the age
31390 U. S., at 639. We quoted from Prince v. Massachusetts, 321 U. S. 158 , 166
(1944): "It is cardinal with us that the custody, care and nurture
of the child reside first in the parents, whose primary function
and freedom include preparation for obligations the state can
neither supply nor hinder."
32 Given the likelihood that many e-mail transmissions from an
adult to a minor are conversations between family members, it is
therefore incorrect for the partial dissent to suggest that the
provisions of the CDA, even in this narrow area, "are no different
from the law we sustained in Ginsberg." Post, at 892. 866 of 17, whereas the CDA, in applying to all those under 18 years,
includes an additional year of those nearest majority.
In Pacifica, we upheld a declaratory order of the Federal
Communications Commission, holding that the broadcast of a
recording of a 12-minute monologue entitled "Filthy Words" that had
previously been delivered to a live audience "could have been the
subject of administrative sanctions." 438 U. S., at 730 (internal
quotation marks omitted). The Commission had found that the
repetitive use of certain words referring to excretory or sexual
activities or organs "in an afternoon broadcast when children are
in the audience was patently offensive" and concluded that the
monologue was indecent "as broadcast." Id., at 735. The
respondent did not quarrel with the finding that the afternoon
broadcast was patently offensive, but contended that it was not
"indecent" within the meaning of the relevant statutes because it
contained no prurient appeal. After rejecting respondent's
statutory arguments, we confronted its two constitutional
arguments: (1) that the Commission's construction of its authority
to ban indecent speech was so broad that its order had to be set
aside even if the broadcast at issue was unprotected; and (2) that
since the recording was not obscene, the First Amendment forbade
any abridgment of the right to broadcast it on the radio.
In the portion of the lead opinion not joined by Justices Powell
and Blackmun, the plurality stated that the First Amendment does
not prohibit all governmental regulation that depends on the
content of speech. Id., at 742-743. Accordingly, the
availability of constitutional protection for a vulgar and
offensive monologue that was not obscene depended on the context of
the broadcast. Id., at 744-748. Relying on the premise that
"of all forms of communication" broadcasting had received the most
limited First Amendment protection, id., at 748-749, the Court
concluded that the ease with which children may obtain access to
broadcasts, 867 "coupled with the concerns recognized in Ginsberg," justified special treatment of indecent broadcasting. Id., at 749-750.
As with the New York statute at issue in Ginsberg, there
are significant differences between the order upheld in
Pa cifica and the CDA. First, the order in Pacifica, issued by an agency that had been regulating radio stations for
decades, targeted a specific broadcast that represented a rather
dramatic departure from traditional program content in order to
designate when-rather than whether-it would be permissible to air
such a program in that particular medium. The CDA's broad
categorical prohibitions are not limited to particular times and
are not dependent on any evaluation by an agency familiar with the
unique characteristics of the Internet. Second, unlike the CDA, the
Commission's declaratory order was not punitive; we expressly
refused to decide whether the indecent broadcast "would justify a
criminal prosecution." 438 U. S., at 750. Finally, the Commission's
order applied to a medium which as a matter of history had
"received the most limited First Amendment protection," id., at
748, in large part because warnings could not adequately protect
the listener from unexpected program content. The Internet,
however, has no comparable history. Moreover, the District Court
found that the risk of encountering indecent material by accident
is remote because a series of affirmative steps is required to
access specific material.
In Renton, we upheld a zoning ordinance that kept adult
movie theaters out of residential neighborhoods. The ordinance was
aimed, not at the content of the films shown in the theaters, but
rather at the "secondary effects" -such as crime and deteriorating
property values-that these theaters fostered: "'It is thee]
secondary effect which these zoning ordinances attempt to avoid,
not the dissemination of "offensive" speech.''' 475 U. S., at 49
(quoting Young v. American Mini Theatres, Inc., 427 U. S. 50 , 71,
n. 34 (1976)). According to the Government, the CDA is
constitutional be- 868 cause it constitutes a sort of "cyberzoning" on the Internet.
But the CDA applies broadly to the entire universe of cyberspace.
And the purpose of the CDA is to protect children from the primary
effects of "indecent" and "patently offensive" speech, rather than
any "secondary" effect of such speech. Thus, the CDA is a
content-based blanket restriction on speech, and, as such, cannot
be "properly analyzed as a form of time, place, and manner
regulation." 475 U. S., at 46. See also Boos v. Barry, 485 U.
S. 312 , 321 (1988) ("Regulations that focus on the direct
impact of speech on its audience" are not properly analyzed under Renton); Forsyth County v. Nationalist Movement, 505 U. S. 123 ,
134 (1992) ("Listeners' reaction to speech is not a content-neutral
basis for regulation").
These precedents, then, surely do not require us to uphold the
CDA and are fully consistent with the application of the most
stringent review of its provisions.
v
In Southeastern Promotions, Ltd. v. Conrad, 420 U. S. 546 ,
557 (1975), we observed that "[e]ach medium of expression ... may
present its own problems." Thus, some of our cases have recognized
special justifications for regulation of the broadcast media that
are not applicable to other speakers, see Red Lion Broadcasting
Co. v. FCC, 395 U. S. 367 (1969); FCC v. Pacifica Foundation, 438 U. S. 726 (1978). In
these cases, the Court relied on the history of extensive
Government regulation of the broadcast medium, see, e. g., Red
Lion, 395 U. S., at 399-400; the scarcity of available
frequencies at its inception, see, e. g., Turner Broadcasting
System, Inc. v. FCC, 512 U. S. 622 , 637-638
(1994); and its "invasive" nature, see Sable Communications of
Cal., Inc. v. FCC, 492 U. S. 115 , 128
(1989).
Those factors are not present in cyberspace. Neither before nor
after the enactment of the CDA have the vast democratic forums of
the Internet been subject to the type 869 of government supervision and regulation that has attended the
broadcast industry.33 Moreover, the Internet is not as "invasive"
as radio or television. The District Court specifically found that
"[c]ommunications over the Internet do not 'invade' an individual's
home or appear on one's computer screen unbidden. Users seldom
encounter content 'by accident.' " 929 F. Supp., at 844 (finding
88). It also found that "[a]lmost all sexually explicit images are
preceded by warnings as to the content," and cited testimony that"
'odds are slim' that a user would come across a sexually explicit
sight by accident." Ibid. We distinguished Pacifica in Sable, 492 U. S., at
128, on just this basis. In Sable, a company engaged in the
business of offering sexually oriented prerecorded telephone
messages (popularly known as "dial-a-porn") challenged the
constitutionality of an amendment to the Communications Act of 1934
that imposed a blanket prohibition on indecent as well as obscene
interstate commercial telephone messages. We held that the statute
was constitutional insofar as it applied to obscene messages but
invalid as applied to indecent messages. In attempting to justify
the complete ban and criminalization of indecent commercial
telephone messages, the Government relied on Pacifica, arguing that the ban was necessary to prevent children from gaining
access to such messages. We agreed that "there is a compelling
interest in protecting the physical and psychological well-being of
minors" which extended to shielding them from indecent messages
that are not obscene by adult standards, 492 U. S., at
33 Cf. Pacifica Foundation v. FCC, 556 F.2d
9 , 36 (CADC 1977) (LevanthaI, J., dissenting), rev'd, FCC v. Pacifica Foundation, 438 U. S. 726 (1978).
When Pacifica was decided, given that radio stations were
allowed to operate only pursuant to federal license, and that
Congress had enacted legislation prohibiting licensees from
broadcasting indecent speech, there was a risk that members of the
radio audience might infer some sort of official or societal
approval of whatever was heard over the radio, see 556 F. 2d, at
37, n. 18. No such risk attends messages received through the
Internet, which is not supervised by any federal agency. 870 126, but distinguished our "emphatically narrow holding" in Pacifica because it did not involve a complete ban and
because it involved a different medium of communication, id., at
127. We explained that "the dial-it medium requires the listener to
take affirmative steps to receive the communication." Id., at 127-128. "Placing a telephone call," we continued, "is not the
same as turning on a radio and being taken by surprise by an
indecent message." Id., at 128.
Finally, unlike the conditions that prevailed when Congress
first authorized regulation of the broadcast spectrum, the Internet
can hardly be considered a "scarce" expressive commodity. It
provides relatively unlimited, low-cost capacity for communication
of all kinds. The Government estimates that "[a]s many as 40
million people use the Internet today, and that figure is expected
to grow to 200 million by 1999."34 This dynamic, multifaceted
category of communication includes not only traditional print and
news services, but also audio, video, and still images, as well as
interactive, real-time dialogue. Through the use of chat rooms, any
person with a phone line can become a town crier with a voice that
resonates farther than it could from any soapbox. Through the use
of Web pages, mail exploders, and newsgroups, the same individual
can become a pamphleteer. As the District Court found, "the content
on the Internet is as diverse as human thought." 929 F. Supp., at
842 (finding 74). We agree with its conclusion that our cases
provide no basis for qualifying the level of First Amendment
scrutiny that should be applied to this medium.
VI
Regardless of whether the CDA is so vague that it violates the
Fifth Amendment, the many ambiguities concerning the scope of its
coverage render it problematic for purposes of the First Amendment.
For instance, each of the two parts
34 Juris. Statement 3 (citing 929 F. Supp., at 831 (finding
3)). 871 of the CDA uses a different linguistic form. The first uses the
word "indecent," 47 U. s. C. § 223(a) (1994 ed., Supp. II), while
the second speaks of material that "in context, depicts or
describes, in terms patently offensive as measured by contemporary
community standards, sexual or excretory activities or organs," §
223(d). Given the absence of a definition of either term,35 this
difference in language will provoke uncertainty among speakers
about how the two standards relate to each other36 and just what
they mean.37 Could a speaker confidently assume that a serious
discussion about birth control practices, homosexuality, the First
Amendment issues raised by the Appendix to our Pacifica opinion, or the consequences of prison rape would not violate the
CDA? This uncertainty undermines the likelihood that the CDA has
been carefully tailored to the congressional goal of protecting
minors from potentially harmful materials.
The vagueness of the CDA is a matter of special concern for two
reasons. First, the CDA is a content-based regulation of speech.
The vagueness of such a regulation raises
35 "Indecent" does not benefit from any textual embellishment at
all.
"Patently offensive" is qualified only to the extent that it
involves "sexual or excretory activities or organs" taken "in
context" and "measured by contemporary community standards."
36 See Gozlon-Peretz v. United States, 498 U. S. 395 , 404 (1991)
("[W]here Congress includes particular language in one section of a
statute but omits it in another section of the same Act, it is
generally presumed that Congress acts intentionally and purposely
in the disparate inclusion and exclusion" (internal quotation marks
omitted)).
37 The statute does not indicate whether the "patently
offensive" and "indecent" determinations should be made with
respect to minors or the population as a whole. The Government
asserts that the appropriate standard is "what is suitable material
for minors." Reply Brief for Appellants 18, n. 13 (citing Ginsberg v. New York, 390 U. S. 629 , 633
(1968)). But the Conferees expressly rejected amendments that would
have imposed such a "harmful to minors" standard. See S. Conf. Rep.
No. 104-230, p. 189 (1996) (S. Conf. Rep.), 142 Congo Rec. H1145,
H1165-H1166 (Feb. 1, 1996). The Conferees also rejected amendments
that would have limited the proscribed materials to those lacking
redeeming value. See ibid. 872 special First Amendment concerns because of its obvious chilling
effect on free speech. See, e. g., Gentile v. State Bar of Nev., 501 U. S. 1030 ,
1048-1051 (1991). Second, the CDA is a criminal statute. In
addition to the opprobrium and stigma of a criminal conviction, the
CDA threatens violators with penalties including up to two years in
prison for each act of violation. The severity of criminal
sanctions may well cause speakers to remain silent rather than
communicate even arguably unlawful words, ideas, and images. See, e. g., Dombrowski v. Pfister, 380 U. S. 479 , 494
(1965). As a practical matter, this increased deterrent effect,
coupled with the "risk of discriminatory enforcement" of vague
regulations, poses greater First Amendment concerns than those
implicated by the civil regulation reviewed in Denver Area Ed.
Telecommunications Consortium, Inc. v. FCC, 518 U. S. 727 (1996).
The Government argues that the statute is no more vague than the
obscenity standard this Court established in Miller v. California, 413
U. S. 15 (1973). But that is not so. In Miller, this
Court reviewed a criminal conviction against a commercial vendor
who mailed brochures containing pictures of sexually explicit
activities to individuals who had not requested such materials. Id., at 18. Having struggled for some time to establish a
definition of obscenity, we set forth in Miller the test for
obscenity that controls to this day: "(a) whether the average person, applying contemporary community
standards would find that the work, taken as a whole, appeals to
the prurient interest; (b) whether the work depicts or describes,
in a patently offensive way, sexual conduct specifically defined by
the applicable state law; and (c) whether the work, taken as a
whole, lacks serious literary, artistic, political, or scientific
value." Id., at 24 (internal quotation marks and citations
omitted). 873 Because the CDA's "patently offensive" standard (and, we assume, arguendo, its synonymous "indecent" standard) is one part of
the three-prong Miller test, the Government reasons, it
cannot be unconstitutionally vague.
The Government's assertion is incorrect as a matter of fact. The
second prong of the Miller test-the purportedly analogous
standard-contains a critical requirement that is omitted from the
CDA: that the proscribed material be "specifically defined by the
applicable state law." This requirement reduces the vagueness
inherent in the open-ended term "patently offensive" as used in the
CDA. Moreover, the Miller definition is limited to "sexual
conduct," whereas the CDA extends also to include (1) "excretory
activities" as well as (2) "organs" of both a sexual and excretory
nature.
The Government's reasoning is also flawed. Just because a
definition including three limitations is not vague, it does not
follow that one of those limitations, standing by itself, is not
vague.38 Each of Miller's additional two prongs-(l) that,
taken as a whole, the material appeal to the "prurient" interest,
and (2) that it "lac[k] serious literary, artistic, political, or
scientific value"-critically limits the uncertain sweep of the
obscenity definition. The second requirement is particularly
important because, unlike the "patently offensive" and "prurient
interest" criteria, it is not judged by contemporary community
standards. See Pope v. Illinois, 481 U. S. 497 , 500
(1987). This "societal value" requirement, absent in the CDA,
allows appellate courts to impose some limitations and regularity
on the definition by setting, as a matter of law, a national floor
for socially redeeming value. The Government's contention that
courts will be able to give such legal limitations to the CDA's
standards is belied by Miller's own rationale for having
juries determine whether material
38 Even though the word "trunk," standing alone, might refer to
luggage, a swimming suit, the base of a tree, or the long nose of
an animal, its meaning is clear when it is one prong of a
three-part description of a species of gray animals. 874 is "patently offensive" according to community standards: that
such questions are essentially ones of fact. 39
In contrast to Miller and our other previous cases, the
CDA thus presents a greater threat of censoring speech that, in
fact, falls outside the statute's scope. Given the vague contours
of the coverage of the statute, it unquestionably silences some
speakers whose messages would be entitled to constitutional
protection. That danger provides further reason for insisting that
the statute not be overly broad. The CDA's burden on protected
speech cannot be justified if it could be avoided by a more
carefully drafted statute.
VII
We are persuaded that the CDA lacks the precision that the First
Amendment requires when a statute regulates the content of speech.
In order to deny minors access to potentially harmful speech, the
CDA effectively suppresses a large amount of speech that adults
have a constitutional right to receive and to address to one
another. That burden on adult speech is unacceptable if less
restrictive alternatives would be at least as effective in
achieving the legitimate purpose that the statute was enacted to
serve.
In evaluating the free speech rights of adults, we have made it
perfectly clear that "[s]exual expression which is indecent but not
obscene is protected by the First Amendment." Sable, 492 U.
S., at 126. See also Carey v. Population Services
Int'l, 431 U. S.
678 , 701 (1977) ("[W]here obscenity is not involved, we have
consistently held that the
39413 U. S., at 30 (Determinations of "what appeals to the
'prurient interest' or is 'patently offensive' ... are essentially
questions of fact, and our Nation is simply too big and too diverse
for this Court to reasonably expect that such standards could be
articulated for all 50 States in a single formulation, even
assuming the prerequisite consensus exists"). The CDA, which
implements the "contemporary community standards" language of
Miller, thus conflicts with the Conferees' own assertion that the
CDA was intended "to establish a uniform national standard of
content regulation." S. Conf. Rep., at 191. 875 fact that protected speech may be offensive to some does not
justify its suppression"). Indeed, Pacifica itself
admonished that "the fact that society may find speech offensive is
not a sufficient reason for suppressing it." 438 U. S., at 745.
It is true that we have repeatedly recognized the governmental
interest in protecting children from harmful materials. See Ginsberg, 390 U. S., at 639; Pacifica, 438 U. S., at
749. But that interest does not justify an unnecessarily broad
suppression of speech addressed to adults. As we have explained,
the Government may not "reduc[e] the adult population ... to ...
only what is fit for children." Denver, 518 U. S., at 759
(internal quotation marks omitted) (quoting Sable, 492 U.
S., at 128).40 "[R]egardless of the strength of the government's
interest" in protecting children, "[t]he level of discourse
reaching a mailbox simply cannot be limited to that which would be
suitable for a sandbox." Bolger v. Youngs Drug Products
Corp., 463 U. S.
60 , 74-75 (1983).
The District Court was correct to conclude that the CDA
effectively resembles the ban on "dial-a-porn" invalidated in Sable. 929 F. Supp., at 854. In Sable, 492 U. S., at
129, this Court rejected the argument that we should defer to the
congressional judgment that nothing less than a total ban would be
effective in preventing enterprising youngsters from gaining access
to indecent communications. Sable thus made clear that the
mere fact that a statutory regulation of speech was enacted for the
important purpose of protecting children from exposure to sexually
explicit material does not foreclose inquiry into its validity.41
As we pointed out last
40 Accord, Butler v. Michigan, 352 U. S. 380 , 383 (1957)
(ban on sale to adults of books deemed harmful to children
unconstitutional); Sable Communications of Cal., Inc. v. FCC, 492 U. S.
115 , 128 (1989) (ban on "dial-aporn" messages
unconstitutional); Bolger v. Youngs Drug Products
Corp., 463 U. S.
60 , 73 (1983) (ban on mailing of unsolicited advertisement for
contraceptives unconstitutional).
41 The lack of legislative attention to the statute at issue in Sable suggests another parallel with this case. Compare 492
U. S., at 129-130 ("[A]side from conc1usory statements during the
debates by proponents of 876 Term, that inquiry embodies an "overarching commitment" to make
sure that Congress has designed its statute to accomplish its
purpose "without imposing an unnecessarily great restriction on
speech." Denver, 518 U. S., at 741.
In arguing that the CDA does not so diminish adult
communication, the Government relies on the incorrect factual
premise that prohibiting a transmission whenever it is known that
one of its recipients is a minor would not interfere with
adult-to-adult communication. The findings of the District Court
make clear that this premise is untenable. Given the size of the
potential audience for most messages, in the absence of a viable
age verification process, the sender must be charged with knowing
that one or more minors will likely view it. Knowledge that, for
instance, one or more members of a 100-person chat group will be a
minor-and therefore that it would be a crime to send the group an
indecent message-would surely burden communication among
adults.42
The District Court found that at the time of trial existing
technology did not include any effective method for a sender to
prevent minors from obtaining access to its communications on the
Internet without also denying access to adults. The Court found no
effective way to determine the age of a user who is accessing
material through e-mail, mail exploders, newsgroups, or chat rooms.
929 F. Supp., at 845 (findings 90-94). As a practical matter, the
Court also found
the bill, as well as similar assertions in hearings on a
substantially identical bill the year before, ... the congressional
record presented to us contains no evidence as to how effective or ineffective the FCC's most recent regulations were or
might prove to be .... No Congressman or Senator purported to
present a considered judgment with respect to how often or to what
extent minors could or would circumvent the rules and have access
to dial-a-porn messages" (footnote omitted)), with n. 24,
supra.
42 The Government agrees that these provisions are applicable
whenever "a sender transmits a message to more than one recipient,
knowing that at least one of the specific persons receiving the
message is a minor." Opposition to Motion to Affirm and Reply to
Juris. Statement 4-5, n. 1. 877 that it would be prohibitively expensive for noncommercialas
well as some commercial-speakers who have Web sites to verify that
their users are adults. Id., at 845-848 (findings 95-116).43
These limitations must inevitably curtail a significant amount of
adult communication on the Internet. By contrast, the District
Court found that "[dJespite its limitations, currently available user-based software suggests that a reasonably effective
method by which parents can prevent their children from
accessing sexually explicit and other material which parents may believe is inappropriate for their children will soon be widely
available." Id., at 842 (finding 73) (emphases added).
The breadth of the CDA's coverage is wholly unprecedented.
Unlike the regulations upheld in Ginsberg and Pa cifica, the scope of the CDA is not limited to commercial
speech or commercial entities. Its open-ended prohibitions embrace
all nonprofit entities and individuals posting indecent messages or
displaying them on their own computers in the presence of minors.
The general, undefined terms "indecent" and "patently offensive"
cover large amounts of nonpornographic material with serious
educational or other value.44 Moreover, the "community standards"
criterion as applied to the Internet means that any communication
avail-
43 The Government asserts that "[t]here is nothing
constitutionally suspect about requiring commercial Web site
operators ... to shoulder the modest burdens associated with their
use." Brief for Appellants 35. As a matter of fact, however, there
is no evidence that a "modest burden" would be effective.
44 Transmitting obscenity and child pornography, whether via the
Internet or other means, is already illegal under federal law for
both adults and juveniles. See 18 U. S. C. §§ 1464-1465
(criminalizing obscenity); § 2251 (criminalizing child
pornography). In fact, when Congress was considering the CDA, the
Government expressed its view that the law was unnecessary because
existing laws already authorized its ongoing efforts to prosecute
obscenity, child pornography, and child solicitation. See 141 Congo
Rec. 16026 (1995) (letter from Kent Markus, Acting Assistant
Attorney General, U. S. Department of Justice, to Sen. Leahy). 878 able to a nationwide audience will be judged by the standards of
the community most likely to be offended by the message.45 The
regulated subject matter includes any of the seven "dirty words"
used in the Pacifica monologue, the use of which the
Government's expert acknowledged could constitute a felony. See
Olsen Testimony, Tr. Vol. V, 53:1654:10. It may also extend to
discussions about prison rape or safe sexual practices, artistic
images that include nude subjects, and arguably the card catalog of
the Carnegie Library.
For the purposes of our decision, we need neither accept nor
reject the Government's submission that the First Amendment does
not forbid a blanket prohibition on all "indecent" and "patently
offensive" messages communicated to a 17-year-old-no matter how
much value the message may contain and regardless of parental
approval. It is at least clear that the strength of the
Government's interest in protecting minors is not equally strong
throughout the coverage of this broad statute. Under the CDA, a
parent allowing her 17-year-old to use the family computer to
obtain information on the Internet that she, in her parental
judgment, deems appropriate could face a lengthy prison term. See
47 U. S. C. § 223(a)(2) (1994 ed., Supp. II). Similarly, a parent
who sent his 17-year-old college freshman information on birth
control via e-mail could be incarcerated even though neither he,
his child, nor anyone in their home community found the material
"indecent" or "patently offensive," if the college town's community
thought otherwise.
45 Citing Church of Lukumi Babalu Aye, Inc. v. Hialeah, 508
U. S. 520 (1993), among other cases, appellees offer an
additional reason why, in their view, the CDA fails strict
scrutiny. Because so much sexually explicit content originates
overseas, they argue, the CDA cannot be "effective." Brief for
Appellees American Library Association et al. 33-34. This argument
raises difficult issues regarding the intended, as well as the
permissible scope of, extraterritorial application of the CDA. We
find it unnecessary to address those issues to dispose of this
case. 879 The breadth of this content-based restriction of speech imposes
an especially heavy burden on the Government to explain why a less
restrictive provision would not be as effective as the CDA. It has
not done so. The arguments in this Court have referred to possible
alternatives such as requiring that indecent material be "tagged"
in a way that facilitates parental control of material coming into
their homes, making exceptions for messages with artistic or
educational value, providing some tolerance for parental choice,
and regulating some portions of the Internet-such as commercial Web
sites-differently from others, such as chat rooms. Particularly in
the light of the absence of any detailed findings by the Congress,
or even hearings addressing the special problems of the CDA, we are
persuaded that the CDA is not narrowly tailored if that requirement
has any meaning at all.
VIII
In an attempt to curtail the CDA's facial overbreadth, the
Government advances three additional arguments for sustaining the
Act's affirmative prohibitions: (1) that the CDA is constitutional
because it leaves open ample "alternative channels" of
communication; (2) that the plain meaning of the CDA's "knowledge"
and "specific person" requirement significantly restricts its
permissible applications; and (3) that the CDA's prohibitions are
"almost always" limited to material lacking redeeming social
value.
The Government first contends that, even though the CDA
effectively censors discourse on many of the Internet's
modalities-such as chat groups, newsgroups, and mail exploders-it
is nonetheless constitutional because it provides a "reasonable
opportunity" for speakers to engage in the restricted speech on the
World Wide Web. Brief for Appellants 39. This argument is
unpersuasive because the CDA regulates speech on the basis of its
content. A "time, place, and manner" analysis is therefore
inapplicable. See Consolidated Edison Co. of N. Y. v. Public Servo Comm'n of N. Y., 880 447 U. S. 530 ,
536 (1980). It is thus immaterial whether such speech would be
feasible on the Web (which, as the Government's own expert
acknowledged, would cost up to $10,000 if the speaker's interests
were not accommodated by an existing Web site, not including costs
for data base management and age verification). The Government's
position is equivalent to arguing that a statute could ban leaflets
on certain subjects as long as individuals are free to publish
books. In invalidating a number of laws that banned leafletting on
the streets regardless of their content, we explained that
"one is not to have the exercise of his liberty of expression in
appropriate places abridged on the plea that it may be exercised in
some other place." Schneider v. State (Town of
Irvington), 308
U. S. 147 , 163 (1939).
The Government also asserts that the "knowledge" requirement of
both §§ 223(a) and (d), especially when coupled with the "specific
child" element found in § 223(d), saves the CDA from overbreadth.
Because both sections prohibit the dissemination of indecent
messages only to persons known to be under 18, the Government
argues, it does not require transmitters to "refrain from
communicating indecent material to adults; they need only refrain
from disseminating such materials to persons they know to be under
18." Brief for Appellants 24. This argument ignores the fact that
most Internet forums-including chat rooms, newsgroups, mail
exploders, and the Web-are open to all comers. The Government's
assertion that the knowledge requirement somehow protects the
communications of adults is therefore untenable. Even the strongest
reading of the "specific person" requirement of § 223(d) cannot
save the statute. It would confer broad powers of censorship, in
the form of a "heckler's veto," upon any opponent of indecent
speech who might simply log on and inform the would-be discoursers
that his 17-year-old child-a "specific person ... under 18 years of
age," 47 U. S. C. §223(d)(1)(A) (1994 ed., Supp. H)-would be
present. 881 Finally, we find no textual support for the Government's
submission that material having scientific, educational, or other
redeeming social value will necessarily fall outside the CDA's
"patently offensive" and "indecent" prohibitions. See also n. 37, supra. IX
The Government's three remaining arguments focus on the defenses
provided in § 223(e)(5).46 First, relying on the "good faith,
reasonable, effective, and appropriate actions" provision, the
Government suggests that "tagging" provides a defense that saves
the constitutionality of the CDA. The suggestion assumes that
transmitters may encode their indecent communications in a way that
would indicate their contents, thus permitting recipients to block
their reception with appropriate software. It is the requirement
that the good-faith action must be "effective" that makes this
defense illusory. The Government recognizes that its proposed
screening software does not currently exist. Even if it did, there
is no way to know whether a potential recipient will actually block
the encoded material. Without the impossible knowledge that every
guardian in America is screening for the "tag," the transmitter
could not reasonably rely on its action to be "effective."
For its second and third arguments concerning defenseswhich we
can consider together-the Government relies on the latter half of §
223(e)(5), which applies when the transmitter has restricted access
by requiring use of a verified credit card or adult identification.
Such verification is not only technologically available but
actually is used by commercial providers of sexually explicit
material. These providers, therefore, would be protected by the
defense. Under the findings of the District Court, however, it is
not economically feasible for most noncommercial speakers to employ
such verification. Accordingly, this defense would not signifi-
46 For the full text of § 223(e )(5), see n. 26, supra. 882 cantly narrow the statute's burden on noncommercial speech. Even
with respect to the commercial pornographers that would be
protected by the defense, the Government failed to adduce any
evidence that these verification techniques actually preclude
minors from posing as adults.47 Given that the risk of criminal
sanctions "hovers over each content provider, like the proverbial
sword of Damocles,"48 the District Court correctly refused to rely
on unproven future technology to save the statute. The Government
thus failed to prove that the proffered defense would significantly
reduce the heavy burden on adult speech produced by the prohibition
on offensive displays.
We agree with the District Court's conclusion that the CDA
places an unacceptably heavy burden on protected speech, and that
the defenses do not constitute the sort of "narrow tailoring" that
will save an otherwise patently invalid unconstitutional provision.
In Sable, 492 U. S., at 127, we remarked that the speech
restriction at issue there amounted to "'burn[ing] the house to
roast the pig.'" The CDA, casting a far darker shadow over free
speech, threatens to torch a large segment of the Internet
community.
X
At oral argument, the Government relied heavily on its ultimate
fall-back position: If this Court should conclude that the CDA is
insufficiently tailored, it urged, we should save the statute's
constitutionality by honoring the severability clause, see 47 U. S.
C. § 608, and construing nonseverable terms narrowly. In only one
respect is this argument acceptable.
A severability clause requires textual provisions that can be
severed. We will follow § 608's guidance by leaving con-
47 Thus, ironically, this defense may significantly protect
commercial purveyors of obscene postings while providing little (or
no) benefit for transmitters of indecent messages that have
significant social or artistic value. 48929 F. Supp., at
855-856. 883 stitutional textual elements of the statute intact in the one
place where they are, in fact, severable. The "indecency"
provision, 47 U. S. C. § 223(a) (1994 ed., Supp. II), applies to
"any comment, request, suggestion, proposal, image, or other
communication which is obscene or indecent." (Emphasis
added.) Appellees do not challenge the application of the statute
to obscene speech, which, they acknowledge, can be banned totally
because it enjoys no First Amendment protection. See Miller, 413 U. S., at 18. As set forth by the statute, the restriction of
"obscene" material enjoys a textual manifestation separate from
that for "indecent" material, which we have held unconstitutional.
Therefore, we will sever the term "or indecent" from the statute,
leaving the rest of § 223(a) standing. In no other respect,
however, can § 223(a) or § 223(d) be saved by such a textual
surgery.
The Government also draws on an additional, less traditional
aspect of the CDA's severability clause, 47 U. S. C. § 608, which
asks any reviewing court that holds the statute facially
unconstitutional not to invalidate the CDA in application to "other
persons or circumstances" that might be constitutionally
permissible. It further invokes this Court's admonition that,
absent "countervailing considerations," a statute should "be
declared invalid to the extent it reaches too far, but otherwise
left intact." Brockett v. Spokane Arcades, Inc., 472 U. S. 491 ,
503-504 (1985). There are two flaws in this argument.
First, the statute that grants our jurisdiction for this
expedited review, § 561 of the Telecommunications Act of 1961, note
following 47 U. S. C. § 223 (1994 ed., Supp. II), limits that
jurisdictional grant to actions challenging the CDA "on its face."
Consistent with § 561, the plaintiffs who brought this suit and the
three-judge panel that decided it treated it as a facial challenge.
We have no authority, in this particular posture, to convert this
litigation into an "as-applied" challenge. Nor, given the vast
array of plaintiffs, the range of their expressive activities, and
the vagueness of the stat- 884 ute, would it be practicable to limit our holding to a
judicially defined set of specific applications.
Second, one of the "countervailing considerations" mentioned in Brockett is present here. In considering a facial challenge,
this Court may impose a limiting construction on a statute only if
it is "readily susceptible" to such a construction. Virginia v. American Booksellers Assn., Inc., 484 U. S. 383, 397
(1988). See also Erznoznik v. Jacksonville, 422 U. S. 205 , 216 (1975)
("readily subject" to narrowing construction). The open-ended
character of the CDA provides no guidance whatever for limiting its
coverage.
This case is therefore unlike those in which we have construed a
statute narrowly because the text or other source of congressional
intent identified a clear line that this Court could draw. Cf., e. g., Brockett, 472 U. S., at 504-505 (invalidating
obscenity statute only to the extent that word "lust" was actually
or effectively excised from statute); United States v. Grace, 461 U.
S. 171 , 180-183 (1983) (invalidating federal statute banning
expressive displays only insofar as it extended to public sidewalks
when clear line could be drawn between sidewalks and other grounds
that comported with congressional purpose of protecting the
building, grounds, and people therein). Rather, our decision in United States v. Treasury Employees, 513 U. S. 454 , 479, n. 26
(1995), is applicable. In that case, we declined to "dra[w] one or
more lines between categories of speech covered by an overly broad
statute, when Congress has sent inconsistent signals as to where
the new line or lines should be drawn" because doing so "involves a
far more serious invasion of the legislative domain."49 This Court
"will not rewrite a ... law
49 As this Court long ago explained: "It would certainly be
dangerous if the legislature could set a net large enough to catch
all possible offenders, and leave it to the courts to step inside
and say who could be rightfully detained, and who should be set at
large. This would, to some extent, substitute the judicial for the
legislative department of the government." United States v. Reese, 92 U. S.
214 , 221 (1876). In part because of these 885 to conform it to constitutional requirements." American
Booksellers, 484 U. S., at 397.50
XI
In this Court, though not in the District Court, the Government
asserts that-in addition to its interest in protecting children-its
"[e]qually significant" interest in fostering the growth of the
Internet provides an independent basis for upholding the
constitutionality of the CDA. Brief for Appellants 19. The
Government apparently assumes that the unregulated availability of
"indecent" and "patently offensive" material on the Internet is
driving countless citizens away from the medium because of the risk
of exposing themselves or their children to harmful material.
We find this argument singularly unpersuasive. The dramatic
expansion of this new marketplace of ideas contradicts the factual
basis of this contention. The record demonstrates that the growth
of the Internet has been and continues to be phenomenal. As a
matter of constitutional tradition, in the absence of evidence to
the contrary, we presume that governmental regulation of the
content of speech is more likely to interfere with the free
exchange of ideas than to encourage it. The interest in encouraging
freedom of expression in a democratic society outweighs any
theoretical but unproven benefit of censorship.
For the foregoing reasons, the judgment of the District Court is
affirmed.
It is so ordered.
separation-of-powers concerns, we have held that a severability
clause is "an aid merely; not an inexorable command." Dorchy v. Kansas, 264
U. S. 286 , 290 (1924).
50 See also Osborne v. Ohio, 495 U. S. 103 , 121 (1990)
(judicial rewriting of statutes would derogate Congress' "incentive
to draft a narrowly tailored law in the first place"). 886 JUSTICE O'CONNOR, with whom THE CHIEF JUSTICE joins, concurring
in the judgment in part and dissenting in part.
I write separately to explain why I view the Communications
Decency Act of 1996 (CDA) as little more than an attempt by
Congress to create "adult zones" on the Internet. Our precedent
indicates that the creation of such zones can be constitutionally
sound. Despite the soundness of its purpose, however, portions of
the CDA are unconstitutional because they stray from the blueprint
our prior cases have developed for constructing a "zoning law" that
passes constitutional muster.
Appellees bring a facial challenge to three provisions of the
CDA. The first, which the Court describes as the "indecency
transmission" provision, makes it a crime to knowingly transmit an
obscene or indecent message or image to a person the sender knows
is under 18 years old. 47 U. S. C. § 223(a)(1)(B) (1994 ed., Supp.
II). What the Court classifies as a single" 'patently offensive
display'" provision, see ante, at 859, is in reality two
separate provisions. The first of these makes it a crime to
knowingly send a patently offensive message or image to a specific
person under the age of 18 ("specific person" provision). §
223(d)(1)(A). The second criminalizes the display of patently
offensive messages or images "in a[ny] manner available" to minors
("display" provision). § 223(d)(1)(B). None of these provisions
purports to keep indecent (or patently offensive) material away
from adults, who have a First Amendment right to obtain this
speech. Sable Communications of Cal., Inc. v. FCC, 492 U. S. 115 ,
126 (1989) ("Sexual expression which is indecent but not obscene is
protected by the First Amendment"). Thus, the undeniable purpose of
the CDA is to segregate indecent material on the Internet into
certain areas that minors cannot access. See S. Conf. Rep. No.
104-230, p. 189 (1996) (CDA imposes "access restrictions ... to
protect minors from exposure to indecent material"). 887 The creation of "adult zones" is by no means a novel concept.
States have long denied minors access to certain establishments
frequented by adults.1 States have also denied minors access to
speech deemed to be "harmful to minors." 2
1 See, e. g., Alaska Stat. Ann. § 11.66.300 (1996) (no
minors in "adult entertainment" places); Ariz. Rev. Stat. Ann. §
13-3556 (1989) (no minors in places where people expose
themselves); Ark. Code Ann. §§ 5-27-223, 5-27-224 (1993) (no minors
in poolrooms and bars); Colo. Rev. Stat. § 18-7502(2) (1986) (no
minors in places displaying movies or shows that are "harmful to
children"); Del. Code Ann., Tit. 11, § 1365(i)(2) (1995) (same); D.
C. Code Ann. § 22-2001(b)(I)(B) (1996) (same); Fla. Stat. §
847.013(2) (1994) (same); Ga. Code Ann. § 16-12-103(b) (1996)
(same); Haw. Rev. Stat. § 712-1215(1)(b) (1994) (no minors in movie
houses or shows that are "pornographic for minors"); Idaho Code §
18-1515(2) (1987) (no minors in places displaying movies or shows
that are "harmful to minors"); La. Rev. Stat. Ann. § 14:91.11(B)
(West 1986) (no minors in places displaying movies that depict sex
acts and appeal to minors' prurient interest); Md. Ann. Code, Art.
27, §416E (1996) (no minors in establishments where certain
enumerated acts are performed or portrayed); Mich. Compo Laws §
750.141 (1991) (no minors without an adult in places where alcohol
is sold); Minn. Stat. § 617.294 (1987 and Supp. 1997) (no minors in
places displaying movies or shows that are "harmful to minors");
Miss. Code Ann. § 97-5-11 (1994) (no minors in poolrooms, billiard
halls, or where alcohol is sold); Mo. Rev. Stat. § 573.507 (1995)
(no minors in adult cabarets); Neb. Rev. Stat. § 28-809 (1995) (no
minors in places displaying movies or shows that are "harmful to
minors"); Nev. Rev. Stat. §201.265(3) (1997) (same); N. H. Rev.
Stat. Ann. § 571-B:2(II) (1986) (same); N. M. Stat. Ann. § 30-37-3
(1989) (same); N. Y. Penal Law §235.21(2) (McKinney 1989) (same);
N. D. Cent. Code § 12.1-27.1-03 (1985 and Supp. 1995) (same); 18
Pa. Cons. Stat. § 5903(a) (Supp. 1997) (same); S. D. Compo Laws
Ann. §22-24-30 (1988) (same); Tenn. Code Ann. §39-17-911(b) (1991)
(same); Vt. Stat. Ann., Tit. 13, §2802(b) (1974) (same); Va. Code
Ann. § 18.2-391 (1996) (same).
2 See, e. g., Ala. Code § 13A-12-200.5 (1994); Ariz. Rev.
Stat. Ann. § 133506 (1989); Ark. Code Ann. § 5-68-502 (1993); Cal.
Penal Code Ann. §313.1 (West Supp. 1997); Colo. Rev. Stat. §
18-7-502(1) (1986); Conn. Gen. Stat. § 53a-196 (1994); Del. Code
Ann., Tit. 11, § 1365(i)(I) (1995); D. C. Code Ann. §
22-2001(b)(I)(A) (1996); Fla. Stat. § 847.012 (1994); Ga. Code Ann.
§ 16-12-103(a) (1996); Haw. Rev. Stat. § 712-1215(1) (1994); Idaho
Code § 18-1515(1) (1987); Ill. Compo Stat., ch. 720, § 5/11-21
(1993); Ind. Code § 35-49-3-3(1) (Supp. 1996); Iowa Code § 728.2
(1993); Kan. Stat. Ann. §21-4301c(a)(2) (1988); La. Rev. Stat. Ann.
§ 14:91.11(B) (West 1986); 888 The Court has previously sustained such zoning laws, but only if
they respect the First Amendment rights of adults and minors. That
is to say, a zoning law is valid if (i) it does not unduly restrict
adult access to the material; and (ii) minors have no First
Amendment right to read or view the banned material. As applied to
the Internet as it exists in 1997, the "display" provision and some
applications of the "indecency transmission" and "specific person"
provisions fail to adhere to the first of these limiting principles
by restricting adults' access to protected materials in certain
circumstances. Unlike the Court, however, I would invalidate the
provisions only in those circumstances.
I
Our cases make clear that a "zoning" law is valid only if adults
are still able to obtain the regulated speech. If they cannot, the
law does more than simply keep children away from speech they have
no right to obtain-it interferes with the rights of adults to
obtain constitutionally protected speech and effectively "reduce[s]
the adult population ... to reading only what is fit for children." Butler v. Michigan, 352 U. S. 380 , 383
(1957). The First Amendment does not tolerate such interference.
See ibid. (striking down a Michi-
Md. Ann. Code, Art. 27, §416B (1996); Mass. Gen. Laws, ch. 272,
§28 (1992); Minn. Stat. § 617.293 (1987 and Supp. 1997); Miss. Code
Ann. § 975-11 (1994); Mo. Rev. Stat. § 573.040 (1995); Mont. Code
Ann. § 45-8-206 (1995); Neb. Rev. Stat. § 28-808 (1995); Nev. Rev.
Stat. §§ 201.265(1), (2) (1997); N. H. Rev. Stat. Ann. § 571-B:2(I)
(1986); N. M. Stat. Ann. § 30-37-2 (1989); N. Y. Penal Law §
235.21(1) (McKinney 1989); N. C. Gen. Stat. § 14190.15(a) (1993);
N. D. Cent. Code § 12.1-27.1-03 (1985 and Supp. 1995); Ohio Rev.
Code Ann. § 2907.31(A)(I) (Supp. 1997); Okla. Stat., Tit. 21, §
1040.76(2) (Supp. 1997); 18 Pa. Cons. Stat. § 5903(c) (Supp. 1997);
R. 1. Gen. Laws § 11-31-10(a) (1996); S. C. Code Ann. §
16-15-385(A) (Supp. 1996); S. D. Compo Laws Ann. §22-24-28 (1988);
Tenn. Code Ann. §39-17911(a) (1991); Tex. Penal Code Ann. §
43.24(b) (1994); Utah Code Ann. § 7610-1206(2) (1995); Vt. Stat.
Ann., Tit. 13, §2802(a) (1974); Va. Code Ann. § 18.2-391 (1996);
Wash. Rev. Code § 9.68.060 (1988 and Supp. 1997); Wis. Stat. §
948.11(2) (Supp. 1995). 889 gan criminal law banning sale of books-to minors or adults-that
contained words or pictures that" 'tende[d] to ... corrup[t] the
morals of youth' "); Sable Communications, supra (invalidating federal law that made it a crime to transmit
indecent, but nonobscene, commercial telephone messages to minors
and adults); Bolger v. Youngs Drug Products Corp., 463 U. S. 60 , 74
(1983) (striking down a federal law prohibiting the mailing of
unsolicited advertisements for contraceptives). If the law does not
unduly restrict adults' access to constitutionally protected
speech, however, it may be valid. In Ginsberg v. New
York, 390 U. S.
629 , 634 (1968), for example, the Court sustained a New York
law that barred store owners from selling pornographic magazines to
minors in part because adults could still buy those magazines.
The Court in Ginsberg concluded that the New York law
created a constitutionally adequate adult zone simply because, on
its face, it denied access only to minors. The Court did not
question-and therefore necessarily assumed-that an adult zone, once
created, would succeed in preserving adults' access while denying
minors' access to the regulated speech. Before today, there was no
reason to question this assumption, for the Court has previously
only considered laws that operated in the physical world, a world
that with two characteristics that make it possible to create
"adult zones": geography and identity. See Lessig, Reading the
Constitution in Cyberspace, 45 Emory L. J. 869, 886 (1996). A minor
can see an adult dance show only if he enters an establishment that
provides such entertainment. And should he attempt to do so, the
minor will not be able to conceal completely his identity (or,
consequently, his age). Thus, the twin characteristics of geography
and identity enable the establishment's proprietor to prevent
children from entering the establishment, but to let adults
inside.
The electronic world is fundamentally different. Because it is
no more than the interconnection of electronic pathways, cyberspace
allows speakers and listeners to mask their iden- 890 tities. Cyberspace undeniably reflects some form of geography;
chat rooms and Web sites, for example, exist at fixed "locations"
on the Internet. Since users can transmit and receive messages on
the Internet without revealing anything about their identities or
ages, see id., at 901, however, it is not currently possible to
exclude persons from accessing certain messages on the basis of
their identity.
Cyberspace differs from the physical world in another basic way:
Cyberspace is malleable. Thus, it is possible to construct barriers
in cyberspace and use them to screen for identity, making
cyberspace more like the physical world and, consequently, more
amenable to zoning laws. This transformation of cyberspace is
already underway. Id., at 888-889; id., at 887 (cyberspace
"is moving ... from a relatively unzoned place to a universe that
is extraordinarily well zoned"). Internet speakers (users who post
material on the Internet) have begun to zone cyberspace itself
through the use of "gateway" technology. Such technology requires
Internet users to enter information about themselves-perhaps an
adult identification number or a credit card number-before they can
access certain areas of cyberspace, 929 F. Supp. 824, 845 (ED Pa.
1996), much like a bouncer checks a person's driver's license
before admitting him to a nightclub. Internet users who access
information have not attempted to zone cyberspace itself, but have
tried to limit their own power to access information in cyberspace,
much as a parent controls what her children watch on television by
installing a lock box. This user-based zoning is accomplished
through the use of screening software (such as Cyber Patrol or
SurfWatch) or browsers with screening capabilities, both of which
search addresses and text for keywords that are associated with
"adult" sites and, if the user wishes, blocks access to such sites. Id., at 839-842. The Platform for Internet Content Selection
project is designed to facilitate user-based zoning by encouraging
Internet speakers to rate the content 891 of their speech using codes recognized by all screening
programs. Id., at 838-839.
Despite this progress, the transformation of cyberspace is not
complete. Although gateway technology has been available on the
World Wide Web for some time now, id., at 845; Shea v. Reno, 930 F. Supp. 916, 933-934 (SDNY 1996), it is not
available to all Web speakers, 929 F. Supp., at 845-846, and is
just now becoming technologically feasible for chat rooms and USE
NET newsgroups, Brief for Appellants 3738. Gateway technology is
not ubiquitous in cyberspace, and because without it "there is no
means of age verification," cyberspace still remains largely
unzoned-and unzoneable. 929 F. Supp., at 846; Shea, supra, at 934. U serbased zoning is also in its infancy. For it to be
effective, (i) an agreed-upon code (or "tag") would have to exist;
(ii) screening software or browsers with screening capabilities
would have to be able to recognize the "tag"; and (iii) those
programs would have to be widely available-and widely used-by
Internet users. At present, none of these conditions is true.
Screening software "is not in wide use today" and "only a handful
of browsers have screening capabilities." Shea, supra, at
945-946. There is, moreover, no agreedupon "tag" for those programs
to recognize. 929 F. Supp., at 848; Shea, supra, at 945.
Although the prospects for the eventual zoning of the Internet
appear promising, I agree with the Court that we must evaluate the
constitutionality of the CDA as it applies to the Internet as it
exists today. Ante, at 881. Given the present state of
cyberspace, I agree with the Court that the "display" provision
cannot pass muster. Until gateway technology is available
throughout cyberspace, and it is not in 1997, a speaker cannot be
reasonably assured that the speech he displays will reach only
adults because it is impossible to confine speech to an "adult
zone." Thus, the only way for a speaker to avoid liability under
the CDA is to refrain completely from using indecent speech. But
this 892 forced silence impinges on the First Amendment right of adults
to make and obtain this speech and, for all intents and purposes,
"reduce[s] the adult population [on the Internet] to reading only
what is fit for children." Butler, 352 U. S., at 383. As a
result, the "display" provision cannot withstand scrutiny. Accord, Sable Communications, 492 U. S., at 126 131; Bolger v. Youngs Drug Products Corp., 463 U. S., at 73-75.
The "indecency transmission" and "specific person" provisions
present a closer issue, for they are not unconstitutional in all of
their applications. As discussed above, the "indecency
transmission" provision makes it a crime to transmit knowingly an
indecent message to a person the sender knows is under 18 years of
age. 47 U. S. C. § 223(a)(1)(B) (1994 ed., Supp. II). The "specific
person" provision proscribes the same conduct, although it does not
as explicitly require the sender to know that the intended
recipient of his indecent message is a minor. § 223(d)(1)(A). The
Government urges the Court to construe the provision to impose such
a knowledge requirement, see Brief for Appellants 2527, and I would
do so. See Edward J. DeBartolo Corp. v. Florida
Gulf Coast Building & Constr. Trades Council, 485 U. S. 568 ,
575 (1988) ("[W]here an otherwise acceptable construction of a
statute would raise serious constitutional problems, the Court will
construe the statute to avoid such problems unless such
construction is plainly contrary to the intent of Congress").
So construed, both provisions are constitutional as applied to a
conversation involving only an adult and one or more minors-e. g.,
when an adult speaker sends an e-mail knowing the addressee is a
minor, or when an adult and minor converse by themselves or with
other minors in a chat room. In this context, these provisions are
no different from the law we sustained in Ginsberg. Restricting what the adult may say to the minors in no way
restricts the adult's ability to communicate with other adults. He
is not prevented from 893 speaking indecently to other adults in a chat room (because
there are no other adults participating in the conversation) and he
remains free to send indecent e-mails to other adults. The relevant
universe contains only one adult, and the adult in that universe
has the power to refrain from using indecent speech and
consequently to keep all such speech within the room in an "adult"
zone.
The analogy to Ginsberg breaks down, however, when more
than one adult is a party to the conversation. If a minor enters a
chat room otherwise occupied by adults, the CDA effectively
requires the adults in the room to stop using indecent speech. If
they did not, they could be prosecuted under the "indecency
transmission" and "specific person" provisions for any indecent
statements they make to the group, since they would be transmitting
an indecent message to specific persons, one of whom is a minor.
Accord, ante, at 876. The CDA is therefore akin to a law
that makes it a crime for a bookstore owner to sell pornographic
magazines to anyone once a minor enters his store. Even assuming
such a law might be constitutional in the physical world as a
reasonable alternative to excluding minors completely from the
store, the absence of any means of excluding minors from chat rooms
in cyberspace restricts the rights of adults to engage in indecent
speech in those rooms. The "indecency transmission" and "specific
person" provisions share this defect.
But these two provisions do not infringe on adults' speech in all situations. And as discussed below, I do not find that
the provisions are overbroad in the sense that they restrict
minors' access to a substantial amount of speech that minors have
the right to read and view. Accordingly, the CDA can be applied
constitutionally in some situations. Normally, this fact would
require the Court to reject a direct facial challenge. United
States v. Salerno, 481 U. S. 739 , 745 (1987)
("A facial challenge to a legislative Act [succeeds only if] the
challenger ... establish[es] that no set of circum- 894 stances exists under which the Act would be valid"). Appellees'
claim arises under the First Amendment, however, and they argue
that the CDA is facially invalid because it is "substantially
overbroad"-that is, it "sweeps too broadly ... [and] penaliz[es] a
substantial amount of speech that is constitutionally protected," Forsyth County v. Nationalist Movement, 505 U. S. 123 , 130
(1992). See Brief for Appellees American Library Association et al.
48; Brief for Appellees American Civil Liberties Union et al.
39-41. I agree with the Court that the provisions are overbroad in
that they cover any and all communications between adults and
minors, regardless of how many adults might be part of the audience
to the communication.
This conclusion does not end the matter, however.
Where, as here, "the parties challenging the statute are those
who desire to engage in protected speech that the overbroad statute
purports to punish, ... [t]he statute may forthwith be declared
invalid to the extent that it reaches too far, but otherwise left
intact." Brockett v. Spokane Arcades, Inc., 472 U. S. 491 , 504
(1985). There is no question that Congress intended to prohibit
certain communications between one adult and one or more minors.
See 47 U. S. C. § 223(a)(1)(B) (1994 ed., Supp. II) (punishing
"[w]hoever ... initiates the transmission of [any indecent
communication] knowing that the recipient of the communication is
under 18 years of age"); § 223(d)(1)(A) (punishing "[w]hoever ...
send[s] to a specific person or persons under 18 years of age [a
patently offensive message]"). There is also no question that
Congress would have enacted a narrower version of these provisions
had it known a broader version would be declared unconstitutional.
47 U. S. C. § 608 ("If ... the application [of any provision of the
CDA] to any person or circumstance is held invalid, ... the
application of such provision to other persons or circumstances
shall not be affected thereby"). I would therefore sustain the
"indecency transmission" and "specific person" provisions to the
extent they 895 apply to the transmission of Internet communications where the
party initiating the communication knows that all of the recipients
are minors.
II
Whether the CDA substantially interferes with the First
Amendment rights of minors, and thereby runs afoul of the second
characteristic of valid zoning laws, presents a closer question. In Ginsberg, the New York law we sustained prohibited the sale
to minors of magazines that were "harmful to minors." Under that
law, a magazine was "harmful to minors" only if it was obscene as
to minors. 390 U. S., at 632-633. Noting that obscene speech is not
protected by the First Amendment, Roth v. United
States, 354 U. S.
476 , 485 (1957), and that New York was constitutionally free to
adjust the definition of obscenity for minors, 390 U. S., at 638,
the Court concluded that the law did not "invad[e] the area of
freedom of expression constitutionally secured to minors," id., at
637. New York therefore did not infringe upon the First Amendment
rights of minors. Cf. Erznoznik v. Jacksonville, 422 U. S. 205 ,
213 (1975) (striking down city ordinance that banned nudity that
was not "obscene even as to minors").
The Court neither "accept[s] nor reject[s]" the argument that
the CDA is facially overbroad because it substantially interferes
with the First Amendment rights of minors. Ante, at 878. I
would reject it. Ginsberg established that minors may
constitutionally be denied access to material that is obscene as to
minors. As Ginsberg explained, material is obscene as to
minors if it (i) is "patently offensive to prevailing standards in
the adult community as a whole with respect to what is suitable ...
for minors"; (ii) appeals to the prurient interest of minors; and
(iii) is "utterly without redeeming social importance for minors."
390 U. S., at 633. Because the CDA denies minors the right to
obtain material that is "patently offensive"-even if it has some
redeeming value for minors and even if it does not appeal to their
pruri- 896 ent interests-Congress' rejection of the Ginsberg "harmful to minors" standard means that the CDA could ban some
speech that is "indecent" (i. e., "patently offensive") but
that is not obscene as to minors.
I do not deny this possibility, but to prevail in a facial
challenge, it is not enough for a plaintiff to show "some"
overbreadth. Our cases require a proof of "real" and "substantial"
overbreadth, Broadrick v. Oklahoma, 413 U. S. 601 , 615
(1973), and appellees have not carried their burden in this case.
In my view, the universe of speech constitutionally protected as to
minors but banned by the CDA-i. e., the universe of material
that is "patently offensive," but which nonetheless has some
redeeming value for minors or does not appeal to their prurient
interest-is a very small one. Appellees cite no examples of speech
falling within this universe and do not attempt to explain why that
universe is substantial "in relation to the statute's plainly
legitimate sweep." Ibid. That the CDA might deny minors the
right to obtain material that has some "value," see ante, at
878, is largely beside the point. While discussions about prison
rape or nude art, see ibid., may have some redeeming
educational value for adults, they do not necessarily have
any such value for minors, and under Ginsberg, minors
only have a First Amendment right to obtain patently offensive
material that has "redeeming social importance for minors," 390 U. S., at 633 (emphasis added). There is also no evidence in
the record to support the contention that "many e-mail
transmissions from an adult to a minor are conversations between
family members," ante, at 865, n. 32, and no support for the
legal proposition that such speech is absolutely immune from
regulation. Accordingly, in my view, the CDA does not burden a
substantial amount of minors' constitutionally protected
speech.
Thus, the constitutionality of the CDA as a zoning law hinges on
the extent to which it substantially interferes with the First
Amendment rights of adults. Because the rights 897 of adults are infringed only by the "display" provision and by
the "indecency transmission" and "specific person" provisions as
applied to communications involving more than one adult, I would
invalidate the CDA only to that extent. Insofar as the "indecency
transmission" and "specific person" provisions prohibit the use of
indecent speech in communications between an adult and one or more
minors, however, they can and should be sustained. The Court
reaches a contrary conclusion, and from that holding I respectfully
dissent. | The Communications Decency Act of 1996 (CDA) sought to protect minors from indecent or obscene material online. The Supreme Court held that the CDA's "indecent transmission" and "patently offensive display" provisions violated the First Amendment freedom of speech. The Court's decision was based on the CDA's overbreadth, as it could ban speech that is indecent but not obscene as to minors, and its vagueness, as it was unclear what constituted "indecent" or "patently offensive" material. The government argued that the CDA was necessary to protect minors, but the Court found that the CDA infringed on the First Amendment rights of adults and could have a chilling effect on free speech. |
Free Speech | Legal Services Corp. v. Velazquez | https://supreme.justia.com/cases/federal/us/531/533/ | OCTOBER TERM, 2000
Syllabus
LEGAL SERVICES CORPORATION v. VELAZQUEZ ET AL.
CERTIORARI TO THE UNITED STATES COURT OF APPEALS FOR THE SECOND
CIRCUIT
No. 99-603. Argued October 4, 2000-Decided February 28, 2001
*
The Legal Services Corporation Act authorizes petitioner Legal
Services Corporation (LSC) to distribute funds appropriated by
Congress to local grantee organizations providing free legal
assistance to indigent clients in, inter alia, welfare
benefits claims. In every annual appropriations Act since 1996,
Congress has prohibited LSC funding of any organization that
represented clients in an effort to amend or otherwise challenge
existing welfare law. Grantees cannot continue representation in a
welfare matter even where a constitutional or statutory validity
challenge becomes apparent after representation is well under way.
Respondents-lawyers employed by LSC grantees, together with
othersfiled suit to declare, inter alia, the restriction
invalid. The District Court denied them a preliminary injunction,
but the Second Circuit invalidated the restriction, finding it
impermissible viewpoint discrimination that violated the First
Amendment. Held: The funding restriction violates the First
Amendment.
Pp.540-549.
(a) LSC and the Government, also a petitioner, claim that Rust v. Sullivan, 500 U. S. 173 , in which
this Court upheld a restriction prohibiting doctors employed by
federally funded family planning clinics from discussing abortion
with their patients, supports the restriction here. However, the
Court has since explained that the Rust counseling
activities amounted to governmental speech, sustaining
viewpoint-based funding decisions in instances in which the
government is itself the speaker, see Board of Regents of Univ.
of Wis. System v. Southworth, 529 U. S. 217 ,229,235, or
instances, like Rust, in which the government uses private
speakers to transmit information pertaining to its own program, Rosenberger v. Rector and Visitors of Univ. of Va., 515 U. S. 819 ,
833. Although the government has the latitude to ensure that its
own message is being delivered, neither that latitude nor its
rationale applies to subsidies for private speech in every
instance. Like the Rosenberger *Together with No. 99-960, United States v. Velazquez
et al., also on certiorari to the same court. 534 program, the LSC program was designed to facilitate private
speech, not to promote a governmental message. An LSC attorney
speaks on behalf of a private, indigent client in a welfare
benefits claim, while the Government's message is delivered by the
attorney defending the benefits decision. The attorney's advice to
the client and advocacy to the courts cannot be classified as
governmental speech even under a generous understanding of that
concept. In this vital respect this suit is distinguishable from Rust. Pp. 540-543.
(b) The private nature of the instant speech, and the extent of
LSC's regulation of private expression, are indicated further by
the circumstance that the Government seeks to control an existing
medium of expression in ways which distort its usual functioning.
Cases involving a limited forum, though not controlling, provide
instruction for evaluating restrictions in governmental subsidies.
Here the program presumes that private, nongovernmental speech is
necessary, and a substantial restriction is placed upon that
speech. By providing subsidies to LSC, the Government seeks to
facilitate suits for benefits by using the State and Federal
Judiciaries and the independent bar on which they depend for the
proper performance of their duties and responsibilities.
Restricting LSC attorneys in advising their clients and in
presenting arguments and analyses to the courts distorts the legal
system by altering the attorneys' traditional role in much the same
way broadcast systems or student publication networks were changed
in the limited forum cases of Arkansas Ed. Television Comm'n v. Forbes, 523
U. S. 666 , and Rosenberger v. Rector and Visitors of
Univ. of Va., supra. The Government may not design a subsidy to
effect such a serious and fundamental restriction on the advocacy
of attorneys and the functioning of the judiciary. An informed,
independent judiciary presumes an informed, independent bar.
However, the instant restriction prevents LSC attorneys from
advising the courts of serious statutory validity questions. It
also threatens severe impairment of the judicial function by
sifting out cases presenting constitutional challenges in order to
insulate the Government's laws from judicial inquiry. The result of
this restriction would be two tiers of cases. There would be
lingering doubt whether an LSC attorney's truncated representation
had resulted in complete analysis of the case, full advice to the
client, and proper presentation to the court; and the courts and
the public would come to question the adequacy and fairness of
professional representations when the attorney avoided all
reference to statutory validity and constitutional authority
questions. A scheme so inconsistent with accepted
separation-of-powers principles is an insufficient basis to sustain
or uphold the restriction on speech. Pp. 543-546. 535 (c) That LSC attorneys can withdraw does not make the
restriction harmless, for the statute is an attempt to draw lines
around the LSC program to exclude from litigation arguments and
theories Congress finds unacceptable but which by their nature are
within the courts' province to consider. The restriction is even
more problematic because in cases where the attorney withdraws, the
indigent client is unlikely to find other counsel. There may be no
alternative source of vital information on the client's
constitutional or statutory rights, in stark contrast to Rust, where a patient could receive both governmentally
subsidized counseling and consultation with independent or
affiliate organizations. Finally, notwithstanding Congress' purpose
to confine and limit its program, the restriction insulates current
welfare laws from constitutional scrutiny and certain other legal
challenges, a condition implicating central First Amendment
concerns. There can be little doubt that the LSC Act funds
constitutionally protected expression; and there is no programmatic
message of the kind recognized in Rust and which sufficed
there to allow the Government to specify the advice deemed
necessary for its legitimate objectives. Pp. 546-549.
(d) The Court of Appeals concluded that the funding restriction
could be severed from the statute, leaving the remaining portions
operative. Because that determination was not contested here, the
Court in the exercise of its discretion and prudential judgment
declines to address it. P. 549. 164 F.3d
757 , affirmed.
KENNEDY, J., delivered the opinion of the Court, in which
STEVENS, SOUTER, GINSBURG, and BREYER, JJ., joined. SCALIA, J.,
filed a dissenting opinion in which REHNQUIST, C. J., and O'CONNOR
and THOMAS, JJ., joined, post, p. 549. Alan Levine argued the cause for petitioner in No.
99-603.
With him on the briefs was Stephen L. Ascher. Deputy Solicitor General Kneedler argued the cause for the
United States in No. 99-960. With him on the briefs were Solicitor
General Waxman, Acting Assistant Attorney General Ogden, Beth S.
Brinkmann, Barbara L. Herwig, and Matthew M. Collette. Burt Neuborne argued the cause for respondents in both
cases. With him on the brief were Laura K. Abel, Kimani 536 Paul-Emile, Paul K. Sonn, David S. Udell, Peter M. Fishbein, and
Alan E. Rothman. t
JUSTICE KENNEDY delivered the opinion of the Court.
In 1974, Congress enacted the Legal Services Corporation Act, 88
Stat. 378, 42 U. S. C. § 2996 et seq. The Act establishes
the Legal Services Corporation (LSC) as a District of Columbia
nonprofit corporation. LSC's mission is to distribute funds
appropriated by Congress to eligible local grantee organizations
"for the purpose of providing financial support for legal
assistance in noncriminal proceedings or matters to persons
financially unable to afford legal assistance." § 2996b(a).
LSC grantees consist of hundreds of local organizations
governed, in the typical case, by local boards of directors. In
many instances the grantees are funded by a combination of LSC
funds and other public or private sources. The grantee
organizations hire and supervise lawyers to provide free legal
assistance to indigent clients. Each year LSC appropriates funds to
grantees or recipients that hire and supervise lawyers for various
professional activities, including representation of indigent
clients seeking welfare benefits.
This suit requires us to decide whether one of the conditions
imposed by Congress on the use of LSC funds violates the First
Amendment rights of LSC grantees and their clients. For purposes of
our decision, the restriction, to be quoted in further detail,
prohibits legal representation
tBriefs of amici curiae urging reversal were filed for
the Pacific Legal Foundation by John H. Findley; and for the
Washington Legal Foundation et al. by Daniel J. Popeo and R. Shawn Gunnarson. Briefs of amici curiae urging affirmance were filed for
the American Civil Liberties Union et al. by Arthur N
Eisenberg and Steven R. Shapiro; and for the New York
State Bar Association et al. by Bruce A. Green and Lawrence S. Lustberg. Frederick A. O. Schwarz, Jr., filed a brief for
the American Judicature Society as amicus curiae. 537 funded by recipients of LSC moneys if the representation
involves an effort to amend or otherwise challenge existing welfare
law. As interpreted by the LSC and by the Government, the
restriction prevents an attorney from arguing to a court that a
state statute conflicts with a federal statute or that either a
state or federal statute by its terms or in its application is
violative of the United States Constitution.
Lawyers employed by New York City LSC grantees, together with
private LSC contributors, LSC indigent clients, and various state
and local public officials whose governments contribute to LSC
grantees, brought suit in the United States District Court for the
Eastern District of New York to declare the restriction, among
other provisions of the Act, invalid. The United States Court of
Appeals for the Second Circuit approved an injunction against
enforcement of the provision as an impermissible viewpoint-based
discrimination in violation of the First Amendment, 164 F.3d
757 (1999). We granted certiorari, and the parties who
commenced the suit in the District Court are here as respondents.
The LSC as petitioner is joined by the Government of the United
States, which had intervened in the District Court. We agree that
the restriction violates the First Amendment, and we affirm the
judgment of the Court of Appeals.
I
From the inception of the LSC, Congress has placed restrictions
on its use of funds. For instance, the LSC Act prohibits recipients
from making available LSC funds, program personnel, or equipment to
any political party, to any political campaign, or for use in
"advocating or opposing any ballot measures." 42 U. S. C. §
2996e(d)(4). See § 2996e(d)(3). The Act further proscribes use of
funds in most criminal proceedings and in litigation involving
nontherapeutic abortions, secondary school desegregation, military
desertion, or violations of the Selective Service statute. §§
2996f(b)(8)-(10) (1994 ed. and Supp. IV). Fund recipients 538 are barred from bringing class-action suits unless express
approval is obtained from LSC. § 2996e(d)(5).
The restrictions at issue were part of a compromise set of
restrictions enacted in the Omnibus Consolidated Rescissions and
Appropriations Act of 1996 (1996 Act), § 504, 110 Stat. 1321-53,
and continued in each subsequent annual appropriations Act. The
relevant portion of § 504(a)(16) prohibits funding of any
organization "that initiates legal representation or participates in any
other way, in litigation, lobbying, or rulemaking, involving an
effort to reform a Federal or State welfare system, except that
this paragraph shall not be construed to preclude a recipient from
representing an individual eligible client who is seeking specific
relief from a welfare agency if such relief does not involve an
effort to amend or otherwise challenge existing law in effect on
the date of the initiation of the representation." The prohibitions apply to all of the activities of an LSC
grantee, including those paid for by non-LSC funds. §§ 504(d)(1)
and (2). We are concerned with the statutory provision which
excludes LSC representation in cases which "involve an effort to
amend or otherwise challenge existing law in effect on the date of
the initiation of the representation."
In 1997, LSC adopted final regulations clarifying § 504(a)(16).
45 CFR pt. 1639 (1999). LSC interpreted the statutory provision to
allow indigent clients to challenge welfare agency determinations
of benefit ineligibility under interpretations of existing law. For
example, an LSC grantee could represent a welfare claimant who
argued that an agency made an erroneous factual determination or
that an agency misread or misapplied a term contained in an
existing welfare statute. According to LSC, a grantee in that
position could argue as well that an agency policy violated
existing law. § 1639.4. Under LSC's interpretation, however, 539 grantees could not accept representations designed to change
welfare laws, much less argue against the constitutionality or
statutory validity of those laws. Brief for Petitioner in No.
99-603, p. 7. Even in cases where constitutional or statutory
challenges became apparent after representation was well under way,
LSC advised that its attorneys must withdraw. Ibid. After the instant suit was filed in the District Court alleging
the restrictions on the use of LSC funds violated the First
Amendment, see 985 F. Supp. 323 (1997), the court denied a
preliminary injunction, finding no probability of success on the
merits. Id., at 344.
On appeal, the Court of Appeals for the Second Circuit affirmed
in part and reversed in part. 164 F.3d
757 (1999). As relevant for our purposes, the court addressed
respondents' challenges to the restrictions in § 504(a)(16). It
concluded the section specified four categories of prohibited
activities, of which "three appear[ed] to prohibit the type of
activity named regardless of viewpoint, while one might be read to
prohibit the activity only when it seeks reform." Id., at
768. The court upheld the restrictions on litigation, lobbying, and
rulemaking "involving an effort to reform a Federal or State
welfare system," since all three prohibited grantees' involvement
in these activities regardless of the side of the issue. Id., at 768-769.
The court next considered the exception to § 504(a)(16) that
allows representation of "'an individual eligible client who is
seeking specific relief from a welfare agency.'" The court
invalidated, as impermissible viewpoint discrimination, the
qualification that representation could "not involve an effort to
amend or otherwise challenge existing law," because it "clearly
seeks to discourage challenges to the status quo." Id., at
769-770.
Left to decide what part of the 1996 Act to strike as invalid,
the court concluded that congressional intent regarding
severability was unclear. It decided to "invalidate the 540 smallest possible portion of the statute, excising only the
viewpoint-based proviso rather than the entire exception of which
it is a part." Id., at 773.
Dissenting in part, Judge Jacobs agreed with the majority except
for its holding that the proviso banning challenges to existing
welfare laws effected impermissible viewpointbased discrimination.
The provision, in his view, was permissible because it merely
defined the scope of services to be funded. Id., at 773-778
(opinion concurring in part and dissenting in part).
LSC filed a petition for certiorari challenging the Court of
Appeals' conclusion that the § 504(a)(16) suits-for-benefits
proviso was unconstitutional. We granted certiorari, 529 U. S. 1052
(2000).
II
The United States and LSC rely on Rust v. Sullivan,
500 U. S. 173 (1991), as support for the LSC program
restrictions. In Rust, Congress established program clinics
to provide subsidies for doctors to advise patients on a variety of
family planning topics. Congress did not consider abortion to be
within its family planning objectives, however, and it forbade
doctors employed by the program from discussing abortion with their
patients. Id., at 179-180. Recipients of funds under Title X
of the Public Health Service Act, §§ 1002, 1008, as added, 84 Stat.
1506, 1508, 42 U. S. C. §§ 300a, 300a-6, challenged the Act's
restriction that provided that none of the Title X funds
appropriated for family planning services could "be used in
programs where abortion is a method of family planning." § 300a-6.
The recipients argued that the regulations constituted
impermissible viewpoint discrimination favoring an antiabortion
position over a proabortion approach in the sphere of family
planning. 500 U. S., at 192. They asserted as well that Congress
had imposed an unconstitutional condition on recipients of federal
funds by requiring them to relinquish their right to engage 541 in abortion advocacy and counseling in exchange for the subsidy. Id., at 196.
We upheld the law, reasoning that Congress had not discriminated
against viewpoints on abortion, but had "merely chosen to fund one
activity to the exclusion of the other." Id., at 193. The
restrictions were considered necessary "to ensure that the limits
of the federal program [were] observed." Ibid. Title X did
not single out a particular idea for suppression because it was
dangerous or disfavored; rather, Congress prohibited Title X
doctors from counseling that was outside the scope of the project. Id., at 194-195.
The Court in Rust did not place explicit reliance on the
rationale that the counseling activities of the doctors under Title
X amounted to governmental speech; when interpreting the holding in
later cases, however, we have explained Rust on this
understanding. We have said that viewpoint-based funding decisions
can be sustained in instances in which the government is itself the
speaker, see Board of Regents of Univ. of Wis. System v. Southworth, 529 U. S. 217, 229, 235 (2000), or instances,
like Rust, in which the government "used private speakers to
transmit specific information pertaining to its own program." Rosenberger v. Rector and Visitors of Univ. of Va., 515 U. S. 819 ,
833 (1995). As we said in Rosenberger, "[w]hen the
government disburses public funds to private entities to convey a
governmental message, it may take legitimate and appropriate steps
to ensure that its message is neither garbled nor distorted by the
grantee." Ibid. The latitude which may exist for
restrictions on speech where the government's own message is being
delivered flows in part from our observation that, "[w]hen the
government speaks, for instance to promote its own policies or to
advance a particular idea, it is, in the end, accountable to the
electorate and the political process for its advocacy. If the
citizenry objects, newly elected officials later could espouse some
different or con- 542 trary position." Board of Regents of Univ. of Wis. System
Neither the latitude for government speech nor its rationale
applies to subsidies for private speech in every instance, however.
As we have pointed out, "[i]t does not follow ... that
viewpoint-based restrictions are proper when the [government] does
not itself speak or subsidize transmittal of a message it favors
but instead expends funds to encourage a diversity of views from
private speakers." Rosenberger, supra, at 834.
Although the LSC program differs from the program at issue in Rosenberger in that its purpose is not to "encourage a
diversity of views," the salient point is that, like the program in Rosenberger, the LSC program was designed to facilitate
private speech, not to promote a governmental message. Congress
funded LSC grantees to provide attorneys to represent the interests
of indigent clients. In the specific context of § 504(a)(16) suits
for benefits, an LSC-funded attorney speaks on the behalf of the
client in a claim against the government for welfare benefits. The
lawyer is not the government's speaker. The attorney defending the
decision to deny benefits will deliver the government's message in
the litigation. The LSC lawyer, however, speaks on the behalf of
his or her private, indigent client. Cf. Polk County v. Dodson, 454 U.
S. 312 , 321-322 (1981) (holding that a public defender does not
act "under color of state law" because he "works under canons of
professional responsibility that mandate his exercise of
independent judgment on behalf of the client" and because there is
an "assumption that counsel will be free of state control").
The Government has designed this program to use the legal
profession and the established Judiciary of the States and the
Federal Government to accomplish its end of assisting welfare
claimants in determination or receipt of their benefits. The advice
from the attorney to the client and the advocacy by the attorney to
the courts cannot be classified 543 as governmental speech even under a generous understanding of
the concept. In this vital respect this suit is distinguishable
from Rust. The private nature of the speech involved here, and the extent
of LSC's regulation of private expression, are indicated further by
the circumstance that the Government seeks to use an existing
medium of expression and to control it, in a class of cases, in
ways which distort its usual functioning. Where the government uses
or attempts to regulate a particular medium, we have been informed
by its accepted usage in determining whether a particular
restriction on speech is necessary for the program's purposes and
limitations. In FCC v. League of Women Voters of
Cal., 468 U. S.
364 (1984), the Court was instructed by its understanding of
the dynamics of the broadcast industry in holding that prohibitions
against editorializing by public radio networks were an
impermissible restriction, even though the Government enacted the
restriction to control the use of public funds. The First Amendment
forbade the Government from using the forum in an unconventional
way to suppress speech inherent in the nature of the medium. See
id., at 396-397. In Arkansas Ed. Television Comm'n v. Forbes, 523 U.
S. 666 , 676 (1998), the dynamics of the broadcasting system
gave station programmers the right to use editorial judgment to
exclude certain speech so that the broadcast message could be more
effective. And in Rosenberger, the fact that student
newspapers expressed many different points of view was an important
foundation for the Court's decision to invalidate viewpoint-based
restrictions. 515 U. S., at 836.
When the government creates a limited forum for speech, certain
restrictions may be necessary to define the limits and purposes of
the program. Perry Ed. Assn. v. Perry Local Educators'
Assn., 460 U. S.
37 (1983); see also Lamb's Chapel v. Center Moriches
Union Free School Dist., 508 U. S. 384 (1993). The
same is true when the government establishes a subsidy for
specified ends. Rust v. Sullivan, 500 U. S. 173 544 (1991). As this suit involves a subsidy, limited forum cases
such as Perry, Lamb's Chapel, and Rosenberger may not
be controlling in a strict sense, yet they do provide some
instruction. Here the program presumes that private,
nongovernmental speech is necessary, and a substantial restriction
is placed upon that speech. At oral argument and in its briefs the
LSC advised us that lawyers funded in the Government program may
not undertake representation in suits for benefits if they must
advise clients respecting the questionable validity of a statute
which defines benefit eligibility and the payment structure. The
limitation forecloses advice or legal assistance to question the
validity of statutes under the Constitution of the United States.
It extends further, it must be noted, so that state statutes
inconsistent with federal law under the Supremacy Clause may be
neither challenged nor questioned.
By providing subsidies to LSC, the Government seeks to
facilitate suits for benefits by using the state and federal courts
and the independent bar on which those courts depend for the proper
performance of their duties and responsibilities. Restricting LSC
attorneys in advising their clients and in presenting arguments and
analyses to the courts distorts the legal system by altering the
traditional role of the attorneys in much the same way broadcast
systems or student publication networks were changed in the limited
forum cases we have cited. Just as government in those cases could
not elect to use a broadcasting network or a college publication
structure in a regime which prohibits speech necessary to the
proper functioning of those systems, see Arkansas Ed. Television
Comm'n, supra, and Rosenberger, supra, it may not design
a subsidy to effect this serious and fundamental restriction on
advocacy of attorneys and the functioning of the judiciary.
LSC has advised us, furthermore, that upon determining a
question of statutory validity is present in any anticipated or
pending case or controversy, the LSC-funded attorney 545 must cease the representation at once. This is true whether the
validity issue becomes apparent during initial attorneyclient
consultations or in the midst of litigation proceedings. A
disturbing example of the restriction was discussed during oral
argument before the Court. It is well understood that when there
are two reasonable constructions for a statute, yet one raises a
constitutional question, the Court should prefer the interpretation
which avoids the constitutional issue. Gomez v. United
States, 490 U. S.
858 , 864 (1989); Ashwander v. TVA, 297 U. S. 288 , 346-348
(1936) (Brandeis, J., concurring). Yet, as the LSC advised the
Court, if, during litigation, a judge were to ask an LSC attorney
whether there was a constitutional concern, the LSC attorney simply
could not answer. Tr. of Oral Arg. 8-9.
Interpretation of the law and the Constitution is the primary
mission of the judiciary when it acts within the sphere of its
authority to resolve a case or controversy. Marbury v. Madison, 1 Cranch 137, 177 (1803) ("It is emphatically the
province and the duty of the judicial department to say what the
law is"). An informed, independent judiciary presumes an informed,
independent bar. Under § 504(a)(16), however, cases would be
presented by LSC attorneys who could not advise the courts of
serious questions of statutory validity. The disability is
inconsistent with the proposition that attorneys should present all
the reasonable and well-grounded arguments necessary for proper
resolution of the case. By seeking to prohibit the analysis of
certain legal issues and to truncate presentation to the courts,
the enactment under review prohibits speech and expression upon
which courts must depend for the proper exercise of the judicial
power. Congress cannot wrest the law from the Constitution which is
its source. "Those then who controvert the principle that the
constitution is to be considered, in court, as a paramount law, are
reduced to the necessity of maintaining that courts must close
their eyes on the constitution, and see only the law." Id., at 178. 546 The restriction imposed by the statute here threatens severe
impairment of the judicial function. Section 504(a)(16) sifts out
cases presenting constitutional challenges in order to insulate the
Government's laws from judicial inquiry. If the restriction on
speech and legal advice were to stand, the result would be two
tiers of cases. In cases where LSC counsel were attorneys of
record, there would be lingering doubt whether the truncated
representation had resulted in complete analysis of the case, full
advice to the client, and proper presentation to the court. The
courts and the public would come to question the adequacy and
fairness of professional representations when the attorney, either
consciously to comply with this statute or unconsciously to
continue the representation despite the statute, avoided all
reference to questions of statutory validity and constitutional
authority. A scheme so inconsistent with accepted
separation-of-powers principles is an insufficient basis to sustain
or uphold the restriction on speech.
It is no answer to say the restriction on speech is harmless
because, under LSC's interpretation of the Act, its attorneys can
withdraw. This misses the point. The statute is an attempt to draw
lines around the LSC program to exclude from litigation those
arguments and theories Congress finds unacceptable but which by
their nature are within the province of the courts to consider.
The restriction on speech is even more problematic because in
cases where the attorney withdraws from a representation, the
client is unlikely to find other counsel. The explicit premise for
providing LSC attorneys is the necessity to make available
representation "to persons financially unable to afford legal
assistance." 42 U. S. C. § 2996(a)(3). There often will be no
alternative source for the client to receive vital information
respecting constitutional and statutory rights bearing upon claimed
benefits. Thus, with respect to the litigation services Congress
has funded, there is no alternative channel for expression of the
advocacy Con- 547 gress seeks to restrict. This is in stark contrast to Rust. There, a patient could receive the approved Title X
family planning counseling funded by the Government and later could
consult an affiliate or independent organization to receive
abortion counseling. Unlike indigent clients who seek LSC
representation, the patient in Rust was not required to
forfeit the Government-funded advice when she also received
abortion counseling through alternative channels. Because LSC
attorneys must withdraw whenever a question of a welfare statute's
validity arises, an individual could not obtain joint
representation so that the constitutional challenge would be
presented by a non-LSC attorney, and other, permitted, arguments
advanced by LSC counsel.
Finally, LSC and the Government maintain that § 504(a)(16) is
necessary to define the scope and contours of the federal program,
a condition that ensures funds can be spent for those cases most
immediate to congressional concern. In support of this contention,
they suggest the challenged limitation takes into account the
nature of the grantees' activities and provides limited
congressional funds for the provision of simple suits for benefits.
In petitioners' view, the restriction operates neither to maintain
the current welfare system nor insulate it from attack; rather, it
helps the current welfare system function in a more efficient and
fair manner by removing from the program complex challenges to
existing welfare laws.
The effect of the restriction, however, is to prohibit advice or
argumentation that existing welfare laws are unconstitutional or
unlawful. Congress cannot recast a condition on funding as a mere
definition of its program in every case, lest the First Amendment
be reduced to a simple semantic exercise. Here, notwithstanding
Congress' purpose to confine and limit its program, the restriction
operates to insulate current welfare laws from constitutional
scrutiny and certain other legal challenges, a condition
implicating central First Amendment concerns. In no lawsuit funded
by the Govern- 548 ment can the LSC attorney, speaking on behalf of a private
client, challenge existing welfare laws. As a result, arguments by
indigent clients that a welfare statute is unlawful or
unconstitutional cannot be expressed in this Governmentfunded
program for petitioning the courts, even though the program was
created for litigation involving welfare benefits, and even though
the ordinary course of litigation involves the expression of
theories and postulates on both, or multiple, sides of an
issue.
It is fundamental that the First Amendment "'was fashioned to
assure unfettered interchange of ideas for the bringing about of
political and social changes desired by the peopie.'" New York
Times Co. v. Sullivan, 376 U. S. 254 , 269 (1964)
(quoting Roth v. United States, 354 U. S. 476 , 484
(1957)). There can be little doubt that the LSC Act funds
constitutionally protected expression; and in the context of this
statute there is no programmatic message of the kind recognized in Rust and which sufficed there to allow the Government to
specify the advice deemed necessary for its legitimate objectives.
This serves to distinguish § 504(a)(16) from any of the Title X
program restrictions upheld in Rust, and to place it beyond
any congressional funding condition approved in the past by this
Court.
Congress was not required to fund an LSC attorney to represent
indigent clients; and when it did so, it was not required to fund
the whole range of legal representations or relationships. The LSC
and the United States, however, in effect ask us to permit Congress
to define the scope of the litigation it funds to exclude certain
vital theories and ideas. The attempted restriction is designed to
insulate the Government's interpretation of the Constitution from
judicial challenge. The Constitution does not permit the Government
to confine litigants and their attorneys in this manner. We must be
vigilant when Congress imposes rules and conditions which in effect
insulate its own laws from legitimate judicial challenge. Where
private speech is involved, even 549 Congress' antecedent funding decision cannot be aimed at the
suppression of ideas thought inimical to the Government's own
interest. Regan v. Taxation With Representation of
Wash., 461 U. S.
540 , 548 (1983); Speiser v. Randall, 357 U. S. 513 , 519
(1958).
For the reasons we have set forth, the funding condition is
invalid. The Court of Appeals considered whether the language
restricting LSC attorneys could be severed from the statute so that
the remaining portions would remain operative. It reached the
reasoned conclusion to invalidate the fragment of § 504(a)(16)
found contrary to the First Amendment, leaving the balance of the
statute operative and in place. That determination was not
discussed in the briefs of either party or otherwise contested
here, and in the exercise of our discretion and prudential judgment
we decline to address it.
The judgment of the Court of Appeals is
Affirmed.
JUSTICE SCALIA, with whom THE CHIEF JUSTICE, JUSTICE O'CONNOR,
and JUSTICE THOMAS join, dissenting.
Section 504(a)(16) of the Omnibus Consolidated Rescissions and
Appropriations Act of 1996 (Appropriations Act) defines the scope
of a federal spending program. I t does not directly regulate
speech, and it neither establishes a public forum nor discriminates
on the basis of viewpoint. The Court agrees with all this, yet
applies a novel and unsupportable interpretation of our
public-forum precedents to declare § 504(a)(16) facially
unconstitutional. This holding not only has no foundation in our
jurisprudence; it is flatly contradicted by a recent decision that
is on all fours with the present cases. Having found the limitation
upon the spending program unconstitutional, the Court then declines
to consider the question of severability, allowing a judgment to
stand that lets the program go forward under a version of 550 the statute Congress never enacted. I respectfully dissent from
both aspects of the judgment.
I
The Legal Services Corporation Act of 1974 (LSC Act), 42 U. S.
C. § 2996 et seq., is a federal subsidy program, the stated
purpose of which is to "provid[e] financial support for legal
assistance in noncriminal proceedings or matters to persons
financially unable to afford legal assistance." § 2996b(a).
Congress, recognizing that the program could not serve its purpose
unless it was "kept free from the influence of or use by it of
political pressures," § 2996(5), has from the program's inception
tightly regulated the use of its funds. See ante, at
537-538. No Legal Services Corporation (LSC) funds may be used, for
example, for "encouraging ... labor or antilabor activities," §
2996f(b)(6), for "litigation relating to the desegregation of any
elementary or secondary school or school system," § 2996f(b)(9), or
for "litigation which seeks to procure a nontherapeutic abortion,"
§ 2996f(b)(8). Congress discovered through experience, however,
that these restrictions did not exhaust the politically
controversial uses to which LSC funds could be put.
Accordingly, in 1996 Congress added new restrictions to the LSC
Act and strengthened existing restrictions. Among the new
restrictions is the one at issue here. Section 504(a)(16) of the
Appropriations Act, 110 Stat. 1321-55 to 1321-56, withholds LSC
funds from every entity that "participates in any ... way ... in
litigation, lobbying, or rulemaking ... involving an effort to
reform a Federal or State welfare system." It thus bans LSC-funded
entities from participating on either side of litigation involving
such statutes, from participating in rulemaking relating to the
implementation of such legislation, and from lobbying Congress
itself regarding any proposed changes to such legislation. See 45
CFR § 1639.3 (2000). 551 The restrictions relating to rulemaking and lobbying are
superfluous; they duplicate general prohibitions on the use of LSC
funds for those activities found elsewhere in the Appropriations
Act. See §§ 504(a)(2), (3), (4). The restriction on litigation,
however, is unique, and it contains a proviso specifying what the
restriction does not cover. Funding recipients may "represen[t] an
individual eligible client who is seeking specific relief from a
welfare agency if such relief does not involve an effort to amend
or otherwise challenge existing law in effect on the date of the
initiation of the representation." The LSC declares in its brief,
and respondents do not deny, that under these provisions the LSC
can sponsor neither challenges to nor defenses of existing
welfare reform law, Brief for Petitioner in No. 99-603, p. 29. The
litigation ban is symmetrical: Litigants challenging the covered
statutes or regulations do not receive LSC funding, and neither do
litigants defending those laws against challenge.
If a suit for benefits raises a claim outside the scope of the
LSC program, the LSC-funded lawyer may not participate in the suit.
As the Court explains, if LSC-funded lawyers anticipate that a
forbidden claim will arise in a prospective client's suit, they
"may not undertake [the] representation," ante, at 544.
Likewise, if a forbidden claim arises unexpectedly at trial,
"LSC-funded attorney[s] must cease the representation at once," ante, at 544-545. See also Brief for Petitioner in No.
99-603, at 7, n.4 (if the issue arises at trial, "the lawyer should
discontinue the representation 'consistent with the applicable
rules of professional responsibility' "). The lawyers may, however,
and indeed must explain to the client why they cannot
represent him. See 164 F.3d
757 , 765 (CA2 1999). They are also free to express their views
of the legality of the welfare law to the client, and they may
refer the client to another attorney who can accept the
representation, ibid. See 985 F. Supp. 323, 335336 (EDNY 1997). 552 II
The LSC Act is a federal subsidy program, not a federal
regulatory program, and "[t]here is a basic difference between [the
two]." Maher v. Roe, 432 U. S. 464 , 475
(1977). Regulations directly restrict speech; subsidies do not.
Subsidies, it is true, may indirectly abridge speech, but
only if the funding scheme is "'manipulated' to have a 'coercive
effeet'" on those who do not hold the subsidized position. National Endowment for Arts v. Finley, 524 U. S. 569 , 587 (1998)
(quoting Arkansas Writers' Project, Inc. v. Ragland, 481 U. S. 221 ,
237 (1987) (SCALIA, J., dissenting)). Proving unconstitutional
coercion is difficult enough when the spending program has
universal coverage and excludes only certain speech-such as a tax
exemption scheme excluding lobbying expenses. The Court has found
such programs unconstitutional only when the exclusion was "aimed
at the suppression of dangerous ideas." Speiser v. Randall, 357 U. S. 513, 519 (1958) (internal quotation marks
omitted); see also Regan v. Taxation With Representation
of Wash., 461 U. S. 540, 550 (1983). Proving the requisite
coercion is harder still when a spending program is not universal
but limited, providing benefits to a restricted number of
recipients, see Rust v. Sullivan, 500 U. S. 173 , 194-195
(1991). The Court has found such selective spending
unconstitutionally coercive only once, when the government created
a public forum with the spending program but then discriminated in
distributing funding within the forum on the basis of viewpoint.
See Rosenberger v. Rector and Visitors of Univ. of
Va., 515 U. S.
819 , 829-830 (1995). When the limited spending program does not
create a public forum, proving coercion is virtually impossible,
because simply denying a subsidy "does not 'coerce' belief," Lyng v. Automobile Workers, 485 U. S. 360, 369
(1988), and because the criterion of unconstitutionality is whether
denial of the subsidy threatens "to drive certain ideas or
viewpoints from the marketplace," National Endowment for
Arts v. Finley, supra, at 587 (internal quota- 553 tion marks omitted). Absent such a threat, "the Government may
allocate ... funding according to criteria that would be
impermissible were direct regulation of speech or a criminal
penalty at stake." 524 U. S., at 587-588.
In Rust v. Sullivan, supra, the Court applied
these principles to a statutory scheme that is in all relevant
respects indistinguishable from § 504(a)(16). The statute in Rust authorized grants for the provision of family planning
services, but provided that "[n]one of the funds ... shall be used
in programs where abortion is a method of family planning." Id., at 178. Valid regulations implementing the statute
required funding recipients to refer pregnant clients "for
appropriate prenatal ... services by furnishing a list of available
providers that promote the welfare of mother and unborn child," but
forbade them to refer a pregnant woman specifically to an abortion
provider, even upon request. Id., at 180. We rejected a
First Amendment free-speech challenge to the funding scheme,
explaining that "[t]he Government can, without violating the
Constitution, selectively fund a program to encourage certain
activities it believes to be in the public interest, without at the
same time funding an alternative program which seeks to deal with
the problem another way." Id., at 193. This was not, we
said, the type of "discriminat[ion] on the basis of viewpoint" that
triggers strict scrutiny, ibid., because the" 'decision not
to subsidize the exercise of a fundamental right does not infringe
the right,'" ibid. (quoting Regan v. Taxation With
Representation of Wash., supra, at 549).
The same is true here. The LSC Act, like the scheme in Rust, see 500 U. S., at 200, does not create a public forum.
Far from encouraging a diversity of views, it has always, as the
Court accurately states, "placed restrictions on its use of funds," ante, at 537. Nor does § 504(a)(16) discriminate on the
basis of viewpoint, since it funds neither challenges to nor
defenses of existing welfare law. The provision simply declines to
subsidize a certain class of litigation, and under 554 Rust that decision "does not infringe the right" to bring
such litigation. Cf. Ortwein v. Schwab, 410 U. S. 656 , 658-660,
and n. 5 (1973) (per curiam) (government not required by
First Amendment or Due Process Clause to waive filing fee for
welfare benefits litigation). The Court's repeated claims that §
504(a)(16) "restricts" and "prohibits" speech, see, e. g., ante, at 545, 546, and "insulates" laws from judicial
review, see, e. g., ante, at 547, are simply baseless. No
litigant who, in the absence of LSC funding, would bring a suit
challenging existing welfare law is deterred from doing so by §
504(a)(16). Rust thus controls these cases and compels the
conclusion that § 504(a)(16) is constitutional.
The Court contends that Rust is different because the
program at issue subsidized government speech, while the LSC funds
private speech. See ante, at 541-542. This is so
unpersuasive it hardly needs response. If the private doctors'
confidential advice to their patients at issue in Rust constituted "government speech," it is hard to imagine what
subsidized speech would not be government speech. Moreover,
the majority's contention that the subsidized speech in these cases
is not government speech because the lawyers have a professional
obligation to represent the interests of their clients founders on
the reality that the doctors in Rust had a professional
obligation to serve the interests of their patients, see 500 U. S.,
at 214 (Blackmun, J., dissenting) ("ethical responsibilities of the
medical profession")-which at the time of Rust we had held
to be highly relevant to the permissible scope of federal
regulation, see Thornburgh v. American College of
Obstetricians and Gynecologists, 476 U. S. 747 , 763 (1986)
("professional responsibilities" of physicians), overruled in part
on other grounds, Planned Parenthood of Southeastern Pa. v. Casey, 505 U.
S. 833 (1992). Even respondents agree that "the true speaker in Rust was not the government, but a doctor." Brief for
Respondents 19, n. 17.
The Court further asserts that these cases are different from Rust because the welfare funding restriction "seeks to 555 use an existing medium of expression and to control it ... in
ways which distort its usual functioning," ante, at 543.
This is wrong on both the facts and the law. It is wrong on the law
because there is utterly no precedent for the novel and facially
implausible proposition that the First Amendment has anything to do
with government funding that-though it does not actually abridge
anyone's speech-"distorts an existing medium of expression." None
of the three cases cited by the Court mentions such an odd
principle. In Ro senberger v. Rector and Visitors of Univ.
of Va., the point critical to the Court's analysis was not, as
the Court would have it, that it is part of the "usual functioning"
of student newspapers to "expres[s] many different points of view," ante, at 543 (it surely is not), but rather that the
spending program itself had been created "to encourage a
diversity of views from private speakers," 515 U. S., at 834. What
could not be distorted was the public forum that the
spending program had created. As for Arkansas Ed. Television
Comm'n v. Forbes, 523 U. S. 666 (1998),
that case discussed the nature of television broadcasting, not to
determine whether government regulation would alter its "usual
functioning" and thus violate the First Amendment (no government
regulation was even at issue in the case), but rather to determine
whether state-owned television is a "public forum" under our First
Amendment jurisprudence. Id., at 673-674. And finally, the
passage the Court cites from FCC v. League of Women
Voters of Cal., 468 U. S. 364 , 396-397
(1984), says nothing whatever about "using the forum [of
public radio] in an unconventional way to suppress speech inherent
in the nature of the medium," ante, at 543. It discusses why
the Government's asserted interest in "preventing [public radio]
stations from becoming a privileged outlet for the political and
ideological opinions of station owners and managers," 468 U. S., at
396 (internal quotation marks omitted), was insubstantial and thus
could not justify the statute's restriction on editorializing. Even
worse for the Court, after invalidat- 556 ing the restriction on this conventional First Amendment ground, League of Women Voters goes on to say that "[o]f course,"
the restriction on editorializing "would plainly be valid" if
"Congress were to adopt a revised version of [the statute] that
permitted [public radio] stations to establish 'affiliate'
organizations which could then use the station's facilities to
editorialize with nonfederal funds." Id., at 400. But of
course that is the case here. Regulations permit funding recipients
to establish affiliate organizations to conduct litigation and
other activities that fall outside the scope of the LSC program.
See 45 CFR pt. 1610 (2000). Far from supporting the Court's
nondistortion analysis, League of Women Voters dooms the
Court's case.
The Court's "nondistortion" principle is also wrong on the
facts, since there is no basis for believing that § 504(a)(16), by
causing "cases [to] be presented by LSC attorneys who [can]not
advise the courts of serious questions of statutory validity," ante, at 545, will distort the operation of the courts. It
may well be that the bar of § 504(a)(16) will cause LSCfunded
attorneys to decline or to withdraw from cases that involve
statutory validity. But that means at most that fewer statutory
challenges to welfare laws will be presented to the courts because
of the unavailability of free legal services for that purpose. So
what? The same result would ensue from excluding LSC-funded lawyers
from welfare litigation entirely. It is not the mandated,
nondistortable function of the courts to inquire into all "serious
questions of statutory validity" in all cases. Courts must consider
only those questions of statutory validity that are presented by
litigants, and if the Government chooses not to subsidize the
presentation of some such questions, that in no way "distorts" the
courts' role. It is remarkable that a Court that has so studiously
avoided deciding whether Congress could entirely eliminate federal jurisdiction over certain matters, see, e. g.,
Webster v. Doe, 486 U. S. 592 , 603
(1988); Bowen v. Michigan Academy of Family
Physicians, 476
U. S. 667 , 557 681, n. 12 (1986), would be so eager to hold the much lesser
step of declining to subsidize the litigation unconstitutional
under the First Amendment.
Nor will the judicial opinions produced by LSC cases
systematically distort the interpretation of welfare laws. Judicial
decisions do not stand as binding "precedent" for points that were
not raised, not argued, and hence not analyzed. See, e. g.,
United States v. Verdugo-Urquidez, 494 U. S. 259 , 272
(1990); Hagans v. Lavine, 415 U. S. 528 , 533, n. 5
(1974); United States v. L. A. Tucker Truck Lines,
Inc., 344 U. S.
33 , 37-38 (1952); United States v. More, 3 Cranch
159, 172 (1805) (Marshall, C. J.). The statutory validity that
courts assume in LSC cases will remain open for full determination
in later cases.
Finally, the Court is troubled "because in cases where the
attorney withdraws from a representation, the client is unlikely to
find other counsel." Ante, at 546. That is surely
irrelevant, since it leaves the welfare recipient in no worse condition than he would have been in had the LSC
program never been enacted. Respondents properly concede that even
if welfare claimants cannot obtain a lawyer anywhere else, the
Government is not required to provide one. Brief for Respondents
16; accord, Goldberg v. Kelly, 397 U. S. 254 , 270 (1970)
(government not required to provide counsel at hearing regarding
termination of welfare benefits). It is hard to see how providing
free legal services to some welfare claimants (those whose claims
do not challenge the applicable statutes) while not providing it to
others is beyond the range of legitimate legislative choice. Rust rejected a similar argument: "Petitioners contend, however, that most Title X clients are
effectively precluded by indigency and poverty from seeing a
health-care provider who will provide abortion-related services.
But once again, even these Title X clients are in no worse position
than if Congress had never enacted Title X. The financial
constraints 558 that restrict an indigent woman's ability to enjoy the full
range of constitutionally protected freedom of choice are the
product not of governmental restrictions on access to abortion, but
rather of her indigency." 500 U. S., at 203 (internal quotation
marks omitted). The only conceivable argument that can be made for
distinguishing Rust is that there even patients who wished
to receive abortion counseling could receive the nonabortion
services that the Government-funded clinic offered, whereas here
some potential LSC clients who wish to receive representation on a
benefits claim that does not challenge the statutes will be unable
to do so because their cases raise a reform claim that an LSC
lawyer may not present. This difference, of course, is required by
the same ethical canons that the Court elsewhere does not wish to
distort. Rather than sponsor "truncated representation," ante, at 546, Congress chose to subsidize only those cases
in which the attorneys it subsidized could work freely. See, e. g., 42 U. S. C. § 2996(6) ("[A]ttorneys providing legal
assistance must have full freedom to protect the best interests of
their clients"). And it is impossible to see how this difference
from Rust has any bearing upon the First Amendment question,
which, to repeat, is whether the funding scheme is "'manipulated'
to have a 'coercive effect'" on those who do not hold the
subsidized position. National Endowment for Arts v. Finley, 524 U. S., at 587 (quoting Arkansas Writers'
Project, Inc. v. Ragland, 481 U. S., at 237 (SCALIA, J.,
dissenting)). It could be claimed to have such an effect if the
client in a case ineligible for LSC representation could eliminate
the ineligibility by waiving the claim that the statute is invalid;
but he cannot. No conceivable coercive effect exists.
This has been a very long discussion to make a point that is
embarrassingly simple: The LSC subsidy neither prevents anyone from
speaking nor coerces anyone to change speech, and is
indistinguishable in all relevant respects from the sub- 559 sidy upheld in Rust v. Sullivan, supra. There is
no legitimate basis for declaring § 504(a)(16) facially
unconstitutional.
III
Even were I to accept the Court's First Amendment analysis, I
could not join its decision to conclude this litigation without
reaching the issue of severability. That issue, although decided by
the Second Circuit, was not included within the question on which
certiorari was granted, and, as the Court points out, was not
briefed or argued here. I nonetheless think it an abuse of
discretion to ignore it.
The Court has said that "[w]e may consider questions outside the
scope of the limited order [granting certiorari] when resolution of
those questions is necessary for the proper disposition of the
case." Piper Aircraft Co. v. Reyno, 454 U. S. 235 ,246-247, n.
12 (1981). I think it necessary to a "proper disposition" here
because the statute concocted by the Court of Appeals bears little
resemblance to what Congress enacted, funding without restriction
welfare-benefits litigation that Congress funded only under the
limitations of § 504(a)(16). Although no party briefed severability
in Den ver Area Ed. Telecommunications Consortium, Inc. v. FCC, 518 U. S.
727 (1996), the Justices finding partial unconstitutionality
considered it necessary to address the issue. Id., at 767
(plurality opinion) ("[W]e must ask whether § 10(a) is severable");
accord, New York v. United States, 505 U. S. 144 , 186
(1992). I think we have that same obligation here. Moreover, by
exercising our "discretion" to leave the severability question
open, we fail to resolve the basic, real-world dispute at issue:
whether LSC attorneys may represent welfare claimants who challenge
the applicable welfare laws. Indeed, we leave the LSC program
subject to even a greater uncertainty than the one we purport to
have eliminated, since other circuits may conclude (as I do) that
if the limitation upon welfare representation is unconstitutional,
LSC attorneys cannot engage in welfare litigation at all. 560 "The inquiry into whether a statute is severable is essentially
an inquiry into legislative intent." Minnesota v. Mille
Lacs Band of Chippewa Indians, 526 U. S. 172 , 191
(1999). If Congress "would not have enacted those provisions which
are within its power, independently of that which is not," then
courts must strike the provisions as a piece. Alaska Airlines,
Inc. v. Brock, 480 U. S. 678 , 684 (1987)
(internal quotation marks omitted). One determines what Congress
would have done by examining what it did. Perhaps the most that can
be said on the subject is contained in a passage written by Chief
Justice Shaw of the Supreme Judicial Court of Massachusetts that we
have often quoted: "[I]f [a statute's provisions] are so mutually connected with
and dependent on each other, as conditions, considerations or
compensations for each other, as to warrant a belief that the
legislature intended them as a whole, and that, if all could not be
carried into effect, the legislature would not pass the residue
independently, and some parts are unconstitutional, all the
provisions which as thus dependent, conditional or connected, must
fall with them." Warren v. Mayor and Aldermen of
Charlestown, 68 Mass. 84, 99 (1854). It is clear to me that the LSC Act's funding of welfare benefits
suits and its prohibition on suits challenging or defending the
validity of existing law are "conditions, considerations [and]
compensations for each other" that cannot be severed. Congress
through the LSC Act intended "to provide high quality legal
assistance to those who would be otherwise unable to afford
adequate legal counsel," 42 U. S. C. § 2996(2), but only if the
program could at the same time "be kept free from the influence of
or use by it of political pressures," § 2996(5). More than a dozen
times in § 504(a) Congress made the decision that certain
activities could not be funded at all without crippling the
LSC program with political pressures. See, e. g., §
504(a)(1) (reapportionment 561 litigation); § 504(a)(4) (local, state, and federal lobbying); §
504(a)(7) (class-action lawsuits); § 504(a)(12) (training programs
for, inter alia, boycotts, picketing, and demonstrations); §
504(a)(14) (litigation with respect to abortion). The severability
question here is, essentially, whether, without the restriction
that the Court today invalidates, the permission for conducting
welfare litigation would have been accorded. As far as appears from
the best evidence (which is the structure of the statute), I think
the answer must be no.
We have in some cases stated that when an "excepting proviso is
found unconstitutional the substantive provisions which it
qualifies cannot stand," for "to hold otherwise would be to extend
the scope of the law ... so as to embrace [situations] which the
legislature passing the statute had, by its very terms, expressly
excluded." Frost v. Corporation Comm'n of Okla., 278 U. S. 515 ,
525 (1929); see also Davis v. Wallace, 257 U. S. 478 , 484 (1922)
("Where an excepting provision in a statute is found
unconstitutional, courts very generally hold that this does not
work an enlargement of the scope or operation of other provisions
with which that provision was enacted, and which it was intended to
qualify or restrain"). I frankly doubt whether this approach has
been followed consistently enough to be called the "general" rule,
but if there were ever an instance in which it is appropriate it is
here. To strike the restriction on welfare benefits suits is to
void § 504(a)(16) altogether. Subsection (a)(16) prohibits
involvement in three types of activities with respect to welfare
reform: lobbying, rulemaking, and litigation. But the proscriptions
against using LSC funds to participate in welfare lobbying and
rulemaking are superfluous, since as described above subsections
(a)(2), (a)(3), and (a)(4) of § 504 withhold LSC funds from those
activities generally. What is unique about subsection (a)(16)-the
only thing it achieves-is its limit on litigation. To remove that
limit is to repeal subsection (a)(16) altogether, and thus to
eliminate a significant quid pro quo of the legislative
compromise. We 562 have no authority to "rewrite [the] statute and give it an
effect altogether different" from what Congress agreed to. Railroad Retirement Bd. v. Alton R. Co., 295 U. S. 330 , 362 (1935)
(quoted in Carter v. Carter Coal Co., 298 U. S. 238 , 313
(1936)).
***
It is illuminating to speculate how these cases would have been
decided if Congress had enacted § 504(a)(16) without its proviso
(prescribing only the general ban against "litigation, lobbying, or
rulemaking, involving an effort to reform a Federal or State
welfare system"), and if the positions of the parties before us
here were reversed. If the LSC-funded lawyers were here arguing
that the statute permitted representation of individual welfare
claimants who did not challenge existing law, I venture to say that
the Court would endorse their argument-perhaps with stirring
language about the importance of aid to welfare applicants and the
Court's unwillingness to presume without clear indication that
Congress would want to eliminate it. And I have little doubt that
in that context the Court would find its current First Amendment
musings as unpersuasive as I find them today.
Today's decision is quite simply inexplicable on the basis of
our prior law. The only difference between Rust and the
present cases is that the former involved "distortion" of (that is
to say, refusal to subsidize) the normal work of doctors, and the
latter involves "distortion" of (that is to say, refusal to
subsidize) the normal work of lawyers. The Court's decision
displays not only an improper special solicitude for our own
profession; it also displays, I think, the very fondness for
"reform through the courts"-the making of innumerable social
judgments through judge-pronounced constitutional imperatives-that
prompted Congress to restrict publicly funded litigation of this
sort. The Court says today, through an unprecedented (and indeed
previously rejected) interpretation of the First Amendment, that we
will not allow this 563 restriction-and then, to add insult to InJury, permits to stand
a judgment that awards the general litigation funding that the
statute does not contain. I respectfully dissent. 564 The next page is purposely numbered 801. The numbers between 563
and 801 were intentionally omitted, in order to make it possible to
publish the orders with permanent page numbers, thus making the
official citations available upon publication of the preliminary
prints of the United States Reports. 565 OCTOBER 2, 2000
Certiorari Granted-Vacated and Remanded
No. 99-1870. ADLER ET AL. V. DUVAL COUNTY SCHOOL BOARD ET AL. C.
A. 11th Cir. Certiorari granted, judgment vacated, and case
remanded for further consideration in light of Santa Fe
Independent School Dist. V. Doe, 530 U. S. 290 (2000).
Reported below: 206 F.3d
1070 .
No. 99-6775. BLUE V. UNITED STATES. C. A. 4th Cir. Motion of
petitioner for leave to proceed in forma pauperis granted.
Certiorari granted, judgment vacated, and case remanded for further
consideration in light of Apprendi V. New Jersey, 530 U. S. 466 (2000). Reported below: 187 F.3d
631 .
No. 99-7351. GIBSON, AKA WILLIS V. UNITED STATES. C. A. 4th Cir.
Motion of petitioner for leave to proceed in forma pauperis granted. Certiorari granted, judgment vacated, and case remanded
for further consideration in light of Apprendi V. New
Jersey, 530 U. S.
466 (2000). Reported below: 187 F.3d
631 .
No. 99-8958. WIMS V. UNITED STATES. C. A. 11th Cir. Motion of
petitioner for leave to proceed in forma pauperis granted.
Certiorari granted, judgment vacated, and case remanded for further
consideration in light of Apprendi V. New Jersey, 530 U. S. 466 (2000). Reported below: 207 F.3d
661 .
No. 99-9902. BURTON V. UNITED STATES. C. A. 5th Cir. Motion of
petitioner for leave to proceed in forma pauperis granted.
Certiorari granted, judgment vacated, and case remanded for further
consideration in light of Apprendi V. New Jersey, 530 U. S. 466 (2000). Reported below: 211 F.3d
125 .
No. 99-9924. MARTIN V. CAIN, WARDEN. C. A. 5th Cir. Motion of
petitioner for leave to proceed in forma pauperis granted.
Certiorari granted, judgment vacated, and case remanded for
fur801 | In Legal Services Corporation v. Velazquez, the Supreme Court ruled that a restriction on funding for organizations that represent clients in welfare benefits claims violates the First Amendment. The Court distinguished this case from Rust v. Sullivan, where the Court upheld a restriction on abortion counseling, by noting that the Legal Services Corporation Act facilitates private speech, not governmental speech. The Court found that the funding restriction was impermissible viewpoint discrimination and could not be justified by the government's interest in ensuring that its message is delivered. |
Free Speech | National Endowment for the Arts v. Finley | https://supreme.justia.com/cases/federal/us/524/569/ | OCTOBER TERM, 1997
Syllabus
NATIONAL ENDOWMENT FOR THE ARTS ET AL. v. FINLEY ET
AL.
CERTIORARI TO THE UNITED STATES COURT OF APPEALS FOR THE NINTH
CIRCUIT No.97-371. Argued March 31, 1998-Decided June 25,1998 The National Foundation on the Arts and the Humanities Act of
1965 vests the National Endowment for the Arts (NEA) with
substantial discretion to award financial grants to support the
arts; it identifies only the broadest funding priorities, including
"artistic and cultural significance, giving emphasis to ...
creativity and cultural diversity," "professional excellence," and
the encouragement of "public ... education ... and appreciation of
the arts." See 20 U. S. C. §§ 954(c)(1)-(10). Applications for NEA
funding are initially reviewed by advisory panels of experts in the
relevant artistic field. The panels report to the National Council
on the Arts (Council), which, in turn, advises the NEA Chairperson.
In 1989, controversial photographs that appeared in two NEA-funded
exhibits prompted public outcry over the agency's grant-making
procedures. Congress reacted to the controversy by inserting an
amendment into the NEA's 1990 reauthorization bill. The amendment
became § 954(d)(1), which directs the Chairperson to ensure that
"artistic excellence and artistic merit are the criteria by which
[grant] applications are judged, taking into consideration general
standards of decency and respect for the diverse beliefs and values
of the American public." The NEA has not promulgated an official
interpretation of the provision, but the Council adopted a
resolution to implement § 954(d)(1) by ensuring that advisory panel
members represent geographic, ethnic, and esthetic diversity. The
four individual respondents are performance artists who applied for
NEA grants before § 954(d)(1) was enacted. An advisory panel
recommended approval of each of their projects, but the Council
subsequently recommended disapproval, and funding was denied. They
filed suit for restoration of the recommended grants or
reconsideration of their applications, asserting First Amendment
and statutory claims. When Congress enacted § 954(d)(1),
respondents, now joined by the N ational Association of Artists'
Organizations, amended their complaint to challenge the provision
as void for vagueness and impermissibly viewpoint based. The
District Court granted summary judgment in favor of respondents on
their facial constitutional challenge to § 954(d)(1). 570 The Ninth Circuit affirmed, holding that § 954(d)(1), on its
face, impermissibly discriminates on the basis of viewpoint and is
void for vagueness under the First and Fifth Amendments. Held: Section 954(d)(1) is facially valid, as it neither
inherently interferes with First Amendment rights nor violates
constitutional vagueness principles. pp. 580-590.
(a) Respondents confront a heavy burden in advancing their
facial constitutional challenge, and they have not demonstrated a
substantial risk that application of § 954(d)(1) will lead to the
suppression of free expression, see Broadrick v. Oklahoma, 413
U. S. 601 , 615. The premise of respondents' claim is that §
954(d)(1) constrains the agency's ability to fund certain
categories of artistic expression. The provision, however, simply
adds "considerations" to the grant-making process; it does not
preclude awards to projects that might be deemed "indecent" or
"disrespectful," nor place conditions on grants, or even specify
that those factors must be given any particular weight in reviewing
an application. Regardless of whether the NEA's view that the
formulation of diverse advisory panels is sufficient to comply with
Congress' command is in fact a reasonable reading, § 954(d)(1)'s
plain text clearly does not impose a categorical requirement.
Furthermore, the political context surrounding the "decency and
respect" clause's adoption is inconsistent with respondents'
assertion. The legislation was a bipartisan proposal introduced as
a counterweight to amendments that would have eliminated the NEA's
funding or substantially constrained its grant-making authority.
Section 954(d)(1) merely admonishes the NEA to take "decency and
respect" into consideration, and the Court does not perceive a
realistic danger that it will be utilized to preclude or punish the
expression of particular views. The Court typically strikes down
legislation as facially unconstitutional when the dangers are both
more evident and more substantial. See, e. g., R. A.
V. v. St. Paul, 505 U. S. 377 . Given the
varied interpretations of the "decency and respect" criteria urged
by the parties, and the provision's vague exhortation to "take them
into consideration," it seems unlikely that § 954(d)(1) will
significantly compromise First Amendment values.
The NEA's enabling statute contemplates a number of indisputably
constitutional applications for both the "decency" and the
"respect" prongs of § 954(d)(1). It is well established that
"decency" is a permissible factor where "educational suitability"
motivates its consideration. See, e. g., Board of Ed.,
Island Trees Union Free School Dist. No. 26 v. Pico, 457 U. S. 853 ,
871. And the statute already provides that the agency must take
"cultural diversity" into account. References to permissible
applications would not alone be sufficient to sustain the
statute, 571 but neither is the Court persuaded that, in other applications,
the language of § 954(d)(1) itself will give rise to the
suppression of protected expression. Any content-based
considerations that may be taken into account are a consequence of
the nature of arts funding; the NEA has limited resources to
allocate among many "artistically excellent" projects, and it does
so on the basis of a wide variety of subjective criteria.
Respondent's reliance on Rosenberger v. Rector and
Visitors of Univ. of Va., 515 U. S. 819 , 837-in
which the Court overturned a public university's objective decision
denying funding to all student publications having religious
editorial viewpoints-is therefore misplaced. The NEA's mandate is
to make esthetic judgments, and the inherently content-based
"excellence" threshold for NEA support sets it apart from the
subsidy at issue in Rosenberger. Moreover, although the
First Amendment applies in the subsidy context, Congress has wide
latitude to set spending priorities. See, e. g., Regan v. Taxation with Representation of Wash., 461 U. S. 540 , 549.
Unless § 954(d)(1) is applied in a manner that raises concern about
the suppression of disfavored viewpoints, the Court will uphold it.
Pp. 580-588.
(b) The lower courts also erred in invalidating § 954(d)(1) as
unconstitutionally vague. The First and Fifth Amendments protect
speakers from arbitrary and discriminatory enforcement of vague
standards. See NAACP v. Button, 371 U. S. 415 , 432-433.
Section 954(d)(1)'s terms are undeniably opaque, and if they
appeared in a criminal statute or regulatory scheme, they could
raise substantial vagueness concerns. It is unlikely, however, that
speakers will be compelled to steer too far clear of any forbidden
area in the context of NEA grants. As a practical matter, artists
may conform their speech to what they believe to be the NEA
decisionmaking criteria in order to acquire funding. But when the
Government is acting as patron rather than sovereign, the
consequences of imprecision are not constitutionally severe. In the
context of selective subsidies, it is not always feasible for
Congress to legislate with clarity. Indeed, to accept respondents'
vagueness argument would be to call into question the
constitutionality of the many valuable Government programs awarding
scholarships and grants on the basis of subjective criteria such as
"excellence." pp. 588-590. 100 F.3d
671 , reversed and remanded.
O'CONNOR, J., delivered the opinion of the Court, in which
REHNQUIST, C. J., and STEVENS, KENNEDY, and BREYER, JJ., joined,
and in all but Part II-B of which GINSBURG, J., joined. SCALIA, J.,
filed an opinion concurring in the judgment, in which THOMAS, J.,
joined, post, p. 590. SOUTER, J., filed a dissenting
opinion, post, p. 600. 572 Solicitor General Waxman argued the cause for petitioners. With
him on the briefs were Assistant Attorney General Hunger, Deputy
Solicitor General Kneedler, Deputy Assistant Attorney General
Preston, Jeffrey P. Minear, William Kanter, Alfred Mollin, and
Karen Christensen.
David Cole argued the cause for respondents. With him on the
briefs were Ellen Yaroshefsky, Marjorie Heins, Steven R. Shapiro,
Mary D. Dorman, and Carol Sobel. *
JUSTICE O'CONNOR delivered the opinion of the Court.t The
National Foundation on the Arts and the Humanities Act of 1965, as
amended in 1990, 104 Stat. 1963, requires the
Chairperson of the National Endowment for the Arts (NEA) to
ensure that "artistic excellence and artistic merit are the
criteria by which [grant] applications are judged, taking into
consideration general standards of decency and respect for the
diverse beliefs and values of the American public." 20 U. S. C. §
954(d)(1). In this case, we review the Court of Ap-
*Briefs of amici curiae urging reversal were filed for
the American Center for Law and Justice by Jay A. Sekulow, Colby
M. May, James M. Henderson, Sr., and John P. Tuskey; for
Liberty Counsel by Mathew D. Staver and Frederick H.
Nelson; and for the National Family Legal Foundation by Len
L. Munsil. Briefs of amici curiae urging affirmance were filed for
the American Association of University Professors et al. by John
Joshua Wheeler, Jonathan R. Alger, and Jeffrey P.
Cunard; for Americans United for Separation of Church and State
by Steven K. Green, Julie A. Segal, and Edward
Tabash; for the Family Research Institute of Wisconsin by Daniel Kelly; for the New School for Social Research et al.
by Floyd Abrams, Burt Neuborne, Kathleen M. Sullivan, Jonathan
Sherman, Elai Katz, and Deborah Goldberg; for the
Rockefeller Foundation by Donald B. Verrilli, Jr.; for
Twenty-Six Arts, Broadcast, Library, Museum and Publishing Amici
Curiae by James F. Fitzpatrick, James A. Dobkin,
Matthew T. Heartney, Mark R. Drozdowski, Elliot M. Mincberg, and Lawrence S. Ottinger; for Volunteer Lawyers for
the Arts et al. by Marci A. Hamilton; and for Claes
Oldenburg et al. by Gloria C. Phares. Paul J. M cGeady and Robert W Peters filed
a brief for Morality in Media, Inc., as amicus curiae. tJUSTICE GINSBURG joins all but Part II-B of this opinion. 573 peals' determination that § 954(d)(1), on its face,
impermissibly discriminates on the basis of viewpoint and is void
for vagueness under the First and Fifth Amendments. We conclude
that § 954(d)(1) is facially valid, as it neither inherently
interferes with First Amendment rights nor violates constitutional
vagueness principles.
I A
With the establishment of the NEA in 1965, Congress embarked on
a "broadly conceived national policy of support for the ... arts in
the United States," see § 953(b), pledging federal funds to "help
create and sustain not only a climate encouraging freedom of
thought, imagination, and inquiry but also the material conditions
facilitating the release of ... creative talent." § 951(7). The
enabling statute vests the NEA with substantial discretion to award
grants; it identifies only the broadest funding priorities,
including "artistic and cultural significance, giving emphasis to
American creativity and cultural diversity," "professional
excellence," and the encouragement of "public knowledge, education,
understanding, and appreciation of the arts." See §§
954(c)(1)-(10).
Applications for NEA funding are initially reviewed by advisory
panels composed of experts in the relevant field of the arts. Under
the 1990 amendments to the enabling statute, those panels must
reflect "diverse artistic and cultural points of view" and include
"wide geographic, ethnic, and minority representation," as well as
"lay individuals who are knowledgeable about the arts." §§
959(c)(1)-(2). The panels report to the 26-member National Council
on the Arts (Council), which, in turn, advises the NEA Chairperson.
The Chairperson has the ultimate authority to award grants but may
not approve an application as to which the Council has made a
negative recommendation. § 955(f). 574 Since 1965, the NEA has distributed over $3 billion in grants to
individuals and organizations, funding that has served as a
catalyst for increased state, corporate, and foundation support for
the arts. Congress has recently restricted the availability of
federal funding for individual artists, confining grants primarily
to qualifying organizations and state arts agencies, and
constraining subgranting. See Department of the Interior and
Related Agencies Appropriations Act, 1998, § 329, 111 Stat. 1600.
By far the largest portion of the grants distributed in fiscal year
1998 were awarded directly to state arts agencies. In the remaining
categories, the most substantial grants were allocated to symphony
orchestras, fine arts museums, dance theater foundations, and opera
associations. See National Endowment for the Arts, FY 1998 Grants,
Creation & Presentation 5-8, 21,20,27.
Throughout the NEA's history, only a handful of the agency's
roughly 100,000 awards have generated formal complaints about
misapplied funds or abuse of the public's trust. Two provocative
works, however, prompted public controversy in 1989 and led to
congressional revaluation of the NEA's funding priorities and
efforts to increase oversight of its grant-making procedures. The
Institute of Contemporary Art at the University of Pennsylvania had
used $30,000 of a visual arts grant it received from the NEA to
fund a 1989 retrospective of photographer Robert Mapplethorpe's
work. The exhibit, entitled The Perfect Moment, included homoerotic
photographs that several Members of Congress condemned as
pornographic. See, e. g., 135 Congo Rec. 22372 (1989).
Members also denounced artist Andres Serrano's work Piss Christ, a
photograph of a crucifix immersed in urine. See, e. g., id.,
at 9789. Serrano had been awarded a $15,000 grant from the
Southeast Center for Contemporary Art, an organization that
received NEA support.
When considering the NEA's appropriations for fiscal year 1990,
Congress reacted to the controversy surrounding the 575 Mapplethorpe and Serrano photographs by eliminating $45,000 from
the agency's budget, the precise amount contributed to the two
exhibits by NEA grant recipients. Congress also enacted an
amendment providing that no NEA funds "may be used to promote,
disseminate, or produce materials which in the judgment of [the
NEA] may be considered obscene, including but not limited to,
depictions of sadomasochism, homoeroticism, the sexual exploitation
of children, or individuals engaged in sex acts and which, when
taken as a whole, do not have serious literary, artistic,
political, or scientific value." Department of the Interior and
Related Agencies Appropriations Act, 1990, 103 Stat. 738-742. The
NEA implemented Congress' mandate by instituting a requirement that
all grantees certify in writing that they would not utilize federal
funding to engage in projects inconsistent with the criteria in the
1990 appropriations bill. That certification requirement was
subsequently invalidated as unconstitutionally vague by a Federal
District Court, see Bella Lewitzky Dance Foundation v. Frohnmayer, 754 F. Supp. 774 (CD Cal. 1991), and the NEA did
not appeal the decision.
In the 1990 appropriations bill, Congress also agreed to create
an Independent Commission of constitutional law scholars to review
the NEA's grant-making procedures and assess the possibility of
more focused standards for public arts funding. The Commission's
report, issued in September 1990, concluded that there is no
constitutional obligation to provide arts funding, but also
recommended that the NEA rescind the certification requirement and
cautioned against legislation setting forth any content
restrictions. Instead, the Commission suggested procedural changes
to enhance the role of advisory panels and a statutory
reaffirmation of "the high place the nation accords to the
fostering of mutual respect for the disparate beliefs and values
among us." See Independent Commission, Report to Congress on the N
a- 576 tional Endowment for the Arts 83-91 (Sept. 1990), 3 Record, Doc.
No. 51, Exh. K (hereinafter Report to Congress).
Informed by the Commission's recommendations, and cognizant of
pending judicial challenges to the funding limitations in the 1990
appropriations bill, Congress debated several proposals to reform
the NEA's grant-making process when it considered the agency's
reauthorization in the fall of 1990. The House rejected the Crane
Amendment, which would have virtually eliminated the NEA, see 136
Congo Rec. 28656-28657 (1990), and the Rohrabacher Amendment, which
would have introduced a prohibition on awarding any grants that
could be used to "promote, distribute, disseminate, or produce
matter that has the purpose or effect of denigrating the beliefs,
tenets, or objects of a particular religion" or "of denigrating an
individual, or group of individuals, on the basis of race, sex,
handicap, or national origin," id., at 28657-28664. Ultimately,
Congress adopted the Williams/ Coleman Amendment, a bipartisan
compromise between Members opposing any funding restrictions and
those favoring some guidance to the agency. In relevant part, the
Amendment became § 954(d)(1), which directs the Chairperson, in
establishing procedures to judge the artistic merit of grant
applications, to "tak[e] into consideration general standards of
decency and respect for the diverse beliefs and values of the
American public." *
*Title 20 U. S. C. § 954(d) provides in full that:
"No payment shall be made under this section except upon
application therefor which is submitted to the National Endowment
for the Arts in accordance with regulations issued and procedures
established by the Chairperson. In establishing such regulations
and procedures, the Chairperson shall ensure that-
"(1) artistic excellence and artistic merit are the criteria by
which applications are judged, taking into consideration general
standards of decency and respect for the diverse beliefs and values
of the American public; and "(2) applications are consistent with
the purposes of this section. Such regulations and procedures shall
clearly indicate that obscenity is without artistic merit, is not
protected speech, and shall not be funded." 577 The NEA has not promulgated any official interpretation of the
provision, but in December 1990, the Council unanimously adopted a
resolution to implement § 954(d)(1) merely by ensuring that the
members of the advisory panels that conduct the initial review of
grant applications represent geographic, ethnic, and esthetic
diversity. See Minutes of the Dec. 1990 Retreat of the National
Council on the Arts, reprinted in App. 12-13; Transcript of the
Dec. 1990 Retreat of the National Council on the Arts, reprinted in
id., at 3233. John Frohnmayer, then Chairperson of the NEA, also
declared that he would "count on [the] procedures" ensuring diverse
membership on the peer review panels to fulfill Congress' mandate.
See id., at 40.
B
The four individual respondents in this case, Karen Finley, John
Fleck, Holly Hughes, and Tim Miller, are performance artists who
applied for NEA grants before § 954(d)(1) was enacted. An advisory
panel recommended approval of respondents' projects, both initially
and after receiving Frohnmayer's request to reconsider three of the
applications. A majority of the Council subsequently recommended
disapproval, and in June 1990, the NEA informed respondents that
they had been denied funding. Respondents filed suit, alleging that
the NEA had violated their First Amendment rights by rejecting the
applications on political grounds, had failed to follow statutory
procedures by basing the denial on criteria other than those set
forth in the NEA's enabling statute, and had breached the
confidentiality of their grant applications through the release of
quotations to the press, in violation of the Privacy Act of 1974, 5
U. S. C. § 552(a). Respondents sought restoration of the
recommended grants or reconsideration of their applications, as
well as damages for the alleged Privacy Act violations. When
Congress enacted § 954(d)(1), respondents, now joined by the
National Association of Artists' Organizations (NAAO), amended 578 their complaint to challenge the provision as void for vagueness
and impermissibly viewpoint based. First Amended Complaint ~ 1.
The District Court denied the NEA's motion for judgment on the
pleadings, 795 F. Supp. 1457, 1463-1468 (CD Cal. 1992), and, after
discovery, the NEA agreed to settle the individual respondents'
statutory and as-applied constitutional claims by paying the
artists the amount of the vetoed grants, damages, and attorney's
fees. See Stipulation and Settlement Agreement, 6 Record, Doc. No.
128, pp. 3-5.
The District Court then granted summary judgment in favor of
respondents on their facial constitutional challenge to § 954(d)(1)
and enjoined enforcement of the provision. See 795 F. Supp., at
1476. The court rejected the argument that the NEA could comply
with § 954(d)(1) by structuring the grant selection process to
provide for diverse advisory panels. Id., at 1471. The
provision, the court stated, "fails adequately to notify applicants
of what is required of them or to circumscribe NEA discretion." Id., at 1472. Reasoning that "the very nature of our
pluralistic society is that there are an infinite number of values
and beliefs, and correlatively, there may be no national 'general
standards of decency,'" the court concluded that § 954(d)(1)
"cannot be given effect consistent with the Fifth Amendment's due
process requirement." Id., at 1471-1472 (citing Grayned v. City of Rockford, 408 U. S. 104 , 108-109
(1972)). Drawing an analogy between arts funding and public
universities, the court further ruled that the First Amendment
constrains the NEA's grant-making process, and that because §
954(d)(1) "clearly reaches a substantial amount of protected
speech," it is impermissibly overbroad on its face. 795 F. Supp.,
at 1476. The Government did not seek a stay of the District Court's
injunction, and consequently the NEA has not applied § 954(d)(1)
since June 1992.
A divided panel of the Court of Appeals affirmed the District
Court's ruling. 100 F.3d
671 (CA9 1996). The major- 579 ity agreed with the District Court that the NEA was compelled by
the adoption of § 954(d)(1) to alter its grant-making procedures to
ensure that applications are judged according to the "decency and
respect" criteria. The Chairperson, the court reasoned, "has no
discretion to ignore this obligation, enforce only part of it, or
give it a cramped construction." I d., at 680. Concluding
that the "decency and respect" criteria are not "susceptible to
objective definition," the court held that § 954(d)(1) "gives rise
to the danger of arbitrary and discriminatory application" and is
void for vagueness under the First and Fifth Amendments. I
d., at 680-681. In the alternative, the court ruled that §
954(d)(1) violates the First Amendment's prohibition on
viewpoint-based restrictions on protected speech. Government
funding of the arts, the court explained, is both a "traditional
sphere of free expression," Rust v. Sullivan, 500 U. S. 173 ,
200 (1991), and an area in which the Government has stated its
intention to "encourage a diversity of views from private
speakers," Rosenberger v. Rector and Visitors of Univ. of
Va., 515 U. S.
819 , 834 (1995). 100 F. 3d, at 681-682. Accordingly, finding
that § 954(d)(1) "has a speech-based restriction as its sole
rationale and operative principle," Rosenberger, supra, at
834, and noting the NEA's failure to articulate a compelling
interest for the provision, the court declared it facially invalid.
100 F. 3d, at 683.
The dissent asserted that the First Amendment protects artists'
rights to express themselves as indecently and disrespectfully as
they like, but does not compel the Government to fund that speech. Id., at 684 (opinion of Kleinfeld, J.). The challenged
provision, the dissent contended, did not prohibit the NEA from
funding indecent or offensive art, but merely required the agency
to consider the "decency and respect" criteria in the grant
selection process. Id., at 689690. Moreover, according to
the dissent's reasoning, the vagueness principles applicable to the
direct regulation of speech have no bearing on the selective award
of prizes, and 580 the Government may draw distinctions based on content and
viewpoint in making its funding decisions. Id., at 684-688.
Three judges dissented from the denial of rehearing en bane,
maintaining that the panel's decision gave the statute an
"implausible construction," applied the "'void for vagueness'
doctrine where it does not belong," and extended "First Amendment
principles to a situation that the First Amendment doesn't cover." 112 F.3d
1015 , 1016-1017 (CA9 1997).
We granted certiorari, 522 U. S. 991 (1997), and now reverse the
judgment of the Court of Appeals.
II A
Respondents raise a facial constitutional challenge to §
954(d)(1), and consequently they confront "a heavy burden" in
advancing their claim. Rust, supra, at 183. Facial
invalidation "is, manifestly, strong medicine" that "has been
employed by the Court sparingly and only as a last resort." Broadrick v. Oklahoma, 413 U. S. 601 , 613
(1973); see also FW/PBS, Inc. v. Dallas, 493 U. S. 215 , 223 (1990)
(noting that "facial challenges to legislation are generally
disfavored"). To prevail, respondents must demonstrate a
substantial risk that application of the provision will lead to the
suppression of speech. See Broadrick, supra, at 615.
Respondents argue that the provision is a paradigmatic example
of viewpoint discrimination because it rejects any artistic speech
that either fails to respect mainstream values or offends standards
of decency. The premise of respondents' claim is that § 954(d)(1)
constrains the agency's ability to fund certain categories of
artistic expression. The NEA, however, reads the provision as
merely hortatory, and contends that it stops well short of an
absolute restriction. Section 954(d)(1) adds "considerations" to
the grant-making process; it does not preclude awards to projects
that might be deemed "indecent" or "disrespectful," nor place
conditions on grants, or even specify that those factors must be
given 581 any particular weight in reviewing an application. Indeed, the
agency asserts that it has adequately implemented § 954(d)(1)
merely by ensuring the representation of various backgrounds and
points of view on the advisory panels that analyze grant
applications. See Declaration of Randolph McAusland, Deputy
Chairman for Programs at the NEA, reprinted in App. 79 (stating
that the NEA implements the provision "by ensuring that the peer
review panels represent a variety of geographical areas, aesthetic
views, professions, areas of expertise, races and ethnic groups,
and gender, and include a lay person"). We do not decide whether
the NEA's view-that the formulation of diverse advisory panels is
sufficient to comply with Congress' command-is in fact a reasonable
reading of the statute. It is clear, however, that the text of §
954(d)(1) imposes no categorical requirement. The advisory language
stands in sharp contrast to congressional efforts to prohibit the
funding of certain classes of speech. When Congress has in fact
intended to affirmatively constrain the NEA's grant-making
authority, it has done so in no uncertain terms. See § 954(d)(2)
("[O]bscenity is without artistic merit, is not protected speech,
and shall not be funded").
Furthermore, like the plain language of § 954(d), the political
context surrounding the adoption of the "decency and respect"
clause is inconsistent with respondents' assertion that the
provision compels the NEA to deny funding on the basis of viewpoint
discriminatory criteria. The legislation was a bipartisan proposal
introduced as a counterweight to amendments aimed at eliminating
the NEA's funding or substantially constraining its grant-making
authority. See, e. g., 136 Congo Rec. 28626, 28632,
28634 (1990). The Independent Commission had cautioned Congress
against the adoption of distinct viewpoint-based standards for
funding, and the Commission's report suggests that "additional
criteria for selection, if any, should be incorporated as part of
the selection process (perhaps as part of a definition of 'artistic
excel- 582 lence'), rather than isolated and treated as exogenous
considerations." Report to Congress 89. In keeping with that
recommendation, the criteria in § 954(d)(1) inform the assessment
of artistic merit, but Congress declined to disallow any particular
viewpoints. As the sponsors of § 954(d)(1) noted in urging
rejection of the Rohrabacher Amendment: "[I]f we start down that
road of prohibiting categories of expression, categories which are
indeed constitutionally protected speech, where do we end? Where
one Member's aversions end, others with different sensibilities and
with different values begin." 136 Congo Rec. 28624 (statement of
Rep. Coleman); see also id., at 28663 (statement of Rep. Williams)
(arguing that the Rohrabacher Amendment would prevent the funding
of Jasper Johns' flag series, The Merchant of Venice, Chorus Line,
Birth of a Nation, and the Grapes of Wrath). In contrast, before
the vote on § 954(d)(1), one of its sponsors stated: "If we have
done one important thing in this amendment, it is this. We have
maintained the integrity of freedom of expression in the United
States." Id., at 28674.
That § 954(d)(1) admonishes the NEA merely to take "decency and
respect" into consideration and that the legislation was aimed at
reforming procedures rather than precluding speech undercut
respondents' argument that the provision inevitably will be
utilized as a tool for invidious viewpoint discrimination. In cases
where we have struck down legislation as facially unconstitutional,
the dangers were both more evident and more substantial. In R.
A. v: v. St. Paul, 505 U. S. 377 (1992), for
example, we invalidated on its face a municipal ordinance that
defined as a criminal offense the placement of a symbol on public
or private property" 'which one knows or has reasonable grounds to
know arouses anger, alarm or resentment in others on the basis of
race, color, creed, religion or gender.'" See id., at 380. That
provision set forth a clear penalty, proscribed views on particular
"disfavored subjects," id., at 391, and suppressed "distinctive
idea[s], conveyed by a distinctive message," id., at 393. 583 In contrast, the "decency and respect" criteria do not silence
speakers by expressly "threaten[ing] censorship of ideas." See
ibid. Thus, we do not perceive a realistic danger that § 954(d)(1)
will compromise First Amendment values. As respondents' own
arguments demonstrate, the considerations that the provision
introduces, by their nature, do not engender the kind of directed
viewpoint discrimination that would prompt this Court to invalidate
a statute on its face. Respondents assert, for example, that "[o]ne
would be hard-pressed to find two people in the United States who
could agree on what the 'diverse beliefs and values of the American
public' are, much less on whether a particular work of art
'respects' them"; and they claim that" '[d]ecency' is likely to
mean something very different to a septegenarian in Tuscaloosa and
a teenager in Las Vegas." Brief for Respondents 41. The NEA
likewise views the considerations enumerated in § 954(d)(1) as
susceptible to multiple interpretations. See Department of the
Interior and Related Agencies Appropriations for 1992, Hearing
before the Subcommittee on Interior and Related Agencies of the
House Committee on Appropriations, 102d Cong., 1st Sess., 234
(1991) (testimony of John Frohnmayer) ("[N]o one individual is wise
enough to be able to consider general standards of decency and the
diverse values and beliefs of the American people all by him or
herself. These are group decisions"). Accordingly, the provision
does not introduce considerations that, in practice, would
effectively preclude or punish the expression of particular views.
Indeed, one could hardly anticipate how "decency" or "respect"
would bear on grant applications in categories such as funding for
symphony orchestras.
Respondents' claim that the provision is facially
unconstitutional may be reduced to the argument that the criteria
in § 954(d)(1) are sufficiently subjective that the agency could
utilize them to engage in viewpoint discrimination. Given the
varied interpretations of the criteria and the vague ex- 584 hortation to "take them into consideration," it seems unlikely
that this provision will introduce any greater element of
selectivity than the determination of "artistic excellence" itself.
And we are reluctant, in any event, to invalidate legislation "on
the basis of its hypothetical application to situations not before
the Court." FCC v. Pacifica Foundation, 438 U. S. 726 , 743
(1978).
The NEA's enabling statute contemplates a number of indisputably
constitutional applications for both the "decency" prong of §
954(d)(1) and its reference to "respect for the diverse beliefs and
values of the American public." Educational programs are central to
the NEA's mission. See § 951(9) ("Americans should receive in
school, background and preparation in the arts and humanities"); §
954(c)(5) (listing "projects and productions that will encourage
public knowledge, education, understanding, and appreciation of the
arts" among the NEA's funding priorities); National Endowment for
the Arts, FY 1999 Application Guidelines 18-19 (describing
"Education & Access" category); Brief for Twentysix Arts,
Broadcast, Library, Museum and Publishing Amici Curiae 5, n.
2 (citing NEA Strategic Plan FY 1997-FY 2002, which identifies
children's festivals and museums, art education, at-risk youth
projects, and artists in schools as examples of the NEA's
activities). And it is well established that "decency" is a
permissible factor where "educational suitability" motivates its
consideration. Board of Ed., Island Trees Union Free School
Dist. No. 26 v. Pico, 457 U. S. 853 , 871
(1982); see also Bethel School Dist. No . .1,03 v. Fraser, 478 U. S. 675, 683 (1986) ("Surely it is a highly
appropriate function of public school education to prohibit the use
of vulgar and offensive terms in public discourse").
Permissible applications of the mandate to consider "respect for
the diverse beliefs and values of the American public" are also
apparent. In setting forth the purposes of the NEA, Congress
explained that "[i]t is vital to a democracy to honor and preserve
its multicultural artistic heritage." 585 § 951(10). The agency expressly takes diversity into account,
giving special consideration to "projects and productions ... that
reach, or reflect the culture of, a minority, inner city, rural, or
tribal community," § 954(c)(4), as well as projects that generally
emphasize "cultural diversity," § 954(c)(1). Respondents do not
contend that the criteria in § 954(d)(1) are impermissibly applied
when they may be justified, as the statute contemplates, with
respect to a project's intended audience.
We recognize, of course, that reference to these permissible
applications would not alone be sufficient to sustain the statute
against respondents' First Amendment challenge. But neither are we
persuaded that, in other applications, the language of § 954(d)(1)
itself will give rise to the suppression of protected expression.
Any content-based considerations that may be taken into account in
the grant-making process are a consequence of the nature of arts
funding. The NEA has limited resources, and it must deny the
majority of the grant applications that it receives, including many
that propose "artistically excellent" projects. The agency may
decide to fund particular projects for a wide variety of reasons,
"such as the technical proficiency of the artist, the creativity of
the work, the anticipated public interest in or appreciation of the
work, the work's contemporary relevance, its educational value, its
suitability for or appeal to special audiences (such as children or
the disabled), its service to a rural or isolated community, or
even simply that the work could increase public knowledge of an art
form." Brief for Petitioners 32. As the dissent below noted, it
would be "impossible to have a highly selective grant program
without denying money to a large amount of constitutionally
protected expression." 100 F. 3d, at 685 (opinion of Kleinfeld,
J.). The "very assumption" of the NEA is that grants will be
awarded according to the "artistic worth of competing applicants,"
and absolute neutrality is simply "inconceivable." Advo- 586 cates for the Arts v. Thomson, 532 F.2d
792 , 795-796 (CA1), cert. denied, 429 U. S. 894
(1976).
Respondents' reliance on our decision in Rosenberger v. Rector and Visitors of Univ. of Va., 515 U. S. 819 (1995), is
therefore misplaced. In Rosenberger, a public university
declined to authorize disbursements from its Student Activities
Fund to finance the printing of a Christian student newspaper. We
held that by subsidizing the Student Activities Fund, the
University had created a limited public forum, from which it
impermissibly excluded all publications with religious editorial
viewpoints. Id., at 837. Although the scarcity of NEA
funding does not distinguish this case from Rosenberger, see id., at 835, the competitive process according to which the
grants are allocated does. In the context of arts funding, in
contrast to many other subsidies, the Government does not
indiscriminately "encourage a diversity of views from private
speakers," id., at 834. The NEA's mandate is to make esthetic
judgments, and the inherently content-based "excellence" threshold
for NEA support sets it apart from the subsidy at issue in Rosenberger-which was available to all student organizations
that were" 'related to the educational purpose of the University,'"
id., at 824-and from comparably objective decisions on allocating
public benefits, such as access to a school auditorium or a
municipal theater, see Lamb's Chapel v. Center Moriches
Union Free School Dist., 508 U. S. 384 , 386
(1993); Southeastern Promotions, Ltd. v. Conrad, 420 U. S. 546 ,
555 (1975), or the second class mailing privileges available to
"'all newspapers and other periodical publications,'" see Hannegan v. Esquire, Inc., 327 U. S. 146 , 148, n. 1
(1946).
Respondents do not allege discrimination in any particular
funding decision. (In fact, after filing suit to challenge §
954(d)(1), two of the individual respondents received NEA grants.
See 4 Record, Doc. No. 57, Exh. 35 (Sept. 30, 1991, letters from
the NEA informing respondents Hughes and Miller that they had been
awarded Solo Performance The- 587 ater Artist Fellowships).) Thus, we have no occasion here to
address an as-applied challenge in a situation where the denial of
a grant may be shown to be the product of invidious viewpoint
discrimination. If the NEA were to leverage its power to award
subsidies on the basis of subjective criteria into a penalty on
disfavored viewpoints, then we would confront a different case. We
have stated that, even in the provision of subsidies, the
Government may not "ai[m] at the suppression of dangerous ideas," Regan v. Taxation with Representation of Wash., 461 U. S. 540 ,
550 (1983) (internal quotation marks omitted), and if a subsidy
were "manipulated" to have a "coercive effect," then relief could
be appropriate. See Arkansas Writers' Project, Inc. v. Ragland, 481 U. S. 221, 237 (1987) (SCALIA, J., dissenting);
see also Leathers v. Medlock, 499 U. S. 439 , 447 (1991)
("[D]ifferential taxation of First Amendment speakers is
constitutionally suspect when it threatens to suppress the
expression of particular ideas or viewpoints"). In addition, as the
NEA itself concedes, a more pressing constitutional question would
arise if Government funding resulted in the imposition of a
disproportionate burden calculated to drive "certain ideas or
viewpoints from the marketplace." Simon & Schuster,
Inc. v. Members of N. Y. State Crime Victims Bd., 502 U. S. 105 ,
116 (1991); see Brief for Petitioners 38, n. 12. Unless § 954(d)(1)
is applied in a manner that raises concern about the suppression of
disfavored viewpoints, however, we uphold the constitutionality of
the provision. Cf. Red Lion Broadcasting Co. v. FCC, 395 U. S. 367 ,
396 (1969) ("[WJe will not now pass upon the constitutionality of
these regulations by envisioning the most extreme applications
conceivable, but will deal with those problems if and when they
arise" (citation omitted)).
B
Finally, although the First Amendment certainly has application
in the subsidy context, we note that the Government may allocate
competitive funding according to criteria 588 that would be impermissible were direct regulation of speech or
a criminal penalty at stake. So long as legislation does not
infringe on other constitutionally protected rights, Congress has
wide latitude to set spending priorities. See Regan, supra, at 549. In the 1990 amendments that incorporated § 954(d)(1),
Congress modified the declaration of purpose in the NEA's enabling
Act to provide that arts funding should "contribute to public
support and confidence in the use of taxpayer funds," and that
"[p]ublic funds ... must ultimately serve public purposes the
Congress defines." § 951(5). And as we held in Rust, Congress may "selectively fund a program to encourage certain
activities it believes to be in the public interest, without at the
same time funding an alternative program which seeks to deal with
the problem in another way." 500 U. S., at 193. In doing so, "the
Government has not discriminated on the basis of viewpoint; it has
merely chosen to fund one activity to the exclusion of the other." Ibid.; see also Maher v. Roe, 432 U. S. 464 , 475 (1977)
("There is a basic difference between direct state interference
with a protected activity and state encouragement of an alternative
activity consonant with legislative policy").
III
The lower courts also erred in invalidating § 954(d)(1) as
unconstitutionally vague. Under the First and Fifth Amendments,
speakers are protected from arbitrary and discriminatory
enforcement of vague standards. See NAACP v. Button, 371 U. S. 415 ,
432-433 (1963). The terms of the provision are undeniably opaque,
and if they appeared in a criminal statute or regulatory scheme,
they could raise substantial vagueness concerns. It is unlikely,
however, that speakers will be compelled to steer too far clear of
any "forbidden area" in the context of grants of this nature. Cf. Board of Airport Comm'rs of Los Angeles v. Jews for
Jesus, Inc., 482
U. S. 569 , 574 (1987) (facially invalidating a flat ban 589 on any "First Amendment" activities in an airport); Hoffman
Estates v. Flipside, Hoffman Estates, Inc., 455 U. S. 489 , 499 (1982)
("prohibitory and stigmatizing effect" of a "quasicriminal"
ordinance relevant to the vagueness analysis); Grayned v. City of Rockford, 408 U. S., at 108 (requiring clear lines
between "lawful and unlawful" conduct). We recognize, as a
practical matter, that artists may conform their speech to what
they believe to be the decisionmaking criteria in order to acquire
funding. See Statement of Charlotte Murphy, Executive Director of
NAAO, reprinted in App. 2122. But when the Government is acting as
patron rather than as sovereign, the consequences of imprecision
are not constitutionally severe.
In the context of selective subsidies, it is not always feasible
for Congress to legislate with clarity. Indeed, if this statute is
unconstitutionally vague, then so too are all Government programs
awarding scholarships and grants on the basis of subjective
criteria such as "excellence." See, e. g., 2 U. S. C. § 802
(establishing the Congressional Award Program to "promote
initiative, achievement, and excellence among youths in the areas
of public service, personal development, and physical and
expedition fitness"); 20 U. S. C. § 956(c)(1) (providing funding to
the National Endowment for the Humanities to promote "progress and
scholarship in the humanities"); § 1134h(a) (authorizing the
Secretary of Education to award fellowships to "students of
superior ability selected on the basis of demonstrated achievement
and exceptional promise"); 22 U. S. C. § 2452(a) (authorizing the
award of Fulbright grants to "strengthen international cooperative
relations"); 42 U. S. C. § 7382c (authorizing the Secretary of
Energy to recognize teachers for "excellence in mathematics or
science education"). To accept respondents' vagueness argument
would be to call into question the constitutionality of these
valuable Government programs and countless others like them. 590 Section 954(d)(1) merely adds some imprecise considerations to
an already subjective selection process. It does not, on its face,
impermissibly infringe on First or Fifth Amendment rights.
Accordingly, the judgment of the Court of Appeals is reversed, and
the case is remanded for further proceedings consistent with this
opinion.
It is so ordered.
JUSTICE SCALIA, with whom JUSTICE THOMAS joins, concurring in
the judgment.
"The operation was a success, but the patient died."
What such a procedure is to medicine, the Court's opinion in
this case is to law. It sustains the constitutionality of 20 U. S.
C. § 954(d)(1) by gutting it. The most avid congressional opponents
of the provision could not have asked for more. I write separately
because, unlike the Court, I think that § 954(d)(1) must be
evaluated as written, rather than as distorted by the agency it was
meant to control. By its terms, it establishes content- and
viewpoint-based criteria upon which grant applications are to be
evaluated. And that is perfectly constitutional.
I
THE STATUTE MEANS WHAT IT SAYS
Section 954(d)(1) provides: "No payment shall be made under this section except upon
application therefor which is submitted to the National Endowment
for the Arts in accordance with regulations issued and procedures
established by the Chairperson. In establishing such regulations
and procedures, the Chairperson shall ensure that- "(1) artistic excellence and artistic merit are the criteria by
which applications are judged, taking into consideration general
standards of decency and respect for the diverse beliefs and values
of the American public." 591 The phrase "taking into consideration general standards of
decency and respect for the diverse beliefs and values of the
American public" is what my grammar-school teacher would have
condemned as a dangling modifier: There is no noun to which the
participle is attached (unless one jumps out of paragraph (1) to
press "Chairperson" into service). Even so, it is clear enough that
the phrase is meant to apply to those who do the judging. The
application reviewers must take into account "general standards of
decency" and "respect for the diverse beliefs and values of the
American public" when evaluating artistic excellence and merit. One
can regard this as either suggesting that decency and respect are
elements of what Congress regards as artistic excellence and merit,
or as suggesting that decency and respect are factors to be taken
into account in addition to artistic excellence and merit.
But either way, it is entirely, 100% clear that decency and respect
are to be taken into account in evaluating applications.
This is so apparent that I am at a loss to understand what the
Court has in mind (other than the gutting of the statute) when it
speculates that the statute is merely "advisory." Ante, at
581. General standards of decency and respect for Americans'
beliefs and values must (for the statute says that the
Chairperson "shall ensure" this result) be taken into account, see, e. g., American Heritage Dictionary 402 (3d ed. 1992)
("consider ... [t]o take into account; bear in mind"), in
evaluating all applications. This does not mean that those factors
must always be dispositive, but it does mean that they must
always be considered. The method of compliance proposed by the
National Endowment for the Arts (NEA)selecting diverse review
panels of artists and nonartists that reflect a wide range of
geographic and cultural perspectives-is so obviously inadequate
that it insults the intelligence. A diverse panel membership
increases the odds that, if and when the panel takes the
factors into account, it will reach an accurate assessment of what
they demand. But it 592 in no way increases the odds that the panel will take the
factors into consideration-much less ensures that the panel
will do so, which is the Chairperson's duty under the statute.
Moreover, the NEA's fanciful reading of § 954(d)(1) would make it
wholly superfluous. Section 959(c) already requires the Chairperson
to "issue regulations and establish procedures ... to ensure that
all panels are composed, to the extent practicable, of individuals
reflecting ... diverse artistic and cultural points of view."
The statute requires the decency and respect factors to be
considered in evaluating all applications-not, for example,
just those applications relating to educational programs, ante, at 584, or intended for a particular audience, ante, at 585. Just as it would violate the statute to apply
the artistic excellence and merit requirements to only select
categories of applications, it would violate the statute to apply
the decency and respect factors less than universally. A reviewer
may, of course, give varying weight to the factors depending on the
context, and in some categories of cases (such as the Court's
example of funding for symphony orchestras, ante, at 583)
the factors may rarely if ever affect the outcome; but § 954(d)(1)
requires the factors to be considered in every case.
I agree with the Court that § 954(d)(1) "imposes no categorical
requirement," ante, at 581, in the sense that it does not
require the denial of all applications that violate general
standards of decency or exhibit disrespect for the diverse beliefs
and values of Americans. Cf. § 954(d)(2) ("[O]bscenity ... shall
not be funded"). But the factors need not be conclusive to be
discriminatory. To the extent a particular applicant exhibits
disrespect for the diverse beliefs and values of the American
public or fails to comport with general standards of decency, the
likelihood that he will receive a grant diminishes. In other words,
the presence of the "tak[e] into consideration" clause "cannot be
regarded as mere surplusage; it means something," Potter v. United 593 States, 155
U. S. 438 , 446 (1894). And the "something" is that the
decisionmaker, all else being equal, will favor applications that
display decency and respect, and disfavor applications that do
not.
This unquestionably constitutes viewpoint discrimination.1 That
conclusion is not altered by the fact that the statute does not
"compe[l]" the denial of funding, ante, at 581, any more
than a provision imposing a five-point handicap on all black
applicants for civil service jobs is saved from being race
discrimination by the fact that it does not compel the rejection of
black applicants. If viewpoint discrimination in this context is
unconstitutional (a point I shall address anon), the law is invalid
unless there are some situations in which the decency and respect
factors do not constitute viewpoint discrimination. And
there is none. The applicant who displays "decency," that is,
"[c]onformity to prevailing standards of propriety or modesty,"
American Heritage Dictionary, at 483 (def. 2), and the applicant
who displays "respect," that is, "deferential regard," for the
diverse beliefs and values of the American people, id., at
1536 (def. 1), will always have an edge over an applicant
who displays the opposite. And finally, the conclusion of viewpoint
discrimination is not affected by the fact that what constitutes
"'decency''' or "'the diverse values and beliefs of the American
people'" is difficult to pin down, ante, at 583-any more
than a civil service preference in favor of those who display
"Republican-Party values" would be rendered nondiscriminatory by
the fact that there is plenty of room for argument as to what
Republican-Party values might be.
1 If there is any uncertainty on the point, it relates only to
the adjective, which is not at issue in the current discussion.
That is, one might argue that the decency and respect factors
constitute content discrimination rather than viewpoint discrimination, which would render them easier to
uphold. Since I believe this statute must be upheld in either
event, I pass over this conundrum and assume the worst. 594 The "political context surrounding the adoption of the 'decency
and respect' clause," which the Court discusses at some length, ante, at 581, does not change its meaning or affect its
constitutionality. All that is proved by the various statements
that the Court quotes from the Report of the Independent Commission
and the floor debates is (1) that the provision was not meant
categorically to exclude any particular viewpoint (which I have
conceded, and which is plain from the text), and (2) that the
language was not meant to do anything that is unconstitutional.
That in no way propels the Court's leap to the countertextual
conclusion that the provision was merely "aimed at reforming
procedures," and cannot be "utilized as a tool for invidious
viewpoint discrimination," ante, at 582. It is evident in
the legislative history that § 954(d)(1) was prompted by, and
directed at, the public funding of such offensive productions as
Serrano's "Piss Christ," the portrayal of a crucifix immersed in
urine, and Mapplethorpe's show of lurid homoerotic photographs.
Thus, even if one strays beyond the plain text it is perfectly
clear that the statute was meant to disfavor-that is, to
discriminate against-such productions. Not to ban their funding
absolutely, to be sure (though as I shall discuss, that also would
not have been unconstitutional), but to make their funding more
difficult.
More fundamentally, of course, all this legislative history has
no valid claim upon our attention at all. It is a virtual certainty
that very few of the Members of Congress who voted for this
language both (1) knew of, and (2) agreed with, the various
statements that the Court has culled from the Report of the
Independent Commission and the floor debate (probably conducted on
an almost empty floor). And it is wholly irrelevant that the
statute was a "bipartisan proposal introduced as a counterweight"
to an alternative proposal that would directly restrict funding on
the basis of viewpoint. See ante, at 581-582. We do not
judge statutes as 595 if we are surveying the scene of an accident; each one is
reviewed, not on the basis of how much worse it could have been,
but on the basis of what it says. See United States v. Estate of Romani, 523 U. S. 519, 535 (1998) (SCALIA, J.,
concurring in part and concurring in judgment). It matters not
whether this enactment was the product of the most partisan
alignment in history or whether, upon its passage, the Members all
linked arms and sang, "The more we get together, the happier we'll
be." It is "not consonant with our scheme of government for a court
to inquire into the motives of legislators." Tenney v. Brandhove, 341
U. S. 367 , 377 (1951). The law at issue in this case is to be
found in the text of § 954(d)(1), which passed both Houses and was
signed by the President, U. S. Const., Art. I, § 7. And that law
unquestionably disfavors-discriminates against-indecency and
disrespect for the diverse beliefs and values of the American
people. I turn, then, to whether such viewpoint discrimination
violates the Constitution.
II
WHAT THE STATUTE SAYS Is CONSTITUTIONAL
The Court devotes so much of its opinion to explaining why this
statute means something other than what it says that it neglects to
cite the constitutional text governing our analysis. The First
Amendment reads: "Congress shall make no law ... abridging the freedom of speech." U. S. Const., Amdt. 1 (emphasis added). To
abridge is "to contract, to diminish; to deprive of." T. Sheridan,
A Complete Dictionary of the English Language (6th ed. 1796). With
the enactment of § 954(d)(1), Congress did not abridge the
speech of those who disdain the beliefs and values of the American
public, nor did it abridge indecent speech. Those who wish
to create indecent and disrespectful art are as unconstrained now
as they were before the enactment of this statute. Avant-garde
artistes such as respondents remain 596 entirely free to epater les bourgeois;2 they are merely
deprived of the additional satisfaction of having the bourgeoisie
taxed to pay for it. It is preposterous to equate the denial of
taxpayer subsidy with measures" '''aimed at the suppression of dangerous ideas."'" Regan v. Taxation with
Representation of Wash., 461 U. S. 540 , 550 (1983)
(emphasis added) (quoting Cammarano v. United States, 358 U. S. 498 ,
513 (1959), in turn quoting Speiser v. Randall, 357 U. S. 513 ,
519 (1958)). "The reason that denial of participation in a tax
exemption or other subsidy scheme does not necessarily 'infringe' a
fundamental right is that-unlike direct restriction or
prohibition-such a denial does not, as a general rule, have any
significant coercive effect." Arkansas Writers' Project,
Inc. v. Ragland, 481 U. S. 221 , 237 (1987)
(SCALIA, J., dissenting).
One might contend, I suppose, that a threat of rejection by the
only available source of free money would constitute coercion and
hence "abridgment" within the meaning of the First Amendment. Cf. Norwood v. Harrison, 413 U. S. 455 , 465
(1973). I would not agree with such a contention, which would make
the NEA the mandatory patron of all art too
2Which they do quite well. The oeuvres d'art for which
the four individual plaintiffs in this case sought funding have
been described as follows:
"Finley's controversial show, 'We Keep Our Victims Ready,'
contains three segments. In the second segment, Finley visually
recounts a sexual assault by stripping to the waist and smearing
chocolate on her breasts and by using profanity to describe the
assault. Holly Hughes' monologue 'World Without End' is a somewhat
graphic recollection of the artist's realization of her lesbianism
and reminiscence of her mother's sexuality. John Fleck, in his
stage performance 'Blessed Are All the Little Fishes,' confronts
alcoholism and Catholicism. During the course of the performance,
Fleck appears dressed as a mermaid, urinates on the stage and
creates an altar out of a toilet bowl by putting a photograph of
Jesus Christ on the lid. Tim Miller derives his performance 'Some
Golden States' from childhood experiences, from his life as a
homosexual, and from the constant threat of AIDS. Miller uses
vegetables in his performances to represent sexual symbols." Note,
48 Wash. & Lee L. Rev. 1545, 1546, n. 2 (1991) (citations
omitted). 597 indecent, too disrespectful, or even too kitsch to
attract private support. But even if one accepts the contention, it
would have no application here. The NEA is far from the sole source
of funding for art-even indecent, disrespectful, or just plain bad
art. Accordingly, the Government may earmark NEA funds for projects
it deems to be in the public interest without thereby abridging
speech. Regan v. Taxation with Representation of Wash.,
supra, at 549.
Section 954(d)(1) is no more discriminatory, and no less
constitutional, than virtually every other piece of funding
legislation enacted by Congress. "The Government can, without
violating the Constitution, selectively fund a program to encourage
certain activities it believes to be in the public interest,
without at the same time funding an alternative program .... " Rust v. Sullivan, 500 U. S. 173 , 193
(1991). As we noted in Rust, when Congress chose to
establish the National Endowment for Democracy it was not
constitutionally required to fund programs encouraging competing
philosophies of government-an example of funding discrimination
that cuts much closer than this one to the core of political speech which is the primary concern of the First Amendment. See
id., at 194. It takes a particularly high degree of chutzpah for
the NEA to contradict this proposition, since the agency itself
discriminates-and is required by law to discriminate-in favor of
artistic (as opposed to scientific, or political, or theological)
expression. Not all the common folk, or even all great minds, for
that matter, think that is a good idea. In 1800, when John Marshall
told John Adams that a recent immigration of Frenchmen would
include talented artists, "Adams denounced all Frenchmen, but most
especially 'schoolmasters, painters, poets, &C.' He warned
Marshall that the fine arts were like germs that infected healthy
constitutions." J. Ellis, After the Revolution:
Profiles of Early American Culture 36 (1979). Surely the NEA
itself is nothing less than an institutionalized discrimination
against that point of view. Nonetheless, it is consti- 598 tutional, as is the congressional determination to favor decency
and respect for beliefs and values over the opposite because such
favoritism does not "abridge" anyone's freedom of speech.
Respondents, relying on Rosenberger v. Rector and
Visitors of Univ. of Va., 515 U. S. 819 , 833
(1995), argue that viewpoint-based discrimination is impermissible
unless the government is the speaker or the government is
"disburs[ing] public funds to private entities to convey a
governmental message." Ibid. It is impossible to imagine why
that should be so; one would think that directly involving the
government itself in the viewpoint discrimination (if it is
unconstitutional) would make the situation even worse. Respondents
are mistaken. It is the very business of government to favor and
disfavor points of view on (in modern times, at least) innumerable
subjects-which is the main reason we have decided to elect those
who run the government, rather than save money by making their
posts hereditary. And it makes not a bit of difference, insofar as
either common sense or the Constitution is concerned, whether these
officials further their (and, in a democracy, our) favored point of
view by achieving it directly (having government-employed artists
paint pictures, for example, or government-employed doctors perform
abortions); or by advocating it officially (establishing an Office
of Art Appreciation, for example, or an Office of Voluntary
Population Control); or by giving money to others who achieve or
advocate it (funding private art classes, for example, or Planned
Parenthood).3 None of this has anything to do with abridging
anyone's speech. Rosenberger, as the Court explains, ante, at 586, found the view-
3 I suppose it would be unconstitutional for the government to
give money to an organization devoted to the promotion of
candidates nominated by the Republican Party-but it would be just
as unconstitutional for the government itself to promote candidates
nominated by the Republican Party, and I do not think that that
unconstitutionality has anything to do with the First
Amendment. 599 point discrimination unconstitutional, not because funding of
"private" speech was involved, but because the government had
established a limited public forum-to which the NEA's granting of
highly selective (if not highly discriminating) awards bears no
resemblance.
The nub of the difference between me and the Court is that I
regard the distinction between "abridging" speech and funding it as
a fundamental divide, on this side of which the First Amendment is
inapplicable. The Court, by contrast, seems to believe that the
First Amendment, despite its words, has some ineffable effect upon
funding, imposing constraints of an indeterminate nature which it
announces (without troubling to enunciate any particular test) are
not violated by the statute here-or, more accurately, are not
violated by the quite different, emasculated statute that it
imagines. "[T]he Government," it says, "may allocate competitive
funding according to criteria that would be impermissible were
direct regulation of speech or a criminal penalty at stake," ante, at 587-588. The Government, I think, may
allocate both competitive and noncompetitive funding ad
libitum, insofar as the First Amendment is concerned.
Finally, what is true of the First Amendment is also true of the
constitutional rule against vague legislation: it has no
application to funding. Insofar as it bears upon First Amendment
concerns, the vagueness doctrine addresses the problems that arise
from government regulation of expressive conduct, see Grayned v. City of Rockford, 408 U. S. 104 , 108-109
(1972), not government grant programs. In the former context,
vagueness produces an abridgment of lawful speech; in the latter it
produces, at worst, a waste of money. I cannot refrain from
observing, however, that if the vagueness doctrine were applicable, the agency charged with making grants under a statutory
standard of "artistic excellence"-and which has itself thought that
standard met by everything from the playing of Beethoven to a
depiction of 600 a crucifix immersed in urine-would be of more dubious
constitutional validity than the "decency" and "respect"
limitations that respondents (who demand to be judged on the same
strict standard of "artistic excellence") have the humorlessness to
call too vague.
***
In its laudatory description of the accomplishments of the NEA, ante, at 574, the Court notes with satisfaction that "only a
handful of the agency's roughly 100,000 awards have generated
formal complaints," ibid. The Congress that felt it
necessary to enact § 954(d)(1) evidently thought it much more noteworthy that any money exacted from American
taxpayers had been used to produce a crucifix immersed in urine or
a display of homoerotic photographs. It is no secret that the
provision was prompted by, and directed at, the funding of such
offensive productions. Instead of banning the funding of such
productions absolutely, which I think would have been entirely
constitutional, Congress took the lesser step of requiring them to
be disfavored in the evaluation of grant applications. The Court's
opinion today renders even that lesser step a nullity. For that
reason, I concur only in the judgment.
JUSTICE SOUTER, dissenting.
The question here is whether the italicized segment of this
statute is unconstitutional on its face: "[A]rtistic excellence and
artistic merit are the criteria by which applications [for grants
from the National Endowment for the Arts (NEA)] are judged, taking into consideration general standards of decency and
respect for the diverse beliefs and values of the American
public." 20 U. S. C. § 954(d) (emphasis added). It is.
The decency and respect proviso mandates viewpointbased
decisions in the disbursement of Government subsidies, and the
Government has wholly failed to explain why the statute should be
afforded an exemption from the funda- 601 mental rule of the First Amendment that viewpoint discrimination
in the exercise of public authority over expressive activity is
unconstitutional. The Court's conclusions that the proviso is not
viewpoint based, that it is not a regulation, and that the NEA may
permissibly engage in viewpoint-based discrimination, are all
patently mistaken. Nor may the question raised be answered in the
Government's favor on the assumption that some constitutional
applications of the statute are enough to satisfy the demand of
facial constitutionality, leaving claims of the proviso's obvious
invalidity to be dealt with later in response to challenges of
specific applications of the discriminatory standards. This
assumption is irreconcilable with our longstanding and sensible
doctrine of facial overbreadth, applicable to claims brought under
the First Amendment's speech clause. I respectfully dissent.
I
"If there is a bedrock principle underlying the First Amendment,
it is that the government may not prohibit the expression of an
idea simply because society finds the idea itself offensive or
disagreeable." Texas v. Johnson, 491 U. S. 397 , 414
(1989). "[A]bove all else, the First Amendment means that
government has no power to restrict expression because of its
message [or] its ideas," Police Dept. of Chicago v. Mosley, 408 U.
S. 92 , 95 (1972), which is to say that "[t]he principle of
viewpoint neutrality ... underlies the First Amendment," Bose
Corp. v. Consumers Union of United States, Inc., 466 U. S. 485 ,
505 (1984). Because this principle applies not only to affirmative
suppression of speech, but also to disqualification for government
favors, Congress is generally not permitted to pivot discrimination
against otherwise protected speech on the offensiveness or
unacceptability of the views it expresses. See, e. g.,
Rosenberger v. Rector and Visitors of Univ. of Va., 515 U. S. 819 (1995) (public university's student activities funds may not be
disbursed on viewpoint-based terms); Lamb's Chapel v. Center Moriches 602 Union Free School Dist., 508 U. S. 384 (1993)
(after-hours access to public school property may not be withheld
on the basis of viewpoint); Leathers v. Medlock, 499 U. S. 439 ,
447 (1991) ("[DJifferential taxation of First Amendment speakers is
constitutionally suspect when it threatens to suppress the
expression of particular ideas or viewpoints"); Pacific Gas & Elec. Co. v. Public Util. Comm'n of Cal., 475 U. S. 1 (1986)
(government-mandated access to public utility's billing envelopes
must not be viewpoint based); Members of City Council of Los
Angeles v. Taxpayers for Vincent, 466 U. S. 789 , 804 (1984)
("[T]he First Amendment forbids the government to regulate speech
in ways that favor some viewpoints or ideas at the expense of
others").
It goes without saying that artistic expression lies within this
First Amendment protection. See, e. g., Hurley v. Irish-American Gay, Lesbian and Bisexual Group of Boston,
Inc., 515 U. S.
557 , 569 (1995) (remarking that examples of painting, music,
and poetry are "unquestionably shielded"); Ward v. Rock
Against Racism, 491 U. S. 781 , 790 (1989)
("Music, as a form of expression and communication, is protected
under the First Amendment"); Schad v. Mount Ephraim, 452 U. S. 61 , 65
(1981) ("Entertainment, as well as political and ideological
speech, is protected; motion pictures, programs broadcast by radio
and television, and live entertainment, such as musical and
dramatic works, fall within the First Amendment guarantee"); Kaplan v. California, 413 U. S. 115 , 119-120
(1973) ("[P]ictures, films, paintings, drawings, and engravings ...
have First Amendment protection"). The constitutional protection of
artistic works turns not on the political significance that may be
attributable to such productions, though they may indeed comment on
the political,l but simply on their expressive character, which
1 Art "may affect public attitudes and behavior in a variety of
ways, ranging from direct espousal of a political or social
doctrine to the subtle shaping of thought which characterizes all
artistic expression." Joseph Burstyn, Inc. v. Wilson, 343 U. S. 495 ,
501 (1952). 603 falls within a spectrum of protected "speech" extending outward
from the core of overtly political declarations. Put differently,
art is entitled to full protection because our "cultural life,"
just like our native politics, "rest[s] upon [the] ideal" of
governmental viewpoint neutrality. Turner Broadcasting System,
Inc. v. FCC, 512 U. S. 622 , 641
(1994).
When called upon to vindicate this ideal, we characteristically
begin by asking "whether the government has adopted a regulation of
speech because of disagreement with the message it conveys. The
government's purpose is the controlling consideration." Ward v. Rock Against Racism, supra, at 791 (citation omitted).
The answer in this case is damning. One need do nothing more than
read the text of the statute to conclude that Congress's purpose in
imposing the decency and respect criteria was to prevent the
funding of art that conveys an offensive message; the decency and
respect provision on its face is quintessentially viewpoint based,
and quotations from the Congressional Record merely confirm the
obvious legislative purpose. In the words of a cosponsor of the
bill that enacted the proviso, "[w]orks which deeply offend the
sensibilities of significant portions of the public ought not to be
supported with public funds." 136 Congo Rec. 28624 (1990).2 Another
supporter of the bill observed that "the Endowment's support for
artists like Robert Mapplethorpe and Andre[s] Serrano has offended
and angered many citizens," behooving "Congress ... to listen to
these complaints about the NEA and make sure that exhibits like
[these] are not funded again." Id., at 28642. Indeed, if
there were any question at all about what Congress had in
2 There is, of course, nothing whatsoever unconstitutional about
this view as a general matter. Congress has no obligation to
support artistic enterprises that many people detest. The First
Amendment speaks up only when Congress decides to participate in
the Nation's artistic life by legal regulation, as it does through
a subsidy scheme like the NEA. If Congress does choose to spend
public funds in this manner, it may not discriminate by viewpoint
in deciding who gets the money. 604 mind, a definitive answer comes in the succinctly accurate
remark of the proviso's author, that the bill "add[s] to the
criteria of artistic excellence and artistic merit, a shell, a
screen, a viewpoint that must be constantly taken into account." Id., at 28631.3
II
In the face of such clear legislative purpose, so plainly
expressed, the Court has its work cut out for it in seeking a
3 On the subject of legislative history and purpose, it is
disturbing that the Court upholds § 954(d) in part because the
statute was drafted in hope of avoiding constitutional objections,
with some Members of Congress proclaiming its constitutionality on
the congressional floor. See ante, at 581582. Like the
Court, I assume that many Members of Congress believed the bill to
be constitutional. Indeed, Members of Congress must take an oath or
affirmation to support the Constitution, see U. S. Const., Art. VI,
cl. 3, and we should presume in every case that Congress believed
its statute to be consistent with the constitutional commands, see, e. g., United States v. X-Citement Video,
Inc., 513 U. S.
64 , 73 (1994) ("[W]e do not impute to Congress an intent to
pass legislation that is inconsistent with the Constitution"); Yates v. United States, 354 U. S. 298 , 319
(1957). But courts cannot allow a legislature's conc1usory belief
in constitutionality, however sincere, to trump incontrovertible
unconstitutionality, for "[i]t is emphatically the province and
duty of the judicial department to say what the law is." Marbury v. Madison, 1 Cranch 137, 177 (1803).
I recognize, as the court explains, ante, at 581, that
the amendment adding the decency and respect proviso was a
bipartisan counterweight to more severe alternatives, and that some
Members of Congress may have voted for it simply because it seemed
the least among various evils. See, e. g., 136 Congo Rec.
28670 (1990) ("I am not happy with all aspects of the
Williams-Coleman substitute .... It ... contains language
concerning standards of decency that I find very troubling. But I
applaud Mr. WILLIAMS for his efforts in achieving this compromise
under very difficult circumstances .... I support the
Williams-Coleman substitute"). Perhaps the proviso was the mildest
alternative available, but that simply proves that the bipartisan
push to reauthorize the NEA could succeed only by including at
least some viewpoint-based limitations. An appreciation of
alternatives does not alter the fact that Congress passed decency
and respect restrictions, and it did so knowing and intending that
those restrictions would prevent future controversies stemming from
the NEA's funding of inflammatory art projects, by declaring the
inflammatory to be disfavored for funding. 605 constitutional reading of the statute. See Edward J. DeBartolo
Corp. v. Florida Gulf Coast Building & Constr. Trades Council, 485 U. S. 568 ,
575 (1988).
A
The Court says, first, that because the phrase "general
standards of decency and respect for the diverse beliefs and values
of the American public" is imprecise and capable of multiple
interpretations, "the considerations that the provision introduces,
by their nature, do not engender the kind of directed viewpoint
discrimination that would prompt this Court to invalidate a statute
on its face." Ante, at 583. Unquestioned case law, however,
is clearly to the contrary.
"Sexual expression which is indecent but not obscene is
protected by the First Amendment," Sable Communications of Cal.,
Inc. v. FCC, 492 U. S. 115 , 126
(1989), and except when protecting children from exposure to
indecent material, see FCC v. Pacifica Foundation, 438 U. S. 726 (1978), the First Amendment has never been read to allow the
government to rove around imposing general standards of decency,
see, e. g., Reno v. American Civil Liberties Union, 521 U. S. 844 (1997) (striking down on its face a statute that regulated
"indecency" on the Internet). Because "the normal definition of
'indecent' ... refers to nonconformance with accepted standards of
morality," FCC v. Pacifica Foundation, supra, at 740,
restrictions turning on decency, especially those couched in terms
of "general standards of decency," are quintessentially viewpoint
based: they require discrimination on the basis of conformity with
mainstream mores. The Government's contrary suggestion that the
NEA's decency standards restrict only the "form, mode, or style" of
artistic expression, not the underlying viewpoint or message, Brief
for Petitioners 39-41, may be a tempting abstraction (and one not
lacking in support, cf. Bolger v. Youngs Drug Products
Corp., 463 U. S.
60 , 83-84 (1983) (STEVENS, J., concurring in judgment)). But
here it suffices to realize that "form, mode, or style" are not
subject to ab- 606 straction from artistic viewpoint, and to quote from an opinion
just two years old: "In artistic ... settings, indecency may have
strong communicative content, protesting conventional norms or
giving an edge to a work by conveying otherwise inexpressible
emotions .... Indecency often is inseparable from the ideas and
viewpoints conveyed, or separable only with loss of truth or
expressive power." Denver Area Ed. Telecommunications
Consortium, Inc. v. FCC, 518 U. S. 727 ,805 (1996)
(KENNEDY, J., joined by GINSBURG, J., concurring) (citation and
internal quotation marks omitted); see also Cohen v. California, 403
U. S. 15 , 26 (1971) ("[WJe cannot indulge the facile assumption
that one can forbid particular words without also running a
substantial risk of suppressing ideas in the process"). "[T]he
inextricability of indecency from expression," Denver Area Ed.
Telecommunications Consortium, supra, at 805, is beyond dispute
in a certain amount of entirely lawful artistic enterprise. Starve
the mode, starve the message.
Just as self-evidently, a statute disfavoring speech that fails
to respect America's "diverse beliefs and values" is the very model
of viewpoint discrimination; it penalizes any view disrespectful to
any belief or value espoused by someone in the American populace.
Boiled down to its practical essence, the limitation obviously
means that art that disrespects the ideology, opinions, or
convictions of a significant segment of the American public is to
be disfavored, whereas art that reinforces those values is not.
After all, the whole point of the proviso was to make sure that
works like Serrano's ostensibly blasphemous portrayal of Jesus
would not be funded, see supra, at 603, while a reverent
treatment, conventionally respectful of Christian sensibilities,
would not run afoul of the law. Nothing could be more viewpoint
based than that. Cf. Rosenberger, 515 U. S., at 831 (a
statute targeting a "prohibited perspective, not the general
subject matter" of religion is viewpoint based); United
States v. Eichman, 496 U. S. 310 , 317 (1990)
(striking down anti-flag- 607 burning statute because it impermissibly prohibited speech that
was "disrespectful" of the flag). The fact that the statute
disfavors art insufficiently respectful of America's "diverse"
beliefs and values alters this conclusion not one whit: the First
Amendment does not validate the ambition to disqualify many
disrespectful viewpoints instead of merely one. See Rosenberger,
supra, at 831-832.
B
Another alternative for avoiding unconstitutionality that the
Court appears to regard with some favor is the Government's
argument that the NEA may comply with § 954(d) merely by populating
the advisory panels that analyze grant applications with members of
diverse backgrounds. See ante, at 577, 581. Would that it
were so easy; this asserted implementation of the law fails even to
"reflec[t] a plausible construction of the plain language of the
statute." Rust v. Sullivan, 500 U. S. 173 , 184
(1991).
The Government notes that § 954(d) actually provides that "[i]n
establishing ... regulations and procedures, the Chairperson [of
the NEA] shall ensure that (1) artistic excellence and artistic
merit are the criteria by which applications are judged, taking
into consideration general standards of decency and respect for the
diverse beliefs and values of the American public." According to
the Government, this language requires decency and respect to be
considered not in judging applications, but in making regulations.
If, then, the Chairperson takes decency and respect into
consideration through regulations ensuring diverse panels, the
statute is satisfied. But it would take a great act of will to find
any plausibility in this reading. The reference to considering
decency and respect occurs in the subparagraph speaking to the
"criteria by which applications are judged," not in the preamble
directing the Chairperson to adopt regulations; it is in judging
applications that decency and respect are most obviously to be
considered. It is no surprise, then, that the 608 Government's reading is directly contradicted by the legislative
history. According to the provision's author, the decency and
respect proviso "mandates that in the awarding of funds, in the
award process itself, general standards of decency must be
accorded." 136 Congo Rec. 28672 (1990). Or, as the cosponsor of the
bill put it, "the decisions of artistic excellence must take into
consideration general standards of decency and respect for the
diverse beliefs and values of the American public." Id., at
28624.
The Government offers a variant of this argument in suggesting
that even if the NEA must take decency and respect into account in
the active review of applications, it may satisfy the statute by
doing so in an indirect way through the natural behavior of
diversely constituted panels. This, indeed, has apparently been the
position of the Chairperson of the NEA since shortly after the
legislation was first passed. But the problems with this position
are obvious. First, it defies the statute's plain language to
suggest that the NEA complies with the law merely by allowing
decency and respect to have their way through the subconscious
inclinations of panel members. "[T]aking into consideration" is a
conscious activity. See Webster's New International Dictionary 2570
(2d ed. 1949) (defining "take into consideration" as "[t]o make
allowance in judging for"); id., at 569 (defining "consideration"
as the "[a]ct or process of considering; continuous and careful
thought; examination; deliberation; attention"); id., at 568
(defining "consider" as "to think on with care ... to bear in
mind"). Second, even assuming that diverse panel composition would
produce a sufficient response to the proviso, that would merely
mean that selection for decency and respect would occur
derivatively through the inclinations of the panel members, instead
of directly through the intentional application of the criteria; at
the end of the day, the proviso would still serve its purpose to
screen out offending artistic works, and it would still be
unconstitutional. Finally, a less obvious but equally dispositive
re- 609 sponse is that reading the statute as a mandate that may be
satisfied merely by selecting diverse panels renders § 954(d)(1)
essentially redundant of § 959(c), which provides that the review
panels must comprise "individuals reflecting a wide geographic,
ethnic, and minority representation as well as individuals
reflecting diverse artistic and cultural points of view." Statutory
interpretations that "render superfluous other provisions in the
same enactment" are strongly disfavored. Freytag v. Commissioner, 501 U. S. 868 , 877 (1991)
(internal quotation marks omitted).
C
A third try at avoiding constitutional problems is the Court's
disclaimer of any constitutional issue here because "[§] 954(d)(1)
adds 'considerations' to the grant-making process; it does not
preclude awards to projects that might be deemed 'indecent' or
'disrespectful,' nor place conditions on grants, or even specify
that those factors must be given any particular weight in reviewing
an application." Ante, at 580-581. Since "§ 954(d)(1)
admonishes the NEA merely to take 'decency and respect' into
consideration," ante, at 582, not to make funding decisions
specifically on those grounds, the Court sees no constitutional
difficulty.
That is not a fair reading. Just as the statute cannot be read
as anything but viewpoint based, or as requiring nothing more than
diverse review panels, it cannot be read as tolerating awards to
spread indecency or disrespect, so long as the review panel, the
National Council on the Arts, and the Chairperson have given some
thought to the offending qualities and decided to underwrite them
anyway. That, after all, is presumably just what prompted the
congressional outrage in the first place, and there was nothing
naive about the Representative who said he voted for the bill
because it does "not tolerate wasting Federal funds for sexually
explicit photographs [or] sacrilegious works." 136 Congo Rec. 28676
(1990). 610 But even if I found the Court's view of "consideration"
plausible, that would make no difference at all on the question of
constitutionality. What if the statute required a panel to apply
criteria "taking into consideration the centrality of Christianity
to the American cultural experience," or "taking into consideration
whether the artist is a communist," or "taking into consideration
the political message conveyed by the art," or even "taking into
consideration the superiority of the white race"? Would the Court
hold these considerations facially constitutional, merely because
the statute had no requirement to give them any particular, much
less controlling, weight? I assume not. In such instances, the
Court would hold that the First Amendment bars the government from
considering viewpoint when it decides whether to subsidize private
speech, and a statute that mandates the consideration of viewpoint
is quite obviously unconstitutional. Cf. Dawson v. Delaware, 503
U. S. 159 , 167 (1992) (holding that the First Amendment forbids
reliance on a defendant's abstract beliefs at sentencing, even if
they are considered as one factor among many); Ozonoff v. Berzak, 744 F.2d
224 , 233 (CA1 1984) (Breyer, J.) (holding that an
Executive Order which provided that a person's political
associations "may be considered" in determining security
clearance violated the First Amendment). Section 954(d)(1) is just
such a statute.
III
A second basic strand in the Court's treatment of today's
question, see ante, at 585-587, and the heart of JUSTICE
SCALIA'S, see ante, at 595-599, in effect assume that
whether or not the statute mandates viewpoint discrimination, there
is no constitutional issue here because government art subsidies
fall within a zone of activity free from First Amendment
restraints. The Government calls attention to the roles of
government-as-speaker and government-as-buyer, in which the
government is of course entitled to engage in view- 611 point discrimination: if the Food and Drug Administration
launches an advertising campaign on the subject of smoking, it may
condemn the habit without also having to show a cowboy taking a
puff on the opposite page; 4 and if the Secretary of Defense wishes
to buy a portrait to decorate the Pentagon, he is free to prefer
George Washington over George the Third.5
The Government freely admits, however, that it neither speaks
through the expression subsidized by the NEA,6 nor buys anything
for itself with its NEA grants. On the contrary, believing that
"[t]he arts ... reflect the high place accorded by the American
people to the nation's rich cultural heritage," § 951(6), and that
"[i]t is vital to a democracy ... to provide financial assistance
to its artists and the organizations that support their work," §
951(10), the Government acts as a patron, financially underwriting
the production of art by private artists and impresarios for
independent consumption. Accordingly, the Government would have us
liberate government-as-patron from First Amendment strictures not
by placing it squarely within the categories of government-as-buyer
or government-as-speaker,
4 See Rust v. Sullivan, 500 U. S. 173 , 194 (1991)
("When Congress established a National Endowment for Democracy to
encourage other countries to adopt democratic principles, 22 U. S.
C. § 4411 (b), it was not constitutionally required to fund a
program to encourage competing lines of political philosophy such
as communism and fascism").
5 On proposing the Public Works Art Project (PWAP), the New Deal
program that hired artists to decorate public buildings, President
Roosevelt allegedly remarked: "I can't have a lot of young
enthusiasts painting Lenin's head on the Justice Building." Quoted
in Mankin, Federal Arts Patronage in the New Deal, in America's
Commitment to Culture: Government and the Arts 77 (K. Mulcahy &
M. Wyszomirski eds. 1995). He was buying, and was free to take his
choice.
6 Here, the "communicative element inherent in the very act of
funding itself," Rosenberger v. Rector and Visitors of
Univ. of Va., 515
U. S. 819 , 892-893, n. 11 (1995) (SOUTER, J., dissenting), is
an endorsement of the importance of the arts collectively, not an
endorsement of the individual message espoused in a given work of
art. 612 but by recogmzmg a new category by analogy to those accepted
ones. The analogy is, however, a very poor fit, and this patronage
falls embarrassingly on the wrong side of the line between
government-as-buyer or -speaker and government-as- regulator-of-
private-speech.
The division is reflected quite clearly in our precedents.
Drawing on the notion of government-as-speaker, we held in Rust v. Sullivan, 500 U. S., at 194, that the
Government was entitled to appropriate public funds for the
promotion of particular choices among alternatives offered by
health and social service providers (e. g., family planning with,
and without, resort to abortion). When the government promotes a
particular governmental program, "it is entitled to define the
limits of that program," and to dictate the viewpoint expressed by
speakers who are paid to participate in it. Ibid. 7 But we
added the important qualifying language that "[t]his is not to
suggest that funding by the Government, even when coupled with the
freedom of the fund recipients to speak outside the scope of the
Government-funded project, is invariably sufficient to justify
Government control over the content of expression." Id., at
199. Indeed, outside of the contexts of government-as-buyer and
government-as-speaker, we have held time and time again that
Congress may not "discriminate invidiously in its subsidies in such
a way as to aim at the suppression of ... ideas." Regan v. Taxation with Representation of Wash., 461 U. S. 540 , 548 (1983)
(internal quotation marks and brackets omitted); see also Lamb's
Chapel, 508 U. S., at 394 (when the government subsidizes
private speech, it may not "favor some viewpoints or ideas at the
expense of others"); Hannegan v. Esquire, Inc., 327
7 In Rust, "the government did not create a program to
encourage private speech but instead used private speakers to
transmit specific information pertaining to its own program. We
recognized that when the government appropriates public funds to
promote a particular policy of its own it is entitled to say what
it wishes." Rosenberger, supra, at 833 (citing Rust,
supra, at 194). 613 u. S. 146, 149 (1946) (the Postmaster General may not deny
subsidies to certain periodicals on the ground that they are
"'morally improper and not for the public welfare and the public
good' ").
Our most thorough statement of these principles is found in the
recent case of Rosenberger v. Rector and Visitors of
Univ. of Va., 515
U. S. 819 (1995), which held that the University of Virginia
could not discriminate on viewpoint in underwriting the speech of
student-run publications. We recognized that the government may act
on the basis of viewpoint "when the State is the speaker" or when
the State "disburses public funds to private entities to convey a
governmental message." Id., at 833. But we explained that
the government may not act on viewpoint when it "does not itself
speak or subsidize transmittal of a message it favors but instead
expends funds to encourage a diversity of views from private
speakers." Id., at 834. When the government acts as patron,
subsidizing the expression of others, it may not prefer one
lawfully stated view over another. Rosenberger controls here. The NEA, like the student
activities fund in Rosenberger, is a subsidy scheme created
to encourage expression of a diversity of views from private
speakers. Congress brought the NEA into being to help all Americans
"achieve a better understanding of the past, a better analysis of
the present, and a better view of the future." § 951(3). The NEA's
purpose is to "support new ideas" and "to help create and sustain
... a climate encouraging freedom of thought, imagination, and
inquiry." §§ 951(10), (7); see also S. Rep. No. 300, 89th Cong.,
1st Sess., 4 (1965) ("[T]he intent of this act should be the
encouragement of free inquiry and expression"); H. R. Rep. No.
99-274, p. 13 (1985) (Committee Report accompanying bill to
reauthorize and amend the NEA's governing statute) ("As the
Preamble of the act directs, the Endowment['s] programs should be
open and richly diverse, reflecting the ferment of ideas which has
always made this Nation strong and free"). Given this 614 congressional choice to sustain freedom of expression,
Ro senberger teaches that the First Amendment forbids
decisions based on viewpoint popularity. So long as Congress
chooses to subsidize expressive endeavors at large, it has no
business requiring the NEA to turn down funding applications of
artists and exhibitors who devote their "freedom of thought,
imagination, and inquiry" to defying our tastes, our beliefs, or
our values. It may not use the NEA's purse to "suppres[s] ...
dangerous ideas." Regan v. Taxation with Representation
of Wash., supra, at 548 (internal quotation marks omitted).
The Court says otherwise, claiming to distinguish Rosenberger on the ground that the student activities funds
in that case were generally available to most applicants, whereas
NEA funds are disbursed selectively and competitively to a choice
few. Ante, at 586. But the Court in Rosenberger anticipated and specifically rejected just this distinction when it
held in no uncertain terms that "[t]he government cannot justify
viewpoint discrimination among private speakers on the economic
fact of scarcity." 515 U. S., at 835.8 Scarce money demands
choices, of course, but choices "on some acceptable [viewpoint]
neutral principle," like artistic excellence and artistic merit; 9
"nothing in our decision[s] in-
8 The Court's attempt to avoid Rosenberger by describing
NEA funding in terms of competition, not scarcity, will not work.
Competition implies scarcity, without which there is no exclusive
prize to compete for; the Court's "competition" is merely a
surrogate for "scarcity."
9While criteria of "artistic excellence and artistic merit" may
raise intractable issues about the identification of artistic
worth, and could no doubt be used covertly to filter out unwanted
ideas, there is nothing inherently viewpoint discriminatory about
such merit-based criteria. We have noted before that an esthetic
government goal is perfectly legitimate. See Metromedia,
Inc. v. San Diego, 453 U. S. 490 , 507-508
(1981) (plurality opinion). Decency and respect, on the other hand,
are inherently and facially viewpoint based, and serve no
legitimate and permissible end. The Court's assertion that the mere
fact that grants must be awarded according to artistic merit
precludes "absolute neutrality" on the part of the 615 dicate[s] that scarcity would give the State the right to
exercise viewpoint discrimination that is otherwise impermissible." Ibid.; see also Arkansas Ed. Television Comm'n v. Forbes, 523 U.
S. 666 , 676 (1998) (scarcity of air time does not justify
viewpoint-based exclusion of candidates from a debate on public
television; neutral selection criteria must be employed). If the
student activities fund at issue in Rosenberger had awarded
competitive, merit-based grants to only 50%, or even 5%, of the
applicants, on the basis of "journalistic merit taking into
consideration the message of the newspaper," it is obvious beyond
peradventure that the Court would not have come out differently,
leaving the University free to refuse funding after considering a
publication's Christian perspective.10
A word should be said, finally, about a proposed alternative to
this failed analogy. As the Solicitor General put it
NEA, ante, at 585, is therefore misdirected. It is not to
the point that the Government necessarily makes choices among
competing applications, or even that its judgments about artistic
quality may be branded as subjective to some greater or lesser
degree; the question here is whether the Government may apply
patently viewpoint-based criteria in making those choices.
10 JUSTICE SCALIA suggests that Rosenberger turned not on
the distinction between government-as-speaker and
government-as-facilitator-ofprivate-speech, but rather on the fact
that "the government had established a limited public forum." Ante, at 599. Leaving aside the proper application of forum
analysis to the NEA and its projects, I cannot agree that the
holding of Rosenberger turned on characterizing its
metaphorical forum as public in some degree. Like this case, Rosenberger involved viewpoint discrimination, and we have
made it clear that such discrimination is impermissible in all
forums, even nonpublic ones, Cornelius v. NAACP Legal
Defense & Ed. Fund, Inc., 473 U. S. 788 ,806 (1985),
where, by definition, the government has not made public property
generally available to facilitate private speech, Perry Ed.
Assn. v. Perry Local Educators' Assn., 460 U. S. 37 ,46 (1983)
(defining a nonpublic forum as "[p]ublic property which is not by
tradition or designation a forum for public communication").
Accordingly, Rosenberger's brief allusion to forum analysis
was in no way determinative of the Court's holding. 616 at oral argument, "there is something unique ... about the
Government funding of the arts for First Amendment purposes." Tr.
of Oral Arg. 27. However different the governmental patron may be
from the governmental speaker or buyer, the argument goes,
patronage is also singularly different from traditional regulation
of speech, and the limitations placed on the latter would be out of
place when applied to viewpoint discrimination in distributing
patronage. To this, there are two answers. The first, again, is Rosenberger, which forecloses any claim that the NEA and the
First Amendment issues that arise under it are somehow unique. But
even if we had no Rosenberger, and even if I thought the
NEA's program of patronage was truly singular, I would not hesitate
to reject the Government's plea to recognize a new, categorical
patronage exemption from the requirement of viewpoint neutrality. I
would reject it for the simple reason that the Government has
offered nothing to justify recognition of a new exempt
category.
The question of who has the burden to justify a categorical
exemption has never been explicitly addressed by this Court,
despite our recognition of the speaker and buyer categories in the
past. The answer is nonetheless obvious in a recent statement by
the Court synthesizing a host of cases on viewpoint discrimination.
"The First Amendment presumptively places this sort of
discrimination beyond the power of the government." Simon & Schuster, Inc. v. Members of N. Y. State
Crime Victims Bd., 502 U. S. 105 , 116
(1991). Because it takes something to defeat a presumption, the
burden is necessarily on the Government to justify a new exception
to the fundamental rules that give life to the First Amendment. It
is up to the Government to explain why a sphere of governmental
participation in the arts (unique or not) should be treated as
outside traditional First Amendment limits. The Government has not
carried this burden here, or even squarely faced it. 617 IV
Although I, like the Court, recognize that "facial challenges to
legislation are generally disfavored," FW/PBS, Inc. v. Dallas, 493 U.
S. 215 , 223 (1990), the proviso is the type of statute that
most obviously lends itself to such an attack. The NEA does not
offer a list of reasons when it denies a grant application, and an
artist or exhibitor whose subject raises a hint of controversy can
never know for sure whether the decency and respect criteria played
a part in any decision by the NEA to deny funding. Hence, the most
that we could hope for in waiting for an as-applied challenge would
be (a) a plaintiff whose rejected proposal raised some risk of
offense and was not aimed at exhibition in a forum in which decency
and respect might serve as permissible selection criteria, or (b) a
plaintiff who sought funding for a project that had been sanitized
to avoid rejection. But no one has denied here that the
institutional plaintiff, the National Association of Artists'
Organizations (NAAO), has representative standing on behalf of some
such potential plaintiffs. See App. 21-25 (declaration of NAAO's
Executive Director, listing examples of the potentially
objectionable works produced by several member organizations). We
would therefore gain nothing at all by dismissing this case and
requiring those individuals or groups to bring essentially the same
suit, restyled as an as-applied challenge raising one of the
possibilities just mentioned.
In entertaining this challenge, the Court finds § 954(d)(1)
constitutional on its face in part because there are "a number of
indisputably constitutional applications" for both the "decency"
and the "respect" criteria, ante, at 584, and it is hard to
imagine "how 'decency' or 'respect' would bear on grant
applications in categories such as funding for symphony
orchestras," ante, at 583. There are circumstances in which
we have rejected facial challenges for similar reasons. "A facial
challenge to a legislative Act is, of course, the most difficult
challenge to mount successfully, since the challenger 618 must establish that no set of circumstances exists under which
the Act would be valid." United States v. Salerno, 481 U. S. 739 ,
745 (1987). But quite apart from any question that might be raised
about that statement as a general rule,l1 it is beyond question, as
the Court freely concedes, that it can have no application here, it
being well settled that the general rule does not limit challenges
brought under the First Amendment's speech clause.
There is an "exception to thee]
[capable-of-constitutionalapplication] rule recognized in our
jurisprudence [for] facial challenge[s] based upon First Amendment
free-speech grounds. We have applied to statutes restricting speech
a so-called 'overbreadth' doctrine, rendering such a statute
invalid in all its applications (i. e., facially invalid) if
it is invalid in any of them." Ada v. Guam Society of
Obstetricians & Gynecologists, 506 U. S. 1011, 1012 (1992)
(SCALIA, J., dissenting from denial of certiorari); 12 see, e.
g., Reno v. American Civil Liberties Union, 521 U. S. 844 (1997)
(striking down decency provision of Communications Decency Act as
facially overbroad); id., at 893-894 (O'CONNOR, J., concurring in
judgment in part and dissenting in part) (declining to apply the
rule of Salerno because the plaintiffs' claim arose under
the First Amendment); Schad v. Mount Ephraim, 452 U.
S., at 66 ("Because appellants' claims are rooted in the First
Amendment, they are entitled to ... raise an overbreadth
challenge") (internal quotation marks omitted); Gooding v. Wilson, 405 U.
S. 518 , 521-522 (1972).13 Thus,
11 Cf., e. g., Planned Parenthood of Southeastern Pa. v. Casey, 505 U.
S. 833 , 895 (1992) (statute restricting abortion will be struck
down if, "in a large fraction of the cases in which [the statute]
is relevant, it will operate as a substantial obstacle to a woman's
choice to undergo an abortion").
12We have, however, recognized that "the overbreadth doctrine
does not apply to commercial speech." Hoffman Estates v. Flipside, Hoffman Estates, Inc., 455 U. S. 489 , 497
(1982).
13 Cf. United States v. Salerno, 481 U. S. 739 , 745 (1987)
("The fact that the Bail Reform Act might operate
unconstitutionally under some conceivable set of circumstances is
insufficient to render it wholly invalid, since 619 we have routinely understood the overbreadth doctrine to apply
where the plaintiff mounts a facial challenge to a law investing
the government with discretion to discriminate on viewpoint when it
parcels out benefits in support of speech. See, e. g., City of
Lakewood v. Plain Dealer Publishing Co., 486 U. S. 750 , 759 (1988)
("[A] facial challenge lies whenever a licensing law gives a
government official or agency substantial power to discriminate
based on the content or viewpoint of speech by suppressing
disfavored speech or disliked speakers"); Forsyth County v. Nationalist Movement, 505 U. S. 123 (1992) (applying
overbreadth doctrine to invalidate on its face an ordinance
allowing for content-based discrimination in the awarding of parade
permits).
To be sure, such a "facial challenge will not succeed unless the
statute is 'substantially' overbroad," New York State Club
Assn., Inc. v. City of New York, 487 U. S. 1 , 11 (1988), by
which we mean that "a law should not be invalidated for overbreadth
unless it reaches a substantial number of impermissible
applications," New York v. Ferber, 458 U. S. 747 , 771
(1982). But that is no impediment to invalidation here. The Court
speculates that the "decency" criterion might permissibly be
applied to applications seeking to create or display art in schools
14 or children's museums, whereas the "respect" criterion might
permissibly be applied to applications
we have not recognized an 'overbreadth' doctrine outside the
limited context of the First Amendment").
14 In placing such emphasis on the potential applicability of
the decency criterion to educational programs, the Court neglects
to point out the existence of § 954a, entitled "[a]ccess to the
arts through support of education," which is concerned specifically
with funding for arts education, especially in elementary and
secondary schools. It seems that the NEA's "mission" to promote
arts education, ante, at 584, is carried out primarily
through § 954a, not § 954. While the decency standard might be
constitutionally permissible when applied to applications for
grants under § 954a, that standard does not appear to be relevant
to such applications at all; the decency and respect provision
appears in § 954(d), which governs grant applications under § 954,
not under § 954a. 620 seeking to create art that celebrates a minority, tribal, rural,
or inner-city culture. But even so, this is certainly a case in
which the challenged statute "reaches a substantial number of
impermissible applications," not one in which the statute's
"legitimate reach dwarfs its arguably impermissible applications." Id., at 771, 773. On the contrary, nothing in the record
suggests that the grant scheme administered under the broad
authorization of the NEA's governing statute, see §§ 951, 954(c),
devotes an overwhelming proportion of its resources to schools and
ethnic commemoration. Since the decency and respect criteria may
not be employed in the very many instances in which the art seeking
a subsidy is neither aimed at children nor meant to celebrate a
particular culture, the statute is facially overbroad. Cf. City of Lakewood, supra, at 766 ("[I]n a host of ... First
Amendment cases we have ... considered on the merits facial
challenges to statutes or policies that embodied discrimination
based on the content or viewpoint of expression, or vested
officials with open-ended discretion that threatened the same, even
where it was assumed that a properly drawn law could have greatly
restricted or prohibited the manner of expression or circulation at
issue"). Accordingly, the Court's observation that there are a
handful of permissible applications of the decency and respect
proviso, even if true, is irrelevant.15
15 The Court seemingly concedes that these isolated
constitutional applications are in fact of little matter. For after
speaking of specific applications that may be valid, the Court goes
on to admit that these "would not alone be sufficient to sustain
the statute." Ante, at 585. The Court nonetheless upholds
the statute because it is not "persuaded that, in other
applications, the language of § 954(d)(1) itself will give rise to
the suppression of protected expression." Ibid. This
conclusion appears to rest on some combination of (a) the Court's
competition rationale as distinguishing Rosenberger and
justifying the discrimination, (b) the Court's reading of the
decency and respect proviso as something other than viewpoint
based, and (c) the Court's treatment of "taking into consideration"
as establishing no firm mandate subject to constitutional scrutiny.
As already explained, 621 The Government takes a different tack, arguing that overbreadth
analysis is out of place in this case because the "prospect for
'chilling' expressive conduct," which forms the basis for the
overbreadth doctrine, see, e. g., Massachusetts v. Oakes, 491 U.
S. 576 , 584 (1989) (plurality opinion of O'CONNOR, J.), "is not
present here." Brief for Petitioners 20-21, n. 5. But that is
simply wrong. We have explained before that the prospect of a
denial of government funding necessarily carries with it the
potential to "chil[l] ... individual thought and expression." Rosenberger, 515 U. S., at 835. In the world of NEA funding,
this is so because the makers or exhibitors of potentially
controversial art will either trim their work to avoid anything
likely to offend, or refrain from seeking NEA funding altogether.
Either way, to whatever extent NEA eligibility defines a national
mainstream, the proviso will tend to create a timid esthetic. And
either way, the proviso's viewpoint discrimination will "chill the
expressive activity of [persons] not before the court." Forsyth
County, supra, at 129. See App. 22-24 (declaration of Charlotte
Murphy, Executive Director of respondent NAAO) (recounting how some
NAAO members have not applied for NEA grants for fear that their
work would be found indecent or disrespectful, while others have
applied but were "chilled in their applications and in the scope of
their projects" by the decency and respect provision). Indeed,
because NEA grants are often matched by funds from private donors,
the constraining impact of § 954(d)(1) is significantly
magnified: "[T]he chilling effect caused by [the NEA's viewpointbased
selection criteria] is exacerbated by the practical realities of
funding in the artistic community. Plainly stated, the NEA occupies
a dominant and influential role in the financial affairs of the art
world in the United however, fair reading of the text and attention to case law
foreclose reliance on any, let alone all, of these arguments. 622 States. Because the NEA provides much of its support with
conditions that require matching or co-funding from private
sources, the NEA's funding involvement in a project necessarily has
a multiplier effect in the competitive market for funding of
artistic endeavors .... [In addition,] most non-federal funding
sources regard the NEA award as an imprimatur that signifies the
recipient's artistic merit and value. NEA grants lend prestige and
legitimacy to projects and are therefore critical to the ability of
artists and companies to attract non-federal funding sources. Grant
applicants rely on the NEA well beyond the dollar value of any
particular grant." Bella Lewitzky Dance Foundation v. Frohnmayer, 754 F. Supp. 774, 783 (CD Cal. 1991) (footnote
and internal quotation marks omitted).16 Since the decency and respect proviso of § 954(d)(1) is
substantially overbroad and carries with it a significant power to
chill artistic production and display, it should be struck down on
its face.17
16 See also, e. g., 131 Congo Rec. 24808 (1985)
("[S]upport from the Endowmen[t] has always represented a 'Good
Housekeeping Seal' of approval which has helped grantees generate
non-Federal dollars for projects and productions").
17 I agree with the Court that § 954(d) is not
unconstitutionally vague.
Any chilling that results from imprecision in the drafting of
standards (such as "artistic excellence and artistic merit") by
which the Government awards scarce grants and scholarships is an
inevitable and permissible consequence of distributing prizes on
the basis of criteria dealing with a subject that defies exactness.
The necessary imprecision of artisticmerit-based criteria justifies
tolerating a degree of vagueness that might be intolerable when
applying the First Amendment to attempts to regulate political
discussion. Cf. Arkansas Ed. Television Comm'n V. Forbes, 523 U.
S. 666 , 694-695 (1998) (STEVENS, J., dissenting). My problem is
not with the chilling that may naturally result from necessarily
open standards; it is with the unacceptable chilling of "dangerous
ideas," Speiser V. Randall, 357 U. S. 513 , 519
(1958), that naturally results from explicitly viewpoint-based
standards. 623 V
The Court does not strike down the proviso, however. Instead, it
preserves the irony of a statutory mandate to deny recognition to
virtually any expression capable of causing offense in any quarter
as the most recent manifestation of a scheme enacted to "create and
sustain ... a climate encouraging freedom of thought, imagination,
and inquiry." § 951(7). | The National Endowment for the Arts (NEA) et al. v. Finley et al.:
**Issue:** Whether a statutory provision directing the NEA Chairperson to consider "general standards of decency and respect for diverse beliefs and values of the American public" when awarding grants violates the First Amendment and is void for vagueness.
**Holding:** The Supreme Court held that the provision, § 954(d)(1), is facially valid and does not inherently interfere with First Amendment rights or violate vagueness principles. The Court found that the NEA's grant-making process was discretionary and that the provision's language was broad and flexible, allowing for a range of viewpoints and expressions.
**Reasoning:** The Court emphasized the NEA's substantial discretion in awarding grants and the absence of a specific mandate to deny funding based on viewpoint or controversial content. It noted that the NEA had not interpreted the provision as a restriction on controversial art and that the provision's language was broad enough to encompass diverse artistic expressions. The Court also rejected the argument that the NEA's dominant role in arts funding heightened First Amendment concerns, finding that artists were free to create and display art regardless of NEA funding.
**Dissent:** Justice Souter disagreed with the majority's conclusion, arguing that the provision's "decency and respect" criterion inherently favored certain viewpoints and disfavored others, thus violating the First Amendment. He also emphasized the NEA's significant influence in the arts funding community, which heightened the potential for chilling artistic expression. |
Free Speech | Pleasant Grove City v. Summum | https://supreme.justia.com/cases/federal/us/555/460/ | OPINION OF THE COURT PLEASANT GROVE CITY V. SUMMUM 555 U. S. ____ (2009) SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES NO. 07-665 PLEASANT GROVE CITY, UTAH, et al., PETITIONERS v. SUMMUM
on writ of certiorari to the united states court of
appeals for the tenth circuit
[February 25, 2009]
Justice Alito delivered the
opinion of the Court.
This case presents the question
whether the Free Speech Clause of the First Amendment entitles a
private group to insist that a municipality permit it to place a
permanent monument in a city park in which other donated monuments
were previously erected. The Court of Appeals held that the
municipality was required to accept the monument because a public
park is a traditional public forum. We conclude, however, that
although a park is a traditional public forum for speeches and
other transitory expressive acts, the display of a permanent
monument in a public park is not a form of expression to which
forum analysis applies. Instead, the placement of a permanent
monument in a public park is best viewed as a form of government
speech and is therefore not subject to scrutiny under the Free
Speech Clause.
I
A
Pioneer Park (or Park) is a 2.5
acre public park located in the Historic District of Pleasant Grove
City (or City) in Utah. The Park currently contains 15 permanent
displays, at least 11 of which were donated by private groups or
individuals. These include an historic granary, a wishing well, the
City’s first fire station, a September 11 monument, and a Ten
Commandments monument donated by the Fraternal Order of Eagles in
1971.
Respondent Summum is a religious
organization founded in 1975 and headquartered in Salt Lake City,
Utah. On two separate occasions in 2003, Summum’s president wrote a
letter to the City’s mayor requesting permission to erect a “stone
monument,” which would contain “the Seven Aphorisms of
SUMMUM”[ Footnote 1 ] and be
similar in size and nature to the Ten Commandments monument. App.
57, 59. The City denied the requests and explained that its
practice was to limit monuments in the Park to those that “either
(1) directly relate to the history of Pleasant Grove, or (2) were
donated by groups with longstanding ties to the Pleasant Grove
community.” Id. , at 61. The following year, the City
passed a resolution putting this policy into writing. The
resolution also mentioned other criteria, such as safety and
esthetics.
In May 2005, respondent’s president again
wrote to the mayor asking to erect a monument, but the letter did
not describe the monument, its historical significance, or Summum’s
connection to the community. The city council rejected this
request.
B
In 2005, respondent filed this
action against the City and various local officials (petitioners),
asserting, among other claims, that petitioners had violated the
Free Speech Clause of the First Amendment by accepting the Ten
Commandments monument but rejecting the proposed Seven Aphorisms
monument. Respondent sought a preliminary injunction directing the
City to permit Summum to erect its monument in Pioneer Park. After
the District Court denied Summum’s preliminary injunction request,
No. 2:05CV00638, 2006 WL 3421838 (D Utah, Nov. 22, 2006),
respondent appealed, pressing solely its free speech claim.
A panel of the Tenth Circuit reversed. 483
F. 3d 1044 (2007). The panel noted that it had previously
found the Ten Commandments monument to be private rather than
government speech. See Summum v. Ogden , 297
F. 3d 995 (2002). Noting that public parks have traditionally
been regarded as public forums, the panel held that the City could
not reject the Seven Aphorisms monument unless it had a compelling
justification that could not be served by more narrowly tailored
means. See 483 F. 3d, at 1054. The panel then concluded that
the exclusion of respondent’s monument was unlikely to survive this
strict scrutiny, and the panel therefore held that the City was
required to erect Summum’s monument immediately.
The Tenth Circuit denied the
City’s petition for rehearing en banc by an equally divided vote.
499 F. 3d 1170 (2007). Judge Lucero dissented, arguing that
the Park was not a traditional public forum for the purpose of
displaying monuments. Id ., at 1171. Judge McConnell also
dissented, contending that the monuments in the Park constitute
government speech. Id ., at 1174.
We granted certiorari, 552 U. S. ___ (2008),
and now reverse.
II
No prior decision of this Court
has addressed the application of the Free Speech Clause to a
government entity’s acceptance of privately donated, permanent
monuments for installation in a public park, and the parties
disagree sharply about the line of precedents that governs this
situation. Petitioners contend that the pertinent cases are those
concerning government speech. Respondent, on the other hand, agrees
with the Court of Appeals panel that the applicable cases are those
that analyze private speech in a public forum. The parties’
fundamental disagreement thus centers on the nature of petitioners’
conduct when they permitted privately donated monuments to be
erected in Pioneer Park. Were petitioners engaging in their own
expressive conduct? Or were they providing a forum for private
speech?
A
If petitioners were engaging in
their own expressive conduct, then the Free Speech Clause has no
application. The Free Speech Clause restricts government regulation
of private speech; it does not regulate government speech. See Johanns v. Livestock Marketing Assn. , 544 U. S. 550 , 553
(2005) (“[T]he Government’s own speech . . . is exempt from First
Amendment scrutiny”); Columbia Broadcasting System, Inc. v. Democratic National Committee, 412 U. S. 94 , 139,
n. 7 (1973) (Stewart, J., concurring) (“Government is not
restrained by the First Amendment from controlling its own
expression”). A government entity has the right to “speak for
itself.” Board of Regents of Univ. of Wis. System v. Southworth , 529 U. S. 217 , 229
(2000). “[I]t is entitled to say what it wishes,” Rosenberger v. Rector and Visitors of Univ. of
Va., 515 U. S.
819 , 833 (1995), and to select the views that it wants to
express. See Rust v. Sullivan , 500 U. S. 173 , 194
(1991); National Endowment for Arts v. Finley , 524 U. S. 569 ,
598 (1998) (Scalia, J., concurring in judgment) (“It is the very
business of government to favor and disfavor points of view”).
Indeed, it is not easy to imagine
how government could function if it lacked this freedom. “If every
citizen were to have a right to insist that no one paid by public
funds express a view with which he disagreed, debate over issues of
great concern to the public would be limited to those in the
private sector, and the process of government as we know it
radically transformed.” Keller v. State Bar of
Cal. , 496 U. S.
1 , 12–13 (1990). See also Johanns , 544 U. S., at 574
(Souter, J., dissenting) (“To govern, government has to say
something, and a First Amendment heckler’s veto of any forced
contribution to raising the government’s voice in the ‘marketplace
of ideas’ would be out of the question” (footnote omitted)).
A government entity may exercise this same
freedom to express its views when it receives assistance from
private sources for the purpose of delivering a
government-controlled message. See id. , at 562 (opinion of
the Court) (where the government controls the message, “it is not
precluded from relying on the government-speech doctrine merely
because it solicits assistance from nongovernmental sources”); Rosenberger , supra , at 833 (a government entity
may “regulate the content of what is or is not expressed … when it
enlists private entities to convey its own message”).
This does not mean that there are no
restraints on government speech. For example, government speech
must comport with the Establishment Clause. The involvement of
public officials in advocacy may be limited by law, regulation, or
practice. And of course, a government entity is ultimately
“accountable to the electorate and the political process for its
advocacy.” Southworth , 529 U. S., at 235. “If the
citizenry objects, newly elected officials later could espouse some
different or contrary position.” Ibid . B While government
speech is not restricted by the Free Speech Clause, the government
does not have a free hand to regulate private speech on government
property. This Court long ago recognized that members of the public
retain strong free speech rights when they venture into public
streets and parks, “which ‘have immemorially been held in trust for
the use of the public and, time out of mind, have been used for
purposes of assembly, communicating thoughts between citizens, and
discussing public questions.’ ” Perry Ed. Assn. v. Perry Local Educators’ Assn. , 460 U. S. 37 , 45 (1983)
(quoting Hague v. Committee for Industrial
Organization , 307 U. S. 496 , 515
(1939) (opinion of Roberts, J.)). In order to preserve this
freedom, government entities are strictly limited in their ability
to regulate private speech in such “traditional public fora.” Cornelius v. NAACP Legal Defense & Ed. Fund,
Inc. , 473 U. S.
788 , 800 (1985). Reasonable time, place, and manner
restrictions are allowed, see Perry Ed. Assn. , supra , at 45, but any restriction based on the content of
the speech must satisfy strict scrutiny, that is, the restriction
must be narrowly tailored to serve a compelling government
interest, see Cornelius , supra , at 800, and
restrictions based on viewpoint are prohibited, see Carey v. Brown , 447 U. S. 455 , 463
(1980). With the concept of
the traditional public forum as a starting point, this Court has
recognized that members of the public have free speech rights on
other types of government property and in certain other government
programs that share essential attributes of a traditional public
forum. We have held that a government entity may create “a
designated public forum” if government property that has not
traditionally been regarded as a public forum is intentionally
opened up for that purpose. See Cornelius , 473 U. S., at
802. Government restrictions on speech in a designated public forum
are subject to the same strict scrutiny as restrictions in a
traditional public forum. Id. , at 800. The Court has also held that a
government entity may create a forum that is limited to use by
certain groups or dedicated solely to the discussion of certain
subjects. Perry Ed. Assn. , supra , at 46,
n. 7. In such a forum, a government entity may impose
restrictions on speech that are reasonable and viewpoint-neutral.
See Good News Club v. Milford Central School , 533 U. S. 98 ,
106–107 (2001). III There may be
situations in which it is difficult to tell whether a government
entity is speaking on its own behalf or is providing a forum for
private speech, but this case does not present such a situation.
Permanent monuments displayed on public property typically
represent government speech. Governments have long
used monuments to speak to the public. Since ancient times, kings,
emperors, and other rulers have erected statues of themselves to
remind their subjects of their authority and power. Triumphal
arches, columns, and other monuments have been built to commemorate
military victories and sacrifices and other events of civic
importance. A monument, by definition, is a structure that is
designed as a means of expression. When a government entity
arranges for the construction of a monument, it does so because it
wishes to convey some thought or instill some feeling in those who
see the structure. Neither the Court of Appeals nor respondent
disputes the obvious proposition that a monument that is
commissioned and financed by a government body for placement on
public land constitutes government speech. Just as government-commissioned
and government-financed monuments speak for the government, so do
privately financed and donated monuments that the government
accepts and displays to the public on government land. It certainly
is not common for property owners to open up their property for the
installation of permanent monuments that convey a message with
which they do not wish to be associated. And because property
owners typically do not permit the construction of such monuments
on their land, persons who observe donated monuments routinely—and
reasonably—interpret them as conveying some message on the property
owner’s behalf. In this context, there is little chance that
observers will fail to appreciate the identity of the speaker. This
is true whether the monument is located on private property or on
public property, such as national, state, or city park
land. We think it is fair to say that
throughout our Nation’s history, the general government practice
with respect to donated monuments has been one of selective
receptivity. A great many of the monuments that adorn the Nation’s
public parks were financed with private funds or donated by private
parties. Sites managed by the National Park Service contain
thousands of privately designed or funded commemorative objects,
including the Statue of Liberty, the Marine Corps War Memorial (the
Iwo Jima monument), and the Vietnam Veterans Memorial. States and
cities likewise have received thousands of donated monuments. See, e.g. , App. to Brief for International Municipal Lawyers
Association as Amicus Curiae 15a–29a (hereinafter IMLA
Brief) (listing examples); Brief for American Legion et al. as Amici Curiae 7, and n. 2 (same). By accepting monuments
that are privately funded or donated, government entities save tax
dollars and are able to acquire monuments that they could not have
afforded to fund on their own. But while government entities
regularly accept privately funded or donated monuments, they have
exercised selectivity. An example discussed by the city of New York
as amicus curiae is illustrative. In the wake of the
controversy generated in 1876 when the city turned down a donated
monument to honor Daniel Webster, the city adopted rules governing
the acceptance of artwork for permanent placement in city parks,
requiring, among other things, that “any proposed gift of art had
to be viewed either in its finished condition or as a model before
acceptance.” Brief for City of New York as Amicus Curiae 4–5 (hereinafter NYC Brief). Across the country, “municipalities
generally exercise editorial control over donated monuments through
prior submission requirements, design input, requested
modifications, written criteria, and legislative approvals of
specific content proposals.” IMLA Brief 21. Public parks are often closely
identified in the public mind with the government unit that owns
the land. City parks—ranging from those in small towns, like
Pioneer Park in Pleasant Grove City, to those in major
metropolises, like Central Park in New York City—commonly play an
important role in defining the identity that a city projects to its
own residents and to the outside world. Accordingly, cities and
other jurisdictions take some care in accepting donated monuments.
Government decisionmakers select the monuments that portray what
they view as appropriate for the place in question, taking into
account such content-based factors as esthetics, history, and local
culture. The monuments that are accepted, therefore, are meant to
convey and have the effect of conveying a government message, and
they thus constitute government speech. IV A In this case, it is
clear that the monuments in Pleasant Grove’s Pioneer Park represent
government speech. Although many of the monuments were not designed
or built by the City and were donated in completed form by private
entities, the City decided to accept those donations and to display
them in the Park. Respondent does not claim that the City ever
opened up the Park for the placement of whatever permanent
monuments might be offered by private donors. Rather, the City has
“effectively controlled” the messages sent by the monuments in the
Park by exercising “final approval authority” over their selection. Johanns , 544 U. S., at 560–561. The City has selected
those monuments that it wants to display for the purpose of
presenting the image of the City that it wishes to project to all
who frequent the Park; it has taken ownership of most of the
monuments in the Park, including the Ten Commandments monument that
is the focus of respondent’s concern; and the City has now
expressly set forth the criteria it will use in making future
selections. B Respondent voices the
legitimate concern that the government speech doctrine not be used
as a subterfuge for favoring certain private speakers over others
based on viewpoint. Respondent’s suggested solution is to require a
government entity accepting a privately donated monument to go
through a formal process of adopting a resolution publicly
embracing “the message” that the monument conveys. See Brief for
Respondent 33–34, 57. We see no reason for
imposing a requirement of this sort. The parks of this country
contain thousands of donated monuments that government entities
have used for their own expressive purposes, usually without
producing the sort of formal documentation that respondent now says
is required to escape Free Speech Clause restrictions. Requiring
all of these jurisdictions to go back and proclaim formally that
they adopt all of these monuments as their own expressive vehicles
would be a pointless exercise that the Constitution does not
mandate. In this case, for example,
although respondent argues that Pleasant Grove City has not
adequately “controll[ed] the message,” id. , at 31, of the
Ten Commandments monument, the City took ownership of that monument
and put it on permanent display in a park that it owns and manages
and that is linked to the City’s identity. All rights previously
possessed by the monument’s donor have been relinquished. The
City’s actions provided a more dramatic form of adoption than the
sort of formal endorsement that respondent would demand,
unmistakably signifying to all Park visitors that the City intends
the monument to speak on its behalf. And the City has made no
effort to abridge the traditional free speech rights—the right to
speak, distribute leaflets, etc.—that may be exercised by
respondent and others in Pioneer Park. What respondent demands, however,
is that the City “adopt” or “embrace” “the message” that it
associates with the monument. Id. , at 33–34, 57.
Respondent seems to think that a monument can convey only one
“message”—which is, presumably, the message intended by the
donor—and that, if a government entity that accepts a monument for
placement on its property does not formally embrace that message, then the government has not engaged in expressive
conduct. This argument fundamentally
misunderstands the way monuments convey meaning. The meaning
conveyed by a monument is generally not a simple one like
“ ‘Beef. It’s What’s for Dinner.’ ” Johanns , supra , at 554. Even when a monument features the written
word, the monument may be intended to be interpreted, and may in
fact be interpreted by different observers, in a variety of ways.
Monuments called to our attention by the briefing in this case
illustrate this phenomenon. What, for example, is “the
message” of the Greco-Roman mosaic of the word “Imagine” that was
donated to New York City’s Central Park in memory of John Lennon?
See NYC Brief 18; App. to id. , at A5. Some observers may
“imagine” the musical contributions that John Lennon would have
made if he had not been killed. Others may think of the lyrics of
the Lennon song that obviously inspired the mosaic and may
“imagine” a world without religion, countries, possessions, greed,
or hunger.[ Footnote
2 ] Or, to take another example, what
is “the message” of the “large bronze statue displaying the word
‘peace’ in many world languages” that is displayed in Fayetteville,
Arkansas?[ Footnote
3 ] These text-based monuments are
almost certain to evoke different thoughts and sentiments in the
minds of different observers, and the effect of monuments that do
not contain text is likely to be even more variable. Consider, for
example, the statue of Pancho Villa that was given to the city of
Tucson, Arizona, in 1981 by the Government of Mexico with,
according to a Tucson publication, “a wry sense of irony.”[ Footnote 4 ] Does this statue
commemorate a “revolutionary leader who advocated for agrarian
reform and the poor” or “a violent bandit”? IMLA Brief
13. Contrary to respondent’s apparent
belief, it frequently is not possible to identify a single
“message” that is conveyed by an object or structure, and
consequently, the thoughts or sentiments expressed by a government
entity that accepts and displays such an object may be quite
different from those of either its creator or its donor.[ Footnote 5 ] By accepting a privately
donated monument and placing it on city property, a city engages in
expressive conduct, but the intended and perceived significance of
that conduct may not coincide with the thinking of the monument’s
donor or creator. Indeed, when a privately donated memorial is
funded by many small donations, the donors themselves may differ in
their interpretation of the monument’s significance.[ Footnote 6 ] By accepting such a monument, a
government entity does not necessarily endorse the specific meaning
that any particular donor sees in the monument. The message that a government
entity conveys by allowing a monument to remain on its property may
also be altered by the subsequent addition of other monuments in
the same vicinity. For example, following controversy over the
original design of the Vietnam Veterans Memorial, a compromise was
reached that called for the nearby addition of a flagstaff and
bronze Three Soldiers statue, which many believed changed the
overall effect of the memorial. See, e.g. , J. Mayo, War
Memorials as Political Landscape: The American Experience and
Beyond 202–203, 205 (1988); K. Hass, Carried to the Wall: American
Memory and the Vietnam Veterans Memorial 15–18 (1998). The “message” conveyed by a
monument may change over time. A study of war memorials found that
“people reinterpret” the meaning of these memorials as “historical
interpretations” and “the society around them changes.” Mayo, supra , at 8–9. A striking example of how the
interpretation of a monument can evolve is provided by one of the
most famous and beloved public monuments in the United States, the
Statue of Liberty. The statue was given to this country by the
Third French Republic to express republican solidarity and
friendship between the two countries. See J. Res. 6, 44th Cong., 2d
Sess. (1877), 19 Stat. 410 (accepting the statue as an “expressive
and felicitous memorial of the sympathy of the citizens of our
sister Republic”). At the inaugural ceremony, President Cleveland
saw the statue as an emblem of international friendship and the
widespread influence of American ideals. See Inauguration of the
Statue of Liberty Enlightening the World 30 (1887). Only later did
the statue come to be viewed as a beacon welcoming immigrants to a
land of freedom. See Public Papers of the Presidents, Ronald
Reagan, Vol. 2, July 3, 1986, pp. 918–919 (1989), Remarks at the
Opening Ceremonies of the Statue of Liberty Centennial Celebration
in New York, New York; J. Higham, The Transformation of the Statue
of Liberty, in Send These To Me 74–80 (rev. ed. 1984). C Respondent and the
Court of Appeals analogize the installation of permanent monuments
in a public park to the delivery of speeches and the holding of
marches and demonstrations, and they thus invoke the rule that a
public park is a traditional public forum for these activities. But
“public forum principles . . . are out of place in the context of
this case.” United States v. American Library Assn.,
Inc. , 539 U. S.
194 , 205 (2003). The forum doctrine has been applied in
situations in which government-owned property or a government
program was capable of accommodating a large number of public
speakers without defeating the essential function of the land or
the program. For example, a park can accommodate many speakers and,
over time, many parades and demonstrations. The Combined Federal
Campaign permits hundreds of groups to solicit donations from
federal employees. See Cornelius , 473 U. S., at 804–805. A
public university’s student activity fund can provide money for
many campus activities. See Rosenberger , 515 U. S., at
825. A public university’s buildings may offer meeting space for
hundreds of student groups. See Widmar v. Vincent , 454 U. S. 263 , 274–275
(1981). A school system’s internal mail facilities can support the
transmission of many messages to and from teachers and school
administrators. See Perry Ed. Assn. , 460 U. S., at 39,
46–47. See also Arkansas Ed. Television Comm’n v. Forbes , 523
U. S. 666 , 680–681 (1998) (noting that allowing any candidate
to participate in a televised political debate would be burdensome
on “logistical grounds” and “would result in less speech, not
more”). By contrast, public
parks can accommodate only a limited number of permanent monuments.
Public parks have been used, “ ‘time out of mind, . . . for
purposes of assembly, communicating thoughts between citizens, and
discussing public questions,’ ” Perry Ed. Assn. , supra , at 45 (quoting Hague , 307 U. S., at 515),
but “one would be hard pressed to find a ‘long tradition’ of
allowing people to permanently occupy public space with any manner
of monuments.” 499 F. 3d, at 1173 (Lucero, J., dissenting from
denial of rehearing en banc). Speakers, no matter how
long-winded, eventually come to the end of their remarks; persons
distributing leaflets and carrying signs at some point tire and go
home; monuments, however, endure. They monopolize the use of the
land on which they stand and interfere permanently with other uses
of public space. A public park, over the years, can provide a
soapbox for a very large number of orators—often, for all who want
to speak—but it is hard to imagine how a public park could be
opened up for the installation of permanent monuments by every
person or group wishing to engage in that form of
expression. Respondent contends that this
issue “can be dealt with through content-neutral time, place and
manner restrictions, including the option of a ban on all
unattended displays.” Brief for Respondent 14. On this view, when
France presented the Statue of Liberty to the United States in
1884, this country had the option of either (a) declining France’s
offer or (b) accepting the gift, but providing a comparable
location in the harbor of New York for other statues of a similar
size and nature ( e.g. , a Statue of Autocracy, if one had
been offered by, say, the German Empire or Imperial
Russia). While respondent and some of its amici deride the fears expressed about the consequences of
the Court of Appeals holding in this case, those concerns are well
founded. If government entities must maintain viewpoint neutrality
in their selection of donated monuments, they must either “brace
themselves for an influx of clutter” or face the pressure to remove
longstanding and cherished monuments. See 499 F. 3d, at 1175
(McConnell, J., dissenting from denial of rehearing en banc). Every
jurisdiction that has accepted a donated war memorial may be asked
to provide equal treatment for a donated monument questioning the
cause for which the veterans fought. New York City, having accepted
a donated statue of one heroic dog (Balto, the sled dog who brought
medicine to Nome, Alaska, during a diphtheria epidemic)[ Footnote 7 ] may be pressed to accept
monuments for other dogs who are claimed to be equally worthy of
commemoration. The obvious truth of the matter is that if public
parks were considered to be traditional public forums for the
purpose of erecting privately donated monuments, most parks would
have little choice but to refuse all such donations. And where the
application of forum analysis would lead almost inexorably to
closing of the forum, it is obvious that forum analysis is out of
place. Respondent compares the present
case to Capitol Square Review and Advisory Bd. v. Pinette , 515 U. S. 753 (1995),
but that case involved a very different situation—a request by a
private group, the Ku Klux Klan, to erect a cross for a period of
16 days on public property that had been opened up for similar
temporary displays, including a Christmas tree and a menorah. See id ., at 758. Although some public parks can accommodate
and may be made generally available for temporary private displays,
the same is rarely true for permanent monuments. To be sure, there are limited
circumstances in which the forum doctrine might properly be applied
to a permanent monument—for example, if a town created a monument
on which all of its residents (or all those meeting some other
criterion) could place the name of a person to be honored or some
other private message. But as a general matter, forum analysis
simply does not apply to the installation of permanent monuments on
public property. V In sum, we hold that
the City’s decision to accept certain privately donated monuments
while rejecting respondent’s is best viewed as a form of government
speech. As a result, the City’s decision is not subject to the Free
Speech Clause, and the Court of Appeals erred in holding otherwise.
We therefore reverse. It is so ordered. Footnote 1 Respondent’s brief describes the
church and the Seven Aphorisms as follows: “The Summum church incorporates
elements of Gnostic Christianity, teaching that spiritual knowledge
is experiential and that through devotion comes revelation, which
‘modifies human perceptions, and transfigures the individual.’ See The Teachings of Summum are the Teachings of Gnostic
Christianity, http://www.summum.us/philosophy/ gnosticism.shtml
(visited Aug. 15, 2008). “Central to Summum religious
belief and practice are the Seven Principles of Creation (the
“Seven Aphorisms”). According to Summum doctrine, the Seven
Aphorisms were inscribed on the original tablets handed down by God
to Moses on Mount Sinai… . Because Moses believed that
the Israelites were not ready to receive the Aphorisms, he shared
them only with a select group of people. In the Summum Exodus
account, Moses then destroyed the original tablets, traveled back
to Mount Sinai, and returned with a second set of tablets con-
taining the Ten Commandments. See The Aphorisms of Summum
and the Ten Commandments, http://www.summum.us/philosophy/
tencommandments.shtml (visited Aug. 15, 2008).” Brief for
Respondent 1–2. Footnote 2 The lyrics are as follows: “Imagine there’s no heaven It’s easy if you try No hell below us Above us only sky Imagine all the people Living for today... “Imagine there’s no countries It isn’t hard to do Nothing to kill or die for And no religion too Imagine all the people Living life in peace... “You may say I’m a dreamer But I’m not the only one I hope someday you’ll join us And the world will be as one “Imagine no possessions I wonder if you can No need for greed or hunger A brotherhood of man Imagine all the people Sharing all the world... “You may say I’m a dreamer But I’m not the only one I hope someday you’ll join us And the world will live as one.” J. Lennon, Imagine,
on Imagine (Apple Records 1971). Footnote 3 See IMLA Brief 6–7. Footnote 4 The Presidio Trail: A Historical
Walking Tour of Downtown Tucson, online at
http://www.visittucson.org/includes/media/docs/
DowntownTour.pdf. Footnote 5 Museum collections illustrate this phenomenon.
Museums display works of art that express many different
sentiments, and the significance of a donated work of art to its
creator or donor may differ markedly from a museum’s reasons for
accepting and displaying the work. For example, a painting of a
religious scene may have been commissioned and painted to express
religious thoughts and feelings. Even if the painting is donated to
the museum by a patron who shares those thoughts and feelings, it
does not follow that the museum, by displaying the painting,
intends to convey or is perceived as conveying the same
“message.” Footnote 6 For example, the Vietnam Veterans
Memorial Fund is a private organization that obtained funding from
over 650,000 donors for the construction of the memorial itself.
These donors expressed a wide range of personal sentiments in
contributing money for the memorial. See, e.g. , J. Scruggs
& J. Swerdlow, To Heal a Nation: The Vietnam Veterans Memorial
23–28, 159 (1985). Footnote 7 See NYC Brief 2; App. to Brief
for American Catholic Lawyers Association as Amicus Curiae 1a–10. 555 U. S. ____ (2009) PLEASANT GROVE CITY V. SUMMUM 555 U. S. ____ (2009) SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES NO. 07-665 PLEASANT GROVE CITY, UTAH, et al., PETITIONERS v. SUMMUM
on writ of certiorari to the united states court of
appeals for the tenth circuit
[February 25, 2009]
Justice Stevens, with whom
Justice Ginsburg joins, concurring.
This case involves a property
owner’s rejection of an offer to place a permanent display on its
land. While I join the Court’s persuasive opinion, I think the
reasons justifying the city’s refusal would have been equally valid
if its acceptance of the monument, instead of being characterized
as “government speech,” had merely been deemed an implicit
endorsement of the donor’s message. See Capitol Square Review
and Advisory Bd. v. Pinette , 515 U. S. 753 , 801–802
(1995) (Stevens, J., dissenting).
To date, our decisions relying on the recently
minted government speech doctrine to uphold government action have
been few and, in my view, of doubtful merit. See, e.g. , Garcetti v. Ceballos , 547 U. S. 410 (2006); Johanns v. Livestock Marketing Assn. , 544 U. S. 550 (2005); Rust v. Sullivan , 500 U. S. 173 (1991).
The Court’s opinion in this case signals no expansion of that
doctrine. And by joining the Court’s opinion, I do not mean to
indicate agreement with our earlier decisions. Unlike other
decisions relying on the government speech doctrine, our decision
in this case excuses no retaliation for, or coercion of, private
speech. Cf. Garcetti , 547 U. S., at 438 (Souter, J.,
dissenting); Rust , 500 U. S., at 212 (Blackmun, J.,
dissenting). Nor is it likely, given the near certainty that
observers will associate permanent displays with the governmental
property owner, that the government will be able to avoid political
accountability for the views that it endorses or expresses through
this means. Cf. Johanns , 544 U. S., at 571–572 (Souter,
J., dissenting). Finally, recognizing permanent displays on public
property as government speech will not give the government free
license to communicate offensive or partisan messages. For even if
the Free Speech Clause neither restricts nor protects government
speech, government speakers are bound by the Constitution’s other
proscriptions, including those supplied by the Establishment and
Equal Protection Clauses. Together with the checks imposed by our
democratic processes, these constitutional safeguards ensure that
the effect of today’s decision will be limited. SCALIA, J., CONCURRING PLEASANT GROVE CITY V. SUMMUM 555 U. S. ____ (2009) SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES NO. 07-665 PLEASANT GROVE CITY, UTAH, et al., PETITIONERS v. SUMMUM
on writ of certiorari to the united states court of
appeals for the tenth circuit
[February 25, 2009]
Justice Scalia, with whom Justice
Thomas joins, concurring.
As framed and argued by the
parties, this case presents a question under the Free Speech Clause
of the First Amendment. I agree with the Court’s analysis of that
question and join its opinion in full. But it is also obvious that
from the start, the case has been litigated in the shadow of the
First Amendment’s Establishment Clause: the city wary of
associating itself too closely with the Ten Commandments monument
displayed in the park, lest that be deemed a breach in the
so-called “wall of separation between church and State,” Reynolds v. United States , 98 U. S. 145 , 164 (1879);
respondent exploiting that hesitation to argue that the monument is
not government speech because the city has not sufficiently
“adopted” its message. Respondent menacingly observed that while
the city could have formally adopted the monument as its own, that
“might of course raise Establishment Clause issues.” Brief for
Respondent 34, n. 11.
The city ought not fear that today’s victory
has propelled it from the Free Speech Clause frying pan into the
Establishment Clause fire. Contrary to respondent’s intimations,
there are very good reasons to be confident that the park displays
do not violate any part of the First Amendment.
In Van Orden v. Perry , 545 U. S. 677 (2005), this Court upheld against Establishment Clause challenge a
virtually identical Ten Commandments monument, donated by the very
same organization (the Fraternal Order of Eagles), which was
displayed on the grounds surrounding the Texas State Capitol.
Nothing in that decision suggested that the outcome turned on a
finding that the monument was only “private” speech. To the
contrary, all the Justices agreed that government speech was at
issue, but the Establishment Clause argument was nonetheless
rejected. For the plurality, that was because the Ten Commandments
“have an undeniable historical meaning” in addition to their
“religious significance,” id. , at 690 (opinion of
Rehnquist, C. J.). Justice Breyer, concurring in the judgment,
agreed that the monument conveyed a permissible secular message, as
evidenced by its location in a park that contained multiple
monuments and historical markers; by the fact that it had been
donated by the Eagles “as part of that organization’s efforts to
combat juvenile delinquency”; and by the length of time (40 years)
for which the monument had gone unchallenged. Id. , at
701–703. See also id. , at 739–740 (Souter, J.,
dissenting).
Even accepting the narrowest reading of the
narrowest opinion necessary to the judgment in Van Orden ,
there is little basis to distinguish the monument in this case:
Pioneer Park includes “15 permanent displays,” ante , at
1–2; it was donated by the Eagles as part of its national effort to
combat juvenile delinquency, Brief for Respondent 3; and it was
erected in 1971, ibid. , which means it is approaching its
(momentous!) 40th anniversary.
The city can safely exhale. Its residents and
visitors can now return to enjoying Pioneer Park’s wishing well,
its historic granary—and, yes, even its Ten Commandments
monument—without fear that they are complicit in an establishment
of religion. 555 U. S. ____ (2009) PLEASANT GROVE CITY V. SUMMUM 555 U. S. ____ (2009) SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES NO. 07-665 PLEASANT GROVE CITY, UTAH, et al., PETITIONERS v. SUMMUM
on writ of certiorari to the united states court of
appeals for the tenth circuit
[February 25, 2009]
Justice Breyer, concurring.
I agree with the Court and join its opinion. I do
so, however, on the understanding that the “government speech”
doctrine is a rule of thumb, not a rigid category. Were the City to
discriminate in the selection of permanent monuments on grounds
unrelated to the display’s theme, say solely on political grounds,
its action might well violate the First Amendment.
In my view, courts must apply categories such as “government
speech,” “public forums,” “limited public forums,” and “nonpublic
forums” with an eye towards their purposes—lest we turn “free
speech” doctrine into a jurisprudence of labels. Cf. United
States v. Kokinda , 497 U. S. 720 , 740–743
(1990) (Brennan, J., dissenting). Consequently, we must sometimes
look beyond an initial categorization. And, in doing so, it helps
to ask whether a government action burdens speech
disproportionately in light of the action’s tendency to further a
legitimate government objective. See, e.g., Ysursa v. Pocatello Ed. Assn. , ante , at 1–4 (Breyer, J.,
concurring in part and dissenting in part); Nixon v. Shrink Missouri Government PAC , 528 U. S. 377 , 404
(2000) (Breyer, J., concurring).
Were we to do so here, we would find—for reasons that the Court
sets forth—that the City’s action, while preventing Summum from
erecting its monument, does not disproportionately restrict
Summum’s freedom of expression. The City has not closed off its
parks to speech; no one claims that the City prevents Summum’s
members from engaging in speech in a form more transient than a
permanent monument. Rather, the City has simply reserved some space
in the park for projects designed to further other than free-speech
goals. And that is perfectly proper. After all, parks do not serve
speech-related interests alone. To the contrary, cities use park
space to further a variety of recreational, historical,
educational, aesthetic, and other civic interests. To reserve to
the City the power to pick and choose among proposed monuments
according to criteria reasonably related to one or more of these
legitimate ends restricts Summum’s expression, but, given the
impracticality of alternatives and viewed in light of the City’s
legitimate needs, the restriction is not disproportionate. Analyzed
either way, as “government speech” or as a proportionate
restriction on Summum’s expression, the City’s action here is
lawful. SOUTER, J., CONCURRING IN JUDGMENT PLEASANT GROVE CITY V. SUMMUM 555 U. S. ____ (2009) SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES NO. 07-665 PLEASANT GROVE CITY, UTAH, et al., PETITIONERS v. SUMMUM
on writ of certiorari to the united states court of
appeals for the tenth circuit
[February 25, 2009]
Justice Souter, concurring in the
judgment.
I agree with the Court that the
Ten Commandments monument is government speech, that is, an
expression of a government’s position on the moral and religious
issues raised by the subject of the monument. See Board of
Regents of Univ. of Wis. System v. Southworth , 529 U. S. 217 ,
235 (2000) (noting government speech may “promote [government’s]
own policies or . . . advance a particular idea”). And although the
government should lose when the character of the speech is at issue
and its governmental nature has not been made clear, see Johanns v. Livestock Marketing Assn. , 544 U. S. 550 , 577
(2005) (Souter, J., dissenting), I also agree with the Court that
the city need not satisfy the particular formality urged by Summum
as a condition of recognizing that the expression here falls within
the public category. I have qualms, however, about accepting the
position that public monuments are government speech categorically.
See ante , at 8 (“Just as government-commissioned and
government-financed monuments speak for the government, so do
privately financed and donated monuments that the government
accepts and displays to the public on government land”).
Because the government speech doctrine, as
Justice Stevens notes, ante , at 1 (concurring opinion), is
“recently minted,” it would do well for us to go slow in setting
its bounds, which will affect existing doctrine in ways not yet
explored. Even though, for example, Establishment Clause issues
have been neither raised nor briefed before us, there is no doubt
that this case and its government speech claim has been litigated
by the parties with one eye on the Establishment Clause, see ante , at 1 (Scalia, J., concurring). The interaction
between the “government speech doctrine” and Establishment Clause
principles has not, however, begun to be worked out.
The case shows that it may not be easy to work
out. After today’s decision, whenever a government maintains a
monument it will presumably be understood to be engaging in
government speech. If the monument has some religious character,
the specter of violating the Establishment Clause will behoove it
to take care to avoid the appearance of a flat-out establishment of
religion, in the sense of the government’s adoption of the tenets
expressed or symbolized. In such an instance, there will be safety
in numbers, and it will be in the interest of a careful government
to accept other monuments to stand nearby, to dilute the appearance
of adopting whatever particular religious position the single
example alone might stand for. As mementoes and testimonials pile
up, however, the chatter may well make it less intuitively obvious
that the government is speaking in its own right simply by
maintaining the monuments.
If a case like that occurred, as suspicion
grew that some of the permanent displays were not government speech
at all (or at least had an equally private character associated
with private donors), a further Establishment Clause prohibition
would surface, the bar against preferring some religious speakers
over others. See Wallace v. Jaffree , 472 U. S. 38 , 113 (1985)
(Rehnquist, J., dissenting) (“The Clause was also designed to stop
the Federal Government from asserting a preference for one
religious denomination or sect over others”). But the government
could well argue, as a development of government speech doctrine,
that when it expresses its own views, it is free of the
Establishment Clause’s stricture against discriminating among
religious sects or groups. Under this view of the relationship
between the two doctrines, it would be easy for a government to
favor some private religious speakers over others by its choice of
monuments to accept.
Whether that view turns out to be sound is
more than I can say at this point. It is simply unclear how the
relatively new category of government speech will relate to the
more traditional categories of Establishment Clause analysis, and
this case is not an occasion to speculate. It is an occasion,
however, to try to keep the inevitable issues open, and as simple
as they can be. One way to do that is to recognize that there are
circumstances in which government maintenance of monuments does not
look like government speech at all. Sectarian identifications on
markers in Arlington Cemetery come to mind. And to recognize that
is to forgo any categorical rule at this point.
To avoid relying on a per se rule to
say when speech is governmental, the best approach that occurs to
me is to ask whether a reasonable and fully informed observer would
understand the expression to be government speech, as distinct from
private speech the government chooses to oblige by allowing the
monument to be placed on public land. This reasonable observer test
for governmental character is of a piece with the one for spotting
forbidden governmental endorsement of religion in the Establishment
Clause cases. See, e.g. , County of Allegheny v. American Civil Liberties Union, Greater Pittsburgh
Chapter , 492 U.
S. 573 , 630, 635–636 (1989) (O’Connor, J., concurring in part
and concurring in judgment). The adoption of it would thus serve
coherence within Establishment Clause law, and it would make sense
of our common understanding that some monuments on public land
display religious symbolism that clearly does not express a
government’s chosen views.
Application of this observer test provides the
reason I find the monument here to be government expression. | In Pleasant Grove City v. Summum, the Supreme Court ruled that a city's acceptance of a privately donated monument for display in a public park constitutes government speech, and therefore does not violate the Free Speech Clause of the First Amendment. The Court determined that a reasonable observer would understand the monument as conveying the government's own message, especially when considering the context of its placement in a public park with other monuments. This decision gives governments significant leeway in accepting or rejecting private monuments without triggering First Amendment concerns. However, Justice Souter's concurrence highlights potential issues with this approach, particularly regarding the Establishment Clause and religious monuments. |
Free Speech | Ashcroft v. ACLU II | https://supreme.justia.com/cases/federal/us/542/656/ | OPINION OF THE COURT ASHCROFT V. AMERICAN CIVIL LIBERTIES UNION 542 U. S. ____ (2004) SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES NO. 03-218 JOHN D. ASHCROFT, ATTORNEY GENERAL, PETITIONER v. AMERICAN CIVIL LIBERTIES UNION et al.
on writ of certiorari to the united states court of
appeals for the third circuit
[June 29, 2004]
Justice Kennedy delivered the
opinion of the Court.
This case presents a challenge to
a statute enacted by Congress to protect minors from exposure to
sexually explicit materials on the Internet, the Child Online
Protection Act (COPA). 112 Stat. 2681–736, codified at 47 U.
S. C. §231. We must decide whether the Court of Appeals was
correct to affirm a ruling by the District Court that enforcement
of COPA should be enjoined because the statute likely violates the
First Amendment.
In enacting COPA, Congress gave consideration
to our earlier decisions on this subject, in particular the
decision in Reno v. American Civil Liberties
Union , 521 U. S. 844 (1997). For that reason,
“the Judiciary must proceed with caution and . . . with care before
invalidating the Act.” Ashcroft v. American Civil
Liberties Union , 535 U. S. 564 , 592
( Ashcroft I ) (Kennedy, J., concurring in judgment). The
imperative of according respect to the Congress, however, does not
permit us to depart from well-established First Amendment
principles. Instead, we must hold the Government to its
constitutional burden of proof.
Content-based prohibitions, enforced by severe
criminal penalties, have the constant potential to be a repressive
force in the lives and thoughts of a free people. To guard against
that threat the Constitution demands that content-based
restrictions on speech be presumed invalid, R. A. V. v. St. Paul , 505 U. S. 377 , 382
(1992), and that the Government bear the burden of showing their
constitutionality. United States v. Playboy
Entertainment Group, Inc. , 529 U. S. 803 , 817
(2000). This is true even when Congress twice has attempted to find
a constitutional means to restrict, and punish, the speech in
question.
This case comes to the Court on certiorari
review of an appeal from the decision of the District Court
granting a preliminary injunction. The Court of Appeals reviewed
the decision of the District Court for abuse of discretion. Under
that standard, the Court of Appeals was correct to conclude that
the District Court did not abuse its discretion in granting the
preliminary injunction. The Government has failed, at this point,
to rebut the plaintiffs’ contention that there are plausible less
restrictive alternatives to the statute. Substantial practical
considerations, furthermore, argue in favor of upholding the
injunction and allowing the case to proceed to trial. For those
reasons, we affirm the decision of the Court of Appeals upholding
the preliminary injunction, and we remand the case so that it may
be returned to the District Court for trial on the issues
presented.
I
A
COPA is the second attempt by
Congress to make the Internet safe for minors by criminalizing
certain Internet speech. The first attempt was
the Communications Decency Act of 1996, Pub. L. 104–104, §502, 110
Stat. 133, 47 U. S. C. §223 (1994 ed., Supp. II). The Court
held the CDA unconstitutional because it was not narrowly tailored
to serve a compelling governmental interest and because less
restrictive alternatives were available. Reno , supra .
In response to the Court’s
decision in Reno , Congress passed COPA. COPA imposes
criminal penalties of a $50,000 fine and six months in prison for
the knowing posting, for “commercial purposes,” of World Wide Web
content that is “harmful to minors.” §231(a)(1). Material that is
"harmful to minors" is defined as:
“any communication, picture, image, graphic image
file, article, recording, writing, or other matter of any kind that
is obscene or that—
“(A) the average person, applying contemporary community
standards, would find, taking the material as a whole and with
respect to minors, is designed to appeal to, or is designed to
pander to, the prurient interest;
“(B) depicts, describes, or represents, in a manner patently
offensive with respect to minors, an actual or simulated sexual act
or sexual contact, an actual or simulated normal or perverted
sexual act, or a lewd exhibition of the genitals or post-pubescent
female breast; and
“(C) taken as a whole, lacks serious literary, artistic,
political, or scientific value for minors.” §231(e)(6).
“Minors” are defined as “any
person under 17 years of age.” §231(e)(7). A person acts for
“commercial purposes only if such person is engaged in the business
of making such communications.” “Engaged in the business,” in
turn,
“means that the person who makes a communication,
or offers to make a communication, by means of the World Wide Web,
that includes any material that is harmful to minors, devotes time,
attention, or labor to such activities, as a regular course of such
person’s trade or business, with the objective of earning a profit
as a result of such activities (although it is not necessary that
the person make a profit or that the making or offering to make
such communications be the person’s sole or principal business or
source of income).” §231(e)(2).
While the statute labels all
speech that falls within these definitions as criminal speech, it
also provides an affirmative defense to those who employ specified
means to prevent minors from gaining access to the prohibited
materials on their Web site. A person may escape conviction under
the statute by demonstrating that he
“has restricted access by minors to material that
is harmful to minors—
“(A) by requiring use of a credit card, debit account, adult
access code, or adult personal identification number;
“(B) by accepting a digital certificate that verifies age,
or
“(C) by any other reasonable measures that are feasible under
available technology.” §231(c)(1).
Since the passage of COPA,
Congress has enacted additional laws regulating the Internet in an
attempt to protect minors. For example, it has enacted a
prohibition on misleading Internet domain names, 18 U.
S. C. A. §2252B (Supp. 2004), in order to prevent Web
site owners from disguising pornographic Web sites in a way likely
to cause uninterested persons to visit them. See Brief for
Petitioner 7 (giving, as an example, the Web site
“whitehouse.com”). It has also passed a statute creating a “Dot
Kids” second-level Internet domain, the content of which is
restricted to that which is fit for minors under the age of 13. 47
U. S. C. A. §941 (Supp. 2004).
B
Respondents, Internet content
providers and others concerned with protecting the freedom of
speech, filed suit in the United States District Court for the
Eastern District of Pennsylvania. They sought a preliminary
injunction against enforcement of the statute. After considering
testimony from witnesses presented by both respondents and the
Government, the District Court issued an order granting the
preliminary injunction. The court first noted that the statute
would place a burden on some protected speech. American Civil
Liberties Union v. Reno , 31 F. Supp. 2d 473, 495
(1999). The court then concluded that respondents were likely to
prevail on their argument that there were less restrictive
alternatives to the statute: “On the record to date, it is not
apparent … that [petitioner] can meet its burden to prove that COPA
is the least restrictive means available to achieve the goal of
restricting the access of minors” to harmful material. Id. , at 497. In particular, it noted that “[t]he record
before the Court reveals that blocking or filtering technology may
be at least as successful as COPA would be in restricting minors’
access to harmful material online without imposing the burden on
constitutionally protected speech that COPA imposes on adult users
or Web site operators.” Ibid .
The Government appealed the
District Court’s decision to the United States Court of Appeals for
the Third Circuit. The Court of Appeals affirmed the preliminary
injunction, but on a different ground. 217 F. 3d 162, 166
(2000). The court concluded that the “community standards” language
in COPA by itself rendered the statute unconstitutionally
overbroad. Id. , at 166. We granted certiorari and
reversed, holding that the community-standards language did not,
standing alone, make the statute unconstitutionally overbroad. Ashcroft I , 535 U. S., at 585. We emphasized, however,
that our decision was limited to that narrow issue. Ibid .
We remanded the case to the Court of Appeals to reconsider whether
the District Court had been correct to grant the preliminary
injunction. On remand, the Court of Appeals again affirmed the
District Court. 322 F. 3d 240 (2003). The Court of Appeals
concluded that the statute was not narrowly tailored to serve a
compelling Government interest, was overbroad, and was not the
least restrictive means available for the Government to serve the
interest of preventing minors from using the Internet to gain
access to materials that are harmful to them. Id. , at
266–271. The Government once again sought review from this Court,
and we again granted certiorari. 540 U. S. 944 (2003).
II
A
“This Court, like other appellate
courts, has always applied the abuse of discretion standard on the
review of a preliminary injunction.” Walters v .
National Assn. of Radiation Survivors , 473 U. S. 305 , 336
(1985) (O’Connor, J., concurring) (internal quotation marks
omitted). “The grant of appellate jurisdiction under [28 U.
S. C.] §1252 does not give the Court license to depart from
established standards of appellate review.” Ibid. If the
underlying constitutional question is close, therefore, we should
uphold the injunction and remand for trial on the merits. Applying
this mode of inquiry, we agree with the Court of Appeals that the
District Court did not abuse its discretion in entering the
preliminary injunction. Our reasoning in support of this
conclusion, however, is based on a narrower, more specific grounds
than the rationale the Court of Appeals adopted. The Court of
Appeals, in its opinion affirming the decision of the District
Court, construed a number of terms in the statute, and held that
COPA, so construed, was unconstitutional. None of those
constructions of statutory terminology, however, were relied on by
or necessary to the conclusions of the District Court. Instead, the
District Court concluded only that the statute was likely to burden
some speech that is protected for adults, 31 F. Supp.2d, at
495, which petitioner does not dispute. As to the definitional
disputes, the District Court concluded only that respondents’
interpretation was “not unreasonable,” and relied on their
interpretation only to conclude that respondents had standing to
challenge the statute, id. , at 481, which, again,
petitioner does not dispute. Because we affirm the District Court’s
decision to grant the preliminary injunction for the reasons relied
on by the District Court, we decline to consider the correctness of
the other arguments relied on by the Court of Appeals.
The District Court, in deciding
to grant the preliminary injunction, concentrated primarily on the
argument that there are plausible, less restrictive alternatives to
COPA. A statute that “effectively suppresses a large amount of
speech that adults have a constitutional right to receive and to
address to one another … is unacceptable if less restrictive
alternatives would be at least as effective in achieving the
legitimate purpose that the statute was enacted to serve.” Reno , 521 U. S., at 874. When plaintiffs challenge a
content-based speech restriction, the burden is on the Government
to prove that the proposed alternatives will not be as effective as
the challenged statute. Id. , at 874.
In considering this question, a court assumes
that certain protected speech may be regulated, and then asks what
is the least restrictive alternative that can be used to achieve
that goal. The purpose of the test is not to consider whether the
challenged restriction has some effect in achieving Congress’ goal,
regardless of the restriction it imposes. The purpose of the test
is to ensure that speech is restricted no further than necessary to
achieve the goal, for it is important to assure that legitimate
speech is not chilled or punished. For that reason, the test does
not begin with the status quo of existing regulations, then ask
whether the challenged restriction has some additional ability to
achieve Congress’ legitimate interest. Any restriction on speech
could be justified under that analysis. Instead, the court should
ask whether the challenged regulation is the least restrictive
means among available, effective alternatives.
In deciding whether to grant a preliminary
injunction stage, a district court must consider whether the
plaintiffs have demonstrated that they are likely to prevail on the
merits. See, e.g. , Doran v. Salem Inn , Inc. , 422
U. S. 922 , 931 (1975). (The court also considers whether the
plaintiff has shown irreparable injury, see id. , at 931,
but the parties in this case do not contest the correctness of the
District Court’s conclusion that a likelihood of irreparable injury
had been established. See 31 F. Supp. 2d, at 497–498). As the
Government bears the burden of proof on the ultimate question of
COPA’s constitutionality, respondents must be deemed likely to
prevail unless the Government has shown that respondents’ proposed
less restrictive alternatives are less effective than COPA.
Applying that analysis, the District Court concluded that
respondents were likely to prevail. Id. , at 496–497. That
conclusion was not an abuse of discretion, because on this record
there are a number of plausible, less restrictive alternatives to
the statute.
The primary alternative considered by the
District Court was blocking and filtering software. Blocking and
filtering software is an alternative that is less restrictive than
COPA, and, in addition, likely more effective as a means of
restricting children’s access to materials harmful to them. The
District Court, in granting the preliminary injunction, did so
primarily because the plaintiffs had proposed that filters are a
less restrictive alternative to COPA and the Government had not
shown it would be likely to disprove the plaintiffs’ contention at
trial. Ibid .
Filters are less restrictive than COPA. They
impose selective restrictions on speech at the receiving end, not
universal restrictions at the source. Under a filtering regime,
adults without children may gain access to speech they have a right
to see without having to identify themselves or provide their
credit card information. Even adults with children may obtain
access to the same speech on the same terms simply by turning off
the filter on their home computers. Above all, promoting the use of
filters does not condemn as criminal any category of speech, and so
the potential chilling effect is eliminated, or at least much
diminished. All of these things are true, moreover, regardless of
how broadly or narrowly the definitions in COPA are construed.
Filters also may well be more effective than
COPA. First, a filter can prevent minors from seeing all
pornography, not just pornography posted to the Web from America.
The District Court noted in its factfindings that one witness
estimated that 40% of harmful-to-minors content comes from
overseas. Id. , at 484. COPA does not prevent minors from
having access to those foreign harmful materials. That alone makes
it possible that filtering software might be more effective in
serving Congress’ goals. Effectiveness is likely to diminish even
further if COPA is upheld, because the providers of the materials
that would be covered by the statute simply can move their
operations overseas. It is not an answer to say that COPA reaches
some amount of materials that are harmful to minors; the question
is whether it would reach more of them than less restrictive
alternatives. In addition, the District Court found that
verification systems may be subject to evasion and circumvention,
for example by minors who have their own credit cards. See id. , at 484, 496–497. Finally, filters also may be more
effective because they can be applied to all forms of Internet
communication, including e-mail, not just communications available
via the World Wide Web.
That filtering software may well be more
effective than COPA is confirmed by the findings of the Commission
on Child Online Protection, a blue-ribbon commission created by
Congress in COPA itself. Congress directed the Commission to
evaluate the relative merits of different means of restricting
minors’ ability to gain access to harmful materials on the
Internet. Note following 47 U. S. C. §231. It unambiguously
found that filters are more effective than age-verification
requirements. See Commission on Child Online Protection (COPA),
Report to Congress, at 19–21, 23–25, 27 (Oct. 20, 2000) (assigning
a score for “Effectiveness” of 7.4 for server-based filters and 6.5
for client-based filters, as compared to 5.9 for independent
adult-id verification, and 5.5 for credit card verification). Thus,
not only has the Government failed to carry its burden of showing
the District Court that the proposed alternative is less effective,
but also a Government Commission appointed to consider the question
has concluded just the opposite. That finding supports our
conclusion that the District Court did not abuse its discretion in
enjoining the statute.
Filtering software, of course, is not a
perfect solution to the problem of children gaining access to
harmful-to-minors materials. It may block some materials that are
not harmful to minors and fail to catch some that are. See 31
F. Supp. 2d, at 492. Whatever the deficiencies of filters,
however, the Government failed to introduce specific evidence
proving that existing technologies are less effective than the
restrictions in COPA. The District Court made a specific
factfinding that “[n]o evidence was presented to the Court as to
the percentage of time that blocking and filtering technology is
over- or underinclusive.” Ibid . In the absence of a
showing as to the relative effectiveness of COPA and the
alternatives proposed by respondents, it was not an abuse of
discretion for the District Court to grant the preliminary
injunction. The Government’s burden is not merely to show that a
proposed less restrictive alternative has some flaws; its burden is
to show that it is less effective. Reno , 521 U. S., at
874. It is not enough for the Government to show that COPA has some
effect. Nor do respondents bear a burden to introduce, or offer to
introduce, evidence that their proposed alternatives are more
effective. The Government has the burden to show they are less so.
The Government having failed to carry its burden, it was not an
abuse of discretion for the District Court to grant the preliminary
injunction.
One argument to the contrary is worth
mentioning—the argument that filtering software is not an available
alternative because Congress may not require it to be used. That
argument carries little weight, because Congress undoubtedly may
act to encourage the use of filters. We have held that Congress can
give strong incentives to schools and libraries to use them. United States v. American Library Assn., Inc , 539 U.S.
194 (2003). It could also take steps to promote their
development by industry, and their use by parents. It is incorrect,
for that reason, to say that filters are part of the current
regulatory status quo. The need for parental cooperation does not
automatically disqualify a proposed less restrictive alternative. Playboy Entertainment Group , 529 U. S., at 824. (“A court
should not assume a plausible, less restrictive alternative would
be ineffective; and a court should not presume parents, given full
information, will fail to act ” ). In enacting COPA,
Congress said its goal was to prevent the “widespread availability
of the Internet” from providing “opportunities for minors to access
materials through the World Wide Web in a manner that can frustrate
parental supervision or control.” Congressional Findings, note
following 47 U. S. C. §231 (quoting Pub. L. 105–277, Tit. XIV,
§1402(1), 112 Stat. 2681–736). COPA presumes that parents lack the
ability, not the will, to monitor what their children see. By
enacting programs to promote use of filtering software, Congress
could give parents that ability without subjecting protected speech
to severe penalties.
The closest precedent on the general point is
our decision in Playboy Entertainment Group . Playboy
Entertainment Group , like this case, involved a content-based
restriction designed to protect minors from viewing harmful
materials. The choice was between a blanket speech restriction and
a more specific technological solution that was available to
parents who chose to implement it. 529 U. S., at 825. Absent a
showing that the proposed less restrictive alternative would not be
as effective, we concluded, the more restrictive option preferred
by Congress could not survive strict scrutiny. Id. , at 826
(reversing because “[t]he record is silent as to the comparative
effectiveness of the two alternatives”). In the instant case, too,
the Government has failed to show, at this point, that the proposed
less restrictive alternative will be less effective. The reasoning
of Playboy Entertainment Group , and the holdings and force
of our precedents require us to affirm the preliminary injunction.
To do otherwise would be to do less than the First Amendment
commands. “The starch in our constitutional standards cannot be
sacrificed to accommodate the enforcement choices of the
Government.” Id., at 830 (Thomas, J., concurring).
B
There are also important
practical reasons to let the injunction stand pending a full trial
on the merits. First, the potential harms from reversing the
injunction outweigh those of leaving it in place by mistake. Where
a prosecution is a likely possibility, yet only an affirmative
defense is available, speakers may self-censor rather than risk the
perils of trial. There is a potential for extraordinary harm and a
serious chill upon protected speech. Cf. id., at 817
(“Error in marking that line exacts an extraordinary cost”). The
harm done from letting the injunction stand pending a trial on the
merits, in contrast, will not be extensive. No prosecutions have
yet been undertaken under the law, so none will be disrupted if the
injunction stands. Further, if the injunction is upheld, the
Government in the interim can enforce obscenity laws already on the
books.
Second, there are substantial
factual disputes remaining in the case. As mentioned above, there
is a serious gap in the evidence as to the effectiveness of
filtering software. See supra , at 9. For us to assume,
without proof, that filters are less effective than COPA would
usurp the District Court’s factfinding role. By allowing the
preliminary injunction to stand and remanding for trial, we require
the Government to shoulder its full constitutional burden of proof
respecting the less restrictive alternative argument, rather than
excuse it from doing so.
Third, and on a related point, the factual
record does not reflect current technological reality—a serious
flaw in any case involving the Internet. The technology of the
Internet evolves at a rapid pace. Yet the factfindings of the
District Court were entered in February 1999, over five years ago.
Since then, certain facts about the Internet are known to have
changed. Compare, e.g., 31 F. Supp. 2d, at 481 (36.7
million Internet hosts as of July 1998) with Internet Systems
Consortium, Internet Domain Survey, Jan. 2004,
http://www.isc.org/index.pl?/ops/ds (as visited June 22, 2004, and
available in the Clerk of Court’s case file) (233.1 million hosts
as of Jan. 2004). It is reasonable to assume that other
technological developments important to the First Amendment
analysis have also occurred during that time. More and better
filtering alternatives may exist than when the District Court
entered its findings. Indeed, we know that after the District Court
entered its factfindings, a congressionally appointed commission
issued a report that found that filters are more effective than
verification screens. See supra , at 8.
Delay between the time that a district court
makes factfindings and the time that a case reaches this Court is
inevitable, with the necessary consequence that there will be some
discrepancy between the facts as found and the facts at the time
the appellate court takes up the question. See, e.g .,
Benjamin, Stepping into the Same River Twice: Rapidly Changing
Facts and the Appellate Process, 78 Texas L. Rev. 269, 290–296
(1999) (noting the problems presented for appellate courts by
changing facts in the context of cases involving the Internet, and
giving as a specific example the Court’s decision in Reno , 521 U. S. 844 ). We do not mean,
therefore, to set up an insuperable obstacle to fair review. Here,
however, the usual gap has doubled because the case has been
through the Court of Appeals twice. The additional two years might
make a difference. By affirming the preliminary injunction and
remanding for trial, we allow the parties to update and supplement
the factual record to reflect current technological realities.
Remand will also permit the
District Court to take account of a changed legal landscape. Since
the District Court made its factfindings, Congress has passed at
least two further statutes that might qualify as less restrictive
alternatives to COPA—a prohibition on misleading domain names, and
a statute creating a minors-safe “Dot Kids” domain. See supra , at 4. Remanding for trial will allow the District
Court to take into account those additional potential
alternatives.
On a final point, it is important to note that
this opinion does not hold that Congress is incapable of enacting
any regulation of the Internet designed to prevent minors from
gaining access to harmful materials. The parties, because of the
conclusion of the Court of Appeals that the statute’s definitions
rendered it unconstitutional, did not devote their attention to the
question whether further evidence might be introduced on the
relative restrictiveness and effectiveness of alternatives to the
statute. On remand, however, the parties will be able to introduce
further evidence on this point. This opinion does not foreclose the
District Court from concluding, upon a proper showing by the
Government that meets the Government’s constitutional burden as
defined in this opinion, that COPA is the least restrictive
alternative available to accomplish Congress’ goal.
* * *
On this record, the Government
has not shown that the less restrictive alternatives proposed by
respondents should be disregarded. Those alternatives, indeed, may
be more effective than the provisions of COPA. The District Court
did not abuse its discretion when it entered the preliminary
injunction. The judgment of the Court of Appeals is affirmed, and
the case is remanded for proceedings consistent with this
opinion.
It is so ordered. STEVENS, J., CONCURRING ASHCROFT V. AMERICAN CIVIL LIBERTIES UNION 542 U. S. ____ (2004) SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES NO. 03-218 JOHN D. ASHCROFT, ATTORNEY GENERAL, PETITIONER v. AMERICAN CIVIL LIBERTIES UNION et al.
on writ of certiorari to the united states court of
appeals for the third circuit
[June 29, 2004]
Justice Stevens, with whom
Justice Ginsburg joins, concurring.
When it first reviewed the
constitutionality of the Child Online Protection Act (COPA), the
Court of Appeals held that the statute’s use of “contemporary
community standards” to identify materials that are “harmful to
minors” was a serious, and likely fatal, defect. American Civil
Liberties Union v. Reno , 217 F. 3d 162 (CA3
2000). I have already explained at some length why I agree with
that holding. See Ashcroft v. American Civil Liberties
Union, 535 U.
S. 564 , 603 (2002) (dissenting opinion) (“In the context of the
Internet, … community standards become a sword, rather than a
shield. If a prurient appeal is offensive in a puritan village, it
may be a crime to post it on the World Wide Web”). I continue to
believe that the Government may not penalize speakers for making
available to the general World Wide Web audience that which the
least tolerant communities in America deem unfit for their
children’s consumption, cf. Reno v. American Civil
Liberties Union, 521 U. S. 844 , 878
(1997), and consider that principle a sufficient basis for deciding
this case.
But COPA’s use of community standards is not
the statute’s only constitutional defect. Today’s decision points
to another: that, as far as the record reveals, encouraging
deployment of user-based controls, such as filtering software,
would serve Congress’ interest in protecting minors from sexually
explicit Internet materials as well or better than attempting to
regulate the vast content of the World Wide Web at its source, and
at a far less significant cost to First Amendment values.
In registering my agreement with the Court’s
less-restrictive-means analysis, I wish to underscore just how
restrictive COPA is. COPA is a content-based restraint on the
dissemination of constitutionally protected speech. It enforces its
prohibitions by way of the criminal law, threatening noncompliant
Web speakers with a fine of as much as $50,000, and a term of
imprisonment as long as six months, for each offense. 47 U.
S. C. §231(a). Speakers who “intentionally” violate COPA are
punishable by a fine of up to $50,000 for each day of the
violation. Ibid. And because implementation of the various
adult-verification mechanisms described in the statute provides
only an affirmative defense, §231(c)(1), even full compliance with
COPA cannot guarantee freedom from prosecution. Speakers who
dutifully place their content behind age screens may nevertheless
find themselves in court, forced to prove the lawfulness of their
speech on pain of criminal conviction. Cf. Ashcroft v. Free Speech Coalition, 535 U. S. 234 , 255
(2002).
Criminal prosecutions are, in my view, an
inappropriate means to regulate the universe of materials
classified as “obscene,” since “the line between communications
which ‘offend’ and those which do not is too blurred to identify
criminal conduct.” Smith v. United
States, 431 U. S. 291 , 316
(1977) (Stevens, J., dissenting). See also Marks v. United States, 430 U. S. 188 , 198
(1977) (Stevens, J., concurring in part and dissenting in part).
COPA’s creation of a new category of criminally punishable speech
that is “harmful to minors” only compounds the problem. It may be,
as Justice Breyer contends, that the statute’s coverage extends
“only slightly” beyond the legally obscene, and therefore intrudes
little into the realm of protected expression. Post, at 4
(dissenting opinion). But even with Justice Breyer’s guidance, I
find it impossible to identify just how far past the already
ill-defined territory of “obscenity” he thinks the statute extends.
Attaching criminal sanctions to a mistaken judgment about the
contours of the novel and nebulous category of “harmful to minors”
speech clearly imposes a heavy burden on the exercise of First
Amendment freedoms.
COPA’s criminal penalties are, moreover,
strong medicine for the ill that the statute seeks to remedy. To be
sure, our cases have recognized a compelling interest in protecting
minors from exposure to sexually explicit materials. See, e.g., Ginsberg v. New
York, 390
U. S. 629 , 640 (1968). As a parent, grandparent, and
great-grandparent, I endorse that goal without reservation. As a
judge, however, I must confess to a growing sense of unease when
the interest in protecting children from prurient materials is
invoked as a justification for using criminal regulation of speech
as a substitute for, or a simple backup to, adult oversight of
children’s viewing habits.
In view of the gravity of the burdens COPA
imposes on Web speech, the possibility that Congress might have
accomplished the goal of protecting children from harmful materials
by other, less drastic means is a matter to be considered with
special care. With that observation, I join the opinion of the
Court. 542 U. S. ____ (2004) ASHCROFT V. AMERICAN CIVIL LIBERTIES UNION 542 U. S. ____ (2004) SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES NO. 03-218 JOHN D. ASHCROFT, ATTORNEY GENERAL, PETITIONER v. AMERICAN CIVIL LIBERTIES UNION et al.
on writ of certiorari to the united states court of
appeals for the third circuit
[June 29, 2004]
Justice Scalia, dissenting.
I agree with Justice Breyer’s
conclusion that the Child Online Protection Act (COPA), 47 U.
S. C. §231, is constitutional. See post , at 14
(dissenting opinion). Both the Court and Justice Breyer err,
however, in subjecting COPA to strict scrutiny. Nothing in the
First Amendment entitles the type of material covered by COPA to
that exacting standard of review. “We have recognized that
commercial entities which engage in ‘the sordid business of
pandering’ by ‘deliberately emphasiz[ing] the sexually provocative
aspects of [their nonobscene products], in order to catch the
salaciously disposed,’ engage in constitutionally unprotected
behavior.” United States v. Playboy Entertainment
Group, Inc., 529 U. S. 803 , 831
(2000) (Scalia, J., dissenting) (quoting Ginzburg v. United States, 383 U. S. 463 , 467, 472
(1966)). See also Los Angeles v. Alameda Books,
Inc., 535 U. S.
425 , 443–444 (2002) (Scalia, J., concurring); FW/PBS,
Inc. v. Dallas, 493 U. S. 215 , 256–261
(1990) (Scalia, J., concurring in part and dissenting in part).
There is no doubt that the commercial
pornography covered by COPA fits this description. The statute
applies only to a person who, “as a regular course of such person’s
trade or business, with the objective of earning a profit,” 47 U.
S. C. §231(e)(2)(B), and “with knowledge of the character of
the material,” §231(a)(1), communicates material that depicts
certain specified sexual acts and that “is designed to appeal to,
or is designed to pander to, the prurient interest,” §231(e)(6)(A).
Since this business could, consistent with the First Amendment, be
banned entirely, COPA’s lesser restrictions raise no constitutional
concern. BREYER, J., DISSENTING ASHCROFT V. AMERICAN CIVIL LIBERTIES UNION 542 U. S. ____ (2004) SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES NO. 03-218 JOHN D. ASHCROFT, ATTORNEY GENERAL, PETITIONER v. AMERICAN CIVIL LIBERTIES UNION et al.
on writ of certiorari to the united states court of
appeals for the third circuit
[June 29, 2004]
Justice Breyer, with whom The
Chief Justice and Justice O’Connor join, dissenting.
The Child Online Protection Act
(Act), 47 U. S. C. §231, seeks to protect children from
exposure to commercial pornography placed on the Internet. It does
so by requiring commercial providers to place pornographic material
behind Internet “screens” readily accessible to adults who produce
age verification. The Court recognizes that we should
“ ‘proceed … with care before invalidating the Act,’ ”
while pointing out that the “imperative of according respect to the
Congress … does not permit us to depart from well-established First
Amendment principles.” Ante, at 1. I agree with these
generalities. Like the Court, I would subject the Act to “the most
exacting scrutiny,” Turner Broadcasting System, Inc. v. FCC, 512 U. S. 622 , 642
(1994), requiring the Government to show that any restriction of
nonobscene expression is “narrowly drawn” to further a “compelling
interest” and that the restriction amounts to the “least
restrictive means” available to further that interest, Sable
Communications of Cal., Inc. v. FCC, 492 U. S. 115 , 126
(1989). See also Denver Area Ed. Telecommunications Consortium,
Inc. v. FCC, 518 U. S. 727 , 755–756
(1996).
Nonetheless, my examination of (1) the burdens
the Act imposes on protected expression, (2) the Act’s ability to
further a compelling interest, and (3) the proposed “less
restrictive alternatives” convinces me that the Court is wrong. I
cannot accept its conclusion that Congress could have accomplished
its statutory objective—protecting children from commercial
pornography on the Internet—in other, less restrictive ways.
I
Although the Court rests its
conclusion upon the existence of less restrictive alternatives, I
must first examine the burdens that the Act imposes upon protected
speech. That is because the term “less restrictive alternative” is
a comparative term. An “alternative” is “less restrictive” only if
it will work less First Amendment harm than the statute itself,
while at the same time similarly furthering the “compelling”
interest that prompted Congress to enact the statute. Unlike the
majority, I do not see how it is possible to make this comparative
determination without examining both the extent to which the Act
regulates protected expression and the nature of the burdens it
imposes on that expression. That examination suggests that the Act,
properly interpreted, imposes a burden on protected speech that is
no more than modest.
A
The Act’s definitions limit the
material it regulates to material that does not enjoy First
Amendment protection, namely legally obscene material, and very
little more. A comparison of this Court’s definition of
unprotected, “legally obscene,” material with the Act’s definitions
makes this clear.
Material is legally obscene
if
“(a) . . . ‘the average person, applying
contemporary community standards’ would find that the work, taken
as a whole, appeals to the prurient interest . . . ; (b) . . . the
work depicts or describes, in a patently offensive way, sexual
conduct specifically defined by the applicable state law; and (c) .
. . the work, taken as a whole, lacks serious literary, artistic,
political, or scientific value.” Miller v. California, 413 U. S. 15 , 24
(1973).
The present statute defines the material that it
regulates as material that meets all of the following criteria:
“(A) the average person, applying contemporary
community standards, would find, taking the material as a whole and with respect to minors , [that the material] is
designed to appeal to, or is designed to pander to, the prurient
interest;
“(B) [the material] depicts, describes, or represents, in a
manner patently offensive with respect to minors, an
actual or simulated sexual act or sexual contact, an actual or
simulated normal or perverted sexual act, or a lewd exhibition of
the genitals or post-pubescent female breast; and
“(C) [the material] taken as a whole, lacks serious literary,
artistic, political, or scientific value for minors .” 47
U. S. C. §231(e)(6) (emphasis added).
Both definitions define the
relevant material through use of the critical terms “prurient
interest” and “lacks serious literary, artistic, political, or
scientific value.” Insofar as material appeals to, or panders to,
“the prurient interest,” it simply seeks a sexual response. Insofar
as “patently offensive” material with “no serious value” simply
seeks that response, it does not seek to educate, it does not seek
to elucidate views about sex, it is not artistic, and it is not
literary. Compare, e.g., Erznoznik v. Jacksonville, 422 U. S. 205 , 213
(1975) (invalidating an ordinance regulating nudity in films, where
the ban was not confined to “sexually explicit nudity” or otherwise
limited), with Ginzburg v. United
States, 383 U. S. 463 , 471
(1966) (finding unprotected material that was “created,
represented, and sold solely as a claimed instrument of the sexual
stimulation it would bring”). That is why this Court, in Miller, held that the First Amendment did not protect
material that fit its definition.
The only significant difference between the
present statute and Miller ’s definition consists of the
addition of the words “with respect to minors,” §231(e)(6)(A), and
“for minors,” §231(e)(6)(C). But the addition of these words to a
definition that would otherwise cover only obscenity expands the
statute’s scope only slightly. That is because the material in
question (while potentially harmful to young children) must, first,
appeal to the “prurient interest” of, i.e., seek a sexual
response from, some group of adolescents or postadolescents (since
young children normally do not so respond). And material that
appeals to the “prurient interest[s]” of some group of adolescents
or postadolescents will almost inevitably appeal to the “prurient
interest[s]” of some group of adults as well.
The “lack of serious value” requirement
narrows the statute yet further—despite the presence of the
qualification “for minors.” That is because one cannot easily
imagine material that has serious literary, artistic, political, or
scientific value for a significant group of adults, but lacks such
value for any significant group of minors. Thus, the statute, read
literally, insofar as it extends beyond the legally obscene, could
reach only borderline cases. And to take the words of the statute
literally is consistent with Congress’ avowed objective in enacting
this law; namely, putting material produced by professional
pornographers behind screens that will verify the age of the
viewer. See S. Rep. No. 105–225, p. 3 (1998) (hereinafter
S. Rep.) (“The bill seeks to restrict access to commercial
pornography on the Web by requiring those engaged in the business
of the commercial distribution of material that is harmful to
minors to take certain prescribed steps to restrict access to such
material by minors …”); H. R. Rep. No. 105–775, pp. 5, 14
(1998) (hereinafter H. R. Rep.) (explaining that the bill is
aimed at the sale of pornographic materials and provides a defense
for the “commercial purveyors of pornography” that the bill seeks
to regulate).
These limitations on the statute’s scope
answer many of the concerns raised by those who attack its
constitutionality. Respondents fear prosecution for the Internet
posting of material that does not fall within the stat- ute’s ambit
as limited by the “prurient interest” and “no serious value”
requirements; for example: an essay about a young man’s experience
with masturbation and sex- ual shame; “a serious discussion about
birth control practices, homosexuality, . . . or the consequences
of prison rape”; an account by a 15-year-old, written for
therapeutic purposes, of being raped when she was 13; a guide to
self-examination for testicular cancer; a graphic illustration of
how to use a condom; or any of the other postings of modern
literary or artistic works or discus- sions of sexual identity,
homosexuality, sexually trans- mitted diseases, sex education, or
safe sex, let alone Aldous Huxley’s Brave New World, J. D.
Salinger’s Catcher in the Rye, or, as the complaint would have it,
“Ken Starr’s report on the Clinton-Lewinsky scan- dal.” See G.
Dillard, Shame on Me, Lodging 609–612; Reno v. American Civil Liberties Union, 521 U. S. 844 , 871
(1997); Brief for Respondents 29 (citing Lodging 732– 736); Brief
for American Society of Journalists and Authors et al. as Amici Curiae 8, and n. 7 (referring to a guide on the
medical advice site www.afraidtoask.com); 322 F. 3d 240, 268
(CA3 2003) (citing Safer Sex Institute,
safersex.org/condoms/how.to.use); Complaint ¶ ;1, Lodging 40–41 (“a
Mapplethorpe photograph,” referring to the work of controversial
artist Robert Mapplethorpe); Id., at 667– 669 (Pl. Exh.
80, PlanetOut Youth Message Boards (Internet discussion board for
gay teens)); declaration of Adam K. Glickman, president and CEO,
Addazi, Inc. d/b/a Condomania, Supp. Lodging of Petitioner 4–10
(describing how Web site has been used for health education);
declaration of Roberta Spyer, president and publisher, OBGYN.net, id., at 15–16 (describing Web site as resource for
obstetrics, gynecology, and women’s health issues); Brief for
Volunteer Lawyers for the Arts et al. as Amici Curiae 15 (listing works of literature removed from some schools);
Complaint ¶ ;1, Lodging 40–41.
These materials are not both (1)
“designed to appeal to, or . . . pander to, the prurient interest”
of significant groups of minors and (2) lacking in
“serious literary, artistic, political, or scientific value” for
significant groups of minors. §§231(e)(6)(A), (C). Thus, they fall
outside the statute’s definition of the material that it restricts,
a fact the Government acknowledged at oral argument. Tr. of Oral
Arg. 50–51.
I have found nothing elsewhere in the
statute’s language that broadens its scope. Other qualifying
phrases, such as “taking the material as a whole,” §§231(e)(6)(A),
(C), and “for commercial purposes,” §231(a)(1), limit the statute’s
scope still more, requiring, for example, that individual images be
considered in context. See Roth v. United
States, 354 U. S. 476 , 490
(1957). In sum, the Act’s definitions limit the statute’s scope to
commercial pornography. It affects unprotected obscene material.
Given the inevitable uncertainty about how to characterize
close-to-obscene material, it could apply to (or chill the
production of) a limited class of borderline material that courts
might ultimately find is protected. But the examples I have just
given fall outside that class.
B
The Act does not censor the
material it covers. Rather, it requires providers of the “harmful
to minors” material to restrict minors’ access to it by verifying
age. They can do so by inserting screens that verify age using a
credit card, adult personal identification number, or other similar
technology. See §231(c)(1). In this way, the Act requires creation
of an internet screen that minors, but not adults, will find
difficult to bypass.
I recognize that the screening
requirement imposes some burden on adults who seek access to the
regulated material, as well as on its providers. The cost is, in
part, monetary. The parties agreed that a Web site could store card
numbers or passwords at between 15 and 20 cents per number. American Civil Liberties Union v. Reno , 31
F. Supp. 2d 473, 488–489, ¶ ;¶ ;45–47 (ED Pa. 1999). And
verification services provide free verification to Web site
operators, while charging users less than $20 per year. Id., at 489–490, ¶ ;¶ ;48–53. According to the trade
association for the commercial pornographers who are the statute’s
target, use of such verification procedures is “standard practice”
in their online operations. See S. Rep., at 7; Legislative
Proposals to Protect Children from Inappropriate Materials on the
Internet: Hearing on H. R. 3783 et al. before the House
Subcommittee on Telecommunications, Trade and Consumer Protection
of the House Committee on Commerce, 105th Cong., 2d Sess., 46, 48
(1998) (prepared statement of Jeffrey J. Douglas, Executive
Director and Chairman, Free Speech Coalition (calling the proposed
child-protecting mechanisms “effective and appropriate”)).
In addition to the monetary cost, and despite
strict requirements that identifying information be kept
confidential, see 47 U. S. C. §§231(d)(1), 501, the
identification requirements inherent in age-screening may lead some
users to fear embarrassment. See 31 F. Supp. 2d, at 495. Both
monetary costs and potential embarrassment can deter potential
viewers and, in that sense, the statute’s requirements may restrict
access to a site. But this Court has held that in the context of
congressional efforts to protect children, restrictions of this
kind do not automatically violate the Constitution. And the Court
has approved their use. See, e.g., United States v. American Library Assn., Inc., 539 U. S. 194 , 209
(2003) (plurality opinion) (“[T]he Constitution does not guarantee
the right to acquire information at a public library without any
risk of embarrassment”). Cf. Reno, 521 U. S., at 890
(O’Connor, J., concurring in judgment in part and dissenting in
part) (calling the age-verification requirement similar to “a
bouncer [who] checks a person’s driver’s license before admitting
him to a nightclub”).
In sum, the Act at most imposes a modest
additional burden on adult access to legally obscene material,
perhaps imposing a similar burden on access to some protected
borderline obscene material as well.
II
I turn next to the question of
“compelling interest,” that of protecting minors from exposure to
commercial pornography. No one denies that such an interest is
“compelling.” See Denver Area Ed. Telecommunications
Consortium, Inc., 518 U. S., at 743 (opinion of Breyer, J.)
(interest in protecting minors is “compelling”); Sable
Communications , 492 U. S., at 126 (same); Ginsberg v. New York, 390 U. S. 629 , 639–640
(1968). Rather, the question here is whether the Act, given its
restrictions on adult access, significantly advances that interest.
In other words, is the game worth the candle?
The majority argues that it is
not, because of the existence of “blocking and filtering software.” Ante, at 8–12. The majority refers to the presence of that
software as a “less restrictive alternative.” But that is a
misnomer—a misnomer that may lead the reader to believe that all we
need do is look to see if the blocking and filtering software is
less restrictive; and to believe that, because in one sense it is
(one can turn off the software), that is the end of the
constitutional matter.
But such reasoning has no place here.
Conceptually speaking, the presence of filtering software is not an alternative legislative approach to the problem of
protecting children from exposure to commercial pornography.
Rather, it is part of the status quo, i.e., the backdrop
against which Congress enacted the present statute. It is always
true, by definition, that the status quo is less restrictive than a
new regulatory law. It is always less restrictive to do nothing than to do something . But “doing nothing”
does not address the problem Congress sought to address—namely
that, despite the availability of filtering software, children were
still being exposed to harmful material on the Internet.
Thus, the relevant constitutional question is
not the question the Court asks: Would it be less restrictive to do
nothing? Of course it would be. Rather, the relevant question
posits a comparison of (a) a status quo that includes filtering
software with (b) a change in that status quo that adds to it an
age-verification screen requirement. Given the existence of
filtering software, does the problem Congress identified remain
significant? Does the Act help to address it? These are questions
about the relation of the Act to the compelling interest. Does the
Act, compared to the status quo, significantly advance the ball?
(An affirmative answer to these questions will not justify “[a]ny
restriction on speech,” as the Court claims, ante , at 8,
for a final answer in respect to constitutionality must take
account of burdens and alternatives as well.)
The answers to these intermediate
questions are clear: Filtering software, as presently available,
does not solve the “child protection” problem. It suffers from four
serious inadequacies that prompted Congress to pass legislation
instead of relying on its voluntary use. First, its filtering is
faulty, allowing some pornographic material to pass through without
hindrance. Just last year, in American Library Assn. ,
Justice Stevens described “fundamental defects in the filtering
software that is now available or that will be available in the
foreseeable future.” 539 U. S., at 221 (dissenting opinion). He
pointed to the problem of underblocking: “Because the software
relies on key words or phrases to block undesirable sites, it does
not have the capacity to exclude a precisely defined category of
images.” Ibid. That is to say, in the absence of words,
the software alone cannot distinguish between the most obscene
pictorial image and the Venus de Milo. No Member of this Court
disagreed.
Second, filtering software costs
money. Not every family has the $40 or so necessary to install it.
See 31 F. Supp. 2d, at 492, ¶ ;65. By way of contrast, age
screening costs less. See supra, at 7 (citing costs of up
to 20 cents per password or $20 per user for an identification
number).
Third, filtering software depends upon parents
willing to decide where their children will surf the Web and able
to enforce that decision. As to millions of American families, that
is not a reasonable possibility. More than 28 million school age
children have both parents or their sole parent in the work force,
at least 5 million children are left alone at home without
supervision each week, and many of those children will spend
afternoons and evenings with friends who may well have access to
computers and more lenient parents. See United States v. Playboy Entertainment Group, Inc., 529 U. S. 803 , 842
(2000) (Breyer, J., dissenting).
Fourth, software blocking lacks precision,
with the result that those who wish to use it to screen out
pornography find that it blocks a great deal of material that is
valuable. As Justice Stevens pointed out, “the software’s reliance
on words to identify undesirable sites necessarily results in the
blocking of thousands of pages that contain content that is
completely innocuous for both adults and minors, and that no
rational person could conclude matches the filtering companies’
category definitions, such as pornography or sex.” American
Library Assn., supra, at 222 (internal quotation marks and
citations omitted). Indeed, the American Civil Liberties Union
(ACLU), one of the respondents here, told Congress that filtering
software “block[s] out valuable and protected information, such as
information about the Quaker religion, and web sites including
those of the American Association of University Women, the AIDS
Quilt, the Town Hall Political Site (run by the Family Resource
Center, Christian Coalition and other conservative groups).”
Hearing on Internet Indecency before the Senate Committee on
Commerce, Science, and Transportation, 105th Cong., 2d Sess., 64
(1998). The software “is simply incapable of discerning between
constitutionally protected and unprotected speech.” Id., at 65. It “inappropriately blocks valuable, protected speech, and
does not effectively block the sites [it is] intended to block.” Id., at 66 (citing reports documenting overblocking).
Nothing in the District Court record suggests
the contrary. No respondent has offered to produce evidence at
trial to the contrary. No party has suggested, for example, that
technology allowing filters to interpret and discern among images
has suddenly become, or is about to become, widely available.
Indeed, the Court concedes that “[f]iltering software, of course,
is not a perfect solution to the problem.” Ante, at
10.
In sum, a “filtering software status quo”
means filtering that underblocks, imposes a cost upon each family
that uses it, fails to screen outside the home, and lacks
precision. Thus, Congress could reasonably conclude that a system
that relies entirely upon the use of such software is not an
effective system. And a law that adds to that system an
age-verification screen requirement significantly increases the
system’s efficacy. That is to say, at a modest additional cost to
those adults who wish to obtain access to a screened program, that
law will bring about better, more precise blocking, both inside and
outside the home.
The Court’s response—that 40% of all
pornographic material may be of foreign origin—is beside the point. Ante, at 9 (citing the District Court’s findings). Even
assuming (I believe unrealistically) that all foreign
originators will refuse to use screening, the Act would make a
difference in respect to 60% of the Internet’s commercial
pornography. I cannot call that difference insignificant.
The upshot is that Congress could
reasonably conclude that, despite the current availability of
filtering software, a child protection problem exists. It also
could conclude that a precisely targeted regulatory statute, adding
an age-verification requirement for a narrow range of material,
would more effectively shield children from commercial
pornography.
Is this justification sufficient?
The lower courts thought not. But that is because those courts
interpreted the Act as imposing far more than a modest burden. They
assumed an interpretation of the statute in which it reached far
beyond legally obscene and borderline-obscene material, affecting
material that, given the interpretation set forth above, would fall
well outside the Act’s scope. But we must interpret the Act to save
it, not to destroy it. NLRB v. Jones & Laughlin
Steel Corp., 301
U. S. 1 , 30 (1937). So interpreted, see supra, at 3–6,
the Act imposes a far lesser burden on access to protected
material. Given the modest nature of that burden and the likelihood
that the Act will significantly further Congress’ compelling
objective, the Act may well satisfy the First Amendment’s stringent
tests. Cf. Sable Communications , 492 U. S., at 130.
Indeed, it does satisfy the First Amendment unless, of course,
there is a genuine alternative, “less restrictive” way similarly to
further that objective.
III
I turn, then, to the actual “less
restrictive alternatives” that the Court proposes. The Court
proposes two real alternatives, i.e., two potentially less
restrictive ways in which Congress might alter the status quo in
order to achieve its “compelling” objective.
First, the Government might “act
to encourage” the use of blocking and filtering software. Ante, at 11. The problem is that any argument that rests
upon this alternative proves too much. If one imagines enough
government resources devoted to the problem and perhaps additional
scientific advances, then, of course, the use of software might
become as effective and less restrictive. Obviously, the Government
could give all parents, schools, and Internet cafes free computers
with filtering programs already installed, hire federal employees
to train parents and teachers on their use, and devote millions of
dollars to the development of better software. The result might be
an alternative that is extremely effective.
But the Constitution does not, because it
cannot, require the Government to disprove the existence of magic
solutions, i.e., solutions that, put in general terms,
will solve any problem less restrictively but with equal
effectiveness.
Otherwise, “the undoubted ability of lawyers and judges,” who
are not constrained by the budgetary worries and other practical
parameters within which Congress must operate, “to imagine some kind of slightly less drastic or restrictive an
approach would make it impossible to write laws that deal with the
harm that called the statute into being.” Playboy Entertainment
Group, 529 U. S., at 841 (Breyer, J., dissenting). As Justice
Blackmun recognized, a “judge would be unimaginative indeed if he
could not come up with something a little less ‘drastic’ or a
little less ‘restrictive’ in almost any situation, and thereby
enable himself to vote to strike legislation down.” Illinois
Bd. of Elections v. Socialist Workers
Party, 440
U. S. 173 , 188–189 (1979) (concurring opinion). Perhaps that is
why no party has argued seriously that additional expenditure of
government funds to encourage the use of screening is a “less
restrictive alternative.”
Second, the majority suggests decriminalizing
the statute, noting the “chilling effect” of criminalizing a
category of speech. Ante, at 9. To remove a major
sanction, however, would make the statute less effective, virtually
by definition.
IV
My conclusion is that the Act, as
properly interpreted, risks imposition of minor burdens on some
protected material—burdens that adults wishing to view the material
may overcome at modest cost. At the same time, it significantly
helps to achieve a compelling congressional goal, protecting
children from exposure to commercial pornography. There is no
serious, practically available “less restrictive” way similarly to
further this compelling interest. Hence the Act is
constitutional.
V
The Court’s holding raises two
more general questions. First, what has happened to the
“constructive discourse between our courts and our legislatures”
that “is an integral and admirable part of the constitutional
design”? Blakely v. Washington, ante, at 1
(Kennedy, J., dissenting). After eight years of legislative effort,
two statutes, and three Supreme Court cases the Court sends this
case back to the District Court for further proceedings. What
proceedings? I have found no offer by either party to present more
relevant evidence. What remains to be litigated? I know the Court
says that the parties may “introduce further evidence” as to the
“relative restrictiveness and effectiveness of alternatives to the
statute.” Ante , at 14–15. But I do not understand what
that new evidence might consist of.
Moreover, Congress passed the
current statute “[i]n response to the Court’s decision in Reno ” striking down an earlier statutory effort to deal
with the same problem. Ante, at 3. Congress read Reno with care. It dedicated itself to the task of
drafting a statute that would meet each and every criticism of the
predecessor statute that this Court set forth in Reno. It
incorporated language from the Court’s precedents, particularly the Miller standard, virtually verbatim. Compare 413 U. S., at
24, with §231(e)(6). And it created what it believed was a statute
that would protect children from exposure to obscene professional
pornography without obstructing adult access to material that the
First Amendment protects. See H. R. Rep., at 5 (explaining
that the bill was “carefully drafted to respond to the Supreme
Court’s decision in Reno” ); S. Rep., at 2
(same). What else was Congress supposed to do?
I recognize that some Members of the Court,
now or in the past, have taken the view that the First Amendment
simply does not permit Congress to legislate in this area. See, e.g., Ginzburg, 383 U. S., at 476 (Black, J., dissenting)
(“[T]he Federal Government is without any power whatever under the
Constitution to put any type of burden on speech and expression of
ideas of any kind”). Others believe that the Amendment does not
permit Congress to legislate in certain ways, e.g., through the imposition of criminal penalties for obscenity. See, e.g., ante, at 2 (Stevens, J., concurring). There
are strong constitutional arguments favoring these views. But the
Court itself does not adopt those views. Instead, it finds that the
Government has not proved the nonexistence of “less restrictive
alternatives.” That finding, if appropriate here, is universally
appropriate. And if universally appropriate, it denies to Congress,
in practice, the legislative leeway that the Court’s language seem
to promise. If this statute does not pass the Court’s “less
restrictive alternative” test, what does? If nothing does, then the
Court should say so clearly.
As I have explained, I believe the First
Amendment permits an alternative holding. We could construe the
statute narrowly—as I have tried to do—removing nearly all
protected material from its scope. By doing so, we could reconcile
its language with the First Amendment’s demands. We would “save”
the statute, “not . . . destroy it.” NLRB, 301 U. S., at
30. Accord, McConnell v. Federal Election Comm’n, 540 U. S. __, __ (2003) (slip op., at 72) (where a saving
construction of the statute’s language “ ‘is fairly
possible,’ ” we must adopt it (quoting Crowell v. Benson, 285 U.S.
22 , 62 (1932))). And in the process, we would permit Congress
to achieve its basic child-protecting objectives.
Second, will the majority’s holding in
practice mean greater or lesser protection for expression? I do not
find the answer to this question obvious. The Court’s decision
removes an important weapon from the prosecutorial arsenal. That
weapon would have given the Government a choice—a choice other than
“ban totally or do nothing at all.” The Act tells the Government
that, instead of prosecuting bans on obscenity to the maximum
extent possible (as respondents have urged as yet another
“alternative”), it can insist that those who make available
material that is obscene or close to obscene keep that material
under wraps, making it readily available to adults who wish to see
it, while restricting access to children. By providing this third
option—a “middle way”—the Act avoids the need for potentially
speech-suppressing prosecutions.
That matters in a world where the obscene and
the nonobscene do not come tied neatly into separate, easily
distinguishable, packages. In that real world, this middle way
might well have furthered First Amendment interests by tempering
the prosecutorial instinct in borderline cases. At least, Congress
might have so believed. And this likelihood, from a First Amendment
perspective, might ultimately have proved more protective of the
rights of viewers to retain access to expression than the
all-or-nothing choice available to prosecutors in the wake of the
majority’s opinion.
For these reasons, I dissent. | The Supreme Court upheld a lower court's decision to block the enforcement of the Child Online Protection Act (COPA), a federal statute designed to protect minors from accessing sexually explicit material online. The Court found that the government failed to demonstrate the constitutionality of COPA's content-based restrictions on speech and did not present sufficient evidence to rebut arguments for less restrictive alternatives to the statute. The case was remanded for further proceedings. |
Free Speech | Ashcroft v. ACLU I | https://supreme.justia.com/cases/federal/us/535/564/ | OCTOBER TERM, 2001
Syllabus
ASHCROFT, ATTORNEY GENERAL v. AMERICAN CIVIL LIBERTIES
UNION ET AL.
CERTIORARI TO THE UNITED STATES COURT OF APPEALS FOR THE THIRD
CIRCUIT
No. 00-1293. Argued November 28, 200l-Decided May 13,2002
In Reno v. American Civil Liberties Union, 521 U. S. 844 ,
this Court found that the Communications Decency Act of 1996
(CDA)-Congress' first attempt to protect children from exposure to
pornographic material on the Internet-ran afoul of the First
Amendment in its regulation of indecent transmissions and the
display of patently offensive material. That conclusion was based,
in part, on the crucial consideration that the CDA's breadth was
wholly unprecedented. After the Court's decision in Reno, Congress attempted to address this concern in the Child Online
Protection Act (COPA). Unlike the CDA, COPA applies only to
material displayed on the World Wide Web, covers only
communications made for commercial purposes, and restricts only
"material that is harmful to minors," 47 U. S. C. § 231(a)(I). In
defining "material that is harmful to minors," COPA draws on the
three-part obscenity test set forth in Miller v. California, 413
U. S. 15 , see § 231(e)(6), and thus requires jurors to apply
"contemporary community standards" in assessing material, see
§231(e)(6)(A). Respondents-who post or have members that post
sexually oriented material on the Web-filed a facial challenge
before COPA went into effect, claiming, inter alia, that the
statute violated adults' First Amendment rights because it
effectively banned constitutionally protected speech, was not the
least restrictive means of accomplishing a compelling governmental
purpose, and was substantially overbroad. The District Court issued
a preliminary injunction barring the enforcement of COPA because it
concluded that the statute was unlikely to survive strict scrutiny.
The Third Circuit affirmed but based its decision on a ground not
relied upon by the District Court: that COPA's use of "contemporary
community standards," § 231(e)(6)(A), to identify material that is
harmful to minors rendered the statute substantially overbroad. Held: COPA's reliance on "community standards" to
identify what material "is harmful to minors" does not by itself
render the statute substantially overbroad for First Amendment
purposes. The Court, however, expresses no view as to whether COPA
suffers from substantial overbreadth for reasons other than its use
of community standards, whether the statute is unconstitutionally
vague, or whether the statute survives 565 strict scrutiny. Prudence dictates allowing the Third Circuit to
first examine these difficult issues. Because petitioner did not
ask to have the preliminary injunction vacated, and because this
Court could not do so without addressing matters the Third Circuit
has yet to consider, the Government remains enjoined from enforcing
COPA absent further action by the lower courts. Pp. 585-586. 217 F.3d
162 , vacated and remanded.
THOMAS, J., announced the judgment of the Court and delivered
the opinion of the Court with respect to Parts I, II, and IV, in
which REHNQUIST, C. J., and O'CONNOR, SCALIA, and BREYER, JJ.,
joined, an opinion with respect to Part III-B, in which REHNQUIST,
C. J., and O'CONNOR and SCALIA, JJ., joined, and an opinion with
respect to Parts III -A, III -C, and III-D, in which
REHNQUIST, C. J., and SCALIA, J., joined. O'CONNOR, J., post, p. 586, and BREYER, J., post, p. 589, filed
opinions concurring in part and concurring in the judgment.
KENNEDY, J., filed an opinion concurring in the judgment, in which
SOUTER and GINSBURG, JJ., joined, post, p. 591. STEVENS, J.,
filed a dissenting opinion, post, p. 602. Solicitor General Olson argued the cause for
petitioner.
With him on the briefs were Acting Assistant Attorney General
Schiffer, Deputy Solicitor General Kneedler, Irving L. Gornstein,
Barbara L. Herwig, Jacob M. Lewis, and Charles Scarborough.
Ann E. Beeson argued the cause for respondents. With her on the
briefs were Christopher A. Hansen, Steven R. Shapiro, Stefan
Presser, David L. Sobel, Alexandra A. E. Shapiro, and Christopher
R. Harris. * *Briefs of amici curiae urging reversal were filed for
the County of DuPage by Richard Hodyl, Jr., Joseph E.
Birkett, and Nancy J. Wolfe; for the
American Center for Law and Justice by Jay Alan Sekulow, James
M. Henderson, Sr., Colby M. May, and Walter M. Weber; for Morality in Media, Inc., et al. by Paul J. McGeady, Robin S. Whitehead, and Janet M.
LaRue; for Wallbuilders, Inc., by Barry C. Hodge; for Senator John S. McCain et al. by Bruce A. Taylor; and
for Senator Raymond N. Haynes et al. by Richard D. Ackerman and Gary G. Kreep. Briefs of amici curiae urging affirmance were filed for
the American Society of Journalists and Authors et al. by Carl
A. Solano, Theresa E. Loscalzo, Jennifer DuFault James, Joseph T.
Lukens, and Dionna K. Litvin; for the Association of
National Advertisers, Inc., by Steven G. Brody 566 566 ASHCROFT v. AMERICAN CIVIL LIBERTIES UNION
JUSTICE THOMAS announced the judgment of the Court and delivered
the opinion of the Court with respect to Parts I, II, and IV, an
opinion with respect to Parts III-A, III-C, and III-D, in which THE
CHIEF JUSTICE and JUSTICE SCALIA join, and an opinion with respect
to Part III-B, in which THE CHIEF JUSTICE, JUSTICE O'CONNOR, and
JusTICE SCALIA join.
This case presents the narrow question whether the Child Online
Protection Act's (COPA or Act) use of "community standards" to
identify "material that is harmful to minors" violates the First
Amendment. We hold that this aspect of COPA does not render the
statute facially unconstitutional.
I
"The Internet ... offer[s] a forum for a true diversity of
political discourse, unique opportunities for cultural development,
and myriad avenues for intellectual activity." 47 U. S. C. §
230(a)(3) (1994 ed., Supp. V). While "surfing" the World Wide Web,
the primary method of remote information retrieval on the Internet
today,1 see App. in No. 99-1324 (CA3), p. 180 (hereinafter
App.), individuals can access material about topics ranging from
aardvarks to Zoroastrianism. One can use the Web to read thousands
of newspapers published around the globe, purchase tickets for a
matinee at the neighborhood movie theater, or follow the progress
of any Major League Baseball team on a pitch-by-pitch basis.
The Web also contains a wide array of sexually explicit
material, including hardcore pornography. See, e. g., Amer- and Gilbert H. Weil; for the Association of American
Publishers, Inc., et al. by R. Bruce Rich and Jonathan
Bloom; for the Chamber of Commerce of the United States by Jodie L. Kelley, Paul M. Smith, and Robert
CornRevere; for the Society for the Scientific Study of
Sexuality et al. by Marjorie Heins and Joan E.
Bertin; and for Volunteer Lawyers for the Arts et al. by Charles L. Kerr, Elliot M. Mincberg, and Lawrence S. Ottinger. 1 For a thorough explanation of the history, structure, and
operation of the Internet and World Wide Web, see Reno v. American Civil Liberties Union, 521 U. S. 844 , 849-853
(1997). 567 ican Civil Liberties Union v. Reno, 31 F. Supp. 2d
473, 484 (ED Pa. 1999). In 1998, for instance, there were
approximately 28,000 adult sites promoting pornography on the Web.
See H. R. Rep. No. 105-775, p. 7 (1998). Because "[n]avigating the
Web is relatively straightforward," Reno v. American
Civil Liberties Union, 521 U. S. 844 , 852
(1997), and access to the Internet is widely available in homes,
schools, and libraries across the country,2 see App. 177-178,
children may discover this pornographic material either by
deliberately accessing pornographic Web sites or by stumbling upon
them. See 31 F. Supp. 2d, at 476 ("A child with minimal knowledge
of a computer, the ability to operate a browser, and the skill to
type a few simple words may be able to access sexual images and
content over the World Wide Web").
Congress first attempted to protect children from exposure to
pornographic material on the Internet by enacting the
Communications Decency Act of 1996 (CDA), 110 Stat. 133. The CDA prohibited the knowing transmission over the Internet of
obscene or indecent messages to any recipient under 18 years of
age. See 47 U. S. C. § 223(a). It also forbade any individual from
knowingly sending over or displaying on the Internet certain
"patently offensive" material in a manner available to persons
under 18 years of age. See § 223(d). The prohibition specifically
extended to "any comment, request, suggestion, proposal, image, or
other communication that, in context, depict[ed] or describ[ed], in
terms patently offensive as measured by contemporary community
standards, sexual or excretory activities or organs." §
223(d)(1).
2 When this litigation commenced in 1998, "[a]pproximately 70.2
million people of all ages use[d] the Internet in the United
States." App. 171. It is now estimated that 115.2 million Americans
use the Internet at least once a month and 176.5 million Americans
have Internet access either at home or at work. See More Americans
Online, New York Times, Nov. 19, 2001, p. C7. 568 568 ASHCROFT v. AMERICAN CIVIL LIBERTIES UNION
The CDA provided two affirmative defenses to those
prosecuted under the statute. The first protected individuals who
took "good faith, reasonable, effective, and appropriate actions"
to restrict minors from accessing obscene, indecent, and patently
offensive material over the Internet. See § 223(e)(5)(A). The
second shielded those who restricted minors from accessing such
material "by requiring use of a verified credit card, debit
account, adult access code, or adult personal identification
number." § 223(e)(5)(B).
Notwithstanding these affirmative defenses, in Reno v. American Civil Liberties Union, we held that the CDA's
regulation of indecent transmissions, see § 223(a), and the display
of patently offensive material, see § 223(d), ran afoul of the
First Amendment. We concluded that "the CDA lack[ed] the
precision that the First Amendment requires when a statute
regulates the content of speech" because, "[i]n order to deny
minors access to potentially harmful speech, the CDA effectively suppress[ed] a large amount of speech that adults ha[d]
a constitutional right to receive and to address to one another."
521 U. S., at 874.
Our holding was based on three crucial considerations.
First, "existing technology did not include any effective method
for a sender to prevent minors from obtaining access to its
communications on the Internet without also denying access to
adults." Id., at 876. Second, "[t]he breadth of the CDA's
coverage [was] wholly unprecedented." Id., at 877. "Its
open-ended prohibitions embrace[d]," not only commercial speech or
commercial entities, but also "all nonprofit entities and
individuals posting indecent messages or displaying them on their
own computers in the presence of minors." Ibid. In addition,
because the CDA did not define the terms "indecent" and
"patently offensive," the statute "cover[ed] large amounts of
nonpornographic material with serious educational or other value." Ibid. As a result, regulated subject matter under the CDA extended to "discussions about prison rape or safe
sexual practices, artistic images that include nude subjects, and
arguably the card 569 catalog of the Carnegie Library." Id., at 878. Third, we
found that neither affirmative defense set forth in the CDA "constitute[d] the sort of 'narrow tailoring' that [would] save an
otherwise patently invalid unconstitutional provision." Id., at 882. Consequently, only the CDA's ban on the knowing
transmission of obscene messages survived scrutiny because obscene
speech enjoys no First Amendment protection. See id., at
883.
After our decision in Reno v. American Civil Liberties
Union, Congress explored other avenues for restricting minors'
access to pornographic material on the Internet. In particular,
Congress passed and the President signed into law the Child Online
Protection Act, 112 Stat. 2681-736 (codified in 47 U. S. C. § 231
(1994 ed., Supp. V)). COPA prohibits any person from "knowingly and
with knowledge of the character of the material, in interstate or
foreign commerce by means of the World Wide Web, mak[ing] any
communication for commercial purposes that is available to any
minor and that includes any material that is harmful to minors." 47
U. S. C. § 231(a)(1).
Apparently responding to our objections to the breadth of the
CDA's coverage, Congress limited the scope of COPA's coverage in at
least three ways. First, while the CDA applied to
communications over the Internet as a whole, including, for
example, e-mail messages, COPA applies only to material displayed
on the World Wide Web. Second, unlike the CDA, COPA covers
only communications made "for commercial purposes." 3 Ibid. And third, while the CDA pro-
3 The statute provides that "[a] person shall be considered to
make a communication for commercial purposes only if such person is
engaged in the business of making such communications." 47 U. S. C.
§231(e)(2)(A) (1994 ed., Supp. V). COPA then defines the term
"engaged in the business" to mean a person:
"who makes a communication, or offers to make a communication,
by means of the World Wide Web, that includes any material that is
harmful to minors, devotes time, attention, or labor to such
activities, as a regular course of such person's trade or business,
with the objective of earning a profit as a result of such
activities (although it is not necessary that the 570 570 ASHCROFT v. AMERICAN CIVIL LIBERTIES UNION
hibited "indecent" and "patently offensive" communications, COPA
restricts only the narrower category of "material that is harmful
to minors." Ibid. Drawing on the three-part test for obscenity set forth in Miller v. California, 413 U. S. 15 (1973), COPA
defines "material that is harmful to minors" as "any communication, picture, image, graphic image file, article,
recording, writing, or other matter of any kind that is obscene or
that- "(A) the average person, applying contemporary community
standards, would find, taking the material as a whole and with
respect to minors, is designed to appeal to, or is designed to
pander to, the prurient interest; "(B) depicts, describes, or represents, in a manner patently
offensive with respect to minors, an actual or simulated sexual act
or sexual contact, an actual or simulated normal or perverted
sexual act, or a lewd exhibition of the genitals or post-pubescent
female breast; and "(C) taken as a whole, lacks serious literary, artistic,
political, or scientific value for minors." 47 U. S. C. §
231(e)(6). Like the CDA, COPA also provides affirmative defenses to
those subject to prosecution under the statute. An individual may
qualify for a defense if he, "in good faith, has restricted access
by minors to material that is harmful to minors-(A) by requiring
the use of a credit card, debit account, adult access code, or
adult personal identification number; (B) by accepting a digital
certificate that verifies age; or (C) by any other
reasonable measures that are feasible under available technology."
§ 231(c)(1). Persons violating COPA are subject to both civil and
criminal sanctions. A civil penalty of up to $50,000 may be imposed
for each violation of
person make a profit or that the making or offering to make such
communications be the person's sole or principal business or source
of income)." § 231(e)(2)(B). 571 the statute. Criminal penalties consist of up to six months in
prison and/or a maximum fine of $50,000. An additional fine of
$50,000 may be imposed for any intentional violation of the
statute. § 231(a).
One month before COPA was scheduled to go into effect,
respondents filed a lawsuit challenging the constitutionality of
the statute in the United States District Court for the Eastern
District of Pennsylvania. Respondents are a diverse group of
organizations,4 most of which maintain their own Web sites. While
the vast majority of content on their Web sites is available for
free, respondents all derive income from their sites. Some, for
example, sell advertising that is displayed on their Web sites,
while others either sell goods directly over their sites or charge
artists for the privilege of posting material. 31 F. Supp. 2d, at
487. All respondents either post or have members that post sexually
oriented material on the Web. Id., at 480. Respondents' Web
sites contain "resources on obstetrics, gynecology, and sexual
health; visual art and poetry; resources designed for gays and
lesbians; information about books and stock photographic images
offered for sale; and online magazines." Id., at 484.
In their complaint, respondents alleged that, although they
believed that the material on their Web sites was valuable for
adults, they feared that they would be prosecuted under COPA
because some of that material "could be construed as 'harmful to
minors' in some communities." App. 63. Respondents' facial
challenge claimed, inter alia, that COPA violated adults'
rights under the First and Fifth Amend-
4 Respondents include the American Civil Liberties Union,
Androgony Books, Inc., d/b/a A Different Light Bookstores, the
American Booksellers Foundation for Free Expression, Artnet
Worldwide Corporation, BlackStripe, Addazi Inc. d/b/a Condomania,
the Electronic Frontier Foundation, the Electronic Privacy
Information Center, Free Speech Media, OBGYN.net, Philadelphia Gay
News, PlanetOut Corporation, Powell's Bookstore, Riotgrrl, Salon
Internet, Inc., and West Stock, Inc., now known as ImageState North
America, Inc. 572 572 ASHCROFT v. AMERICAN CIVIL LIBERTIES UNION
ments because it (1) "create[d] an effective ban on
constitutionally protected speech by and to adults"; (2) "[was] not
the least restrictive means of accomplishing any compelling
governmental purpose"; and (3) "[was] substantially overbroad." 5 Id., at 100-10l.
The District Court granted respondents' motion for a preliminary
injunction, barring the Government from enforcing the Act until the
merits of respondents' claims could be adjudicated. 31 F. Supp. 2d,
at 499. Focusing on respondents' claim that COPA abridged the free
speech rights of adults, the District Court concluded that
respondents had established a likelihood of success on the merits. Id., at 498. The District Court reasoned that because COPA
constitutes content-based regulation of sexual expression protected
by the First Amendment, the statute, under this Court's precedents,
was "presumptively invalid" and "subject to strict scrutiny." Id., at 493. The District Court then held that respondents
were likely to establish at trial that COPA could not withstand
such scrutiny because, among other reasons, it was not apparent
that COPA was the least restrictive means of preventing minors from
accessing "harmful to minors" material. Id., at 497.
The Attorney General of the United States appealed the District
Court's ruling. American Civil Liberties Union v. Reno, 217 F.3d
162 (CA3 2000). The United States Court of Appeals for
the Third Circuit affirmed. Rather than reviewing the District
Court's "holding that COPA was not likely to succeed in surviving
strict scrutiny analysis," the Court of Appeals based its decision
entirely on a ground that was not relied upon below and that was
"virtually ignored by the parties and the amicus in their
respective briefs." I d., at 173-174. The Court of Appeals
concluded that
5 In three other claims, which are not relevant to resolving the
dispute at hand, respondents alleged that COPA infringed the free
speech rights of older minors, violated the right to "communicate
and access information anonymously," and was "unconstitutionally
vague." App. 101-102. 573 COPA's use of "contemporary community standards" to identify
material that is harmful to minors rendered the statute
substantially overbroad. Because "Web publishers are without any
means to limit access to their sites based on the geographic
location of particular Internet users," the Court of Appeals
reasoned that COPA would require "any material that might be deemed
harmful by the most puritan of communities in any state" to be
placed behind an age or credit card verification system. Id., at 175. Hypothesizing that this step would require Web
publishers to shield "vast amounts of material," ibid., the
Court of Appeals was "persuaded that this aspect of COPA, without
reference to its other provisions, must lead inexorably to a
holding of a likelihood of unconstitutionality of the entire COPA
statute," id., at 174.
We granted the Attorney General's petition for certiorari, 532
U. S. 1037 (2001), to review the Court of Appeals' determination
that COPA likely violates the First Amendment because it relies, in
part, on community standards to identify material that is harmful
to minors, and now vacate the Court of Appeals' judgment.
II
The First Amendment states that "Congress shall make no law ...
abridging the freedom of speech." This provision embodies "[o]ur
profound national commitment to the free exchange of ideas." Harte-Hanks Communications, Inc. v. Connaughton, 491 U. S. 657 ,
686 (1989). "[A]s a general matter, 'the First Amendment means that
government has no power to restrict expression because of its
message, its ideas, its subject matter, or its content.'" Bolger v. Youngs Drug Products Corp., 463 U. S. 60 , 65 (1983)
(quoting Police Dept. of Chicago v. Mosley, 408 U. S. 92 , 95 (1972)).
However, this principle, like other First Amendment principles, is
not absolute. Cf. Hustler Magazine, Inc. v. Falwell,
485 U. S. 46, 56 (1988). 574 574 ASHCROFT v. AMERICAN CIVIL LIBERTIES UNION
Obscene speech, for example, has long been held to fall outside
the purview of the First Amendment. See, e. g., Roth v. United States, 354 U. S. 476 , 484-485
(1957). But this Court struggled in the past to define obscenity in
a manner that did not impose an impermissible burden on protected
speech. See Interstate Circuit, Inc. v. Dallas, 390 U. S. 676, 704 (1968) (Harlan, J., concurring in part and
dissenting in part) (referring to the "intractable obscenity
problem"); see also Miller v. California, 413 U. S.,
at 20-23 (reviewing "the somewhat tortured history of th[is]
Court's obscenity decisions"). The difficulty resulted from the
belief that "in the area of freedom of speech and press the courts
must always remain sensitive to any infringement on genuinely
serious literary, artistic, political, or scientific expression." Id., at 22-23.
Ending over a decade of turmoil, this Court in Miller set
forth the governing three-part test for assessing whether material
is obscene and thus unprotected by the First Amendment: "(a)
[W]hether 'the average person, applying contemporary community
standards' would find that the work, taken as a whole, appeals
to the prurient interest; (b) whether the work depicts or
describes, in a patently offensive way, sexual conduct specifically
defined by the applicable state law; and (c) whether the work,
taken as a whole, lacks serious literary, artistic, political, or
scientific value." Id., at 24 (citations omitted; emphasis
added). Miller adopted the use of "community standards" from Roth, which repudiated an earlier approach for assessing
objectionable material. Beginning in the 19th century, English
courts and some American courts allowed material to be evaluated
from the perspective of particularly sensitive persons. See, e.
g., Queen v. Hicklin [1868] L. R. 3 Q. B. 360; see also Roth, 354 U. S., at 488-489, and n. 25 (listing relevant
cases). But in Roth, this Court held that this sensitive
person standard was "unconstitutionally restrictive of 575 the freedoms of speech and press" and approved a standard
requiring that material be judged from the perspective of "the
average person, applying contemporary community standards." Id., at 489. The Court preserved the use of community
standards in formulating the Miller test, explaining that
they furnish a valuable First Amendment safeguard: "[T]he primary
concern ... is to be certain that ... [material] will be judged by
its impact on an average person, rather than a particularly
susceptible or sensitive person-or indeed a totally insensitive
one." Miller, supra, at 33 (internal quotation marks
omitted); see also Hamling v. United States, 418 U. S. 87 , 107 (1974)
(emphasizing that the principal purpose of the community standards
criterion "is to assure that the material is judged neither on the
basis of each juror's personal opinion, nor by its effect on a
particularly sensitive or insensitive person or group").
III
The Court of Appeals, however, concluded that this Court's prior
community standards jurisprudence "has no applicability to the
Internet and the Web" because "Web publishers are currently without
the ability to control the geographic scope of the recipients of
their communications." 217 F. 3d, at 180. We therefore must decide
whether this technological limitation renders COPA's reliance on
community standards constitutionally infirm.6
6While petitioner contends that a speaker on the Web possesses
the ability to communicate only with individuals located in
targeted geographic communities, Brief for Petitioner 29, n. 3, he
stipulated below that "[o]nce a provider posts its content on the
Internet and chooses to make it available to all, it generally
cannot prevent that content from entering any geographic
community." App. 187. The District Court adopted this stipulation
as a finding of fact, see American Civil Liberties Union v. Reno, 31 F. Supp. 2d 473, 484 (ED Pa. 1999), and petitioner
points to no evidence in the record suggesting that this finding is
clearly erroneous. 576 576 ASHCROFT v. AMERICAN CIVIL LIBERTIES UNION
Opinion of THOMAS, J.
A
In addressing this question, the parties first dispute the
nature of the community standards that jurors will be instructed to
apply when assessing, in prosecutions under COPA, whether works
appeal to the prurient interest of minors and are patently
offensive with respect to minors.7 Respondents contend that jurors
will evaluate material using "local community standards," Brief for
Respondents 40, while petitioner maintains that jurors will not
consider the community standards of any particular geographic area,
but rather will be "instructed to consider the standards of the
adult community as a whole, without geographic specification."
Brief for Petitioner 38.
In the context of this case, which involves a facial challenge
to a statute that has never been enforced, we do not think it
prudent to engage in speculation as to whether certain hypothetical
jury instructions would or would not be consistent with COP A, and
deciding this case does not require us to do so. It is sufficient
to note that community standards need not be defined by reference
to a precise geographic area. See Jenkins v. Georgia, 418 U. S. 153 ,
157 (1974) ("A State may choose to define an obscenity offense in
terms of 'contemporary community standards' as defined in Miller without further specification ... or it may choose to
define the standards in more precise geographic terms, as was done
by California in Miller"). Absent geographic
7 Although the phrase "contemporary community standards" appears
only in the "prurient interest" prong of the Miller test,
see Miller v. California, 413 U. S. 15 , 24 (1973),
this Court has indicated that the "patently offensive" prong of the
test is also a question of fact to be decided by a jury applying
contemporary community standards. See, e. g., Pope v. Illinois, 481
U. S. 497 , 500 (1987). The parties here therefore agree that
even though "contemporary community standards" are similarly
mentioned only in the "prurient interest" prong of COPA's
harmful-to-minors definition, see 47 U. S. C. § 231(e)(6)(A),
jurors will apply "contemporary community standards" as well in
evaluating whether material is "patently offensive with respect to
minors," § 231(e)(6)(B). 577 specification, a juror applying community standards will
inevitably draw upon personal "knowledge of the community or
vicinage from which he comes." Hamling, supra, at 105.
Petitioner concedes the latter point, see Reply Brief for
Petitioner 3-4, and admits that, even if jurors were instructed
under COPA to apply the standards of the adult population as a
whole, the variance in community standards across the country could
still cause juries in different locations to reach inconsistent
conclusions as to whether a particular work is "harmful to minors."
Brief for Petitioner 39.
B
Because juries would apply different standards across the
country, and Web publishers currently lack the ability to limit
access to their sites on a geographic basis, the Court of Appeals
feared that COPA's "community standards" component would
effectively force all speakers on the Web to abide by the "most
puritan" community's standards. 217 F. 3d, at 175. And such a
requirement, the Court of Appeals concluded, "imposes an
overreaching burden and restriction on constitutionally protected
speech." Id., at 177.
In evaluating the constitutionality of the CDA, this
Court expressed a similar concern over that statute's use of
community standards to identify patently offensive material on the
Internet. We noted that "the 'community standards' criterion as
applied to the Internet means that any communication available to a
nationwide audience will be judged by the standards of the
community most likely to be offended by the message." Reno, 521 U. S., at 877-878. The Court of Appeals below relied heavily on
this observation, stating that it was "not persuaded that the
Supreme Court's concern with respect to the 'community standards'
criterion has been sufficiently remedied by Congress in COPA." 217
F. 3d, at 174.
The CDA's use of community standards to identify patently
offensive material, however, was particularly problem- 578 578 ASHCROFT v. AMERICAN CIVIL LIBERTIES UNION
Opinion of THOMAS, J.
atic in light of that statute's unprecedented breadth and
vagueness. The statute covered communications depicting or
describing "sexual or excretory activities or organs" that were
"patently offensive as measured by contemporary community
standards"-a standard somewhat similar to the second prong of Miller's three-prong test. But the CDA did not
include any limiting terms resembling Miller's additional
two prongs. See Reno, 521 U. S., at 873. It neither
contained any requirement that restricted material appeal to the
prurient interest nor excluded from the scope of its coverage works
with serious literary, artistic, political, or scientific value. Ibid. The tremendous breadth of the CDA magnified the
impact caused by differences in community standards across the
country, restricting Web publishers from openly displaying a
significant amount of material that would have constituted
protected speech in some communities across the country but run
afoul of community standards in others.
COPA, by contrast, does not appear to suffer from the same flaw
because it applies to significantly less material than did the CDA and defines the harmful-to-minors material restricted by
the statute in a manner parallel to the Miller definition of
obscenity. See supra, at 569-570, 574-575. To fall within
the scope of COPA, works must not only "depic[t], describ[e], or
represen[t], in a manner patently offensive with respect to
minors," particular sexual acts or parts of the anatomy,S they must
also be designed to appeal to the prurient interest of minors and,
"taken as a whole, lac[k] serious
8 While the CDA allowed juries to find material to be patently
offensive so long as it depicted or described "sexual or excretory
activities or organs," COPA specifically delineates the sexual
activities and anatomical features, the depictions of which may be
found to be patently offensive: "an actual or simulated sexual act
or sexual contact, an actual or simulated normal or perverted
sexual act, or a lewd exhibition of the genitals or post-pubescent
female breast." 47 U. S. C. § 231(e)(6)(B). 579 literary, artistic, political, or scientific value for minors."
47 U. S. C. § 231(e)(6).
These additional two restrictions substantially limit the amount
of material covered by the statute. Material appeals to the
prurient interest, for instance, only if it is in some sense
erotic. Cf. Erznoznik v. Jacksonville, 422 U. S. 205 , 213, and
n. 10 (1975).9 Of even more significance, however, is COPA's
exclusion of material with serious value for minors. See 47 U. S.
C. §231(e)(6)(C). In Reno, we emphasized that the serious
value "requirement is particularly important because, unlike the
'patently offensive' and 'prurient interest' criteria, it is not
judged by contemporary community standards." 521 U. S., at 873
(citing Pope v. Illinois, 481 U. S. 497 , 500
(1987)). This is because "the value of [a] work [does not] vary
from community to community based on the degree of local acceptance
it has won." Ibid. Rather, the relevant question is "whether
a reasonable person would find ... value in the material, taken as
a whole." Id., at 501. Thus, the serious value requirement
"allows appellate courts to impose some limitations and regularity
on the definition by setting, as a matter of law, a national
floor for socially redeeming value." Reno, supra, at 873
(emphasis added), a safeguard nowhere present in the CDA.l0
9 JUSTICE STEVENS argues that the "prurient interest" prong does
not "substantially narrow the category of images covered" by COPA
because "[a]rguably every depiction of nudity-partial or full-is in
some sense erotic with respect to minors," post, at 607-608
(dissenting opinion) (emphasis in original). We do not agree. For
example, we have great difficulty understanding how pictures of a
war victim's wounded nude body could reasonably be described under
the vast majority of circumstances as erotic, especially when
evaluated from the perspective of minors. See Webster's Ninth New
Collegiate Dictionary 422 (1991) (defining erotic as "of, devoted
to, or tending to arouse sexual love or desire").
10 JUSTICE STEVENS contends that COPA's serious value prong only
marginally limits the sweep of the statute because it does not
protect all material with serious value but just those works with
serious value for minors. See post, at 608. His
dissenting opinion, however, does not refer to any evidence
supporting this counterintuitive assertion, and there 580 580 ASHCROFT v. AMERICAN CIVIL LIBERTIES UNION
Opinion of THOMAS, J.
C
When the scope of an obscenity statute's coverage is
sufficiently narrowed by a "serious value" prong and a "prurient
interest" prong, we have held that requiring a speaker
disseminating material to a national audience to observe varying
community standards does not violate the First Amendment. In Hamling v. United States, 418 U. S. 87 (1974), this
Court considered the constitutionality of applying community
standards to the determination of whether material is obscene under
18 U. S. C. § 1461, the federal statute prohibiting the mailing of
obscene material. Although this statute does not define obscenity,
the petitioners in Hamling were tried and convicted under
the definition of obscenity set forth in Book Named "John
Cleland's Memoirs of a Woman of Pleasure" v. Attorney
General of Mass., 383 U. S. 413 (1966),
which included both a "prurient interest" requirement and a
requirement that prohibited material be "'utterly without redeeming
social value.'" Hamling, supra, at 99 (quoting Memoirs,
supra, at 418).
Like respondents here, the dissenting opinion in Hamling argued that it was unconstitutional for a federal statute to rely
on community standards to regulate speech. Justice Brennan
maintained that "[n]ational distributors choosing to send their
products in interstate travels [would] be forced to cope with the
community standards of every hamlet into which their goods [might]
wander." 418 U. S., at 144. As a result, he claimed that the
inevitable result of this situation would be "debilitating
self-censorship that abridges the First Amendment rights of the
people." Ibid. This Court, however, rejected Justice Brennan's argument that
the federal mail statute unconstitutionally compelled
is certainly none in the record suggesting that COPA restricts
about the same amount of material as did the CDA. Moreover, JUSTICE
STEVENS does not dispute that COPA's "serious value" prong serves
the important purpose of allowing appellate courts to set "as a
matter of law, a national floor for socially redeeming value." Reno, 521 U. S., at 873. 581 speakers choosing to distribute materials on a national basis to
tailor their messages to the least tolerant community:
"The fact that distributors of allegedly obscene materials may
be subjected to varying community standards in the various federal
judicial districts into which they transmit the materials does not
render a federal statute unconstitutional." Id., at 106.
Fifteen years later, Hamling's holding was reaffirmed in Sable Communications of Cal., Inc. v. FCC, 492 U. S. 115 (1989).
Sable addressed the constitutionality of 47 U. S. C. § 223(b)
(1982 ed., Supp. V), a statutory provision prohibiting the use of
telephones to make obscene or indecent communications for
commercial purposes. The petitioner in that case, a "dial-a-porn"
operator, challenged, in part, that portion of the statute banning
obscene phone messages. Like respondents here, the "dial-a-porn"
operator argued that reliance on community standards to identify
obscene material impermissibly compelled "message senders ... to
tailor all their messages to the least tolerant community." 492 U.
S., at 124.11 Relying on Hamling, however, this Court once
again rebuffed this attack on the use of community standards in a
federal statute of national scope: "There is no constitutional
barrier under Miller to prohibiting communications that are
obscene in some communities under local standards even though they
are not obscene in others. If Sable's audience is comprised of
different communities with different local standards, Sable
ultimately bears the burden of complying with the prohibition on
obscene messages." 492 U. S., at 125-126 (emphasis added).
The Court of Appeals below concluded that Hamling and Sable "are easily distinguished from the present case"
because in both of those cases "the defendants had the ability
11 Although nowhere mentioned in the relevant statutory text,
this Court has held that the Miller test defines regulated
speech for purposes of federal obscenity statutes such as 47 U. S.
C. § 223(b) (1994 ed.). See, e. g., Smith v. United States, 431 U. S. 291 , 299
(1977). 582 582 ASHCROFT v. AMERICAN CIVIL LIBERTIES UNION
Opinion of THOMAS, J.
to control the distribution of controversial material with
respect to the geographic communities into which they released it"
whereas "Web publishers have no such comparable control." 217 F.
3d, at 175-176. In neither Hamling nor Sable, however, was the speaker's ability to target the release of
material into particular geographic areas integral to the legal
analysis. In Hamling, the ability to limit the distribution
of material to targeted communities was not mentioned, let alone
relied upon,12 and in Sable, a dial-a-porn operator's
ability to screen incoming calls from particular areas was
referenced only as a supplemental point, see 492 U. S., at 125.13
In the latter case, this Court made no effort to evaluate how
burdensome it would have been for dial-aporn operators to tailor
their messages to callers from thousands of different communities
across the Nation, instead concluding that the burden of complying
with the statute rested with those companies. See id., at
126.
12 This fact was perhaps omitted because under the federal
statute at issue in Hamling v. United States, 418 U. S. 87 (1974), a defendant could be prosecuted in any district through
which obscene mail passed while it was on route to its destination,
see id., at 143-144 (Brennan, J., dissenting), and a postal
customer obviously lacked the ability to control the path his
letter traveled as it made its way to its intended recipient.
13 JUSTICE STEVENS' contention that this Court "upheld the
application of community standards to a nationwide medium" in Sable due to the fact that "[it] was at least possible" for
dial-a-porn operators to tailor their messages to particular
communities is inaccurate. See post, at 605 (dissenting
opinion). This Court's conclusion clearly did not hinge either on
the fact that dial-a-porn operators could prevent callers in
particular communities from accessing their messages or on an
assessment of how burdensome it would have been for dial-a-porn
operators to take that step. Rather, these companies were required
to abide by the standards of various communities for the sole
reason that they transmitted their material into those communities.
See Sable, 492 U. S., at 126 ("If Sable's audience is
comprised of different communities with different local standards,
Sable ultimately bears the burden of complying with the prohibition
on obscene messages"). 583 While JUSTICE KENNEDY and JUSTICE STEVENS question the
applicability of this Court's community standards jurisprudence to
the Internet, we do not believe that the medium's "unique
characteristics" justify adopting a different approach than that
set forth in Hamling and Sable. See post, at
594-595 (KENNEDY, J., concurring in judgment). If a publisher
chooses to send its material into a particular community, this
Court's jurisprudence teaches that it is the publisher's
responsibility to abide by that community's standards. The
publisher's burden does not change simply because it decides to
distribute its material to every community in the Nation. See Sable, supra, at 125-126. Nor does it change because the
publisher may wish to speak only to those in a "community where
avant garde culture is the norm," post, at 595 (KENNEDY, J.,
concurring in judgment), but nonetheless utilizes a medium that
transmits its speech from coast to coast. If a publisher wishes for
its material to be judged only by the standards of particular
communities, then it need only take the simple step of utilizing a
medium that enables it to target the release of its material into
those communities.14
Respondents offer no other grounds upon which to distinguish
this case from Hamling and Sable. While those cases
involved obscenity rather than material that is harmful to minors,
we have no reason to believe that the practical effect of varying
community standards under COPA, given the statute's definition of
"material that is harmful to minors," is significantly greater than
the practical effect of varying
14 In addition, COPA does not, as JUSTICE KENNEDY suggests,
"'foreclose an entire medium of expression.''' Post, at 596
(quoting City of Ladue v. Gilleo, 512 U. S. 43 , 55 (1994)).
While JUSTICE KENNEDY and JUSTICE STEVENS repeatedly imply that
COPA banishes from the Web material deemed harmful to minors by
reference to community standards, see, e. g., post, at 596
(opinion concurring in judgment); post, at 608-609, 612
(dissenting opinion), the statute does no such thing. It only
requires that such material be placed behind adult identification
screens. 584 584 ASHCROFT v. AMERICAN CIVIL LIBERTIES UNION
Opinion of THOMAS, J.
community standards under federal obscenity statutes. It is
noteworthy, for example, that respondents fail to point out even a
single exhibit in the record as to which coverage under COPA would
depend upon which community in the country evaluated the material.
As a result, if we were to hold COPA unconstitutional because
of its use of community standards, federal obscenity statutes
would likely also be unconstitutional as applied to the Web,15 a
result in substantial tension with our prior suggestion that the
application of the CDA to obscene speech was constitutional.
See Reno, 521 U. S., at 877, n. 44, 882-883.
D
Respondents argue that COPA is "unconstitutionally overbroad"
because it will require Web publishers to shield some material
behind age verification screens that could be displayed openly in
many communities across the Nation if Web speakers were able to
limit access to their sites on a geographic basis. Brief for
Respondents 33-34. "[T]o prevail in a facial challenge," however,
"it is not enough for a plaintiff to show 'some' overbreadth." Reno, supra, at 896 (O'CONNOR, J., concurring in judgment in
part and dissenting in part). Rather, "the overbreadth of a statute
must not only be real, but substantial as well." Broadrick v. Okla homa, 413 U. S. 601 , 615
(1973). At this stage of the litigation, respondents have failed to
satisfy this burden, at least solely as a result of COPA's reliance
on community standards.16 Because Congress has narrowed the range
of con-
15 Obscene material, for instance, explicitly falls within the
coverage of COPA. See 47 U. S. C. §231(e)(6) (1994 ed., Supp.
V).
16 JUSTICE STEVENS' conclusion to the contrary is based on
little more than "speculation." See, e. g., post, at 598 (KENNEDY, J., concurring in judgment). The only
objective evidence cited in the dissenting opinion for the
proposition that COPA "will restrict a substantial amount of
protected speech that would not be considered harmful to minors in
many communities" are various anecdotes compiled in an amici brief. See post, at 611, and n. 7 (citing Brief for
Volunteer Lawyers for the Arts et al. as Amici 585 tent restricted by COPA in a manner analogous to Miller's definition of obscenity, we conclude, consistent with our holdings
in Hamling and Sable, that any variance caused by the
statute's reliance on community standards is not substantial enough
to violate the First Amendment.
IV
The scope of our decision today is quite limited. We hold only
that COPA's reliance on community standards to identify "material
that is harmful to minors" does not by itself render the
statute substantially overbroad for purposes of the First
Amendment. We do not express any view as to whether COPA suffers
from substantial overbreadth for other reasons, whether the statute
is unconstitutionally vague, or whether the District Court
correctly concluded that the statute likely will not survive strict
scrutiny analy- Curiae 4-10). JUSTICE STEVENS, however, is not even
willing to represent that these anecdotes relate to material
restricted under COPA, see post, at 611, and we understand
his reluctance for the vast majority of the works cited in that
brief, if not all of them, are likely unaffected by the statute.
See Brief for Volunteer Lawyer for the Arts et al. as Amici
Curiae 4-10 (describing, among other incidents, controversies
in various communities regarding Maya Angelou's I Know Why The
Caged Bird Sings, Judy Blume's Are You There God? It's Me,
Margaret, Aldous Huxley's Brave New World, J. D. Salinger's Catcher
in the Rye, 1993 Academy Award Best Picture nominee The Piano, the
American Broadcasting Corporation television network's NYPD Blue,
and songs of the "popular folkrock duo" the Indigo Girls). These
anecdotes are therefore of questionable relevance to the matter at
hand and certainly do not constitute a sufficient basis for
invalidating a federal statute.
Moreover, we do not agree with JUSTICE KENNEDY'S suggestion that
it is necessary for the Court of Appeals to revisit this question
upon remand. See post, at 597-599. The lack of evidence in
the record relevant to the question presented does not indicate
that "we should vacate for further consideration." Post, at
599. Rather, it indicates that respondents, by offering little more
than "speculation," have failed to meet their burden of
demonstrating in this facial challenge that COPA's reliance on
community standards renders the statute substantially
overbroad. 586 586 ASHCROFT v. AMERICAN CIVIL LIBERTIES UNION
Opinion of O'CONNOR, J.
sis once adjudication of the case is completed below. While
respondents urge us to resolve these questions at this time,
prudence dictates allowing the Court of Appeals to first examine
these difficult issues.
Petitioner does not ask us to vacate the preliminary injunction
entered by the District Court, and in any event, we could not do so
without addressing matters yet to be considered by the Court of
Appeals. As a result, the Government remains enjoined from
enforcing COPA absent further action by the Court of Appeals or the
District Court.
For the foregoing reasons, we vacate the judgment of the Court
of Appeals and remand the case for further proceedings.
It is so ordered.
JUSTICE O'CONNOR, concurring in part and concurring in the
judgment.
I agree with the plurality that even if obscenity on the
Internet is defined in terms of local community standards,
respondents have not shown that the Child Online Protection Act
(COPA) is overbroad solely on the basis of the variation in the
standards of different communities. See ante, at 577579.
Like JUSTICE BREYER, however, see post, at 589 (opinion
concurring in part and concurring in judgment), I write separately
to express my views on the constitutionality and desirability of
adopting a national standard for obscenity for regulation of the
Internet.
The plurality's opinion argues that, even under local community
standards, the variation between the most and least restrictive
communities is not so great with respect to the narrow category of
speech covered by COPA as to, alone, render the statute
substantially overbroad. See ante, at 577-579. I agree,
given respondents' failure to provide examples of materials that
lack literary, artistic, political, and scientific value for
minors, which would nonetheless result in variation among
communities judging the other elements of the test. Respondents'
examples of material for which com- 587 munity standards would vary include such things as the
appropriateness of sex education and the desirability of adoption
by same-sex couples. Brief for Respondents 43. Material addressing
the latter topic, however, seems highly unlikely to be seen to
appeal to the prurient interest in any community, and educational
material like the former must, on any objective inquiry, see ante, at 579, have scientific value for minors.
But respondents' failure to prove substantial overbreadth on a
facial challenge in this case still leaves open the possibility
that the use of local community standards will cause problems for
regulation of obscenity on the Internet, for adults as well as
children, in future cases. In an as-applied challenge, for
instance, individual litigants may still dispute that the standards
of a community more restrictive than theirs should apply to them.
And in future facial challenges to regulation of obscenity on the
Internet, litigants may make a more convincing case for substantial
overbreadth. Where adult speech is concerned, for instance, there
may in fact be a greater degree of disagreement about what is
patently offensive or appeals to the prurient interest.
Nor do I think such future cases can be resolved by application
of the approach we took in Hamling v. United States, 418 U. S. 87 (1974), and Sable Communications of Cal., Inc. v. FCC, 492 U. S.
115 (1989). I agree with JUSTICE KENNEDY that, given Internet
speakers' inability to control the geographic location of their
audience, expecting them to bear the burden of controlling the
recipients of their speech, as we did in Hamling and Sable, may be entirely too much to ask, and would
potentially suppress an inordinate amount of expression. See post, at 594-596 (opinion concurring in judgment); contra, ante, at 580-584. For these reasons, adoption of a national
standard is necessary in my view for any reasonable regulation of
Internet obscenity.
Our precedents do not forbid adoption of a national standard.
Local community-based standards originated with 588 588 ASHCROFT v. AMERICAN CIVIL LIBERTIES UNION
Opinion of O'CONNOR, J. Miller v. California, 413 U. S. 15 (1973). In
that case, we approved jury instructions that based the relevant
"community standards" on those of the State of California rather
than on the Nation as a whole. In doing so, we held that "[n]othing
in the First Amendment requires" that a jury consider national
standards when determining if something is obscene as a matter of
fact. Id., at 31. The First Amendment, we held, did not
require that "the people of Maine or Mississippi accept public
depiction of conduct found tolerable in Las Vegas, or New York
City." Id., at 32. But we said nothing about the
constitutionality of jury instructions that would contemplate a
national standard-i. e., requiring that the people who live
in all of these places hold themselves to what the nationwide
community of adults would find was patently offensive and appealed
to the prurient interest.
Later, in Jenkins v. Georgia, 418 U. S. 153 , 157
(1974), we confirmed that "Miller approved the use of
[instructions based on local standards]; it did not mandate their
use." The instructions we approved in that case charged the jury
with applying "community standards" without designating any
particular "community." In holding that a State may define the
obscenity standard by stating the Miller standard without
further specification, 418 U. S., at 157, Jenkins left open
the possibility that jurors would apply any number of standards,
including a national standard, in evaluating material's
obscenity.
To be sure, the Court in Miller also stated that a
national standard might be "unascertainable," 413 U. S., at 31, and
"[un]realistic," id., at 32. But where speech on the
Internet is concerned, I do not share that skepticism. It is true
that our Nation is diverse, but many local communities encompass a
similar diversity. For instance, in Miller itself, the jury
was instructed to consider the standards of the entire State of
California, a large (today, it has a population of greater than 33
million people, see U. S. Dept. of Commerce, Bureau of Census,
Statistical Abstract of the United States 23 (120th 589 ed. 2000) (Table 20)) and diverse State that includes both
Berkeley and Bakersfield. If the Miller Court believed
generalizations about the standards of the people of California
were possible, and that jurors would be capable of assessing them,
it is difficult to believe that similar generalizations are not
also possible for the Nation as a whole. Moreover, the existence of
the Internet, and its facilitation of national dialogue, has itself
made jurors more aware of the views of adults in other parts of the
United States. Although jurors asked to evaluate the obscenity of
speech based on a national standard will inevitably base their
assessments to some extent on their experience of their local
communities, I agree with JUSTICE BREYER that the lesser degree of
variation that would result is inherent in the jury system and does
not necessarily pose a First Amendment problem. See post, at
591. In my view, a national standard is not only constitutionally
permissible, but also reasonable.
While I would prefer that the Court resolve the issue before it
by explicitly adopting a national standard for defining obscenity
on the Internet, given respondents' failure to demonstrate
substantial overbreadth due solely to the variation between local
communities, I join Parts I, II, III-B, and IV of JUSTICE THOMAS'
opinion and the judgment.
JUSTICE BREYER, concurring in part and concurring in the
judgment.
I write separately because I believe that Congress intended the
statutory word "community" to refer to the N ation's adult
community taken as a whole, not to geographically separate local
areas. The statutory language does not explicitly describe the
specific "community" to which it refers. It says only that the
"average person, applying contemporary community standards," must
find that the "material as a whole and with respect to minors, is
designed to appeal to, or is designed to pander to, the prurient
interest .... " 47 U. S. C. § 231(e)(6) (1994 ed., Supp. V). 590 590 ASHCROFT v. AMERICAN CIVIL LIBERTIES UNION
Opinion of BREYER, J.
In the statute's legislative history, however, Congress made
clear that it did not intend this ambiguous statutory phrase to
refer to separate standards that might differ significantly among
different communities. The relevant House of Representatives Report
says: "The Committee recognizes that the applicability of community
standards in the context of the Web is controversial, but
understands it as an 'adult' standard, rather than a 'geographic'
standard, and one that is reasonably constant among adults in
America with respect to what is suitable for minors." H. R. Rep.
No. 105-775, p. 28 (1998) (emphasis added). This statement, reflecting what apparently was a uniform view
within Congress, makes clear that the standard, and the relevant
community, is national and adult.
At the same time, this view of the statute avoids the need to
examine the serious First Amendment problem that would otherwise
exist. See Almendarez-Torres v. United States, 523 U. S. 224 ,
237-238 (1998); Ashwander v. TV A, 297 U. S. 288, 348
(1936) (Brandeis, J., concurring) (" 'When the validity of an act
of the Congress is drawn in question, and even if a serious doubt
of constitutionality is raised, it is a cardinal principle that
this Court will first ascertain whether a construction of the
statute is fairly possible by which the question may be avoided'
"). To read the statute as adopting the community standards of
every locality in the United States would provide the most puritan
of communities with a heckler's Internet veto affecting the rest of
the Nation. The technical difficulties associated with efforts to
confine Internet material to particular geographic areas make the
problem particularly serious. See American Civil Liberties
Union v. Reno, 217 F.3d
162 , 175-176 (CA3 2000). And these special difficulties
also potentially weaken the authority of prior cases in which they
were not present. Cf. Sable 591 Communications of Cal., Inc. v. FCC, 492 U. S. 115 (1989); Hamling v. United States, 418 U. S. 87 (1974). A
nationally uniform adult-based standard-which Congress, in its
Committee Report, said that it intended-significantly alleviates
any special need for First Amendment protection. Of course some
regional variation may remain, but any such variations are inherent
in a system that draws jurors from a local geographic area and they
are not, from the perspective of the First Amendment, problematic.
See id., at 105-106.
For these reasons I do not join Part III of JUSTICE THOMAS'
opinion, although I agree with much of the reasoning set forth in
Parts III-B and III-D, insofar as it explains the conclusion to
which I just referred, namely, that variation reflecting
application of the same national standard by different local juries
does not violate the First Amendment.
JUSTICE KENNEDY, with whom JUSTICE SOUTER and JUSTICE GINSBURG
join, concurring in the judgment.
I
If a law restricts substantially more speech than is justified,
it may be subject to a facial challenge. Broadrick v. Oklahoma, 413
U. S. 601 , 615 (1973). There is a very real likelihood that the
Child Online Protection Act (COPA or Act) is overbroad and cannot
survive such a challenge. Indeed, content-based regulations like
this one are presumptively invalid abridgments of the freedom of
speech. See R. A. v: v. St. Paul, 505 U. S. 377 , 382
(1992). Yet COPA is a major federal statute, enacted in the wake of
our previous determination that its predecessor violated the First
Amendment. See Reno v. American Civil Liberties
Union, 521 U. S.
844 (1997). Congress and the President were aware of our
decision, and we should assume that in seeking to comply with it
they have given careful consideration to the constitutionality of
the new enactment. For these reasons, even if this facial challenge
appears to have consider- 592 592 ASHCROFT v. AMERICAN CIVIL LIBERTIES UNION
KENNEDY, J., concurring in judgment
able merit, the Judiciary must proceed with caution and identify
overbreadth with care before invalidating the Act.
In this case, the District Court issued a preliminary injunction
against enforcement of COPA, finding it too broad across several
dimensions. The Court of Appeals affirmed, but on a different
ground. COPA defines "material that is harmful to minors" by
reference to "contemporary community standards," 47 U. s. C. §
231(e)(6) (1994 ed., Supp. V); and on the theory that these vary
from place to place, the Court of Appeals held that the definition
dooms the statute "without reference to its other provisions." American Civil Liberties Union v. Reno, 217 F.3d
162 , 174 (CA3 2000). The Court of Appeals found it
unnecessary to construe the rest of the Act or address the District
Court's reasoning.
This single, broad proposition, stated and applied at such a
high level of generality, cannot suffice to sustain the Court of
Appeals' ruling. To observe only that community standards vary
across the country is to ignore the antecedent question: community
standards as to what? Whether the national variation in community
standards produces overbreadth requiring invalidation of COPA, see Broadrick, supra, depends on the breadth of COPA's coverage
and on what community standards are being invoked. Only by
identifying the universe of speech burdened by COPA is it possible
to discern whether national variation in community standards
renders the speech restriction overbroad. In short, the ground on
which the Court of Appeals relied cannot be separated from those
that it overlooked.
The statute, for instance, applies only to "communication for
commercial purposes." 47 U. S. C. § 231(e)(2)(A). The Court of
Appeals, however, did not consider the amount of commercial
communication, the number of commercial speakers, or the character
of commercial speech covered by the Act. Likewise, the statute's
definition of "harmful to minors" requires material to be judged
"as a whole." § 231(e)(6)(C). The notion of judging work as a whole
is 593 familiar in other media, but more difficult to define on the
World Wide Web. It is unclear whether what is to be judged as a
whole is a single image on a Web page, a whole Web page, an entire
multipage Web site, or an interlocking set of Web sites. Some
examination of the group of covered speakers and the categories of
covered speech is necessary in order to comprehend the extent of
the alleged overbreadth.
The Court of Appeals found that COP A in effect subjects every
Internet speaker to the standards of the most puritanical community
in the United States. This concern is a real one, but it alone
cannot suffice to invalidate COPA without careful examination of
the speech and the speakers within the ambit of the Act. For this
reason, I join the judgment of the Court vacating the opinion of
the Court of Appeals and remanding for consideration of the statute
as a whole. Unlike JUSTICE THOMAS, however, I would not assume that
the Act is narrow enough to render the national variation in
community standards unproblematic. Indeed, if the District Court
correctly construed the statute across its other dimensions, then
the variation in community standards might well justify enjoining
enforcement of the Act. I would leave that question to the Court of
Appeals in the first instance.
II
COPA provides a three-part conjunctive definition of "material
that is harmful to minors." The first part of the definition is
that "the average person, applying contemporary community
standards, would find, taking the material as a whole and with
respect to minors, [that it] is designed to appeal to, or is
designed to pander to, the prurient interest." 47 U. S. C. §
231(e)(6)(A). (The parties agree that the second part of the
definition, § 231(e)(6)(B), likewise invokes contemporary community
standards, though only implicitly. See ante, at 576, n. 7.)
The nub of the problem is, as the Court has said, that "the
'community standards' criterion as applied to the Internet means
that any communication available to 594 594 ASHCROFT v. AMERICAN CIVIL LIBERTIES UNION
KENNEDY, J., concurring in judgment
a nationwide audience will be judged by the standards of the
community most likely to be offended by the message." Reno, 521 U. S., at 877-878. If material might be considered harmful to
minors in any community in the United States, then the material is
covered by COPA, at least when viewed in that place. This
observation was the linchpin of the Court of Appeals' analysis, and
we must now consider whether it alone suffices to support the
holding below.
The quoted sentence from Reno was not casual dicta;
rather, it was one rationale for the holding of the case. In Reno, the Court found "[t]he breadth of [COPA's predecessor]
... wholly unprecedented," id., at 877, in part because of
variation in community standards. The Court also relied on that
variation to assess the strength of the Government's interest,
which it found "not equally strong throughout the coverage of this
broad statute." Id., at 878. The Court illustrated the point
with an example: A parent who e-mailed birth control information to
his 17-year-old child at college might violate the Act, "even
though neither he, his child, nor anyone in their home community
found the material 'indecent' or 'patently offensive,' if the
college town's community thought otherwise." Ibid. Variation
in community standards rendered the statute broader than the scope
of the Government's own expressed compelling interest.
It is true, as JUSTICE THOMAS points out, ante, at
580-583, that requiring a speaker addressing a national audience to
meet varying community standards does not always violate the First
Amendment. See Hamling v. United States, 418 U. S.
87, 106 (1974) (obscene mailings); Sable Communications of Cal.,
Inc. v. FCC, 492 U. S. 115 , 125-126
(1989) (obscene phone messages). These cases, however, are of
limited utility in analyzing the one before us, because each mode
of expression has its own unique characteristics, and each "must be
assessed for First Amendment purposes by standards suited to it." Southeastern Promotions, Ltd. v. Con- 595 rad, 420 U.
S. 546 , 557 (1975). Indeed, when Congress purports to abridge
the freedom of a new medium, we must be particularly attentive to
its distinct attributes, for "differences in the characteristics of
new media justify differences in the First Amendment standards
applied to them." Red Lion Broadcasting Co. v. FCC, 395 U. S. 367 ,
386 (1969). The economics and the technology of each medium affect
both the burden of a speech restriction and the Government's
interest in maintaining it.
In this case the District Court found as a fact that "[o]nce a
provider posts its content on the Internet and chooses to make it
available to all, it generally cannot prevent that content from
entering any geographic community." American Civil Liberties
Union v. Reno, 31 F. Supp. 2d 473, 484 (ED Pa. 1999). By
contrast, in upholding a ban on obscene phone messages, we
emphasized that the speaker could "hire operators to determine the
source of the calls or engag[e] with the telephone company to
arrange for the screening and blocking of out-of-area calls or
fined] another means for providing messages compatible with
community standards." Sable, supra, at 125. And if we did
not make the same point in Hamling, that is likely because
it is so obvious that mailing lends itself to geographic
restriction. (The Court has had no occasion to consider whether
venue would be proper in "every hamlet into which [obscene
mailings] may wander," Hamling, supra, at 144 (dissenting
opinion), for the petitioners in Hamling did not challenge
the statute as overbroad on its face.) A publisher who uses the
mails can choose the location of his audience.
The economics and technology of Internet communication differ in
important ways from those of telephones and mail. Paradoxically, as
the District Court found, it is easy and cheap to reach a worldwide
audience on the Internet, see 31 F. Supp. 2d, at 482, but expensive
if not impossible to reach a geographic subset, id., at 484.
A Web publisher in a community where avant garde culture is the
norm may have no 596 596 ASHCROFT v. AMERICAN CIVIL LIBERTIES UNION
KENNEDY, J., concurring in judgment
desire to reach a national market; he may wish only to speak to
his neighbors; nevertheless, if an eavesdropper in a more
traditional, rural community chooses to listen in, there is nothing
the publisher can do. As a practical matter, COPA makes the
eavesdropper the arbiter of propriety on the Web. And it is no
answer to say that the speaker should "take the simple step of
utilizing a [different] medium." Ante, at 583 (principal
opinion of THOMAS, J.). "Our prior decisions have voiced particular
concern with laws that foreclose an entire medium of expression
.... [T]he danger they pose to the freedom of speech is readily
apparent-by eliminating a common means of speaking, such measures
can suppress too much speech." City of Ladue v. Gilleo, 512 U.
S. 43 , 55 (1994).
JUSTICE BREYER would alleviate the problem oflocal variation in
community standards by construing the statute to comprehend the "N
ation's adult community taken as a whole," rather than the local
community from which the jury is drawn. Ante, at 589
(opinion concurring in part and concurring in judgment); see also ante, at 586-589 (O'CONNOR, J., concurring in part and
concurring in judgment). There is one statement in a House
Committee Report to this effect, "reflecting," JUSTICE BREYER
writes, "what apparently was a uniform view within Congress." Ante, at 590. The statement, perhaps, reflects the view of a
majority of one House committee, but there is no reason to believe
that it reflects the view of a majority of the House of
Representatives, let alone the "uniform view within Congress." Ibid. In any event, we need not decide whether the statute invokes
local or national community standards to conclude that vacatur and
remand are in order. If the statute does incorporate some concept
of national community standards, the actual standard applied is
bound to vary by community nevertheless, as the Attorney General
concedes. See ante, at 577 (principal opinion of THOMAS,
J.); Brief for Petitioner 39. 597 For this reason the Court of Appeals was correct to focus on
COPA's incorporation of varying community standards; and it may
have been correct as well to conclude that in practical effect COPA
imposes the most puritanical community standard on the entire
country. We have observed that it is "neither realistic nor
constitutionally sound to read the First Amendment as requiring
that the people of Maine or Mississippi accept public depiction of
conduct found tolerable in Las Vegas, or New York City." Miller v. California, 413 U. S. 15 , 32 (1973).
On the other hand, it is neither realistic nor beyond
constitutional doubt for Congress, in effect, to impose the
community standards of Maine or Mississippi on Las Vegas and New
York. "People in different States vary in their tastes and
attitudes, and this diversity is not to be strangled by the
absolutism of imposed uniformity." Id., at 33. In striking
down COPA's predecessor, the Reno Court identified this
precise problem, and if the Hamling and Sable Courts
did not find the problem fatal, that is because those cases
involved quite different media. The national variation in community
standards constitutes a particular burden on Internet speech.
III
The question that remains is whether this observation "by itself" suffices to enjoin the Act. See ante, at 585. I
agree with the Court that it does not. Ibid. We cannot know
whether variation in community standards renders the Act
substantially overbroad without first assessing the extent of the
speech covered and the variations in community standards with
respect to that speech.
First, the breadth of the Act itself will dictate the degree of
overbreadth caused by varying community standards. Indeed, JUSTICE
THOMAS sees this point and uses it in an attempt to distinguish the
Communications Decency Act of 1996, which was at issue in Reno. See ante, at 577-578 ("The CDA's use of
community standards to identify patently 598 598 ASHCROFT v. AMERICAN CIVIL LIBERTIES UNION
KENNEDY, J., concurring in judgment
offensive material, however, was particularly problematic in
light of that statute's unprecedented breadth and vagueness"); ante, at 578 ("The tremendous breadth of the CDA magnified the impact caused by differences in community standards
across the country"). To explain the ways in which COPA is narrower
than the CDA, JUSTICE THOMAS finds that he must construe
sections of COPA elided by the Court of Appeals. Though I agree
with the necessity for doing so, JUSTICE THOMAS'
interpretation-undertaken without substantial arguments or
briefing-is not altogether persuasive, and I would leave this task
to the Court of Appeals in the first instance. As this case comes
to us, once it is accepted that we cannot strike down the Act based
merely on the phrase "contemporary community standards," we should
go no further than to vacate and remand for a more comprehensive
analysis of the Act.
Second, community standards may have different degrees of
variation depending on the question posed to the community.
Defining the scope of the Act, therefore, is not relevant merely to
the absolute number of Web pages covered, as JusTICE STEVENS
suggests, post, at 609-610 (dissenting opinion); it is also
relevant to the proportion of overbreadth, "judged in relation to
the statute's plainly legitimate sweep," Broadrick, 413 U.
S., at 615. Because this issue was "virtually ignored by the
parties and the amicus" in the Court of Appeals, 217 F. 3d, at 173,
we have no information on the question. Instead, speculation meets
speculation. On the one hand, the Court of Appeals found "no
evidence to suggest that adults everywhere in America would
share the same standards for determining what is harmful to
minors." Id., at 178. On the other hand, JUSTICE THOMAS
finds "no reason to believe that the practical effect of varying
community standards under COPA ... is significantly greater than
the practical effect of varying community standards under federal
obscenity statutes." Ante, at 583-584. When a key issue has
"no evidence" on one side and "no reason to be- 599 lieve" the other, it is a good indication that we should vacate
for further consideration.
The District Court attempted a comprehensive analysis of COPA
and its various dimensions of potential overbreadth. The Court of
Appeals, however, believed that its own analysis of "contemporary
community standards" obviated all other concerns. It dismissed the
District Court's analysis in a footnote: "[W]e do not find it necessary to address the District Court's
analysis of the definition of 'commercial purposes'; whether the
breadth of the forms of content covered by COPA could have been
more narrowly tailored; whether the affirmative defenses impose too
great a burden on Web publishers or whether those affirmative
defenses should have been included as elements of the crime itself;
whether COPA's inclusion of criminal as well as civil penalties was
excessive; whether COPA is designed to include communications made
in chat rooms, discussion groups and links to other Web sites;
whether the government is entitled to so restrict communications
when children will continue to be able to access foreign Web sites
and other sources of material that is harmful to them; what taken
'as a whole' should mean in the context of the Web and the
Internet; or whether the statute's failure to distinguish between
material that is harmful to a six year old versus a sixteen year
old is problematic." 217 F. 3d, at 174, n. 19. As I have explained, however, any problem caused by variation in
community standards cannot be evaluated in a vacuum. In order to
discern whether the variation creates substantial overbreadth, it
is necessary to know what speech COPA regulates and what community
standards it invokes.
It is crucial, for example, to know how limiting is the Act's
limitation to "communication for commercial purposes." 47 U. S. C.
§231(e)(2)(A). In Reno, we remarked that COPA's 600 600 ASHCROFT v. AMERICAN CIVIL LIBERTIES UNION
KENNEDY, J., concurring in judgment
predecessor was so broad in part because it had no such
limitation. 521 U. S., at 877. COPA, by contrast, covers a speaker
only if: "the person who makes a communication or offers to make a
communication, by means of the World Wide Web, that includes any
material that is harmful to minors, devotes time, attention, or
labor to such activities, as a regular course of such person's
trade or business, with the objective of earning a profit as a
result of such activities (although it is not necessary that the
person make a profit or that the making or offering to make such
communications be the person's sole or principal business or source
of income)." 47 U. S. C. § 231(e)(2)(B). So COPA is narrower across this dimension than its predecessor;
but how much narrower is a matter of debate. In the District Court,
the Attorney General contended that the Act applied only to
professional panderers, but the court rejected that contention,
finding "nothing in the text of the COPA ... that limits its
applicability to so-called commercial pornographers only." 31 F.
Supp. 2d, at 480. Indeed, the plain text of the Act does not limit
its scope to pornography that is offered for sale; it seems to
apply even to speech provided for free, so long as the speaker
merely hopes to profit as an indirect result. The statute might be
susceptible of some limiting construction here, but again the Court
of Appeals did not address itself to this question. The answer
affects the breadth of the Act and hence the significance of any
variation in community standards.
Likewise, it is essential to answer the vexing question of what
it means to evaluate Internet material "as a whole," 47 U. S. C. §§
231(e)(6)(A), (C), when everything on the Web is connected
to everything else. As a general matter, "[t]he artistic merit of a
work does not depend on the presence of a single explicit scene
.... [T]he First Amendment requires 601 that redeeming value be judged by considering the work as a
whole. Where the scene is part of the narrative, the work itself
does not for this reason become obscene, even though the scene in
isolation might be offensive." Ashcroft v. Free Speech
Coalition, ante, at 248. COPA appears to respect this principle
by requiring that the material be judged "as a whole," both as to
its prurient appeal, § 231(e)(6)(A), and as to its social value, §
231(e)(6)(C). It is unclear, however, what constitutes the
denominator-that is, the material to be taken as a whole-in the
context of the World Wide Web. See 31 F. Supp. 2d, at 483
("Although information on the Web is contained in individual
computers, the fact that each of these computers is connected to
the Internet through World Wide Web protocols allows all of the
information to become part of a single body of knowledge"); id., at 484 ("From a user's perspective, [the World Wide
Web] may appear to be a single, integrated system"). Several of the
respondents operate extensive Web sites, some of which include only
a small amount of material that might run afoul of the Act. The
Attorney General contended that these respondents had nothing to
fear from COP A, but the District Court disagreed, noting that the
Act prohibits communication that "includes" any material harmful to
minors. § 231(a)(1). In the District Court's view, "it logically
follows that [COPA] would apply to any Web site that contains only
some harmful to minors material." Id., at 480. The
denominator question is of crucial significance to the coverage of
the Act.
Another issue is worthy of mention, because it too may inform
whether the variation in community standards renders the Act
substantially overbroad. The parties and the Court of Appeals did
not address the question of venue, though it would seem to be bound
up with the issue of varying community standards. COPA does not
address venue in explicit terms, so prosecution may be proper "in
any district in which [an] offense was begun, continued, or
completed." 18 U. S. C. § 3237(a). The Act's prohibition includes
an inter- 602 602 ASHCROFT v. AMERICAN CIVIL LIBERTIES UNION
STEVENS, J., dissenting
state commerce element, 47 U. S. C. § 231(a)(1), and "[a]ny
offense involving ... interstate ... commerce ... may be inquired
of and prosecuted in any district from, through, or into which such
commerce ... moves." 18 U. S. C. § 3237(a). In the context of COPA,
it seems likely that venue would be proper where the material
originates or where it is viewed. Whether it may be said that a Web
site moves "through" other venues in between is less certain. And
since, as discussed above, juries will inevitably apply their own
community standards, the choice of venue may be determinative of
the choice of standard. The more venues the Government has to
choose from, the more speech will be chilled by variation across
communities.
IV
In summary, the breadth of the Act depends on the issues
discussed above, and the significance of varying community
standards depends, in turn, on the breadth of the Act. The Court of
Appeals was correct to focus on the national variation in community
standards, which can constitute a substantial burden on Internet
communication; and its ultimate conclusion may prove correct. There
may be grave doubts that COPA is consistent with the First
Amendment; but we should not make that determination with so many
questions unanswered. The Court of Appeals should undertake a
comprehensive analysis in the first instance.
JUSTICE STEVENS, dissenting.
Appeals to prurient interests are commonplace on the Internet,
as in older media. Many of those appeals lack serious value for
minors as well as adults. Some are offensive to certain viewers but
welcomed by others. For decades, our cases have recognized that the
standards for judging their acceptability vary from viewer to
viewer and from community to community. Those cases developed the
requirement that communications should be protected if they do not
violate contemporary community standards. In its original 603 form, the community standard provided a shield for
communications that are offensive only to the least tolerant
members of society. Thus, the Court "has emphasized on more than
one occasion that a principal concern in requiring that a judgment
be made on the basis of 'contemporary community standards' is to
assure that the material is judged neither on the basis of each
juror's personal opinion, nor by its effect on a particularly
sensitive or insensitive person or group." Hamling v. United States, 418 U. S. 87 , 107 (1974).
In the context of the Internet, however, community standards become
a sword, rather than a shield. If a prurient appeal is offensive in
a puritan village, it may be a crime to post it on the World Wide
Web.
The Child Online Protection Act (COPA) restricts access by
adults as well as children to materials that are "harmful to
minors." 47 U. S. C. § 231(a)(1) (1994 ed., Supp. V). COPA is a
substantial improvement over its predecessor, the Communications
Decency Act of 1996 (CDA), which we held unconstitutional
five years ago in Reno v. American Civil Liberties
Union, 521 U. S.
844 (1997) (ACLU 1). Congress has thoughtfully addressed
several of the First Amendment problems that we identified in that
case. Nevertheless, COPA preserves the use of contemporary
community standards to define which materials are harmful to
minors. As we explained in ACLU I, 521 U. S., at 877-878,
"the 'community standards' criterion as applied to the Internet
means that any communication available to a nationwide audience
will be judged by the standards of the community most likely to be
offended by the message."
We have recognized that the State has a compelling interest in
protecting minors from harmful speech, Sable Communications of
Cal., Inc. v. FCC, 492 U. S. 115 , 126
(1989), and on one occasion we upheld a restriction on indecent
speech that was made available to the general public, because it
could be accessed by minors, FCC v. Pacifica
Foundation, 438
U. S. 726 (1978). Our decision in that case was influ- 604 604 ASHCROFT v. AMERICAN CIVIL LIBERTIES UNION
STEVENS, J., dissenting
enced by the distinctive characteristics of the broadcast
medium, as well as the expertise of the agency, and the narrow
scope of its order. Id., at 748-750; see also ACLU I,
521 U. S., at 867. On the other hand, we have repeatedly
rejected the position that the free speech rights of adults can be
limited to what is acceptable for children. See id., at 875
(quoting Bolger v. Youngs Drug Products Corp., 463 U. S. 60 ,
74-75 (1983) ("[R]egardless of the strength of the government's
interest" in protecting children, "[t]he level of discourse
reaching a mailbox simply cannot be limited to that which would be
suitable for a sandbox" (internal quotation marks omitted))); Sable, 492 U. S., at 128; Butler v. Michigan, 352 U. S. 380 ,
383 (1957).
Petitioner relies on our decision in Ginsberg v. New
York, 390 U. S.
629 (1968), for the proposition that Congress can prohibit the display of materials that are harmful to minors. But the
statute upheld in Ginsberg prohibited selling indecent materials directly to children, id., at 633
(describing N. Y. Penal Law § 484-h, making it unlawful "'knowingly
to sell ... to a minor ... ' "), whereas the speech implicated here
is simply posted on a medium that is accessible to both adults and
children, 47 U. S. C. § 231(a)(1) (prohibiting anyone from
"knowingly ... mak[ing] any communication for commercial purposes
that is available to any minor ... "). Like the restriction on
indecent "dial-a-porn" numbers invalidated in Sable, the
prohibition against mailing advertisements for contraceptives
invalidated in Bolger, and the ban against selling adult
books found impermissible in Butler, COPA seeks to limit
protected speech that is not targeted at children, simply because
it can be obtained by them while surfing the Web.1 In evaluating
the overbreadth of such a
1 Petitioner cites examples of display statutes in 23 States
that require magazine racks to shield minors from the covers of
pornographic magazines. Brief for Petitioner 22, 3a. This Court has
yet to rule on the constitutionality of any of these statutes,
which are in any event of little relevance to regulation of speech
on the Internet. As we recognized in 605 statute, we should be mindful of Justice Frankfurter's
admonition not to "burn the house to roast the pig," Butler,
352 U. S., at 383.
COPA not only restricts speech that is made available to the
general public, it also covers a medium in which speech cannot be
segregated to avoid communities where it is likely to be considered
harmful to minors. The Internet presents a unique forum for
communication because information, once posted, is accessible
everywhere on the network at once. The speaker cannot control
access based on the location of the listener, nor can it choose the
pathways through which its speech is transmitted. By approving the
use of community standards in this context, JUSTICE THOMAS endorses
a construction of COPA that has "the intolerable consequence of
denying some sections of the country access to material, there
deemed acceptable, which in others might be considered offensive to
prevailing community standards of decency." Manual Enterprises,
Inc. v. Day, 370 U. S. 478 , 488
(1962).
If the material were forwarded through the mails, as in Hamling, or over the telephone, as in Sable, the
sender could avoid destinations with the most restrictive
standards. Indeed, in Sable, we upheld the application of
community standards to a nationwide medium because the speaker was
"free to tailor its messages ... to the communities it chooses to serve," by either "hir[ing] operators to
determine the source of the calls ... [or] arrang[ing] for the
screening and blocking of out-of-area calls." 492 U. S., at 125
(emphasis added). Our conclusion that it was permissible for the
speaker to bear the ultimate burden of compliance, id., at
126, assumed that such compliance was at least possible without
requiring the speaker to choose another medium or to limit its
speech to what all would find acceptable. Given the ACLU I, 521
U. S. 844 , 854 (1997), '''the receipt of information on the
Internet requires a series of affirmative steps more deliberate and
directed than merely turning a dial' "--or scanning a magazine
rack. 606 606 ASHCROFT v. AMERICAN CIVIL LIBERTIES UNION
STEVENS, J., dissenting
undisputed fact that a provider who posts material on the
Internet cannot prevent it from entering any geographic community,
see ante, at 575, n. 6 (opinion of THOMAS, J.), a law that
criminalizes a particular communication in just a handful of
destinations effectively prohibits transmission of that message to
all of the 176.5 million Americans that have access to the
Internet, see ante, at 567, n. 2 (majority opinion). In
light of this fundamental difference in technologies, the rules
applicable to the mass mailing of an obscene montage or to obscene
dial-a-porn should not be used to judge the legality of messages on
the World Wide Web.2
In his attempt to fit this case within the framework of Hamling and Sable, JUSTICE THOMAS overlooks the more
obvious comparison-namely, the CDA invalidated in ACLU 1. When we confronted a similar attempt by Congress to
limit speech on the Internet based on community standards, we
explained that because Web publishers cannot control who accesses
their Web sites, using community standards to regulate speech on
the Internet creates an overbreadth problem. "[T]he 'community
standards' criterion as applied to the Internet means that any
communication available to a nationwide audience will be judged by
the standards of the community most likely to be offended by the
message." 521 U. S., at 877-878. Although our holding in ACLU
I did not turn on that factor alone, we did not adopt the
position relied on by JUSTICE THOMAs-that applying community
standards to the Internet is constitutional based on Hamling and
2 It is hardly a solution to say, as JUSTICE THOMAS suggests, ante, at 583, that a speaker need only choose a different
medium in order to avoid having its speech judged by the least
tolerant community. Our overbreadth doctrine would quickly become a
toothless protection if we were to hold that substituting a more
limited forum for expression is an acceptable price to pay. Since a
content-based restriction is presumptively invalid, I would place
the burden on parents to "take the simple step of utilizing a
medium that enables," ibid., them to avoid this material
before requiring the speaker to find another forum. 607 Sable. See Reply Brief for Appellants in Reno v. ACLU, O. T. 1996, No. 96-511, p. 19.3
JUSTICE THOMAS points to several other provisions in COPA to
argue that any overbreadth will be rendered insubstantial by the
rest of the statute. Ante, at 578-579. These provisions
afford little reassurance, however, as they only marginally limit
the sweep of the statute. It is true that, in addition to COP A's
"appeals to the prurient interest of minors" prong, the material
must be "patently offensive with respect to minors" and it must
lack "serious literary, artistic, political, or scientific value
for minors." 47 U. S. C. § 231(e)(6). Nonetheless, the "patently
offensive" prong is judged according to contemporary community
standards as well, ante, at 576, n. 7 (opinion of THOMAS,
J.). Whatever disparity exists between various communities'
assessment of the content that appeals to the prurient interest of
minors will surely be matched by their differing opinions as to
3 JUSTICE BREYER seeks to avoid the problem by effectively
reading the phrase "contemporary national standards" into the
statute, ante, at 589 (opinion concurring in part and
concurring in judgment). While the legislative history of COPA
provides some support for this reading, it is contradicted by the
clear text of the statute, which directs jurors to consider
"community" standards. This phrase is a term of art that has taken
on a particular meaning in light of our precedent. Although we have
never held that applying a national standard would be
constitutionally impermissible, we have said that asking a jury to
do so is "an exercise in futility," Miller v. California, 413
U. S. 15 , 30 (1973), and that "[a] juror is entitled to draw on
his own knowledge of the views of the average person in the
community or vicinage from which he comes for making the required
determination," Hamling v. United States, 418 U. S. 87 , 104 (1974).
Any lingering doubts about the meaning of the phrase were certainly
dispelled by our discussion of the issue in ACLU 1,521 U.
S., at 874, n. 39, and we presume that Congress legislates against
the backdrop of our decisions. Therefore, JUSTICE THOMAS has
correctly refused to rewrite the statute to substitute a standard
that Congress clearly did not choose. And even if the plurality
were willing to do so, we would still have to acknowledge, as
petitioner does, that jurors instructed to apply a national, or
adult, standard will reach widely different conclusions throughout
the country, see ante, at 577; Brief for Petitioner 39. 608 608 ASHCROFT v. AMERICAN CIVIL LIBERTIES UNION
STEVENS, J., dissenting
whether descriptions of sexual acts or depictions of nudity are
patently offensive with respect to minors. Nor does the requirement
that the material be "in some sense erotic," see ante, at
579 (citing Erznoznik v. Jacksonville, 422 U. S. 205 , 213, and
n. 10 (1975)), substantially narrow the category of images covered.
Arguably every depiction of nudity-partial or full-is in some sense
erotic with respect to minors. 4 Petitioner's argument that the "serious value" prong minimizes
the statute's overbreadth is also unpersuasive. Although we have
recognized that the serious value determination in obscenity cases
should be based on an objective, reasonable person standard, Pope v. Illinois, 481 U. S. 497 , 500
(1987), this criterion is inadequate to cure COPA's overbreadth
because COPA adds an important qualifying phrase to the standard Miller v. California, 413 U. S. 15 (1973),
formulation of the serious value prong. The question for the jury
is not whether a reasonable person would conclude that the
materials have serious value; instead, the jury must determine
whether the materials have serious value for minors. Congress reasonably concluded that a substantial number of works,
which have serious value for adults, do not have serious value for
minors. Cf. ACLU I, 521 U. S., at 896 (O'CONNOR, J.,
concurring in judgment in part and dissenting in part) ("While
discussions about prison rape or nude art ... may have some
redeeming educational value for adults, they do not
necessarily have any such value for minors"). Thus, even
though the serious value prong limits the total amount of speech
covered by the statute, it remains true that there is a significant
amount of protected speech within the category of materials that
have no serious value for minors. That speech is effectively
prohibited whenever
4 Of course, JUSTICE THOMAS' example of the image "of a war
victim's wounded nude body," ante, at 579, n. 9, would not
be covered by the statute unless it depicted "a lewd exhibition of
the genitals or post-pubescent female breast" and lacked serious
political value for minors, 47 U. S. C. §§ 231(e)(6)(B)-(C) (1994
ed., Supp. V). 609 the least tolerant communities find it harmful to minors.5 While
the objective nature of the inquiry may eliminate any worry that
the serious value determination will be made by the least tolerant
community, it does not change the fact that, within the subset of
images deemed to have no serious value for minors, the decision
whether minors and adults throughout the country will have access
to that speech will still be made by the most restrictive
community.
JUSTICE KENNEDY makes a similar misstep, ante, at 592
(opinion concurring in judgment), when he ties the overbreadth
inquiry to questions about the scope of the other provisions of the
statute. According to his view, we cannot determine whether the
statute is substantially overbroad based on its use of community
standards without first determining how much of the speech on the
Internet is saved by the other restrictions in the statute. But
this represents a fundamental misconception of our overbreadth
doctrine. As Justice White explained in Broadrick v. Oklahoma, 413 U. s.
5 The Court also notes that the limitation to communications
made for commercial purposes narrows the category of speech as
compared to the CDA, ante, at 569. While it is certainly
true that this condition limits the scope of the statute, the
phrase "commercial purposes" is somewhat misleading. The definition
of commercial purposes, 47 U. S. C. § 231(e)(2)(B), covers anyone
who generates revenue from advertisements or merchandise,
regardless of the amount of advertising or whether the
advertisements or products are related to the images that allegedly
are harmful to minors. As the District Court noted: "There is
nothing in the text of the COPA, however, that limits its
applicability to so-called commercial pornographers only; indeed,
the text of COPA imposes liability on a speaker who knowingly makes
any communication for commercial purposes 'that includes any
material that is harmful to minors,'" App. to Pet. for Cert.
52a. In the context of the Internet, this is hardly a serious
limitation. A 1998 study, for example, found that 83 percent of Web
sites contain commercial content. Lawrence & Giles,
Accessibility of information of the web, 400 Nature 107-109 (1999);
Guernsey, Seek-but on the Web, You Might Not Find, N. Y. Times,
July 8, 1999, p. G3. Interestingly, this same study found that only
1.5 percent of the 2.8 million sites cataloged contained
pornographic content. 610 610 ASHCROFT v. AMERICAN CIVIL LIBERTIES UNION
STEVENS, J., dissenting
601, 615 (1973), "the overbreadth of a statute must not only be
real, but substantial as well, judged in relation to the
statute's plainly legitimate sweep." (Emphasis added.)
Regardless of how the Court of Appeals interprets the "commercial
purposes" or "as a whole" provisions on remand, the question we
must answer is whether the statute restricts a substantial amount
of protected speech relative to its legitimate sweep by virtue of
the fact that it uses community standards.6 These other provisions
may reduce the absolute number of Web pages covered by the statute,
but even the narrowest version of the statute abridges a
substantial amount of protected speech that many communities would
not find harmful to minors. Because Web speakers cannot limit
access to those specific communities, the statute is substantially
overbroad regardless of how its other provisions are construed.
JUSTICE THOMAS acknowledges, and petitioner concedes, that
juries across the country will apply different standards and reach
different conclusions about whether particular works are harmful to
minors. See ante, at 577; Brief for Petitioner 3-4, 39. We
recognized as much in ACLU I when we noted that "discussions
about prison rape or safe sexual practices, artistic images that
include nude subjects, and arguably the card catalog of the
Carnegie Library" might offend some community's standards and not
others, 521 U. S., at 878. In fact, our own division on that
question provides further evidence of the range of attitudes about
such material. See, e. g., id., at 896 (O'CONNOR, J.,
concurring in judg-
6JUSTICE KENNEDY accuses the Court of Appeals of evaluating
overbreadth in a vacuum by dismissing most of the concerns raised
by the District Court, ante, at 599. But most of those
concerns went to whether COPA survives strict scrutiny, not
overbreadth. Even under JUSTICE KENNEDY'S formulation, it is
unclear why it is relevant to an overbreadth analysis, for example,
whether COPA could have been more narrowly tailored, whether the
affirmative defenses impose too great a burden, or whether
inclusion of criminal as well as civil penalties was excessive. 611 ment in part and dissenting in part). Moreover, amici for
respondents describe studies showing substantial variation among
communities in their attitudes toward works involving
homosexuality, masturbation, and nudity. 7
Even if most, if not all, of these works would be excluded from
COPA's coverage by the serious value prong, they illustrate the
diversity of public opinion on the underlying themes depicted. This
diversity of views surely extends to whether materials with the
same themes, that do not have serious value for minors, appeal to
their prurient interests and are patently offensive. There is no
reason to think the differences between communities' standards will
disappear once the image or description is no longer within the
context of a work that has serious value for minors.8 Because
communities differ widely in their attitudes toward sex,
particularly when minors are concerned, the Court of Appeals was
correct to conclude that, regardless of how COP A's other
provisions are construed, applying community standards to the
Internet will restrict a substantial amount of protected speech
that would not be considered harmful to minors in many
communities.
Whether that consequence is appropriate depends, of course, on
the content of the message. The kind of hardcore pornography
involved in Hamling, which I assume would be obscene under
any community's standard, does not belong on the Internet. Perhaps
"teasers" that serve no function except to invite viewers to
examine hardcore materials, or the hidden terms written into a Web
site's "metatags" in order to dupe unwitting Web surfers into
visiting pornographic sites, deserve the same fate. But COPA
ex-
7 Brief for Volunteer Lawyers for the Arts et al. as Amici
Curiae 4-10 (describing findings of the People for the American
Way Foundation Annual Freedom to Learn Reports).
8 Nor is there any reason to expect that a particular
community's view of the material will change based on how the Court
of Appeals construes the statute's "for commercial purposes" or "as
a whole" provisions. 612 612 ASHCROFT v. AMERICAN CIVIL LIBERTIES UNION
STEVENS, J., dissenting
tends to a wide range of prurient appeals in advertisements,
online magazines, Web-based bulletin boards and chat rooms, stock
photo galleries, Web diaries, and a variety of illustrations
encompassing a vast number of messages that are unobjectionable in
most of the country and yet provide no "serious value" for minors.
It is quite wrong to allow the standards of a minority consisting
of the least tolerant communities to regulate access to relatively
harmless messages in this burgeoning market.
In the context of most other media, using community standards to
differentiate between permissible and impermissible speech has two
virtues. As mentioned above, community standards originally served
as a shield to protect speakers from the least tolerant members of
society. By aggregating values at the community level, the Miller test eliminated the outliers at both ends of the
spectrum and provided some predictability as to what constitutes
obscene speech. But community standards also serve as a shield to
protect audience members, by allowing people to self-sort based on
their preferences. Those who abhor and those who tolerate sexually
explicit speech can seek out like-minded people and settle in
communities that share their views on what is acceptable for
themselves and their children. This sorting mechanism, however,
does not exist in cyberspace; the audience cannot self-segregate.
As a result, in the context of the Internet this shield also
becomes a sword, because the community that wishes to live without
certain material rids not only itself, but the entire Internet, of
the offending speech.
In sum, I would affirm the judgment of the Court of Appeals and
therefore respectfully dissent. | The Supreme Court case Ashcroft v. American Civil Liberties Union dealt with the Child Online Protection Act (COPA), which aimed to protect minors from exposure to harmful material on the internet. The case centered on the question of whether COPA's use of "community standards" to identify harmful material rendered the statute substantially overbroad and in violation of the First Amendment. The Court held that the use of community standards alone did not make COPA substantially overbroad, but expressed no view on other potential issues with the statute, such as vagueness or strict scrutiny. The Court left it to the Third Circuit to examine these remaining issues. The case highlights the challenges of regulating speech on the internet while balancing the protection of minors and the freedom of speech rights of adults. |
Free Speech | Virginia v. Black | https://supreme.justia.com/cases/federal/us/538/343/ | OCTOBER TERM, 2002
Syllabus
VIRGINIA v. BLACK ET AL.
CERTIORARI TO THE SUPREME COURT OF VIRGINIA No. 01-1107. Argued
December 11, 2002-Decided April 7, 2003
Respondents were convicted separately of violating a Virginia
statute that makes it a felony "for any person . . .,
with the intent of intimidating any person or group . . .
, to burn a cross on the property of another, a highway or other
public place," and specifies that "[a]ny such burning
. . . shall be prima facie evidence of an intent to
intimidate a person or group." When respondent Black objected on
First Amendment grounds to his trial court's jury instruction that
cross burning by itself is sufficient evidence from which the
required "intent to intimidate" could be inferred, the prosecutor
responded that the instruction was taken straight out of the
Virginia Model Instructions. Respondent O'Mara pleaded guilty to
charges of violating the statute, but reserved the right to
challenge its constitutionality. At respondent Elliott's trial, the
judge instructed the jury as to what the Commonwealth had to prove,
but did not give an instruction on the meaning of the word
"intimidate," nor on the statute's prima facie evidence provision.
Consolidating all three cases, the Virginia Supreme Court held that
the crossburning statute is unconstitutional on its face; that it
is analytically indistinguishable from the ordinance found
unconstitutional in R. A. V. v. St. Paul , 505 U. S. 377 ; that it
discriminates on the basis of content and viewpoint since it
selectively chooses only cross burning because of its distinctive
message; and that the prima facie evidence provision renders the
statute overbroad because the enhanced probability of prosecution
under the statute chills the expression of protected speech. Held: The judgment is affirmed in part, vacated in
part, and remanded. 262 Va. 764, 553 S. E. 2d 738, affirmed in
part, vacated in part, and remanded.
JUSTICE O'CONNOR delivered the opinion of the Court with respect
to Parts I, II, and III, concluding that a State, consistent with
the First Amendment, may ban cross burning carried out with the
intent to intimidate. Pp. 352-363.
(a) Burning a cross in the United States is inextricably
intertwined with the history of the Ku Klux Klan, which, following
its formation in 1866, imposed a reign of terror throughout the
South, whipping, threatening, and murdering blacks, southern whites
who disagreed with the Klan, and "carpetbagger" northern whites.
The Klan has often used cross burnings as a tool of intimidation
and a threat of impending vio- [344] lence, although such burnings have also remained potent symbols
of shared group identity and ideology, serving as a central feature
of Klan gatherings. To this day, however, regardless of whether the
message is a political one or is also meant to intimidate, the
burning of a cross is a "symbol of hate." Capitol Square Review
and Advisory Bd. v. Pinette , 515 U. S. 753 , 771. While
cross burning does not inevitably convey a message of intimidation,
often the cross burner intends that the recipients of the message
fear for their lives. And when a cross burning is used to
intimidate, few if any messages are more powerful. Pp. 352-357.
(b) The protections the First Amendment affords speech and
expressive conduct are not absolute. This Court has long recognized
that the government may regulate certain categories of expression
consistent with the Constitution. See, e. g., Chaplinsky v. New
Hampshire , 315
U. S. 568 , 571-572. For example, the First Amendment permits a
State to ban "true threats," e. g., Watts v. United
States , 394 U.
S. 705 , 708 (per curiam) , which encompass those
statements where the speaker means to communicate a serious
expression of an intent to commit an act of unlawful violence to a
particular individual or group of individuals, see, e. g.,
ibid. The speaker need not actually intend to carry out the
threat. Rather, a prohibition on true threats protects individuals
from the fear of violence and the disruption that fear engenders,
as well as from the possibility that the threatened violence will
occur. R. A. V. , supra , at 388. Intimidation in
the constitutionally proscribable sense of the word is a type of
true threat, where a speaker directs a threat to a person or group
of persons with the intent of placing the victim in fear of bodily
harm or death. Respondents do not contest that some cross burnings
fit within this meaning of intimidating speech, and rightly so. As
the history of cross burning in this country shows, that act is
often intimidating, intended to create a pervasive fear in victims
that they are a target of violence. pp. 358-360.
(c) The First Amendment permits Virginia to outlaw cross
burnings done with the intent to intimidate because burning a cross
is a particularly virulent form of intimidation. Instead of
prohibiting all intimidating messages, Virginia may choose to
regulate this subset of intimidating messages in light of cross
burning's long and pernicious history as a signal of impending
violence. A ban on cross burning carried out with the intent to
intimidate is fully consistent with this Court's holding in R.
A. V. Contrary to the Virginia Supreme Court's ruling, R.
A. V. did not hold that the First Amendment prohibits all forms of contentbased discrimination within a
proscribable area of speech. Rather, the Court specifically stated
that a particular type of content discrimination does not violate
the First Amendment when the basis for it consists [345] entirely of the very reason its entire class of speech is
proscribable. 505 U. S., at 388. For example, it is permissible to
prohibit only that obscenity that is most patently offensive in its
prurience-i. e. , that which involves the most lascivious
displays of sexual activity. Ibid. Similarly, Virginia's
statute does not run afoul of the First Amendment insofar as it
bans cross burning with intent to intimidate. Unlike the statute at
issue in R. A. V. , the Virginia statute does not single
out for opprobrium only that speech directed toward "one of the
specified disfavored topics." Id. , at 391. It does not
matter whether an individual burns a cross with intent to
intimidate because of the victim's race, gender, or religion, or
because of the victim's "political affiliation, union membership,
or homosexuality." Ibid. Thus, just as a State may
regulate only that obscenity which is the most obscene due to its
prurient content, so too may a State choose to prohibit only those
forms of intimidation that are most likely to inspire fear of
bodily harm. Pp. 360-363.
JUSTICE O'CONNOR, joined by THE CHIEF JUSTICE, JUSTICE STEVENS,
and JUSTICE BREYER, concluded in Parts IV and V that the Virginia
statute's prima facie evidence provision, as interpreted through
the jury instruction given in respondent Black's case and as
applied therein, is unconstitutional on its face. Because the
instruction is the same as the Commonwealth's Model Jury
Instruction, and because the Virginia Supreme Court had the
opportunity to expressly disavow it, the instruction's construction
of the prima facie provision is as binding on this Court as if its
precise words had been written into the statute. E. g.,
Terminiello v. Chicago , 337 U. S. 1 , 4. As
construed by the instruction, the prima facie provision strips away
the very reason why a State may ban cross burning with the intent
to intimidate. The provision permits a jury to convict in every
cross burning case in which defendants exercise their
constitutional right not to put on a defense. And even where a
defendant like Black presents a defense, the provision makes it
more likely that the jury will find an intent to intimidate
regardless of the particular facts of the case. It permits the
Commonwealth to arrest, prosecute, and convict a person based
solely on the fact of cross burning itself. As so interpreted, it
would create an unacceptable risk of the suppression of ideas. E.g., Secretary of State of Md. v. Joseph H. Munson Co. , 467 U. S. 947 ,
965, n. 13. The act of burning a cross may mean that a person is
engaging in constitutionally proscribable intimidation, or it may
mean only that the person is engaged in core political speech. The
prima facie evidence provision blurs the line between these
meanings, ignoring all of the contextual factors that are necessary
to decide whether a particular cross burning is intended to
intimidate. The First Amendment does not permit such a shortcut.
Thus, Black's conviction cannot stand, and the judgment as [346] to him is affirmed. Conversely, Elliott's jury did not receive
any instruction on the prima facie provision, and the provision was
not an issue in O'Mara's case because he pleaded guilty. The
possibility that the provision is severable, and if so, whether
Elliott and O'Mara could be retried under the statute, is left
open. Also left open is the theoretical possibility that, on
remand, the Virginia Supreme Court could interpret the prima facie
provision in a manner that would avoid the constitutional
objections described above. Pp. 363-368.
JUSTICE SCALIA agreed that this Court should vacate and remand
the judgment of the Virginia Supreme Court with respect to
respondents Elliott and O'Mara so that that court can have an
opportunity authoritatively to construe the cross-burning statute's
prima-facie-evidence provision. Pp. 368, 379.
JUSTICE SOUTER, joined by JUSTICE KENNEDY and JUSTICE GINSBURG,
concluded that the Virginia statute is unconstitutional and cannot
be saved by any exception under R. A. V. v. St. Paul , 505 U. S. 377 ,
and therefore concurred in the Court's judgment insofar as it
affirms the invalidation of respondent Black's conviction. Pp.
380-381, 387.
O'CONNOR, J., announced the judgment of the Court and delivered
the opinion of the Court with respect to Parts I, II, and III, in
which REHNQUIST, C. J., and STEVENS, SCALIA, and BREYER, JJ.,
joined, and an opinion with respect to Parts IV and V, in which
REHNQUIST, C. J., and STEVENS and BREYER, JJ., joined. STEVENS, J.,
filed a concurring opinion, post , p. 368. SCALIA, J.,
filed an opinion concurring in part, concurring in the judgment in
part, and dissenting in part, in which THOMAS, J., joined as to
Parts I and II, post , p. 368. SOUTER, J., filed an opinion
concurring in the judgment in part and dissenting in part, in which
KENNEDY and GINSBURG, JJ., joined, post , p. 380. THOMAS,
J., filed a dissenting opinion, post , p. 388. William H. Hurd , State Solicitor of Virginia, argued
the cause for petitioner. With him on the brief were Jerry W
Kilgore , Attorney General, Maureen Riley Matsen and William E. Thro , Deputy State Solicitors, and Alison
P. Landry , Assistant Attorney General.
Deputy Solicitor General Dreeben argued the cause for the United
States as amicus curiae urging reversal. With him on the brief were
Solicitor General Olson, Assistant Attorney General Boyd, Barbara
McDowell, Jessica Dunsay Silver, and Linda F. Thome. [347] Rodney A. Smolla argued the cause for respondents.
With him on the brief were James O. Broccoletti, David P. Baugh,
and Kevin E. Martingayle.[ Footnote * ]
JUSTICE O'CONNOR announced the judgment of the Court and
delivered the opinion of the Court with respect to Parts I, II, and
III, and an opinion with respect to Parts IV and V, in which THE
CHIEF JUSTICE, JUSTICE STEVENS, and JUSTICE BREYER join.
In this case we consider whether the Commonwealth of Virginia's
statute banning cross burning with "an intent to intimidate a
person or group of persons" violates the First Amendment. Va. Code
Ann. § 18.2-423 (1996). We conclude that while a State, consistent
with the First Amendment, may ban cross burning carried out with
the intent to intimidate, the provision in the Virginia statute
treating any [348] cross burning as prima facie evidence of intent to intimidate
renders the statute unconstitutional in its current form.
I
Respondents Barry Black, Richard Elliott, and Jonathan O'Mara
were convicted separately of violating Virginia's cross-burning
statute, § 18.2-423. That statute provides: "It shall be unlawful for any person or persons, with the intent
of intimidating any person or group of persons, to burn, or cause
to be burned, a cross on the property of another, a highway or
other public place. Any person who shall violate any provision of
this section shall be guilty of a Class 6 felony.
"Any such burning of a cross shall be prima facie evidence of an
intent to intimidate a person or group of persons." On August 22, 1998, Barry Black led a Ku Klux Klan rally in
Carroll County, Virginia. Twenty-five to thirty people attended
this gathering, which occurred on private property with the
permission of the owner, who was in attendance. The property was
located on an open field just off Brushy Fork Road (State Highway
690) in Cana, Virginia.
When the sheriff of Carroll County learned that a Klan rally was
occurring in his county, he went to observe it from the side of the
road. During the approximately one hour that the sheriff was
present, about 40 to 50 cars passed the site, a "few" of which
stopped to ask the sheriff what was happening on the property. App.
71. Eight to ten houses were located in the vicinity of the rally.
Rebecca Sechrist, who was related to the owner of the property
where the rally took place, "sat and watched to see wha[t] [was]
going on" from the lawn of her in-laws' house. She looked on as the
Klan prepared for the gathering and subsequently conducted the
rally itself. Id. , at 103.
During the rally, Sechrist heard Klan members speak about "what
they were" and "what they believed in." Id. , [349] at 106. The speakers "talked real bad about the blacks and the
Mexicans." Id. , at 109. One speaker told the assembled
gathering that "he would love to take a .30/.30 and just random[ly]
shoot the blacks." Ibid. The speakers also talked about
"President Clinton and Hillary Clinton," and about how their tax
money "goes to . . . the black people." Ibid. Sechrist testified that this language made her "very
. . . scared." Id. , at 110.
At the conclusion of the rally, the crowd circled around a 25-
to 30-foot cross. The cross was between 300 and 350 yards away from
the road. According to the sheriff, the cross "then all of a sudden
. . . went up in a flame." Id. , at 71. As the
cross burned, the Klan played Amazing Grace over the loudspeakers.
Sechrist stated that the cross burning made her feel "awful" and
"terrible." Id. , at 110.
When the sheriff observed the cross burning, he informed his
deputy that they needed to "find out who's responsible and explain
to them that they cannot do this in the State of Virginia." Id. , at 72. The sheriff then went down the driveway,
entered the rally, and asked "who was responsible for burning the
cross." Id. , at 74. Black responded, "I guess I am because
I'm the head of the rally." Ibid. The sheriff then told
Black, "[T]here's a law in the State of Virginia that you cannot
burn a cross and I'll have to place you under arrest for this." Ibid. Black was charged with burning a cross with the intent of
intimidating a person or group of persons, in violation of §
18.2-423. At his trial, the jury was instructed that "intent to
intimidate means the motivation to intentionally put a person or a
group of persons in fear of bodily harm. Such fear must arise from
the willful conduct of the accused rather than from some mere
temperamental timidity of the victim." Id. , at 146. The
trial court also instructed the jury that "the burning of a cross
by itself is sufficient evidence from which you may infer the
required intent." Ibid. When Black objected to this last
instruction on First Amendment grounds, [350] the prosecutor responded that the instruction was "taken
straight out of the [Virginia] Model Instructions." Id. ,
at 134. The jury found Black guilty, and fined him $2,500. The
Court of Appeals of Virginia affirmed Black's conviction. Rec. No.
1581-99-3 (Va. App., Dec. 19, 2000), App. 201.
On May 2, 1998, respondents Richard Elliott and Jonathan O'Mara,
as well as a third individual, attempted to burn a cross on the
yard of James Jubilee. Jubilee, an AfricanAmerican, was Elliott's
next-door neighbor in Virginia Beach, Virginia. Four months prior
to the incident, Jubilee and his family had moved from California
to Virginia Beach. Before the cross burning, Jubilee spoke to
Elliott's mother to inquire about shots being fired from behind the
Elliott home. Elliott's mother explained to Jubilee that her son
shot firearms as a hobby, and that he used the backyard as a firing
range.
On the night of May 2, respondents drove a truck onto Jubilee's
property, planted a cross, and set it on fire. Their apparent
motive was to "get back" at Jubilee for complaining about the
shooting in the backyard. Id. , at 241. Respondents were
not affiliated with the Klan. The next morning, as Jubilee was
pulling his car out of the driveway, he noticed the partially
burned cross approximately 20 feet from his house. After seeing the
cross, Jubilee was "very nervous" because he "didn't know what
would be the next phase," and because "a cross burned in your yard
. . . tells you that it's just the first round." Id. , at 231.
Elliott and O'Mara were charged with attempted cross burning and
conspiracy to commit cross burning. O'Mara pleaded guilty to both
counts, reserving the right to challenge the constitutionality of
the cross-burning statute. The judge sentenced O'Mara to 90 days in
jail and fined him $2,500. The judge also suspended 45 days of the
sentence and $1,000 of the fine.
At Elliott's trial, the judge originally ruled that the jury
would be instructed "that the burning of a cross by itself is [351] sufficient evidence from which you may infer the required
intent." Id. , at 221-222. At trial, however, the court
instructed the jury that the Commonwealth must prove that "the
defendant intended to commit cross burning," that "the defendant
did a direct act toward the commission of the cross burning," and
that "the defendant had the intent of intimidating any person or
group of persons." Id. , at 250. The court did not instruct
the jury on the meaning of the word "intimidate," nor on the prima
facie evidence provision of § 18.2-423. The jury found Elliott
guilty of attempted cross burning and acquitted him of conspiracy
to commit cross burning. It sentenced Elliott to 90 days in jail
and a $2,500 fine. The Court of Appeals of Virginia affirmed the
convictions of both Elliott and O'Mara. O'Mara v.
Common wealth, 33 Va. App. 525, 535 S. E. 2d 175 (2000).
Each respondent appealed to the Supreme Court of Virginia,
arguing that § 18.2-423 is facially unconstitutional. The Supreme
Court of Virginia consolidated all three cases, and held that the
statute is unconstitutional on its face. 262 Va. 764, 553 S. E. 2d
738 (2001). It held that the Virginia cross-burning statute "is
analytically indistinguishable from the ordinance found
unconstitutional in R. A. V. v. St. Paul , 505 U. S. 377 (1992)]." Id. , at 772, 553 S. E. 2d, at 742. The Virginia statute,
the court held, discriminates on the basis of content since it
"selectively chooses only cross burning because of its distinctive
message." Id. , at 774, 553 S. E. 2d, at 744. The court
also held that the prima facie evidence provision renders the
statute overbroad because "[t]he enhanced probability of
prosecution under the statute chills the expression of protected
speech." Id. , at 777, 553 S. E. 2d, at 746.
Three justices dissented, concluding that the Virginia
cross-burning statute passes constitutional muster because it
proscribes only conduct that constitutes a true threat. The
justices noted that unlike the ordinance found unconstitutional in R. A. V. v. St. Paul , 505 U. S. 377 (1992), the
Virginia [352] statute does not just target cross burning "on the basis of
race, color, creed, religion or gender." 262 Va., at 791, 553 S. E.
2d, at 753. Rather, "the Virginia statute applies to any individual
who burns a cross for any reason provided the cross is burned with
the intent to intimidate." Ibid. The dissenters also
disagreed with the majority's analysis of the prima facie provision
because the inference alone "is clearly insufficient to establish
beyond a reasonable doubt that a defendant burned a cross with the
intent to intimidate." Id. , at 795, 553 S. E. 2d, at 756.
The dissent noted that the burden of proof still remains on the
Commonwealth to prove intent to intimidate. We granted certiorari.
535 U. S. 1094 (2002).[ Footnote 1 ]
II
Cross burning originated in the 14th century as a means for
Scottish tribes to signal each other. See M. Newton & J.
Newton, The Ku Klux Klan: An Encyclopedia 145 (1991). Sir Walter
Scott used cross burnings for dramatic effect in The Lady of the
Lake, where the burning cross signified both a summons and a call
to arms. See W. Scott, The Lady of The Lake, canto third. Cross
burning in this country, however, long ago became unmoored from its
Scottish ancestry. Burning a cross in the United States is
inextricably intertwined with the history of the Ku Klux Klan.
The first Ku Klux Klan began in Pulaski, Tennessee, in the
spring of 1866. Although the Ku Klux Klan started as a social club,
it soon changed into something far different. The Klan fought
Reconstruction and the corresponding drive to allow freed blacks to
participate in the political process. [353] Soon the Klan imposed "a veritable reign of terror" throughout
the South. S. Kennedy, Southern Exposure 31 (1991) (hereinafter
Kennedy). The Klan employed tactics such as whipping, threatening
to burn people at the stake, and murder. W. Wade, The Fiery Cross:
The Ku Klux Klan in America 48-49 (1987) (hereinafter Wade). The
Klan's victims included blacks, southern whites who disagreed with
the Klan, and "carpetbagger" northern whites.
The activities of the Ku Klux Klan prompted legislative action
at the national level. In 1871, "President Grant sent a message to
Congress indicating that the Klan's reign of terror in the Southern
States had rendered life and property insecure." Jett v. Dallas
Independent School Dist., 491 U. S. 701, 722 (1989) (internal
quotation marks and alterations omitted). In response, Congress
passed what is now known as the Ku Klux Klan Act. See "An Act to
enforce the Provisions of the Fourteenth Amendment to the
Constitution of the United States, and for other Purposes," 17
Stat. 13 (now codified at 42 U. S. C. §§ 1983,1985, and 1986).
President Grant used these new powers to suppress the Klan in South
Carolina, the effect of which severely curtailed the Klan in other
States as well. By the end of Reconstruction in 1877, the first
Klan no longer existed.
The genesis of the second Klan began in 1905, with the
publication of Thomas Dixon's The Clansmen: An Historical Romance
of the Ku Klux Klan. Dixon's book was a sympathetic portrait of the
first Klan, depicting the Klan as a group of heroes "saving" the
South from blacks and the "horrors" of Reconstruction. Although the
first Klan never actually practiced cross burning, Dixon's book
depicted the Klan burning crosses to celebrate the execution of
former slaves. Id. , at 324-326; see also Capitol
Square Review and Advisory Bd. v. Pinette , 515 U. S. 753 , 770-771
(1995) (THOMAS, J., concurring). Cross burning thereby became
associated with the first Ku Klux Klan. When D. W. Griffith turned
Dixon's book into the movie The Birth of a Nation in 1915, [354] the association between cross burning and the Klan became
indelible. In addition to the cross burnings in the movie, a poster
advertising the film displayed a hooded Klansman riding a hooded
horse, with his left hand holding the reins of the horse and his
right hand holding a burning cross above his head. Wade 127. Soon
thereafter, in November 1915, the second Klan began.
From the inception of the second Klan, cross burnings have been
used to communicate both threats of violence and messages of shared
ideology. The first initiation ceremony occurred on Stone Mountain
near Atlanta, Georgia. While a 40-foot cross burned on the
mountain, the Klan members took their oaths of loyalty. See Kennedy
163. This cross burning was the second recorded instance in the
United States. The first known cross burning in the country had
occurred a little over one month before the Klan initiation, when a
Georgia mob celebrated the lynching of Leo Frank by burning a
"gigantic cross" on Stone Mountain that was "visible throughout"
Atlanta. Wade 144 (internal quotation marks omitted).
The new Klan's ideology did not differ much from that of the
first Klan. As one Klan publication emphasized, "We avow the
distinction between [the] races, . . . and we shall ever
be true to the faithful maintenance of White Supremacy and will
strenuously oppose any compromise thereof in any and all things." Id. , at 147-148 (internal quotation marks omitted).
Violence was also an elemental part of this new Klan. By September
1921, the New York World newspaper documented 152 acts of Klan
violence, including 4 murders, 41 floggings, and 27
tar-and-featherings. Wade 160.
Often, the Klan used cross burnings as a tool of intimidation
and a threat of impending violence. For example, in 1939 and 1940,
the Klan burned crosses in front of synagogues and churches. See
Kennedy 175. After one cross burning at a synagogue, a Klan member
noted that if the cross burning did not "shut the Jews up, we'll
cut a few [355] throats and see what happens." Ibid. (internal
quotation marks omitted). In Miami in 1941, the Klan burned four
crosses in front of a proposed housing project, declaring, "We are
here to keep niggers out of your town . . . . When
the law fails you, call on us." Id. , at 176 (internal
quotation marks omitted). And in Alabama in 1942, in "a whirlwind
climax to weeks of flogging and terror," the Klan burned crosses in
front of a union hall and in front of a union leader's home on the
eve of a labor election. Id. , at 180. These cross burnings
embodied threats to people whom the Klan deemed antithetical to its
goals. And these threats had special force given the long history
of Klan violence.
The Klan continued to use cross burnings to intimidate after
World War II. In one incident, an African-American "school teacher
who recently moved his family into a block formerly occupied only
by whites asked the protection of city police . . . after
the burning of a cross in his front yard." Richmond News Leader,
Jan. 21, 1949, p. 19, App. 312. And after a cross burning in
Suffolk, Virginia, during the late 1940's, the Virginia Governor
stated that he would "not allow any of our people of any race to be
subjected to terrorism or intimidation in any form by the Klan or
any other organization." D. Chalmers, Hooded Americanism: The
History of the Ku Klux Klan 333 (1980) (hereinafter Chalmers).
These incidents of cross burning, among others, helped prompt
Virginia to enact its first version of the cross-burning statute in
1950.
The decision of this Court in Brown v. Board of
Education , 347
U. S. 483 (1954), along with the civil rights movement of the
1950's and 1960's, sparked another outbreak of Klan violence. These
acts of violence included bombings, beatings, shootings, stabbings,
and mutilations. See, e.g. , Chalmers 349-350; Wade
302-303. Members of the Klan burned crosses on the lawns of those
associated with the civil rights movement, assaulted the Freedom
Riders, bombed churches, and murdered blacks as well as whites [356] whom the Klan viewed as sympathetic toward the civil rights
movement.
Throughout the history of the Klan, cross burnings have also
remained potent symbols of shared group identity and ideology. The
burning cross became a symbol of the Klan itself and a central
feature of Klan gatherings. According to the Klan constitution
(called the kloran), the "fiery cross" was the "emblem of that
sincere, unselfish devotedness of all klansmen to the sacred
purpose and principles we have espoused." The Ku Klux Klan Hearings
before the House Committee on Rules, 67th Cong., 1st Sess., 114,
Exh. G (1921); see also Wade 419. And the Klan has often published
its newsletters and magazines under the name The Fiery Cross. See id. , at 226, 489.
At Klan gatherings across the country, cross burning became the
climax of the rally or the initiation. Posters advertising an
upcoming Klan rally often featured a Klan member holding a cross.
See N. MacLean, Behind the Mask of Chivalry: The Making of the
Second Ku Klux Klan 142-143 (1994). Typically, a cross burning
would start with a prayer by the "Klavern" minister, followed by
the singing of Onward Christian Soldiers. The Klan would then light
the cross on fire, as the members raised their left arm toward the
burning cross and sang The Old Rugged Cross. Wade 185. Throughout
the Klan's history, the Klan continued to use the burning cross in
their ritual ceremonies.
For its own members, the cross was a sign of celebration and
ceremony. During a joint Nazi-Klan rally in 1940, the proceeding
concluded with the wedding of two Klan members who "were married in
full Klan regalia beneath a blazing cross." Id. , at 271.
In response to antimasking bills introduced in state legislatures
after World War II, the Klan burned crosses in protest. See
Chalmers 340. On March 26, 1960, the Klan engaged in rallies and
cross burnings throughout the South in an attempt to recruit 10
million members. See Wade 305. Later in 1960, the Klan became [357] an issue in the third debate between Richard Nixon and John
Kennedy, with both candidates renouncing the Klan. After this
debate, the Klan reiterated its support for Nixon by burning
crosses. See id. , at 309. And cross burnings featured
prominently in Klan rallies when the Klan attempted to move toward
more nonviolent tactics to stop integration. See id. , at
323; cf. Chalmers 368-369, 371-372, 380, 384. In short, a burning
cross has remained a symbol of Klan ideology and of Klan unity.
To this day, regardless of whether the message is a political
one or whether the message is also meant to intimidate, the burning
of a cross is a "symbol of hate." Capitol Square Review and
Advisory Bd. v. Pinette , 515 U. S., at 771 (THOMAS, J.,
concurring). And while cross burning sometimes carries no
intimidating message, at other times the intimidating message is
the only message conveyed. For example, when a cross
burning is directed at a particular person not affiliated with the
Klan, the burning cross often serves as a message of intimidation,
designed to inspire in the victim a fear of bodily harm. Moreover,
the history of violence associated with the Klan shows that the
possibility of injury or death is not just hypothetical. The person
who burns a cross directed at a particular person often is making a
serious threat, meant to coerce the victim to comply with the
Klan's wishes unless the victim is willing to risk the wrath of the
Klan. Indeed, as the cases of respondents Elliott and O'Mara
indicate, individuals without Klan affiliation who wish to threaten
or menace another person sometimes use cross burning because of
this association between a burning cross and violence.
In sum, while a burning cross does not inevitably convey a
message of intimidation, often the cross burner intends that the
recipients of the message fear for their lives. And when a cross
burning is used to intimidate, few if any messages are more
powerful. [358] III A
The First Amendment, applicable to the States through the
Fourteenth Amendment, provides that "Congress shall make no law
. . . abridging the freedom of speech." The hallmark of
the protection of free speech is to allow "free trade in
ideas"-even ideas that the overwhelming majority of people might
find distasteful or discomforting. Abrams v. United
States , 250 U.
S. 616 , 630 (1919) (Holmes, J., dissenting); see also Texas
v. Johnson , 491
U. S. 397 , 414 (1989) ("If there is a bedrock principle
underlying the First Amendment, it is that the government may not
prohibit the expression of an idea simply because society finds the
idea itself offensive or disagreeable"). Thus, the First Amendment
"ordinarily" denies a State "the power to prohibit dissemination of
social, economic and political doctrine which a vast majority of
its citizens believes to be false and fraught with evil
consequence." Whitney v. California , 274 U. S. 357 , 374 (1927)
(Brandeis, J., concurring). The First Amendment affords protection
to symbolic or expressive conduct as well as to actual speech. See, e.g., R. A. V. v. City of St. Paul , 505 U. S., at 382; Texas v. Johnson, supra , at 405-406; United States v.
O'Brien , 391 U.
S. 367 , 376-377 (1968); Tinker v. Des Moines Independent
Community School Dist. , 393 U. S. 503 , 505
(1969).
The protections afforded by the First Amendment, however, are
not absolute, and we have long recognized that the government may
regulate certain categories of expression consistent with the
Constitution. See, e. g., Chaplinsky v. New Hampshire , 315 U. S. 568 ,
571-572 (1942) ("There are certain well-defined and narrowly
limited classes of speech, the prevention and punishment of which
has never been thought to raise any Constitutional problem"). The
First Amendment permits "restrictions upon the content of speech in
a few limited areas, which are 'of such slight social value [359] as a step to truth that any benefit that may be derived from
them is clearly outweighed by the social interest in order and
morality.'" R. A. V. v. City of St. Paul, supra , at
382-383 (quoting Chaplinsky v. New Hampshire, supra , at
572).
Thus, for example, a State may punish those words "which by
their very utterance inflict injury or tend to incite an immediate
breach of the peace." Chaplinsky v. New Hampshire, supra ,
at 572; see also R. A. V. v. City of St. Paul, supra , at
383 (listing limited areas where the First Amendment permits
restrictions on the content of speech). We have consequently held
that fighting words-"those personally abusive epithets which, when
addressed to the ordinary citizen, are, as a matter of common
knowledge, inherently likely to provoke violent reaction" -are
generally proscribable under the First Amendment. Cohen v.
California, 403 U. S. 15, 20 (1971); see also Chaplinsky
v. New Hampshire, supra , at 572. Furthermore, "the
constitutional guarantees of free speech and free press do not
permit a State to forbid or proscribe advocacy of the use of force
or of law violation except where such advocacy is directed to
inciting or producing imminent lawless action and is likely to
incite or produce such action." Brandenburg v. Ohio , 395 U. S. 444 ,
447 (1969) (per curiam). And the First Amendment also
permits a State to ban a "true threat." Watts v. United States,
394 U. S. 705, 708 (1969) (per curiam) (internal
quotation marks omitted); accord, R. A. V. v. City of St. Paul,
supra , at 388 ("[T]hreats of violence are outside the First
Amendment"); Madsen v. Women's Health Center, Inc. , 512 U. S. 753 ,
774 (1994); Schenck v. Pro-Choice Network of Western N.Y. , 519 U. S. 357 ,
373 (1997).
"True threats" encompass those statements where the speaker
means to communicate a serious expression of an intent to commit an
act of unlawful violence to a particular individual or group of
individuals. See Watts v. United States, supra , at 708
("political hyberbole" is not a true threat); R. A. V. v. City
of St. Paul , 505 U. S., at 388. The [360] speaker need not actually intend to carry out the threat.
Rather, a prohibition on true threats "protect[s] individuals from
the fear of violence" and "from the disruption that fear
engenders," in addition to protecting people "from the possibility
that the threatened violence will occur." Ibid. Intimidation in the constitutionally proscribable sense of the word
is a type of true threat, where a speaker directs a threat to a
person or group of persons with the intent of placing the victim in
fear of bodily harm or death. Respondents do not contest that some
cross burnings fit within this meaning of intimidating speech, and
rightly so. As noted in Part II, supra , the history of
cross burning in this country shows that cross burning is often
intimidating, intended to create a pervasive fear in victims that
they are a target of violence.
B
The Supreme Court of Virginia ruled that in light of R. A.
V. v. City of St. Paul, supra , even if it is constitutional to
ban cross burning in a content-neutral manner, the Virginia
cross-burning statute is unconstitutional because it discriminates
on the basis of content and viewpoint. 262 Va., at 771-776, 553 S.
E. 2d, at 742-745. It is true, as the Supreme Court of Virginia
held, that the burning of a cross is symbolic expression. The
reason why the Klan burns a cross at its rallies, or individuals
place a burning cross on someone else's lawn, is that the burning
cross represents the message that the speaker wishes to
communicate. Individuals burn crosses as opposed to other means of
communication because cross burning carries a message in an
effective and dramatic manner.[ Footnote 2 ] [361] The fact that cross burning is symbolic expression, however,
does not resolve the constitutional question. The Supreme Court of
Virginia relied upon R. A. V. v. City of St. Paul , supra,
to conclude that once a statute discriminates on the basis of this
type of content, the law is unconstitutional. We disagree.
In R. A. V. , we held that a local ordinance that banned
certain symbolic conduct, including cross burning, when done with
the knowledge that such conduct would "'arouse anger, alarm or
resentment in others on the basis of race, color, creed, religion
or gender'" was unconstitutional. Id. , at 380 (quoting the
St. Paul Bias-Motivated Crime Ordinance, St. Paul, Minn., Legis.
Code § 292.02 (1990)). We held that the ordinance did not pass
constitutional muster because it discriminated on the basis of
content by targeting only those individuals who "provoke violence"
on a basis specified in the law. 505 U. S., at 391. The ordinance
did not cover "[t]hose who wish to use 'fighting words' in
connection with other ideas-to express hostility, for example, on
the basis of political affiliation, union membership, or
homosexuality." Ibid. This content-based discrimination
was unconstitutional because it allowed the city "to impose special
prohibitions on those speakers who express views on disfavored
subjects." Ibid. We did not hold in R. A. V. that the First Amendment
prohibits all forms of content-based discrimination within
a proscribable area of speech. Rather, we specifically stated that
some types of content discrimination did not violate the First
Amendment: "When the basis for the content discrimination consists entirely
of the very reason the entire class of speech at issue is
proscribable, no significant danger of idea or [362] viewpoint discrimination exists. Such a reason, having been
adjudged neutral enough to support exclusion of the entire class of
speech from First Amendment protection, is also neutral enough to
form the basis of distinction within the class." Id. , at
388. Indeed, we noted that it would be constitutional to ban only a
particular type of threat: "[T]he Federal Government can
criminalize only those threats of violence that are directed
against the President . . . since the reasons why threats
of violence are outside the First Amendment . . . have
special force when applied to the person of the President." Ibid. And a State may "choose to prohibit only that
obscenity which is the most patently offensive in its
prurience--i. e. , that which involves the most lascivious
displays of sexual activity." Ibid. (emphasis in
original). Consequently, while the holding of R. A. V. does not permit a State to ban only obscenity based on "offensive political messages," ibid. , or "only those
threats against the President that mention his policy on aid to
inner cities," ibid. , the First Amendment permits content
discrimination "based on the very reasons why the particular class
of speech at issue . . . is proscribable," id. ,
at 393.
Similarly, Virginia's statute does not run afoul of the First
Amendment insofar as it bans cross burning with intent to
intimidate. Unlike the statute at issue in R. A. V. , the
Virginia statute does not single out for opprobrium only that
speech directed toward "one of the specified disfavored topics." Id. , at 391. It does not matter whether an individual
burns a cross with intent to intimidate because of the victim's
race, gender, or religion, or because of the victim's "political
affiliation, union membership, or homosexuality." Ibid. Moreover, as a factual matter it is not true that cross burners
direct their intimidating conduct solely to racial or religious
minorities. See, e. g., supra , at 355 (noting the
instances of cross burnings directed at union members); State
v. Miller , 6 Kan. App. 2d 432,629 P. 2d 748 (1981)
(describing [363] the case of a defendant who burned a cross in the yard of the
lawyer who had previously represented him and who was currently
prosecuting him). Indeed, in the case of Elliott and O'Mara, it is
at least unclear whether the respondents burned a cross due to
racial animus. See 262 Va., at 791, 553 S. E. 2d, at 753 (Hassell,
J., dissenting) (noting that "these defendants burned a cross
because they were angry that their neighbor had complained about
the presence of a firearm shooting range in the Elliott's yard, not
because of any racial animus").
The First Amendment permits Virginia to outlaw cross burnings
done with the intent to intimidate because burning a cross is a
particularly virulent form of intimidation. Instead of prohibiting
all intimidating messages, Virginia may choose to regulate this
subset of intimidating messages in light of cross burning's long
and pernicious history as a signal of impending violence. Thus,
just as a State may regulate only that obscenity which is the most
obscene due to its prurient content, so too may a State choose to
prohibit only those forms of intimidation that are most likely to
inspire fear of bodily harm. A ban on cross burning carried out
with the intent to intimidate is fully consistent with our holding
in R. A. V. and is proscribable under the First
Amendment.
IV
The Supreme Court of Virginia ruled in the alternative that
Virginia's cross-burning statute was unconstitutionally overbroad
due to its provision stating that "[a]ny such burning of a cross
shall be prima facie evidence of an intent to intimidate a person
or group of persons." Va. Code Ann. § 18.2-423 (1996). The
Commonwealth added the prima facie provision to the statute in
1968. The court below did not reach whether this provision is
severable from the rest of the cross-burning statute under Virginia
law. See § 1-17.1 ("The provisions of all statutes are severable
unless . . . it is [364] Opinion of O'CONNOR, J.
apparent that two or more statutes or provisions must operate in
accord with one another"). In this Court, as in the Supreme Court
of Virginia, respondents do not argue that the prima facie evidence
provision is unconstitutional as applied to anyone of them. Rather,
they contend that the provision is unconstitutional on its
face.
The Supreme Court of Virginia has not ruled on the meaning of
the prima facie evidence provision. It has, however, stated that
"the act of burning a cross alone, with no evidence of intent to
intimidate, will nonetheless suffice for arrest and prosecution and
will insulate the Commonwealth from a motion to strike the evidence
at the end of its case-inchief." 262 Va., at 778, 553 S. E. 2d, at
746. The jury in the case of Richard Elliott did not receive any
instruction on the prima facie evidence provision, and the
provision was not an issue in the case of Jonathan O'Mara because
he pleaded guilty. The court in Barry Black's case, however,
instructed the jury that the provision means: "The burning of a
cross, by itself, is sufficient evidence from which you may infer
the required intent." App. 196. This jury instruction is the same
as the Model Jury Instruction in the Commonwealth of Virginia. See
Virginia Model Jury Instructions, Criminal, Instruction No. 10.250
(1998 and Supp. 2001).
The prima facie evidence provision, as interpreted by the jury
instruction, renders the statute unconstitutional. Because this
jury instruction is the Model Jury Instruction, and because the
Supreme Court of Virginia had the opportunity to expressly disavow
the jury instruction, the jury instruction's construction of the
prima facie provision "is a ruling on a question of state law that
is as binding on us as though the precise words had been written
into" the statute. E. g., Terminiello v. Chicago , 337 U. S. 1 , 4
(1949) (striking down an ambiguous statute on facial grounds based
upon the instruction given to the jury); see also New York v.
Ferber , 458 U.
S. 747 , 768, n. 21 (1982) (noting that Terminiello involved a facial challenge to the statute); Secretary of
State [365] of Md. v. Joseph H. Munson Co. , 467 U. S. 947 , 965, n. 13
(1984); Note, The First Amendment Overbreadth Doctrine, 83 Harv. L.
Rev. 844, 845-846, n. 8 (1970); Monaghan, Overbreadth, 1981 S. Ct.
Rev. 1, 10-12; Blakey & Murray, Threats, Free Speech, and the
Jurisprudence of the Federal Criminal Law, 2002 B. Y. U. L. Rev.
829, 883, n. 133. As construed by the jury instruction, the prima
facie provision strips away the very reason why a State may ban
cross burning with the intent to intimidate. The prima facie
evidence provision permits a jury to convict in every cross-burning
case in which defendants exercise their constitutional right not to
put on a defense. And even where a defendant like Black presents a
defense, the prima facie evidence provision makes it more likely
that the jury will find an intent to intimidate regardless of the
particular facts of the case. The provision permits the
Commonwealth to arrest, prosecute, and convict a person based
solely on the fact of cross burning itself.
It is apparent that the provision as so interpreted "'would
create an unacceptable risk of the suppression of ideas.''' Secretary of State of Md. v. Joseph H. Munson Co., supra ,
at 965, n. 13 (quoting Members of City Council of Los Angeles
v. Taxpayers for Vincent , 466 U. S. 789 , 797
(1984)). The act of burning a cross may mean that a person is
engaging in constitutionally proscribable intimidation. But that
same act may mean only that the person is engaged in core political
speech. The prima facie evidence provision in this statute blurs
the line between these two meanings of a burning cross. As
interpreted by the jury instruction, the provision chills
constitutionally protected political speech because of the
possibility that the Commonwealth will prosecute-and potentially
convict-somebody engaging only in lawful political speech at the
core of what the First Amendment is designed to protect.
As the history of cross burning indicates, a burning cross is
not always intended to intimidate. Rather, sometimes the cross
burning is a statement of ideology, a symbol of group [366] Opinion of O'CONNOR, J.
solidarity. It is a ritual used at Klan gatherings, and it is
used to represent the Klan itself. Thus, "[b]urning a cross at a
political rally would almost certainly be protected expression." R. A. V. v. St. Paul , 505 U. S., at 402, n. 4 (White, J.,
concurring in judgment) (citing Brandenburg v. Ohio, 395 U. S., at 445). Cf. National Socialist Party of America v.
Skokie , 432 U. S.
43 (1977) (per curiam). Indeed, occasionally a person
who burns a cross does not intend to express either a statement of
ideology or intimidation. Cross burnings have appeared in movies
such as Mississippi Burning, and in plays such as the stage
adaptation of Sir Walter Scott's The Lady of the Lake.
The prima facie provision makes no effort to distinguish among
these different types of cross burnings. It does not distinguish
between a cross burning done with the purpose of creating anger or
resentment and a cross burning done with the purpose of threatening
or intimidating a victim. It does not distinguish between a cross
burning at a public rally or a cross burning on a neighbor's lawn.
It does not treat the cross burning directed at an individual
differently from the cross burning directed at a group of
like-minded believers. It allows a jury to treat a cross burning on
the property of another with the owner's acquiescence in the same
manner as a cross burning on the property of another without the
owner's permission. To this extent I agree with JUSTICE SOUTER that
the prima facie evidence provision can "skew jury deliberations
toward conviction in cases where the evidence of intent to
intimidate is relatively weak and arguably consistent with a solely
ideological reason for burning." Post , at 385 (opinion
concurring in judgment in part and dissenting in part).
It may be true that a cross burning, even at a political rally,
arouses a sense of anger or hatred among the vast majority of
citizens who see a burning cross. But this sense of anger or hatred
is not sufficient to ban all cross burnings. As Gerald Gunther has
stated, "The lesson I have drawn [367] from my childhood in Nazi Germany and my happier adult life in
this country is the need to walk the sometimes difficult path of
denouncing the bigot's hateful ideas with all my power, yet at the
same time challenging any community's attempt to suppress hateful
ideas by force of law." Casper, Gerry, 55 Stan. L. Rev. 647, 649
(2002) (internal quotation marks omitted). The prima facie evidence
provision in this case ignores all of the contextual factors that
are necessary to decide whether a particular cross burning is
intended to intimidate. The First Amendment does not permit such a
shortcut.
For these reasons, the prima facie evidence provision, as
interpreted through the jury instruction and as applied in Barry
Black's case, is unconstitutional on its face. We recognize that
the Supreme Court of Virginia has not authoritatively interpreted
the meaning of the prima facie evidence provision. Unlike JUSTICE
SCALIA, we refuse to speculate on whether any interpretation of the prima facie evidence provision would satisfy
the First Amendment. Rather, all we hold is that because of the
interpretation of the prima facie evidence provision given by the
jury instruction, the provision makes the statute facially invalid
at this point. We also recognize the theoretical possibility that
the court, on remand, could interpret the provision in a manner
different from that so far set forth in order to avoid the
constitutional objections we have described. We leave open that
possibility. We also leave open the possibility that the provision
is severable, and if so, whether Elliott and O'Mara could be
retried under § 18.2-423.
V
With respect to Barry Black, we agree with the Supreme Court of
Virginia that his conviction cannot stand, and we affirm the
judgment of the Supreme Court of Virginia. With respect to Elliott
and O'Mara, we vacate the judgment [368] Opinion of SCALIA, J.
of the Supreme Court of Virginia, and remand the case for
further proceedings.
It is so ordered.
JUSTICE STEVENS, concurring.
Cross burning with "an intent to intimidate," Va. Code Ann. §
18.2-423 (1996), unquestionably qualifies as the kind of threat
that is unprotected by the First Amendment. For the reasons stated
in the separate opinions that Justice White and I wrote in R.
A. V. v. St. Paul , 505 U. S. 377 (1992),
that simple proposition provides a sufficient basis for upholding
the basic prohibition in the Virginia statute even though it does
not cover other types of threatening expressive conduct. With this
observation, I join JUSTICE O'CONNOR'S opinion.
JUSTICE SCALIA, with whom JUSTICE THOMAS joins as to Parts I and
II, concurring in part, concurring in the judgment in part, and
dissenting in part.
I agree with the Court that, under our decision in R. A. V.
v. St. Paul , 505
U. S. 377 (1992), a State may, without infringing the First
Amendment, prohibit cross burning carried out with the intent to
intimidate. Accordingly, I join Parts I-III of the Court's opinion.
I also agree that we should vacate and remand the judgment of the
Virginia Supreme Court so that that court can have an opportunity
authoritatively to construe the prima-facie-evidence provision of
Va. Code Ann. § 18.2-423 (1996). I write separately, however, to
describe what I believe to be the correct interpretation of §
18.2-423, and to explain why I believe there is no justification
for the plurality's apparent decision to invalidate that provision
on its face.
I
Section 18.2-423 provides that the burning of a cross in public
view "shall be prima facie evidence of an intent to intimidate." In
order to determine whether this component [369] of the statute violates the Constitution, it is necessary,
first, to establish precisely what the presentation of prima facie
evidence accomplishes.
Typically, "prima facie evidence" is defined as: "Such evidence as, in the judgment of the law, is sufficient to
establish a given fact . . . and which if not rebutted or
contradicted, will remain sufficient. [Such evidence], if
unexplained or uncontradicted, is sufficient to sustain a judgment
in favor of the issue which it supports, but [it] may be
contradicted by other evidence." Black's Law Dictionary 1190 (6th
ed. 1990). The Virginia Supreme Court has, in prior cases, embraced this
canonical understanding of the pivotal statutory language. e.g. , Babbitt v. Miller , 192 Va. 372, 379-380, 64
S. E. 2d 718, 722 (1951) ("Prima facie evidence is
evidence which on its first appearance is sufficient to raise a
presumption of fact or establish the fact in question unless
rebutted"). For example, in Nance v. Commonwealth , 203 Va.
428, 124 S. E. 2d 900 (1962), the Virginia Supreme Court
interpreted a law of the Commonwealth that (1) prohibited the
possession of certain "burglarious" tools "with intent to commit
burglary, robbery, or larceny . . . ," and (2) provided
that "[t]he possession of such burglarious tools . . .
shall be prima facie evidence of an intent to commit burglary,
robbery or larceny." Va. Code Ann. § 18.1-87 (1960). The court
explained that the prima-facie-evidence provision "cuts off no
defense nor interposes any obstacle to a contest of the facts, and
'relieves neither the court nor the jury of the duty to determine
all of the questions of fact from the weight of the whole
evidence.'" Nance v. Commonwealth , 203 Va., at 432, 124 S.
E. 2d, at 903-904; see also ibid. , 124 S. E. 2d, at 904
(noting that the prima-facie-evidence provision" 'is merely a rule
of evidence and not the determination of a fact
. . .'").
The established meaning in Virginia, then, of the term "prima
facie evidence" appears to be perfectly orthodox: It [370] is evidence that suffices, on its own, to establish a particular
fact. But it is hornbook law that this is true only to the extent
that the evidence goes unrebutted. "Prima facie evidence of a fact
is such evidence as, in judgment of law, is sufficient to establish
the fact; and, if not rebutted, remains sufficient for the
purpose." 7B Michie's Jurisprudence of Virginia and West Virginia §
32 (1998) (emphasis added).
To be sure, Virginia is entirely free, if it wishes, to discard
the canonical understanding of the term "prima facie evidence." Its
courts are also permitted to interpret the phrase in different ways
for purposes of different statutes. In this case, however, the
Virginia Supreme Court has done nothing of the sort. To the extent
that tribunal has spoken to the question of what "prima facie
evidence" means for purposes of § 18.2-423, it has not deviated a
whit from its prior practice and from the ordinary legal meaning of
these words. Rather, its opinion explained that under § 18.2-423,
"the act of burning a cross alone, with no evidence of intent to
intimidate, will . . . suffice for arrest and prosecution
and will insulate the Commonwealth from a motion to strike the
evidence at the end of its case-in-chief." 262 Va. 764, 778, 553 S.
E. 2d 738,746 (2001). Put otherwise, where the Commonwealth has
demonstrated through its case in chief that the defendant burned a
cross in public view, this is sufficient, at least until the
defendant has come forward with rebuttal evidence, to create a jury
issue with respect to the intent element of the offense.
It is important to note that the Virginia Supreme Court did not
suggest (as did the trial court's jury instructions in respondent
Black's case, see infra , at 377) that a jury may, in light
of the prima-facie-evidence provision, ignore any rebuttal evidence
that has been presented and, solely on the basis of a showing that
the defendant burned a cross, find that he intended to intimidate.
Nor, crucially, did that court say that the presentation of prima
facie evidence is always sufficient to get a case to a jury, i. e. , that a court may never [371] direct a verdict for a defendant who has been shown to have
burned a cross in public view, even if, by the end of trial, the
defendant has presented rebuttal evidence. Instead, according to
the Virginia Supreme Court, the effect of the prima-facie-evidence
provision is far more limited. It suffices to "insulate the
Commonwealth from a motion to strike the evidence at the end of
its case-in-chief," but it does nothing more. 262 Va., at 778,
553 S. E. 2d, at 746 (emphasis added). That is, presentation of
evidence that a defendant burned a cross in public view is
automatically sufficient, on its own, to support an inference that
the defendant intended to intimidate only until the
defendant comes forward with some evidence in rebuttal.
II
The question presented, then, is whether, given this
understanding of the term "prima facie evidence," the crossburning
statute is constitutional. The Virginia Supreme Court answered that
question in the negative. It stated that "§ 18.2-423 sweeps within
its ambit for arrest and prosecution, both protected and
unprotected speech." Ibid. "The enhanced probability of
prosecution under the statute chills the expression of protected
speech sufficiently to render the statute overbroad." Id. ,
at 777, 553 S. E. 2d, at 746.
This approach toward overbreadth analysis is unprecedented. We
have never held that the mere threat that individuals who engage in
protected conduct will be subject to arrest and prosecution
suffices to render a statute overbroad. Rather, our overbreadth
jurisprudence has consistently focused on whether the
prohibitory terms of a particular statute extend to protected
conduct; that is, we have inquired whether individuals who engage
in protected conduct can be convicted under a statute, not
whether they might be subject to arrest and prosecution. E. g.,
Houston v. Hill , 482 U. S. 451 , 459 (1987)
(a statute "that makers] unlawful a substantial amount of
constitutionally protected conduct may be held facially invalid"
(emphasis added)); Grayned v. City of Rock- [372] ford , 408
U. S. 104 , 114 (1972) (a statute may be overbroad "if in its
reach it prohibits constitutionally protected conduct"
(emphasis added)); R. A. V. v. St. Paul , 505 U. S., at 397
(White, J., concurring in judgment) (deeming the ordinance at issue
"fatally overbroad because it criminalizes . . . expression protected by the First Amendment" (emphasis added)).
Unwilling to embrace the Virginia Supreme Court's novel mode of
overbreadth analysis, today's opinion properly focuses on the
question of who may be convicted, rather than who may be arrested
and prosecuted, under § 18.2-423. Thus, it notes that "[t]he prima
facie evidence provision permits a jury to convict in
every cross-burning case in which defendants exercise their
constitutional right not to put on a defense."[ Footnote 1 ] Ante , at 365 (emphasis added). In
such cases, the plurality explains, "[t]he provision permits the
Commonwealth to arrest, prosecute, and convict a person
based solely on the fact of cross burning itself." Ibid. (emphasis added). And this, according to the plurality, is
constitutionally problematic because "a burning cross is not always
intended to intimidate," and nonintimidating cross burning cannot
be prohibited. Ibid. In particular, the opinion notes that
cross burning may serve as "a statement of ideology" or "a symbol
of group solidarity" at Ku Klux Klan rituals, and may even serve
artistic purposes as in the case of the film Mississippi Burning. Ante , at 365-366.
The plurality is correct in all of this--and it means that some
individuals who engage in protected speech may, be- [373] cause of the prima-facie-evidence provision, be subject to
conviction. Such convictions, assuming they are unconstitutional,
could be challenged on a case-by-case basis. The plurality,
however, with little in the way of explanation, leaps to the
conclusion that the possibility of such convictions
justifies facial invalidation of the statute.
In deeming § 18.2-423 facially invalid, the plurality presumably
means to rely on some species of overbreadth doctrine.[ Footnote 2 ] But it must be a rare species indeed. We
have noted that "[i]n a facial challenge to the overbreadth and
vagueness of a law, a court's first task is to determine whether
the enactment reaches a substantial amount of constitutionally
protected conduct." Hoffman Estates v. Flipside, Hoffman
Estates, Inc. , 455 U. S. 489 , 494
(1982). If one looks only to the core provision of §
18.2-423--"[i]t shall be unlawful for any person or persons, with
the intent of intimidating any person or group of persons, to burn,
or cause to be burned, a cross . . . "--it appears not to capture any protected conduct; that language is
limited in its reach to con- [374] duct which a State is, under the Court's holding, ante ,
at 363, allowed to prohibit. In order to identify any protected conduct that is affected by Virginia's cross-burning law,
the plurality is compelled to focus not on the statute's core
prohibition, but on the prima-facie-evidence provision, and hence
on the process through which the prohibited conduct may be
found by a jury.[ Footnote 3 ] And even in that
context, the plurality cannot claim that improper convictions will
result from the operation of the prima-facie-evidence provision alone. As the plurality concedes, the only persons who
might impermissibly be convicted by reason of that provision are
those who adopt a particular trial strategy, to wit, abstaining
from the presentation of a defense.
The plurality is thus left with a strikingly attenuated argument
to support the claim that Virginia's cross-burning statute is
facially invalid. The class of persons that the plurality
contemplates could impermissibly be convicted under § 18.2-423
includes only those individuals who (1) burn a cross in public
view, (2) do not intend to intimidate, (3) are nonetheless charged
and prosecuted, and (4) refuse to present a defense. Ante ,
at 365 ("The prima facie evidence provision permits a jury to
convict in every cross-burning case in which defendants exercise
their constitutional right not to put on a defense").
Conceding (quite generously, in my view) that this class of
persons exists, it cannot possibly give rise to a viable facial
challenge, not even with the aid of our First Amendment [375] overbreadth doctrine. For this Court has emphasized repeatedly
that "where a statute regulates expressive conduct, the scope of
the statute does not render it unconstitutional unless its
overbreadth is not only real, but substantial as well,
judged in relation to the statute's plainly legitimate sweep." Osborne v. Ohio , 495 U. S. 103 , 112 (1990)
(internal quotation marks omitted; emphasis added). See also Houston v. Hill , 482 U. S., at 458 ("Only a statute that
is substantially overbroad may be invalidated on its face"); Members of City Council of Los Angeles v. Taxpayers for
Vincent, 466 U. S. 789, 800 (1984) ("[T]he mere fact that one
can conceive of some impermissible applications of a statute is not
sufficient to render it susceptible to an overbreadth challenge"); New York v. Ferber , 458 U. S. 747 , 771 (1982)
("[A] law should not be invalidated for overbreadth unless it
reaches a substantial number of impermissible applications
. . . "). The notion that the set of cases identified by
the plurality in which convictions might improperly be obtained is
sufficiently large to render the statute substantially overbroad is fanciful. The potential improper convictions of which
the plurality complains are more appropriately classified as the
sort of "marginal applications" of a statute in light of which
"facial invalidation is inappropriate." Parker v. Levy , 417 U. S. 733 ,
760 (1974).[ Footnote 4 ] [376] Perhaps more alarming, the plurality concedes, ante , at
364, 365, that its understanding of the prima-facie-evidence
provision is premised on the jury instructions given in respondent
Black's case. This would all be well and good were it not for the
fact that the plurality facially invalidates § 18.2-423. Ante , at 367 ("[T]he prima facie evidence provision, as
interpreted through the jury instruction and as applied in Barry
Black's case, is unconstitutional on its face"). I am aware of no
case--and the plurality cites none--in which we have facially
invalidated an ambiguous statute on the basis of a
constitutionally troubling jury instruction.[ Footnote 5 ] And it is alto- [377] gether unsurprising that there is no precedent for such a
holding. For where state law is ambiguous, treating jury
instructions as binding interpretations would cede an enormous
measure of power over state law to trial judges. A single judge's
idiosyncratic reading of a state statute could trigger its
invalidation. In this case, the troubling instruction--"The burning
of a cross, by itself, is sufficient evidence from which you may
infer the required intent," App. 196--was taken verbatim from
Virginia's Model Jury Instructions. But these Model Instructions
have been neither promulgated by the legislature nor formally
adopted by the Virginia Supreme Court. And it is hornbook law, in
Virginia as elsewhere, that "[p]roffered instructions which do not
correctly state the law . . . are erroneous and should be
refused." lOA Michie's Jurisprudence of Virginia and West Virginia,
Instructions § 15, p. 35 (Supp. 2000).
The plurality's willingness to treat this jury instruction as
binding (and to strike down § 18.2-423 on that basis) would be
shocking enough had the Virginia Supreme Court offered no guidance
as to the proper construction of the prima-facieevidence provision.
For ordinarily we would decline to pass upon the constitutionality
of an ambiguous state statute until that State's highest court had
provided a binding construc- [378] tion. E. g., Arizonans for Official English v. Arizona,
520 U. S. 43, 78 (1997). If there is any exception to that
rule, it is the case where one of two possible interpretations of
the state statute would clearly render it unconstitutional, and the
other would not. In that situation, applying the maxim "ut res
magis valeat quam pereat" we would do precisely the
opposite of what the plurality does here-that is, we would
adopt the alternative reading that renders the statute
constitutional rather than unconstitutional. The plurality's
analysis is all the more remarkable given the dissonance between
the interpretation of § 18.2-423 implicit in the jury instruction
and the one suggested by the Virginia Supreme Court. That court's
opinion did not state that, once proof of public cross burning is
presented, a jury is permitted to infer an intent to intimidate solely on this basis and regardless of whether a defendant
has offered evidence to rebut any such inference. To the contrary,
in keeping with the black-letter understanding of "prima facie
evidence," the Virginia Supreme Court explained that such evidence
suffices only to "insulate the Commonwealth from a motion to strike
the evidence at the end of its case-in-chief." 262 Va., at 778, 553
S. E. 2d, at 746. The court did not so much as hint that a jury is
permitted, under § 18.2-423, to ignore rebuttal evidence and infer
an intent to intimidate strictly on the basis of the prosecution's
prima facie case. And unless and until the Supreme Court of
Virginia tells us that the prima-facieevidence provision permits a
jury to infer intent under such conditions, this Court is entirely
unjustified in facially invalidating § 18.2-423 on this basis.
As its concluding performance, in an apparent effort to paper
over its unprecedented decision facially to invalidate a statute in
light of an errant jury instruction, the plurality states: "We recognize that the Supreme Court of Virginia has not
authoritatively interpreted the meaning of the prima facie evidence
provision . . . . We also recognize the [379] theoretical possibility that the court, on remand, could
interpret the provision in a manner different from that so far set
forth in order to avoid the constitutional objections we have
described. We leave open that possibility." Ante , at
367. Now this is truly baffling. Having declared, in the immediately
preceding sentence, that § 18.2-423 is "unconstitutional on its
face," ibid. (emphasis added), the plurality holds out the
possibility that the Virginia Supreme Court will offer some saving
construction of the statute. It should go without saying that if a
saving construction of § 18.2-423 is possible, then facial
invalidation is inappropriate. E. g., Harrison v. NAACp , 360 U. S. 167 ,
176 (1959) ("[N]o principle has found more consistent or clear
expression than that the federal courts should not adjudicate the
constitutionality of state enactments fairly open to interpretation
until the state courts have been afforded a reasonable opportunity
to pass upon them"). So, what appears to have happened is that the
plurality has facially invalidated not § 18.2-423, but its own
hypothetical interpretation of § 18.2-423, and has then remanded to
the Virginia Supreme Court to learn the actual interpretation of § 18.2-423. Words cannot express my wonderment at
this virtuoso performance.
III
As the analysis in Part I, supra , demonstrates, I
believe the prima-facie-evidence provision in Virginia's
crossburning statute is constitutionally unproblematic.
Nevertheless, because the Virginia Supreme Court has not yet
offered an authoritative construction of § 18.2-423, I concur in
the Court's decision to vacate and remand the judgment with respect
to respondents Elliott and O'Mara. I also agree that respondent
Black's conviction cannot stand. As noted above, the jury in
Black's case was instructed that "[t]he burning of a cross, by
itself , is sufficient evidence from which you may infer the
required intent." App. 196 (emphasis [380] added). Where this instruction has been given, it is impossible
to determine whether the jury has rendered its verdict (as it must)
in light of the entire body of facts before it-- including evidence that might rebut the presumption that the cross burning
was done with an intent to intimidate--or, instead, has chosen to
ignore such rebuttal evidence and focused exclusively on the fact
that the defendant burned a cross.[ Footnote 6 ]
Still, I cannot go along with the Court's decision to affirm the
judgment with respect to Black. In that judgment, the Virginia
Supreme Court, having erroneously concluded that § 18.2-423 is
overbroad, not only vacated Black's conviction, but dismissed the
indictment against him as well. 262 Va., at 779, 553 S. E. 2d, at
746. Because I believe the constitutional defect in Black's
conviction is rooted in a jury instruction and not in the statute
itself, I would not dismiss the indictment and would permit the
Commonwealth to retry Black if it wishes to do so. It is an
interesting question whether the plurality's willingness to let the
Virginia Supreme Court resolve the plurality's make-believe facial
invalidation of the statute extends as well to the facial
invalidation insofar as it supports dismissal of the indictment
against Black. Logically, there is no reason why it would not.
JUSTICE SOUTER, with whom JUSTICE KENNEDY and JusTICE GINSBURG
join, concurring in the judgment in part and dissenting in
part.
I agree with the majority that the Virginia statute makes a
content-based distinction within the category of punishable
intimidating or threatening expression, the very type of dis- [381] tinction we considered in R. A. V. v. St. Paul , 505 U. S. 377 (1992). I disagree that any exception should save Virginia's law
from unconstitutionality under the holding in R. A. V. or
any acceptable variation of it.
I
The ordinance struck down in R. A. V. , as it had been
construed by the State's highest court, prohibited the use of
symbols (including but not limited to a burning cross) as the
equivalent of generally proscribable fighting words, but the
ordinance applied only when the symbol was provocative " 'on the
basis of race, color, creed, religion or gender.''' Id. ,
at 380 (quoting St. Paul, Minn., Legis. Code § 292.02 (1990)).
Although the Virginia statute in issue here contains no such
express "basis of" limitation on prohibited subject matter, the
specific prohibition of cross burning with intent to intimidate
selects a symbol with particular content from the field of all
proscribable expression meant to intimidate. To be sure, that
content often includes an essentially intimidating message, that
the cross burner will harm the victim, most probably in a physical
way, given the historical identification of burning crosses with
arson, beating, and lynching. But even when the symbolic act is
meant to terrify, a burning cross may carry a further, ideological
message of white Protestant supremacy. The ideological message not
only accompanies many threatening uses of the symbol, but is also
expressed when a burning cross is not used to threaten but merely
to symbolize the supremacist ideology and the solidarity of those
who espouse it. As the majority points out, the burning cross can
broadcast threat and ideology together, ideology alone, or threat
alone, as was apparently the choice of respondents Elliott and
O'Mara. Ante , at 354357,363.
The issue is whether the statutory prohibition restricted to
this symbol falls within one of the exceptions to R. A.
V. 's general condemnation of limited content-based
proscription [382] within a broader category of expression proscribable generally.
Because of the burning cross's extraordinary force as a method of
intimidation, the R. A. V. exception most likely to cover
the statute is the first of the three mentioned there, which the R. A. V. opinion called an exception for content
discrimination on a basis that "consists entirely of the very
reason the entire class of speech at issue is proscribable." 505 U.
S., at 388. This is the exception the majority speaks of here as
covering statutes prohibiting "particularly virulent" proscribable
expression. Ante , at 363.
I do not think that the Virginia statute qualifies for this
virulence exception as R. A. V. explained it. The statute
fits poorly with the illustrative examples given in R. A.
V. , none of which involves communication generally associated
with a particular message, and in fact, the majority's discussion
of a special virulence exception here moves that exception toward a
more flexible conception than the version in R. A. V. I
will reserve judgment on that doctrinal development, for even on a
pragmatic conception of R. A. V. and its exceptions the
Virginia statute could not pass muster, the most obvious hurdle
being the statute's prima facie evidence provision. That provision
is essential to understanding why the statute's tendency to
suppress a message disqualifies it from any rescue by exception
from R. A. V. 's general rule.
II R. A. V. defines the special virulence exception to the
rule barring content-based subclasses of categorically pros
cribable expression this way: prohibition by subcategory is
nonetheless constitutional if it is made "entirely" on the "basis"
of "the very reason" that "the entire class of speech at issue is
proscribable" at all. 505 U. S., at 388. The Court explained that
when the subcategory is confined to the most obviously proscribable
instances, "no significant danger of idea or viewpoint
discrimination exists," ibid. , and the expla- [383] nation was rounded out with some illustrative examples. None of
them, however, resembles the case before us.[ Footnote 1 ]
The first example of permissible distinction is for a
prohibition of obscenity unusually offensive "in its prurience," ibid. (emphasis deleted), with citation to a case in which
the Seventh Circuit discussed the difference between obscene
depictions of actual people and simulations. As that court noted,
distinguishing obscene publications on this basis does not suggest
discrimination on the basis of the message conveyed. Kucharek
v. Hanaway , 902 F.2d
513 , 517-518 (1990). The opposite is true, however, when a
general prohibition of intimidation is rejected in favor of a
distinct proscription of intimidation by cross burning. The cross
may have been selected because of its special power to threaten,
but it may also have been singled out because of disapproval of its
message of white supremacy, either because a legislature thought
white supremacy was a pernicious doctrine or because it found that
dramatic, public espousal of it was a civic embarrassment. Thus,
there is no kinship between the cross-burning statute and the core
prurience example.
Nor does this case present any analogy to the statute
prohibiting threats against the President, the second of R. A.
V. 's examples of the virulence exception and the one the
majority relies upon. Ante , at 362. The content
discrimination in that statute relates to the addressee of the
threat and reflects the special risks and costs associated with
threatening the President. Again, however, threats against the
President are not generally identified by reference to the content
of any message that may accompany the threat, let alone any
viewpoint, and there is no obvious correlation in fact between
victim and message. Millions of statements are made about the
President every day on every subject [384] and from every standpoint; threats of violence are not an
integral feature of anyone subject or viewpoint as distinct from
others. Differential treatment of threats against the President,
then, selects nothing but special risks, not special messages. A
content-based proscription of cross burning, on the other hand, may
be a subtle effort to ban not only the intensity of the
intimidation cross burning causes when done to threaten, but also
the particular message of white supremacy that is broadcast even by
nonthreatening cross burning.
I thus read R. A. V. 's examples of the particular
virulence exception as covering prohibitions that are not clearly
associated with a particular viewpoint, and that are consequently
different from the Virginia statute. On that understanding of
things, I necessarily read the majority opinion as treating R.
A. V. 's virulence exception in a more flexible, pragmatic
manner than the original illustrations would suggest. Ante , at 363. Actually, another way of looking at today's
decision would see it as a slight modification of R. A.
V. 's third exception, which allows content-based
discrimination within a proscribable category when its "nature" is
such "that there is no realistic possibility that official
suppression of ideas is afoot." R. A. V. , supra ,
at 390. The majority's approach could be taken as recognizing an
exception to R. A. V. when circumstances show that the
statute's ostensibly valid reason for punishing particularly
serious proscribable expression probably is not a ruse for message
suppression, even though the statute may have a greater (but not
exclusive) impact on adherents of one ideology than on others, ante , at 362-363.
III
My concern here, in any event, is not with the merit of a
pragmatic doctrinal move. For whether or not the Court should
conceive of exceptions to R. A. V. 's general rule in a
more practical way, no content-based statute should survive even
under a pragmatic recasting of R. A. V. without a high
probability that no "official suppression of ideas is afoot," [385] 505 U. S., at 390. I believe the prima facie evidence provision
stands in the way of any finding of such a high probability
here.
Virginia's statute provides that burning a cross on the property
of another, a highway, or other public place is "prima facie
evidence of an intent to intimidate a person or group of persons."
Va. Code Ann. § 18.2-423 (1996). While that language was added by
amendment to the earlier portion of the statute criminalizing cross
burning with intent to intimidate, ante , at 363 (plurality
opinion), it was a part of the prohibitory statute at the time
these respondents burned crosses, and the whole statute at the time
of respondents' conduct is what counts for purposes of the First
Amendment.
As I see the likely significance of the evidence provision, its
primary effect is to skew jury deliberations toward conviction in
cases where the evidence of intent to intimidate is relatively weak
and arguably consistent with a solely ideological reason for
burning. To understand how the provision may work, recall that the
symbolic act of burning a cross, without more, is consistent with
both intent to intimidate and intent to make an ideological
statement free of any aim to threaten. Ante , at 354-357.
One can tell the intimidating instance from the wholly ideological
one only by reference to some further circumstance. In the real
world, of course, and in real-world prosecutions, there will always
be further circumstances, and the factfinder will always learn
something more than the isolated fact of cross burning. Sometimes
those circumstances will show an intent to intimidate, but
sometimes they will be at least equivocal, as in cases where a
white supremacist group burns a cross at an initiation ceremony or
political rally visible to the public. In such a case, if the
factfinder is aware of the prima facie evidence provision, as the
jury was in respondent Black's case, ante , at 349-350, the
provision will have the practical effect of tilting the jury's
thinking in favor of the prosecution. What is significant is not
that the provision [386] permits a factfinder's conclusion that the defendant acted with
proscribable and punishable intent without any further indication,
because some such indication will almost always be presented. What
is significant is that the provision will encourage a factfinder to
err on the side of a finding of intent to intimidate when the
evidence of circumstances fails to point with any clarity either to
the criminal intent or to the permissible one. The effect of such a
distortion is difficult to remedy, since any guilty verdict will
survive sufficiency review unless the defendant can show that,
"viewing the evidence in the light most favorable to the
prosecution, [no] rational trier of fact could have found the
essential elements of the crime beyond a reasonable doubt." Jackson v. Virginia , 443 U. S. 307 , 319
(1979). The provision will thus tend to draw nonthreatening
ideological expression within the ambit of the prohibition of
intimidating expression, as JUSTICE O'CONNOR notes. Ante ,
at 365-366 (plurality opinion).
To the extent the prima facie evidence provision skews
prosecutions, then, it skews the statute toward suppressing ideas.
Thus, the appropriate way to consider the statute's prima facie
evidence term, in my view, is not as if it were an overbroad
statutory definition amenable to severance or a narrowing
construction. The question here is not the permissible scope of an
arguably overbroad statute, but the claim of a clearly
content-based statute to an exception from the general prohibition
of content-based proscriptions, an exception that is not warranted
if the statute's terms show that suppression of ideas may be afoot.
Accordingly, the way to look at the prima facie evidence provision
is to consider it for any indication of what is afoot. And if we
look at the provision for this purpose, it has a very obvious
significance as a mechanism for bringing within the statute's
prohibition some expression that is doubtfully threatening though
certainly distasteful.
It is difficult to conceive of an intimidation case that could
be easier to prove than one with cross burning, assum- [387] ing any circumstances suggesting intimidation are present. The
provision, apparently so unnecessary to legitimate prosecution of
intimidation, is therefore quite enough to raise the question
whether Virginia's content-based statute seeks more than mere
protection against a virulent form of intimidation. It consequently
bars any conclusion that an exception to the general rule of R.
A. V. is warranted on the ground "that there is no realistic
[or little realistic] possibility that official suppression of
ideas is afoot," 505 U. S., at 390.[ Footnote 2 ]
Since no R. A. V. exception can save the statute as
content based, it can only survive if narrowly tailored to serve a
compelling state interest, id. , at 395-396, a stringent
test the statute cannot pass; a content-neutral statute banning
intimidation would achieve the same object without singling out
particular content.
IV
I conclude that the statute under which all three of the
respondents were prosecuted violates the First Amendment, since the
statute's content-based distinction was invalid at the time of the
charged activities, regardless of whether the prima facie evidence
provision was given any effect in any respondent's individual case.
In my view, severance of the prima facie evidence provision now
could not eliminate the unconstitutionality of the whole statute at
the time of the respondents' conduct. I would therefore affirm the
judgment of the Supreme Court of Virginia vacating the respondents'
convictions and dismissing the indictments. Accordingly, I concur
in the Court's judgment as to respondent Black and dissent as to
respondents Elliott and O'Mara. [388] In every culture, certain things acquire meaning well beyond
what outsiders can comprehend. That goes for both the sacred, see Texas v. Johnson , 491 U. S. 397 , 422-429
(1989) (REHNQUIST, C. J., dissenting) (describing the unique
position of the American flag in our Nation's 200 years of
history), and the profane. I believe that cross burning is the
paradigmatic example of the latter.
I
Although I agree with the majority's conclusion that it is
constitutionally permissible to "ban . . . cross burning
carried out with the intent to intimidate," ante , at 363,
I believe that the majority errs in imputing an expressive
component to the activity in question, see ante , at 362
(relying on one of the exceptions to the First Amendment's
prohibition on content-based discrimination outlined in R. A.
V. v. St. Paul , 505 U. S. 377 (1992)). In
my view, whatever expressive value cross burning has, the
legislature simply wrote it out by banning only intimidating
conduct undertaken by a particular means. A conclusion that the
statute prohibiting cross burning with intent to intimidate sweeps
beyond a prohibition on certain conduct into the zone of expression
overlooks not only the words of the statute but also reality.
A
"In holding [the ban on cross burning with intent to intimidate]
unconstitutional, the Court ignores Justice Holmes' familiar
aphorism that 'a page of history is worth a volume of logic.'" Texas v. Johnson, supra , at 421 (REHNQUIST, C. J.,
dissenting) (quoting New York Trust Co. v. Eisner , 256 U. S. 345 ,
349 (1921)). "The world's oldest, most persistent terrorist organization is
not European or even Middle Eastern in origin. Fifty years before
the Irish Republican Army was orga- [389] nized, a century before Al Fatah declared its holy war on
Israel, the Ku Klux Klan was actively harassing, torturing, and
murdering in the United States. Today . . . its members
remain fanatically committed to a course of violent opposition to
social progress and racial equality in the United States." M.
Newton & J. Newton, The Ku Klux Klan: An Encyclopedia vii
(1991) (hereinafter Newton & Newton). To me, the majority's brief history of the Ku Klux Klan only
reinforces this common understanding of the Klan as a terrorist
organization, which, in its endeavor to intimidate, or even
eliminate those it dislikes, uses the most brutal of methods.
Such methods typically include cross burning-"a tool for the
intimidation and harassment of racial minorities, Catholics, Jews,
Communists, and any other groups hated by the Klan." Capitol
Square Review and Advisory Bd. v. Pinette , 515 U. S. 753 , 770 (1995)
(THOMAS, J., concurring). For those not easily frightened, cross
burning has been followed by more extreme measures, such as
beatings and murder. J. Williams, Eyes on the Prize: America's
Civil Rights Years, 1954-1965, p. 39 (1987). As the Government
points out, the association between acts of intimidating cross
burning and violence is well documented in recent American history.
Brief for United States as Amicus Curiae 3-4, and n.
2.[ Footnote 1 ] [390] Indeed, the connection between cross burning and violence is
well ingrained, and lower courts have so recognized: "After the mother saw the burning cross, she was crying on her
knees in the living room. [She] felt feelings of frustration and
intimidation and feared for her husband's life. She testified what
the burning cross symbolized to her as a black American: 'Nothing
good. Murder, hanging, rape, lynching. Just anything bad [391] that you can name. It is the worst thing that could happen to a
person.' . . . Mr. Heisser told the probation officer
that at the time of the occurrence, if the family did not leave, he
believed someone would return to commit murder
. . . . Seven months after the incident, the
family still lived in fear . . . . This is a
reaction reasonably to be anticipated from this criminal conduct."
United States v. Skillman , 922 F.2d
1370 , 1378 (CA9 1991) (emphasis added). But the perception that a burning cross is a threat and a
precursor of worse things to come is not limited to blacks. Because
the modern Klan expanded the list of its enemies beyond blacks and
"radical[sJ" to include Catholics, Jews, most immigrants, and labor
unions, Newton & Newton ix, a burning cross is now widely
viewed as a signal of impending terror and lawlessness. I
wholeheartedly agree with the observation made by the Commonwealth
of Virginia: "A white, conservative, middle-class Protestant, waking up at
night to find a burning cross outside his home, will reasonably
understand that someone is threatening him. His reaction is likely
to be very different than if he were to find, say, a burning circle
or square. In the latter case, he may call the fire department. In
the former, he will probably call the police." Brief for Petitioner
26. In our culture, cross burning has almost invariably meant
lawlessness and understandably instills in its victims wellgrounded
fear of physical violence.
B
Virginia's experience has been no exception. In Virginia, though
facing widespread opposition in the 1920's, the Klan developed
localized strength in the southeastern part of the Commonwealth,
where there were reports of scattered raids and floggings. Newton
& Newton 585. Although the Klan was disbanded at the national
level in 1944, ibid. , a series of [392] cross burnings in Virginia took place between 1949 and 1952. See
262 Va. 764, 771, n. 2, 553 S. E. 2d 738, 742, n. 2 (2001)
(collecting newspaper accounts of cross burnings in Virginia during
that time period); see also Cross Fired Near Suffolk Stirs Probe,
Burning Second in Past Week, Richmond Times-Dispatch, Jan. 23,
1949, section 2, p. 1, App. 313, 314-315 (The second reported cross
burning within a week in 1949 "brought to eight the number which
have occurred in Virginia during the past year. Six of the
incidents have occurred in N ansemond County. Four crosses were
burned near Suffolk last Spring, and about 150 persons took part in
the December 11 cross burning near Whaleyville. No arrests have
been made in connection with any of the incidents").
Most of the crosses were burned on the lawns of black families,
who either were business owners or lived in predominantly white
neighborhoods. See Police Aid Requested by Teacher, Cross is Burned
in Negro's Yard, Richmond News Leader, Jan. 21, 1949, p. 19, App.
312; Cross Fired Near Suffolk Stirs Probe, Burning Second in Past
Week, supra , at 313; Cross is Burned at Reedville Home,
Richmond News Leader, Apr. 14, 1951, p. 1, App. 321. At least one
of the cross burnings was accompanied by a shooting. Cross Burned
at Manakin, Third in Area, supra n. 1, at 318. The crosses
burned near residences were about five to six feet tall, while a
"huge cross reminiscent of the Ku Klux Klan days" that burned "atop
a hill" as part of the initiation ceremony of the secret
organization of the Knights of Kavaliers was 12 feet tall. Huge
Cross is Burned on Hill Just South of Covington, Richmond
Times-Dispatch, Apr. 14, 1950, p. 6, App. 316. These incidents
were, in the words of the time, "terroristic [sic]" and
"un-American act[s], designed to intimidate Negroes from
seeking their rights as citizens." Cross Fired Near Suffolk Stirs
Probe, Burning Second in Past Week, supra , at 315
(emphasis added). [393] In February 1952, in light of this series of cross burnings and
attendant reports that the Klan, "long considered dead in Virginia,
is being revitalized in Richmond," Governor Battle announced that
"Virginia 'might well consider passing legislation' to restrict the
activities of the Ku Klux Klan." "State Might Well Consider"
Restrictions on Ku Klux Klan, Governor Battle Comments, Richmond
Times-Dispatch, Feb. 6, 1952, p. 7, App. 321. As newspapers
reported at the time, the bill was "to ban the burning of crosses
and other similar evidences of terrorism." Name Rider
Approved by House, Richmond News Leader, Feb. 23,1952, p.1, App.
325 (emphasis added). The bill was presented to the House of
Delegates by a former FBI agent and future two-term Governor,
Delegate Mills E. Godwin, Jr. "Godwin said law and order in the
State were impossible if organized groups could create
fear by intimidation." Bill to Curb KKK Passed By the House,
Action is Taken Without Debate, Richmond TimesDispatch, Mar. 8,
1952, p. 5, App. 325 (emphasis added).
That in the early 1950's the people of Virginia viewed cross
burning as creating an intolerable atmosphere of terror is not
surprising: Although the cross took on some religious significance
in the 1920's when the Klan became connected with certain southern
white clergy, by the postwar period it had reverted to its original
function "as an instrument of intimidation." W. Wade, The Fiery
Cross: The Ku Klux Klan in America 185, 279 (1987).
Strengthening Delegate Godwin's explanation, as well as my
conclusion, that the legislature sought to criminalize terrorizing conduct is the fact that at the time the statute was
enacted, racial segregation was not only the prevailing practice,
but also the law in Virginia.[ Footnote 2 ] And,
just two years [394] after the enactment of this statute, Virginia's General Assembly
embarked on a campaign of "massive resistance" in response to Brown v. Board of Education , 347 U. S. 483 (1954). See
generally Griffin v. School Bd. of Prince Edward Cty. , 377 U. S. 218 ,
221 (1964); Harrison v. Day, 200 Va. 439, 448-454, 106 S.
E. 2d 636, 644-648 (1959) (describing massive resistance as
legislatively mandated attempt to close public schools rather than
desegregate).
It strains credulity to suggest that a state legislature that
adopted a litany of segregationist laws self-contradictorily
intended to squelch the segregationist message. Even for
segregationists, violent and terroristic conduct, the Siamese twin
of cross burning, was intolerable. The ban on cross burning with
intent to intimidate demonstrates that even segregationists
understood the difference between intimidating and terroristic
conduct and racist expression. It is simply beyond belief that, in
passing the statute now under review, the Virginia Legislature was
concerned with anything but penalizing conduct it must have viewed
as particularly vicious.
Accordingly, this statute prohibits only conduct, not
expression. And, just as one cannot burn down someone's house to
make a political point and then seek refuge in the First Amendment,
those who hate cannot terrorize and intimidate to make their point.
In light of my conclusion that [395] the statute here addresses only conduct, there is no need to
analyze it under any of our First Amendment tests.
II
Even assuming that the statute implicates the First Amendment,
in my view, the fact that the statute permits a jury to draw an
inference of intent to intimidate from the cross burning itself
presents no constitutional problems. Therein lies my primary
disagreement with the plurality.
A
"The threshold inquiry in ascertaining the constitutional
analysis applicable to [a jury instruction involving a presumption]
is to determine the nature of the presumption it describes." Francis v. Franklin , 471 U. S. 307 , 313-314
(1985) (internal quotation marks omitted). We have categorized the
presumptions as either permissive inferences or mandatory
presumptions. Id. , at 314.
To the extent we do have a construction of this statute by the
Virginia Supreme Court, we know that both the majority and the
dissent agreed that the presumption was "a statutorily supplied inference," 262 Va., at 778, 553 S. E. 2d, at 746
(emphasis added); id. , at 795, 553 S. E. 2d, at 755
(Hassell, J., dissenting) ("Code § 18.2-423 creates a statutory inference" (emphasis added)). Under Virginia law, the term
"inference" has a well-defined meaning and is distinct from the
term "presumption." Martin v. Phillips , 235 Va. 523, 526,
369 S. E. 2d 397, 399 (1988). "A presumption is a rule of law that compels the fact finder to
draw a certain conclusion or a certain inference from a given set
of facts.[1] The primary significance of a presumption is that it
operates to shift to the opposing party the burden of producing
evidence tending to rebut the presumption.[2] No presumption,
however, can operate to shift the ultimate burden of persuasion
from the party upon whom it was originally cast. [396] "[1] In contrast, an inference, sometimes loosely referred to as
a presumption of fact, does not compel a specific conclusion. An
inference merely applies to the rational potency or probative value
of an evidentiary fact to which the fact finder may attach whatever
force or weight it deems best. 9 J. Wigmore, Evidence in Trials at
Common Law § 2491(1), at 304 (Chad. rev. 1981).
"[2] An inference, on the other hand, does not invoke this
procedural consequence of shifting the burden of production. Id. " Ibid. (some citations omitted; emphasis added). Both the majority and the dissent below classified the clause in
question as an "inference," and I see no reason to disagree,
particularly in light of the instructions given to the jury in
Black's case, requiring it to find guilt beyond a reasonable doubt
both as to the fact that "the defendant burned or caused to be
burned a cross in a public place," and that "he did so with the
intent to intimidate any person or group of persons," 262 Va., at
796, 553 S. E. 2d, at 756 (Hassell, J., dissenting) (quoting jury
instructions in Black's case).
Even though under Virginia law the statutory provision at issue
here is characterized as an "inference," the Court must still
inquire whether the label Virginia attaches corresponds to the
categorization our cases have given such clauses. In this respect,
it is crucial to observe that what Virginia law calls an
"inference" is what our cases have termed a "permissive inference
or presumption." County Court of Ulster Cty. v. Allen , 442 U. S. 140 ,
157 (1979).[ Footnote 3 ] Given that this
3 As the Court explained in Allen , a permissive
inference or presumption "allows-but does not require-the trier of
fact to infer the elemental fact from proof by the prosecutor of
the basic one and which places no burden of any kind on the
defendant. In that situation the basic fact may constitute prima
facie evidence of the elemental fact . . . . Because
this permissive presumption leaves the trier of fact free to credit
or reject the inference and does not shift the burden of proof, it
affects the application of the 'beyond a reasonable doubt' standard
only if, under the facts of the case, there is no rational way the
trier could make the connection permit- [397] Court's definitions of a "permissive inference" and a "mandatory
presumption" track Virginia's definitions of "inference" and
"presumption," the Court should judge the Virginia statute based on
the constitutional analysis applicable to "inferences": they raise
no constitutional flags unless there is "no rational way the trier
could make the connection permitted by the inference." Ibid. As explained in Part I, supra, not making a
connection between cross burning and intimidation would be
irrational.
But even with respect to statutes containing a mandatory
irrebuttable presumption as to intent, the Court has not shown much
concern. For instance, there is no scienter requirement for
statutory rape. See, e.g. , Tenn. Code Ann. § 39-13-506
(1997); Ore. Rev. Stat. Ann. § 163.365 (1989); Mo. Rev. Stat. §
566.032 (2000); Ga. Code Ann. § 16-6-3 (1996). That is, a person
can be arrested, prosecuted, and convicted for having sex with a
minor, without the government ever producing any evidence, let
alone proving beyond a reasonable doubt, that a minor did not
consent. In fact, "[f]or purposes of the child molesting statute
. . . consent is irrelevant. The legislature has
determined in such cases that children under the age of sixteen
(16) cannot, as a matter of law, consent to have sexual acts
performed upon them, or consent to engage in a sexual act with
someone over the age of sixteen (16)." Warrick v. State ,
538 N. E. 2d 952, 954 (Ind. App. 1989) (citing Ind. Code §
35-42-4-3 (1988)). The legislature finds the behavior so
reprehensible that the intent is satisfied by the mere act
committed by a perpetrator. Considering [398] the horrific effect cross burning has on its victims, it is also
reasonable to presume intent to intimidate from the act itself.
Statutes prohibiting possession of drugs with intent to
distribute operate much the same way as statutory rape laws. Under
these statutes, the intent to distribute is effectively satisfied
by possession of some threshold amount of drugs. See, e.g. , Del. Code Ann., Tit. 16, §4753A (1987); Mass. Gen.
Laws, ch. 94C , § 32E (West 1997); S. C. Code Ann. §
44-53-370 (West 2000). As with statutory rape, the presumption of
intent in such statutes is irrebuttable-not only can a person be
arrested for the crime of possession with intent to distribute (or
"trafficking") without any evidence of intent beyond quantity of
drugs, but such person cannot even mount a defense to the element
of intent. However, as with statutory rape statutes, our cases do
not reveal any controversy with respect to the presumption of
intent in these drug statutes.
Because the prima facie clause here is an inference, not an
irrebuttable presumption, there is all the more basis under our due
process precedents to sustain this statute.
B
The plurality, however, is troubled by the presumption because
this is a First Amendment case. The plurality laments the fate of
an innocent cross burner who burns a cross, but does so without an
intent to intimidate. The plurality fears the chill on expression
because, according to the plurality, the inference permits "the
Commonwealth to arrest, prosecute, and convict a person based
solely on the fact of cross burning itself." Ante , at 365.
First, it is, at the very least, unclear that the inference comes
into play during arrest and initiation of a prosecution, that is,
prior to the instructions stage of an actual trial. Second, as I
explained above, the inference is rebuttable and, as the jury
instructions given in this case demonstrate, Virginia law still
re- [399] quires the jury to find the existence of each element, including
intent to intimidate, beyond a reasonable doubt.
Moreover, even in the First Amendment context, the Court has
upheld such regulations where conduct that initially appears
culpable ultimately results in dismissed charges. A regulation of
pornography is one such example. While possession of child
pornography is illegal, New York v. Ferber , 458 U. S. 747 , 764
(1982), possession of adult pornography, as long as it is not
obscene, is allowed, Miller v. California , 413 U. S. 15 (1973). As a
result, those pornographers trafficking in images of adults who
look like minors may be not only deterred but also arrested and
prosecuted for possessing what a jury might find to be legal
materials. This "chilling" effect has not, however, been a cause
for grave concern with respect to overbreadth of such statutes
among the Members of this Court.
That the First Amendment gives way to other interests is not a
remarkable proposition. What is remarkable is that, under the
plurality's analysis, the determination whether an interest is
sufficiently compelling depends not on the harm a regulation in
question seeks to prevent, but on the area of society at which it
aims. For instance, in Hill v. Colorado , 530 U. S. 703 (2000), the
Court upheld a restriction on protests near abortion clinics,
explaining that the State had a legitimate interest, which was
sufficiently narrowly tailored, in protecting those seeking
services of such establishments from "unwanted advice" and
"unwanted communication," id. , at 708, 716, 717, 729. In
so concluding, the Court placed heavy reliance on the "vulnerable
physical and emotional conditions" of patients. Id. , at
729. Thus, when it came to the rights of those seeking abortions,
the Court deemed restrictions on "unwanted advice," which, notably,
can be given only from a distance of at least eight feet from a
prospective patient, justified by the countervailing interest in
obtaining an abortion. Yet, here, the plurality strikes down the
statute because one day an individual might wish to burn a
cross, [400] but might do so without an intent to intimidate anyone. That
cross burning subjects its targets, and, sometimes, an unintended
audience, see 262 Va., at 782, 553 S. E. 2d, at 748-749 (Hassell,
J., dissenting); see also App. 93-97, to extreme emotional
distress, and is virtually never viewed merely as "unwanted
communication," but rather, as a physical threat, is of no concern
to the plurality. Henceforth, under the plurality's view, physical
safety will be valued less than the right to be free from unwanted
communications.
III
Because I would uphold the validity of this statute, I
respectfully dissent. Notes [ Footnote * ]
Briefs of amici curiae urging reversal were filed for
the State of California by Bill Lockyer , Attorney General, Manuel M. Medeiros , State Solicitor General, Richard
M. Frank , Chief Assistant Attorney General, and Angela
Sierra , Deputy Attorney General; for the State of New Jersey
et al. by David Samson , Attorney General of New Jersey,
and Carol Johnston , Deputy Attorney General, and by the
Attorneys General for their respective States as follows: Janet
Napolitano of Arizona, Richard Blumenthal of
Connecticut, Thomas J. Miller of Iowa, J. Joseph Curran, Jr. , of Maryland, Thomas F. Reilly of Massachusetts, Jennifer
M. Granholm of Michigan, Don Stenberg of Nebraska, Frankie Sue Del Papa of Nevada, Roy Cooper of
North Carolina, W A. Drew Edmondson of Oklahoma, Hardy
Myers of Oregon, Mark L. Shurtleff of Utah, and William H. Sorrell of Vermont; and for the Criminal
Justice Legal Foundation by Kent Briefs of amici curiae urging affirmance were filed for
the Council of Conservative Citizens by Edgar J. Steele; for the Rutherford Institute by John W
Whitehead and Steven H. Aden; and for the Thomas
Jefferson Center for the Protection of Free Expression by Robert M. O'Neil and J. Joshua
Wheeler. Martin E. Karlinsky , Howard W. Goldstein , Steven M. Freeman , Frederick M. Lawrence , and Elliot M. Mincberg filed a brief for the Anti-Defamation
League et al. as amici curiae .
[ Footnote 1 ]
After we granted certiorari, the Commonwealth enacted another
statute designed to remedy the constitutional problems identified
by the state court. See Va. Code Ann. § 18.2-423.01 (2002). Section
18.2-423.01 bans the burning of "an object" when done "with the
intent of intimidating any person or group of persons." The statute
does not contain any prima facie evidence provision. Section
18.2-423.01, however, did not repeal § 18.2-423, the cross-burning
statute at issue in this case.
[ Footnote 2 ]
JUSTICE THOMAS argues in dissent that cross burning is "conduct,
not expression." Post , at 394. While it is of course true
that burning a cross is conduct, it is equally true that the First
Amendment protects symbolic conduct as well as pure speech. See supra , at 358. As JUSTICE THOMAS has previously
recognized, a burning cross is a "symbol of hate," and a "a symbol
of white supremacy." Capitol Square Review and Advisory Bd. v.
Pinette , 515 U.
S. 753 , 770-771 (1995) (concurring opinion).
[ Footnote 1 ]
The plurality also asserts that "even where a defendant like
Black presents a defense, the prima facie evidence provision makes
it more likely that the jury will find an intent to intimidate
regardless of the particular facts of the case." Ante , at
365. There is no basis for this assertion. The Virginia Supreme
Court's opinion in Nance v. Commonwealth, 203 Va. 428,
432, 124 S. E. 2d 900, 903-904 (1962), states, in no uncertain
terms, that the presentation of a prima facie case "'relieves
neither the court nor the jury of the duty to determine all of the
questions of fact from the weight of the whole evidence.'" (Emphasis added.)
[ Footnote 2 ]
Overbreadth was, of course, the framework of analysis employed
by the Virginia Supreme Court. See 262 Va. 764, 777-778, 553 S. E.
2d 738, 745-746 (2001) (examining the prima-facie-evidence
provision in a section labeled "OVERBREADTH ANALYSIS" and holding
that the provision "is overbroad"). Likewise, in their submissions
to this Court, the parties' analyses of the prima-facie-evidence
provision focus on the question of overbreadth. Brief for
Petitioner 41-50 (confining its discussion of the
prima-facie-evidence provision to a section titled "THE VIRGINIA
STATUTE IS NOT OVERBROAD"); Brief for Respondents 39-41 (arguing
that "[t]he prima facie evidence provision . . .
render[s] [the statute] overbroad"); Reply Brief for Petitioner
13-20 (dividing its discussion of the prima-facie-evidence
provision into sections titled "There Is No Real Overbreadth" and
"There Is No Substantial Overbreadth"). This reliance on
overbreadth doctrine is understandable. This Court has made clear
that to succeed in a facial challenge without relying on
overbreadth doctrine, "the challenger must establish that no set of
circumstances exists under which the Act would be valid." United States v. Salerno , 481 U. S. 739 ,745 (1987).
As the Court's opinion concedes, some of the speech covered by §
18.2-423 can constitutionally be proscribed, ante , at
363.
[ Footnote 3 ]
Unquestionably, the process through which elements of a criminal
offense are established in a jury trial may raise serious
constitutional concerns. Typically, however, such concerns sound in
due process, not First Amendment overbreadth. E. g. , County Court of Ulster Cty. v. Allen , 442 U. S. 140 ,
156-157 (1979); Barnes v. United States , 412 U. S. 837 ,838 (1973); In re Winship , 397 U. S. 358 , 359
(1970). Respondents in this case have not challenged § 18.2-423
under the Due Process Clause, and neither the plurality nor the
Virginia Supreme Court relies on due process in declaring the
statute invalid.
[ Footnote 4 ]
Confronted with the incontrovertible fact that this statute
easily passes overbreadth analysis, the plurality is driven to the
truly startling assertion that a statute which is not invalid in
all of its applications may nevertheless be facially invalidated even if it is not overbroad. The only
expression of that proposition that the plurality can find in
our jurisprudence appears in footnote dictum in the 5-to-4 opinion
in Secretary of State of Md. v. Joseph H. Munson Co. , 467 U. S. 947 ,
965-966, n. 13 (1984). See id. , at 975 (REHNQUIST, J.,
joined by Burger, C. J., and Powell and O'CONNOR, JJ., dissenting). Stare decisis cannot explain the newfound affection for
this errant doctrine (even if stare decisis applied to
dictum), because the holding of a later opinion (joined by
six Justices) flatly repudiated it. See United States v.
Salerno, supra , at 745 (REHNQUIST, C. J., joined by White,
Blackmun, Powell, O'CONNOR, and SCALIA, JJ.) (to succeed in a
facial challenge without relying on overbreadth doctrine, "the
challenger must establish that no set of circumstances exists under
which the Act would be valid").
Even if I were willing, as the plurality apparently is, to
ignore our repudiation of the Munson dictum, that case
provides no foundation whatever for facially invalidating a statute
under the conditions presented here. Our willingness facially to
invalidate the statute in Munson without reliance on First
Amendment overbreadth was premised on our conclusion that the
challenged provision was invalid in all of its
applications. We explained that "there is no core of easily
identifiable and constitutionally proscribable conduct that the
statute prohibits." Munson , 467 U. S., at 965-966. And we
stated that "[t]he flaw in the statute is not simply that it
includes within its sweep some impermissible applications, but that
in all its applications it operates on a fundamentally mistaken
premise that high solicitation costs are an accurate measure of
fraud." Id. , at 966. Unless the Court is prepared to
abandon a contention that it takes great pains to establish-that
"the history of cross burning in this country shows that cross
burning is often intimidating, intended to create a pervasive fear
in victims that they are a target of violence," ante , at
360-it is difficult to see how Munson has any bearing on
the constitutionality of the prima-facie-evidence provision.
[ Footnote 5 ]
The plurality's reliance on Terminiello v. Chicago , 337 U. S. 1 (1949),
is mistaken. In that case the Court deemed only the jury
instruction, rather than the ordinance under review, to be
constitutionally infirm. To be sure, it held that such a jury
instruction could never support a constitutionally valid
conviction, but that is quite different from holding the or dinance to be facially invalid. Insofar as the ordinance
was concerned, Terminiello made repeated references to the
as-applied nature of the challenge. Id. , at 3 (noting that
the defendant "maintained at all times that the ordinance as
applied to his conduct violated his right of free speech
. . . " (emphasis added)); id. , at 5 (noting
that "[aJs construed and applied [the provision] at least
contains parts that are unconstitutional" (emphasis added)); id. , at 6 ("The pinch of the statute is in its
application" (emphasis added)); ibid. ("The record
makes clear that petitioner at all times challenged the
constitutionality of the ordinance as construed and applied to
him" (emphasis added)). See also Isserles, Overcoming
Overbreadth: Facial Challenges and the Valid Rule Requirement, 48
Am. U. L. Rev. 359, 433, n. 333 (1998) (characterizing Terminiello as "adopting a court's jury instruction as an
authoritative narrowing construction of a breach of the peace
ordinance but ultimately confining its decision to overturning the
defendant's conviction rather than invalidating the statute on its
face").
[ Footnote 6 ]
Though the jury may well have embraced the former
(constitutionally permissible) understanding of its duties, that
possibility is not enough to dissipate the cloud of constitutional
doubt. See Sandstrom v. Montana , 442 U. S. 510 , 517 (1979)
(refusing to assume that the jury embraced a constitutionally sound
understanding of an ambiguous instruction: "[W]e cannot discount
the possibility that the jury may have interpreted the instruction
[improperly]").
[ Footnote 1 ]
Although three examples are given, the third may be skipped
here. It covers misleading advertising in a particular industry in
which the risk of fraud is thought to be great, and thus deals with
commercial speech with its separate doctrine and standards. R.
A. V. , 505 U. S., at 388-389.
[ Footnote 2 ]
The same conclusion also goes for the second R. A. V. exception relating to "'secondary effects.''' 505 U. S., at 389
(citing Renton v. Playtime Theatres, Inc. , 475 U. S. 41 , 48 (1986)).
Our "secondary effects" jurisprudence presupposes that the
regulation at issue is "unrelated to the suppression of free
expression." Ibid. [ Footnote 1 ] United States v. Guest , 383 U. S. 745 , 747-748,
n. 1 (1966) (quoting indictment charging conspiracy under 18 U. S.
C. § 241 (1964 ed.) to interfere with federally secured rights by, inter alia , "burning crosses at night in public view,"
"shooting Negroes," "beating Negroes," "killing Negroes," "damaging
and destroying property of Negroes," and "pursuing Negroes in
automobiles and threatening them with guns"); United States v.
Pospisil , 186 F.3d
1023 , 1027 (CA8 1999) (defendants burned a cross in
victims' yard, slashed their tires, and fired guns), cert. denied,
529 U. S. 1089 (2000); United States v. Stewart , 65 F.3d
918 , 922 (CA11 1995) (cross burning precipitated an exchange of
gunfire between victim and perpetrators), cert. denied sub nom.
Daniel v. United States , 516 U. S. 1134 (1996); United
States v. McDermott , 29 F.3d
404 , 405 (CA8 1994) (defendants sought to discourage
blacks from using public park by burning a cross in the park, as
well as by "waving baseball bats, axe handles, and knives; throwing
rocks and bottles; veering cars towards black persons; and
physically chasing black persons out of the park"); Cox v.
State , 585 So. 2d 182, 202 (Ala. Crim. App. 1991) (defendant
participated in evening of cross burning and murder), cert. denied,
503 U. S. 987 (1992); R. Caro, The Years of Lyndon Johnson: Master
of the Senate 847 (2002) (referring to a wave of "southern
bombings, beatings, sniper fire, and cross-burnings" in late 1956
in response to efforts to desegregate schools, buses, and parks);
Newton & Newton 21 (observing that "Jewish merchants were
subjected to boycotts, threats, cross burnings, and sometimes acts
of violence" by the Klan and its sympathizers); id. , at
361-362 (describing cross burning and beatings directed at a black
family that refused demands to sell the home); id. , at 382
(describing incident of cross burning and brick throwing at home of
Jewish officeholder); id. , at 583 (describing campaign of
cross burning and property damage directed at Vietnamese immigrant
fishermen); W. Wade, The Fiery Cross: The Ku Klux Klan in America
262-263 (1987) (describing incidents of cross burning, beatings,
kidnaping, and other "terrorism" directed against union organizers
in the South); id. , at 376 (cross burnings associated with
shooting into cars); id. , at 377 (cross burnings
associated with assaults on blacks); 1 R. Kluger, Simple Justice
378 (1975) (describing cross burning at, and subsequent shooting
into, home of federal judge who issued desegregation decisions);
Rubinowitz & Perry, Crimes Without Punishment: White Neighbors'
Resistance to Black Entry, 92 J. Crim. L. & C. 335, 342,
354-355, 388, 408-410, 419, 420, 421, 423 (Fall2001-Winter 2002)
(noting that an "escalating campaign to eject a [minority] family"
from a white neighborhood could begin with "cross burnings, window
breaking, or threatening telephone calls," and culminate with
bombings; describing other incidents of cross burning accompanied
by violence); Cross Burned at Manakin, Third in Area, Richmond
TimesDispatch, Feb. 26, 1951, p. 4, App. 318 (describing 1951
Virginia cross burning accompanied by gunfire).
[ Footnote 2 ]
See, e.g. , Va. Code Ann. § 18-327 (1950) (repealed
1960) (required separation of "white" and "colored" at any place of
entertainment or other public assemblage; violation was
misdemeanor); Va. Code Ann. § 20-54 (1960) (repealed 1968)
(prohibited racial intermarriage); Va. Code Ann. § 22-221 (1969)
(repealed 1972) ("White and colored persons shall not be taught in
the same school"); Va. Code Ann. §24-120 (1969) (repealed 1970)
(required separate listings for "white and colored persons" who
failed to pay poll tax); Va. Code Ann. § 38-281 (1950) (repealed
1952) (prohibited fraternal associations from having "both white
and colored members"); Va. Code Ann. § 53-42 (1967) (amended to
remove "race" 1968) (required racial separation in prison); Va.
Code Ann. § 56-114 (1974) (repealed 1975) (authorized State
Corporation Commission to require "separate waiting rooms" for
"white and colored races"); Va. Code Ann. § 56-326 (1969) (repealed
1970) (required motor carriers to "separate" their "white and
colored passengers," violation was misdemeanor); §§ 56-390 and
56-396 (repealed 1970) (same for railroads); § 58-880 (repealed
1970) (required separate personal property tax books for "white[s]"
and "colored").
[ Footnote 3 ]
As the Court explained in Allen , a permissive inference
or presumption "allows-but does not require-the trier of fact to
infer the elemental fact from proof by the prosecutor of the basic
one and which places no burden of any kind on the defendant. In
that situation the basic fact may constitute prima facie evidence
of the elemental fact . . . . Because this
permissive presumption leaves the trier of fact free to credit or
reject the inference and does not shift the burden of proof, it
affects the application of the 'beyond a reasonable doubt' standard
only if, under the facts of the case, there is no rational way the
trier could make the connection permitted by the inference." 442 U.
S., at 157 (citations omitted). By contrast, "[a] mandatory
presumption . . . may affect not only the strength of the
'no reasonable doubt' burden but also the placement of that burden;
it tells the trier that he or they must find the elemental
fact upon proof of the basic fact, at least unless the defendant
has come forward with some evidence to rebut the presumed
connection between the two facts." Ibid. | The Supreme Court of the United States ruled on a case regarding the constitutionality of a Virginia statute that criminalizes cross burning with the intent to intimidate. The Court affirmed in part, vacated in part, and remanded the judgment of the Virginia Supreme Court, which had held the statute unconstitutional on First Amendment grounds.
The Court's decision focused on the historical context of cross burning in the United States, particularly its association with the Ku Klux Klan and its use as a tool of intimidation and violence. The Court recognized that cross burning conveys a symbolic message that is often meant to intimidate and instill fear.
The Court concluded that a state may ban cross burning carried out with the intent to intimidate, as such an act is a true threat that falls outside the protection of the First Amendment. However, the Court also noted that the Virginia statute's prima facie evidence provision, which allowed intent to intimidate to be inferred from the act of cross burning alone, raised overbreadth concerns by potentially chilling protected speech.
The Court affirmed the Virginia Supreme Court's judgment that the statute was unconstitutional but vacated its decision to invalidate the entire statute. The case was remanded for further proceedings consistent with the Supreme Court's opinion, allowing for a narrower interpretation or application of the statute that addressed the overbreadth concerns. |
Free Speech | Republican Party of Minnesota v. White | https://supreme.justia.com/cases/federal/us/536/765/ | OCTOBER TERM, 2001
Syllabus
REPUBLICAN PARTY OF MINNESOTA ET AL. v. WHITE, CHAIRPERSON, MINNESOTA BOARD OF JUDICIAL STANDARDS, ET
AL.
CERTIORARI TO THE UNITED STATES COURT OF APPEALS FOR THE EIGHTH
CIRCUIT No.01-521. Argued March 26, 2002-Decided June 27, 2002 The Minnesota Supreme Court has adopted a canon of judicial
conduct that prohibits a "candidate for a judicial office" from
"announc[ing] his or her views on disputed legal or political
issues" (hereinafter announce clause). While running for associate
justice of that court, petitioner Gregory Wersal (and others) filed
this suit seeking a declaration that the announce clause violates
the First Amendment and an injunction against its enforcement. The
District Court granted respondent officials summary judgment, and
the Eighth Circuit affirmed. Held: The announce clause violates the First Amendment.
Pp. 770-788.
(a) The record demonstrates that the announce clause prohibits a
judicial candidate from stating his views on any specific
nonfancifullegal question within the province of the court for
which he is running, except in the context of discussing past
decisions-and in the latter context as well, if he expresses the
view that he is not bound by stare decisis. Pp. 770-774.
(b) The announce clause both prohibits speech based on its
content and burdens a category of speech that is at the core of
First Amendment freedoms-speech about the qualifications of
candidates for public office. The Eighth Circuit concluded, and the
parties do not dispute, that the proper test to be applied to
determine the constitutionality of such a restriction is strict
scrutiny, under which respondents have the burden to prove that the
clause is (1) narrowly tailored, to serve (2) a compelling state
interest. E. g., Eu v. San Francisco County
Democratic Central Comm., 489 U. S. 214 , 222. That
court found that respondents had established two interests as
sufficiently compelling to justify the announce clause: preserving
the state judiciary's impartiality and preserving the appearance of
that impartiality. Pp. 774-775.
(c) Under any definition of "impartiality," the announce clause
fails strict scrutiny. First, it is plain that the clause is not
narrowly tailored to serve impartiality (or its appearance) in the
traditional sense of the word, i. e., as a lack of bias for
or against either party to the proceeding. Indeed, the clause is
barely tailored to serve that interest at all, inasmuch as it does
not restrict speech for or against particular parties, 766 but rather speech for or against particular issues. Second,
although "impartiality" in the sense of a lack of preconception in
favor of or against a particular legal view may well be an interest
served by the announce clause, pursuing this objective is not a
compelling state interest, since it is virtually impossible, and
hardly desirable, to find a judge who does not have preconceptions
about the law, see Laird v. Tatum, 409 U. S. 824 , 835.
Third, the Court need not decide whether achieving "impartiality"
(or its appearance) in the sense of openmindedness is a compelling
state interest because, as a means of pursuing this interest, the
announce clause is so woefully underinclusive that the Court does
not believe it was adopted for that purpose. See, e. g., City of
Ladue v. Gilleo, 512 U. S. 43 , 52-53.
Respondents have not carried the burden imposed by strict scrutiny
of establishing that statements made during an election campaign
are uniquely destructive of openmindedness. See, e. g., Landmark
Communications, Inc. v. Virginia, 435 U. S. 829 , 841. Pp.
775-784.
(d) A universal and long-established tradition of prohibiting
certain conduct creates a strong presumption that the prohibition
is constitutional, see McIntyre v. Ohio Elections
Comm'n, 514 U. S.
334 , 375-377. However, the practice of prohibiting speech by
judicial candidates is neither ancient nor universal. The Court
knows of no such prohibitions throughout the 19th and the first
quarter of the 20th century, and they are still not universally
adopted. This does not compare well with the traditions deemed
worthy of attention in, e. g., Burson v. Freeman,
504 (e) There is an obvious tension between Minnesota's
Constitution, which requires judicial elections, and the announce
clause, which places most subjects of interest to the voters off
limits. The First Amendment does not permit Minnesota to leave the
principle of elections in place while preventing candidates from
discussing what the elections are about. See, e. g., Renne v. Geary, 501
U. S. 312 , 349. Pp. 787-788. 247 F.3d
854 , reversed and remanded.
SCALIA, J., delivered the opinion of the Court, in which
REHNQUIST, C. J., and O'CONNOR, KENNEDY, and THOMAS, JJ., joined.
O'CONNOR, J., post, p. 788, and KENNEDY, J., post, p.
792, filed concurring opinions. STEVENS, J., filed a dissenting
opinion, in which SOUTER, GINSBURG, and BREYER, JJ., joined, post, p. 797. GINSBURG, J., filed a dissenting opinion, in
which STEVENS, SOUTER, and BREYER, JJ., joined, post, p.
803. James Bopp, Jr., argued the cause for petitioners
Republican Party of Minnesota et al. With him on the briefs
were 767 Thomas J. Marzen, Richard E. Coleson, and Ronald D.
Rotunda. William F. Mohrman and Erick G. Kaardal filed briefs for
petitioners Wersal et al. Alan 1. Gilbert, Chief Deputy and Solicitor
General of Minnesota, argued the cause for respondents. With him on
the brief were Mike Hatch, Attorney General, Kristine L.
Eiden, Deputy Attorney General, and Julie Ralston Aoki, Mark
B. Lev inger, and Thomas C. Vasaly, Assistant
Attorneys General. *
*Briefs of amici curiae urging reversal were filed for
the American Center for Law and Justice by Jay Alan Sekulow,
James H. Henderson, Sr., Colby M. May, and Walter M.
Weber; for the American Civil Liberties Union et al. by David B. Isbell, David H. Remes, and Steven R.
Shapiro; for the Chamber of Commerce of the United States by Jan Witold Baran and Stephen A. Bokat; for Minnesota
State Representative Philip Krinkie et al. by Raymond C. Ortman, Jr.; for Public Citizen by Allison M. Zieve,
David C. Vladeck, and Scott L. Nelson; and for
State Supreme Court Justices by Erik S. Jaffe. Briefs of amici curiae urging affirmance were filed for
the State of California et al. by Bill Lockyer, Attorney
General of California, and Manuel M. Medeiros, State
Solicitor, and by the Attorneys General for their respective States
as follows: Janet Napolitano of Arizona, Jeremiah W (Jay)
Nixon of Missouri, Mike McGrath of Montana, W A. Drew
Edmondson of Oklahoma, Hardy Myers of Oregon, John
Cornyn of Texas, and Christine Q Gregoire of Washington;
for the Ad hoc Committee of Former Justices and Friends Dedicated
to an Independent Judiciary by S. Shawn Stephens and Andy
Taylor; for the American Bar Association by Robert E.
Hirshon, Reagan Wm. Simpson, and Warren S. Huang; for the Minnesota State Bar Association by Wayne D. Struble; for the Brennan Center for Justice at NYU School of Law et al. by Scott Bales and Deborah Goldberg; for the Conference
of Chief Justices by Roy A. Schotland, George T. Patton, Jr.,
Sarah Steele Riordan, and Robert F. Bauer; for
the Missouri Bar by Joseph C. Blanton, Jr.; and for
Pennsylvanians for Modern Courts by Edmund B. Spaeth, Jr., and Brett G. Sweitzer. Briefs of amici curiae were filed for the Idaho
Conservation League et al. by John D. Echeverria; and for
the National Association of Criminal Defense Lawyers by David W
Ogden, Jonathan J. Frankel, Neil M. Richards, and Lisa Kemler. 768 JUSTICE SCALIA delivered the opinion of the Court.
The question presented in this case is whether the First
Amendment permits the Minnesota Supreme Court to prohibit
candidates for judicial election in that State from announcing
their views on disputed legal and political issues.
I
Since Minnesota's admission to the Union in 1858, the State's
Constitution has provided for the selection of all state judges by
popular election. Minn. Const., Art. VI, § 7. Since 1912, those
elections have been nonpartisan. Act of June 19, ch. 2,1912 Minn.
Laws Special Sess., pp. 4-6. Since 1974, they have been subject to
a legal restriction which states that a "candidate for a judicial
office, including an incumbent judge," shall not "announce his or
her views on disputed legal or political issues." Minn. Code of
Judicial Conduct, Canon 5(A)(3)(d)(i) (2000). This prohibition,
promulgated by the Minnesota Supreme Court and based on Canon 7(B)
of the 1972 American Bar Association (ABA) Model Code of Judicial
Conduct, is known as the "announce clause." Incumbent judges who
violate it are subject to discipline, including removal, censure,
civil penalties, and suspension without pay. Minn. Rules of Board
on Judicial Standards 4(a)(6), l1(d) (2002). Lawyers who run for
judicial office also must comply with the announce clause. Minn.
Rule of Professional Conduct 8.2(b) (2002) ("A lawyer who is a
candidate for judicial office shall comply with the applicable
provisions of the Code of Judicial Conduct"). Those who violate it
are subject to, inter alia, disbarment, suspension, and
probation. Rule 8.4(a); Minn. Rules on Lawyers Professional
Responsibility 8-14, 15(a) (2002).
In 1996, one of the petitioners, Gregory Wersal, ran for
associate justice of the Minnesota Supreme Court. In the course of
the campaign, he distributed literature criticizing several
Minnesota Supreme Court decisions on issues such as crime, welfare,
and abortion. A complaint against Wersal 769 challenging, among other things, the propriety of this
literature was filed with the Office of Lawyers Professional
Responsibility, the agency which, under the direction of the
Minnesota Lawyers Professional Responsibility Board,1 investigates
and prosecutes ethical violations of lawyer candidates for judicial
office. The Lawyers Board dismissed the complaint; with regard to
the charges that his campaign materials violated the announce
clause, it expressed doubt whether the clause could
constitutionally be enforced. Nonetheless, fearing that further
ethical complaints would jeopardize his ability to practice law,
Wersal withdrew from the election. In 1998, Wersal ran again for
the same office. Early in that race, he sought an advisory opinion
from the Lawyers Board with regard to whether it planned to enforce
the announce clause. The Lawyers Board responded equivocally,
stating that, although it had significant doubts about the
constitutionality of the provision, it was unable to answer his
question because he had not submitted a list of the announcements
he wished to make.2
Shortly thereafter, Wersal filed this lawsuit in Federal
District Court against respondents,3 seeking, inter alia, a
1 The Eighth Circuit did not parse out the separate functions of
these two entities in the case at hand, referring to the two of
them collectively as the "Lawyers Board." We take the same
approach.
2 Nor did Wersal have any success receiving answers from the
Lawyers Board when he included "concrete examples," post, at
799, n. 2 (STEVENS, J., dissenting), in his request for an advisory
opinion on other subjects a month later:
"As you are well aware, there is pending litigation over the
constitutionality of certain portions of Canon 5. You are a
plaintiff in this action and you have sued, among others, me as
Director of the Office of Lawyers Professional Responsibility and
Charles Lundberg as the Chair of the Board of Lawyers Professional
Responsibility. Due to this pending litigation, I will not be
answering your request for an advisory opinion at this time." App.
153.
3 Respondents are officers of the Lawyers Board and of the
Minnesota Board on Judicial Standards (Judicial Board), which
enforces the ethical rules applicable to judges. 770 declaration that the announce clause violates the First
Amendment and an injunction against its enforcement. Wersal alleged
that he was forced to refrain from announcing his views on disputed
issues during the 1998 campaign, to the point where he declined
response to questions put to him by the press and public, out of
concern that he might run afoul of the announce clause. Other
plaintiffs in the suit, including the Minnesota Republican Party,
alleged that, because the clause kept Wersal from announcing his
views, they were unable to learn those views and support or oppose
his candidacy accordingly. The parties filed cross-motions for
summary judgment, and the District Court found in favor of
respondents, holding that the announce clause did not violate the
First Amendment. 63 F. Supp. 2d 967 (Minn. 1999). Over a dissent by
Judge Beam, the United States Court of Appeals for the Eighth
Circuit affirmed. Republican Party of Minn. v. Kelly, 247 F.3d
854 (2001). We granted certiorari. 534 U. S. 1054 (2001).
II
Before considering the constitutionality of the announce clause,
we must be clear about its meaning. Its text says that a candidate
for judicial office shall not "announce his or her views on
disputed legal or political issues." Minn. Code of Judicial
Conduct, Canon 5(A)(3)(d)(i) (2002).
We know that "announc[ing] ... views" on an issue covers much
more than promising to decide an issue a particular way. The
prohibition extends to the candidate's mere statement of his
current position, even if he does not bind himself to maintain that
position after election. All the parties agree this is the case,
because the Minnesota Code contains a so-called "pledges or
promises" clause, which separately prohibits judicial
candidates from making "pledges or promises of conduct in office
other than the faithful and impartial performance of the duties of
the office," ibid.-a prohibition that is not challenged here
and on which we express no view. 771 There are, however, some limitations that the Minnesota Supreme
Court has placed upon the scope of the announce clause that are not
(to put it politely) immediately apparent from its text. The
statements that formed the basis of the complaint against Wersal in
1996 included criticism of past decisions of the Minnesota Supreme
Court. One piece of campaign literature stated that "[t]he
Minnesota Supreme Court has issued decisions which are marked by
their disregard for the Legislature and a lack of common sense."
App. 37. It went on to criticize a decision excluding from evidence
confessions by criminal defendants that were not tape-recorded,
asking "[s]hould we conclude that because the Supreme Court does
not trust police, it allows confessed criminals to go free?" Ibid. It criticized a decision striking down a state law
restricting welfare benefits, asserting that "[i]t's the
Legislature which should set our spending policies." Ibid. And it criticized a decision requiring public financing of
abortions for poor women as "unprecedented" and a "pro-abortion
stance." Id., at 38. Although one would think that all of
these statements touched on disputed legal or political issues,
they did not (or at least do not now) fall within the scope of the
announce clause. The Judicial Board issued an opinion stating that
judicial candidates may criticize past decisions, and the Lawyers
Board refused to discipline Wersal for the foregoing statements
because, in part, it thought they did not violate the announce
clause. The Eighth Circuit relied on the Judicial Board's opinion
in upholding the announce clause, 247 F. 3d, at 882, and the
Minnesota Supreme Court recently embraced the Eighth Circuit's
interpretation, In re Code of Judicial Conduct, 639 N. W. 2d
55 (2002).
There are yet further limitations upon the apparent plain
meaning of the announce clause: In light of the constitutional
concerns, the District Court construed the clause to reach only
disputed issues that are likely to come before the candidate if he
is elected judge. 63 F. Supp. 2d, at 986. The 772 Eighth Circuit accepted this limiting interpretation by the
District Court, and in addition construed the clause to allow
general discussions of case law and judicial philosophy. 247 F. 3d,
at 881-882. The Supreme Court of Minnesota adopted these
interpretations as well when it ordered enforcement of the announce
clause in accordance with the Eighth Circuit's opinion. In re
Code of Judicial Conduct, supra. It seems to us, however, that-like the text of the announce
clause itself-these limitations upon the text of the announce
clause are not all that they appear to be. First, respondents
acknowledged at oral argument that statements critical of past
judicial decisions are not permissible if the candidate also
states that he is against stare decisis. Tr. of Oral Arg.
33-34.4 Thus, candidates must choose between stating their views
critical of past decisions and stating their views in opposition to stare decisis. Or, to look at it more concretely, they may
state their view that prior decisions were erroneous only if they
do not assert that they, if elected, have any power to eliminate
erroneous decisions. Second, limiting the scope of the clause to
issues likely to come before a court is not much of a limitation at
all. One would hardly expect the "disputed legal or political
issues" raised in the course of a state judicial election to
include such matters as whether the Federal Government should end
the embargo of Cuba. Quite obviously, they will be those legal or
political disputes that are the proper (or by past decisions have
been made the improper) business of the state courts. And within
that relevant category, "[t]here is almost no legal or political
issue that is unlikely to come before a judge of an American court,
state or federal, of general jurisdiction."
4JUSTICE GINSBURG argues that we should ignore this concession
at oral argument because it is inconsistent with the Eighth
Circuit's interpretation of the announce clause. Post, at
810 (dissenting opinion). As she appears to acknowledge, however,
the Eighth Circuit was merely silent on this particular question. Ibid. Silence is hardly inconsistent with what respondents
conceded at oral argument. 773 Buckley v. Illinois Judicial Inquiry Bd., 997 F.2d
224 , 229 (CA7 1993). Third, construing the clause to
allow "general" discussions of case law and judicial philosophy
turns out to be of little help in an election campaign. At oral
argument, respondents gave, as an example of this exception, that a
candidate is free to assert that he is a "'strict constructionist.'
" Tr. of Oral Arg. 29. But that, like most other philosophical
generalities, has little meaningful content for the electorate
unless it is exemplified by application to a particular issue of
construction likely to come before a court-for example, whether a
particular statute runs afoul of any provision of the Constitution.
Respondents conceded that the announce clause would prohibit the
candidate from exemplifying his philosophy in this fashion. Id., at 43. Without such application to real-life issues,
all candidates can claim to be "strict constructionists" with equal
(and unhelpful) plausibility.
In any event, it is clear that the announce clause prohibits a
judicial candidate from stating his views on any specific
nonfanciful legal question within the province of the court for
which he is running, except in the context of discussing past
decisions-and in the latter context as well, if he expresses the
view that he is not bound by stare decisis. 5
5 In 1990, in response to concerns that its 1972 Model
Canon-which was the basis for Minnesota's announce clause-violated
the First Amendment, see L. Milord, The Development of the ABA
Judicial Code 50 (1992), the ABA replaced that canon with a
provision that prohibits a judicial candidate from making
"statements that commit or appear to commit the candidate with
respect to cases, controversies or issues that are likely to come
before the court." ABA Model Code of Judicial Conduct, Canon
5(A)(3)(d)(ii) (2000). At oral argument, respondents argued that
the limiting constructions placed upon Minnesota's announce clause
by the Eighth Circuit, and adopted by the Minnesota Supreme Court,
render the scope of the clause no broader than the ABA's 1990
canon. Tr. of Oral Arg. 38. This argument is somewhat curious
because, based on the same constitutional concerns that had
motivated the ABA, the Minnesota Supreme Court was urged to replace
the announce clause with the new ABA language, but, unlike other
jurisdictions, declined. Final Report of the Advi- 774 Respondents contend that this still leaves plenty of topics for
discussion on the campaign trail. These include a candidate's
"character," "education," "work habits," and "how [he] would handle
administrative duties if elected." Brief for Respondents 35-36.
Indeed, the Judicial Board has printed a list of preapproved
questions which judicial candidates are allowed to answer. These
include how the candidate feels about cameras in the courtroom, how
he would go about reducing the caseload, how the costs of judicial
administration can be reduced, and how he proposes to ensure that
minorities and women are treated more fairly by the court system.
Minnesota State Bar Association Judicial Elections Task Force
Report & Recommendations, App. C (June 19, 1997), reprinted at
App. 97-103. Whether this list of preapproved subjects, and other
topics not prohibited by the announce clause, adequately fulfill
the First Amendment's guarantee of freedom of speech is the
question to which we now turn.
III
As the Court of Appeals recognized, the announce clause both
prohibits speech on the basis of its content and burdens a category
of speech that is "at the core of our First Amendment
freedoms"-speech about the qualifications of candidates for public
office. 247 F. 3d, at 861, 863. The Court of Appeals concluded that
the proper test to be applied to determine the constitutionality of
such a restriction is what our cases have called strict scrutiny, id., at 864; the parties do not dispute that this is
correct. Under the strict-scrutiny test, respondents have the
burden to prove that the an-
sory Committee to Review the ABA Model Code of Judicial Conduct
and the Rules of the Minnesota Board on Judicial Standards 5-6
(June 29, 1994), reprinted at App. 367-368. The ABA, however,
agrees with respondents' position, Brief for ABA as Amicus
Curiae 5. We do not know whether the announce clause (as
interpreted by state authorities) and the 1990 ABA canon are one
and the same. No aspect of our constitutional analysis turns on
this question. 775 nounce clause is (1) narrowly tailored, to serve (2) a
compelling state interest. E. g., Eu v. San Francisco
County Democratic Central Comm., 489 U. S. 214 , 222
(1989). In order for respondents to show that the announce clause
is narrowly tailored, they must demonstrate that it does not
"unnecessarily circumscrib[e] protected expression." Brown v. Hartlage, 456 U. S. 45 , 54
(1982).
The Court of Appeals concluded that respondents had established
two interests as sufficiently compelling to justify the announce
clause: preserving the impartiality of the state judiciary and
preserving the appearance of the impartiality of the state
judiciary. 247 F. 3d, at 867. Respondents reassert these two
interests before us, arguing that the first is compelling because
it protects the due process rights of litigants, and that the
second is compelling because it preserves public confidence in the
judiciary.6 Respondents are rather vague, however, about what they
mean by "impartiality." Indeed, although the term is used
throughout the Eighth Circuit's opinion, the briefs, the Minnesota
Code of Judicial Conduct, and the ABA Codes of Judicial Conduct,
none of these sources bothers to define it. Clarity on this point
is essential before we can decide whether impartiality is indeed a
compelling state interest, and, if so, whether the announce clause
is narrowly tailored to achieve it.
A
One meaning of "impartiality" in the judicial context-and of
course its root meaning-is the lack of bias for or against either party to the proceeding. Impartiality in this sense
6 Although the Eighth Circuit also referred to the compelling
interest in an "independent" judiciary, 247 F. 3d, at 864-868, both
it and respondents appear to use that term, as applied to the
issues involved in this case, as interchangeable with "impartial."
See id., at 864 (describing a judge's independence as his
"ability to apply the law neutrally"); Brief for Respondents 20, n.
4 ("[J]udicial impartiality is linked to judicial
independence"). 776 assures equal application of the law. That is, it guarantees a
party that the judge who hears his case will apply the law to him
in the same way he applies it to any other party. This is the
traditional sense in which the term is used. See Webster's New
International Dictionary 1247 (2d ed. 1950) (defining "impartial"
as "[n]ot partial; esp., not favoring one more than another;
treating all alike; unbiased; equitable; fair; just"). It is also
the sense in which it is used in the cases cited by respondents and amici for the proposition that an impartial judge is
essential to due process. Tumey v. Ohio, 273 U. S. 510 , 523,
531-534 (1927) (judge violated due process by sitting in a case in
which it would be in his financial interest to find against one of
the parties); Aetna Life Ins. Co. v. Lavoie, 475 U. S. 813 , 822-825
(1986) (same); Ward v. Monroeville, 409 U. S. 57 , 58-62 (1972)
(same); Johnson v. Mississippi, 403 U. S. 212 , 215-216
(1971) (per curiam) (judge violated due process by sitting
in a case in which one of the parties was a previously successful
litigant against him); Bracy v. Gramley, 520 U. S. 899 , 905 (1997)
(would violate due process if a judge was disposed to rule against
defendants who did not bribe him in order to cover up the fact that
he regularly ruled in favor of defendants who did bribe him); In
re Murchison, 349
U. S. 133 , 137-139 (1955) (judge violated due process by
sitting in the criminal trial of defendant whom he had
indicted).
We think it plain that the announce clause is not narrowly
tailored to serve impartiality (or the appearance of impartiality)
in this sense. Indeed, the clause is barely tailored to serve that
interest at all, inasmuch as it does not restrict speech for
or against particular parties, but rather speech for or
against particular issues. To be sure, when a case arises
that turns on a legal issue on which the judge (as a candidate) had
taken a particular stand, the party taking the opposite stand is
likely to lose. But not because of any bias against that party, or
favoritism toward the other party. 777 Any party taking that position is just as likely to lose.
The judge is applying the law (as he sees it) evenhandedly.7
B
It is perhaps possible to use the term "impartiality" in the
judicial context (though this is certainly not a common usage) to
mean lack of preconception in favor of or against a particular legal view. This sort of impartiality would be concerned,
not with guaranteeing litigants equal application of the law, but
rather with guaranteeing them an equal chance to persuade the court
on the legal points in their case. Impartiality in this sense may
well be an interest served by the announce clause, but it is not a compelling state interest, as strict scrutiny requires. A
judge's lack of predisposition regarding the relevant legal issues
in a case has never been thought a necessary component of equal
justice, and with good reason. For one thing, it is virtually
impossible to find a judge who does not have preconceptions about
the law. As then-JusTICE REHNQUIST observed of our own Court:
"Since most Justices come to this bench no earlier than their
middle years, it would be unusual if they had not by that time
formulated at least some tentative notions that would influence
them in their interpretation of the sweeping clauses of the
Constitution and their interaction with one another. It would be
not merely unusual, but extraordinary, if they had
7 JUSTICE STEVENS asserts that the announce clause "serves the
State's interest in maintaining both the appearance of this form of
impartiality and its actuality." Post, at 801. We do not
disagree. Some of the speech prohibited by the announce clause may
well exhibit a bias against parties-including JUSTICE STEVENS'S
example of an election speech stressing the candidate's unbroken
record of affirming convictions for rape, ante, at 800-801.
That is why we are careful to say that the announce clause is "barely tailored to serve that interest," supra, at
776 (emphasis added). The question under our strict scrutiny test,
however, is not whether the announce clause serves this interest at all, but whether it is narrowly tailored to serve
this interest. It is not. 778 not at least given opinions as to constitutional issues in their
previous legal careers." Laird v. Tatum, 409 U. S. 824 , 835 (1972)
(memorandum opinion). Indeed, even if it were possible to select
judges who did not have preconceived views on legal issues, it
would hardly be desirable to do so. "Proof that a Justice's mind at
the time he joined the Court was a complete tabula rasa in
the area of constitutional adjudication would be evidence of lack
of qualification, not lack of bias." Ibid. The Minnesota
Constitution positively forbids the selection to courts of general
jurisdiction of judges who are impartial in the sense of having no
views on the law. Minn. Const., Art. VI, § 5 ("Judges of the
supreme court, the court of appeals and the district court shall be
learned in the law"). And since avoiding judicial preconceptions on
legal issues is neither possible nor desirable, pretending
otherwise by attempting to preserve the "appearance" of that type
of impartiality can hardly be a compelling state interest
either.
C
A third possible meaning of "impartiality" (again not a common
one) might be described as openmindedness. This quality in a judge
demands, not that he have no preconceptions on legal issues, but
that he be willing to consider views that oppose his
preconceptions, and remain open to persuasion, when the issues
arise in a pending case. This sort of impartiality seeks to
guarantee each litigant, not an equal chance to win the
legal points in the case, but at least some chance of doing
so. It may well be that impartiality in this sense, and the
appearance of it, are desirable in the judiciary, but we need not
pursue that inquiry, since we do not believe the Minnesota Supreme
Court adopted the announce clause for that purpose.
Respondents argue that the announce clause serves the interest
in openmindedness, or at least in the appearance of openmindedness,
because it relieves a judge from pressure to rule a certain way in
order to maintain consistency with 779 statements the judge has previously made. The problem is,
however, that statements in election campaigns are such an
infinitesimal portion of the public commitments to legal positions
that judges (or judges-to-be) undertake, that this object of the
prohibition is implausible. Before they arrive on the bench
(whether by election or otherwise) judges have often committed
themselves on legal issues that they must later rule upon. See, e. g., Laird, supra, at 831-833 (describing Justice Black's
participation in several cases construing and deciding the
constitutionality of the Fair Labor Standards Act, even though as a
Senator he had been one of its principal authors; and Chief Justice
Hughes's authorship of the opinion overruling Adkins v. Children's Hospital of D. c., 261 U. S. 525 (1923), a
case he had criticized in a book written before his appointment to
the Court). More common still is a judge's confronting a legal
issue on which he has expressed an opinion while on the bench. Most
frequently, of course, that prior expression will have occurred in
ruling on an earlier case. But judges often state their views on
disputed legal issues outside the context of adjudication-in
classes that they conduct, and in books and speeches. Like the ABA
Codes of Judicial Conduct, the Minnesota Code not only permits but
encourages this. See Minn. Code of Judicial Conduct, Canon 4(B)
(2002) ("A judge may write, lecture, teach, speak and participate
in other extra-judicial activities concerning the law ... "); Minn.
Code of Judicial Conduct, Canon 4(B), Comment. (2002) ("To the
extent that time permits, a judge is encouraged to do so ... ").
That is quite incompatible with the notion that the need for
openmindedness (or for the appearance of openmindedness) lies
behind the prohibition at issue here.
The short of the matter is this: In Minnesota, a candidate for
judicial office may not say "I think it is constitutional for the
legislature to prohibit same-sex marriages." He may say the very
same thing, however, up until the very day before he declares
himself a candidate, and may say it repeat- 780 edly (until litigation is pending) after he is elected. As a
means of pursuing the objective of openmindedness that respondents
now articulate, the announce clause is so woefully underinclusive
as to render belief in that purpose a challenge to the credulous.
See City of Ladue v. Gilleo, 512 U. S. 43 , 52-53 (1994)
(noting that underinclusiveness "diminish[es] the credibility of
the government's rationale for restricting speech"); Florida
Star v. B. J. F., 491 U. S. 524 , 541-542
(1989) (SCALIA, J., concurring in judgment) ("[A] law cannot be
regarded as protecting an interest of the highest order, and thus
as justifying a restriction upon truthful speech, when it leaves
appreciable damage to that supposedly vital interest unprohibited"
(internal quotation marks and citation omitted)).
JUSTICE STEVENS asserts that statements made in an election
campaign pose a special threat to openmindedness because the
candidate, when elected judge, will have a particular reluctance to contradict them. Post, at 801. That might be
plausible, perhaps, with regard to campaign promises. A
candidate who says "If elected, I will vote to uphold the
legislature's power to prohibit same-sex marriages" will positively
be breaking his word if he does not do so (although one would be
naive not to recognize that campaign promises are-by long
democratic tradition-the least binding form of human commitment).
But, as noted earlier, the Minnesota Supreme Court has adopted a
separate prohibition on campaign "pledges or promises," which is
not challenged here. The proposition that judges feel significantly
greater compulsion, or appear to feel significantly greater
compulsion, to maintain consistency with nonpromissory statements made during a judicial campaign than with such
statements made before or after the campaign is not self-evidently
true. It seems to us quite likely, in fact, that in many cases the
opposite is true. We doubt, for example, that a mere statement of
position enunciated during the pendency of an election will be
regarded by a judge as more binding-or as more likely 781 to subject him to popular disfavor if reconsidered-than a
carefully considered holding that the judge set forth in an earlier
opinion denying some individual's claim to justice. In any event,
it suffices to say that respondents have not carried the burden
imposed by our strict-scrutiny test to establish this proposition
(that campaign statements are uniquely destructive of
openmindedness) on which the validity of the announce clause rests.
See, e. g., Landmark Communications, Inc. v. Virginia, 435
U. S. 829 , 841 (1978) (rejecting speech restriction subject to
strict scrutiny where the State "offered little more than assertion
and conjecture to support its claim that without criminal sanctions
the objectives of the statutory scheme would be seriously
undermined"); United States v. Playboy Entertainment
Group, Inc., 529
U. S. 803 , 816-825 (2000) (same).8
Moreover, the notion that the special context of electioneering
justifies an abridgment of the right to speak out on
disputed issues sets our First Amendment jurisprudence on its head.
"[D]ebate on the qualifications of candidates" is "at the core of
our electoral process and of the First Amendment freedoms," not at
the edges. Eu, 489 U. S., at 222-223 (internal quotation
marks omitted). "The role that elected officials play in our
society makes it all the more imperative that they be allowed
freely to express themselves on matters
8We do not agree with JUSTICE STEVENS'S broad assertion that "to
the extent that [statements on legal issues] seek to enhance the
popularity of the candidate by indicating how he would rule in
specific cases if elected, they evidence a lack offitness for
office." Post, at 798 (emphasis added). Of course all statements on real-world legal issues "indicate" how the speaker
would rule "in specific cases." And if making such statements (of honestly held views) with the hope of enhancing one's
chances with the electorate displayed a lack of fitness for office,
so would similarly motivated honest statements of judicial
candidates made with the hope of enhancing their chances of
confirmation by the Senate, or indeed of appointment by the
President. Since such statements are made, we think, in every
confirmation hearing, JUSTICE STEVENS must contemplate a federal
bench filled with the unfit. 782 of current public importance." Wood v. Georgia, 370 U. S. 375 ,
395 (1962). "It is simply not the function of government to select
which issues are worth discussing or debating in the course of a
political campaign." Brown, 456 U. S., at 60 (internal
quotation marks and citation omitted). We have never allowed the
government to prohibit candidates from communicating relevant
information to voters during an election.
JUSTICE GINSBURG would do so-and much of her dissent confirms
rather than refutes our conclusion that the purpose behind the
announce clause is not openmindedness in the judiciary, but the
undermining of judicial elections. She contends that the announce
clause must be constitutional because due process would be denied
if an elected judge sat in a case involving an issue on which he
had previously announced his view. Post, at 816, 819. She
reaches this conclusion because, she says, such a judge would have
a "direct, personal, substantial, and pecuniary interest" in ruling
consistently with his previously announced view, in order to reduce
the risk that he will be "voted off the bench and thereby lose
[his] salary and emoluments," post, at 816 (internal
quotation marks and alterations omitted). But elected
judges-regardless of whether they have announced any views beforehand-always face the pressure of an electorate who
might disagree with their rulings and therefore vote them off the
bench. Surely the judge who frees Timothy McVeigh places his job
much more at risk than the judge who (horror of horrors!)
reconsiders his previously announced view on a disputed legal
issue. So if, as JUSTICE GINSBURG claims, it violates due process
for a judge to sit in a case in which ruling one way rather than
another increases his prospects for reelection, then-quite
simply-the practice of electing judges is itself a violation of due
process. I t is not difficult to understand how one with these
views would approve the election-nullifying effect of the
announce 783 clause.9 They are not, however, the views reflected in the Due
Process Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment, which has coexisted
with the election of judges ever since it was adopted, see infra, at 785-786.
JUSTICE GINSBURG devotes the rest of her dissent to attacking
arguments we do not make. For example, despite the number of pages
she dedicates to disproving this proposition, post, at
805-809, we neither assert nor imply that the First Amendment
requires campaigns for judicial office to sound the same as those
for legislative office.lO What we do assert, and what JUSTICE
GINSBURG ignores, is that, even if the First Amendment
allows greater regulation of judicial election campaigns than
legislative election campaigns, the announce clause still fails
strict scrutiny because it is woefully underinclusive, prohibiting
announcements by judges (and would-be judges) only at certain times
and in certain forms. We rely on the cases involving speech during
elections, supra, at 781-782, only to make the obvious point
that this underinclusiveness cannot be explained by resort to the
notion that the First Amendment provides less protection during an
election campaign than at other times.ll
9 JUSTICE GINSBURG argues that the announce clause is not
election nullifying because Wersal criticized past decisions of the
Minnesota Supreme Court in his campaign literature and the Lawyers
Board decided not to discipline him for doing so. Post, at
811-812. As we have explained, however, had Wersal additionally
stated during his campaign that he did not feel bound to follow
those erroneous decisions, he would not have been so lucky. Supra, at 772-773. This predicament hardly reflects "the
robust communication of ideas and views from judicial candidate to
voter." Post, at 812.
10 JUSTICE STEVENS devotes most of his dissent to this same
argument that we do not make.
11 Nor do we assert that candidates for judicial office should
be com pelled to announce their views on disputed
legal issues. Thus, JUSTICE GINSBURG'S repeated invocation of
instances in which nominees to this Court declined to announce such
views during Senate confirmation hearings is pointless. Post, at 807-808, n. 1, 818-819, n. 4. That the practice 784 But in any case, JUSTICE GINSBURG greatly exaggerates the
difference between judicial and legislative elections. She asserts
that "the rationale underlying unconstrained speech in elections
for political office-that representative government depends on the
public's ability to choose agents who will act at its behest-does
not carry over to campaigns for the bench." Post, at 806.
This complete separation of the judiciary from the enterprise of
"representative government" might have some truth in those
countries where judges neither make law themselves nor set aside
the laws enacted by the legislature. It is not a true picture of
the American system. Not only do state-court judges possess the
power to "make" common law, but they have the immense power to
shape the States' constitutions as well. See, e. g., Baker v. State, 170 Vt. 194, 744 A. 2d 864 (1999).
Which is precisely why the election of state judges became
popular.12
of voluntarily demurring does not establish the
legitimacy of legal compulsion to demur is amply
demonstrated by the unredacted text of the sentence she quotes in
part, post, at 819, from Laird v. Tatum, 409 U. S. 824 ,
836, n. 5 (1972): "In terms of propriety, rather than
disqualification, I would distinguish quite sharply between a
public statement made prior to nomination for the bench, on the one
hand, and a public statement made by a nominee to the bench."
(Emphasis added.)
12 Although JUSTICE STEVENS at times appears to agree with
JUSTICE GINSBURG'S premise that the judiciary is completely
separated from the enterprise of representative government, post, at 798 ("[E]very good judge is fully aware of the
distinction between the law and a personal point of view"), he
eventually appears to concede that the separation does not hold
true for many judges who sit on courts of last resort, ante, at 799 ("If he is not a judge on the highest court in the State, he
has an obligation to follow the precedent of that court, not his
personal views or public opinion polls"); post, at 799, n.
2. Even if the policymaking capacity of judges were limited to
courts of last resort, that would only prove that the announce
clause fails strict scrutiny. "[I]f announcing one's views in the
context of a campaign for the State Supreme Court might be"
protected speech, ibid., then-even if announcing one's views
in the context of a campaign for a lower court were not protected speech, ibid.-the announce clause would not be
narrowly tailored, since it applies to high- 785 IV
To sustain the announce clause, the Eighth Circuit relied
heavily on the fact that a pervasive practice of prohibiting
judicial candidates from discussing disputed legal and political
issues developed during the last half of the 20th century. 247 F.
3d, at 879-880. It is true that a "universal and longestablished"
tradition of prohibiting certain conduct creates "a strong
presumption" that the prohibition is constitutional:
"Principles of liberty fundamental enough to have been embodied
within constitutional guarantees are not readily erased from the
Nation's consciousness." McIntyre v. Ohio Elections
Comm'n, 514 U. S.
334 , 375-377 (1995) (SCALIA, J., dissenting). The practice of
prohibiting speech by judicial candidates on disputed issues,
however, is neither long nor universal.
At the time of the founding, only Vermont (before it became a
State) selected any of its judges by election. Starting with
Georgia in 1812, States began to provide for judicial election, a
development rapidly accelerated by Jacksonian democracy. By the
time of the Civil War, the great majority of States elected their
judges. E. Haynes, Selection and Tenure of Judges 99-135 (1944);
Berkson, Judicial Selection in the United States: A Special Report,
64 Judicature 176 (1980). We know of no restrictions upon
statements that could be made by judicial candidates (including
judges) throughout the 19th and the first quarter of the 20th
century. Indeed, judicial elections were generally partisan during
this period, the movement toward nonpartisan judicial elections not
even beginning until the 1870's. Id., at 176-177;
and low-court candidates alike. In fact, however, the judges of
inferior courts often "make law," since the precedent of the
highest court does not cover every situation, and not every case is
reviewed. JUSTICE STEVENS has repeatedly expressed the view that a
settled course of lower court opinions binds the highest court.
See, e. g., Reves v. Ernst & Young, 494 U.
S. 56, 74 (1990) (concurring opinion); McNally v. United
States, 483 U. S.
350 , 376-377 (1987) (dissenting opinion). 786 M. Comisky & P. Patterson, The Judiciary-Selection,
Compensation, Ethics, and Discipline 4, 7 (1987). Thus, not only
were judicial candidates (including judges) discussing disputed
legal and political issues on the campaign trail, but they were
touting party affiliations and angling for party nominations all
the while.
The first code regulating judicial conduct was adopted by the
ABA in 1924. 48 ABA Reports 74 (1923) (report of Chief Justice
Taft); P. McFadden, Electing Justice: The Law and Ethics of
Judicial Election Campaigns 86 (1990). It contained a provision
akin to the announce clause: "A candidate for judicial position ...
should not announce in advance his conclusions of law on disputed
issues to secure class support .... " ABA Canon of Judicial Ethics
30 (1924). The States were slow to adopt the canons, however. "By
the end of World War II, the canons ... were binding by the bar
associations or supreme courts of only eleven states." J.
MacKenzie, The Appearance of Justice 191 (1974). Even today,
although a majority of States have adopted either the announce
clause or its 1990 ABA successor, adoption is not unanimous. Of the
31 States that select some or all of their appellate and
general-jurisdiction judges by election, see American Judicature
Society, Judicial Selection in the States:
Appellate and General Jurisdiction Courts (Apr. 2002), 4 have
adopted no candidate-speech restriction comparable to the announce
clause,13 and 1 prohibits only the discussion of "pending
litigation." 14 This practice, relatively new to judicial elections
and still not universally adopted, does not compare well with the
traditions deemed worthy of our attention in prior cases. E. g., Burson v. Freeman, 504 U. S. 191 ,205206
(1992) (crediting tradition of prohibiting speech around
13 Idaho Code of Judicial Conduct, Canon 7 (2001); Mich. Code of
Judicial Conduct, Canon 7 (2002); N. C. Code of Judicial Conduct,
Canon 7 (2001); Ore. Code of Judicial Conduct, Rule 4-102 (2002).
All of these States save Idaho have adopted the pledges or promises
clause.
14 Ala. Canon of Judicial Ethics 7(B)(1)(c) (2002). 787 polling places that began with the very adoption of the secret
ballot in the late 19th century, and in which every State
participated); id., at 214-216 (SCALIA, J., concurring in
judgment) (same); McIntyre, supra, at 375-377 (SCALIA, J.,
dissenting) (crediting tradition of prohibiting anonymous election
literature, which again began in 1890 and was universally
adopted).
***
There is an obvious tension between the article of Minnesota's
popularly approved Constitution which provides that judges shall be
elected, and the Minnesota Supreme Court's announce clause which
places most subjects of interest to the voters off limits. (The
candidate-speech restrictions of all the other States that have
them are also the product of judicial fiat.15) The disparity is
perhaps unsurprising, since the ABA, which originated the announce
clause, has long been an opponent of judicial elections. See ABA
Model Code of Judicial Conduct, Canon 5(C)(2), Comment
(2000) ("[M]erit selection of judges is a preferable manner in
which to select the judiciary"); An Independent Judiciary: Report
of the ABA Commission on Separation of Powers and Judicial
Independence 96 (1997) ("The American Bar Association strongly
endorses the merit selection of judges, as opposed to their
election .... Five times between August 1972 and August 1984 the
House of Delegates has approved recommendations stating the
preference for merit selection and encouraging bar associations in
jurisdictions where judges are elected ... to work for the adoption
of merit selection and retention"). That opposition may be well
taken (it certainly had the sup-
15 These restrictions are all contained in these States' codes
of judicial conduct, App. to Brief for ABA as Amicus Curiae. "In every state, the highest court promulgates the Code of Judicial
Conduct, either by express constitutional provision, statutory
authorization, broad constitutional grant, or inherent power." In
the Supreme Court of Texas: Per Curiam Opinion Concerning
Amendments to Canons 5 and 6 of the Code of Judicial Conduct, 61
Tex. B. J. 64, 66 (1998) (collecting provisions). 788 port of the Founders of the Federal Government), but the First
Amendment does not permit it to achieve its goal by leaving the
principle of elections in place while preventing candidates from
discussing what the elections are about. "[T]he greater power to
dispense with elections altogether does not include the lesser
power to conduct elections under conditions of state-imposed voter
ignorance. If the State chooses to tap the energy and the
legitimizing power of the democratic process, it must accord the
participants in that process ... the First Amendment rights that
attach to their roles." Renne v. Geary, 501 U. S. 312 , 349 (1991)
(Marshall, J., dissenting); accord, Meyer v. Grant, 486 U. S. 414 ,
424425 (1988) (rejecting argument that the greater power to end
voter initiatives includes the lesser power to prohibit paid
petition-circulators).
The Minnesota Supreme Court's canon of judicial conduct
prohibiting candidates for judicial election from announcing their
views on disputed legal and political issues violates the First
Amendment. Accordingly, we reverse the grant of summary judgment to
respondents and remand the case for proceedings consistent with
this opinion.
It is so ordered.
JUSTICE O'CONNOR, concurring.
I join the opinion of the Court but write separately to express
my concerns about judicial elections generally. Respondents claim
that "[t]he Announce Clause is necessary ... to protect the State's
compelling governmental interes[t] in an actual and perceived ...
impartial judiciary." Brief for Respondents 8. I am concerned that,
even aside from what judicial candidates may say while campaigning,
the very practice of electing judges undermines this interest.
We of course want judges to be impartial, in the sense of being
free from any personal stake in the outcome of the cases to which
they are assigned. But if judges are subject to regular elections
they are likely to feel that they have at 789 least some personal stake in the outcome of every publicized
case. Elected judges cannot help being aware that if the public is
not satisfied with the outcome of a particular case, it could hurt
their reelection prospects. See Eule, Crocodiles in the Bathtub:
State Courts, Voter Initiatives and the Threat of Electoral
Reprisal, 65 U. Colo. L. Rev. 733, 739 (1994) (quoting former
California Supreme Court Justice Otto Kaus' statement that ignoring
the political consequences of visible decisions is "'like ignoring
a crocodile in your bathtub' "); Bright & Keenan, Judges and
the Politics of Death: Deciding Between the Bill of Rights and the
Next Election in Capital Cases, 75 B. U. L. Rev. 759, 793-794
(1995) (citing statistics indicating that judges who face elections
are far more likely to override jury sentences of life without
parole and impose the death penalty than are judges who do not run
for election). Even if judges were able to suppress their awareness
of the potential electoral consequences of their decisions and
refrain from acting on it, the public's confidence in the judiciary
could be undermined simply by the possibility that judges would be
unable to do so.
Moreover, contested elections generally entail campaigning. And
campaigning for a judicial post today can require substantial
funds. See Schotland, Financing Judicial Elections, 2000: Change
and Challenge, 2001 L. Rev. Mich. State U. Detroit College of Law
849, 866 (reporting that in 2000, the 13 candidates in a partisan
election for 5 seats on the Alabama Supreme Court spent an average
of $1,092,076 on their campaigns); American Bar Association, Report
and Recommendations of the Task Force on Lawyers' Political
Contributions, pt. 2 (July 1998) (reporting that in 1995, one
candidate for the Pennsylvania Supreme Court raised $1,848,142 in
campaign funds, and that in 1986, $2,700,000 was spent on the race
for Chief Justice of the Ohio Supreme Court). Unless the pool of
judicial candidates is limited to those wealthy enough to
independently fund their campaigns, a limitation unrelated to
judicial skill, the cost of 790 campaigning requires judicial candidates to engage in
fundraising. Yet relying on campaign donations may leave judges
feeling indebted to certain parties or interest groups. See Thomas,
National L. J., Mar. 16, 1998, p. A8, col. 1 (reporting that a
study by the public interest group Texans for Public Justice found
that 40 percent of the $9,200,000 in contributions of $100 or more
raised by seven of Texas' nine Supreme Court justices for their
1994 and 1996 elections "came from parties and lawyers with cases
before the court or contributors closely linked to these parties").
Even if judges were able to refrain from favoring donors, the mere
possibility that judges' decisions may be motivated by the desire
to repay campaign contributors is likely to undermine the public's
confidence in the judiciary. See Greenberg Quinlan Rosner Research,
Inc., and American Viewpoint, National Public Opinion Survey
Frequency Questionnaire 4 (2001) (available at
http://www.justiceatstake. org/files/JASN ationalSurvey
Results.pdf) (describing survey results indicating that 76 percent
of registered voters believe that campaign contributions influence
judicial decisions); id., at 7 (describing survey results
indicating that two-thirds of registered voters believe individuals
and groups who give money to judicial candidates often receive
favorable treatment); Barnhizer, "On the Make": Campaign Funding
and the Corrupting of the American Judiciary, 50 Cath. U. L. Rev.
361, 379 (2001) (relating anecdotes of lawyers who felt that their
contributions to judicial campaigns affected their chance of
success in court).
Despite these significant problems, 39 States currently employ
some form of judicial elections for their appellate courts, general
jurisdiction trial courts, or both. American Judicature Society,
Judicial Selection in the States: Appellate and General
Jurisdiction Courts (Apr. 2002). Judicial elections were not always
so prevalent. The first 29 States of the Union adopted methods for
selecting judges that did not involve popular elections. See
Croley, The Majoritarian Dif- 791 ficulty: Elective Judiciaries and the Rule of Law, 62 U. Chi. L.
Rev. 689, 716 (1995). As the Court explains, however, beginning
with Georgia in 1812, States began adopting systems for judicial
elections. See ante, at 785. From the 1830's until the
1850's, as part of the Jacksonian movement toward greater popular
control of public office, this trend accelerated, see Goldschmidt,
Merit Selection: Current Status, Procedures, and Issues, 49 U.
Miami L. Rev. 1, 5 (1994), and by the Civil War, 22 of the 34
States elected their judges, ibid. By the beginning of the
20th century, however, elected judiciaries increasingly came to be
viewed as incompetent and corrupt, and criticism of partisan
judicial elections mounted. Croley, supra, at 723. In 1906,
Roscoe Pound gave a speech to the American Bar Association in which
he claimed that "compelling judges to become politicians, in many
jurisdictions has almost destroyed the traditional respect for the
bench." The Causes of Popular Dissatisfaction with the
Administration of Justice, 8 Baylor L. Rev. 1, 23 (1956)
(reprinting Pound's speech).
In response to such concerns, some States adopted a modified
system of judicial selection that became known as the Missouri Plan
(because Missouri was the first State to adopt it for most of its
judicial posts). See Croley, 62 U. Chi. L. Rev., at 724. Under the
Missouri Plan, judges are appointed by a high elected official,
generally from a list of nominees put together by a nonpartisan
nominating commission, and then subsequently stand for unopposed
retention elections in which voters are asked whether the judges
should be recalled. Ibid. If a judge is recalled, the
vacancy is filled through a new nomination and appointment. Ibid. This system obviously reduces threats to judicial
impartiality, even if it does not eliminate all popular pressure on
judges. See Grodin, Developing a Consensus of Constraint:
A Judge's Perspective on Judicial Retention Elections, 61 S.
Cal. L. Rev. 1969, 1980 (1988) (admitting that he cannot be sure
that his votes as a California Supreme Court Justice 792 in "critical cases" during 1986 were not influenced
subconsciously by his awareness that the outcomes could affect his
chances in the retention elections being conducted that year). The
Missouri Plan is currently used to fill at least some judicial
offices in 15 States. Croley, supra, at 725-726; American
Judicature Society, supra. Thirty-one States, however, still use popular elections to
select some or all of their appellate and/or general jurisdiction
trial court judges, who thereafter run for reelection periodically. Ibid. Of these, slightly more than half use nonpartisan
elections, and the rest use partisan elections. Ibid. Most
of the States that do not have any form of judicial elections
choose judges through executive nomination and legislative
confirmation. See Croley, supra, at 725.
Minnesota has chosen to select its judges through contested
popular elections instead of through an appointment system or a
combined appointment and retention election system along the lines
of the Missouri Plan. In doing so the State has voluntarily taken
on the risks to judicial bias described above. As a result, the
State's claim that it needs to significantly restrict judges'
speech in order to protect judicial impartiality is particularly
troubling. If the State has a problem with judicial impartiality,
it is largely one the State brought upon itself by continuing the
practice of popularly electing judges.
JUSTICE KENNEDY, concurring.
I agree with the Court that Minnesota's prohibition on judicial
candidates' announcing their legal views is an unconstitutional
abridgment of the freedom of speech. There is authority for the
Court to apply strict scrutiny analysis to resolve some First
Amendment cases, see, e. g., Simon & Schuster, Inc. v. Members of N. Y. State Crime Victims Bd., 502 U. S. 105 (1991), and
the Court explains in clear and forceful terms why the Minnesota
regulatory scheme fails that test. So I join its opinion. 793 I adhere to my view, however, that content-based speech
restrictions that do not fall within any traditional exception
should be invalidated without inquiry into narrow tailoring or
compelling government interests. The speech at issue here does not
come within any of the exceptions to the First Amendment recognized
by the Court. "Here, a law is directed to speech alone where the
speech in question is not obscene, not defamatory, not words
tantamount to an act otherwise criminal, not an impairment of some
other constitutional right, not an incitement to lawless action,
and not calculated or likely to bring about imminent harm the State
has the substantive power to prevent. No further inquiry is
necessary to reject the State's argument that the statute should be
upheld." Id., at 124 (KENNEDY, J., concurring in judgment).
The political speech of candidates is at the heart of the First
Amendment, and direct restrictions on the content of candidate
speech are simply beyond the power of government to impose.
Here, Minnesota has sought to justify its speech restriction as
one necessary to maintain the integrity of its judiciary. Nothing
in the Court's opinion should be read to cast doubt on the vital
importance of this state interest. Courts, in our system, elaborate
principles of law in the course of resolving disputes. The power
and the prerogative of a court to perform this function rest, in
the end, upon the respect accorded to its judgments. The citizen's
respect for judgments depends in turn upon the issuing court's
absolute probity. Judicial integrity is, in consequence, a state
interest of the highest order.
Articulated standards of judicial conduct may advance this
interest. See Shepard, Campaign Speech: Restraint and Liberty in
Judicial Ethics, 9 Geo. J. Legal Ethics 1059 (1996). To comprehend,
then to codify, the essence of judicial integrity is a hard task,
however. "The work of deciding cases goes on every day in hundreds
of courts throughout the land. Any judge, one might suppose, would
find it easy to describe 794 the process which he had followed a thousand times and more.
Nothing could be farther from the truth." B. Cardozo, The Nature of
the Judicial Process 9 (1921). Much the same can be said of
explicit standards to ensure judicial integrity. To strive for
judicial integrity is the work of a lifetime. That should not
dissuade the profession. The difficulty of the undertaking does not
mean we should refrain from the attempt. Explicit standards of
judicial conduct provide essential guidance for judges in the
proper discharge of their duties and the honorable conduct of their
office. The legislative bodies, judicial committees, and
professional associations that promulgate those standards perform a
vital public service. See, e. g., Administrative
Office of U. S. Courts, Code of Judicial Conduct for United States
Judges (1999). Yet these standards may not be used by the State to
abridge the speech of aspiring judges in a judicial campaign.
Minnesota may choose to have an elected judiciary. It may strive
to define those characteristics that exemplify judicial excellence.
It may enshrine its definitions in a code of judicial conduct. It
may adopt recusal standards more rigorous than due process
requires, and censure judges who violate these standards. What
Minnesota may not do, however, is censor what the people hear as
they undertake to decide for themselves which candidate is most
likely to be an exemplary judicial officer. Deciding the relevance
of candidate speech is the right of the voters, not the State. See Brown v. Hartlage, 456 U. S. 45 , 60 (1982).
The law in question here contradicts the principle that unabridged
speech is the foundation of political freedom.
The State of Minnesota no doubt was concerned, as many citizens
and thoughtful commentators are concerned, that judicial campaigns
in an age of frenetic fundraising and mass media may foster
disrespect for the legal system. Indeed, from the beginning there
have been those who believed that the rough-and-tumble of politics
would bring our governmental institutions into ill repute. And some
have sought to 795 cure this tendency with governmental restrictions on political
speech. See Sedition Act of 1798, ch. 74, 1 Stat. 596. Cooler heads
have always recognized, however, that these measures abridge the
freedom of speech-not because the state interest is insufficiently
compelling, but simply because content-based restrictions on
political speech are" 'expressly and positively forbidden by''' the
First Amendment. See New York Times Co. v. Sullivan, 376 U. S. 254 ,
274 (1964) (quoting the Virginia Resolutions of 1798). The State
cannot opt for an elected judiciary and then assert that its
democracy, in order to work as desired, compels the abridgment of
speech.
If Minnesota believes that certain sorts of candidate speech
disclose flaws in the candidate's credentials, democracy and free
speech are their own correctives. The legal profession, the legal
academy, the press, voluntary groups, political and civic leaders,
and all interested citizens can use their own First Amendment
freedoms to protest statements inconsistent with standards of
judicial neutrality and judicial excellence. Indeed, if democracy
is to fulfill its promise, they must do so. They must reach voters
who are uninterested or uninformed or blinded by partisanship, and
they must urge upon the voters a higher and better understanding of
the judicial function and a stronger commitment to preserving its
finest traditions. Free elections and free speech are a powerful
combination: Together they may advance our understanding of the
rule of law and further a commitment to its precepts.
There is general consensus that the design of the Federal
Constitution, including lifetime tenure and appointment by
nomination and confirmation, has preserved the independence of the
Federal Judiciary. In resolving this case, however, we should
refrain from criticism of the State's choice to use open elections
to select those persons most likely to achieve judicial excellence.
States are free to choose this mechanism rather than, say,
appointment and confirmation. 796 By condemning judicial elections across the board, we implicitly
condemn countless elected state judges and without warrant. Many of
them, despite the difficulties imposed by the election system, have
discovered in the law the enlightenment, instruction, and
inspiration that make them independent-minded and faithful jurists
of real integrity. We should not, even by inadvertence, "impute to
judges a lack of firmness, wisdom, or honor." Bridges v. California, 314 U. S. 252 , 273
(1941).
These considerations serve but to reinforce the conclusion that
Minnesota's regulatory scheme is flawed. By abridging speech based
on its content, Minnesota impeaches its own system of free and open
elections. The State may not regulate the content of candidate
speech merely because the speakers are candidates. This case does
not present the question whether a State may restrict the speech of
judges because they are judges-for example, as part of a code of
judicial conduct; the law at issue here regulates judges only when
and because they are candidates. Whether the rationale of Pickering v. Board of Ed. of Township High School
Dist.205, Will Cty., 391 U. S. 563 , 568
(1968), and Connick v. Myers, 461 U. S. 138 (1983),
could be extended to allow a general speech restriction on sitting
judges-regardless of whether they are campaigning-in order to
promote the efficient administration of justice, is not an issue
raised here.
Petitioner Gregory Wersal was not a sitting judge but a
challenger; he had not voluntarily entered into an employment
relationship with the State or surrendered any First Amendment
rights. His speech may not be controlled or abridged in this
manner. Even the undoubted interest of the State in the excellence
of its judiciary does not allow it to restrain candidate speech by
reason of its content. Minnesota's attempt to regulate campaign
speech is impermissible. 797 JUSTICE STEVENS, with whom JUSTICE SOUTER, JUSTICE GINSBURG, and
JUSTICE BREYER join, dissenting.
In her dissenting opinion, JUSTICE GINSBURG has cogently
explained why the Court's holding is unsound. I therefore join her
opinion without reservation. I add these comments to emphasize the
force of her arguments and to explain why I find the Court's
reasoning even more troubling than its holding. The limits of the
Court's holding are evident: Even if the Minnesota Lawyers
Professional Responsibility Board (Board) may not sanction a
judicial candidate for announcing his views on issues likely to
come before him, it may surely advise the electorate that such
announcements demonstrate the speaker's unfitness for judicial
office. If the solution to harmful speech must be more speech, so
be it. The Court's reasoning, however, will unfortunately endure
beyond the next election cycle. By obscuring the fundamental
distinction between campaigns for the judiciary and the political
branches, and by failing to recognize the difference between
statements made in articles or opinions and those made on the
campaign trail, the Court defies any sensible notion of the
judicial office and the importance of impartiality in that
context.
The Court's disposition rests on two seriously flawed
premises-an inaccurate appraisal of the importance of judicial
independence and impartiality, and an assumption that judicial
candidates should have the same freedom" 'to express themselves on
matters of current public importance'" as do all other elected
officials. Ante, at 781-782. Elected judges, no less than
appointed judges, occupy an office of trust that is fundamentally
different from that occupied by policymaking officials. Although
the fact that they must stand for election makes their job more
difficult than that of the tenured judge, that fact does not lessen
their duty to respect essential attributes of the judicial office
that have been embedded in Anglo-American law for centuries. 798 There is a critical difference between the work of the judge and
the work of other public officials. In a democracy, issues of
policy are properly decided by majority vote; it is the business of
legislators and executives to be popular. But in litigation, issues
of law or fact should not be determined by popular vote; it is the
business of judges to be indifferent to unpopularity. Sir Matthew
Hale pointedly described this essential attribute of the judicial
office in words which have retained their integrity for
centuries: "'11. That popular or court applause or distaste have no
influence in anything I do, in point of distribution of
justice. "'12. Not to be solicitous what men will say or think, so long
as I keep myself exactly according to the rule of justice.'" 1 Consistent with that fundamental attribute of the office,
countless judges in countless cases routinely make rulings that are
unpopular and surely disliked by at least 50 percent of the
litigants who appear before them. It is equally common for them to
enforce rules that they think unwise, or that are contrary to their
personal predilections. For this reason, opinions that a lawyer may
have expressed before becoming a judge, or a judicial candidate, do
not disqualify anyone for judicial service because every good judge
is fully aware of the distinction between the law and a personal
point of view. It is equally clear, however, that such expressions
after a lawyer has been nominated to judicial office shed little,
if any, light on his capacity for judicial service. Indeed, to the
extent that such statements seek to enhance the popularity of the
candidate by indicating how he would rule in specific cases if
elected, they evidence a lack of fitness for the office.
12 J. Campbell, Lives of the Chief Justices of England 208
(1873) (quoting Hale's Rules For His Judicial Guidance, Things
Necessary to be Continually Had in Remembrance). 799 Of course, any judge who faces reelection may believe that he
retains his office only so long as his decisions are popular.
Nevertheless, the elected judge, like the lifetime appointee, does
not serve a constituency while holding that office. He has a duty
to uphold the law and to follow the dictates of the Constitution.
If he is not a judge on the highest court in the State, he has an
obligation to follow the precedent of that court, not his personal
views or public opinion polls.2 He may make common law, but judged
on the merits of individual cases, not as a mandate from the
voters.
By recognizing a conflict between the demands of electoral
politics and the distinct characteristics of the judiciary, we
2 The Court largely ignores the fact that judicial elections are
not limited to races for the highest court in the State. Even if
announcing one's views in the context of a campaign for the State
Supreme Court might be permissible, the same statements are surely
less appropriate when one is running for an intermediate or trial
court judgeship. Such statements not only display a
misunderstanding of the judicial role, but also mislead the voters
by giving them the false impression that a candidate for the trial
court will be able to and should decide cases based on his personal
views rather than precedent.
Indeed, the Court's entire analysis has a hypothetical quality
to it that stems, in part, from the fact that no candidate has yet
been sanctioned for violating the announce clause. The one
complaint filed against petitioner Gregory Wersal for campaign
materials during his 1996 election run was dismissed by the Board.
App. 16-21. Moreover, when Wersal sought an advisory opinion during
his 1998 campaign, the Board could not evaluate his request because
he had "not specified what statement [he] would make that mayor may
not be a view on a disputed, legal or political issue." Id., at 32. Since Wersal failed to provide examples of statements he
wished to make, and because the Board had its own doubts about the
constitutionality of the announce clause, it advised Wersal that
"unless the speech at issue violates other prohibitions listed in
Canon 5 or other portions of the Code of Judicial Conduct, it is
our belief that this section is not, as written, constitutionally
enforceable." Ibid. Consequently, the Court is left to
decide a question of great constitutional importance in a case in
which either the petitioner's statements were not subject to the
prohibition in question, or he neglected to supply any concrete
examples of statements he wished to make, and the Board refused to
enforce the prohibition because of its own constitutional
concerns. 800 do not have to put States to an all or nothing choice of
abandoning judicial elections or having elections in which anything
goes. As a practical matter, we cannot know for sure whether an
elected judge's decisions are based on his interpretation of the
law or political expediency. In the absence of reliable evidence
one way or the other, a State may reasonably presume that elected
judges are motivated by the highest aspirations of their office.
But we do know that a judicial candidate, who announces his views
in the context of a campaign, is effectively telling the
electorate: "Vote for me because I believe X, and I will judge
cases accordingly." Once elected, he may feel free to disregard his
campaign statements, ante, at 780-781, but that does not
change the fact that the judge announced his position on an issue
likely to come before him as a reason to vote for him. Minnesota has a compelling interest in sanctioning such
statements.
A candidate for judicial office who goes beyond the expression
of "general observation about the law ... in order to obtain
favorable consideration" of his candidacy, Laird v. Tatum, 409 U.
S. 824 , 836, n. 5 (1972) (memorandum of REHNQUIST, J., on
motion for recusal), demonstrates either a lack of impartiality or
a lack of understanding of the importance of maintaining public
confidence in the impartiality of the judiciary. It is only by
failing to recognize the distinction, clearly stated by
then-JusTIcE REHNQUIST, between statements made during a campaign
or confirmation hearing and those made before announcing one's
candidacy, that the Court is able to conclude: "[S]ince avoiding
judicial preconceptions on legal issues is neither possible nor
desirable, pretending otherwise by attempting to preserve the
'appearance' of that type of impartiality can hardly be a
compelling state interest either," ante, at 778.
Even when "impartiality" is defined in its narrowest sense to
embrace only "the lack of bias for or against either party to the proceeding," ante, at 775, the announce clause serves
that interest. Expressions that stress a candidate's unbro- 801 ken record of affirming convictions for rape,3 for example,
imply a bias in favor of a particular litigant (the prosecutor) and
against a class of litigants (defendants in rape cases). Contrary
to the Court's reasoning in its first attempt to define
impartiality, ante, at 775-776, an interpretation of the
announce clause that prohibits such statements serves the State's
interest in maintaining both the appearance of this form of
impartiality and its actuality.
When the Court evaluates the importance of impartiality in its
broadest sense, which it describes as "the interest in
openmindedness, or at least in the appearance of openmindedness," ante, at 778, it concludes that the announce clause is "so
woefully underinclusive as to render belief in that purpose a
challenge to the credulous," ante, at 780. It is
underinclusive, in the Court's view, because campaign statements
are an infinitesimal portion of the public commitments to legal
positions that candidates make during their professional careers.
It is not, however, the number of legal views that a candidate may
have formed or discussed in his prior career that is significant.
Rather, it is the ability both to reevaluate them in the light of
an adversarial presentation, and to apply the governing rule of law
even when inconsistent with those views, that characterize judicial
openmindedness.
The Court boldly asserts that respondents have failed to carry
their burden of demonstrating "that campaign statements are
uniquely destructive of openmindedness," ante, at 781. But
the very purpose of most statements prohibited by the announce
clause is to convey the message that the candidate's mind is not
open on a particular issue. The lawyer who writes an article
advocating harsher penalties for polluters surely does not commit
to that position to the same degree as the candidate who says "vote
for me because I believe all polluters deserve harsher penalties."
At the
3 See Buckley v. Illinois Judicial Inquiry Bd., 997 F.2d
224 , 226 (CA7 1993). 802 very least, such statements obscure the appearance of
openmindedness. More importantly, like the reasoning in the Court's
opinion, they create the false impression that the standards for
the election of political candidates apply equally to candidates
for judicial office.4
The Court seems to have forgotten its prior evaluation of the
importance of maintaining public confidence in the
"disinterestedness" of the judiciary. Commenting on the danger that
participation by judges in a political assignment might erode that
public confidence, we wrote: "While the problem of individual bias
is usually cured through recusal, no such mechanism can overcome
the appearance of institutional partiality that may arise from
judiciary involvement in the making of policy. The legitimacy of
the Judicial Branch ultimately depends on its reputation for
impartiality and nonpartisanship. That reputation may not be
borrowed by the political Branches to cloak their work in the
neutral colors of judicial action." Mistretta v. United
States, 488 U. S. 361, 407 (1989).
Conversely, the judicial reputation for impartiality and
openmindedness is compromised by electioneering that emphasizes the
candidate's personal predilections rather than his qualifications
for judicial office. As an elected judge recently noted: "Informed criticism of court rulings, or of the professional or
personal conduct of judges, should play an 4JUSTICE KENNEDY would go even further and hold that no
contentbased restriction of a judicial candidate's speech is
permitted under the First Amendment. Ante, at 793
(concurring opinion). While he does not say so explicitly, this
extreme position would preclude even Minnesota's prohibition
against "pledges or promises" by a candidate for judicial office.
Minn. Code of Judicial Conduct, Canon 5(A)(3)(d)(i) (2002). A
candidate could say "vote for me because I promise to never reverse
a rape conviction," and the Board could do nothing to formally
sanction that candidate. The unwisdom of this proposal illustrates
why the same standards should not apply to speech in campaigns for
judicial and legislative office. 803 important role in maintaining judicial accountability. However,
attacking courts and judges-not because they are wrong on the law
or the facts of a case, but because the decision is considered
wrong simply as a matter of political judgment-maligns one of the
basic tenets of judicial independence-intellectual honesty and
dedication to enforcement of the rule of law regardless of popular
sentiment. Dedication to the rule of law requires judges to rise
above the political moment in making judicial decisions. What is so
troubling about criticism of court rulings and individual judges
based solely on political disagreement with the outcome is that it
evidences a fundamentally misguided belief that the judicial branch
should operate and be treated just like another constituency-driven
political arm of government. Judges should not have 'political
constituencies.' Rather, a judge's fidelity must be to enforcement
of the rule of law regardless of perceived popular will." De Muniz,
Politicizing State Judicial Elections: A Threat to Judicial
Independence, 38 Willamette L. Rev. 367, 387 (2002). The disposition of this case on the flawed premise that the
criteria for the election to judicial office should mirror the
rules applicable to political elections is profoundly misguided. I
therefore respectfully dissent.
JUSTICE GINSBURG, with whom JUSTICE STEVENS, JusTICE SOUTER, and
JUSTICE BREYER join, dissenting.
Whether state or federal, elected or appointed, judges perform a
function fundamentally different from that of the people's elected
representatives. Legislative and executive officials act on behalf
of the voters who placed them in office; "judge[s] represen[t] the
Law." Chisom v. Roemer, 501 U. S. 380 , 411 (1991)
(SCALIA, J., dissenting). Unlike their counterparts in the
political branches, judges are expected to 804 refrain from catering to particular constituencies or committing
themselves on controversial issues in advance of adversarial
presentation. Their mission is to decide "individual cases and
controversies" on individual records, Plaut v. Spendthrift Farm, Inc., 514 U. S. 211 , 266 (1995)
(STEVENS, J., dissenting), neutrally applying legal principles,
and, when necessary, "stand[ing] up to what is generally supreme in
a democracy: the popular will," Scalia, The Rule of Law as a Law of
Rules, 56 U. Chi. L. Rev. 1175, 1180 (1989).
A judiciary capable of performing this function, owing fidelity
to no person or party, is a "longstanding AngloAmerican tradition," United States v. Will, 449 U. S. 200 , 217
(1980), an essential bulwark of constitutional government, a
constant guardian of the rule of law. The guarantee of an
independent, impartial judiciary enables society to "withdraw
certain subjects from the vicissitudes of political controversy, to
place them beyond the reach of majorities and officials and to
establish them as legal principles to be applied by the courts." West Virginia Bd. of Ed. v. Barnette, 319 U. S. 624 , 638
(1943). "Without this, all the reservations of particular rights or
privileges would amount to nothing." The Federalist No. 78, p. 466 (C. Rossiter ed. 1961).
The ability of the judiciary to discharge its unique role rests
to a large degree on the manner in which judges are selected. The
Framers of the Federal Constitution sought to advance the judicial
function through the structural protections of Article III, which
provide for the selection of judges by the President on the advice
and consent of the Senate, generally for lifetime terms. Through
its own Constitution, Minnesota, in common with most other States,
has decided to allow its citizens to choose judges directly in
periodic elections. But Minnesota has not thereby opted to install
a corps of political actors on the bench; rather, it has endeavored
to preserve the integrity of its judiciary by other means.
Recognizing that the influence of political parties is incompatible
with the judge's role, for example, Minnesota 805 has designated all judicial elections nonpartisan. See Pe terson v. Stafford, 490 N. W. 2d 418, 425 (Minn.
1992). And it has adopted a provision, here called the Announce
Clause, designed to prevent candidates for judicial office from
"publicly making known how they would decide issues likely to come
before them as judges." Republican Party of Minn. The question this case presents is whether the First Amendment
stops Minnesota from furthering its interest in judicial integrity
through this precisely targeted speech restriction.
I
The speech restriction must fail, in the Court's view, because
an electoral process is at stake; if Minnesota opts to elect its
judges, the Court asserts, the State may not rein in what
candidates may say. See ante, at 781 (notion that "right to
speak out on disputed issues" may be abridged in an election
context "sets our First Amendment jurisprudence on its head"); ante, at 787-788 (power to dispense with elections does not
include power to curtail candidate speech if State leaves election
process in place); 247 F. 3d, at 897 (Beam, J., dissenting)
("[W]hen a state opts to hold an election, it must commit itself to
a complete election, replete with free speech and association."); id., at 903 (same).
I do not agree with this unilocular, "an election is an
election," approach. Instead, I would differentiate elections for
political offices, in which the First Amendment holds full sway,
from elections designed to select those whose office it is to
administer justice without respect to persons. Minnesota's choice
to elect its judges, I am persuaded, does not preclude the State
from installing an election process geared to the judicial
office.
Legislative and executive officials serve in representative
capacities. They are agents of the people; their primary function
is to advance the interests of their constituencies. Candidates for
political offices, in keeping with their repre- 806 sentative role, must be left free to inform the electorate of
their positions on specific issues. Armed with such information,
the individual voter will be equipped to cast her ballot
intelligently, to vote for the candidate committed to positions the
voter approves. Campaign statements committing the candidate to
take sides on contentious issues are therefore not only appropriate
in political elections; they are "at the core of our electoral
process," Williams v. Rhodes, 393 U. S. 23 , 32 (1968),
for they "enhance the accountability of government officials to the
people whom they represent," Brown v. Hartlage, 456 U. S. 45 , 55
(1982).
Judges, however, are not political actors. They do not sit as
representatives of particular persons, communities, or parties;
they serve no faction or constituency. "[I]t is the business of
judges to be indifferent to popularity." Chisom, 501 U. S.,
at 401, n. 29 (internal quotation marks omitted). They must strive
to do what is legally right, all the more so when the result is not
the one "the home crowd" wants. Rehnquist, Dedicatory Address: Act
Well Your Part: Therein All Honor Lies, 7 Pepperdine L. Rev. 227,
229-300 (1980). Even when they develop common law or give concrete
meaning to constitutional text, judges act only in the context of
individual cases, the outcome of which cannot depend on the will of
the public. See Barnette, 319 U. S., at 638 ("One's right to
life, liberty, and property, to free speech, a free press, freedom
of worship and assembly, and other fundamental rights may not be
submitted to vote; they depend on the outcome of no
elections.").
Thus, the rationale underlying unconstrained speech in elections
for political office-that representative government depends on the
public's ability to choose agents who will act at its behest-does
not carryover to campaigns for the bench. As to persons aiming to
occupy the seat of judgment, the Court's unrelenting reliance on
decisions involving contests for legislative and executive posts is
manifestly out of place. E. g., ante, at 781-782 (quoting Wood v. Georgia, 807 370 U. S. 375 ,
395 (1962) ("The role that elected officials play in our
society makes it all the more imperative that they be allowed
freely to express themselves on matters of current public
importance." (Emphasis added.))). See O'Neil, The Canons in the
Courts: Recent First Amendment Rulings, 35 Ind. L. Rev. 701, 717
(2002) (reliance on cases involving nonjudicial campaigns,
particularly Brown v. Hartlage, is "grievously
misplaced"; "[h]ow any thoughtful judge could derive from that
ruling any possible guidance for cases that involve judicial
campaign speech seems baffling"). In view of the magisterial role
judges must fill in a system of justice, a role that removes them
from the partisan fray, States may limit judicial campaign speech
by measures impermissible in elections for political office. See Buckley v. Illinois Judicial Inquiry Bd., 997 F.2d
224 , 228 (CA71993) ("Mode of appointment is only one
factor that enables distinctions to be made among different kinds
of public official. Judges remain different from legislators and
executive officials, even when all are elected, in ways that bear
on the strength of the state's interest in restricting their
freedom of speech.").
The Court sees in this conclusion, and in the Announce Clause
that embraces it, "an obvious tension," ante, at 787:
The Minnesota electorate is permitted to select its judges by
popular vote, but is not provided information on "subjects of
interest to the voters," ibid.-in particular, the voters are
not told how the candidate would decide controversial cases or
issues if elected. This supposed tension, however, rests on the
false premise that by departing from the federal model with respect
to who chooses judges, Minnesota necessarily departed from
the federal position on the criteria relevant to the
exercise of that choice.1
1 In the context of the federal system, how a prospective
nominee for the bench would resolve particular contentious issues
would certainly be "of interest" to the President and the Senate in
the exercise of their respective nomination and confirmation
powers, just as information of that type would "interest" a
Minnesota voter. But in accord with a longstand- 808 The Minnesota Supreme Court thought otherwise: "The methods by which the federal system and other states
initially select and then elect or retain judges are varied, yet
the explicit or implicit goal of the constitutional provisions and
enabling legislation is the same: to create and maintain an
independent judiciary as free from political, economic and social
pressure as possible so judges can decide cases without those
influences." Peterson, 490 N. W. 2d, at 420. Nothing in the Court's opinion convincingly explains why
Minnesota may not pursue that goal in the manner it did.
Minnesota did not choose a judicial selection system with all
the trappings of legislative and executive races. While providing
for public participation, it tailored judicial selection to fit the
character of third branch office holding. See id., at 425
(Minnesota's system "keep[s] the ultimate choice with the voters
while, at the same time, recognizing the unique independent nature
of the judicial function."). The balance the State sought to
achieve-allowing the people to elect judges, but safeguarding the
process so that the integrity of the judiciary would not be
compromised-should en-
ing norm, every Member of this Court declined to furnish such
information to the Senate, and presumably to the President as well.
See Brief for Respondents 17-42 (collecting statements at Senate
confirmation hearings). Surely the Court perceives no tension here;
the line each of us drew in response to preconfirmation
questioning, the Court would no doubt agree, is crucial to the
health of the Federal Judiciary. But by the Court's reasoning, the
reticence of prospective and current federal judicial nominees
dishonors Article II, for it deprives the President and the Senate
of information that might aid or advance the decision to nominate
or confirm. The point is not, of course, that this "practice of
voluntarily demurring" by itself "establish[es] the legitimacy of
legal compulsion to demur," ante, at 783-784, n. 11
(emphasis deleted). The federal norm simply illustrates that,
contrary to the Court's suggestion, there is nothing inherently
incongruous in depriving those charged with choosing judges of
certain information they might desire during the selection
process. 809 counter no First Amendment shoal. See generally O'Neil, supra, at 715-723.
II
Proper resolution of this case requires correction of the
Court's distorted construction of the provision before us for
review. According to the Court, the Announce Clause "prohibits a
judicial candidate from stating his views on any specific
nonfanciful legal question within the province of the court for
which he is running, except in the context of discussing past
decisions-and in the latter context as well, if he expresses the
view that he is not bound by stare decisis." Ante, at 773.
In two key respects, that construction misrepresents the meaning of
the Announce Clause as interpreted by the Eighth Circuit and
embraced by the Minnesota Supreme Court, In re Code of Judicial
Conduct, 639 N. W. 2d 55 (2002), which has the final word on
this matter, see Hortonville Joint School Dist. No. 1 v. Hortonville Ed. Assn., 426 U. S. 482 , 488 (1976)
("We are, of course, bound to accept the interpretation of [the
State's] law by the highest court of the State.").
First and most important, the Court ignores a cruciallimiting
construction placed on the Announce Clause by the courts below. The
provision does not bar a candidate from generally "stating [her]
views" on legal questions, ante, at 773; it prevents her
from "publicly making known how [she] would decide" disputed
issues, 247 F. 3d, at 881-882 (emphasis added). That limitation
places beyond the scope of the Announce Clause a wide range of
comments that may be highly informative to voters. Consistent with
the Eighth Circuit's construction, such comments may include, for
example, statements of historical fact ("As a prosecutor, I
obtained 15 drunk driving convictions"); qualified statements
("Judges should use sparingly their discretion to grant
lenient sentences to drunk drivers"); and statements framed 810 at a sufficient level of generality ("Drunk drivers are a threat
to the safety of every driver"). What remains within the Announce
Clause is the category of statements that essentially commit the
candidate to a position on a specific issue, such as "I think all
drunk drivers should receive the maximum sentence permitted by
law." See Tr. of Oral Arg. 45 (candidate may not say" 'I'm going to
decide this particular issue this way in the future' ").
Second, the Court misportrays the scope of the Clause as applied
to a candidate's discussion of past decisions. Citing an apparent
concession by respondents at argument, id., at 33-34, the
Court concludes that "statements critical of past judicial
decisions are not permissible if the candidate also states that he
is against stare decisis," ante, at 772 (emphasis deleted).
That conclusion, however, draws no force from the meaning
attributed to the Announce Clause by the Eighth Circuit. In line
with the Minnesota Board on Judicial Standards, the Court of
Appeals stated without qualification that the Clause "does not
prohibit candidates from discussing appellate court decisions." 247
F. 3d, at 882 (citing Minn. Bd. on Judicial Standards, Informal
Opinion, Oct. 10, 1990, App. 55 ("In all election contests, a
candidate for judicial office may discuss decisions and opinions of
the Appellate courts.")). The Eighth Circuit's controlling
construction should not be modified by respondents' on the spot
answers to fast-paced hypothetical questions at oral argument. Moose Lodge No. 107 v. Irvis, 407 U. S. 163 , 170 (1972)
("We are loath to attach conclusive weight to the relatively
spontaneous responses of counsel to equally spontaneous questioning
from the Court during oral argument.").
The Announce Clause is thus more tightly bounded, and campaigns
conducted under that provision more robust, than the Court
acknowledges. Judicial candidates in Minnesota may not only convey
general information about themselves, see ante, at 774, they
may also describe their conception of the role of a judge and their
views on a wide range of sub- 811 jects of interest to the voters. See App. 97-103; Brief for
Minnesota State Bar Association as Amicus Curiae 22-23 (e. g., the criteria for deciding whether to depart from
sentencing guidelines, the remedies for racial and gender bias, and
the balance between "free speech rights [and] the need to control
[hate crimes]" (internal quotation marks omitted)). Further, they
may discuss, criticize, or defend past decisions of interest to
voters. What candidates may not do-simply or with sophistication-is
remove themselves from the constraints characteristic of the
judicial office and declare how they would decide an issue, without
regard to the particular context in which it is presented, sans briefs, oral argument, and, as to an appellate bench,
the benefit of one's colleagues' analyses. Properly construed, the
Announce Clause prohibits only a discrete subcategory of the
statements the Court's misinterpretation encompasses.
The Court's characterization of the Announce Clause as
"election-nullifying," ante, at 782, "plac[ing] most
subjects of interest to the voters off limits," ante, at
787, is further belied by the facts of this case. In his 1996 bid
for office, petitioner Gregory Wersal distributed literature
sharply criticizing three Minnesota Supreme Court decisions. Of the
court's holding in the first case-that certain unrecorded
confessions must be suppressed-Wersal asked, "Should we conclude
that because the Supreme Court does not trust police, it allows
confessed criminals to go free?" App. 37. Of the second case,
invalidating a state welfare law, Wersal stated: "The Court should
have deferred to the Legislature. It's the Legislature which should
set our spending policies." Ibid. And of the third case, a
decision involving abortion rights, Wersal charged that the court's
holding was "directly contrary to the opinion of the U. S. Supreme
Court," "unprecedented," and a "pro-abortion stance." Id., at 38.
When a complaint was filed against Wersal on the basis of those
statements, id., at 12-15, the Lawyers Professional
Responsibility Board concluded that no discipline was war- 812 ranted, in part because it thought the disputed campaign
materials did not violate the Announce Clause, id., at
20-21. And when, at the outset of his 1998 campaign, Wersal sought
to avoid the possibility of sanction for future statements, he
pursued the option, available to all Minnesota judicial candidates,
Tr. of Oral Arg. 12-13, of requesting an advisory opinion
concerning the application of the Announce Clause. App. 24-26. In
response to that request, the Board indicated that it did not
anticipate any adverse action against him. Id., at 31-33.2
Wersal has thus never been sanctioned under the Announce Clause for
any campaign statement he made. On the facts before us, in sum, the
Announce Clause has hardly stifled the robust communication of
ideas and views from judicial candidate to voter.
III
Even as it exaggerates the reach of the Announce Clause, the
Court ignores the significance of that provision to the integrated
system of judicial campaign regulation Minnesota has developed.
Coupled with the Announce Clause in Minnesota's Code of Judicial
Conduct is a provision that prohibits candidates from "mak[ing]
pledges or promises of conduct in office other than the faithful
and impartial performance of the duties of the office." Minn. Code
of Judicial Conduct, Canon 5(A)(3)(d)(i) (2002). Although the Court
is correct that this "pledges or promises" provision is not
directly at issue in this case, see ante, at 770, the Court
errs in overlooking the interdependence of that prohibition and the
one before us. In my view, the constitutionality of the
Announce
2 In deciding not to sanction Wersal for his campaign
statements, and again in responding to his inquiry about the
application of the Announce Clause, the Board expressed "doubts
about the constitutionality of the current Minnesota Canon." App.
20; id., at 32. Those doubts, however, concerned the meaning
of the Announce Clause before the Eighth Circuit applied, and the
Minnesota Supreme Court adopted, the limiting constructions that
now define that provision's scope. 813 Clause cannot be resolved without an examination of that
interaction in light of the interests the pledges or promises
provision serves.
A
All parties to this case agree that, whatever the validity of
the Announce Clause, the State may constitutionally prohibit
judicial candidates from pledging or promising certain results. See
Brief for Petitioners Republican Party of Minnesota et al. 36-37;
Tr. of Oral Arg. 14-16 (petitioners' acknowledgment that candidates
may be barred from making a "pledge or promise of an outcome");
Brief for Respondents 11; see also Brief for Brennan Center for
Justice et al. as Amici Curiae 23 ("All of the parties and amici in this case agree that judges should not make
explicit promises or commitments to decide particular cases in a
particular manner.").
The reasons for this agreement are apparent. Pledges or promises
of conduct in office, however commonplace in races for the
political branches, are inconsistent "with the judge's obligation
to decide cases in accordance with his or her role." Tr. of Oral
Arg. 16; see Brief for Petitioners Republican Party of Minnesota et
al. 36 ("[B]ecause [judges] have a duty to decide a case on the
basis of the law and facts before them, they can be prohibited, as
candidates, from making such promises."). This judicial obligation
to avoid prejudgment corresponds to the litigant's right, protected
by the Due Process Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment, to "an
impartial and disinterested tribunal in both civil and criminal
cases," Marshall v. Jerrico, Inc., 446 U. S. 238 , 242
(1980). The proscription against pledges or promises thus
represents an accommodation of "constitutionally protected
interests [that] lie on both sides of the legal equation." Nixon v. Shrink Missouri Government PAC, 528 U. S. 377 , 400 (2000)
(BREYER, J., concurring). Balanced against the candidate's interest
in free expression is the litigant's "powerful and independent
constitutional interest in fair adjudicative procedure." Marshall, 446 U. S., at 243; see Buckley, 997 F.
2d, 814 at 227 ("Two principles are in conflict and must, to the extent
possible, be reconciled .... The roots of both principles lie deep
in our constitutional heritage.").
The impartiality guaranteed to litigants through the Due Process
Clause adheres to a core principle: "[N]o man is permitted to try
cases where he has an interest in the outcome." In re
Murchison, 349 U.
S. 133 , 136 (1955). Our cases have "jealously guarded" that
basic concept, for it "ensur[es] that no person will be deprived of
his interests in the absence of a proceeding in which he may
present his case with assurance that the arbiter is not predisposed
to find against him." Marshall, 446 U. S., at 242.
Applying this principle in Tumey v. Ohio, 273 U. S. 510 (1927), we
held that due process was violated where a judge received a portion
of the fines collected from defendants whom he found guilty. Such
an arrangement, we said, gave the judge a "direct, personal,
substantial[, and] pecuniary interest" in reaching a particular
outcome and thereby denied the defendant his right to an impartial
arbiter. Id., at 523. Ward v. Monroeville, 409 U. S. 57 (1972), extended Tumey's reasoning, holding that due process
was similarly violated where fines collected from guilty defendants
constituted a large part of a village's finances, for which the
judge, who also served as the village mayor, was responsible. Even
though the mayor did not personally share in those fines, we
concluded, he "perforce occupie[d] two practically and seriously
inconsistent positions, one partisan and the other judicial." 409
U. S., at 60 (internal quotation marks omitted).
We applied the principle of Tumey and Ward most
recently in Aetna Life Ins. Co. v. Lavoie, 475 U. S. 813 (1986).
That decision invalidated a ruling of the Alabama Supreme Court
written by a justice who had a personal interest in the resolution
of a dispositive issue. The Alabama Supreme Court's ruling was
issued while the justice was pursuing a separate lawsuit in an
Alabama lower court, and its outcome "had the clear and immediate
effect of enhancing both the legal status 815 and the settlement value" of that separate suit. Id., at
824. As in Ward and Tumey, we held, the justice
therefore had an interest in the outcome of the decision that
unsuited him to participate in the judgment. 475 U. S., at 824. It
mattered not whether the justice was actually influenced by this
interest; "[t]he Due Process Clause," we observed, "may sometimes
bar trial by judges who have no actual bias and who would do their
very best to weigh the scales of justice equally between contending
parties." Id., at 825 (internal quotation marks
omitted).
These cases establish three propositions important to this
dispute. First, a litigant is deprived of due process where the
judge who hears his case has a "direct, personal, substantial, and
pecuniary" interest in ruling against him. Id., at 824
(internal quotation marks and alteration omitted). Second, this
interest need not be as direct as it was in Tumey, where the
judge was essentially compensated for each conviction he obtained;
the interest may stem, as in Ward, from the judge's
knowledge that his success and tenure in office depend on certain
outcomes. "[T]he test," we have said, "is whether the ... situation
is one 'which would offer a possible temptation to the average man
as a judge [that] might lead him not to hold the balance nice,
clear and true.''' Ward, 409 U. S., at 60 (quoting Tumey, 273 U. S., at 532). And third, due process does not
require a showing that the judge is actually biased as a result of
his self-interest. Rather, our cases have "always endeavored to
prevent even the probability of unfairness." In re
Murchison, 349 U. S., at 136. "[T]he requirement of due process
of law in judicial procedure is not satisfied by the argument that
men of the highest honor and the greatest self-sacrifice could
carry it on without danger of injustice." Tumey, 273 U. S.,
at 532.3
3 To avoid the import of our due process decisions, the Court
dissects the concept of judicial "impartiality," ante, at
775-779, concluding that only one variant of that concept-lack of
prejudice against a party-is secured by the Fourteenth
Amendment, ante, at 775-777. Our Due Proc- 816 The justification for the pledges or promises prohibition
follows from these principles. When a judicial candidate promises
to rule a certain way on an issue that may later reach the courts,
the potential for due process violations is grave and manifest. If
successful in her bid for office, the judicial candidate will
become a judge, and in that capacity she will be under pressure to
resist the pleas of litigants who advance positions contrary to her
pledges on the campaign trail. If the judge fails to honor her
campaign promises, she will not only face abandonment by supporters
of her professed views; she will also "ris[k] being assailed as a
dissembler," 247 F. 3d, at 878, willing to say one thing to win an
election and to do the opposite once in office.
A judge in this position therefore may be thought to have a
"direct, personal, substantial, [and] pecuniary interest" in ruling
against certain litigants, Tumey, 273 U. S., at 523, for she
may be voted off the bench and thereby lose her salary and
emoluments unless she honors the pledge that secured her election.
See Shepard, Campaign Speech: Restraint and Liberty in Judicial
Ethics, 9 Geo. J. Legal Ethics 1059, 10831092 (1996); see id., at 1088 ("[A] campaign promise [may be characterized
as] a bribe offered to voters, paid with rulings consistent with
that promise, in return for continued employ-
ess Clause cases do not focus solely on bias against a
particular party, but rather inquire more broadly into whether the
surrounding circumstances and incentives compromise the judge's
ability faithfully to discharge her assigned duties. See supra, at 815. To be sure, due process violations may arise
where a judge has been so personally "enmeshed in matters"
concerning one party that he is biased against him. See Johnson v. Mississippi, 403 U. S. 212 , 215 (1971) (per curiam) (judge had been "a defendant in one of
petitioner's civil rights suits and a losing party at that"). They
may also arise, however, not because of any predisposition toward a
party, but rather because of the judge's personal interest in
resolving an issue a certain way. See Aetna Life Ins. Co. v. Lavoie, 475 U. S. 813 (1986). Due process will not
countenance the latter situation, even though the self-interested
judge "will apply the law to [the losing party] in the same way he
[would apply] it to any other party" advancing the same position, ante, at 776. 817 ment as a judge."); see also The Federalist No. 79, p. 472 (C. Rossiter ed. 1961) ("In the general course of human
nature, a power over a man's subsistence amounts to a power over
his will." (emphasis deleted)).
Given this grave danger to litigants from judicial campaign
promises, States are justified in barring expression of such
commitments, for they typify the "situatio[n] ... in which
experience teaches that the probability of actual bias on the part
of the judge ... is too high to be constitutionally tolerable." Withrow v. Larkin, 421 U. S. 35 , 47 (1975).
By removing this source of "possible temptation" for a judge to
rule on the basis of self-interest, Tumey, 273 U. S., at
532, the pledges or promises prohibition furthers the State's
"compellin[g] interest in maintaining a judiciary fully capable of
performing" its appointed task, Gregory v. Ashcroft,
501 U. S. 452, 472 (1991): "judging [each] particular
controversy fairly on the basis of its own circumstances," United States v. Morgan, 313 U. S. 409 , 421
(1941). See O'Neil, 35 Ind. L. Rev., at 723 ("What is at stake here
is no less than the promise of fairness, impartiality, and
ultimately of due process for those whose lives and fortunes depend
upon judges being selected by means that are not fully subject to
the vagaries of American politics.").
In addition to protecting litigants' due process rights, the
parties in this case further agree, the pledges or promises clause
advances another compelling state interest: preserving the public's
confidence in the integrity and impartiality of its judiciary. See
Tr. of Oral Arg. 16 (petitioners' statement that pledges or
promises properly fosters "public perception of the impartiality of
the judiciary"). See Cox v. Louisiana, 379 U. S. 559 , 565 (1965)
("A State may ... properly protect the judicial process from being
misjudged in the minds of the public."); In re Murchison, 349 U. S., at 136 ("[T]o perform its high function in the best
way[,] 'justice must satisfy the appearance of justice.'" (quoting Offutt v. United States, 348 U. S. 11 , 14 (1954))).
Because courts con- 818 trol neither the purse nor the sword, their authority ultimately
rests on public faith in those who don the robe. See Mistretta v. United States, 488 U. S. 361 , 407 (1989)
("The legitimacy of the Judicial Branch ultimately depends on its
reputation for impartiality and nonpartisanship."). As the
Minnesota Supreme Court has recognized, all legal
systems-regardless of their method of judicial selection-"can
function only so long as the public, having confidence in the
integrity of its judges, accepts and abides by judicial decisions." Complaint Concerning Winton, 350 N. W. 2d 337, 340
(1984).
Prohibiting a judicial candidate from pledging or promising
certain results if elected directly promotes the State's interest
in preserving public faith in the bench. When a candidate makes
such a promise during a campaign, the public will no doubt perceive
that she is doing so in the hope of garnering votes. And the public
will in turn likely conclude that when the candidate decides an
issue in accord with that promise, she does so at least in part to
discharge her undertaking to the voters in the previous election
and to prevent voter abandonment in the next. The perception of
that unseemly quid pro quo-a judicial candidate's promises
on issues in return for the electorate's votes at the
polls-inevitably diminishes the public's faith in the ability of
judges to administer the law without regard to personal or
political self-interest.4 Then-JusTICE REHNQUIST'S observations
4 The author of the Court's opinion declined on precisely these
grounds to tell the Senate whether he would overrule a particular
case:
"Let us assume that I have people arguing before me to do it or
not to do it. I think it is quite a thing to be arguing to somebody
who you know has made a representation in the course of his
confirmation hearings, and that is, by way of condition to his
being confirmed, that he will do this or do that. I think I would
be in a very bad position to adjudicate the case without being
accused of having a less than impartial view of the matter." 13 R.
Mersky & J. Jacobstein, The Supreme Court of the United
States:
Hearings and Reports on Successful and Unsuccessful Nominations
of Supreme Court Justices by the Senate Judiciary Committee,
1916-1986, 819 about the federal system apply with equal if not greater force
in the context of Minnesota's elective judiciary: Regarding the
appearance of judicial integrity, "[one must] distinguish quite sharply between a public statement
made prior to nomination for the bench, on the one hand, and a
public statement made by a nominee to the bench. For the latter to
express any but the most general observation about the law would
suggest that, in order to obtain favorable consideration of his
nomination, he deliberately was announcing in advance, without
benefit of judicial oath, briefs, or argument, how he would decide
a particular question that might come before him as a judge." Laird v. Tatum, 409 U. S. 824 , 836, n. 5
(1972) (memorandum opinion). B
The constitutionality of the pledges or promises clause is thus
amply supported; the provision not only advances due process of law
for litigants in Minnesota courts, it also reinforces the authority
of the Minnesota judiciary by promoting public confidence in the
State's judges. The Announce Clause, however, is equally vital to
achieving these compelling ends, for without it, the pledges or
promises provision would be feeble, an arid form, a matter of no
real importance.
Uncoupled from the Announce Clause, the ban on pledges or
promises is easily circumvented. By prefacing a campaign commitment
with the caveat, "although I cannot promise anything," or by simply
avoiding the language of promises or pledges altogether, a
candidate could declare with impunity how she would decide specific
issues. Semantic sanitizing of the candidate's commitment would
not, however, diminish its pernicious effects on actual and
perceived judicial impartiality. To use the Court's example, a
candidate
p. 131 (1989) (hearings before the Senate Judiciary Committee on
the nomination of then-Judge Scalia). 820 who campaigns by saying, "If elected, I will vote to uphold the
legislature's power to prohibit same-sex marriages," ante, at 780, will feel scarcely more pressure to honor that statement
than the candidate who stands behind a podium and tells a throng of
cheering supporters: "I think it is constitutional for the
legislature to prohibit same-sex marriages," ante, at 779.
Made during a campaign, both statements contemplate a quid pro
quo between candidate and voter. Both effectively "bind [the
candidate] to maintain that position after election." Ante, at 770. And both convey the impression of a candidate prejudging an
issue to win votes. Contrary to the Court's assertion, the
"nonpromissory" statement averts none of the dangers posed by the
"promissory" one. See ante, at 780-781 (emphasis
deleted).
By targeting statements that do not technically constitute
pledges or promises but nevertheless "publicly mak[e] known how
[the candidate] would decide" legal issues, 247 F. 3d, at 881-882,
the Announce Clause prevents this end run around the letter and
spirit of its companion provision.5 No less than the pledges or
promises clause itself, the Announce
5 In the absence of the Announce Clause, other components of the
Minnesota Code of Judicial Conduct designed to maintain the
nonpartisan character of the State's judicial elections would
similarly unravel. A candidate would have no need to "attend
political gatherings" or "make speeches on behalf of a political
organization," Minn. Code of Judical Conduct, Canon 5(A)(1)(c), (d)
(2002), for she could simply state her views elsewhere, counting on
her supporters to carry those views to the party faithful. And
although candidates would remain barred from "seek[ing],
accept[ing,] or us[ing] endorsements from a political
organization," Canon 5(A)(1)(d), parties might well provide such
endorsements unsolicited upon hearing candidates' views on specific
issues. Cf. ante, at 770 (Minnesota Republican Party sought
to learn Wersal's views so party could support or oppose his
candidacy). Those unsolicited endorsements, in turn, would render
ineffective the prohibition against candidates "identify[ing]
themselves as members of a political organization," Canon
5(A)(1)(a). "Indeed, it is not too much to say that the entire
fabric of Minnesota's non[p]artisan elections hangs by the Announce
clause thread." Brief for Minnesota State Bar Association as Amicus Curiae 20. 821 Clause is an indispensable part of Minnesota's effort to
maintain the health of its judiciary, and is therefore
constitutional for the same reasons.
***
This Court has recognized in the past, as JUSTICE O'CONNOR does
today, see ante, at 788-790 (concurring opinion), a
"fundamental tension between the ideal character of the judicial
office and the real world of electoral politics," Chisom, 501 U. S., at 400. We have no warrant to resolve that tension,
however, by forcing States to choose one pole or the other. Judges
are not politicians, and the First Amendment does not require that
they be treated as politicians simply because they are chosen by
popular vote. Nor does the First Amendment command States that wish
to promote the integrity of their judges in fact and appearance to
abandon systems of judicial selection that the people, in the
exercise of their sovereign prerogatives, have devised.
For more than three-quarters of a century, States like Minnesota
have endeavored, through experiment tested by experience, to
balance the constitutional interests in judicial integrity and free
expression within the unique setting of an elected judiciary. P.
McFadden, Electing Justice: The Law and Ethics of Judicial Election
Campaigns 86 (1990); Brief for the Conference of Chief Justices as Amicus Curiae 5. The Announce Clause, borne of this long
effort, "comes to this Court bearing a weighty title of respect," Teamsters v. Hanke, 339 U. S. 470 , 475
(1950). I would uphold it as an essential component in Minnesota's
accommodation of the complex and competing concerns in this
sensitive area. Accordingly, I would affirm the judgment of the
Court of Appeals for the Eighth Circuit. | The Minnesota Supreme Court's canon of judicial conduct, which prohibits candidates from announcing their views on disputed legal or political issues, violates the First Amendment. The canon restricts speech based on content and burdens core political speech about candidate qualifications. While impartiality is an important judicial value, the canon is not narrowly tailored to achieve this goal as it restricts speech on specific issues rather than bias towards parties. The canon also fails to serve a compelling state interest as it is impossible to find judges without preconceived legal views, and judicial integrity can be maintained through other means such as recusal. |
Free Speech | Snyder v. Phelps | https://supreme.justia.com/cases/federal/us/562/443/ | OPINION OF THE COURT SNYDER V. PHELPS 562 U. S. ____ (2011) SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES NO. 09-751 ALBERT SNYDER, PETITIONER v. FRED W.
PHELPS, SR., et al.
on writ of certiorari to the united states court of
appeals for the fourth circuit
[March 2, 2011]
Chief Justice Roberts delivered
the opinion of the Court.
A jury held members of the
Westboro Baptist Church liable for millions of dollars in damages
for picketing near a soldier’s funeral service. The picket signs
reflected the church’s view that the United States is overly
tolerant of sin and that God kills American soldiers as punishment.
The question presented is whether the First Amendment shields the
church members from tort liability for their speech in this
case.
I
A
Fred Phelps founded the Westboro
Baptist Church in Topeka, Kansas, in 1955. The church’s
congregation believes that God hates and punishes the United States
for its tolerance of homosexuality, particularly in America’s
military. The church frequently communicates its views by
picketing, often at military funerals. In the more than 20 years
that the members of Westboro Baptist have publicized their message,
they have picketed nearly 600 funerals. Brief for Rutherford
Institute as Amicus Curiae 7, n. 14.
Marine Lance Corporal Matthew
Snyder was killed in Iraq in the line of duty. Lance Corporal
Snyder’s father selected the Catholic church in the Snyders’
hometown of Westminster, Maryland, as the site for his son’s
funeral. Local newspapers provided notice of the time and location
of the service.
Phelps became aware of Matthew Snyder’s
funeral and decided to travel to Maryland with six other Westboro
Baptist parishioners (two of his daughters and four of his
grandchildren) to picket. On the day of the memorial service, the
Westboro congregation members picketed on public land adjacent to
public streets near the Maryland State House, the United States
Naval Academy, and Matthew Snyder’s funeral. The Westboro picketers
carried signs that were largely the same at all three locations.
They stated, for instance: “God Hates the USA/Thank God for 9/11,”
“America is Doomed,” “Don’t Pray for the USA,” “Thank God for
IEDs,” “Thank God for Dead Soldiers,” “Pope in Hell,” “Priests Rape
Boys,” “God Hates Fags,” “You’re Going to Hell,” and “God Hates
You.”
The church had notified the authorities in
advance of its intent to picket at the time of the funeral, and the
picketers complied with police instructions in staging their
demonstration. The picketing took place within a 10- by 25-foot
plot of public land adjacent to a public street, behind a temporary
fence. App. to Brief for Appellants in No. 08–1026 (CA4),
pp. 2282–2285 (hereinafter App.). That plot was approximately
1,000 feet from the church where the funeral was held. Several
buildings separated the picket site from the church. Id .,
at 3758. The Westboro picketers displayed their signs for about 30
minutes before the funeral began and sang hymns and recited Bible
verses. None of the picketers entered church property or went to
the cemetery. They did not yell or use profanity, and there was no
violence associated with the picketing. Id ., at 2168,
2371, 2286, 2293.
The funeral procession passed within 200 to
300 feet of the picket site. Although Snyder testified that he
could see the tops of the picket signs as he drove to the funeral,
he did not see what was written on the signs until later that
night, while watching a news broadcast covering the event. Id. , at 2084–2086.[ Footnote 1 ]
B
Snyder filed suit against Phelps,
Phelps’s daughters, and the Westboro Baptist Church (collectively
Westboro or the church) in the United States District Court for the
District of Maryland under that court’s diversity jurisdiction.
Snyder alleged five state tort law claims: defamation, publicity
given to private life, intentional infliction of emotional
distress, intrusion upon seclusion, and civil conspiracy. Westboro
moved for summary judgment contending, in part, that the church’s
speech was insulated from liability by the First Amendment. See 533
F. Supp. 2d 567, 570 (Md. 2008).
The District Court awarded
Westboro summary judgment on Snyder’s claims for defamation and
publicity given to private life, concluding that Snyder could not
prove the necessary elements of those torts. Id., at
572–573. A trial was held on the remaining claims. At trial, Snyder
described the severity of his emotional injuries. He testified that
he is unable to separate the thought of his dead son from his
thoughts of Westboro’s picketing, and that he often becomes
tearful, angry, and physically ill when he thinks about it. Id., at 588–589. Expert witnesses testified that Snyder’s
emotional anguish had resulted in severe depression and had
exacerbated pre-existing health conditions.
A jury found for Snyder on the intentional
infliction of emotional distress, intrusion upon seclusion, and
civil conspiracy claims, and held Westboro liable for $2.9 million
in compensatory damages and $8 million in punitive damages.
Westboro filed several post-trial motions, including a motion
contending that the jury verdict was grossly excessive and a motion
seeking judgment as a matter of law on all claims on First
Amendment grounds. The District Court remitted the punitive damages
award to $2.1 million, but left the jury verdict otherwise intact. Id., at 597.
In the Court of Appeals, Westboro’s primary
argument was that the church was entitled to judgment as a matter
of law because the First Amendment fully protected Westboro’s
speech. The Court of Appeals agreed. 580 F. 3d 206, 221 (CA4
2009). The court reviewed the picket signs and concluded that
Westboro’s statements were entitled to First Amendment protection
because those statements were on matters of public concern, were
not provably false, and were expressed solely through hyperbolic
rhetoric. Id. , at 222–224.[ Footnote 2 ]
We granted certiorari. 559 U. S. ___
(2010).
II
To succeed on a claim for
intentional infliction of emotional distress in Maryland, a
plaintiff must demonstrate that the defendant intentionally or
recklessly engaged in extreme and outrageous conduct that caused
the plaintiff to suffer severe emotional distress. See Harris v. Jones , 281 Md. 560, 565–566, 380
A. 2d 611, 614 (1977). The Free Speech Clause of the First
Amendment—“Congress shall make no law … abridging the freedom of
speech”—can serve as a defense in state tort suits, including suits
for intentional infliction of emotional distress. See, e.g., Hustler Magazine, Inc. v. Falwell , 485 U. S. 46 ,
50–51 (1988).[ Footnote 3 ]
Whether the First Amendment
prohibits holding Westboro liable for its speech in this case turns
largely on whether that speech is of public or private concern, as
determined by all the circumstances of the case. “[S]peech on
‘matters of public concern’ … is ‘at the heart of the First
Amendment’s protection.’ ” Dun & Bradstreet, Inc. v. Greenmoss Builders, Inc. , 472 U. S. 749 , 758–759
(1985) (opinion of Powell, J.) (quoting First Nat. Bank of
Boston v. Bellotti , 435 U. S. 765 , 776
(1978)). The First Amendment reflects “a profound national
commitment to the principle that debate on public issues should be
uninhibited, robust, and wide-open.” New York Times Co. v. Sullivan , 376 U. S. 254 , 270
(1964). That is because “speech concerning public affairs is more
than self-expression; it is the essence of self-government.” Garrison v. Louisiana , 379 U. S. 64 , 74–75
(1964). Accordingly, “speech on public issues occupies the highest
rung of the hierarchy of First Amendment values, and is entitled to
special protection.” Connick v. Myers , 461 U. S. 138 , 145
(1983) (internal quotation marks omitted).
“ ‘[N]ot all speech is of equal First
Amendment importance,’ ” however, and where matters of purely
private significance are at issue, First Amendment protections are
often less rigorous. Hustler , supra, at 56
(quoting Dun & Bradstreet , supra, at 758);
see Connick , supra, at 145–147. That is because
restricting speech on purely private matters does not implicate the
same constitutional concerns as limiting speech on matters of
public interest: “[T]here is no threat to the free and robust
debate of public issues; there is no potential interference with a
meaningful dialogue of ideas”; and the “threat of liability” does
not pose the risk of “a reaction of self-censorship” on matters of
public import. Dun & Bradstreet , supra, at
760 (internal quotation marks omitted).
We noted a short time ago, in considering
whether public employee speech addressed a matter of public
concern, that “the boundaries of the public concern test are not
well defined.” San Diego v. Roe , 543 U. S. 77 , 83 (2004)
( per curiam ). Although that remains true today, we have
articulated some guiding principles, principles that accord broad
protection to speech to ensure that courts themselves do not become
inadvertent censors.
Speech deals with matters of public concern
when it can “be fairly considered as relating to any matter of
politi- cal, social, or other concern to the community,” Connick , supra, at 146, or when it “is a subject
of legitimate news interest; that is, a subject of general interest
and of value and concern to the public,” San Diego , supra, at 83–84. See Cox Broadcasting Corp. v. Cohn , 420
U. S. 469 , 492–494 (1975); Time, Inc. v. Hill , 385
U. S. 374 , 387– 388 (1967). The arguably “inappropriate or
controversial character of a statement is irrelevant to the
question whether it deals with a matter of public concern.” Rankin v. McPherson , 483 U. S. 378 , 387
(1987).
Our opinion in Dun & Bradstreet ,
on the other hand, provides an example of speech of only private
concern. In that case we held, as a general matter, that
information about a particular individual’s credit report “concerns
no public issue.” 472 U. S., at 762. The content of the report, we
explained, “was speech solely in the individual interest of the
speaker and its specific business audience.” Ibid. That
was confirmed by the fact that the particular report was sent to
only five subscribers to the reporting service, who were bound not
to disseminate it further. Ibid. To cite another example,
we concluded in San Diego v. Roe that, in the
context of a government employer regulating the speech of its
employees, videos of an employee engaging in sexually explicit acts
did not address a public concern; the videos “did nothing to inform
the public about any aspect of the [employing agency’s] functioning
or operation.” 543 U. S., at 84.
Deciding whether speech is of public or
private concern requires us to examine the “ ‘content, form,
and context’ ” of that speech, “ ‘as revealed by the
whole record.’ ” Dun & Bradstreet , supra, at 761 (quoting Connick , supra, at 147–148). As in other First Amendment cases, the court is
obligated “to ‘make an independent examination of the whole record’
in order to make sure that ‘the judgment does not constitute a
forbidden intrusion on the field of free expression.’ ” Bose Corp. v. Consumers Union of United States,
Inc. , 466 U. S.
485 , 499 (1984) (quoting New York Times , supra, at 284–286). In considering content, form, and
context, no factor is dispositive, and it is necessary to evaluate
all the circumstances of the speech, including what was said, where
it was said, and how it was said.
The “content” of Westboro’s signs plainly
relates to broad issues of interest to society at large, rather
than matters of “purely private concern.” Dun &
Bradstreet , supra, at 759. The placards read “God
Hates the USA/Thank God for 9/11,” “America is Doomed,” “Don’t Pray
for the USA,” “Thank God for IEDs,” “Fag Troops,” “Semper Fi Fags,”
“God Hates Fags,” “Maryland Taliban,” “Fags Doom Nations,” “Not
Blessed Just Cursed,” “Thank God for Dead Soldiers,” “Pope in
Hell,” “Priests Rape Boys,” “You’re Going to Hell,” and “God Hates
You.” App. 3781–3787. While these messages may fall short of
refined social or political commentary, the issues they
highlight—the political and moral conduct of the United States and
its citizens, the fate of our Nation, homosexuality in the
military, and scandals involving the Catholic clergy—are matters of
public import. The signs certainly convey Westboro’s position on
those issues, in a manner designed, unlike the private speech in Dun & Bradstreet , to reach as broad a public audience
as possible. And even if a few of the signs—such as “You’re Going
to Hell” and “God Hates You”—were viewed as containing messages
related to Matthew Snyder or the Snyders specifically, that would
not change the fact that the overall thrust and dominant theme of
Westboro’s demonstration spoke to broader public issues.
Apart from the content of Westboro’s signs,
Snyder contends that the “context” of the speech—its connection
with his son’s funeral—makes the speech a matter of private rather
than public concern. The fact that Westboro spoke in connection
with a funeral, however, cannot by itself transform the nature of
Westboro’s speech. Westboro’s signs, displayed on public land next
to a public street, reflect the fact that the church finds much to
condemn in modern society. Its speech is “fairly characterized as
constituting speech on a matter of public concern,” Connick , 461 U. S., at 146, and the funeral setting does
not alter that conclusion.
Snyder argues that the church members in fact
mounted a personal attack on Snyder and his family, and then
attempted to “immunize their conduct by claiming that they were
actually protesting the United States’ tolerance of homosexuality
or the supposed evils of the Catholic Church.” Reply Brief for
Petitioner 10. We are not concerned in this case that Westboro’s
speech on public matters was in any way contrived to insulate
speech on a private matter from liability. Westboro had been
actively engaged in speaking on the subjects addressed in its
picketing long before it became aware of Matthew Snyder, and there
can be no serious claim that Westboro’s picketing did not represent
its “honestly believed” views on public issues. Garrison ,
379 U. S., at 73. There was no pre-existing relationship or
conflict between Westboro and Snyder that might suggest Westboro’s
speech on public matters was intended to mask an attack on Snyder
over a private matter. Contrast Connick , supra, at 153 (finding public employee speech a matter of private concern
when it was “no coincidence that [the speech] followed upon the
heels of [a] transfer notice” affecting the employee).
Snyder goes on to argue that Westboro’s speech
should be afforded less than full First Amendment protection “not
only because of the words” but also because the church members
exploited the funeral “as a platform to bring their message to a
broader audience.” Brief for Petitioner 44, 40. There is no doubt
that Westboro chose to stage its picketing at the Naval Academy,
the Maryland State House, and Matthew Snyder’s funeral to increase
publicity for its views and because of the relation between those
sites and its views—in the case of the military funeral, because
Westboro believes that God is killing American soldiers as
punishment for the Nation’s sinful policies.
Westboro’s choice to convey its views in
conjunction with Matthew Snyder’s funeral made the expression of
those views particularly hurtful to many, especially to Matthew’s
father. The record makes clear that the applicable legal
term—“emotional distress”—fails to capture fully the anguish
Westboro’s choice added to Mr. Snyder’s already incalculable grief.
But Westboro conducted its picketing peacefully on matters of
public concern at a public place adjacent to a public street. Such
space occupies a “special position in terms of First Amendment
protection.” United States v. Grace , 461 U. S. 171 , 180
(1983). “[W]e have repeatedly referred to public streets as the
archetype of a traditional public forum,” noting that
“ ‘[t]ime out of mind’ public streets and sidewalks have been
used for public assembly and debate.” Frisby v. Schultz , 487 U. S. 474 , 480
(1988).[ Footnote 4 ]
That said, “[e]ven protected speech is not
equally permissible in all places and at all times.” Id., at 479 (quoting Cornelius v. NAACP Legal Defense &
Ed. Fund, Inc. , 473 U. S. 788 , 799
(1985)). Westboro’s choice of where and when to conduct its
picketing is not beyond the Government’s regulatory reach—it is
“subject to reasonable time, place, or manner restrictions” that
are consistent with the standards announced in this Court’s
precedents. Clark v. Community for Creative
Non-Violence , 468 U. S. 288 , 293
(1984). Maryland now has a law imposing restrictions on funeral
picketing, Md. Crim. Law Code Ann. §10–205 (Lexis Supp. 2010), as
do 43 other States and the Federal Government. See Brief for
American Legion as Amicus Curiae 18–19, n. 2 (listing
statutes). To the extent these laws are content neutral, they raise
very different questions from the tort verdict at issue in this
case. Maryland’s law, however, was not in effect at the time of the
events at issue here, so we have no occasion to consider how it
might apply to facts such as those before us, or whether it or
other similar regulations are constitutional.[ Footnote 5 ]
We have identified a few limited situations
where the location of targeted picketing can be regulated under
provisions that the Court has determined to be content neutral. In Frisby , for example, we upheld a ban on such picketing
“before or about” a particular residence, 487 U. S., at 477. In Madsen v. Women’s Health Center, Inc. , we
approved an injunction requiring a buffer zone between protesters
and an abortion clinic entrance. 512 U. S. 753 , 768
(1994). The facts here are obviously quite different, both with
respect to the activity being regulated and the means of
restricting those activities.
Simply put, the church members had the right
to be where they were. Westboro alerted local authorities to its
funeral protest and fully complied with police guidance on where
the picketing could be staged. The picketing was conducted under
police supervision some 1,000 feet from the church, out of the
sight of those at the church. The protest was not unruly; there was
no shouting, profanity, or violence.
The record confirms that any distress
occasioned by Westboro’s picketing turned on the content and
viewpoint of the message conveyed, rather than any interference
with the funeral itself. A group of parishioners standing at the
very spot where Westboro stood, holding signs that said “God Bless
America” and “God Loves You,” would not have been subjected to
liability. It was what Westboro said that exposed it to tort
damages.
Given that Westboro’s speech was at a public
place on a matter of public concern, that speech is entitled to
“special protection” under the First Amendment. Such speech cannot
be restricted simply because it is upsetting or arouses contempt.
“If there is a bedrock principle underlying the First Amendment, it
is that the government may not prohibit the expression of an idea
simply because society finds the idea itself offensive or
disagreeable.” Texas v. Johnson , 491 U. S. 397 , 414
(1989). Indeed, “the point of all speech protection … is to shield
just those choices of content that in someone’s eyes are misguided,
or even hurtful.” Hurley v. Irish-American Gay,
Lesbian and Bisexual Group of Boston, Inc. , 515 U. S. 557 , 574
(1995).
The jury here was instructed that it could
hold Westboro liable for intentional infliction of emotional
distress based on a finding that Westboro’s picketing was
“outrageous.” “Outrageousness,” however, is a highly malleable
standard with “an inherent subjectiveness about it which would
allow a jury to impose liability on the basis of the jurors’ tastes
or views, or perhaps on the basis of their dislike of a particular
expression.” Hustler , 485 U. S., at 55 (internal quotation
marks omitted). In a case such as this, a jury is “unlikely to be
neutral with respect to the content of [the] speech,” posing “a
real danger of becoming an instrument for the suppression of …
‘vehement, caustic, and sometimes unpleasan[t]’ ” expression. Bose Corp. , 466 U. S., at 510 (quoting New York
Times , 376 U. S., at 270). Such a risk is unacceptable; “in
public debate [we] must tolerate insulting, and even outrageous,
speech in order to provide adequate ‘breathing space’ to the
freedoms protected by the First Amendment.” Boos v. Barry , 485
U. S. 312 , 322 (1988) (some internal quotation marks omitted).
What Westboro said, in the whole context of how and where it chose
to say it, is entitled to “special protection” under the First
Amendment, and that protection cannot be overcome by a jury finding
that the picketing was outrageous.
For all these reasons, the jury verdict
imposing tort liability on Westboro for intentional infliction of
emotional distress must be set aside.
III
The jury also found Westboro
liable for the state law torts of intrusion upon seclusion and
civil conspiracy. The Court of Appeals did not examine these torts
independently of the intentional infliction of emotional distress
tort. Instead, the Court of Appeals reversed the District Court
wholesale, holding that the judgment wrongly “attache[d] tort
liability to constitutionally protected speech.” 580 F. 3d, at
226.
Snyder argues that even assuming
Westboro’s speech is entitled to First Amendment protection
generally, the church is not immunized from liability for intrusion
upon seclusion because Snyder was a member of a captive audience at
his son’s funeral. Brief for Petitioner 45–46. We do not agree. In
most circumstances, “the Constitution does not permit the
government to decide which types of otherwise protected speech are
sufficiently offensive to require protection for the unwilling
listener or viewer. Rather, … the burden normally falls upon the
viewer to avoid further bombardment of [his] sensibilities simply
by averting [his] eyes.” Erznoznik v. Jacksonville , 422 U. S. 205 , 210–211
(1975) (internal quotation marks omitted). As a result, “[t]he
ability of government, consonant with the Constitution, to shut off
discourse solely to protect others from hearing it is … dependent
upon a showing that substantial privacy interests are being invaded
in an essentially intolerable manner.” Cohen v. California , 403 U. S. 15 , 21
(1971).
As a general matter, we have applied the
captive audience doctrine only sparingly to protect unwilling
listeners from protected speech. For example, we have upheld a
statute allowing a homeowner to restrict the delivery of offensive
mail to his home, see Rowan v. Post Office Dept. , 397 U. S. 728 ,
736–738 (1970), and an ordinance prohibiting picketing “before or
about” any individual’s residence, Frisby , 487 U. S., at
484–485.
Here, Westboro stayed well away from the
memorial service. Snyder could see no more than the tops of the
signs when driving to the funeral. And there is no indication that
the picketing in any way interfered with the funeral service
itself. We decline to expand the captive audience doctrine to the
circumstances presented here.
Because we find that the First Amendment bars
Snyder from recovery for intentional infliction of emotional
distress or intrusion upon seclusion—the alleged unlawful activity
Westboro conspired to accomplish—we must likewise hold that Snyder
cannot recover for civil conspiracy based on those torts.
IV
Our holding today is narrow. We
are required in First Amendment cases to carefully review the
record, and the reach of our opinion here is limited by the
particular facts before us. As we have noted, “the sensitivity and
significance of the interests presented in clashes between First
Amendment and [state law] rights counsel relying on limited
principles that sweep no more broadly than the appropriate context
of the instant case.” Florida Star v. B. J. F. , 491 U. S. 524 , 533
(1989).
Westboro believes that America is
morally flawed; many Americans might feel the same about Westboro.
Westboro’s funeral picketing is certainly hurtful and its
con-tribution to public discourse may be negligible. But Westboro
addressed matters of public import on public property, in a
peaceful manner, in full compliance with the guidance of local
officials. The speech was indeed planned to coincide with Matthew
Snyder’s funeral, but did not itself disrupt that funeral, and
Westboro’s choice to conduct its picketing at that time and place
did not alter the nature of its speech.
Speech is powerful. It can stir people to
action, move them to tears of both joy and sorrow, and—as it did
here—inflict great pain. On the facts before us, we cannot react to
that pain by punishing the speaker. As a Nation we have chosen a
different course—to protect even hurtful speech on public issues to
ensure that we do not stifle public debate. That choice requires
that we shield Westboro from tort liability for its picketing in
this case.
The judgment of the United States Court of
Appeals for the Fourth Circuit is affirmed.
It is so ordered. Footnote 1 A few weeks after the funeral, one of the
picketers posted a message on Westboro’s Web site discussing the
picketing and containing religiously oriented denunciations of the
Snyders, interspersed among lengthy Bible quotations. Snyder
discovered the posting, referred to by the parties as the “epic,”
during an Internet search for his son’s name. The epic is not
properly before us and does not factor in our analysis. Although
the epic was submitted to the jury and discussed in the courts
below, Snyder never mentioned it in his petition for certiorari.
See Pet. for Cert. i (“Snyder’s claim arose out of Phelps’
intentional acts at Snyder’s son’s funeral ” (emphasis
added)); this Court’s Rule 14.1(g) (petition must contain statement
“setting out the facts material to consideration of the question
presented”). Nor did Snyder respond to the statement in the
opposition to certiorari that “[t]hough the epic was asserted as a
basis for the claims at trial, the petition … appears to be
addressing only claims based on the picketing.” Brief in Opposition
9. Snyder devoted only one paragraph in the argument section of his
opening merits brief to the epic. Given the foregoing and the fact
that an Internet posting may raise distinct issues in this context,
we decline to consider the epic in deciding this case. See Ontario v. Quon , 560 U. S. ___,
___ – ___ (2010) (slip op., at 10–12). Footnote 2 One judge concurred in the judgment on the
ground that Snyder had failed to introduce sufficient evidence at
trial to support a jury verdict on any of his tort claims. 580
F. 3d, at 227 (opinion of Shedd, J.). The Court of Appeals
majority determined that the picketers had “voluntarily waived” any
such contention on appeal. Id., at 216. Like the court
below, we proceed on the unexamined premise that respondents’
speech was tortious. Footnote 3 The dissent attempts to draw parallels
between this case and hy-pothetical cases involving defamation or
fighting words. Post , at 10–11 (opinion of
Alito, J.). But, as the court below noted, there is “no
suggestion that the speech at issue falls within one of the
categorical exclusions from First Amendment protection, such as
those for obscenity or ‘fighting words.’ ” 580 F. 3d, at
218, n. 12; see United States v. Stevens ,
559 U. S. ___ , ___ (2010) (slip op., at 5). Footnote 4 The dissent is wrong to suggest that the
Court considers a public street “a free-fire zone in which
otherwise actionable verbal attacks are shielded from liability.” Post , at 10–11. The fact that Westboro conducted its
picketing adjacent to a public street does not insulate the speech
from liability, but instead heightens concerns that what is at
issue is an effort to communicate to the public the church’s views
on matters of public concern. That is why our precedents so clearly
recognize the special significance of this traditional public
forum. Footnote 5 The Maryland law prohibits picketing within
100 feet of a funeral service or funeral procession; Westboro’s
picketing would have complied with that restriction. BREYER, J., CONCURRING SNYDER V. PHELPS 562 U. S. ____ (2011) SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES NO. 09-751 ALBERT SNYDER, PETITIONER v. FRED W.
PHELPS, Sr., et al.
on writ of certiorari to the united states court of
appeals for the fourth circuit
[March 2, 2011]
Justice Breyer, concurring.
I agree with the Court and join
its opinion. That opinion restricts its analysis here to the matter
raised in the petition for certiorari, namely, Westboro’s picketing
activity. The opinion does not examine in depth the effect of
television broadcasting. Nor does it say anything about Internet
postings. The Court holds that the First Amendment protects the
picketing that occurred here, primarily because the picketing
addressed matters of “public concern.”
While I agree with the Court’s conclusion that
the picketing addressed matters of public concern, I do not believe
that our First Amendment analysis can stop at that point. A State
can sometimes regulate picketing, even picketing on matters of
public concern. See Frisby v. Schultz , 487 U. S. 474 (1988).
Moreover, suppose that A were physically to assault B, knowing that
the assault (being newsworthy) would provide A with an opportunity
to transmit to the public his views on a matter of public concern.
The constitutionally protected nature of the end would not shield
A’s use of unlawful, unprotected means. And in some circumstances
the use of certain words as means would be similarly unprotected.
See Chaplinsky v. New Hampshire , 315 U. S. 568 (1942)
(“fighting words”).
The dissent recognizes that the means used
here consist of speech. But it points out that the speech, like an
assault, seriously harmed a private individual. Indeed, the state
tort of “intentional infliction of emotional distress” forbids only
conduct that produces distress “so severe that no reasonable man
could be expected to endure it,” and which itself is “so outrageous
in character, and so extreme in degree, as to go beyond all
possible bounds of decency, and to be regarded as atrocious, and
utterly intolerable in a civilized community.” Post , at
2–3 (opinion of Alito, J.) (quoting Harris v. Jones , 281 Md. 560, 567, 571, 380 A. 2d 611, 614, 616
(1977); internal quotation marks omitted) . The dissent
requires us to ask whether our holding unreasonably limits
liability for intentional infliction of emotional distress—to the
point where A (in order to draw attention to his views on a public
matter) might launch a verbal assault upon B, a private person,
publicly revealing the most intimate details of B’s private life,
while knowing that the revelation will cause B severe emotional
harm. Does our decision leave the State powerless to protect the
individual against invasions of, e.g. , personal privacy,
even in the most horrendous of such circumstances?
As I understand the Court’s opinion, it does
not hold or imply that the State is always powerless to provide
private individuals with necessary protection. Rather, the Court
has reviewed the underlying facts in detail, as will sometimes
prove necessary where First Amendment values and state-protected
(say, privacy-related) interests seriously conflict. Cf. Florida Star v. B. J. F. , 491 U. S. 524 , 533
(1989); Bose Corp. v. Consumers Union of United
States, Inc. , 466 U. S. 485 , 499
(1984). That review makes clear that Westboro’s means of
communicating its views consisted of picketing in a place where
picketing was lawful and in compliance with all police directions.
The picketing could not be seen or heard from the funeral ceremony
itself. And Snyder testified that he saw no more than the tops of
the picketers’ signs as he drove to the funeral. To uphold the
application of state law in these circumstances would punish
Westboro for seeking to communicate its views on matters of public
concern without proportionately advancing the State’s interest in
protecting its citizens against severe emotional harm.
Consequently, the First Amendment protects Westboro. As I read the
Court’s opinion, it holds no more. ALITO, J., DISSENTING SNYDER V. PHELPS 562 U. S. ____ (2011) SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES NO. 09-751 ALBERT SNYDER, PETITIONER v. FRED W.
PHELPS, Sr., et al.
on writ of certiorari to the united states court of
appeals for the fourth circuit
[March 2, 2011]
Justice Alito, dissenting.
Our profound national commitment
to free and open debate is not a license for the vicious verbal
assault that occurred in this case.
Petitioner Albert Snyder is not a public
figure. He is simply a parent whose son, Marine Lance Corporal
Matthew Snyder, was killed in Iraq. Mr. Snyder wanted what is
surely the right of any parent who experiences such an incalculable
loss: to bury his son in peace. But respondents, members of the
Westboro Baptist Church, deprived him of that elementary right.
They first issued a press release and thus turned Matthew’s funeral
into a tumultuous media event. They then appeared at the church,
approached as closely as they could without trespassing, and
launched a malevolent verbal attack on Matthew and his family at a
time of acute emotional vulnerability. As a result, Albert Snyder
suffered severe and lasting emotional injury.[ Footnote 1 ] The Court now holds that the First
Amendment protected respondents’ right to brutalize Mr. Snyder. I
cannot agree.
I
Respondents and other members of
their church have strong opinions on certain moral, religious, and
political issues, and the First Amendment ensures that they have
almost limitless opportunities to express their views. They may
write and distribute books, articles, and other texts; they may
create and disseminate video and audio recordings; they may
circulate petitions; they may speak to individuals and groups in
public forums and in any private venue that wishes to accommodate
them; they may picket peacefully in countless locations; they may
appear on television and speak on the radio; they may post messages
on the Internet and send out e-mails. And they may express their
views in terms that are “uninhibited,” “vehement,” and “caustic.” New York Times Co. v. Sullivan , 376 U. S. 254 , 270
(1964).
It does not follow, however, that
they may intentionally inflict severe emotional injury on private
persons at a time of intense emotional sensitivity by launching
vicious verbal attacks that make no contribution to public debate.
To protect against such injury, “most if not all jurisdictions”
permit recovery in tort for the intentional infliction of emotional
distress (or IIED). Hustler Magazine , Inc. v. Falwell , 485 U. S. 46 , 53 (1988).
This is a very narrow tort with requirements
that “are rigorous, and difficult to satisfy.” W. Keeton, D. Dobbs,
R. Keeton, & D. Owen, Prosser and Keeton on Law of Torts §12,
p. 61 (5th ed. 1984). To recover, a plaintiff must show that the
conduct at issue caused harm that was truly severe. See Figueiredo-Torres v. Nickel , 321 Md. 642, 653,
584 A. 2d 69, 75 (1991) (“[R]ecovery will be meted out
sparingly, its balm reserved for those wounds that are truly severe
and incapable of healing themselves” (internal quotation marks
omitted)); Harris v. Jones , 281 Md. 560, 571, 380
A. 2d 611, 616 (1977) (the distress must be “ ‘so severe
that no reasonable man could be expected to endure it’ ”
(quoting Restatement (Second) of Torts §46, Comment j (1963–1964))).
A plaintiff must also establish that the
defendant’s conduct was “ ‘so outrageous in character, and so
extreme in degree, as to go beyond all possible bounds of decency,
and to be regarded as atrocious, and utterly intolerable in a
civilized community.’ ” Id. , at 567, 380 A. 2d,
at 614 (quoting Restatement (Second) of Torts §46, Comment d ).
Although the elements of the IIED tort are
difficult to meet, respondents long ago abandoned any effort to
show that those tough standards were not satisfied here. On appeal,
they chose not to contest the sufficiency of the evidence. See 580
F. 3d 206, 216 (CA4 2009). They did not dispute that Mr.
Snyder suffered “ ‘wounds that are truly severe and incapable
of healing themselves.’ ” Figueiredo-Torres , supra , at 653, 584 A. 2d, at 75. Nor did they dispute
that their speech was “ ‘so outrageous in character, and so
extreme in degree, as to go beyond all possible bounds of decency,
and to be regarded as atrocious, and utterly intolerable in a
civilized community.’ ” Harris , supra , at
567, 380 A. 2d, at 614. Instead, they maintained that the
First Amendment gave them a license to engage in such conduct. They
are wrong.
II
It is well established that a
claim for the intentional infliction of emotional distress can be
satisfied by speech. Indeed, what has been described as “[t]he
leading case” recognizing this tort involved speech. Prosser and
Keeton, supra, §12, at 60 (citing Wilkinson v. Downton , [1897] 2 Q. B. 57); see also Restatement
(Second) of Torts §46, illustration 1. And although this Court has
not decided the question, I think it is clear that the First
Amendment does not entirely preclude liability for the intentional
infliction of emotional distress by means of speech.
This Court has recognized that
words may “by their very utterance inflict injury” and that the
First Amendment does not shield utterances that form “no essential
part of any exposition of ideas, and are of such slight social
value as a step to truth that any benefit that may be derived from
them is clearly outweighed by the social interest in order and
morality.” Chaplinsky v. New Hampshire , 315 U. S. 568 , 572
(1942); see also Cantwell v. Connecticut , 310 U. S. 296 ,
310 (1940) (“[P]ersonal abuse is not in any proper sense
communication of information or opinion safeguarded by the
Constitution”). When grave injury is intentionally inflicted by
means of an attack like the one at issue here, the First Amendment
should not interfere with recovery.
III
In this case, respondents
brutally attacked Matthew Snyder, and this attack, which was almost
certain to inflict injury, was central to respondents’
well-practiced strategy for attracting public attention.
On the morning of Matthew
Snyder’s funeral, respondents could have chosen to stage their
protest at countless locations. They could have picketed the United
States Capitol, the White House, the Supreme Court, the Pentagon,
or any of the more than 5,600 military recruiting stations in this
country. They could have returned to the Maryland State House or
the United States Naval Academy, where they had been the day
before. They could have selected any public road where pedestrians
are allowed. (There are more than 4,000,000 miles of public roads
in the United States.[ Footnote
2 ]) They could have staged their protest in a public park.
(There are more than 20,000 public parks in this country.[ Footnote 3 ]) They could have chosen any
Catholic church where no funeral was taking place. (There are
nearly 19,000 Catholic churches in the United States.[ Footnote 4 ]) But of course, a small group
picketing at any of these locations would have probably gone
unnoticed.
The Westboro Baptist Church, however, has
devised a strategy that remedies this problem. As the Court notes,
church members have protested at nearly 600 military funerals. Ante , at 1. They have also picketed the funerals of police
officers,[ Footnote 5 ]
firefighters,[ Footnote 6 ] and
the victims of natural disasters,[ Footnote 7 ] accidents,[ Footnote 8 ] and shocking crimes.[ Footnote 9 ] And in advance of these protests, they
issue press releases to ensure that their protests will attract
public attention.[ Footnote
10 ]
This strategy works because it is expected
that respondents’ verbal assaults will wound the family and friends
of the deceased and because the media is irresistibly drawn to the
sight of persons who are visibly in grief. The more outrageous the
funeral protest, the more publicity the Westboro Baptist Church is
able to obtain. Thus, when the church recently announced its
intention to picket the funeral of a 9-year-old girl killed in the
shooting spree in Tucson—proclaiming that she was “better off
dead”[ Footnote 11 ]—their
announcement was national news,[ Footnote 12 ] and the church was able to obtain free air
time on the radio in exchange for canceling its protest.[ Footnote 13 ] Similarly, in 2006, the
church got air time on a talk radio show in exchange for canceling
its threatened protest at the funeral of five Amish girls killed by
a crazed gunman.[ Footnote
14 ]
In this case, respondents implemented the
Westboro Baptist Church’s publicity-seeking strategy. Their press
release stated that they were going “to picket the funeral of Lance
Cpl. Matthew A. Snyder” because “God Almighty killed Lance Cpl.
Snyder. He died in shame, not honor—for a fag nation cursed by God
… . Now in Hell—sine die.” Supp. App. in No. 08–1026 (CA4),
p. 158a. This announcement guaranteed that Matthew’s funeral
would be transformed into a raucous media event and began the
wounding process. It is well known that anticipation may heighten
the effect of a painful event.
On the day of the funeral, respondents, true
to their word, displayed placards that conveyed the message
promised in their press release. Signs stating “God Hates You” and
“Thank God for Dead Soldiers” reiterated the message that God had
caused Matthew’s death in retribution for his sins. App. to Brief
for Appellants in No. 08–1026 (CA4), pp. 3787, 3788 (hereinafter
App.). Others, stating “You’re Going to Hell” and “Not Blessed Just
Cursed,” conveyed the message that Matthew was “in Hell—sine die.” Id., at 3783.
Even if those who attended the funeral were
not alerted in advance about respondents’ intentions, the meaning
of these signs would not have been missed. Since respondents chose
to stage their protest at Matthew Snyder’s funeral and not at any
of the other countless available venues, a reasonable person would
have assumed that there was a connection between the messages on
the placards and the deceased. Moreover, since a church funeral is
an event that naturally brings to mind thoughts about the
afterlife, some of respondents’ signs— e.g ., “God Hates
You,” “Not Blessed Just Cursed,” and “You’re Going to Hell”—would
have likely been interpreted as referring to God’s judgment of the
deceased.
Other signs would most naturally have been
understood as suggesting—falsely—that Matthew was gay.
Homosexuality was the theme of many of the signs. There were signs
reading “God Hates Fags,” “Semper Fi Fags,” “Fags Doom Nations,”
and “Fag Troops.” Id. , at 3781–3787. Another placard
depicted two men engaging in anal intercourse. A reasonable
bystander seeing those signs would have likely concluded that they
were meant to suggest that the deceased was a homosexual.
After the funeral, the Westboro picketers
reaffirmed the meaning of their protest. They posted an online
account entitled “The Burden of Marine Lance Cpl. Matthew A.
Snyder. The Visit of Westboro Baptist Church to Help the
Inhabitants of Maryland Connect the Dots!” Id., at
3788.[ Footnote 15 ] Belying
any suggestion that they had simply made general comments about
homosexuality, the Catholic Church, and the United States military,
the “epic” addressed the Snyder family directly:
“God blessed you, Mr. and Mrs.
Snyder, with a resource and his name was Matthew. He was an arrow
in your quiver! In thanks to God for the comfort the child could
bring you, you had a DUTY to prepare that child to serve the LORD
his GOD—PERIOD! You did JUST THE OPPOSITE—you raised him for the
devil.
. . . . .
“Albert and Julie RIPPED that body apart and
taught Matthew to defy his Creator, to divorce, and to commit
adultery. They taught him how to support the largest pedophile
machine in the history of the entire world, the Roman Catholic
monstrosity. Every dime they gave the Roman Catholic monster they
condemned their own souls. They also, in supporting satanic
Catholicism, taught Matthew to be an idolater.
. . . . .
“Then after all that they sent him to fight
for the United States of Sodom, a filthy country that is in lock
step with his evil, wicked, and sinful manner of life, putting him
in the cross hairs of a God that is so mad He has smoke coming from
his nostrils and fire from his mouth! How dumb was that?” Id., at 3791.
In light of this evidence, it is
abundantly clear that respondents, going far beyond commentary on
matters of public concern, specifically attacked Matthew Snyder
because (1) he was a Catholic and (2) he was a member of the United
States military. Both Matthew and petitioner were private
figures,[ Footnote 16 ] and
this attack was not speech on a matter of public concern. While
commentary on the Catholic Church or the United States military
constitutes speech on matters of public concern, speech regarding
Matthew Snyder’s purely private conduct does not.
Justice Breyer provides an apt analogy to a
case in which the First Amendment would permit recovery in tort for
a verbal attack:
“[S]uppose that A were physically to assault B,
knowing that the assault (being newsworthy) would provide A with an
opportunity to transmit to the public his views on a matter of
public concern. The constitutionally protected nature of the end
would not shield A’s use of unlawful, unprotected means. And in
some circumstances the use of certain words as means would be
similarly unprotected.” Ante , at 1 (concurring
opinion).
This captures what respondents
did in this case. Indeed, this is the strategy that they have
routinely employed—and that they will now continue to
employ—inflicting severe and lasting emotional injury on an ever
growing list of innocent victims.
IV
The Court concludes that
respondents’ speech was protected by the First Amendment for
essentially three reasons, but none is sound.
First—and most important—the
Court finds that “the overall thrust and dominant theme of [their]
demonstration spoke to” broad public issues. Ante, at 8.
As I have attempted to show, this portrayal is quite inaccurate;
respondents’ attack on Matthew was of central importance. But in
any event, I fail to see why actionable speech should be immunized
simply because it is interspersed with speech that is protected.
The First Amendment allows recovery for defamatory statements that
are interspersed with nondefamatory statements on matters of public
concern, and there is no good reason why respondents’ attack on
Matthew Snyder and his family should be treated differently. Second, the Court suggests that
respondents’ personal attack on Matthew Snyder is entitled to First
Amendment protection because it was not motivated by a private
grudge, see ante , at 9, but I see no basis for the strange
distinction that the Court appears to draw. Respondents’
motivation—“to increase publicity for its views,” ibid. —did not transform their statements attacking the
character of a private figure into statements that made a
contribution to debate on matters of public concern. Nor did their
publicity-seeking motivation soften the sting of their attack. And
as far as culpability is concerned, one might well think that
wounding statements uttered in the heat of a private feud are less,
not more, blameworthy than similar statements made as part of a
cold and calculated strategy to slash a stranger as a means of
attracting public attention.
Third, the Court finds it significant that
respondents’ protest occurred on a public street, but this fact
alone should not be enough to preclude IIED liability. To be sure,
statements made on a public street may be less likely to satisfy
the elements of the IIED tort than statements made on private
property, but there is no reason why a public street in close
proximity to the scene of a funeral should be regarded as a
free-fire zone in which otherwise actionable verbal attacks are
shielded from liability. If the First Amendment permits the States
to protect their residents from the harm inflicted by such
attacks—and the Court does not hold otherwise—then the location of
the tort should not be dispositive. A physical assault may occur
without trespassing; it is no defense that the perpetrator had “the
right to be where [he was].” See ante , at 11. And the same
should be true with respect to unprotected speech. Neither classic
“fighting words” nor defamatory statements are immunized when they
occur in a public place, and there is no good reason to treat a
verbal assault based on the conduct or character of a private
figure like Matthew Snyder any differently.
One final comment about the opinion of the
Court is in order. The Court suggests that the wounds inflicted by
vicious verbal assaults at funerals will be prevented or at least
mitigated in the future by new laws that restrict picketing within
a specified distance of a funeral. See ante , at
10–11 . It is apparent, however, that the enactment of
these laws is no substitute for the protection provided by the
established IIED tort; according to the Court, the verbal attacks
that severely wounded petitioner in this case complied with the new
Maryland law regulating funeral picketing. See ante , at
11, n. 5. And there is absolutely nothing to suggest that Congress
and the state legislatures, in enacting these laws, intended them
to displace the protection provided by the well-established IIED
tort.
The real significance of these new laws is not
that they obviate the need for IIED protection. Rather, their
enactment dramatically illustrates the fundamental point that
funerals are unique events at which special protection against
emotional assaults is in order. At funerals, the emotional
well-being of bereaved relatives is particularly vulnerable. See National Archives and Records Admin. v. Favish , 541 U. S. 157 ,
168 (2004). Exploitation of a funeral for the purpose of attracting
public attention “intrud[es] upon their … grief,” ibid. ,
and may permanently stain their memories of the final moments
before a loved one is laid to rest. Allowing family members to have
a few hours of peace without harassment does not undermine public
debate. I would therefore hold that, in this setting, the First
Amendment permits a private figure to recover for the intentional
infliction of emotional distress caused by speech on a matter of
private concern.
V
In reversing the District Court
judgment in favor of petitioner, the Court of Appeals relied on
several grounds not discussed in the opinion of this Court or in
the separate opinion supporting affirmance. I now turn briefly to
those issues.
First, the Court of Appeals held
that the District Court erred by allowing the jury to decide
whether respondents’ speech was “ ‘directed specifically at
the Snyder family.’ ” 580 F. 3d, at 221. It is not clear
whether the Court of Appeals thought that this was a question for
the trial judge alone or a question on which the judge had to make
a preliminary ruling before sending it to the jury. In either
event, however, the submission of this question to the jury was not
reversible error because, as explained above, it is clear that
respondents’ statements targeted the Snyders.
Second, the Court of Appeals held that the
trial judge went astray in allowing the jury to decide whether
respondents’ speech was so “ ‘offensive and shocking as to not
be entitled to First Amendment protection.’ ” Ibid. This instruction also did respondents no harm. Because their speech
did not relate to a matter of public concern, it was not protected
from liability by the First Amendment, and the only question for
the jury was whether the elements of the IIED tort were met.
Third, the Court of Appeals appears to have
concluded that the First Amendment does not permit an IIED
plaintiff to recover for speech that cannot reasonably be
interpreted as stating actual facts about an individual. See id., at 222. In reaching this conclusion, the Court of
Appeals relied on two of our cases— Milkovich v. Lorain
Journal Co ., 497
U. S. 1 (1990), and Hustler, 485 U. S. 46 —but neither supports the
broad proposition that the Court of Appeals adopted. Milkovich was a defamation case, and
falsity is an element of defamation. Nothing in Milkovich even hints that the First Amendment requires that this defamation
element be engrafted onto the IIED tort. Hustler did involve an IIED claim,
but the plaintiff there was a public figure, and the Court did not
suggest that its holding would also apply in a case involving a
private figure. Nor did the Court suggest that its holding applied
across the board to all types of IIED claims. Instead, the holding
was limited to “publications such as the one here at issue,”
namely, a caricature in a magazine. 485 U. S., at 56. Unless a
caricature of a public figure can reasonably be interpreted as
stating facts that may be proved to be wrong, the caricature does
not have the same potential to wound as a personal verbal assault
on a vulnerable private figure.
Because I cannot agree either with the holding
of this Court or the other grounds on which the Court of Appeals
relied, I would reverse the decision below and remand for further
proceedings.[ Footnote
17 ]
VI
Respondents’ outrageous conduct
caused petitioner great injury, and the Court now compounds that
injury by depriving petitioner of a judgment that acknowledges the
wrong he suffered.
In order to have a society in
which public issues can be openly and vigorously debated, it is not
necessary to allow the brutalization of innocent victims like
petitioner. I therefore respectfully dissent. Footnote 1 See 580 F. 3d 206, 213–214, 216 (CA4
2009). Footnote 2 See Dept. of Transp., Federal Highway
Administration, Highway Statistics 2008, Table HM–12M,
http://www.fhwa.dot.gov/policyinformation/
statistics/2008/hm12m.cfm (all Internet materials as visited Feb.
25, 2011, and available in Clerk of Court’s case file). Footnote 3 See Trust for Public Land, 2010 City Park
Facts, http://
www.tpl.org/content_documents/CityParkFacts_2010.pdf. Footnote 4 See United States Conference of Catholic
Bishops, Catholic Information Project,
http://www.usccb.org/comm/cip.shtml#toc4. Footnote 5 See
http://www.godhatesfags.com/fliers/20110124_St-Petersburg-FL-
Dead-Police.pdf. Footnote 6 See http: //www.godhatesfags.com / fliers/20110120_Dead-Volunteer-Firefighter-Connecting_the_Dots-Baltimore-MD.pdf. Footnote 7 See
http://www.godhatesfags.com/fliers/20110104_Newburg-and-Rolla-MO-Tornado-Connecting-the-Dots.pdf. Footnote 8 See
http://www.godhatesfags.com/fliers/20101218_Wichita-KS-Two-Dead-Wichita-Bikers.pdf. Footnote 9 See
http://www.godhatesfags.com/fliers/20110129_Tampa-FL-God-Sent-Military-Mom-Shooter-to-Kill-Kids.pdf. Footnote 10 See nn. 5–9, supra . Footnote 11 See
http://www.godhatesfags.com/fliers/20110109_AZ-Shooter-Connecting-the-Dots-Day-2.pdf. Footnote 12 See, e.g., Stanglin, Anti-Gay Church
Group Plans to Picket Tucson Funerals, USA Today, Jan. 10, 2011,
http://content.usatoday.com/communities/
ondeadline / post / 2011/01/anti-gay-church-group-plans-to-picket-tucston-
funerals/1; Mohanani, Group to Picket 9-Year-Old Tucson Victim’s
Funeral, Palm Beach Post, Jan. 11, 2011,
http://www.palmbeachpost.com/
news/nation/group-to-picket-9-year-old-tucson-victims-1177921.html;
Mehta & Santa Cruz, Tucson Rallies to Protect Girl’s Family
from Protesters, Los Angeles Times, Jan. 11, 2011,
http://articles.latimes.com/
2011/jan/11/nation/la-na-funeral-protest-20110112; Medrano, Funeral
Protest: Arizona Rallies to Foil Westboro Baptist Church, Christian
Science Monitor, Jan. 11, 2011, http://www.csmonitor.com/USA/2011/
0111/Funeral-protest-Arizona-rallies-to-foil-Westboro-Baptist-Church. Footnote 13 See Santa Cruz & Mehta, Westboro Church
Agrees Not to Take Protest to Shooting Victims’ Funerals, Los
Angeles Times, Jan. 13, 2011,
http://articles.latimes.com/2011/jan/13/nation/la-na-funeral-protest-20110113;
http://www.godhatesfags.com/fliers/20110112_AZ-Shooter-Mike-Gallagher-Radio-Exchange.pdf. Footnote 14 See Steinberg, Air Time Instead of Funeral
Protest, N. Y. Times, Oct. 6, 2006, p. A14. Footnote 15 The Court refuses to consider the epic
because it was not discussed in Snyder’s petition for certiorari. Ante , at 3, n. 1. The epic, however, is not a
distinct claim but a piece of evidence that the jury considered in
imposing liability for the claims now before this Court. The
protest and the epic are parts of a single course of conduct that
the jury found to constitute intentional infliction of emotional
distress. See 580 F. 3d, at 225 (“[T]he Epic cannot be
divorced from the general context of the funeral protest”). The
Court’s strange insistence that the epic “is not properly before
us,” ante , at 3, n. 1, means that the Court has not
actually made “an independent examination of the whole record,” ante , at 7 (internal quotation marks omitted). And the
Court’s refusal to consider the epic contrasts sharply with its
willingness to take notice of Westboro’s protest activities at
other times and locations. See ante , at 9. Footnote 16 See 533 F. Supp. 2d 567, 577 (Md.
2008). Footnote 17 The Court affirms the decision of the Fourth
Circuit with respect to petitioner’s claim of intrusion upon
seclusion on a ground not addressed by the Fourth Circuit. I would
not reach out to decide that issue but would instead leave it for
the Fourth Circuit to decide on remand. I would likewise allow the
Fourth Circuit on remand to decide whether the judgment on the
claim of civil conspiracy can survive in light of the ultimate
disposition of the IIED and intrusion upon seclusion claims. | In Snyder v. Phelps, the Supreme Court ruled that the First Amendment protected a church's right to engage in hate speech near a soldier's funeral, despite the hurtful and offensive nature of their picket signs. The court affirmed that free speech, even hateful speech, is a fundamental right in the United States. |
Free Speech | Morse v. Frederick | https://supreme.justia.com/cases/federal/us/551/393/ | OPINION OF THE COURT MORSE V. FREDERICK 551 U. S. ____ (2007) SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES NO. 06-278 DEBORAH MORSE, et al., PETITIONERS v. JOSEPH FREDERICK
on writ of certiorari to the united states court of
appeals for the ninth circuit
[June 25, 2007]
Chief Justice Roberts delivered
the opinion of the Court.
At a school-sanctioned and
school-supervised event, a high school principal saw some of her
students unfurl a large banner conveying a message she reasonably
regarded as promoting illegal drug use. Consistent with established
school policy prohibiting such messages at school events, the
principal directed the students to take down the banner. One
student—among those who had brought the banner to the event—refused
to do so. The principal confiscated the banner and later suspended
the student. The Ninth Circuit held that the principal’s actions
violated the First Amendment, and that the student could sue the
principal for damages.
Our cases make clear that students do not
“shed their constitutional rights to freedom of speech or
expression at the schoolhouse gate.” Tinker v. Des
Moines Independent Community School Dist. , 393 U. S. 503 , 506
(1969). At the same time, we have held that “the constitutional
rights of students in public school are not automatically
coextensive with the rights of adults in other settings,” Bethel School Dist. No. 403 v. Fraser , 478 U. S. 675 , 682 (1986), and that
the rights of students “must be ‘applied in light of the special
characteristics of the school environment.’ ” Hazelwood
School Dist. v. Kuhlmeier , 484 U. S. 260 , 266
(1988) (quoting Tinker , supra, at 506).
Consistent with these principles, we hold that schools may take
steps to safeguard those entrusted to their care from speech that
can reasonably be regarded as encouraging illegal drug use. We
conclude that the school officials in this case did not violate the
First Amendment by confiscating the pro-drug banner and suspending
the student responsible for it.
I
On January 24, 2002, the Olympic
Torch Relay passed through Juneau, Alaska, on its way to the winter
games in Salt Lake City, Utah. The torchbearers were to proceed
along a street in front of Juneau-Douglas High School (JDHS) while
school was in session. Petitioner Deborah Morse, the school
principal, decided to permit staff and students to participate in
the Torch Relay as an approved social event or class trip. App.
22–23. Students were allowed to leave class to observe the relay
from either side of the street. Teachers and administrative
officials monitored the students’ actions.
Respondent Joseph Frederick, a
JDHS senior, was late to school that day. When he arrived, he
joined his friends (all but one of whom were JDHS students) across
the street from the school to watch the event. Not all the students
waited patiently. Some became rambunctious, throwing plastic cola
bottles and snowballs and scuffling with their classmates. As the
torchbearers and camera crews passed by, Frederick and his friends
unfurled a 14-foot banner bearing the phrase: “BONG HiTS 4 JESUS.”
App. to Pet. for Cert. 70a. The large banner was easily readable by
the students on the other side of the street.
Principal Morse immediately crossed the street
and demanded that the banner be taken down. Everyone but Frederick
complied. Morse confiscated the banner and told Frederick to report
to her office, where she suspended him for 10 days. Morse later
explained that she told Frederick to take the banner down because
she thought it encouraged illegal drug use, in violation of
established school policy. Juneau School Board Policy No. 5520
states: “The Board specifically prohibits any assembly or public
expression that … advocates the use of substances that are illegal
to minors … .” Id., at 53a. In addition, Juneau
School Board Policy No. 5850 subjects “[p]upils who participate in
approved social events and class trips” to the same student conduct
rules that apply during the regular school program. Id., at 58a.
Frederick administratively appealed his
suspension, but the Juneau School District Superintendent upheld
it, limiting it to time served (8 days). In a memorandum setting
forth his reasons, the superintendent determined that Frederick had
displayed his banner “in the midst of his fellow students, during
school hours, at a school-sanctioned activity.” Id., at
63a. He further explained that Frederick “was not disciplined
because the principal of the school ‘disagreed’ with his message,
but because his speech appeared to advocate the use of illegal
drugs.” Id., at 61a.
The superintendent continued:
“The common-sense understanding of the phrase ‘bong
hits’ is that it is a reference to a means of smoking marijuana.
Given [Frederick’s] inability or unwillingness to express any other
credible meaning for the phrase, I can only agree with the
principal and countless others who saw the banner as advocating the
use of illegal drugs. [Frederick’s] speech was not political. He
was not advocating the legalization of marijuana or promoting a
religious belief. He was displaying a fairly silly message
promoting illegal drug usage in the midst of a school activity, for
the benefit of television cameras covering the Torch Relay.
[Frederick’s] speech was potentially disruptive to the event and
clearly disruptive of and inconsistent with the school’s
educational mission to educate students about the dangers of
illegal drugs and to discourage their use.” Id., at
61a–62a.
Relying on our decision in Fraser , supra , the superintendent concluded that the principal’s
actions were permissible because Frederick’s banner was “speech or
action that intrudes upon the work of the schools.” App. to Pet.
for Cert. 62a (internal quotation marks omitted). The Juneau School
District Board of Education upheld the suspension.
Frederick then filed suit under 42 U.
S. C. §1983, alleging that the school board and Morse had
violated his First Amendment rights. He sought declaratory and
injunctive relief, unspecified compensatory damages, punitive
damages, and attorney’s fees. The District Court granted summary
judgment for the school board and Morse, ruling that they were
entitled to qualified immunity and that they had not infringed
Frederick’s First Amendment rights. The court found that Morse
reasonably interpreted the banner as promoting illegal drug use—a
message that “directly contravened the Board’s policies relating to
drug abuse prevention.” App. to Pet. for Cert. 36a–38a. Under the
circumstances, the court held that “Morse had the authority, if not
the obligation, to stop such messages at a school-sanctioned
activity.” Id., at 37a.
The Ninth Circuit reversed. Deciding that
Frederick acted during a “school-authorized activit[y],” and
“proceed[ing] on the basis that the banner expressed a positive
sentiment about marijuana use,” the court nonetheless found a
violation of Frederick’s First Amendment rights because the school
punished Frederick without demonstrating that his speech gave rise
to a “risk of substantial disruption.” 439 F. 3d 1114, 1118,
1121–1123 (2006). The court further concluded that Frederick’s
right to display his banner was so “clearly established” that a
reasonable principal in Morse’s position would have understood that
her actions were unconstitutional, and that Morse was therefore not
entitled to qualified immunity. Id., at 1123–1125.
We granted certiorari on two questions:
whether Frederick had a First Amendment right to wield his banner,
and, if so, whether that right was so clearly established that the
principal may be held liable for damages. 549 U. S. ___ (2006). We
resolve the first question against Frederick, and therefore have no
occasion to reach the second.[ Footnote 1 ]
II
At the outset, we reject
Frederick’s argument that this is not a school speech case—as has
every other authority to address the question. See App. 22–23
(Principal Morse); App. to Pet. for Cert. 63a (superintendent); id., at 69a (school board); id., at 34a–35a
(District Court); 439 F. 3d, at 1117 (Ninth Circuit). The
event occurred during normal school hours. It was sanctioned by
Principal Morse “as an approved social event or class trip,” App.
22–23, and the school district’s rules expressly provide that
pupils in “approved social events and class trips are subject to
district rules for student conduct.” App. to Pet. for Cert. 58a.
Teachers and administrators were interspersed among the students
and charged with supervising them. The high school band and
cheerleaders performed. Frederick, standing among other JDHS
students across the street from the school, directed his banner
toward the school, making it plainly visible to most students.
Under these circumstances, we agree with the superintendent that
Frederick cannot “stand in the midst of his fellow students, during
school hours, at a school-sanctioned activity and claim he is not
at school.” Id., at 63a. There is some uncertainty at the
outer boundaries as to when courts should apply school-speech
precedents, see Porter v. Ascension Parish School
Bd. , 393 F. 3d 608, 615, n. 22 (CA5 2004), but not on
these facts.
III
The message on Frederick’s banner
is cryptic. It is no doubt offensive to some, perhaps amusing to
others. To still others, it probably means nothing at all.
Frederick himself claimed “that the words were just nonsense meant
to attract television cameras.” 439 F. 3d, at 1117–1118. But
Principal Morse thought the banner would be interpreted by those
viewing it as promoting illegal drug use, and that interpretation
is plainly a reasonable one.
As Morse later explained in a
declaration, when she saw the sign, she thought that “the reference
to a ‘bong hit’ would be widely understood by high school students
and others as referring to smoking marijuana.” App. 24. She further
believed that “display of the banner would be construed by
students, District personnel, parents and others witnessing the
display of the banner, as advocating or promoting illegal drug
use”—in violation of school policy. Id., at 25; see ibid. (“I told Frederick and the other members of his
group to put the banner down because I felt that it violated the
[school] policy against displaying … material that advertises or
promotes use of illegal drugs”).
We agree with Morse. At least two
interpretations of the words on the banner demonstrate that the
sign advocated the use of illegal drugs. First, the phrase could be
interpreted as an imperative: “[Take] bong hits …”—a message
equivalent, as Morse explained in her declaration, to “smoke
marijuana” or “use an illegal drug.” Alternatively, the phrase
could be viewed as celebrating drug use—“bong hits [are a good
thing],” or “[we take] bong hits”—and we discern no meaningful
distinction between celebrating illegal drug use in the midst of
fellow students and outright advocacy or promotion. See Guiles v. Marineau , 461 F. 3d 320, 328 (CA2
2006) (discussing the present case and describing the sign as “a
clearly pro-drug banner”).
The pro-drug interpretation of the banner
gains further plausibility given the paucity of alternative
meanings the banner might bear. The best Frederick can come up with
is that the banner is “meaningless and funny.” 439 F. 3d, at
1116. The dissent similarly refers to the sign’s message as
“curious,” post, at 1, “ambiguous,” ibid. ,
“nonsense,” post, at 2, “ridiculous,” post, at 6,
“obscure,” post, at 7, “silly,” post, at 12,
“quixotic,” post, at 13, and “stupid,” ibid. Gibberish is surely a possible interpretation of the words on the
banner, but it is not the only one, and dismissing the banner as
meaningless ignores its undeniable reference to illegal drugs.
The dissent mentions Frederick’s “credible and
uncontradicted explanation for the message—he just wanted to get on
television.” Post, at 12. But that is a description of
Frederick’s motive for displaying the banner; it is not an
interpretation of what the banner says. The way Frederick
was going to fulfill his ambition of appearing on television was by
unfurling a pro-drug banner at a school event, in the presence of
teachers and fellow students.
Elsewhere in its opinion, the dissent
emphasizes the importance of political speech and the need to
foster “national debate about a serious issue,” post, at
16, as if to suggest that the banner is political speech. But not
even Frederick argues that the banner conveys any sort of political
or religious message. Contrary to the dissent’s suggestion, see post, at 14–16, this is plainly not a case about political
debate over the criminalization of drug use or possession.
IV
The question thus becomes whether
a principal may, consistent with the First Amendment, restrict
student speech at a school event, when that speech is reasonably
viewed as promoting illegal drug use. We hold that she may.
In Tinker , this Court
made clear that “First Amendment rights, applied in light of the
special characteristics of the school environment, are available to
teachers and students.” 393 U. S., at 506. Tinker involved
a group of high school students who decided to wear black armbands
to protest the Vietnam War. School officials learned of the plan
and then adopted a policy prohibiting students from wearing
armbands. When several students nonetheless wore armbands to
school, they were suspended. Id., at 504. The students
sued, claiming that their First Amendment rights had been violated,
and this Court agreed. Tinker held that student expression
may not be suppressed unless school officials reasonably conclude
that it will “materially and substantially disrupt the work and
discipline of the school.” Id., at 513. The essential
facts of Tinker are quite stark, implicating concerns at
the heart of the First Amendment. The students sought to engage in
political speech, using the armbands to express their “disapproval
of the Vietnam hostilities and their advocacy of a truce, to make
their views known, and, by their example, to influence others to
adopt them.” Id., at 514. Political speech, of course, is
“at the core of what the First Amendment is designed to protect.” Virginia v. Black , 538 U. S. 343 , 365
(2003). The only interest the Court discerned underlying the
school’s actions was the “mere desire to avoid the discomfort and
unpleasantness that always accompany an unpopular viewpoint,” or
“an urgent wish to avoid the controversy which might result from
the expression.” Tinker , 393 U. S., at 509, 510. That
interest was not enough to justify banning “a silent, passive
expression of opinion, unaccompanied by any disorder or
disturbance.” Id., at 508.
This Court’s next student speech case was Fraser , 478 U. S. 675 . Matthew Fraser was
suspended for delivering a speech before a high school assembly in
which he employed what this Court called “an elaborate, graphic,
and explicit sexual metaphor.” Id., at 678. Analyzing the
case under Tinker , the District Court and Court of Appeals
found no disruption, and therefore no basis for disciplining
Fraser. 478 U. S., at 679–680. This Court reversed, holding that
the “School District acted entirely within its permissible
authority in imposing sanctions upon Fraser in response to his
offensively lewd and indecent speech.” Id., at 685.
The mode of analysis employed in Fraser is not entirely clear. The Court was plainly
attuned to the content of Fraser’s speech, citing the “marked
distinction between the political ‘message’ of the armbands in Tinker and the sexual content of [Fraser’s] speech.” Id., at 680. But the Court also reasoned that school
boards have the authority to determine “what manner of speech in
the classroom or in school assembly is inappropriate.” Id., at 683. Cf. id., at 689 (Brennan, J.,
concurring in judgment) (“In the present case, school officials
sought only to ensure that a high school assembly proceed in an
orderly manner. There is no suggestion that school officials
attempted to regulate [Fraser’s] speech because they disagreed with
the views he sought to express”).
We need not resolve this debate to decide this
case. For present purposes, it is enough to distill from Fraser two basic principles. First, Fraser ’s
holding demonstrates that “the constitutional rights of students in
public school are not automatically coextensive with the rights of
adults in other settings.” Id., at 682. Had Fraser
delivered the same speech in a public forum outside the school
context, it would have been protected. See Cohen v. California , 403 U. S. 15 (1971); Fraser , supra, at 682–683. In school, however,
Fraser’s First Amendment rights were circumscribed “in light of the
special characteristics of the school environment.” Tinker , supra, at 506. Second, Fraser established that the mode of analysis set forth in Tinker is not absolute. Whatever approach Fraser employed, it
certainly did not conduct the “substantial disruption” analysis
prescribed by Tinker, supra, at 514. See Kuhlmeier , 484 U. S., at 271, n. 4 (disagreeing with the
proposition that there is “no difference between the First
Amendment analysis applied in Tinker and that applied in Fraser ,” and noting that the holding in Fraser was not based on any showing of substantial disruption).
Our most recent student speech case, Kuhlmeier , concerned “expressive activities that students,
parents, and members of the public might reasonably perceive to
bear the imprimatur of the school.” 484 U. S., at 271. Staff
members of a high school newspaper sued their school when it chose
not to publish two of their articles. The Court of Appeals analyzed
the case under Tinker , ruling in favor of the students
because it found no evidence of material disruption to classwork or
school discipline. 795 F. 2d 1368, 1375 (CA8 1986). This Court
reversed, holding that “educators do not offend the First Amendment
by exercising editorial control over the style and content of
student speech in school-sponsored expressive activities so long as
their actions are reasonably related to legitimate pedagogical
concerns.” Kuhlmeier, supra, at 273. Kuhlmeier does not control this case
because no one would reasonably believe that Frederick’s banner
bore the school’s imprimatur. The case is nevertheless instructive
because it confirms both principles cited above. Kuhlmeier acknowledged that schools may regulate some speech “even though the
government could not censor similar speech outside the school.” Id., at 266. And, like Fraser , it confirms that
the rule of Tinker is not the only basis for restricting
student speech.[ Footnote 2 ]
Drawing on the principles applied in our
student speech cases, we have held in the Fourth Amendment context
that “while children assuredly do not ‘shed their constitutional
rights . . . at the schoolhouse gate,’ . . . the nature of those
rights is what is appropriate for children in school.” Vernonia
School Dist. 47J v. Acton , 515 U. S. 646 , 655–656
(1995) (quoting Tinker , supra, at 506). In
particular, “the school setting requires some easing of the
restrictions to which searches by public authorities are ordinarily
subject.” New Jersey v. T. L. O. , 469 U. S. 325 ,
340 (1985). See Vernonia , supra, at 656 (“Fourth
Amendment rights, no less than First and Fourteenth Amendment
rights, are different in public schools than elsewhere . . .”); Board of Ed. of Independent School Dist. No. 92 of Pottawatomie
Cty. v. Earls , 536 U. S. 822 , 829-830
(2002) (“ ‘special needs’ inhere in the public school
context”; “[w]hile schoolchildren do not shed their constitutional
rights when they enter the schoolhouse, Fourth Amendment rights . .
. are different in public schools than elsewhere; the
‘reasonableness’ inquiry cannot disregard the schools’ custodial
and tutelary responsibility for children” (quoting Vernonia , 515 U. S., at 656; citation and some internal
quotation marks omitted).
Even more to the point, these cases also
recognize that deterring drug use by schoolchildren is an
“important—indeed, perhaps compelling” interest. Id., at
661. Drug abuse can cause severe and permanent damage to the health
and well-being of young people:
“School years are the time when the physical,
psychological, and addictive effects of drugs are most severe.
Maturing nervous systems are more critically impaired by
intoxicants than mature ones are; childhood losses in learning are
lifelong and profound; children grow chemically dependent more
quickly than adults, and their record of recovery is depressingly
poor. And of course the effects of a drug-infested school are
visited not just upon the users, but upon the entire student body
and faculty, as the educational process is disrupted.” Id., at 661–662 (citations and internal quotation marks
omitted).
Just five years ago, we wrote: “The drug abuse
problem among our Nation’s youth has hardly abated since Vernonia was decided in 1995. In fact, evidence suggests
that it has only grown worse.” Earls , supra, at
834, and n. 5.
The problem remains serious today. See
generally 1 National Institute on Drug Abuse, National Institutes
of Health, Monitoring the Future: National Survey Results on Drug
Use, 1975–2005, Secondary School Students (2006). About half of
American 12th graders have used an illicit drug, as have more than
a third of 10th graders and about one-fifth of 8th graders. Id., at 99. Nearly one in four 12th graders has used an
illicit drug in the past month. Id., at 101. Some 25% of
high schoolers say that they have been offered, sold, or given an
illegal drug on school property within the past year. Dept. of
Health and Human Services, Centers for Disease Control and
Prevention, Youth Risk Behavior Surveillance—United States, 2005,
55 Morbidity and Mortality Weekly Report, Surveillance Summaries,
No. SS–5, p. 19 (June 9, 2006).
Congress has declared that part of a school’s
job is educating students about the dangers of illegal drug use. It
has provided billions of dollars to support state and local
drug-prevention programs, Brief for United States as Amicus Curiae 1, and required that schools
receiving federal funds under the Safe and Drug-Free Schools and
Communities Act of 1994 certify that their drug prevention programs
“convey a clear and consistent message that … the illegal use of
drugs [is] wrong and harmful.” 20 U. S. C. §7114(d)(6) (2000
ed., Supp. IV).
Thousands of school boards throughout the
country—including JDHS—have adopted policies aimed at effectuating
this message. See Pet. for Cert. 17–21. Those school boards know
that peer pressure is perhaps “the single most important factor
leading schoolchildren to take drugs,” and that students are more
likely to use drugs when the norms in school appear to tolerate
such behavior. Earls , supra, at 840 (Breyer, J.,
concurring). Student speech celebrating illegal drug use at a
school event, in the presence of school administrators and
teachers, thus poses a particular challenge for school officials
working to protect those entrusted to their care from the dangers
of drug abuse.
The “special characteristics of the school
environment,” Tinker , 393 U. S., at 506, and the
governmental interest in stopping student drug abuse—reflected in
the policies of Congress and myriad school boards, including
JDHS—allow schools to restrict student expression that they
reasonably regard as promoting illegal drug use. Tinker warned that schools may not prohibit student speech because of
“undifferentiated fear or apprehension of disturbance” or “a mere
desire to avoid the discomfort and unpleasantness that always
accompany an unpopular viewpoint.” Id., at 508, 509. The
danger here is far more serious and palpable. The particular
concern to prevent student drug abuse at issue here, embodied in
established school policy, App. 92–95; App. to Pet. for Cert. 53a,
extends well beyond an abstract desire to avoid controversy.
Petitioners urge us to adopt the broader rule
that Frederick’s speech is proscribable because it is plainly
“offensive” as that term is used in Fraser . See Reply
Brief for Petitioners 14–15. We think this stretches Fraser too far; that case should not be read to encompass
any speech that could fit under some definition of “offensive.”
After all, much political and religious speech might be perceived
as offensive to some. The concern here is not that Frederick’s
speech was offensive, but that it was reasonably viewed as
promoting illegal drug use.
Although accusing this decision of doing
“serious violence to the First Amendment” by authorizing “viewpoint
discrimination,” post, at 2, 5 (opinion of
Stevens, J.), the dissent concludes that “it might well be
appropriate to tolerate some targeted viewpoint discrimination in
this unique setting,” post, at 6–7. Nor do we understand
the dissent to take the position that schools are required to
tolerate student advocacy of illegal drug use at school events,
even if that advocacy falls short of inviting “imminent” lawless
action. See post, at 7 (“[I]t is possible that our rigid
imminence requirement ought to be relaxed at schools”). And even
the dissent recognizes that the issues here are close enough that
the principal should not be held liable in damages, but should
instead enjoy qualified immunity for her actions. See post, at 1. Stripped of rhetorical flourishes, then, the
debate between the dissent and this opinion is less about
constitutional first principles than about whether Frederick’s
banner constitutes promotion of illegal drug use. We have explained
our view that it does. The dissent’s contrary view on that
relatively narrow question hardly justifies sounding the First
Amendment bugle.
* * *
School principals have a
difficult job, and a vitally important one. When Frederick suddenly
and unexpectedly unfurled his banner, Morse had to decide to act—or
not act—on the spot. It was reasonable for her to conclude that the
banner promoted illegal drug use—in violation of established school
policy—and that failing to act would send a powerful message to the
students in her charge, including Frederick, about how serious the
school was about the dangers of illegal drug use. The First
Amendment does not require schools to tolerate at school events
student expression that contributes to those dangers.
The judgment of the United States
Court of Appeals for the Ninth Circuit is reversed, and the case is
remanded for further proceedings consistent with this opinion.
It is so ordered. Footnote 1 Justice Breyer would rest decision on
qualified immunity without reaching the underlying First Amendment
question. The problem with this approach is the rather significant
one that it is inadequate to decide the case before us. Qualified
immunity shields public officials from money damages only. See Wood v. Strickland , 420 U. S. 308 , 314,
n. 6 (1975). In this case, Frederick asked not just for
damages, but also for declaratory and injunctive relief. App. 13.
Justice Breyer’s proposed decision on qualified immunity grounds
would dispose of the damages claims, but Frederick’s other claims
would remain unaddressed. To get around that problem, Justice
Breyer hypothesizes that Frederick’s suspension—the target of his
request for injunctive relief—“may well be justified on
non-speech-related grounds.” See post, at 9. That
hypothesis was never considered by the courts below, never raised
by any of the parties, and is belied by the record, which nowhere
suggests that the suspension would have been justified solely on
non-speech-related grounds. Footnote 2 The dissent’s effort to find inconsistency
between our approach here and the opinion in Federal Election
Commission v. Wisconsin Right to Life, Inc. , 551 U.
S. ___ (2007), see post, at 12 (opinion of
Stevens, J.), overlooks what was made clear in Tinker , Fraser , and Kuhlmeier : student
First Amendment rights are “applied in light of the special
characteristics of the school environment.” Tinker , 393 U.
S., at 506. See Fraser , 478 U. S., at 682; Kuhlmeier , 484 U. S., at 266. And, as discussed above, supra, at 8, there is no serious argument that Frederick’s
banner is political speech of the sort at issue in Wisconsin
Right to Life . ALITO, J., CONCURRING MORSE V. FREDERICK 551 U. S. ____ (2007) SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES NO. 06-278 DEBORAH MORSE, et al., PETITIONERS v. JOSEPH FREDERICK
on writ of certiorari to the united states court of
appeals for the ninth circuit
[June 25, 2007]
Justice Alito, with whom Justice
Kennedy joins, concurring.
I join the opinion of the Court
on the understanding that (a) it goes no further than to hold that
a public school may restrict speech that a reasonable observer
would interpret as advocating illegal drug use and (b) it provides
no support for any restriction of speech that can plausibly be
interpreted as commenting on any political or social issue,
including speech on issues such as “the wisdom of the war on drugs
or of legalizing marijuana for medicinal use.” See post ,
at 13 (Stevens, J., dissenting).
The opinion of the Court correctly reaffirms
the recognition in Tinker v. Des Moines Independent
Community School Dist. , 393 U. S. 503 , 506
(1969), of the fundamental principle that students do not “shed
their constitutional rights to freedom of speech or expression at
the schoolhouse gate.” The Court is also correct in noting that Tinker, which permits the regulation of student speech
that threatens a concrete and “substantial disruption , ” id. , at 514, does not set out the only ground on which
in-school student speech may be regulated by state actors in a way
that would not be constitutional in other settings. But I do not read the opinion to mean
that there are necessarily any grounds for such regulation that are
not already recognized in the holdings of this Court. In addition
to Tinker , the decision in the present case allows the
restriction of speech advocating illegal drug use; Bethel
School Dist. No. 403 v. Fraser , 478 U. S. 675 (1986),
permits the regulation of speech that is delivered in a lewd or
vulgar manner as part of a middle school program; and Hazelwood
School Dist. v. Kuhlmeier , 484 U. S. 260 (1988),
allows a school to regulate what is in essence the school’s own
speech, that is, articles that appear in a publication that is an
official school organ. I join the opinion of the Court on the
understanding that the opinion does not hold that the special
characteristics of the public schools necessarily justify any other
speech restrictions.
The opinion of the Court does not endorse the
broad argument advanced by petitioners and the United States that
the First Amendment permits public school officials to censor any
student speech that interferes with a school’s “educational
mission.” See Brief for Petitioners 21; Brief for United States as Amicus Curiae 6. This argument can easily be manipulated
in dangerous ways, and I would reject it before such abuse occurs.
The “educational mission” of the public schools is defined by the
elected and appointed public officials with authority over the
schools and by the school administrators and faculty. As a result,
some public schools have defined their educational missions as
including the inculcation of whatever political and social views
are held by the members of these groups.
During the Tinker era, a public
school could have defined its educational mission to include
solidarity with our soldiers and their families and thus could have
attempted to outlaw the wearing of black armbands on the ground
that they undermined this mission. Alternatively, a school could
have defined its educational mission to include the promotion of
world peace and could have sought to ban the wearing of buttons
expressing support for the troops on the ground that the buttons
signified approval of war. The “educational mission” argument would
give public school authorities a license to suppress speech on
political and social issues based on disagreement with the
viewpoint expressed. The argument, therefore, strikes at the very
heart of the First Amendment.
The public schools are invaluable and
beneficent institutions, but they are, after all, organs of the
State. When public school authorities regulate student speech, they
act as agents of the State; they do not stand in the shoes of the
students’ parents. It is a dangerous fiction to pretend that
parents simply delegate their authority—including their authority
to determine what their children may say and hear—to public school
authorities. It is even more dangerous to assume that such a
delegation of authority somehow strips public school authorities of
their status as agents of the State. Most parents, realistically,
have no choice but to send their children to a public school and
little ability to influence what occurs in the school. It is
therefore wrong to treat public school officials, for purposes
relevant to the First Amendment, as if they were private,
nongovernmental actors standing in loco parentis .
For these reasons, any argument for altering
the usual free speech rules in the public schools cannot rest on a
theory of delegation but must instead be based on some special
characteristic of the school setting. The special characteristic
that is relevant in this case is the threat to the physical safety
of students. School attendance can expose students to threats to
their physical safety that they would not otherwise face. Outside
of school, parents can attempt to protect their children in many
ways and may take steps to monitor and exercise control over the
persons with whom their children associate. Similarly, students,
when not in school, may be able to avoid threatening individuals
and situations. During school hours, however, parents are not
present to provide protection and guidance, and students’ movements
and their ability to choose the persons with whom they spend time
are severely restricted. Students may be compelled on a daily basis
to spend time at close quarters with other students who may do them
harm. Experience shows that schools can be places of special
danger.
In most settings, the First Amendment strongly
limits the government’s ability to suppress speech on the ground
that it presents a threat of violence. See Brandenburg v. Ohio , 395
U. S. 444 (1969) (per curiam) . But due to the special
features of the school environment, school officials must have
greater authority to intervene before speech leads to violence.
And, in most cases, Tinker ’s “substantial disruption”
standard permits school officials to step in before actual violence
erupts. See 393 U. S., at 508–509.
Speech advocating illegal drug use poses a
threat to student safety that is just as serious, if not always as
immediately obvious. As we have recognized in the past and as the
opinion of the Court today details, illegal drug use presents a
grave and in many ways unique threat to the physical safety of
students. I therefore conclude that the public schools may ban
speech advocating illegal drug use. But I regard such regulation as
standing at the far reaches of what the First Amendment permits. I
join the opinion of the Court with the understanding that the
opinion does not endorse any further extension. THOMAS, J., CONCURRING MORSE V. FREDERICK 551 U. S. ____ (2007) SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES NO. 06-278 DEBORAH MORSE, et al., PETITIONERS v. JOSEPH FREDERICK
on writ of certiorari to the united states court of
appeals for the ninth circuit
[June 25, 2007]
Justice Thomas, concurring.
The Court today decides that a
public school may prohibit speech advocating illegal drug use. I
agree and therefore join its opinion in full. I write separately to
state my view that the standard set forth in Tinker v. Des Moines Independent Community School Dist. , 393 U. S. 503 (1969), is
without basis in the Constitution.
I
The First Amendment states that
“Congress shall make no law … abridging the freedom of speech.” As
this Court has previously observed, the First Amendment was not
originally understood to permit all sorts of speech; instead,
“[t]here are certain well-defined and narrowly limited classes of
speech, the prevention and punishment of which have never been
thought to raise any Constitutional problem.” Chaplinsky v. New Hampshire , 315 U. S. 568 , 571–572
(1942); see also Cox v. Louisiana , 379 U. S. 536 , 554
(1965). In my view, the history of public education suggests that
the First Amendment, as originally understood, does not protect
student speech in public schools. Although colonial schools were
exclusively private, public education proliferated in the early
1800’s. By the time the States ratified the Fourteenth Amendment,
public schools had become relatively common. W. Reese, America’s
Public Schools: From the Common School to “No Child Left Behind”
11–12 (2005) (hereinafter Reese). If students in public schools
were originally understood as having free-speech rights, one would
have expected 19th-century public schools to have respected those
rights and courts to have enforced them.[ Footnote 1 ] They did not.
A
During the colonial era, private
schools and tutors offered the only educational opportunities for
children, and teachers managed classrooms with an iron hand. R.
Butts & L. Cremin, A History of Education in American Culture
121, 123 (1953) (hereinafter Butts). Public schooling arose, in
part, as a way to educate those too poor to afford private schools.
See Kaestle & Vinovskis, From Apron Strings to ABCs: Parents,
Children, and Schooling in Nineteenth-Century Massachusetts, 84 Am.
J. Sociology S39, S49 (Supp. 1978). Because public schools were
initially created as substitutes for private schools, when States
developed public education systems in the early 1800’s, no one
doubted the government’s ability to educate and discipline children
as private schools did. Like their private counterparts, early
public schools were not places for freewheeling debates or
exploration of competing ideas. Rather, teachers instilled “a core
of common values” in students and taught them self-control. Reese
23; A. Potter & G. Emerson, The School and the Schoolmaster: A
Manual 125 (1843) (“By its discipline it contributes, insensibly,
to generate a spirit of subordination to lawful authority, a power
of self-control, and a habit of postponing present indulgence to a
greater future good …”); D. Parkerson & J. Parkerson, The
Emergence of the Common School in the U. S. Countryside 6 (1998)
(hereinafter Parkerson) (noting that early education activists,
such as Benjamin Rush, believed public schools “help[ed] control
the innate selfishness of the individual”). Teachers instilled these
values not only by presenting ideas but also through strict
discipline. Butts 274–275. Schools punished students for behavior
the school considered disrespectful or wrong. Parkerson 65 (noting
that children were punished for idleness, talking, profanity, and
slovenliness). Rules of etiquette were enforced, and courteous
behavior was demanded. Reese 40. To meet their educational
objectives, schools required absolute obedience. C. Northend, The
Teacher’s Assistant or Hints and Methods in School Discipline and
Instruction 44, 52 (1865) (“I consider a school judiciously
governed, where order prevails; where the strictest sense of
propriety is manifested by the pupils towards the teacher, and
towards each other . . .” (internal quotation marks
omitted)).[ Footnote 2 ] In short, in the earliest public schools,
teachers taught, and students listened. Teachers commanded, and
students obeyed. Teachers did not rely solely on the power of ideas
to persuade; they relied on discipline to maintain order. B Through the legal doctrine of
in loco parentis , courts upheld the right of schools to
discipline students, to enforce rules, and to maintain
order.[ Footnote 3 ] Rooted in
the English common law, in loco parentis originally
governed the legal rights and obligations of tutors and private
schools. 1 W. Blackstone, Commentaries on the Laws of England 441
(1765) (“[A parent] may also delegate part of his parental
authority, during his life, to the tutor or schoolmaster of his
child; who is then in loco parentis , and has such a
portion of the power of the parent committed to his charge, viz.
that of restraint and correction, as may be necessary to answer the
purposes for which he is employed”). Chancellor James Kent noted
the acceptance of the doctrine as part of American law in the early
19th century. 2 J. Kent, Commentaries on American Law *205,
*206–*207 (“So the power allowed by law to the parent over the
person of the child may be delegated to a tutor or instructor, the
better to accomplish the purpose of education”).
As early as 1837, state courts
applied the in loco parentis principle to public
schools:
“One of the most sacred duties of parents, is to
train up and qualify their children, for becoming useful and
virtuous members of society; this duty cannot be effectually
performed without the ability to command obedience, to control
stubbornness, to quicken diligence, and to reform bad habits
… . The teacher is the substitute of the parent; … and in the
exercise of these delegated duties, is invested with his power.” State v. Pendergrass , 19 N. C. 365, 365–366,
(1837).
Applying in loco parentis , the judiciary
was reluctant to interfere in the routine business of school
administration, allowing schools and teachers to set and enforce
rules and to maintain order. Sheehan v. Sturges, 53 Conn. 481, 483–484, 2 A. 841, 842 (1885). Thus, in the early
years of public schooling, schools and teachers had considerable
discretion in disciplinary matters:
“To accomplish th[e] desirable ends [of teaching
self-restraint, obedience, and other civic virtues], the master of
a school is necessarily invested with much discretionary
power… . He must govern these pupils, quicken the slothful,
spur the indolent, restrain the impetuous, and control the
stubborn. He must make rules, give commands, and punish
disobedience. What rules, what commands, and what punishments shall
be imposed, are necessarily largely within the discretion of the
master, where none are defined by the school board.” Patterson v. Nutter , 78 Me. 509, 511, 7 A. 273,
274 (1886).[ Footnote 4 ]
A review of the case law shows
that in loco parentis allowed schools to regulate student
speech as well. Courts routinely preserved the rights of teachers
to punish speech that the school or teacher thought was contrary to
the interests of the school and its educational goals. For example,
the Vermont Supreme Court upheld the corporal punishment of a
student who called his teacher “Old Jack Seaver” in front
of other students. Lander v. Seaver , 32 Vt. 114,
115 (1859). The court explained its decision as follows:
“[L]anguage used to other scholars to stir up
disorder and subordination, or to heap odium and disgrace upon the
master; writings and pictures placed so as to suggest evil and
corrupt language, images and thoughts to the youth who must
frequent the school; all such or similar acts tend directly to
impair the usefulness of the school, the welfare of the scholars
and the authority of the master. By common consent and by the
universal custom in our New England schools, the master has always
been deemed to have the right to punish such offences. Such power
is essential to the preservation of order, decency, decorum and
good government in schools.” Id. , at 121.
Similarly, the California Court
of Appeal upheld the expulsion of a student who gave a speech
before the student body that criticized the administration for
having an unsafe building “because of the possibility of fire.” Wooster v. Sunderland , 27 Cal. App. 51, 52, 148
P. 959, (1915). The punishment was appropriate, the court stated,
because the speech “was intended to discredit and humiliate the
board in the eyes of the students, and tended to impair the
discipline of the school.” Id. , at 55, 148 P., at 960.
Likewise, the Missouri Supreme Court explained that a “rule which
forbade the use of profane language [and] quarrelling” “was not
only reasonable, but necessary to the orderly conduct of the
school.” Deskins v. Gose , 85 Mo. 485, 487, 488
(1885). And the Indiana Supreme Court upheld the punishment of a
student who made distracting demonstrations in class for “a breach
of good deportment.” Vanvactor v. State , 113 Ind.
276, 281, 15 N. E. 341, 343 (1888).[ Footnote 5 ]
The doctrine of in loco parentis limited the ability of schools to set rules and control their
classrooms in almost no way. It merely limited the imposition of
excessive physical punishment. In this area, the case law was
split. One line of cases specified that punishment was wholly
discretionary as long as the teacher did not act with legal malice
or cause permanent injury. E.g., Boyd v. State ,
88 Ala. 169, 170–172, 7 So. 268, 269 (1890) (allowing liability
where the “punishment inflicted is immoderate or excessive, and …
it was induced by legal malice, or wickedness of motive”). Another
line allowed courts to intervene where the corporal punishment was
“ clearly excessive.” E.g., Lander, supra , at 124.
Under both lines of cases, courts struck down only punishments that
were excessively harsh; they almost never questioned the
substantive restrictions on student conduct set by teachers and
schools. E.g., Sheehan , supra , at 483–484, 2 A.,
at 842; Gardner v. State , 4 Ind. 632, 635 (1853); Anderson v. State , 40 Tenn. 455, 456 (1859); Hardy v. James , 5 Ky. Op. 36 (1872).[ Footnote 6 ]
II Tinker effected a sea
change in students’ speech rights, extending them well beyond
traditional bounds. The case arose when a school punished several
students for wearing black armbands to school to protest the
Vietnam War. Tinker , 393 U. S., at 504. Determining that
the punishment infringed the students’ First Amendment rights, this
Court created a new standard for students’ freedom of speech in
public schools:
“[W]here there is no finding and no showing that
engaging in the forbidden conduct would materially and
substantially interfere with the requirements of appropriate
discipline in the operation of the school, the prohibition cannot
be sustained.” Id., at 509 (internal quotation marks
omitted).
Accordingly, unless a student’s speech would
disrupt the educational process, students had a fundamental right
to speak their minds (or wear their armbands)—even on matters the
school disagreed with or found objectionable. Ibid. (“[The
school] must be able to show that its action was caused by
something more than a mere desire to avoid the discomfort and
unpleasantness that always accompany an unpopular viewpoint”).
Justice Black dissented, criticizing the Court
for “subject[ing] all the public schools in the country to the
whims and caprices of their loudest-mouthed, but maybe not their
brightest, students.” Id. , at 525. He emphasized the
instructive purpose of schools: “[T]axpayers send children to
school on the premise that at their age they need to learn, not
teach.” Id. , at 522. In his view, the Court’s decision
“surrender[ed] control of the American public school system to
public school students.” Id. , at 526.
Of course, Tinker ’s reasoning
conflicted with the traditional understanding of the judiciary’s
role in relation to public schooling, a role limited by in loco
parentis . Perhaps for that reason, the Court has since scaled
back Tinker ’s standard, or rather set the standard aside
on an ad hoc basis. In Bethel School Dist. No. 403 v. Fraser , 478 U. S. 675 , 677, 678 (1986), a
public school suspended a student for delivering a speech that
contained “an elaborate, graphic, and explicit sexual metaphor.”
The Court of Appeals found that the speech caused no disruption
under the Tinker standard, and this Court did not question
that holding. 478 U. S., at 679–680. The Court nonetheless
permitted the school to punish the student because of the
objectionable content of his speech. Id. , at 685 (“A high
school assembly or classroom is no place for a sexually explicit
monologue directed towards an unsuspecting audience of teenage
students”). Signaling at least a partial break with Tinker , Fraser left the regulation of indecent
student speech to local schools.[ Footnote 7 ] 478 U. S., at 683.
Similarly, in Hazelwood School Dist. v. Kuhlmeier , 484 U. S. 260 (1988),
the Court made an exception to Tinker for school-sponsored
activities. The Court characterized newspapers and similar
school-sponsored activities “as part of the school curriculum” and
held that “[e]ducators are entitled to exercise greater control
over” these forms of student expression. 484 U. S., at 271.
Accordingly, the Court expressly refused to apply Tinker ’s
standard. 484 U. S., at 272–273. Instead, for school-sponsored
activities, the Court created a new standard that permitted school
regulations of student speech that are “reasonably related to
legitimate pedagogical concerns.” Id. , at 273.
Today, the Court creates another exception. In
doing so, we continue to distance ourselves from Tinker ,
but we neither overrule it nor offer an explanation of when it
operates and when it does not. Ante , at 10–14. I am afraid
that our jurisprudence now says that students have a right to speak
in schools except when they don’t—a standard continuously developed
through litigation against local schools and their administrators.
In my view, petitioners could prevail for a much simpler reason: As
originally understood, the Constitution does not afford students a
right to free speech in public schools.
III
In light of the history of
American public education, it cannot seriously be suggested that
the First Amendment “freedom of speech” encompasses a student’s
right to speak in public schools. Early public schools gave total
control to teachers, who expected obedience and respect from
students. And courts routinely deferred to schools’ authority to
make rules and to discipline students for violating those rules.
Several points are clear: (1) under in loco parentis ,
speech rules and other school rules were treated identically; (2)
the in loco parentis doctrine imposed almost no limits on
the types of rules that a school could set while students were in
school; and (3) schools and teachers had tremendous discretion in
imposing punishments for violations of those rules.
It might be suggested that the
early school speech cases dealt only with slurs and profanity. But
that criticism does not withstand scrutiny. First, state courts
repeatedly reasoned that schools had discretion to impose
discipline to maintain order. The substance of the student’s speech
or conduct played no part in the analysis. Second, some cases
involved punishment for speech on weightier matters, for instance a
speech criticizing school administrators for creating a fire
hazard. See Wooster , 27 Cal. App., at 52–53, 148 P., at
959. Yet courts refused to find an exception to in loco
parentis even for this advocacy of public safety.
To be sure, our educational system faces
administrative and pedagogical challenges different from those
faced by 19th-century schools. And the idea of treating children as
though it were still the 19th century would find little support
today. But I see no constitutional imperative requiring public
schools to allow all student speech. Parents decide whether to send
their children to public schools. Cf. Hamilton v. Regents of Univ. of Cal. , 293 U. S. 245 , 262
(1934) (“California has not drafted or called them to attend the
university. They are seeking education offered by the State and at
the same time insisting that they be excluded from the prescribed
course …”); id. , at 266 (Cardozo, J., concurring). If
parents do not like the rules imposed by those schools, they can
seek redress in school boards or legislatures; they can send their
children to private schools or home school them; or they can simply
move. Whatever rules apply to student speech in public schools,
those rules can be challenged by parents in the political
process.
In place of that democratic regime, Tinker substituted judicial oversight of the day-to-day
affairs of public schools. The Tinker Court made little
attempt to ground its holding in the history of education or in the
original understanding of the First Amendment.[ Footnote 8 ] Instead, it imposed a new and
malleable standard: Schools could not inhibit student speech unless
it “substantially interfere[d] with the requirements of appropriate
discipline in the operation of the school.” 393 U. S., at 509
(internal quotation marks omitted). Inherent in the application of
that standard are judgment calls about what constitutes
interference and what constitutes appropriate discipline. See id. , at 517–518 (Black, J., dissenting) (arguing that the
armbands in fact caused a disruption). Historically, courts
reasoned that only local school districts were entitled to make
those calls. The Tinker Court usurped that traditional
authority for the judiciary.
And because Tinker utterly ignored
the history of public education, courts (including this one)
routinely find it necessary to create ad hoc exceptions to its
central premise. This doctrine of exceptions creates confusion
without fixing the underlying problem by returning to first
principles. Just as I cannot accept Tinker ’s standard, I
cannot subscribe to Kuhlmeier ’s alternative. Local school
boards, not the courts, should determine what pedagogical interests
are “legitimate” and what rules “reasonably relat[e]” to those
interests. 484 U. S., at 273.
Justice Black may not have been “a prophet or
the son of a prophet,” but his dissent in Tinker has
proved prophetic. 393 U. S., at 525. In the name of the First
Amendment, Tinker has undermined the traditional authority
of teachers to maintain order in public schools. “Once a society
that generally respected the authority of teachers, deferred to
their judgment, and trusted them to act in the best interest of
school children, we now accept defiance, disrespect, and disorder
as daily occurrences in many of our public schools.” Dupre, Should
Students Have Constitutional Rights? Keeping Order in the Public
Schools, 65 Geo. Wash. L. Rev. 49, 50 (1996). We need look no
further than this case for an example: Frederick asserts a
constitutional right to utter at a school event what is either
“[g]ibberish,” ante , at 7, or an open call to use illegal
drugs. To elevate such impertinence to the status of constitutional
protection would be farcical and would indeed be to “surrender
control of the American public school system to public school
students.” Tinker , supra , at 526 (Black, J.,
dissenting).
* * *
I join the Court’s opinion
because it erodes Tinker ’s hold in the realm of student
speech, even though it does so by adding to the patchwork of
exceptions to the Tinker standard. I think the better
approach is to dispense with Tinker altogether, and given
the opportunity, I would do so. Footnote 1 Although the First Amendment did not apply to
the States until at least the ratification of the Fourteenth
Amendment, most state constitutions included free-speech guarantees
during the period when public education expanded. E.g. ,
Cal. Const., Art. I, §9 (1849); Conn. Const., Art. I, §5
(1818); Ind. Const., Art. I, §9 (1816). Footnote 2 Even at the college level, strict obedience
was required of students: “The English model fostered absolute
institutional control of students by faculty both inside and
outside the classroom. At all the early American schools, students
lived and worked under a vast array of rules and restrictions. This
one-sided relationship between the student and the college mirrored
the situation at English schools where the emphasis on hierarchical
authority stemmed from medieval Christian theology and the unique
legal privileges afforded the university corporation.” Note, 44
Vand. L. Rev. 1135, 1140 (1991) (footnote omitted). Footnote 3 My discussion is limited to elementary and
secondary education. In these settings, courts have applied the
doctrine of in loco parentis regardless of the student’s
age. See, e.g., Stevens v. Fassett, 27 Me. 266,
281 (1847) (holding that a student over the age of 21 is “liab[le]
to punishment” on the same terms as other students if he
“present[s] himself as a pupil, [and] is received and instructed by
the master”); State v. Mizner , 45 Iowa 248,
250–252 (1876) (same); Sheehan v. Sturges , 53
Conn. 481, 484, 2 A. 841, 843 (1885) (same). Therefore, the fact
that Frederick was 18 and not a minor under Alaska law, 439
F. 3d 1114, 1117, n. 4 (CA9 2006), is
inconsequential. Footnote 4 Even courts that did not favor the broad
discretion given to teachers to impose corporal punishment
recognized that the law provided it. Cooper v. McJunkin , 4 Ind. 290, 291 (1853) (stating that “[t]he
public seem to cling to a despotism in the government of schools
which has been discarded everywhere else”). Footnote 5 Courts also upheld punishment when children
refused to speak after being requested to do so by their teachers.
See Board of Ed. v. Helston , 32 Ill. App. 300,
305–307 (1890) (upholding the suspension of a boy who refused to
provide information about who had defaced the school building); cf. Sewell v. Board of Ed. of Defiance Union School, 29 Ohio St. 89, 92 (1876) (upholding the suspension of a student
who failed to complete a rhetorical exercise in the allotted
time). Footnote 6 At least nominally, this Court has continued
to recognize the applicability of the in loco parentis doctrine to public schools. See Vernonia School Dist. 47J v. Acton , 515 U. S. 646 , 654, 655
(1995) (“Traditionally at common law, and still today,
unemancipated minors lack some of the most fundamental rights of
self-determination … . They are subject … to the control of
their parents or guardians. When parents place minor children in
private schools for their education, the teachers and
administrators of those schools stand in loco parentis over the children entrusted to them” (citation omitted)); Bethel School Dist. No. 403 v. Fraser , 478 U. S. 675 , 684 (1986) (“These
cases recognize the obvious concern on the part of parents, and
school authorities acting in loco parentis , to protect
children—especially in a captive audience—from exposure to sexually
explicit, indecent, or lewd speech”). Footnote 7 Distancing itself from Tinker ’s
approach, the Fraser Court quoted Justice Black’s dissent
in Tinker . 478 U. S., at 686. Footnote 8 The Tinker Court claimed that “[i]t
can hardly be argued that either students or teachers shed their
constitutional rights to freedom of speech or expression at the
schoolhouse gate. This has been the unmistakable holding of this
Court for almost 50 years.” 393 U. S., at 506. But the cases the
Court cited in favor of that bold proposition do not support it. Tinker chiefly relies upon Meyer v. Nebraska , 262 U. S. 390 (1923)
(striking down a law prohibiting the teaching of German). However, Meyer involved a challenge by a private school, id. , at 396, and the Meyer Court was quick to
note that no “challenge [has] been made of the State’s power to
prescribe a curriculum for institutions which it supports.” Id. , at 402. Meyer provides absolutely no support
for the proposition that that free-speech rights apply within
schools operated by the State. And notably, Meyer relied
as its chief support on the Lochner v. New York, 198 U. S. 45 (1905), line of cases, 262 U. S., at 399, a line of cases that has
long been criticized, United Haulers Assn., Inc. v. Oneida-Herkimer Solid Waste Management Authority , 550 U.
S. ___ (2007). Tinker also relied on Pierce v. Society of Sisters , 268 U. S. 510 (1925). Pierce has nothing to say on this issue either. Pierce simply upheld the right of parents to send their
children to private school. Id ., at 535. STEVENS, J., DISSENTING MORSE V. FREDERICK 551 U. S. ____ (2007) SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES NO. 06-278 DEBORAH MORSE, et al., PETITIONERS v. JOSEPH FREDERICK
on writ of certiorari to the united states court of
appeals for the ninth circuit
[June 25, 2007]
Justice Stevens, with whom
Justice Souter and Justice Ginsburg join, dissenting.
A significant fact barely
mentioned by the Court sheds a revelatory light on the motives of
both the students and the principal of Juneau-Douglas High School
(JDHS). On January 24, 2002, the Olympic Torch Relay gave those
Alaska residents a rare chance to appear on national television. As
Joseph Frederick repeatedly explained, he did not address the
curious message—“BONG HiTS 4 JESUS”—to his fellow students. He just
wanted to get the camera crews’ attention. Moreover, concern about
a nationwide evaluation of the conduct of the JDHS student body
would have justified the principal’s decision to remove an
attention-grabbing 14-foot banner, even if it had merely proclaimed
“Glaciers Melt!”
I agree with the Court that the principal
should not be held liable for pulling down Frederick’s banner. See Harlow v. Fitzgerald , 457 U. S. 800 , 818
(1982). I would hold, however, that the school’s interest in
protecting its students from exposure to speech “reasonably
regarded as promoting illegal drug use,” ante , at 1,
cannot justify disciplining Frederick for his attempt to make an
ambiguous statement to a television audience simply because it
contained an oblique reference to drugs. The First Amendment
demands more, indeed, much more.
The Court holds otherwise only after laboring
to establish two uncontroversial propositions: first, that the
constitutional rights of students in school settings are not
coextensive with the rights of adults, see ante , at 8–12;
and second, that deterring drug use by schoolchildren is a valid
and terribly important interest, see ante , at 12–14. As to
the first, I take the Court’s point that the message on Frederick’s
banner is not necessarily protected speech, even though it
unquestionably would have been had the banner been unfurled
elsewhere. As to the second, I am willing to assume that the Court
is correct that the pressing need to deter drug use supports JDHS’s
rule prohibiting willful conduct that expressly “advocates the use
of substances that are illegal to minors.” App. to Pet. for Cert.
53a. But it is a gross non sequitur to draw from these two
unremarkable propositions the remarkable conclusion that the school
may suppress student speech that was never meant to persuade anyone
to do anything.
In my judgment, the First Amendment protects
student speech if the message itself neither violates a permissible
rule nor expressly advocates conduct that is illegal and harmful to
students. This nonsense banner does neither, and the Court does
serious violence to the First Amendment in upholding—indeed,
lauding—a school’s decision to punish Frederick for expressing a
view with which it disagreed.
I
In December 1965, we were engaged
in a controversial war, a war that “divided this country as few
other issues ever have.” Tinker v. Des Moines
Independent Community School Dist. , 393 U. S. 503 , 524
(1969) (Black, J., dissenting). Having learned that some students
planned to wear black armbands as a symbol of opposition to the
country’s involvement in Vietnam, officials of the Des Moines
public school district adopted a policy calling for the suspension
of any student who refused to remove the armband. As we explained
when we considered the propriety of that policy, “[t]he school
officials banned and sought to punish petitioners for a silent,
passive expression of opinion, unaccompanied by any disorder or
disturbance on the part of petitioners.” Id., at 508. The
district justified its censorship on the ground that it feared that
the expression of a controversial and unpopular opinion would
generate disturbances. Because the school officials had
insufficient reason to believe that those disturbances would
“materially and substantially interfere with the requirements of
discipline in the operation of the school,” we found the
justification for the rule to lack any foundation and therefore
held that the censorship violated the First Amendment. Id., at 509 (internal quotation marks omitted).
Justice Harlan dissented, but not
because he thought the school district could censor a message with
which it disagreed. Rather, he would have upheld the district’s
rule only because the students never cast doubt on the district’s
anti-disruption justification by proving that the rule was
motivated “by other than legitimate school concerns—for example, a
desire to prohibit the expression of an unpopular point of view
while permitting expression of the dominant opinion.” Id., at 526.
Two cardinal First Amendment principles
animate both the Court’s opinion in Tinker and Justice
Harlan’s dissent. First, censorship based on the content of speech,
par- ticularly censorship that depends on the viewpoint of the
speaker, is subject to the most rigorous burden of
justification:
“Discrimination against speech because of its
message is presumed to be unconstitutional… . When the
government targets not subject matter, but particular views taken
by speakers on a subject, the violation of the First Amendment is
all the more blatant. Viewpoint discrimination is thus an egregious
form of content discrimination. The government must abstain from
regulating speech when the specific motivating ideology or the
opinion or perspective of the speaker is the rationale for the
restriction.” Rosenberger v. Rector and Visitors of
Univ. of Va. , 515 U. S. 819 , 828–829
(1995) (citation omitted).
Second, punishing someone for advocating illegal
conduct is constitutional only when the advocacy is likely to
provoke the harm that the government seeks to avoid. See Brandenburg v. Ohio , 395 U. S. 444 , 449
(1969) (per curiam) (distinguishing “mere advocacy” of
illegal conduct from “incitement to imminent lawless action”).
However necessary it may be to modify those
principles in the school setting, Tinker affirmed their
continuing vitality. 393 U. S., at 509 (“In order for the State in
the person of school officials to justify prohibition of a
particular expression of opinion, it must be able to show that its
action was caused by something more than a mere desire to avoid the
discomfort and unpleasantness that always accompany an unpopular
viewpoint. Certainly where there is no finding and no showing that
engaging in that conduct would materially and substantially
interfere with the requirements of appropriate discipline in the
operation of the school, the prohibition cannot be sustained”
(internal quotation marks omitted)). As other federal courts have
long recognized, under Tinker ,
“regulation of student speech is generally
permissible only when the speech would substantially disrupt or
interfere with the work of the school or the rights of other
students. … Tinker requires a specific and significant
fear of disruption, not just some remote apprehension of
disturbance .” Saxe v. State College Area School
Dist. , 240 F. 3d 200, 211 (CA3 2001) (Alito, J.) (emphasis
added).
Yet today the Court fashions a
test that trivializes the two cardinal principles upon which Tinker rests. See ante , at 14 (“[S]chools [may]
restrict student expression that they reasonably regard as
promoting illegal drug use”). The Court’s test invites stark
viewpoint discrimination. In this case, for example, the principal
has unabashedly acknowledged that she disciplined Frederick because
she disagreed with the pro-drug viewpoint she ascribed to the
message on the banner, see App. 25—a viewpoint, incidentally, that
Frederick has disavowed, see id., at 28. Unlike our recent
decision in Tennessee Secondary School Athletic Assn. v. Brentwood Academy , 551 U. S. ___, ___ (2007) (slip op., at
3), see also ante , at 3 (Alito, J., concurring), the
Court’s holding in this case strikes at “the heart of the First
Amendment” because it upholds a punishment meted out on the basis
of a listener’s disagreement with her understanding (or, more
likely, misunderstanding) of the speaker’s viewpoint. “If there is
a bedrock principle underlying the First Amendment, it is that the
Government may not prohibit the expression of an idea simply
because society finds the idea itself offensive or disagreeable.” Texas v. Johnson , 491 U. S. 397 , 414
(1989).
It is also perfectly clear that “promoting
illegal drug use,” ante , at 14, comes nowhere close to
proscribable “incitement to imminent lawless action.” Brandenburg , 395 U. S., at 447. Encouraging drug use might
well increase the likelihood that a listener will try an illegal
drug, but that hardly justifies censorship:
“Every denunciation of existing law tends in some
measure to increase the probability that there will be violation of
it. Condonation of a breach enhances the probability. Expressions
of approval add to the probability. … Advocacy of law-breaking
heightens it still further. But even advocacy of violation, however
reprehensible morally, is not a justification for denying free
speech where the advocacy falls short of incitement and there is
nothing to indicate that the advocacy would be immediately acted
upon.” Whitney v. California , 274 U. S. 357 , 376 (1927) (Brandeis,
J., concurring).
No one seriously maintains that drug advocacy (much
less Frederick’s ridiculous sign) comes within the vanishingly
small category of speech that can be prohibited because of its
feared consequences. Such advocacy, to borrow from Justice Holmes,
“ha[s] no chance of starting a present conflagration.” Gitlow v. New York , 268 U. S. 652 , 673
(1925) (dissenting opinion).
II
The Court rejects outright these
twin foundations of Tinker because, in its view, the
unusual importance of protecting children from the scourge of drugs
supports a ban on all speech in the school environment that
promotes drug use. Whether or not such a rule is sensible as a
matter of policy, carving out pro-drug speech for uniquely harsh
treatment finds no support in our case law and is inimical to the
values protected by the First Amendment.[ Footnote 1 ] See infra , at 14–16.
I will nevertheless assume for
the sake of argument that the school’s concededly powerful interest
in protecting its students adequately supports its restriction on
“any assembly or public expression that . . . advocates the use of
substances that are illegal to minors … .” App. to Pet. for
Cert. 53a. Given that the relationship between schools and students
“is custodial and tutelary, permitting a degree of supervision and
control that could not be exercised over free adults,” Vernonia
School Dist. 47J v. Acton , 515 U. S. 646 , 655
(1995), it might well be appropriate to tolerate some targeted
viewpoint discrimination in this unique setting. And while
conventional speech may be restricted only when likely to “incit[e]
imminent lawless action,” Brandenburg , 395 U. S., at 449,
it is possible that our rigid imminence requirement ought to be
relaxed at schools. See Bethel School Dist. No. 403 v. Fraser , 478
U. S. 675 , 682 (1986) (“[T]he constitutional rights of students
in public school are not automatically coextensive with the rights
of adults in other settings”).
But it is one thing to restrict speech that advocates drug use. It is another thing entirely to
prohibit an obscure message with a drug theme that a third party
subjectively—and not very reasonably—thinks is tantamount to
express advocacy. Cf. Masses Publishing Co. v. Patten , 244 F. 535, 540, 541 (SDNY 1917) (Hand, J.)
(distinguishing sharply between “agitation, legitimate as such” and
“the direct advocacy” of unlawful conduct). Even the school
recognizes the paramount need to hold the line between, on the one
hand, non-disruptive speech that merely expresses a viewpoint that
is unpopular or contrary to the school’s preferred message, and on
the other hand, advocacy of an illegal or unsafe course of conduct.
The district’s prohibition of drug advocacy is a gloss on a more
general rule that is otherwise quite tolerant of non-disruptive
student speech:
“Students will not be disturbed in the exercise of
their constitutionally guaranteed rights to assemble peaceably and
to express ideas and opinions, privately or publicly, provided that
their activities do not infringe on the rights of others and do not
interfere with the operation of the educational program.
“The Board will not permit the conduct on
school premises of any willful activity … that interferes with the
orderly operation of the educational program or offends the rights
of others. The Board specifically prohibits … any assembly or
public expression that . . . advocates the use of substances that
are illegal to minors … .” App. to Pet. for Cert. 53a;
see also ante , at 3 (quoting rule in part).
There is absolutely no evidence that Frederick’s
banner’s reference to drug paraphernalia “willful[ly]” infringed on
anyone’s rights or interfered with any of the school’s educational
programs.[ Footnote 2 ] On its
face, then, the rule gave Frederick wide berth “to express [his]
ideas and opinions” so long as they did not amount to “advoca[cy]”
of drug use. Ibid. If the school’s rule is, by hypothesis,
a valid one, it is valid only insofar as it scrupulously preserves
adequate space for constitutionally protected speech. When First
Amendment rights are at stake, a rule that “sweep[s] in a great
variety of conduct under a general and indefinite characterization”
may not leave “too wide a discretion in its application.” Cantwell v. Connecticut , 310 U. S. 296 , 308
(1940). Therefore, just as we insisted in Tinker that the
school establish some likely connection between the armbands and
their feared consequences, so too JDHS must show that Frederick’s
supposed advocacy stands a meaningful chance of making
otherwise-abstemious students try marijuana.
But instead of demanding that the school make
such a showing, the Court punts. Figuring out just how it
punts is tricky; “[t]he mode of analysis [it] employ[s] is not
entirely clear,” see ante , at 9. On occasion, the Court
suggests it is deferring to the principal’s “reasonable” judgment
that Frederick’s sign qualified as drug advocacy.[ Footnote 3 ] At other times, the Court seems
to say that it thinks the banner’s message constitutes
express advocacy.[ Footnote 4 ]
Either way, its approach is indefensible.
To the extent the Court defers to the
principal’s ostensibly reasonable judgment, it abdicates its
constitutional responsibility. The beliefs of third parties,
reasonable or otherwise, have never dictated which messages amount
to proscribable advocacy. Indeed, it would be a strange
constitutional doctrine that would allow the prohibition of only
the narrowest category of speech advocating unlawful conduct, see Brandenburg , 395 U. S., at 447–448, yet would permit a
listener’s perceptions to determine which speech deserved
constitutional protection.[ Footnote
5 ]
Such a peculiar doctrine is alien to our case
law. In Abrams v. United States , 250 U. S. 616 (1919),
this Court affirmed the conviction of a group of Russian “rebels,
revolutionists, [and] anarchists,” id ., at 617–618
(internal quotation marks omitted), on the ground that the leaflets
they distributed were thought to “incite, provoke, and encourage
resistance to the United States,” id. , at 617 (internal
quotation marks omitted). Yet Justice Holmes’ dissent—which has
emphatically carried the day—never inquired into the reasonableness
of the United States’ judgment that the leaflets would likely
undermine the war effort. The dissent instead ridiculed that
judgment: “nobody can suppose that the surreptitious publishing of
a silly leaflet by an unknown man, without more, would present any
immediate danger that its opinions would hinder the success of the
government arms or have any appreciable tendency to do so.” Id., at 628. In Thomas v. Collins , 323 U. S. 516 (1945) (opinion for the Court by Rutledge, J.), we overturned the
conviction of a union organizer who violated a restraining order
forbidding him from exhorting workers. In so doing, we held that
the distinction between advocacy and incitement could not depend on
how one of those workers might have understood the organizer’s
speech. That would “pu[t] the speaker in these circumstances wholly
at the mercy of the varied understanding of his hearers and
consequently of whatever inference may be drawn as to his intent
and meaning.” Id ., at 535. In Cox v. Louisiana , 379 U. S. 536 , 543
(1965), we vacated a civil rights leader’s conviction for
disturbing the peace, even though a Baton Rouge sheriff had
“deem[ed]” the leader’s “appeal to … students to sit in at the
lunch counters to be ‘inflammatory.’ ” We never asked if the
sheriff’s in-person, on-the-spot judgment was “reasonable.” Even in Fraser , we made no inquiry into whether the school
administrators reasonably thought the student’s speech was obscene
or profane; we rather satisfied ourselves that “[t]he pervasive
sexual innuendo in Fraser’s speech was plainly offensive to both
teachers and students—indeed, to any mature person.” 478 U. S., at
683. Cf. Bose Corp. v. Consumers Union of United
States, Inc. , 466 U. S. 485 , 499
(1984) (“[I]n cases raising First Amendment issues we have
repeatedly held that an appellate court has an obligation to make
an independent examination of the whole record in order to make
sure that the judgment does not constitute a forbidden intrusion on
the field of free expression” (internal quotation marks
omitted)).[ Footnote 6 ]
To the extent the Court independently finds
that “BONG HiTS 4 JESUS” objectively amounts to the
advocacy of illegal drug use—in other words, that it can most reasonably be interpreted as such—that conclusion
practically refutes itself. This is a nonsense message, not
advocacy. The Court’s feeble effort to divine its hidden meaning is
strong evidence of that. Ante , at 7 (positing that the
banner might mean, alternatively, “ ‘[Take] bong hits,’ ”
“ ‘bong hits [are a good thing],’ ” or “ ‘[we take]
bong hits’ ”). Frederick’s credible and uncontradicted
explanation for the message—he just wanted to get on television—is
also relevant because a speaker who does not intend to persuade his
audience can hardly be said to be advocating anything.[ Footnote 7 ] But most importantly, it takes
real imagination to read a “cryptic” message (the Court’s
characterization, not mine, see ibid., at 6) with a
slanting drug reference as an incitement to drug use. Admittedly,
some high school students (including those who use drugs) are dumb.
Most students, however, do not shed their brains at the schoolhouse
gate, and most students know dumb advocacy when they see it. The
notion that the message on this banner would actually persuade
either the average student or even the dumbest one to change his or
her behavior is most implausible. That the Court believes such a
silly message can be proscribed as advocacy underscores the novelty
of its position, and suggests that the principle it articulates has
no stopping point.
Even if advocacy could somehow be wedged into
Frederick’s obtuse reference to marijuana, that advocacy was at
best subtle and ambiguous. There is abundant precedent, including
another opinion The Chief Justice announces today, for the
proposition that when the “First Amendment is implicated, the tie
goes to the speaker,” Federal Election Comm’n v. Wisconsin Right to Life, Inc. , 551 U. S. ___ (2007) (slip
op., at 21) and that “when it comes to defining what speech
qualifies as the functional equivalent of express advocacy … we
give the benefit of the doubt to speech, not censorship,” post, at 29. If this were a close case, the tie would have
to go to Frederick’s speech, not to the principal’s strained
reading of his quixotic message.
Among other things, the Court’s ham-handed,
categorical approach is deaf to the constitutional imperative to
permit unfettered debate, even among high-school students, about
the wisdom of the war on drugs or of legalizing marijuana for
medicinal use.[ Footnote 8 ] See Tinker , 393 U. S., at 511 (“[Students] may not be confined
to the expression of those sentiments that are officially
approved”). If Frederick’s stupid reference to marijuana can in the
Court’s view justify censorship, then high school students
everywhere could be forgiven for zipping their mouths about drugs
at school lest some “reasonable” observer censor and then punish
them for promoting drugs. See also ante , at 2 (Breyer, J.,
concurring in judgment in part and dissenting in part).
Consider, too, that the school district’s rule
draws no distinction between alcohol and marijuana, but applies
evenhandedly to all “substances that are illegal to minors.” App.
to Pet. for Cert. 53a; see also App. 83 (expressly defining
“ ‘drugs’ ” to include “all alcoholic beverages”). Given
the tragic consequences of teenage alcohol consumption—drinking
causes far more fatal accidents than the misuse of marijuana—the
school district’s interest in deterring teenage alcohol use is at
least comparable to its interest in preventing marijuana use. Under
the Court’s reasoning, must the First Amendment give way whenever a
school seeks to punish a student for any speech mentioning beer, or
indeed anything else that might be deemed risky to teenagers? While
I find it hard to believe the Court would support punishing
Frederick for flying a “WINE SiPS 4 JESUS” banner—which could quite
reasonably be construed either as a protected religious message or
as a pro-alcohol message—the breathtaking sweep of its opinion
suggests it would.
III
Although this case began with a
silly, nonsensical banner, it ends with the Court inventing out of
whole cloth a special First Amendment rule permitting the
censorship of any student speech that mentions drugs, at least so
long as someone could perceive that speech to contain a latent
pro-drug message. Our First Amendment jurisprudence has identified
some categories of expression that are less deserving of protection
than others—fighting words, obscenity, and commercial speech, to
name a few. Rather than reviewing our opinions discussing such
categories, I mention two personal recollections that have no doubt
influenced my conclusion that it would be profoundly unwise to
create special rules for speech about drug and alcohol use.
The Vietnam War is remembered
today as an unpopular war. During its early stages, however, “the
dominant opinion” that Justice Harlan mentioned in his Tinker dissent regarded opposition to the war as
unpatriotic, if not treason. 393 U. S., at 526. That dominant
opinion strongly supported the prosecution of several of those who
demonstrated in Grant Park during the 1968 Democratic Convention in
Chicago, see United States v. Dellinger , 472
F. 2d 340 (CA7 1972), and the vilification of vocal opponents
of the war like Julian Bond, cf. Bond v. Floyd , 385 U. S. 116 (1966). In 1965, when the Des Moines students wore their armbands,
the school district’s fear that they might “start an argument or
cause a disturbance” was well founded. Tinker , 393 U. S.,
at 508. Given that context, there is special force to the Court’s
insistence that “our Constitution says we must take that risk; and
our history says that it is this sort of hazardous freedom—this
kind of openness—that is the basis of our national strength and of
the independence and vigor of Americans who grow up and live in
this relatively permissive, often disputatious, society.” Id., at 508–509 (citation omitted). As we now know, the
then-dominant opinion about the Vietnam War was not etched in
stone.
Reaching back still further, the current
dominant opinion supporting the war on drugs in general, and our
antimarijuana laws in particular, is reminiscent of the opinion
that supported the nationwide ban on alcohol consumption when I was
a student. While alcoholic beverages are now regarded as ordinary
articles of commerce, their use was then condemned with the same
moral fervor that now supports the war on drugs. The ensuing change
in public opinion occurred much more slowly than the relatively
rapid shift in Americans’ views on the Vietnam War, and progressed
on a state-by-state basis over a period of many years. But just as
prohibition in the 1920’s and early 1930’s was secretly questioned
by thousands of otherwise law-abiding patrons of bootleggers and
speakeasies, today the actions of literally millions of otherwise
law-abiding users of marijuana,[ Footnote 9 ] and of the majority of voters in each of the
several States that tolerate medicinal uses of the
product,[ Footnote 10 ] lead
me to wonder whether the fear of disapproval by those in the
majority is silencing opponents of the war on drugs. Surely our
national experience with alcohol should make us wary of dampening
speech suggesting—however inarticulately—that it would be better to
tax and regulate marijuana than to persevere in a futile effort to
ban its use entirely.
Even in high school, a rule that permits only
one point of view to be expressed is less likely to produce correct
answers than the open discussion of countervailing views. Whitney , 274 U. S., at 377 (Brandeis, J., concurring); Abrams , 250 U. S., at 630 (Holmes, J., dissenting); Tinker , 393 U. S., at 512. In the national debate about a
serious issue, it is the expression of the minority’s viewpoint
that most demands the protection of the First Amendment. Whatever
the better policy may be, a full and frank discussion of the costs
and benefits of the attempt to prohibit the use of marijuana is far
wiser than suppression of speech because it is unpopular.
I respectfully dissent. Footnote 1 I also seriously question whether such a ban
could really be enforced. Consider the difficulty of monitoring
student conversations between classes or in the cafeteria. Footnote 2 It is also relevant that the display did not
take place “on school premises,” as the rule contemplates. App. to
Pet. for Cert. 53a. While a separate district rule does make the
policy applicable to “social events and class trips,” id., at 58a, Frederick might well have thought that the Olympic Torch
Relay was neither a “social event” (for example, prom) nor a “class
trip.” Footnote 3 See ante , at 1 (stating that the
principal “reasonably regarded” Frederick’s banner as “promoting
illegal drug use”); ante, at 6 (explaining that “Principal
Morse thought the banner would be interpreted by those viewing it
as promoting illegal drug use, and that interpretation is plainly a
reasonable one”); ante, at 8 (asking whether “a principal
may … restrict student speech … when that speech is reasonably
viewed as promoting illegal drug use”); ante, at 14
(holding that “schools [may] restrict student expression that they
reasonably regard as promoting illegal drug use”); see also ante , at 1 (Alito, J., concurring) (“[A] public school may
restrict speech that a reasonable observer would interpret as
advocating illegal drug use”). Footnote 4 See ante, at 7 (“We agree with
Morse. At least two interpretations of the words on the banner
demonstrate that the sign advocated the use of illegal drugs”); ante, at 15 (observing that “[w]e have explained our view”
that “Frederick’s banner constitutes promotion of illegal drug
use”). Footnote 5 The reasonableness of the view that
Frederick’s message was unprotected speech is relevant to
ascertaining whether qualified immunity should shield the principal
from liability, not to whether her actions violated Frederick’s
constitutional rights. Cf. Saucier v. Katz , 533 U. S. 194 ,
202 (2001) (“The relevant, dispositive inquiry in determining
whether a right is clearly established is whether it would be clear
to a reasonable officer that his conduct was unlawful in the
situation he confronted”). Footnote 6 This same reasoning applies when the
interpreter is not just a listener, but a legislature. We have
repeatedly held that “[d]eference to a legislative finding” that
certain types of speech are inherently harmful “cannot limit
judicial inquiry when First Amendment rights are at stake,”
reasoning that “the judicial function commands analysis of whether
the specific conduct charged falls within the reach of the statute
and if so whether the legislation is consonant with the
Constitution.” Landmark Communications, Inc. v. Virginia , 435 U. S. 829 , 843, 844
(1978); see also Whitney v. California , 274 U. S. 357 , 378–379 (1927)
(Brandeis, J., concurring) (“[A legislative declaration] does not
preclude enquiry into the question whether, at the time and under
the circumstances, the conditions existed which are essential to
validity under the Federal Constitution… . Whenever the
fundamental rights of free speech and assembly are alleged to have
been invaded, it must remain open to a defendant to present the
issue whether there actually did exist at the time a clear danger;
whether the danger, if any, was imminent; and whether the evil
apprehended was so substantial as to justify the stringent
restriction interposed by the legislature”). When legislatures are
entitled to no deference as to whether particular speech amounts to
a “clear and present danger,” id., at 379, it is hard to
understand why the Court would so blithely defer to the judgment of
a single school principal. Footnote 7 In affirming Frederick’s suspension, the JDHS
superintendent acknowledged that Frederick displayed his message
“for the benefit of television cameras covering the Torch Relay.”
App. to Pet. for Cert. 62a. Footnote 8 The Court’s opinion ignores the fact that the
legalization of marijuana is an issue of considerable public
concern in Alaska. The State Supreme Court held in 1975 that
Alaska’s constitution protects the right of adults to possess less
than four ounces of marijuana for personal use. Ravin v. State , 537 P. 2d 494 (Alaska). In 1990, the voters of
Alaska attempted to undo that decision by voting for a ballot
initiative recriminalizing marijuana possession. Initiative
Proposal No. 2, §§1–2 (effective Mar. 3, 1991), 11 Alaska Stat., p.
872 (Lexis 2006). At the time Frederick unfurled his banner, the
constitutionality of that referendum had yet to be tested. It was
subsequently struck down as unconstitutional. See Noy v. State , 83 P. 3d 538 (Alaska App. 2003). In the
meantime, Alaska voters had approved a ballot measure
decriminalizing the use of marijuana for medicinal purposes, 1998
Ballot Measure No. 8 (approved Nov. 3, 1998), 11 Alaska Stat., p.
882 (codified at Alaska Stat. §§11.71.090, 17.37.010–17.37.080),
and had rejected a much broader measure that would have
decriminalized marijuana possession and granted amnesty to anyone
convicted of marijuana-related crimes, see 2000 Ballot Measure No.
5 (failed Nov. 7, 2000), 11 Alaska Stat., p. 886. Footnote 9 See Gonzales v. Raich , 545 U. S. 1 , 21,
n. 31 (2005) (citing a Government estimate “that in 2000 American
users spent $10.5 billion on the purchase of
marijuana”). Footnote 10 Id., at 5 (noting that “at least
nine States … authorize the use of marijuana for medicinal
purposes”). DEBORAH MORSE, et al., PETITIONERS v. JOSEPH FREDERICK
on writ of certiorari to the united states court of
appeals for the ninth circuit
[June 25, 2007]
Justice Breyer, concurring in the
judgment in part and dissenting in part.
This Court need not and should
not decide this difficult First Amendment issue on the merits.
Rather, I believe that it should simply hold that qualified
immunity bars the student’s claim for monetary damages and say no
more.
I
Resolving the First Amendment
question presented in this case is, in my view, unwise and
unnecessary. In part that is because the question focuses upon
specific content narrowly defined: May a school board punish
students for speech that advocates drug use and, if so, when? At
the same time, the underlying facts suggest that Principal Morse
acted as she did not simply because of the specific content and
viewpoint of Joseph Frederick’s speech but also because of the
surrounding context and manner in which Frederick expressed his
views. To say that school officials might reasonably prohibit
students during school-related events from unfurling 14-foot
banners (with any kind of irrelevant or inappropriate message)
designed to attract attention from television cameras seems
unlikely to undermine basic First Amendment principles. But to
hold, as the Court does, that “schools may take steps to safeguard
those entrusted to their care from speech that can reasonably be
regarded as encouraging illegal drug use” (and that “schools” may
“restrict student expression that they reasonably regard as
promoting illegal drug use”) is quite a different matter. Ante , at 2, 14. This holding, based as it is on viewpoint
restrictions, raises a host of serious concerns.
One concern is that, while the
holding is theoretically limited to speech promoting the use of
illegal drugs, it could in fact authorize further viewpoint-based
restrictions. Illegal drugs, after all, are not the only illegal
substances. What about encouraging the underage consumption of
alcohol? Moreover, it is unclear how far the Court’s rule regarding
drug advocacy extends. What about a conversation during the lunch
period where one student suggests that glaucoma sufferers should
smoke marijuana to relieve the pain? What about deprecating
commentary about an antidrug film shown in school? And what about
drug messages mixed with other, more expressly political, content?
If, for example, Frederick’s banner had read “LEGALIZE BONG HiTS,”
he might be thought to receive protection from the majority’s rule,
which goes to speech “encouraging illegal drug use.” Ante , at 2 (emphasis added). But speech advocating change
in drug laws might also be perceived of as promoting the disregard
of existing drug laws.
Legal principles must treat like instances
alike. Those principles do not permit treating “drug use”
separately without a satisfying explanation of why drug use is sui generis . To say that illegal drug use is harmful to
students, while surely true, does not itself constitute a
satisfying explanation because there are many such harms. During a
real war, one less metaphorical than the war on drugs, the Court
declined an opportunity to draw narrow subject-matter-based lines.
Cf. West Virginia Bd. of Ed. v. Barnette , 319 U. S. 624 (1943) (holding students cannot be compelled to recite the Pledge
of Allegiance during World War II). We should decline this
opportunity today.
Although the dissent avoids some of the
majority’s pitfalls, I fear that, if adopted as law, it would risk
significant interference with reasonable school efforts to maintain
discipline. What is a principal to do when a student unfurls a
14-foot banner (carrying an irrelevant or inappropriate message)
during a school-related event in an effort to capture the attention
of television cameras? Nothing? In my view, a principal or a
teacher might reasonably view Frederick’s conduct, in this setting,
as simply beyond the pale. And a school official, knowing that
adolescents often test the outer boundaries of acceptable behavior,
may believe it is important (for the offending student and his
classmates) to establish when a student has gone too far.
Neither can I simply say that Morse may have
taken the right action (confiscating Frederick’s banner) but for
the wrong reason (“drug speech”). Teachers are neither lawyers nor
police officers; and the law should not demand that they fully
understand the intricacies of our First Amendment jurisprudence. As
the majority rightly points out, the circumstances here called for
a quick decision. See ante , at 15 (noting that “Morse had
to decide to act—or not act—on the spot”). But this consideration
is better understood in terms of qualified immunity than of the
First Amendment. See infra, at 5–8.
All of this is to say that, regardless of the
outcome of the constitutional determination, a decision on the
underlying First Amendment issue is both difficult and unusually
portentous. And that is a reason for us not to decide the
issue unless we must.
In some instances, it is appropriate to decide
a constitutional issue in order to provide “guidance” for the
future. But I cannot find much guidance in today’s decision. The
Court makes clear that school officials may “restrict” student
speech that promotes “illegal drug use” and that they may “take
steps” to “safeguard” students from speech that encourages “illegal
drug use.” Ante , at 2, 8. Beyond “steps” that prohibit the
unfurling of banners at school outings, the Court does not explain
just what those “restrict[ions]” or those “steps” might be.
Nor, if we are to avoid the risk of
interpretations that are too broad or too narrow, is it easy to
offer practically valuable guidance. Students will test the limits
of acceptable behavior in myriad ways better known to
schoolteachers than to judges; school officials need a degree of
flexible authority to respond to disciplinary challenges; and the
law has always considered the relationship between teachers and
students special. Under these circumstances, the more detailed the
Court’s supervision becomes, the more likely its law will engender
further disputes among teachers and students. Consequently, larger
numbers of those disputes will likely make their way from the
schoolhouse to the courthouse. Yet no one wishes to substitute
courts for school boards, or to turn the judge’s chambers into the
principal’s office.
In order to avoid resolving the fractious
underlying constitutional question, we need only decide a different
question that this case presents, the question of “qualified
immunity.” See Pet. for Cert. 23–28. The principle of qualified
immunity fits this case perfectly and, by saying so, we would
diminish the risk of bringing about the adverse consequences I have
identified. More importantly, we should also adhere to a basic
constitutional obligation by avoiding unnecessary decision of
constitutional questions. See Ashwander v. TVA , 297 U. S. 288 ,
347 (1936) (Brandeis, J., concurring) (“The Court will not pass
upon a constitutional question although properly presented on the
record, if there is also present some other ground upon which the
case may be disposed of ”).
II
A
The defense of “qualified
immunity” requires courts to enter judgment in favor of a
government employee unless the employee’s conduct violates “clearly
established statutory or constitutional rights of which a
reasonable person would have known.” Harlow v. Fitzgerald , 457 U. S. 800 , 818
(1982). The defense is designed to protect “all but the plainly
incompetent or those who knowingly violated the law.” Malley v. Briggs , 475 U. S. 335 , 341
(1986).
Qualified immunity applies here
and entitles Principal Morse to judgment on Frederick’s monetary
damages claim because she did not clearly violate the law during
her confrontation with the student. At the time of that
confrontation, Tinker v. Des Moines Independent
Community School Dist., 393 U. S. 503 , 513
(1969), indicated that school officials could not prohibit students
from wearing an armband in protest of the Vietnam War, where the
conduct at issue did not “materially and substantially disrupt the
work and discipline of the school;” Bethel School Dist. No.
403 v. Fraser, 478 U. S. 675 (1986),
indicated that school officials could restrict a student’s freedom
to give a school assembly speech containing an elaborate sexual
metaphor; and Hazelwood School Dist. v. Kuhlmeier, 484 U. S. 260 (1988),
indicated that school officials could restrict student
contributions to a school-sponsored newspaper, even without threat
of imminent disruption. None of these cases clearly governs the
case at hand.
The Ninth Circuit thought it “clear” that
these cases did not permit Morse’s actions. See 439 F. 3d
1114, 1124 (2006). That is because, in the Ninth Circuit’s view,
this case involved neither lewd speech, cf. Fraser , supra , nor school sponsored speech, cf. Kuhlmeier,
supra , and hence Tinker ’s substantial disruption test
must guide the inquiry. See 439 F. 3d, at 1123. But unlike the
Ninth Circuit, other courts have described the tests these cases
suggest as complex and often difficult to apply. See, e.g. , Guiles ex rel. Guiles v. Marineau ,
461 F. 3d 320, 326 (CA2 2006) (“It is not entirely clear
whether Tinker ’s rule applies to all student speech that
is not sponsored by schools, subject to the rule of Fraser , or whether it applies only to political speech or
to political viewpoint-based discrimination”); Baxter v. Vigo Cty. School Corp. , 26 F. 3d 728, 737 (CA7 1994)
(pointing out that Fraser “cast some doubt on the extent
to which students retain free speech rights in the school
setting”). Indeed, the fact that this Court divides on the
constitutional question (and that the majority reverses the Ninth
Circuit’s constitutional determination) strongly suggests that the
answer as to how to apply prior law to these facts was unclear.
The relative ease with which we could decide
this case on the qualified immunity ground, and thereby avoid
deciding a far more difficult constitutional question, underscores
the need to lift the rigid “order of battle” decisionmaking
requirement that this Court imposed upon lower courts in Saucier v. Katz , 533 U. S. 194 , 201–202
(2001). In Saucier , the Court wrote that lower courts’
“first inquiry must be whether a constitutional right would have
been violated on the facts alleged.” Id. , at 200. Only if
there is a constitutional violation, can lower courts proceed to
consider whether the official is entitled to “qualified immunity.”
See ibid. I have previously explained why I believe we
should abandon Saucier ’s order-of-battle rule. See Scott v. Harris , 550 U. S. ___, ___ (2007) (slip
op., at 1–2) (Breyer, J., concurring); Brosseau v. Haugen , 543
U. S. 194 , 201–202 (2004) (Breyer, J., concurring).
Sometimes the rule will require lower courts unnecessarily to
answer difficult constitutional questions, thereby wasting judicial
resources. Sometimes it will require them to resolve constitutional
issues that are poorly presented. Sometimes the rule will immunize
an incorrect constitutional holding from further review. And often
the rule violates the longstanding principle that courts should
“not … pass on questions of constitutionality … unless such
adjudication is unavoidable.” Spector Motor Service, Inc. v. McLaughlin , 323 U. S. 101 , 105
(1944).
This last point warrants amplification. In
resolving the underlying constitutional question, we produce
several differing opinions. It is utterly unnecessary to do so.
Were we to decide this case on the ground of qualified immunity,
our decision would be unanimous , for the dissent concedes
that Morse should not be held liable in damages for confiscating
Frederick’s banner. Post , at 1 (opinion of
Stevens, J.). And the “cardinal principle of judicial
restraint” is that “if it is not necessary to decide more, it is
necessary not to decide more.” PDK Labs., Inc. v. Drug
Enforcement Admin. , 362 F. 3d 786, 799 (CADC 2004)
(Roberts, J., concurring in part and concurring in judgment).
If it is Saucier that tempts this
Court to adhere to the rigid “order of battle” that binds lower
courts, it should resist that temptation. Saucier does not
bind this Court. Regardless, the rule of Saucier has
generated considerable criticism from both commentators and judges.
See Leval, Judging Under the Constitution: Dicta About Dicta, 81
N. Y. U. L. Rev. 1249, 1275 (2006) (calling the requirement “a
puzzling misadventure in constitutional dictum”); Dirrane v. Brookline Police Dept. , 315 F. 3d 65, 69–70 (CA1 2002)
(referring to the requirement as “an uncomfortable exercise” when
“the answer whether there was a violation may depend on a
kaleidoscope of facts not yet fully developed”); Lyons v. Xenia , 417 F. 3d 565, 580–584 (CA6 2005) (Sutton, J.,
concurring). While Saucier justified its rule by
contending that it was necessary to permit constitutional law to
develop, see 533 U. S., at 201, this concern is overstated because
overruling Saucier would not mean that the law prohibited judges from passing on constitutional
questions, only that it did not require them to do so.
Given that Saucier is a judge-made procedural rule, stare decisis concerns supporting preservation of the rule
are weak. See, e.g. , Payne v. Tennessee , 501 U. S. 808 ,
828 (1991) (“Considerations in favor of stare decisis ” are
at their weakest in cases “involving procedural and evidentiary
rules”).
Finally, several Members of this Court have
previously suggested that always requiring lower courts
first to answer constitutional questions is misguided. See County of Sacramento v. Lewis , 523 U. S. 833 , 859
(1998) (Stevens, J., concurring in judgment) (resolving the
constitutional question first is inappropriate when that “question
is both difficult and unresolved”); Bunting v. Mellen , 541 U. S. 1019 , 1025
(2004) (Scalia, J., dissenting from denial of certiorari) (“We
should either make clear that constitutional determinations are not insulated from our re- view … or else drop any
pretense at requiring the ordering in every case”); Saucier,
supra , at 210 (Ginsburg, J., concurring in judgment) (“The
two-part test today’s decision imposes holds large potential to
confuse”); Siegert v. Gilley , 500 U. S. 226 , 235
(1991) (Kennedy, J., concurring) (“If it is plain that a
plaintiff’s required malice allegations are insufficient but there
is some doubt as to the constitutional right asserted, it seems to
reverse the usual ordering of issues to tell the trial and
appellate courts that they should resolve the constitutional
question first”). I would end the failed Saucier experiment now.
B
There is one remaining objection
to deciding this case on the basis of qualified immunity alone. The
plaintiff in this case has sought not only damages; he has also
sought an injunction requiring the school district to expunge his
suspension from its records. A “qualified immunity” defense applies
in respect to damages actions, but not to injunctive relief. See, e.g. , Wood v. Strickland , 420 U. S. 308 , 314,
n. 6 (1975). With respect to that claim, the underlying
question of constitutionality, at least conceivably, remains.
I seriously doubt, however, that
it does remain. At the plaintiff’s request, the school
superintendent reviewed Frederick’s 10-day suspension. The
superintendent, in turn, reduced the suspension to the eight days
that Frederick had served before the appeal. But in doing so the
superintendent noted that several actions independent of
Frederick’s speech supported the suspension, including the
plaintiff’s disregard of a school official’s instruction, his
failure to report to the principal’s office on time, his “defiant
[and] disruptive behavior,” and the “belligerent attitude” he
displayed when he finally reported. App. to Pet. for Cert. 65a. The
superintendent wrote that “were” he to “concede” that Frederick’s
“speech . . . is protected, … the remainder of his behavior was not
excused.” Id., at 66a.
The upshot is that the school board’s refusal
to erase the suspension from the record may well be justified on
non-speech-related grounds. In addition, plaintiff’s counsel
appeared to agree with the Court’s suggestion at oral argument that
Frederick “would not pursue” injunctive relief if he prevailed on
the damages question. Tr. of Oral Arg. 46–48. And finding that
Morse was entitled to qualified immunity would leave only the
question of injunctive relief.
Given the high probability that Frederick’s
request for an injunction will not require a court to resolve the
constitutional issue, see Ashwander , 297 U. S., at 347
(Brandeis, J., concurring), I would decide only the qualified
immunity question and remand the rest of the case for an initial
consideration. | The Supreme Court ruled that schools can restrict student speech that promotes illegal drug use, upholding the suspension of a student who displayed a banner advocating drug use at a school-sanctioned event. The Court balanced students' free speech rights with schools' duty of care, concluding that the school's actions were reasonable and did not violate the First Amendment. |
Free Speech | McConnell v. FEC | https://supreme.justia.com/cases/federal/us/540/93/ | OPINION OF THE COURT MCCONNELL V. FEDERAL ELECTION COMM'N 540 U. S. ____ (2003) SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES NOS. 02-1674, 02-1675, 02-1676, 02-1702, 02-1727, 02-1733,
02-1734;02-1740, 02-1747, 02-1753, 02-1755, AND
02-1756 MITCH McCONNELL, UNITED STATES SENATOR,
et al., APPELLANTS
02–1674 v .
FEDERAL ELECTION COMMISSION, et al.;
NATIONAL RIFLE ASSOCIATION, et al.,
APPELLANTS
02–1675 v .
FEDERAL ELECTION COMMISSION, et al.;
FEDERAL ELECTION COMMISSION, et al.,
APPELLANTS
02–1676 v .
MITCH McCONNELL, UNITED STATES SENATOR,
et al.;
JOHN McCAIN, UNITED STATES SENATOR, et al.,
APPELLANTS
02–1702 v .
MITCH McCONNELL, UNITED STATES SENATOR,
et al.;
REPUBLICAN NATIONAL COMMITTEE, et al.,
APPELLANTS
02–1727 v .
FEDERAL ELECTION COMMISSION, et al.;
NATIONAL RIGHT TO LIFE COMMITTEE, INC.,
et al., APPELLANTS
02–1733 v .
FEDERAL ELECTION COMMISSION, et al.;
AMERICAN CIVIL LIBERTIES UNION, APPELLANTS
02–1734 v .
FEDERAL ELECTION COMMISSION, et al.;
VICTORIA JACKSON GRAY ADAMS, et al.,
APPELLANTS
02–1740 v .
FEDERAL ELECTION COMMISSION, et al.;
RON PAUL, UNITED STATES CONGRESSMAN, et al.,
APPELLANTS
02–1747 v .
FEDERAL ELECTION COMMISSION, et al.;
CALIFORNIA DEMOCRATIC PARTY, et al.,
APPELLANTS
02–1753 v .
FEDERAL ELECTION COMMISSION, et al.;
AMERICAN FEDERATION OF LABOR AND CONGRESS OF
INDUSTRIAL ORGANIZATIONS, et al., APPELLANTS
02–1755 v .
FEDERAL ELECTION COMMISSION, et al.;
CHAMBER OF COMMERCE OF THE UNITED STATES,
et al., APPELLANTS
02–1756 v .
FEDERAL ELECTION COMMISSION, et al.
on appeals from the united states district court
for the district of columbia
[December 10, 2003]
Chief Justice Rehnquist delivered
the opinion of the Court with respect to BCRA Titles III and
IV.*
This opinion addresses issues
involving miscellaneous Title III and IV provisions of the
Bipartisan Campaign Reform Act of 2002 (BCRA), 116 Stat. 81. For
the reasons discussed below, we affirm the judgment of the District
Court with respect to these provisions. BCRA §305 BCRA §305 amends the federal
Communications Act of 1934 (Communications Act) §315(b), 48 Stat.
1088, as amended, 86 Stat. 4, which requires that, 45 days before a
primary or 60 days before a general election, broadcast stations
must sell a qualified candidate the “lowest unit charge of the
station for the same class and amount of time for the same period,”
47 U. S. C. §315(b). Section 305’s amendment, in turn, denies
a candidate the benefit of that lowest unit charge unless the
candidate “provides written certification to the broadcast station
that the candidate (and any authorized committee of the candidate)
shall not make any direct reference to another candidate for the
same office,” or the candidate, in the manner prescribed in BCRA
§305(a)(3), clearly identifies herself at the end of the broadcast
and states that she approves of the broadcast. 47 U.
S. C. A. §§315(b)(2)(A), (C) (Supp. 2003). The McConnell plaintiffs
challenge §305. They argue that Senator McConnell’s testimony that
he plans to run advertisements critical of his opponents in the
future and that he had run them in the past is sufficient to
establish standing. We think not. Article III of the Constitution limits the
“judicial power” to the resolution of “cases” and “controversies.”
One element of the “bedrock” case-or-controversy requirement is
that plaintiffs must establish that they have standing to sue.
Raines v. Byrd, 521 U. S. 811 , 818
(1997). On many occasions, we have reiterated the three
requirements that constitute the “ ‘irreducible constitutional
minimum’ ” of standing. Vermont Agency of Natural
Resources v. United States ex rel. Stevens, 529 U. S. 765 , 771
(2000). First, a plaintiff must demonstrate an “injury in fact,”
which is “concrete,” “distinct and palpable,” and “actual or
imminent.” Whitmore v. Arkansas, 495 U. S. 149 , 155
(1990) (internal quotation marks and citation omitted). Second, a
plaintiff must establish “a causal connection between the injury
and the conduct complained of—the injury has to be ‘fairly
trace[able] to the challenged action of the defendant, and not …
th[e] result [of] some third party not before the court.’ ” Lujan v. Defenders of Wildlife, 504 U. S. 555 , 560–561
(1992) (quoting Simon v. Eastern Ky. Welfare Rights
Organization, 426 U. S. 26 , 41–42
(1976)). Third, a plaintiff must show the “ ‘substantial
likelihood’ that the requested relief will remedy the alleged
injury in fact.” Stevens, supra, at 771.
As noted above, §305 amended the Communication
Act’s requirements with respect to the lowest unit charge for
broadcasting time. But this price is not available to qualified
candidates until 45 days before a primary election or 60 days
before a general election. Because Senator McConnell’s current term
does not expire until 2009, the earliest day he could be affected
by §305 is 45 days before the Republican primary election in 2008.
This alleged injury in fact is too remote temporally to satisfy
Article III standing. See Whitmore, supra, at 158 (“A
threatened injury must be certainly impending to
constitute injury in fact” (internal quotation marks and citations
omitted)); see also Los Angeles v. Lyons, 461 U. S. 95 , 102 (1983)
(A plaintiff seeking injunctive relief must show he is
“ ‘immediately in danger of sustaining some direct injury’ as
[a] result” of the challenged conduct). Because we hold that the
McConnell plaintiffs lack standing to challenge §305, we affirm the
District Court’s dismissal of the challenge to BCRA §305. BCRA §307 BCRA §307, which amends
§315(a)(1) of the Federal Election Campaign Act of 1971 (FECA), 86
Stat. 3, as added, 90 Stat. 487, increases and indexes for
inflation certain FECA contribution limits. The Adams and Paul
plaintiffs challenge §307 in this Court. Both groups contend that
they have standing to sue. Again, we disagree. The Adams plaintiffs, a group
consisting of voters, organizations representing voters, and
candidates, allege two injuries, and argue each is legally
cognizable, “as established by case law outlawing electoral
discrimination based on economic status … and upholding the right
to an equally meaningful vote … .” Brief for Appellants Adams
et al. in No. 02–1740, p. 31. First, they assert that the increases in
hard money limits enacted by §307 deprive them of an equal ability
to participate in the election process based on their economic
status. But, to satisfy our standing requirements, a plaintiff’s
alleged injury must be an invasion of a concrete and particularized
legally protected interest. Lujan, supra , at 560. We have
noted that “[a]lthough standing in no way depends on the merits of
the plaintiff’s contention that particular conduct is illegal, … it
often turns on the nature and source of the claim asserted.” Warth v. Seldin, 422 U. S. 490 , 500
(1975) (internal quotation marks and citations omitted). We have
never recognized a legal right comparable to the broad and diffuse
injury asserted by the Adams plaintiffs. Their reliance on this
Court’s voting rights cases is misplaced. They rely on cases
requiring nondiscriminatory access to the ballot and a single,
equal vote for each voter. See, e.g. , Lubin v. Panish, 415 U. S. 709 (1974)
(invalidating a statute requiring a ballot-access fee fixed at a
percentage of the salary for the office sought because it
unconstitutionally burdened the right to vote); Harper v. Virginia Bd. of Elections, 383 U. S. 663 , 666–668
(1966) (invalidating a state poll tax because it effectively denied
the right to vote).
None of these plaintiffs claims a denial of
equal access to the ballot or the right to vote. Instead, the
plaintiffs allege a curtailment of the scope of their participation
in the electoral process. But we have noted that “[p]olitical ‘free
trade’ does not necessarily require that all who participate in the
political marketplace do so with exactly equal resources.” Federal Election Comm’n v. Massachusetts Citizens for
Life, Inc., 479 U. S. 238 , 257
(1986); see also Buckley v. Valeo, 424 U. S. 1 , 48 (1976) (per curiam) (rejecting the asserted government interest
of “equalizing the relative ability of individuals and groups to
influence the outcome of elections” to justify the burden on speech
presented by expenditure limits). This claim of injury by the Adams
plaintiffs is, therefore, not to a legally cognizable right.
Second, the Adams plaintiffs-candidates
contend that they have suffered a competitive injury. Their
candidates “do not wish to solicit or accept large campaign
contributions as permitted by BCRA” because “[t]hey believe such
contributions create the appearance of unequal access and
influence.” Adams Complaint ¶ ;53. As a result, they claim that
BCRA §307 puts them at a “fundraising disadvantage,” making it more
difficult for them to compete in elections. See id. , ¶
;56.
The second claimed injury is based on the same
premise as the first: BCRA §307’s increased hard money limits allow
plaintiffs-candidates’ opponents to raise more money, and,
consequently, the plaintiffs-candidates’ ability to compete or
participate in the electoral process is diminished. But they cannot
show that their alleged injury is “fairly traceable” to BCRA §307.
See Lujan, supra, at 562. Their alleged inability to
compete stems not from the operation of §307, but from their own
personal “wish” not to solicit or accept large contributions, i.e ., their personal choice. Accordingly, the Adams
plaintiffs fail here to allege an injury in fact that is “fairly
traceable” to BCRA.
The Paul plaintiffs maintain that BCRA §307
violates the Freedom of Press Clause of the First Amendment. They
contend that their political campaigns and public interest advocacy
involve traditional press activities and that, therefore, they are
protected by the First Amendment’s guarantee of the freedom of
press. The Paul plaintiffs argue that the contribution limits
imposed by BCRA §307, together with the individual and political
action committee contribution limitations of FECA §315, impose
unconstitutional editorial control upon candidates and their
campaigns. The Paul plaintiffs argue that by imposing economic
burdens upon them, but not upon the institutional media, see 2 U.
S. C. §431(9)(B)(i) (exempting “any news story, commentary, or
editorial distributed through the facilities of any broadcasting
station, newspaper, magazine, or other periodical publication,
unless such facilities are owned or controlled by any political
party, political committee, or candidate” from the definition of
expenditure), BCRA §307 and FECA §315 violate the freedom of the
press.
The Paul plaintiffs cannot show the
“ ‘substantial likelihood’ that the requested relief will
remedy [their] alleged injury in fact,” Stevens , 529 U.
S., at 771. The relief the Paul plaintiffs seek is for this Court
to strike down the contribution limits, removing the alleged
disparate editorial controls and economic burdens imposed on them.
But §307 merely increased and indexed for inflation certain FECA
contribution limits. This Court has no power to adjudicate a
challenge to the FECA limits in this case because challenges to the
constitutionality of FECA provisions are subject to direct review
before an appropriate en banc court of appeals, as provided in 2 U.
S. C. §437h, not in the three-judge District Court convened
pursuant to BCRA §403(a). Although the Court has jurisdiction to
hear a challenge to §307, if the Court were to strike down the
increases and indexes established by BCRA §307, it would not remedy
the Paul plaintiffs’ alleged injury because both the limitations
imposed by FECA and the exemption for news media would remain
unchanged. A ruling in the Paul plaintiffs’ favor, therefore, would
not redress their alleged injury, and they accordingly lack
standing. See Steel Co. v. Citizens for Better
Environment, 523
U. S. 83 , 105–110 (1998).
For the reasons above, we affirm the District
Court’s dismissal of the Adams and Paul plaintiffs’ challenges to
BCRA §307 for lack of standing. BCRA §§304, 316, and 319 BCRA §§304 and 316, which
amend FECA §315, and BCRA §319, which adds FECA §315A, collectively
known as the “millionaire provisions,” provide for a series of
staggered increases in otherwise applicable
contribution-to-candidate limits if the candidate’s opponent spends
a triggering amount of his personal funds.[ Footnote 1 ] The provisions also eliminate the
coordinated expenditure limits in certain circumstances.[ Footnote 2 ] In their challenge to the
millionaire provisions, the Adams plaintiffs allege the same
injuries that they alleged with regard to BCRA §307. For the
reasons discussed above, they fail to allege a cognizable injury
that is “fairly traceable” to BCRA. Additionally, as the District
Court noted, “none of the Adams plaintiffs is a candidate in an
election affected by the millionaire provisions—i.e., one in
which an opponent chooses to spend the triggering amount in his own
funds—and it would be purely ‘conjectural’ for the court to assume
that any plaintiff ever will be.” 251 F. Supp. 2d 176, 431 (DC
2003) (case below) (Henderson, J., concurring in judgment in part
and dissenting in part) (quoting Lujan , 504 U. S., at
560). We affirm the District Court’s dismissal of the Adams
plaintiffs’ challenge to the millionaire provisions for lack of
standing. BCRA §311 FECA §318 requires that
certain communications “authorized” by a candidate or his political
committee clearly identify the candidate or committee or, if not so
authorized, identify the payor and announce the lack of
authorization. 2 U. S. C. A. §441d (main ed. and Supp.
2003). BCRA §311 makes several amendments to FECA §318, among them
the expansion of this identification regime to include
disbursements for “electioneering communications” as defined in
BCRA §201. The McConnell and Chamber of
Commerce plaintiffs challenge BCRA §311 by simply noting that §311,
along with all of the “electioneering communications” provisions of
BCRA, is unconstitutional. We disagree. We think BCRA §311’s
inclusion of electioneering communications in the FECA §318
disclosure regime bears a sufficient relationship to the important
governmental interest of “shed[ding] the light of publicity” on
campaign financing. Buckley , 424 U. S., at 81. Assuming as we
must that FECA §318 is valid to begin with, and that FECA §318 is
valid as amended by BCRA §311’s amendments other than the inclusion
of electioneering communications, the challenged inclusion of
electioneering communications is not itself unconstitutional. We
affirm the District Court’s decision upholding §311’s expansion of
FECA §318(a) to include disclosure of disbursements for
electioneering communications. BCRA §318 BCRA §318, which adds FECA
§324, prohibits individuals “17 years old or younger” from making
contributions to candidates and contributions or donations to
political parties. 2 U. S. C. A. §441k (Supp. 2003). The
McConnell and Echols plaintiffs challenge the provision; they argue
that §318 violates the First Amendment rights of minors. We
agree. Minors enjoy the protection
of the First Amendment. See, e.g ., Tinker v. Des
Moines Independent Community School Dist., 393 U. S. 503 , 511–513
(1969). Limitations on the amount that an individual may contribute
to a candidate or political committee impinge on the protected
freedoms of expression and association. See Buckley,
supra, at 20–22. When the Government burdens the right to
contribute, we apply heightened scrutiny. See ante , at
25–26 (joint opinion of Stevens and O’Connor, JJ.) (“[A]
contribution limit involving even ‘significant interference’ with
associational rights is nevertheless valid if it satisfies the
‘lesser demand’ of being ‘closely drawn’ to match a ‘sufficiently
important interest.’ ” (quoting Federal Election
Comm’n v. Beaumont, 539 U. S. ___, ___ (2003) (slip
op., at 15)). We ask whether there is a “sufficiently important
interest” and whether the statute is “closely drawn” to avoid
unnecessary abridgment of First Amendment freedoms. Ante, at 25–26; Buckley , 424 U. S., at 25. The Government
asserts that the provision protects against corruption by conduit;
that is, donations by parents through their minor children to
circumvent contribution limits applicable to the parents. But the
Government offers scant evidence of this form of evasion.[ Footnote 3 ] Perhaps the Government’s
slim evidence results from sufficient deterrence of such activities
by §320 of FECA, which prohibits any person from “mak[ing] a
contribution in the name of another person” or “knowingly
accept[ing] a contribution made by one person in the name of
another,” 2 U. S. C. §441f. Absent a more convincing case of
the claimed evil, this interest is simply too attenuated for §318
to withstand heightened scrutiny. See Nixon v. Shrink
Missouri Government PAC , 528 U. S. 377 , 391
(2000) (“The quantum of empirical evidence needed to satisfy
heightened judicial scrutiny of legislative judgments will vary up
or down with the novelty and plausibility of the justification
raised”).
Even assuming, arguendo , the
Government advances an important interest, the provision is
overinclusive. The States have adopted a variety of more tailored
approaches— e.g., counting contributions by minors against
the total permitted for a parent or family unit, imposing a lower
cap on contributions by minors, and prohibiting contributions by
very young children. Without deciding whether any of these
alternatives is sufficiently tailored, we hold that the provision
here sweeps too broadly. We therefore affirm the District Court’s
decision striking down §318 as unconstitutional. BCRA §403(b) The National Right to Life
plaintiffs argue that the District Court’s grant of intervention to
the intervenor-defendants, pursuant to Federal Rule of Civil
Procedure 24(a) and BCRA §403(b), must be reversed because the
intervenor-defendants lack Article III standing. It is clear,
however, that the Federal Election Commission (FEC) has standing,
and therefore we need not address the standing of the
intervenor-defendants, whose position here is identical to the
FEC’s. See, e.g. , Clinton v. City of New
York, 524 U. S.
417 , 431–432, n. 19 (1998); Bowsher v. Synar, 478 U. S. 714 , 721
(1986). Cf. Diamond v. Charles, 476 U. S. 54 , 68–69,
n. 21 (1986) (reserving the question for another day).
For the foregoing reasons, we
affirm the District Court’s judgment finding the plaintiffs’
challenges to BCRA §305, §307, and the millionaire provisions
nonjusticiable, striking down as unconstitutional BCRA §318, and
upholding BCRA §311. The judgment of the District Court is
Affirmed.
* Justice O’Connor, Justice Scalia, Justice
Kennedy, and Justice Souter join this opinion in its entirety.
Justice Stevens, Justice Ginsburg, and Justice Breyer join this
opinion, except with respect to BCRA §305. Justice Thomas joins
this opinion with respect to BCRA §§304, 305, 307, 316, 319, and
403(b). Footnote 1 To qualify for increased candidate
contribution limits, the “opposition personal funds amount,” which
depends on expenditures by a candidate and her self-financed
opponent, must exceed a “threshold amount.” 2 U. S. C. A.
§§441a(i)(1)(D), 441a–1(a)(2)(A) (Supp. 2003). Footnote 2 If the “opposition personal funds amount” is
at least 10 times the “threshold amount” in a Senate race, or
exceeds $350,000 in a House of Representatives race, the
coordinated party expenditure limits do not apply.
§§441a(i)(1)(C)(iii), 441a–1(a)(1)(C). Footnote 3 Although some examples were presented to the
District Court, 251 F. Supp. 2d 176, 588–590 (2003)
(Kollar-Kotelly, J.), none were offered to this Court. OPINION OF THE COURT MCCONNELL V. FEDERAL ELECTION COMM'N 540 U. S. ____ (2003) SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES NOS. 02-1674, 02-1675, 02-1676, 02-1702, 02-1727, 02-1733,
02-1734;02-1740, 02-1747, 02-1753, 02-1755, AND
02-1756 MITCH McCONNELL, UNITED STATES SENATOR,
et al., APPELLANTS
02–1674 v .
FEDERAL ELECTION COMMISSION, et al.;
NATIONAL RIFLE ASSOCIATION, et al.,
APPELLANTS
02–1675 v .
FEDERAL ELECTION COMMISSION, et al.;
FEDERAL ELECTION COMMISSION, et al.,
APPELLANTS
02–1676 v .
MITCH McCONNELL, UNITED STATES SENATOR,
et al.;
JOHN McCAIN, UNITED STATES SENATOR, et al.,
APPELLANTS
02–1702 v .
MITCH McCONNELL, UNITED STATES SENATOR,
et al.;
REPUBLICAN NATIONAL COMMITTEE, et al.,
APPELLANTS
02–1727 v .
FEDERAL ELECTION COMMISSION, et al.;
NATIONAL RIGHT TO LIFE COMMITTEE, INC.,
et al., APPELLANTS
02–1733 v .
FEDERAL ELECTION COMMISSION, et al.;
AMERICAN CIVIL LIBERTIES UNION, APPELLANTS
02–1734 v .
FEDERAL ELECTION COMMISSION, et al.;
VICTORIA JACKSON GRAY ADAMS, et al.,
APPELLANTS
02–1740 v .
FEDERAL ELECTION COMMISSION, et al.;
RON PAUL, UNITED STATES CONGRESSMAN, et al.,
APPELLANTS
02–1747 v .
FEDERAL ELECTION COMMISSION, et al.;
CALIFORNIA DEMOCRATIC PARTY, et al.,
APPELLANTS
02–1753 v .
FEDERAL ELECTION COMMISSION, et al.;
AMERICAN FEDERATION OF LABOR AND CONGRESS OF
INDUSTRIAL ORGANIZATIONS, et al., APPELLANTS
02–1755 v .
FEDERAL ELECTION COMMISSION, et al.;
CHAMBER OF COMMERCE OF THE UNITED STATES,
et al., APPELLANTS
02–1756 v .
FEDERAL ELECTION COMMISSION, et al.
on appeals from the united states district court
for the district of columbia
[December 10, 2003]
Justice Stevens and Justice
O’Connor delivered the opinion of the Court with respect to BCRA
Titles I and II.*
The Bipartisan Campaign Reform
Act of 2002 (BCRA), 116 Stat. 81, contains a series of amendments
to the Federal Election Campaign Act of 1971 (FECA), 86 Stat. 11,
as amended, 2 U. S. C. A. §431 et seq. (main ed.
and Supp. 2003), the Communications Act of 1934, 48 Stat. 1088, as
amended, 47 U. S. C. A. §315, and other portions of the
United States Code, 18 U. S. C. A. §607 (Supp. 2003), 36
U. S. C. A. §§510–511, that are challenged in these
cases.[ Footnote 1 ] In this
opinion we discuss Titles I and II of BCRA. The opinion of the
Court delivered by The Chief Justice, post, p. ___,
discusses Titles III and IV, and the opinion of the Court delivered
by Justice Breyer, post , p. ___, discusses Title V.
I
More than a century ago the
“sober-minded Elihu Root” advocated legislation that would prohibit
political contributions by corporations in order to prevent
“ ‘the great aggregations of wealth, from using their
corporate funds, directly or indirectly,’ ” to elect
legislators who would “ ‘vote for their protection and the
advancement of their interests as against those of the
public.’ ” United States v. Automobile
Workers, 352 U. S. 567 , 571 (1957) (quoting E.
Root, Addresses on Government and Citizenship 143 (R. Bacon &
J. Scott eds. 1916)). In Root’s opinion, such legislation would
“ ‘strik[e] at a constantly growing evil which has done more
to shake the confidence of the plain people of small means of this
country in our political institutions than any other practice which
has ever obtained since the foundation of our Government.’ ”
352 U. S., at 571. The Congress of the United States has repeatedly
enacted legislation endorsing Root’s judgment.
BCRA is the most recent federal
enactment designed “to purge national politics of what was
conceived to be the pernicious influence of ‘big money’ campaign
contributions.” Id., at 572. As Justice Frankfurter
explained in his opinion for the Court in Automobile
Workers , the first such enactment responded to President
Theodore Roosevelt’s call for legislation forbidding all
contributions by corporations “ ‘to any political committee or
for any political purpose.’ ” Ibid. (quoting 40 Cong.
Rec. 96 (1906)). In his annual message to Congress in December
1905, President Roosevelt stated that “ ‘directors should not
be permitted to use stockholders’ money’ ” for political
purposes, and he recommended that “ ‘a prohibition’ ” on
corporate political contributions “ ‘would be, as far as it
went, an effective method of stopping the evils aimed at in corrupt
practices acts.’ ” 352 U. S., at 352. The resulting 1907
statute completely banned corporate contributions of “money … in
connection with” any federal election. Tillman Act, ch. 420, 34
Stat. 864. Congress soon amended the statute to require the public
disclosure of certain contributions and expenditures and to place
“maximum limits on the amounts that congressional candidates could
spend in seeking nomination and election.” Automobile
Workers, supra , at 575–576.
In 1925 Congress extended the prohibition of
“contributions” “to include ‘anything of value,’ and made
acceptance of a corporate contribution as well as the giving of
such a contribution a crime.” Federal Election Comm’n v. National Right to Work Comm., 459 U. S. 197 , 209 (1982) (citing
Federal Corrupt Practices Act, 1925, §§301, 313, 43 Stat. 1070,
1074). During the debates preceding that amendment, a leading
Senator characterized “ ‘the apparent hold on political
parties which business interests and certain organizations seek and
sometimes obtain by reason of liberal campaign
contributions’ ” as “ ‘one of the great political evils
of the time.’ ” Automobile Workers, supra ,
at 576 (quoting 65 Cong. Rec. 9507–9508 (1924)). We upheld the
amended statute against a constitutional challenge, observing that
“[t]he power of Congress to protect the election of President and
Vice President from corruption being clear, the choice of means to
that end presents a question primarily addressed to the judgment of
Congress.” Burroughs v. United
States, 290 U. S. 534 , 547
(1934).
Congress’ historical concern with the
“political potentialities of wealth” and their “untoward
consequences for the democratic process,” Automobile
Workers , supra , at 577–578, has long reached beyond
corporate money. During and shortly after World War II, Congress
reacted to the “enormous financial outlays” made by some unions in
connection with national elections. 352 U. S., at 579. Congress
first restricted union contributions in the Hatch Act, 18 U.
S. C. §610,[ Footnote 2 ]
and it later prohibited “union contributions in connection with
federal elections … altogether.” National Right to Work,
supra , at 209 (citing War Labor Disputes Act (Smith-Connally
Anti-Strike Act), ch. 144, §9, 57 Stat. 167). Congress subsequently
extended that prohibition to cover unions’ election-related
expenditures as well as contributions, and it broadened the
coverage of federal campaigns to include both primary and general
elections. Labor Management Relations Act, 1947 (Taft-Hartley Act),
61 Stat. 136. See Automobile Workers, supra , at 578–584.
During the consideration of those measures, legislators repeatedly
voiced their concerns regarding the pernicious influence of large
campaign contributions. See 93 Cong. Rec. 3428, 3522 (1947);
H. R. Rep. No. 245, 80th Cong., 1st Sess. (1947); S. Rep.
No. 1, 80th Cong., 1st Sess., pt. 2 (1947); H. R. Rep. No.
2093, 78th Cong., 2d Sess. (1945). As we noted in a unanimous
opinion recalling this history, Congress’ “careful legislative
adjustment of the federal election laws, in a ‘cautious advance,
step by step,’ to account for the particular legal and economic
attributes of corporations and labor organizations warrants
considerable deference.” National Right to Work, 352 U.
S., at 209 (citations omitted).
In early 1972 Congress continued its steady
improvement of the national election laws by enacting FECA, 86
Stat. 3. As first enacted, that statute required disclosure of all
contributions exceeding $100 and of expenditures by candidates and
political committees that spent more than $1,000 per year. Id. , at 11–19. It also prohibited contributions made in
the name of another person, id., at 19, and by Government
contractors, id., at 10. The law ratified the earlier
prohibition on the use of corporate and union general treasury
funds for political contributions and expenditures, but it
expressly permitted corporations and unions to establish and
administer separate segregated funds (commonly known as political
action committees, or PACs) for election-related contributions and
expenditures. Id ., at 12–13.[ Footnote 3 ] See Pipefitters v. United
States, 407 U. S. 385 , 409–410
(1972).
As the 1972 presidential elections made clear,
however, FECA’s passage did not deter unseemly fundraising and
campaign practices. Evidence of those practices persuaded Congress
to enact the Federal Election Campaign Act Amendments of 1974, 88
Stat. 1263. Reviewing a constitutional challenge to the amendments,
the Court of Appeals for the District of Columbia Circuit described
them as “by far the most comprehensive … reform legislation [ever]
passed by Congress concerning the election of the President,
Vice-President and members of Congress.” Buckley v. Valeo , 519 F. 2d 821, 831 (1975) (en banc) (per
curiam) .
The 1974 amendments closed the loophole that
had allowed candidates to use an unlimited number of political
committees for fundraising purposes and thereby to circumvent the
limits on individual committees’ receipts and disbursements. They
also limited individual political contributions to any single
candidate to $1,000 per election, with an overall annual limitation
of $25,000 by any contributor; imposed ceilings on spending by
candidates and political parties for national conventions; required
reporting and public disclosure of contributions and expenditures
exceeding certain limits; and established the Federal Election
Commission (FEC) to administer and enforce the legislation. Id ., at 831–834 . The Court of Appeals upheld the 1974
amendments almost in their entirety.[ Footnote 4 ] It concluded that the clear and compelling
interest in preserving the integrity of the electoral process
provided a sufficient basis for sustaining the substantive
provisions of the Act. Id. , at 841. The court’s opinion
relied heavily on findings that large contributions facilitated
access to public officials[ Footnote
5 ] and described methods of evading the contribution limits
that had enabled contributors of massive sums to avoid disclosure. Id. , at 837–841.[ Footnote
6 ]
The Court of Appeals upheld the provisions
establishing contribution and expenditure limitations on the theory
that they should be viewed as regulations of conduct rather than
speech. Id. , at 840–841 (citing United States v. O’Brien, 391 U. S. 367 , 376–377
(1968)). This Court, however, concluded that each set of
limitations raised serious—though different—concerns under the
First Amendment. Buckley v. Valeo , 424 U. S. 1 , 14–23 (1976) (per
curiam) . We treated the limitations on candidate and
individual expenditures as direct restraints on speech, but we
observed that the contribution limitations, in contrast, imposed
only “a marginal restriction upon the contributor’s ability to
engage in free communication.” Id. , at 20–21. Considering
the “deeply disturbing examples” of corruption related to candidate
contributions discussed in the Court of Appeals’ opinion, we
determined that limiting contributions served an interest in
protecting “the integrity of our system of representative
democracy.” Id. , at 26–27. In the end, the Act’s primary
purpose—“to limit the actuality and appearance of corruption
resulting from large individual financial contributions”—provided
“a constitutionally sufficient justification for the $1,000
contribution limitation.” Id., at 26.
We prefaced our analysis of the $1,000
limitation on expenditures by observing that it broadly encompassed
every expenditure “ ‘relative to a clearly identified
candidate.’ ” Id. , at 39 (quoting 18 U. S. C.
§608(e)(1) (1970 ed., Supp. IV)). To avoid vagueness concerns we
construed that phrase to apply only to “communications that in
express terms advocate the election or defeat of a clearly
identified candidate for federal office.” 424 U. S., at 42– 44. We
concluded, however, that as so narrowed, the provision would not
provide effective protection against the dangers of quid pro
quo arrangements, because persons and groups could eschew
expenditures that expressly advocated the election or defeat of a
clearly identified candidate while remaining “free to spend as much
as they want to promote the candidate and his views.” Id. ,
at 45. We also rejected the argument that the expenditure limits
were necessary to prevent attempts to circumvent the Act’s
contribution limits, because FECA already treated expenditures
controlled by or coordinated with the candidate as contributions,
and we were not persuaded that independent expenditures posed the
same risk of real or apparent corruption as coordinated
expenditures. Id. , at 46–47. We therefore held that
Congress’ interest in preventing real or apparent corruption was
inadequate to justify the heavy burdens on the freedoms of
expression and association that the expenditure limits imposed.
We upheld all of the disclosure and reporting
requirements in the Act that were challenged on appeal to this
Court after finding that they vindicated three important interests:
providing the electorate with relevant information about the
candidates and their supporters; deterring actual corruption and
discouraging the use of money for improper purposes; and
facilitating enforcement of the prohibitions in the Act. Id. , at 66–68. In order to avoid an overbreadth problem,
however, we placed the same narrowing construction on the term
“expenditure” in the disclosure context that we had adopted in the
context of the expenditure limitations. Thus, we construed the
reporting requirement for persons making expenditures of more than
$100 in a year “to reach only funds used for communications that
expressly advocate the election or defeat of a clearly identified
candidate.” Id. , at 80 (footnote omitted).
Our opinion in Buckley addressed
issues that primarily related to contributions and expenditures by
individuals, since none of the parties challenged the prohibition
on contributions by corporations and labor unions. We noted,
however, that the statute authorized the use of corporate and union
resources to form and administer segregated funds that could be
used for political purposes. Id. , at 28–29, n. 31;
see also n. 3, supra .
Three important developments in the years
after our decision in Buckley persuaded Congress that
further legislation was necessary to regulate the role that
corporations, unions, and wealthy contributors play in the
electoral process. As a preface to our discussion of the specific
provisions of BCRA, we comment briefly on the increased importance
of “soft money,” the proliferation of “issue ads,” and the
disturbing findings of a Senate investigation into campaign
practices related to the 1996 federal elections. Soft Money Under FECA, “contributions”
must be made with funds that are subject to the Act’s disclosure
requirements and source and amount limitations. Such funds are
known as “federal” or “hard” money. FECA defines the term
“contribution,” however, to include only the gift or advance of
anything of value “made by any person for the purpose of
influencing any election for Federal office.” 2 U. S. C.
§431(8)(A)(i) (emphasis added). Donations made solely for the
purpose of influencing state or local elections are therefore
unaffected by FECA’s requirements and prohibitions. As a result,
prior to the enactment of BCRA, federal law permitted corporations
and unions, as well as individuals who had already made the maximum
permissible contributions to federal candidates, to contribute
“nonfederal money”—also known as “soft money”—to political parties
for activities intended to influence state or local elections.
Shortly after Buckley was decided, questions arose concerning the treatment of
contributions intended to influence both federal and state
elections. Although a literal reading of FECA’s definition of
“contribution” would have required such activities to be funded
with hard money, the FEC ruled that political parties could fund
mixed-purpose activities—including get-out-the-vote drives and
generic party advertising—in part with soft money.[ Footnote 7 ] In 1995 the FEC concluded that
the parties could also use soft money to defray the costs of
“legislative advocacy media advertisements,” even if the ads
mentioned the name of a federal candidate, so long as they did not
expressly advocate the candidate’s election or defeat. FEC Advisory
Op. 1995–25.
As the permissible uses of soft money
expanded, the amount of soft money raised and spent by the national
political parties increased exponentially. Of the two major
parties’ total spending, soft money accounted for 5% ($21.6
million) in 1984, 11% ($45 million) in 1988, 16% ($80 million) in
1992, 30% ($272 million) in 1996, and 42% ($498 million) in
2000.[ Footnote 8 ] The national
parties transferred large amounts of their soft money to the state
parties, which were allowed to use a larger percentage of soft
money to finance mixed-purpose activities under FEC rules.[ Footnote 9 ] In the year 2000, for
example, the national parties diverted $280 million—more than half
of their soft money—to state parties.
Many contributions of soft money were
dramatically larger than the contributions of hard money permitted
by FECA. For example, in 1996 the top five corporate soft-money
donors gave, in total, more than $9 million in nonfederal funds to
the two national party committees.[ Footnote 10 ] In the most recent election cycle the
political parties raised almost $300 million—60% of their total
soft-money fundraising—from just 800 donors, each of which
contributed a minimum of $120,000.[ Footnote 11 ] Moreover, the largest corporate donors often
made substantial contributions to both parties.[ Footnote 12 ] Such practices corroborate
evidence indicating that many corporate contributions were
motivated by a desire for access to candidates and a fear of being
placed at a disadvantage in the legislative process relative to
other contributors, rather than by ideological support for the
candidates and parties.[ Footnote
13 ]
Not only were such soft-money contributions
often designed to gain access to federal candidates, but they were
in many cases solicited by the candidates themselves. Candidates
often directed potential donors to party committees and tax-exempt
organizations that could legally accept soft money. For example, a
federal legislator running for reelection solicited soft money from
a supporter by advising him that even though he had already
“contributed the legal maximum” to the campaign committee, he could
still make an additional contribution to a joint program supporting
federal, state, and local candidates of his party.[ Footnote 14 ] Such solicitations were not
uncommon.[ Footnote 15 ]
The solicitation, transfer, and use of soft
money thus enabled parties and candidates to circumvent FECA’s
limitations on the source and amount of contributions in connection
with federal elections. Issue Advertising In Buckley we construed
FECA’s disclosure and reporting requirements, as well as its
expenditure limitations, “to reach only funds used for
communications that expressly advocate the election or defeat of a
clearly identified candidate.” 424 U. S., at 80 (footnote omitted).
As a result of that strict reading of the statute, the use or
omission of “magic words” such as “Elect John Smith” or “Vote
Against Jane Doe” marked a bright statutory line separating
“express advocacy” from “issue advocacy.” See id. , at 44,
n. 52. Express advocacy was subject to FECA’s limitations and could
be financed only using hard money. The political parties, in other
words, could not use soft money to sponsor ads that used any magic
words, and corporations and unions could not fund such ads out of
their general treasuries. So-called issue ads, on the other hand,
not only could be financed with soft money, but could be aired
without disclosing the identity of, or any other information about,
their sponsors.
While the distinction between
“issue” and express advocacy seemed neat in theory, the two
categories of advertisements proved functionally identical in
important respects. Both were used to advocate the election or
defeat of clearly identified federal candidates, even though the
so-called issue ads eschewed the use of magic words.[ Footnote 16 ] Little difference existed,
for example, between an ad that urged viewers to “vote against Jane
Doe” and one that condemned Jane Doe’s record on a particular issue
before exhorting viewers to “call Jane Doe and tell her what you
think.”[ Footnote 17 ] Indeed,
campaign professionals testified that the most effective campaign
ads, like the most effective commercials for products such as
Coca-Cola, should, and did, avoid the use of the magic
words.[ Footnote 18 ]
Moreover, the conclusion that such ads were specifically intended
to affect election results was confirmed by the fact that almost
all of them aired in the 60 days immediately preceding a federal
election.[ Footnote 19 ]
Corporations and unions spent hundreds of millions of dollars of
their general funds to pay for these ads,[ Footnote 20 ] and those expenditures, like soft-money
donations to the political parties, were unregulated under FECA.
Indeed, the ads were attractive to organizations and candidates
precisely because they were beyond FECA’s reach, enabling
candidates and their parties to work closely with friendly interest
groups to sponsor so-called issue ads when the candidates
themselves were running out of money.[ Footnote 21 ]
Because FECA’s disclosure requirements did not
apply to so-called issue ads, sponsors of such ads often used
misleading names to conceal their identity. “Citizens for Better
Medicare,” for instance, was not a grassroots organization of
citizens, as its name might suggest, but was instead a platform for
an association of drug manufacturers.[ Footnote 22 ] And “Republicans for Clean Air,” which ran
ads in the 2000 Republican Presidential primary, was actually an
organization consisting of just two individuals—brothers who
together spent $25 million on ads supporting their favored
candidate.[ Footnote 23 ]
While the public may not have been fully
informed about the sponsorship of so-called issue ads, the record
indicates that candidates and officeholders often were. A former
Senator confirmed that candidates and officials knew who their
friends were and “sometimes suggest[ed] that corporations or
individuals make donations to interest groups that run ‘issue
ads.’ ”[ Footnote 24 ] As
with soft-money contributions, political parties and candidates
used the availability of so-called issue ads to circumvent FECA’s
limitations, asking donors who contributed their permitted quota of
hard money to give money to nonprofit corporations to spend on
“issue” advocacy.[ Footnote
25 ] Senate Committee Investigation In 1998 the Senate Committee
on Governmental Affairs issued a six-volume report summarizing the
results of an extensive investigation into the campaign practices
in the 1996 federal elections. The report gave particular attention
to the effect of soft money on the American political system,
including elected officials’ practice of granting special access in
return for political contributions. The committee’s principal
findings relating to Democratic Party fundraising were set forth in
the majority’s report, while the minority report primarily
described Republican practices. The two reports reached consensus,
however, on certain central propositions. They agreed that the
“soft money loophole” had led to a “meltdown” of the campaign
finance system that had been intended “to keep corporate, union and
large individual contributions from influencing the electoral
process.”[ Footnote 26 ] One
Senator stated that “the hearings provided overwhelming evi- dence
that the twin loopholes of soft money and bogus issue advertising
have virtually destroyed our campaign finance laws, leaving us with
little more than a pile of legal rubble.”[ Footnote 27 ] The report was critical of both parties’
methods of raising soft money, as well as their use of those funds.
It concluded that both parties promised and provided special access
to candidates and senior Government officials in exchange for large
soft-money contributions. The Committee majority described the
White House coffees that rewarded major donors with access to
President Clinton,[ Footnote
28 ] and the courtesies extended to an international businessman
named Roger Tamraz, who candidly acknowledged that his donations of
about $300,000 to the DNC and to state parties were motivated by
his interest in gaining the Federal Government’s support for an
oil-line project in the Caucasus.[ Footnote 29 ] The minority described the promotional
materials used by the RNC’s two principal donor programs, “Team
100” and the “Republican Eagles,” which promised “special access to
high-ranking Republican elected officials, including governors,
senators, and representatives.”[ Footnote 30 ] One fundraising letter recited that the
chairman of the RNC had personally escorted a donor on appointments
that “ ‘turned out to be very significant in legislation
affecting public utility holding companies’ ” and made the
donor “ ‘a hero in his industry.’ ”[ Footnote 31 ]
In 1996 both parties began to use large
amounts of soft money to pay for issue advertising designed to
influence federal elections. The Committee found such ads highly
problematic for two reasons. Since they accomplished the same
purposes as express advocacy (which could lawfully be funded only
with hard money), the ads enabled unions, corporations, and wealthy
contributors to circumvent protections that FECA was intended to
provide. Moreover, though ostensibly independent of the candidates,
the ads were often actually coordinated with, and controlled by,
the campaigns.[ Footnote 32 ]
The ads thus provided a means for evading FECA’s candidate
contribution limits.
The report also emphasized the role of state
and local parties. While the FEC’s allocation regime permitted
national parties to use soft money to pay for up to 40% of the
costs of both generic voter activities and issue advertising, they
allowed state and local parties to use larger percentages of soft
money for those purposes.[ Footnote 33 ] For that reason, national parties often made
substantial transfers of soft money to “state and local political
parties for ‘generic voter activities’ that in fact ultimately
benefit[ed] federal candidates because the funds for all practical
purposes remain[ed] under the control of the national committees.”
The report concluded that “[t]he use of such soft money thus
allow[ed] more corporate, union treasury, and large contributions
from wealthy individuals into the system.”[ Footnote 34 ]
The report discussed potential reforms,
including a ban on soft money at the national and state party
levels and restrictions on sham issue advocacy by nonparty
groups.[ Footnote 35 ] The
majority expressed the view that a ban on the raising of soft money
by national party committees would effectively address the use of
union and corporate general treasury funds in the federal political
process only if it required that candidate-specific ads be funded
with hard money.[ Footnote
36 ] The minority similarly recommended the elimination of
soft-money contributions to political parties from individuals,
corporations, and unions, as well as “reforms addressing candidate
advertisements masquerading as issue ads.”[ Footnote 37 ]
II
In BCRA, Congress enacted many of
the committee’s proposed reforms. BCRA’s central provisions are
designed to address Congress’ concerns about the increasing use of
soft money and issue advertising to influence federal elections.
Title I regulates the use of soft money by political parties,
officeholders, and candidates. Title II primarily prohibits
corporations and labor unions from using general treasury funds for
communications that are intended to, or have the effect of,
influencing the outcome of federal elections.
Section 403 of BCRA provides
special rules for actions challenging the constitutionality of any
of the Act’s provisions. 2 U. S. C. A. §437h note (Supp.
2003). Eleven such actions were filed promptly after the statute
went into effect in March 2002. As required by §403, those actions
were filed in the District Court for the District of Columbia and
heard by a three-judge court. Section 403 directed the District
Court to advance the cases on the docket and to expedite their
disposition “to the greatest possible extent.” The court received a
voluminous record compiled by the parties and ultimately delivered
a decision embodied in a two-judge per curiam opinion and
three separate, lengthy opinions, each of which contained extensive
commentary on the facts and a careful analysis of the legal issues.
251 F. Supp. 2d 176 (2003). The three judges reached unanimity on
certain issues but differed on many. Their judgment, entered on May
1, 2003, held some parts of BCRA unconstitutional and upheld
others. 251 F. Supp. 2d 948.
As authorized by §403, all of the losing
parties filed direct appeals to this Court within 10 days. 2 U.
S. C. A. §437h note. On June 5, 2003, we noted probable
jurisdiction and ordered the parties to comply with an expedited
briefing schedule and present their oral arguments at a special
hearing on September 8, 2003. 539 U. S. ___. To simplify the
presentation, we directed the parties challenging provisions of
BCRA to proceed first on all issues, whether or not they prevailed
on any issue in the District Court. Ibid . Mindful of
§403’s instruction that we expedite our disposition of these
appeals to the greatest extent possible, we also consider each of
the issues in order. Accordingly, we first turn our attention to
Title I of BCRA.
III
Title I is Congress’ effort to
plug the soft-money loophole. The cornerstone of Title I is new
FECA §323(a), which prohibits national party committees and their
agents from soliciting, receiving, directing, or spending any soft
money. 2 U. S. C. A. §441i(a) (Supp. 2003).[ Footnote 38 ] In short, §323(a) takes
national parties out of the soft-money business.
The remaining provisions of new
FECA §323 largely reinforce the restrictions in §323(a). New FECA
§323(b) prevents the wholesale shift of soft-money influence from
national to state party committees by prohibiting state and local
party committees from using such funds for activities that affect
federal elections. 2 U. S. C. A. §441i(b). These “Federal
election activit[ies],” defined in new FECA §301(20)(A), are almost
identical to the mixed-purpose activities that have long been
regulated under the FEC’s pre-BCRA allocation regime. 2 U.
S. C. A. §431(20)(A). New FECA §323(d) reinforces these
soft-money restrictions by prohibiting political parties from
soliciting and donating funds to tax-exempt organizations that
engage in electioneering activities. 2 U. S. C. A.
§441i(d). New FECA §323(e) restricts federal candidates and
officeholders from receiving, spending, or soliciting soft money in
connection with federal elections and limits their ability to do so
in connection with state and local elections. 2 U.
S. C. A. §441i(e). Finally, new FECA §323(f) prevents
circumvention of the restrictions on national, state, and local
party committees by prohibiting state and local candidates from
raising and spending soft money to fund advertisements and other
public communications that promote or attack federal candidates. 2
U. S. C. A. §441i(f).
Plaintiffs mount a facial First Amendment
challenge to new FECA §323, as well as challenges based on the
Elections Clause, U. S. Const., Art. I, §4, principles of
federalism, and the equal protection component of the Due Process
Clause. We address these challenges in turn.
A
In Buckley and
subsequent cases, we have subjected restrictions on campaign
expenditures to closer scrutiny than limits on campaign
contributions. See, e.g., Federal Election Comm’n v. Beaumont, 539 U. S. ___, ___ (2003) (slip op., at 14);
see also Nixon v. Shrink Missouri Government PAC, 528 U. S. 377 , 387–388 (2000); Buckley , 424 U. S., at 19. In these cases we have
recognized that contribution limits, unlike limits on expenditures,
“entai[l] only a marginal restriction upon the contributor’s
ability to engage in free communication.” Id., at 20; see
also, e.g., Beaumont , supra, at ___
(slip op., at 14); Shrink Missouri , supra, at
386–388. In Buckley we said that:
“A contribution serves as a general expression of
support for the candidate and his views, but does not communicate
the underlying basis for the support. The quantity of communication
by the contributor does not increase perceptibly with the size of
the contribution, since the expression rests solely on the
undifferentiated, symbolic act of contributing. At most, the size
of the contribution provides a very rough index of the intensity of
the contributor’s support for the candidate. A limitation on the
amount of money a person may give to a candidate or campaign
organization thus involves little direct restraint on his political
communication, for it permits the symbolic expression of support
evidenced by a contribution but does not in any way infringe the
contributor’s freedom to discuss candidates and issues. While
contributions may result in political expression if spent by a
candidate or an association to present views to the voters, the
transformation of contributions into political debate involves
speech by someone other than the contributor.” 424 U. S., at 21
(footnote omitted).
Because the communicative value of large
contributions inheres mainly in their ability to facilitate the
speech of their recipients, we have said that contribution limits
impose serious burdens on free speech only if they are so low as to
“preven[t] candidates and political committees from amassing the
resources necessary for effective advocacy.” Ibid. We have recognized that contribution limits
may bear “more heavily on the associational right than on freedom
to speak,” Shrink Missouri , supra , at 388, since
contributions serve “to affiliate a person with a candidate” and
“enabl[e] like-minded persons to pool their resources,” Buckley , 424 U. S., at 22. Unlike expenditure limits,
however, which “preclud[e] most associations from effectively
amplifying the voice of their adherents,” contribution limits both
“leave the contributor free to become a member of any political
association and to assist personally in the association’s efforts
on behalf of candidates,” and allow associations “to aggregate
large sums of money to promote effective advocacy.” Ibid. The “overall effect” of dollar limits on contributions is “merely
to require candidates and political committees to raise funds from
a greater number of persons.” Id., at 21–22. Thus, a
contribution limit involving even “ ‘significant
interference’ ” with associational rights is nevertheless
valid if it satisfies the “lesser demand” of being “ ‘closely
drawn’ ” to match a “ ‘sufficiently important
interest.’ ” Beaumont , supra , at ___ (slip
op., at 15) (quoting Shrink Missouri , supra , at
387–388).[ Footnote 39 ]
Our treatment of contribution restrictions
reflects more than the limited burdens they impose on First
Amendment freedoms. It also reflects the importance of the
interests that underlie contribution limits—interests in preventing
“both the actual corruption threatened by large financial
contributions and the eroding of public confidence in the electoral
process through the appearance of corruption.” National Right
to Work, 459 U. S., at 208; see also Federal Election
Comm’n v. Colorado Republican Federal Campaign Comm., 533 U. S. 431 , 440–441 (2001) (Colorado II) . We have said that these interests directly
implicate “ ‘the integrity of our electoral process, and, not
less, the responsibility of the individual citizen for the
successful functioning of that process.’ ” National Right
to Work, supra , at 208 (quoting Automobile
Workers, 352 U. S., at 570). Because the electoral process is
the very “means through which a free society democratically
translates political speech into concrete governmental action,” Shrink Missouri , 528 U. S., at 401 (Breyer, J.,
concurring), contribution limits, like other measures aimed at
protecting the integrity of the process, tangibly benefit public
participation in political debate. For that reason, when reviewing
Congress’ decision to enact contribution limits, “there is no place
for a strong presumption against constitutionality, of the sort
often thought to accompany the words ‘strict scrutiny.’ ” Id. , at 400 (Breyer, J., concurring). The less rigorous
standard of review we have applied to contribution limits
( Buckley ’s “closely drawn” scrutiny) shows proper
deference to Congress’ ability to weigh competing constitutional
interests in an area in which it enjoys particular expertise. It
also provides Congress with sufficient room to anticipate and
respond to concerns about circumvention of regulations designed to
protect the integrity of the political process.
Our application of this less rigorous degree
of scrutiny has given rise to significant criticism in the past
from our dissenting colleagues. See, e.g. , Shrink
Missouri , 528 U. S., at 405–410 (Kennedy, J., dissenting); id. , at 410–420 (Thomas, J., dissenting); Colorado
Republican Federal Campaign Comm. v. Federal Election
Comm’n, 518 U. S. 604 , 635–644 (1996) (Colorado I) (Thomas, J., dissenting). We have rejected
such criticism in previous cases for the reasons identified above.
We are also mindful of the fact that in its lengthy deliberations
leading to the enactment of BCRA, Congress properly relied on the
recognition of its authority contained in Buckley and its
progeny. Considerations of stare decisis , buttressed by
the respect that the Legislative and Judicial Branches owe to one
another, provide additional powerful reasons for adhering to the
analysis of contribution limits that the Court has consistently
followed since Buckley was decided. See Hilton v. South Carolina Public Railways Comm’n, 502 U. S. 197 , 202
(1991).[ Footnote 40 ]
Like the contribution limits we upheld in Buckley , §323’s restrictions have only a marginal impact
on the ability of contributors, candidates, officeholders, and
parties to engage in effective political speech. Beaumont ,
539 U. S., at ___ (slip op., at 14). Complex as its provisions may
be, §323, in the main, does little more than regulate the ability
of wealthy individuals, corporations, and unions to contribute
large sums of money to influence federal elections, federal
candidates, and federal officeholders.
Plaintiffs contend that we must apply strict
scrutiny to §323 because many of its provisions restrict not only
contributions but also the spending and solicitation of funds
raised outside of FECA’s contribution limits. But for purposes of
determining the level of scrutiny, it is irrelevant that Congress
chose in §323 to regulate contributions on the demand rather than
the supply side. See, e.g. , National Right to Work,
supra, at 206–211 (upholding a provision restricting PACs’
ability to solicit funds). The relevant inquiry is whether the
mechanism adopted to implement the contribution limit, or to
prevent circumvention of that limit, burdens speech in a way that a
direct restriction on the contribution itself would not. That is
not the case here.
For example, while §323(a) prohibits national
parties from receiving or spending nonfederal money, and §323(b)
prohibits state party committees from spending nonfederal money on
federal election activities, neither provision in any way limits
the total amount of money parties can spend. 2 U.
S. C. A. §§441i(a), (b) (Supp. 2003). Rather, they simply
limit the source and individual amount of donations. That they do
so by prohibiting the spending of soft money does not render them
expenditure limitations.[ Footnote 41 ]
Similarly, the solicitation provisions of
§323(a) and §323(e), which restrict the ability of national party
committees, federal candidates, and federal officeholders to
solicit nonfederal funds, leave open ample opportunities for
soliciting federal funds on behalf of entities subject to FECA’s
source and amount restrictions. Even §323(d), which on its face
enacts a blanket ban on party solicitations of funds to certain
tax-exempt organizations, nevertheless allows parties to solicit
funds to the organizations’ federal PACs. 2 U. S. C. A.
§441i(d). As for those organizations that cannot or do not
administer PACs, parties remain free to donate federal funds
directly to such organizations, and may solicit funds expressly for
that purpose. See infra , at 72–73 (construing §323(d)’s
restriction on donations by parties to apply only to donations from
a party committee’s nonfederal or soft-money account). And as with
§323(a), §323(d) places no limits on other means of endorsing
tax-exempt organizations or any restrictions on solicitations by
party officers acting in their individual capacities. 2 U.
S. C. A. §§441i(a), (d).
Section 323 thus shows “due regard for the
reality that solicitation is characteristically intertwined with
informative and perhaps persuasive speech seeking support for
particular causes or for particular views.” Schaumburg v. Citizens for a Better Environment, 444 U. S. 620 , 632
(1980). The fact that party committees and federal candidates and
officeholders must now ask only for limited dollar amounts or
request that a corporation or union contribute money through its
PAC in no way alters or impairs the political message “intertwined”
with the solicitation. Cf. Riley v. National
Federation of Blind of N. C., Inc., 487 U. S. 781 , 795
(1988) (treating solicitation restriction that required fundraisers
to disclose particular information as a content-based regulation
subject to strict scrutiny because it “necessarily alter[ed] the
content of the speech”). And rather than chill such solicitations,
as was the case in Schaumburg , the restriction here tends
to increase the dissemination of information by forcing parties,
candidates, and officeholders to solicit from a wider array of
potential donors. As with direct limits on contributions,
therefore, §323’s spending and solicitation restrictions have only
a marginal impact on political speech.[ Footnote 42 ]
Finally, plaintiffs contend that the type of
associational burdens that §323 imposes are fundamentally different
from the burdens that accompanied Buckley ’s contribution
limits, and merit the type of strict scrutiny we have applied to
attempts to regulate the internal processes of political parties. E.g. , California Democratic Party v. Jones, 530 U. S. 567 , 573–574 (2000). In
making this argument, plaintiffs greatly exaggerate the effect of
§323, contending that it precludes any collaboration among
national, state, and local committees of the same party in
fundraising and electioneering activities. We do not read the
provisions in that way. See infra , at 51–52. Section 323
merely subjects a greater percentage of contributions to parties
and candidates to FECA’s source and amount limitations. Buckley has already acknowledged that such limitations
“leave the contributor free to become a member of any political
association and to assist personally in the association’s efforts
on behalf of candidates.” 424 U. S., at 22. The modest impact that
§323 has on the ability of committees within a party to associate
with each other does not independently occasion strict scrutiny.
None of this is to suggest that the alleged associational burdens
imposed on parties by §323 have no place in the First Amendment
analysis; it is only that we account for them in the application,
rather than the choice, of the appropriate level of
scrutiny.[ Footnote 43 ]
With these principles in mind, we apply the
less rigorous scrutiny applicable to contribution limits to
evaluate the constitutionality of new FECA §323. Because the five
challenged provisions of §323 implicate different First Amendment
concerns, we discuss them separately. We are mindful, however, that
Congress enacted §323 as an integrated whole to vindicate the
Government’s important interest in preventing corruption and the
appearance of corruption. New FECA §323(a)’s Restrictions on National
Party Committees The core of Title I is new
FECA §323(a), which provides that “national committee[s] of a
political party … may not solicit, receive, or direct to another
person a contribution, donation, or transfer of funds or any other
thing of value, or spend any funds, that are not subject to the
limitations, prohibitions, and reporting requirements of this Act.”
2 U. S. C. A. §441i(a)(1) (Supp. 2003). The prohibition
extends to “any officer or agent acting on behalf of such a
national committee, and any entity that is directly or indirectly
established, financed, or maintained, or controlled by such a
national committee.” §441(a)(2). The main goal of §323(a) is
modest. In large part, it simply effects a return to the scheme
that was approved in Buckley and that was subverted by the
creation of the FEC’s allocation regime, which permitted the
political parties to fund federal electioneering efforts with a
combination of hard and soft money. See supra , at 11–13,
and n. 7. Under that allocation regime, national parties were
able to use vast amounts of soft money in their efforts to elect
federal candidates. Consequently, as long as they directed the
money to the political parties, donors could contribute large
amounts of soft money for use in activities designed to influence
federal elections.[ Footnote
44 ] New §323(a) is designed to put a stop to that practice.
1. Governmental Interests Underlying
New FECA §323(a) The Government defends
§323(a)’s ban on national parties’ involvement with soft money as
necessary to prevent the actual and apparent corruption of federal
candidates and officeholders. Our cases have made clear that the
prevention of corruption or its appearance constitutes a
sufficiently important interest to justify political contribution
limits. We have not limited that interest to the elimination of
cash-for-votes exchanges. In Buckley , we expressly rejected
the argument that antibribery laws provided a less restrictive
alternative to FECA’s contribution limits, noting that such laws
“deal[t] with only the most blatant and specific attempts of those
with money to influence government action.” 424 U. S., at 28. Thus,
“[i]n speaking of ‘improper influence’ and ‘opportunities for
abuse’ in addition to ‘ quid pro quo arrangements,’ we
[have] recognized a concern not confined to bribery of public
officials, but extending to the broader threat from politicians too
compliant with the wishes of large contributors.” Shrink
Missouri , 528 U. S., at 389; see also Colorado II ,
533 U. S., at 441 (acknowledging that corruption extends beyond
explicit cash-for-votes agreements to “undue influence on an
officeholder’s judgment”).
Of “almost equal” importance has
been the Government’s interest in combating the appearance or
perception of corruption engendered by large campaign
contributions. Buckley , supra , at 27; see also Shrink Missouri, supra, at 390; Federal Election
Comm’n v. National Conservative Political Action
Comm., 470
U. S. 480 , 496–497 (1985). Take away Congress’ authority to
regulate the appearance of undue influence and “the cynical
assumption that large donors call the tune could jeopardize the
willingness of voters to take part in democratic governance.” Shrink Missouri , 528 U. S., at 390; see also id .,
at 401 (Breyer, J., concurring). And because the First Amendment
does not require Congress to ignore the fact that “candidates,
donors, and parties test the limits of the current law,” Colorado II , 533 U. S., at 457, these interests have been
sufficient to justify not only contribution limits themselves, but
laws preventing the circumvention of such limits, id ., at
456 (“[A]ll Members of the Court agree that circumvention is a
valid theory of corruption”).
“The quantum of empirical evidence needed to
satisfy heightened judicial scrutiny of legislative judgments will
vary up or down with the novelty or the plausibility of the
justification raised.” Shrink Missouri, supra, at 391. The
idea that large contributions to a national party can corrupt or,
at the very least, create the appearance of corruption of federal
candidates and officeholders is neither novel nor implausible. For
nearly 30 years, FECA has placed strict dollar limits and source
restrictions on contributions that individuals and other entities
can give to national, state, and local party committees for the
purpose of influencing a federal election. The premise behind these
restrictions has been, and continues to be, that contributions to a
federal candidate’s party in aid of that candidate’s campaign
threaten to create—no less than would a direct contribution to the
candidate—a sense of obligation. See Buckley , supra, at 38 (upholding FECA’s $25,000 limit on aggregate
yearly contributions to a candidate, political committee, and
political party committee as a “quite modest restraint … to prevent
evasion of the $1,000 contribution limitation” by, among other
things, “huge contributions to the candidate’s political party”).
This is particularly true of contributions to national parties,
with which federal candidates and officeholders enjoy a special
relationship and unity of interest. This close affiliation has
placed national parties in a unique position, “whether they like it
or not,” to serve as “agents for spending on behalf of those who
seek to produce obligated officeholders.” Colorado II , supra, at 452; see also Shrink Missouri , supra, at 406 (Kennedy, J., dissenting) (“[Respondent]
asks us to evaluate his speech claim in the context of a system
which favors candidates and officeholders whose campaigns are
supported by soft money, usually funneled through political
parties ” (emphasis added)). As discussed below, rather than
resist that role, the national parties have actively embraced
it.
The question for present purposes is whether
large soft-money contributions to national party
committees have a corrupting influence or give rise to the
appearance of corruption. Both common sense and the ample record in
these cases confirm Congress’ belief that they do. As set forth
above, supra , at 11–13, and n. 7, the FEC’s
allocation regime has invited widespread circumvention of FECA’s
limits on contributions to parties for the purpose of influencing
federal elections. Under this system, corporate, union, and wealthy
individual donors have been free to contribute substantial sums of
soft money to the national parties, which the parties can spend for
the specific purpose of influencing a particular candidate’s
federal election. It is not only plausible, but likely, that
candidates would feel grateful for such donations and that donors
would seek to exploit that gratitude.[ Footnote 45 ]
The evidence in the record shows that
candidates and donors alike have in fact exploited the soft-money
loophole, the former to increase their prospects of election and
the latter to create debt on the part of officeholders, with the
national parties serving as willing intermediaries. Thus, despite
FECA’s hard-money limits on direct contributions to candidates,
federal officeholders have commonly asked donors to make soft-money
donations to national and state committees “solely in order to
assist federal campaigns,” including the officeholder’s own. 251
F. Supp. 2d, at 472 (Kollar-Kotelly, J.) (quoting declaration
of Wade Randlett, CEO, Dashboard Technology ¶ ;¶ ;6–9 (hereinafter
Randlett Decl.), App. 713–714); see also 251 F. Supp. 2d, at
471–473, 478–479 (Kollar-Kotelly, J.); id ., at 842–843
(Leon, J.). Parties kept tallies of the amounts of soft money
raised by each officeholder, and “the amount of money a Member of
Congress raise[d] for the national political committees often
affect[ed] the amount the committees g[a]ve to assist the Member’s
campaign.” Id ., at 474–475 (Kollar-Kotelly, J.). Donors
often asked that their contributions be credited to particular
candidates, and the parties obliged, irrespective of whether the
funds were hard or soft. Id ., at 477–478 (Kollar-Kotelly,
J.); id ., at 824, 847 (Leon, J.). National party
committees often teamed with individual candidates’ campaign
committees to create joint fundraising committees, which enabled
the candidates to take advantage of the party’s higher contribution
limits while still allowing donors to give to their preferred
candidate. Id ., at 478 (Kollar-Kotelly, J.); id .,
at 847–848 (Leon, J.); see also App. 1286 (Krasno & Sorauf
Expert Report (characterizing the joint fundraising committee as
one “in which Senate candidates in effect rais[e] soft money for
use in their own races”)). Even when not participating directly in
the fundraising, federal officeholders were well aware of the
identities of the donors: National party committees would
distribute lists of potential or actual donors, or donors
themselves would report their generosity to officeholders. 251
F. Supp. 2d, at 487–488 (Kollar-Kotelly, J.) (“[F]or a Member
not to know the identities of these donors, he or she must actively
avoid such knowledge, as it is provided by the national political
parties and the donors themselves”); id ., at 853–855
(Leon, J.).
For their part, lobbyists, CEOs, and wealthy
individuals alike all have candidly admitted donating substantial
sums of soft money to national committees not on ideological
grounds, but for the express purpose of securing influence over
federal officials. For example, a former lobbyist and partner at a
lobbying firm in Washington, D. C., stated in his
declaration:
“ ‘You are doing a favor for somebody by
making a large [soft-money] donation and they appreciate it.
Ordinarily, people feel inclined to reciprocate favors. Do a bigger
favor for someone—that is, write a larger check—and they feel even
more compelled to reciprocate. In my experience, overt words are
rarely exchanged about contributions, but people do have
understandings.’ ” Id., at 493 (Kollar-Kotelly, J.)
(quoting declaration of Robert Rozen, partner, Ernst & Young ¶
;14; see 8–R Defs. Exhs., Tab 33).[ Footnote 46 ]
Particularly telling is the fact that, in 1996 and
2000, more than half of the top 50 soft-money donors gave
substantial sums to both major national parties, leaving
room for no other conclusion but that these donors were seeking
influence, or avoiding retaliation, rather than promoting any
particular ideology. See, e.g., 251 F. Supp. 2d, at
508–510 (Kollar-Kotelly, J.) (citing Mann Expert Report Tbls. 5–6);
251 F. Supp. 2d, at 509 (“ ‘Giving soft money to both
parties, the Republicans and the Democrats, makes no sense at all
unless the donor feels that he or she is buying access.’ ”
(quoting declaration of former Sen. Dale Bumpers ¶ ;15, App.
175)).[ Footnote 47 ]
The evidence from the federal officeholders’
perspective is similar. For example, one former Senator described
the influence purchased by nonfederal donations as follows:
“ ‘Too often, Members’ first thought is not
what is right or what they believe, but how it will affect
fundraising. Who, after all, can seriously contend that a $100,000
donation does not alter the way one thinks about—and quite possibly
votes on—an issue? … When you don’t pay the piper that
finances your campaigns, you will never get any more money from
that piper. Since money is the mother’s milk of politics, you never
want to be in that situation.’ ” 251 F. Supp. 2d, at 481
(Kollar-Kotelly, J.) (quoting declaration of former Sen. Alan
Simpson ¶ ;10 (hereinafter Simpson Decl.), App. 811); 251
F. Supp. 2d, at 851 (Leon, J.) (same).
See also id ., at 489 (Kollar-Kotelly, J.)
(“ ‘The majority of those who contribute to political parties
do so for business reasons, to gain access to influential Members
of Congress and to get to know new Members.” (quoting Hickmott
Decl., Exh. A, ¶ ;46)). By bringing soft-money donors and federal
candidates and officeholders together, “[p]arties are thus
necessarily the instruments of some contributors whose object is
not to support the party’s message or to elect party candidates
across the board, but rather to support a specific candidate for
the sake of a position on one narrow issue, or even to support any
candidate who will be obliged to the contributors.” Colorado
II , 533 U. S., at 451–452.
Plaintiffs argue that without concrete
evidence of an instance in which a federal officeholder has
actually switched a vote (or, presumably, evidence of a specific
instance where the public believes a vote was switched), Congress
has not shown that there exists real or apparent corruption. But
the record is to the contrary. The evidence connects soft money to
manipulations of the legislative calendar, leading to Congress’
failure to enact, among other things, generic drug legislation,
tort reform, and tobacco legislation. See, e.g. , 251 F.
Supp. 2d, at 482 (Kollar-Kotelly, J.); id ., at 852 (Leon,
J.); App. 390–394 (declaration of Sen. John McCain ¶ ;¶ ;5, 8–11
(hereinafter McCain Decl.)); App. 811 (Simpson Decl. ¶ ;10)
(“Donations from the tobacco industry to Republicans scuttled
tobacco legislation, just as contributions from the trial lawyers
to Democrats stopped tort reform”); App. 805 (declaration of former
Sen. Paul Simon ¶ ;¶ ;13–14). To claim that such actions do not
change legislative outcomes surely misunderstands the legislative
process.
More importantly, plaintiffs conceive of
corruption too narrowly. Our cases have firmly established that
Congress’ legitimate interest extends beyond preventing simple
cash-for-votes corruption to curbing “undue influence on an
officeholder’s judgment, and the appearance of such influence.” Colorado II , supra , at 441. Many of the “deeply
disturbing examples” of corruption cited by this Court in Buckley, 424 U. S., at 27, to justify FECA’s contribution
limits were not episodes of vote buying, but evidence that various
corporate interests had given substantial donations to gain access
to high-level government officials. See Buckley , 519
F. 2d, at 821, 839–840, n. 36; nn. 5–6, supra. Even if that access did not secure actual influence, it certainly
gave the “appearance of such influence.” Colorado II , supra , at 441; see also 519 F. 2d , at 838.
The record in the present case is replete with
similar examples of national party committees peddling access to
federal candidates and officeholders in exchange for large
soft-money donations. See 251 F. Supp. 2d, at 492–506
(Kollar-Kotelly, J.). As one former Senator put it:
“ ‘Special interests who give large amounts of
soft money to political parties do in fact achieve their
objectives. They do get special access. Sitting Senators and House
Members have limited amounts of time, but they make time available
in their schedules to meet with representatives of business and
unions and wealthy individuals who gave large sums to their
parties. These are not idle chit-chats about the philosophy of
democracy… . Senators are pressed by their benefactors to
introduce legislation, to amend legislation, to block legislation,
and to vote on legislation in a certain way.’ ” Id. ,
at 496 (Kollar-Kotelly, J.) (quoting declaration of former Sen.
Warren Rudman ¶ ;7 (hereinafter Rudman Decl.), App. 742); 251 F.
Supp. 2d, at 858 (Leon, J.) (same).
So pervasive is this practice that the six national
party committees actually furnish their own menus of opportunities
for access to would-be soft-money donors, with increased prices
reflecting an increased level of access. For example, the DCCC
offers a range of donor options, starting with the $10,000-per-year
Business Forum program, and going up to the $100,000-per-year
National Finance Board program. The latter entitles the donor to
bimonthly conference calls with the Democratic House leadership and
chair of the DCCC, complimentary invitations to all DCCC
fundraising events, two private dinners with the Democratic House
leadership and ranking members, and two retreats with the
Democratic House leader and DCCC chair in Telluride, Colorado, and
Hyannisport, Massachusetts. Id ., at 504–505
(Kollar-Kotelly, J.); see also id ., at 506 (describing
records indicating that DNC offered meetings with President in
return for large donations); id ., at 502–503 (describing
RNC’s various donor programs); id ., at 503–504 (same for
NRSC); id ., at 500–503 (same for DSCC); id ., at
504 (same for NRCC). Similarly, “the RNC’s donor programs offer
greater access to federal office holders as the donations grow
larger, with the highest level and most personal access offered to
the largest soft money donors.” Id ., at 500–503 (finding,
further, that the RNC holds out the prospect of access to
officeholders to attract soft-money donations and encourages
officeholders to meet with large soft-money donors); accord, id ., at 860–861 (Leon, J.).
Despite this evidence and the close ties that
candidates and officeholders have with their parties, Justice
Kennedy would limit Congress’ regulatory interest only to
the prevention of the actual or apparent quid pro quo corruption “inherent in” contributions made directly to,
contributions made at the express behest of, and expenditures made
in coordination with, a federal officeholder or candidate. Post , at 8–10, 15. Regulation of any other donation or
expenditure—regardless of its size, the recipient’s relationship to
the candidate or officeholder, its potential impact on a
candidate’s election, its value to the candidate, or its unabashed
and explicit intent to purchase influence—would, according to
Justice Kennedy, simply be out of bounds. This crabbed view of
corruption, and particularly of the appearance of corruption,
ignores precedent, common sense, and the realities of political
fundraising exposed by the record in this litigation.[ Footnote 48 ]
Justice Kennedy’s interpretation of the First
Amendment would render Congress powerless to address more subtle
but equally dispiriting forms of corruption. Just as troubling to a
functioning democracy as classic quid pro quo corruption
is the danger that officeholders will decide issues not on the
merits or the desires of their constituencies, but according to the
wishes of those who have made large financial contributions valued
by the officeholder. Even if it occurs only occasionally, the
potential for such undue influence is manifest. And unlike straight
cash-for-votes transactions, such corruption is neither easily
detected nor practical to criminalize. The best means of prevention
is to identify and to remove the temptation. The evidence set forth
above, which is but a sampling of the reams of disquieting evidence
contained in the record, convincingly demonstrates that soft-money
contributions to political parties carry with them just such
temptation.
Justice Kennedy likewise takes too narrow a
view of the appearance of corruption. He asserts that only those
transactions with “inherent corruption potential,” which he again
limits to contributions directly to candidates, justify the
inference “that regulating the conduct will stem the appearance of
real corruption.” Post , at 14.[ Footnote 49 ] In our view, however, Congress is not
required to ignore historical evidence regarding a particular
practice or to view conduct in isolation from its context. To be
sure, mere political favoritism or opportunity for influence alone
is insufficient to justify regulation. Post , at 12–14. As
the record demonstrates, it is the manner in which parties have sold access to federal candidates and officeholders that
has given rise to the appearance of undue influence. Implicit (and,
as the record shows, sometimes explicit) in the sale of access is
the suggestion that money buys influence. It is no surprise then
that purchasers of such access unabashedly admit that they are
seeking to purchase just such influence. It was not unwarranted for
Congress to conclude that the selling of access gives rise to the
appearance of corruption.
In sum, there is substantial evidence to
support Congress’ determination that large soft-money contributions
to national political parties give rise to corruption and the
appearance of corruption.
2. New FECA §323(a)’s Restriction on
Spending and Receiving Soft Money Plaintiffs and The Chief
Justice contend that §323(a) is impermissibly overbroad because it
subjects all funds raised and spent by national parties to
FECA’s hard-money source and amount limits, including, for example,
funds spent on purely state and local elections in which no federal
office is at stake.[ Footnote
50 ] Post , 2–5 (Rehnquist, C. J., dissenting).
Such activities, The Chief Justice asserts, pose “little or no
potential to corrupt … federal candidates or officeholders.” Post, at 5 (dissenting opinion). This observation is
beside the point. Section 323(a), like the remainder of §323,
regulates contributions, not activities. As the record
demonstrates, it is the close relationship between federal
officeholders and the national parties, as well as the means by
which parties have traded on that relationship, that have made all
large soft-money contributions to national parties suspect.
As one expert noted,
“ ‘[t]here is no meaningful distinction between the national
party committees and the public officials who control them.’ ”
251 F. Supp. 2d, at 468–469 (Kollar-Kotelly, J.) (quoting Mann
Expert Report 29). The national committees of the two major parties
are both run by, and largely composed of, federal officeholders and
candidates. Indeed, of the six national committees of the two major
parties, four are composed entirely of federal officeholders. Ibid . The nexus between national parties and federal
officeholders prompted one of Title I’s framers to conclude:
“Because the national parties operate at the
national level, and are inextricably intertwined with federal
officeholders and candidates, who raise the money for the national
party committees, there is a close connection between the funding
of the national parties and the corrupting dangers of soft money on
the federal political process. The only effective way to address
this [soft-money] problem of corruption is to ban entirely all
raising and spending of soft money by the national parties.” 148
Cong. Rec. H409 (Feb. 13, 2002) (statement of Rep. Shays).
Given this close connection and alignment of
interests, large soft-money contributions to national parties are
likely to create actual or apparent indebtedness on the part of
federal officeholders, regardless of how those funds are ultimately
used.
This close affiliation has also placed
national parties in a position to sell access to federal
officeholders in exchange for soft-money contributions that the
party can then use for its own purposes. Access to federal
officeholders is the most valuable favor the national party
committees are able to give in exchange for large donations. The
fact that officeholders comply by donating their valuable time
indicates either that officeholders place substantial value on the
soft-money contribution themselves, without regard to their end
use, or that national committees are able to exert considerable
control over federal officeholders. See, e.g. , App.
1196–1198 (Expert Report of Donald P. Green, Yale University)
(“Once elected to legislative office, public officials enter an
environment in which political parties-in-government control the
resources crucial to subsequent electoral success and legislative
power. Political parties organize the legislative caucuses that
make committee assignments”); App. 1298 (Krasno & Sorauf Expert
Report) (indicating that officeholders’ re-election prospects are
significantly influenced by attitudes of party leadership). Either
way, large soft-money donations to national party committees are
likely to buy donors preferential access to federal officeholders
no matter the ends to which their contributions are eventually put.
As discussed above, Congress had sufficient grounds to regulate the
appearance of undue influence associated with this practice. The
Government’s strong interests in preventing corruption, and in
particular the appearance of corruption, are thus sufficient to
justify subjecting all donations to national parties to the source,
amount, and disclosure limitations of FECA.[ Footnote 51 ]
3. New FECA §323(a)’s Restriction on
Soliciting or Directing Soft Money Plaintiffs also contend that
§323(a)’s prohibition on national parties’ soliciting or directing
soft-money contributions is substantially overbroad. The reach of
the solicitation prohibition, however, is limited. It bars only
solicitations of soft money by national party committees and by
party officers in their official capacities. The committees remain
free to solicit hard money on their own behalf, as well as to
solicit hard money on behalf of state committees and state and
local candidates.[ Footnote
52 ] They also can contribute hard money to state committees and
to candidates. In accordance with FEC regulations, furthermore,
officers of national parties are free to solicit soft money in
their individual capacities, or, if they are also officials of
state parties, in that capacity. See 67 Fed. Reg. 49083
(2002). This limited restriction on
solicitation follows sensibly from the prohibition on national
committees’ receiving soft money. The same observations that led us
to approve the latter compel us to reach the same conclusion
regarding the former. A national committee is likely to respond
favorably to a donation made at its request regardless of whether
the recipient is the committee itself or another entity. This
principle accords with common sense and appears elsewhere in
federal laws. E.g. , 18 U. S. C. §201(b)(2) (prohibition
on public officials “demand[ing] [or] seek[ing] … anything of value
personally or for any other person or entity …” (emphasis
added)); 5 CFR §2635.203(f)(2) (2003) (restriction on gifts to
federal employees encompasses gifts “[g]iven to any other person,
including any charitable organization, on the basis of designation,
recommendation, or other specification by the employee”).
Plaintiffs argue that BCRA itself demonstrates
the overbreadth of §323(a)’s solicitation ban. They point in
particular to §323(e), which allows federal candidates and
officeholders to solicit limited amounts of soft money from
individual donors under certain circumstances. Compare 2 U.
S. C. A §441i(a) with §441i(e) (Supp. 2003). The
differences between §§323(a) and 323(e), however, are without
constitutional significance. We have recognized that “the
‘differing structures and purposes’ of different entities ‘may
require different forms of regulation in order to protect the
integrity of the electoral process,’ ” National Right to
Work , 459 U. S., at 210, and we respect Congress’ decision to
proceed in incremental steps in the area of campaign finance
regulation, see Federal Election Comm’n v. Massachusetts Citizens for Life, Inc., 479
U. S. 238 , 258, n. 11 (1986) (MCFL); Buckley , 424 U. S., at 105. The differences between the
two provisions reflect Congress’ reasonable judgments about the
function played by national committees and the interactions between
committees and officeholders, subjects about which Members of
Congress have vastly superior knowledge.
4. New FECA §323(a)’s Application to
Minor Parties The McConnell and political
party plaintiffs contend that §323(a) is substantially overbroad
and must be stricken on its face because it impermissibly infringes
the speech and associational rights of minor parties such as the
Libertarian National Committee, which, owing to their slim
prospects for electoral success and the fact that they receive few
large soft-money contributions from corporate sources, pose no
threat of corruption comparable to that posed by the RNC and DNC.
In Buckley , we rejected a similar argument concerning limits
on contributions to minor-party candidates, noting that “any
attempt to exclude minor parties and independents en masse from the
Act’s contribution limitations overlooks the fact that minor-party
candidates may win elective office or have a substantial impact on
the outcome of an election.” 424 U. S., at 34–35. We have thus
recognized that the relevance of the interest in avoiding actual or
apparent corruption is not a function of the number of legislators
a given party manages to elect. It applies as much to a minor party
that manages to elect only one of its members to federal office as
it does to a major party whose members make up a majority of
Congress. It is therefore reasonable to require that all parties
and all candidates follow the same set of rules designed to protect
the integrity of the electoral process.
We add that nothing in §323(a)
prevents individuals from pooling resources to start a new national
party. Post , at 5 (Kennedy, J., dissenting). Only when an
organization has gained official status, which carries with it
significant benefits for its members, will the proscriptions of
§323(a) apply. Even then, a nascent or struggling minor party can
bring an as-applied challenge if §323(a) prevents it from “amassing
the resources necessary for effective advocacy.” Buckley , supra , at 21.
5. New FECA §323(a)’s Associational
Burdens Finally, plaintiffs assert
that §323(a) is unconstitutional because it impermissibly
interferes with the ability of national committees to associate
with state and local committees. By way of example, plaintiffs
point to the Republican Victory Plans, whereby the RNC acts in
concert with the state and local committees of a given State to
plan and implement joint, full-ticket fundraising and
electioneering programs. See App. 693, 694–697 (declaration of John
Peschong, RNC Western Reg. Political Dir. (describing the
Republican Victory Plans)). The political parties assert that
§323(a) outlaws any participation in Victory Plans by RNC
officers, including merely sitting down at a table and engaging in
collective decisionmaking about how soft money will be solicited,
received, and spent. Such associational burdens, they argue, are
too great for the First Amendment to bear.
We are not persuaded by this
argument because it hinges on an unnaturally broad reading of the
terms “spend,” “receive,” “direct,” and “solicit.” 2 U.
S. C. A. §441i(a) (Supp. 2003). Nothing on the face of
§323(a) prohibits national party officers, whether acting in their
official or individual capacities, from sitting down with state and
local party committees or candidates to plan and advise how to
raise and spend soft money. As long as the national party officer
does not personally spend, receive, direct, or solicit soft money,
§323(a) permits a wide range of joint planning and electioneering
activity. Intervenor-defendants, the principal drafters and
proponents of the legislation, concede as much. Brief for
Intervenor-Defendants Sen. John McCain et al. in No. 02– 1674
et al., p. 22 (“BCRA leaves parties and candidates free
to coordinate campaign plans and activities, political messages,
and fundraising goals with one another”). The FEC’s current
definitions of §323(a)’s terms are consistent with that view. See, e.g. , 11 CFR §300.2(m) (2002) (defining “solicit” as “to ask … another person” (emphasis added)); §300.2(n)
(defining “direct” as “to ask a person who has expressed
an intent to make a contribution . . . to make that contribution …
including through a conduit or intermediary” (emphasis added));
§300.2(c) (laying out the factors that determine whether an entity
will be considered to be controlled by a national committee).
Given the straightforward meaning of this
provision, Justice Kennedy is incorrect that “[a] national party’s
mere involvement in the strategic planning of fundraising for a
state ballot initiative” or its assistance in developing a state
party’s Levin-money fundraising efforts risks a finding that the
officers are in “ ‘indirect control’ ” of the state party
and subject to criminal penalties. Post , at 5–6. Moreover,
§323(a) leaves national party committee officers entirely free to
participate, in their official capacities, with state and local
parties and candidates in soliciting and spending hard money; party
officials may also solicit soft money in their unofficial
capacities.
Accordingly, we reject the plaintiffs’ First
Amendment challenge to new FECA §323(a). New FECA §323(b)’s Restrictions on State and
Local Party Committees In constructing a coherent
scheme of campaign finance regulation, Congress recognized that,
given the close ties between federal candidates and state party
committees, BCRA’s restrictions on national committee activity
would rapidly become ineffective if state and local committees
remained available as a conduit for soft-money donations.[ Footnote 53 ] Section 323(b) is
designed to foreclose wholesale evasion of §323(a)’s anticorruption
measures by sharply curbing state committees’ ability to use large
soft-money contributions to influence federal elections. The core
of §323(b) is a straightforward contribution regulation: It
prevents donors from contributing nonfederal funds to state and
local party committees to help finance “Federal election activity.”
2 U. S. C A. §441i(b)(1) (Supp. 2003). The term “Federal
election activity” encompasses four distinct categories of
electioneering: (1) voter registration activity during the 120 days
preceding a regularly scheduled federal election; (2) voter
identification, get-out-the-vote (GOTV), and generic campaign
activity[ Footnote 54 ] that
is “conducted in connection with an election in which a candidate
for Federal office appears on the ballot”; (3) any “public
communication”[ Footnote 55 ]
that “refers to a clearly identified candidate for Federal office”
and “promotes,” “supports,” “attacks,” or “opposes” a candidate for
that office; and (4) the services provided by a state committee
employee who dedicates more than 25% of his or her time to
“activities in connection with a Federal election.”
§§431(20)(A)(i)–(iv). The Act explicitly excludes several
categories of activity from this definition: public communications
that refer solely to nonfederal candidates;[ Footnote 56 ] contributions to nonfederal
candidates;[ Footnote 57 ]
state and local political conventions; and the cost of grassroots
campaign materials like bumper stickers that refer only to state
candidates. §431(20)(B). All activities that fall within the
statutory definition must be funded with hard money.
§441i(b)(1). Section 323(b)(2), the
so-called Levin Amendment, carves out an exception to this general
rule. A refinement on the pre-BCRA regime that permitted parties to
pay for certain activities with a mix of federal and nonfederal
funds, the Levin Amendment allows state and local party committees
to pay for certain types of federal election activity with an
allocated ratio of hard money and “Levin funds”—that is, funds
raised within an annual limit of $10,000 per person. 2 U.
S. C. A. §441i(b)(2). Except for the $10,000 cap and
certain related restrictions to prevent circumvention of that
limit, §323(b)(2) leaves regulation of such contributions to the
States.[ Footnote
58 ] The scope of the Levin Amendment is
limited in two ways. First, state and local parties can use Levin
money to fund only activities that fall within categories (1) and
(2) of the statute’s definition of federal election
activity—namely, voter registration activity, voter identification
drives, GOTV drives, and generic campaign activities. 2 U.
S. C. A. §441i(b)(2)(A). And not all of these activities
qualify: Levin funds cannot be used to pay for any activities that
refer to “a clearly identified candidate for Federal office”; they
likewise cannot be used to fund broadcast communications unless
they refer “solely to a clearly identified candidate for State or
local office.” §§441i(b)(2)(B)(i)–(ii). Second, both the Levin funds and the
allocated portion of hard money used to pay for such activities
must be raised entirely by the state or local committee that spends
them. §441i(b)(2)(B)(iv). This means that a state party committee
cannot use Levin funds transferred from other party committees to
cover the Levin funds portion of a Levin Amendment expenditure. It
also means that a state party committee cannot use hard money
transferred from other party committees to cover the hard-money
portion of a Levin Amendment expenditure. Furthermore, national
committees, federal candidates, and federal officeholders generally
may not solicit Levin funds on behalf of state committees, and
state committees may not team up to raise Levin funds.
§441i(b)(2)(C). They can, however, jointly raise the hard money
used to make Levin expenditures. 1. Governmental Interests Underlying
New FECA §323(b) We begin by noting that, in
addressing the problem of soft-money contributions to state
committees, Congress both drew a conclusion and made a prediction.
Its conclusion, based on the evidence before it, was that the
corrupting influence of soft money does not insinuate itself into
the political process solely through national party committees.
Rather, state committees function as an alternate avenue for
precisely the same corrupting forces.[ Footnote 59 ] Indeed, both candidates and parties already
ask donors who have reached the limit on their direct contributions
to donate to state committees.[ Footnote 60 ] There is at least as much evidence as there
was in Buckley that such donations have been made with the
intent—and in at least some cases the effect—of gaining influence
over federal officeholders.[ Footnote 61 ] Section 323(b) thus promotes an important
governmental interest by confronting the corrupting influence that
soft-money donations to political parties already have.
Congress also made a prediction.
Having been taught the hard lesson of circumvention by the entire
history of campaign finance regulation, Congress knew that
soft-money donors would react to §323(a) by scrambling to find
another way to purchase influence. It was “neither novel nor
implausible,” Shrink Missouri , 528 U. S., at 391, for
Congress to conclude that political parties would react to §323(a)
by directing soft-money contributors to the state committees, and
that federal candidates would be just as indebted to these
contributors as they had been to those who had formerly contributed
to the national parties. We “must accord substantial deference to
the predictive judgments of Congress,” Turner Broadcasting
System, Inc. v. FCC, 512 U. S. 622 , 665
(1994), particularly when, as here, those predictions are so firmly
rooted in relevant history and common sense. Preventing corrupting
activity from shifting wholesale to state committees and thereby
eviscerating FECA clearly qualifies as an important governmental
interest.
2. New FECA §323(b)’s
Tailoring Plaintiffs argue that even if
some legitimate interest might be served by §323(b), the
provision’s restrictions are unjustifiably burdensome and therefore
cannot be considered “closely drawn” to match the Government’s
objectives. They advance three main contentions in support of this
proposition. First, they argue that the provision is substantially
overbroad because it federalizes activities that pose no
conceivable risk of corrupting or appearing to corrupt federal
officeholders. Second, they argue that the Levin Amendment imposes
an unconstitutional burden on the associational rights of political
parties. Finally, they argue that the provision prevents them from
amassing the resources they need to engage in effective advocacy.
We address these points in turn. a. §323(b)’s Application to Federal
Election Activity Plaintiffs assert that
§323(b) represents a new brand of pervasive federal regulation of
state-focused electioneering activities that cannot possibly
corrupt or appear to corrupt federal officeholders and thus goes
well beyond Congress’ concerns about the corruption of the federal
electoral process. We disagree. It is true that §323(b)
captures some activities that affect state campaigns for nonfederal
offices. But these are the same sorts of activities that already
were covered by the FEC’s pre-BCRA allocation rules, and thus had
to be funded in part by hard money, because they affect federal as
well as state elections. See 11 CFR §106.5 (2002). As a practical
matter, BCRA merely codifies the principles of the FEC’s allocation
regime while at the same time justifiably adjusting the formulas
applicable to these activities in order to restore the efficacy of
FECA’s longtime statutory restriction—approved by the Court and
eroded by the FEC’s allocation regime—on contributions to state and
local party committees for the purpose of influencing federal
elections. See 2 U. S. C. §§431(8)(A), 441a(a)(1)(C); see also
Buckley , 424 U. S., at 38 (upholding FECA’s $25,000 limit on
aggregate contributions to candidates and political committees);
cf. California Medical Assn. v. Federal Election
Comm’n, 453
U. S. 182 (1981) (upholding FECA’s $5,000 limit on
contributions to multicandidate political committees).
Like the rest of Title I, §323(b) is premised
on Congress’ judgment that if a large donation is capable of
putting a federal candidate in the debt of the contributor, it
poses a threat of corruption or the appearance of corruption. As we
explain below, §323(b) is narrowly focused on regulating
contributions that pose the greatest risk of this kind of
corruption: those contributions to state and local parties that can
be used to benefit federal candidates directly. Further, these
regulations all are reasonably tailored, with various temporal and
substantive limitations designed to focus the regulations on the
important anti-corruption interests to be served. We conclude that
§323(b) is a closely-drawn means of countering both corruption and
the appearance of corruption.
The first two categories of “Federal election
activity,” voter registration efforts, §301(20)(A)(i), and voter
identification, GOTV, and generic campaign activities conducted in
connection with a federal election, §301(20)(A)(ii), clearly
capture activity that benefits federal candidates. Common sense
dictates, and it was “undisputed” below, that a party’s efforts to
register voters sympathetic to that party directly assist the
party’s candidates for federal office. 251 F. Supp. 2d, at 460
(Kollar-Kotelly, J.). It is equally clear that federal candidates
reap substantial rewards from any efforts that increase the number
of like-minded registered voters who actually go to the
polls.[ Footnote 62 ] See, e.g. , id ., at 459 (“ ‘[The evidence] shows
quite clearly that a campaign that mobilizes residents of a highly
Republican precinct will produce a harvest of votes for Republican
candidates for both state and federal offices. A campaign need not
mention federal candidates to have a direct effect on voting for
such a candidate… . [G]eneric campaign activity has a direct
effect on federal elections’ ” (quoting Green Expert Report
14)). Representatives of the four major congressional campaign
committees confirmed that they “ ‘transfe[r] federal and
nonfederal money to state and/or local party committees for’ ”
both voter registration and get-out-the-vote activities, and that
“ ‘[t]hese efforts have a significant effect on the election
of federal candidates.’ ” 251 F. Supp. 2d, at 459, 461
(citations omitted).
The record also makes quite clear that federal
officeholders are grateful for contributions to state and local
parties that can be converted into GOTV-type efforts. See id. , at 459 (quoting a letter thanking a California
Democratic Party donor and noting that CDP’s voter registration and
GOTV efforts would help “ ‘increase the number of Californian
Democrats in the United States Congress’ ” and “ ‘deliver
California’s 54 electoral votes’ ” to the Democratic
presidential candidate).
Because voter registration, voter
identification, GOTV, and generic campaign activity all confer
substantial benefits on federal candidates, the funding of such
activities creates a significant risk of actual and apparent
corruption. Section 323(b) is a reasonable response to that risk.
Its contribution limitations are focused on the subset of voter
registration activity that is most likely to affect the election
prospects of federal candidates: activity that occurs within 120
days before a federal election. And if the voter registration drive
does not specifically mention a federal candidate, state committees
can take advantage of the Levin Amendment’s higher contribution
limits and relaxed source restrictions. 2 U. S. C. A.
§§441i(b)(2)(B)(i)–(ii) (Supp. 2003). Similarly, the contribution
limits applicable to §301(20)(A)(ii) activities target only those
voter identification, GOTV, and generic campaign efforts that occur
“in connection with an election in which a candidate for a Federal
office appears on the ballot.” 2 U. S. C. A.
§431(20)(A)(ii). Appropriately, in implementing this subsection,
the FEC has categorically excluded all activity that takes place
during the run-up to elections when no federal office is at
stake.[ Footnote 63 ]
Furthermore, state committees can take advantage of the Levin
Amendment’s higher contribution limits to fund any §301(A)(20)(i)
and §301(A)(20)(ii) activities that do not specifically mention a
federal candidate. 2 U. S. C. A. §§441i(b)(2)(B)(i)–(ii).
The prohibition on the use of soft money in connection with these
activities is therefore closely drawn to meet the sufficiently
important governmental interests of avoiding corruption and its
appearance.
“Public communications” that promote or attack
a candidate for federal office—the third category of “Federal
election activity,” §301(20)(A)(iii)—also undoubtedly have a
dramatic effect on federal elections. Such ads were a prime
motivating force behind BCRA’s passage. See 3 1998 Senate Report
4535 (additional views of Sen. Collins) (“[T]he hearings provided
overwhelming evidence that the twin loopholes of soft money and
bogus issue advertising have virtually destroyed our campaign
finance laws, leaving us with little more than a pile of legal
rubble”). As explained below, any public communication that
promotes or attacks a clearly identified federal candidate directly
affects the election in which he is participating. The record on
this score could scarcely be more abundant. Given the overwhelming
tendency of public communications, as carefully defined in
§301(20)(A)(iii), to benefit directly federal candidates, we hold
that application of §323(b)’s contribution caps to such
communications is also closely drawn to the anticorruption interest
it is intended to address.[ Footnote 64 ]
As for the final category of “Federal election
activity,” §301(20)(A)(iv), we find that Congress’ interest in
preventing circumvention of §323(b)’s other restrictions justifies
the requirement that state and local parties spend federal funds to
pay the salary of any employee spending more than 25% of his or her
compensated time on activities in connection with a federal
election. In the absence of this provision, a party might use soft
money to pay for the equivalent of a full-time employee engaged in
federal electioneering, by the simple expedient of dividing the
federal workload among multiple employees. Plaintiffs have
suggested no reason for us to strike down this provision.
Accordingly, we give “deference to [the] congressional
determination of the need for [this] prophylactic rule.” National Conservative Political Action Comm. , 470 U. S.,
at 500.
b. Associational Burdens Imposed by
the Levin Amendment Plaintiffs also contend that
§323(b) is unconstitutional because the Levin Amendment
unjustifiably burdens association among party committees by
forbidding transfers of Levin funds among state parties, transfers
of hard money to fund the allocable federal portion of Levin
expenditures, and joint fundraising of Levin funds by state
parties. We recognize, as we have in the past, the importance of
preserving the associational freedom of parties. See, e.g. , California Democratic Party v. Jones , 530 U. S. 567 (2000); Eu v. San Francisco County Democratic Central Comm. , 489 U. S. 214 (1989).
But not every minor restriction on parties’ otherwise unrestrained
ability to associate is of constitutional dimension. See Colorado II , 533 U. S., at 450, n. 11.
As an initial matter, we note
that state and local parties can avoid these associational burdens
altogether by forgoing the Levin Amendment option and electing to
pay for federal election activities entirely with hard money. But
in any event, the restrictions on the use, transfer, and raising of
Levin funds are justifiable anticircumvention measures. Without the
ban on transfers of Levin funds among state committees, donors
could readily circumvent the $10,000 limit on contributions to a
committee’s Levin account by making multiple $10,000 donations to
various committees that could then transfer the donations to the
committee of choice.[ Footnote
65 ] The same anticircumvention goal undergirds the ban on joint
solicitation of Levin funds. Without this restriction, state and
local committees could organize “all hands” fundraisers at which
individual, corporate, or union donors could make large soft-money
donations to be divided between the committees. In that case, the
purpose, if not the letter, of §323(b)(2)’s $10,000 limit would be
thwarted: Donors could make large, visible contributions at
fundraisers, which would provide ready means for corrupting federal
officeholders. Given the delicate and interconnected regulatory
scheme at issue here, any associational burdens imposed by the
Levin Amendment restrictions are far outweighed by the need to
prevent circumvention of the entire scheme.
Section 323(b)(2)(B)(iv)’s apparent
prohibition on the transfer of hard money by a national, state, or
local committee to help fund the allocable hard-money portion of a
separate state or local committee’s Levin expenditures presents a
closer question. 2 U. S. C. A. §441i(b)(2)(B)(iv) (Supp.
2003). The Government defends the restriction as necessary to
prevent the donor committee, particularly a national committee,
from leveraging the transfer of federal money to wrest control over
the spending of the recipient committee’s Levin funds. This
purported interest is weak, particularly given the fact that
§323(a) already polices attempts by national parties to engage in
such behavior. See 2 U. S. C. A. §441i(a)(2) (extending
§323(a)’s restrictions to entities controlled by national
party committees). However, the associational burdens posed by the
hard-money transfer restriction are so insubstantial as to be de minimis . Party committees, including national party
committees, remain free to transfer unlimited hard money so long as
it is not used to fund Levin expenditures. State and local party
committees can thus dedicate all “homegrown” hard money to their
Levin activities while relying on outside transfers to defray the
costs of other hard-money expenditures. Given the strong
anticircumvention interest vindicated by §323(b)(2)(B)(iv)’s
restriction on the transfer of Levin funds, we will not strike down
the entire provision based upon such an attenuated claim of
associational infringement.
c. New FECA §323(b)’s Impact on
Parties’ Ability to Engage in Effective
Advocacy Finally, plaintiffs contend
that §323(b) is unconstitutional because its restrictions on
soft-money contributions to state and local party committees will
prevent them from engaging in effective advocacy. As Judge
Kollar-Kotelly noted, the political parties’ evidence regarding the
impact of BCRA on their revenues is “speculative and not based on
any analysis.” 251 F. Supp. 2d, at 524. If the history of
campaign finance regulation discussed above proves anything, it is
that political parties are extraordinarily flexible in adapting to
new restrictions on their fundraising abilities. Moreover, the mere
fact that §323(b) may reduce the relative amount of money available
to state and local parties to fund federal election activities is
largely inconsequential. The question is not whether §323(b)
reduces the amount of funds available over previous election
cycles, but whether it is “so radical in effect as to … drive the
sound of [the recipient’s] voice below the level of notice.” Shrink
Missouri , 528 U. S., at 397. If indeed state or local parties
can make such a showing, as-applied challenges remain
available.
We accordingly conclude that
§323(b), on its face, is closely drawn to match the important
governmental interests of preventing corruption and the appearance
of corruption. New FECA §323(d)’s Restrictions on Parties’
Solicitations for, and Donations to, Tax-Exempt
Organizations Section 323(d)
prohibits national, state, and local party committees, and their
agents or subsidiaries, from “solicit[ing] any funds for, or
mak[ing] or direct[ing] any donations” to, any organization
established under §501(c) of the Internal Revenue Code[ Footnote 66 ] that makes expenditures
in connection with an election for federal office, and any
political organizations established under §527 “other than a
political committee, a State, district, or local committee of a
political party, or the authorized campaign committee of a
candidate for State or local office.”[ Footnote 67 ] 2 U. S. C. A. §441i(d) (Supp.
2003). The District Court struck down the provision on its face. We
reverse and uphold §323(d), narrowly construing the section’s ban
on donations to apply only to the donation of funds not raised in
compliance with FECA. 1. New FECA §323(d)’s
Regulation of Solicitations The Government
defends §323(d)’s ban on solicitations to tax-exempt organizations
engaged in political activity as preventing circumvention of Title
I’s limits on contributions of soft money to national, state, and
local party committees. That justification is entirely reasonable.
The history of Congress’ efforts at campaign finance reform well
demonstrates that “candidates, donors, and parties test the limits
of the current law.” Colorado II , 533 U. S., at 457. Absent
the solicitation provision, national, state, and local party
committees would have significant incentives to mobilize their
formidable fundraising apparatuses, including the peddling of
access to federal officeholders, into the service of like-minded
tax-exempt organizations that conduct activities benefiting their
candidates.[ Footnote 68 ] All
of the corruption and appearance of corruption attendant on the
operation of those fundraising apparatuses would follow. Donations
made at the behest of party committees would almost certainly be
regarded by party officials, donors, and federal officeholders
alike as benefiting the party as well as its candidates. Yet, by
soliciting the donations to third-party organizations, the parties
would avoid FECA’s source-and-amount limitations, as well as its
disclosure restrictions. See 251 F. Supp. 2d, at 348
(Henderson, J.) (citing various declarations demonstrating that,
prior to BCRA, most tax-exempt organizations did not disclose the
source or amount of contributions); id ., at 521
(Kollar-Kotelly, J.) (same). Experience under the
current law demonstrates that Congress’ concerns about
circumvention are not merely hypothetical. Even without the added
incentives created by Title I, national, state, and local parties
already solicit unregulated soft-money donations to tax-exempt
organizations for the purpose of supporting federal electioneering
activity. See , e.g., 3 1998 Senate Report 4013 (“In
addition to direct contributions from the RNC to nonprofit groups,
the senior leadership of the RNC helped to raise funds for many of
the coalition’s nonprofit organizations”); id ., at 5983
(minority views) (“Tax-exempt ‘issue advocacy’ groups and other
conduits were systematically used to circumvent federal campaign
finance laws”); 251 F. Supp. 2d, at 517 (Kollar-Kotelly, J.); id ., at 848 (Leon, J.). Parties and candidates have also
begun to take advantage of so-called “politician 527s,” which are
little more than soft-money fronts for the promotion of particular
federal officeholders and their interests. See id., at 519
(Kollar-Kotelly, J.) (“ ‘Virtually every member of Congress in
a formal leadership position has his or her own 527 group… .
In all, Public Citizen found 63 current members of Congress who
have their own 527s’ ” (quoting Public Citizen Congress Watch,
Congressional Leaders’ Soft Money Accounts Show Need for Campaign
Finance Reform Bills, Feb. 26, 2002, p. 6)); 251 F. Supp. 2d,
at 849–850 (Leon, J.). These 527s have been quite successful at
raising substantial sums of soft money from corporate interests, as
well as from the national parties themselves. See id. , at
519–520 (Kollar-Kotelly, J.) (finding that 27 industries had each
donated over $100,000 in a single year to the top 25 politician 527
groups and that the DNC was the single largest contributor to
politician 527 groups (citing Public Citizen Congress Watch, supra, at 10–11)); 251 F. Supp. 2d, at 850 (Leon, J.)
(same). Given BCRA’s tighter restrictions on the raising and
spending of soft money, the incentives for parties to exploit such
organizations will only increase. Section 323(d)’s solicitation
restriction is closely drawn to prevent political parties from
using tax-exempt organizations as soft-money surrogates. Though
phrased as an absolute prohibition, the restriction does nothing
more than subject contributions solicited by parties to FECA’s
regulatory regime, leaving open substantial opportunities for
solicitation and other expressive activity in support of these
organizations. First, and most obviously, §323(d) restricts
solicitations only to those §501(c) groups “mak[ing] expenditures
or disbursements in connection with an election for Federal
office,” 2 U. S. C. A. §441i(d)(1) (Supp. 2003), and to
§527 organizations, which by definition engage in partisan
political activity, §441i(d)(2); 26 U. S. C. §527(e). Second,
parties remain free to solicit hard-money contributions to a
§501(c)’s federal PAC, as well as to §527 organizations that
already qualify as federal PACs.[ Footnote 69 ] Third, §323(d) allows parties to endorse
qualifying organizations in ways other than direct solicitations of
unregulated donations. For example, with respect to §501(c)
organizations that are prohibited from administering PACs, parties
can solicit hard-money donations to themselves for the express
purpose of donating to these organizations. See supra , at
72–73. Finally, as with §323(a), §323(d) in no way restricts
solicitations by party officers acting in their individual
capacities. 2 U. S. C. A. §441i(d) (extending
restrictions to solicitations and donations made by “an officer or
agent acting on behalf of any such party committee”
(emphasis added)). In challenging §323(d)’s ban on
solicitations, plaintiffs renew the argument they made with respect
to §323(a)’s solicitation restrictions: that it cannot be squared
with §323(e), which allows federal candidates and officeholders to
solicit limited donations of soft money to tax-exempt organizations
that engage in federal election activities. Compare 2 U.
S. C. A. §441i(d) with §441i(e)(4). But if §323(d)’s
restrictions on solicitations are otherwise valid, they are not
rendered unconstitutional by the mere fact that Congress chose not
to regulate the activities of another group as stringently as it
might have. See National Right to Work , 459 U. S., at 210;
see also Katzenbach v. Morgan, 384 U. S. 641 , 656–657
(1966). In any event, the difference between the two provisions is
fully explained by the fact that national party officers, unlike
federal candidates and officeholders, are able to solicit soft
money on behalf of nonprofit organizations in their individual
capacities. Section 323(e), which is designed to accommodate the
individual associational and speech interests of candidates and
officeholders in lending personal support to nonprofit
organizations, also places tight content, source, and amount
restrictions on solicitations of soft money by federal candidates
and officeholders. Given those limits, as well as the less rigorous
standard of review, the greater allowances of §323(e) do not render
§323(d)’s solicitation restriction facially invalid. 2. New FECA §323(d)’s
Regulation of Donations Section 323(d)
also prohibits national, state, and local party committees from
making or directing “any donatio[n]” to qualifying §501(c) or §527
organizations. 2 U. S. C. A. §441i(d) (Supp. 2003). The
Government again defends the restriction as an anticircumvention
measure. We agree insofar as it prohibits the donation of soft
money. Absent such a restriction, state and local party committees
could accomplish directly what the antisolicitation restrictions
prevent them from doing indirectly— namely, raising large sums of
soft money to launder through tax-exempt organizations engaging in
federal election activities. Because the party itself would be
raising and collecting the funds, the potential for corruption
would be that much greater. We will not disturb Congress’
reasonable decision to close that loophole, particularly given a
record demonstrating an already robust practice of parties’ making
such donations. See 251 F. Supp. 2d, at 517–518
(Kollar-Kotelly); id ., at 848–849 (Leon, J.). The prohibition does
raise overbreadth concerns if read to restrict donations from a
party’s federal account— i.e. , funds that have already been
raised in compliance with FECA’s source, amount, and disclosure
limitations. Parties have many valid reasons for giving to
tax-exempt organizations, not the least of which is to associate
themselves with certain causes and, in so doing, to demonstrate the
values espoused by the party. A complete ban on donations prevents
parties from making even the “general expression of support” that a
contribution represents. Buckley , 424 U. S., at 21. At the
same time, prohibiting parties from donating funds already raised
in compliance with FECA does little to further Congress’ goal of
preventing corruption or the appearance of corruption of federal
candidates and officeholders. The Government asserts that the
restriction is necessary to prevent parties from leveraging their
hard money to gain control over a tax-exempt group’s soft money.
Even if we accepted that rationale, it would at most justify a
dollar limit, not a flat ban. Moreover, any legitimate concerns
over capture are diminished by the fact that the restrictions set
forth in §§323(a) and (b) apply not only to party committees, but
to entities under their control. See 2 U. S. C. A.
§441i(a)(2) (extending prohibitions on national party committees to
“any entity that is directly or indirectly established, financed,
maintained, or controlled by such a national committee”
(emphasis added)); §441i(b)(1) (same for state and local party
committees). These observations do not,
however, require us to sustain plaintiffs’ facial challenge to
§323(d)’s donation restriction. “When the validity of an act of the
Congress is drawn in question, and … a serious doubt of
constitutionality is raised, it is a cardinal principle that this
Court will first ascertain whether a construction of the statute is
fairly possible by which the question may be avoided.” Crowell v. Benson , 285 U. S. 22 , 62 (1932);
see also Boos v. Barry , 485 U. S. 312 , 331
(1988); New York v. Ferber , 458 U. S. 747 , 769, n.
24 (1982). Given our obligation to avoid constitutional problems,
we narrowly construe §323(d)’s ban to apply only to donations of
funds not raised in compliance with FECA. This construction is
consistent with the concerns animating Title I, whose purpose is to
plug the soft-money loophole. Though there is little legislative
history regarding BCRA generally, and almost nothing on §323(d)
specifically, the abuses identified in the 1998 Senate report
regarding campaign finance practices involve the use of nonprofit
organizations as conduits for large soft-money donations.
See, e.g. , 3 1998 Senate Report 4565 (“The evidence
indicates that the soft-money loophole is fueling many of the
campaign abuses investigated by the Committee… . Soft money
also supplied the funds parties used to make contributions to
tax-exempt groups, which in turn used the funds to pay for
election-related activities”); id. , at 4568–4569
(describing as an “egregious exampl[e]” of misuse a $4.6 million
donation of nonfederal funds by the RNC to Americans for Tax
Reform, which the organization spent on “direct mail and phone bank
operations to counter anti-Republican advertising”). We have found
no evidence that Congress was concerned about, much less that it
intended to prohibit, donations of money already fully regulated by
FECA. Given Title I’s exclusive focus on abuses related to soft
money, we would expect that if Congress meant §323(d)’s restriction
to have this dramatic and constitutionally questionable effect, it
would say so explicitly. Because there is nothing that compels us
to conclude that Congress intended “donations” to include transfers
of federal money, and because of the constitutional infirmities
such an interpretation would raise, we decline to read §323(d) in
that way. Thus, political parties remain free to make or direct
donations of money to any tax-exempt organization that has
otherwise been raised in compliance with FECA. New FECA §323(e)’s Restrictions on
Federal Candidates and Officeholders New FECA §323(e)
regulates the raising and soliciting of soft money by federal
candidates and officeholders. 2 U. S. C. A. §441i(e)
(Supp. 2003). It prohibits federal candidates and officeholders
from “solicit[ing], receiv[ing], direct[ing], transfer[ing], or
spend[ing]” any soft money in connection with federal elections.
§441i(e)(1)(A). It also limits the ability of federal candidates
and officeholders to solicit, receive, direct, transfer, or spend
soft money in connection with state and local elections.
§441i(e)(1)(B).[ Footnote
70 ] Section 323(e)’s
general prohibition on solicitations admits of a number of
exceptions. For instance, federal candidates and officeholders are
permitted to “attend, speak, or be a featured guest” at a state or
local party fundraising event. 2 U. S. C. A. §441i(e)(3).
Section 323(e) specifically provides that federal candidates and
officeholders may make solicitations of soft money to §501(c)
organizations whose primary purpose is not to engage in “Federal
election activit[ies]” as long as the solicitation does not specify
how the funds will be spent, 2 U. S. C. A.
§441i(e)(4)(A); to §501(c) organizations whose primary purpose
is to engage in “Federal election activit[ies]” as long as the
solicitations are limited to individuals and the amount solicited
does not exceed $20,000 per year per individual, 2 U.
S. C. A. §441i(e)(4)(B); and to §501(c) organizations for
the express purpose of carrying out such activities, again so long
as the amount solicited does not exceed $20,000 per year per
individual, 2 U. S. C. A. §441(e)(4)(B). No party seriously questions the
constitutionality of §323(e)’s general ban on donations of soft
money made directly to federal candidates and officeholders, their
agents, or entities established or controlled by them. Even on the
narrowest reading of Buckley , a regulation restricting
donations to a federal candidate, regardless of the ends to which
those funds are ultimately put, qualifies as a contribution limit
subject to less rigorous scrutiny. Such donations have only
marginal speech and associational value, but at the same time pose
a substantial threat of corruption. By severing the most direct
link between the soft-money donor and the federal candidate,
§323(e)’s ban on donations of soft money is closely drawn to
prevent the corruption or the appearance of corruption of federal
candidates and officeholders. Section 323(e)’s restrictions on
solicitations are justified as valid anticircumvention measures.
Large soft-money donations at a candidate’s or officeholder’s
behest give rise to all of the same corruption concerns posed by
contributions made directly to the candidate or officeholder.
Though the candidate may not ultimately control how the funds are
spent, the value of the donation to the candidate or officeholder
is evident from the fact of the solicitation itself. Without some
restriction on solicitations, federal candidates and officeholders
could easily avoid FECA’s contribution limits by soliciting funds
from large donors and restricted sources to like-minded
organizations engaging in federal election activities. As the
record demonstrates, even before the passage of BCRA, federal
candidates and officeholders had already begun soliciting donations
to state and local parties, as well as tax-exempt organizations, in
order to help their own, as well as their party’s, electoral cause.
See Colorado II , 533 U. S., at 458 (quoting fundraising
letter from a Congressman explaining to contributor that
“ ‘you are at the limit of what you can directly contribute to
my campaign,’ but ‘you can further help my campaign by assisting
the Colorado Republican Party’ ”); 251 F. Supp. 2d, at
479–480 (Kollar-Kotelly, J.) (surveying evidence of federal
officeholders’ soliciting funds to state and local parties); id ., at 848 (Leon, J.) (same); id ., at 518
(Kollar-Kotelly, J.) (surveying evidence of federal officeholders’
soliciting funds for nonprofits for electioneering purposes); id ., at 849 (Leon, J.) (same). The incentives to do so, at
least with respect to solicitations to tax-exempt organizations,
will only increase with Title I’s restrictions on the raising and
spending of soft money by national, state, and local
parties. Section 323(e) addresses these
concerns while accommodating the individual speech and
associational rights of federal candidates and officeholders.
Rather than place an outright ban on solicitations to tax-exempt
organizations, §323(e)(4) permits limited solicitations of soft
money. 2 U. S. C. A. §441i(e)(4). This allowance
accommodates individuals who have long served as active members of
nonprofit organizations in both their official and individual
capacities. Similarly, §§323(e)(1)(B) and 323(e)(3) preserve the
traditional fundraising role of federal officeholders by providing
limited opportunities for federal candidates and officeholders to
associate with their state and local colleagues through joint
fundraising activities. 2 U. S. C. A. §§441i(e)(1)(B),
441i(e)(3). Given these many exceptions, as well as the substantial
threat of corruption or its appearance posed by donations to or at
the behest of federal candidates and officeholders, §323(e) is
clearly constitutional. We accordingly uphold §323(e) against
plaintiffs’ First Amendment challenge. New FECA §323(f)’s Restrictions on
State Candidates and Officeholders The final
provision of Title I is new FECA §323(f). 2 U. S. C. A.
§441i(f) (Supp. 2003). Section 323(f) generally prohibits
candidates for state or local office, or state or local
officeholders, from spending soft money to fund “public
communications” as defined in §301(20)(A)(iii)— i.e. , a
communication that “refers to a clearly identified candidate for
Federal office … and that promotes or supports a candidate for that
office, or attacks or opposes a candidate for that office.” 2 U.
S. C. A. §441i(f)(1); §431(20)(A)(iii). Exempted from
this restriction are communications made in connection with an
election for state or local office which refer only to the state or
local candidate or officeholder making the expenditure or to any
other candidate for the same state or local office.
§441i(f)(2). Section 323(f) places
no cap on the amount of money that state or local candidates can
spend on any activity. Rather, like §§323(a) and 323(b), it limits
only the source and amount of contributions that state and local
candidates can draw on to fund expenditures that directly impact
federal elections. And, by regulating only contributions used to
fund “public communications,” §323(f) focuses narrowly on those
soft-money donations with the greatest potential to corrupt or give
rise to the appearance of corruption of federal candidates and
officeholders. Plaintiffs advance two principal
arguments against §323(f). We have already rejected the first
argument, that the definition of “public communications” in new
FECA §301(20)(A)(iii) is unconstitutionally vague and overbroad.
See supra , 62, n. 64. We add only that, plaintiffs’
and Justice Kennedy’s contrary reading notwithstanding, post , at 34, this provision does not prohibit a state or
local candidate from advertising that he has received a federal
officeholder’s endorsement.[ Footnote 71 ] The second argument, that
soft-money contributions to state and local candidates for “public
communications” do not corrupt or appear to corrupt federal
candidates, ignores both the record in this litigation and
Congress’ strong interest in preventing circumvention of otherwise
valid contribution limits. The proliferation of sham issue ads has
driven the soft-money explosion. Parties have sought out every
possible way to fund and produce these ads with soft money: They
have labored to bring them under the FEC’s allocation regime; they
have raised and transferred soft money from national to state party
committees to take advantage of favorable allocation ratios; and
they have transferred and solicited funds to tax-exempt
organizations for production of such ads. We will not upset
Congress’ eminently reasonable prediction that, with these other
avenues no longer available, state and local candidates and
officeholders will become the next conduits for the soft-money
funding of sham issue advertising. We therefore uphold §323(f)
against plaintiffs’ First Amendment challenge.[ Footnote 72 ] B Several plaintiffs
contend that Title I exceeds Congress’ Election Clause authority to
“make or alter” rules governing federal elections, U. S. Const.,
Art. I, §4, and, by impairing the authority of the States to
regulate their own elections, violates constitutional principles of
federalism. In examining congressional enactments for infirmity
under the Tenth Amendment, this Court has focused its attention on
laws that commandeer the States and state officials in carrying out
federal regulatory schemes. See Printz v. United
States , 521 U.
S. 898 (1997); New York v. United States , 505 U. S. 144 (1992). By contrast, Title I of BCRA only regulates the conduct of
private parties. It imposes no requirements whatsoever upon States
or state officials, and, because it does not expressly pre-empt
state legislation, it leaves the States free to enforce their own
restrictions on the financing of state electoral campaigns. It is
true that Title I, as amended, prohibits some fundraising tactics
that would otherwise be permitted under the laws of various States,
and that it may therefore have an indirect effect on the financing
of state electoral campaigns. But these indirect effects do not
render BCRA unconstitutional. It is not uncommon for federal law to
prohibit private conduct that is legal in some States. See, e.g. , United States v. Oakland Cannabis
Buyers’ Cooperative, 532 U. S. 483 (2001).
Indeed, such conflict is inevitable in areas of law that involve
both state and federal concerns. It is not in and of itself a
marker of constitutional infirmity. See Ex parte Siebold , 100 U. S. 371 ,
392 (1879). Of course, in
maintaining the federal system envisioned by the Founders, this
Court has done more than just prevent Congress from commandeering
the States. We have also policed the absolute boundaries of
congressional power under Article I. See United States v. Morrison, 529 U. S. 598 (2000); United States v. Lopez, 514 U. S. 549 (1995).
But plaintiffs offer no reason to believe that Congress has
overstepped its Elections Clause power in enacting BCRA. Congress
has a fully legitimate interest in maintaining the integrity of
federal officeholders and preventing corruption of federal
electoral processes through the means it has chosen. Indeed, our
above analysis turns on our finding that those interests are
sufficient to satisfy First Amendment scrutiny. Given that finding,
we cannot conclude that those interests are insufficient to ground
Congress’ exercise of its Elections Clause power. See Morrison , supra, at 607 (respect owed to
coordinate branches “demands that we invalidate a congressional
enactment only upon a plain showing that Congress has exceeded its
constitutional bounds”). C Finally, plaintiffs
argue that Title I violates the equal protection component of the
Due Process Clause of the Fifth Amendment because it discriminates
against political parties in favor of special interest groups such
as the National Rifle Association (NRA), American Civil Liberties
Union (ACLU), and Sierra Club. As explained earlier, BCRA imposes
numerous restrictions on the fundraising abilities of political
parties, of which the soft-money ban is only the most prominent.
Interest groups, however, remain free to raise soft money to fund
voter registration, GOTV activities, mailings, and broadcast
advertising (other than electioneering communications). We conclude
that this disparate treatment does not offend the
Constitution. As an initial matter,
we note that BCRA actually favors political parties in many ways.
Most obviously, party committees are entitled to receive individual
contributions that substantially exceed FECA’s limits on
contributions to nonparty political committees; individuals can
give $25,000 to political party committees whereas they can give a
maximum of $5,000 to nonparty political committees. In addition,
party committees are entitled in effect to contribute to candidates
by making coordinated expenditures, and those expenditures may
greatly exceed the contribution limits that apply to other donors.
See 2 U. S. C. A. §441a(d) (Supp. 2003). More importantly, however,
Congress is fully entitled to consider the real-world differences
between political parties and interest groups when crafting a
system of campaign finance regulation. See National Right to
Work , 459 U. S., at 210. Interest groups do not select slates
of candidates for elections. Interest groups do not determine who
will serve on legislative committees, elect congressional
leadership, or organize legislative caucuses. Political parties
have influence and power in the legislature that vastly exceeds
that of any interest group. As a result, it is hardly surprising
that party affiliation is the primary way by which voters identify
candidates, or that parties in turn have special access to and
relationships with federal officeholders. Congress’ efforts at
campaign finance regulation may account for these salient
differences. Taken seriously, appellants’ equal protection
arguments would call into question not just Title I of BCRA, but
much of the pre-existing structure of FECA as well. We therefore
reject those arguments. Accordingly, we affirm the
judgment of the District Court insofar as it upheld §§323(e) and
323(f). We reverse the judgment of the District Court insofar as it
invalidated §§323(a), 323(b), and 323(d). IV Title II of BCRA,
entitled “Noncandidate Campaign Expenditures,” is divided into two
subtitles: “Electioneering Communications” and “Independent and
Coordinated Expenditures.” We consider each challenged section of
these subtitles in turn. BCRA §201’s Definition of
“Electioneering Communication” The first section
of Title II, §201, comprehensively amends FECA §304, which requires
political committees to file detailed periodic financial reports
with the FEC. The amendment coins a new term, “electioneering
communication,” to replace the narrowing construction of FECA’s
disclosure provisions adopted by this Court in Buckley . As
discussed further below, that construction limited the coverage of
FECA’s disclosure requirement to communications expressly
advocating the election or defeat of particular candidates. By
contrast, the term “electioneering communication” is not so
limited, but is defined to encompass any “broadcast, cable, or
satellite communication” that “(I) refers to a clearly identified
candidate for Federal office; “(II) is made within— “(aa) 60 days before a general,
special, or runoff election for the office sought by the candidate;
or “(bb) 30 days before a primary or
preference election, or a convention or caucus of a political party
that has authority to nominate a candidate, for the office sought
by the candidate; and “(III) in the case of a communication which refers
to a candidate other than President or Vice President, is targeted
to the relevant electorate.” 2 U. S. C. A.
§434(f)(3)(A)(i) (Supp. 2003).[ Footnote 73 ] New FECA §304(f)(3)(C) further provides
that a communication is “ ‘targeted to the relevant
electorate’ ” if it “can be received by 50,000 or more
persons” in the district or State the candidate seeks to represent.
2 U. S. C. A. §434(f )(3)(C). In addition to setting forth this
definition, BCRA’s amendments to FECA §304 specify significant
disclosure requirements for persons who fund electioneering
communications. BCRA’s use of this new term is not, however,
limited to the disclosure context: A later section of the Act (BCRA
§203, which amends FECA §316(b)(2)) restricts corporations’ and
labor unions’ funding of electioneering communications. Plaintiffs
challenge the constitutionality of the new term as it applies in
both the disclosure and the expenditure contexts. The major premise of plaintiffs’
challenge to BCRA’s use of the term “electioneering communication”
is that Buckley drew a constitutionally mandated line
between express advocacy and so-called issue advocacy, and that
speakers possess an inviolable First Amendment right to engage in
the latter category of speech. Thus, plaintiffs maintain, Congress
cannot constitutionally require disclosure of, or regulate
expenditures for, “electioneering communications” without making an
exception for those “communications” that do not meet Buckley ’s definition of express advocacy. That position misapprehends our
prior decisions, for the express advocacy restriction was an
endpoint of statutory interpretation, not a first principle of
constitutional law. In Buckley we began by examining
then-18 U. S. C. §608(e)(1) (1970 ed., Supp. IV), which
restricted expenditures “ ‘relative to a clearly identified
candidate,’ ” and we found that the phrase “ ‘relative
to’ ” was impermissibly vague. 424 U. S., at 40–42 . We concluded that the vagueness deficiencies could “be avoided only
by reading §608(e)(1) as limited to communications that include
explicit words of advocacy of election or defeat of a
candidate.”[ Footnote 74 ] Id ., at 43. We provided examples of words of express
advocacy, such as “ ‘vote for,’ ‘elect,’ ‘support,’ …
‘defeat,’ [and] ‘reject,’ ” id ., at 44, n. 52, and
those examples eventually gave rise to what is now known as the
“magic words” requirement. We then considered FECA’s
disclosure provisions, including 2 U. S. C. §431(f) (1970 ed.,
Supp. IV), which defined “ ‘expenditur[e]’ ” to include
the use of money or other assets “ ‘for the purpose of …
influencing’ ” a federal election. Buckley, 424 U.
S., at 77. Finding that the “ambiguity of this phrase” posed
“constitutional problems,” ibid., we noted our “obligation
to construe the statute, if that can be done consistent with the
legislature’s purpose, to avoid the shoals of vagueness,” id ., at 77–78 (citations omitted). “To insure that the
reach” of the disclosure requirement was “not impermissibly broad,
we construe[d] ‘expenditure’ for purposes of that section in the
same way we construed the terms of §608(e)—to reach only funds used
for communications that expressly advocate the election or defeat
of a clearly identified candidate.” Id ., at 80 (footnote
omitted). Thus, a plain reading of Buckley makes clear that the express advocacy limitation,
in both the expenditure and the disclosure contexts, was the
product of statutory interpretation rather than a constitutional
command.[ Footnote 75 ] In
narrowly reading the FECA provisions in Buckley to avoid
problems of vagueness and overbreadth, we nowhere suggested that a
statute that was neither vague nor overbroad would be required to
toe the same express advocacy line. Nor did we suggest as much in MCFL, 479
U. S. 238 (1986), in which we addressed the scope of another
FECA expenditure limitation and confirmed the understanding that Buckley ’s express advocacy category was a product of
statutory construction.[ Footnote
76 ] In short, the concept of express
advocacy and the concomitant class of magic words were born of an
effort to avoid constitutional infirmities. See NLRB v. Catholic Bishop of Chicago, 440 U. S. 490 , 500
(1979) (citing Murray v. Schooner Charming Betsy ,
2 Cranch 64, 118 (1804)). We have long “rigidly adhered” to the
tenet “ ‘never to formulate a rule of constitutional law
broader than is required by the precise facts to which it is to be
applied,’ ” United States v. Raines, 362 U. S. 17 , 21 (1960)
(citation omitted), for “[t]he nature of judicial review constrains
us to consider the case that is actually before us,” James B.
Beam Distilling Co. v. Georgia, 501 U. S. 529 , 547
(1991) (Blackmun, J., dissenting). Consistent with that principle,
our decisions in Buckley and MCFL were specific
to the statutory language before us; they in no way drew a
constitutional boundary that forever fixed the permissible scope of
provisions regulating campaign-related speech. Nor are we persuaded, independent
of our precedents, that the First Amendment erects a rigid barrier
between express advocacy and so-called issue advocacy. That notion
cannot be squared with our longstanding recognition that the
presence or absence of magic words cannot meaningfully distinguish
electioneering speech from a true issue ad. See Buckley,
supra , at 45. Indeed, the unmistakable lesson from the record
in this litigation, as all three judges on the District Court
agreed, is that Buckley ’s magic-words requirement is
functionally meaningless. 251 F. Supp. 2d, at 303–304
(Henderson, J.); id. , at 534 (Kollar-Kotelly, J.); id. , at 875–879 (Leon, J.). Not only can advertisers
easily evade the line by eschewing the use of magic words, but they
would seldom choose to use such words even if permitted.[ Footnote 77 ] And although the
resulting advertisements do not urge the viewer to vote for or
against a candidate in so many words, they are no less clearly
intended to influence the election.[ Footnote 78 ] Buckley ’s express advocacy line, in
short, has not aided the legislative effort to combat real or
apparent corruption, and Congress enacted BCRA to correct the flaws
it found in the existing system. Finally we observe that new FECA
§304(f)(3)’s definition of “electioneering communication” raises
none of the vagueness concerns that drove our analysis in Buckley . The term “electioneering communication” applies
only (1) to a broadcast (2) clearly identifying a candidate for
federal office, (3) aired within a specific time period, and (4)
targeted to an identified audience of at least 50,000 viewers or
listeners. These components are both easily understood and
objectively determinable. See Grayned v. City of
Rockford, 408 U. S. 104 , 108–114 (1972). Thus,
the constitutional objection that persuaded the Court in Buckley to limit FECA’s reach to express advocacy is
simply inapposite here. BCRA §201’s Disclosure
Requirements Having rejected
the notion that the First Amendment requires Congress to treat
so-called issue advocacy differently from express advocacy, we turn
to plaintiffs’ other concerns about the use of the term
“electioneering communication” in amended FECA §304’s disclosure
provisions. Under those provisions, whenever any person makes
disbursements totaling more than $10,000 during any calendar year
for the direct costs of producing and airing electioneering
communications, he must file a statement with the FEC identifying
the pertinent elections and all persons sharing the costs of the
disbursements. 2 U. S. C. A. §§434(f)(2)(A), (B), and (D)
(Supp. 2003). If the disbursements are made from a corporation’s or
labor union’s segregated account,[ Footnote 79 ] or by a single individual who has collected
contributions from others, the statement must identify all persons
who contributed $1,000 or more to the account or the individual
during the calendar year. §§434(f)(2)(E), (F). The statement must
be filed within 24 hours of each “disclosure date”—a term defined
to include the first date and all subsequent dates on which a
person’s aggregate undisclosed expenses for electioneering
communications exceed $10,000 for that calendar year. §§434(f)(1),
(2) and (4). Another subsection further provides that the execution
of a contract to make a disbursement is itself treated as a
disbursement for purposes of FECA’s disclosure requirements.
§434(f)(5). In addition to
the failed argument that BCRA’s amendments to FECA §304 improperly
extend to both express and issue advocacy, plaintiffs challenge
amended FECA §304’s disclosure requirements as unnecessarily (1)
requiring disclosure of the names of persons who contributed $1,000
or more to the individual or group that paid for a communication,
and (2) mandating disclosure of executory contracts for
communications that have not yet aired. The District Court rejected
the former submission but accepted the latter, finding invalid new
FECA §304(f)(5), which governs executory contracts. Relying on
BCRA’s severability provision,[ Footnote 80 ] the court held that invalidation of the
executory contracts subsection did not render the balance of BCRA’s
amendments to FECA §304 unconstitutional. 251 F. Supp. 2d, at 242
(per curiam) . We agree with the District Court
that the important state interests that prompted the Buckley Court to uphold FECA’s disclosure
requirements—providing the electorate with information, deterring
actual corruption and avoiding any appearance thereof, and
gathering the data necessary to enforce more substantive
electioneering restrictions—apply in full to BCRA.[ Footnote 81 ] Accordingly, Buckley amply supports application of FECA §304’s disclosure requirements
to the entire range of “electioneering communications.” As the
authors of the District Court’s per curiam opinion
concluded after reviewing evidence concerning the use of purported
“issue ads” to influence federal elections: “The factual record demonstrates that
the abuse of the present law not only permits corporations and
labor unions to fund broadcast advertisements designed to influence
federal elections, but permits them to do so while concealing their
identities from the public. BCRA’s disclosure provisions require
these organizations to reveal their identities so that the public
is able to identify the source of the funding behind broadcast
advertisements influencing certain elections. Plaintiffs’ disdain
for BCRA’s disclosure pro-visions is nothing short of surprising.
Plaintiffs chal-lenge BCRA’s restrictions on electioneering
communications on the premise that they should be permitted to
spend corporate and labor union general treasury funds in the sixty
days before the federal elections on broadcast advertisements,
which refer to federal candidates, because speech needs to be
‘uninhibited, robust, and wide-open.’ McConnell Br. at 44 (quoting New York Times Co. v. Sullivan, 376 U. S. 254 , 270
(1964)). Curiously, Plaintiffs want to preserve the ability to run
these advertisements while hiding behind dubious and misleading
names like: ‘The Coalition-Americans Working for Real Change’
(funded by business organizations opposed to organized labor),
‘Citizens for Better Medicare’ (funded by the pharmaceutical
industry), ‘Republicans for Clean Air’ (funded by brothers Charles
and Sam Wyly). Findings ¶ ;¶ ;44, 51, 52. Given these tactics,
Plaintiffs never satisfactorily answer the question of how
‘uninhibited, robust, and wide-open’ speech can occur when
organizations hide themselves from the scrutiny of the voting
public. McConnell Br. at 44. Plaintiffs’ argument for striking down
BCRA’s disclosure provisions does not reinforce the precious First
Amendment values that Plaintiffs argue are trampled by BCRA, but
ignores the competing First Amendment interests of individual
citizens seeking to make informed choices in the political
marketplace.” 251 F. Supp. 2d, at 237. The District Court
was also correct that Buckley forecloses a facial attack
on the new provision in §304 that requires disclosure of the names
of persons contributing $1,000 or more to segregated funds or
individuals that spend more than $10,000 in a calendar year on
electioneering communications. Like our earlier decision in NAACP v. Alabama ex rel. Patterson, 357 U. S. 449 (1958),[ Footnote 82 ] Buckley recognized that compelled disclosures may impose
an unconstitutional burden on the freedom to associate in support
of a particular cause. Nevertheless, Buckley rejected the
contention that FECA’s disclosure requirements could not
constitutionally be applied to minor parties and independent
candidates because the Government’s interest in obtaining
information from such parties was minimal and the danger of
infringing their rights substantial. In Buckley , unlike NAACP , we found no evidence that any party had been
exposed to economic reprisals or physical threats as a result of
the compelled disclosures. Buckley , 424 U. S., at 69–70.
We acknowledged that such a case might arise in the future,
however, and addressed the standard of proof that would then
apply: “We recognize that unduly strict
requirements of proof could impose a heavy burden, but it does not
follow that a blanket exemption for minor parties is necessary.
Minor parties must be allowed sufficient flexibility in the proof
of injury to assure a fair consideration of their claim. The
evidence offered need show only a reasonable probability that the
compelled disclosure of a party’s contributors’ names will subject
them to threats, harassment, or reprisals from either Government
officials or private parties.” Id. , at 74. A few years later we used that standard
to resolve a minor party’s challenge to the constitutionality of
the State of Ohio’s disclosure requirements. We held that the First
Amendment prohibits States from compelling disclosures that would
subject identified persons to “threats, harassment, and reprisals,”
and that the District Court’s findings had established a
“reasonable probability” of such a result.[ Footnote 83 ] Brown v. Socialist
Workers ’74 Campaign Comm. (Ohio), 459 U. S. 87 , 100 (1982). In this litigation the District
Court applied Buckley ’s evidentiary standard and
found—consistent with our conclusion in Buckley , and in
contrast to that in Brown —that the evidence did not
establish the requisite “reasonable probability” of harm to any
plaintiff group or its members. The District Court noted that some
parties had expressed such concerns, but it found a “lack of
specific evidence about the basis for these concerns.” 251
F. Supp. 2d, at 247 (per curiam) . We agree, but we
note that, like our refusal to recognize a blanket exception for
minor parties in Buckley, our rejection of plaintiffs’
facial challenge to the requirement to disclose individual donors
does not foreclose possible future challenges to particular
applications of that requirement. We also are unpersuaded by
plaintiffs’ challenge to new FECA §304(f)(5), which requires
disclosure of executory contracts for electioneering
communications: “Contracts to disburse “For purposes of this subsection,
a person shall be treated as having made a disbursement if the
person has executed a contract to make the disbursement.” 2 U.
S. C. A. §434(f)(5) (Supp. 2003). In our view, this provision serves an
important purpose the District Court did not advance. BCRA’s
amendments to FECA §304 mandate disclosure only if and when a
person makes disbursements totaling more than $10,000 in any
calendar year to pay for electioneering communications. Plaintiffs
do not take issue with the use of a dollar amount, rather than the
number or dates of the ads, to identify the time when a person
paying for electioneering communications must make disclosures to
the FEC. Nor do they question the need to make the contents of
parties’ disclosure statements available to curious voters in
advance of elections. Given the relatively short time frames in
which electioneering communications are made, the interest in
assuring that disclosures are made promptly and in time to provide
relevant information to voters is unquestionably significant. Yet
fixing the deadline for filing disclosure statements based on the
date when aggregate disbursements exceed $10,000 would open a
significant loophole if advertisers were not required to disclose
executory contracts. In the absence of that requirement, political
supporters could avoid preelection disclosures concerning ads
slated to run during the final week of a campaign simply by making
a preelection downpayment of less than $10,000, with the balance
payable after the election. Indeed, if the advertiser waited to pay
that balance until the next calendar year then, as long as the
balance did not itself exceed $10,000, the advertiser might avoid
the disclosure requirements completely. The record contains little
evidence identifying any harm that might flow from the enforcement
of §304(f)(5)’s “advance” disclosure requirement. The District
Court speculated that disclosing information about contracts “that
have not been performed, and may never be performed, may lead to
confusion and an unclear record upon which the public will evaluate
the forces operating in the political marketplace.” 251
F. Supp. 2d, at 241 (per curiam) . Without evidence
relating to the frequency of nonperformance of executed contracts,
such speculation cannot outweigh the public interest in ensuring
full disclosure before an election actually takes place. It is no
doubt true that §304(f)(5) will sometimes require the filing of
disclosure statements in advance of the actual broadcast of an
advertisement.[ Footnote 84 ]
But the same would be true in the absence of an advance disclosure
requirement, if a television station insisted on advance payment
for all of the ads covered by a contract. Thus, the possibility
that amended §304 may sometimes require disclosures prior to the
airing of an ad is as much a function of the use of disbursements
(rather than the date of an ad) to trigger the disclosure
requirement as it is a function of §304(f)(5)’s treatment of
executory contracts. As the District Court observed,
amended FECA §304’s disclosure requirements are constitutional
because they “ ‘d[o] not prevent anyone from speaking.’ ” Ibid . (quoting Brief for FEC in Opposition in No. 02–582
et al. (DC), p. 112). Moreover, the required disclosures
“ ‘would not have to reveal the specific content of the
advertisements, yet they would perform an important function in
informing the public about various candidates’ supporters before election day.’ ” 251 F. Supp. 2d, at 241
(quoting Brief for FEC in Opposition, supra , at 112)
(emphasis in original). Accordingly, we affirm the judgment of the
District Court insofar as it upheld the disclosure requirements in
amended FECA §304 and rejected the facial attack on the provisions
relating to donors of $1,000 or more, and reverse that judgment
insofar as it invalidated FECA §304(f)(5). BCRA §202’s Treatment of
“Coordinated Communications” as Contributions Section 202 of
BCRA amends FECA §315(a)(7)(C) to provide that disbursements for
“electioneering communication[s]” that are coordinated with a
candidate or party will be treated as contributions to, and
expenditures by, that candidate or party. 2 U. S. C. A.
§441a(a)(7)(C) (Supp. 2003).[ Footnote 85 ] The amendment clarifies the scope of the
preceding subsection, §315(a)(7)(B), which states more generally
that “expenditures made by any person in cooperation, consultation,
or concert, with, or at the request or suggestion of ” a
candidate or party will constitute contributions. 2 U. S. C.
§§441a(a)(7)(B)(i)–(ii). In Buckley we construed the statutory
term “expenditure” to reach only spending for express advocacy. 424
U. S., at 40–43, and n. 52 (addressing 18 U. S. C. §608(e)(1)
(1970 ed., Supp. IV), which placed a $1,000 cap on expenditures
“ ‘relative to a clearly identified candidate’ ”). BCRA
§202 pre-empts a possible claim that §315(a)(7)(B) is similarly
limited, such that coordinated expenditures for communications that
avoid express advocacy cannot be counted as contributions. As we
explained above, see supra , at 83–86, Buckley ’s
narrow interpretation of the term “expenditure” was not a
constitutional limitation on Congress’ power to regulate federal
elections. Accordingly, there is no reason why Congress may not
treat coordinated disbursements for electioneering communications
in the same way it treats all other coordinated expenditures. We
affirm the judgment of the District Court insofar as it held that
plaintiffs had advanced “no basis for finding Section 202
unconstitutional.” 251 F. Supp. 2d, at 250. BCRA §203’s Prohibition of
Corporate and Labor Disbursements for Electioneering
Communications Since our
decision in Buckley , Congress’ power to prohibit corporations
and unions from using funds in their treasuries to finance
advertisements expressly advocating the election or defeat of
candidates in federal elections has been firmly embedded in our
law. The ability to form and administer separate segregated funds
authorized by FECA §316, 2 U. S. C. A. §441b (main ed.
and Supp. 2003), has provided corporations and unions with a
constitutionally sufficient opportunity to engage in express
advocacy. That has been this Court’s unanimous view,[ Footnote 86 ] and it is not challenged in
this litigation. Section 203 of BCRA
amends FECA §316(b)(2) to extend this rule, which previously
applied only to express advocacy, to all “electioneering
communications” covered by the definition of that term in amended
FECA §304(f)(3), discussed above. 2 U. S. C. A.
§441b(b)(2) (Supp. 2003).[ Footnote 87 ] Thus, under BCRA, corporations and unions
may not use their general treasury funds to finance electioneering
communications, but they remain free to organize and administer
segregated funds, or PACs, for that purpose. Because corporations
can still fund electioneering communications with PAC money, it is
“simply wrong” to view the provision as a “complete ban” on
expression rather than a regulation. Beaumont , 539 U. S.,
at ___, ___ (slip op., at 15). As we explained in Beaumont: “The PAC option allows corporate
political participation without the temptation to use corporate
funds for political influence, quite possibly at odds with the
sentiments of some shareholders or members, and it lets the
government regulate campaign activity through registration and
disclosure, see [2 U. S. C.] §§432–434, without jeopardizing
the associational rights of advocacy organizations’ members.”
Id. , at ___ (slip op., at 16) (citation omitted). See also Austin v. Michigan Chamber of Commerce, 494 U. S. 652 , 658
(1990). Rather than arguing that the
prohibition on the use of general treasury funds is a complete ban
that operates as a prior restraint, plaintiffs instead challenge
the expanded regulation on the grounds that it is both overbroad
and underinclusive. Our consideration of plaintiffs’ challenge is
informed by our earlier conclusion that the distinction between
express advocacy and so-called issue advocacy is not
constitutionally compelled. In that light, we must examine the
degree to which BCRA burdens First Amendment expression and
evaluate whether a compelling governmental interest justifies that
burden. Id., at 657. The latter question—whether the state
interest is compelling—is easily answered by our prior decisions
regarding campaign finance regulation, which “represent respect for
the ‘legislative judgment that the special characteristics of the
corporate structure require particularly careful
regulation.’ ” Beaumont , supra , at ___ (slip
op., at 8) (quoting National Right to Work, 459 U. S., at
209–210). We have repeatedly sustained legislation aimed at “the
corrosive and distorting effects of immense aggregations of wealth
that are accumulated with the help of the corporate form and that
have little or no correlation to the public’s support for the
corporation’s political ideas.” Austin, supra , at 660; see Beaumont, supra , at ___ (slip op., at 7–8); National
Right to Work, supra , at 209–210. Moreover, recent cases have
recognized that certain restrictions on corporate electoral
involvement permissibly hedge against “ ‘circumvention of
[valid] contribution limits.’ ” Beaumont , supra , at ___ (slip op., at 7) (quoting Colorado
II, 533 U. S., at 456, and n. 18.) In light of our precedents,
plaintiffs do not contest that the Government has a compelling
interest in regulating advertisements that expressly advocate the
election or defeat of a candidate for federal office. Nor do they
contend that the speech involved in so-called issue advocacy is any
more core political speech than are words of express advocacy.
After all, “the constitutional guarantee has its fullest and most
urgent application precisely to the conduct of campaigns for
political office,” Monitor Patriot Co. v. Roy, 401 U. S. 265 , 272
(1971), and “[a]dvocacy of the election or defeat of candidates for
federal office is no less entitled to protection under the First
Amendment than the discussion of political policy generally or
advocacy of the passage or defeat of legislation.” Buckley, 424 U. S., at 48. Rather, plaintiffs argue that
the justifications that adequately support the regulation of
express advocacy do not apply to significant quantities of speech
encompassed by the definition of electioneering
communications. This argument fails to the extent
that the issue ads broadcast during the 30- and 60-day periods
preceding federal primary and general elections are the functional
equivalent of express advocacy. The justifications for the
regulation of express advocacy apply equally to ads aired during
those periods if the ads are intended to influence the voters’
decisions and have that effect. The precise percentage of issue ads
that clearly identified a candidate and were aired during those
relatively brief preelection time spans but had no electioneering
purpose is a matter of dispute between the parties and among the
judges on the District Court. See 251 F. Supp. 2d, at 307–312
(Henderson, J.); id ., at 583–587 (Kollar-Kotelly, J.); id ., at 796–798 (Leon, J.). Nevertheless, the vast
majority of ads clearly had such a purpose. Annenberg Report 13–14;
App. 1330–1348 (Krasno & Sorauf Expert Report); 251
F. Supp. 2d, at 573–578 (Kollar-Kotelly, J.); id ., at
826–827 (Leon, J.). Moreover, whatever the precise percentage may
have been in the past, in the future corporations and unions may
finance genuine issue ads during those time frames by simply
avoiding any specific reference to federal candidates, or in
doubtful cases by paying for the ad from a segregated
fund.[ Footnote
88 ] We are therefore not persuaded
that plaintiffs have carried their heavy burden of proving that
amended FECA §316(b)(2) is overbroad. See Broadrick v. Oklahoma, 413 U. S. 601 , 613 (1973). Even if we
assumed that BCRA will inhibit some constitutionally protected
corporate and union speech, that assumption would not “justify
prohibiting all enforcement” of the law unless its application to
protected speech is substantial, “not only in an absolute sense,
but also relative to the scope of the law’s plainly legitimate
applications.” Virginia v. Hicks, 539 U. S. ___,
___ (2003) (slip op., at 5–6). Far from establishing that BCRA’s
application to pure issue ads is substantial, either in an absolute
sense or relative to its application to election-related
advertising, the record strongly supports the contrary
conclusion. Plaintiffs also argue that FECA
§316(b)(2)’s segregated-fund requirement for electioneering
communications is underinclusive because it does not apply to
advertising in the print media or on the Internet. 2 U.
S. C. A. §434(f)(3)(A) (Supp. 2003). The records
developed in this litigation and by the Senate Committee adequately
explain the reasons for this legislative choice. Congress found
that corporations and unions used soft money to finance a virtual
torrent of televised election-related ads during the periods
immediately preceding federal elections, and that remedial
legislation was needed to stanch that flow of money. 251
F. Supp. 2d, at 569–573 (Kollar-Kotelly, J.); id ., at
799 (Leon, J.); 3 1998 Senate Report 4465, 4474–4481; 5 id., at 7521–7525. As we held in Buckley, “reform
may take one step at a time, addressing itself to the phase of the
problem which seems most acute to the legislative mind.” 424 U. S.,
at 105 (internal quotation marks and citations omitted). One might
just as well argue that the electioneering communication definition
is underinclusive because it leaves advertising 61 days in advance
of an election entirely unregulated. The record amply justifies
Congress’ line drawing. In addition to arguing that
§316(b)(2)’s segregated-fund requirement is underinclusive, some
plaintiffs contend that it unconstitutionally discriminates in
favor of media companies. FECA §304(f)(3)(B)(i) excludes from the
definition of electioneering communications any “communication
appearing in a news story, commentary, or editorial distributed
through the facilities of any broadcasting station, unless such
facilities are owned or controlled by any political party,
political committee, or candidate.” 2 U. S. C. A.
§434(f)(3)(B)(i) (Supp. 2003). Plaintiffs argue this provision
gives free rein to media companies to engage in speech without
resort to PAC money. Section 304(f)(3)(B)(i)’s effect, however, is
much narrower than plaintiffs suggest. The provision excepts news
items and commentary only; it does not afford carte
blanche to media companies generally to ignore FECA’s
provisions. The statute’s narrow exception is wholly consistent
with First Amendment principles. “A valid distinction … exists
between corporations that are part of the media industry and other
corporations that are not involved in the regular business of
imparting news to the public.” Austin, 494 U. S., at 668.
Numerous federal statutes have drawn this distinction to ensure
that the law “does not hinder or prevent the institutional press
from reporting on, and publishing editorials about, newsworthy
events.” Ibid . (citations omitted); see, e.g. , 2
U. S. C. §431(9)(B)(i) (exempting news stories, commentaries,
and editorials from FECA’s definition of “expenditure”); 15 U.
S. C. §§1801–1804 (providing a limited antitrust exemption for
newspapers); 47 U. S. C. §315(a) (excepting newscasts, news
interviews, and news documentaries from the requirement that
broadcasters provide equal time to candidates for public
office).[ Footnote
89 ] We affirm the District Court’s
judgment to the extent that it upheld the constitutionality of FECA
§316(b)(2); to the extent that it invalidated any part of
§316(b)(2), we reverse the judgment. BCRA §204’s Application to
Nonprofit Corporations Section 204 of
BCRA, which adds FECA §316(c)(6), applies the prohibition on the
use of general treasury funds to pay for electioneering
communications to not-for-profit corporations.[ Footnote 90 ] Prior to the enactment of BCRA,
FECA required such corporations, like business corporations, to pay
for their express advocacy from segregated funds rather than from
their general treasuries. Our recent decision in Federal Election
Comm’n v. Beaumont , 539 U. S. ___ (2003), confirmed
that the requirement was valid except insofar as it applied to a
sub-category of corporations described as “ MCFL organizations,” as defined by our decision in MCFL, 479
U. S. 238 (1986).[ Footnote
91 ] The constitutional objection to applying FECA’s
segregated-fund requirement to so-called MCFL organizations necessarily applies with equal force to FECA
§316(c)(6). Our decision in MCFL related to a carefully defined category of entities.
We identified three features of the organization at issue in that
case that were central to our holding: “ First , it was formed for the
express purpose of promoting political ideas, and cannot engage in
business activities. If political fundraising events are expressly
denominated as requests for contributions that will be used for
political purposes, including direct expenditures, these events
cannot be considered business activities. This ensures that
political resources reflect political support. Second , it
has no shareholders or other persons affiliated so as to have a
claim on its assets or earnings. This ensures that persons
connected with the organization will have no economic disincentive
for disassociating with it if they disagree with its political
activity. Third , MCFL was not established by a business
corporation or a labor union, and it is its policy not to accept
contributions from such entities. This prevents such corporations
from serving as conduits for the type of direct spending that
creates a threat to the political marketplace.” Id. , at
264. That FECA §316(c)(6)
does not, on its face, exempt MCFL organizations from its
prohibition is not a sufficient reason to invalidate the entire
section. If a reasonable limiting construction “has been or could
be placed on the challenged statute” to avoid constitutional
concerns, we should embrace it. Broadrick, 413 U. S., at
613; Buckley, 424 U. S., at 44. Because our decision in
the MCFL case was on the books for many years before BCRA
was enacted, we presume that the legislators who drafted §316(c)(6)
were fully aware that the provision could not validly apply to MCFL -type entities. See Bowen v. Massachusetts, 487 U. S. 879 , 896
(1988); Cannon v. University of
Chicago, 441 U. S. 677 , 696–697
(1979). Indeed, the Government itself concedes that §316(c)(6) does
not apply to MCFL organizations. As so construed, the
provision is plainly valid. See Austin, 494 U. S., at
661–665 (holding that a segregated-fund requirement that did not
explicitly carve out an MCFL exception could apply to a
nonprofit corporation that did not qualify for MCFL status). Accordingly, the judgment of the
District Court upholding §316(c)(6) as so limited is
affirmed. BCRA §212’s Reporting Requirement
for $1,000 Expenditures Section 212 of
BCRA amends FECA §304 to add a new disclosure requirement, FECA
§304(g), which applies to persons making independent expenditures
of $1,000 or more during the 20-day period immediately preceding an
election. Like FECA §304(f)(5), discussed above, new §304(g) treats
the execution of a contract to make a disbursement as the
functional equivalent of a payment for the goods or services
covered by the contract.[ Footnote 92 ] In challenging this provision, plaintiffs
renew the argument we rejected in the context of §304(f)(5): that
they have a constitutional right to postpone any disclosure until
after the performance of the services purchased by their
expenditure. The District
Court held that the challenge to FECA §304(g) was not ripe because
the FEC has issued regulations “provid[ing] Plaintiffs with the
exact remedy they seek”—that is, specifically declining to “require
disclosure of independent express advocacy expenditures prior to
their ‘publi[c] disseminat[ion].’ ” 251 F. Supp. 2d, at
251, and n. 85 (per curiam) (citing 68 Fed. Reg. 404, 452
(2003) (codified at 11 CFR §§109.10(c), (d) (2003))). We are not
certain that a regulation purporting to limit the range of
circumstances in which a speech-burdening statute will be enforced
can render nonjusticiable a facial challenge to the (concededly
broader) underlying statute. Nevertheless, we need not separately
address the constitutionality of §304(g), for our ruling as to BCRA
§201, see supra , at 82– 89, renders the issue essentially
moot. BCRA §213’s Requirement that
Political Parties Choose Between Coordinated and Independent
Expenditures After Nominating a Candidate Section 213 of
BCRA amends FECA §315(d)(4) to impose certain limits on party
spending during the postnomination, preelection period.[ Footnote 93 ] At first blush, the
text of §315(d)(4)(A) appears to require political parties to make
a straightforward choice between using limited coordinated
expenditures or unlimited independent expenditures to support their
nominees. All three judges on the District Court concluded that the
provision placed an unconstitutional burden on the parties’ right
to make unlimited independent expenditures. 251 F. Supp. 2d,
at 388 (Henderson, J.); id. , at 650–651 (Kollar-Kotelly, J.), id. , at 805–808 (Leon, J.). In the end, we agree with that
conclusion but believe it important to identify certain
complexities in the text of §315(d)(4) that affect our analysis of
the issue. Section 315 of FECA
sets forth various limitations on contributions and expenditures by
individuals, political parties, and other groups. Section 315(a)(2)
restricts “contributions” by parties to $5,000 per candidate. 2 U.
S. C. A. §441a(a)(2). Because §315(a)(7) treats
expenditures that are coordinated with a candidate as contributions
to that candidate, 2 U. S. C. A. §441(a)(7) (Supp. 2003),
the $5,000 limit also operates as a cap on parties’ coordinated
expenditures. Section 315(d), however, provides that,
“[n]otwithstanding any other provision of law with respect to
limitations on expenditures or limitations on contributions,”
political parties may make “expenditures” in support of their
candidates under a formula keyed to the voting-age population of
the candidate’s home State or, in the case of a candidate for
President, the voting-age population of the United States. 2 U.
S. C. A. §§441a(d)(1)–(3) (main ed. and Supp.
2003).[ Footnote 94 ] In the
year 2000, that formula permitted expenditures ranging from $33,780
to $67,650 for House of Representatives races, and from $67,650 to
$1.6 million for Senate races. Colorado II, 533 U. S., at
439, n. 3. We held in Colorado I that parties have a
constitutional right to make unlimited independent expenditures,
and we invalidated §315(d) to the extent that it restricted such
expenditures. As a result of that decision, §315(d) applies only to
coordinated expenditures, replacing the $5,000 cap on contributions
set out in §315(a)(2) with the more generous limitations prescribed
by §§315(d)(1)–(3). We sustained that limited application in Colorado II, supra . Section 213 of BCRA amends §315(d)
by adding a new paragraph (4). New §315(d)(4)(A) provides that,
after a party nominates a candidate for federal office, it must
choose between two spending options. Under the first option, a
party that “makes any independent expenditure (as defined in
section [301(17)])” is thereby barred from making “any coordinated
expenditure under this subsection.” 2 U. S. C. A.
§441a(d)(4)(A)(i) (Supp. 2003). The phrase “this subsection” is a
reference to subsection (d) of §315. Thus, the consequence of
making an independent expenditure is not a complete prohibition of
any coordinated expenditure: Although the party cannot take
advantage of the increased spending limits under §§315(d)(1)–(3),
it still may make up to $5,000 in coordinated expenditures under
§315(a)(2). As the difference between $5,000 and $1.6 million
demonstrates, however, that is a significant cost to impose on the
exercise of a constitutional right. The second option is the converse
of the first. It provides that a party that makes any coordinated
expenditure “under this subsection” ( i.e. , one that
exceeds the ordinary $5,000 limit) cannot make “any independent
expenditure (as defined in section [301(17)]) with respect to the
candidate.” 2 U. S. C. A. §441a(d)(4)(A)(ii). Section
301(17) defines “ ‘independent expenditure’ ” to mean a
non-coordinated expenditure “expressly advocating the election or
defeat of a clearly identified candidate.” 2 U. S. C. A.
§431(17)(A).[ Footnote 95 ]
Therefore, as was true of the first option, the party’s choice is
not as stark as it initially appears: The consequence of the larger
coordinated expenditure is not a complete prohibition of any
independent expenditure, but the forfeiture of the right to make
independent expenditures for express advocacy . As we
explained in our discussion of the provisions relating to
electioneering communications, supra , at 83–87, express
advocacy represents only a tiny fraction of the political
communications made for the purpose of electing or defeating
candidates during a campaign. Regardless of which option parties
choose, they remain free to make independent expenditures for the
vast majority of campaign ads that avoid the use of a few magic
words. In sum, the coverage of new FECA
§315(d)(4) is much more limited than it initially appears. A party
that wishes to spend more than $5,000 in coordination with its
nominee is forced to forgo only the narrow category of independent
expenditures that make use of magic words. But while the category
of burdened speech is relatively small, it plainly is entitled to
First Amendment protection. See Buckley , 424 U. S., at
44–45, 48. Under §315(d)(4), a political party’s exercise of its
constitutionally protected right to engage in “core First Amendment
expression,” id., at 48, results in the loss of a valuable
statutory benefit that has been available to parties for many
years. To survive constitutional scrutiny, a provision that has
such consequences must be supported by a meaningful governmental
interest. The interest in requiring
political parties to avoid the use of magic words is not such an
interest. We held in Buckley that a $1,000 cap on
expenditures that applied only to express advocacy could not be
justified as a means of avoiding circumvention of contribution
limits or preventing corruption and the appearance of corruption
because its restrictions could easily be evaded: “So long as
persons and groups eschew expenditures that in express terms
advocate the election or defeat of a clearly identified candidate,
they are free to spend as much as they want to promote the
candidate and his views.” Id. , at 45. The same is true in
this litigation. Any claim that a restriction on independent
express advocacy serves a strong Government interest is belied by
the overwhelming evidence that the line between express advocacy
and other types of election-influencing expression is, for
Congress’ purposes, functionally meaningless. Indeed, Congress
enacted the new “electioneering communication[s]” provisions
precisely because it recognized that the express advocacy test was
woefully inadequate at capturing communications designed to
influence candidate elections. In light of that recognition, we are
hard pressed to conclude that any meaningful purpose is served by
§315(d)(4)’s burden on a party’s right to engage independently in
express advocacy. The Government argues that
§315(d)(4) nevertheless is constitutional because it is not an
outright ban (or cap) on independent expenditures, but rather
offers parties a voluntary choice between a constitutional right
and a statutory benefit. Whatever merit that argument might have in
the abstract, it fails to account for new §315(d)(4)(B), which
provides: “For purposes of this paragraph, all
political committees established and maintained by a national
political party (including all congressional campaign committees)
and all political committees established and maintained by a State
political party (including any subordinate committee of a State
committee) shall be considered to be a single political committee.”
2 U. S. C. A. §441a(d)(4)(B) (Supp. 2003). Given that provision,
it simply is not the case that each party committee can make a
voluntary and independent choice between exercising its right to
engage in independent advocacy and taking advantage of the
increased limits on coordinated spending under §§315(d)(1)–(3).
Instead, the decision resides solely in the hands of the first
mover, such that a local party committee can bind both the state
and national parties to its chosen spending option.[ Footnote 96 ] It is one thing to say that
Congress may require a party committee to give up its right to make
independent expenditures if it believes that it can accomplish more
with coordinated expenditures. It is quite another thing, however,
to say that the RNC must limit itself to $5,000 in coordinated
expenditures in support of its presidential nominee if any state or
local committee first makes an independent expenditure for an ad
that uses magic words. That odd result undermines any claim that
new §315(d)(4) can withstand constitutional scrutiny simply because
it is cast as a voluntary choice rather than an outright
prohibition on independent expenditures. The portion of the judgment of the
District Court invalidating BCRA §213 is affirmed. BCRA §214’s Changes in FECA’s
Provisions Covering Coordinated Expenditures Ever since our
decision in Buckley , it has been settled that expenditures by
a noncandidate that are “controlled by or coordinated with the
candidate and his campaign” may be treated as indirect
contributions subject to FECA’s source and amount limitations. 424
U. S., at 46. Thus, FECA §315(a)(7)(B)(i) long has provided that
“expenditures made by any person in cooperation, consultation, or
concert, with, or at the request or suggestion of, a candidate, his
authorized political committees, or their agents, shall be
considered to be a contribution to such candidate.” 2 U.
S. C. A. §441a(a)(7)(B)(i) (Supp. 2003). Section 214(a)
of BCRA creates a new FECA §315(a)(7)(B)(ii) that applies the same
rule to expenditures coordinated with “a national, State, or local
committee of a political party.” 2 U. S. C. A.
§441a(a)(7)(B)(ii).[ Footnote
97 ] Sections 214(b) and (c) direct the FEC to repeal its
current regulations[ Footnote
98 ] and to promulgate new regulations dealing with “coordinated
communications” paid for by persons other than candidates or their
parties. Subsection (c) provides that the new “regulations shall
not require agreement or formal collaboration to establish
coordination.” 2 U. S. C. A. §441a(a) note. Plaintiffs do not
dispute that Congress may apply the same coordination rules to
parties as to candidates. They argue instead that new FECA
§315(a)(7)(B)(ii) and its implementing regulations are overbroad
and unconstitutionally vague because they permit a finding of
coordination even in the absence of an agreement. Plaintiffs point
out that political supporters may be subjected to criminal
liability if they exceed the contribution limits with expenditures
that ultimately are deemed coordinated. Thus, they stress the
importance of a clear definition of “coordination” and argue any
definition that does not hinge on the presence of an agreement
cannot provide the “precise guidance” that the First Amendment
demands. Brief for Chamber of Commerce of the United States
et al., Appellant in No. 02–1756, p. 48. As plaintiffs readily
admit, that argument reaches beyond BCRA, calling into question
FECA’s pre-existing provisions governing expenditures coordinated
with candidates. We are not persuaded that the
presence of an agreement marks the dividing line between
expenditures that are coordinated—and therefore may be regulated as
indirect contributions—and expenditures that truly are independent.
We repeatedly have struck down limitations on expenditures “made
totally independently of the candidate and his campaign,” Buckley , 424 U. S., at 47, on the ground that such
limitations “impose far greater restraints on the freedom of speech
and association” than do limits on contributions and coordinated
expenditures, id. , at 44, while “fail[ing] to serve any
substantial governmental interest in stemming the reality or
appearance of corruption in the electoral process,” id .,
at 47–48. See also Colorado I, 518 U. S., at 613–614
(striking down limit on expenditure made by party officials prior
to nomination of candidates and without any consultation with
potential nominees). We explained in Buckley: “Unlike contributions, …
independent expenditures may well provide little assistance to the
candidate’s campaign and indeed may prove counterproductive. The
absence of prearrangement and coordination of an expenditure with
the candidate or his agent not only undermines the value of the
expenditure to the candidate, but also alleviates the danger that
expenditures will be given as a quid pro quo for improper
commitments from the candidate.” 424 U. S., at 47. Thus, the rationale
for affording special protection to wholly independent expenditures
has nothing to do with the absence of an agreement and everything
to do with the functional consequences of different types of
expenditures. Independent expenditures “are poor sources of
leverage for a spender because they might be duplicative or
counterproductive from a candidate’s point of view.” Colorado
II, 533 U. S., at 446. By contrast, expenditures made after a
“wink or nod” often will be “as useful to the candidate as cash.” Id. , at 442, 446. For that reason, Congress has always
treated expenditures made “at the request or suggestion of” a
candidate as coordinated.[ Footnote 99 ] 2 U. S. C. A. §441a(a)(7)(B)(i)
(Supp. 2003). A supporter easily could comply with a candidate’s
request or suggestion without first agreeing to do so, and the
resulting expenditure would be “ ‘virtually indistinguishable
from [a] simple contributio[n],’ ” Colorado II , supra , at 444–445. Therefore, we cannot agree with the
submission that new FECA §315(a)(7)(B)(ii) is overbroad because it
permits a finding of coordination or cooperation notwithstanding
the absence of a pre-existing agreement. Nor are we persuaded that the
absence of an agreement requirement renders §315(a)(7)(B)(ii)
unconstitutionally vague. An agreement has never been required to
support a finding of coordination with a candidate under
§315(a)(7)(B)(i), which refers to expenditures made “in
cooperation, consultation, or concer[t] with, or at the request or
suggestion of” a candidate. Congress used precisely the same
language in new §315(a)(7)(B)(ii) to address expenditures
coordinated with parties. FECA’s longstanding definition of
coordination “delineates its reach in words of common
understanding.” Cameron v. Johnson, 390 U. S. 611 , 616
(1968). Not surprisingly, therefore, the relevant statutory
language has survived without constitutional challenge for almost
three decades. Although that fact does not insulate the definition
from constitutional scrutiny, it does undermine plaintiffs’ claim
that the language of §315(a)(7)(B)(ii) is intolerably vague.
Plaintiffs do not present any evidence that the definition has
chilled political speech, whether between candidates and their
supporters or by the supporters to the general public. See Reno v. American Civil Liberties
Union, 521
U. S. 844 , 874 (1997) (noting risk that vague statutes may
chill protected expression). And, although plaintiffs speculate
that the FEC could engage in intrusive and politically motivated
investigations into alleged coordination, they do not even attempt
to explain why an agreement requirement would solve that problem.
Moreover, the only evidence plaintiffs have adduced regarding the
enforcement of the coordination provision during its 27-year
history concerns three investigations in the late 1990’s into
groups on different sides of the political aisle. Such meager
evidence does not support the claim that §315(a)(7)(B)(ii) will
“foster ‘arbitrary and discriminatory application.’ ” Buckley, supra, at 41, n. 48 (quoting Grayned v. City of Rockford , 408 U. S., at 108–109). We conclude that
FECA’s definition of coordination gives “fair notice to those to
whom [it] is directed,” American Communications Assn. v. Douds, 339 U. S. 382 , 412
(1950), and is not unconstitutionally vague. Finally, portions of plaintiffs’
challenge to BCRA §214 focus on the regulations the FEC has
promulgated under §214(c). 11 CFR §109.21 (2003). As the District
Court explained, issues concerning the regulations are not
appropriately raised in this facial challenge to BCRA, but must be
pursued in a separate proceeding. Thus, we agree with the District
Court that plaintiffs’ challenge to §§214(b) and (c) is not ripe to
the extent that the alleged constitutional infirmities are found in
the implementing regulations rather than the statute
itself. The portions of the District Court
judgment rejecting plaintiffs’ challenges to BCRA §214 are
affirmed. V Many years ago we
observed that “[t]o say that Congress is without power to pass
appropriate legislation to safeguard … an election from the
improper use of money to influence the result is to deny to the
nation in a vital particular the power of self protection.” Burroughs v. United States, 290 U. S., at 545. We
abide by that conviction in considering Congress’ most recent
effort to confine the ill effects of aggregated wealth on our
political system. We are under no illusion that BCRA will be the
last congressional statement on the matter. Money, like water, will
always find an outlet. What problems will arise, and how Congress
will respond, are concerns for another day. In the main we uphold
BCRA’s two principal, complementary features: the control of soft
money and the regulation of electioneering communications.
Accordingly, we affirm in part and reverse in part the District
Court’s judgment with respect to Titles I and II. It is so ordered. * Justice Souter, Justice
Ginsburg, and Justice Breyer join this opinion in its
entirety. Footnote 1 The parties to the litigation are
described in the findings of the District Court. 251 F. Supp.
2d 176, 221–226 (DC 2003) (per curiam) . For the sake of
clarity, we refer to the parties who challenged the law in the
District Court as the “plaintiffs,” referring to specific
plaintiffs by name where necessary. We refer to the parties who
intervened in defense of the law as the
“intervenor-defendants.” Footnote 2 The Hatch Act also limited both
the amount political committees could expend and the amount they
could receive in contributions. Act of July 19, 1940, ch. 640, 54
Stat. 767. Senator Bankhead, in offering the amendment from the
Senate floor, said: “ ‘We all know that money is
the chief source of corruption. We all know that large
contributions to political campaigns not only put the political
party under obligation to the large contributors, who demand pay in
the way of legislation, but we also know that large sums of money
are used for the purpose of conducting expensive campaigns through
the newspapers and over the radio; in the publication of all sorts
of literature, true and untrue; and for the purpose of paying the
expenses of campaigners sent out into the country to spread
propaganda, both true and untrue.’ ” United States v. Automobile Workers, 352 U. S. 567 , 577–578 (1957) (quoting
86 Cong. Rec. 2720 (1940)). Footnote 3 As a general rule, FECA permits
corporations and unions to solicit contributions to their PACs from
their shareholders or members, but not from outsiders. 2 U.
S. C. §§441b(b)(4)(A), (C); see Federal Election
Comm’n v. National Right to Work Comm., 459 U. S. 197 , 198–199, and n. 1
(1982). Footnote 4 The court held that one
disclosure provision was unconstitutionally vague and overbroad. Buckley v. Valeo , 519 F. 2d 821, 832 (CADC
1975) (en banc) (per curiam) (invalidating 2 U. S. C.
§437a (1970 ed., Supp. V)). No appeal was taken from that holding. Buckley v. Valeo , 424 U. S. 1 , 10, n. 7 (1976) (per
curiam) . Footnote 5 The Court of Appeals
found: “Large contributions are intended
to, and do, gain access to the elected official after the campaign
for consideration of the contributor’s particular concerns. Senator
Mathias not only describes this but also the corollary, that the
feeling that big contributors gain special treatment produces a
reaction that the average American has no significant role in the
political process.” Buckley , 519 F. 2d, at 838
(footnotes omitted). The court also noted: “Congress found and the District Court confirmed
that such contributions were often made for the purpose of
furthering business or private interests by facilitating access to
government officials or influencing governmental decisions, and
that, conversely, elected officials have tended to afford special
treatment to large contributors. See S. Rep. No. 93–689,
93d Cong., 2d Sess. 4–5; Findings I, ¶ ;¶ ;108, 110, 118, 170.” Id. , at 838, n. 32. Citing further evidence of
corruption, the court explained: “The disclosures of illegal
corporate contributions in 1972 included the testimony of
executives that they were motivated by the perception that this was
necessary as a ‘calling card, something that would get us in the
door and make our point of view heard,’ Hearings before the
Senate Select Comm. on Presidential Campaign Activities , 93d
Cong., 1st Sess. 5442 (1973) (Ashland Oil Co.—Orin Atkins,
Chairman) or ‘in response to pressure for fear of a competitive
disadvantage that might result,’ id. at 5495, 5514
(American Airlines—George Spater, former chairman); see Findings I, ¶ ;105. The record before Congress was replete with
specific examples of improper attempts to obtain governmental favor
in return for large campaign contributions. See Findings
I, ¶ ;¶ ;159–64.” Id. , at 839, n. 37. Footnote 6 The court cited the intricate
scheme of the American Milk Producers, Inc., as an example of the
lengths to which contributors went to avoid their duty to
disclose: “Since the milk producers, on
legal advice, worked on a $2500 limit per committee, they evolved a
procedure, after consultation in November 1970 with Nixon fund
raisers, to break down [their $2 million donation] into numerous
smaller contributions to hundreds of committees in various states
which could then hold the money for the President’s reelection
campaign, so as to permit the producers to meet independent
reporting requirements without disclosure.” Id., at 839,
n. 36. The milk producers contributed
large sums to the Nixon campaign “in order to gain a meeting with
White House officials on price supports.” Ibid. Footnote
7 In 1977 the FEC promulgated a
rule allowing parties to allocate their administrative expenses “on
a reasonable basis” between accounts containing funds raised in
compliance with FECA and accounts containing nonfederal funds,
including corporate and union donations. 11 CFR §102.6(a)(2). In
advisory opinions issued in 1978 and 1979, the FEC allowed parties
similarly to allocate the costs of voter registration and
get-out-the-vote drives between federal and nonfederal accounts.
FEC Advisory Op. 1978–10; FEC Advisory Op. 1979–17. See 251
F. Supp. 2d, at 195–197 (per curiam) . In 1990 the FEC clarified the
phrase “on a reasonable basis” by promulgating fixed allocation
rates. 11 CFR §106.5 (1991). The regulations required the
Republican National Committee (RNC) and Democratic National
Committee (DNC) to pay for at least 60% of mixed-purpose activities
(65% in presidential election years) with funds from their federal
accounts. §106.5(b)(2). By contrast, the regulations required state
and local committees to allocate similar expenditures based on the
ratio of federal to nonfederal offices on the State’s ballot,
§106.5(d)(1), which in practice meant that they could expend a
substantially greater proportion of soft money than national
parties to fund mixed-purpose activities affecting both federal and
state elections. See 251 F. Supp. 2d, at 198–199 (per
curiam) . Footnote 8 1 Defs. Exhs., Tab 1, Tbl. 2
(report of Thomas E. Mann, Chair & Sr. Fellow, Brookings
Institution (hereinafter Mann Expert Report)); 251 F. Supp.
2d, at 197–201 (per curiam). Footnote
9 Mann Expert Report 26;
251 F. Supp. 2d, at 441 (Kollar-Kotelly, J.). Footnote
10 Id., at 494 (Kollar-Kotelly,
J.). Footnote
11 Mann Expert Report 24. Footnote
12 In the 2000 election cycle, 35 of
the 50 largest soft-money donors gave to both parties; 28 of the 50
gave more than $100,000 to both parties. Mann Expert Report Tbl. 6;
see also 251 F. Supp. 2d, at 509 (Kollar-Kotelly, J.); id. , at 785, n. 77 (Leon, J.). Footnote
13 A former chief executive officer of a
large corporation explained: “Business and labor leaders
believe, based on their experience, that disappointed Members, and
their party colleagues, may shun or disfavor them because they have
not contributed. Equally, these leaders fear that if they refuse to
contribute (enough), competing interests who do contribute
generously will have an advantage in gaining access to and
influencing key Congressional leaders on matters of importance to
the company or union.” App. 283, ¶ ;9 (declaration of Gerald
Greenwald, United Airlines (hereinafter Greenwald
Decl.)). Amici Curiae Committee
for Economic Development and various business leaders attest that
corporate soft-money contributions are “coerced and, at bottom,
wholly commercial” in nature, and that “[b]usiness leaders
increasingly wish to be freed from the grip of a system in which
they fear the adverse consequences of refusing to fill the coffers
of the major parties.” Brief for Committee for Economic Development
et al. as Amici Curiae 28. Footnote
14 See 251 F. Supp. 2d, at 480
(Kollar-Kotelly, J.); id. , at 842 (Leon, J.). Footnote
15 See id. , at 479–480
(Kollar-Kotelly, J.); id. , at 842–843 (Leon, J.). One
former party official explained to the District Court: “ ‘Once you’ve helped a federal candidate by
contributing hard money to his or her campaign, you are sometimes
asked to do more for the candidate by making donations of hard
and/or soft money to the national party committees, the relevant
state party (assuming it can accept corporate contributions), or an
outside group that is planning on doing an independent expenditure
or issue advertisement to help the candidate’s campaign.’ ” Id. , at 479 (Kollar-Kotelly, J.). Footnote
16 Id. , at 532–537
(Kollar-Kotelly, J.); id ., at 875–879 (Leon, J.). As the
former chair of one major advocacy organization’s PAC put it,
“ ‘[i]t is foolish to believe there is any practical
difference between issue advocacy and advocacy of a political
candidate. What separates issue advocacy and political advocacy is
a line in the sand drawn on a windy day.’ ” Id., at
536–537 (Kollar-Kotelly, J.) (quoting Tanya K. Metaksa, Opening
Remarks at the American Assn. of Political Consultants Fifth
General Session on “Issue Advocacy,” Jan. 17, 1997, p. 2); 251
F. Supp. 2d, at 878–879 (Leon, J.) (same). Footnote
17 Id., at 304 (Henderson, J.,
concurring in judgment in part and dissenting in part); id. , at 534 (Kollar-Kotelly, J.); id. , at 875–879
(Leon, J.). Footnote
18 It is undisputed that very few
ads—whether run by candidates, parties, or interest groups—used
words of express advocacy. Id., at 303 (Henderson, J.); id. , at 529 (Kollar-Kotelly, J.); id. , at 874
(Leon, J.). In the 1998 election cycle, just 4% of candidate
advertisements used magic words; in 2000, that number was a mere
5%. App. 1334 (report of Jonathan S. Krasno, Yale University, &
Frank J. Sorauf, University of Minnesota, pp. 53–54 (hereinafter
Krasno & Sorauf Expert Report); see 1 Defs. Exhs., Tab 2, pp.
53–54). Footnote
19 251 F. Supp. 2d, at 564, and
n. 6 (Kollar-Kotelly, J.) (citing report of Kenneth M.
Goldstein, University of Wisconsin-Madison, App. A, Tbl. 16; see
3–R Defs. Exhs., Tab 7); Tr. of Oral Arg. 202–203; see also 251
F. Supp. 2d, at 305 (Henderson, J.). Footnote
20 The spending on electioneering
communications climbed dramatically during the last decade. In the
1996 election cycle, $135 to $150 million was spent on multiple
broadcasts of about 100 ads. In the next cycle (1997-1998), 77
organizations aired 423 ads at a total cost between $270 and $340
million. By the 2000 election, 130 groups spent over an estimated
$500 million on more than 1,100 different ads. Two out of every
three dollars spent on issue ads in the 2000 cycle were
attributable to the two major parties and six major interest
groups. Id., at 303–304 (Henderson, J.) (citing Annenberg
Public Policy Center, Issue Advertising in the 1999–2000 Election
Cycle 1–15 (2001) (hereinafter Annenberg Report); see 38 Defs.
Exhs., Tab 22); 251 F. Supp. 2d, at 527 (Kollar-Kotelly, J.)
(same); id ., at 879 (Leon, J.) (same). Footnote
21 Id., at 540 (Kollar-Kotelly,
J.) (quoting internal AFL-CIO Memorandum from Brian Weeks to Mike
Klein, “Electronic Buy for Illinois Senator,” (Oct. 9, 1996),
AFL-CIO 005244); 251 F. Supp. 2d, at 886 (Leon, J.)
(same). Footnote
22 The association was known as the
Pharmaceutical Research and Manufacturers of America (PhRMA). Id. , at 232 (per curiam) . Footnote
23 Id ., at 232–233. Other
examples of mysterious groups included “Voters for Campaign Truth,”
“Aretino Industries,” “Montanans for Common Sense Mining Laws,”
“American Seniors, Inc.,” “American Family Voices,” App. 1355
(Krasno & Sorauf Expert Report 71–77), and the “Coalition to
Make our Voices Heard,” 251 F. Supp. 2d, at 538
(Kollar-Kotelly, J.). Some of the actors behind these groups
frankly acknowledged that “ ‘in some places it’s much more
effective to run an ad by the ‘Coalition to Make Our Voices Heard’
than it is to say paid for by ‘the men and women of the
AFL–CIO.’ ” Ibid. (Kollar-Kotelly, J.) (quoting
report of David B. Magleby, Brigham Young University 18–19
(hereinafter Magleby Expert Report), App. 1484–1485). Footnote
24 251 F. Supp. 2d, at 518–519
(Kollar-Kotelly, J.). Footnote
25 Id., at 478–479
(Kollar-Kotelly, J.) (citing declaration of Robert Hickmott, Senior
V. P., Smith-Free Group, ¶ ;8 (hereinafter Hickmott Decl.);
see 6–R Defs. Exhs., Tab 19, ¶ ;8). Footnote
26 S. Rep. No. 105–167, vol. 4,
p. 4611 (1998) (hereinafter 1998 Senate Report); 5 id., at 7515. Footnote
27 3 id., at 4535
(additional views of Sen. Collins). Footnote
28 1 id., at 41–42,
195–200. The report included a memorandum written by the DNC
finance chairman suggesting the use of White House coffees and
“overnights” to give major donors “quality time” with the
President, and noted that the guests accounted for $26.4 million in
contributions. Id. , at 194, 196. Footnote
29 2 id., at 2913–2914,
2921. Despite concerns about Tamraz’s background and a possible
conflict with United States foreign policy interests, he was
invited to six events attended by the President. Id. , at
2920–2921. Similarly, the minority noted that in exchange for
Michael Kojima’s contribution of $500,000 to the 1992 President’s
Dinner, he and his wife had been placed at the head table with
President and Mrs. Bush. Moreover, Kojima received several
additional meetings with the President, other administration
officials, and United States embassy officials. 4 id., at
5418, 5422, 5428. Footnote
30 The former requires an initial
contribution of $100,000, and $25,000 for each of the next three
years; the latter requires annual contributions of $15,000. 5 id., at 7968. Footnote
31 Id. , at 7971. Footnote
32 1 id., at 49; 3 id., at 3997–4006. Footnote
33 Id ., at 4466. Footnote
34 Ibid. Footnote
35 Id. , at 4468–4470,
4480–4481, 4491–4494. Footnote
36 Id. , at 4492. Footnote
37 6 id., at
9394. Footnote
38 The national party committees of
the two major political parties are: the Republican National
Committee (RNC); the Democratic National Committee (DNC); the
National Republican Senatorial Committee (NRSC); the National
Republican Congressional Committee (NRCC); the Democratic
Senatorial Campaign Committee (DSCC); and the Democratic
Congressional Campaign Committee (DCCC). 251 F. Supp. 2d, at
468 (Kollar-Kotelly, J.). Footnote
39 Justice Kennedy accuses us of
engaging in a sleight of hand by conflating “unseemly corporate
speech” with the speech of political parties and candidates, and
then adverting to the “corporate speech rationale as if it were the
linchpin of the litigation.” Post , at 7 (opinion
concurring in part and dissenting in part). This is incorrect. The
principles set forth here and relied upon in assessing Title I are
the same principles articulated in Buckley and its progeny
that regulations of contributions to candidates, parties, and
political committees are subject to less rigorous scrutiny than
direct restraints on speech—including “unseemly corporate
speech.” Footnote
40 Since our decision in Buckley , we have consistently applied less rigorous
scrutiny to contribution restrictions aimed at the prevention of
corruption and the appearance of corruption. See, e.g. ,
424 U. S., at 23–36 (applying less rigorous scrutiny to FECA’s
$1,000 limit on individual contributions to a candidate and FECA’s
$5,000 limit on PAC contributions to a candidate); id. , at
38 (applying less rigorous scrutiny to FECA’s $25,000 aggregate
yearly limit on contributions to candidates, political party
committees, and political committees); California Medical
Assn. v. Federal Election Comm’n, 453
U. S. 182 , 195–196 (1981) (plurality opinion) (applying less
rigorous scrutiny to FECA’s $5,000 limit on contributions to
multicandidate political committees); National Right to
Work , 459 U. S., at 208–211 (applying less rigorous scrutiny
to antisolicitation provision buttressing an otherwise valid
contribution limit); Colorado II , 533 U. S. 431 , 456 (2001) (applying
less rigorous scrutiny to expenditures coordinated with a
candidate); Federal Election Comm’n v . Beaumont, 539 U. S.___, ___ (2003) (slip op., at 14–15) (applying less
rigorous scrutiny to provisions intended to prevent circumvention
of otherwise valid contribution limits). Footnote
41 Indeed, Congress structured
§323(b) in such a way as to free individual, corporate, and union
donations to state committees for nonfederal elections
from federal source and amount restrictions. Footnote
42 Justice Kennedy’s contention that
less rigorous scrutiny applies only to regulations burdening
political association, rather than political speech, misreads Buckley . In Buckley , we recognized that
contribution limits burden both protected speech and association,
though they generally have more significant impacts on the latter.
424 U. S., at 20–22. We nevertheless applied less rigorous scrutiny
to FECA’s contribution limits because neither burden was
sufficiently weighty to overcome Congress’ countervailing interest
in protecting the integrity of the political process. See Nixon v. Shrink Missouri Government PAC , 528 U. S. 377 , 388 (2000) (“While we
did not [in Buckley ] attempt to parse [the] distinctions
between the speech and association standards of scrutiny for
contribution limits, we did make it clear that those restrictions
bore more heavily on the associational right than on [the] freedom
to speak. We consequently proceeded on the understanding that a
contribution limitation surviving a claim of associational
abridgment would survive a speech challenge as well, and we held
the standard satisfied by the contribution limits under review.”
(citation omitted)). It is thus simply untrue in the campaign
finance context that all “burdens on speech necessitate strict
scrutiny review.” Post , at 29. Footnote
43 Justice Kennedy is no doubt
correct that the associational burdens imposed by a particular
piece of campaign-finance regulation may at times be so severe as
to warrant strict scrutiny. Ibid. In light of our
interpretation of §323(a), however, see infra, at 46–47,
§323 does not present such a case. As Justice Kennedy himself
acknowledges, even “ significant interference” with
“protected rights of association” are subject to less rigorous
scrutiny. Beaumont , 539 U. S., at _____ (slip op., at 15);
see post , at 28. There is thus nothing inconsistent in our
decision to account for the particular associational burdens
imposed by §323(a) when applying the appropriate level of
scrutiny. Footnote
44 The fact that the post-1990
explosion in soft-money spending on federal electioneering was
accompanied by a series of efforts in Congress to clamp down on
such uses of soft money (culminating, of course, in BCRA)
underscores the fact that the FEC regulations permitted more than
Congress, in enacting FECA, had ever intended. See J. Cantor,
Congressional Research Service Report for Congress: Campaign
Finance Legislation in the 101st Congress (1990) (9 bills seeking
to limit the influence of soft money introduced); J. Cantor, CRS
Report for Congress: Campaign Finance Legislation in the 102nd
Congress (1991) (10 such bills introduced); J. Cantor, CRS Report
for Congress: Campaign Finance Legislation in the 103rd Congress
(1993) (16 bills); J. Cantor, CRS Report for Congress: Campaign
Finance Legislation in the 104th Congress (1996) (18 bills); see
also 251 F. Supp. 2d, at 201–206 (per curiam) (discussing legislative efforts to curb soft money in 105th and
subsequent Congresses). Footnote
45 Justice Kennedy contends that the
plurality’s observation in Colorado I that large
soft-money donations to a political party pose little threat of
corruption “establish[es] that” such contributions are not
corrupting. Post , at 17–18 (citing Colorado I , 518 U. S. 604 , 616, 617–618 (1996)).
The cited dictum has no bearing on the present case. Colorado
I addressed an entirely different question—namely, whether
Congress could permissibly limit a party’s independent
expenditures—and did so on an entirely different set of facts. It
also had before it an evidentiary record frozen in 1990—well before
the soft-money explosion of the 1990’s. See Federal Election
Comm’n v. Colorado Republican Fed. Campaign Comm. ,
839 F. Supp. 1448, 1451 (Colo. 1993). Footnote
46 Other business leaders agreed.
For example, the chairman of the board and CEO of a major toy
company explained: “ ‘Many in the corporate world view large soft
money donations as a cost of doing business. … I remain convinced
that in some of the more publicized cases, federal officeholders
actually appear to have sold themselves and the party cheaply. They
could have gotten even more money, because of the potential
importance of their decisions to the affected business.’ ” 251
F. Supp. 2d, at 491 (Kollar-Kotelly, J.) (quoting declaration
of Alan G. Hassenfeld, CEO, Hasbro, Inc., ¶ ;16; see 6–R Defs.
Exhs., Tab 17). Similarly the chairman emeritus of a major airline
opined: “ ‘Though a soft money check might be made out
to a political party, labor and business leaders know that those
checks open the doors of the offices of individual and important
Members of Congress and the Administration… . Labor and
business leaders believe—based on experience and with good
reason—that such access gives them an opportunity to shape and
affect governmental decisions and that their ability to do so
derives from the fact that they have given large sums of money to
the parties.’ ” 251 F. Supp. 2d, at 498 (Kollar-Kotelly,
J.) (quoting Greenwald Decl. ¶ ;12, App. 283–284, ¶ ;10); 251
F. Supp. 2d, at 858–859 (Leon, J.) (same). Footnote
47 Even more troubling is evidence
in the record showing that national parties have actively exploited
the belief that contributions purchase influence or protection to
pressure donors into making contributions. As one CEO
explained: “ ‘[I]f you’re giving a lot of soft money to
one side, the other side knows. For many economically-oriented
donors, there is a risk in giving to only one side, because the
other side may read through FEC reports and have staff or a
friendly lobbyist call and indicate that someone with interests
before a certain committee has had their contributions to the other
side noticed. They’ll get a message that basically asks: ‘Are you
sure you want to be giving only to one side? Don’t you want to have
friends on both sides of the aisle?’ If your interests are subject
to anger from the other side of the aisle, you need to fear that
you may suffer a penalty if you don’t give… . [D]uring the
1990’s, it became more and more acceptable to call someone, saying
you saw he gave to this person, so he should also give to you or
the person’s opponent.’ ” Id. , at 510
(Kollar-Kotelly, J.) (quoting Randlett Decl. ¶ ;12, App. 715); 251
F. Supp. 2d, at 868 (Leon, J.) (same). Footnote
48 In addition to finding no support
in our recent cases, see, e.g. , Colorado II , 533
U. S., at 441 (defining corruption more broadly than quid pro
quo arrangements); Shrink Missouri , 528 U. S., at 389
(same), Justice Kennedy’s contention that Buckley limits
Congress to regulating contributions to a candidate ignores Buckley itself. There, we upheld FECA’s $25,000 limit on
aggregate yearly contributions to candidates, political
committees , and party committees out of recognition
that FECA’s $1,000 limit on candidate contributions would be
meaningless if individuals could instead make “huge contributions
to the candidate’s political party.” 424 U. S., at 38. Likewise, in California Medical Assn. v. Federal Election
Comm’n, 453
U. S. 182 (1981), we upheld FECA’s $5,000 limit on
contributions to multicandidate political committees. It is no
answer to say that such limits were justified as a means of
preventing individuals from using parties and political committees
as pass-throughs to circumvent FECA’s $1,000 limit on individual
contributions to candidates. Given FECA’s definition of
“contribution,” the $5,000 and $25,000 limits restricted not only
the source and amount of funds available to parties and political
committees to make candidate contributions, but also the source and
amount of funds available to engage in express advocacy and
numerous other noncoordinated expenditures. If indeed the First
Amendment prohibited Congress from regulating contributions to fund
the latter, the otherwise-easy-to-remedy exploitation of parties as
pass-throughs ( e.g. , a strict limit on donations that
could be used to fund candidate contributions) would have provided
insufficient justification for such overbroad
legislation. Footnote
49 At another point, describing our
“flawed reasoning,” Justice Kennedy seems to suggest that Congress’
interest in regulating the appearance of corruption extends only to
those contributions that actually “create … corrupt donor
favoritism among … officeholders.” Post , at 16. This
latter formulation would render Congress’ interest in stemming the
appearance of corruption indistinguishable from its interest in
preventing actual corruption. Footnote
50 In support of this claim, the
political party plaintiffs assert that, in 2001, the RNC spent
$15.6 million of nonfederal funds (30% of the nonfederal amount
raised that year) on purely state and local election activity,
including contributions to state and local candidates, transfers to
state parties, and direct spending. See Tr. of Oral Arg. 102–103
(statement of counsel Bobby R. Burchfield); 251 F. Supp. 2d, at
336–337 (Henderson, J.); id ., at 464–465 (Kollar-Kotelly,
J.); id. , at 830 (Leon, J.). Footnote
51 The close relationship of federal
officeholders and candidates to their parties answers not only The
Chief Justice’s concerns about §323(a), but also his fear that our
analysis of §323’s remaining provisions bespeaks no limiting
principle. Post , at 6–7 (dissenting opinion). As set forth
in our discussion of those provisions, the record demonstrates
close ties between federal officeholders and the state and local
committees of their parties. That close relationship makes state
and local parties effective conduits for donors desiring to corrupt
federal candidates and officeholders. Thus, in upholding §§323(b),
(d), and (f), we rely not only on the fact that they regulate
contributions used to fund activities influencing federal
elections, but also that they regulate contributions to or at the
behest of entities uniquely positioned to serve as conduits for
corruption. We agree with The Chief Justice that Congress could not
regulate financial contributions to political talk show hosts or
newspaper editors on the sole basis that their activities conferred
a benefit on the candidate. Post , at 7
(dissenting opinion). Footnote
52 Plaintiffs claim that the option
of soliciting hard money for state and local candidates is an
illusory one, since several States prohibit state and local
candidates from establishing multiple campaign accounts, which
would preclude them from establishing separate accounts for federal
funds. See Cal. Fair Pol. Practs. Comm’n Advisory Op. A–91–448
(Dec. 16, 1991), 1991 WL 772902; Colo. Const., Art. XXVIII, §2(3);
Iowa Code §56.5A (Supp. 2003); and Ohio Rev. Code Ann. §3517.10(J)
(Anderson Supp. 2002). Plaintiffs maintain that §323(a) combines
with these state laws to make it impossible for state and local
candidates to receive hard-money donations. But the challenge we
are considering is a facial one, and on its face §323(a) permits
solicitations. The fact that a handful of States might interfere
with the mechanism Congress has chosen for such solicitations is an
argument that may be addressed in an as-applied
challenge. Footnote
53 Even opponents of campaign
finance reform acknowledged that “a prohibition of soft money
donations to national party committees alone would be wholly
ineffective.” The Constitution and Campaign Reform: Hearings on S.
522 before the Senate Committee on Rules and Administration, 106th
Cong., 2d Sess., 301 (2000) (statement of Bobby R. Burchfield,
Partner, Covington & Burling). Footnote
54 Generic campaign activity
promotes a political party rather than a specific candidate. 2 U.
S. C. A. §431(21). Footnote
55 A public communication is “a
communication by means of any broadcast, cable, or satellite
communication, newspaper, magazine, outdoor advertising facility,
mass mailing, or telephone bank to the general public, or any other
form of general public political advertising.” §431(22). Footnote
56 So long as the communication does
not constitute voter registration, voter identification, GOTV, or
generic campaign activity. §431(20)(B)(i). Footnote
57 Unless the contribution is
earmarked for federal election activity.
§431(20)(B)(ii). Footnote
58 The statute gives the FEC
responsibility for setting the allocation ratio. §441i(b)(2)(A);
see also 11 CFR §300.33(b) (2003) (defining allocation
ratios). Footnote
59 One former Senator
noted: “ ‘The fact is that much of
what state and local parties do helps to elect federal candidates.
The national parties know it; the candidates know it; the state and
local parties know it. If state and local parties can use soft
money for activities that affect federal elections, then the
problem will not be solved at all. The same enormous incentives to
raise the money will exist; the same large contributions by
corporations, unions, and wealthy individuals will be made; the
federal candidates who benefit from state party use of these funds
will know exactly whom their benefactors are; the same degree of
beholdenness and obligation will arise; the same distortions on the
legislative process will occur; and the same public cynicism will
erode the foundations of our democracy—except it will all be worse
in the public’s mind because a perceived reform was undercut once
again by a loophole that allows big money into the system.’ ”
251 F. Supp. 2d, at 467 (Kollar-Kotelly, J.) (quoting Rudman
Decl. ¶ ;19, App. 746). Footnote
60 E.g ., 251 F. Supp.
2d, at 479 (Kollar-Kotelly, J.) (“ ‘It is … not uncommon for
the RNC to put interested donors in touch with various state
parties. This often occurs when a donor has reached his or her
federal dollar limits to the RNC, but wishes to make additional
contributions to the state party’ ” (quoting declaration of
Thomas Josefiak, RNC Chief Counsel ¶ ;68, App 308)); see also Colorado II , 533 U. S., at 458 (quoting Congressman Wayne
Allard’s Aug. 27, 1996, fundraising letter informing the recipient
that “ ‘you are at the limit of what you can directly
contribute to my campaign,’ ” but “ ‘you can further help
my campaign by assisting the Colorado Republican Party’ ”);
251 F. Supp 2d, at 454 (Kollar-Kotelly, J.) (“ ‘Both political
parties have found spending soft money with its accompanying hard
money match through their state parties to work smoothly, for the
most part, and state officials readily acknowledge they are simply
‘pass throughs’ to the vendors providing the broadcast ads or
direct mail’ ” (quoting Magleby Expert Report 37, App.
1510–1511.)). Footnote
61 The 1998 Senate Report found
that, in exchange for a substantial donation to state Democratic committees and candidates, the DNC arranged meetings for
the donor with the President and other federal officials. 1 1998
Senate Report 43–44; 2 id. , at 2907–2931; 5 id .,
at 7519. That same Report also detailed how Native American tribes
that operated casinos made sizable soft-money contributions to
state Democratic committees in apparent exchange for access and
influence. 1 id ., at 44–46; 2 id., at 3167–3194;
see also McCain Decl., Exh. I (Weisskopf, The Busy Back-Door Men,
Time, Mar. 31, 1997, p. 40)). Footnote
62 Since voter identification is a
necessary precondition of any GOTV program, the findings regarding
GOTV funding obviously apply with equal force to the funding of
voter identification efforts. Footnote
63 With respect to GOTV, voter
identification, and other generic campaign activity, the FEC has
interpreted §323(b) to apply only to those activities conducted
after the earliest filing deadline for access to the federal
election ballot or, in States that do not conduct primaries, after
January 1 of even-numbered years. 11 CFR §100.24(a)(1) (2002). Any
activities conducted outside of those periods are completely exempt
from regulation under §323(b). Of course, this facial challenge
does not present the question of the FEC regulations’
constitutionality. But the fact that the statute provides this
basis for the FEC reasonably to narrow §301(20)(A)(ii) further
calls into question plaintiffs’ claims of facial overbreadth. See Broadrick v. Oklahoma, 413 U. S. 601 , 613 (1973). Footnote
64 We likewise reject the argument
that §301(20)(A)(iii) is unconstitutionally vague. The words
“promote,” “oppose,” “attack,” and “support” clearly set forth the
confines within which potential party speakers must act in order to
avoid triggering the provision. These words “provide explicit
standards for those who apply them” and “give the person of
ordinary intelligence a reasonable opportunity to know what is
prohibited.” Grayned v. City of
Rockford, 408 U. S. 104 , 108–109 (1972). This is
particularly the case here, since actions taken by political
parties are presumed to be in connection with election campaigns.
See Buckley , 424 U. S., at 79 (noting that a general
requirement that political committees disclose their expenditures
raised no vagueness problems because the term “political committee”
“need only encompass organizations that are under the control of a
candidate or the major purpose of which is the nomination or
election of a candidate” and thus a political committee’s
expenditures “are, by definition, campaign related”). Furthermore,
should plaintiffs feel that they need further guidance, they are
able to seek advisory opinions for clarification, see 2 U.
S. C. §437f (a)(1), and thereby “remove any doubt there
may be as to the meaning of the law,” Civil Service Comm’n v. Letter Carriers, 413 U. S. 548 , 580
(1973). Footnote
65 Any doubts that donors would
engage in such a seemingly complex scheme are put to rest by the
record evidence in Buckley itself. See n. 6, supra (setting forth the Court of Appeals’ findings
regarding the efforts of milk producers to obtain a meeting with
White House officials). Footnote
66 Section 501(c) organizations are
groups generally exempted from taxation under the Internal Revenue
Code. 26 U. S. C. §501(a). These include §501(c)(3) charitable
and educational organizations, as well as §501(c)(4) social welfare
groups. Footnote
67 Section 527 “political
organizations” are, unlike §501(c) groups, organized for the
express purpose of engaging in partisan political activity. They
include any “party, committee, association, fund, or other
organization (whether or not incorporated) organized and operated
primarily for the purpose of directly or indirectly accepting
contributions or making expenditures” for the purpose of
“influencing or attempting to influence the selection, nomination,
or appointment of any individual for Federal, State, or local
public office.” 26 U. S. C. §527(e). Footnote
68 The record shows that many of the
targeted tax-exempt organizations engage in sophisticated and
effective electioneering activities for the purpose of influencing
federal elections, including waging broadcast campaigns promoting
or attacking particular candidates and conducting large-scale voter
registration and GOTV drives. For instance, during the final weeks
of the 2000 presidential campaign, the NAACP’s National Voter Fund
registered more than 200,000 people, promoted a GOTV hotline, ran
three newspaper print ads, and made several direct mailings. 251
F. Supp. 2d, at 348–349 (Henderson, J.). The NAACP reports
that the program turned out one million additional African-American
voters and increased turnout over 1996 among targeted groups by 22%
in New York, 50% in Florida, and 140% in Missouri. Ibid .
The effort, which cost $10 million, was funded primarily by a $7
million contribution from an anonymous donor. Id., at 349
(citing cross-examination of Donald P. Green, Yale University
15–20, Exh. 3; see I Defs. Refiling Trs. on Pub. Record); 251
F. Supp. 2d, at 522 (Kollar-Kotelly, J.) (same); id .,
at 851 (Leon, J.) (same); see also id., at 349 (Henderson,
J.) (stating that in 2000 the National Abortion and Reproductive
Rights Action League (NARAL) spent $7.5 million and mobilized 2.1
million pro-choice voters (citing declaration of Mary Jane
Gallagher, Exec. V. P., NARAL, 8, App. 271–272, ¶ ;24)); 251
F. Supp. 2d, at 522 (Kollar-Kotelly, J.) (same). Footnote
69 Notably, the FEC has interpreted
§323(d)(2) to permit state, district, and local party committees to
solicit donations to §527 organizations that are state-registered
PACs, that support only state or local candidates, and that do not
make expenditures or disbursements in connection with federal
elections. 11 CFR §300.37(a)(3)(iv) (2003). The agency determined
that this interpretation of “political committee”—at least with
respect to state, district, and local committees—was consistent
with BCRA’s fundamental purpose of prohibiting soft money from
being used in connection with federal elections. 67 Fed. Reg. 49106
(2002). Footnote
70 Section 323(e)(1)(B) tightly
constrains the ability of federal candidates and officeholders to
solicit or spend nonfederal money in connection with state or local
elections. Contributions cannot exceed FECA’s analogous hard-money
contribution limits or come from prohibited sources. In effect,
§323(e)(1)(B) doubles the limits on what individuals can contribute
to or at the behest of federal candidates and officeholders, while
restricting the use of the additional funds to activities not
related to federal elections. If the federal candidate or
officeholder is also a candidate for state or local office, he or
she may solicit, receive, and spend an unlimited amount of
nonfederal money in connection with that election, subject only to
state regulation and the requirement that such solicitation or
expenditures refer only to the relevant state or local office. 2 U.
S. C. A. §441i(e)(2). Footnote
71 See 148 Cong. Rec. S2143 (Mar.
20, 2002) (statement of Sen. Feingold) (Section 323(f) does not
prohibit “spending non-federal money to run advertisements that
mention that [state or local candidates] have been endorsed by a
Federal candidate or say that they identify with a position of a
named Federal candidate, so long as those advertisements do not
support, attack, promote or oppose the Federal
candidate”). Footnote
72 Justice Kennedy faults our
“unwillingness” to confront that “Title I’s entirety … look[s] very
much like an incumbency protection plan,” citing §323(e), which
provides officeholders and candidates with greater opportunities to
solicit soft money than §§323(a) and (d) permit party officers. Post , at 23–24. But, §323(e) applies to both officeholders and candidates and allows only minimally greater
opportunities for solicitation out of regard for the fact that
candidates and officeholders, unlike party officers, can never step
out of their official roles. Supra , at 70–71; 42 U.
S. C. A. §441i(e). Any concern that Congress might
opportunistically pass campaign-finance regulation for self-serving
ends is taken into account by the applicable level of scrutiny.
Congress must show concrete evidence that a particular type of
financial transaction is corrupting or gives rise to the appearance
of corruption and that the chosen means of regulation are closely
drawn to address that real or apparent corruption. It has done so
here. At bottom, Justice Kennedy has long disagreed with the basic
holding of Buckley and its progeny that less rigorous
scrutiny—which shows a measure of deference to Congress in an area
where it enjoys particular expertise—applies to assess limits on
campaign contributions. Colorado II , 533 U. S., at 465
(Thomas, J., dissenting) (joining Justice Thomas for the
proposition that “ Buckley should be overrruled” (citation
omitted)); Shrink Missouri , 528 U. S., at 405–410
(Kennedy, J., dissenting). Footnote
73 BCRA also provides a “backup”
definition of “electioneering communication,” which would become
effective if the primary definition were “held to be
constitutionally insufficient by final judicial decision to support
the regulation provided herein.” 2 U. S. C. A.
§434(f)(3)(A)(ii). We uphold all applications of the primary
definition and accordingly have no occasion to discuss the backup
definition. Footnote
74 We then held that, so construed,
the expenditure restriction did not advance a substantial
government interest, because independent express advocacy did not
pose a danger of real or apparent corruption, and the line between
express advocacy and other electioneering activities was easily
circumvented. Concluding that §608(e)(1)’s heavy First Amendment
burden was not justified, we invalidated the provision. Buckley, 424 U. S., at 45–48. Footnote
75 Our adoption of a narrowing
construction was consistent with our vagueness and overbreadth
doctrines. See Broadrick, 413 U. S., at 613; Grayned, 408 U. S., at 108–114. Footnote
76 The provision at issue in MCFL —2 U. S. C. §441b (1982 ed.)—required
corporations and unions to use separate segregated funds, rather
than general treasury moneys, on expenditures made “ ‘in
connection with’ ” a federal election. MCFL, 479 U.
S., at 241. We noted that Buckley had limited the
statutory term “ ‘expenditure’ ” to words of express
advocacy “in order to avoid problems of overbreadth.” 479 U. S., at
248. We held that “a similar construction ” must apply to
the expenditure limitation before us in MCFL and that the
reach of 2 U. S. C. §441b was therefore constrained to express
advocacy. 479 U. S., at 249 (emphasis added). Footnote
77 As one major-party political
consultant testified, “ ‘it is rarely advisable to use such
clumsy words as “vote for” or “vote against.” ’ ” 251
F. Supp. 2d, at 305 (Henderson, J.) (quoting declaration of
Douglas L. Bailey, founder, Bailey, Deardourff & Assoc., 1–2,
App. 24, ¶ ;3). He explained: “ ‘All advertising professionals
understand that the most effective advertising leads the viewer to
his or her own conclusion without forcing it down their
throat.’ ” 251 F. Supp. 2d, at 305 (Henderson, J.). Other
political professionals and academics confirm that the use of magic
words has become an anachronism. See id ., at 531
(Kollar-Kotelly, J.) (quoting declaration of Raymond D. Strother,
Pres., Strother/Duffy/Strother ¶ ;4, 9 Defs. Exhs., Tab 40); see
Unsealed Pp. Vol., Tab 7); App. 1334–1335 (Krasno & Sorauf
Expert Report)); see also 251 F. Supp. 2d, at 305 (Henderson,
J.); id. , at 532 (Kollar-Kotelly, J.); id. , at
875–76 (Leon, J.). Footnote
78 One striking example is an ad
that a group called “Citizens for Reform” sponsored during the 1996
Montana congressional race, in which Bill Yellowtail was a
candidate. The ad stated: “Who is Bill Yellowtail? He
preaches family values but took a swing at his wife. And
Yellowtail’s response? He only slapped her. But ‘her nose was not
broken.’ He talks law and order … but is himself a convicted felon.
And though he talks about protecting children, Yellowtail failed to
make his own child support payments—then voted against child
support enforcement. Call Bill Yellowtail. Tell him to support
family values.” 5 1998 Senate Report 6305 (minority
views). The notion that this advertisement was designed
purely to discuss the issue of family values strains
credulity. Footnote
79 As discussed below, infra , at 97–103, BCRA §203 bars corporations and labor
unions from funding electioneering communications with money from
their general treasuries, instead requiring them to establish a
“separate segregated fund” for such expenditures. 2 U.
S. C. A. §441b(b)(2). Footnote
80 Section 401 of BCRA
provides: “If any provision of this Act or
amendment made by this Act . . ., or the application of a provision
or amendment to any person or circumstance, is held to be
unconstitutional, the remainder of this Act and amendments made by
this Act, and the application of the provisions and amendment to
any person or circumstance, shall not be affected by the holding.”
2 U. S. C. A. §454 note. Footnote
81 The disclosure requirements that
BCRA §201 added to FECA §304 are actually somewhat less intrusive
than the comparable requirements that have long applied to persons
making independent expenditures. For example, the previous version
of §304 required groups making independent expenditures to identify
donors who contributed more than $200. 2 U. S. C. §434(c)(2)(C)
(2000 ed.). The comparable requirement in the amendments applies
only to donors of $1,000 or more. 2 U. S. C. A.
§§434(f)(2)(E), (F) (Supp. 2003). Footnote
82 NAACP v. Alabama arose out of a judgment holding the NAACP in
contempt for refusing to produce the names and addresses of its
members and agents in Alabama. The NAACP “made an uncontroverted
showing that on past occasions revelation of the identity of its
rank-and-file members ha[d] exposed these members to economic
reprisal, loss of employment, threat of physical coercion, and
other manifestations of public hostility.” 357 U. S., at 462. We
thought it apparent that the compelled disclosure would “affect
adversely” the NAACP and its members’ ability “to pursue their
collective effort to foster beliefs which they admittedly have the
right to advocate.” Id. , at 462–463. Under these
circumstances, we concluded that Alabama’s interest in determining
whether the NAACP was doing business in the State was plainly
insufficient to justify its production order. Id. , at
464–466. Footnote
83 We stated: “The District Court properly
applied the Buckley test to the facts of this case. The
District Court found ‘substantial evidence of both governmental and
private hostility toward and harassment of [Socialist Workers Party
(SWP)] members and supporters.’ Appellees introduced proof of
specific incidents of private and government hostility toward the
SWP and its members within the four years preceding the trial.
These incidents, many of which occurred in Ohio and neighboring
States, included threatening phone calls and hate mail, the burning
of SWP literature, the destruction of SWP members’ property, police
harassment of a party candidate, and the firing of shots at an SWP
office. There was also evidence that in the 12-month period before
trial 22 SWP members, including 4 in Ohio, were fired because of
their party membership. Although appellants contend that two of the
Ohio firings were not politically motivated, the evidence amply
supports the District Court’s conclusion that ‘private hostility
and harassment toward SWP members make it difficult for them to
maintain employment.’ The District Court also found a past history
of Government harassment of the SWP.” Brown v. Socialist Workers ’74 Campaign Comm. (Ohio), 459 U. S. 87 , 98–99 (1982) (paragraph
break omitted). Footnote
84 We cannot judge the likelihood
that this will occur, as the record contains little if any
description of the contractual provisions that commonly govern
payments for electioneering communications. Nor does the record
contain any evidence relating to Justice Kennedy’s speculation, post , at 39–40, that advance disclosure may disadvantage
an advertiser. Footnote
85 New FECA §315(a)(7)(C) reads as
follows: “if — “(i) any person makes, or
contracts to make, any disbursement for any electioneering
communication (within the meaning of section 434(f)(3) of this
title); and “(ii) such disbursement is
coordinated with a candidate or an authorized committee of such
candidate, a Federal, State, or local political party or committee
thereof, or an agent or official of any such candidate, party, or
committee; such disbursement or contracting shall be treated as
a contribution to the candidate supported by the electioneering
communication or that candidate’s party and as an expenditure by
that candidate or that candidate’s party. . . .” 2 U.
S. C. A. §441a(a)(7)(C). Footnote
86 We have explained: “The statutory purpose of §441b …
is to prohibit contributions or expenditures by corporations or
labor organizations in connection with federal elections. 2 U.
S. C. §441b(a). The section, however, permits some
participation of unions and corporations in the federal electoral
process by allowing them to establish and pay the administrative
expenses of ‘separate segregated fund[s],’ which may be ‘utilized
for political purposes.’ 2 U. S. C. §441b(b)(2)(C). The Act
restricts the operations of such segregated funds, however, by
making it unlawful for a corporation to solicit contributions to a
fund established by it from persons other than its ‘stockholders
and their families and its executive or administrative personnel
and their families.’ 2 U. S. C. §441b(b)(4)(A).” National
Right to Work, 459 U. S., at 201–202. Footnote
87 The amendment is straightforward.
Prior to BCRA, FECA §316(a) made it “unlawful … for any corporation
whatever, or any labor organization, to make a contribution or
expenditure in connection with” certain federal elections. 2 U.
S. C. §441b(a) (2000 ed.). BCRA amends FECA §316(b)(2)’s
definition of the term “contribution or expenditure” to include
“any applicable electioneering communication.” 2 U.
S. C. A. §441b(b)(2) (Supp. 2003). Footnote
88 As Justice Kennedy emphasizes in
dissent, post , at 44–45, we assume that the interests that
justify the regulation of campaign speech might not apply to the
regulation of genuine issue ads. The premise that apparently
underlies Justice Kennedy’s principal submission is a conclusion
that the two categories of speech are nevertheless entitled to the
same constitutional protection. If that is correct, Justice Kennedy
must take issue with the basic holding in Buckley and,
indeed, with our recognition in First Nat. Bank of Boston v. Bellotti, 435 U. S. 765 (1978),
that unusually important interests underlie the regulation of
corporations’ campaign-related speech. In Bellotti we
cited Buckley , among other cases, for the proposition that
“[p]reserving the integrity of the electoral process, preventing
corruption, and ‘sustain[ing] the active, alert responsibility of
the individual citizen in a democracy for the wise conduct of the
government’ are interests of the highest importance.” 435 U. S., at
788–789 (citations and footnote omitted). “Preservation of the
individual citizen’s confidence in government,” we added, “is
equally important.” Id ., at 789. BCRA’s fidelity to those
imperatives sets it apart from the statute in Bellotti —and, for that matter, from the Ohio statute
banning the distribution of anonymous campaign literature, struck
down in McIntyre v. Ohio Elections
Comm’n, 514 U. S. 334 (1995). Footnote
89 In a different but somewhat
related argument, one set of plaintiffs contends that political
campaigns and issue advocacy involve press activities, and that
BCRA therefore interferes with speakers’ rights under the Freedom
of the Press Clause. U. S. Const., Amdt. 1. We affirm the District
Court’s conclusion that this contention lacks merit. Footnote
90 The statutory scheme is somewhat
complex. In its provision dealing with “Rules Relating to
Electioneering Communications,” BCRA §203(c)(2) (adding FECA
§316(c)(2)) makes a blanket exception for designated nonprofit
organizations, which reads as follows: “Exception “Notwithstanding paragraph (1),
the term ‘applicable electioneering communication’ does not include
a communication by a section 501(c)(4) organization or a political
organization (as defined in section 527(e)(1) of Title 26) made
under section 434(f)(2)(E) or (F) of this title if the
communication is paid for exclusively by funds provided directly by
individuals who are United States citizens or nationals or lawfully
admitted for permanent residence (as defined in section 1101(a)(20)
of Title 8). For purposes of the preceding sentence, the term
‘provided directly by individuals’ does not include funds the
source of which is an entity described in subsection (a) of this
section.” 2 U. S. C. A. §441b(c)(2) (Supp.
2003). BCRA §204, however, amends FECA
§316(c) to exclude “targeted communications” from that exception.
New FECA §316(c)(6) states that the §316(c)(2) exception “shall not
apply in the case of a targeted communication that is made by an
organization described” in §316(b)(2). 2 U. S. C. A. ¶
;441b(c)(6)(A). Subparagraph (B) then defines the term “targeted
communication” for the purpose of the provision as including all
electioneering communications. The parties and the judges on the
District Court have assumed that amended FECA §316(c)(6) completely
canceled the exemption for nonprofit corporations set forth in
§316(c)(2). 251 F. Supp. 2d, at 804 (Leon, J.) (“Section 204
completely cancels out the exemption for all nonprofit corporations
provided by Section 203”). Footnote
91 “[A] unanimous Court in National Right to Work did not think the regulatory
burdens on PACs, including restrictions on their ability to solicit
funds, rendered a PAC unconstitutional as an advocacy corporation’s
sole avenue for making political contributions. See 459 U. S., at
201–202. There is no reason to think the burden on advocacy
corporations is any greater today, or to reach a different
conclusion here.” Beaumont , 539 U. S., at ___ (slip op.,
at 16). Footnote
92 New FECA §304(g)
provides: “Time for reporting certain expenditures “(1) Expenditures aggregating
$1,000 “(A) Initial report “A person (including a political
committee) that makes or contracts to make independent expenditures
aggregating $1,000 or more after the 20th day, but more than 24
hours, before the date of an election shall file a report
describing the expenditures within 24 hours. “(B) Additional reports “After a person files a report
under subparagraph (A), the person shall file an additional report
within 24 hours after each time the person makes or contracts to
make independent expenditures aggregating an additional $1,000 with
respect to the same election as that to which the initial report
relates.” 2 U. S. C. A. §434 (Supp. 2003). Footnote
93 New FECA §315(d)(4) reads as
follows: “Independent versus coordinated
expenditures by party “(A) In general “On or after the date on which a
political party nominates a candidate, no committee of the
political party may make— “(i) any coordinated expenditure
under this subsection with respect to the candidate during the
election cycle at any time after it makes any independent
expenditure (as defined in section 431(17) of this title) with
respect to the candidate during the election cycle; or “(ii) any independent expenditure
(as defined in section 431(17) of this title) with respect to the
candidate during the election cycle at any time after it makes any
coordinated expenditure under this subsection with respect to the
candidate during the election cycle. “(B) Application “For purposes of this paragraph,
all political committees established and maintained by a national
political party (including all congressional campaign committees)
and all political committees established and maintained by a State
political party (including any subordinate committee of a State
committee) shall be considered to be a single political
committee. “(C) Transfers “A committee of a political party
that makes coordinated expenditures under this subsection with
respect to a candidate shall not, during an election cycle,
transfer any funds to, assign authority to make coordinated
expenditures under this subsection to, or receive a transfer of
funds from, a committee of the political party that has made or
intends to make an independent expenditure with respect to the
candidate.” 2 U. S. C. A. §441a(d)(4) (Supp.
2003). Footnote
94 After exempting political parties
from the general contribution and expenditure limitations of the
statute, 2 U. S. C. A. §441a(d)(1), FECA §315(d) imposes
the following substitute limitations on party spending: “(2) The national committee of a
political party may not make any expenditure in connection with the
general election campaign of any candidate for President of the
United States who is affiliated with such party which exceeds an
amount equal to 2 cents multiplied by the voting age population of
the United States (as certified under subsection (e) of this
section). Any expenditure under this paragraph shall be in addition
to any expenditure by a national committee of a political party
serving as the principal campaign committee of a candidate for
office of President of the United States. “(3) The national committee of a
political party, or a State committee of a political party,
including any subordinate committee of a State committee, may not
make any expenditure in connection with the general election
campaign of a candidate for Federal office in a State who is
affiliated with such party which exceeds— “(A) in the case of a candidate
for election to the office of Senator, or of Representative from a
State which is entitled to only one Representative, the greater
of— “(i) 2 cents multiplied by the
voting age population of the State (as certified under subsection
(e) of this section); or “(ii) $20,000; and “(B) in the case of a candidate
for election to the officer of Representative, Delegate, or
Resident Commissioner in any other State, $10,000.” 2 U. S. C.
§§441a(d)(2)–(3). Footnote
95 As amended by BCRA, §301(17)
provides: “Independent
expenditure “The term ‘independent
expenditure’ means an expenditure by a person— “(A) expressly advocating the
election or defeat of a clearly identified candidate;
and “(B) that is not made in concert
or cooperation with or at the request or suggestion of such
candidate, the candidate’s authorized political committee, or their
agents, or a political party committee or its agents.” 2 U.
S. C. A. §431(17) (Supp. 2003). The version of the definition
prior to its amendment by BCRA also included the phrase “expressly
advocating the election or defeat of a clearly identified
candidate.” 2 U. S. C. §431(17) (2000 ed.). That definition
had been adopted in 1976, presumably to reflect the narrowing
construction that the Court adopted in Buckley . Federal
Election Campaign Act Amendments of 1976, 90 Stat. 475. Footnote
96 Although the District Court and
all the parties to this litigation endorse the interpretation set
forth in the text, it is not clear that subparagraph (B) should be
read so broadly: The reference to “a State” instead of “the States”
suggests that Congress meant to distinguish between committees
associated with the party for each State (which would be grouped
together by State, with each grouping treated as a single committee
for purposes of the choice) and committees associated with a
national party (which would likewise be grouped together and
treated as a separate political committee). We need not resolve the
interpretive puzzle, however, because even under the more limited
reading a local party committee would be able to tie the hands of a
state committee or other local committees in the same
State. Footnote
97 The italicized portion of the
following partial quotation of FECA §315(a)(7) was added by §214 of
BCRA: “For purposes of this
subsection— “(A) contributions to a named
candidate made to any political committee authorized by such
candidate to accept contributions on his behalf shall be considered
to be contributions made to such candidate; “(B)(i) expenditures made by any
person in cooperation, consultation, or concert, with, or at the
request or suggestion of, a candidate, his authorized political
committees, or their agents, shall be considered to be a
contribution to such candidate; “(ii) expenditures made by any
person (other than a candidate or candidate’s authorized committee)
in cooperation, consultation, or concert with, or at the request or
suggestion of, a national, State, or local committee of a political
party, shall be considered to be contributions made to such party
committee … .” 2 U. S. C. A. §441a(a)(7) (Supp.
2003). Footnote
98 Pre-BCRA FEC regulations defined
coordinated expenditures to include expenditures made “[a]t the
request or suggestion of” a candidate or party; communications in
which a candidate or party “exercised control or decision-making
authority over the content, timing, location, mode, intended
audience, volume of distribution, or frequency of placement”; and
communications produced “[a]fter substantial discussion or
negotiation” with a party or candidate, “the result of which is
collaboration or agreement.” 11 CFR §100.23(c)(2)
(2001). Footnote
99 Contrary to plaintiffs’
contention, the statutory framework was not significantly different
at the time of our decision in Buckley . The relevant
provision, 18 U. S. C. §608(e)(1), treated as coordinated any
expenditures “authorized or requested by the candidate.”
(Emphasis added.) And the legislative history, on which we relied
for “guidance in differentiating individual expenditures that are
contributions … from those treated as independent expenditures,”
described as “independent” an expenditure made by a supporter
“ ‘completely on his own, and not at the request or suggestion
of the candidate or his agen[t].’ ” 424 U. S., at 46–47, n. 53
(quoting S. Rep. No. 93–689, p. 18 (1974)). OPINION OF THE COURT MCCONNELL V. FEDERAL ELECTION COMM'N 540 U. S. ____ (2003) SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES NOS. 02-1674, 02-1675, 02-1676, 02-1702, 02-1727, 02-1733,
02-1734;02-1740, 02-1747, 02-1753, 02-1755, AND
02-1756 MITCH McCONNELL, UNITED STATES SENATOR,
et al., APPELLANTS
02–1674 v .
FEDERAL ELECTION COMMISSION, et al.;
NATIONAL RIFLE ASSOCIATION, et al.,
APPELLANTS
02–1675 v .
FEDERAL ELECTION COMMISSION, et al.;
FEDERAL ELECTION COMMISSION, et al.,
APPELLANTS
02–1676 v .
MITCH McCONNELL, UNITED STATES SENATOR,
et al.;
JOHN McCAIN, UNITED STATES SENATOR, et al.,
APPELLANTS
02–1702 v .
MITCH McCONNELL, UNITED STATES SENATOR,
et al.;
REPUBLICAN NATIONAL COMMITTEE, et al.,
APPELLANTS
02–1727 v .
FEDERAL ELECTION COMMISSION, et al.;
NATIONAL RIGHT TO LIFE COMMITTEE, INC.,
et al., APPELLANTS
02–1733 v .
FEDERAL ELECTION COMMISSION, et al.;
AMERICAN CIVIL LIBERTIES UNION, APPELLANTS
02–1734 v .
FEDERAL ELECTION COMMISSION, et al.;
VICTORIA JACKSON GRAY ADAMS, et al.,
APPELLANTS
02–1740 v .
FEDERAL ELECTION COMMISSION, et al.;
RON PAUL, UNITED STATES CONGRESSMAN, et al.,
APPELLANTS
02–1747 v .
FEDERAL ELECTION COMMISSION, et al.;
CALIFORNIA DEMOCRATIC PARTY, et al.,
APPELLANTS
02–1753 v .
FEDERAL ELECTION COMMISSION, et al.;
AMERICAN FEDERATION OF LABOR AND CONGRESS OF
INDUSTRIAL ORGANIZATIONS, et al., APPELLANTS
02–1755 v .
FEDERAL ELECTION COMMISSION, et al.;
CHAMBER OF COMMERCE OF THE UNITED STATES,
et al., APPELLANTS
02–1756 v .
FEDERAL ELECTION COMMISSION, et al.
on appeals from the united states district court
for the district of columbia
[December 10, 2003]
Justice Breyer delivered the
opinion of the Court with respect to BCRA Title V.*
We consider here the
constitutionality of §504 of the Bipartisan Campaign Reform Act of
2002 (BCRA), amending the Communications Act of 1934. That section
requires broadcasters to keep publicly available records of
politically related broadcasting requests. 47 U. S. C. A.
§315(e) (Supp. 2003). The McConnell plaintiffs, who include the
National Association of Broadcasters, argue that §504 imposes
onerous administrative burdens, lacks any offsetting justification,
and consequently violates the First Amendment. For similar reasons,
the three judges on the District Court found BCRA §504
unconstitutional on its face. 251 F. Supp. 2d 176, 186 (DC
2003) (per curiam) (case below). We disagree, and we
reverse that determination.
I
BCRA §504’s key requirements are
the following:
(1) A “candidate request”
requirement calls for broadcasters to keep records of broadcast
requests “made by or on behalf of” any “legally qualified candidate
for public office.” 47 U. S. C. A. §315(e)(1)(A) (Supp.
2003).
(2) An “election message request” requirement
calls for broadcasters to keep records of requests (made by anyone)
to broadcast “message[s]” that refer either to a “legally qualified
candidate” or to “any election to Federal office.”
§§315(e)(1)(B)(i), (ii).
(3) An “issue request” requirement calls for
broadcasters to keep records of requests (made by anyone) to
broadcast “message[s]” related to a “national legislative issue of
public importance,” §315(e)(1)(B)(iii), or otherwise relating to a
“political matter of national importance,” §315(e)(1)(B).
We shall consider each provision in turn.
II
BCRA §504’s “candidate request”
requirements are virtually identical to those contained in a
regulation that the Federal Communications Commission (FCC)
promulgated as early as 1938 and which with slight modifications
the FCC has maintained in effect ever since. 47 CFR §73.1943
(2002); compare 3 Fed. Reg. 1692 (1938) (47 CFR §36a4); 13 Fed.
Reg. 7486 (1948) (47 CFR §§3.190(d), 3.290(d), 3.690(d)); 17 Fed.
Reg. 4711 (1952) (47 CFR §3.590(d)); 19 Fed. Reg. 5949 (1954); 23
Fed. Reg. 7817 (1958); 28 Fed. Reg. 13593 (1963) (47 CFR
§73.120(d)); 43 Fed. Reg. 32795 (1978) (47 CFR §73.1940(d)); 57
Fed. Reg. 210 (1992) (47 CFR §73.1943). See generally Brief in
Opposition to Motion of Appellee National Association of
Broadcasters for Summary Affirmance in No. 02–1676, pp. 9–10
(hereinafter Brief Opposing Summary Affirmance).
In its current form the FCC
regulation requires broadcast licensees to “keep” a publicly
available file “of all requests for broadcast time made by or on
behalf of a candidate for public office,” along with a notation
showing whether the request was granted, and (if granted) a history
that includes “classes of time,” “rates charged,” and when the
“spots actually aired.” 47 CFR §73.1943(a) (2002); §76.1701(a)
(same for cable systems). These regulation-imposed requirements
mirror the statutory requirements imposed by BCRA §504 with minor
differences which no one here challenges. Compare 47 CFR §73.1943
with 47 U. S. C. A. §315(e)(2) (see Appendix, infra ).
The McConnell plaintiffs argue that these
requirements are “intolerabl[y]” “burdensome and invasive.” Brief
for Appellants/Cross-Appellees Senator Mitch McConnell et al.
in No. 02–1674 et al., p. 74 (hereinafter Brief for McConnell
Plaintiffs). But we do not see how that could be so. The FCC has
consistently estimated that its “candidate request” regulation
imposes upon each licensee an additional administrative burden of
six to seven hours of work per year. See 66 Fed. Reg. 37468 (2001); id., at 18090; 63 Fed. Reg. 26593 (1998); id., at
10379; 57 Fed. Reg. 18492 (1992); see also 66 Fed. Reg. 29963
(2001) (total annual burden of one hour per cable system). That
burden means annual costs of a few hundred dollars at most, a
microscopic amount compared to the many millions of dollars of
revenue broadcasters receive from candidates who wish to
advertise.
Perhaps for this reason, broadcasters in the
past did not strongly oppose the regulation or its extension. Cf., e.g. , 17 Fed. Reg. 4711 (1952) (“No comments adverse to
the adoption of the proposed rule have been received”); 43 Fed.
Reg. 32794 (1978) (no adverse comments). Indeed in 1992, “CBS”
itself “suggest[ed]” that the candidate file “include a record of
all requests for time.” 57 Fed. Reg. 206 (1992); cf. 63 Fed. Reg.
49493 (1998) (FCC “not persuaded that the current retention period
[two years] is overly burdensome to licensees”).
In any event, as the FCC wrote in an analogous
context, broadcaster recordkeeping requirements “ ‘simply run
with the territory.’ ” 40 Fed. Reg. 18398 (1975). Broadcasters
must keep and make publicly available numerous records. See 47 CFR
§73.3526 (2002) (general description of select recordkeeping
requirements for commercial stations); see also §§73.1202,
73.3526(e)(9)(i) (retention of all “written comments and
suggestions [including letters and e-mail] received from the public
regarding operation of the station” for three years); §73.1212(e)
(sponsorship identification records, including the identification
of a sponsoring entity’s executive officers and board-level members
when sponsoring “political matter or matter involving the
discussion of a controversial issue of public importance”);
§73.1840 (retention of station logs); §73.1942 (candidate broadcast
records); §73.2080 (equal employment oppor- tunities records);
§§73.3526(e)(11)(i), (e)(12) (“list of programs that have provided
the station’s most significant treatment of community issues during
the preceding three month period,” including “brief narrative
describing [the issues, and] time, date, duration, and title”);
§§73.3526(e)(11)(ii), (iii) (reports of children’s program, and
retention of records sufficient to substantiate “compliance with
the commercial limits on children’s programming”); §73.3613(a)
(network affiliation contracts); §§73.3613(b), 73.3615,
73.3526(e)(5) (ownership-related reports); §73.3613(c)
(“[m]anagement consultant agreements”); §73.3613(d) (“[t]ime
brokerage agreements”). Compared to these longstanding
recordkeeping requirements, an additional six to seven hours is a
small drop in a very large bucket.
The McConnell plaintiffs also
claim that the “candidate requests” requirement fails significantly
to further any important governmental interest. Brief for McConnell
Plaintiffs 74. But, again, we cannot agree. The FCC has pointed out
that “[t]hese records are necessary to permit political candidates
and others to verify that licensees have complied with their
obligations relating to use of their facilities by candidates for
political office” pursuant to the “equal time” provision of 47 U.
S. C. §315(a). 63 Fed. Reg. 49493 (1998). They also help the
FCC determine whether broadcasters have violated their obligation
to sell candidates time at the “lowest unit charge.” 47 U.
S. C. §315(b). As reinforced by BCRA, the “candidate request”
requirements will help the FCC, the Federal Election Commission,
and “the public to evaluate whether broadcasters are processing
[candidate] requests in an evenhanded fashion,” Brief Opposing
Summary Affirmance 9, thereby helping to assure broadcasting
fairness. 47 U. S. C. §315(a); Red Lion Broadcasting
Co. v. FCC, 395 U. S. 367 , 390
(1969). They will help make the public aware of how much money
candidates may be prepared to spend on broadcast messages. 2 U.
S. C. A. §434 (main ed. and Supp. 2003); see ante , at 87–93 (joint opinion of Stevens and O’Connor,
JJ.) (hereinafter joint opinion). And they will provide an
independently compiled set of data for purposes of verifying
candidates’ compliance with the disclosure requirements and source
limitations of BCRA and the Federal Election Campaign Act of 1971.
2 U. S. C. A. §434; cf. Adventure Communications,
Inc. v. Kentucky Registry of Election Finance , 191
F. 3d 429, 433 (CA4 1999) (candidate compliance verification);
63 Fed. Reg. 49493 (1998) (FCC finding record retention provision
provides public with “necessary and adequate
access”).
We note, too, that the FCC’s
regulatory authority is broad. Red Lion , supra ,
at 380 (“broad” mandate to assure broadcasters operate in public
interest); National Broadcasting Co. v. United
States, 319 U. S. 190 , 219
(1943) (same). And we have previously found broad governmental
authority for agency information demands from regulated entities.
Compare United States v. Morton Salt
Co., 338
U. S. 632 , 642–643 (1950); Oklahoma Press Publishing
Co. v. Walling, 327 U. S. 186 , 209
(1946); Donovan v. Lone Steer,
Inc., 464
U. S. 408 , 414–415 (1984).
The Chief Justice suggests that the Government
has not made these particular claims. But it has—though
succinctly—for it has cross-referenced the relevant regulatory
rules. Compare post , at 12–13 (opinion of Rehnquist, C.
J.), with Brief Opposing Summary Affirmance; Brief for McConnell
Plaintiffs 73–74; Brief for FEC et al. in No. 02–1674
et al., pp. 132–133. And succinctness through cross-reference
was necessary given our procedural requirement that the Government
set forth in a 140-page brief all its arguments concerning
each of the 20 BCRA provisions here under contest. 251
F. Supp. 2d, at 186–188.
In sum, given the Government’s reference to
the 65-year-old FCC regulation and the related considerations we
have mentioned, we cannot accept the argument that the
constitutionality of the “candidate request” provision lacks
evidentiary support. The challengers have made no attempt to
explain away the FCC’s own contrary conclusions and the mass of
evidence in related FCC records and proceedings. E.g. , 57
Fed. Reg. 189 (1992); cf. s upra , at 4–5; ante , at
117–118 (joint opinion) (upholding BCRA’s coordination provision
based, in part, on prior experience under similar provision).
Because we cannot, on the present record, find the longstanding FCC
regulation unconstitutional, we likewise cannot strike down the
“candidate request” provision in BCRA §504; for the latter simply
embodies the regulation in a statute, thereby blocking any agency
attempt to repeal it.
III
BCRA §504’s “election message
request” requirements call for broadcasters to keep records of
requests (made by any member of the public) to broadcast a
“message” about “a legally qualified candidate” or “any election to
Federal office.” 47 U. S. C. A. §§315(e)(1)(B)(i), (ii)
(Supp. 2003). Although these requirements are somewhat broader than
the “candidate request” requirement, they serve much the same
purposes. A candidate’s supporters or opponents account for many of
the requests to broadcast “message[s]” about a “candidate.”
Requests to broadcast messages about an “election” may include
messages that favor one candidate or another, along with other
messages that may be more neutral.
Given the nature of many of the
messages, recordkeeping can help both the regulatory agencies and
the public evaluate broadcasting fairness, and determine the amount
of money that individuals or groups, supporters or opponents,
intend to spend to help elect a particular candidate. Cf. ante , at 100–101 (joint opinion) (upholding stringent
restrictions on all election-time advertising that refers
to a candidate because such advertising will often convey
message of support or opposition). Insofar as the request is to
broadcast neutral material about a candidate or election, the
disclosure can help the FCC carry out other statutory functions,
for example, determining whether a broadcasting station is
fulfilling its licensing obligation to broadcast material important
to the community and the public. 47 U. S. C. §315(a)
(“obligation … to afford reasonable opportunity for the discussion
of conflicting views on issues of public importance”); 47 CFR
§73.1910 (2002); §§73.3526(e)(11)(i), (e)(12) (recordkeeping
requirements for issues important to the community).
For reasons previously discussed, supra , at 4–5, and on the basis of the material presented,
we cannot say that these requirements will impose disproportionate
administrative burdens. They ask the broadcaster to keep
information about the disposition of the request, and information
identifying the individual or company requesting the broadcast time
(name, address, contact information, or, if the requester is not an
individual, the names of company officials). 47 U.
S. C. A. §315(e)(2) (Supp. 2003). Insofar as the
“request” is made by a candidate’s “supporters,” the “candidate
request” regulation apparently already requires broadcasters to
keep such records. 43 Fed. Reg. 32794 (1978). Regardless, the
information should prove readily available, for the individual
requesting a broadcast must provide it to the broadcaster should
the broadcaster accept the request. 47 CFR §73.1212(e) (2002). And
as we have previously pointed out, the recordkeeping requirements
do not reach significantly beyond other FCC recordkeeping rules,
for example, those requiring broadcasting licensees to keep
material showing com- pliance with their license-related promises
to broad- cast material on issues of public importance. See, e.g. , §§73.3526(e)(11)(i), (e)(12) (recordkeeping
requirements for issues important to the community); supra , at 4–5 (collecting regulations); Office of
Communication of United Church of Christ v. FCC , 707
F. 2d 1413, 1421–1422 (CADC 1983) (describing FCC rules, in
force during 1960–1981, that required nonentertainment programming
in 14 specific areas and mandated publicly available records
detailing date, time, source, and description to substantiate
compliance). If, as we have held, the “candidate request”
requirements are constitutional, supra , at 7, the
“election message” requirements, which serve similar governmental
interests and impose only a small incremental burden, must be
constitutional as well.
IV
The “issue request” requirements
call for broadcasters to keep records of requests (made by any
member of the public) to broadcast “message[s]” about “a national
legislative issue of public importance” or “any political matter of
national importance.” 47 U. S. C. A. §§315(e)(1)(B),
(e)(1)(B)(iii) (Supp. 2003). These recordkeeping requirements seem
likely to help the FCC determine whether broadcasters are carrying
out their “obligations to afford reasonable opportunity for the
discussion of conflicting views on issues of public importance,” 47
CFR §73.1910 (2002), and whether broadcasters are too heavily
favoring entertainment, and discriminating against broadcasts
devoted to public affairs, see ibid.; 47 U. S. C
§315(a); Red Lion , 395 U. S., at 380.
The McConnell plaintiffs claim
that the statutory language—“political matter of national
importance” or “national legislative issue of public importance”—is
unconstitutionally vague or overbroad. Brief for McConnell
Plaintiffs 74–75. But that language is no more general than the
language that Congress has used to impose other obligations upon
broadcasters. Compare 47 U. S. C. A. §315(e)(1)(B) (Supp.
2003) (“political matter of national importance”) and
§315(e)(1)(B)(iii) (“national legislative issue of public
importance”) (both added by BCRA §504), with 47 U. S. C.
§315(a) (“obligation … to operate in the public interest” and to
afford reasonable opportunity for discussion of “issues of public
importance”); §317(a)(2) (FCC disclosure requirements relating to
any “political program” or “discussion of any controversial
issue”); cf. 47 CFR §73.1212(e) (2002) (“political matter or … a
controversial issue of public importance”); and 9 Fed. Reg. 14734
(1944) (“public controversial issues”); ante , at 117–118
(joint opinion) (noting that the experience under longstanding
regulations undermines claims of chilling effect). And that
language is also roughly comparable to other language in BCRA that
we uphold today. E.g. , ante , at 61–62, and
n. 64 (joint opinion) (upholding 2 U. S. C. A.
§431(20)(A)(iii) (Supp. 2003) (“public communication that refers to
a clearly identified candidate for Federal office … and that
promotes or supports a candidate for that office, or attacks or
opposes a candidate for that office”)), ante, at 117–118
(upholding 2 U. S. C. A. §441a(a)(7)(B)(ii) (Supp. 2003)
(counting as coordinated disbursements that are made “in
cooperation, consultation, or concert with, or at the request or
suggestion of [a political party]”) against challenge and noting
that an “agreement” is not necessary for precision).
Whether these requirements impose
disproportionate administrative burdens is more difficult to say.
On the one hand, the burdens are likely less heavy than many that
other FCC regulations have imposed, for example, the burden of
keeping and disclosing “[a]ll written comments and suggestions”
received from the public, including every e-mail. 47 CFR §§73.1202,
73.3526(e)(9) (2002); see also supra , at 4–5. On the other
hand, the burdens are likely heavier than those imposed by BCRA
§504’s other provisions, previously discussed.
The regulatory burden, in practice, will
depend on how the FCC interprets and applies this provision. The
FCC has adequate legal authority to write regulations that may
limit, and make more specific, the provision’s potential linguistic
reach. 47 U. S. C. §315(d). It has often ameliorated
regulatory burdens by interpretation in the past, and there is no
reason to believe it will not do so here. See 14 FCC Rcd. 4653, ¶
;25 (1999) (relaxing the recordkeeping requirements in respect to
cable systems that serve fewer than 5,000 subscribers); 14 FCC Rcd.
11121, ¶ ;¶ ;20–22 (1999) (requiring candidates to inspect the
political file at a station rather than requiring licensees to send
out photocopies of the files to candidates upon telephone request).
The parties remain free to challenge the provisions, as interpreted
by the FCC in regulations, or as otherwise applied. Any such
challenge will likely provide greater information about the
provisions’ justifications and administrative burdens. Without that
additional information, we cannot now say that the burdens are so
great, or the justifications so minimal, as to warrant finding the
provisions unconstitutional on their face.
The McConnell plaintiffs and The Chief Justice
make one final claim. They say that the “issue request” requirement
will force them to disclose information that will reveal their
political strategies to opponents, perhaps prior to a broadcast.
See post , at 14–15 (dissenting opinion). We are willing to
assume that the Constitution includes some form of protection
against premature disclosure of campaign strategy—though, given the
First Amendment interest in free and open discussion of campaign
issues, we make this assumption purely for argument’s sake.
Nonetheless, even on that assumption we do not see how BCRA §504
can be unconstitutional on its face.
For one thing, the statute requires disclosure
of names, addresses, and the fact of a request; it does not require
disclosure of substantive campaign content. See 47 U.
S. C. A. §315(e)(2) (Supp. 2003). For another, the
statutory words “as soon as possible,” §315(e)(3), would seem to
permit FCC disclosure-timing rules that would avoid any premature
disclosure that the Constitution itself would forbid. Further, the
plaintiffs do not point to—and our own research cannot find—any
specific indication of such a “strategy-disclosure” problem arising
during the past 65 years in respect to the existing FCC “candidate
request” requirement, where the strategic problem might be expected
to be more acute. Finally, we today reject an analogous facial
attack—premised on speculations of “advance disclosure”—on a
similar BCRA provision. See ante , at 94 (joint opinion).
Thus, the “strategy disclosure” argument does not show that BCRA
§504 is unconstitutional on its face, but the plaintiffs remain
free to raise this argument when §504 is applied.
V
The Chief Justice makes two
important arguments in response to those we have set forth. First,
he says that we “approac[h] §504 almost exclusively from the
perspective of the broadcast licensees, ignoring the interests of
candidates and other purchasers, whose speech and association
rights are affected.” Post , at 11 (dissenting opinion).
The Chief Justice is certainly correct in emphasizing the
importance of the speech interests of candidates and other
potential speakers, but we have not ignored their First Amendment
“perspective.”
To the contrary, we have
discussed the speakers’ interests together with the broadcasters’
interests because the two sets of interests substantially overlap.
For example, the speakers’ vagueness argument is no different from
the broadcasters’, and it fails for the same reasons, e.g. , the fact that BCRA §504’s language is just as
definite and precise as other language that we today uphold. See supra , at 10.
We have separately discussed the one and
only speech-related claim advanced on behalf of candidates (or
other speakers) that differs from the claims set forth by the
broadcasters. See supra , at 11–12. This is the claim that
the statute’s disclosure requirements will require candidates to
reveal their political strategies to opponents. We just said, and
we now repeat, that BCRA §504 can be applied, in a significant
number of cases, without requiring any such political-strategy
disclosure—either because disclosure in many cases will not create
any such risk or because the FCC may promulgate rules requiring
disclosure only after any such risk disappears, or both.
Moreover, candidates (or other speakers) whom
§504 affects adversely in this way (or in other ways) remain free
to challenge the lawfulness of FCC implementing regulations and to
challenge the constitutionality of §504 as applied. To find that
the speech-related interests of candidates and others may be
vindicated in an as-applied challenge is not to “ignor[e]” those
interests.
Second, The Chief Justice says that “the
Government, in its brief, proffers no interest whatever to support
§504 as a whole,” adding that the existence of “pre-existing
unchallenged agency regulations imposing similar disclosure
requirements” cannot “compel the conclusion that §504 is
constitutional,” nor somehow “relieve the Government of its burden
of advancing a constitutionally sufficient justification for §504.” Post , at 12–13 (dissenting opinion).
Again The Chief Justice is correct in saying
that the mere existence of similar FCC regulation-imposed
requirements—even if unchallenged for at least 65 years—cannot
prove that those requirements are constitutional. But the existence
of those regulations means that we must read beyond the briefs in
this case before holding those requirements unconstitutional.
Before evaluating the relevant burdens and justifications, we must
at least become acquainted with the FCC’s own view of the matter.
We must follow the Government’s regulation-related references to
the relevant regulatory records, related FCC regulatory
conclusions, and the FCC’s enforcement experience. We must take
into account, for example, the likelihood that the reason there is “nothing in the record that indicates licensees have
treated purchasers unfairly,” post , at 13 (Rehnquist,
C. J., dissenting), is that for many decades similar FCC
regulations have made that unfair treatment unlawful. And, if we
are to avoid disrupting related agency law, we must evaluate what
we find in agency records and related experience before holding
this similar statutory provision unconstitutional on its face.
Even a superficial examination of
those relevant agency materials reveals strong supporting
justifications, and a lack of significant administrative burdens.
And any additional burden that the statute, viewed facially,
imposes upon interests protected by the First Amendment seems
slight compared to the strong enforcement-related interests that it
serves. Given the FCC regulations and their history, the statutory
requirements must survive a facial attack under any
potentially applicable First Amendment standard, including that of
heightened scrutiny.
That is why the regulations are relevant. That
is why the brevity of the Government’s discussion here cannot be
determinative. That is why we fear that The Chief Justice’s
contrary view would lead us into an unfortunate—and at present
unjustified—revolution in communications law. And that is why we
disagree with his dissent.
The portion of the judgment of the District
Court invalidating BCRA §504 is reversed.
It is so ordered.
APPENDIX TO OPINION OF THE COURT
Title 47 U. S. C. A.
§315(e) (Supp. 2003), as amended by BCRA §504, provides:
“Political record
“(1) In general
“A licensee shall maintain, and make available
for public inspection, a complete record of a request to purchase
broadcast time that—
“(A) is made by or on behalf of a legally
qualified candidate for public office; or
“(B) communicates a message relating to any
political matter of national importance, including—
“(i) a legally qualified candidate;
“(ii) any election to Federal office; or
“(iii) a national legislative issue of public
importance.
“(2) Contents of record
“A record maintained under paragraph (1) shall
contain information regarding—
“(A) whether the request to purchase broadcast
time is accepted or rejected by the licensee;
“(B) the rate charged for the broadcast
time;
“(C) the date and time on which the
communication is aired;
“(D) the class of time that is purchased;
“(E) the name of the candidate to which the
communication refers and the office to which the candidate is
seeking election, the election to which the communication refers,
or the issue to which the communication refers (as applicable);
“(F) in the case of a request made by, or on
behalf of, a candidate, the name of the candidate, the authorized
committee of the candidate, and the treasurer of such committee;
and
“(G) in the case of any other request, the
name of the person purchasing the time, the name, address, and
phone number of a contact person for such person, and a list of the
chief executive officers or members of the executive committee or
of the board of directors of such person.
“(3) Time to maintain file
“The information required under this
subsection shall be placed in a political file as soon as possible
and shall be retained by the licensee for a period of not less than
2 years.”
Title 47 CFR §73.1943 (2002) provides:
“Political file.
“(a) Every licensee shall keep and permit
public inspection of a complete and orderly record (political file)
of all requests for broadcast time made by or on behalf of a
candidate for public office, together with an appropriate notation
showing the disposition made by the licensee of such requests, and
the charges made, if any, if the request is granted. The
‘disposition’ includes the schedule of time purchased, when spots
actually aired, the rates charged, and the classes of time
purchased.
“(b) When free time is provided for use by or
on behalf of candidates, a record of the free time provided shall
be placed in the political file.
“(c) All records required by this paragraph
shall be placed in the political file as soon as possible and shall
be retained for a period of two years. As soon as possible means
immediately absent unusual circumstances.”
*Justice Stevens, Justice O’Connor, Justice Souter,
and Justice Ginsburg join this opinion in its entirety. REHNQUIST, C. J., DISSENTING MCCONNELL V. FEDERAL ELECTION COMM'N 540 U. S. ____ (2003) SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES NOS. 02-1674, 02-1675, 02-1676, 02-1702, 02-1727, 02-1733,
02-1734;02-1740, 02-1747, 02-1753, 02-1755, AND
02-1756 MITCH McCONNELL, UNITED STATES SENATOR,
et al., APPELLANTS
02–1674 v .
FEDERAL ELECTION COMMISSION, et al.;
NATIONAL RIFLE ASSOCIATION, et al.,
APPELLANTS
02–1675 v .
FEDERAL ELECTION COMMISSION, et al.;
FEDERAL ELECTION COMMISSION, et al.,
APPELLANTS
02–1676 v .
MITCH McCONNELL, UNITED STATES SENATOR,
et al.;
JOHN McCAIN, UNITED STATES SENATOR, et al.,
APPELLANTS
02–1702 v .
MITCH McCONNELL, UNITED STATES SENATOR,
et al.;
REPUBLICAN NATIONAL COMMITTEE, et al.,
APPELLANTS
02–1727 v .
FEDERAL ELECTION COMMISSION, et al.;
NATIONAL RIGHT TO LIFE COMMITTEE, INC.,
et al., APPELLANTS
02–1733 v .
FEDERAL ELECTION COMMISSION, et al.;
AMERICAN CIVIL LIBERTIES UNION, APPELLANTS
02–1734 v .
FEDERAL ELECTION COMMISSION, et al.;
VICTORIA JACKSON GRAY ADAMS, et al.,
APPELLANTS
02–1740 v .
FEDERAL ELECTION COMMISSION, et al.;
RON PAUL, UNITED STATES CONGRESSMAN, et al.,
APPELLANTS
02–1747 v .
FEDERAL ELECTION COMMISSION, et al.;
CALIFORNIA DEMOCRATIC PARTY, et al.,
APPELLANTS
02–1753 v .
FEDERAL ELECTION COMMISSION, et al.;
AMERICAN FEDERATION OF LABOR AND CONGRESS OF
INDUSTRIAL ORGANIZATIONS, et al., APPELLANTS
02–1755 v .
FEDERAL ELECTION COMMISSION, et al.;
CHAMBER OF COMMERCE OF THE UNITED STATES,
et al., APPELLANTS
02–1756 v .
FEDERAL ELECTION COMMISSION, et al.
on appeals from the united states district court
for the district of columbia
[December 10, 2003]
Chief Justice Rehnquist,
dissenting with respect to BCRA Titles I and V.*
Although I join Justice Kennedy’s
opinion in full, I write separately to highlight my disagreement
with the Court on Title I of the Bipartisan Campaign Reform Act of
2002 (BCRA), 116 Stat. 81, and to dissent from the Court’s opinion
upholding §504 of Title V.
I
The issue presented by Title I is
not, as the Court implies, whether Congress can permissibly
regulate campaign contributions to candidates, de facto or
otherwise, or seek to eliminate corruption in the political
process. Rather, the issue is whether Congress can permissibly
regulate much speech that has no plausible connection to candidate
contributions or corruption to achieve those goals. Under our
precedent, restrictions on political contributions implicate
important First Amendment values and are constitutional only if
they are “closely drawn” to reduce the corruption of federal
candidates or the appearance of corruption. Buckley v. Valeo, 424 U. S. 1 , 26– 27 (1976) (per curiam). Yet, the Court glosses over the breadth of
the restrictions, characterizing Title I of BCRA as “do[ing] little
more that regulat[ing] the ability of wealthy individuals,
corporations, and unions to contribute large sums of money to
influence federal elections, federal candidates, and federal
officeholders.” Ante , at 28 (joint opinion of Stevens and
O’Connor, JJ.). Because, in reality, Title I is much broader than
the Court allows, regulating a good deal of speech that does not have the potential to corrupt federal candidates and
officeholders, I dissent.
The lynchpin of Title I, new FECA
§323(a), prohibits national political party committees from
“solicit[ing],” “receiv[ing],” “direct[ing] to another person,” and
“spend[ing]” any funds not subject to federal regulation,
even if those funds are used for nonelection related activities. 2
U. S. C. A. §441i(a)(1) (Supp. 2003). The Court concludes
that such a restriction is justified because under FECA, “donors
have been free to contribute substantial sums of soft money to the
national parties, which the parties can spend for the specific
purpose of influencing a particular candidate’s federal election.” Ante , at 36. Accordingly, “[i]t is not only plausible, but
likely, that candidates would feel grateful for such donations and
that donors would seek to exploit that gratitude.” Ibid .
But the Court misses the point. Certainly “infusions of money into
[candidates’] campaigns,” Federal Election Comm’n v. National Conservative Political Action
Comm., 470
U. S. 480 , 497 (1985), can be regulated, but §323(a) does not
regulate only donations given to influence a particular federal
election; it regulates all donations to national political
committees, no matter the use to which the funds are put.
The Court attempts to sidestep the
unprecedented breadth of this regulation by stating that the “close
relationship between federal officeholders and the national
parties” makes all donations to the national parties “suspect.” Ante, at 45. But a close association with others,
especially in the realm of political speech, is not a surrogate for
corruption; it is one of our most treasured First Amendment rights.
See California Democratic Party v. Jones, 530 U. S. 567 , 574
(2000); Eu v. San Francisco County Democratic Central
Comm., 489
U. S. 214 , 225 (1989); Tashjian v. Republican
Party of Conn., 479 U. S. 208 , 214
(1986). The Court’s willingness to impute corruption on the basis
of a relationship greatly infringes associational rights and
expands Congress’ ability to regulate political speech. And there
is nothing in the Court’s analysis that limits congressional
regulation to national political parties. In fact, the Court relies
in part on this closeness rationale to regulate nonprofit
organizations . Ante , at 47–48, n. 51. Who knows
what association will be deemed too close to federal officeholders
next. When a donation to an organization has no potential to
corrupt a federal officeholder, the relationship between the
officeholder and the organization is simply irrelevant.
The Court fails to recognize that the national
political parties are exemplars of political speech at all levels
of government, in addition to effective fundraisers for federal
candidates and officeholders. For sure, national political party
committees exist in large part to elect federal candidates, but as
a majority of the District Court found, they also promote
coordinated political messages and participate in public policy
debates unrelated to federal elections, promote, even in off-year
elections, state and local candidates and seek to influence policy
at those levels, and increase public participation in the electoral
process. See 251 F. Supp. 2d 176, 334–337 (DC 2003) (per
curiam) (Henderson, J., concurring in judgment in part and
dissenting in part); id. , at 820–821 (Leon, J.). Indeed,
some national political parties exist primarily for the purpose of
expressing ideas and generating debate. App. 185–186 (declaration
of Stephen L. Dasbach et al. ¶ ;11 (describing Libertarian
Party)).
As these activities illustrate, political
parties often foster speech crucial to a healthy democracy, 251
F. Supp. 2d, at 820 (Leon, J.), and fulfill the need for
like-minded individuals to ban together and promote a political
philosophy, see Jones, supra , at 574; Eu , supra , at 225. When political parties engage
in pure political speech that has little or no potential to corrupt
their federal candidates and officeholders, the government cannot
constitutionally burden their speech any more than it could burden
the speech of individuals engaging in these same activities. E.g. , National Conservative Political Action
Comm., supra , at 496–497; Citizens Against Rent
Control/Coalition for Fair Housing v. Berkeley, 454 U. S. 290 , 297–298
(1981); Buckley , 424 U. S., at 27. Notwithstanding the
Court’s citation to the numerous abuses of FECA, under any
definition of “exacting scrutiny,” the means chosen by Congress,
restricting all donations to national parties no matter the purpose
for which they are given or are used, are not “closely drawn to
avoid unnecessary abridgment of associational freedoms,” id. , at 25.
BCRA’s overinclusiveness is not limited to
national political parties. To prevent the circumvention of the ban
on the national parties’ use of nonfederal funds, BCRA extensively
regulates state parties, primarily state elections, and state
candidates. For example, new FECA §323(b), by reference to new FECA
§§301(20)(A)(i)–(ii), prohibits state parties from using nonfederal
funds[ Footnote 1 ] for general
partybuilding activities such as voter registration, voter
identification, and get out the vote for state candidates even if
federal candidates are not mentioned. See 2 U. S. C. A.
§§441i(b), 431(20)(A)(i)–(ii) (Supp. 2003). New FECA §323(d)
prohibits state and local political party committees, like their
national counterparts, from soliciting and donating “any funds” to
nonprofit organizations such as the National Rifle Association or
the National Association for the Advancement of Colored People
(NAACP). See 2 U. S. C. A. §441i(d). And, new FECA
§323(f) requires a state gubernatorial candidate to abide by
federal funding restrictions when airing a television ad that tells
voters that, if elected, he would oppose the President’s policy of
increased oil and gas exploration within the State because it would
harm the environment. See 2 U. S. C. A. §§441i(f),
431(20)(A)(iii) (regulating “public communication[s] that refe[r]
to a clearly identified candidate for Federal office (regardless of
whether a candidate for State or local office is also mentioned or
identified) and that … attacks or opposes a candidate for that
office”).
Although these provisions are more focused on
activities that may affect federal elections, there is
scant evidence in the record to indicate that federal candidates or
officeholders are corrupted or would appear corrupted by donations
for these activities. See 251 F. Supp. 2d, at 403, 407, 416,
422 (Henderson, J., concurring in judgment in part and dissenting
in part); id. , at 779–780, 791 (Leon, J.); see also Colorado Republican Federal Campaign Comm. v. Federal
Election Comm’n, 518 U. S. 604 , 616
(1996) (plurality opinion) (noting that “the opportunity for
corruption posed by [nonfederal contributions for state elections,
get-out-the-vote, and voter registration activities] is, at best,
attenuated”). Nonetheless, the Court concludes that because these
activities benefit federal candidates and officeholders,
see ante , at 59 or prevent the circumvention of
pre-existing or contemporaneously enacted restrictions,[ Footnote 2 ] see ante , at 57,
67, 71, 78, it must defer to the “ ‘predictive judgments of
Congress,’ ” ante , at 57 (quoting Turner
Broadcasting System, Inc. v. FCC, 512 U. S. 622 , 665
(1994)).
Yet the Court cannot truly mean what it says.
Newspaper editorials and political talk shows benefit federal candidates and officeholders every bit as much as a generic
voter registration drive conducted by a state party; there is
little doubt that the endorsement of a major newspaper affects federal elections, and federal candidates and
officeholders are surely “grateful,” ante , at 60, for
positive media coverage. I doubt, however, the Court would
seriously contend that we must defer to Congress’ judgment if it
chose to reduce the influence of political endorsements in federal
elections.[ Footnote 3 ] See Miami Herald Publishing Co. v. Tornillo, 418 U. S. 241 , 247, 250
(1974) (holding unconstitutional a state law that required
newspapers to provide “right to reply” to any candidate who was
personally or professionally assailed in order to eliminate the
“abuses of bias and manipulative reportage” by the press).
It is also true that any circumvention
rationale ultimately must rest on the circumvention itself leading
to the corruption of federal candidates and officeholders. See Buckley, 424 U. S., at 38 (upholding restrictions on funds
donated to national political parties “for the purpose of
influencing any election for a Federal office” because they were
prophylactic measures designed “to prevent evasion” of the
contribution limit on candidates ). All political speech
that is not sifted through federal regulation circumvents the
regulatory scheme to some degree or another, and thus by the
Court’s standard would be a “loophole” in the current
system.[ Footnote 4 ] Unless the
Court would uphold federal regulation of all funding of political
speech, a rationale dependent on circumvention alone will not do.
By untethering its inquiry from corruption or the appearance of
corruption, the Court has removed the touchstone of our campaign
finance precedent and has failed to replace it with any logical
limiting principle.
But such an untethering is necessary to the
Court’s analysis. Only by using amorphous language to conclude a
federal interest, however vaguely defined, exists can the Court
avoid the obvious fact that new FECA §§323(a), (b), (d), and
(f ) are vastly overinclusive. Any campaign finance law aimed
at reducing corruption will almost surely affect federal elections
or prohibit the circumvention of federal law, and if broad enough,
most laws will generally reduce some appearance of corruption.
Indeed, it is precisely because broad laws are likely to nominally
further a legitimate interest that we require Congress to tailor
its restrictions; requiring all federal candidates to self-finance
their campaigns would surely reduce the appearance of donor
corruption, but it would hardly be constitutional. In allowing
Congress to rely on general principles such as affecting a federal
election or prohibiting the circumvention of existing law, the
Court all but eliminates the “closely drawn” tailoring requirement
and meaningful judicial review.
No doubt Congress was convinced by the many
abuses of the current system that something in this area must be
done. Its response, however, was too blunt. Many of the abuses
described by the Court involve donations that were made for the
“purpose of influencing a federal election,” and thus are already
regulated. See Buckley , supra . Congress could
have sought to have the existing restrictions enforced or to enact
other restrictions that are “closely drawn” to its legitimate
concerns. But it should not be able to broadly restrict political
speech in the fashion it has chosen. Today’s decision, by not
requiring tailored restrictions, has significantly reduced the
protection for political speech having little or nothing to do with
corruption or the appearance of corruption.
II
BCRA §504 amends §315 of the
Communications Act to require broadcast licensees to maintain and
disclose records of any request to purchase broadcast time
that “is made by or on behalf of a legally qualified candidate for
public office” or that “communicates a message relating to any
political matter of national importance,” including communications
relating to “a legally qualified candidate,” “any election to
Federal office,” and “a national legislative issue of public
importance.” BCRA §504; 47 U. S. C. A. §315(e)(1) (Supp.
2003).[ Footnote 5 ] This section
differs from other BCRA disclosure sections because it requires broadcast licensees to disclose requests to
purchase broadcast time rather than requiring purchasers to disclose their disbursements for broadcast time. See, e.g. , BCRA §201. The Court concludes that §504 “must
survive a facial attack under any potentially applicable
First Amendment standard, including that of heightened scrutiny.” Ante , at 15 (opinion of Breyer, J.). I disagree.
This section is deficient because
of the absence of a sufficient governmental interest to justify
disclosure of mere requests to purchase broadcast time, as well as
purchases themselves. The Court approaches §504 almost exclusively
from the perspective of the broadcast licensees, ignoring the
interests of candidates and other purchasers, whose speech and
association rights are affected by §504. See, e.g. , ante, at 5 (noting that broadcasters are subject to
numerous recordkeeping requirements); ante , at 7 (opining
that this Court has recognized “broad governmental authority for
agency information demands from regulated entities”); ante , at 8–9 (“[W]e cannot say that these requirements
will impose disproportionate administrative burdens”). An approach
that simply focuses on whether the administrative burden is
justifiable is untenable. Because §504 impinges on core First
Amendment rights, it is subject to a more demanding test than mere
rational-basis review. The Court applies the latter by asking
essentially whether there is any conceivable reason to support
§504. See ante , at 8 (discussing the ways in which the
disclosure “can help” the FCC and the public); ante , at 10
(noting that the “recordkeeping requirements seem likely to help
the FCC” enforce the fairness doctrine).
Required disclosure provisions that deter
constitutionally protected association and speech rights are
subject to heightened scrutiny. See Buckley , 424 U. S., at
64. When applying heightened scrutiny, we first ask whether the
Government has asserted an interest sufficient to justify the
disclosure of requests to purchase broadcast time. Ibid.; see ante , at 89 (joint opinion of Stevens and O’Connor,
JJ.) (concluding that the important state interests the Buckley Court held justified FECA’s disclosure
requirements apply to BCRA §201’s disclosure requirement). But the
Government, in its brief, proffers no interest whatever to support
§504 as a whole.
Contrary to the Court’s suggestion, ante , at 7 (opinion of Breyer, J.), the Government’s brief
does not succinctly present interests sufficient to support §504.
The two paragraphs that the Court relies on provide the
following:
“As explained in the government’s
brief in opposition to the motion for summary affirmance on this
issue filed by plaintiff National Association of Broadcasters
(NAB), longstanding FCC regulations impose disclosure requirements
with respect to the sponsorship of broadcast matter ‘involving the
discussion of a controversial issue of public importance.’ 47
C. F. R. 73.1212(d) and (e) (2002); see 47
C. F. R. 76.1701(d) (2002) (same standard used in
disclosure regulation governing cablecasting). By enabling viewers
and listeners to identify the persons actually responsible for
communications aimed at a mass audience, those regulations assist
the public in evaluating the message transmitted. See Bellotti , 435 U.S. at 792 n. 32 (‘Identification of
the source of advertising may be required … so that the people will
be able to evaluate the arguments to which they are being
subjected.’).
“The range of information required to be
disclosed under BCRA §504 is comparable to the disclosures mandated
by pre-existing FCC rules. Compare 47 U. S. C. 315(e)(2)(G)
(added by BCRA §504), with 47 C. F. R. 73.1212(e) and
76.1701(d) (2002). Plaintiffs do not attempt to show that BCRA
§504’s requirements are more onerous than the FCC’s longstanding
rules, nor do they contend that the pre-existing agency regulations
are themselves unconstitutional. See generally 02–1676 Gov’t Br. in
Opp. to Mot. of NAB for Summ. Aff. 4–9. Because BCRA §504 is
essentially a codification of established and unchallenged
regulatory requirements, plaintiffs’ First Amendment claim should
be rejected.” Brief for FEC et al. in No. 02–1674 et al.,
pp. 132–133; ante, at 7.
While these paragraphs attempt to set forth a
justification for the new Communications Act §315(e)(1)(B),
discussed below, I fail to see any justification for BCRA §504 in
its entirety. Nor do I find persuasive the Court’s and the
Government’s argument that pre-existing unchallenged agency
regulations imposing similar disclosure requirements compel the
conclusion that §504 is constitutional and somehow relieve the
Government of its burden of advancing a constitutionally sufficient
justification for §504.
At oral argument, the Government counsel
indicated that one of the interests supporting §504 in its entirety
stems from the fairness doctrine, Tr. of Oral Arg. 192, which in
general imposes an obligation on licensees to devote a “reasonable
percentage” of broadcast time to issues of public importance in a
way that reflects opposing views. See Red Lion Broadcasting
Co. v. FCC, 395 U. S. 367 (1969).
Assuming, arguendo , this latter-day assertion should be
considered, I think the District Court correctly noted that there
is nothing in the record that indicates licensees have treated
purchasers unfairly. 251 F. Supp. 2d, at 812 (Leon, J.). In
addition, this interest seems wholly unconnected to the central
purpose of BCRA, and it is not at all similar to the governmental
interests in Buckley that we found to be “sufficiently
important to outweigh the possibility of infringement,” 424 U. S.,
at 66.
As to the disclosure requirements involving
“any political matter of national importance” under the new
Communications Act §315(e)(1)(B), the Government suggests that the
disclosure enables viewers to evaluate the message
transmitted.[ Footnote 6 ] First,
insofar as BCRA §504 requires reporting of “request[s for]
broadcast time” as well as actual broadcasts, it is not supported
by this goal. Requests that do not mature into actual purchases
will have no viewers, but the information may allow competitors or
adversaries to obtain information regarding organizational or
political strategies of purchasers. Second, even as to broadcasts
themselves, in this noncandidate-related context, this goal is a
far cry from the Government interests endorsed in Buckley ,
which were limited to evaluating and preventing corruption of
federal candidates. Ibid.; see also McIntyre v. Ohio Elections Comm’n, 514 U. S. 334 , 354
(1995).
As to disclosure requirements with respect to
candidates under the new Communications Act §315(e)(1)(A), BCRA
§504 significantly overlaps with §201, which is today also upheld
by this Court, ante , at 87–95 (joint opinion of Stevens
and O’Connor, JJ.), and requires purchasers of “electioneering
communications” to disclose a wide array of information, including
the amount of each disbursement and the elections to which
electioneering communications pertain. While I recognize that there
is this overlap, §504 imposes a different burden on the purchaser’s
First Amendment rights: as noted above, §201 is limited to purchasers’ disclosure of disbursements for
electioneering communications, whereas §504 requires broadcast
licensees’ disclosure of requests for broadcast time
by purchasers. Not only are the purchasers’ requests, which may
never result in an actual advertisement, subject to the disclosure
requirements, but §504 will undoubtedly result in increased costs
of communication because the licensees will shift the costs of the
onerous disclosure and recordkeeping requirements to purchasers.
The Government fails to offer a reason for the separate burden and
apparent overlap.
The Government cannot justify, and for that
matter, has not attempted to justify, its requirement that
“request[s for] broadcast” time be publicized. On the record before
this Court, I cannot even speculate as to a governmental interest
that would allow me to conclude that the disclosure of “requests”
should be upheld. Such disclosure risks, inter alia ,
allowing candidates and political groups the opportunity to ferret
out a purchaser’s political strategy and, ultimately, unduly
burdens the First Amendment freedoms of purchasers.
Absent some showing of a Government interest
served by §504 and in light of the breadth of disclosure of
“requests,” I must conclude that §504 fails to satisfy First
Amendment scrutiny.
* Justice Scalia and Justice Kennedy join this
opinion in its entirety. Footnote 1 The Court points out that state parties may
use Levin funds for certain activities. Levin funds, however, are
still federal restrictions on speech, even if they are less onerous
than the restrictions placed on national parties. Footnote 2 Ironically, in the Court’s view, Congress
cannot be trusted to exercise judgment independent of its parties’
large donors in its usual voting decisions because donations may be
used to further its members’ reelection campaigns, but yet must be
deferred to when it passes a comprehensive regulatory regime that
restricts election-related speech. It seems to me no less likely
that Congress would create rules that favor its Members’ reelection
chances, than be corrupted by the influx of money to its political
parties, which may in turn be used to fund a portion of the
Members’ reelection campaigns. Footnote 3 The Court’s suggestion that the “close
relationship” between federal officeholders and state and local
political parties in some way excludes the media from its rationale
is unconvincing, see ante, at 24, n. 15 (Thomas, J.,
concurring in part, concurring in result in part, and dissenting in
part), particularly because such a relationship may be proved with
minimal evidence. Indeed, although the Court concludes that local
political parties have a “close relationship” with federal
candidates, thus warranting greater congressional regulation, I am
unaware of any evidence in the record that indicates that
local political parties have any relationship with federal
candidates. Footnote 4 BCRA does not even close all of the
“loopholes” that currently exist. Nonprofit organizations are
currently able to accept, without disclosing, unlimited donations
for voter registration, voter identification, and get-out-the-vote
activities, and the record indicates that such organizations
already receive large donations, sometimes in the millions of
dollars, for these activities, 251 F. Supp. 2d 176, 323 (DC
2003) (Henderson, J., concurring in judgment in part and dissenting
in part) (noting that the NAACP Voter Fund received a single,
anonymous $7 million donation for get-out-the-vote activities).
There is little reason why all donations to these nonprofit
organizations, no matter the purpose for which the money is used,
will deserve any more protection than the Court provides state
parties if Congress decides to regulate them. And who knows what
the next “loophole” will be. Footnote 5 Section 315(e), as amended by BCRA §504,
provides:
“Political record
“(1) In general
“A licensee shall maintain, and make available
for public inspection, a complete record of a request to purchase
broadcast time that—
“(A) is made by or on behalf of a legally
qualified candidate for public office; or
“(B) communicates a message relating to any
political matter of national importance, including—
“(i) a legally qualified candidate;
“(ii) any election to Federal office; or
“(iii) a national legislative issue of public
importance.
“(2) Contents of record
“A record maintained under paragraph (1) shall
contain information regarding—
“(A) whether the request to purchase broadcast
time is accepted or rejected by the licensee;
“(B) the rate charged for the broadcast
time;
“(C) the date and time on which the
communication is aired;
“(D) the class of time that is purchased;
“(E) the name of the candidate to which the
communication refers and the office to which the candidate is
seeking election, the election to which the communication refers,
or the issue to which the communication refers (as applicable);
“(F) in the case of a request made by, or on
behalf of, a candidate, the name of the candidate, the authorized
committee of the candidate, and the treasurer of such committee;
and
“(G) in the case of any other request, the
name of the person purchasing the time, the name, and phone number
of a contact person for such person, and a list of the chief
executive officers or members of the executive committee or of the
board of directors of such person.
“(3) Time to maintain file
“The information required under this
subsection shall be placed in a political file as soon as possible
and shall be retained by the licensee for a period of not less than
2 years.” Footnote 6 Communications relating to candidates will be
covered by the new Communications Act §315(e)(1)(A), so, in this
context, we must consider, for example, the
plaintiff-organizations, which may attempt to use the broadcast
medium to convey a message espoused by the organizations. STEVENS, J., DISSENTING MCCONNELL V. FEDERAL ELECTION COMM'N 540 U. S. ____ (2003) SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES NOS. 02-1674, 02-1675, 02-1676, 02-1702, 02-1727, 02-1733,
02-1734;02-1740, 02-1747, 02-1753, 02-1755, AND
02-1756 MITCH McCONNELL, UNITED STATES SENATOR,
et al., APPELLANTS
02–1674 v .
FEDERAL ELECTION COMMISSION, et al.;
NATIONAL RIFLE ASSOCIATION, et al.,
APPELLANTS
02–1675 v .
FEDERAL ELECTION COMMISSION, et al.;
FEDERAL ELECTION COMMISSION, et al.,
APPELLANTS
02–1676 v .
MITCH McCONNELL, UNITED STATES SENATOR,
et al.;
JOHN McCAIN, UNITED STATES SENATOR, et al.,
APPELLANTS
02–1702 v .
MITCH McCONNELL, UNITED STATES SENATOR,
et al.;
REPUBLICAN NATIONAL COMMITTEE, et al.,
APPELLANTS
02–1727 v .
FEDERAL ELECTION COMMISSION, et al.;
NATIONAL RIGHT TO LIFE COMMITTEE, INC.,
et al., APPELLANTS
02–1733 v .
FEDERAL ELECTION COMMISSION, et al.;
AMERICAN CIVIL LIBERTIES UNION, APPELLANTS
02–1734 v .
FEDERAL ELECTION COMMISSION, et al.;
VICTORIA JACKSON GRAY ADAMS, et al.,
APPELLANTS
02–1740 v .
FEDERAL ELECTION COMMISSION, et al.;
RON PAUL, UNITED STATES CONGRESSMAN, et al.,
APPELLANTS
02–1747 v .
FEDERAL ELECTION COMMISSION, et al.;
CALIFORNIA DEMOCRATIC PARTY, et al.,
APPELLANTS
02–1753 v .
FEDERAL ELECTION COMMISSION, et al.;
AMERICAN FEDERATION OF LABOR AND CONGRESS OF
INDUSTRIAL ORGANIZATIONS, et al., APPELLANTS
02–1755 v .
FEDERAL ELECTION COMMISSION, et al.;
CHAMBER OF COMMERCE OF THE UNITED STATES,
et al., APPELLANTS
02–1756 v .
FEDERAL ELECTION COMMISSION, et al.
on appeals from the united states district court
for the district of columbia
[December 10, 2003]
Justice Stevens, dissenting with
respect to §305.*
The Chief Justice, writing for
the Court, concludes that the McConnell plaintiffs lack standing to
challenge §305 of BCRA because Senator McConnell cannot be affected
by the provision until “45 days before the Republican primary
election in 2008.” Ante , at 4. I am not persuaded that
Article III’s case-or-controversy requirement imposes such a strict
temporal limit on our jurisdiction. By asserting that he has run
attack ads in the past, that he plans to run such ads in his next
campaign, and that §305 will adversely affect his campaign
strategy, Senator McConnell has identified a “concrete,”
“ ‘distinct,’ ” and “ ‘actual’ ” injury, Whitmore v. Arkansas, 495 U. S. 149 , 155
(1990). That the injury is distant in time does not make it
illusory.
The second prong of the standing
inquiry—whether the alleged injury is fairly traceable to the
defendants’ challenged action and not the result of a third party’s
independent choices† OPINION OF KENNEDY, J. MCCONNELL V. FEDERAL ELECTION COMM'N 540 U. S. ____ (2003) SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES NOS. 02-1674, 02-1675, 02-1676, 02-1702, 02-1727, 02-1733,
02-1734;02-1740, 02-1747, 02-1753, 02-1755, AND
02-1756 MITCH McCONNELL, UNITED STATES SENATOR,
et al., APPELLANTS
02–1674 v .
FEDERAL ELECTION COMMISSION, et al.;
NATIONAL RIFLE ASSOCIATION, et al.,
APPELLANTS
02–1675 v .
FEDERAL ELECTION COMMISSION, et al.;
FEDERAL ELECTION COMMISSION, et al.,
APPELLANTS
02–1676 v .
MITCH McCONNELL, UNITED STATES SENATOR,
et al.;
JOHN McCAIN, UNITED STATES SENATOR, et al.,
APPELLANTS
02–1702 v .
MITCH McCONNELL, UNITED STATES SENATOR,
et al.;
REPUBLICAN NATIONAL COMMITTEE, et al.,
APPELLANTS
02–1727 v .
FEDERAL ELECTION COMMISSION, et al.;
NATIONAL RIGHT TO LIFE COMMITTEE, INC.,
et al., APPELLANTS
02–1733 v .
FEDERAL ELECTION COMMISSION, et al.;
AMERICAN CIVIL LIBERTIES UNION, APPELLANTS
02–1734 v .
FEDERAL ELECTION COMMISSION, et al.;
VICTORIA JACKSON GRAY ADAMS, et al.,
APPELLANTS
02–1740 v .
FEDERAL ELECTION COMMISSION, et al.;
RON PAUL, UNITED STATES CONGRESSMAN, et al.,
APPELLANTS
02–1747 v .
FEDERAL ELECTION COMMISSION, et al.;
CALIFORNIA DEMOCRATIC PARTY, et al.,
APPELLANTS
02–1753 v .
FEDERAL ELECTION COMMISSION, et al.;
AMERICAN FEDERATION OF LABOR AND CONGRESS OF
INDUSTRIAL ORGANIZATIONS, et al., APPELLANTS
02–1755 v .
FEDERAL ELECTION COMMISSION, et al.;
CHAMBER OF COMMERCE OF THE UNITED STATES,
et al., APPELLANTS
02–1756 v .
FEDERAL ELECTION COMMISSION, et al.
on appeals from the united states district court
for the district of columbia
[December 10, 2003]
Justice Kennedy, concurring in
the judgment in part and dissenting in part with respect to BCRA
Titles I and II.*
The First Amendment guarantees
our citizens the right to judge for themselves the most effective
means for the expression of political views and to decide for
themselves which entities to trust as reliable speakers.
Significant portions of Titles I and II of the Bipartisan Campaign
Reform Act of 2002 (BCRA or Act) constrain that freedom. These new
laws force speakers to abandon their own preference for speaking
through parties and organizations. And they provide safe harbor to
the mainstream press, suggesting that the corporate media alone
suffice to alleviate the burdens the Act places on the rights and
freedoms of ordinary citizens.
Today’s decision upholding these laws purports
simply to follow Buckley v. Valeo, 424 U. S. 1 (1976) (per curiam) , and to abide by stare decisis , see ante , at 27 (joint opinion of Stevens and O’Connor, JJ.
(hereinafter Court or majority)); but the majority, to make its
decision work, must abridge free speech where Buckley did
not. Buckley did not authorize Congress to decide what
shapes and forms the national political dialogue is to take. To
reach today’s decision, the Court surpasses Buckley ’s
limits and expands Congress’ regulatory power. In so doing, it
replaces discrete and respected First Amendment principles with
new, amorphous, and unsound rules, rules which dismantle basic
protections for speech.
A few examples show how BCRA reorders speech
rights and codifies the Government’s own preferences for certain
speakers. BCRA would have imposed felony punishment on Ross Perot’s
1996 efforts to build the Reform Party. Compare Federal Election
Campaign Act of 1971 (FECA) §§309(d)(1)(A), 315(a)(1)(B), and
323(a)(1) (prohibiting, by up to five years’ imprisonment, any
individual from giving over $25,000 annually to a national party),
with Spending By Perot, The Houston Chronicle, Dec. 13, 1996,
p. 43 (reporting Perot’s $8 million founding contribution to
the Reform Party). BCRA makes it a felony for an environmental
group to broadcast an ad, within 60 days of an election, exhorting
the public to protest a Congressman’s impending vote to permit
logging in national forests. See BCRA §203. BCRA escalates
Congress’ discrimination in favor of the speech rights of giant
media corporations and against the speech rights of other
corporations, both profit and nonprofit. Compare BCRA §203, with Austin v. Michigan Chamber of
Commerce, 494 U. S. 652 , 659–660 (1990) (first
sanctioning this type of discrimination).
To the majority, all this is not only valid
under the First Amendment but also is part of Congress’ “steady
improvement of the national election laws.” Ante , at 6. We
should make no mistake. It is neither. It is the codification of an
assumption that the mainstream media alone can protect freedom of
speech. It is an effort by Congress to ensure that civic discourse
takes place only through the modes of its choosing. And BCRA is
only the beginning, as its congressional proponents freely
admit:
“This is a modest step, it is a first step, it is
an essential step, but it does not even begin to address, in some
ways, the fundamental problems that exist with the hard money
aspect of the system.” 148 Cong. Rec. S2101 (Mar. 20, 2002)
(statement of Sen. Feingold). Id., at S2097 (statement of Sen.
Wellstone) (“[P]assing this legislation … will whet people’s
appetite for more”); id., at S2101 (statement of Sen.
Boxer) (“[T]his bill is not the be-all or the end-all, but it is a
strong start”); id., at S2152 (statement of Sen. Corzine)
(“[T]his should not and will not be the last time campaign finance
reform is debated on the Senate floor. We have many more important
campaign finance issues to explore”); id., at S2157
(statement of Sen. Torricelli) (“Make [BCRA] the beginning of a
reform, not the end of reform”); id., at H442 (Feb. 13,
2002) (statement of Rep. Doggett) (“Mr. Chairman, if [BCRA] has any
defect, it is that it does too little, not too much”).
Our precedents teach, above all, that
Government cannot be trusted to moderate its own rules for
suppression of speech. The dangers posed by speech regulations have
led the Court to insist upon principled constitutional lines and a
rigorous standard of review. The majority now abandons these
distinctions and limitations.
With respect, I dissent from the majority
opinion upholding BCRA Titles I and II. I concur in the judgment as
to BCRA §213 and new FECA §323(e) and concur in the judgment in
part and dissent in part as to BCRA §§201, 202, and 214.
I. TITLE I AND COORDINATION PROVISIONS
Title I principally bans the
solicitation, receipt, transfer and spending of soft money by the
national parties (new FECA §323(a), 2 U. S. C. A.
§441i(a) (Supp. 2003)). It also bans certain uses of soft money by
state parties (new FECA §323(b)); the transfer of soft money from
national parties to nonprofit groups (new FECA §323(d)); the
solicitation, receipt, transfer, and spending of soft money by
federal candidates and officeholders (new FECA §323(e)); and
certain uses of soft money by state candidates (new FECA §323(f)).
These provisions, and the other provisions with which this opinion
is principally concerned, are set out in full, see Appendix, infra . Even a cursory review of the speech and association
burdens these laws create makes their First Amendment infirmities
obvious:
Title I bars individuals with
shared beliefs from pooling their money above limits set by
Congress to form a new third party. See new FECA §323(a).
Title I bars national party officials from
soliciting or directing soft money to state parties for use on a
state ballot initiative. This is true even if no federal office
appears on the same ballot as the state initiative. See new FECA
§323(a).
A national party’s mere involvement in the
strategic planning of fundraising for a state ballot initiative
risks a determination that the national party is exercising
“indirect control” of the state party. If that determination is
made, the state party must abide by federal regulations. And this
is so even if the federal candidate on the ballot, if there is one,
runs unopposed or is so certain of election that the only voter
interest is in the state and local campaigns. See new FECA
§323(a).
Title I compels speech. Party officials who
want to engage in activity such as fundraising must now speak magic
words to ensure the solicitation cannot be interpreted as anything
other than a solicitation for hard, not soft, money. See ibid. Title I prohibits the national parties from
giving any sort of funds to nonprofit entities, even federally
regulated hard money, and even if the party hoped to sponsor the
interest group’s exploration of a particular issue in advance of
the party’s addition of it to their platform. See new FECA
§323(d).
By express terms, Title I imposes multiple
different forms of spending caps on parties, candidates, and their
agents. See new FECA §§323(a), (e), and (f).
Title I allows state parties to raise
quasi-soft money Levin funds for use in activities that might
affect a federal election; but the Act prohibits national parties
from assisting state parties in developing and executing these
fundraising plans, even when the parties seek only to advance state
election interests. See new FECA §323(b).
Until today’s consolidated cases,
the Court has accepted but two principles to use in determining the
validity of campaign finance restrictions. First is the
anticorruption rationale. The principal concern, of course, is the
agreement for a quid pro quo between officeholders (or
candidates) and those who would seek to influence them. The Court
has said the interest in preventing corruption allows limitations
on receipt of the quid by a candidate or officeholder,
regardless of who gives it or of the intent of the donor or
officeholder. See Buckley , 424 U. S., at 26– 27, 45–48; infra , at 7–10. Second, the Court has analyzed laws
that classify on the basis of the speaker’s corporate or union
identity under the corporate speech rationale. The Court has said
that the willing adoption of the entity form by corporations and
unions justifies regulating them differently: Their ability to give
candidates quids may be subject not only to limits but
also to outright bans; their electoral speech may likewise be
curtailed. See Austin, 494 U. S., at 659–660; Federal
Election Comm’n v. National Right to Work
Comm., 459
U. S. 197 , 201–211 (1982).
The majority today opens with rhetoric that
suggests a conflation of the anticorruption rationale with the
corporate speech rationale. See ante , at 3–6 (hearkening
back to, among others, Elihu Root and his advocacy against the use
of corporate funds in political campaigning). The conflation
appears designed to cast the speech regulated here as unseemly
corporate speech. The effort, however, is unwarranted, and not just
because money is not per se the evil the majority thinks.
Most of the regulations at issue, notably all of the Title I soft
money bans and the Title II coordination provisions, do not draw
distinctions based on corporate or union status. Referring to the
corporate speech rationale as if it were the linchpin of the case,
when corporate speech is not primarily at issue, adds no force to
the Court’s analysis. Instead, the focus must be on Buckley ’s anticorruption rationale and the First Amendment
rights of individual citizens.
A. Constitutionally Sufficient Interest
In Buckley, the Court
held that one, and only one, interest justified the significant
burden on the right of association involved there: eliminating, or
preventing, actual corruption or the appearance of corruption
stemming from contributions to candidates.
“It is unnecessary to look beyond the Act’s primary
purpose—to limit the actuality and appearance of corruption
resulting from large individual financial contributions—in order to
find a constitutionally sufficient justification for the $1,000
contribution limitation.” 424 U. S., at 26.
See also ibid. (concluding this corruption
interest was sufficiently “significant” to sustain “closely drawn”
interference with protected First Amendment rights).
In parallel, Buckley concluded the
expenditure limitations in question were invalid because they did
not advance that same interest. See id., at 47–48 (“[T]he
independent expenditure ceiling thus fails to serve any substantial
governmental interest in stemming the reality or appearance of
corruption in the electoral process”); see also id., at
45, 46.
Thus, though Buckley subjected
expenditure limits to strict scrutiny and contribution limits to
less exacting review, it held neither could withstand
constitutional challenge unless it was shown to advance the
anticorruption interest. In these consolidated cases, unless Buckley is to be repudiated, we must conclude that the
regulations further that interest before considering whether they
are closely drawn or narrowly tailored. If the interest is not
advanced, the regulations cannot comport with the Constitution,
quite apart from the standard of review. Buckley made clear, by its express
language and its context, that the corruption interest only
justifies regulating candidates’ and officeholders’ receipt of what
we can call the “ quids ” in the quid pro quo formulation. The Court rested its decision on the principle that
campaign finance regulation that restricts speech without requiring
proof of particular corrupt action withstands constitutional
challenge only if it regulates conduct posing a demonstrable quid pro quo danger:
“To the extent that large contributions are given
to secure a political quid pro quo from current and
potential office holders, the integrity of our system of
representative democracy is undermined.” Id., at
26–27.
See also id., at 45 (“[A]ssuming, arguendo, that large independent expenditures pose the
same dangers of actual or apparent quid pro quo arrangements as do large contributions …”). That Buckley rested its decision on this quid pro quo standard is not a
novel observation. We have held this was the case:
“The exception [of contribution limits being
justified under the First Amendment] relates to the perception of
undue influence of large contributions to a candidate: ‘ To the extent that large contributions are given to secure a
political quid pro quo from current and potential office
holders, the integrity of our system of representative democracy is
undermined.’ ” Citizens Against Rent Control/Coalition for
Fair Housing v. Berkeley, 454 U. S. 290 , 297 (1981) (quoting Buckley, supra, at 26–27).
See also Federal Election Comm’n v. Beaumont , 539 U. S. ___ (2003) (furthering this
anticorruption rationale by upholding limits on contributions given
directly to candidates); Nixon v. Shrink Missouri
Government PAC, 528 U. S. 377 (2000)
(same).
Despite the Court’s attempt to rely on
language from cases like Shrink Missouri to establish that
the standard defining corruption is broader than conduct that
presents a quid pro quo danger, see ante , at 43,
n. 48, in those cases the Court in fact upheld limits on conduct
possessing quid pro quo dangers, and nothing more. See
also infra , 12. For example, the Shrink Missouri Court’s distinguishing of what was at issue there and quid pro
quo , in fact, shows only that it used the term quid pro
quo to refer to actual corrupt, vote-buying exchanges, as
opposed to interactions that possessed quid pro quo potential even if innocently undertaken. Thus, the Court said:
“[W]e spoke in Buckley of the perception of
corruption ‘inherent in a regime of large individual financial
contributions’ to candidates for public office . . . as a source of
concern “almost equal” to quid pro quo improbity.” 528 U.
S., at 390 (citations omitted).
Thus, the perception of corruption that the
majority now asserts is somehow different from the quid pro
quo potential discussed in this opinion, was created by an
exchange featuring quid pro quo potential—contributions
directly to a candidate.
In determining whether conduct poses a quid pro quo danger the analysis is functional. In Buckley , the Court confronted an expenditure limitation
provision that capped the amount of money individuals could spend
on any activity intended to influence a federal election
( i.e. , it reached to both independent and coordinated
expenditures). See 424 U. S., at 46–47. The Court concluded that
though the limitation reached both coordinated and independent
expenditures, there were other valid FECA provisions that barred
coordinated expenditures. Hence, the limit at issue only added
regulation to independent expenditures. On that basis it concluded
the provision was unsupported by any valid corruption interest. The
conduct to which it added regulation (independent expenditures)
posed no quid pro quo danger. See ibid .
Placing Buckley ’s anticorruption
rationale in the context of the federal legislative power yields
the following rule: Congress’ interest in preventing corruption
provides a basis for regulating federal candidates’ and
officeholders’ receipt of quids , whether or not the
candidate or officeholder corruptly received them. Conversely, the
rule requires the Court to strike down campaign finance regulations
when they do not add regulation to “actual or apparent quid pro
quo arrangements.” Id., at 45.
The Court ignores these constitutional bounds
and in effect interprets the anticorruption rationale to allow
regulation not just of “actual or apparent quid pro quo arrangements,” ibid., but of any conduct that wins
goodwill from or influences a Member of Congress. It is not that
there is any quarrel between this opinion and the majority that the
inquiry since Buckley has been whether certain conduct
creates “undue influence.” See ante , at 40–41. On that we
agree. The very aim of Buckley ’s standard, however, was to
define undue influence by reference to the presence of quid pro
quo involving the officeholder. The Court, in contrast,
concludes that access, without more, proves influence is undue.
Access, in the Court’s view, has the same legal ramifications as
actual or apparent corruption of officeholders. This new definition
of corruption sweeps away all protections for speech that lie in
its path.
The majority says it is not abandoning our
cases in this way, but its reasoning shows otherwise:
“More importantly, plaintiffs
conceive of corruption too narrowly. Our cases have firmly
established that Congress’ legitimate interest extends beyond
preventing simple cash-for-votes corruption to curbing ‘undue
influence on an officeholder’s judgment, or the appearance of such
influence.’ [ Federal Election Comm’n v. Colorado
Republican Federal Campaign Comm., 533 U. S. 431 , 441
(2001) (Colorado II) ]. Many of the ‘deeply disturbing
examples’ of corruption cited by this Court in Buckley to
justify FECA’s contribution limits were not episodes of vote
buying, but evidence that various corporate interests had given
substantial donations to gain access to high-level government
officials. Even if that access did not secure actual influence, it
certainly gave the ‘appearance of such influence.’ Colorado
II , supra , at 441; see also [ Buckley v. Valeo, 519 F. 2d 821, 838 (CADC 1975)].
“The record in the present case is replete
with similar examples of national party committees peddling access
to federal candidates and officeholders in exchange for large
soft-money donations. See [251 F. Supp. 2d 176, 492–506 (DC
2003) (Kollar-Kotelly, J.)].” Ante, at 40–41.
The majority notes that access
flowed from the regulated conduct at issue in Buckley and
its progeny, then uses that fact as the basis for concluding that
access peddling by the parties equals corruption by the candidates.
That conclusion, however, is tenable only by a quick and subtle
shift, and one that breaks new ground: The majority ignores the quid pro quo nature of the regulated conduct central to
our earlier decisions. It relies instead solely on the fact that
access flowed from the conduct.
To ignore the fact that in Buckley the money at issue was given to candidates, creating an obvious quid pro quo danger as much as it led to the candidates
also providing access to the donors, is to ignore the Court’s
comments in Buckley that show quid pro quo was of
central importance to the analysis. See 424 U. S., at 26–27, 45.
The majority also ignores that in Buckley , and ever since,
those party contributions that have been subject to congressional
limit were not general party-building contributions but were only
contributions used to influence particular elections. That is, they
were contributions that flowed to a particular candidate’s benefit,
again posing a quid pro quo danger. And it ignores that in Colorado II , the party spending was that which was
coordinated with a particular candidate, thereby implicating quid pro quo dangers. In all of these ways the majority
breaks the necessary tether between quid and access and
assumes that access, all by itself, demonstrates corruption and so
can support regulation. See also ante , at 47 (“[L]arge
soft-money donations to national party committees are likely to buy
donors preferential access to federal officeholders no matter the
ends to which their contributions are eventually put”).
Access in itself, however, shows only that in
a general sense an officeholder favors someone or that someone has
influence on the officeholder. There is no basis, in law or in
fact, to say favoritism or influence in general is the same as
corrupt favoritism or influence in particular. By equating vague
and generic claims of favoritism or influence with actual or
apparent corruption, the Court adopts a definition of corruption
that dismantles basic First Amendment rules, permits Congress to
suppress speech in the absence of a quid pro quo threat,
and moves beyond the rationale that is Buckley ’s very
foundation.
The generic favoritism or influence theory
articulated by the Court is at odds with standard First Amendment
analyses because it is unbounded and susceptible to no limiting
principle. Any given action might be favored by any given person,
so by the Court’s reasoning political loyalty of the purest sort
can be prohibited. There is no remaining principled method for
inquiring whether a campaign finance regulation does in fact
regulate corruption in a serious and meaningful way. We are left to
defer to a congressional conclusion that certain conduct creates
favoritism or influence.
Though the majority cites common sense as the
foundation for its definition of corruption, see ante, at
35, 43, in the context of the real world only a single definition
of corruption has been found to identify political corruption
successfully and to distinguish good political responsiveness from
bad—that is quid pro quo . Favoritism and influence are
not, as the Government’s theory suggests, avoidable in
representative politics. It is in the nature of an elected
representative to favor certain policies, and, by necessary
corollary, to favor the voters and contributors who support those
policies. It is well understood that a substantial and legitimate
reason, if not the only reason, to cast a vote for, or to make a
contribution to, one candidate over another is that the candidate
will respond by producing those political outcomes the supporter
favors. Democracy is premised on responsiveness. Q uid pro
quo corruption has been, until now, the only agreed upon
conduct that represents the bad form of responsiveness and presents
a justiciable standard with a relatively clear limiting principle:
Bad responsiveness may be demonstrated by pointing to a
relationship between an official and a quid .
The majority attempts to mask its extension of Buckley under claims that BCRA prevents the appearance of
corruption, even if it does not prevent actual corruption, since
some assert that any donation of money to a political party is
suspect. See ante , at 40–42. Under Buckley ’s
holding that Congress has a valid “interest in stemming the reality
or appearance of corruption,” 424 U. S., at 47–48, however, the
inquiry does not turn on whether some persons assert that an
appearance of corruption exists. Rather, the inquiry turns on
whether the Legislature has established that the regulated conduct
has inherent corruption potential, thus justifying the inference
that regulating the conduct will stem the appearance of real
corruption. Buckley was guided and constrained by this
analysis. In striking down expenditure limits the Court in Buckley did not ask whether people thought large election
expenditures corrupt, because clearly at that time many persons,
including a majority of Congress and the President, did. See id., at 25 (“According to the parties and amici ,
the primary interest served . . . by the Act as a whole, is the
prevention of corruption and the appearance of corruption”).
Instead, the Court asked whether the Government had proved that the
regulated conduct, the expenditures, posed inherent quid pro
quo corruption potential. See id., at 46.
The Buckley decision made this
analysis even clearer in upholding contribution limitations. It
stated that even if actual corrupt contribution practices had not
been proved, Congress had an interest in regulating the appearance
of corruption that is “inherent in a regime of large individual
financial contributions.” Id., at 27 (discussing
contributions to candidates). See also id., at 28, 30. The quid pro quo nature of candidate contributions justified
the conclusion that the contributions pose inherent corruption
potential; and this in turn justified the conclusion that their
regulation would stem the appearance of real corruption.
From that it follows that the Court today
should not ask, as it does, whether some persons, even Members of
Congress, conclusorily assert that the regulated conduct appears
corrupt to them. Following Buckley , it should instead
inquire whether the conduct now prohibited inherently poses a real
or substantive quid pro quo danger, so that its regulation
will stem the appearance of quid pro quo corruption.
1. New FECA §§323(a), (b), (d), and (f)
Sections 323(a), (b), (d), and
(f), 2 U. S. C. A. §§441i(a), (b), (d), and (f )
(Supp. 2003), cannot stand because they do not add regulation to
conduct that poses a demonstrable quid pro quo danger.
They do not further Buckley ’s corruption interest.
The majority, with a broad brush,
paints §323(a) as aimed at limiting contributions possessing
federal officeholder corruption potential. From there it would
justify §323’s remaining provisions as necessary complements to
ensure the national parties cannot circumvent §323(a)’s
prohibitions. The broad brush approach fails, however, when the
provisions are reviewed under Buckley ’s proper definition
of corruption potential.
On its face §323(a) does not regulate federal
candidates’ or officeholders’ receipt of quids because it
does not regulate contributions to, or conduct by, candidates or
officeholders. See BCRA §101(a) (setting out new FECA §323(a):
National parties may not “solicit, receive, or direct to another
person … or spend any [soft money]”).
The realities that underlie the statute,
furthermore, do not support the majority’s interpretation. Before
BCRA’s enactment, parties could only use soft money for a
candidate’s “benefit” ( e.g. , through issue ads, which all
parties now admit may influence elections) independent of that
candidate. And, as discussed later, §323(e) validly prohibits
federal candidate and officeholder solicitation of soft money party
donations. See infra , at 31. Section 323(a), therefore,
only adds regulation to soft money party donations not solicited
by, or spent in coordination with, a candidate or officeholder.
These donations (noncandidate or officeholder
solicited soft money party donations that are independently spent)
do not pose the quid pro quo dangers that provide the
basis for restricting protected speech. Though the government
argues §323(a) does regulate federal candidates’ and officeholders’
receipt of quids , it bases its argument on this flawed
reasoning:
(1) “[F]ederal elected
officeholders are inextricably linked to their political parties,”
Brief for Appellees/Cross Appellants FEC et al. in No. 02–1674
et al., p. 21; cf. Colorado Republican Federal
Campaign Comm. v. Federal Election
Comm’n, 518 U. S. 604 , 626 (1996) (Colorado I) (Kennedy, J., concurring in judgment and
dissenting in part).
(2) All party receipts must be connected to,
and must create, corrupt donor favoritism among these
officeholders.
(3) Therefore, regulation of party receipts
equals regulation of quids to the party’s
officeholders.
The reasoning is flawed because
the Government’s reliance on reasoning parallel to the Colorado
I concurrence only establishes the first step in its chain of
logic: that a party is a proxy for its candidates generally. It
does not establish the second step: that as a proxy for its
candidates generally, all moneys the party receives (not
just candidate solicited-soft money donations, or donations used in
coordinated activity) represent quids for all the party’s
candidates and officeholders. The Government’s analysis is
inconsistent with what a majority of the Justices, in different
opinions, have said.
Justice Thomas’ dissent in Colorado
II , 533 U. S., at 476–477, taken together with Justice
Breyer’s opinion announcing the judgment of the Court in Colorado I , rebuts the second step of the Government’s
argument. Justice Thomas demonstrated that a general
party-candidate corruption linkage does not exist. As he pointed
out:
“The dearth of evidence [of such corruption] is
unsurprising in light of the unique relationship between a
political party and its candidates: ‘The very aim of a political
party is to influence its candidate’s stance on issues and, if the
candidate takes office or is reelected, his votes.’ If coordinated
expenditures help achieve this aim, the achievement ‘does not …
constitute “a subversion of the political process.” ’ ” Colorado II, supra, at 476–477 (citations
omitted) . Justice Breyer reached
the same conclusion about the corrupting effect general party
receipts could have on particular candidates, though on narrower
grounds. He concluded that independent party conduct lacks quid
pro quo corruption potential. See Colorado I, 518 U.
S., at 617–618; id., at 617 (“If anything, an independent
[party] expenditure made possible by a $20,000 donation, but
controlled and directed by a party rather than the donor, would
seem less likely to corrupt than the same (or a much larger)
independent expenditure made directly by that donor”); id., at 616 (“[T]he opportunity for corruption posed by
[soft money] contributions is, at best, attenuated” because they
may not be used for the purposes of influencing a federal election
under FECA).
These opinions establish that independent
party activity, which by definition includes independent receipt
and spending of soft money, lacks a possibility for quid pro
quo corruption of federal officeholders. This must be all the
more true of a party’s independent receipt and spending of soft
money donations neither directed to nor solicited by a
candidate.
The Government’s premise is also unsupported
by the record before us. The record confirms that soft money party
contributions, without more, do not create quid pro quo corruption potential. As a conceptual matter, generic party
contributions may engender good will from a can- didate or
officeholder because, as the Government says: “[A] Member of
Congress can be expected to feel a natural temptation to favor
those persons who have helped the ‘team,’ ” Brief for
Appellees/Cross-Appellants FEC et al. in No. 02–1674
et al., p. 33. Still, no Member of Congress testified
this favoritism changed voting behavior.
The piece of record evidence the Government
puts forward on this score comes by way of deposition testimony
from former Senator Simon and Senator Feingold. See 251
F. Supp. 2d 176, 482 (DC 2003) (Kollar-Kotelly, J.). Senator
Simon reported an unidentified colleague indicated frustration with
Simon’s opposition to legislation that would benefit a party
contributor on the grounds that “ ‘we’ve got to pay attention
to who is buttering our bread’ ” and testified he did not
think there was any question “ ‘this’ ” ( i.e. ,
“donors getting their way”) was why the legislation passed. See
App. 805. Senator Feingold, too, testified an unidentified
colleague suggested he support the legislation because “ ‘they
[ i.e. , the donor] just gave us [ i.e. , the party]
$100,000.’ ” 251 F. Supp. 2d, at 482 (Kollar-Kotelly,
J.).
That evidence in fact works against the
Government. These two testifying Senators expressed disgust toward
the favoring of a soft money giver, and not the good will one would
have expected under the Government’s theory. That necessarily
undercuts the inference of corruption the Government would have us
draw from the evidence.
Even more damaging to the Government’s
argument from the testimony is the absence of testimony that the
Senator who allegedly succumbed to corrupt influence had himself
solicited soft money from the donor in question. Equally, there is
no indication he simply favored the company with his vote because
it had, without any involvement from him, given funds to the party
to which he belonged. This fact is crucial. If the Senator himself
had been the solicitor of the soft money funds in question, the
incident does nothing more than confirm that Congress’ efforts at
campaign finance reform ought to be directed to conduct that
implicates quid pro quo relationships. Only if there was
some evidence that the officeholder had not solicited funds from
the donor could the Court extrapolate from this episode that
general party contributions function as quids , inspiring
corrupt favoritism among party members. The episode is the single
one of its type reported in the record and does not seem sufficient
basis for major incursions into settled practice. Given the
Government’s claim that the corrupt favoritism problem is
widespread, its inability to produce more than a single instance
purporting to illustrate the point demonstrates the Government has
not fairly characterized the general attitudes of Members towards
soft money donors from whom they have not solicited.
Other aspects of the record confirm the
Government has not produced evidence that Members corruptly favor
soft money donors to their party as a per se matter. Most
testimony from which the Government would have the Court infer
corruption is testimony that Members are rewarded by their parties
for soliciting soft money. See i d., at 438–521
(Kollar-Kotelly, J.). This says nothing about how Members feel
about a party’s soft money donors from whom they have not
solicited. Indeed, record evidence on this point again cuts against
the Government:
“ ‘As a Member of the Senate Finance
Committee, I experienced the pressure first hand. On several
occasions when we were debating important tax bills, I needed a
police escort to get into the Finance Committee hearing room
because so many lobbyists were crowding the halls, trying to get
one last chance to make their pitch to each Senator. Senators
generally knew which lobbyist represented the interests of which
large donor. I was often glad that I limited the amount of soft
money fundraising I did and did not take PAC contributions, because
it would be extremely difficult not to feel beholden to these
donors otherwise.’ ” Id., at 482 (testimony of former
Senator Boren; see 6–R Defs. Exhs., Tab 8, ¶ ;8).
Thus, one of the handful of Senators on whom the
Government relies to make its case candidly admits the pressure of
appeasing soft money donors derives from the Members’ solicitation
of donors, not from those donors’ otherwise giving to their
party.
In light of all this, §323(a) has no valid
anticorruption interest. The anticircumvention interests the
Government offers in defense of §§323(b), (d), and (f) must also
fall with the interests asserted to justify §323(a). Any
anticircumvention interest can be only as compelling as the
interest justifying the underlying regulation.
None of these other sections has an
independent justifying interest. Section 323(b), for example, adds
regulation only to activity undertaken by a state party. In the
District Court two of the three judges found as fact that
particular state and local parties exist primarily to participate
in state and local elections, that they spend the majority of their
resources on those elections, and that their voter registration and
Get Out The Vote (GOTV) activities, in particular, are directed
primarily at state and local elections. See 251 F. Supp. 2d,
at 301–302 (Henderson, J., concurring in judgment in part and
dissenting in part); id., at 837–840 (Leon, J.). These
findings, taken together with BCRA’s other, valid prohibitions
barring coordination with federal candidates or officeholders and
their soft money solicitation, demonstrate that §323(b) does not
add regulation to conduct that poses a danger of a federal
candidate’s or officeholder’s receipt of quids .
Even §323(b)’s narrowest regulation, which
bans state party soft money funded ads that (1) refer to a clearly
identified federal candidate, and (2) either support or attack any
candidate for the office of the clearly mentioned federal
candidate, see new FECA §301(20)(A)(iii), fails the constitutional
test. The ban on conduct that by the statute’s own definition may
serve the interest of a federal candidate suggests to the majority
that it is conduct that poses quid pro quo danger for
federal candidates or officeholders. Yet, even this
effect—considered after excising the coordination and
candidate-solicited funding aspects elsewhere prohibited by BCRA
§§202 and 214(a) and new FECA §323(a)—poses no danger of a federal
candidate’s or officeholder’s receipt of a quid . That
conduct is no different from an individual’s independent
expenditure referring to and supporting a clearly identified
candidate—and this poses no regulable danger.
Section 323(d), which governs relationships
between the national parties and nonprofit groups, fails for
similar reasons. It is worth noting that neither the record nor our
own experience tells us how significant these funds transfers are
at this time. It is plain, however, that the First Amendment ought
not to be manipulated to permit Congress to forbid a political
party from aiding other speakers whom the party deems more
effective in addressing discrete issues. One of the central flaws
in BCRA is that Congress is determining what future course the
creation of ideas and the expression of views must follow. Its
attempt to foreclose new and creative partnerships for speech, as
illustrated here, is consistent with neither the traditions nor
principles of our Free Speech guarantee, which insists that the
people, and not the Congress, decide what modes of expression are
the most legitimate and effective.
The majority’s upholding §323(d) is all the
more unsettling because of the way it ignores the Act as Congress
wrote it. Congress said national parties “shall not solicit any
funds for, or make or direct any donations to” §501(c) nonprofit
organizations that engage in federal election activity or to §527
political committees. The Court, however, reads out the word “any”
and construes the words “funds” and “donations” to mean “soft money
funds” and “soft money donations.” See ante , at 72 (“This
construction is consistent with the concerns animating Title I,
whose purpose is to plug the soft-money loophole”). The Court’s
statutory amendment may be consistent with its anti-soft-money
rationale; it is not, however, consistent with the plain and
unavoidable statutory text Congress has given us. Even as construed
by the Court, moreover, it is invalid.
The majority strains to save the provision
from what must seem to it an unduly harsh First Amendment. It does
so by making a legislative determination Congress chose not to
make: to prefer hard money to soft money within the construct of
national party relationships with nonprofit groups. Congress gave
no indication of a preference to regulate either hard money or soft
in this context. Rather, it simply proscribed all transfers of
money between the two organizations and all efforts by the national
parties to raise any money on the nonprofit groups’ behalf. The
question the Court faces is not which part of a text to sever and
strike, but whether Congress can prohibit such transfers
altogether. The answer, as the majority recognizes, is no. See ante , at 71 (“[P]rohibiting parties from donating funds
already raised in compliance with FECA does little to further
Congress’ goal of preventing corruption or the appearance of
corruption of federal candidates and officeholders”).
Though §323(f) in effect imposes limits on
candidate contributions, it does not address federal candidate and
officeholder contributions. Yet it is the possibility of federal
officeholder quid pro quo corruption potential that
animates Buckley ’s rule as it relates to Acts of Congress
(as opposed to Acts of state legislatures). See 424 U. S., at 13
(“The constitutional power of Congress to regulate federal
elections is well established”).
When one recognizes that §§323(a), (b), (d),
and (f) do not serve the interest the anticorruption rationale
contemplates, Title I’s entirety begins to look very much like an
incumbency protection plan. See J. Miller, Monopoly Politics 84–101
(1999) (concluding that regulations limiting election fundraising
and spending constrain challengers more than incumbents). That
impression is worsened by the fact that Congress exempted its
officeholders from the more stringent prohibitions imposed on party
officials. Compare new FECA §323(a) with new FECA §323(e). Section
323(a) raises an inflexible bar against soft money solicitation, in
any way, by parties or party officials. Section 323(e), in
contrast, enacts exceptions to the rule for federal officeholders
(the very centerpiece of possible corruption), and allows them to
solicit soft money for various uses and organizations.
The law in some respects even weakens the
regulation of federal candidates and officeholders. Under former
law, officeholders were understood to be limited to receipt of hard
money by their campaign committees. See 2 U. S. C. §§431, 441a
(setting out the pre-BCRA FECA regime). BCRA, however, now allows
them and their campaign committees to receive soft money that fits
the hard money source and amount restrictions, so long as the
officeholders direct that money on to other nonfederal candidates.
See new FECA §323(e)(1)(B). The majority’s characterization of this
weakening of the regime as “tightly constrain[ing]” candidates, ante, at 73, n. 70, is a prime example of its
unwillingness to confront Congress’ own interest or the persisting
fact that the regulations violate First Amendment freedoms. The
more lenient treatment accorded to incumbency-driven politicians
than to party officials who represent broad national constituencies
must render all the more suspect Congress’ claim that the Act’s
sole purpose is to stop corruption.
The majority answers this charge
by stating the obvious, that “§323(e) applies to both officeholders and candidates .” Ante , at 78, n. 72. The
controlling point, of course, is the practical burden on
challengers. That the prohibition applies to both incumbents and
challengers in no way establishes that it burdens them equally in
that regard. Name recognition and other advantages held by
incumbents ensure that as a general rule incumbents will be
advantaged by the legislation the Court today upholds.
The Government identifies no
valid anticorruption interest justifying §§323(a), (b), (d), and
(f). The very nature of the restrictions imposed by these
provisions makes one all the more skeptical of the Court’s
explanation of the interests at stake. These provisions cannot
stand under the First Amendment.
2. New FECA §323(e)
Ultimately, only one of the
challenged Title I provisions satisfies Buckley ’s
anticorruption rationale and the First Amendment’s guarantee. It is
§323(e). This provision is the sole aspect of Title I that is a
direct and necessary regulation of federal candidates’ and
officeholders’ receipt of quids . Section 323(e) governs
“candidate[s], individual[s] holding Federal office, agent[s] of a
candidate or an individual holding Federal office, or an entity
directly or indirectly established, financed, maintained or
controlled by or acting on behalf of 1 or more candidates or
individuals holding Federal office.” 2 U. S. C. A.
§441i(e) (Supp. 2003). These provisions, and the regulations that
follow, limit candidates’ and their agents’ solicitation of soft
money. The regulation of a candidate’s receipt of funds furthers a
constitutionally sufficient interest. More difficult, however, is
the question whether regulation of a candidate’s solicitation of
funds also furthers this interest if the funds are given to
another.
I agree with the Court that the
broader solicitation regulation does further a sufficient interest.
The making of a solicited gift is a quid both to the
recipient of the money and to the one who solicits the payment (by
granting his request). Rules governing candidates’ or
officeholders’ solicitation of contributions are, therefore,
regulations governing their receipt of quids . This
regulation fits under Buckley ’s anticorruption
rationale.
B. Standard of Review
It is common ground between the
majority and this opinion that a speech-suppressing campaign
finance regulation, even if supported by a sufficient Government
interest, is unlawful if it cannot satisfy our designated standard
of review. See ante , at 24–27. In Buckley , we
applied “closely drawn” scrutiny to contribution limitations and
strict scrutiny to expenditure limitations. Compare 424 U. S., at
25, with id., at 44–45. Against that backdrop, the
majority assumes that because Buckley applied the
rationale in the context of contribution and expenditure limits,
its application gives Congress and the Court the capacity to
classify any challenged campaign finance regulation as either a
contribution or an expenditure limit. Thus, it first concludes
Title I’s regulations are contributions limits and then proceeds to
apply the lesser scrutiny.
“Complex as its provisions may be, §323, in the
main, does little more than regulate the ability of wealthy
individuals, corporations, and unions to contribute large sums of
money to influence federal elections, federal candidates, and
federal officeholders.” Ante, at 28.
Though the majority’s analysis
denies it, Title I’s dynamics defy this facile, initial
classification.
Title I’s provisions prohibit the receipt of
funds; and in most instances, but not all, this can be defined as a
contribution limit. They prohibit the spending of funds; and in
most instances this can be defined as an expenditure limit. They
prohibit the giving of funds to nonprofit groups; and this falls
within neither definition as we have ever defined it. Finally, they
prohibit fundraising activity; and the parties dispute the
classification of this regulation (the challengers say it is core
political association, while the Government says it ultimately
results only in a limit on contribution receipts).
The majority’s classification overlooks these
competing characteristics and exchanges Buckley ’s
substance for a formulaic caricature of it. Despite the parties’
and the majority’s best efforts on both sides of the question, it
ignores reality to force these regulations into one of the two
legal categories as either contribution or expenditure limitations.
Instead, these characteristics seem to indicate Congress has
enacted regulations that are neither contribution nor expenditure
limits, or are perhaps both at once.
Even if the laws could be classified in broad
terms as only contribution limits, as the majority is inclined to
do, that still leaves the question what “contribution limits” can
include if they are to be upheld under Buckley . Buckley ’s application of a less exacting review to
contribution limits must be confined to the narrow category of
money gifts that are directed, in some manner, to a candidate or
officeholder. Any broader definition of the category contradicts Buckley ’s quid pro quo rationale and overlooks Buckley ’s language, which contemplates limits on
contributions to a candidate or campaign committee in explicit
terms. See 424 U. S., at 13 (applying less exacting review to
“contribution … limitations in the Act prohibit[ing] individuals
from contributing more than $25,000 in a single year or more than
$1,000 to any single candidate for an election campaign”); id., at 45 (“[T]he contribution limitations’ [apply a]
total ban on the giving of large amounts of money to candidates”).
See also id., at 20, 25, 28.
The Court, it must be acknowledged, both in Buckley and on other occasions, has described contribution
limits due some more deferential review in less than precise terms.
At times it implied that donations to political parties would also
qualify as contributions whose limitation too would be subject to
less exacting review. See id., at 23–24, n. 24
(“[T]he general understanding of what constitutes a political
contribution[:] Funds provided to a candidate or political party or
campaign committee either directly or indirectly through an
intermediary constitute a contribution”). See also Federal
Election Comm’n v. Beaumont , 539 U. S., at ___ (2003)
(slip op., at 14) (“ ‘[C]ontributions may result in political
expression if spent by a candidate or an association’ ”).
These seemingly conflicting statements are
best reconciled by reference to Buckley ’s underlying
rationale for applying less exacting review. In a similar, but more
imperative, sense proper application of the standard of review to
regulations that are neither contribution nor expenditure limits
(or which are both at once) can only be determined by reference to
that rationale. Buckley ’s underlying rationale is
this: Less exacting review applies to Government regulations that
“significantly interfere” with First Amendment rights of
association. But any regulation of speech or associational rights
creating “markedly greater interference” than such significant
interference receives strict scrutiny. Unworkable and ill advised
though it may be, Buckley unavoidably sets forth this
test:
“Even a ‘ “significant interference” with
protected rights of political association’ may be sustained if the
State demonstrates [1] a sufficiently important interest and [2]
employs means closely drawn to avoid unnecessary abridgment of
associational freedoms. Cousins v. Wigoda ,
[ 419 U. S. 477 ,
488 (1975)]; NAACP v. Button, [ 371 U. S. 415 , 438
(1963)]; Shelton v. Tucker [ 364 U. S. 479 , 488
(1960)] .” 424 U. S., at 25.
“The markedly greater burden on basic freedoms [referring to
‘the freedom of speech and association’] caused by [expenditure
limits] thus cannot be sustained simply by invoking the interest in
maximizing the effectiveness of the less intrusive contribution
limitations. Rather, the constitutionality of [the expenditure
limits] turns on whether the governmental interests advanced in its
support satisfy the exacting scrutiny applicable to limitations on
core First Amendment rights of political expression.” Id., at 44–45.† OPINION OF SCALIA, J. MCCONNELL V. FEDERAL ELECTION COMM'N 540 U. S. ____ (2003) SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES NOS. 02-1674, 02-1675, 02-1676, 02-1702, 02-1727, 02-1733,
02-1734;02-1740, 02-1747, 02-1753, 02-1755, AND
02-1756 MITCH McCONNELL, UNITED STATES SENATOR,
et al., APPELLANTS
02–1674 v .
FEDERAL ELECTION COMMISSION, et al.;
NATIONAL RIFLE ASSOCIATION, et al.,
APPELLANTS
02–1675 v .
FEDERAL ELECTION COMMISSION, et al.;
FEDERAL ELECTION COMMISSION, et al.,
APPELLANTS
02–1676 v .
MITCH McCONNELL, UNITED STATES SENATOR,
et al.;
JOHN McCAIN, UNITED STATES SENATOR, et al.,
APPELLANTS
02–1702 v .
MITCH McCONNELL, UNITED STATES SENATOR,
et al.;
REPUBLICAN NATIONAL COMMITTEE, et al.,
APPELLANTS
02–1727 v .
FEDERAL ELECTION COMMISSION, et al.;
NATIONAL RIGHT TO LIFE COMMITTEE, INC.,
et al., APPELLANTS
02–1733 v .
FEDERAL ELECTION COMMISSION, et al.;
AMERICAN CIVIL LIBERTIES UNION, APPELLANTS
02–1734 v .
FEDERAL ELECTION COMMISSION, et al.;
VICTORIA JACKSON GRAY ADAMS, et al.,
APPELLANTS
02–1740 v .
FEDERAL ELECTION COMMISSION, et al.;
RON PAUL, UNITED STATES CONGRESSMAN, et al.,
APPELLANTS
02–1747 v .
FEDERAL ELECTION COMMISSION, et al.;
CALIFORNIA DEMOCRATIC PARTY, et al.,
APPELLANTS
02–1753 v .
FEDERAL ELECTION COMMISSION, et al.;
AMERICAN FEDERATION OF LABOR AND CONGRESS OF
INDUSTRIAL ORGANIZATIONS, et al., APPELLANTS
02–1755 v .
FEDERAL ELECTION COMMISSION, et al.;
CHAMBER OF COMMERCE OF THE UNITED STATES,
et al., APPELLANTS
02–1756 v .
FEDERAL ELECTION COMMISSION, et al.
on appeals from the united states district court
for the district of columbia
[December 10, 2003]
Justice Scalia, concurring with
respect to BCRA Titles III and IV, dissenting with respect to BCRA
Titles I and V, and concurring in the judgment in part and
dissenting in part with respect to BCRA Title II.
With respect to Titles I, II, and
V: I join in full the dissent of The Chief Justice; I join the
opinion of Justice Kennedy, except to the extent it upholds new
§323(e) of the Federal Election Campaign Act of 1971 (FECA) and
§202 of the Bipartisan Campaign Reform Act of 2002 (BCRA) in part;
and because I continue to believe that Buckley v. Valeo, 424 U. S. 1 (1976) (per
curiam), was wrongly decided, I also join Parts I, II–A, and
II–B of the opinion of Justice Thomas. With respect to Titles III
and IV, I join The Chief Justice’s opinion for the Court. Because
these cases are of such extraordinary importance, I cannot avoid
adding to the many writings a few words of my own.
This is a sad day for the freedom of speech.
Who could have imagined that the same Court which, within the past
four years, has sternly disapproved of restrictions upon such
inconsequential forms of expression as virtual child pornography, Ashcroft v. Free Speech Coalition, 535 U. S. 234 (2002),
tobacco advertising, Lorillard Tobacco Co. v. Reilly, 533
U. S. 525 (2001), dissemination of illegally intercepted
communications, Bartnicki v. Vopper, 532 U. S. 514 (2001),
and sexually explicit cable programming, United States v. Playboy Entertainment Group, Inc., 529 U. S. 803 (2000),
would smile with favor upon a law that cuts to the heart of what
the First Amendment is meant to protect: the right to criticize the
government. For that is what the most offensive provisions of this
legislation are all about. We are governed by Congress, and this
legislation prohibits the criticism of Members of Congress by those
entities most capable of giving such criticism loud voice: national
political parties and corporations, both of the commercial and the
not-for-profit sort. It forbids pre-election criticism of
incumbents by corporations, even not-for-profit corporations, by
use of their general funds; and forbids national-party use of
“soft” money to fund “issue ads” that incumbents find so
offensive.
To be sure, the legislation is evenhanded: It
similarly prohibits criticism of the candidates who oppose Members
of Congress in their reelection bids. But as everyone knows, this
is an area in which evenhandedness is not fairness. If all electioneering were evenhandedly prohibited, incumbents would have
an enormous advantage. Likewise, if incumbents and challengers are
limited to the same quantity of electioneering, incumbents are
favored. In other words, any restriction upon a type of
campaign speech that is equally available to challengers and
incumbents tends to favor incumbents.
Beyond that, however, the present legislation targets for prohibition certain categories of campaign
speech that are particularly harmful to incumbents. Is it
accidental, do you think, that incumbents raise about three times
as much “hard money”—the sort of funding generally not restricted by this legislation—as do their challengers? See FEC,
1999–2000 Financial Activity of All Senate and House Campaigns
(Jan. 1, 1999–Dec. 31, 2000) (last modified on May 15, 2001),
http://www.fec.gov/press/ 051501congfinact/tables/allcong2000.xls
(all Internet ma-terials as visited Dec. 4, 2003, and available in
Clerk of Court’s case file). Or that lobbyists (who seek the favor
of incumbents) give 92 percent of their money in “hard”
contributions? See U. S. Public Interest Research Group (PIRG), The
Lobbyist’s Last Laugh: How K Street Lob- byists Would Benefit from
the McCain-Feingold Cam- paign Finance Bill 3 (July 5, 2001),
http://www.pirg.org/ democracy/democracy.asp?id2=5068. Is it an
oversight, do you suppose, that the so-called “millionaire
provisions” raise the contribution limit for a candidate running
against an individual who devotes to the campaign (as challengers
often do) great personal wealth, but do not raise the limit for a
candidate running against an individual who devotes to the campaign
(as incumbents often do) a massive election “war chest”? See BCRA
§§304, 316, and 319. And is it mere happenstance, do you estimate,
that national-party funding, which is severely limited by the Act,
is more likely to assist cash-strapped challengers than
flush-with-hard-money incumbents? See A. Gierzynski &
D. Breaux, The Financing Role of Parties, in Campaign Finance
in State Legislative Elections 195–200 (J. Thompson &
S. Moncrief eds. 1998). Was it unintended, by any chance, that
incumbents are free personally to receive some soft money and even
to solicit it for other organizations, while national parties are
not? See new FECA §§323(a) and (e).
I wish to address three fallacious
propositions that might be thought to justify some or all of the
provisions of this legislation—only the last of which is explicitly
embraced by the principal opinion for the Court, but all of which
underlie, I think, its approach to these cases.
(a) Money is Not Speech
It was said by congressional
proponents of this legislation, see 143 Cong. Rec. 20746 (1997)
(remarks of Sen. Boxer), 145 Cong. Rec. S12612 (Oct. 14, 1999)
(remarks of Sen. Cleland), 147 Cong. Rec. S2436 (Mar. 19, 2001)
(remarks of Sen. Dodd), with support from the law reviews, see, e.g. , Wright, Politics and the Constitution: Is Money
Speech?, 85 Yale L. J. 1001 (1976), that since this
legislation regulates nothing but the expenditure of money for
speech, as opposed to speech itself, the burden it imposes is not
subject to full First Amendment scrutiny; the government may
regulate the raising and spending of campaign funds just as it
regulates other forms of conduct, such as burning draft cards, see United States v. O’Brien, 391 U. S. 367 (1968), or
camping out on the National Mall, see Clark v. Community for Creative
Non&nbhyph;Violence, 468 U. S. 288 (1984).
That proposition has been endorsed by one of the two authors of
today’s principal opinion: “The right to use one’s own money to
hire gladiators, [and] to fund ‘speech by proxy,’ … [are] property
rights . . . not entitled to the same protection as the right to
say what one pleases.” Nixon v. Shrink Missouri
Government PAC, 528 U. S. 377 , 399
(2000) (Stevens, J., concurring). Until today, however, that view
has been categorically rejected by our jurisprudence. As we said in Buckley, 424 U. S., at 16, “this Court has never suggested
that the dependence of a communication on the expenditure of money
operates itself to introduce a nonspeech element or to reduce the
exacting scrutiny required by the First Amendment.”
Our traditional view was correct,
and today’s cavalier attitude toward regulating the financing of
speech (the “exacting scrutiny” test of Buckley , see ibid. , is not uttered in any majority opinion, and is not
observed in the ones from which I dissent) frustrates the
fundamental purpose of the First Amendment. In any economy operated
on even the most rudimentary principles of division of labor,
effective public communication requires the speaker to make use of
the services of others. An author may write a novel, but he will
seldom publish and distribute it himself. A freelance reporter may
write a story, but he will rarely edit, print, and deliver it to
subscribers. To a government bent on suppressing speech, this mode
of organization presents opportunities: Control any cog in the
machine, and you can halt the whole apparatus. License printers,
and it matters little whether authors are still free to write.
Restrict the sale of books, and it matters little who prints them.
Predictably, repressive regimes have exploited these principles by
attacking all levels of the production and dissemination of ideas.
See, e.g. , Printing Act of 1662, 14 Car. II, c. 33, §§1,
4, 7 (punishing printers, importers, and booksellers); Printing Act
of 1649, 2 Acts and Ordinances of the Interregnum 245, 246, 250
(punishing authors, printers, booksellers, importers, and buyers).
In response to this threat, we have interpreted the First Amendment
broadly. See, e.g. , Bantam Books, Inc. v. Sullivan, 372 U. S. 58 , 65,
n. 6 (1963) (“The constitutional guarantee of freedom of the
press embraces the circulation of books as well as their
publication …”).
Division of labor requires a means of
mediating exchange, and in a commercial society, that means is
supplied by money. The publisher pays the author for the right to
sell his book; it pays its staff who print and assemble the book;
it demands payments from booksellers who bring the book to market.
This, too, presents opportunities for repression: Instead of
regulating the various parties to the enterprise individually, the
government can suppress their ability to coordinate by regulating
their use of money. What good is the right to print books without a
right to buy works from authors? Or the right to publish newspapers
without the right to pay deliverymen? The right to speak would be
largely ineffective if it did not include the right to engage in
financial transactions that are the incidents of its exercise.
This is not to say that any regulation of money is a regulation of speech. The government may
apply general commercial regulations to those who use money for
speech if it applies them evenhandedly to those who use money for
other purposes. But where the government singles out money used to
fund speech as its legislative object, it is acting against speech
as such, no less than if it had targeted the paper on which a book
was printed or the trucks that deliver it to the bookstore.
History and jurisprudence bear this out. The
best early examples derive from the British efforts to tax the
press after the lapse of licensing statutes by which the press was
first regulated. The Stamp Act of 1712 imposed levies on all
newspapers, including an additional tax for each advertisement. 10
Anne, c. 18, §113. It was a response to unfavorable war coverage,
“obvious[ly] … designed to check the publication of those
newspapers and pamphlets which depended for their sale on their
cheapness and sensationalism.” F. Siebert, Freedom of the
Press in England, 1476–1776, pp. 309–310 (1952). It succeeded
in killing off approximately half the newspapers in England in its
first year. Id. , at 312. In 1765, Parliament applied a
similar Act to the Colonies. 5 Geo. III, c. 12, §1. The colonial
Act likewise placed exactions on sales and advertising revenue, the
latter at 2s. per advertisement, which was “by any standard . . .
excessive, since the publisher himself received only from 3 to 5s.
and still less for repeated insertions.” A. Schlesinger, Prelude to
Independence: The Newspaper War on Britain, 1764–1776, p. 68
(1958). The founding generation saw these taxes as grievous
incursions on the freedom of the press. See, e.g. , 1
D. Ramsay, History of the American Revolution 61–62 (L. Cohen
ed. 1990); J. Adams, A Dissertation on the Canon and Feudal
Law (1765), reprinted in 3 Life and Works of John Adams 445, 464
(C. Adams ed. 1851). See generally Grosjean v. American Press Co., 297 U. S. 233 , 245–249
(1936); Schlesinger, supra, at 67–84.
We have kept faith with the Founders’
tradition by prohibiting the selective taxation of the press. Minneapolis Star & Tribune Co. v. Minnesota Comm’r
of Revenue, 460 U. S. 575 (1983)
(ink and paper tax); Grosjean , supra (advertisement tax). And we have done so whether the tax was the
product of illicit motive or not. See Minneapolis Star &
Tribune Co., supra , at 592. These press-taxation cases belie
the claim that regulation of money used to fund speech is not
regulation of speech itself. A tax on a newspaper’s advertising
revenue does not prohibit anyone from saying anything; it merely
appropriates part of the revenue that a speaker would otherwise
obtain. That is even a step short of totally prohibiting
advertising revenue— which would be analogous to the total
prohibition of certain campaign-speech contributions in the present
cases. Yet it is unquestionably a violation of the First
Amendment.
Many other cases exemplify the same principle
that an attack upon the funding of speech is an attack upon speech
itself. In Schaumburg v. Citizens for a Better
Environment, 444 U. S. 620 (1980), we
struck down an ordinance limiting the amount charities could pay
their solicitors. In Simon & Schuster, Inc. v. Members of N. Y. State Crime Victims Bd., 502 U. S. 105 (1991), we
held unconstitutional a state statute that appropriated the
proceeds of criminals’ biographies for payment to the victims. And
in Rosenberger v. Rector and Visitors of Univ. of
Va., 515
U. S. 819 (1995), we held unconstitutional a university’s
discrimination in the disbursement of funds to speakers on the
basis of viewpoint. Most notable, perhaps, is our famous opinion in New York Times Co. v. Sullivan, 376 U. S. 254 (1964),
holding that paid advertisements in a newspaper were entitled to
full First Amendment protection:
“Any other conclusion would discourage newspapers
from carrying ‘editorial advertisements’ of this type, and so might
shut off an important outlet for the promulgation of information
and ideas by persons who do not themselves have access to
publishing facilities—who wish to exercise their freedom of speech
even though they are not members of the press. The effect would be
to shackle the First Amendment in its attempt to secure ‘the widest
possible dissemination of information from diverse and antagonistic
sources.’ ” Id ., at 266 (citations omitted).
This passage was relied on in Buckley for
the point that restrictions on the expenditure of money for speech
are equivalent to restrictions on speech itself. 424 U. S., at
16–17. That reliance was appropriate. If denying protection to
paid-for speech would “shackle the First Amendment,” so also does
forbidding or limiting the right to pay for speech.
It should be obvious, then, that a law
limiting the amount a person can spend to broadcast his political
views is a direct restriction on speech. That is no different from
a law limiting the amount a newspaper can pay its editorial staff
or the amount a charity can pay its leafletters. It is equally
clear that a limit on the amount a candidate can raise from any one individual for the purpose of speaking is also a
direct limitation on speech. That is no different from a law
limiting the amount a publisher can accept from any one shareholder
or lender, or the amount a newspaper can charge any one advertiser
or customer.
(b) Pooling Money is Not Speech
Another proposition which could
explain at least some of the results of today’s opinion is that the
First Amendment right to spend money for speech does not include
the right to combine with others in spending money for speech. Such
a proposition fits uncomfortably with the concluding words of our
Declaration of Independence: “And for the support of this
Declaration, . . . we mutually pledge to each other our Lives, our Fortunes and our sacred Honor.” (Emphasis added.) The
freedom to associate with others for the dissemination of ideas—not
just by singing or speaking in unison, but by pooling financial
resources for expressive purposes—is part of the freedom of
speech.
“Our form of government is built on the premise
that every citizen shall have the right to engage in political
expression and association. This right was enshrined in the First
Amendment of the Bill of Rights. Exercise of these basic freedoms
in America has traditionally been through the media of political
associations. Any interference with the freedom of a party is
simultaneously an interference with the freedom of its adherents.” NAACP v. Button , 371 U. S. 415 , 431
(1963) (internal quotation marks omitted).
“The First Amendment protects political association as well as
political expression. The constitutional right of association
explicated in NAACP v. Alabama, 357 U. S. 449 , 460
(1958), stemmed from the Court’s recognition that ‘[e]ffective
advocacy of both public and private points of view, particularly
controversial ones, is undeniably enhanced by group association.’
Subsequent decisions have made clear that the First and Fourteenth
Amendments guarantee ‘ “freedom to associate with others for
the common advancement of political beliefs and ideas,” ’
… .” Buckley, supra, at 15.
We have said that “implicit in the right to engage
in activities protected by the First Amendment” is “a corresponding
right to associate with others in pursuit of a wide variety of
political, social, economic, educational, religious, and cultural
ends.” Roberts v. United States
Jaycees, 468 U. S. 609 , 622
(1984). That “right to associate . . . in pursuit” includes the
right to pool financial resources.
If it were otherwise, Congress would be
empowered to enact legislation requiring newspapers to be sole
proprietorships, banning their use of partnership or corporate
form. That sort of restriction would be an obvious violation of the
First Amendment, and it is incomprehensible why the conclusion
should change when what is at issue is the pooling of funds for the
most important (and most perennially threatened) category of
speech: electoral speech. The principle that such financial
association does not enjoy full First Amendment protection
threatens the existence of all political parties.
(c) Speech by Corporations Can Be Abridged
The last proposition that might
explain at least some of today’s casual abridgment of free-speech
rights is this: that the particular form of association known as a
corporation does not enjoy full First Amendment protection. Of
course the text of the First Amendment does not limit its
application in this fashion, even though “[b]y the end of the
eighteenth century the corporation was a familiar figure in
American economic life.” C. Cooke, Corporation, Trust and Company
92 (1951). Nor is there any basis in reason why First Amendment
rights should not attach to corporate associations—and we have said
so. In First Nat. Bank of Boston v. Bellotti, 435 U. S. 765 (1978), we
held unconstitutional a state prohibition of corporate speech
designed to influence the vote on referendum proposals. We
said:
“[T]here is practically universal
agreement that a major purpose of [the First] Amendment was to
protect the free discussion of governmental affairs. If the
speakers here were not corporations, no one would suggest that the
State could silence their proposed speech. It is the type of speech
indispensable to decisionmaking in a democracy, and this is no less
true because the speech comes from a corporation rather than an
individual. The inherent worth of the speech in terms of its
capacity for informing the public does not depend upon the identity
of its source, whether corporation, association, union, or
individual.” Id. , at 776–777 (internal quotation marks,
footnotes, and citations omitted).
In NAACP v. Button, supra , at
428–429, 431, we held that the NAACP could assert First Amendment
rights “on its own behalf, . . . though a corporation,” and that
the activities of the corporation were “modes of expression and
association protected by the First and Fourteenth Amendments.” In Pacific Gas & Elec. Co. v. Public Util. Comm’n of
Cal. , 475 U. S.
1 , 8 (1986), we held unconstitutional a state effort to compel
corporate speech. “The identity of the speaker,” we said, “is not
decisive in determining whether speech is protected. Corporations
and other associations, like individuals, contribute to the
‘discussion, debate, and the dissemination of information and
ideas’ that the First Amendment seeks to foster.” And in Buckley , 424 U. S. 1 , we held unconstitutional
FECA’s limitation upon independent corporate expenditures.
The Court changed course in Austin v. Michigan Chamber of Commerce , 494 U. S. 652 (1990),
upholding a state prohibition of an independent corporate
expenditure in support of a candidate for state office. I dissented
in that case, see id ., at 679, and remain of the view that
it was error. In the modern world, giving the government power to
exclude corporations from the political debate enables it
effectively to muffle the voices that best represent the most
significant segments of the economy and the most passionately held
social and political views. People who associate—who pool their
financial resources—for purposes of economic enterprise
overwhelmingly do so in the corporate form; and with increasing
frequency, incorporation is chosen by those who associate to defend
and promote particular ideas—such as the American Civil Liberties
Union and the National Rifle Association, parties to these cases.
Imagine, then, a government that wished to suppress nuclear
power—or oil and gas exploration, or automobile manufacturing, or
gun ownership, or civil liberties—and that had the power to
prohibit corporate advertising against its proposals. To be sure,
the individuals involved in, or benefited by, those industries, or
interested in those causes, could (given enough time) form
political action committees or other associations to make their
case. But the organizational form in which those enterprises
already exist , and in which they can most quickly and most
effectively get their message across, is the corporate form. The
First Amendment does not in my view permit the restriction of that
political speech. And the same holds true for corporate electoral
speech: A candidate should not be insulated from the most effective
speech that the major participants in the economy and major
incorporated interest groups can generate.
But what about the danger to the political
system posed by “amassed wealth”? The most direct threat from that
source comes in the form of undisclosed favors and payoffs to
elected officials—which have already been criminalized, and will be
rendered no more discoverable by the legislation at issue here. The
use of corporate wealth (like individual wealth) to speak to the
electorate is unlikely to “distort” elections— especially if disclosure requirements tell the people where the
speech is coming from. The premise of the First Amendment is that
the American people are neither sheep nor fools, and hence fully
capable of considering both the substance of the speech presented
to them and its proximate and ultimate source. If that premise is
wrong, our democracy has a much greater problem to overcome than
merely the influence of amassed wealth. Given the premises of
democracy, there is no such thing as too much speech.
But, it is argued, quite apart from its effect
upon the electorate, corporate speech in the form of contributions
to the candidate’s campaign, or even in the form of independent
expenditures supporting the candidate, engenders an obligation
which is later paid in the form of greater access to the
officeholder, or indeed in the form of votes on particular bills.
Any quid-pro-quo agreement for votes would of course
violate criminal law, see 18 U. S. C. §201, and actual payoff votes have not even been claimed by those favoring the
restrictions on corporate speech. It cannot be denied, however,
that corporate (like noncorporate) allies will have greater access
to the officeholder, and that he will tend to favor the same causes
as those who support him (which is usually why they
supported him). That is the nature of politics—if not indeed human
nature—and how this can properly be considered “corruption” (or
“the appearance of corruption”) with regard to corporate allies and
not with regard to other allies is beyond me. If the Bill of Rights
had intended an exception to the freedom of speech in order to
combat this malign proclivity of the officeholder to agree with
those who agree with him, and to speak more with his supporters
than his opponents, it would surely have said so. It did not do so,
I think, because the juice is not worth the squeeze. Evil corporate
(and private affluent) influences are well enough checked (so long
as adequate campaign-expenditure disclosure rules exist) by the
politician’s fear of being portrayed as “in the pocket” of
so-called moneyed interests. The incremental benefit obtained by
muzzling corporate speech is more than offset by loss of the
information and persuasion that corporate speech can contain. That,
at least, is the assumption of a constitutional guarantee which
prescribes that Congress shall make no law abridging the freedom of
speech.
But let us not be deceived. While the
Government’s briefs and arguments before this Court focused on the
horrible “appearance of corruption,” the most passionate floor
statements during the debates on this legislation pertained to
so-called attack ads, which the Constitution surely protects, but
which Members of Congress analogized to “crack cocaine,” 144 Cong.
Rec. S868 (Feb. 24, 1998) (remarks of Sen. Daschle), “drive-by
shooting[s],” id., at S879 (remarks of Sen. Durbin), and
“air pollution,” 143 Cong. Rec. 20505 (1997) (remarks of Sen.
Dorgan). There is good reason to believe that the ending of
negative campaign ads was the principal attraction of the
legislation. A Senate sponsor said, “I hope that we will not allow
our attention to be distracted from the real issues at hand—how to
raise the tenor of the debate in our elections and give people real
choices. No one benefits from negative ads. They don’t aid our
Nation’s political dialog.” Id., at 20521–20522 (remarks
of Sen. McCain). He assured the body that “[y]ou cut off the soft
money, you are going to see a lot less of that [attack ads].
Prohibit unions and corporations, and you will see a lot less of
that. If you demand full disclosure for those who pay for those
ads, you are going to see a lot less of that . . . .” 147 Cong.
Rec. S3116 (Mar. 29, 2001) (remarks of Sen. McCain). See also, e.g. , 148 Cong. Rec. S2117 (Mar. 20, 2002) (remarks of
Sen. Cantwell) (“This bill is about slowing the ad war. . . . It is
about slowing political advertising and making sure the flow of
negative ads by outside interest groups does not continue to
permeate the airwaves”); 143 Cong. Rec. 20746 (1997) (remarks of
Sen. Boxer) (“These so-called issues ads are not regulated at all
and mention candidates by name. They directly attack candidates
without any accountability. It is brutal… . We have an
opportunity in the McCain-Feingold bill to stop that . . .”); 145
Cong. Rec. S12606–S12607 (Oct. 14, 1999) (remarks of Sen.
Wellstone) (“I think these issue advocacy ads are a nightmare. I
think all of us should hate them… . [By passing the
legislation], [w]e could get some of this poison politics off
television”).
Another theme prominent in the legislative
debates was the notion that there is too much money spent on
elections. The first principle of “reform” was that “there should
be less money in politics.” 147 Cong. Rec. S3236 (Apr. 2, 2001)
(remarks of Sen. Murray). “The enormous amounts of special interest
money that flood our political system have become a cancer in our
democracy.” 148 Cong. Rec. S2151 (Mar. 20, 2002) (remarks of Sen.
Kennedy). “[L]arge sums of money drown out the voice of the average
voter.” 148 Cong. Rec. H373 (Feb. 13, 2002) (remarks of Rep.
Langevin). The system of campaign finance is “drowning in money.” Id., at H404 (remarks of Rep. Menendez). And most
expansively:
“Despite the ever-increasing sums spent on
campaigns, we have not seen an improvement in campaign discourse,
issue discussion or voter education. More money does not mean more
ideas, more substance or more depth. Instead, it means more of what
voters complain about most. More 30-second spots, more negativity
and an increasingly longer campaign period.” 148 Cong. Rec. S2150
(Mar. 20, 2002) (remarks of Sen. Kerry).
Perhaps voters do detest these 30-second
spots—though I suspect they detest even more hour-long
campaign-debate interruptions of their favorite entertainment
programming. Evidently, however, these ads do persuade voters, or else they would not be so routinely used by
sophisticated politicians of all parties. The point, in any event,
is that it is not the proper role of those who govern us to judge
which campaign speech has “substance” and “depth” (do you think it
might be that which is least damaging to incumbents?) and to
abridge the rest.
And what exactly are these outrageous sums
frittered away in determining who will govern us? A report prepared
for Congress concluded that the total amount, in hard and soft
money, spent on the 2000 federal elections was between $2.4 and
$2.5 billion. J. Cantor, CRS Report for Congress, Campaign Finance
in the 2000 Federal Elections: Overview and Estimates of the Flow
of Money (2001). All campaign spending in the United
States, including state elections, ballot initiatives, and judicial
elections, has been estimated at $3.9 billion for 2000, Nelson,
Spending in the 2000 Elections, in Financing the 2000 Election 24,
Tbl. 2–1 (D. Magleby ed. 2002), which was a year that “shattered
spending and contribution records,” id. , at 22. Even
taking this last, larger figure as the benchmark, it means that
Americans spent about half as much electing all their Nation’s
officials, state and federal, as they spent on movie tickets ($7.8
billion); about a fifth as much as they spent on cosmetics and
perfume ($18.8 billion); and about a sixth as much as they spent on
pork (the nongovernmental sort) ($22.8 billion). See U. S. Dept. of
Commerce, Bureau of Economic Analysis, Tbl. 2.6U (Col. AS; Rows
356, 214, and 139), http:// www.bea.doc.gov/bea/dn/206u.csv. If our
democracy is drowning from this much spending, it cannot swim.
* * *
Which brings me back to where I
began: This litigation is about preventing criticism of the
government. I cannot say for certain that many, or some, or even
any, of the Members of Congress who voted for this legislation did
so not to produce “fairer” campaigns, but to mute criticism of
their records and facilitate reelection. Indeed, I will stipulate
that all those who voted for the Act believed they were acting for
the good of the country. There remains the problem of the Charlie
Wilson Phenomenon, named after Charles Wilson, former president of
General Motors, who is supposed to have said during the Senate
hearing on his nomination as Secretary of Defense that “what’s good
for General Motors is good for the country.”* Those in power, even
giving them the benefit of the greatest good will, are inclined to
believe that what is good for them is good for the country. Whether
in prescient recognition of the Charlie Wilson Phenomenon, or out
of fear of good old-fashioned, malicious, self-interested
manipulation, “[t]he fundamental approach of the First Amendment .
. . was to assume the worst, and to rule the regulation of
political speech ‘for fairness’ sake’ simply out of bounds.” Austin , 494 U. S., at 693 (Scalia, J., dissenting). Having
abandoned that approach to a limited extent in Buckley , we
abandon it much further today.
We will unquestionably be called upon to
abandon it further still in the future. The most frightening
passage in the lengthy floor debates on this legislation is the
following assurance given by one of the cosponsoring Senators to
his colleagues:
“This is a modest step, it is a first step, it is
an essential step, but it does not even begin to address, in some
ways, the fundamental problems that exist with the hard money
aspect of the system.” 148 Cong. Rec. S2101 (Mar. 20, 2002)
(statement of Sen. Feingold).
The system indeed. The first instinct of power is
the retention of power, and, under a Constitution that requires
periodic elections, that is best achieved by the suppression of
election-time speech. We have witnessed merely the second scene of
Act I of what promises to be a lengthy tragedy. In scene 3 the
Court, having abandoned most of the First Amendment weaponry that Buckley left intact, will be even less equipped to resist
the incumbents’ writing of the rules of political debate. The
federal election campaign laws, which are already (as today’s
opinions show) so voluminous, so detailed, so complex, that no
ordinary citizen dare run for office, or even contribute a
significant sum, without hiring an expert advisor in the field, can
be expected to grow more voluminous, more detailed, and more
complex in the years to come—and always, always, with the objective
of reducing the excessive amount of speech.
* It is disillusioning to learn that the
fabled quote is inaccurate. Wilson actually said: “[F]or years I
thought what was good for our country was good for General Motors,
and vice versa. The difference did not exist.” Hearings before the
Senate Committee on Armed Services, 83d Cong., 1st Sess., 26
(1953). OPINION OF THOMAS, J. MCCONNELL V. FEDERAL ELECTION COMM'N 540 U. S. ____ (2003) SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES NOS. 02-1674, 02-1675, 02-1676, 02-1702, 02-1727, 02-1733,
02-1734;02-1740, 02-1747, 02-1753, 02-1755, AND
02-1756 MITCH McCONNELL, UNITED STATES SENATOR,
et al., APPELLANTS
02–1674 v .
FEDERAL ELECTION COMMISSION, et al.;
NATIONAL RIFLE ASSOCIATION, et al.,
APPELLANTS
02–1675 v .
FEDERAL ELECTION COMMISSION, et al.;
FEDERAL ELECTION COMMISSION, et al.,
APPELLANTS
02–1676 v .
MITCH McCONNELL, UNITED STATES SENATOR,
et al.;
JOHN McCAIN, UNITED STATES SENATOR, et al.,
APPELLANTS
02–1702 v .
MITCH McCONNELL, UNITED STATES SENATOR,
et al.;
REPUBLICAN NATIONAL COMMITTEE, et al.,
APPELLANTS
02–1727 v .
FEDERAL ELECTION COMMISSION, et al.;
NATIONAL RIGHT TO LIFE COMMITTEE, INC.,
et al., APPELLANTS
02–1733 v .
FEDERAL ELECTION COMMISSION, et al.;
AMERICAN CIVIL LIBERTIES UNION, APPELLANTS
02–1734 v .
FEDERAL ELECTION COMMISSION, et al.;
VICTORIA JACKSON GRAY ADAMS, et al.,
APPELLANTS
02–1740 v .
FEDERAL ELECTION COMMISSION, et al.;
RON PAUL, UNITED STATES CONGRESSMAN, et al.,
APPELLANTS
02–1747 v .
FEDERAL ELECTION COMMISSION, et al.;
CALIFORNIA DEMOCRATIC PARTY, et al.,
APPELLANTS
02–1753 v .
FEDERAL ELECTION COMMISSION, et al.;
AMERICAN FEDERATION OF LABOR AND CONGRESS OF
INDUSTRIAL ORGANIZATIONS, et al., APPELLANTS
02–1755 v .
FEDERAL ELECTION COMMISSION, et al.;
CHAMBER OF COMMERCE OF THE UNITED STATES,
et al., APPELLANTS
02–1756 v .
FEDERAL ELECTION COMMISSION, et al.
on appeals from the united states district court
for the district of columbia
[December 10, 2003]
Justice Thomas, concurring with
respect to BCRA Titles III and IV, except for BCRA §§311 and 318,
concurring in the result with respect to BCRA §318, concurring in
the judgment in part and dissenting in part with respect to BCRA
Title II, and dissenting with respect to BCRA Titles I, V, and
§311.*
The First Amendment provides that
“Congress shall make no law … abridging the freedom of speech.”
Nevertheless, the Court today upholds what can only be described as
the most significant abridgment of the freedoms of speech and
association since the Civil War. With breathtaking scope, the
Bipartisan Campaign Reform Act of 2002 (BCRA), directly targets and
constricts core political speech, the “primary object of First
Amendment protection.” Nixon v. Shrink Missouri
Government PAC, 528 U. S. 377 , 410–411
(2000) (Thomas, J., dissenting). Because “the First Amendment ’has
its fullest and most urgent application’ to speech uttered during a
campaign for political office,” Eu v. San Francisco
County Democratic Central Comm., 489 U. S. 214 , 223
(1989) (quoting Monitor Patriot Co. v. Roy, 401 U. S. 265 , 272
(1971)), our duty is to approach these restrictions “with the
utmost skepticism” and subject them to the “strictest scrutiny.” Shrink Missouri , supra , at 412 (Thomas, J.,
dissenting).
In response to this assault on the free
exchange of ideas and with only the slightest consideration of the
appropriate standard of review or of the Court’s traditional role
of protecting First Amendment freedoms, the Court has placed its imprimatur on these unprecedented restrictions. The very
“purpose of the First Amendment [is] to preserve an uninhibited
marketplace of ideas in which truth will ultimately prevail.” Red Lion Broadcasting Co. v. FCC, 395 U. S. 367 , 390
(1969). Yet today the fundamental principle that “the best test of
truth is the power of the thought to get itself accepted in the
competition of the market,” Abrams v. United
States, 250 U. S. 616 , 630
(1919) (Holmes, J., dissenting), is cast aside in the purported
service of preventing “corruption,” or the mere “appearance of
corruption.” Buckley v. Valeo, 424 U. S. 1 , 26 (1976) (per curiam). Apparently, the marketplace of ideas is to
be fully open only to defamers, New York Times Co. v. Sullivan, 376 U. S. 254 (1964);
nude dancers, Barnes v. Glen Theatre,
Inc., 501
U. S. 560 (1991) (plurality opinion); pornographers, Ashcroft v. Free Speech Coalition, 535 U. S. 234 (2002);
flag burners, United States v. Eichman, 496 U. S. 310 (1990);
and cross burners, Virginia v. Black, 538 U. S.
___ (2003).
Because I cannot agree with the treatment
given by Justice Stevens’ and Justice O’Connor’s opinion
(hereinafter joint opinion) to speech that is “indispensable to the
effective and intelligent use of the processes of popular
government to shape the destiny of modern industrial society,” Thornhill v. Alabama, 310 U. S. 88 , 103 (1940),
I respectfully dissent. I also dissent from Justice Breyer’s
opinion upholding BCRA §504. I join The Chief Justice’s opinion in
regards to BCRA §§304, 305, 307, 316, 319, and 403(b); concur in
the result as to §318; and dissent from the opinion as to §311. I
also fully agree with Justice Kennedy’s discussion of §213 and join
that portion of his opinion. Post , at 37–38.
I
A
“[C]ampaign finance laws are
subject to strict scrutiny,” Federal Election Comm’n v. Beaumont , 539 U. S. ___, ___ (2003) (slip op., at 1)
(Thomas, J., dissenting), and thus Title I must satisfy that
demanding standard even if it were (incorrectly) conceived of as
nothing more than a contribution limitation. The defendants do not
even attempt to defend Title I under this standard, and for good
reason: The various restrictions imposed by Title I are much less
narrowly tailored to target only corrupting or problematic
donations than even the contribution limits in Shrink
Missouri . See 528 U. S., at 427–430 (Thomas, J., dissenting);
see also Colorado Republican Federal Campaign Comm. v. Federal Election Comm’n, 518 U. S. 604 , 641–644
(1996) (Thomas, J., dissenting) (Colorado I). And, as I
have previously noted, it is unclear why “[b]ribery laws [that] bar
precisely the quid pro quo arrangements that are targeted
here” and “disclosure laws” are not “less restrictive means of
addressing [the Government’s] interest in curtailing corruption.” Shrink Missouri , supra , at 428.
The joint opinion not only
continues the errors of Buckley v. Valeo, by
applying a low level of scrutiny to contribution ceilings, but also
builds upon these errors by expanding the anticircumvention
rationale beyond reason. Admittedly, exploitation of an
anticircumvention concept has a long pedigree, going back at least
to Buckley itself. Buckley upheld a $1,000
contribution ceiling as a way to combat both the “actuality and
appearance of corruption.” 424 U. S., at 26. The challengers in Buckley contended both that bribery laws represented “a
less restrictive means of dealing with ‘proven and suspected quid pro quo arrangements,’ ” id ., at 27,
and that the $1,000 contribution ceiling was overbroad as “most
large contributors do not seek improper influence over a
candidate’s position or an officeholder’s action,” id ., at
29. The Court rejected the first argument on the grounds that “laws
making criminal the giving and taking of bribes deal with only the
most blatant and specific attempts of those with money to influence
governmental action,” id ., at 27–28, and rejected the
second on the grounds that “it [is] difficult to isolate suspect
contributions,” id ., at 30.[ Footnote 1 ] But a broadly drawn bribery law[ Footnote 2 ] would cover even subtle and
general attempts to influence government officials corruptly,
eliminating the Court’s first concern. And, an effective bribery
law would deter actual quid pro quos and would, in all
likelihood, eliminate any appearance of corruption in the
system.
Hence, at root, the Buckley Court was
concerned that bribery laws could not be effectively enforced to
prevent quid pro quos between donors and officeholders,
and the only rational reading of Buckley is that it
approved the $1,000 contribution ceiling on this ground. The Court
then, however, having at least in part concluded that individual
contribution ceilings were necessary to prevent easy evasion of
bribery laws, proceeded to uphold a separate contribution
limitation, using, as the only justification, the “prevent[ion]
[of] evasion of the $1,000 contribution limitation.” Id .,
at 38. The need to prevent circumvention of a limitation that was
itself an anticircumvention measure led to the upholding of another
significant restriction on individuals’ freedom of speech.
The joint opinion now repeats this process.
New Federal Election Campaign Act of 1971 (FECA) §323(a), 2 U.
S. C. A. §441i(a) (Supp. 2003), is intended to prevent
easy circumvention of the (now) $2,000 contribution ceiling. The
joint opinion even recognizes this, relying heavily on evidence
that, for instance, “candidates and donors alike have in fact
exploited the soft-money loophole, the former to increase their
prospects of election and the latter to create debt on the part of
officeholders, with the national parties serving as willing
intermediaries.” Ante , at 36. The joint opinion upholds
§323(a), in part, on the grounds that it had become too easy to
circumvent the $2,000 cap by using the national parties as
go-betweens.
And the remaining provisions of new FECA §323
are upheld mostly as measures preventing circumvention of other
contribution limits, including §323(a), ante, at 55–57
(§323(b)); ante, at 66–69 (§323(d)); ante, at 75
(§323(e)); ante, at 77–78 (§323(f)), which, as I have
already explained, is a second-order anticircumvention measure. The
joint opinion’s handling of §323(f) is perhaps most telling, as it
upholds §323(f) only because of “Congress’ eminently reasonable prediction that … state and local candidates and
officeholders will become the next conduits for the soft-money
funding of sham issue advertising.” Ante, at 78 (emphasis
added). That is, this Court upholds a third-order anticircumvention
measure based on Congress’ anticipation of circumvention of these
second-order anticircumvention measures that might possibly, at
some point in the future, pose some problem.
It is not difficult to see where this leads.
Every law has limits, and there will always be behavior not covered
by the law but at its edges; behavior easily characterized as
“circumventing” the law’s prohibition. Hence, speech regulation
will again expand to cover new forms of “circumvention,” only to
spur supposed circumvention of the new regulations, and so forth.
Rather than permit this never-ending and self-justifying process, I
would require that the Government explain why proposed speech
restrictions are needed in light of actual Government interests,
and, in particular, why the bribery laws are not sufficient.
B
But Title I falls even on the
joint opinion’s terms. This Court has held that “[t]he quantum of
empirical evidence needed to satisfy heightened judicial scrutiny
of legislative judgments will vary up or down with the novelty and
plausibility of the justification raised.” Shrink
Missouri , 528 U. S., at 391. And three Members of today’s
majority have observed that “the opportunity for corruption”
presented by “[u]nregulated ‘soft money’ contributions” is “at
best, attenuated.” Colorado I , 518 U. S., at 616 (opinion
of Breyer, J., joined by O’Connor and Souter, JJ.). Such an
observation is quite clearly correct. A donation to a political
party is a clumsy method by which to influence a candidate, as the
party is free to spend the donation however it sees fit, and could
easily spend the money as to provide no help to the candidate. And,
a soft-money donation to a party will be of even less benefit to a
candidate, “because of legal restrictions on how the money may be
spent.” Brief for FEC et al. in No. 02–1674 et al.,
p. 43. It follows that the defendants bear an especially heavy
empirical burden in justifying Title I.
The evidence cited by the joint
opinion does not meet this standard and would barely suffice for
anything more than rational-basis review. The first category of the
joint opinion’s evidence is evidence that “federal officeholders
have commonly asked donors to make soft-money donations to national
and state committees solely in order to assist federal campaigns,
including the officeholder’s own.” Ante , at 36 (internal
quotation marks omitted). But to the extent that donors and federal
officeholders have collaborated so that donors could give donations
to a national party committee “for the purpose of influencing any
election for Federal office,” the alleged soft-money donation is in
actuality a regular “contribution” as already defined and regulated
by FECA. See 2 U. S. C. §431(8)(A)(i). Neither the joint
opinion nor the defendants present evidence that enforcement of
pre-BCRA law has proved to be impossible, ineffective, or even
particularly difficult.
The second category is evidence that
“lobbyists, CEOs, and wealthy individuals” have “donat[ed]
substantial sums of soft money to national committees not on
ideological grounds, but for the express purpose of securing
influence over federal officials.” Ante , at 37. Even if
true (and the cited evidence consists of nothing more than vague
allegations of wrongdoing), it is unclear why existing bribery laws
could not address this problem. Again, neither the joint opinion
nor the defendants point to evidence that the enforcement of
bribery laws has been or would be ineffective. If the problem has
been clear and widespread, as the joint opinion suggests, I would
expect that convictions, or at least prosecutions, would be more
frequent.
The third category is evidence characterized
by the joint opinion as “connect[ing] soft money to manipulations
of the legislative calendar, leading to Congress’ failure to enact,
among other things, generic drug legislation, tort reform, and
tobacco legislation.” Ante , at 40. But the evidence for
this is no stronger than the evidence that there has been actual
vote buying or vote switching for soft money. The joint opinion’s
citations to the record do not stand for the propositions that they
claim. For instance, the McCain declaration does not provide any
evidence of any exchange of legislative action for donations of any
kind (hard or soft).[ Footnote
3 ] Neither do the Simpson or Simon declarations, with perhaps
one exception effectively addressed by Justice Kennedy’s
opinion.[ Footnote 4 ] See post , at 18–19. In fact, the findings by two of the
District Court’s judges confirm that the evidence of any quid
pro quo corruption is exceedingly weak, if not nonexistent.
See 251 F. Supp. 2d 176, 349–352 (DC 2003) (Henderson, J.,
concurring in judgment in part and dissenting in part); id ., at 851–853 (Leon, J.). The evidence cited by the
joint opinion is properly described as “at best, [the Members of
Congress’] personal conjecture regarding the impact of soft money
donations on the voting practices of their present and former
colleagues.” Id. , at 852 (Leon, J.).
The joint opinion also places a substantial
amount of weight on the fact that “in 1996 and 2000, more than half
of the top 50 soft-money donors gave substantial sums to both major national parties,” and suggests that this fact
“leav[es] room for no other conclusion but that these donors were
seeking influence, or avoiding retaliation, rather than promoting
any particular ideology.” Ante , at 38 (emphasis in
original). But that is not necessarily the case. The two major
parties are not perfect ideological opposites, and supporters or
opponents of certain policies or ideas might find substantial
overlap between the two parties. If donors feel that both major
parties are in general agreement over an issue of importance to
them, it is unremarkable that such donors show support for both
parties. This commonsense explanation surely belies the joint
opinion’s too-hasty conclusion drawn from a relatively innocent
fact.
The Court today finds such sparse evidence
sufficient. This cannot be held to satisfy even the “relatively
complaisant review” of Beaumont , 539 U. S., at ___ (slip
op., at 14), unless, as it appears, the Court intends to abdicate
entirely its role.[ Footnote
5 ]
II
The Court is not content with
“balanc[ing] away First Amendment freedoms,” Shrink
Missouri, 528 U. S., at 410 (Thomas, J., dissenting), in the
context of the restrictions imposed by Title I, which could
arguably (if wrongly) be thought to be mere contribution limits.
The Court also, in upholding virtually all of Title II, proceeds to
do the same for limitations on expenditures, which constitute
“political expression ‘at the core of our electoral process and of
the First Amendment freedoms,’ ” Buckley, 424 U. S.,
at 39 (quoting Williams v. Rhodes , 393 U. S. 23 , 32 (1968)).
Today’s holding continues a disturbing trend: the steady decrease
in the level of scrutiny applied to restrictions on core political
speech. See Buckley , supra , at 16 (First
Amendment requires “exacting scrutiny”); Shrink Missouri , supra , at 387 (applying “ Buckley ’s standard of
scrutiny”); Beaumont, supra , at ___ (slip op., at 14)
(referencing “relatively complaisant review”).[ Footnote 6 ] Although this trend is most obvious
in the review of contribution limits, it has now reached what even
this Court today would presumably recognize as a direct restriction
on core political speech: limitations on independent
expenditures.
A
Of course, by accepting Congress’
expansion of what constitutes “coordination” for purposes of
treating expenditures as limitations, the Court can pretend that it
is, in fact, still only restricting primarily “contributions.” I
need not say much about this illusion. I have already discussed how
the language used in new FECA §315(a)(7)(B)(ii) is, even under Buckley ’s framework, overly broad and restricts fully
protected speech. See Federal Election Comm’n v. Colorado Republican Federal Campaign Comm., 533 U. S. 431 , 467–468
(2001) (Thomas, J., dissenting) (Colorado II). The
particular language used, “expenditures made by any person … in
cooperation, consultation, or concert with, or at the request or
suggestion of, a national, State, or local committee of a political
party,” BCRA §214(a)(2), captures expenditures with “no
constitutional difference” from “a purely independent one.” Id., at 468 (Thomas, J., dissenting).[ Footnote 7 ] And new FECA
§315(a)(7)(C), although using the neutral term “coordinated,”
certainly has the purpose of “clarif[ying] the scope of the
preceding subsection, §315(a)(7)(B),” ante , at 95 (joint
opinion), and thus should be read to be as expansive as the overly
broad language in §315(a)(7)(B). Hence, it too is
unconstitutional. B As for §§203 and 204,
the Court rests its decision on another vast expansion of the First
Amendment framework described in Buckley , this time of the
Court’s, rather than Congress’, own making. In Austin v. Michigan Chamber of Commerce, 494 U. S. 652 , 659–660
(1990), the Court recognized a “different type of corruption” from
the “ ‘financial quid pro quo’ ” : the “corrosive
and distorting effects of immense aggregations of wealth that are
accumulated with the help of the corporate form and that have
little or no correlation to the public’s support for the
corporation’s political ideas.” The only effect, however, that the
“immense aggregations” of wealth will have (in the context of
independent expenditures) on an election is that they might be used
to fund communications to convince voters to select certain
candidates over others. In other words, the “corrosive and
distorting effects” described in Austin are that
corporations, on behalf of their shareholders, will be able to
convince voters of the correctness of their ideas. Apparently,
winning in the marketplace of ideas is no longer a sign that “the
ultimate good” has been “reached by free trade in ideas,” or that
the speaker has survived “the best test of truth” by having “the
thought … get itself accepted in the competition of the market.” Abrams , 250 U. S., at 630 (Holmes, J., dissenting). It is
now evidence of “corruption.” This conclusion is antithetical to
everything for which the First Amendment stands. See, e.g.,
First Nat. Bank of Boston v. Bellotti, 435 U. S. 765 , 790 (1978) (“[T]he fact
that advocacy may persuade the electorate is hardly a reason to
suppress it”); Kingsley Int’l Pictures Corp. v. Regents of Univ. of N. Y., 360 U. S. 684 , 689
(1959) (“[I]n the realm of ideas [the Constitution] protects
expression which is eloquent no less than that which is
unconvincing”). Because Austin ’s definition of “corruption” is incompatible with
the First Amendment, I would overturn Austin and hold that
the potential for corporations and unions to influence voters, via
independent expenditures aimed at convincing these voters to adopt
particular views, is not a form of corruption justifying any state
regulation or suppression. Without Austin ’s peculiar
variation of “corruption,” §§203 and 204 are supported by no
compelling government interest. The joint opinion does not even
argue that these provisions address quid pro quo corruption.[ Footnote 8 ] And the
shareholder protection rationale is equally unavailing. The
“shareholder invests in a corporation of his own volition and is
free to withdraw his investment at any time and for any reason,” Bellotti, supra , at 794, n. 34. Hence, no
compelling interest can be found in protecting minority
shareholders from the corporation’s use of its general treasury,
especially where, in other contexts, “equally important and
controversial corporate decisions are made by management or by a
predetermined percentage of the shareholders.” Ibid . C I must now address an
issue on which I differ from all of my colleagues: the disclosure
provisions in BCRA §201, now contained in new FECA §304(f). The
“historical evidence indicates that Founding-era Americans opposed
attempts to require that anonymous authors reveal their identities
on the ground that forced disclosure violated the ‘freedom of the
press.’ ” McIntyre v. Ohio Elections
Comm’n, 514 U. S. 334 , 361 (1995) (Thomas, J.,
concurring).[ Footnote 9 ]
Indeed, this Court has explicitly recognized that “the interest in
having anonymous works enter the marketplace of ideas
unquestionably outweighs any public interest in requiring
disclosure as a condition of entry,” and thus that “an author’s
decision to remain anonymous … is an aspect of the freedom of
speech protected by the First Amendment.” Id ., at 342. The
Court now backs away from this principle, allowing the established
right to anonymous speech to be stripped away based on the
flimsiest of justifications. The only plausible
interest asserted by the defendants to justify the disclosure
provisions is the interest in providing “information” about the
speaker to the public. But we have already held that “[t]he simple
interest in providing voters with additional relevant information
does not justify a state requirement that a writer make statements
or disclosures she would otherwise omit.” Id., at 348. Of
course, Buckley upheld the disclosure requirement on
expenditures for communications using words of express advocacy
based on this informational interest. 424 U. S., at 81. And
admittedly, McIntyre purported to distinguish Buckley . McIntyre , supra, at 355–356.
But the two ways McIntyre distinguished Buckley —one, that the disclosure of “an expenditure and
its use, without more, reveals far less information [than a forced
identification of the author of a pamphlet,]” 514 U. S., at 355;
and two, that in candidate elections, the “Government can identify
a compelling state interest in avoiding the corruption that might
result from campaign expenditures,” id ., at 356—are
inherently implausible. The first is simply wrong. The revelation
of one’s political expenditures for independent communications
about candidates can be just as revealing as the revelation of
one’s name on a pamphlet for a noncandidate election. See also id. , at 384 (Scalia, J., dissenting). The second was
outright rejected in Buckley itself, where the Court
concluded that independent expenditures did not create any
substantial risk of real or apparent corruption. 424 U. S., at 47.
Hence, the only reading of McIntyre that remains
consistent with the principles it contains is that it overturned Buckley to the extent that Buckley upheld a
disclosure requirement solely based on the governmental interest in
providing information to the voters. The right to anonymous speech
cannot be abridged based on the interests asserted by the
defendants. I would thus hold that the disclosure requirements of
BCRA §201 are unconstitutional. Because of this conclusion, the
so-called advance disclosure requirement of §201 necessarily falls
as well.[ Footnote
10 ] D I have long
maintained that Buckley was incorrectly decided and should
be overturned. See Colorado II , 533 U. S., at 465; Shrink Missouri , 528 U. S., at 410; Colorado I ,
518 U. S., at 640. But, most of Title II should still be held
unconstitutional even under the Buckley framework. Under Buckley and Federal Election Comm’n v. Massachusetts Citizens for Life, Inc., 479 U. S. 238 (1986) (MCFL) , it is, or at least was, clear that any regulation
of political speech beyond communications using words of express
advocacy is unconstitutional. Hence, even under the joint opinion’s
framework, most of Title II is unconstitutional, as both the
“primary definition” and “backup definition” of “electioneering
communications” cover a significant number of communications that
do not use words of express advocacy. 2 U. S. C. A.
§434(f)(3)(A) (Supp. 2003).[ Footnote 11 ] In Buckley ,
the Court was presented with the ambiguous language “ ‘any
expenditure … relative to a clearly identified candidate.’ ”
424 U. S., at 41. The Court noted that the “use of so indefinite a
phrase as ‘relative to’ a candidate fails to clearly mark the
boundary between permissible and impermissible speech.” Ibid . Hence, the Court read the phrase to mean “advocating
the election or defeat of a candidate.” Id ., at 42
(internal quotation marks omitted). But this construction did not
complete the vagueness inquiry. As the Court observed: “[T]he distinction between discussion
of issues and candidates and advocacy of election or defeat of
candidates may often dissolve in practical application. Candidates,
especially incumbents, are intimately tied to public issues
involving legislative proposals and governmental actions. Not only
do candidates campaign on the basis of their positions on various
public issues, but campaigns themselves generate issues of public
interest.” Ibid. The Court then recognized that the
constitutional issues raised by the provision “can be avoided only
by reading §608(e)(1) as limited to communications that include
explicit words of advocacy of election or defeat of a candidate.”
Id ., at 43. The joint opinion argues that Buckley adopted this narrow reading only to avoid
addressing a constitutional question. “[T]he concept of express
advocacy and the concomitant class of magic words were born of an
effort to avoid constitutional infirmities,” concludes the joint
opinion after examining the language of Buckley . Ante , at 85. This ignores the fact that the Court then
struck down the expenditure limitation precisely because it was too
narrow: “The exacting interpretation of the
statutory language necessary to avoid unconstitutional vagueness
thus undermines the limitation’s effectiveness as a
loophole-closing provision by facilitating circumvention by those
seeking to exert improper influence upon a candidate or
officeholder. It would naively underestimate the ingenuity and
resourcefulness of persons and groups desiring to buy influence to
believe that they would have much difficulty devising expenditures
that skirted the restriction on express advocacy of election or
defeat but nevertheless benefited the candidate’s campaign. Yet no
substantial societal interest would be served by a loophole-closing
provision designed to check corruption that permitted unscrupulous
persons and organizations to expend unlimited sums of money in
order to obtain improper influence over candidates for elective
office.” 424 U. S., at 45. Far from saving the provision from
constitutional doubt, the Court read the provision in such a way as
to guarantee its unconstitutionality. If there were some
possibility that regulation of communications without words of
express advocacy were constitutional, the provision would have to
have been read to include these communications, and the
constitutional question addressed head on.[ Footnote 12 ] Indeed, the exceedingly narrow
reading of the relevant language in Buckley is far from
mandated by the text; it is, in fact, a highly strained reading.
“ ‘[A]ny expenditure … relative to a clearly identified
candidate,’ ” id ., at 41, would be better read to
cover, for instance, any expenditure for an advertisement aired
close to an election that is “intended to influence the voters’
decisions and ha[s] that effect,” a standard apparently endorsed by
the joint opinion as being sufficiently “equivalent” to express
advocacy to justify its regulation. Ante , at 99–100. By
deliberately adopting a strained and narrow reading of the
statutory text and then striking down the provision in question for
being too narrow, the Court made clear that regulation of
nonexpress advocacy was strictly forbidden. This reading is confirmed by other
portions of Buckley and by other cases. For instance, in
limiting FECA’s disclosure provisions to expenditures involving
express advocacy, the Court noted that it gave such a narrowing
interpretation “[t]o insure that the reach of [the disclosure
provision] is not impermissibly broad .” 424 U. S., at 80
(emphasis added). If overbreadth were a concern in limiting the
scope of a disclosure provision, it surely was equally a concern in
the limitation of an actual cap on expenditures. And, in MCFL , the Court arguably eliminated any ambiguity
remaining in Buckley when it explicitly stated that the
narrowing interpretations taken in Buckley were necessary
“in order to avoid problems of overbreadth.” MCFL , 479 U.
S., at 248. The joint opinion’s attempt to explain away MCFL ’s uncomfortable language is unpersuasive. The joint
opinion emphasizes that the MCFL Court “held that a
‘similar construction ’ must apply to the expenditure
limitation,” as if that somehow proved its point. Ante , at
85, n. 76 (emphasis in original). The fact that the MCFL Court said this does not establish anything, of
course; adopting a narrow construction of a statute “in order to
avoid problems of overbreadth,” 479 U. S., at 248, is perfectly
consistent with a holding that, lacking the narrowing construction,
the statute would be overly broad, i.e. ,
unconstitutional. The defendants’ principal argument
in response is that “it would be bizarre to conclude that
the Constitution permits Congress to prohibit the use of corporate
or union general treasury funds for electioneering advertisements,
but that the only standard that it can constitutionally
use (express advocacy) is one that misses the vast majority (88.6
percent) of advertisements that candidates themselves use for
electioneering.” Brief for FEC et al. in No. 02–1674
et al., p. 103 (emphasis in original). The joint opinion echoes this, stating
that the express advocacy line “cannot be squared with our
longstanding recognition that the presence or absence of magic
words cannot meaningfully distinguish electioneering speech from a
true issue ad.” Ante , at 86. First, the presence of the
“magic words” does differentiate in a meaningful way
between categories of speech. Speech containing the “magic words”
is “unambiguously campaign related,” Buckley , supra , at 81, while speech without these words is not.
Second, it is far from bizarre to suggest that (potentially
regulable) speech that is in practice impossible to differentiate
from fully protected speech must be fully protected. It is, rather,
part and parcel of First Amendment first principles. See, e.g., Free Speech Coalition, 535 U. S., at 255
(“The Government may not suppress lawful speech as the means to
suppress unlawful speech. Protected speech does not become
unprotected merely because it resembles the latter. The
Constitution requires the reverse”). In fact, First Amendment
protection was extended to that fundamental category of artistic
and entertaining speech not for its own sake, but only because it
was indistinguishable, practically, from speech intended to inform.
See Joseph Burstyn, Inc. v. Wilson, 343 U. S. 495 , 501
(1952); Winters v. New York, 333 U. S. 507 , 510
(1948) (rejecting suggestion that “the constitutional protection
for a free press applies only to the exposition of ideas” as the
“line between the informing and the entertaining is too elusive for
the protection of that basic right,” noting that “[w]hat is one
man’s amusement, teaches another’s doctrine”). This principle
clearly played a significant role in Buckley itself, see
424 U. S., at 42 (after noting that “the distinction between
discussion of issues and candidates and advocacy of election or
defeat of candidates may often dissolve in practical application,”
holding that the “express advocacy” standard must be adopted as the
interpretation of the relevant language in FECA). The
express-advocacy line was drawn to ensure the protection of the
“discussion of issues and candidates,” not out of some strange
obsession of the Court to create meaningless lines. And the joint
opinion misses the point when it notes that “ Buckley ’s
express advocacy line, in short, has not aided the legislative
effort to combat real or apparent corruption.” Ante , at
86–87. Buckley did not draw this line solely to aid in
combating real or apparent corruption, but rather also to ensure
the protection of speech unrelated to election campaigns.[ Footnote 13 ] Nor is this to say that speech
with words of express advocacy is somehow less protected, as the
joint opinion claims. Ante, at 99. The Court in Buckley recognized an informational interest that
justified the imposition of a disclosure requirement on
campaign-related speech. See 424 U. S., at 81. This interest is not
implicated with regard to speech that is unrelated to an election
campaign. Hence, it would be unconstitutional to impose such a
disclosure requirement on non-election-related speech. And, as “the
distinction between discussion of issues and candidates … may often
dissolve in practical application,” id ., at 42, the only
way to prevent the unjustified burdening of nonelection speech is
to impose the regulation only on speech that is “unambiguously
campaign related,” id ., at 81, i.e. , speech using
words of express advocacy. Hence, speech that uses words of express
advocacy is protected under the same standard, strict scrutiny, as
all other forms of speech. The only difference is that, under Buckley , there is a governmental interest supporting some
regulation of those using words of express advocacy not present in
other forms of speech. * * * The chilling endpoint
of the Court’s reasoning is not difficult to foresee: outright
regulation of the press. None of the rationales offered by the
defendants, and none of the reasoning employed by the Court,
exempts the press. “This is so because of the difficulty, and
perhaps impossibility, of distinguishing, either as a matter of
fact or constitutional law, media corporations from [nonmedia]
corporations.” Bellotti, 435 U. S., at 796 (Burger,
C. J., concurring). Media companies can run procandidate
editorials as easily as nonmedia corporations can pay for
advertisements. Candidates can be just as grateful to media
companies as they can be to corporations and unions. In terms of
“the corrosive and distorting effects” of wealth accumulated by
corporations that has “little or no correlation to the public’s
support for the corporation’s political ideas,” Austin ,
494 U. S., at 660, there is no distinction between a media
corporation and a nonmedia corporation.[ Footnote 14 ] Media corporations are influential. There
is little doubt that the editorials and commentary they run can
affect elections. Nor is there any doubt that media companies often
wish to influence elections. One would think that the New York
Times fervently hopes that its endorsement of Presidential
candidates will actually influence people. What is to stop a future
Congress from determining that the press is “too influential,” and
that the “appearance of corruption” is significant when media
organizations endorse candidates or run “slanted” or “biased” news
stories in favor of candidates or parties? Or, even easier, what is
to stop a future Congress from concluding that the availability of
unregulated media corporations creates a loophole that allows for
easy “circumvention” of the limitations of the current campaign
finance laws?[ Footnote
15 ] Indeed, I believe
that longstanding and heretofore unchallenged opinions such as Miami Herald Publishing Co. v. Tornillo, 418 U. S. 241 (1974), are in peril.
There, the Court noted that “[c]hains of newspapers, national
newspapers, national wire and news services, and one-newspaper
towns, are the dominant features of a press that has become
noncompetitive and enormously powerful and influential in its
capacity to manipulate popular opinion and change the course of
events.” Id ., at 249. Despite expressing some sympathy for
those arguing for a legally created “right of access” to encourage
diversity in viewpoints in the media, the Court struck down such
laws, noting that these laws acted both to suppress speech and to
“intru[de] into the function of editors” by interfering with “the
exercise of editorial control and judgment.” Id ., at
257–258. Now, supporters of such laws need only argue that the
press’ “capacity to manipulate popular opinion” gives rise to an
“appearance of corruption,” especially when this capacity is used
to promote a particular candidate or party. After drumming up some
evidence,[ Footnote 16 ] laws
regulating media outlets in their issuance of editorials would be
upheld under the joint opinion’s reasoning (a result considered so
beyond the pale in Miami Herald Publishing that the Court
there used it as a reductio ad absurdum against the
right-of-access law being addressed, see id ., at 256). Nor
is there anything in the joint opinion that would prevent Congress
from imposing the Fairness Doctrine, not just on radio and
television broadcasters, but on the entire media. See Red Lion
Broadcasting , 395 U. S., at 369 (defining the “fairness
doctrine” as a “requirement that discussion of public issues be
presented … and that each side of those issues must be given fair
coverage”). Hence, “the freedom of the press,”
described as “one of the greatest bulwarks of liberty,” 1 J.
Elliot, Debates on the Federal Constitution 335 (___ ed. 1876)
(declaration of Rhode Island upon the ratification of the
Constitution),[ Footnote 17 ]
could be next on the chopping block. Although today’s opinion does
not expressly strip the press of First Amendment protection, there
is no principle of law or logic that would prevent the application
of the Court’s reasoning in that setting. The press now operates at
the whim of Congress. * Justice Scalia joins Parts
I, II–A, and II–B of this opinion. Footnote 1 The Court also rejected an
overbreadth challenge, reasoning that “Congress was justified in
concluding that the interest in safeguarding against the appearance
of impropriety requires that the opportunity for abuse inherent in
the process of raising large monetary contributions be eliminated.” Buckley , 424 U. S., at 30. But this justification was
inextricably intertwined with the Court’s concern over the
difficulty of isolating suspect contributions. If it were easy to
isolate suspect contributions, and if bribery laws could be quickly
and effectively enforced, then there would be no “opportunity for
abuse inherent in the process,” ibid., and hence no need
for an otherwise overbroad contribution ceiling. Footnote 2 Arguably, the current antibribery
statute, 18 U. S. C. §201, is broad enough to cover the
unspecified other “attempts … to influence governmental action”
that the Buckley Court seemed worried about. 424 U. S., at
28. Footnote 3 Indeed, the principal contents of
Senator McCain’s declaration are his complaints that several bills
he supported were defeated. The Senator also suggests, without
evidence, that there had been some connection between the defeat of
his favored policy outcomes and certain soft-money donors. See, e.g. , App. 393–394, ¶ ;10 (declaration of Sen. John McCain
¶ ;10) (noting Democratic “parliamentary procedural device” used to
block one of Senator McCain’s proposed amendments to the
Sarbanes-Oxley corporate governance bill). The possibility that his
favored policy outcomes lost due to lack of public support, or
because the opponents of the amendment honestly believed it would
do harm to the public, does not appear to be addressed. Footnote 4 Former Senators Simpson and Simon
both seem to have the same response as Senator McCain, see
n. 3, supra, in having their favored interests voted
down, and similarly do not consider alternative explanations for
the failure of their proposals. See App. 811, ¶ ;11 (declaration of
former Sen. Alan Simpson ¶ ;11); App. 805, ¶ ;14 (declaration of
former Sen. Paul Simon ¶ ;14). Footnote 5 Because there is not an iota of
evidence supporting the Government’s asserted interests in BCRA
§318, I concur in the Court’s conclusion that this provision is
unconstitutional. Footnote 6 The joint opinion continues yet
another disturbing trend: the application of a complaisant level of
scrutiny under the guise of “strict scrutiny.” See Grutter v. Bollinger , 539 U. S. ___ (2003). Footnote 7 This is doubly so now that the
Court has decided that there is no constitutional need for the
showing even of an “agreement” in order to transform an expenditure
into a “coordinated expenditur[e]” and hence into a contribution
for FECA purposes. Ante , at 115–117 (joint
opinion). Footnote 8 The National Rifle Association
(NRA) plaintiffs compellingly state that “[a]s a measure designed
to prevent official corruption, of either the quid pro quo or the ‘gratitude’ variety, Title II … makes no more sense than a
bribery statute requiring corporations to pay for their bribes
using funds from PACs.” Brief for Appellants NRA et al. in No.
02–1675, pp. 24–25. And, regarding the appearance of
corruption: “Defendants’ own witnesses concede that the public’s
perceptions of ads is not affected in the slightest by whether they
are purchased with general treasury funds or with PAC money.” Id ., at 25. Footnote 9 The fact that the Founders
located the right to anonymous speech in the “freedom of the press”
is of no moment, as “it makes little difference in terms of our
analysis, which seeks to determine only whether the First
Amendment, as originally understood, protects anonymous writing.” McIntyre , 514 U. S., at 360 (Thomas, J.,
concurring). Footnote
10 BCRA §212(a) is also
unconstitutional. Although the plaintiffs only challenge the
advance disclosure requirement of §212(a), by requiring disclosure
of communications using express advocacy, the entire reporting
requirement is unconstitutional for the same reasons that §201 is
unconstitutional. Consequently, it follows that the advance
disclosure provision is unconstitutional. BCRA §§311 and 504 also violate
the First Amendment. By requiring any television or radio
advertisement that satisfies the definition of “electioneering
communication” to include the identity of the sponsor, and even a
“full-screen view of a representative of the political committee or
other person making the statement” in the case of a television
advertisement, new FECA §318, §311 is a virtual carbon copy of the
law at issue in McIntyre v. Ohio Elections
Comm’n, 514 U. S. 334 (1995) (the only
difference being the irrelevant distinction between a printed
pamphlet and a television or radio advertisement). And §504 not
only has the precise flaws of §201, but also sweeps broadly as
well, covering any “message relating to any political matter of
national importance, including … a national legislative issue of
public importance.” Hence, both §§311 and 504 should be struck
down. Footnote
11 The Court, in upholding most of
its provisions by concluding that the “express advocacy” limitation
derived by Buckley is not a constitutionally mandated
line, has, in one blow, overturned every Court of Appeals that has
addressed this question (except, perhaps, one). See Clifton v. FEC , 114 F. 3d 1309, 1312 (CA1
1997); Vermont Right to Life Comm., Inc. v. Sorrell , 221 F. 3d 376, 387 (CA2 2000); FEC v. Christian Action Network, Inc ., 110 F. 3d 1049,
1064 (CA4 1997); Chamber of Commerce v. Moore ,
288 F. 3d 187, 193 (CA5 2000); Iowa Right to Life Comm.,
Inc. v. Williams , 187 F. 3d 963, 968–970 (CA8
1999); Citizens for Responsible Govt. State Political Action
Comm. v. Davidson , 236 F. 3d 1174, 1187 (CA10
2000). The one possible exception is the Ninth Circuit. See FEC v. Furgatch , 807 F. 2d 857, 862–863
(1987). Footnote
12 After all, the constitutional
avoidance doctrine counsels us to adopt constructions of statutes
to “avoid decision of constitutional questions,” not to
deliberately create constitutional questions. United
States v. Thirty&nbhyph;seven
Photographs, 402 U. S. 363 , 373
(1971); see also United States ex rel. Attorney General v. Delaware & Hudson Co., 213 U. S. 366 , 408
(1909). Footnote
13 This very case is an excellent
example of why such a bright-line rule is necessary. The Court,
having “rejected the notion that the First Amendment requires
Congress to treat so-called issue advocacy differently from express
advocacy,” ante , at 87–88, proceeds to uphold significant
new restrictions on speech that is, in every sense of the word,
pure issue-related speech. The Court abandons the bright-line rule,
and now subjects political speech of virtually any kind to the risk
of regulation by Congress. Footnote
14 Chief Justice Burger presciently
commented on precisely this point in First Nat. Bank of
Boston v. Bellotti, 435 U. S. 765 , 796–797 (1978)
(citations omitted): “In terms of ‘unfair advantage in the political
process’ and ‘corporate domination of the electoral process,’ it
could be argued that such media conglomerates as I describe pose a
much more realistic threat to valid interests than do appellants
and similar entities not regularly concerned with shaping popular
opinion on public issues. See Miami Herald Publishing Co. v. Tornillo , [ 418 U. S. 241 (1974)]. In Tornillo , for example, we noted the serious contentions
advanced that a result of the growth of modern media empires ‘has
been to place in a few hands the power to inform the American
people and shape public opinion.’ 418 U. S., at 250.” Footnote
15 It appears that “circumvention”
of the campaign finance laws by exploiting media exemptions is
already being planned by one of the plaintiffs in this litigation.
See Theimer, NRA Seeks Status as News Outlet , Washington
Post A09 (Dec. 7, 2003) (reporting that the NRA is looking to
acquire a broadcast outlet and seeking to be classified as a news
organization). Footnote
16 Given the quality of the evidence
the Court relies upon to uphold Title I, the evidence should not be
hard to come by. See Kane & Preston, Fox Chief on Hot Seat,
Roll Call (June 12, 2003) (“GOP leaders such as House Majority
Leader Tom DeLay (R-Texas) have labeled CNN as the ‘Communist News
Network’ and the ‘Clinton News Network’—suggesting they only
presented the liberal viewpoint and that of former President
Clinton”); Jones, Fox News Moves from the Margins to the
Mainstream, Shorenstein Center, Harvard (Dec. 1, 2002) (quoting Al
Gore as describing Fox News and the Washington Times as “part and
parcel of the Republican Party”). Footnote
17 See also 4 W. Blackstone,
Commentaries on the Laws of England 151 (1769) (“The liberty of the
press is indeed essential to the nature of a free
state”). | In McConnell v. FEC, the Supreme Court upheld the constitutionality of the Bipartisan Campaign Reform Act of 2002, including its provisions on broadcast advertising and campaign finance regulations. The Court affirmed the District Court's judgment, finding that the Act's amendments to the Communications Act of 1934 were valid. The case addressed a range of issues related to political speech and campaign finance, with the Court ultimately siding with increased regulation. |
Free Speech | Manhattan Community Access Corp. v. Halleck | https://supreme.justia.com/cases/federal/us/587/17-1702/ | NOTICE: This opinion is subject to
formal revision before publication in the preliminary print of the
United States Reports. Readers are requested to notify the Reporter
of Decisions, Supreme Court of the United States, Washington,
D. C. 20543, of any typographical or other formal errors, in
order that corrections may be made before the preliminary print
goes to press.
SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES
_________________
No. 17–1702
_________________
MANHATTAN COMMUNITY ACCESS CORPORATION,
et al., PETITIONERS v. DEEDEE HALLECK, et al.
on writ of certiorari to the united states
court of appeals for the second circuit
[June 17, 2019]
Justice Kavanaugh delivered the opinion of the
Court.
The Free Speech Clause of the First Amendment
constrains governmental actors and protects private actors. To draw
the line between governmental and private, this Court applies what
is known as the state-action doctrine. Under that doctrine, as
relevant here, a private entity may be considered a state actor
when it exercises a function “traditionally exclusively reserved to
the State.” Jackson v. Metropolitan Edison Co. , 419 U.S.
345 , 352 (1974).
This state-action case concerns the public
access channels on Time Warner’s cable system in Manhattan. Public
access channels are available for private citizens to use. The
public access channels on Time Warner’s cable system in Manhattan
are operated by a private nonprofit corporation known as MNN. The
question here is whether MNN—even though it is a private
entity—nonetheless is a state actor when it operates the public
access channels. In other words, is operation of public access
channels on a cable system a traditional, exclusive public
function? If so, then the First Amendment would restrict MNN’s
exercise of editorial discretion over the speech and speakers on
the public access channels.
Under the state-action doctrine as it has been
articulated and applied by our precedents, we conclude that
operation of public access channels on a cable system is not a
traditional, exclusive public function. Moreover, a private entity
such as MNN who opens its property for speech by others is not
transformed by that fact alone into a state actor. In operating the
public access channels, MNN is a private actor, not a state actor,
and MNN therefore is not subject to First Amendment constraints on
its editorial discretion. We reverse in relevant part the judgment
of the Second Circuit, and we remand the case for further
proceedings consistent with this opinion.
I
A
Since the 1970s, public access channels have
been a regular feature on cable television systems throughout the
United States. In the 1970s, Federal Communications Commission
regulations required certain cable operators to set aside channels
on their cable systems for public access. In 1979, however, this
Court ruled that the FCC lacked statutory authority to impose that
mandate. See FCC v. Midwest Video Corp. , 440 U.S.
689 (1979). A few years later, Congress passed and President
Reagan signed the Cable Communications Policy Act of 1984. 98Stat.
2779. The Act authorized state and local governments to require
cable operators to set aside channels on their cable systems for
public access. 47 U. S. C. §531(b).
The New York State Public Service Commission
regulates cable franchising in New York State and requires cable
operators in the State to set aside channels on their cable systems
for public access. 16 N. Y. Codes, Rules & Regs.
§§895.1(f), 895.4(b) (2018). State law requires that use of the
public access channels be free of charge and first-come,
first-served. §§895.4(c)(4) and (6). Under state law, the cable
operator operates the public access channels unless the local
government in the area chooses to itself operate the channels or
designates a private entity to operate the channels.
§895.4(c)(1).
Time Warner (now known as Charter) operates a
cable system in Manhattan. Under state law, Time Warner must set
aside some channels on its cable system for public access. New York
City (the City) has designated a private nonprofit corporation
named Manhattan Neighborhood Network, commonly referred to as MNN,
to operate Time Warner’s public access channels in Manhattan. This
case involves a complaint against MNN regarding its management of
the public access channels.
B
Because this case comes to us on a motion to
dismiss, we accept the allegations in the complaint as true. See Ashcroft v. Iqbal , 556 U.S.
662 , 678 (2009).
DeeDee Halleck and Jesus Papoleto Melendez
produced public access programming in Manhattan. They made a film
about MNN’s alleged neglect of the East Harlem community. Halleck
submitted the film to MNN for airing on MNN’s public access
channels, and MNN later televised the film. Afterwards, MNN fielded
multiple complaints about the film’s content. In response, MNN
temporarily suspended Halleck from using the public access
channels.
Halleck and Melendez soon became embroiled in
another dispute with MNN staff. In the wake of that dispute, MNN
ultimately suspended Halleck and Melendez from all MNN services and
facilities.
Halleck and Melendez then sued MNN, among other
parties, in Federal District Court. The two producers claimed that
MNN violated their First Amendment free-speech rights when MNN
restricted their access to the public access channels because of
the content of their film.
MNN moved to dismiss the producers’ First
Amendment claim on the ground that MNN is not a state actor and
therefore is not subject to First Amendment restrictions on its
editorial discretion. The District Court agreed with MNN and
dismissed the producers’ First Amendment claim.
The Second Circuit reversed in relevant part.
882 F.3d 300, 308 (2018). In the majority opinion authored by Judge
Newman and joined by Judge Lohier, the court stated that the public
access channels in Manhattan are a public forum for purposes of the
First Amendment. Reasoning that “public forums are usually operated
by governments,” the court concluded that MNN is a state actor
subject to First Amendment constraints. Id. , at 306–307.
Judge Lohier added a concurring opinion, explaining that MNN also
qualifies as a state actor for the independent reason that “New
York City delegated to MNN the traditionally public function of
administering and regulating speech in the public forum of
Manhattan’s public access channels.” Id., at 309.
Judge Jacobs dissented in relevant part, opining
that MNN is not a state actor. He reasoned that a private entity’s
operation of an open forum for speakers does not render the host
entity a state actor. Judge Jacobs further stated that the
operation of public access channels is not a traditional, exclusive
public function.
We granted certiorari to resolve disagreement
among the Courts of Appeals on the question whether private
operators of public access cable channels are state actors subject
to the First Amendment. 586 U. S. __ (2018). Compare 882 F.3d
300 (case below), with Wilcher v. Akron , 498 F.3d 516
(CA6 2007); and Alliance for Commu- nity Media v. FCC , 56 F.3d 105 (CADC 1995).
II
Ratified in 1791, the First Amendment provides
in relevant part that “Congress shall make no law . . .
abridging the freedom of speech.” Ratified in 1868, the Fourteenth
Amendment makes the First Amendment’s Free Speech Clause applicable
against the States: “No State shall make or enforce any law which
shall abridge the privileges or immunities of citizens of the
United States; nor shall any State deprive any person of life,
liberty, or property, without due process of law
. . . .” §1. The text and original meaning of those
Amendments, as well as this Court’s longstanding precedents,
establish that the Free Speech Clause prohibits only governmental abridgment of speech. The Free Speech Clause
does not prohibit private abridgment of speech. See, e.g., Denver Area Ed. Telecommunications Consortium, Inc. v. FCC , 518
U.S. 727 , 737 (1996) (plurality opinion); Hurley v. Irish-American Gay, Lesbian and Bisexual Group of Boston,
Inc. , 515 U.S.
557 , 566 (1995); Hudgens v. NLRB , 424 U.S.
507 , 513 (1976); cf. Miami Herald Publishing Co. v. Tornillo , 418 U.S.
241 , 256 (1974).
In accord with the text and structure of the
Constitution, this Court’s state-action doctrine distinguishes the
government from individuals and private entities. See Brentwood
Academy v. Tennessee Secondary School Athletic Assn. , 531 U.S.
288 , 295–296 (2001). By enforcing that constitutional boundary
between the governmental and the private, the state-action doctrine
protects a robust sphere of individual liberty.
Here, the producers claim that MNN, a private
entity, restricted their access to MNN’s public access channels
because of the content of the producers’ film. The producers have
advanced a First Amendment claim against MNN. The threshold problem
with that First Amendment claim is a fundamental one: MNN is a
private entity.
Relying on this Court’s state-action precedents,
the producers assert that MNN is nonetheless a state actor subject
to First Amendment constraints on its editorial discretion. Under
this Court’s cases, a private entity can qualify as a state actor
in a few limited circumstances—including, for example,
(i) when the private entity performs a traditional, exclusive
public function, see, e.g., Jackson , 419 U. S., at
352–354; (ii) when the government compels the private entity
to take a particular action, see, e.g., Blum v. Yaretsky , 457 U.S.
991 , 1004–1005 (1982); or (iii) when the government acts
jointly with the private entity, see, e.g., Lugar v. Edmondson Oil Co. , 457 U.S.
922 , 941–942 (1982).
The producers’ primary argument here falls into
the first category: The producers contend that MNN exercises a
traditional, exclusive public function when it operates the public
access channels on Time Warner’s cable system in Manhattan. We
disagree.
A
Under the Court’s cases, a private entity may
qualify as a state actor when it exercises “powers traditionally
exclusively reserved to the State.” Jackson , 419 U. S.,
at 352. It is not enough that the federal, state, or local
government exercised the function in the past, or still does. And
it is not enough that the function serves the public good or the
public interest in some way. Rather, to qualify as a traditional,
exclusive public function within the meaning of our state-action
precedents, the government must have traditionally and exclusively performed the function. See Rendell-Baker v. Kohn , 457 U.S.
830 , 842 (1982); Jackson , 419 U. S., at 352–353; Evans v. Newton , 382 U.S.
296 , 300 (1966).
The Court has stressed that “very few” functions
fall into that category. Flagg Bros., Inc. v. Brooks , 436 U.S.
149 , 158 (1978). Under the Court’s cases, those functions
include, for example, running elections and operating a company
town. See Terry v. Adams , 345
U.S. 461 , 468–470 (1953) (elections); Marsh v. Alabama , 326 U.S.
501 , 505–509 (1946) (company town); Smith v. Allwright , 321 U.S.
649 , 662–666 (1944) (elections); Nixon v. Condon , 286 U.S.
73 , 84–89 (1932) (elections).[ 1 ] The Court has ruled that a variety of functions do not
fall into that category, including, for example: running sports
associations and leagues, administering insurance payments,
operating nursing homes, providing special education, representing
indigent criminal defendants, resolving private disputes, and
supplying electricity. See American Mfrs. Mut. Ins. Co. v. Sullivan , 526 U.S.
40 , 55–57 (1999) (insurance payments); National Collegiate
Athletic Assn. v. Tarkanian , 488
U.S. 179 , 197, n. 18 (1988) (college sports); San
Francisco Arts & Athletics, Inc. v. United States
Olympic Comm. , 483 U.S.
522 , 544–545 (1987) (amateur sports); Blum , 457
U. S., at 1011–1012 (nursing home); Rendell-Baker , 457
U. S., at 842 (special education); Polk County v. Dodson , 454 U.S.
312 , 318–319 (1981) (public defender); Flagg Bros. , 436
U. S., at 157–163 (private dispute resolution); Jackson , 419 U. S., at 352–354 (electric service).
The relevant function in this case is operation
of public access channels on a cable system. That function has not
traditionally and exclusively been performed by government.
Since the 1970s, when public access channels
became a regular feature on cable systems, a variety of private and
public actors have operated public access channels, including:
private cable operators; private nonprofit organizations;
municipalities; and other public and private community
organizations such as churches, schools, and libraries. See Denver Area , 518 U. S., at 761–762 (plurality opinion);
R. Oringel & S. Buske, The Access Manager’s Handbook: A Guide
for Managing Community Television 14–17 (1987).
The history of public access channels in
Manhattan further illustrates the point. In 1971, public access
channels first started operating in Manhattan. See D. Brenner, M.
Price, & M. Meyerson, Cable Television and Other Nonbroadcast
Video §6:29, p. 6–47 (2018). Those early Manhattan public
access channels were operated in large part by private cable
operators, with some help from private nonprofit organizations. See
G. Gillespie, Public Access Cable Television in the United States
and Canada 37–38 (1975); Janes, History and Structure of Public
Access Television, 39 J. Film & Video, No. 3, pp. 15–17 (1987).
Those private cable operators continued to operate the public
access channels until the early 1990s, when MNN (also a private
entity) began to operate the public access channels.
In short, operating public access channels on a
cable system is not a traditional, exclusive public function within
the meaning of this Court’s cases.
B
To avoid that conclusion, the producers widen
the lens and contend that the relevant function here is not simply
the operation of public access channels on a cable system, but
rather is more generally the operation of a public forum for
speech. And according to the producers, operation of a public forum
for speech is a traditional, exclusive public function.
That analysis mistakenly ignores the threshold
state-action question. When the government provides a forum for
speech (known as a public forum), the government may be constrained
by the First Amendment, meaning that the government ordinarily may
not exclude speech or speakers from the forum on the basis of
viewpoint, or sometimes even on the basis of content. See, e.g.,
Southeastern Promotions, Ltd. v. Conrad , 420 U.S.
546 , 547, 555 (1975) (private theater leased to the city); Police Dept. of Chicago v. Mosley , 408 U.S.
92 , 93, 96 (1972) (sidewalks); Hague v. Committee for
Industrial Organization , 307 U.S.
496 , 515–516 (1939) (streets and parks).
By contrast, when a private entity provides a
forum for speech, the private entity is not ordinarily constrained
by the First Amendment because the private entity is not a state
actor. The private entity may thus exercise editorial discretion
over the speech and speakers in the forum. This Court so ruled in
its 1976 decision in Hudgens v. NLRB . There, the
Court held that a shopping center owner is not a state actor
subject to First Amendment requirements such as the public forum
doctrine. 424 U. S., at 520–521; see also Lloyd Corp. v. Tanner , 407 U.S.
551 , 569–570 (1972); Central Hardware Co. v. NLRB , 407 U.S.
539 , 547 (1972); Alliance for Community Media , 56
F. 3d, at 121–123.
The Hudgens decision reflects a
commonsense principle: Providing some kind of forum for speech is
not an activity that only governmental entities have traditionally
performed. Therefore, a private entity who provides a forum for
speech is not transformed by that fact alone into a state actor.
After all, private property owners and private lessees often open
their property for speech. Grocery stores put up community bulletin
boards. Comedy clubs host open mic nights. As Judge Jacobs
persuasively explained, it “is not at all a near-exclusive function
of the state to provide the forums for public expression, politics,
information, or entertainment.” 882 F. 3d, at 311 (opinion
concurring in part and dissenting in part).
In short, merely hosting speech by others is not
a traditional, exclusive public function and does not alone
transform private entities into state actors subject to First
Amendment constraints.
If the rule were otherwise, all private property
owners and private lessees who open their property for speech would
be subject to First Amendment constraints and would lose the
ability to exercise what they deem to be appropriate editorial
discretion within that open forum. Private property owners and
private lessees would face the unappetizing choice of allowing all
comers or closing the platform altogether. “The Constitution by no
means requires such an attenuated doctrine of dedication of private
property to public use.” Hudgens , 424 U. S., at 519
(internal quotation marks omitted). Benjamin Franklin did not have
to operate his newspaper as “a stagecoach, with seats for
everyone.” F. Mott, American Journalism 55 (3d ed. 1962). That
principle still holds true. As the Court said in Hudgens , to
hold that private property owners providing a forum for speech are
constrained by the First Amendment would be “to create a court-made
law wholly disregarding the constitutional basis on which private
ownership of property rests in this country.” 424 U. S., at
517 (internal quotation marks omitted). The Constitution does not
disable private property owners and private lessees from exercising
editorial discretion over speech and speakers on their
property.[ 2 ]
The producers here are seeking in effect to
circumvent this Court’s case law, including Hudgens . But Hudgens is sound, and we therefore reaffirm our holding in
that case.[ 3 ]
C
Next, the producers retort that this case
differs from Hudgens because New York City has designated
MNN to operate the public access channels on Time Warner’s cable
system, and because New York State heavily regulates MNN with
respect to the public access channels. Under this Court’s cases,
however, those facts do not establish that MNN is a state
actor.
New York City’s designation of MNN to operate
the public access channels is analogous to a government license, a
government contract, or a government-granted monopoly. But as the
Court has long held, the fact that the government licenses,
contracts with, or grants a monopoly to a private entity does not
convert the private entity into a state actor—unless the private
entity is performing a traditional, exclusive public function. See, e.g., San Francisco Arts & Athletics , 483
U. S., at 543–544 (exclusive-use rights and corporate
charters); Blum , 457 U. S., at 1011 (licenses); Rendell-Baker , 457 U. S., at 840–841 (contracts); Polk County , 454 U. S., at 319, n. 9, and 320–322
(law licenses); Jackson , 419 U. S., at 351–352
(electric monopolies); Columbia Broadcasting System, Inc. v. Democratic National Committee , 412 U.S.
94 , 120–121 (1973) (broadcast licenses); Moose Lodge No.
107 v. Irvis , 407 U.S.
163 , 176–177 (1972) (liquor licenses); cf. Trustees of
Dartmouth College v. Woodward , 4 Wheat. 518, 638–639
(1819) (corporate charters). The same principle applies if the
government funds or subsidizes a private entity. See Blum ,
457 U. S., at 1011; Rendell - Baker , 457
U. S., at 840.
Numerous private entities in America obtain
government licenses, government contracts, or government-granted
monopolies. If those facts sufficed to transform a private entity
into a state actor, a large swath of private entities in America
would suddenly be turned into state actors and be subject to a
variety of constitutional constraints on their activities. As this
Court’s many state-action cases amply demonstrate, that is not the
law. Here, therefore, the City’s designation of MNN to operate the
public access channels on Time Warner’s cable system does not make
MNN a state actor.
So, too, New York State’s extensive regulation
of MNN’s operation of the public access channels does not make MNN
a state actor. Under the State’s regulations, air time on the
public access channels must be free, and programming must be aired
on a first-come, first-served basis. Those regulations restrict
MNN’s editorial discretion and in effect require MNN to operate
almost like a common carrier. But under this Court’s cases, those
restrictions do not render MNN a state actor.
In Jackson v. Metropolitan Edison
Co. , the leading case on point, the Court stated that the “fact
that a business is subject to state regulation does not by itself
convert its action into that of the State.” 419 U. S., at 350.
In that case, the Court held that “a heavily regulated, privately
owned utility, enjoying at least a partial monopoly in the
providing of electrical service within its territory,” was not a
state actor. Id. , at 358. The Court explained that the “mere
existence” of a “regulatory scheme”—even if “extensive and
detailed”—did not render the utility a state actor. Id., at
350, and n. 7. Nor did it matter whether the State had
authorized the utility to provide electric service to the
community, or whether the utility was the only entity providing
electric service to much of that community.
This case closely parallels Jackson . Like
the electric utility in Jackson , MNN is “a heavily
regulated, privately owned” entity. Id., at 358. As in Jackson , the regulations do not transform the regulated
private entity into a state actor.
Put simply, being regulated by the State does
not make one a state actor. See Sullivan , 526 U. S., at
52; Blum , 457 U. S., at 1004; Rendell-Baker , 457
U. S., at 841–842; Jackson , 419 U. S., at 350; Moose Lodge , 407 U. S., at 176–177. As the Court’s
cases have explained, the “being heavily regulated makes you a
state actor” theory of state action is entirely circular and would
significantly endanger individual liberty and private enterprise.
The theory would be especially problematic in the speech context,
because it could eviscerate certain private entities’ rights to
exercise editorial control over speech and speakers on their
properties or platforms. Not surprisingly, as Justice Thomas has
pointed out, this Court has “never even hinted that regulatory
control, and particularly direct regulatory control over a private
entity’s First Amendment speech rights,” could justify subjecting
the regulated private entity to the constraints of the First
Amendment. Denver Area , 518 U. S., at 829 (opinion
concurring in judgment in part and dissenting in part).
In sum, we conclude that MNN is not subject to
First Amendment constraints on how it exercises its editorial
discretion with respect to the public access channels. To be sure,
MNN is subject to state-law constraints on its editorial discretion
(assuming those state laws do not violate a federal statute or the
Constitution). If MNN violates those state laws, or violates any
applicable contracts, MNN could perhaps face state-law sanctions or
liability of some kind. We of course take no position on any
potential state-law questions. We simply conclude that MNN, as a
private actor, is not subject to First Amendment constraints on how
it exercises editorial discretion over the speech and speakers on
its public access channels.
III
Perhaps recognizing the problem with their
argument that MNN is a state actor under ordinary state-action
principles applicable to private entities and private property, the
producers alternatively contend that the public access channels are
actually the property of New York City, not the property of Time
Warner or MNN. On this theory, the producers say (and the dissent
agrees) that MNN is in essence simply managing government property
on behalf of New York City.
The short answer to that argument is that the
public access channels are not the property of New York City.
Nothing in the record here suggests that a government (federal,
state, or city) owns or leases either the cable system or the
public access channels at issue here. Both Time Warner and MNN are
private entities. Time Warner is the cable operator, and it owns
its cable network, which contains the public access channels. MNN
operates those public access channels with its own facilities and
equipment. The City does not own or lease the public access
channels, and the City does not possess a formal easement or other
property interest in those channels. The franchise agreements
between the City and Time Warner do not say that the City has any
property interest in the public access channels. On the contrary,
the franchise agreements expressly place the public access channels
“under the jurisdiction” of MNN. App. 22. Moreover, the producers
did not allege in their complaint that the City has a property
interest in the channels. And the producers have not cited any
basis in state law for such a conclusion. Put simply, the City does
not have “any formal easement or other property interest in those
channels.” Denver Area , 518 U. S., at 828 (opinion of
Thomas, J.).
It does not matter that a provision in the
franchise agreements between the City and Time Warner allowed the
City to designate a private entity to operate the public access
channels on Time Warner’s cable system. Time Warner still owns the
cable system. And MNN still operates the public access channels. To
reiterate, nothing in the franchise agreements suggests that the
City possesses any property interest in Time Warner’s cable system,
or in the public access channels on that system.
It is true that the City has allowed the cable
operator, Time Warner, to lay cable along public rights-of-way in
the City. But Time Warner’s access to public rights-of-way does not
alter the state-action analysis. For Time Warner, as for other
cable operators, access to public rights-of-way is essential to lay
cable and construct a physical cable infrastructure. See Turner
Broadcasting System, Inc. v. FCC , 512
U.S. 622 , 628 (1994). But the same is true for utility
providers, such as the electric utility in Jackson . Put
simply, a private entity’s permission from government to use public
rights-of-way does not render that private entity a state
actor.
Having said all that, our point here should not
be read too broadly. Under the laws in certain States, including
New York, a local government may decide to itself operate the
public access channels on a local cable system (as many local
governments in New York State and around the country already do),
or could take appropriate steps to obtain a property interest in
the public access channels. Depending on the circumstances, the
First Amendment might then constrain the local government’s
operation of the public access channels. We decide only the case
before us in light of the record before us.
* * *
It is sometimes said that the bigger the
government, the smaller the individual. Consistent with the text of
the Constitution, the state-action doctrine enforces a critical
boundary between the government and the individual, and thereby
protects a robust sphere of individual liberty. Expanding the
state-action doctrine beyond its traditional boundaries would
expand governmental control while restricting individual liberty
and private enterprise. We decline to do so in this case.
MNN is a private entity that operates public
access channels on a cable system. Operating public access channels
on a cable system is not a traditional, exclusive public function.
A private entity such as MNN who opens its property for speech by
others is not transformed by that fact alone into a state actor.
Under the text of the Constitution and our precedents, MNN is not a
state actor subject to the First Amendment. We reverse in relevant
part the judgment of the Second Circuit, and we remand the case for
further proceedings consistent with this opinion.
It is so ordered. Notes 1 Relatedly, this Court has
recognized that a private entity may, under certain circumstances,
be deemed a state actor when the government has outsourced one of
its constitutional obligations to a private entity. In West v. Atkins , for example, the State was constitutionally
obligated to provide medical care to prison inmates. 487 U.S.
42 , 56 (1988). That scenario is not present here because the
government has no such obligation to operate public access
channels. 2 A distinct question not
raised here is the degree to which the First Amendment protects private entities such as Time Warner or MNN from
government legislation or regulation requiring those private
entities to open their property for speech by others. Cf. Turner
Broadcasting System, Inc. v. FCC , 512 U.S.
622 , 636–637 (1994). 3 In Cornelius v. NAACP Legal Defense & Educational Fund, Inc. , this Court
said in passing dicta that “a speaker must seek access to public
property or to private property dedicated to public use to evoke
First Amendment concerns.” 473 U.S.
788 , 801 (1985). But Cornelius dealt with
government-owned property. As Justice Thomas explained in Denver
Area Educational Telecommunications Consortium, Inc. v. FCC , the Court’s admittedly imprecise and overbroad phrase
in Cornelius is not consistent with this Court’s case law
and should not be read to suggest that private property owners or
private lessees are subject to First Amendment constraints whenever
they dedicate their private property to public use or otherwise
open their property for speech. 518 U.S.
727 , 827–828 (1996) (opinion concurring in judgment in part and
dissenting in part). SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES
_________________
No. 17–1702
_________________
MANHATTAN COMMUNITY ACCESS CORPORATION,
et al., PETITIONERS v. DEEDEE HALLECK, et al.
on writ of certiorari to the united states
court of appeals for the second circuit
[June 17, 2019]
Justice Sotomayor, with whom Justice Ginsburg,
Justice Breyer, and Justice Kagan join, dissenting.
The Court tells a very reasonable story about a
case that is not before us. I write to address the one that is.
This is a case about an organization appointed
by the government to administer a constitutional public forum. (It
is not, as the Court suggests, about a private property owner that
simply opened up its property to others.) New York City (the City)
secured a property interest in public-access television channels
when it granted a cable franchise to a cable company. State
regulations require those public-access channels to be made open to
the public on terms that render them a public forum. The City
contracted out the administration of that forum to a private
organization, petitioner Manhattan Community Access Corporation
(MNN). By accepting that agency relationship, MNN stepped into the
City’s shoes and thus qualifies as a state actor, subject to the
First Amendment like any other.
I
A
A cable-television franchise is, essentially,
a license to create a system for distributing cable TV in a certain
area. It is a valuable right, usually conferred on a private
company by a local government. See 47 U. S. C.
§§522(9)–(10), 541(a)(2), (b)(1); Turner Broadcasting
System , Inc. v. FCC , 512
U.S. 622 , 628 (1994). A private company cannot enter a local
cable market without one. §541(b)(1).
Cable companies transmit content through wires
that stretch “between a transmission facility and the television
sets of individual subscribers.” Id. , at 627–628. Creating
this network of wires is a disruptive undertaking that “entails the
use of public rights-of-way and easements.” Id. , at 628.
New York State authorizes municipalities to
grant cable franchises to cable companies of a certain size only if
those companies agree to set aside at least one public access
channel. 16 N. Y. Codes, Rules & Regs. §§895.1(f),
895.4(b)(1) (2016). New York then requires that those public-access
channels be open to all comers on “a first-come, first-served,
nondiscriminatory basis.” §895.4(c)(4). Likewise, the State
prohibits both cable franchisees and local governments from
“exercis[ing] any editorial control” over the channels, aside from
regulating obscenity and other unprotected content.
§§895.4(c)(8)–(9).
B
Years ago, New York City (no longer a party to
this suit) and Time Warner Entertainment Company (never a party to
this suit) entered into a cable-franchise agreement. App. 22. Time
Warner received a cable franchise; the City received public-access
channels. The agreement also provided that the public-access
channels would be operated by an independent, nonprofit corporation
chosen by the Manhattan borough president. But the City, as the
practice of other New York municipalities confirms, could have
instead chosen to run the channels itself. See §895.4(c)(1); Brief
for Respondents 35 (citing examples).
MNN is the independent nonprofit that the
borough president appointed to run the channels; indeed, MNN
appears to have been incorporated in 1991 for that precise purpose,
with seven initial board members selected by the borough president
(though only two thus selected today). See App. 23; Brief for
Respondents 7, n. 1. The City arranged for MNN to receive
startup capital from Time Warner and to be funded through franchise
fees from Time Warner and other Manhattan cable franchisees. App.
23; Brief for New York County Lawyers Association (NYCLA) as Amicus Curiae 27; see also App. to Brief for Respondents
19a. As the borough president announced upon MNN’s formation in
1991, MNN’s “central charge is to administer and manage all the
public access channels of the cable television systems in
Manhattan.” App. to Brief for NYCLA as Amicus Curiae 1.
As relevant here, respondents DeeDee Halleck and
Jesus Papoleto Melendez sued MNN in U. S. District Court for
the Southern District of New York under 42 U. S. C.
§1983. They alleged that the public-access channels, “[r]equired by
state regulation and [the] local franchise agreements,” are “a
designated public forum of unlimited character”; that the City had
“delegated control of that public forum to MNN”; and that MNN had,
in turn, engaged in viewpoint discrimination in violation of
respondents’ First Amendment rights. App. 39.
The District Court dismissed respondents’ First
Amendment claim against MNN. The U. S. Court of Appeals for
the Second Circuit reversed that dismissal, concluding that the
public-access channels “are public forums and that [MNN’s]
employees were sufficiently alleged to be state actors taking
action barred by the First Amendment.” 882 F.3d 300, 301–302
(2018). Because the case before us arises from a motion to dismiss,
respondents’ factual allegations must be accepted as true. Hernandez v. Mesa , 582 U. S. ___, ___ (2017)
( per curiam ) (slip op., at 1).
II
I would affirm the judgment below. The
channels are clearly a public forum: The City has a property
interest in them, and New York regulations require that access to
those channels be kept open to all. And because the City (1) had a
duty to provide that public forum once it granted a cable franchise
and (2) had a duty to abide by the First Amendment once it provided
that forum, those obligations did not evaporate when the City
delegated the administration of that forum to a private entity.
Just as the City would have been subject to the First Amendment had
it chosen to run the forum itself, MNN assumed the same
responsibility when it accepted the delegation.
A
When a person alleges a violation of the right
to free speech, courts generally must consider not only what was
said but also in what context it was said.
On the one hand, there are “public forums,” or
settings that the government has opened in some way for speech by
the public (or some subset of it). The Court’s precedents subdivide
this broader category into various subcategories, with the level of
leeway for government regulation of speech varying accordingly. See Minnesota Voters Alliance v. Mansky , 585 U. S.
___, ___ (2018) (slip op., at 7). Compare Frisby v. Schultz , 487 U.S.
474 , 480 (1988) (streets and public parks, traditional public
forums), with Southeastern Promotions, Ltd. v. Conrad , 420 U.S.
546 , 555 (1975) (city-leased theater, designated public forum),
with Christian Legal Soc. Chapter of Univ. of Cal., Hastings
College of Law v. Martinez , 561
U.S. 661 , 669, 679, and n. 12 (2010) (program for registered
student organizations, limited public forum). But while many cases
turn on which type of “forum” is implicated, the important point
here is that viewpoint discrimination is impermissible in them all.
See Good News Club v. Milford Central School , 533 U.S.
98 , 106 (2001).
On the other hand, there are contexts that do
not fall under the “forum” rubric. For one, there are contexts in
which the government is simply engaging in its own speech and thus
has freedom to select the views it prefers. See, e.g. , Walker v. Texas Div. , Sons of Confederate
Veterans , Inc. , 576 U. S. ___, ___–___ (2015) (slip
op., at 6–7) (specialty license plates); Pleasant Grove City v. Summum , 555 U.S.
460 , 467–469, 481 (2009) (privately donated permanent monuments
in a public park).[ 1 ] In
addition, there are purely private spaces, where the First
Amendment is (as relevant here) inapplicable. The First Amendment
leaves a private store owner (or homeowner), for example, free to
remove a customer (or dinner guest) for expressing unwanted views.
See, e.g. , Lloyd Corp. v. Tanner , 407 U.S.
551 , 569–570 (1972). In these settings, there is no First
Amendment right against viewpoint discrimination.
Here, respondents alleged viewpoint
discrimination. App. 39. So a key question in this case concerns
what the Manhattan public-access channels are: a public forum of
some kind, in which a claim alleging viewpoint discrimination would
be cognizable, or something else, such as government speech or
purely private property, where picking favored viewpoints is
appropriately commonplace.[ 2 ]
Neither MNN nor the majority suggests that this is an instance of
government speech. This case thus turns first and foremost on
whether the public-access channels are or are not purely private
property.[ 3 ]
1
This Court has not defined precisely what kind
of governmental property interest (if any) is necessary for a
public forum to exist. See Cornelius v. NAACP Legal
Defense & Ed. Fund, Inc. , 473 U.S.
788 , 801 (1985) (“a speaker must seek access to public property
or to private property dedicated to public use”). But see ante , at 11, n. 3 (appearing to reject the phrase
“private property dedicated to public use” as “passing dicta”). I
assume for the sake of argument in this case that public-forum
analysis is inappropriate where the government lacks a “significant
property interest consistent with the communicative purpose of the
forum.” Denver Area Ed. Telecommunications Consortium, Inc. v. FCC , 518 U.S.
727 , 829 (1996) (Thomas, J., concurring in judgment in part and
dissenting in part).
Such an interest is present here. As described
above, New York State required the City to obtain public-access
channels from Time Warner in exchange for awarding a cable
franchise. See supra , at 2. The exclusive right to use these
channels (and, as necessary, Time Warner’s infrastructure)
qualifies as a property interest, akin at the very least to an
easement.
The last time this Court considered a case
centering on public-access channels, five Justices described an
interest like the one here as similar to an easement. Although
Justice Breyer did not conclude that a public-access channel was
indeed a public forum, he likened the cable company’s agreement to
reserve such channels “to the reservation of a public easement, or
a dedication of land for streets and parks, as part of a
municipality’s approval of a subdivision of land.” Denver
Area , 518 U. S., at 760–761 (joined by Stevens and Souter,
JJ.). And Justice Kennedy observed not only that an easement would
be an appropriate analogy, id., at 793–794 (opinion
concurring in part, concurring in judgment in part, and dissenting
in part, joined by Ginsburg, J.), but also that “[p]ublic access
channels meet the definition of a public forum,” id., at
791, “even though they operate over property to which the cable
operator holds title,” id., at 792; see also id., at
792–793 (noting that the entire cable system’s existence stems from
the municipality’s decision to grant the franchise). What those
five Justices suggested in 1996 remains true today.
“A common idiom describes property as a
‘bundle of sticks’—a collection of individual rights
which, in certain combinations, constitute property.” United
States v. Craft , 535 U.S.
274 , 278 (2002). Rights to exclude and to use are two of the
most crucial sticks in the bundle. See id., at 283. “State
law determines . . . which sticks are in a person’s
bundle,” id., at 278, and therefore defining property itself
is a state-law exercise.[ 4 ] As
for whether there is a sufficient property interest to trigger
First Amendment forum analysis, related precedents show that there
is.
As noted above, there is no disputing that Time
Warner owns the wires themselves. See Turner , 512
U. S., at 628. If the wires were a road, it would be easy to
define the public’s right to walk on it as an easement. See, e.g. , In re India Street , 29 N.Y.2d 97 , 100–103, 272 N. E 2d 518, 518–520 (1971).
Similarly, if the wires were a theater, there would be no question
that a government’s long-term lease to use it would be sufficient
for public-forum pur- poses. Southeastern Promotions , 420
U. S., at 547, 555. But some may find this case more
complicated because the wires are not a road or a theater that one
can physically occupy; they are a conduit for transmitting signals
that appear as television channels. In other words, the question is
how to understand the right to place content on those channels
using those wires.
The right to convey expressive content using
someone else’s physical infrastructure is not new. To give another
low-tech example, imagine that one company owns a billboard and
another rents space on that billboard. The renter can have a
property interest in placing content on the billboard for the lease
term even though it does not own the billboard itself. See, e.g., Naegele Outdoor Advertising Co. of Minneapolis v. Lakeville , 532 N.W.2d 249 , 253 (Minn. 1995); see also Matter of XAR
Corp. v. Di Donato , 76 App. Div. 2d 972, 973, 429
N.Y.S.2d 59, 60 (1980) (“Although invariably labeled ‘leases,’
agreements to erect advertising signs or to place signs on walls or
fences are easements in gross”).
The same principle should operate in this higher
tech realm. Just as if the channels were a billboard, the City
obtained rights for exclusive use of the channels by the public for
the foreseeable future; no one is free to take the channels away,
short of a contract renegotiation. Cf. Craft , 535
U. S., at 283. The City also obtained the right to administer,
or delegate the administration of, the channels. The channels are
more intangible than a billboard, but no one believes that a right
must be tangible to qualify as a property interest. See, e.g. , Armstrong v. United States , 364 U.S.
40 , 48–49 (1960) (treating destruction of valid liens as a
taking); Adams Express Co. v. Ohio State Auditor , 166 U.S.
185 , 219 (1897) (treating “privileges, corporate franchises,
contracts or obligations” as taxable property). And it is hardly
unprecedented for a government to receive a right to transmit
something over a private entity’s infrastructure in exchange for
conferring something of value on that private entity; examples go
back at least as far as the 1800s.[ 5 ]
I do not suggest that the government always
obtains a property interest in public-access channels created by
franchise agreements. But the arrangement here is consistent with
what the Court would treat as a governmental property interest in
other contexts. New York City gave Time Warner the right to lay
wires and sell cable TV. In exchange, the City received an
exclusive right to send its own signal over Time Warner’s
infrastructure—no different than receiving a right to place ads on
another’s billboards. Those rights amount to a governmental
property interest in the channels, and that property interest is
clearly “consistent with the communicative purpose of the forum,” Denver Area , 518 U. S., at 829 (opinion of Thomas, J.).
Indeed, it is the right to transmit the very content to which New
York law grants the public open and equal access.
2
With the question of a governmental property
interest resolved, it should become clear that the public-access
channels are a public forum.[ 6 ]
Outside of classic examples like sidewalks and parks, a public
forum exists only where the government has deliberately opened up
the setting for speech by at least a subset of the public. Cornelius , 473 U. S., at 802. “Accordingly, the Court
has looked to the policy and practice of the government,” as well
as the nature of the property itself, “to ascertain whether it
intended to designate a place not traditionally open to assembly
and debate as a public forum.” See ibid. For example, a
state college might make its facilities open to student groups, or
a municipality might open up an auditorium for certain public
meetings. See id. , at 802–803.
The requisite governmental intent is manifest
here. As noted above, New York State regulations require that the
channels be made available to the public “on a first-come,
first-served, nondiscriminatory basis.” 16 N. Y. Codes, Rules
& Regs. §895.4(c)(4); see also §§895.4(c)(8)–(9). The State, in
other words, mandates that the doors be wide open for public
expression. MNN’s contract with Time Warner follows suit. App. 23.
And that is essentially how MNN itself describes things. See Tr. of
Oral Arg. 9 (“We do not prescreen videos. We—they come into the
door. We put them on the air”).[ 7 ] These regulations “evidenc[e] a clear intent to create
a public forum.” Cornelius , 473 U. S., at 802.
B
If New York’s public-access channels are a
public forum, it follows that New York cannot evade the First
Amendment by contracting out administration of that forum to a
private agent. When MNN took on the responsibility of administering
the forum, it stood in the City’s shoes and became a state actor
for purposes of 42 U. S. C. §1983.
This conclusion follows from the Court’s
decision in West v. Atkins , 487 U.S.
42 (1988). The Court in West unanimously held that a
doctor hired to provide medical care to state prisoners was a state
actor for purposes of §1983. Id. , at 54; see also id., at 58 (Scalia, J., concurring in part and concurring in
judgment). Each State must provide medical care to prisoners, the
Court explained, id., at 54, and when a State hires a
private doctor to do that job, the doctor becomes a state actor,
“ ‘clothed with the authority of state law,’ ” id. , at 55. If a doctor hired by the State abuses his role,
the harm is “caused, in the sense relevant for state-action
inquiry,” by the State’s having incarcerated the prisoner and put
his medical care in that doctor’s hands. Ibid. The fact that the doctor was a private
contractor, the Court emphasized, made no difference. Ibid. It was “the physician’s function within the state system,” not his
private-contractor status, that determined whether his conduct
could “fairly be attributed to the State.” Id. , at 55–56.
Once the State imprisoned the plaintiff, it owed him duties under
the Eighth Amendment; once the State delegated those duties to a
private doctor, the doctor became a state actor. See ibid. ;
see also id. , at 56–57. If the rule were any different, a
State would “ ‘be free to contract out all services which it
is constitutionally obligated to provide and leave its citizens
with no means for vindication of those rights, whose protection has
been delegated to ‘private’ actors, when they have been
denied.’ ” Id., at 56, n. 14. West resolves this case. Although the
settings are different, the legal features are the same: When a
government (1) makes a choice that triggers constitutional
obligations, and then (2) contracts out those constitutional
responsibilities to a private entity, that entity—in agreeing to
take on the job—becomes a state actor for purposes of
§1983.[ 8 ]
Not all acts of governmental delegation
necessarily trigger constitutional obligations, but this one did.
New York State regulations required the City to secure
public-access channels if it awarded a cable franchise. 16
N. Y. Codes, Rules & Regs. §895.4(b)(1). The City did
award a cable franchise. The State’s regulations then required the
City to make the channels it obtained available on a “first-come,
first-served, nondiscriminatory basis.”[ 9 ] §895.4(c)(4). That made the channels a public forum.
See supra, at 9–10. Opening a public forum, in turn,
entailed First Amendment obligations.
The City could have done the job itself, but it
instead delegated that job to a private entity, MNN. MNN could have
said no, but it said yes. (Indeed, it appears to exist entirely to
do this job.) By accepting the job, MNN accepted the City’s
responsibilities. See West , 487 U. S., at 55. The First
Amendment does not fall silent simply because a government hands
off the administration of its constitutional duties to a private
actor.
III
The majority acknowledges that the First
Amendment could apply when a local government either (1) has a
property interest in public-access channels or (2) is more directly
involved in administration of those channels than the City is here. Ante , at 15. And it emphasizes that it “decide[s] only the
case before us in light of the record before us.” Ibid .
These case-specific qualifiers sharply limit the immediate effect
of the majority’s decision, but that decision is still meaningfully
wrong in two ways. First, the majority erroneously decides the
property question against the plaintiffs as a matter of law.
Second, and more fundamentally, the majority mistakes a case about
the government choosing to hand off responsibility to an agent for
a case about a private entity that simply enters a marketplace.
A
The majority’s explanation for why there is no
governmental property interest here, ante , at 14–15, does
not hold up. The majority focuses on the fact that “[b]oth Time
Warner and MNN are private entities”; that Time Warner “owns its
cable network, which contains the public access channels”; and that
“MNN operates those public access channels with its own facilities
and equipment.” Ante , at 14; see also ante , at 15.
Those considerations cannot resolve this case. The issue is not who
owns the cable network or that MNN uses its own property to operate
the channels. The key question, rather, is whether the channels
themselves are purely private property. An advertiser may not own a
billboard, but that does not mean that its long-term lease is not a
property interest. See supra , at 8.
The majority also says that “[n]othing in the
record here suggests that a government . . . owns or
leases either the cable system or the public access channels at
issue here.” Ante , at 14. But the cable system itself is
irrelevant, and, as explained above, the details of the exchange
that yielded Time Warner’s cable franchise suggest a governmental
property interest in the channels. See supra, at 6–9.
The majority observes that “the franchise
agreements expressly place the public access channels ‘under the
jurisdiction’ of MNN,” ante , at 14, but that language sim-
ply describes the City’s appointment of MNN to administer the
channels. The majority also chides respondents for failing to
“alleg[e] in their complaint that the City has a property interest
in the channels,” ibid. , but, fairly read, respondents’
complaint includes such an assertion.[ 10 ] In any event, any ambiguity or imprecision does not
justify resolving the case against respondents at the
motion-to-dismiss stage. To the extent the majority has doubts
about respondents’ complaint—or factual or state-law issues that
may bear upon the existence of a property interest—the more prudent
course would be to vacate and remand for the lower courts to
consider those matters more fully. In any event, as I have
explained, the best course of all would be to affirm.
B
More fundamentally, the majority’s opinion
erroneously fixates on a type of case that is not before us: one in
which a private entity simply enters the marketplace and is then
subject to government regulation. The majority swings hard at the
wrong pitch.
The majority focuses on Jackson v. Metropolitan Edison Co. , 419 U.S.
345 (1974), which is a paradigmatic example of a line of cases
that reject §1983 liability for private actors that simply operate
against a regulatory backdrop. Jackson emphasized that the
“fact that a business is subject to state regulation does not by
itself convert its action into that of the State.” Id. , at
350; accord, ante , at 12. Thus, the fact that a utility
company entered the marketplace did not make it a state actor, even
if it was highly regulated. See Jackson , 419 U. S., at
358; accord, ante , at 12–13. The same rule holds, of course,
for private comedy clubs and grocery stores. See ante , at
9.[ 11 ]
The Jackson line of cases is inapposite
here. MNN is not a private entity that simply ventured into the
marketplace. It occupies its role because it was asked to do so by
the City, which secured the public-access channels in exchange for
giving up public rights of way, opened those channels up (as
required by the State) as a public forum, and then deputized MNN to
administer them. That distinguishes MNN from a private entity that
simply sets up shop against a regulatory backdrop. To say that MNN
is nothing more than a private organization regulated by the
government is like saying that a waiter at a restaurant is an
independent food seller who just happens to be highly regulated by
the restaurant’s owners.
The majority also relies on the Court’s
statements that its “public function” test requires that a function
have been “traditionally and exclusively performed” by the
government. Ante , at 6 (emphasis deleted); see Jackson , 419 U. S., at 352. Properly understood, that
rule cabins liability in cases, such as Jackson , in which a
private actor ventures of its own accord into territory shared (or
regulated) by the government ( e.g. , by opening a power com-
pany or a shopping center). The Court made clear in West that the rule did not reach further, explaining that “the fact that
a state employee’s role parallels one in the private sector” does
not preclude a finding of state action. 487 U. S., at 56,
n. 15.
When the government hires an agent, in other
words, the question is not whether it hired the agent to do
something that can be done in the private marketplace too. If that
were the key question, the doctor in West would not have
been a state actor. Nobody thinks that orthopedics is a function
“traditionally exclusively reserved to the State,” Jackson ,
419 U. S., at 352.
The majority consigns West to a footnote,
asserting that its “scenario is not present here because the
government has no [constitutional] obligation to operate public
access channels.” Ante , at 7, n. 1. The majority
suggests that West is different because “the State was
constitutionally obligated to provide medical care to prison
inmates.” Ante , at 7, n. 1. But what the majority
ignores is that the State in West had no constitutional
obligation to open the prison or incarcerate the prisoner in the
first place; the obligation to provide medical care arose when it
made those prior choices.
The City had a comparable constitutional
obligation here—one brought about by its own choices, made against
a state-law backdrop. The City, of course, had no constitutional
obligation to award a cable franchise or to operate public-access
channels. But once the City did award a cable franchise, New York
law required the City to obtain public-access channels, see supra , at 2, and to open them up as a public forum, see supra , at 9–10. That is when the City’s obligation to act in
accordance with the First Amendment with respect to the channels
arose. That is why, when the City handed the administration of that
forum off to an agent, the Constitution followed. See supra ,
at 10–13.[ 12 ]
The majority is surely correct that “when a
private entity provides a forum for speech, the private entity is
not ordinarily constrained by the First Amendment.” Ante , at
9. That is because the majority is not talking about constitutional forums—it is talking about spaces where
private entities have simply invited others to come speak. A comedy
club can decide to open its doors as wide as it wants, but it
cannot appoint itself as a government agent. The difference is
between providing a service of one’s own accord and being asked by
the government to administer a constitutional responsibility
(indeed, here, existing to do so) on the government’s
behalf.[ 13 ]
To see more clearly the difference between the
cases on which the majority fixates and the present case, leave
aside the majority’s private comedy club. Imagine instead that a
state college runs a comedy showcase each year, renting out a local
theater and, pursuant to state regulations mandating open access to
certain kinds of student activities, allowing students to sign up
to perform on a first-come, first-served basis. Cf. Rosenberger v. Rector and Visitors of Univ. of Va. , 515 U.S.
819 (1995). After a few years, the college decides that it is
tired of running the show, so it hires a performing-arts nonprofit
to do the job. The nonprofit prefers humor that makes fun of a
certain political party, so it allows only student acts that share
its views to participate. Does the majority believe that the
nonprofit is indistinguishable, for purposes of state action, from
a private comedy club opened by local entrepreneurs?
I hope not. But two dangers lurk here
regardless. On the one hand, if the City’s decision to outsource
the channels to a private entity did render the First Amendment
irrelevant, there would be substantial cause to worry about the
potential abuses that could follow. Can a state university evade
the First Amendment by hiring a nonprofit to apportion funding to
student groups? Can a city do the same by appointing a corporation
to run a municipal theater? What about its parks?
On the other hand, the majority hastens to
qualify its decision, see ante , at 7, n. 1, 15, and to
cabin it to the specific facts of this case, ante , at 15.
Those are prudent limitations. Even so, the majority’s focus on Jackson still risks sowing confusion among the lower courts
about how and when government outsourcing will render any abuses
that follow beyond the reach of the Constitution.
In any event, there should be no confusion here.
MNN is not a private entity that ventured into the marketplace and
found itself subject to government regulation. It was asked to do a
job by the government and compensated accordingly. If it does not
want to do that job anymore, it can stop (subject, like any other
entity, to its contractual obligations). But as long as MNN
continues to wield the power it was given by the government, it
stands in the government’s shoes and must abide by the First
Amendment like any other government actor.
IV
This is not a case about bigger governments
and smaller individuals, ante , at 16; it is a case about
principals and agents. New York City opened up a public forum on
public-access channels in which it has a property interest. It
asked MNN to run that public forum, and MNN accepted the job. That
makes MNN subject to the First Amendment, just as if the City had
decided to run the public forum itself.
While the majority emphasizes that its decision
is narrow and factbound, ante , at 15, that does not make it
any less misguided. It is crucial that the Court does not continue
to ignore the reality, fully recognized by our precedents, that
private actors who have been delegated constitutional
responsibilities like this one should be accountable to the
Constitution’s demands. I respectfully dissent. Notes 1 That does not mean that
no restrictions apply at all to the government’s expression in such
spaces, but it does mean that the government can pick and choose
among different views. See Walker , 576 U. S., at ___,
___–___ (slip op., at 6, 17–18); Summum , 555 U. S., at
468. 2 The channels are not, of
course, a physical place. Under the Court’s precedents, that makes
no difference: Regardless of whether something “is a forum more in
a metaphysical than in a spatial or geographic sense,
. . . the same principles are applicable.” Rosenberger v. Rector and Visitors of Univ. of Va. , 515 U.S.
819 , 830 (1995) (treating “Student Activities Fund” as the
forum at issue and citing cases in which a school’s mail system and
a charity drive were the relevant forums). 3 As discussed below, it is
possible that some (or even many) public-access channels are
government speech. The channels that MNN administers, however, are
clearly better thought of as a public forum given the New York
regulations mandating open and equal access. See infra , at
9–10, and n. 7. 4 The parties have not
pointed this Court to any New York law definitively establishing
the status of the channels. But even if there were uncertainty
about the status of the channels under New York law, that would not
be a reason to resolve the case against respondents (plaintiffs
below) at the motion to dismiss stage. See infra , at 12,
n. 9, 14. 5 For example, during the
railroad boom, governments obtained not only physical easements in
favor of the public over tracks used, owned, and managed by private
railroads, including rights to use the rails and all relevant
“fixtures and appurtenances,” see, e.g., Lake Superior &
Mississippi R. Co. v. United States , 93 U.S.
442 , 444, 453–454 (1877), but also, in some situations, rights
to transmit personnel and freight for free or at reduced rates,
Ellis, Railroad Land Grant Rates, 1850–1945, 21 J. Land & P. U.
Econ. 207, 209, 211–212 (1945). 6 Though the majority
disagrees on the property question, I do not take it seriously to
dispute that this point would follow. See ante , at
14–15. 7 New York may be uncommon
(as it often is); public-access channels in other States may well
have different policies and practices that make them more like
government speech than constitutional forums. See Brief for
Respondents 30–31; Brief for American Civil Liberties Union
et al. as Amici Curiae 13–15. New York’s scheme,
however, is the only one before us. 8 Governments are, of
course, not constitutionally required to open prisons or public
forums, but once they do either of these things, constitutional
obligations attach. The rule that a government may not evade the
Constitution by substituting a private administrator, meanwhile, is
not a prison-specific rule. More than 50 years ago, for example,
this Court made clear in Evans v. Newton , 382 U.S.
296 (1966), that the city of Macon, Georgia, could not evade
the Fourteenth Amendment’s Equal Protection Clause by handing off
control of a park to a group “of ‘private’ trustees.” Id. ,
at 301. Rather, “the public character of [the] park require[d] that
it be treated as a public institution subject to the command of the
Fourteenth Amendment, regardless of who ha[d] title under state
law.” Id. , at 302. 9 Accordingly, this is not
a case in which a private entity has been asked to exercise
standardless discretion. See, e.g., American Mfrs. Mut.
Ins. Co. v. Sullivan , 526 U.S.
40 , 52 (1999). Had New York law left MNN free to choose its
favorite submissions, for example, a different result might well
follow. MNN has suggested to this Court that its contract with Time
Warner allows it “to curate content, to decide to put shows
together on one of our channels or a different channel.” Tr. of
Oral Arg. 6; see Reply Brief 9. But MNN’s contract cannot defeat
New York law’s “first-come, first-served, nondiscriminatory”
scheduling requirement, 16 N. Y. Codes, Rules & Regs.
§895.4(c)(4), and the discretion MNN asserts seems to be at most
some limited authority to coordinate the exact placement and timing
of the content it is obliged to accept indiscriminately, see Tr. of
Oral Arg. 25–26. That seems akin to the authority to make
reasonable time, place, and manner provisions, which is consistent
with administering any public forum. See Ward v. Rock
Against Racism , 491 U.S.
781 , 791 (1989). As for any factual assertions about how the
channels are operated in practice, this case arises from MNN’s
motion to dismiss, so the facts asserted against it must be
accepted as true. Hernandez v. Mesa , 582 U. S.
___, ___ (2017) ( per curiam ) (slip op., at 1). And any
uncertainty about the facts or New York law, in any event, would be
a reason to vacate and remand, not reverse. 10 Respondents alleged that the City
“created an electronic public forum” and “delegat[ed] control of
that forum to” MNN. App. 17. They further alleged that “[a]lmost
all cable franchise agreements require cable operators—as a
condition for easements to use the public rights-of-way—to dedicate
some channels for programming by the public,” id ., at 20,
invoked the state regulations requiring the designation of a
channel here, id ., at 21, and then alleged that the City’s
franchise agreement “requires Time Warner to set aside” the
channels, id ., at 22. While the complaint does not use the
words “property interest,” those allegations can be read to include
the idea that whatever was “set aside” or “dedicate[d],” id ., at 20, 22, qualified as a sufficient City property
interest to support respondents’ assertion of a public forum. Cf. People v. Brooklyn & Queens Transit Corp. , 273
N.Y. 394, 400–401, 7 N.E.2d 833, 835 (1937) (discussing dedications
of property to public use); cf. also Denver Area Ed.
Telecommunications Consortium, Inc. v. FCC , 518 U.S.
727 , 794 (1996) (Kennedy, J., concurring in part, concurring in
judgment in part, and dissenting in part) (noting
thistheory). 11 There
was a time when this Court’s precedents may have portended the kind
of First Amendment liability for purely private property owners
that the majority spends so much time rejecting. See Marsh v. Alabama , 326 U.S.
501 , 505–509 (1946) (treating a company-owned town as subject
to the First Amendment); Food Employees v. Logan Valley
Plaza , Inc. , 391 U.S.
308 , 315–320, and n. 9, 325 (1968) (extending Marsh to cover a private shopping center to the extent that it sought to
restrict speech about its businesses). But the Court soon stanched
that trend. See Lloyd Corp. v. Tanner , 407 U.S.
551 , 561–567 (1972) (cabining Marsh and refusing to
extend Logan Valley ); Hudgens v. NLRB , 424
U.S. 507 , 518 (1976) (making clear that “the rationale of Logan Valley did not survive” Lloyd ). Ever since,
this Court has been reluctant to find a “public function” when it
comes to “private commercial transactions” (even if they occur
against a legal or regulatory backdrop), see, e.g., Flagg
Bros. , Inc. v. Brooks , 436
U.S. 149 , 161–163 (1978), instead requiring a closer connection
between the private entity and a government or its agents, see, e.g. , Brentwood Academy v. Tennessee Secondary
School Athletic Assn. , 531 U.S.
288 , 298 (2001) (nonprofit interscholastic athletic association
“pervasive[ly] entwine[d]” with governmental institutions and
officials); Lugar v. Edmondson Oil Co. , 457 U.S.
922 , 942 (1982) (state-created system “whereby state officials
[would] attach property on the ex parte application of
one party to a private dispute”); see also Burton v. Wilmington Parking Authority , 365 U.S.
715 , 723–725 (1961) (restaurant in municipal parking garage
partly maintained by municipal agency); accord, ante , at
6–7. Jackson exemplifies the line of cases that supplanted
cases like Logan Valley —not cases like this
one. 12 Jackson v. Metropolitan
Edison Co ., 419 U.S.
345 (1974), by contrast, exemplifies a type of case in which a
private actor provides a service that there is no governmental
obligation to provide at all. See id ., at 353 (no state
requirement for government to provide utility service); see also, e.g., Hudgens , 424 U.S.
507 (shopping center). In West v. Atkins , 487 U.S.
42 (1988), by contrast, the prison was obli-gated to provide
health care in accordance with the Eighth Amendment to its
prisoners once it incarcerated them, and here, the City was
required to provide a public forum to its residents in accordance
with the First Amendment once it granted the cable franchise. See supra, at 11–13. 13 Accordingly, the majority need not
fear that “all private property owners and private lessees who open
their property for speech [c]ould be subject to First Amendment
constraints.” Ante , at 10. Those kinds of entities are not
the government’s agents; MNN is. Whether such entities face
“extensive regulation” or require “government licenses, government
contracts, or government-granted monopolies,” ante , at 12,
is immaterial, so long as they have not accepted the government’s
request to fulfill the government’s duties on its
behalf. | The Supreme Court ruled that a private nonprofit corporation, MNN, operating public access channels on a cable system in Manhattan, is not a state actor and is therefore not subject to First Amendment constraints on its editorial discretion. The Court applied the state-action doctrine, which distinguishes between governmental and private actors, and concluded that operating public access channels is not a traditional, exclusive public function. The Court also emphasized that a private entity opening its property for speech by others does not automatically become a state actor. This decision upholds the editorial discretion of private entities managing public access channels, even when granted a government-authorized monopoly. |
Free Speech | Sorrel v. IMS Health, Inc. | https://supreme.justia.com/cases/federal/us/564/552/ | OPINION OF THE COURT SORRELL V. IMS HEALTH INC. 564 U. S. ____ (2011) SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES NO. 10-779 WILLIAM H. SORRELL, ATTORNEY GENERAL OF VERMONT,
et al., PETITIONERS v. IMS HEALTH INC.
et al.
on writ of certiorari to the united states court of
appeals for the second circuit
[June 23, 2011]
Justice Kennedy delivered the
opinion of the Court.
Vermont law restricts the sale,
disclosure, and use of pharmacy records that reveal the prescribing
practices of individual doctors. Vt. Stat. Ann., Tit. 18, §4631
(Supp. 2010). Subject to certain exceptions, the information may
not be sold, disclosed by pharmacies for marketing purposes, or
used for marketing by pharmaceutical manufacturers. Vermont argues
that its prohibitions safeguard medical privacy and diminish the
likelihood that marketing will lead to prescription decisions not
in the best interests of patients or the State. It can be assumed
that these interests are significant. Speech in aid of
pharmaceutical marketing, however, is a form of expression
protected by the Free Speech Clause of the First Amendment. As a
consequence, Vermont’s statute must be subjected to heightened
judicial scrutiny. The law cannot satisfy that standard.
I
A
Pharmaceutical manufacturers
promote their drugs to doctors through a process called
“detailing.” This often in- volves a scheduled visit to a doctor’s
office to persuade the doctor to prescribe a particular
pharmaceutical. Detailers bring drug samples as well as medical
studies that explain the “details” and potential advantages of
various prescription drugs. Interested physicians listen, ask
questions, and receive followup data. Salespersons can be more
effective when they know the background and purchasing preferences
of their clientele, and pharmaceutical salespersons are no
exception. Knowledge of a physi- cian’s prescription
practices—called “prescriber-identifying information”—enables a
detailer better to ascertain which doctors are likely to be
interested in a particular drug and how best to present a
particular sales message. Detailing is an expensive undertaking, so
pharmaceutical companies most often use it to promote high-profit
brand-name drugs protected by patent. Once a brand-name drug’s
patent expires, less expensive bioequivalent generic alternatives
are manufactured and sold.
Pharmacies, as a matter of
business routine and federal law, receive prescriber-identifying
information when processing prescriptions. See 21 U. S. C.
§353(b); see also Vt. Bd. of Pharmacy Admin. Rule 9.1 (2009); Rule
9.2. Many pharmacies sell this information to “data miners,” firms
that analyze prescriber-identifying information and produce reports
on prescriber behavior. Data miners lease these reports to
pharmaceutical manufacturers subject to nondisclosure agreements.
Detailers, who represent the manufacturers, then use the reports to
refine their marketing tactics and increase sales.
In 2007, Vermont enacted the Prescription
Confidentiality Law. The measure is also referred to as Act 80. It
has several components. The central provision of the present case
is §4631(d).
“A health insurer, a self-insured employer, an
electronic transmission intermediary, a pharmacy, or other similar
entity shall not sell, license, or exchange for value regulated
records containing prescriber-identifiable information, nor permit
the use of regulated records containing prescriber-identifiable
information for marketing or promoting a prescription drug, unless
the prescriber consents … . Pharmaceutical manufacturers
and pharmaceutical marketers shall not use prescriber-identifiable
information for marketing or promoting a prescription drug unless
the prescriber consents … .”
The quoted provision has three component parts. The
provision begins by prohibiting pharmacies, health insurers, and
similar entities from selling prescriber-identifying information,
absent the prescriber’s consent. The parties here dispute whether
this clause applies to all sales or only to sales for marketing.
The provision then goes on to prohibit pharmacies, health insurers,
and similar enti- ties from allowing prescriber-identifying
information to be used for marketing, unless the prescriber
consents. This prohibition in effect bars pharmacies from
disclosing the information for marketing purposes. Finally, the
provision’s second sentence bars pharmaceutical manufacturers and
pharmaceutical marketers from using prescriber-identifying
information for marketing, again absent the prescriber’s consent.
The Vermont attorney general may pursue civil remedies against
violators. §4631(f).
Separate statutory provisions elaborate the
scope of the prohibitions set out in §4631(d). “Marketing” is
defined to include “advertising, promotion, or any activity” that
is “used to influence sales or the market share of a prescription
drug.” §4631(b)(5). Section 4631(c)(1) further provides that
Vermont’s Department of Health must allow “a prescriber to give
consent for his or her identifying information to be used for the
purposes” identified in §4631(d). Finally, the Act’s prohibitions
on sale, disclosure, and use are subject to a list of exceptions.
For example, prescriber-identifying information may be disseminated
or used for “health care research”; to enforce “compliance” with
health insurance formularies, or preferred drug lists; for “care
management educational communications provided to” patients on such
matters as “treatment options”; for law enforcement operations; and
for purposes “otherwise provided by law.” §4631(e).
Act 80 also authorized funds for an
“evidence-based pre-scription drug education program” designed to
provide doctors and others with “information and education on the
therapeutic and cost-effective utilization of prescription drugs.”
§4622(a)(1). An express aim of the program is to advise prescribers
“about commonly used brand-name drugs for which the patent has
expired” or will soon expire. §4622(a)(2). Similar efforts to
promote the use of generic pharmaceuticals are sometimes referred
to as “counter-detailing.” App. 211; see also IMS Health
Inc. v. Ayotte , 550 F. 3d 42, 91 (CA1 2008)
(Lipez, J., concurring and dissenting). The counterdetailer’s
recommended substitute may be an older, less expensive drug and not
a bioequivalent of the brand-name drug the physician might
otherwise prescribe. Like the pharmaceutical manufacturers whose
efforts they hope to resist, counterdetailers in some States use
prescriber-identifying information to increase their effectiveness.
States themselves may supply the prescriber-identifying information
used in these programs. See App. 313; id. , at 375 (“[W]e
use the data given to us by the State of Pennsylvania … to
figure out which physicians to talk to”); see also id ., at
427–429 (Director of the Office of Vermont Health Access explaining
that the office collects prescriber-identifying information but
“does not at this point in time have a counterdetailing or
detailing effort”). As first enacted, Act 80 also required
detailers to provide information about alternative treatment
options. The Vermont Legislature, however, later repealed that
provision. 2008 Vt. Laws No. 89, §3.
Act 80 was accompanied by legislative
findings. Vt. Acts No. 80, §1. Vermont found, for example, that the
“goals of marketing programs are often in conflict with the goals
of the state” and that the “marketplace for ideas on medicine
safety and effectiveness is frequently one-sided in that brand-name
companies invest in expensive pharmaceutical marketing campaigns to
doctors.” §§1(3), (4). Detailing, in the legislature’s view, caused
doctors to make decisions based on “incomplete and biased
information.” §1(4). Because they “are unable to take the time to
research the quickly changing pharmaceutical market,” Vermont
doctors “rely on information provided by pharmaceutical
representatives.” §1(13). The legislature further found that
detailing increases the cost of health care and health insurance,
§1(15); encourages hasty and excessive reliance on brand-name
drugs, before the profession has observed their effectiveness as
compared with older and less expensive generic alternatives, §1(7);
and fosters disruptive and repeated marketing visits tantamount to
harassment, §§1(27)–(28). The legislative findings further noted
that use of prescriber-identifying information “increase[s] the
effect of detailing programs” by allowing detailers to target their
visits to particular doctors. §§1(23)–(26). Use of
prescriber-identifying data also helps detailers shape their
messages by “tailoring” their “presentations to individual
prescriber styles, preferences, and attitudes.” §1(25).
B
The present case involves two
consolidated suits. One was brought by three Vermont data miners,
the other by an association of pharmaceutical manufacturers that
produce brand-name drugs. These entities are the respondents here.
Contending that §4631(d) violates their First Amendment rights as
incorporated by the Fourteenth Amendment, the respondents sought
declaratory and injunctive relief against the petitioners, the
Attorney General and other officials of the State of Vermont.
After a bench trial, the United
States District Court for the District of Vermont denied relief.
631 F. Supp. 2d 434 (2009). The District Court found that
“[p]harmaceutical manufacturers are essentially the only paying
customers of the data vendor industry” and that, because detailing
unpatented generic drugs is not “cost-effective,” pharmaceutical
sales representatives “detail only branded drugs.” Id ., at
451, 442. As the District Court further con- cluded, “the
Legislature’s determination that [prescriber-identifying] data is
an effective marketing tool that enables detailers to increase
sales of new drugs is supported in the record.” Id ., at
451. The United States Court of Appeals for the Second Circuit
reversed and remanded. It held that §4631(d) violates the First
Amendment by burdening the speech of pharmaceutical marketers and
data miners without an adequate justification. 630 F. 3d 263.
Judge Livingston dissented.
The decision of the Second Circuit is in
conflict with de- cisions of the United States Court of Appeals for
the First Circuit concerning similar legislation enacted by Maine
and New Hampshire. See IMS Health Inc. v. Mills ,
616 F. 3d 7 (CA1 2010) (Maine); Ayotte , supra (New Hamp- shire). Recognizing a division of
authority regarding the constitutionality of state statutes, this
Court granted certiorari. 562 U. S. __ (2011).
II
The beginning point is the text
of §4631(d). In the pro- ceedings below, Vermont stated that the
first sentence of §4631(d) prohibits pharmacies and other regulated
entities from selling or disseminating prescriber-identifying
information for marketing. The information, in other words, could
be sold or given away for purposes other than marketing. The
District Court and the Court of Appeals accepted the State’s
reading. See 630 F. 3d, at 276. At oral argument in this
Court, however, the State for the first time advanced an
alternative reading of §4631(d)—namely, that pharmacies, health
insurers, and similar entities may not sell prescriber-identifying
information for any purpose, subject to the statutory exceptions
set out at §4631(e). See Tr. of Oral Arg. 19–20. It might be argued
that the State’s newfound interpretation comes too late in the day.
See Sprietsma v. Mercury Marine , 537 U. S. 51 , 56,
n. 4 (2002) (waiver); New Hampshire v. Maine , 532
U. S. 742 , 749 (2001) (judicial estoppel). The respondents, the
District Court, and the Court of Appeals were entitled to rely on
the State’s plausible interpretation of the law it is charged with
enforcing. For the State to change its position is particularly
troubling in a First Amendment case, where plaintiffs have a
special interest in obtaining a prompt adjudication of their
rights, despite potential ambiguities of state law. See Houston v. Hill , 482 U. S. 451 , 467–468,
and n. 17 (1987); Zwickler v. Koota , 389 U. S. 241 ,
252 (1967).
In any event, §4631(d) cannot be
sustained even under the interpretation the State now adopts. As a
consequence this Court can assume that the opening clause of
§4631(d) prohibits pharmacies, health insurers, and similar
entities from selling prescriber-identifying information, subject
to the statutory exceptions set out at §4631(e). Under that
reading, pharmacies may sell the information to private or academic
researchers, see §4631(e)(1), but not, for example, to
pharmaceutical marketers. There is no dispute as to the remainder
of §4631(d). It prohibits pharmacies, health insurers, and similar
entities from disclosing or otherwise allowing
prescriber-identifying information to be used for marketing. And it
bars pharmaceutical manufacturers and detailers from using the
information for marketing. The questions now are whether §4631(d)
must be tested by heightened judicial scrutiny and, if so, whether
the State can justify the law.
A
1
On its face, Vermont’s law enacts
content- and speaker-based restrictions on the sale, disclosure,
and use of prescriber-identifying information. The provision first
forbids sale subject to exceptions based in large part on the
content of a purchaser’s speech. For example, those who wish to
engage in certain “educational communications,” §4631(e)(4), may
purchase the information. The measure then bars any disclosure when
recipient speakers will use the information for marketing. Finally,
the provision’s second sentence prohibits pharmaceutical
manufacturers from using the information for marketing. The statute
thus disfavors marketing, that is, speech with a particular
content. More than that, the statute disfavors specific speakers,
namely pharmaceutical manufacturers. As a result of these content-
and speaker-based rules, detailers cannot obtain
prescriber-identifying information, even though the information may
be purchased or acquired by other speakers with diverse purposes
and viewpoints. Detailers are likewise barred from using the
information for marketing, even though the information may be used
by a wide range of other speakers. For example, it appears that
Vermont could supply academic organizations with
prescriber-identifying information to use in countering the
messages of brand-name pharmaceutical manufacturers and in
promoting the prescription of generic drugs. But §4631(d) leaves
detailers no means of purchasing, acquiring, or using
prescriber-identifying information. The law on its face burdens
disfavored speech by disfavored speakers.
Any doubt that §4631(d) imposes
an aimed, content-based burden on detailers is dispelled by the
record and by formal legislative findings. As the District Court
noted, “[p]harmaceutical manufacturers are essentially the only
paying customers of the data vendor industry”; and the almost
invariable rule is that detailing by pharmaceutical manufacturers
is in support of brand-name drugs. 631 F. Supp. 2d, at 451.
Vermont’s law thus has the effect of preventing detailers—and only
detailers—from communicating with physicians in an effective and
informative manner. Cf. Edenfield v. Fane , 507 U. S. 761 ,
766 (1993) (explaining the “considerable value” of in-person
solicitation). Formal legislative findings accompanying §4631(d)
confirm that the law’s express purpose and practical effect are to
diminish the effectiveness of marketing by manufacturers of
brand-name drugs. Just as the “inevitable effect of a statute on
its face may render it unconstitutional,” a statute’s stated
purposes may also be considered. United States v. O’Brien , 391 U. S. 367 , 384
(1968). Here, the Vermont Legislature explained that detailers, in
particular those who promote brand-name drugs, convey messages that
“are often in conflict with the goals of the state.” 2007 Vt. No.
80, §1(3). The legislature designed §4631(d) to target those
speakers and their messages for disfavored treatment. “In its
practical operation,” Vermont’s law “goes even beyond mere content
discrimination, to actual viewpoint discrimination.” R. A. V. v. St. Paul , 505 U. S. 377 ,
391 (1992). Given the legislature’s expressed statement of purpose,
it is apparent that §4631(d) imposes burdens that are based on the
content of speech and that are aimed at a particular viewpoint.
Act 80 is designed to impose a specific,
content-based burden on protected expression. It follows that
heightened judicial scrutiny is warranted. See Cincinnati v. Discovery Network, Inc. , 507 U. S. 410 , 418
(1993) (applying heightened scrutiny to “a categorical prohibition
on the use of newsracks to disseminate commercial messages”); id ., at 429 (“[T]he very basis for the regulation is the
difference in content between ordinary newspapers and commercial
speech” in the form of “commercial handbills … . Thus, by
any commonsense understanding of the term, the ban in this case is
‘content based’ ” (some internal quotation marks omitted));
see also Turner Broadcasting System, Inc. v. FCC , 512 U. S. 622 ,
658 (1994) (explaining that strict scrutiny applies to regulations
reflecting “aversion” to what “disfavored speakers” have to say).
The Court has recognized that the “distinction between laws
burdening and laws banning speech is but a matter of degree” and
that the “Government’s content-based burdens must satisfy the same
rigorous scrutiny as its content-based bans.” United
States v. Playboy Entertainment Group, Inc. , 529 U. S. 803 , 812
(2000). Lawmakers may no more silence unwanted speech by burdening
its utterance than by censoring its content. See Simon &
Schuster, Inc. v. Mem- bers of N. Y. State Crime Victims
Bd. , 502 U. S.
105 , 115 (1991) (content-based financial burden); Minneapolis Star & Tribune Co. v. Minnesota Comm’r
of Revenue , 460 U. S. 575 (1983) (speaker-based
financial burden).
The First Amendment requires heightened
scrutiny whenever the government creates “a regulation of speech
because of disagreement with the message it conveys.” Ward v. Rock Against Racism , 491 U. S. 781 , 791
(1989); see also Renton v. Playtime Theatres,
Inc. , 475 U. S.
41 , 48 (1986) (explaining that “ ‘content-neutral’ speech
regulations” are “those that are justified without
reference to the content of the regulated speech” (internal
quotation marks omitted)). A government bent on frustrating an
impending demonstration might pass a law demanding two years’
notice before the issuance of parade permits. Even if the
hypothetical measure on its face appeared neutral as to content and
speaker, its purpose to suppress speech and its unjustified burdens
on expression would render it unconstitutional. Ibid. Commercial speech is no exception. See Discovery Network , supra , at 429–430 (commercial speech restriction lacking a
“neutral justification” was not content neutral). A “consumer’s
concern for the free flow of commercial speech often may be far
keener than his concern for urgent political dialogue.” Bates v. State Bar of Ariz. , 433 U. S. 350 , 364
(1977). That reality has great relevance in the fields of medicine
and public health, where information can save lives.
2
The State argues that heightened
judicial scrutiny is unwarranted because its law is a mere
commercial regulation. It is true that restrictions on protected
expression are distinct from restrictions on economic activity or,
more generally, on nonexpressive conduct. It is also true that the
First Amendment does not prevent restrictions directed at commerce
or conduct from imposing inciden- tal burdens on speech. That is
why a ban on race-based hiring may require employers to remove
“ ‘White Applicants Only’ ” signs, Rumsfeld v. Forum for Academic and Institutional Rights, Inc. , 547 U. S. 47 , 62
(2006); why “an ordinance against outdoor fires” might forbid
“burning a flag,” R. A. V. , supra , at
385; and why antitrust laws can prohibit “agreements in restraint
of trade,” Giboney v. Empire Storage & Ice
Co. , 336 U. S.
490 , 502 (1949).
But §4631(d) imposes more than an
incidental burden on protected expression. Both on its face and in
its practical operation, Vermont’s law imposes a burden based on
the content of speech and the identity of the speaker. See supra , at 8–11. While the burdened speech results from an
economic motive, so too does a great deal of vital expression. See Bigelow v. Virginia , 421 U. S. 809 , 818
(1975); New York Times Co. v. Sullivan , 376 U. S. 254 , 266
(1964); see also United States v. United Foods,
Inc. , 533 U. S.
405 , 410–411 (2001) (applying “First Amendment scrutiny” where
speech effects were not incidental and noting that “those whose
business and livelihood depend in some way upon the product
involved no doubt deem First Amendment protection to be just as
important for them as it is for other discrete, little noticed
groups”). Vermont’s law does not simply have an effect on speech,
but is directed at certain content and is aimed at particular
speakers. The Constitution “does not enact Mr. Herbert Spencer’s
Social Statics.” Lochner v. New York , 198 U. S. 45 , 75 (1905)
(Holmes, J., dissenting). It does enact the First Amendment.
Vermont further argues that §4631(d) regulates
not speech but simply access to information. Prescriber-identifying
information was generated in compliance with a legal mandate, the
State argues, and so could be considered a kind of governmental
information. This argument finds some support in Los Angeles
Police Dept. v. United Reporting Publishing Corp. , 528 U. S. 32 (1999), where the Court held that a plaintiff could not raise a
facial challenge to a content-based restriction on access to
government- held information. Because no private party faced a
threat of legal punishment, the Court characterized the law at
issue as “nothing more than a governmental denial of access to
information in its possession.” Id ., at 40. Under those
circumstances the special reasons for permitting First Amendment
plaintiffs to invoke the rights of others did not apply. Id. , at 38–39. Having found that the plaintiff could not
raise a facial challenge, the Court remanded for consideration of
an as-applied challenge. Id ., at 41. United
Reporting is thus a case about the availability of facial
challenges. The Court did not rule on the merits of any First
Amendment claim. United Reporting is distinguishable
in at least two respects. First, Vermont has imposed a restriction
on access to information in private hands. This confronts the Court
with a point reserved, and a situation not addressed, in United
Reporting . Here, unlike in United Reporting , we do
have “a case in which the government is prohibiting a speaker from
conveying information that the speaker already possesses.” Id ., at 40. The difference is significant. An individual’s
right to speak is implicated when information he or she possesses
is subjected to “restraints on the way in which the information
might be used” or disseminated. Seattle Times Co. v. Rhinehart , 467 U. S. 20 , 32 (1984);
see also Bartnicki v. Vopper , 532 U. S. 514 , 527
(2001); Florida Star v. B. J. F. , 491 U. S. 524 (1989); New York Times Co. v. United States , 403 U. S. 713 (1971) (per curiam) . In Seattle Times , this Court
applied heightened judicial scrutiny before sustaining a trial
court order prohibiting a newspaper’s disclosure of information it
learned through coercive discovery. It is true that the respondents
here, unlike the newspaper in Seattle Times , do not
themselves possess information whose disclosure has been curtailed.
That information, however, is in the hands of pharmacies and other
private entities. There is no question that the “threat of
prosecution … hangs over their heads.” United Reporting ,
528 U. S., at 41. For that reason United Reporting does
not bar respondents’ facial challenge. United Reporting is distinguishable
for a second and even more important reason. The plaintiff in United Reporting had neither “attempt[ed] to qualify” for
access to the government’s information nor presented an as-applied
claim in this Court. Id ., at 40. As a result, the Court
assumed that the plaintiff had not suffered a personal First
Amendment injury and could prevail only by invoking the rights of
others through a facial challenge. Here, by contrast, the
respondents claim—with good reason—that §4631(d) burdens their own
speech. That argument finds support in the separate writings in United Reporting , which were joined by eight Justices. All
of those writings recognized that restrictions on the disclosure of
government-held information can facilitate or burden the expression
of potential recipients and so transgress the First Amendment. See id ., at 42 (Scalia, J., concurring) (suggesting that “a
restriction upon access that allows access to the press …
but at the same time denies access to persons who wish to
use the information for certain speech purposes, is in reality a
restriction upon speech”); id. , at 43 (Ginsburg, J.,
concurring) (noting that “the provision of [government] information
is a kind of subsidy to people who wish to speak” about certain
subjects, “and once a State decides to make such a benefit
available to the public, there are no doubt limits to its freedom
to decide how that benefit will be distributed”); id ., at
46 (Stevens, J., dissenting) (concluding that, “because the State’s
discrimination is based on its desire to prevent the information
from being used for constitutionally protected purposes, [i]t must
assume the burden of justifying its conduct”). Vermont’s law
imposes a content- and speaker-based burden on respondents’ own
speech. That consideration provides a separate basis for
distinguishing United Reporting and requires heightened
judicial scrutiny.
The State also contends that heightened
judicial scrutiny is unwarranted in this case because sales,
transfer, and use of prescriber-identifying information are
conduct, not speech. Consistent with that submission, the United
States Court of Appeals for the First Circuit has characterized
prescriber-identifying information as a mere “commodity” with no
greater entitlement to First Amend- ment protection than “beef
jerky.” Ayotte , 550 F. 3d, at 52–53. In contrast the
courts below concluded that a prohibition on the sale of
prescriber-identifying information is a content-based rule akin to
a ban on the sale of cookbooks, laboratory results, or train
schedules. See 630 F. 3d, at 271–272 (“The First Amendment
protects even dry information, devoid of advocacy, political
relevance, or artistic expression” (internal quotation marks and
alteration omitted)); 631 F. Supp. 2d, at 445 (“A restriction
on disclosure is a regulation of speech, and the ‘sale’ of
[information] is simply disclosure for profit”).
This Court has held that the creation and
dissemination of information are speech within the meaning of the
First Amendment. See, e.g. , Bartnicki , supra , at 527 (“[I]f the acts of ‘disclosing’ and
‘publishing’ information do not constitute speech, it is hard to
imagine what does fall within that category, as distinct from the
category of expressive conduct” (some internal quotation marks
omitted)); Rubin v. Coors Brewing Co. , 514 U. S. 476 , 481
(1995) (“information on beer labels” is speech); Dun &
Bradstreet, Inc. v. Greenmoss Builders, Inc. , 472 U. S. 749 ,
759 (1985) (plurality opinion) (credit report is “speech”). Facts,
after all, are the beginning point for much of the speech that is
most essential to advance human knowledge and to conduct human
affairs. There is thus a strong argument that
prescriber-identifying information is speech for First Amendment
purposes.
The State asks for an exception to the rule
that information is speech, but there is no need to consider that
request in this case. The State has imposed content- and
speaker-based restrictions on the availability and use of
prescriber-identifying information. So long as they do not engage
in marketing, many speakers can obtain and use the information. But
detailers cannot. Vermont’s statute could be compared with a law
prohibiting trade magazines from purchasing or using ink. Cf. Minneapolis Star , 460 U. S. 575 . Like that hypothetical
law, §4631(d) imposes a speaker- and content-based burden on
protected expression, and that circumstance is sufficient to
justify application of heightened scrutiny. As a consequence, this
case can be resolved even assuming, as the State argues, that
prescriber-identifying information is a mere commodity.
B
In the ordinary case it is all
but dispositive to conclude that a law is content-based and, in
practice, viewpoint-discriminatory. See R. A. V. , 505 U. S., at 382 (“Content-based
regulations are presumptively invalid”); id. , at 391–392.
The State argues that a different analysis applies here because,
assuming §4631(d) burdens speech at all, it at most burdens only
commercial speech. As in previous cases, however, the outcome is
the same whether a special commercial speech inquiry or a stricter
form of judicial scrutiny is applied. See, e.g. , Greater New Orleans Broadcasting Assn., Inc. v. United
States , 527 U.
S. 173 , 184 (1999). For the same reason there is no need to
determine whether all speech hampered by §4631(d) is commercial, as
our cases have used that term. Cf. Board of Trustees of State
Univ. of N. Y. v. Fox , 492 U. S. 469 , 474
(1989) (discussing whether “pure speech and commercial speech” were
inextricably intertwined, so that “the entirety must … be
classified as noncommercial”).
Under a commercial speech
inquiry, it is the State’s burden to justify its content-based law
as consistent with the First Amendment. Thompson v. Western States Medical Center , 535 U. S. 357 , 373
(2002). To sustain the targeted, content-based burden §4631(d)
imposes on protected expression, the State must show at least that
the statute directly advances a substantial governmental interest
and that the measure is drawn to achieve that interest. See Fox , supra , at 480–481; Central Hudson Gas
& Elec. Corp. v. Public Serv. Comm’n of
N. Y. , 447
U. S. 557 , 566 (1980). There must be a “fit between the
legislature’s ends and the means chosen to accomplish those ends.” Fox , supra , at 480 (internal quotation marks
omitted). As in other contexts, these standards ensure not only
that the State’s interests are proportional to the result- ing
burdens placed on speech but also that the law does not seek to
suppress a disfavored message. See Turner Broadcasting ,
512 U. S., at 662–663.
The State’s asserted justifications for
§4631(d) come under two general headings. First, the State contends
that its law is necessary to protect medical privacy, including
physician confidentiality, avoidance of harassment, and the
integrity of the doctor-patient relationship. Second, the State
argues that §4631(d) is integral to the achievement of policy
objectives—namely, improved public health and reduced healthcare
costs. Neither justification withstands scrutiny.
1
Vermont argues that its
physicians have a “reasonable expectation” that their
prescriber-identifying information “will not be used for purposes
other than … filling and processing” prescriptions. See 2007 Vt.
Laws No. 80, §1(29). It may be assumed that, for many reasons,
physicians have an interest in keeping their prescription decisions
confidential. But §4631(d) is not drawn to serve that interest.
Under Vermont’s law, pharmacies may share prescriber-identifying
information with anyone for any rea- son save one: They must not
allow the information to be used for marketing. Exceptions further
allow pharmacies to sell prescriber-identifying information for
certain purposes, including “health care research.” §4631(e). And
the measure permits insurers, researchers, journalists, the State
itself, and others to use the information. See §4631(d); cf. App.
370–372; id ., at 211. All but conceding that §4631(d) does
not in itself advance confidentiality interests, the State suggests
that other laws might impose separate bars on the disclosure of
prescriber-identifying information. See Vt. Bd. of Pharmacy Admin.
Rule 20.1. But the potential effectiveness of other measures cannot
justify the distinctive set of prohibitions and sanctions imposed
by §4631(d).
Perhaps the State could have
addressed physician confidentiality through “a more coherent
policy.” Greater New Orleans Broadcasting , supra ,
at 195; see also Discovery Network , 507 U. S., at 428. For
instance, the State might have advanced its asserted privacy
interest by allowing the information’s sale or disclosure in only a
few narrow and well-justified circumstances. See, e.g. ,
Health Insurance Portability and Accountability Act of 1996, 42 U.
S. C. §1320d–2; 45 CFR pts. 160 and 164 (2010). A statute of
that type would present quite a different case than the one
presented here. But the State did not enact a statute with that
purpose or design. Instead, Vermont made prescriber-identifying
information available to an almost limitless audience. The explicit
structure of the statute allows the information to be studied and
used by all but a narrow class of disfavored speakers. Given the
information’s widespread availability and many permissible uses,
the State’s asserted interest in physician confidentiality does not
justify the burden that §4631(d) places on protected
expression.
The State points out that it allows doctors to
forgo the advantages of §4631(d) by consenting to the sale,
disclosure, and use of their prescriber-identifying information.
See §4631(c)(1). It is true that private decisionmaking can avoid
governmental partiality and thus insulate privacy measures from
First Amendment challenge. See Rowan v. Post Office
Dept. , 397 U.
S. 728 (1970); cf. Bolger v. Youngs Drug Products
Corp. , 463 U. S.
60 , 72 (1983). But that principle is inapposite here. Vermont
has given its doctors a contrived choice: Either consent, which
will allow your prescriber-identifying information to be
disseminated and used without constraint; or, withhold consent,
which will allow your information to be used by those speakers
whose message the State supports. Section 4631(d) may offer a
limited degree of privacy, but only on terms favorable to the
speech the State prefers. Cf. Rowan , supra , at
734, 737, 739, n. 6 (sustaining a law that allowed private
parties to make “unfettered,” “unlimited,” and “unreviewable”
choices regarding their own privacy). This is not to say that all
privacy measures must avoid content-based rules. Here, however, the
State has conditioned privacy on acceptance of a content-based rule
that is not drawn to serve the State’s asserted interest. To obtain
the limited privacy allowed by §4631(d), Vermont physicians are
forced to acquiesce in the State’s goal of burdening disfavored
speech by disfavored speakers.
Respondents suggest that a further defect of
§4631(d) lies in its presumption of applicability absent a
physician’s election to the contrary. Vermont’s law might burden
less speech if it came into operation only after an individual
choice, but a revision to that effect would not necessarily save
§4631(d). Even reliance on a prior election would not suffice, for
instance, if available categories of coverage by design favored
speakers of one political persuasion over another. Rules that
burden protected expression may not be sustained when the options
provided by the State are too narrow to advance legitimate
interests or too broad to protect speech. As already explained,
§4631(d) permits extensive use of prescriber-identifying
information and so does not advance the State’s asserted interest
in physician confidentiality. The limited range of available
privacy options instead reflects the State’s impermissible purpose
to burden disfavored speech. Vermont’s argument accordingly fails,
even if the availability and scope of private election might be
relevant in other contexts, as when the statute’s design is
unrelated to any purpose to advance a preferred message.
The State also contends that §4631(d) protects
doctors from “harassing sales behaviors.” 2007 Vt. Laws No. 80,
§1(28). “Some doctors in Vermont are experiencing an undesired
increase in the aggressiveness of pharmaceutical sales
representatives,” the Vermont Legislature found, “and a few have
reported that they felt coerced and harassed.” §1(20). It is
doubtful that concern for “a few” physicians who may have “felt
coerced and harassed” by pharmaceutical marketers can sustain a
broad content-based rule like §4631(d). Many are those who must
endure speech they do not like, but that is a necessary cost of
freedom. See Erznoznik v. Jacksonville , 422 U. S. 205 , 210–211
(1975); Cohen v. California , 403 U. S. 15 , 21 (1971).
In any event the State offers no explanation why remedies other
than content-based rules would be inadequate. See 44
Liquormart, Inc. v. Rhode Island , 517 U. S. 484 , 503
(1996) (opinion of Stevens, J.). Physicians can, and often do,
simply decline to meet with detailers, including detailers who use
prescriber-identifying information. See, e.g. , App. 180,
333–334. Doctors who wish to forgo detailing altogether are free to
give “No Solicitation” or “No Detailing” instructions to their
office managers or to receptionists at their places of work.
Personal privacy even in one’s own home receives “ample protection”
from the “resident’s unquestioned right to refuse to engage in
conversation with unwelcome visitors.” Watchtower Bible &
Tract Soc. of N. Y., Inc. v. Village of
Stratton , 536
U. S. 150 , 168 (2002); see also Bolger , supra , at 72. A physician’s office is no more private and
is entitled to no greater protection.
Vermont argues that detailers’ use of
prescriber-identifying information undermines the doctor-patient
relationship by allowing detailers to influence treatment
decisions. According to the State, “unwanted pressure occurs” when
doctors learn that their prescription decisions are being
“monitored” by detailers. 2007 Vt. Laws No. 80, §1(27). Some
physicians accuse detailers of “spying” or of engaging in
“underhanded” conduct in order to “subvert” prescription decisions.
App. 336, 380, 407–408; see also id. , at 326–328. And
Vermont claims that detailing makes people “anxious” about whether
doctors have their patients’ best interests at heart. Id .,
at 327. But the State does not explain why detailers’ use of
prescriber-identifying information is more likely to prompt these
objections than many other uses permitted by §4631(d). In any
event, this asserted interest is contrary to basic First Amendment
principles. Speech remains protected even when it may “stir people
to action,” “move them to tears,” or “inflict great pain.” Snyder v. Phelps , 562 U. S. ___, ___ (2011) (slip
op., at 15). The more benign and, many would say, beneficial speech
of pharmaceutical marketing is also entitled to the protection of
the First Amendment. If pharmaceutical marketing affects treatment
decisions, it does so because doctors find it persuasive. Absent
circumstances far from those presented here, the fear that speech
might persuade provides no lawful basis for quieting it. Brandenburg v. Ohio , 395 U. S. 444 , 447
(1969) (per curiam) .
2
The State contends that §4631(d)
advances impor- tant public policy goals by lowering the costs of
medical services and promoting public health. If
prescriber-identifying information were available for use by
detailers, the State contends, then detailing would be effective in
promoting brand-name drugs that are more expensive and less safe
than generic alternatives. This logic is set out at length in the
legislative findings accompanying §4631(d). Yet at oral argument
here, the State declined to acknowledge that §4631(d)’s objective
purpose and practical effect were to inhibit detailing and alter
doctors’ prescription decisions. See Tr. of Oral Arg. 5–6. The
State’s reluctance to embrace its own legislature’s rationale
reflects the vulnerability of its position.
While Vermont’s stated policy
goals may be proper, §4631(d) does not advance them in a
permissible way. As the Court of Appeals noted, the “state’s own
explanation of how” §4631(d) “advances its interests cannot be said
to be direct.” 630 F. 3d, at 277. The State seeks to achieve
its policy objectives through the indirect means of restraining
certain speech by certain speakers—that is, by diminishing
detailers’ ability to influence prescription decisions. Those who
seek to censor or burden free expression often assert that
disfavored speech has adverse effects. But the “fear that people
would make bad decisions if given truthful information” cannot
justify content-based burdens on speech. Thompson , 535 U.
S., at 374; see also Virginia Bd. of Pharmacy v. Virginia Citizens Consumer Council, Inc. , 425 U. S. 748 , 769–770
(1976). “The First Amendment directs us to be especially skeptical
of regulations that seek to keep people in the dark for what the
government perceives to be their own good.” 44 Liquormart , supra , at 503 (opinion of Stevens, J.); see also Linmark Associates, Inc. v. Willingboro , 431 U. S. 85 , 97 (1977).
These precepts apply with full force when the audience, in this
case prescribing physicians, consists of “sophisticated and
experienced” consumers. Edenfield , 507 U. S., at 775.
As Vermont’s legislative findings acknowledge,
the prem- ise of §4631(d) is that the force of speech can justify
the government’s attempts to stifle it. Indeed the State defends
the law by insisting that “pharmaceutical marketing has a strong
influence on doctors’ prescribing practices.” Brief for Petitioners
49–50. This reasoning is incompatible with the First Amendment. In
an attempt to reverse a disfavored trend in public opinion, a State
could not ban campaigning with slogans, picketing with signs, or
marching during the daytime. Likewise the State may not seek to
remove a popular but disfavored product from the marketplace by
prohibiting truthful, nonmisleading advertisements that contain
impressive endorsements or catchy jingles. That the State finds
expression too persuasive does not permit it to quiet the speech or
to burden its messengers.
The defect in Vermont’s law is made clear by
the fact that many listeners find detailing instructive. Indeed the
record demonstrates that some Vermont doctors view targeted
detailing based on prescriber-identifying information as “very
helpful” because it allows detailers to shape their messages to
each doctor’s practice. App. 274; see also id. , at 181,
218, 271–272. Even the United States, which appeared here in
support of Vermont, took care to dispute the State’s “unwarranted
view that the dangers of [n]ew drugs outweigh their benefits to
patients.” Brief for United States as Amicus Curiae 24,
n. 4. There are divergent views regarding detailing and the
prescription of brand-name drugs. Under the Constitution,
resolution of that debate must result from free and uninhibited
speech. As one Vermont physician put it: “We have a saying in
medicine, information is power. And the more you know, or anyone
knows, the better decisions can be made.” App. 279. There are
similar sayings in law, including that “information is not in
itself harmful, that people will perceive their own best interests
if only they are well enough informed, and that the best means to
that end is to open the channels of communication rather than to
close them.” Virginia Bd. , 425 U. S., at 770. The choice
“between the dangers of suppressing information, and the dangers of
its misuse if it is freely available” is one that “the First
Amendment makes for us.” Ibid .
Vermont may be displeased that detailers who
use prescriber-identifying information are effective in promoting
brand-name drugs. The State can express that view through its own
speech. See Linmark , 431 U. S., at 97; cf. §4622(a)(1)
(establishing a prescription drug educational program). But a
State’s failure to persuade does not allow it to hamstring the
opposition. The State may not burden the speech of others in order
to tilt public debate in a preferred direction. “The commercial
marketplace, like other spheres of our social and cultural life,
provides a forum where ideas and information flourish. Some of the
ideas and information are vital, some of slight worth. But the
general rule is that the speaker and the audience, not the
government, assess the value of the information presented.” Edenfield , supra , at 767.
It is true that content-based restrictions on
protected expression are sometimes permissible, and that principle
applies to commercial speech. Indeed the government’s legitimate
interest in protecting consumers from “commercial harms” explains
“why commercial speech can be subject to greater governmental
regulation than noncommercial speech.” Discovery Network ,
507 U. S., at 426; see also 44 Liquormart , 517 U. S., 502
(opinion of Stevens, J.). The Court has noted, for example, that “a
State may choose to regulate price advertising in one industry but
not in others, because the risk of fraud … is in its view greater
there.” R. A. V. , 505 U. S., at 388–389 (citing Virginia Bd. , supra , at 771–772). Here, however,
Vermont has not shown that its law has a neutral justification.
The State nowhere contends that detailing is
false or misleading within the meaning of this Court’s First
Amendment precedents. See Thompson , 535 U. S., at 373. Nor
does the State argue that the provision challenged here will
prevent false or misleading speech. Cf. post , at 10–11
(Breyer, J., dissenting) (collecting regulations that the
government might defend on this ground). The State’s interest in
burdening the speech of detailers instead turns on nothing more
than a difference of opinion. See Bolger , 463 U. S., at
69; Thompson , supra , at 376.
* * *
The capacity of technology to
find and publish personal information, including records required
by the government, presents serious and unresolved issues with
respect to personal privacy and the dignity it seeks to secure. In
considering how to protect those interests, however, the State
cannot engage in content-based discrimination to advance its own
side of a debate.
If Vermont’s statute provided
that prescriber-identifying information could not be sold or
disclosed except in narrow circumstances then the State might have
a stronger position. Here, however, the State gives possessors of
the information broad discretion and wide latitude in disclosing
the information, while at the same time restricting the
information’s use by some speakers and for some purposes, even
while the State itself can use the information to counter the
speech it seeks to suppress. Privacy is a concept too integral to
the person and a right too essential to freedom to allow its
manipulation to support just those ideas the government
prefers.
When it enacted §4631(d), the Vermont
Legislature found that the “marketplace for ideas on medicine
safety and effectiveness is frequently one-sided in that brand-name
companies invest in expensive pharmaceutical marketing campaigns to
doctors.” 2007 Vt. Laws No. 80, §1(4). “The goals of marketing
programs,” the legislature said, “are often in conflict with the
goals of the state.” §1(3). The text of §4631(d), associated
legislative findings, and the record developed in the District
Court establish that Vermont enacted its law for this end. The
State has burdened a form of protected expression that it found too
persuasive. At the same time, the State has left unburdened those
speakers whose messages are in accord with its own views. This the
State cannot do.
The judgment of the Court of Appeals is
affirmed.
It is so ordered. BREYER, J., DISSENTING SORRELL V. IMS HEALTH INC. 564 U. S. ____ (2011) SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES NO. 10-779 WILLIAM H. SORRELL, ATTORNEY GENERAL OF VERMONT,
et al., PETITIONERS v. IMS HEALTH INC.
et al.
on writ of certiorari to the united states court of
appeals for the second circuit
[June 23, 2011]
Justice Breyer, with whom Justice
Ginsburg and Justice Kagan join, dissenting.
The Vermont statute before us
adversely affects expression in one, and only one, way. It deprives
pharmaceutical and data-mining companies of data, collected
pursuant to the government’s regulatory mandate, that could help
pharmaceutical companies create better sales messages. In my view,
this effect on expression is inextricably related to a lawful
governmental effort to regulate a commercial enterprise. The First
Amendment does not require courts to apply a special “heightened”
standard of review when reviewing such an effort. And, in any
event, the statute meets the First Amendment standard this Court
has previously applied when the government seeks to regulate
commercial speech. For any or all of these reasons, the Court
should uphold the statute as constitutional.
I
The Vermont statute before us
says pharmacies and certain other entities
“shall not [1] sell … regulated records containing
prescriber-identifiable information, nor [2] permit the use of
[such] records … for marketing or promoting a prescription drug,
unless the prescriber consents.” Vt. Stat. Ann., Tit. 18, §4631(d)
(Supp. 2010).
It also says that
“[3] [p]harmaceutical manufacturers and
pharmaceutical marketers shall not use prescriber-identifiable
information for marketing or promoting a prescription drug unless
the prescriber consents.” Ibid. For the most part, I shall focus upon the first
and second of these prohibitions. In Part IV, I shall explain why
the third prohibition makes no difference to the result. II In Glickman v. Wileman Brothers & Elliott, Inc. , 521 U. S. 457 (1997),
this Court considered the First Amendment’s application to federal
agricultural commodity mar-keting regulations that required growers
of fruit to make compulsory contributions to pay for collective
adver- tising. The Court reviewed the lawfulness of the
regulation’s negative impact on the growers’ freedom voluntarily to
choose their own commercial messages “under the standard
appropriate for the review of economic regulation.” Id. ,
at 469.
In this case I would ask whether
Vermont’s regulatory provisions work harm to First Amendment
interests that is disproportionate to their furtherance of
legitimate regulatory objectives. And in doing so, I would give
significant weight to legitimate commercial regulatory
objectives—as this Court did in Glickman . The far
stricter, specially “heightened” First Amendment standards that the
majority would apply to this instance of commercial regulation are
out of place here. Ante , at 1, 8, 9, 10, 11, 13, 14,
15.
A
Because many, perhaps most,
activities of human beings living together in communities take
place through speech, and because speech-related risks and
offsetting justifications differ depending upon context, this Court
has distinguished for First Amendment purposes among different
contexts in which speech takes place. See, e.g., Snyder v. Phelps , 562 U. S. ___, ___–___ (2011)
(slip op., at 5–6). Thus, the First Amendment imposes tight
constraints upon government efforts to restrict, e.g., “core” political speech, while imposing looser constraints when the
government seeks to restrict, e.g., commercial speech, the
speech of its own employees, or the regulation-related speech of a
firm subject to a traditional regulatory program. Compare Boos v. Barry , 485 U. S. 312 , 321
(1988) (political speech), with Central Hudson Gas & Elec.
Corp. v. Public Serv. Comm’n of N. Y. , 447 U. S. 557 (1980)
(commercial speech), Pickering v. Board of Ed. of
Township High School Dist. 205, Will Cty. , 391 U. S. 563 (1968)
(government employees), and Glickman , supra (economic regulation).
These test-related distinctions
reflect the constitutional importance of maintaining a free
marketplace of ideas, a marketplace that provides access to
“social, political, esthetic, moral, and other ideas and
experiences.” Red Lion Broadcasting Co. v. FCC , 395 U. S. 367 ,
390 (1969); see Abrams v. United States , 250 U. S. 616 , 630
(1919) (Holmes, J., dissenting). Without such a marketplace, the
public could not freely choose a government pledged to implement
policies that reflect the people’s informed will.
At the same time, our cases make clear that
the First Amendment offers considerably less protection to the
maintenance of a free marketplace for goods and services. See Florida Bar v. Went For It, Inc. , 515 U. S. 618 , 623
(1995) (“We have always been careful to distinguish commercial
speech from speech at the First Amendment’s core”). And they also
reflect the democratic importance of permitting an elected
government to implement through effective programs policy choices
for which the people’s elected representatives have voted.
Thus this Court has recognized that commercial
speech including advertising has an “informational function” and is
not “valueless in the marketplace of ideas.” Central
Hudson , supra , at 563; Bigelow v. Virginia , 421 U. S. 809 , 826
(1975). But at the same time it has applied a less than strict,
“intermediate” First Amendment test when the government directly
restricts commercial speech. Under that test, government laws and
regulations may significantly restrict speech, as long as they also
“directly advance” a “substantial” government interest that could
not “be served as well by a more limited restriction.” Central
Hudson , supra , at 564. Moreover, the Court has found
that “sales practices” that are “misleading, deceptive, or
aggressive” lack the protection of even this “intermediate”
standard. 44 Liquormart, Inc. v. Rhode Island , 517 U. S. 484 ,
501 (1996) (opinion of Stevens, J.); see also Central
Hudson , supra , at 563; Virginia Bd. of
Pharmacy v. Virginia Citizens Consumer Council, Inc. , 425 U. S. 748 ,
772 (1976). And the Court has emphasized the need, in applying an
“intermediate” test, to maintain the
“ ‘commonsense’ distinction between speech
proposing a commercial transaction, which occurs in an area
traditionally subject to government regulation , and other
varieties of speech.” Ohralik v. Ohio State Bar
Assn. , 436 U.
S. 447 , 455–456 (1978) (quoting Virginia Bd. of
Pharmacy , supra , at 771, n. 24; emphasis
added).
The Court has also normally
applied a yet more lenient approach to ordinary commercial or
regulatory legislation that affects speech in less direct ways. In
doing so, the Court has taken account of the need in this area of
law to defer significantly to legislative judgment—as the Court has
done in cases involving the Commerce Clause or the Due Process
Clause. See Glickman , supra , at 475–476. “Our
function” in such cases, Justice Brandeis said, “is only to
determine the reasonableness of the legislature’s belief in the
existence of evils and in the effectiveness of the remedy
provided.” New State Ice Co. v. Liebmann , 285 U. S. 262 ,
286–287 (1932) (dissenting opinion); Williamson v. Lee
Optical of Okla., Inc. , 348 U. S. 483 , 488
(1955) (“It is enough that there is an evil at hand for correction,
and that it might be thought that the particular legisla-tive
measure was a rational way to correct it”); United States v. Carolene Products Co. , 304 U. S. 144 , 152
(1938) (“[R]egulatory legislation affecting ordinary commercial
transactions is not to be pronounced unconstitutional” if it rests
“upon some rational basis within the knowledge and experience of
the legislators”).
To apply a strict First Amendment standard
virtually as a matter of course when a court reviews ordinary
economic regulatory programs (even if that program has a modest
impact upon a firm’s ability to shape a commercial message) would
work at cross-purposes with this more basic constitutional
approach. Since ordinary regulatory programs can affect speech,
particularly commercial speech, in myriad ways, to apply a
“heightened” First Amendment standard of review whenever such a
program burdens speech would transfer from legislatures to judges
the primary power to weigh ends and to choose means, threatening to
distort or undermine legitimate legislative ob-jectives. See Glickman , 521 U. S., at 476 (“Doubts concerning the policy
judgments that underlie” a program requiring fruit growers to pay
for advertising they disagree with does not “justify reliance on
the First Amendment as a basis for reviewing economic
regulations”). Cf. Johanns v. Livestock Marketing
Assn. , 544 U.
S. 550 , 560–562 (2005) (applying less scrutiny when the
compelled speech is made by the Government); United States v. United Foods, Inc. , 533 U. S. 405 , 411
(2001) (applying greater scrutiny where compelled speech was not
“ancillary to a more comprehensive program restricting marketing
autonomy”). To apply a “heightened” standard of review in such
cases as a matter of course would risk what then-Justice Rehnquist,
dissenting in Central Hudson , described as a
“retur[n] to the bygone era of Lochner v. New York , 198 U. S. 45 (1905), in which it was
common practice for this Court to strike down economic regulations
adopted by a State based on the Court’s own notions of the most
appropriate means for the State to implement its considered
policies.” 447 U. S., at 589.
B
There are several reasons why the
Court should review Vermont’s law “under the standard appropriate
for the review of economic regulation,” not “under a heightened
standard appropriate for the review of First Amendment issues.” Glickman , 521 U. S., at 469. For one thing, Vermont’s
statute neither forbids nor requires anyone to say anything, to
engage in any form of symbolic speech, or to endorse any particular
point of view, whether ideological or related to the sale of a
product. Cf. id. , at 469–470. (And I here assume that Central Hudson might otherwise apply. See Part III, infra .)
For another thing, the same First
Amendment standards that apply to Vermont here would apply to
similar regulatory actions taken by other States or by the Federal
Government acting, for example, through Food and Drug
Administration (FDA) regulation. (And the Federal Government’s
ability to pre-empt state laws that interfere with existing or
contemplated federal forms of regulation is here irrelevant.)
Further, the statute’s requirements form part
of a tra-ditional, comprehensive regulatory regime. Cf. United
Foods , supra , at 411. The pharmaceutical drug
industry has been heavily regulated at least since 1906. See Pure
Food and Drugs Act, 34 Stat. 768. Longstanding statutes and
regulations require pharmaceutical companies to engage in complex
drug testing to ensure that their drugs are both “safe” and
“effective.” 21 U. S. C. §§355(b)(1), 355(d). Only then can
the drugs be marketed, at which point drug companies are subject to
the FDA’s exhaustive regulation of the content of drug labels and
the manner in which drugs can be advertised and sold. §352(f)(2);
21 CFR pts. 201–203 (2010).
Finally, Vermont’s statute is directed toward
information that exists only by virtue of government regulation.
Under federal law, certain drugs can be dispensed only by a
pharmacist operating under the orders of a medical practitioner. 21
U. S. C. §353(b). Vermont regulates the qualifications, the
fitness, and the practices of pharmacists themselves, and requires
pharmacies to maintain a “patient record system” that, among other
things, tracks who prescribed which drugs. Vt. Stat. Ann., Tit. 26,
§§2041(a), 2022(14) (Supp. 2010); Vt. Bd. of Pharmacy Admin. Rules
(Pharmacy Rules) 9.1, 9.24(e) (2009). But for these regulations,
pharmacies would have no way to know who had told customers to buy
which drugs (as is the case when a doctor tells a patient to take a
daily dose of aspirin).
Regulators will often find it necessary to
create tailored restrictions on the use of information subject to
their regulatory jurisdiction. A car dealership that obtains credit
scores for customers who want car loans can be prohibited from
using credit data to search for new customers. See 15 U. S. C.
§1681b (2006 ed. and Supp. III); cf. Trans Union Corp. v. FTC , 245 F. 3d 809, reh’g denied, 267 F. 3d 1138
(CADC 2001). Medical specialists who obtain medical records for
their existing patients cannot purchase those records in order to
identify new patients. See 45 CFR §164.508(a)(3) (2010). Or,
speaking hypothetically, a public utilities commission that directs
local gas distributors to gather usage information for individual
customers might permit the distributors to share the data with
researchers (trying to lower energy costs) but forbid sales of the
data to appliance manufacturers seeking to sell gas stoves.
Such regulatory actions are subject to
judicial review, e.g., for compliance with applicable
statutes. And they would normally be subject to review under the
Administrative Procedure Act to make certain they are not
“arbitrary, capricious, [or] an abuse of discretion.” 5 U.
S. C. §706(2)(A) (2006 ed.). In an appropriate case, such
review might be informed by First Amendment considerations. But
regulatory actions of the kind present here have not previously
been thought to raise serious additional constitutional concerns
under the First Amendment. But cf. Trans Union LLC v. FTC , 536 U.
S. 915 (2002) (Kennedy, J., dissenting from denial of
certiorari) (questioning ban on use of consumer credit reports for
target marketing). The ease with which one can point to actual or
hypothet-ical examples with potentially adverse speech-related
effects at least roughly comparable to those at issue here
indicates the danger of applying a “heightened” or “intermediate”
standard of First Amendment review where typical regulatory actions
affect commercial speech (say, by withholding information that a
commercial speaker might use to shape the content of a
message).
Thus, it is not surprising that, until today,
this Court has never found that the First
Amendment prohibits the government from restricting the use of
information gathered pursuant to a regulatory mandate—whether the
information rests in government files or has remained in the hands
of the private firms that gathered it. But cf. ante , at
11–14. Nor has this Court ever previously applied any form
of “heightened” scrutiny in any even roughly similar case. See Los Angeles Police Dept. v. United Reporting
Publishing Corp. , 528 U. S. 32 (1999) (no
heightened scrutiny); compare Cincinnati v. Discovery
Network, Inc. , 507 U. S. 410 , 426
(1993) (“[C]ommercial speech can be subject to greater governmental
regulation than noncommercial speech” because of the government’s
“interest in preventing commercial harms”), with ante , at
9–10, 11, 17–18, 24 (suggesting that Discovery Network supports heightened scrutiny when regulations target commercial
speech).
C
The Court (suggesting a standard
yet stricter than Central Hudson ) says that we must give content-based restrictions that burden speech “heightened”
scrutiny. It adds that “[c]ommercial speech is no exception.” Ante , at 10–11. And the Court then emphasizes that this is
a case involving both “content-based” and “speaker-based”
restrictions. See ante , at 8, 9, 10, 12, 14, 15, 16, 19,
20, 22, 24.
But neither of these
categories—“content-based” nor “speaker-based”—has ever before
justified greater scrutiny when regulatory activity affects
commercial speech. See, e.g., Capital Broadcasting
Co. v. Mitchell , 333 F. Supp. 582 (DC 1971)
(three-judge court), summarily aff’d sub nom . Capital Broadcasting Co. v. Acting Attorney
General , 405
U. S. 1000 (1972) (upholding ban on radio and television
marketing of tobacco). And the absence of any such precedent is
understandable.
Regulatory programs necessarily draw
distinctions on the basis of content. Virginia Bd. of
Pharmacy , 425 U. S., at 761, 762 (“If there is a kind of
commercial speech that lacks all First Amendment protection, … it
must be distinguished by its content”). Electricity regulators, for
example, oversee company statements, pronouncements, and proposals,
but only about electricity. See, e.g., Vt. Pub. Serv. Bd.
Rules 3.100 (1983), 4.200 (1986), 5.200 (2004). The Federal Reserve
Board regulates the content of statements, advertising, loan
proposals, and interest rate disclosures, but only when made by
financial institutions. See 12 CFR pts. 226, 230 (2011). And the
FDA oversees the form and content of labeling, advertising, and
sales proposals of drugs, but not of furniture. See 21 CFR pts.
201–203. Given the ubiquity of content-based regulatory categories,
why should the “content-based” nature of typical regulation require
courts (other things being equal) to grant legislators and
regulators less deference? Cf. Board of Trustees of
State Univ. of N. Y. v. Fox , 492 U. S. 469 , 481
(1989) (courts, in First Amendment area, should “provide the
Legislative and Executive Branches needed leeway” when regulated
industries are at issue).
Nor, in the context of a regulatory program,
is it unusual for particular rules to be “speaker-based,” affecting
only a class of entities, namely, the regulated firms. An energy
regulator, for example, might require the manu-facturers of home
appliances to publicize ways to reduce energy consumption, while
exempting producers of industrial equipment. See, e.g., 16
CFR pt. 305 (2011) (prescribing labeling requirements for certain
home appliances); Nev. Admin. Code §§704.804, 704.808 (2010)
(requiring utilities to provide consumers with information on
conservation). Or a trade regulator might forbid a particular firm
to make the true claim that its cosmetic product contains
“cleansing grains that scrub away dirt and ex-cess oil” unless it
substantiates that claim with detailed backup testing, even though
opponents of cosmetics use need not substantiate their claims.
Morris, F. T. C. Orders Data to Back Ad Claims,
N. Y. Times, Nov. 3, 1973, p. 32; Boys’ Life, Oct. 1973,
p. 64; see 36 Fed. Reg. 12058 (1971). Or the FDA might control in
detail just what a pharmaceutical firm can, and cannot, tell
potential purchasers about its products. Such a firm, for example,
could not suggest to a potential purchaser (say, a doctor) that he
or she might put a pharmaceutical drug to an “off label” use, even
if the manufacturer, in good faith and with considerable evidence,
believes the drug will help. All the while, a third party (say, a
researcher) is free to tell the doctor not to use the drug for that
purpose. See 21 CFR pt. 99; cf. Buckman Co. v. Plaintiffs’ Legal Comm ., 531 U. S. 341 , 350–351
(2001) (discussing effect of similar regulations in respect to
medical devices); see also Proposed Rule, Revised Effectiveness
Determination; Sunscreen Drug Products for Over-the-Counter Human
Use, 76 Fed. Reg. 35672 (2011) (proposing to prohibit marketing of
sunscreens with sun protection factor (SPF) of greater than 50 due
to insufficient data “to indicate that there is additional clinical
benefit”).
If the Court means to create constitutional
barriers to regulatory rules that might affect the content of a com-mercial message, it has embarked upon an unprecedented
task—a task that threatens significant judicial interference with
widely accepted regulatory activity. Cf., e.g., 21 CFR
pts. 201–203. Nor would it ease the task to limit its “heightened”
scrutiny to regulations that only affect certain speakers. As the
examples that I have set forth illustrate, many regulations affect
only messages sent by a small class of regulated speakers, for
example, electricity generators or natural gas pipelines.
The Court also uses the words “aimed” and
“targeted” when describing the relation of the statute to drug
manufacturers. Ante , at 8, 9, 12, 16. But, for the reasons
just set forth, to require “heightened” scrutiny on this basis is
to require its application early and often when the State seeks to
regulate industry. Any statutory initiative stems from a
legislative agenda. See, e.g., Message to Congress, May
24, 1937, H. R. Doc. No. 255, 75th Cong., 1st Sess., 4
(request from President Franklin Roosevelt for legislation to ease
the plight of factory workers). Any administrative initiative stems
from a regulatory agenda. See, e.g., Exec. Order No.
12866, 58 Fed. Reg. 51735 (1993) (specifying how to identify
regulatory priorities and requiring agencies to prepare agendas).
The related statutes, regulations, programs, and initiatives almost
always reflect a point of view, for example, of the Congress and
the administration that enacted them and ultimately the voters. And
they often aim at, and target, particular firms that engage in
practices about the merits of which the Government and the firms
may disagree. Section 2 of the Sherman Act, 15 U. S. C. §2,
for example, which limits the truthful, nonmisleading speech of
firms that, due to their market power, can affect the competitive
landscape, is directly aimed at, and targeted at, monopolists.
In short, the case law in this area reflects
the need to ensure that the First Amendment protects the
“marketplace of ideas,” thereby facilitating the democratic
creation of sound government policies without improperly hampering
the ability of government to introduce an agenda, to implement its
policies, and to favor them to the exclusion of contrary policies.
To apply “heightened” scrutiny when the regulation of commercial
activities (which often involve speech) is at issue is
unnecessarily to undercut the latter constitutional goal. The
majority’s view of this case presents that risk.
Moreover, given the sheer quantity of
regulatory initiatives that touch upon commercial messages, the
Court’s vision of its reviewing task threatens to return us to a
happily bygone era when judges scrutinized legislation for its
interference with economic liberty. History shows that the power
was much abused and resulted in the constitutionalization of
economic theories preferred by individual jurists. See Lochner v. New York , 198 U. S. 45 , 75–76 (1905) (Holmes, J.,
dissenting). By inviting courts to scrutinize whether a State’s
legitimate regulatory interests can be achieved in less restrictive
ways whenever they touch (even indirectly) upon commercial speech,
today’s majority risks repeating the mistakes of the past in a
manner not anticipated by our precedents. See Central
Hudson , 447 U. S., at 589 (Rehnquist, J., dissenting); cf. Railroad Comm’n of Tex. v. Rowan & Nichols Oil
Co. , 310 U. S.
573 , 580–581 (1940) (“A controversy like this always calls for
fresh reminder that courts must not substitute their notions of
expediency and fairness for those which have guided the agencies to
whom the formulation and execution of policy have been
entrusted”).
Nothing in Vermont’s statute undermines the
ability of persons opposing the State’s policies to speak their
mind or to pursue a different set of policy objectives through the
democratic process. Whether Vermont’s regulatory statute “targets”
drug companies (as opposed to affecting them unintentionally) must
be beside the First Amendment point.
This does not mean that economic regulation
having some effect on speech is always lawful. Courts typically
review the lawfulness of statutes for rationality and of
regulations (if federal) to make certain they are not “arbitrary,
capricious, [or] an abuse of discretion.” 5 U. S. C.
§706(2)(A). And our valuable free-speech tradition may play an
important role in such review. But courts do not normally view
these matters as requiring “heightened” First Amendment
scrutiny—and particularly not the un-forgiving brand of
“intermediate” scrutiny employed by the majority. Because the
imposition of “heightened” scrutiny in such instances would
significantly change the legislative/judicial balance, in a way
that would significantly weaken the legislature’s authority to
regulate commerce and industry, I would not apply a “heightened”
First Amendment standard of review in this case.
III
Turning to the constitutional
merits, I believe Vermont’s statute survives application of Central Hudson ’s “intermediate” commercial speech standard
as well as any more limited “economic regulation” test.
A
The statute threatens only modest
harm to commercial speech. I agree that it withholds from
pharmaceutical companies information that would help those entities
create a more effective selling message. But I cannot agree with
the majority that the harm also involves unjustified discrimination
in that it permits “pharmacies” to “share prescriber-identifying
information with anyone for any reason” (but marketing). Ante , at 17. Whatever the First Amendment relevance of
such discrimination, there is no evidence that it exists in
Vermont. The record contains no evidence that
prescriber-identifying data is widely disseminated. See App. 248,
255. Cf. Burson v. Freeman , 504 U. S. 191 , 207
(1992) (plurality opinion) (“States adopt laws to address the
problems that confront them. The First Amendment does not require
States to regulate for problems that do not exist”); Bates v. State Bar of Ariz. , 433 U. S. 350 , 380
(1977) (“[T]he justification for the application of overbreadth
analysis applies weakly, if at all, in the ordinary commercial
context”).
The absence of any such evidence
likely reflects the presence of other legal rules that forbid
widespread release of prescriber-identifying information. Vermont’s
Pharmacy Rules, for example, define “unprofessional conduct” to
include “[d]ivulging or revealing to unauthorized persons patient or practitioner information or the nature of professional
pharmacy services rendered.” Rule 20.1(i) (emphasis added); see
also Reply Brief for Petitioners 21. The statute reinforces this
prohibition where pharmaceutical marketing is at issue. And the
exceptions that it creates are narrow and concern common and often
essential uses of prescription data. See Vt. Stat. Ann., Tit. 18,
§4631(e)(1) (pharmacy reimbursement, patient care management,
health care research); §4631(e)(2) (drug dispensing); §4631(e)(3)
(communications between prescriber and pharmacy); §4631(e)(4)
(information to patients); §§4631(e)(5)–(6) (as otherwise provided
by state or federal law). Cf. Trans Union Corp. , 245
F. 3d, at 819 (rejecting an underinclusiveness challenge
because an exception to the Fair Credit Reporting Act concerned
“ ‘exactly the sort of thing the Act seeks to promote’ ”
(quoting Trans Union Corp. v. FTC , 81 F. 3d
228, 234 (CADC 1996)).
Nor can the majority find record support for
its claim that the statute helps “favored” speech and imposes a
“burde[n]” upon “disfavored speech by disfavored speakers.” Ante , at 19. The Court apparently means that the statute
(1) prevents pharmaceutical companies from creating individualized
messages that would help them sell their drugs more effectively,
but (2) permits “counterdetailing” programs, which often promote
generic drugs, to create such messages using prescriber-identifying
data. I am willing to assume, for argument’s sake, that this
consequence would significantly increase the statute’s negative
impact upon commercial speech. But cf. 21 CFR §§202.1(e)(1),
202.1(e)(5)(ii) (FDA’s “fair balance” requirement); App. 193 (no
similar FDA requirement for nondrug manufacturers). The record
before us, however, contains no evidentiary basis for the
conclusion that any such individualized counterdetailing is
widespread, or exists at all, in Vermont.
The majority points out, ante , at 4,
that Act 80, of which §4631 was a part, also created an
“evidence-based prescription drug education program,” in which the
Vermont Department of Health, the Department of Vermont Health
Access, and the University of Vermont, among others, work together
“to provide information and education on the therapeutic and
cost-effective utilization of prescription drugs” to health
professionals responsible for prescribing and dispensing
prescription drugs, Vt. Stat. Ann., Tit. 18, §4622(a)(1). See
generally §§4621–4622. But that program does not make use
of prescriber-identifying data. Reply Brief for Petitioners 11.
The majority cites testimony by two witnesses
in support of its statement that “States themselves may supply the
prescriber-identifying information used in [counterdetailing]
programs.” Ante , at 4. One witness explained that academic
detailers in Pennsylvania work with state health officials
to identify physicians serving patients whose health care is
likewise state provided. App. 375. The other, an IMS Health
officer, observed that Vermont has its own multipayer database
containing prescriber-identifying data, which could be
used to talk to doctors about their prescription patterns and the
lower costs associated with generics. Id. , at 313. But
nothing in the record indicates that any “counterdetailing” of this
kind has ever taken place in fact in Vermont .
State-sponsored health care professionals sometimes meet with small
groups of doctors to discuss best practices and generic drugs
generally. See University of Vermont, College of Medicine, Office
of Primary Care, Vermont Academic Detailing Program (July 2010),
http://www.med.uvm.edu/ ahec/downloads/VTAD_overview_2010.07.08.pdf
(all Inter-net materials as visited June 21, 2011, and available in
Clerk of Court’s case file). Nothing in Vermont’s statute prohibits
brand-name manufacturers from undertaking a similar effort.
The upshot is that the only
commercial-speech-related harm that the record shows this statute
to have brought about is the one I have previously described: The
withholding of information collected through a regulatory program,
thereby preventing companies from shaping a commercial message they
believe maximally effective. The absence of precedent suggesting
that this kind of harm is serious reinforces the conclusion that
the harm here is modest at most.
B
The legitimate state interests
that the statute serves are “substantial.” Central Hudson ,
447 U. S., at 564. Vermont enacted its statute
“to advance the state’s interest in protecting the
public health of Vermonters, protecting the privacy of prescribers
and prescribing information, and to ensure costs are contained in
the private health care sector, as well as for state purchasers of
prescription drugs, through the promotion of less costly drugs and
ensuring prescribers receive unbiased information.” §4631(a).
These objectives are important. And the interests
they embody all are “neutral” in respect to speech. Cf. ante , at 24.
The protection of public health falls within
the traditional scope of a State’s police powers. Hillsborough
County v. Automated Medical Laboratories, Inc. , 471 U. S. 707 ,
719 (1985). The fact that the Court normally exempts the regulation
of “misleading” and “deceptive” information even from the rigors of
its “intermediate” commercial speech scrutiny testifies to the
importance of securing “unbiased information,” see 44
Liquormart , 517 U. S., at 501 (opinion of Stevens, J.); Central Hudson , supra , at 563, as does the fact
that the FDA sets forth as a federal regulatory goal the need to
ensure a “fair balance” of information about marketed drugs, 21 CFR
§§202.1(e)(1), 202.1(e)(5)(ii). As major payers in the health care
system, health care spending is also of crucial state interest. And
this Court has affirmed the importance of maintaining “privacy” as
an important public policy goal—even in respect to information
already disclosed to the public for particular purposes (but not
others). See Department of Justice v. Reporters Comm.
for Freedom of Press , 489 U. S. 749 , 762–771
(1989); see also Solove, A Taxonomy of Privacy, 154 U. Pa.
L. Rev. 477, 520–522 (2006); cf. NASA v. Nelson , 562 U. S. ___, ___–___ (2011) (slip op., at 8–9)
(discussing privacy interests in nondisclosure).
At the same time, the record evidence is
sufficient to permit a legislature to conclude that the statute
“directly advances” each of these objectives. The statute helps to
focus sales discussions on an individual drug’s safety,
effectiveness, and cost, perhaps compared to other drugs (including
generics). These drug-related facts have everything to do with
general information that drug manufacturers likely possess. They
have little, if anything, to do with the name or prior prescription
practices of the particular doctor to whom a detailer is speaking.
Shaping a detailing message based on an individual doctor’s prior
prescription habits may help sell more of a particular
manufacturer’s particular drugs. But it does so by diverting
attention from scientific research about a drug’s safety and
effectiveness, as well as its cost. This diversion comes at the
expense of public health and the State’s fiscal interests.
Vermont compiled a substantial legislative
record to corroborate this line of reasoning. See Testimony of Sean
Flynn (Apr. 11, 2007), App. in No. 09–1913–cv(L) etc. (CA2), p.
A–1156 (hereinafter CA2 App.) (use of data mining helps drug
companies “to cover up information that is not in the best of light
of their drug and to highlight information that makes them look
good”); Volker & Outterson, New Legislative Trends Threaten the
Way Health Information Companies Operate, Pharmaceutical Pricing
& Reimbursement 2007, id. , at A–4235 (one former
detailer considered prescriber-identifying data the
“ ‘greatest tool in planning our approach to manipulating
doctors’ ” (quoting Whitney, Big (Brother) Pharma: How Drug
Reps Know Which Doctors to Target, New Republic, Aug. 29, 2006,
http://www.tnr.com/article/84056/health-care-eli-lilly-pfizer-ama);
Testimony of Paul Harrington (May 3, 2007), id. , at A–1437
(describing data mining practices as “secret and manipulative
activities by the marketers”); Testimony of Julie Brill (May 3,
2007), id. , at A–1445 (restrictions on data mining
“ensur[e] that the FDA’s requirement of doctors receiving fair and
balanced information actually occurs”); Written Statement of Jerry
Avorn & Aaron Kesselheim, id. , at A–4310 (citing
studies that “indicate that more physician-specific detailing will
lead to more prescriptions of brand-name agents, often with no
additional patient benefit but at much higher cost to patients and
to state-based insurance programs, which will continue to drive up
the cost of health care”); id. , at 4311 (“Making it more
difficult for manufacturers to tailor their marketing strategies to
the prescribing histories of individual physicians would actually
encourage detailers to present physicians with a more neutral
description of the product”); see also Record in No.
1:07–cv–00188–jgm (D Vt.), Doc. 414, pp. 53–57, 64 (hereinafter
Doc. 414) (summarizing record evidence).
These conclusions required the legislature to
make judgments about whether and how to ameliorate these problems.
And it is the job of regulatory agencies and legislatures to make
just these kinds of judgments. Vermont’s attempts to ensure a “fair
balance” of information is no different from the FDA’s similar
requirement, see 21 CFR §§202.1(e)(1), 202.1(e)(5)(ii). No one has
yet suggested that substantial portions of federal drug regulation
are unconstitutional. Why then should we treat Vermont’s law
differently?
The record also adequately supports the
State’s privacy objective. Regulatory rules in Vermont make clear
that the confidentiality of an individual doctor’s prescribing
practices remains the norm. See, e.g., Pharmacy Rule
8.7(c) (“Prescription and other patient health care information
shall be secure from access by the public, and the information
shall be kept confidential”); Pharmacy Rule 20.1(i) (forbidding
disclosure of patient or prescriber information to “unauthorized
persons” without consent). Exceptions to this norm are
comparatively few. See, e.g., ibid . (identifying
“authorized persons”); Vt. Stat. Ann., Tit. 18, §4631(e); App. 248,
255 (indicating that prescriber-identifying data is not widely
disseminated). There is no indication that the State of Vermont, or
others in the State, makes use of this information for
counterdetailing efforts. See supra , at 15.
Pharmaceutical manufacturers and the data
miners who sell information to those manufacturers would like to
create (and did create) an additional exception, which means
additional circulation of otherwise largely confi-dential
information. Vermont’s statute closes that door. At the same time,
the statute permits doctors who wish to permit use of their
prescribing practices to do so. §§4631(c)–(d). For purposes of Central Hudson , this would seem sufficiently to show that
the statute serves a meaningful interest in increasing the
protection given to prescriber privacy. See Fox , 492 U.
S., at 480 (in commercial speech area, First Amendment requires “a
fit that is not necessarily perfect, but reasonable; that
represents not necessarily the single best disposition but one
whose scope is in proportion to the interest served” (internal
quotation marks omitted)); see also United States v. Edge Broadcasting Co. , 509 U. S. 418 , 434
(1993) (The First Amendment does not “require that the Government
make progress on every front before it can make progress on any
front”); Burson , 504 U. S., at 207 (plurality
opinion).
C
The majority cannot point to any
adequately supported, similarly effective “more limited
restriction.” Central Hudson , 447 U. S., at 564. It says
that doctors “can, and often do, simply decline to meet with
detailers.” Ante , at 20. This fact, while true, is beside
the point. Closing the office door entirely has no similar tendency
to lower costs (by focusing greater attention upon the comparative
advantages and disadvantages of generic drug alternatives). And it
would not protect the confidentiality of information already
released to, say, data miners. In any event, physicians are
unlikely to turn detailers away at the door, for those detailers,
whether delivering a balanced or imbalanced message, are
nonetheless providers of much useful information. See Manchanda
& Honka, The Effects and Role of Direct-to-Physician Marketing
in the Pharmaceutical Industry: An Integrative Review, 5 Yale J.
Health Pol’y L. & Ethics 785, 793–797, 815–816 (2005); Ziegler,
Lew, & Singer, The Accuracy of Drug Information from
Pharmaceutical Sales Representatives, 273 JAMA 1296 (1995). Forcing
doctors to choose between targeted detailing and no detailing at
all could therefore jeopardize the State’s interest in promoting
public health.
The majority also suggests that
if the “statute provided that prescriber-identifying information
could not be sold or disclosed except in narrow circumstances then
the State might have a stronger position.” Ante , at 24–25;
see also ante , at 17. But the disclosure-permitting
exceptions here are quite narrow, and they serve useful,
indeed essential purposes. See supra , at 14. Compare Vt.
Stat. Ann., Tit. 18, §4631(e) with note following 42 U. S. C.
§1320d–2, p. 1190, and 45 CFR §164.512 (uses and disclosures not
requiring consent under the Health Insurance Portability and
Accountability Act of 1996). Regardless, this alternative is not “a more limited restriction,” Central Hudson , supra , at 564 (emphasis added), for it would impose a greater , not a lesser , burden upon the
dissemination of information.
Respondents’ alternatives are no more helpful.
Respondents suggest that “Vermont can simply inform physicians that
pharmaceutical companies … use prescription history information to
communicate with doctors.” Brief for Respondent Pharmaceutical
Research and Manufacturers of America 48. But how would that help
serve the State’s basic purposes? It would not create the “fair
balance” of information in pharmaceutical marketing that the State,
like the FDA, seeks. Cf. Reno v. American Civil
Liberties Union , 521 U. S. 844 , 874
(1997) (alternative must be “at least as effective in achieving the
legitimate purpose that the statute was enacted to serve”).
Respondents also suggest policies requiring use of generic drugs or
educating doctors about their benefits. Brief for Respondent
Pharmaceutical Research and Manufacturers of America 54–55. Such
programs have been in effect for some time in Vermont or other
States, without indication that they have prevented the imbalanced
sales tactics at which Vermont’s statute takes aim. See, e.g., Written Statement of Jerry Avorn & Aaron
Kesselheim, CA2 App. 4310; Doc. 414, at 60–61. And in any event,
such laws do not help protect prescriber privacy.
Vermont has thus developed a record that
sufficiently shows that its statute meaningfully furthers
substantial state interests. Neither the majority nor respondents
suggests any equally effective “more limited” restriction. And the
First Amendment harm that Vermont’s statute works is, at most,
modest. I consequently conclude that, even if we apply an
“intermediate” test such as that in Central Hudson, this
statute is constitutional.
IV
What about the statute’s third
restriction, providing that “[p]harmaceutical manufacturers and
pharmaceutical marketers” may not “ use prescriber-identifiable information for marketing or promoting a
prescription drug unless the prescriber consents”? Vt. Stat. Ann.,
Tit. 18, §4631(d) (emphasis added). In principle, I should not
reach this question. That is because respondent pharmaceutical
manufacturers, marketers, and data miners seek a declaratory
judgment and injunction prohibiting the enforcement of this
statute. See 28 U. S. C. §2201; App. 49–128. And they have
neither shown nor claimed that they could obtain significant
amounts of “prescriber-identifiable information” if the first two
prohibitions are valid. If, as I believe, the first two statutory
prohibitions (related to selling and disclosing the information)
are valid, then the dispute about the validity of the third
provision is not “ ‘real and substantial’ ” or
“ ‘definite and concrete.’ ” MedImmune, Inc. v. Genentech, Inc. , 549 U. S. 118 , 127
(2007) (quoting Aetna Life Ins. Co. v. Haworth , 300 U. S. 227 ,
240–241 (1937)) (Article III does not permit courts to entertain
such disputes).
The Court, however, strikes down
all three provisions, and so I add that I disagree with the
majority as to the constitutionality of the third restriction as
well—basically for the reasons I have already set out. The
prohibition against pharmaceutical firms using this
prescriber-identifying information works no more than modest First
Amendment harm; the prohibition is justified by the need to ensure
unbiased sales presentations, prevent unnecessarily high drug
costs, and protect the privacy of prescribing physicians. There is
no obvious equally effective, more limited alternative.
V
In sum, I believe that the
statute before us satisfies the “intermediate” standards this Court
has applied to restrictions on commercial speech. A
fortiori it satisfies less demanding standards that are more
appropriately applied in this kind of commercial regulatory case—a
case where the government seeks typical regulatory ends (lower drug
prices, more balanced sales messages) through the use of ordinary
regulatory means (limiting the commercial use of data gathered
pursuant to a regulatory mandate). The speech-related consequences
here are indirect, incidental, and entirely commercial. See supra , at 6–9.
The Court reaches its conclusion
through the use of important First Amendment
categories—“content-based,” “speaker-based,” and “neutral”—but
without taking full account of the regulatory context, the nature
of the speech effects, the values these First Amendment categories
seek to promote, and prior precedent. See supra , at 2–6,
9–13, 17. At best the Court opens a Pandora’s Box of First
Amendment challenges to many ordinary regulatory practices that may
only incidentally affect a commercial message. See, e.g., supra , at 7–8, 9–11. At worst, it reawakens Lochner ’s pre-New Deal threat of substituting judicial for
democratic decisionmaking where ordinary economic regulation is at
issue. See Central Hudson , 447 U. S., at 589 (Rehnquist,
J., dissenting).
Regardless, whether we apply an ordinary
commercial speech standard or a less demanding standard, I believe
Vermont’s law is consistent with the First Amendment. And with
respect, I dissent. | In *Sorrell v. IMS Health Inc.*, the Supreme Court ruled that a Vermont law restricting the sale and use of pharmacy records revealing doctors' prescribing practices violated the Free Speech Clause of the First Amendment. The Court applied heightened judicial scrutiny to the law, which prohibited pharmacies from selling or disclosing prescriber-identifying information for marketing purposes and pharmaceutical manufacturers from using such information for marketing. The Court found that while Vermont's interests in safeguarding medical privacy and promoting prescription decisions in the best interests of patients were significant, the law's restrictions on commercial speech failed to meet the required standard. Justice Kennedy delivered the opinion, stating that the law's speech-related consequences were indirect, incidental, and entirely commercial, and thus unconstitutional. |
Free Speech | U.S. v. Alvarez | https://supreme.justia.com/cases/federal/us/567/709/ | NOTICE: This opinion is subject to
formal revision before publication in the preliminary print of the
United States Reports. Readers are requested to notify the Reporter
of Decisions, Supreme Court of the United States, Washington,
D. C. 20543, of any typographical or other formal errors, in
order that corrections may be made before the preliminary print
goes to press.
SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES
_________________
No. 11–210
_________________
UNITED STATES, PETITIONER v. XAVIER
ALVAREZ
on writ of certiorari to the united states
court of appeals for the ninth circuit
[June 28, 2012]
Justice Kennedy announced the judgment of the
Court and delivered an opinion, in which The Chief Justice, Justice
Ginsburg, and Justice Sotomayor join.
Lying was his habit. Xavier Alvarez, the
respondent here, lied when he said that he played hockey for the
Detroit Red Wings and that he once married a starlet from Mexico.
But when he lied in announcing he held the Con-gressional Medal of
Honor, respondent ventured onto new ground; for that lie violates a
federal criminal statute, the Stolen Valor Act of 2005. 18
U. S. C. §704.
In 2007, respondent attended his first public
meeting as a board member of the Three Valley Water District Board.
The board is a governmental entity with headquarters in Claremont,
California. He introduced himself as follows: “I’m a retired marine
of 25 years. I retired in the year 2001. Back in 1987, I was
awarded the Congressional Medal of Honor. I got wounded many times
by the same guy.” 617 F.3d 1198, 1201–1202 (CA9 2010). None of this
was true. For all the record shows, respondent’s statements were
but a pathetic attempt to gain respect that eluded him. The
statements do not seem to have been made to secure employment or
financial benefits or admission to privileges reserved for those
who had earned the Medal.
Respondent was indicted under the Stolen Valor
Act for lying about the Congressional Medal of Honor at the
meeting. The United States District Court for the Central District
of California rejected his claim that the statute is invalid under
the First Amendment. Respondent pleaded guilty to one count,
reserving the right to appeal on his First Amendment claim. The
United States Court of Appeals for the Ninth Circuit, in a decision
by a divided panel, found the Act invalid under the First Amendment
and reversed the conviction. Id. , at 1218. With further
opinions on the issue, and over a dissent by seven judges,
rehearing en banc was denied. 638 F.3d 666 (2011). This Court
granted certiorari. 565 U. S. ___ (2011).
After certiorari was granted, and in an
unrelated case, the United States Court of Appeals for the Tenth
Circuit, also in a decision by a divided panel, found the Act
constitutional. United States v. Strandlof , 667 F.3d
1146 (2012). So there is now a conflict in the Courts of Appeals on
the question of the Act’s validity.
This is the second case in two Terms requiring
the Court to consider speech that can disparage, or attempt to
steal, honor that belongs to those who fought for this Nation in
battle. See Snyder v. Phelps , 562 U. S. ___
(2011) (hateful protests directed at the funeral of a serviceman
who died in Iraq). Here the statement that the speaker held the
Medal was an intended, undoubted lie.
It is right and proper that Congress, over a
century ago, established an award so the Nation can hold in its
high- est respect and esteem those who, in the course of carrying
out the “supreme and noble duty of contributing to the defense of
the rights and honor of the nation,” Selective Draft Law
Cases, 245 U.S.
366 , 390 (1918), have acted with extraordinary honor. And it should be
uncontested that this is a legitimate Government objective, indeed
a most valued national aspiration and purpose. This does not end
the inquiry, however. Fundamental constitutional principles require
that laws enacted to honor the brave must be consistent with the
precepts of the Constitution for which they fought.
The Government contends the criminal prohibition
is a proper means to further its purpose in creating and awarding
the Medal. When content-based speech regulation is in question,
however, exacting scrutiny is required. Statutes suppressing or
restricting speech must be judged by the sometimes inconvenient
principles of the First Amendment. By this measure, the statutory
provisions under which respondent was convicted must be held
invalid, and his conviction must be set aside.
I
Respondent’s claim to hold the Congressional
Medal of Honor was false. There is no room to argue about
in-terpretation or shades of meaning. On this premise, respondent
violated §704(b); and, because the lie concerned the Congressional
Medal of Honor, he was subject to an enhanced penalty under
subsection (c). Those statutory provisions are as follows:
“(b) False Claims About Receipt of Military
Decorations or Medals.––Whoever falsely represents himself or
herself, verbally or in writing, to have been awarded any
decoration or medal authorized by Congress for the Armed Forces of
the United States . . . shall be fined under this title,
imprisoned not more than six months, or both.
“(c) Enhanced Penalty for Offenses Involving
Congressional Medal of Honor.––
“(1) In General.––If a decoration or medal
involved in an offense under subsection (a) or (b) is a
Congressional Medal of Honor, in lieu of the punishment provided in
that subsection, the offender shall be fined under this title,
imprisoned not more than 1 year, or both.”
Respondent challenges the statute as a
content-based suppression of pure speech, speech not falling within
any of the few categories of expression where content-based
regulation is permissible. The Government defends the statute as
necessary to preserve the integrity and purpose of the Medal, an
integrity and purpose it contends are compromised and frustrated by
the false statements the statute prohibits. It argues that false
statements “have no First Amendment value in themselves,” and thus
“are protected only to the extent needed to avoid chilling fully
protected speech.” Brief for United States 18, 20. Al-though the
statute covers respondent’s speech, the Government argues that it
leaves breathing room for pro-tected speech, for example speech
which might criticize the idea of the Medal or the importance of
the military. The Government’s arguments cannot suffice to save the
statute.
II
“[A]s a general matter, the First Amendment
means that government has no power to restrict expression because
of its message, its ideas, its subject matter, or its content.” Ashcroft v. American Civil Liberties Union , 535 U.S.
564 , 573 (2002) (internal quotation marks omitted). As a
result, the Constitution “demands that content-based restrictions
on speech be presumed invalid . . . and that the
Government bear the burden of showing their constitutionality.” Ashcroft v. American Civil Liberties Union , 542 U.S.
656 , 660 (2004).
In light of the substantial and expansive
threats to free expression posed by content-based restrictions,
this Court has rejected as “startling and dangerous” a
“free-floating test for First Amendment coverage . . .
[based on] an ad hoc balancing of relative social costs and
benefits.” United States v. Stevens , 559 U. S.
___, ___ (2010) (slip op., at 7). Instead, content-based
restrictions on speech have been permitted, as a general matter,
only when confined to the few “ ‘historic and traditional
categories [of expression] long familiar to the bar,’ ” Id., at ___ (slip op., at 5) (quoting Simon &
Schuster, Inc. v. Members of N. Y. State Crime Victims
Bd. , 502 U.S.
105 , 127 (1991) (Kennedy, J., concurring in judgment)). Among
these categories are advocacy intended, and likely, to incite
imminent lawless action, see Brandenburg v. Ohio , 395 U.S.
444 (1969) (per curiam); obscenity, see, e.g., Miller v. California , 413 U.S.
15 (1973); defamation, see, e.g., New York Times Co. v. Sullivan , 376 U.S.
254 (1964) (providing substantial protection for speech about
public figures); Gertz v. Robert Welch, Inc. , 418 U.S.
323 (1974) (imposing some limits on liability for defaming a
private figure); speech integral to criminal conduct, see, e.g., Giboney v. Empire Storage & Ice Co. , 336 U.S.
490 (1949); so-called “fighting words,” see Chaplinsky v. New Hampshire , 315 U.S.
568 (1942); child pornography, see New York v. Ferber , 458 U.S.
747 (1982); fraud, see Virginia Bd. of Pharmacy v. Virginia Citizens Consumer Council, Inc. , 425 U.S.
748 , 771 (1976); true threats, see Watts v. United
States , 394 U.S.
705 (1969) (per curiam); and speech presenting some
grave and imminent threat the government has the power to prevent,
see Near v. Minnesota ex rel. Olson , 283 U.S.
697 , 716 (1931), although a restriction under the last category
is most difficult to sustain, see New York Times Co. v. United States , 403 U.S.
713 (1971) (per curiam) . These categories have a
historical foundation in the Court’s free speech tradition. The
vast realm of free speech and thought always protected in our
tradition can still thrive, and even be furthered, by adherence to
those categories and rules.
Absent from those few categories where the law
allows content-based regulation of speech is any general exception
to the First Amendment for false statements. This comports with the
common understanding that some false statements are inevitable if
there is to be an open and vigorous expression of views in public
and private con-versation, expression the First Amendment seeks to
guarantee. See Sullivan, supra, at 271 (“Th[e] erroneous
statement is inevitable in free debate”).
The Government disagrees with this proposition.
It cites language from some of this Court’s precedents to support
its contention that false statements have no value and hence no
First Amendment protection. See also Brief for Eugene Volokh et al.
as Amici Curiae 2–11. These isolated statements in some
earlier decisions do not support the Government’s submission that
false statements, as a general rule, are beyond constitutional
protection. That conclusion would take the quoted language far from
its proper context. For instance, the Court has stated “[f]alse
statements of fact are particularly valueless [because] they
interfere with the truth-seeking function of the marketplace of
ideas,” Hustler Magazine, Inc. v. Falwell , 485 U.S.
46 , 52 (1988), and that false statements “are not protected by
the First Amendment in the same manner as truthful statements,” Brown v. Hartlage , 456 U.S.
45 , 60–61 (1982). See also, e.g., Virginia Bd. of
Pharmacy , supra , at 771 (“Untruthful speech, commercial
or otherwise, has never been protected for its own sake”); Herbert v. Lando , 441 U.S.
153 , 171 (1979) (“Spreading false information in and of itself
carries no First Amendment credentials”); Gertz , supra , at 340 (“[T]here is no constitutional value in false
statements of fact”); Garrison v. Louisiana , 379 U.S.
64 , 75 (1964) (“[T]he knowingly false statement and the false
statement made with reckless disregard of the truth, do not enjoy
constitutional protection”).
These quotations all derive from cases
discussing def-amation, fraud, or some other legally cognizable
harm associated with a false statement, such as an invasion of
privacy or the costs of vexatious litigation. See Brief for United
States 18–19. In those decisions the falsity of the speech at issue
was not irrelevant to our analysis, but neither was it
determinative. The Court has never endorsed the categorical rule
the Government advances: that false statements receive no First
Amendment protection. Our prior decisions have not confronted a
measure, like the Stolen Valor Act, that targets falsity and
nothing more.
Even when considering some instances of
defamation and fraud, moreover, the Court has been careful to
instruct that falsity alone may not suffice to bring the speech
outside the First Amendment. The statement must be a knowing or
reckless falsehood. See Sullivan , supra , at 280
(prohibiting recovery of damages for a defamatory falsehood made
about a public official unless the statement was made “with
knowledge that it was false or with reckless disregard of whether
it was false or not”); see also Garrison , supra , at
73 (“[E]ven when the utterance is false, the great principles of
the Constitution which secure freedom of expression . . .
preclude attaching adverse consequences to any except the knowing
or reckless falsehood”); Illinois ex rel. Madigan v. Telemarketing Associates, Inc. , 538
U.S. 600 , 620 (2003) (“False statement alone does not subject a
fundraiser to fraud liability”).
The Government thus seeks to use this principle
for a new purpose. It seeks to convert a rule that limits liability
even in defamation cases where the law permits recovery for
tortious wrongs into a rule that expands liability in a different,
far greater realm of discourse and expression. That inverts the
rationale for the exception. The requirements of a knowing
falsehood or reckless disregard for the truth as the condition for
recovery in certain defamation cases exists to allow more speech,
not less. A rule designed to tolerate certain speech ought not
blossom to become a rationale for a rule restricting it.
The Government then gives three examples of
regulations on false speech that courts generally have found
per-missible: first, the criminal prohibition of a false statement
made to a Government official, 18 U. S. C. §1001; second,
laws punishing perjury; and third, prohibi-tions on the false
representation that one is speaking as a Government official or on
behalf of the Government, see, e.g., §912; §709. These
restrictions, however, do not establish a principle that all
proscriptions of false statements are exempt from exacting First
Amendment scrutiny.
The federal statute prohibiting false statements
to Government officials punishes “whoever, in any matter within the
jurisdiction of the executive, legislative, or judicial branch of
the Government . . . makes any mate-rially false,
fictitious, or fraudulent statement or repre-sentation.” §1001.
Section 1001’s prohibition on false statements made to Government
officials, in communications concerning official matters, does not
lead to the broader proposition that false statements are
unprotected when made to any person, at any time, in any
context.
The same point can be made about what the Court
has confirmed is the “unquestioned constitutionality of perjury
statutes,” both the federal statute, §1623, and its state-law
equivalents. United States v. Grayson , 438 U.S.
41 , 54 (1978). See also Konigsberg v. State Bar of
Cal. , 366 U.S.
36 , 51, n. 10 (1961). It is not simply because perjured
statements are false that they lack First Amendment protection.
Perjured testimony “is at war with justice” because it can cause a
court to render a “judgment not resting on truth.” In re
Michael , 326 U.S.
224 , 227 (1945). Perjury undermines the function and province
of the law and threatens the integrity of judgments that are the
basis of the legal system. See United States v. Dunnigan , 507 U.S.
87 , 97 (1993) (“To uphold the integrity of our trial system
. . . the constitutionality of perjury statutes is
unquestioned”). Unlike speech in other contexts, testi-mony under
oath has the formality and gravity necessary to remind the witness
that his or her statements will be the basis for official
governmental action, action that often affects the rights and
liberties of others. Sworn testimony is quite distinct from lies
not spoken under oath and sim-ply intended to puff up oneself.
Statutes that prohibit falsely representing that
one is speaking on behalf of the Government, or that prohibit
im-personating a Government officer, also protect the integrity of
Government processes, quite apart from merely restricting false
speech. Title 18 U. S. C. §912, for ex-ample, prohibits
impersonating an officer or employee of the United States. Even if
that statute may not require proving an “actual financial or
property loss” resulting from the deception, the statute is itself
confined to “maintain[ing] the general good repute and dignity of
. . . government . . . service itself.” United States v. Lepowitch , 318
U.S. 702 , 704 (1943) (internal quotation marks omitted). The
same can be said for prohibitions on the unauthorized use of the
names of federal agencies such as the Federal Bureau of
Investigation in a manner calculated to convey that the
communication is approved, see §709, or using words such as
“Federal” or “United States” in the collection of private debts in
order to convey that the communication has official authorization,
see §712. These examples, to the extent that they implicate fraud
or speech integral to criminal conduct, are inapplicable here.
As our law and tradition show, then, there are
instances in which the falsity of speech bears upon whether it is
protected. Some false speech may be prohibited even if analogous
true speech could not be. This opinion does not imply that any of
these targeted prohibitions are somehow vulnerable. But it also
rejects the notion that false speech should be in a general
category that is presumptively unprotected.
Although the First Amendment stands against any
“freewheeling authority to declare new categories of speech outside
the scope of the First Amendment,” Stevens , 559 U. S.,
at ___ (slip op., at 9), the Court has acknowledged that perhaps
there exist “some categories of speech that have been historically
unprotected . . . but have not yet been specifically
identified or discussed . . . in our case law.” Ibid . Before exempting a category of speech from the normal
prohibition on content-based re-strictions, however, the Court must
be presented with “per-suasive evidence that a novel restriction on
content is part of a long (if heretofore unrecognized) tradition of
proscription,” Brown v. Entertainment Merchants
Assn., 564 U. S. ___, ___ (2011) (slip op., at 4). The
Government has not demonstrated that false statements generally
should constitute a new category of unprotected speech on this
basis.
III
The probable, and adverse, effect of the Act
on free- dom of expression illustrates, in a fundamental way, the
reasons for the Law’s distrust of content-based speech
prohibitions.
The Act by its plain terms applies to a false
statement made at any time, in any place, to any person. It can be
assumed that it would not apply to, say, a theatrical performance.
See Milkovich v. Lorain Journal Co. , 497 U.S.
1 , 20 (1990) (recognizing that some statements nominally
purporting to contain false facts in reality “cannot reasonably be
interpreted as stating actual facts about an individual” (internal
quotation marks and brackets omitted)). Still, the sweeping, quite
unprecedented reach of the statute puts it in conflict with the
First Amendment. Here the lie was made in a public meeting, but the
statute would apply with equal force to personal, whispered
conversations within a home. The statute seeks to control and
suppress all false statements on this one subject in almost
limitless times and settings. And it does so en-tirely without
regard to whether the lie was made for the purpose of material
gain. See San Francisco Arts & Athletics, Inc. v. United States Olympic Comm. , 483 U.S.
522 , 539–540 (1987) (prohibiting a nonprofit corporation from
exploiting the “commercial magnetism” of the word “Olym-pic” when
organizing an athletic competition (internal quotation marks
omitted)).
Permitting the government to decree this speech
to be a criminal offense, whether shouted from the rooftops or made
in a barely audible whisper, would endorse government authority to
compile a list of subjects about which false statements are
punishable. That governmental power has no clear limiting
principle. Our constitutional tradition stands against the idea
that we need Oceania’s Ministry of Truth. See G. Orwell, Nineteen
Eighty-Four (1949) (Centennial ed. 2003). Were this law to be
sustained, there could be an endless list of subjects the National
Government or the States could single out. Where false claims are
made to effect a fraud or secure moneys or other valuable
considerations, say offers of employment, it is well established
that the Government may restrict speech without affronting the
First Amendment. See, e.g., Virginia Bd. of Pharmacy , 425
U. S., at 771 (noting that fraudulent speech generally falls
outside the protections of the First Amendment). But the Stolen
Valor Act is not so limited in its reach. Were the Court to hold
that the interest in truthful discourse alone is sufficient to
sustain a ban on speech, absent any evidence that the speech was
used to gain a material advantage, it would give government a broad
censorial power unprecedented in this Court’s cases or in our
constitutional tradition. The mere potential for the exercise of
that power casts a chill, a chill the First Amendment cannot permit
if free speech, thought, and discourse are to remain a foundation
of our freedom.
IV
The previous discussion suffices to show that
the Act conflicts with free speech principles. But even when
examined within its own narrow sphere of operation, the Act cannot
survive. In assessing content-based restrictions on protected
speech, the Court has not adopted a free-wheeling approach, see Stevens , 559 U. S., at ___ (slip op., at 7) (“The First
Amendment’s guarantee of free speech does not extend only to
categories of speech that survive an ad hoc balancing of
relative social costs and benefits”), but rather has applied the
“most exacting scrutiny.” Turner Broadcasting System, Inc. v. FCC , 512 U.S.
622 , 642 (1994). Although the objectives the Government seeks
to further by the statute are not without significance, the Court
must, and now does, find the Act does not satisfy exacting
scrutiny.
The Government is correct when it states
military medals “serve the important public function of recognizing
and expressing gratitude for acts of heroism and sacrifice in
military service,” and also “ ‘foste[r] morale, mission
accomplishment and esprit de corps’ among service members.” Brief
for United States 37, 38. General George Washington observed that
an award for valor would “cherish a virtuous ambition in
. . . soldiers, as well as foster and encourage every
species of military merit.” General Orders of George Washington
Issued at Newburgh on the Hudson, 1782–1783 (Aug. 7, 1782),
p. 30 (E. Boynton ed. 1883). Time has not diminished this
idea. In periods of war and peace alike public recognition of valor
and noble sacrifice by men and women in uniform reinforces the
pride and national resolve that the military relies upon to fulfill
its mission.
These interests are related to the integrity of
the military honors system in general, and the Congressional Medal
of Honor in particular. Although millions have served with brave
resolve, the Medal, which is the highest military award for valor
against an enemy force, has been given just 3,476 times.
Established in 1861, the Medal is reserved for those who have
distinguished themselves “conspicuously by gallantry and
intrepidity at the risk of his life above and beyond the call of
duty.” 10 U. S. C. §§3741 (Army), 6241 (Navy and Marine
Corps), 8741 (Air Force), 14 U. S. C. §491 (Coast Guard).
The stories of those who earned the Medal inspire and fascinate,
from Dakota Meyer who in 2009 drove five times into the midst of a
Taliban ambush to save 36 lives, see Curtis, President Obama Awards
Medal of Honor to Dakota Meyer, The White House Blog (Sept. 15,
2011) (all Internet materials as visited June 25, 2012, and
available in Clerk of Court’s case file); to Desmond Doss who
served as an army medic on Okinawa and on June 5, 1945, rescued 75
fellow soldiers, and who, after being wounded, gave up his own
place on a stretcher so others could be taken to safety, see
America’s Heroes 88–90 (J. Willbanks ed. 2011); to William Carney
who sustained multiple gunshot wounds to the head, chest, legs, and
arm, and yet carried the flag to ensure it did not touch the ground
during the Union army’s assault on Fort Wagner in July 1863, id., at 44–45. The rare acts of courage the Medal celebrates
led President Truman to say he would “rather have that medal round
my neck than . . . be president of the United States.”
Truman Gives No. 1 Army Medal to 15 Heroes, Washington Post, Oct. 13, 1945, p. 5. The Government’s interest in protecting
the integrity of the Medal of Honor is beyond question.
But to recite the Government’s compelling
interests is not to end the matter. The First Amendment requires
that the Government’s chosen restriction on the speech at issue be
“actually necessary” to achieve its interest. En-tertainment
Merchants Assn. , 564 U. S., at ___ (slip op., at 12).
There must be a direct causal link between the restriction imposed
and the injury to be prevented. See ibid . The link between
the Government’s interest in protecting the integrity of the
military honors system and the Act’s restriction on the false
claims of liars like respondent has not been shown. Although
appearing to concede that “an isolated misrepresentation by itself
would not tarnish the meaning of military honors,” the Government
asserts it is “common sense that false representations have the
tendency to dilute the value and meaning of military awards,” Brief
for United States 49, 54. It must be acknowledged that when a
pretender claims the Medal to be his own, the lie might harm the
Government by demeaning the high purpose of the award, diminishing
the honor it confirms, and creating the appearance that the Medal
is awarded more often than is true. Furthermore, the lie may offend
the true holders of the Medal. From one perspective it in-sults
their bravery and high principles when falsehood puts them in the
unworthy company of a pretender.
Yet these interests do not satisfy the
Government’s heavy burden when it seeks to regulate protected
speech. See United States v. Playboy Entertainment Group,
Inc. , 529 U.S.
803 , 818 (2000). The Government points to no evidence to
support its claim that the public’s general perception of military
awards is diluted by false claims such as those made by Alvarez.
Cf. Entertainment Merchants Assn., supra, at ___–___ (slip
op., at 12–13) (analyzing and rejecting the findings of research
psychologists demonstrating the causal link between violent video
games and harmful effects on children). As one of the Government’s amici notes “there is nothing that charlatans such as Xavier
Alvarez can do to stain [the Medal winners’] honor.” Brief for
Veterans of Foreign Wars of the United States et al. as Amici Curiae 1. This general proposition is sound, even if
true holders of the Medal might experience anger and
frustration.
The lack of a causal link between the
Government’s stated interest and the Act is not the only way in
which the Act is not actually necessary to achieve the Government’s
stated interest. The Government has not shown, and cannot show, why
counterspeech would not suffice to achieve its interest. The facts
of this case indicate that the dynamics of free speech, of
counterspeech, of refutation, can overcome the lie. Respondent lied
at a public meeting. Even before the FBI began investigating him
for his false statements “Alvarez was perceived as a phony,” 617
F. 3d, at 1211. Once the lie was made public, he was ridiculed
online, see Brief for Respondent 3, his actions were reported in
the press, see Ortega, Alvarez Again Denies Claim, Ontario, CA,
Inland Valley Daily Bulletin (Sept. 27, 2007), and a fellow board
member called for his resignation, see, e.g., Bigham, Water
District Rep Requests Alvarez Resign in Wake of False Medal Claim,
San Bernardino Cty., CA, The Sun (May 21, 2008). There is good
reason to believe that a similar fate would befall other false
claimants. See Brief for Reporters Committee for Freedom of the
Press et al. as Amici Curiae 30–33 (listing numerous
examples of public exposure of false claimants). Indeed, the
outrage and contempt expressed for respondent’s lies can serve to
reawaken and reinforce the public’s respect for the Medal, its
recipients, and its high purpose. The acclaim that recipients of
the Congressional Medal of Honor receive also casts doubt on the
proposition that the public will be misled by the claims of
charlatans or become cynical of those whose heroic deeds earned
them the Medal by right. See, e.g., Well Done, Washington Post, Feb. 5, 1943, p. 8 (reporting on Pres-ident
Roosevelt’s awarding the Congressional Medal of Honor to Maj. Gen.
Alexander Vandegrift); Devroy, Medal of Honor Given to 2 Killed in
Somalia, Washington Post, May 24, 1994, p. A6
(reporting on President Clinton’s awarding the Congressional Medal
of Honor to two special forces soldiers killed during operations in
Somalia).
The remedy for speech that is false is speech
that is true. This is the ordinary course in a free society. The
response to the unreasoned is the rational; to the uninformed, the
enlightened; to the straight-out lie, the simple truth. See Whitney v. California , 274 U.S.
357 , 377 (1927) (Brandeis, J., concurring) (“If there be time
to expose through discussion the falsehood and fallacies, to avert
the evil by the processes of education, the remedy to be ap-plied
is more speech, not enforced silence”). The theory of our
Constitution is “that the best test of truth is the power of the
thought to get itself accepted in the competition of the market,” Abrams v. United States , 250
U.S. 616 , 630 (1919) (Holmes, J., dissenting). The First
Amendment itself ensures the right to respond to speech we do not
like, and for good reason. Freedom of speech and thought flows not
from the beneficence of the state but from the inalienable rights
of the person. And suppression of speech by the government can make
exposure of falsity more difficult, not less so. Society has the
right and civic duty to engage in open, dynamic, rational
discourse. These ends are not well served when the government seeks
to orchestrate public discussion through content-based
mandates.
Expressing its concern that counterspeech is
insuf- ficient, the Government responds that because “some military
records have been lost . . . some claims [are]
un-verifiable,” Brief for United States 50. This proves little,
however; for without verifiable records, successful criminal
prosecution under the Act would be more difficult in any event. So,
in cases where public refutation will not serve the Government’s
interest, the Act will not either. In addition, the Government
claims that “many [false claims] will remain unchallenged.” Id., at 55. The Government provides no support for the
contention. And in any event, in order to show that public
refutation is not an adequate alternative, the Government must
demonstrate that unchallenged claims undermine the public’s
perception of the military and the integrity of its awards system.
This showing has not been made.
It is a fair assumption that any true holders of
the Medal who had heard of Alvarez’s false claims would have been
fully vindicated by the community’s expression of outrage, showing
as it did the Nation’s high regard for the Medal. The same can be
said for the Government’s interest. The American people do not need
the assistance of a government prosecution to express their high
regard for the special place that military heroes hold in our
tradi-tion. Only a weak society needs government protection or
intervention before it pursues its resolve to preserve the truth.
Truth needs neither handcuffs nor a badge for its vindication.
In addition, when the Government seeks to
regulate protected speech, the restriction must be the “least
restrictive means among available, effective alternatives.” Ashcroft , 542 U. S., at 666. There is, however, at
least one less speech-restrictive means by which the Government
could likely protect the integrity of the military awards system. A
Government-created database could list Congressional Medal of Honor
winners. Were a database accessible through the Internet, it would
be easy to verify and expose false claims. It appears some private
individuals have already created databases similar to this, see
Brief for Respondent 25, and at least one data- base of past
winners is online and fully searchable, see Congressional Medal of
Honor Society, Full Archive,
http://www.cmohs.org/recipient-archive.php. The Solicitor General
responds that although Congress and the Department of Defense
investigated the feasibility of establishing a database in 2008,
the Government “concluded that such a database would be
impracticable and insuf-ficiently comprehensive.” Brief for United
States 55. Without more explanation, it is difficult to assess the
Gov-ernment’s claim, especially when at least one database of
Congressional Medal of Honor winners already exists.
The Government may have responses to some of
these criticisms, but there has been no clear showing of the
necessity of the statute, the necessity required by exacting
scrutiny.
* * *
The Nation well knows that one of the costs of
the First Amendment is that it protects the speech we detest as
well as the speech we embrace. Though few might find respondent’s
statements anything but contemptible, his right to make those
statements is protected by the Constitution’s guarantee of freedom
of speech and expression. The Stolen Valor Act infringes upon
speech protected by the First Amendment.
The judgment of the Court of Appeals is
affirmed.
It is so ordered. SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES
_________________
No. 11–210
_________________
UNITED STATES, PETITIONER v. XAVIER
ALVAREZ
on writ of certiorari to the united states
court of appeals for the ninth circuit
[June 28, 2012]
Justice Breyer, with whom Justice Kagan joins,
con- curring in the judgment.
I agree with the plurality that the Stolen Valor
Act of 2005 violates the First Amendment. But I do not rest my
conclusion upon a strict categorical analysis. Ante, at
4–10. Rather, I base that conclusion upon the fact that the statute
works First Amendment harm, while the Government can achieve its
legitimate objectives in less restrictive ways.
I
In determining whether a statute violates the
First Amendment, this Court has often found it appropriate to
examine the fit between statutory ends and means. In doing so, it
has examined speech-related harms, justifications, and potential
alternatives. In particular, it has taken account of the
seriousness of the speech-related harm the provision will likely
cause, the nature and importance of the provision’s countervailing
objectives, the extent to which the provision will tend to achieve
those objectives, and whether there are other, less restrictive
ways of doing so. Ultimately the Court has had to determine whether
the statute works speech-related harm that is out of proportion to
its justifications.
Sometimes the Court has referred to this
approach as “intermediate scrutiny,” sometimes as “proportionality”
review, sometimes as an examination of “fit,” and sometimes it has
avoided the application of any label at all. See, e.g., Turner
Broadcasting System, Inc. v. FCC , 512 U.S.
622 , 641–652 (1994) (intermediate scrutiny); Randall v. Sorrell , 548 U.S.
230 , 249 (2006) (plurality opinion) (proportionality); Board
of Trustees of State Univ. of N. Y. v. Fox , 492 U.S.
469 , 480 (1989) (requiring a “fit” be- tween means and ends
that is “ ‘in proportion to the in- terest served’ ”); In re R. M. J. , 455 U.S.
191 , 203 (1982) (“[I]nterference with speech must be in
proportion to the [substantial governmental] interest served”); Pickering v. Board of Ed. of Township High School Dist.
205, Will Cty. , 391 U.S.
563 , 568 (1968).
Regardless of the label, some such approach is
necessary if the First Amendment is to offer proper protection in
the many instances in which a statute adversely affects
constitutionally protected interests but warrants neither
near-automatic condemnation (as “strict scrutiny” implies) nor
near-automatic approval (as is implicit in “rational basis”
review). See, e.g., Turner Broadcasting System, Inc. , supra , at 641–652 (“must-carry” cable regulations); Central Hudson Gas & Elec. Corp. v. Public Serv.
Comm’n of N. Y. , 447 U.S.
557 , 566 (1980) (nonmisleading commercial speech); Burdick v. Takushi , 504 U.S.
428 , 433–434 (1992) (election regulation); Pickering , supra, at 568 (government employee speech); United
States v. O’Brien , 391 U.S.
367 , 377 (1968) (application of generally appli- cable laws to
expressive conduct). I have used the term “proportionality” to
describe this approach. Thompson v. Western States
Medical Center , 535 U.S.
357 , 388 (2002) (dissenting opinion); see also Bartnicki v. Vopper , 532 U.S.
514 , 536 (2001) (concurring opinion); Nixon v. Shrink
Missouri Government PAC , 528 U.S.
377 , 402–403 (2000) (concurring opinion). But in this case, the
Court’s term “intermediate scrutiny” describes what I think we
should do.
As the dissent points out, “there are broad
areas in which any attempt by the state to penalize purportedly
false speech would present a grave and unacceptable dan- ger of
suppressing truthful speech.” Post, at 14. Laws restricting
false statements about philosophy, religion, history, the social
sciences, the arts, and the like raise such concerns, and in many
contexts have called for strict scrutiny. But this case does not
involve such a law. The dangers of suppressing valuable ideas are
lower where, as here, the regulations concern false statements
about easily verifiable facts that do not concern such subject
matter. Such false factual statements are less likely than are true
factual statements to make a valuable contribution to the
marketplace of ideas. And the government often has good reasons to
prohibit such false speech. See infra, at 5–7 (listing
examples of statutes and doctrines regulating false factual
speech). But its regulation can nonetheless threaten speech-related
harms. Those circumstances lead me to apply what the Court has
termed “intermediate scrutiny” here.
II
A
The Stolen Valor Act makes it a crime
“falsely” to “represen[t]” oneself “to have been awarded any
decoration or medal authorized by Congress for the Armed Forces of
the United States.” 18 U. S. C. §704(b). I would read the
statute favorably to the Government as criminalizing only false
factual statements made with knowledge of their fal- sity and with
the intent that they be taken as true. See Staples v. United States , 511 U.S.
600 , 605 (1994) (courts construe statutes “in light of the
background rules of the common law, . . . in which the
requirement of some mens rea for a crime is firmly
embedded”); cf. New York Times Co. v. Sullivan , 376 U.S.
254 , 279–280 (1964) ( First Amendment allows a public official
to recover for defamation only upon a showing of “ ‘actual
malice’ ”). As so interpreted the statute covers only lies.
But although this interpretation diminishes the extent to which the
statute endangers First Amendment values, it does not eliminate the
threat.
I must concede, as the Government points out,
that this Court has frequently said or implied that false factual
statements enjoy little First Amendment protection. See, e.g., BE&K Constr. Co. v. NLRB , 536 U.S.
516 , 531 (2002) (“[F]alse statements may be unprotected for
their own sake”); Hustler Magazine, Inc. v. Falwell , 485 U.S.
46 , 52 (1988) (“False statements of fact are particularly
valueless”); Gertz v. Robert Welch, Inc. , 418 U.S.
323 , 340 (1974) (“[T]he erroneous statement of fact is not
worthy of constitutional protection”).
But these judicial statements cannot be read to
mean “no protection at all.” False factual statements can serve
useful human objectives, for example: in social contexts, where
they may prevent embarrassment, protect privacy, shield a person
from prejudice, provide the sick with comfort, or preserve a
child’s innocence; in public contexts, where they may stop a panic
or otherwise preserve calm in the face of danger; and even in
technical, philosophical, and scientific contexts, where (as
Socrates’ methods suggest) examination of a false statement (even
if made deliberately to mislead) can promote a form of thought that
ultimately helps realize the truth. See, e.g., 638 F.3d 666,
673–675 (CA9 2011) (Kozinski, J., concurring in denial of rehearing
en banc) (providing numerous examples); S. Bok, Lying: Moral Choice
in Public and Private Life (1999) (same); New York Times
Co. , supra, at 279, n. 19 (“Even a false statement
may be deemed to make a valuable contribution to public debate,
since it brings about ‘the clearer perception and livelier
impression of truth, produced by its collision with error’ ”
(quoting J. Mill, On Liberty 15 (Blackwell ed. 1947))).
Moreover, as the Court has often said, the
threat of criminal prosecution for making a false statement can
inhibit the speaker from making true statements, thereby “chilling”
a kind of speech that lies at the First Amendment’s heart. See, e.g., Gertz , supra, at 340–341. Hence, the Court
emphasizes mens rea requirements that provide “breathing
room” for more valuable speech by reducing an honest speaker’s fear
that he may accidentally incur liability for speaking.
Further, the pervasiveness of false statements,
made for better or for worse motives, made thoughtlessly or de-
liberately, made with or without accompanying harm, provides a
weapon to a government broadly empowered to prosecute falsity
without more. And those who are unpopular may fear that the
government will use that weapon selectively, say by prosecuting a
pacifist who sup- ports his cause by (falsely) claiming to have
been a war hero, while ignoring members of other political groups
who might make similar false claims.
I also must concede that many statutes and
common-law doctrines make the utterance of certain kinds of false
statements unlawful. Those prohibitions, however, tend to be
narrower than the statute before us, in that they limit the scope
of their application, sometimes by requiring proof of specific harm
to identifiable victims; sometimes by specifying that the lies be
made in contexts in which a tangible harm to others is especially
likely to occur; and sometimes by limiting the prohibited lies to
those that are particularly likely to produce harm.
Fraud statutes, for example, typically require
proof of a misrepresentation that is material, upon which the
victim relied, and which caused actual injury. See Restatement
(Second) of Torts §525 (1976). Defamation statutes focus upon
statements of a kind that harm the reputation of another or deter
third parties from association or dealing with the victim. See id. , §§558, 559. Torts involving the intentional infliction
of emotional distress (like torts involving placing a victim in a
false light) concern falsehoods that tend to cause harm to a
specific victim of an emotional-, dignitary-, or privacy-related
kind. See id. , §652E.
Perjury statutes prohibit a particular set of
false statements—those made under oath—while requiring a showing of
materiality. See, e.g., 18 U. S. C. §1621.
Statutes forbidding lying to a government official (not under oath)
are typically limited to circumstances where a lie is likely to
work particular and specific harm by interfering with the
functioning of a government department, and those statutes also
require a showing of materiality. See, e.g., §1001.
Statutes prohibiting false claims of terrorist
attacks, or other lies about the commission of crimes or
catastrophes, require proof that substantial public harm be
directly foreseeable, or, if not, involve false statements that are
very likely to bring about that harm. See, e.g., 47 CFR
§73.1217 (2011) (requiring showing of foreseeability and actual
substantial harm); 18 U. S. C. §1038(a)(1) (prohibiting
knowing false statements claiming that terrorist attacks have
taken, are taking, or will take, place).
Statutes forbidding impersonation of a public
official typically focus on acts of impersonation, not mere
speech, and may require a showing that, for example, someone was
deceived into following a “course [of action] he would not have
pursued but for the deceitful conduct.” United States v. Lepowitch , 318 U.S.
702 , 704 (1943); see, e.g., §912 (liability attaches to
“[w]hoever falsely assumes or pretends to be an officer or employee
acting under the authority of the United States . . . and acts as such ” (emphasis added)).
Statutes prohibiting trademark infringement
present, perhaps, the closest analogy to the present statute.
Trademarks identify the source of a good; and infringement causes
harm by causing confusion among potential customers (about the
source) and thereby diluting the value of the mark to its owner, to
consumers, and to the econ- omy. Similarly, a false claim of
possession of a medal or other honor creates confusion about who is
entitled to wear it, thus diluting its value to those who have
earned it, to their families, and to their country. But trademark
statutes are focused upon commercial and promotional activities
that are likely to dilute the value of a mark. Indeed, they
typically require a showing of likely confusion, a showing that
tends to assure that the feared harm will in fact take place. See
15 U. S. C. §1114(1)(a); KP Permanent Make-Up,
Inc. v. Lasting Impression I, Inc. , 543 U.S.
111 , 117 (2004); see also San Francisco Arts &
Athletics, Inc. v. United States Olympic Comm. , 483 U.S.
522 , 539–540, 548 (1987) (upholding statute giving the United
States Olympic Committee the right to prohibit certain commercial and promotional uses of the word “Olympic”).
While this list is not exhaustive, it is
sufficient to show that few statutes, if any, simply prohibit
without limitation the telling of a lie, even a lie about one
particular matter. Instead, in virtually all these instances
limitations of context, requirements of proof of injury, and the
like, narrow the statute to a subset of lies where specific harm is
more likely to occur. The limitations help to make certain that the
statute does not allow its threat of liability or criminal
punishment to roam at large, discouraging or forbidding the telling
of the lie in contexts where harm is unlikely or the need for the
prohibition is small.
The statute before us lacks any such limiting
features. It may be construed to prohibit only knowing and
intentional acts of deception about readily verifiable facts within
the personal knowledge of the speaker, thus reducing the risk that
valuable speech is chilled. Supra, at 3–4. But it still
ranges very broadly. And that breadth means that it creates a
significant risk of First Amendment harm. As written, it applies in
family, social, or other private contexts, where lies will often
cause little harm. It also applies in political contexts, where
although such lies are more likely to cause harm, the risk of
censorious se- lectivity by prosecutors is also high. Further,
given the potential haziness of individual memory along with the
large number of military awards covered (ranging from medals for
rifle marksmanship to the Congressional Medal of Honor), there
remains a risk of chilling that is not completely eliminated by mens rea requirements; a speaker might still be worried
about being prosecuted for a careless false statement, even
if he does not have the intent required to render him liable. And
so the prohibition may be applied where it should not be applied,
for example, to bar stool braggadocio or, in the political arena,
subtly but selectively to speakers that the Government does not
like. These considerations lead me to believe that the statute as
written risks significant First Amendment harm.
B
Like both the plurality and the dissent, I
believe the statute nonetheless has substantial justification. It
seeks to protect the interests of those who have sacrificed their
health and life for their country. The statute serves this interest
by seeking to preserve intact the country’s recognition of that
sacrifice in the form of military honors. To permit those who have
not earned those honors to claim otherwise dilutes the value of the
awards. Indeed, the Nation cannot fully honor those who have
sacrificed so much for their country’s honor unless those who claim
to have received its military awards tell the truth. Thus, the
statute risks harming protected interests but only in order to
achieve a substantial countervailing objective.
C
We must therefore ask whether it is possible
substantially to achieve the Government’s objective in less
burdensome ways. In my view, the answer to this question is “yes.”
Some potential First Amendment threats can be alleviated by
interpreting the statute to require knowledge of falsity, etc. Supra, at 3–4. But other First Amendment risks, primarily
risks flowing from breadth of coverage, remain. Supra, at
4–5, 7–8. As is indicated by the limitations on the scope of the
many other kinds of statutes regulating false factual speech, supra, at 5–7, it should be possible significantly to
diminish or eliminate these re- maining risks by enacting a similar
but more finely tailored statute. For example, not all military
awards are alike. Congress might determine that some warrant
greater protection than others. And a more finely tailored statute
might, as other kinds of statutes prohibiting false factual
statements have done, insist upon a showing that the false
statement caused specific harm or at least was material, or focus
its coverage on lies most likely to be harmful or on contexts where
such lies are most likely to cause harm.
I recognize that in some contexts, particularly
political contexts, such a narrowing will not always be easy to
achieve. In the political arena a false statement is more likely to
make a behavioral difference (say, by leading the listeners to vote
for the speaker) but at the same time criminal prosecution is
particularly dangerous (say, by radically changing a potential
election result) and consequently can more easily result in
censorship of speakers and their ideas. Thus, the statute may have
to be significantly narrowed in its applications. Some lower courts
have upheld the constitutionality of roughly comparable but
narrowly tailored statutes in political contexts. See, e.g., United We Stand America, Inc. v. United We Stand, America
New York, Inc. , 128 F.3d 86 , 93 (CA2 1997) (upholding against First Amendment
challenge application of Lanham Act to a political organization); Treasure of the Committee to Elect Gerald D. Lostracco v. Fox , 150 Mich. App. 617, 389 N.W.2d 446 (1986) (upholding
under First Amendment statute prohibiting campaign material falsely
claiming that one is an incumbent). Without expressing any view on
the validity of those cases, I would also note, like the plurality,
that in this area more accurate information will normally
counteract the lie. And an accurate, publicly available register of
military awards, easily obtainable by political opponents, may well
adequately protect the integrity of an award against those who
would falsely claim to have earned it. See ante, at 17–18.
And so it is likely that a more narrowly tailored statute combined
with such information-disseminating devices will effectively serve
Congress’ end.
The Government has provided no convincing
explanation as to why a more finely tailored statute would not
work. In my own view, such a statute could significantly reduce the
threat of First Amendment harm while permitting the statute to
achieve its important protective objective. That being so, I find
the statute as presently drafted works disproportionate
constitutional harm. It consequently fails intermediate scrutiny,
and so violates the First Amendment.
For these reasons, I concur in the Court’s
judgment. SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES
_________________
No. 11–210
_________________
UNITED STATES, PETITIONER v. XAVIER
ALVAREZ
on writ of certiorari to the united states
court of appeals for the ninth circuit
[June 28, 2012]
Justice Alito, with whom Justice Scalia and
Jus- tice Thomas join, dissenting.
Only the bravest of the brave are awarded the
Congressional Medal of Honor, but the Court today holds that every
American has a constitutional right to claim to have received this
singular award. The Court strikes down the Stolen Valor Act of
2005, which was enacted to stem an epidemic of false claims about
military decorations. These lies, Congress reasonably concluded,
were undermining our country’s system of military honors and
inflicting real harm on actual medal recipients and their
families.
Building on earlier efforts to protect the
military awards system, Congress responded to this problem by
crafting a narrow statute that presents no threat to the freedom of
speech. The statute reaches only knowingly false statements about
hard facts directly within a speaker’s per- sonal knowledge. These
lies have no value in and of themselves, and proscribing them does
not chill any valuable speech.
By holding that the First Amendment nevertheless
shields these lies, the Court breaks sharply from a long line of
cases recognizing that the right to free speech does not protect
false factual statements that inflict real harm and serve no
legitimate interest. I would adhere to that principle and would
thus uphold the constitutionality of this valuable law.
I
The Stolen Valor Act makes it a misdemeanor to
“falsely represen[t]” oneself as having been awarded a medal,
decoration, or badge for service in the Armed Forces of the United
States. 18 U. S. C. §704(b). Properly construed, this
statute is limited in five significant respects. First, the Act
applies to only a narrow category of false representations about
objective facts that can almost always be proved or disproved with
near certainty. Second, the Act concerns facts that are squarely
within the speaker’s personal knowledge. Third, as the Government
maintains, see Brief for United States 15–17, and both the
plurality, see ante, at 7, and the concurrence, see ante, at 3 (Breyer, J., concurring in judgment), seemingly
accept, a conviction under the Act requires proof beyond a
reasonable doubt that the speaker actually knew that the
representation was false.[ 1 ]
Fourth, the Act applies only to statements that could reasonably be
interpreted as communicating actual facts; it does not reach
dramatic performances, satire, parody, hyperbole, or the
like.[ 2 ] Finally, the Act is
strictly viewpoint neutral. The false statements proscribed by the
Act are highly unlikely to be tied to any particular political or
ideological message. In the rare cases where that is not so, the
Act applies equally to all false statements, whether they tend to
disparage or commend the Government, the military, or the system of
mil- itary honors.
The Stolen Valor Act follows a long tradition of
efforts to protect our country’s system of military honors. When
George Washington, as the commander of the Continental Army,
created the very first “honorary badges of distinction” for service
in our country’s military, he established a rigorous system to
ensure that these awards would be received and worn by only the
truly deserving. See General Orders of George Washington Issued at
Newburgh on the Hudson, 1782–1783, p. 35 (E. Boynton ed. 1883)
(reprint 1973) (requiring the submission of “incontest- ible proof”
of “singularly meritorious action” to the Commander in Chief).
Washington warned that anyone with the “insolence to assume” a
badge that had not actually been earned would be “severely
punished.” Id. , at 34.
Building on this tradition, Congress long ago
made it a federal offense for anyone to wear, manufacture, or sell
certain military decorations without authorization. See Act of Feb.
24, 1923, ch. 110, 42Stat. 1286 (codified as amended at 18
U. S. C. §704(a)). Although this Court has never opined
on the constitutionality of that particular provision, we have said
that §702, which makes it a crime to wear a United States military
uniform without authorization, is “a valid statute on its face.” Schacht v. United States , 398 U.S.
58 , 61 (1970).
Congress passed the Stolen Valor Act in response
to a proliferation of false claims concerning the receipt of
military awards. For example, in a single year, more than
600 Virginia residents falsely claimed to have won the Medal of
Honor.[ 3 ] An investigation of
the 333 people listed in the online edition of Who’s Who as having
received a top military award revealed that fully a third of the
claims could not be substantiated.[ 4 ] When the Library of Congress compiled oral histories
for its Veterans History Project, 24 of the 49 individuals who
identified themselves as Medal of Honor recipients had not actually
received that award.[ 5 ] The
same was true of 32 individuals who claimed to have been awarded
the Distinguished Service Cross and 14 who claimed to have won the
Navy Cross.[ 6 ] Notorious cases
brought to Congress’ attention included the case of a judge who
falsely claimed to have been awarded two Medals of Honor and
displayed counterfeit medals in his courtroom;[ 7 ] a television network’s military consultant who
falsely claimed that he had received the Silver Star;[ 8 ] and a former judge advocate in the Marine
Corps who lied about receiving the Bronze Star and a Purple
Heart.[ 9 ]
As Congress recognized, the lies proscribed by
the Stolen Valor Act inflict substantial harm. In many instances,
the harm is tangible in nature: Individuals often falsely represent
themselves as award recipients in order to obtain financial or
other material rewards, such as lucrative contracts and government
benefits.[ 10 ] An
investigation of false claims in a single region of the United
States, for example, revealed that 12 men had defrauded the
Department of Veterans Affairs out of more than $1.4 million in
veteran’s benefits.[ 11 ] In
other cases, the harm is less tangible, but nonetheless
significant. The lies proscribed by the Stolen Valor Act tend to
debase the distinctive honor of military awards. See Stolen Valor
Act of 2005, §2, 120Stat. 3266, note following 18
U. S. C. §704 (finding that “[f]raudulent claims
surrounding the receipt of [military decorations and medals] damage
the reputation and meaning of such decorations and medals”). And
legitimate award recipients and their families have expressed the
harm they endure when an imposter takes credit for he- roic actions
that he never performed. One Medal of Honor recipient described the
feeling as a “ ‘slap in the face of veterans who have paid the
price and earned their medals.’ ”[ 12 ]
It is well recognized in trademark law that the
proliferation of cheap imitations of luxury goods blurs the
“ ‘signal’ given out by the purchasers of the originals.”
Landes & Posner, Trademark Law: An Economic Perspective, 30 J.
Law & Econ. 265, 308 (1987). In much the same way, the
proliferation of false claims about military awards blurs the
signal given out by the actual awards by making them seem more
common than they really are, and this diluting effect harms the
military by hampering its efforts to foster morale and esprit de
corps. Surely it was reasonable for Congress to conclude that the
goal of preserving the in- tegrity of our country’s top military
honors is at least as worthy as that of protecting the prestige
associated with fancy watches and designer handbags. Cf. San
Francisco Arts & Athletics, Inc. v. United States
Olympic Comm. , 483 U.S.
522 , 539–541 (1987) (rejecting First Amendment challenge to law
prohibiting certain unauthorized uses of the word “Olympic” and
recognizing that such uses harm the U. S. Olympic Committee by
“lessening the distinctiveness” of the term).
Both the plurality and Justice Breyer argue that
Congress could have preserved the integrity of military honors by
means other than a criminal prohibition, but Congress had ample
reason to believe that alternative approaches would not be
adequate. The chief alternative that is recommended is the
compilation and release of a comprehensive list or database of
actual medal recipients. If the public could readily access such a
resource, it is argued, imposters would be quickly and easily
exposed, and the proliferation of lies about military honors would
come to an end.
This remedy, unfortunately, will not work. The
Department of Defense has explained that the most that it can do is
to create a database of recipients of certain top military honors
awarded since 2001. See Office of Undersecretary of Defense, Report
to the Senate and House Armed Services Committees on a Searchable
Military Valor Decorations Database 4–5 (2009).[ 13 ]
Because a sufficiently comprehensive database is
not practicable, lies about military awards cannot be remedied by
what the plurality calls “counterspeech.” Ante, at 15.
Without the requisite database, many efforts to refute false claims
may be thwarted, and some legitimate award recipients may be
erroneously attacked. In addition, a steady stream of stories in
the media about the exposure of imposters would tend to increase
skepticism among members of the public about the entire awards
system. This would only exacerbate the harm that the Stolen Valor
Act is meant to prevent.
The plurality and the concurrence also suggest
that Congress could protect the system of military honors by
enacting a narrower statute. The plurality recommends a law that
would apply only to lies that are intended to “secure moneys or
other valuable considerations.” Ante , at 11. In a similar
vein, the concurrence comments that “a more finely tailored statute
might . . . insist upon a showing that the false
statement caused specific harm.” Ante, at 9 (opinion of
Breyer, J.). But much damage is caused, both to real award
recipients and to the system of mili- tary honors, by false
statements that are not linked to any financial or other tangible
reward. Unless even a small financial loss—say, a dollar given to a
homeless man falsely claiming to be a decorated veteran—is more
important in the eyes of the First Amendment than the damage caused
to the very integrity of the military awards system, there is no
basis for distinguishing between the Stolen Valor Act and the
alternative statutes that the plurality and concurrence appear
willing to sustain.
Justice Breyer also proposes narrowing the
statute so that it covers a shorter list of military awards, ante, at 9 (opinion concurring in judgment), but he does not
provide a hint about where he thinks the line must be drawn.
Perhaps he expects Congress to keep trying until it eventually
passes a law that draws the line in just the right place.
II
A
Time and again, this Court has recognized that
as a general matter false factual statements possess no intrinsic
First Amendment value. See Illinois ex rel. Madigan v. Telemarketing Associates, Inc. , 538
U.S. 600 , 612 (2003) (“Like other forms of public deception,
fraudulent charitable solicitation is unprotected speech”); BE&K Constr. Co. v. NLRB , 536
U.S. 516 , 531 (2002) (“[F]alse statements may be unprotected
for their own sake”); Hustler Magazine, Inc. v. Falwell , 485 U.S.
46 , 52 (1988) (“False statements of fact are particularly
valueless; they interfere with the truth-seeking function of the
marketplace of ideas, and they cause damage to an individual’s
reputation that cannot easily be repaired by counterspeech, however
persuasive or effective”); Keeton v. Hustler Magazine,
Inc. , 465 U.S.
770 , 776 (1984) (“There is ‘no constitutional value in false
statements of fact’ ” (quoting Gertz v. Robert
Welch, Inc. , 418 U.S.
323 , 340 (1974))); Bill John- son’s Restaurants, Inc. v. NLRB , 461 U.S.
731 , 743 (1983) (“[F]alse statements are not immunized by the
First Amendment right to freedom of speech”); Brown v. Hartlage , 456 U.S.
45 , 60 (1982) (“Of course, demonstrable falsehoods are not
protected by the First Amendment in the same manner as truthful
statements”); Herbert v. Lando , 441 U.S.
153 , 171 (1979) (“Spreading false information in and of itself
carries no First Amendment credentials”); Virginia Bd. of
Pharmacy v. Virginia Citizens Consumer Council, Inc. , 425 U.S.
748 , 771 (1976) (“Untruthful speech, commercial or otherwise,
has never been protected for its own sake”); Gertz , supra, at 340 (“[T]he erroneous statement of fact is not
worthy of constitutional protection”); Time, Inc. v. Hill , 385 U.S.
374 , 389 (1967) (“[T]he constitutional guarantees [of the First
Amendment] can tolerate sanctions against calculated falsehood without significant impairment of their essential
function”); Garrison v. Louisiana , 379 U.S.
64 , 75 (1964) (“[T]he knowingly false statement and the false
statement made with reckless disregard of the truth, do not enjoy
constitutional protection”).
Consistent with this recognition, many kinds of
false factual statements have long been proscribed without
“ ‘rais[ing] any Constitutional problem.’ ” United
States v. Stevens , 559 U. S. ___, ___ (2010) (slip
op., at 6) (quoting Chaplinsky v. New Hampshire , 315 U.S.
568 , 571–572 (1942)). Laws prohibiting fraud, perjury, and
defamation, for example, were in existence when the First Amendment
was adopted, and their constitutionality is now beyond question.
See, e.g., Donaldson v. Read Magazine, Inc. , 333 U.S.
178 , 190 (1948) (explaining that the government’s power “to
protect people against fraud” has “always been recognized in this
country and is firmly established”); United States v. Dunnigan , 507 U.S.
87 , 97 (1993) (observing that “the constitutionality of perjury
statutes is unquestioned”); Beauharnais v. Illinois , 343 U.S.
250 , 256 (1952) (noting that the “prevention and punishment” of
libel “have never been thought to raise any Constitutional
problem”).
We have also described as falling outside the
First Amendment’s protective shield certain false factual
statements that were neither illegal nor tortious at the time of
the Amendment’s adoption. The right to freedom of speech has been
held to permit recovery for the intentional infliction of emotional
distress by means of a false statement, see Falwell , supra, at 56, even though that tort did not enter our law
until the late 19th century, see W. Keeton, D. Dobbs, R. Keeton,
& D. Owen, Prosser and Keeton on Law of Torts §12, p. 60, and
n. 47. (5th ed. 1984) (hereinafter Prosser and Keeton). And in Hill , supra, at 390, the Court concluded that the
free speech right allows recovery for the even more modern tort of
false-light invasion of privacy, see Prosser and Keeton §117, at
863.
In line with these holdings, it has long been
assumed that the First Amendment is not offended by prominent
criminal statutes with no close common-law analog. The most well
known of these is probably 18 U. S. C. §1001, which makes
it a crime to “knowingly and willfully” make any “materially false,
fictitious, or fraudulent statement or representation” in “any
matter within the jurisdiction of the executive, legislative, or
judicial branch of the Government of the United States.” Unlike
perjury, §1001 is not limited to statements made under oath or
before an official government tribunal. Nor does it require any
showing of “pecuniary or property loss to the government.” United States v. Gilliland , 312 U.S.
86 , 93 (1941). Instead, the statute is based on the need to
protect “agencies from the perversion which might result
from the deceptive practices described.” Ibid. (emphasis
added).
Still other statutes make it a crime to falsely
represent that one is speaking on behalf of, or with the approval
of, the Federal Government. See, e.g., 18 U. S. C.
§912 (making it a crime to falsely impersonate a federal officer);
§709 (making it a crime to knowingly use, without authorization,
the names of enumerated federal agencies, such as “Federal Bureau
of Investigation,” in a manner reasonably calculated to convey the
impression that a communication is approved or authorized by the
agency). We have recognized that §912, like §1001, does not require
a showing of pecuniary or property loss and that its purpose is to
“ ‘maintain the general good repute and dignity’ ” of
Government service. United States v. Lepowitch , 318 U.S.
702 , 704 (1943) (quoting United States v. Barnow , 239 U.S.
74 , 80 (1915)). All told, there are more than 100 federal
criminal statutes that punish false statements made in connection
with areas of federal agency concern. See United States v. Wells , 519 U.S.
482 , 505–507, and nn. 8–10 (1997) (Stevens, J.,
dissenting) (citing “at least 100 federal false statement statutes”
in the United States Code).
These examples amply demonstrate that false
statements of fact merit no First Amendment protection in their own
right.[ 14 ] It is true, as
Justice Breyer notes, that many in our society either approve or
condone certain discrete categories of false statements, including
false statements made to prevent harm to innocent victims and
so-called “white lies.” See ante , at 4. But respondent’s
false claim to have received the Medal of Honor did not fall into
any of these categories. His lie did not “prevent embarrassment,
protect privacy, shield a person from prejudice, provide the sick
with comfort, or preserve a child’s innocence.” Ibid . Nor
did his lie “stop a panic or otherwise preserve calm in the face of
danger” or further philosophical or scientific debate. Ibid. Respondent’s claim, like all those covered by the Stolen Valor Act,
served no valid purpose.
Respondent and others who join him in attacking
the Stolen Valor Act take a different view. Respondent’s brief
features a veritable paean to lying. According to respondent, his
lie about the Medal of Honor was nothing out of the ordinary for
21st-century Americans. “Everyone lies,” he says. Brief for
Respondent 10. “We lie all the time.” Ibid. “[H]uman beings
are constantly forced to choose the persona we present to the
world, and our choices nearly always involve intentional omissions
and misrepresentations, if not outright deception.” Id., at
39. An academic amicus tells us that the First Amendment
protects the right to construct “self-aggrandizing fabrications
such as having been awarded a military decoration.” Brief for
Jonathan D. Varat as Amicus Curiae 5.
This radical interpretation of the First
Amendment is not supported by any precedent of this Court. The lies
covered by the Stolen Valor Act have no intrinsic value and thus
merit no First Amendment protection unless their prohibition would
chill other expression that falls within the Amendment’s scope. I
now turn to that question.
B
While we have repeatedly endorsed the
principle that false statements of fact do not merit First
Amendment protection for their own sake, we have recognized that it
is sometimes necessary to “exten[d] a measure of strategic
protection” to these statements in order to ensure sufficient
“ ‘breathing space’ ” for protected speech. Gertz ,
418 U. S., at 342 (quoting NAACP v. Button , 371 U.S.
415 , 433 (1963)). Thus, in order to prevent the chilling of
truthful speech on matters of public concern, we have held that
liability for the defamation of a public official or figure
requires proof that defamatory statements were made with knowledge
or reckless disregard of their falsity. See New York Times
Co. v. Sullivan , 376 U.S.
254 , 279–280 (1964) (civil liability); Garrison , 379
U. S., at 74–75 (criminal liability). This same requirement
applies when public officials and figures seek to recover for the
tort of intentional infliction of emotional distress. See Falwell , 485 U. S., at 55–56. And we have imposed
“[e]xacting proof requirements” in other contexts as well when
necessary to ensure that truthful speech is not chilled. Madigan , 538 U. S., at 620 (complainant in a fraud
action must show that the defendant made a knowingly false
statement of material fact with the intent to mislead the listener
and that he succeeded in doing so); see also BE&K
Constr. , 536 U. S., at 531 (regulation of baseless
lawsuits limited to those that are both “objectively baseless and subjectively motivated by an unlawful purpose”); Hartlage , 456 U. S., at 61 (sustaining as-applied First
Amendment challenge to law prohibiting certain “factual
misstatements in the course of political debate” where there had
been no showing that the disputed statement was made “other than in
good faith and without knowledge of its falsity, or . . .
with reckless disregard as to whether it was false or not”). All of
these proof requirements inevitably have the effect of bringing
some false factual statements within the protection of the First
Amendment, but this is justified in order to prevent the chilling
of other, valuable speech.
These examples by no means exhaust the
circumstances in which false factual statements enjoy a degree of
instrumental constitutional protection. On the contrary, there are
broad areas in which any attempt by the state to penalize
purportedly false speech would present a grave and unacceptable
danger of suppressing truthful speech. Laws restricting false
statements about philosophy, religion, history, the social
sciences, the arts, and other matters of public concern would
present such a threat. The point is not that there is no such thing
as truth or falsity in these areas or that the truth is always
impossible to ascertain, but rather that it is perilous to permit
the state to be the arbiter of truth.
Even where there is a wide scholarly consensus
concerning a particular matter, the truth is served by allowing
that consensus to be challenged without fear of reprisal. Today’s
accepted wisdom sometimes turns out to be mistaken. And in these
contexts, “[e]ven a false statement may be deemed to make a
valuable contribution to public debate, since it brings about ‘the
clearer perception and livelier impression of truth, produced by
its collision with error.’ ” Sullivan , supra , at
279, n. 19 (quoting J. Mill, On Liberty 15 (R. McCallum ed.
1947)).
Allowing the state to proscribe false statements
in these areas also opens the door for the state to use its power
for political ends. Statements about history illustrate this point.
If some false statements about historical events may be banned, how
certain must it be that a statement is false before the ban may be
upheld? And who should make that calculation? While our cases
prohibiting viewpoint discrimination would fetter the state’s power
to some degree, see R. A. V. v. St. Paul , 505 U.S.
377 , 384–390 (1992) (explaining that the First Amendment does
not permit the government to engage in viewpoint discrimination
under the guise of regulating unprotected speech), the potential
for abuse of power in these areas is simply too great.
In stark contrast to hypothetical laws
prohibiting false statements about history, science, and similar
matters, the Stolen Valor Act presents no risk at all that valuable
speech will be suppressed. The speech punished by the Act is not
only verifiably false and entirely lacking in intrinsic value, but
it also fails to serve any instrumen- tal purpose that the First
Amendment might protect. Tell- ingly, when asked at oral argument
what truthful speech the Stolen Valor Act might chill, even
respondent’s counsel conceded that the answer is none. Tr. of Oral
Arg. 36.
C
Neither of the two opinions endorsed by
Justices in the majority claims that the false statements covered
by the Stolen Valor Act possess either intrinsic or instrumental
value. Instead, those opinions appear to be based on the distinct
concern that the Act suffers from overbreadth. See ante, at
10 (plurality opinion) (the Act applies to “personal, whispered
conversations within a home”); ante, at 8 (Breyer, J.,
concurring in judgment) (the Act “applies in family, social, or
other private contexts” and in “political contexts”). But to strike
down a statute on the basis that it is overbroad, it is necessary
to show that the statute’s “overbreadth [is] substantial ,
not only in an absolute sense, but also relative to [its] plainly
legitimate sweep.” United States v. Williams , 553 U.S.
285 , 292 (2008); see also ibid. (noting that this
requirement has been “vigorously enforced”). The plurality and the
concurrence do not even attempt to make this showing.
The plurality additionally worries that a
decision sustaining the Stolen Valor Act might prompt Congress and
the state legislatures to enact laws criminalizing lies about “an
endless list of subjects.” Ante, at 11. The plurality
apparently fears that we will see laws making it a crime to lie
about civilian awards such as college degrees or certificates of
achievement in the arts and sports.
This concern is likely unfounded. With very good
reason, military honors have traditionally been regarded as quite
different from civilian awards. Nearly a century ago, Congress made
it a crime to wear a military medal without authorization; we have
no comparable tradition regarding such things as Super Bowl rings,
Oscars, or Phi Beta Kappa keys.
In any event, if the plurality’s concern is not
entirely fanciful, it falls outside the purview of the First
Amendment. The problem that the plurality foresees—that legislative
bodies will enact unnecessary and overly intrusive criminal
laws—applies regardless of whether the laws in question involve
speech or nonexpressive conduct. If there is a problem with, let us
say, a law making it a criminal offense to falsely claim to have
been a high school valedictorian, the problem is not the
suppression of speech but the misuse of the criminal law, which
should be reserved for conduct that inflicts or threatens truly
serious societal harm. The objection to this hypothetical law would
be the same as the objection to a law making it a crime to eat
potato chips during the graduation ceremony at which the high
school valedictorian is recognized. The safeguard against such laws
is democracy, not the First Amendment. Not every foolish law is
unconstitutional.
The Stolen Valor Act represents the judgment of
the people’s elected representatives that false statements about
military awards are very different from false statements about
civilian awards. Certainly this is true with respect to the high
honor that respondent misappropri- ated. Respondent claimed that he
was awarded the Medal of Honor in 1987 for bravery during the Iran
hostage crisis. This singular award, however, is bestowed only on
those members of the Armed Forces who “distinguis[h] [themselves]
conspicuously by gallantry and intrepidity at the risk of [their
lives] above and beyond the call of duty.” 10 U. S. C.
§3741; see also §§6241, 8741. More than half of the heroic
individuals to have been awarded the Medal of Honor after World War
I received it posthumously.[ 15 ] Congress was entitled to conclude that falsely
claiming to have won the Medal of Honor is qualitatively different
from even the most prestigious civilian awards and that the
misappropriation of that honor warrants criminal sanction.
* * *
The Stolen Valor Act is a narrow law enacted
to address an important problem, and it presents no threat to
freedom of expression. I would sustain the constitutionality of the
Act, and I therefore respectfully dissent. Notes 1 Although the Act does not
use the term “knowing” or “knowingly,” we have explained that
criminal statutes must be construed “in light of the background
rules of the common law . . . in which the requirement of
some mens rea for a crime is firmly embedded.” Staples v. United States , 511
U.S. 600 , 605 (1994). The Act’s use of the phrase “falsely
represents,” moreover, connotes a knowledge requirement. See
Black’s Law Dictionary 1022 (8th ed. 2004) (defining a
“misrepresentation” or “false representation” to mean “[t]he act of
making a false or misleading assertion about something, usu. with
the intent to deceive ” (emphasis added)). 2 See Black’s Law
Dictionary, supra , at 1327 (defining “representation” to
mean a “presentation of fact”); see also Milkovich v. Lorain Journal Co. , 497 U.S.
1 , 20 (1990) (explaining that the Court has protected
“statements that cannot ‘reasonably [be] interpreted as stating
actual facts’ about an individual” so that “public debate will not
suffer for lack of ‘imaginative expression’ or the ‘rhetorical
hyperbole’ which has traditionally added much to the discourse of
our Nation” (quoting Hustler Magazine, Inc. v. Falwell , 485 U.S.
46 , 50 (1988); alteration in original)). 3 Colimore, Pinning Crime
on Fake Heroes: N. J. Agent Helps Expose and Convict Those
with Bogus U. S. Medals, Philadelphia Inquirer, Feb. 11, 2004,
http://articles.philly.com/2004-02-11/news/25374213_1_medals-military-imposters-distinguished-flying-cross
(all Internet mate-rials as visited June 25, 2012, and available in
Clerk of Court’s casefile). 4 Crewdson, Claims of
Medals Amount to Stolen Valor, Chicago Tribune, Oct. 26, 2008,
http://www.chicagotribune.com/news/local/chi-valor-oct25,0,4301227.story?page=1. 5 Half of MOH Entries in
Oral History Project Are Incorrect, Marine Corps Times, Oct. 1,
2007, 2007 WLNR 27917486. 6 Ibid. 7 Young, His Honor Didn’t
Get Medal of Honor, Chicago Tribune, Oct. 21, 1994,
http://articles.chicagotribune.com/1994-10-21/news/941021031
8_1_congressional-medal-highest-fritz. 8 Rutenberg, At Fox News,
the Colonel Who Wasn’t, N. Y. Times, Apr. 29, 2002,
http://www.nytimes.com/2002/04/29/business/at-fox-news-the-colonel-who-wasn-t.html?pagewanted=all&src=pm. 9 B. Burkett & G.
Whitley, Stolen Valor: How the Vietnam Generation Was Robbed of Its
Heroes and Its History 179 (1998). 10 Indeed, the first person to be
prosecuted under the Stolen ValorAct apparently “parlayed his
medals into lucrative security consulting contracts.” Zambito, War
Crime: FBI Targets Fake Heroes, New York Daily News, May 6, 2007,
http://www.nydailynews.com/news/crime/war-crime-fbi-targets-fake-heroes-article-1.249168. 11 Dept.
of Justice, Northwest Crackdown on Fake Veterans in “Operation
Stolen Valor,” Sept. 21, 2007, http://www.justice.gov/usao/waw/
press/2007/sep/operationstolenvalor.html. 12 Cato,
High Court Tussles With False Heroics: Free Speech or Fel-ony?
Pittsburg Tribune Review, Feb. 23, 2012, http://triblive.com/
usworld/nation/1034434-85/court-military-law-false-medals-supreme-valor-act-federal-free. 13 In
addition, since the Department may not disclose the Social Security
numbers or birthdates of recipients, this database would be of
limited use in ascertaining the veracity of a claim involving a
person with a common name. Office of Undersecretary of Defense,
Report, at 3–4. 14 The
plurality rejects this rule. Although we have made clear that
“[u]ntruthful speech . . . has never been protected for
its own sake,” Virginia Bd. of Pharmacy v. Virginia
Citizens Consumer Council, Inc. , 425 U.S.
748 , 771 (1976), the most the plurality is willing to concede
is that “the falsity of speech bears upon whether it is protected,” ante, at 9. This represents a dramatic—and entirely
unjustified—departure from the sound approach taken in past cases.
Respondent and his supporting amici attempt to limit this
rule to certain subsets of false statements, see, e.g., Brief for Respondent 53 (asserting that, at most, only falsity that
is proved to cause specific harm is stripped of its First Amendment
protection), but the examples described above belie that attempt.
These examples show that the rule at least applies to (1) specific
types of false statements that were neither illegal nor tortious in
1791 (the torts of intentional infliction of emotional distress and
false-light invasion of privacy did not exist when the First
Amendment was adopted); (2) false speech that does not cause
pecuniary harm (the harm remedied by the torts of defamation,
intentional infliction of emotional distress, and false-light
invasion of privacy is often nonpecuniary in nature, as is the harm
inflicted by statements that are illegal under §§912 and 1001); (3)
false speech that does not cause detrimental reliance (neither
perjury laws nor many of the federal false statement statutes
require that anyone actually rely on the false statement); (4)
particular false statements that are not shown in court to have
caused specific harm (damages can be presumed in defamation actions
involving knowing or reckless falsehoods, and no showing of
specific harm is required in prosecutions under many of the federal
false statement statutes); and (5) false speech that does not cause
harm to a specific individual (the purpose of many of the federal
false statement statutes is to protect government
processes). 15 See
U. S. Army Center of Military History, Medal of Honor
Statistics,
http://www.history.army.mil/html/moh/mohstats.html. | The Supreme Court ruled that the Stolen Valor Act, which criminalizes lying about receiving military honors, is unconstitutional under the First Amendment. The Court found that the government's interest in protecting the integrity of the Medal of Honor does not justify restricting speech, even if it is false. The respondent, Xavier Alvarez, had falsely claimed to have received the Congressional Medal of Honor at a public meeting, but the Court determined that his lie was not sufficient to warrant criminal punishment. |
Free Speech | Brown v. Entertainment Merchants Ass'n | https://supreme.justia.com/cases/federal/us/564/786/ | OPINION OF THE COURT BROWN V. ENTERTAINMENT MERCHANTS ASSN. 564 U. S. ____ (2011) SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES NO. 08-1448 EDMUND G. BROWN, Jr., GOVERNOR OF CAL- IFORNIA,
et al., PETITIONERS v. ENTERTAIN- MENT MERCHANTS
ASSOCIATION et al.
on writ of certiorari to the united states court of
appeals for the ninth circuit
[June 27, 2011]
Justice Scalia delivered the
opinion of the Court.
We consider whether a California
law imposing restrictions on violent video games comports with the
First Amendment.
I
California Assembly Bill 1179
(2005), Cal. Civ. Code Ann. §§1746–1746.5 (West 2009) (Act),
prohibits the sale or rental of “violent video games” to minors,
and requires their packaging to be labeled “18.” The Act covers
games “in which the range of options available to a player includes
killing, maiming, dismembering, or sexually assaulting an image of
a human being, if those acts are depicted” in a manner that “[a]
reasonable person, considering the game as a whole, would find
appeals to a deviant or morbid interest of minors,” that is
“patently offensive to prevailing standards in the community as to
what is suitable for minors,” and that “causes the game, as a
whole, to lack serious literary, artistic, political, or scientific
value for minors.” §1746(d)(1)(A). Violation of the Act is
punishable by a civil fine of up to $1,000. §1746.3.
Respondents, representing the
video-game and software industries, brought a preenforcement
challenge to the Act in the United States District Court for the
Northern District of California. That court concluded that the Act
violated the First Amendment and permanently enjoined its
enforcement. Video Software Dealers Assn. v. Schwarzenegger , No. C–05–04188 RMW (2007), App. to Pet.
for Cert. 39a. The Court of Appeals affirmed, Video Software
Dealers Assn. v. Schwarzenegger , 556 F. 3d 950
(CA9 2009), and we granted certiorari, 559 U. S. ____ (2010).
II
California correctly acknowledges
that video games qualify for First Amendment protection. The Free
Speech Clause exists principally to protect discourse on public
matters, but we have long recognized that it is difficult to
distinguish politics from entertainment, and dangerous to try.
“Everyone is familiar with instances of propaganda through fiction.
What is one man’s amusement, teaches another’s doctrine.” Winters v. New York , 333 U. S. 507 , 510 (1948). Like the
protected books, plays, and movies that preceded them, video games
communicate ideas—and even social messages—through many familiar
literary devices (such as characters, dialogue, plot, and music)
and through features distinctive to the medium (such as the
player’s interaction with the virtual world). That suffices to
confer First Amendment protection. Under our Constitution,
“esthetic and moral judgments about art and literature … are for
the individual to make, not for the Government to decree, even with
the mandate or approval of a majority.” United States v. Playboy Entertainment Group, Inc. , 529 U. S. 803 , 818
(2000). And whatever the challenges of applying the Constitution to
ever-advancing technology, “the basic principles of freedom of
speech and the press, like the First Amendment’s command, do not
vary” when a new and different medium for communication appears. Joseph Burstyn, Inc. v. Wilson , 343 U. S. 495 , 503
(1952).
The most basic of those
principles is this: “[A]s a general matter, … government has no
power to restrict expression because of its message, its ideas, its
subject matter, or its content.” Ashcroft v. American
Civil Liberties Union , 535 U. S. 564 , 573
(2002) (internal quotation marks omitted). There are of course
exceptions. “ ‘From 1791 to the present,’ … the First
Amendment has ‘permitted restrictions upon the content of speech in
a few limited areas,’ and has never ‘include[d] a freedom to
disregard these traditional limitations.’ ” United
States v. Stevens , 559 U. S. ___, ___ (2010) (slip
op., at 5) (quoting R. A. V. v. St.
Paul , 505 U. S.
377 , 382–383 (1992)). These limited areas—such as obscenity, Roth v. United States , 354 U. S. 476 , 483
(1957), incitement, Brandenburg v. Ohio , 395 U. S. 444 , 447–449
(1969) (per curiam) , and fighting words, Chaplinsky v. New Hampshire , 315 U. S. 568 , 572
(1942)—represent “well-defined and narrowly limited classes of
speech, the prevention and punishment of which have never been
thought to raise any Constitutional problem,” id. , at
571–572.
Last Term, in Stevens , we held that
new categories of unprotected speech may not be added to the list
by a legislature that concludes certain speech is too harmful to be
tolerated. Stevens concerned a federal statute purporting
to criminalize the creation, sale, or possession of certain
depictions of animal cruelty. See 18 U. S. C. §48 (amended
2010). The statute covered depictions “in which a living animal is
intentionally maimed, mutilated, tortured, wounded, or killed” if
that harm to the animal was illegal where the “the creation, sale,
or possession t[ook] place,” §48(c)(1). A saving clause largely
borrowed from our obscenity jurisprudence, see Miller v. California , 413 U. S. 15 , 24 (1973),
exempted depictions with “serious religious, political, scientific,
educational, journalistic, historical, or artistic value,” §48(b).
We held that statute to be an impermissible content-based
restriction on speech. There was no American tradition of
forbidding the depiction of animal cruelty—though States
have long had laws against committing it.
The Government argued in Stevens that
lack of a historical warrant did not matter; that it could create
new categories of unprotected speech by applying a “simple
balancing test” that weighs the value of a particular category of
speech against its social costs and then punishes that category of
speech if it fails the test. Stevens , 559 U. S., at ___
(slip op., at 7). We emphatically rejected that “startling and
dangerous” proposition. Ibid. “Maybe there are some
categories of speech that have been historically unprotected, but
have not yet been specifically identified or discussed as such in
our case law.” Id. , at ___ (slip op., at 9). But without
persuasive evidence that a novel restriction on content is part of
a long (if heretofore unrecognized) tradition of proscription, a
legislature may not revise the “judgment [of] the American people,”
embodied in the First Amendment, “that the benefits of its
restrictions on the Government outweigh the costs.” Id. ,
at ___ (slip op., at 7).
That holding controls this case.[ Footnote 1 ] As in Stevens ,
California has tried to make violent-speech regulation look like
obscenity regulation by appending a saving clause required for the
latter. That does not suffice. Our cases have been clear that the
obscenity exception to the First Amendment does not cover whatever
a legislature finds shocking, but only depictions of “sexual
conduct,” Miller , supra, at 24. See also Cohen v. California , 403 U. S. 15 , 20 (1971); Roth , supra, at 487, and n. 20. Stevens was not the first time we
have encountered and rejected a State’s attempt to shoehorn speech
about violence into obscenity. In Winters , we considered a
New York criminal statute “forbid[ding] the massing of stories of
bloodshed and lust in such a way as to incite to crime against the
person,” 333 U. S., at 514. The New York Court of Appeals upheld
the provision as a law against obscenity. “[T]here can be no more
precise test of written indecency or obscenity,” it said, “than the
continuing and changeable experience of the community as to what
types of books are likely to bring about the corruption of public
morals or other analogous injury to the public order. ” Id. , at 514 (internal quotation marks omitted). That is of
course the same expansive view of governmental power to abridge the
freedom of speech based on interest-balancing that we rejected in Stevens . Our opinion in Winters , which concluded
that the New York statute failed a heightened vagueness standard
applicable to restrictions upon speech entitled to First Amendment
protection, 333 U. S., at 517–519, made clear that violence is not
part of the obscenity that the Constitution permits to be
regulated. The speech reached by the statute contained “no
indecency or obscenity in any sense heretofore known to the law.” Id. , at 519.
Because speech about violence is not obscene,
it is of no consequence that California’s statute mimics the New
York statute regulating obscenity-for-minors that we upheld in Ginsberg v. New York , 390 U. S. 629 (1968).
That case approved a prohibition on the sale to minors of sexual material that would be obscene from the perspective
of a child.[ Footnote 2 ] We held
that the legislature could “adjus[t] the definition of obscenity
‘to social realities by permitting the appeal of this type of
material to be assessed in terms of the sexual interests …’ of …
minors. ” Id. , at 638 (quoting Mishkin v. New York , 383 U. S. 502 , 509
(1966)). And because “obscenity is not protected expression,” the
New York statute could be sustained so long as the legislature’s
judgment that the proscribed materials were harmful to children
“was not irrational.” 390 U. S., at 641.
The California Act is something else entirely.
It does not adjust the boundaries of an existing category of
unprotected speech to ensure that a definition designed for adults
is not uncritically applied to children. California does not argue
that it is empowered to prohibit selling offensively violent works to adults —and it is wise not to, since that is but a
hair’s breadth from the argument rejected in Stevens .
Instead, it wishes to create a wholly new category of content-based
regulation that is permissible only for speech directed at
children.
That is unprecedented and mistaken. “[M]inors
are entitled to a significant measure of First Amendment
protection, and only in relatively narrow and well-defined
circumstances may government bar public dissemination of protected
materials to them.” Erznoznik v. Jacksonville , 422 U. S. 205 ,
212–213 (1975) (citation omitted). No doubt a State possesses
legitimate power to protect children from harm, Ginsberg , supra , at 640–641; Prince v. Massachusetts , 321 U. S. 158 , 165
(1944), but that does not include a free-floating power to restrict
the ideas to which children may be exposed. “Speech that is neither
obscene as to youths nor subject to some other legitimate
proscription cannot be suppressed solely to protect the young from
ideas or images that a legislative body thinks unsuitable for
them.” Erznoznik , supra, at 213–214.[ Footnote 3 ]
California’s argument would fare better if
there were a longstanding tradition in this country of specially
restricting children’s access to depictions of violence, but there
is none. Certainly the books we give children to read—or
read to them when they are younger—contain no shortage of gore.
Grimm’s Fairy Tales, for example, are grim indeed. As her just
deserts for trying to poison Snow White, the wicked queen is made
to dance in red hot slippers “till she fell dead on the floor, a
sad example of envy and jealousy.” The Complete Brothers Grimm
Fairy Tales 198 (2006 ed.). Cinderella’s evil stepsisters have
their eyes pecked out by doves. Id. , at 95. And Hansel and
Gretel (children!) kill their captor by baking her in an oven. Id. , at 54.
High-school reading lists are full of similar
fare. Homer’s Odysseus blinds Polyphemus the Cyclops by grinding
out his eye with a heated stake. The Odyssey of Homer, Book IX, p.
125 (S. Butcher & A. Lang transls. 1909) (“Even so did we seize
the fiery-pointed brand and whirled it round in his eye, and the
blood flowed about the heated bar. And the breath of the flame
singed his eyelids and brows all about, as the ball of the eye
burnt away, and the roots thereof crackled in the flame”). In the
Inferno, Dante and Virgil watch corrupt politicians struggle to
stay submerged beneath a lake of boiling pitch, lest they be
skewered by devils above the surface. Canto XXI, pp. 187–189 (A.
Mandelbaum transl. Bantam Classic ed. 1982). And Golding’s Lord of
the Flies recounts how a schoolboy called Piggy is savagely
murdered by other children while marooned on an island. W.
Golding, Lord of the Flies 208–209 (1997 ed.).[ Footnote 4 ]
This is not to say that minors’ consumption of
violent entertainment has never encountered resistance. In the
1800’s, dime novels depicting crime and “penny dreadfuls” (named
for their price and content) were blamed in some quarters for
juvenile delinquency. See Brief for Cato Institute as Amicus
Curiae 6–7. When motion pictures came along, they became the
villains instead. “The days when the police looked upon dime novels
as the most dangerous of textbooks in the school for crime are
drawing to a close… . They say that the moving picture machine
… tends even more than did the dime novel to turn the thoughts of
the easily influenced to paths which sometimes lead to prison.”
Moving Pictures as Helps to Crime, N. Y. Times, Feb. 21, 1909,
quoted in Brief for Cato Institute, at 8. For a time, our Court did
permit broad censorship of movies because of their capacity to be
“used for evil,” see Mutual Film Corp. v. Industrial
Comm’n of Ohio , 236 U. S. 230 , 242
(1915), but we eventually reversed course, Joseph Burstyn,
Inc. , 343 U. S., at 502; see also Erznoznik , supra, at 212–214 (invalidating a drive-in movies
restriction designed to protect children). Radio dramas were next,
and then came comic books. Brief for Cato Institute, at 10–11. Many
in the late 1940’s and early 1950’s blamed comic books for
fostering a “preoccupation with violence and horror” among the
young, leading to a rising juvenile crime rate. See Note,
Regulation of Comic Books, 68 Harv. L. Rev. 489, 490 (1955).
But efforts to convince Congress to restrict comic books failed.
Brief for Comic Book Legal Defense Fund as Amicus Curiae 11–15.[ Footnote 5 ] And, of
course, after comic books came television and music lyrics.
California claims that video games present
special problems because they are “interactive,” in that the player
participates in the violent action on screen and determines its
outcome. The latter feature is nothing new: Since at least the
publication of The Adventures of You: Sugarcane Island in 1969,
young readers of choose-your-own-adventure stories have been able
to make decisions that determine the plot by following instructions
about which page to turn to. Cf. Interactive Digital Software
Assn. v. St. Louis County, 329 F. 3d 954,
957–958 (CA8 2003). As for the argument that video games enable
participation in the violent action, that seems to us more a matter
of degree than of kind. As Judge Posner has observed, all
literature is interactive. “[T]he better it is, the more
interactive. Literature when it is successful draws the reader into
the story, makes him identify with the characters, invites him to
judge them and quarrel with them, to experience their joys and
sufferings as the reader’s own.” American Amusement Machine
Assn. v. Kendrick , 244 F. 3d 572, 577 (CA7 2001)
(striking down a similar restriction on violent video games).
Justice Alito has done considerable
independent re-search to identify, see post , at 14–15, nn.
13–18, video games in which “the violence is astounding,” post , at 14. “Victims are dismembered, decapitated,
disemboweled, set on fire, and chopped into little pieces. . . .
Blood gushes, splatters, and pools.” Ibid. Justice Alito recounts all these disgusting video games in order to disgust
us—but disgust is not a valid basis for restricting expression. And
the same is true of Justice Alito’s description, post , at
14–15, of those video games he has discovered that have a racial or
ethnic motive for their violence—“ ‘ethnic cleansing’ [of] . .
. African Americans, Latinos, or Jews.” To what end does he relate
this? Does it somehow increase the “aggressiveness” that California
wishes to suppress? Who knows? But it does arouse the reader’s ire,
and the reader’s desire to put an end to this horrible message.
Thus, ironically, Justice Alito’s argument highlights the precise
danger posed by the California Act: that the ideas expressed by speech—whether it be violence, or gore, or racism—and
not its objective effects, may be the real reason for governmental
proscription.
III
Because the Act imposes a
restriction on the content of protected speech, it is invalid
unless California can demonstrate that it passes strict
scrutiny—that is, unless it is justified by a compelling government
interest and is narrowly drawn to serve that interest. R. A. V. , 505 U. S., at 395. The State must
specifically identify an “actual problem” in need of solving, Playboy , 529 U. S., at 822–823, and the curtailment of
free speech must be actually necessary to the solution, see R.
A. V. , supra, at 395. That is a demanding standard.
“It is rare that a regulation restricting speech because of its
content will ever be permissible.” Playboy , supra, at 818.
California cannot meet that
standard. At the outset, it acknowledges that it cannot show a
direct causal link between violent video games and harm to minors.
Rather, relying upon our decision in Turner Broadcasting
System, Inc. v. FCC , 512 U. S. 622 (1994),
the State claims that it need not produce such proof because the
legislature can make a predictive judgment that such a link exists,
based on competing psychological studies. But reliance on Turner Broadcasting is misplaced. That decision applied intermediate scrutiny to a content-neutral regulation. Id. , at 661–662. California’s burden is much higher, and
because it bears the risk of uncertainty, see Playboy , supra, at 816–817, ambiguous proof will not suffice.
The State’s evidence is not compelling.
California relies primarily on the research of Dr. Craig Anderson
and a few other research psychologists whose studies purport to
show a connection between exposure to violent video games and
harmful effects on children. These studies have been rejected by
every court to consider them,[ Footnote 6 ] and with good reason: They do not prove that
violent video games cause minors to act aggressively (which would at least be a beginning). Instead,
“[n]early all of the research is based on correlation, not evidence
of causation, and most of the studies suffer from significant,
admitted flaws in methodology.” Video Software Dealers
Assn. 556 F. 3d, at 964. They show at best some
correlation between exposure to violent entertainment and minuscule
real-world effects, such as children’s feeling more aggressive or
making louder noises in the few minutes after playing a violent
game than after playing a nonviolent game.[ Footnote 7 ]
Even taking for granted Dr. Anderson’s
conclusions that violent video games produce some effect on
children’s feelings of aggression, those effects are both small and
indistinguishable from effects produced by other media. In his
testimony in a similar lawsuit, Dr. Anderson admitted that the
“effect sizes” of children’s exposure to violent video games are
“about the same” as that produced by their exposure to violence on
television. App. 1263. And he admits that the same effects
have been found when children watch cartoons starring Bugs Bunny or
the Road Runner, id., at 1304, or when they play video
games like Sonic the Hedgehog that are rated “E” (appropriate for
all ages), id., at 1270, or even when they “vie[w] a
picture of a gun,” id., at 1315–1316.[ Footnote 8 ]
Of course, California has (wisely) declined to
restrict Saturday morning cartoons, the sale of games rated for
young children, or the distribution of pictures of guns. The
consequence is that its regulation is wildly underinclusive when
judged against its asserted justification, which in our view is
alone enough to defeat it. Underinclusiveness raises serious doubts
about whether the government is in fact pursuing the interest it
invokes, rather than disfavoring a particular speaker or viewpoint.
See City of Ladue v. Gilleo , 512 U. S. 43 , 51 (1994); Florida Star v. B. J. F. , 491 U. S. 524 , 540
(1989). Here, California has singled out the purveyors of video
games for disfavored treatment—at least when compared to
booksellers, cartoonists, and movie producers—and has given no
persuasive reason why.
The Act is also seriously underinclusive in
another respect—and a respect that renders irrelevant the
contentions of the concurrence and the dissents that video games
are qualitatively different from other portrayals of violence. The
California Legislature is perfectly willing to leave this
dangerous, mind-altering material in the hands of children so long
as one parent (or even an aunt or uncle) says it’s OK. And there
are not even any requirements as to how this parental or avuncular
relationship is to be verified; apparently the child’s or putative
parent’s, aunt’s, or uncle’s say-so suffices. That is not how one
addresses a serious social problem.
California claims that the Act is justified in
aid of parental authority: By requiring that the purchase of
violent video games can be made only by adults, the Act ensures
that parents can decide what games are appropriate. At the outset,
we note our doubts that punishing third parties for conveying
protected speech to children just in case their parents
disapprove of that speech is a proper governmental means of aiding
parental authority. Accepting that position would largely vitiate
the rule that “only in relatively narrow and well-defined
circumstances may government bar public dissemination of protected
materials to [minors].” Erznoznik , 422 U. S., at
212–213.
But leaving that aside, California cannot show
that the Act’s restrictions meet a substantial need of parents who
wish to restrict their children’s access to violent video games but
cannot do so. The video-game industry has in place a voluntary
rating system designed to inform consumers about the content of
games. The system, implemented by the Entertainment Software Rating
Board (ESRB), assigns age-specific ratings to each video game
submitted: EC (Early Childhood); E (Everyone); E10+ (Everyone 10
and older); T (Teens); M (17 and older); and AO (Adults Only—18 and
older). App. 86. The Video Software Dealers Association encourages
retailers to prominently display information about the ESRB system
in their stores; to refrain from renting or selling adults-only
games to minors; and to rent or sell “M” rated games to minors only
with parental consent. Id., at 47. In 2009, the Federal
Trade Commission (FTC) found that, as a result of this system, “the
video game industry outpaces the movie and music industries” in
“(1) restricting target-marketing of mature-rated products to
children; (2) clearly and prominently disclosing rating
information; and (3) re-stricting children’s access to mature-rated
products at retail.” FTC, Report to Congress, Marketing Violent
Entertainment to Children 30 (Dec. 2009), online at http://
www.ftc.gov / os/ 2009 / 12/ P994511violententertainment.pdf
(as visited June 24, 2011, and available in Clerk of Court’s case
file) (FTC Report). This system does much to ensure that minors
cannot purchase seriously violent games on their own, and that
parents who care about the matter can readily evaluate the games
their children bring home. Filling the remaining modest gap in
concerned-parents’ control can hardly be a compelling state
interest.[ Footnote 9 ]
And finally, the Act’s purported aid to
parental authority is vastly overinclusive. Not all of the children
who are forbidden to purchase violent video games on their own have
parents who care whether they purchase violent video
games. While some of the legislation’s effect may indeed be in
support of what some parents of the restricted children actually
want, its entire effect is only in support of what the State thinks
parents ought to want. This is not the narrow tailoring to
“assisting parents” that restriction of First Amendment rights
requires.
* * *
California’s effort to regulate
violent video games is the latest episode in a long series of
failed attempts to censor violent entertainment for minors. While
we have pointed out above that some of the evidence brought forward
to support the harmfulness of video games is unpersuasive, we do
not mean to demean or disparage the concerns that underlie the
attempt to regulate them—concerns that may and doubtless do prompt
a good deal of parental oversight. We have no business passing
judgment on the view of the California Legislature that violent
video games (or, for that matter, any other forms of speech)
corrupt the young or harm their moral development. Our task is only
to say whether or not such works constitute a “well-defined and
narrowly limited clas[s] of speech, the prevention and punishment
of which have never been thought to raise any Constitutional
problem,” Chaplinsky , 315 U. S., at 571–572 (the answer
plainly is no); and if not, whether the regulation of such works is
justified by that high degree of necessity we have described as a
compelling state interest (it is not). Even where the protection of
children is the object, the constitutional limits on governmental
action apply.
California’s legislation
straddles the fence between (1) addressing a serious social problem
and (2) helping concerned parents control their children. Both ends
are legitimate, but when they affect First Amendment rights they
must be pursued by means that are neither seriously underinclusive
nor seriously overinclusive. See Church of Lukumi Babalu Aye,
Inc. v. Hialeah , 508 U. S. 520 , 546
(1993). As a means of protecting children from portrayals of
violence, the legislation is seriously underinclusive, not only
because it excludes portrayals other than video games, but also
because it permits a parental or avuncular veto. And as a means of
assisting concerned parents it is seriously overinclusive because
it abridges the First Amendment rights of young people whose
parents (and aunts and uncles) think violent video games are a
harmless pastime. And the overbreadth in achieving one goal is not
cured by the underbreadth in achieving the other. Legislation such
as this, which is neither fish nor fowl, cannot survive strict
scrutiny.
We affirm the judgment below.
It is so ordered. Footnote 1 Justice Alito distinguishes Stevens on several grounds that seem to us ill founded. He suggests, post , at 10 (opinion concurring in judgment), that Stevens did not apply strict scrutiny. If that is so (and
we doubt it), it would make this an a fortiori case. He
says, post , at 9, 10, that the California Act punishes the
sale or rental rather than the “creation” or “possession” of
violent depictions. That distinction appears nowhere in Stevens itself, and for good reason: It would make
permissible the prohibition of printing or selling books—though not
the writing of them. Whether government regulation applies to
creating, distributing, or consuming speech makes no difference.
And finally, Justice Alito points out, post , at 10, that Stevens “left open the possibility that a more narrowly
drawn statute” would be constitutional. True, but entirely
irrelevant. Stevens said, 559 U. S., at ___ (slip op., at
19), that the “crush-video” statute at issue there might pass
muster if it were limited to videos of acts of animal cruelty that
violated the law where the acts were performed. There is no
contention that any of the virtual characters depicted in the
imaginative videos at issue here are criminally liable. Footnote 2 The statute in Ginsberg restricted
the sale of certain depictions of “nudity, sexual conduct, sexual
excitement, or sado-masochistic abuse,” that were “ ‘[h]armful
to minors.’ ” A depiction was harmful to minors if it:
“(i) predominantly appeals to the prurient,
shameful or morbid interests of minors, and
“(ii) is patently offensive to prevailing
standards in the adult community as a whole with respect to what is
suitable material for minors, and
“(iii) is utterly without redeeming social
importance for minors.” 390 U. S., at 646 (Appendix A to opinion of
the Court) (quoting N. Y. Penal Law §484–h(1)(f)). Footnote 3 Justice Thomas ignores the holding of Erznoznik , and denies that persons under 18 have any
constitutional right to speak or be spoken to without their
parents’ consent. He cites no case, state or federal, supporting
this view, and to our knowledge there is none. Most of his dissent
is devoted to the proposition that parents have traditionally had
the power to control what their children hear and say. This is true
enough. And it perhaps follows from this that the state has the
power to enforce parental prohibitions—to require, for
example, that the promoters of a rock concert exclude those minors
whose parents have advised the promoters that their children are
forbidden to attend. But it does not follow that the state has the
power to prevent children from hearing or saying anything without their parents’ prior consent . The latter would
mean, for example, that it could be made criminal to admit persons
under 18 to a political rally without their parents’ prior written
consent—even a political rally in support of laws against corporal
punishment of children, or laws in favor of greater rights for
minors. And what is good for First Amendment rights of speech must
be good for First Amendment rights of religion as well: It could be
made criminal to admit a person under 18 to church, or to give a
person under 18 a religious tract, without his parents’ prior
consent. Our point is not, as Justice Thomas believes, post , at 16, n. 2, merely that such laws are
“undesirable.” They are obviously an infringement upon the
religious freedom of young people and those who wish to proselytize
young people. Such laws do not enforce parental authority
over children’s speech and religion; they impose governmental authority, subject only to a parental veto.
In the absence of any precedent for state control, uninvited by the
parents, over a child’s speech and religion (Justice Thomas cites
none), and in the absence of any justification for such control
that would satisfy strict scrutiny, those laws must be
unconstitutional. This argument is not, as Justice Thomas asserts,
“circular,” ibid. It is the absence of any historical
warrant or compelling justification for such restrictions, not our ipse dixit , that renders them invalid. Footnote 4 Justice Alito accuses us of pronouncing that
playing violent video games “is not different in ‘kind’ ” from
reading violent literature. Post , at 2. Well of course it
is different in kind, but not in a way that causes the provision
and viewing of violent video games, unlike the provision and
reading of books, not to be expressive activity and hence not to
enjoy First Amendment protection. Reading Dante is unquestionably
more cultured and intellectually edifying than playing Mortal
Kombat. But these cultural and intellectual differences are not constitutional ones. Crudely violent video games, tawdry
TV shows, and cheap novels and magazines are no less forms of
speech than The Divine Comedy, and restrictions upon them must
survive strict scrutiny—a question to which we devote our attention
in Part III, infra. Even if we can see in them “nothing of
any possible value to society . . . , they are as much entitled to
the protection of free speech as the best of literature.” Winters v. New York , 333 U. S. 507 , 510 (1948). Footnote 5 The crusade against comic books was led by a
psychiatrist, Frederic Wertham, who told the Senate Judiciary
Committee that “as long as the crime comic books industry exists in
its present forms there are no secure homes.” Juvenile Delinquency
(Comic Books): Hearings before the Subcommittee to Investigate
Juvenile Delinquency, 83d Cong., 2d Sess., 84 (1954). Wertham’s
objections extended even to Superman comics, which he described as
“particularly injurious to the ethical development of children.” Id. , at 86. Wertham’s crusade did convince the New York
Legislature to pass a ban on the sale of certain comic books to
minors, but it was vetoed by Governor Thomas Dewey on the ground
that it was unconstitutional given our opinion in Winters,
supra. See People v. Bookcase, Inc. , 14
N. Y. 2d 409, 412–413, 201 N. E. 2d 14, 15–16 (1964). Footnote 6 See Video Software Dealers Assn. v. Schwarzenegger, 556 F. 3d 950, 963–964 (CA9 2009); Interactive Digital Software Assn. v. St. Louis
County, 329 F. 3d 954 (CA8 2003); American Amusement
Machine Assn. v. Kendrick , 244 F. 3d 572,
578–579 (CA7 2001); Entertainment Software Assn. v. Foti , 451 F. Supp. 2d 823, 832–833 (MD La. 2006); Entertainment Software Assn. v. Hatch , 443 F.
Supp. 2d 1065, 1070 (Minn. 2006), aff ’d, 519 F. 3d 768 (CA8
2008); Entertainment Software Assn. v. Granholm ,
426 F. Supp. 2d 646, 653 (ED Mich. 2006); Entertainment
Software Assn. v. Blagojevich , 404 F. Supp. 2d
1051, 1063 (ND Ill. 2005), aff ’d, 469 F. 3d 641 (CA7
2006). Footnote 7 One study, for example, found that children
who had just finished playing violent video games were more likely
to fill in the blank letter in “explo_e” with a “d” (so that it
reads “explode”) than with an “r” (“explore”). App. 496, 506
(internal quotation marks omitted). The prevention of this
phenomenon, which might have been anticipated with common sense, is
not a compelling state interest. Footnote 8 Justice Alito is mistaken in thinking that we fail
to take account of “new and rapidly evolving technology,” post , at 1. The studies in question pertain to that new
and rapidly evolving technology, and fail to show, with the degree
of certitude that strict scrutiny requires, that this
subject-matter restriction on speech is justified. Nor is Justice
Alito correct in attributing to us the view that “violent video
games really present no serious problem.” Post , at 2.
Perhaps they do present a problem, and perhaps none of us would
allow our own children to play them. But there are all sorts of
“problems”—some of them surely more serious than this one—that
cannot be addressed by governmental restriction of free expression:
for example, the problem of encouraging anti-Semitism ( National
Socialist Party of America v. Skokie , 432 U. S. 43 (1977) (per curiam) ), the problem of spreading a political
philosophy hostile to the Constitution ( Noto v. United
States , 367 U.
S. 290 (1961)), or the problem of encouraging disrespect for
the Nation’s flag ( Texas v. Johnson , 491 U. S. 397 (1989)).
Justice Breyer would hold that California has
satisfied strict scrutiny based upon his own research into the
issue of the harmfulness of violent video games. See post ,
at 20–35 (Appendixes to dissenting opinion) (listing competing
academic articles discussing the harmfulness vel non of
violent video games). The vast preponderance of this research is
outside the record—and in any event we do not see how it could lead
to Justice Breyer’s conclusion, since he admits he cannot say
whether the studies on his side are right or wrong. Post ,
at 15. Similarly, Justice Alito says he is not “sure” whether there
are any constitutionally dispositive differences between video
games and other media. Post , at 2. If that is so, then
strict scrutiny plainly has not been satisfied. Footnote 9 Justice Breyer concludes that the remaining
gap is compelling because, according to the FTC’s report, some “20%
of those under 17 are still able to buy M-rated games.” Post , at 18 (citing FTC Report 28). But some gap in
compliance is unavoidable. The sale of alcohol to minors, for
example, has long been illegal, but a 2005 study suggests that
about 18% of retailers still sell alcohol to those under the
drinking age. Brief for State of Rhode Island et al . as Amici Curiae 18. Even if the sale of violent video
games to minors could be deterred further by increasing regulation,
the government does not have a compelling interest in each marginal
percentage point by which its goals are advanced. ALITO, J., CONCURRING IN JUDGMENT BROWN V. ENTERTAINMENT MERCHANTS ASSN. 564 U. S. ____ (2011) SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES NO. 08-1448 EDMUND G. BROWN, Jr., GOVERNOR OF CAL- IFORNIA,
et al., PETITIONERS v. ENTERTAIN- MENT MERCHANTS
ASSOCIATION et al.
on writ of certiorari to the united states court of
appeals for the ninth circuit
[June 27, 2011]
Justice Alito, with whom The
Chief Justice joins, concurring in the judgment.
The California statute that is
before us in this case represents a pioneering effort to address
what the state legislature and others regard as a potentially
serious social problem: the effect of exceptionally violent video
games on impressionable minors, who often spend countless hours
immersed in the alternative worlds that these games create.
Although the California statute is well intentioned, its terms are
not framed with the precision that the Constitution demands, and I
therefore agree with the Court that this particular law cannot be
sustained.
I disagree, however, with the approach taken
in the Court’s opinion. In considering the application of
unchanging constitutional principles to new and rapidly evolving
technology, this Court should proceed with caution. We should make
every effort to understand the new technology. We should take into
account the possibility that developing technology may have
important societal implications that will become apparent only with
time. We should not jump to the conclusion that new technology is
fundamentally the same as some older thing with which we are
familiar. And we should not hastily dismiss the judgment of
legislators, who may be in a better position than we are to assess
the implications of new technology. The opinion of the Court
exhibits none of this caution.
In the view of the Court, all those concerned
about the effects of violent video games—federal and state
legislators, educators, social scientists, and parents—are unduly
fearful, for violent video games really present no serious problem.
See ante , at 10–13, 15–16. Spending hour upon hour
controlling the actions of a character who guns down scores of
innocent victims is not different in “kind” from reading a
description of violence in a work of literature. See ante ,
at 10–11.
The Court is sure of this; I am not. There are
reasons to suspect that the experience of playing violent video
games just might be very different from reading a book, listening
to the radio, or watching a movie or a television show.
I
Respondents in this case,
representing the video-game industry, ask us to strike down the
California law on two grounds: The broad ground adopted by the
Court and the narrower ground that the law’s definition of “violent
video game,” see Cal. Civ. Code Ann. §1746(d)(1)(A) (West 2009), is
impermissibly vague. See Brief for Respondents 23–61. Because I
agree with the latter argument, I see no need to reach the broader
First Amendment issues addressed by the Court.[ Footnote 1 ]
A
Due process requires that laws
give people of ordinary intelligence fair notice of what is
prohibited. Grayned v. City of Rockford , 408 U. S. 104 , 108
(1972). The lack of such notice in a law that regulates expression
“raises special First Amendment concerns because of its obvious
chilling effect on free speech.” Reno v. American
Civil Liberties Union , 521 U. S. 844 , 871–872
(1997). Vague laws force potential speakers to “ ‘steer far
wider of the unlawful zone’ … than if the boundaries of the
forbidden areas were clearly marked.” Baggett v. Bullitt , 377 U. S. 360 , 372
(1964) (quoting Speiser v. Randall , 357 U. S. 513 , 526
(1958)). While “perfect clarity and precise guidance have never
been required even of regulations that restrict expressive
activity,” Ward v. Rock Against Racism , 491 U. S. 781 , 794
(1989), “government may regulate in the area” of First Amendment
freedoms “only with narrow specificity,” NAACP v. Button , 371
U. S. 415 , 433 (1963); see also Hoffman Estates v. Flipside, Hoffman Estates, Inc. , 455 U. S. 489 , 499
(1982). These principles apply to laws that regulate expression for
the purpose of protecting children. See Interstate Circuit,
Inc. v. Dallas , 390 U. S. 676 , 689
(1968).
Here, the California law does not
define “violent video games” with the “narrow specificity” that the
Constitution demands. In an effort to avoid First Amendment
problems, the California Legislature modeled its violent video game
statute on the New York law that this Court upheld in Ginsberg v. New York , 390 U. S. 629 (1968)—a law that
prohibited the sale of certain sexually related materials to
minors, see id. , at 631–633. But the California
Legislature departed from the Ginsberg model in an
important respect, and the legislature overlooked important
differences between the materials falling within the scope of the
two statutes.
B
The law at issue in Ginsberg prohibited the sale to minors of materials that
were deemed “harmful to minors,” and the law defined “harmful to
minors” simply by adding the words “for minors” to each element of
the definition of obscenity set out in what were then the Court’s
leading obscenity decisions, see Roth v. United
States , 354 U.
S. 476 (1957), and Book Named “John Cleland’s Memoirs of a
Woman of Pleasure” v. Attorney General of Mass. , 383 U. S. 413 (1966).
Seeking to bring its violent
video game law within the protection of Ginsberg , the
California Legislature began with the obscenity test adopted in Miller v. California , 413 U. S. 15 (1973), a
decision that revised the obscenity tests previously set out in Roth and Memoirs . The legislature then made
certain modifications to accommodate the aim of the violent video
game law.
Under Miller , an obscenity statute
must contain a thresh-old limitation that restricts the statute’s
scope to specifically described “hard core” materials. See 413 U.
S., at 23–25, 27. Materials that fall within this “hard core”
category may be deemed to be obscene if three additional
requirements are met:
(1) an “average person, applying contemporary community
standards [must] find … the work, taken as a whole, appeals to the
prurient interest”;
(2) “the work [must] depic[t] or describ[e], in a patently
offensive way, sexual conduct specifically defined by the
applicable state law; and”
(3) “the work, taken as a whole, [must] lac[k] serious literary,
artistic, political, or scientific value.” Id. , at 24
(internal quotation marks omitted).
Adapting these standards, the
California law imposes the following threshold limitation: “[T]he
range of options available to a player [must] includ[e] killing,
maiming, dismembering, or sexually assaulting an image of a human
being.” §1746(d)(1). Any video game that meets this threshold test
is subject to the law’s restrictions if it also satisfies three
further requirements:
“(i) A reasonable person, considering the game
as a whole, would find [the game] appeals to a deviant or morbid
interest of minors.
“(ii) It is patently offensive to prevailing
standards in the community as to what is suitable for minors.
“(iii) It causes the game, as a whole, to lack
serious literary, artistic, political, or scientific value for
minors.” §1746(d)(1)(A).[ Footnote
2 ]
C
The first important difference
between the Ginsberg law and the California violent video
game statute concerns their respective threshold requirements. As
noted, the Ginsberg law built upon the test for adult
obscenity, and the current adult obscenity test, which was set out
in Miller, requires an obscenity statute to contain a
threshold limitation that restricts the statute’s coverage to
specifically defined “hard core” depictions. See 413 U. S., at
23–25, 27. The Miller Court gave as an example a statute
that applies to only “[p]atently offensive representations or
descriptions of ultimate sexual acts,” “masturbation, excretory
functions, and lewd exhibition of the genitals.” Id ., at
25. The Miller Court clearly viewed this threshold
limitation as serving a vital notice function. “We are satisfied,”
the Court wrote, “that these specific prerequisites will provide
fair notice to a dealer in such materials that his public and
commercial activities may bring prosecution.” Id. , at 27;
see also Reno , supra , at 873 (observing that Miller ’s threshold limitation “reduces the vagueness
inherent in the open-ended term ‘patently
offensive’ ”).[ Footnote
3 ]
By contrast, the threshold
requirement of the California law does not perform the narrowing
function served by the limitation in Miller . At least when Miller was decided, depictions of “hard core” sexual
conduct were not a common feature of mainstream entertainment. But
nothing similar can be said about much of the conduct covered by
the California law. It provides that a video game cannot qualify as
“violent” unless “the range of options available to a player
includes killing, maiming, dismembering, or sexually assaulting an
image of a human being . ” §1746(d)(1).
For better or worse, our society has long
regarded many depictions of killing and maiming[ Footnote 4 ] as suitable features of popular
entertainment, including entertainment that is widely available to
minors. The California law’s threshold requirement would more
closely resemble the limitation in Miller if it targeted a
narrower class of graphic depictions.
Because of this feature of the California
law’s threshold test, the work of providing fair notice is left in
large part to the three requirements that follow, but those
elements are also not up to the task. In drafting the violent video
game law, the California Legislature could have made its own
judgment regarding the kind and degree of violence that is
acceptable in games played by minors (or by minors in particular
age groups). Instead, the legislature relied on undefined societal
or community standards.
One of the three elements at issue here refers
expressly to “prevailing standards in the community as to what is
suitable for minors.” §1746(d)(1)(A)(ii). Another element points in
the same direction, asking whether “[a] reasonable person,
considering [a] game as a whole,” would find that it “appeals to a deviant or morbid interest of minors.”
§1746(d)(1)(A)(i) (emphasis added).
The terms “deviant” and “morbid” are not
defined in the statute, and California offers no reason to think
that its courts would give the terms anything other than their
ordinary meaning. See Reply Brief for Petitioners 5 (arguing that
“[a] reasonable person can make this judgment through … a common
understanding and definition of the applicable terms”). I therefore
assume that “deviant” and “morbid” carry the meaning that they
convey in ordinary speech. The adjective “deviant” ordinarily means
“deviating … from some accepted norm,” and the term “morbid” means
“of, relating to, or characteristic of disease.” Webster’s 618,
1469. A “deviant or morbid interest” in violence, therefore,
appears to be an interest that de- viates from what is
regarded—presumably in accordance with some generally accepted
standard—as normal and healthy. Thus, the application of the
California law is heavily dependent on the identification of
generally accepted standards regarding the suitability of violent
entertainment for minors.
The California Legislature seems to have
assumed that these standards are sufficiently well known so that a
person of ordinary intelligence would have fair notice as to
whether the kind and degree of violence in a particular game is
enough to qualify the game as “violent.” And because the Miller test looks to community standards, the legislature
may have thought that the use of undefined community standards in
the violent video game law would not present vagueness
problems.
There is a critical difference, however,
between obscenity laws and laws regulating violence in
entertainment. By the time of this Court’s landmark obscenity cases
in the 1960’s, obscenity had long been prohibited, see Roth , 354 U. S., at 484–485, and this experience had
helped to shape certain generally accepted norms concerning
expression related to sex.
There is no similar history regarding
expression related to violence. As the Court notes, classic
literature contains descriptions of great violence, and even
children’s stories sometimes depict very violent scenes. See ante , at 8–9.
Although our society does not generally regard
all depictions of violence as suitable for children or adolescents,
the prevalence of violent depictions in children’s literature and
entertainment creates numerous opportunities for reasonable people
to disagree about which depictions may excite “deviant” or “morbid”
impulses. See Edwards & Berman, Regulating Violence on
Television, 89 Nw. U. L. Rev. 1487, 1523 (1995) (observing that the Miller test would be difficult to apply to violent
expression because “there is nothing even approaching a consensus
on low-value violence”).
Finally, the difficulty of ascertaining the
community standards incorporated into the California law is
compounded by the legislature’s decision to lump all minors
together. The California law draws no distinction between young
children and adolescents who are nearing the age of majority.
In response to a question at oral argument,
the attorney defending the constitutionality of the California law
said that the State would accept a narrowing construction of the
law under which the law’s references to “minors” would be
interpreted to refer to the oldest minors—that is, those just short
of 18. Tr. of Oral Arg. 11–12. However, “it is not within our power
to construe and narrow state laws.” Grayned , 408 U. S., at
110. We can only “ ‘extrapolate [their] allowable
meaning’ ” from the statutory text and authoritative
interpretations of similar laws by courts of the State. Ibid . (quoting Garner v. Louisiana , 368 U. S. 157 ,
174 (1961) (Frankfurter, J., concurring in judgment)).
In this case, California has not provided any
evidence that the California Legislature intended the law to be
limited in this way, or cited any decisions from its courts that
would support an “oldest minors” construction.[ Footnote 5 ]
For these reasons, I conclude that the
California violent video game law fails to provide the fair notice
that the Constitution requires. And I would go no further. I would
not express any view on whether a properly drawn statute would or
would not survive First Amendment scrutiny. We should address that
question only if and when it is necessary to do so.
II
Having outlined how I would
decide this case, I will now briefly elaborate on my reasons for
questioning the wisdom of the Court’s approach. Some of these
reasons are touched upon by the dissents, and while I am not
prepared at this time to go as far as either Justice Thomas or
Justice Breyer, they raise valid concerns.
A
The Court is wrong in saying that
the holding in United States v. Stevens , 559 U.
S. ___ (2010), “controls this case.” Ante , at 4. First,
the statute in Stevens differed sharply from the statute
at issue here. Stevens struck down a law that broadly
prohibited any person from creating, selling, or
possessing depictions of animal cruelty for commercial gain. The
California law involved here, by contrast, is limited to the sale
or rental of violent video games to minors . The California
law imposes no restriction on the creation of violent video games,
or on the possession of such games by anyone, whether above or
below the age of 18. The California law does not regulate the sale
or rental of violent games by adults. And the California law does
not prevent parents and certain other close relatives from buying
or renting violent games for their children or other young
relatives if they see fit.
Second, Stevens does not
support the proposition that a law like the one at issue must
satisfy strict scrutiny. The portion of Stevens on which
the Court relies rejected the Government’s contention that
depictions of animal cruelty were categorically outside the range
of any First Amendment protection. 559 U. S., at __ (slip
op., at 5). Going well beyond Steven s, the Court now holds
that any law that attempts to prevent minors from purchasing
violent video games must satisfy strict scrutiny instead of the
more lenient standard applied in Ginsberg , 390 U. S. 629 , our most closely
related precedent. As a result of today’s decision, a State may
prohibit the sale to minors of what Ginsberg described as
“girlie magazines,” but a State must surmount a formidable (and
perhaps insurmountable) obstacle if it wishes to prevent children
from purchasing the most violent and depraved video games
imaginable.
Third, Stevens expressly left open
the possibility that a more narrowly drawn statute targeting
depictions of animal cruelty might be compatible with the First
Amendment. See 559 U. S., at ___ (slip op., at 19). In this case,
the Court’s sweeping opinion will likely be read by many, both
inside and outside the video-game industry, as suggesting that no
regulation of minors’ access to violent video games is allowed—at
least without supporting evidence that may not be realistically
obtainable given the nature of the phenomenon in question.
B
The Court’s opinion distorts the
effect of the California law. I certainly agree with the Court that
the government has no “free-floating power to restrict the ideas to
which children may be exposed,” ante , at 7, but the
California law does not exercise such a power. If parents want
their child to have a violent video game, the California law does
not interfere with that parental prerogative. Instead, the
California law reinforces parental decisionmaking in exactly the
same way as the New York statute upheld in Ginsberg . Under
both laws, minors are prevented from purchasing certain materials;
and under both laws, parents are free to supply their children with
these items if that is their wish.
Citing the video-game industry’s
voluntary rating system, the Court argues that the California law
does not “meet a substantial need of parents who wish to restrict
their children’s access to violent video games but cannot do so.” Ante , at 15. The Court does not mention the fact that the
industry adopted this system in response to the threat of federal
regulation, Brief for Activision Blizzard, Inc., as Amicus
Curiae 7–10, a threat that the Court’s opinion may now be seen
as largely eliminating. Nor does the Court acknowledge that
compliance with this system at the time of the enactment of the
California law left much to be desired[ Footnote 6 ]—or that future enforcement may decline if the
video-game industry perceives that any threat of government
regulation has vanished. Nor does the Court note, as Justice Breyer
points out, see post , at 11 (dissenting opinion), that
many parents today are simply not able to monitor their children’s
use of computers and gaming devices.
C
Finally, the Court is far too
quick to dismiss the possibility that the experience of playing
video games (and the effects on minors of playing violent video
games) may be very different from anything that we have seen
before. Any assessment of the experience of playing video games
must take into account certain characteristics of the video games
that are now on the market and those that are likely to be
available in the near future.
Today’s most advanced video games
create realistic alternative worlds in which millions of players
immerse themselves for hours on end. These games feature visual
imagery and sounds that are strikingly realistic, and in the near
future video-game graphics may be virtually indistinguishable from
actual video footage.[ Footnote
7 ] Many of the games already on the market can produce high
definition images,[ Footnote 8 ]
and it is predicted that it will not be long before video-game
images will be seen in three dimensions.[ Footnote 9 ] It is also forecast that video games will
soon provide sensory feedback.[ Footnote 10 ] By wearing a special vest or other device, a
player will be able to experience physical sensations supposedly
felt by a character on the screen.[ Footnote 11 ] Some amici who support respondents
foresee the day when “ ‘virtual-reality shoot-‘em-ups’ ”
will allow children to “ ‘actually feel the splatting blood
from the blown-off head’ ” of a victim. Brief for Reporters
Comm. for Freedom of the Press et al. as Amici Curiae 29
(quoting H. Schechter, Savage Pastimes 18 (2005)).
Persons who play video games also have an
unprecedented ability to participate in the events that take place
in the virtual worlds that these games create. Players can create
their own video-game characters and can use photos to produce
characters that closely resemble actual people. A person playing a
sophisticated game can make a multitude of choices and can thereby
alter the course of the action in the game. In addition, the means
by which players control the action in video games now bear a
closer relationship to the means by which people control action in
the real world. While the action in older games was often directed
with buttons or a joystick, players dictate the action in newer
games by engaging in the same motions that they desire a character
in the game to perform.[ Footnote
12 ] For example, a player who wants a video-game character to
swing a baseball bat—either to hit a ball or smash a skull—could
bring that about by simulating the motion of actually swinging a
bat.
These present-day and emerging characteristics
of video games must be considered together with characteristics of
the violent games that have already been marketed.
In some of these games, the violence is
astounding.[ Footnote 13 ]
Victims by the dozens are killed with every imaginable implement,
including machine guns, shotguns, clubs, hammers, axes, swords, and
chainsaws. Victims are dismembered, decapitated, disemboweled, set
on fire, and chopped into little pieces. They cry out in agony and
beg for mercy. Blood gushes, splatters, and pools. Severed body
parts and gobs of human remains are graphically shown. In some
games, points are awarded based, not only on the number of victims
killed, but on the killing technique employed.
It also appears that there is no antisocial
theme too base for some in the video-game industry to exploit.
There are games in which a player can take on the identity and
reenact the killings carried out by the perpetrators of the murders
at Columbine High School and Virginia Tech.[ Footnote 14 ] The objective of one game is to
rape a mother and her daughters;[ Footnote 15 ] in another, the goal is to rape Native
American women.[ Footnote 16 ]
There is a game in which players engage in “ethnic cleansing” and
can choose to gun down African-Americans, Latinos, or
Jews.[ Footnote 17 ] In still
another game, players attempt to fire a rifle shot into the head of
President Kennedy as his motorcade passes by the Texas School Book
Depository.[ Footnote 18 ]
If the technological characteristics of the
sophisticated games that are likely to be available in the near
future are combined with the characteristics of the most violent
games already marketed, the result will be games that allow
troubled teens to experience in an extraordinarily personal and
vivid way what it would be like to carry out unspeakable acts of
violence.
The Court is untroubled by this possibility.
According to the Court, the “interactive” nature of video games is
“nothing new” because “all literature is interactive.” Ante , at 10–11. Disagreeing with this assessment, the
International Game Developers Association (IGDA)—a group that
presumably understands the nature of video games and that supports
respondents—tells us that video games are “far more concretely
interactive.” Brief for IGDA et al. as Amici Curiae 3. And on this point, the game developers are surely correct.
It is certainly true, as the Court notes, that
“ ‘[l]it-erature, when it is successful draws the reader into
the story, makes him identify with the characters, invites him to
judge them and quarrel with them, to experience their joys and
sufferings as the reader’s own.’ ” Ante , at 11
(quoting American Amusement Machine Assn. v. Kendrick , 244 F. 3d 572, 577 (CA7 2001)). But only an
extraordinarily imaginative reader who reads a description of a
killing in a literary work will experience that event as vividly as
he might if he played the role of the killer in a video game. To
take an example, think of a person who reads the passage in Crime
and Punishment in which Raskolni- kov kills the old pawn broker
with an axe. See F. Dostoyevsky, Crime and Punishment 78 (Modern
Library ed. 1950). Compare that reader with a video-game player who
creates an avatar that bears his own image; who sees a realistic
image of the victim and the scene of the killing in high definition
and in three dimensions; who is forced to decide whether or not to
kill the victim and decides to do so; who then pretends to grasp an
axe, to raise it above the head of the victim, and then to bring it
down; who hears the thud of the axe hitting her head and her cry of
pain; who sees her split skull and feels the sensation of blood on
his face and hands. For most people, the two experiences will not
be the same.[ Footnote
19 ]
When all of the characteristics of video games
are taken into account, there is certainly a reasonable basis for
thinking that the experience of playing a video game may be quite
different from the experience of reading a book, listening to a
radio broadcast, or viewing a movie. And if this is so, then for at
least some minors, the effects of playing violent video games may
also be quite different. The Court acts prematurely in dismissing
this possibility out of hand.
* * *
For all these reasons, I would
hold only that the particular law at issue here fails to provide
the clear notice that the Constitution requires. I would not
squelch legislative efforts to deal with what is perceived by some
to be a significant and developing social problem. If differently
framed statutes are enacted by the States or by the Federal
Government, we can consider the constitutionality of those laws
when cases challenging them are presented to us. Footnote 1 It is well established that a judgment may be
affirmed on an alternative ground that was properly raised but not
addressed by the lower court. Washington v. Confederated Bands and Tribes of Yakima Nation , 439 U. S. 463 , 478,
n. 20 (1979). Footnote 2 Under the California law, a game that meets
the threshold requirement set out in text also qualifies as
“violent” if it “[e]nables the player to virtually inflict serious
injury upon images of human beings or characters with substantially
human characteristics in a manner which is especially heinous,
cruel, or depraved in that it involves torture or serious physical
abuse to the victim.” §1746(d)(1)(B). In the Court of Appeals,
California conceded that this alternative definition is
unconstitutional, 556 F. 3d 950, 954, n. 5 (CA9 2009),
and therefore only the requirements set out in text are now before
us. Footnote 3 The provision of New York law under which the
petitioner was convicted in Ginsberg was framed with
similar specificity. This provision applied to depictions of
“nudity” and “sexual conduct,” and both those terms were
specifically and unambiguously defined. See 390 U. S., at 645–647
(Appendix A to opinion of the Court). Footnote 4 The California law does not define the term
“maiming,” nor has the State cited any decisions from its courts
that define the term in this context. Accordingly, I take the term
to have its ordinary meaning, which includes the infliction of any
serious wound, see Webster’s Third New International Dictionary
1362 (2002) (hereinafter Webster’s). Footnote 5 At oral argument, California also proposed
that the term “minors” could be interpreted as referring to the
“typical age group of minors” who play video games. Tr. of Oral
Arg. 11. But nothing in the law’s text supports such a limitation.
Nor has California cited any decisions indicating that its courts
would restrict the law in this way. And there is nothing in the
record indicating what this age group might be. Footnote 6 A 2004 Federal Trade Commission Report showed
that 69 percent of unaccompanied children ages 13 to 16 were able
to buy M-rated games and that 56 percent of 13-year-olds were able
to buy an M-rated game. Marketing Violent Entertainment to
Children: A Fourth Follow-Up Review of Industry Practices in the
Motion Picture, Music Recording & Electronic Game Industries
26–28 (July 2004), http://www.ftc.gov/os/
2004/07/040708kidsviolencerpt.pdf (all Internet materials as
visited June 24, 2011, and available in Clerk of Court’s case
file). Footnote 7 See Chayka, Visual Games: Photorealism in
Crisis, Kill Screen (May 2011),
http://killscreendaily.com/articles/visual-games-photorealism-crisis. Footnote 8 To see brief video excerpts from games with
highly realistic graphics, see Spike TV Video Game Awards 2010—Game
of the Year Nominees, GameTrailers.com (Dec. 10, 2010),
http://www.gametrailers.com/
video/game-of-spike-tv-vga/707755?type=flv. Footnote 9 See Selleck, Sony PS3 Launching 50 3D-Capable
Video Games in the Near Future, SlashGear (Nov. 23, 2010),
http://www.slashgear.com/
sony-ps3-launching-50-3d-capable-video-games-in-the-near-future-23115866;
Sofge, Why 3D Doesn’t Work for TV, But Is Great for Gaming, Popu-
lar Mechanics (Mar. 11, 2010), http://www.popularmechanics.com/
technology/digital/gaming/4342437. Footnote 10 T. Chatfield, Fun Inc.: Why Games are the
Twenty-first Century’s Most Serious Business 211 (2010) (predicting
that “[w]e can expect … physical feedback and motion detection as
standard in every gaming device in the near future”); J. Blascovich
& J. Bailenson, Infinite Reality: Avatars, Eternal Life, New
Worlds, and the Dawn of the Virtual Revolution 2 (2011)
(“Technological developments powering virtual worlds are
accelerating, ensuring that virtual experiences will become more immersive by providing sensory information that makes
people feel they are ‘inside’ virtual worlds” (emphasis in the
original)). Footnote 11 See Topolsky, The Mindwire V5 Turns Gaming
into Pure Electroshock Torture, Engadget (Mar. 9, 2008),
http://www.engadget.com/
2008 / 03 / 09 / the - mindwire - v5 - turns - gaming - into - pure-electroshock-torture;
Greenemeier, Video Game Vest Simulates Sensation of Being Capped,
Scientific American (Oct. 25, 2007),
http://www.scientificamerican.com/
article.cfm?id=video-game-vest-simulates. Footnote 12 See Schiesel, A Real Threat Now Faces the
Nintendo Wii, N. Y. Times, Dec. 3, 2010, p. F7 (describing how
leading developers of video-game consoles are competing to deliver
gesture-controlled gaming devices). Footnote 13 For a sample of violent video games, see
Wilson, The 10 Most Violent Video Games of All Time, PCMag.com
(Feb. 10, 2011),
http://www.pcmag.com/article2/0,2817,2379959,00.asp. To see brief
video excerpts from violent games, see Chomik, Top 10: Most Violent
Video Games, AskMen.com, http://www.askmen.com/top_10/videogame/
top-10-most-violent-video-games.html; Sayed, 15 Most Violent Video
Games That Made You Puke, Gamingbolt (May 2, 2010), http://
gamingbolt.com/15-most-violent-video-games-that-made-you-puke. Footnote 14 Webley, “School Shooter” Video Game to
Reenact Columbine, Virginia Tech Killings, Time (Apr. 20, 2011),
http://newsfeed.time.com/
2011 / 04 / 20 / school - shooter - video - game - reenacts-columbine-virginia-tech-killings.
After a Web site that made School Shooter available for download
removed it in response to mounting criticism, the developer stated
that it may make the game available on its own Web site. Inside the
Sick Site of a School Shooter Mod (Mar. 26, 2011),
http://ssnat.com. Footnote 15 Lah, “RapeLay” Video Game Goes Viral Amid
Outrage, CNN (Mar. 30, 2010),
http://articles.cnn.com/2010-03-30/world/japan.video.
game.rape_1_game-teenage-girl-japanese-government?_s=PM:WORLD. Footnote 16 Graham, Custer May be Shot Down Again in a
Battle of the Sexes Over X-Rated Video Games, People, Nov. 15,
1982, pp. 110, 115. Footnote 17 Scheeres, Games Elevate Hate to Next Level,
Wired (Feb. 20, 2002),
http://www.wired.com/culture/lifestyle/news/2002/02/50523. Footnote 18 Thompson, A View to a Kill: JFK Reloaded is
Just Plain Creepy, Slate (Nov. 22, 2004),
http://www.slate.com/id/2110034. Footnote 19 As the Court notes, there are a few
children’s books that ask young readers to step into the shoes of a
character and to make choices that take the stories along one of a
very limited number of possible lines. See ante , at 10.
But the very nature of the print medium makes it impossible for a
book to offer anything like the same number of choices as those
provided by a video game. THOMAS, J., DISSENTING BROWN V. ENTERTAINMENT MERCHANTS ASSN. 564 U. S. ____ (2011) SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES NO. 08-1448 EDMUND G. BROWN, Jr., GOVERNOR OF CAL- IFORNIA,
et al., PETITIONERS v. ENTERTAIN- MENT MERCHANTS
ASSOCIATION et al.
on writ of certiorari to the united states court of
appeals for the ninth circuit
[June 27, 2011]
Justice Thomas, dissenting.
The Court’s decision today does
not comport with the original public understanding of the First
Amendment. The majority strikes down, as facially unconstitutional,
a state law that prohibits the direct sale or rental of certain
video games to minors because the law “abridg[es] the freedom of
speech.” U. S. Const., Amdt. 1. But I do not think the First
Amendment stretches that far. The practices and beliefs of the
founding generation establish that “the freedom of speech,” as
originally understood, does not include a right to speak to minors
(or a right of minors to access speech) without going through the
minors’ parents or guardians. I would hold that the law at issue is
not facially unconstitutional under the First Amendment, and
reverse and remand for further proceedings.[ Footnote 1 ]
I
When interpreting a
constitutional provision, “the goal is to discern the most likely
public understanding of [that] provision at the time it was
adopted.” McDonald v. Chicago , 561 U. S. ___, ___
(2010) (slip op., at 25) (Thomas, J., concurring in part and
concurring in judgment). Because the Constitution is a written
instrument, “its meaning does not alter.” McIntyre v. Ohio Elections Comm’n , 514 U. S. 334 , 359 (1995) (Thomas, J.,
concurring in judgment) (internal quotation marks omitted). “That
which it meant when adopted, it means now.” Ibid. (internal quotation marks omitted). As originally
understood, the First Amendment’s protection against laws
“abridging the freedom of speech” did not extend to all speech. “There are certain well-defined and narrowly limited
classes of speech, the prevention and punishment of which have
never been thought to raise any Constitutional problem.” Chaplinsky v. New Hampshire , 315 U. S. 568 , 571–572
(1942); see also United States v. Stevens , 559 U.
S. ___, ___ (2010) (slip op., at 5–6). Laws regulating such speech
do not “abridg[e] the freedom of speech” because such speech is
understood to fall outside “the freedom of speech.” See Ashcroft v. Free Speech Coalition , 535 U. S. 234 , 245–246
(2002). In my view, the “practices and
beliefs held by the Founders” reveal another category of excluded
speech: speech to minor children bypassing their parents. McIntyre , supra, at 360. The historical evidence
shows that the founding generation believed parents had absolute
authority over their minor children and expected parents to use
that authority to direct the proper development of their children.
It would be absurd to suggest that such a society understood “the
freedom of speech” to include a right to speak to minors (or a
corresponding right of minors to access speech) without going
through the minors’ parents. Cf. Brief for Common Sense Media as Amicus Curiae 12–15. The founding generation would not
have considered it an abridgment of “the freedom of speech” to
support parental authority by restricting speech that bypasses
minors’ parents. A Attitudes toward
children were in a state of transition around the time that the
States ratified the Bill of Rights. A complete understanding of the
founding generation’s views on children and the parent-child
relationship must therefore begin roughly a century earlier, in
colonial New England. In the Puritan
tradition common in the New England Colonies, fathers ruled
families with absolute authority. “The patriarchal family was the
basic building block of Puritan society.” S. Mintz, Huck’s Raft 13
(2004) (hereinafter Mintz); see also R. MacDonald, Literature for
Children in England and America from 1646 to 1774, p. 7 (1982)
(hereinafter MacDonald). The Puritans rejected many customs, such
as godparenthood, that they considered inconsistent with the
patriarchal structure. Mintz 13. Part of the father’s absolute
power was the right and duty “to fill his children’s minds with
knowledge and … make them apply their knowledge in right action.”
E. Morgan, The Puritan Family 97 (rev. ed. 1966) (herein-after
Morgan). Puritans thought children were “innately sinful and that
parents’ primary task was to suppress their children’s natural
depravity.” S. Mintz & S. Kellogg, Domestic Revolutions 2
(1988) (hereinafter Mintz & Kellogg); see also B. Wadsworth,
The Well-Ordered Family 55 (1712) (“Children should not be left to
themselves … to do as they please; … not being fit to govern
themselves”); C. Mather, A Family Well-Ordered 38 (1699).
Accordingly, parents were not to let their children read “vain
Books, profane Ballads, and filthy Songs” or “fond and amorous
Romances, … fabulous Histories of Giants, the bom- bast
Achievements of Knight Errantry, and the like.” The History of
Genesis, pp. vi–vii (3d ed. corrected 1708). This conception of parental
authority was reflected in laws at that time. In the Massachusetts
Colony, for example, it was unlawful for tavern keepers (or anyone
else) to entertain children without their parents’ consent. 2
Records and Files of the Quarterly Courts of Essex County,
Massachusetts, p. 180 (1912); 4 id., at 237, 275 (1914); 5 id., at 143 (1916); see also Morgan 146. And a “stubborn
or rebellious son” of 16 years or more committed a capital offense
if he disobeyed “the voice of his Father, or the voice of his
Mother.” The Laws and Liberties of Massachusetts 6 (1648) (reprint
M. Farrand ed. 1929); see also J. Kamensky, Governing the Tongue
102, n. 14 (1997) (citing similar laws in the Connecticut, New
Haven, Plymouth, and New Hampshire Colonies in the late
1600’s). B In the decades
leading up to and following the Revolution, attitudes towards
children changed. See, e.g., J. Reinier, From Virtue to
Character: American Childhood, 1775–1850, p. 1 (1996) (hereinafter
Reinier). Children came to be seen less as innately sinful and more
as blank slates requiring careful and deliberate development. But
the same overarching principles remained. Parents continued to have
both the right and duty to ensure the proper development of their
children. They exercised significant authority over their children,
including control over the books that children read. And laws at
the time continued to reflect strong support for parental author-
ity and the sense that children were not fit to govern
themselves. 1 The works of John
Locke and Jean-Jacques Rousseau were a driving force behind the
changed understanding of children and childhood. See Reinier 2–5;
H. Brewer, By Birth or Consent 97 (2005) (hereinafter Brewer); K.
Calvert, Children in the House 59–60 (1992) (hereinafter Calvert).
Locke taught that children’s minds were blank slates and that
parents therefore had to be careful and deliberate about what their
children were told and observed. Parents had only themselves to
blame if, “by hu-mouring and cockering” their children, they
“poison’d the fountain” and later “taste[d] the bitter waters.”
Some Thoughts Concerning Education (1692), in 37 English
Philosophers of the Seventeenth and Eighteenth Centuries 27–28 (C.
Eliot ed. 1910). All vices, he explained, were sowed by parents and
“those about children.” Id., at 29. Significantly, Locke
did not suggest circumscribing parental authority but rather
articulated a new basis for it. Rousseau disagreed with Locke in
important respects, but his philosophy was similarly premised on
parental control over a child’s development. Although Rousseau
advocated that children should be allowed to develop naturally, he
instructed that the environment be directed by “a tutor who is
given total control over the child and who removes him from
society, from all competing sources of authority and influence.” J.
Fliegelman, Prodigals and Pilgrims 30 (1982) (hereinafter
Fliegelman); see also Reinier 15. These writings
received considerable attention in America. Locke’s An Essay
Concerning Human Understanding and his Some Thoughts Concerning
Education were significantly more popular than his Two Treatises of
Government, according to a study of 92 colonial libraries between
1700 and 1776. Lundberg & May, The Enlightened Reader in
America, 28 American Quarterly 262, 273 (1976) (hereinafter
Lundberg). And Rousseau’s Emile, a treatise on education, was more
widely advertised and distributed than his political work, The
Social Contract. Fliegelman 29; see also Lundberg 285. In general,
the most popular books in the Colonies on the eve of the American
Revolution were not political discourses but ones concerned with
child rearing. See Mintz & Kellogg 45. 2 Locke’s and
Rousseau’s writings fostered a new conception of childhood.
Children were increasingly viewed as malleable creatures, and
childhood came to be seen as an important period of growth,
development, and preparation for adulthood. See Mintz & Kellogg
17, 21, 47; M. Grossberg, Governing the Hearth 8 (1985)
(hereinafter Grossberg). Noah Webster, called the father of
American education, wrote that “[t]he impressions received in early
life usually form the characters of individuals.” On the Education
of Youth in America (1790) (hereinafter Webster), in Essays on
Education in the Early Republic 43 (F. Rudolph ed. 1965)
(hereinafter Rudolph); cf. Slater, Noah Webster: Founding Father of
American Scholarship and Education, in Noah Webster’s First Edition
of an American Dictionary of the English Language (1967). Elizabeth
Smith, sister-in-law to John Adams, similarly wrote: “The Infant
Mind, I beleive[,] is a blank, that eassily receives any
impression.” M. Norton, Liberty’s Daughters 101 (1996) (internal
quotation marks omitted) (hereinafter Norton); see also S. Doggett,
A Discourse on Education (1796) (hereinafter Doggett), in Rudolph
151 (“[I]n early youth, … every power and capacity is pliable and
susceptible of any direction or impression”); J. Abbott, The Mother
at Home 2 (1834) (hereinafter Abbott) (“What impressions can be
more strong, and more lasting, than those received upon the mind in
the freshness and the susceptibility of youth”). Children lacked
reason and decisionmaking ability. They “have not Judgment or Will
of their own,” John Adams noted. Letter to James Sullivan (May 26,
1776), in 4 Papers of John Adams 210 (R. Taylor ed. 1979); see also
Vol. 1 1787: Drafting the Constitution, p. 229 (W. Benton ed. 1986)
(quoting Gouvernor Morris in James Madison’s notes from the
Constitutional Convention explaining that children do not vote
because they “want prudence” and “have no will of their own”).
Children’s “utter incapacity” rendered them “almost wholly at the
mercy of their Parents or Instructors for a set of habits to
regulate their whole conduct through life.” J. Burgh, Thoughts on
Education 7 (1749) (hereinafter Burgh). This conception of childhood
led to great concern about influences on children. “Youth are ever
learning to do what they see others around them doing, and these
imitations grow into habits.” Doggett, in Rudolph 151; see also B.
Rush, A Plan for the Establishment of Public Schools (1786)
(hereinafter Rush), in Rudolph 16 (“The vices of young people are
generally learned from each other”); Webster, in Rudolph 58
(“[C]hildren, artless and unsuspecting, resign their hearts to any
person whose manners are agreeable and whose conduct is
respectable”). Books therefore advised parents “not to put children
in the way of those whom you dare not trust.” L. Child, The
Mother’s Book 149 (1831) (hereinafter Child); see also S. Coontz,
The Social Origins of Private Life 149–150 (1988) (noting that it
was “considered dangerous to leave children to the supervision of
servants or apprentices”). As a result, it was widely
accepted that children needed close monitoring and carefully
planned development. See B. Wishy, The Child and the Republic
24–25, 32 (1968) (hereinafter Wishy); Grossberg 8. Managing the
young mind was considered “infinitely important.” Doggett, in
Rudolph 151; see also A. MacLeod, A Moral Tale 72–73 (1975)
(hereinafter MacLeod). In an essay on the education of youth in
America, Noah Webster described the human mind as “a rich field,
which, without constant care, will ever be covered with a luxuriant
growth of weeds.” Rudolph 54. He advocated sheltering children from
“every low-bred, drunken, immoral character” and keeping their
minds “untainted till their reasoning faculties have acquired
strength and the good principles which may be planted in their
minds have taken deep root.” Id., at 63; see also Rush, in id., at 16 (“[T]he most useful citizens have been formed
from those youth who have never known or felt their own wills till
they were one and twenty years of age”); Burgh 7 (“[T]he souls of
Youth are more immediately committed to the care of Parents and
Instructors than even those of a People are to their
Pastor”). The Revolution only amplified
these concerns. The Re-public would require virtuous citizens,
which necessi- tated proper training from childhood. See Mintz 54,
71; MacLeod 40; Saxton, French and American Childhoods, in Children
and Youth in a New Nation 69 (J. Marten ed. 2009) (hereinafter
Marten); see also W. Cardell, Story of Jack Halyard, pp. xv–xvi
(30th ed. 1834) (hereinafter Cardell) (“[T]he glory and efficacy of
our institutions will soon rest with those who are growing up to
succede us”). Children were “the pivot of the moral world,” and
their proper development was “a subject of as high interest, as any
to which the human mind ha[d] ever been called.” Id., at
xvi. 3 Based on these
views of childhood, the founding generation understood parents to
have a right and duty to govern their children’s growth. Parents
were expected to direct the development and education of their
children and ensure that bad habits did not take root. See Calvert
58–59; MacLeod 72; Mintz & Kellogg 23. They were responsible
for instilling “moral prohibitions, behavioral standards, and a
capacity for self-government that would prepare a child for the
outside world.” Mintz & Kellogg 58; see also Youth’s Companion,
Apr. 16, 1827, p. 1 (hereinafter Youth’s Companion) (“Let
[children’s] minds be formed, their hearts prepared, and their
characters moulded for the scenes and the duties of a brighter
day”). In short, “[h]ome and family bore the major responsibility
for the moral training of children and thus, by implication, for
the moral health of the nation.” MacLeod 29; see also Introduction,
in Marten 6; Reinier, p. xi; Smith, Autonomy and Affection: Parents
and Children in Eighteenth-Century Chesapeake Families, in Growing
up in America 54 (N. Hiner & J. Hawes eds. 1985). This conception
of parental rights and duties was exemplified by Thomas Jefferson’s
approach to raising children. He wrote letters to his daughters
constantly and often gave specific instructions about what the
children should do. See, e.g., Letter to Martha Jefferson
(Nov. 28, 1783), in S. Randolph, The Domestic Life of Thomas
Jefferson 44 (1939) (dictating her daily schedule of music,
dancing, drawing, and studying); Letter to Martha Jefferson (Dec.
22, 1783), in id., at 45–46 (“I do not wish you to be
gaily clothed at this time of life … . [A]bove all things and
at all times let your clothes be neat, whole, and properly put
on”). Jefferson expected his daughter, Martha, to write “by every
post” and instructed her, “Inform me what books you read [and] what
tunes you learn.” Letter (Nov. 28, 1783), in id., at 44.
He took the same approach with his nephew, Peter Carr, after Carr’s
father died. See Letter (Aug. 19, 1785), in 8 The Papers of Thomas
Jefferson 405–408 (J. Boyd ed. 1953) (detailing a course of reading
and exercise, and asking for monthly progress reports describing
“in what manner you employ every hour in the day”); see also 3
Dictionary of Virginia Biography 29 (2006). Jefferson’s rigorous
management of his charges was not uncommon. “[M]uch evidence
indicates that mothers and fathers both believed in giving their
children a strict upbringing, enforcing obedience to their commands
and stressing continued subjection to the parental will.” Norton
96. Two parenting books published in the 1830’s gave prototypical
advice. In The Mother’s Book, Lydia Child advised that “[t]he first
and most important step in management is, that whatever a mother
says, always must be done.” Child 26. John Abbott, the
author of The Mother at Home, likewise advised that “[o]bedience is
absolutely essential to proper family government.” Abbott 18.
Echoing Locke, Abbott warned that parents who indulged a child’s
“foolish and unreasonable wishes” would doom that child to be
indulgent in adulthood. Id., at 16. The concept of total parental
control over children’s lives extended into the schools. “The
government both of families and schools should be absolute,”
declared Noah Webster. Rudolph 57–58. Dr. Benjamin Rush concurred:
“In the education of youth, let the authority of our masters be as absolute as possible.” Id., at 16. Through the
doctrine of in loco parentis , teachers assumed the
“ ‘sacred dut[y] of parents … to train up and qualify their
children’ ” and exercised the same authority “ ‘to
command obedience, to control stubbornness, to quicken diligence,
and to reform bad habits.’ ” Morse v. Frederick , 551 U. S. 393 , 413–414
(2007) (Thomas, J., concurring) (quoting State v. Pendergrass , 19 N. C. 365, 365–366 (1837)); see also
Wishy 73. Thus, the quality of teachers and schools had to “be
watched with the most scrupulous attention.” Webster, in Rudolph
64. For their part, children were
expected to be dutiful and obedient. Mintz & Kellogg 53; Wishy
31; cf. J. Kett, Rites of Passage 45 (1977). Schoolbooks instructed
children to do so and frequently featured vignettes illustrating
the consequences of disobedience. See Adams, “Pictures of the
Vicious ultimately overcome by misery and shame”: The Cultural Work
of Early National Schoolbooks (hereinafter Adams), in Marten 156.
One oft-related example was the hangings of 19 alleged witches in
1692, which, the schoolbooks noted, likely began with false
complaints by two young girls. See J. Morse, The American Geography
191 (1789); see also Adams, in Marten 164. An entire genre of books,
“loosely termed ‘advice to youth,’ ” taught similar lessons
well into the 1800’s. J. Demos, Circles and Lines: The Shape of
Life in Early America 73 (2004); cf. Wishy 54. “Next to your duty
to God,” advised one book, “is your duty to your parents” even if
the child did not “understand the reason of their commands.” L.
Sigourney, The Girl’s Reading Book 44 (14th ed. 1843); see also
Filial Duty Recommended and Enforced, Introduction, p. iii (c.
1798); The Parent’s Present 44 (3d ed. 1841). “Disobedience is
generally punished in some way or other,” warned another, “and
often very severely.” S. Goodrich, Peter Parley’s Book of Fables 43
(1836); see also The Country School-House 27 (1848) (“[T]he number
of children who die from the effects of disobedience to their
parents is very large”). 4 Society’s concern with children’s development
extended to the books they read. “Vice always spreads by being
published,” Noah Webster observed. Rudolph 62. “[Y]oung people are
taught many vices by fiction, books, or pub- lic exhibitions, vices
which they never would have known had they never read such books or
attended such pub- lic places.” Ibid.; see also Cardell,
p. xii (cautioning parents that “[t]he first reading lessons for
children have an extensive influence on the acquisitions and habits
of future years”); Youth’s Companion 1 (“[T]he capacities of
children, and the peculiar situation and duties of youth, require
select and appropriate reading”). Prominent children’s authors
harshly criticized fairy tales and the use of anthropomorphic
animals. See, e.g., S. Goodrich, 2 Recollections of a
Lifetime 320, n.* (1856) (describing fairy tales as “calculated to
familiarize the mind with things shocking and monstrous; to
cultivate a taste for tales of bloodshed and violence; to teach the
young to use coarse language, and cherish vulgar ideas; … and to
fill [the youthful mind] with the horrors of a debased and
debauched fancy”); 1 id., at 167 (recalling that
children’s books were “full of nonsense” and “lies”); Cardell, p.
xiv (“The fancy of converting inferior animals into ‘teachers of
children,’ has been carried to ridiculous extravagance”); see also
MacDonald 83, 103 (noting that fables and works of fantasy were not
popular in America in the 1700’s). Adults carefully controlled what they
published for children. Stories written for children were dedicated
to moral instruction and were relatively austere, lacking details
that might titillate children’s minds. See MacLeod 24–25, 42–48;
see also id., at 42 (“The authors of juvenile fiction
imposed the constraints upon themselves in the name of duty, and
for the sake of giving children what they thought children should
have, although they were often well aware that children might
prefer more excit- ing fare”); Francis, American Children’s
Literature, 1646–1880, in American Childhood 208–209 (J. Hawes
& N. Hiner eds. 1985). John Newbery, the publisher often
credited with creating the genre of children’s literature, removed
traditional folk characters, like Tom Thumb, from their original
stories and placed them in new morality tales in which good
children were rewarded and disobedient children punished. Reinier
12 . Parents had total
authority over what their children read. See A. MacLeod, American
Childhood 177 (1994) (“Ideally, if not always actually,
nineteenth-century parents regulated their children’s lives fully,
certainly including their reading”). Lydia Child put it bluntly in
The Mother’s Book: “Children … should not read anything without a
mother’s knowledge and sanction; this is particularly necessary
between the ages of twelve and sixteen.” Child 92; see also id., at 143 (“[P]arents, or some guardian friends, should
carefully examine every volume they put into the hands of young
people”); E. Monaghan, Learning to Read and Write in Colonial
America 337 (2005) (reviewing a 12-year-old girl’s journal from the
early 1770’s and noting that the child’s aunts monitored and guided
her reading). 5 The
law at the time reflected the founding generation’s understanding
of parent-child relations. According to Sir William Blackstone,
parents were responsible for maintaining, protecting, and education
their children, and therefore had “power” over their children. 1
Commentaries on the Laws of England 434, 440 (1765); cf. Washington v. Glucksberg , 521 U. S. 702 , 712
(1997) (Blackstone’s Commentaries was “a primary legal authority
for 18th- and 19th-century American lawyers”). Chancellor James
Kent agreed. 2 Commentaries on American Law *189–*207. The law
entitled parents to “the custody of their [children],” “the value
of th[e] [children’s] labor and services,” and the “right to the
exercise of such discipline as may be requisite for the discharge
of their sacred trust.” Id., at *193, *203. Children, in
turn, were charged with “obedience and assistance during their own
minority, and gratitude and reverance during the rest of their
lives.” Id., at *207. Thus,
in case after case, courts made clear that parents had a right to
the child’s labor and services until the child reached majority. In
1810, the Supreme Judicial Court of Massachusetts explained, “There
is no question but that a father, who is entitled to the services
of his minor son, and for whom he is obliged to provide, may, at
the common law, assign those services to others, for a
consideration to enure to himself.” Day v. Everett, 7 Mass. 145, 147; see also Benson v. Remington , 2 Mass. 113, 115 (1806) (opinion of Parsons,
C. J.) (“The law is very well settled, that parents are under
obligations to support their children, and that they are entitled
to their earnings”). Similarly, the Supreme Court of Judicature of
New Hampshire noted that the right of parents to recover for the
services of their child, while a minor, “cannot be contested.” Gale v. Parrot , 1 N. H. 28, 29 (1817). And
parents could bring tort suits against those who knowingly enticed
a minor away from them. See, e.g., Kirkpatrick v. Lockhart , 2 Brev. 276 (S. C. Constitutional Ct.
1809); Jones v. Tevis , 4 Litt. 25 (Ky. App.
1823). Relatedly, boys
could not enlist in the military without parental consent. Many of
those who did so during the Revolutionary War found, afterwards,
that their fathers were entitled to their military wages. See Cox,
Boy Soldiers of the American Revolution, in Marten 21–24. And after
the war, minors who enlisted without parental consent in violation
of federal law could find themselves returned home on writs of
habeas corpus issued at their parents’ request. See, e.g., United States v. Anderson , 24 F. Cas. 813 (No.
14,449) (CC Tenn. 1812); Commonwealth v. Callan ,
6 Binn. 255 (Pa. 1814) (per curiam) . Laws also set age
limits restricting marriage without parental consent. For example,
from 1730 until at least 1849, Pennsylvania law required parental
consent for the marriage of anyone under the age of 21. See 4
Statutes at Large of Pennsylvania 153 (J. Mitchell & H.
Flanders eds. 1897) (hereinafter Pa. Stats. at Large); General Laws
of Pennsylvania 82–83 (J. Dunlop 2d ed. 1849) (including the 1730
marriage law with no amendments); see also Perpetual Laws of the
Commonwealth of Massachusetts 253 (1788), in The First Laws of the
Commonwealth of Massachusetts (J. Cushing ed. 1981). In general,
“[p]ost-Revolutionary marriage law assumed that below a certain
age, children could … no[t] intellectually understand its
significance.” Grossberg 105. Indeed, the law
imposed age limits on all manner of activities that required
judgment and reason. Children could not vote, could not serve on
juries, and generally could not be witnesses in criminal cases
unless they were older than 14. See Brewer 43, 145, 148, 159. Nor
could they swear loyalty to a State. See, e.g., 9 Pa.
Stats. at Large 111 (1903 ed.). Early federal laws granting aliens
the ability to become citizens provided that those under 21 were
deemed citizens if their fathers chose to naturalize. See, e.g., Act of Mar. 26, 1790, 1 Stat. 104; Act of Jan. 29,
1795, ch. 20, 1 Stat. 415. C The
history clearly shows a founding generation that believed parents
to have complete authority over their minor children and expected
parents to direct the development of those children. The Puritan
tradition in New England laid the foundation of American parental
authority and duty. See MacDonald 6 (“The Puritans are virtually
the inventors of the family as we know it today”). In the decades
leading up to and following the Revolution, the conception of the
child’s mind evolved but the duty and authority of parents
remained. Indeed, society paid closer attention to potential
influences on children than before. See Mintz 72 (“By weakening
earlier forms of patriarchal authority, the Revolution enhanced the
importance of childrearing and education in ensuring social
stability”). Teachers and schools came under scrutiny, and
children’s reading material was carefully supervised. Laws
reflected these concerns and often supported parental authority
with the coercive power of the state. II A In
light of this history, the Framers could not possibly have
understood “the freedom of speech” to include an unqualified right
to speak to minors. Specifically, I am sure that the founding
generation would not have understood “the freedom of speech” to
include a right to speak to children without going through their
parents. As a consequence, I do not believe that laws limiting such
speech—for example, by requiring parental consent to speak to a
minor—“abridg[e] the freedom of speech” within the original meaning
of the First Amendment. We
have recently noted that this Court does not have “freewheeling
authority to declare new categories of speech outside the scope of
the First Amendment.” Stevens , 559 U. S., at ___ (slip
op., at 9). But we also recognized that there may be “some
categories of speech that have been historically unprotected [and]
have not yet been specifically identified or discussed as such in
our case law.” Ibid. In my opinion, the historical
evidence here plainly reveals one such category.[ Footnote 2 ] B Admittedly, the original public understanding
of a constitutional provision does not always comport with modern
sensibilities. See Morse , 551 U. S., at 419 (Thomas, J.,
concurring) (treating students “as though it were still the 19th
century would find little support today”). It may also be
inconsistent with precedent. See McDonald , 561 U. S., at
___–___ (Thomas, J., concurring in part and concurring in judgment)
(slip op., at 48– 52) (rejecting the Slaughter-House
Cases , 16 Wall. 36 (1873), as inconsistent with the original
public meaning of the Privileges or Immunities Clause of the
Fourteenth Amendment). This,
however, is not such a case. Although much has changed in this
country since the Revolution, the notion that parents have
authority over their children and that the law can support that
authority persists today. For example, at least some States make it
a crime to lure or entice a minor away from the minor’s parent.
See, e.g., Cal. Penal Code Ann. §272(b)(1) (West 2008);
Fla. Stat. §787.03 (2010). Every State in the Union still
establishes a minimum age for marriage without parental or judicial
consent. Cf. Roper v. Simmons , 543 U. S. 551 , 558
(Appendix D to opinion of Court) (2005). Individuals less than 18
years old cannot enlist in the military without parental consent.
10 U. S. C. §505(a). And minors remain subject to curfew laws
across the country, see Brief for Louisiana et al. as Amici Curiae 16, and cannot unilaterally consent to most
medical procedures, id., at 15. Moreover, there
are many things minors today cannot do at all, whether they have
parental consent or not. State laws set minimum ages for voting and
jury duty. See Roper , supra, at 581–585
(Appendixes B and C to opinion of Court). In California (the State
at issue here), minors cannot drive for hire or drive a school bus,
Cal. Veh. Code Ann. §§12515, 12516 (West 2010), purchase tobacco,
Cal. Penal Code Ann. §308(b) (West 2008), play bingo for money,
§326.5(e), or execute a will, Cal. Probate Code Ann. §6220 (West
2009). My understanding
of “the freedom of speech” is also consistent with this Court’s
precedents. To be sure, the Court has held that children are
entitled to the protection of the First Amendment, see, e.g., Erznoznik v. Jacksonville , 422 U. S. 205 ,
212–213 (1975), and the government may not unilaterally dictate
what children can say or hear, see id., at 213–214; Tinker v. Des Moines Independent Community School
Dist. , 393 U.
S. 503 , 511 (1969). But this Court has never held, until today,
that “the freedom of speech” includes a right to speak to minors
(or a right of minors to access speech) without going through the
minors’ parents. To the contrary, “[i]t is well settled that a
State or municipality can adopt more stringent controls on
communicative materials available to youths than on those available
to adults.” Erznoznik , supra, at 212; cf. post , at 3 (Breyer, J., dissenting). The Court’s
constitutional jurisprudence “historically has reflected Western
civilization concepts of the family as a unit with broad parental
authority over minor children.” Parham v. J. R. , 442 U. S. 584 , 602
(1979). Under that case law, “legislature[s] [can] properly
conclude that parents and others, teachers for example, who have …
primary responsibility for children’s well-being are entitled to
the support of laws designed to aid discharge of that
responsibility.” Ginsberg v. New York , 390 U. S. 629 , 639
(1968); see also Bellotti v. Baird , 443 U. S. 622 , 635
(1979) (opinion of Powell, J.) (“[T]he State is entitled to adjust
its legal system to account for children’s vulnerability and their
needs for concern, … sympathy, and … paternal attention” (internal
quotation marks omitted)). This is because “the tradition of
parental authority is not inconsistent with our tradition of
individual liberty; rather, the former is one of the basic
presuppositions of the latter.” Id., at 638; id. ,
at 638–639 (“Legal restrictions on minors, especially those
supportive of the parental role, may be important to the child’s
chances for the full growth and maturity that make eventual
participation in a free society meaningful and
rewarding”). III The
California law at issue here prohibits the sale or rental of
“violent video game[s]” to minors, defined as anyone “under 18
years of age.” Cal. Civ. Code Ann. §§1746.1(a), 1746 (West 2009). A
violation of the law is punishable by a civil fine of up to $1,000.
§1746.3. Critically, the law does not prohibit adults from buying
or renting violent video games for a minor or prohibit minors from
playing such games. Cf. ante , at 10 (Alito, J., concurring
in judgment); post , at 10 (Breyer, J., dissenting). The
law also does not restrict a “minor’s parent, grandparent, aunt,
uncle, or legal guardian” from selling or renting him a violent
video game. §1746.1(c). Respondents, associations of companies in the
video game industry, brought a preenforcement challenge to
California’s law, claiming that on its face the law violates the
free speech rights of their members. The Court holds that video
games are speech for purposes of the First Amendment and finds the
statute facially unconstitutional. See ante , at 2–3,
11–17. I disagree. Under any of this
Court’s standards for a facial First Amendment challenge, this one
must fail. The video game associations cannot show “that no set of
circumstances exists under which [the law] would be valid,” “that
the statute lacks any plainly legitimate sweep,” or that “a
substantial number of its applications are unconstitutional, judged
in relation to the statute’s plainly legitimate sweep.” Stevens , 559 U. S., at ___ (slip op., at 10) (internal
quotation marks omitted). Even assuming that video games are
speech, in most applications the California law does not implicate
the First Amendment. All that the law does is prohibit the direct
sale or rental of a violent video game to a minor by someone other
than the minor’s parent, grandparent, aunt, uncle, or legal
guardian. Where a minor has a parent or guardian, as is usually
true, the law does not prevent that minor from obtaining a violent
video game with his parent’s or guardian’s help. In the typical
case, the only speech affected is speech that bypasses a minor’s
parent or guardian. Because such speech does not fall within “the
freedom of speech” as originally understood, California’s law does
not ordinarily implicate the First Amendment and is not facially
unconstitutional.[ Footnote
3 ] * * * “The
freedom of speech,” as originally understood, does not include a
right to speak to minors without going through the minors’ parents
or guardians. Therefore, I cannot agree that the statute at issue
is facially unconstitutional under the First
Amendment. I
respectfully dissent. Footnote 1 Justice Alito
concludes that the law is too vague to satisfy due process, but
neither the District Court nor the Court of Appeals addressed that
question. Ante , at 2–9 (opinion concurring in judgment).
As we have often said, this Court is “one of final review, ‘not of
first view.’ ” FCC v. Fox Television Stations,
Inc. , 556 U. S. ___, ___ (2009) (slip op., at 25) (quoting Cutter v. Wilkinson , 544 U. S. 709 , 718,
n. 7 (2005)). Footnote 2 The majority
responds that “it does not follow” from the historical evidence
“that the state has the power to prevent children from hearing …
anything without their parents’ prior consent .” Ante , at 7, n. 3. Such a conclusion, the majority
asserts, would lead to laws that, in its view, would be undesirable
and “obviously” unconstitutional. Ibid. The majority’s
circular argument misses the point. The question is not whether
certain laws might make sense to judges or legislators today, but
rather what the public likely understood “the freedom of speech” to
mean when the First Amendment was adopted. See District of
Columbia v. Heller , 554 U. S. 570 , 634–635
(2008). I believe it is clear that the founding public would not
have understood “the freedom of speech” to include speech to minor
children bypassing their parents. It follows that the First
Amendment imposes no restriction on state regulation of such
speech. To note that there may not be “precedent for [such] state
control,” ante , at 8, n. 3, “is not to establish that
[there] is a constitutional right,” McIntyre v. Ohio
Elections Comm’n , 514 U. S. 334 , 373 (1995) (Scalia, J.,
dissenting). Footnote 3 Whether the
statute would survive an as-applied challenge in the unusual case
of an emancipated minor is a question for another day. To decide
this case, it is enough that the statute is not unconstitutional on
its face. BREYER, J., DISSENTING BROWN V. ENTERTAINMENT MERCHANTS ASSN. 564 U. S. ____ (2011) SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES NO. 08-1448 EDMUND G. BROWN, Jr., GOVERNOR OF CAL- IFORNIA,
et al., PETITIONERS v. ENTERTAIN- MENT MERCHANTS
ASSOCIATION et al.
on writ of certiorari to the united states court of
appeals for the ninth circuit
[June 27, 2011]
Justice Breyer, dissenting.
California imposes a civil fine
of up to $1,000 upon any person who distributes a violent video
game in California without labeling it “18,” or who sells or rents
a labeled violent video game to a person under the age of 18. Rep-
resentatives of the video game and software industries, claiming
that the statute violates the First Amendment on its face, seek an
injunction against its enforcement. Applying traditional First
Amendment analysis, I would uphold the statute as constitutional on
its face and would consequently reject the industries’ facial
challenge.
I
A
California’s statute defines a
violent video game as: A game in which a player “kill[s], maim[s],
dismember[s], or sexually assault[s] an image of a human
being,” and “[a] reasonable person, considering the game as
a whole, would find [the game] appeals to a deviant or morbid
interest of minors,” and “[the game] is patently offensive to prevailing
standards in the community as to what is suitable for
minors,” and “the game, as a whole, … lack[s] serious
literary, artistic, political, or scientific value for minors.”
Cal. Civ. Code Ann. §1746(d)(1) (West 2009). The statute in effect forbids the sale of such
a game to minors unless they are accompanied by a parent; it
requires the makers of the game to affix a label identifying it as
a game suitable only for those aged 18 and over; it exempts
retailers from liability unless such a label is properly affixed to
the game; and it imposes a civil fine of up to $1,000 upon a
violator. See §§1746.1–1746.3. B A facial challenge to this
statute based on the First Amendment can succeed only if “a
substantial number of its applications are unconstitutional, judged
in relation to the statute’s plainly legitimate sweep.” United
States v. Stevens , 559 U. S. __, __ (2010) (slip op.,
at 10) (internal quotation marks omitted) . Moreover, it is
more difficult to mount a facial First Amendment attack on a
statute that seeks to regulate activity that involves action as
well as speech. See Broadrick v. Oklahoma , 413 U. S. 601 ,
614–615 (1973). Hence, I shall focus here upon an area within which
I believe the State can legitimately apply its statute, namely
sales to minors under the age of 17 (the age cutoff used by the
industry’s own ratings system), of highly realistic violent video
games, which a reasonable game maker would know meet the Act’s
criteria. That area lies at the heart of the statute. I shall
assume that the number of instances in which the State will enforce
the statute within that area is comparatively large, and that the
number outside that area (for example, sales to 17-year-olds) is
comparatively small. And the activity the statute regulates
combines speech with action (a virtual form of target
practice).
C
In determining whether the
statute is unconstitutional, I would apply both this Court’s
“vagueness” precedents and a strict form of First Amendment
scrutiny. In doing so, the special First Amendment category I find
relevant is not (as the Court claims) the category of “depictions
of violence,” ante , at 8, but rather the category of
“protection of children.” This Court has held that the “power of
the state to control the conduct of children reaches beyond the
scope of its authority over adults.” Prince v. Massachusetts , 321 U. S. 158 , 170
(1944). And the “ ‘regulatio[n] of communication addressed to
[children] need not conform to the requirements of the [F]irst
[A]mendment in the same way as those applicable to adults.’ ” Ginsberg v. New York , 390 U. S. 629 , 638, n. 6
(1968) (quoting Emerson, Toward a General Theory of the First
Amendment, 72 Yale L. J. 877, 939 (1963)).
The majority’s claim that the
California statute, if upheld, would create a “new categor[y] of
unprotected speech,” ante , at 3, 6, is overstated. No one
here argues that depictions of violence, even extreme violence, automatically fall outside the First Amendment’s
protective scope as, for example, do obscenity and depictions of
child pornography. We properly speak of categories of
expression that lack protection when, like “child pornography,” the
category is broad, when it applies automatically, and when the
State can prohibit everyone, including adults, from obtaining
access to the material within it. But where, as here, careful
analysis must precede a narrower judicial conclusion (say, denying
protection to a shout of “fire” in a crowded theater, or to an
effort to teach a terrorist group how to peacefully petition the
United Nations), we do not normally describe the result as creating
a “new category of unprotected speech.” See Schenck v. United States , 249 U. S. 47 , 52 (1919); Holder v. Humanitarian Law Project , 561 U. S. __
(2010).
Thus, in Stevens, after rejecting the
claim that all de-pictions of animal cruelty (a category)
fall outside the First Amendment’s protective scope, we went on to
decide whether the particular statute at issue violates the First
Amendment under traditional standards; and we held that, because
the statute was overly broad, it was invalid. Similarly, here the
issue is whether, applying traditional First Amendment standards,
this statute does, or does not, pass muster.
II
In my view, California’s statute
provides “fair notice of what is prohibited,” and consequently it
is not impermissibly vague. United States v. Williams , 553 U. S. 285 , 304
(2008). Ginsberg explains why that is so. The Court there
considered a New York law that forbade the sale to minors of a
“picture, photograph, drawing, sculpture, motion
picture film, or similar visual representation or image of a person
or portion of the human body which depicts nudity . . . ,” that “predominately appeals to the prurient,
shameful or morbid interest of minors,” and “is patently offensive to prevailing standards
in the adult community as a whole with respect to what is suitable
material for minors,” and “is utterly without redeeming social importance
for minors.” 390 U. S., at 646–647. This Court upheld the New York statute in
Ginsberg (which is sometimes unfortunately confused with a
very different, earlier case, Ginzburg v. United
States , 383 U.
S. 463 (1966)). The five-Justice majority, in an opinion
written by Justice Brennan, wrote that the statute was suf-
ficiently clear. 390 U. S., at 643–645. No Member of the Court
voiced any vagueness objection. See id. , at 648–650
(Stewart, J., concurring in result); id. , at 650–671
(Douglas, J., joined by Black, J., dissenting); id. , at
671–675 (Fortas, J., dissenting).
Comparing the language of California’s statute
(set forth supra , at 1–2) with the language of New York’s
statute (set forth immediately above), it is difficult to find any
vagueness-related difference. Why are the words “kill,” “maim,” and
“dismember” any more difficult to understand than the word
“nudity?” Justice Alito objects that these words do “not perform
the narrowing function” that this Court has required in adult
obscenity cases, where statutes can only cover “ ‘hard
core’ ” depictions. Ante , at 6 (opinion concurring in
judgment). But the relevant comparison is not to adult obscenity
cases but to Ginsberg , which dealt with “nudity,” a
category no more “narrow” than killing and maiming. And in any
event, narrowness and vagueness do not
necessarily have anything to do with one another. All that is
required for vagueness purposes is that the terms “kill,” “maim,”
and “dismember” give fair notice as to what they cover, which they
do.
The remainder of California’s definition
copies, almost word for word, the language this Court used in Miller v. California , 413 U. S. 15 (1973), in
permitting a total ban on material that satisfied its
definition (one enforced with criminal penalties). The
California law’s reliance on “community standards” adheres to Miller , and in Fort Wayne Books, Inc. v. Indiana , 489
U. S. 46 , 57–58 (1989) , this Court specifically upheld
the use of Miller’ s language against charges of vagueness.
California only departed from the Miller formulation in
two significant respects: It substituted the word “deviant” for the
words “prurient” and “shameful,” and it three times added the words
“for minors.” The word “deviant” differs from “prurient” and
“shameful,” but it would seem no less suited to defining and
narrowing the reach of the statute. And the addition of “for
minors” to a version of the Miller standard was approved
in Ginsberg , 390 U. S., at 643, even though the New York
law “dr[ew] no distinction between young children and adolescents
who are nearing the age of majority,” ante , at 8 (opinion
of Alito, J.).
Both the Miller standard and the law
upheld in Ginsberg lack perfect clarity. But that fact
reflects the dif- ficulty of the Court’s long search for words
capable of protecting expression without depriving the State of a
legitimate constitutional power to regulate. As is well known, at
one point Justice Stewart thought he could do no better in defining
obscenity than, “I know it when I see it.” Jacobellis v. Ohio , 378
U. S. 184 , 197 (1964) (concurring opinion). And Justice Douglas
dissented from Miller ’s standard, which he thought was
still too vague. 413 U. S., at 39–40. Ultimately, however, this
Court accepted the “community standards” tests used in Miller and Ginsberg . They reflect the fact that
sometimes, even when a precise standard proves elusive, it is easy
enough to identify instances that fall within a legitimate
regulation. And they seek to draw a line, which, while favoring
free expression, will nonetheless permit a legislature to find the
words necessary to accomplish a legitimate constitutional
objective. Cf. Williams , supra , at 304 (the
Constitution does not always require “ ‘perfect clarity and
precise guidance,’ ” even when “ ‘expressive
activity’ ” is involved).
What, then, is the difference between Ginsberg and Miller on the one hand and the
California law on the other? It will often be easy to pick out
cases at which California’s statute directly aims, involving, say,
a character who shoots out a police officer’s knee, douses him with
gasoline, lights him on fire, urinates on his burning body, and
finally kills him with a gunshot to the head. (Foot- age of one
such game sequence has been submitted in the record.) See also ante , at 14–15 (Alito, J., concurring in judgment). As in Miller and Ginsberg , the California law clearly protects even the most violent games that possess serious
literary, artistic, political, or scientific value.
§1746(d)(1)(A)(iii). And it is easier here than in Miller or Ginsberg to separate the sheep from the goats at the
statute’s border. That is because here the industry it- self has
promulgated standards and created a review process, in which adults
who “typically have experience with children” assess what games are
inappropriate for minors. See Entertainment Software Rating Board,
Rating Process, online at http://www.esrb.org/ratings/&ratings_
process.jsp (all Internet materials as visited June 24, 2011, and
available in Clerk of Court’s case file).
There is, of course, one obvious difference:
The Ginsberg statute concerned depictions of “nudity,”
while California’s statute concerns extremely violent video games.
But for purposes of vagueness, why should that matter? Justice
Alito argues that the Miller standard sufficed because
there are “certain generally accepted norms concerning expression
related to sex,” whereas there are no similarly “accepted standards
regarding the suitability of violent entertainment.” Ante ,
at 7–8. But there is no evidence that is so. The Court relied on
“community standards” in Miller precisely because of the
difficulty of articulating “accepted norms” about depictions of
sex. I can find no difference—historical or otherwise—that is relevant to the vagueness question. Indeed, the majority’s
examples of literary descriptions of violence, on which Justice
Alito relies, do not show anything relevant at all.
After all, one can find in literature as many
(if not more) descriptions of physical love as descriptions of
violence. Indeed, sex “has been a theme in art and literature
throughout the ages.” Ashcroft v. Free Speech
Coalition , 535
U. S. 234 , 246 (2002) . For every Homer, there is a
Titian. For every Dante, there is an Ovid. And for all the
teenagers who have read the original versions of Grimm’s Fairy
Tales, I suspect there are those who know the story of Lady
Godiva.
Thus, I can find no meaningful
vagueness-related dif-ferences between California’s law and the New
York law upheld in Ginsberg . And if there remain any
vagueness problems, the state courts can cure them through
interpretation. See Erznoznik v. Jacksonville , 422 U. S. 205 ,
216 (1975) (“[S]tate statute should not be deemed facially invalid
unless it is not readily subject to a narrowing construction by the
state courts”). Cf. Ginsberg , supra , at 644
(relying on the fact that New York Court of Appeals would read a
knowledge requirement into the statute); Berry v. Santa Barbara , 40 Cal. App. 4th 1075, 1088–1089, 47 Cal.
Rptr. 2d 661, 669 (1995) (reading a knowledge requirement into a
statute). Consequently, for purposes of this facial challenge, I
would not find the statute unconstitutionally vague.
III
Video games combine physical
action with expression. Were physical activity to predominate in a
game, government could appropriately intervene, say by requiring
parents to accompany children when playing a game in-volving actual
target practice, or restricting the sale of toys presenting
physical dangers to children. See generally Consumer Product Safety
Improvement Act of 2008, 122 Stat. 3016 (“Title I—Children’s
Product Safety”). But because video games also embody important
expressive and artistic elements, I agree with the Court that the
First Amendment significantly limits the State’s power to regulate.
And I would determine whether the State has exceeded those limits
by applying a strict standard of review.
Like the majority, I believe that
the California law must be “narrowly tailored” to further a
“compelling interest,” without there being a “less restrictive”
alternative that would be “at least as effective.” Reno v. American Civil Liberties Union , 521 U. S. 844 , 874, 875,
879 (1997). I would not apply this strict standard “mechanically.” United States v. Playboy Entertainment Group,
Inc. , 529 U. S.
803 , 841 (2000) (Breyer, J., joined by Rehnquist, C. J.,
and O’Connor and Scalia, JJ., dissenting). Rather, in applying it,
I would evaluate the degree to which the statute injures
speech-related interests, the nature of the potentially-justifying
“compelling interests,” the degree to which the statute furthers
that interest, the nature and effectiveness of possible
alternatives, and, in light of this evaluation, whether, overall,
“the statute works speech-related harm . . . out of proportion to
the benefits that the statute seeks to provide.” Ibid. See
also Burson v. Freeman , 504 U. S. 191 , 210
(1992) (plurality opinion) (applying strict scrutiny and finding
relevant the lack of a “significant impingement” on speech).
First Amendment standards applied in this way
are difficult but not impossible to satisfy. Applying “strict
scrutiny” the Court has upheld restrictions on speech that, for
example, ban the teaching of peaceful dispute resolution to a group
on the State Department’s list of terrorist organizations, Holder , 561 U. S., at ___ (slip op., at 22–34); but cf. id. , at ___ (slip op., at 1 ) (Breyer, J.,
dissenting), and limit speech near polling places, Burson , supra , at 210–211 (plurality opinion). And applying less
clearly defined but still rigorous standards, the Court has allowed
States to require disclosure of petition signers, Doe v. Reed , 561 U. S. ___ (2010), and to impose campaign
contribution limits that were “ ‘closely drawn’ to match a
‘sufficiently important interest,’ ” Nixon v. Shrink Missouri Government PAC , 528 U. S. 377 , 387–388
(2000).
Moreover, although the Court did not specify
the “level of scrutiny” it applied in Ginsberg , we have
subsequently described that case as finding a “compelling interest”
in protecting children from harm sufficient to justify limitations
on speech. See Sable Communications of Cal., Inc. v. FCC , 492 U.
S. 115 , 126 (1989). Since the Court in Ginsberg specified that the statute’s prohibition applied to material that
was not obscene, 390 U. S., at 634, I cannot dismiss Ginsberg on the ground that it concerned obscenity. But
cf. ante , at 6 (majority opinion). Nor need I depend upon
the fact that the Court in Ginsberg insisted only that the
legislature have a “rational” basis for finding the depictions
there at issue harmful to children. 390 U. S., at 639. For in this
case, California has substan-tiated its claim of harm with
considerably stronger evidence.
A
California’s law imposes no more
than a modest restriction on expression. The statute prevents no
one from playing a video game, it prevents no adult from buying a
video game, and it prevents no child or adolescent from obtaining a
game provided a parent is willing to help. §1746.1(c). All it
prevents is a child or adolescent from buying, without a parent’s
assistance, a gruesomely violent video game of a kind that the
industry itself tells us it wants to keep out of the hands
of those under the age of 17. See Brief for Respondents 8.
Nor is the statute, if upheld,
likely to create a prece- dent that would adversely affect other
media, say films, or videos, or books. A typical video game
involves a significant amount of physical activity. See ante , at 13–14 (Alito, J., concurring in judgment) (citing
examples of the increasing interactivity of video game
controllers). And pushing buttons that achieve an interactive,
virtual form of target practice (using images of human beings as
targets), while containing an expressive component, is not just
like watching a typical movie. See infra , at 14.
B
The interest that California
advances in support of the statute is compelling. As this Court has
previously described that interest, it consists of both (1) the
“basic” parental claim “to authority in their own household to
direct the rearing of their children,” which makes it proper to
enact “laws designed to aid discharge of [parental]
responsibility,” and (2) the State’s “independent interest in the
well-being of its youth.” Ginsberg , 390 U. S., at 639–640.
Cf. id. , at 639, n. 7 (“ ‘[O]ne can well distinguish
laws which do not impose a morality on children, but which support
the right of parents to deal with the morals of their children as
they see fit’ ” (quoting Henkin, Morals and the Constitution:
The Sin of Obscenity, 63 Colum. L. Rev. 391, 413, n. 68 (1963))).
And where these interests work in tandem, it is not fatally
“underinclusive” for a State to advance its interests in protecting
children against the special harms present in an interactive video
game medium through a default rule that still allows parents to
provide their children with what their parents wish.
Both interests are present here.
As to the need to help parents guide their children, the Court
noted in 1968 that “ ‘parental control or guidance cannot
always be provided.’ ” 390 U. S., at 640. Today, 5.3 million
grade-school-age children of working parents are routinely home
alone. See Dept. of Commerce, Census Bureau, Who’s Minding the
Kids? Child Care Arrangements: Spring 2005/Summer 2006, p. 12
(2010), online at http:// www.census.gov/prod/2010pubs/p70-121.pdf.
Thus, it has, if anything, become more important to supplement
parents’ authority to guide their children’s development.
As to the State’s independent interest, we
have pointed out that juveniles are more likely to show a
“ ‘lack of maturity’ ” and are “more vulnerable or
susceptible to negative influences and outside pressures,” and that
their “character . . . is not as well formed as that of an adult.” Roper v. Simmons , 543 U. S. 551 , 569–570
(2005). And we have therefore recognized “a compelling interest in
protecting the physical and psychological well-being of minors.” Sable Communications , supra , at 126.
At the same time, there is considerable
evidence that California’s statute significantly furthers this
compelling interest. That is, in part, because video games are
excellent teaching tools. Learning a practical task often means
developing habits, becoming accustomed to performing the task, and
receiving positive reinforcement when performing that task well.
Video games can help develop habits, accustom the player to
performance of the task, and reward the player for performing that
task well. Why else would the Armed Forces incorporate video games
into its training? See CNN, War Games: Military Train- ing Goes
High-Tech (Nov. 22, 2001), online at
http://articles.cnn.com / 2001–11–2 / tech /2war.games_1_ict-
bill-swartout-real-world-training?_s=PM:TECH.
When the military uses video games to help
soldiers train for missions, it is using this medium for a
beneficial purpose. But California argues that when the teaching
features of video games are put to less desirable ends, harm can
ensue. In particular, extremely violent games can harm children by
rewarding them for being violently aggressive in play, and thereby
often teaching them to be violently aggressive in life. And video
games can cause more harm in this respect than can typically
passive media, such as books or films or television programs.
There are many scientific studies that support
California’s views. Social scientists, for example, have found causal evidence that playing these games results in harm.
Longitudinal studies, which measure changes over time, have found
that increased exposure to violent video games causes an increase
in aggression over the same period. See Möller & Krahé,
Exposure to Violent Video Games and Aggression in German
Adolescents: A Longitudinal Analysis, 35 Aggressive Behavior 75
(2009); Gentile & Gentile, Violent Video Games as Exemplary
Teachers: A Conceptual Analysis, 37 J. Youth & Adolescence 127
(2008); Anderson et al., Longitudinal Effects of Violent Video
Games on Aggression in Japan and the United States, 122 Pediatrics
e1067 (2008); Wallenius & Punamäki, Digital Game Violence and
Direct Aggression in Adolescence: A Longitudinal Study of the Roles
of Sex, Age, and Parent-Child Communication, 29 J. Applied
Developmental Psychology 286 (2008).
Experimental studies in laboratories have
found that subjects randomly assigned to play a violent video game
subsequently displayed more characteristics of aggression than
those who played nonviolent games. See, e.g. , Anderson
et al., Violent Video Games: Specific Effects of Violent
Content on Aggressive Thoughts and Behavior, 36 Advances in
Experimental Soc. Psychology 199 (2004).
Surveys of 8th and 9th grade students have
found a correlation between playing violent video games and
aggression. See, e.g. , Gentile, Lynch, Linder, &
Walsh, The Effects of Violent Video Game Habits On Adolescent
Hostility, Aggressive Behaviors, and School Performance, 27 J.
Adolescence 5 (2004).
Cutting-edge neuroscience has shown that
“virtual violence in video game playing results in those neural
patterns that are considered characteristic for aggressive
cognition and behavior.” Weber, Ritterfeld, & Mathiak, Does
Playing Violent Video Games Induce Aggression? Empirical Evidence
of a Functional Magnetic Resonance Imaging Study, 8 Media
Psychology 39, 51 (2006).
And “meta-analyses,” i.e. , studies of
all the studies, have concluded that exposure to violent video
games “was positively associated with aggressive behavior,
aggressive cognition, and aggressive affect,” and that “playing
violent video games is a causal risk factor for long-term
harmful outcomes.” Anderson et al., Violent Video Game Effects
on Aggression, Empathy, and Prosocial Behavior in Eastern and
Western Countries: A Meta-Analytic Review, 136 Psychological
Bulletin 151, 167, 169 (2010) (emphasis added).
Some of these studies take care to explain in
a common- sense way why video games are potentially more harmful
than, say, films or books or television. In essence, they say that
the closer a child’s behavior comes, not to watching, but to acting out horrific violence, the greater the potential
psychological harm. See Bushman & Huesmann, Aggression, in 2
Handbook of Social Pscyhology 833, 851 (S. Fiske, D. Gilbert, &
G. Lindzey eds., 5th ed. 2010) (video games stimulate more
aggression because “[p]eople learn better when they are actively
involved,” players are “more likely to identify with violent
characters,” and “violent games directly reward violent behavior”);
Polman, de Castro, & van Aken, Experimental Study of the
Differential Effects of Playing Versus Watching Violent Video Games
on Children’s Aggressive Behavior, 34 Aggressive Behavior 256
(2008) (finding greater aggression resulting from playing, as
opposed to watching, a violent game); C. Anderson, D. Gentile,
& K. Buckley, Violent Video Game Effects on Children and
Adolescents 136–137 (2007) (three studies finding greater effects
from games as opposed to television). See also infra , at
15–16 (statements of expert public health associations agreeing
that interactive games can be more harmful than “passive” media
like television); ante , at 12–17 (Alito, J., concurring in
judgment).
Experts debate the conclusions of all these
studies. Like many, perhaps most, studies of human behavior, each
study has its critics, and some of those critics have produced
studies of their own in which they reach different conclusions. (I
list both sets of research in the appendixes.) I, like most judges,
lack the social science expertise to say definitively who is right.
But associations of public health professionals who do possess that
expertise have reviewed many of these studies and found a
significant risk that violent video games, when compared with more
passive media, are particularly likely to cause children harm.
Eleven years ago, for example, the American
Academy of Pediatrics, the American Academy of Child &
Adolescent Psychiatry, the American Psychological Association, the
American Medical Association, the American Academy of Family
Physicians, and the American Psychiatric Association released a
joint statement, which said:
“[O]ver 1000 studies . . . point overwhelmingly to
a causal connection between media violence and aggressive behavior
in some children . . . [and, though less research had been done at
that time, preliminary studies indicated that] the impact of
violent interactive entertainment (video games and other
interactive media) on young people . . . may be significantly
more severe than that wrought by television, movies, or
music.” Joint Statement on the Impact of Entertainment Violence on
Children (2000) (emphasis added), online at
http://www.aap.org/advocacy/releases/jstmtevc.htm.
Five years later, after more
research had been done, the American Psychological Association
adopted a resolution that said:
“[C]omprehensive analysis of violent interactive
video game research suggests such exposure . . . increases
aggressive behavior, . . . increases aggressive thoughts, . . .
increases angry feelings, . . . decreases helpful behavior, and . .
. increases physio- logical arousal.” Resolution on Violence in
Video Games and Interactive Media (2005), online at
http:// www.apa.org / about / governance / council / policy/
interactive-media.pdf.
The Association added:
“[T]he practice, repetition, and rewards for acts
of violence may be more conducive to increasing aggressive
behavior among children and youth than passively watching violence
on TV and in films.” Ibid. (emphasis added).
Four years after that, in 2009, the American
Academy of Pediatrics issued a statement in significant part about
interactive media. It said:
“Studies of these rapidly growing and
ever-more-sophisticated types of media have indicated that the
effects of child-initiated virtual violence may be even more
profound than those of passive media such as television. In
many games the child or teenager is ‘embedded’ in the game and uses
a ‘joystick’ (handheld controller) that enhances both the
experience and the aggressive feelings.” Policy Statement—Media
Violence, 124 Pediatrics 1495, 1498 (2009) (emphasis added).
It added:
“Correlational and experimental studies have
revealed that violent video games lead to increases in aggressive
behavior and aggressive thinking and decreases in prosocial
behavior. Recent longitudinal studies . . . have revealed that in
as little as 3 months, high exposure to violent video games
increased physical aggression. Other recent longitudinal studies .
. . have revealed similar effects across 2 years.” Ibid. (footnotes omitted).
Unlike the majority, I would find
sufficient grounds in these studies and expert opinions for this
Court to defer to an elected legislature’s conclusion that the
video games in question are particularly likely to harm children.
This Court has always thought it owed an elected legislature some
degree of deference in respect to legislative facts of this kind,
particularly when they involve technical matters that are beyond
our competence, and even in First Amendment cases. See Holder , 561 U. S., at ___ (slip op., at 28–29) (deferring,
while applying strict scrutiny, to the Government’s national
security judgments); Turner Broadcasting System, Inc. v. FCC , 520 U.
S. 180 , 195–196 (1997) (deferring, while applying intermediate
scrutiny, to the Government’s technological judgments). The
majority, in reaching its own, opposite conclusion about the
validity of the relevant studies, grants the legislature no
deference at all. Compare ante , at 12–13 (stating that the
studies do not provide evidence that violent video games “cause”
harm (emphasis deleted)), with supra , at 12–13 (citing
longitudinal studies finding causation).
C
I can find no “less restrictive”
alternative to California’s law that would be “at least as
effective.” See Reno , 521 U. S., at 874. The majority
points to a voluntary alternative: The industry tries to prevent
those under 17 from buying extremely violent games by labeling
those games with an “M” (Mature) and encouraging retailers to
restrict their sales to those 17 and older. See ante , at
15–16. But this voluntary system has serious enforcement gaps. When
California enacted its law, a Federal Trade Commission (FTC) study
had found that nearly 70% of unaccompanied 13- to 16-year-olds were
able to buy M-rated video games. FTC, Marketing Violent
Entertainment to Children 27 (2004), online at
http://www.ftc.gov/os/2004/ 07/040708kidsviolencerpt.pdf.
Subsequently the volun- tary program has become more effective. But
as of the FTC’s most recent update to Congress, 20% of those under
17 are still able to buy M-rated video games, and, breaking down
sales by store, one finds that this num- ber rises to nearly 50% in
the case of one large national chain. FTC, Marketing Violent
Entertainment to Chil- dren 28 (2009), online at
http://www.ftc.gov/os/2009/12/ P994511violententertainment.pdf. And
the industry could easily revert back to the substantial
noncompliance that existed in 2004, particularly after today’s
broad ruling reduces the industry’s incentive to police itself.
The industry also argues for an
alternative technological solution, namely “filtering at the
console level.” Brief for Respondents 53. But it takes only a quick
search of the Internet to find guides explaining how to circum-
vent any such technological controls. YouTube viewers, for example,
have watched one of those guides (called “How to bypass parental
controls on the Xbox 360”) more than 47,000 times. See
http://www.youtube.com/watch?v= CFlVfVmvN6k.
IV
The upshot is that California’s
statute, as applied to its heartland of applications
( i.e., buyers under 17; extremely violent, realistic video
games), imposes a restriction on speech that is modest at most.
That restriction is justified by a compelling interest
(supplementing parents’ efforts to prevent their children from
purchasing potentially harmful violent, interactive material). And
there is no equally effective, less restrictive alternative.
California’s statute is consequently constitutional on its
face—though litigants remain free to challenge the statute as
applied in particular instances, including any effort by the State
to apply it to minors aged 17.
I add that the majority’s
different conclusion creates a serious anomaly in First Amendment
law. Ginsberg makes clear that a State can prohibit the
sale to minors of depictions of nudity; today the Court makes clear
that a State cannot prohibit the sale to minors of the most violent
interactive video games. But what sense does it make to forbid
selling to a 13-year-old boy a magazine with an image of a nude
woman, while protecting a sale to that 13-year-old of an
interactive video game in which he actively, but virtually, binds
and gags the woman, then tortures and kills her? What kind of First
Amendment would permit the government to protect children by
restrict- ing sales of that extremely violent video game only when the woman—bound, gagged, tortured, and killed—is
also topless?
This anomaly is not compelled by the First
Amendment. It disappears once one recognizes that extreme violence,
where interactive, and without literary, artistic, or similar
justification , can prove at least as, if not more, harmful to
children as photographs of nudity. And the record here is more than
adequate to support such a view. That is why I believe that Ginsberg controls the outcome here a fortiori. And it is why I believe California’s law is constitutional on its
face.
This case is ultimately less about censorship
than it is about education. Our Constitution cannot succeed in
securing the liberties it seeks to protect unless we can raise
future generations committed cooperatively to making our system of
government work. Education, however, is about choices. Sometimes,
children need to learn by making choices for themselves. Other
times, choices are made for children—by their parents, by their
teachers, and by the people acting democratically through their
governments. In my view, the First Amendment does not disable
government from helping parents make such a choice here—a choice
not to have their children buy extremely violent, interactive video
games, which they more than reasonably fear pose only the risk of
harm to those children.
For these reasons, I respectfully dissent.
APPENDIXES
With the assistance of the
Supreme Court Library, I have compiled these two appendixes listing
peer-reviewed academic journal articles on the topic of
psychological harm resulting from playing violent video games. The
library conducted a search for relevant articles on the following
databases: PsycINFO, PubMed, Academic Search Premier, ArticleFirst
(OCLC), and Dialog (files 1, 7, 34, 98, 121, 142, 144, 149). The
following search terms were used: “(video* or computer or arcade or
online) and (game*) and (attack* or fight* or aggress* or violen*
or hostil* or ang* or arous* or prosocial or help* or desens* or
empathy).” After eliminating irrelevant matches based on title or
abstract, I categorized these articles as either supporting the
hypothesis that violent video games are harmful (listed in Appendix
A), or not supporting/rejecting the hypothesis that violent video
games are harmful (listed in Appendix B).
Many, but not all, of these
articles were available to the California Legislature or the
parties in briefing this case. I list them because they suggest
that there is substantial (though controverted) evidence supporting
the expert associations of public health professionals that have
concluded that violent video games can cause children
psychological harm. See supra , at 15–16. And consequently,
these studies help to substantiate the validity of the original
judgment of the California Legislature, as well as that judgment’s
continuing validity.
A
Anderson & Bushman, Effects of Violent Video
Games on Aggressive Behavior, Aggressive Cognition, Aggressive
Affect, Physiological Arousal, and Prosocial Behavior: A
Meta-Analytic Review of the Scientific Literature, 12 Psychological
Science: J. Am. Psychological Society 353 (2001).
Anderson & Dill, Video Games and Aggressive
Thoughts, Feelings, & Behavior in the Laboratory and in Life,
78 J. Personality & Soc. Psychology 772 (2000).
Anderson et al., Violent Video Games: Specific Effects of
Violent Content on Aggressive Thoughts and Behavior, 36 Advances in
Experimental Soc. Psychology 199 (2004).
Anderson & Ford, Affect of the Game Player: Short-Term
Effects of Highly and Mildly Aggressive Video Games, 12 Personality
& Soc. Psychology Bull. 390 (1986).
Anderson & Morrow, Competitive Aggression Without
Interaction: Effects of Competitive Versus Cooperative Instructions
on Aggressive Behavior in Video Games, 21 Personality & Soc.
Psychology Bull. 1020 (1995).
Anderson et al., Longitudinal Effects of Violent Video
Games on Aggression in Japan and the United States, 122 Pediatrics
e1067 (2008).
Anderson et al., Violent Video Game Effects on Aggression,
Empathy, and Prosocial Behavior in Eastern and Western Countries: A
Meta-Analytic Review, 136 Psychological Bull. 151 (2010).
Anderson, An Update on the Effects of Playing Violent Video
Games, 27 J. Adolescence 113 (2004).
Anderson et al., The Influence of Media Violence on Youth,
4 Psychological Science in the Public Interest 81 (2003).
Anderson & Carnagey, Causal Effects of Violent Sports Video
Games on Aggression: Is it Competitiveness or Violent Content? 45
J. Experimental Soc. Psychology 731 (2009).
Anderson & Murphy, Violent Video Games and Aggressive
Behavior in Young Women, 29 Aggressive Behavior 423 (2003).
Arriaga, Esteves, Carneiro, & Monteiro, Violent Computer
Games and Their Effects on State Hostility and Physiological
Arousal, 32 Aggressive Behavior 358 (2006).
Arriaga, Esteves, Carneiro, & Monteiro, Are the Effects of
Unreal Violent Video Games Pronounced When Playing With a Virtual
Reality System? 34 Aggressive Behavior 521 (2008).
Baldaro et al., Aggressive and Non-Violent Videogames:
Short-Term Psychological and Cardiovascular Effects on Habitual
Players, 20 Stress & Health: J. Int’l Society for Investigation
of Stress 203 (2004).
Ballard, Hamby, Panee, & Nivens, Repeated Exposure to Video
Game Play Results in Decreased Blood Pressure Responding, 8 Media
Psychology 323 (2006).
Ballard & Lineberger, Video Game Violence and Confederate
Gender: Effects on Reward and Punishment Given by College Males, 41
Sex Roles 541 (1999).
Ballard & Wiest, Mortal Kombat (tm): The Effects of Violent
Videogame Play on Males’ Hostility and Cardiovascular Responding,
26 J. Applied Soc. Psychology 717 (1996).
Barlett, Branch, Rodeheffer, & Harris, How Long do the
Short-Term Violent Video Game Effects Last? 35 Aggressive Behavior
225 (2009).
Barlett, Rodeheffer, Baldassaro, Hinkin, & Harris, The
Effect of Advances in Video Game Technology and Content on
Aggressive Cognitions, Hostility, and Heart Rate, 11 Media
Psychology 540 (2008).
Barlett, Harris, & Baldassaro, Longer You Play, the More
Hostile You Feel: Examination of First Person Shooter Video Games
and Aggression During Video Game Play, 33 Aggressive Behavior 486
(2007).
Barlett, Harris, & Bruey, The Effect of the Amount of Blood
in a Violent Video Game on Aggression, Hostility, and Arousal, 44
J. Experimental Soc. Psychology 539 (2008).
Barlett & Rodeheffer, Effects of Realism on Extended Violent
and Nonviolent Video Game Play on Aggressive Thoughts, Feelings,
and Physiological Arousal, 35 Aggressive Behavior 213 (2009).
Barlett, Anderson, & Swing, Video Game Effects—Confirmed,
Suspected, and Speculative: A Review of the Evidence, 40 Simulation
& Gaming 377 (2009).
Bartholow, Sestir, & Davis, Correlates and Consequences of
Exposure to Video Game Violence: Hostile Personality, Empathy, and
Aggressive Behavior, 31 Personality & Soc. Psychology Bull.
1573 (2005).
Bartholow & Anderson, Effects of Violent Video Games on
Aggressive Behavior: Potential Sex Differences, 38 J. Experimental
Soc. Psychology 283 (2002).
Bartholow, Bushman, & Sestir, Chronic Violent Video Game
Exposure and Desensitization to Violence: Behavioral and
Event-Related Brain Potential Data, 42 J. Experimental Soc.
Psychology 532 (2006).
Bluemke, Friedrich, & Zumbach, The Influence of Violent and
Nonviolent Computer Games on Implicit Measures of Aggressiveness,
36 Aggressive Behavior 1 (2010).
Brady & Matthews, Effects of Media Violence on
Health-Related Outcomes Among Young Men, 160 Archives of Pediatrics
& Adolescent Med. 341 (2006).
Browne & Hamilton-Giachritsis, The Influence of Violent
Media on Children and Adolescents: A Public-Health Approach, 365
Lancet 702 (2005).
Bushman & Anderson, Violent Video Games and Hostile
Expectations: A Test of the General Aggression Model, 28
Personality & Soc. Psychology Bull. 1679 (2002).
Bushman & Anderson, Comfortably Numb: Desensitizing Effects
of Violent Media on Helping Others, 20 Psychological Science: J.
Am. Psychological Society 273 (2009).
Bushman, Rothstein, & Anderson, Much Ado About Something:
Violent Video Game Effects and a School of Red Herring: Reply to
Ferguson and Kilburn, 136 Psychological Bull. 182 (2010).
Calvert & Tan, Impact of Virtual Reality on Young Adults’
Physiological Arousal and Aggressive Thoughts: Interaction Versus
Observation, 15 J. Applied Developmental Psychology 125 (1994).
Carnagey, Anderson, & Bartholow, Media Violence and Social
Neuroscience: New Questions and New Opportunities, 16 Current
Directions in Psychological Science 178 (2007).
Carnagey & Anderson, Violent Video Game Exposure and
Aggression: A Literature Review, 45 Minerva Psichiatrica 1
(2004).
Carnagey & Anderson, The Effects of Reward and Punishment in
Violent Video Games on Aggressive Affect, Cognition, and Behavior,
16 Psychological Science: J. Am. Psychological Society 882
(2005).
Carnagey, Anderson, & Bushman, The Effect of Video Game
Violence on Physiological Desensitization to Real-life Violence, 43
J. Experimental Soc. Psychology 489 (2007).
Chambers & Ascione, The Effects of Prosocial and Aggressive
Videogames on Children’s Donating and Helping, 148 J. Genetic
Psychology: Research and Theory on Human Development 499
(1987).
Chory & Cicchirillo, The Relationship Between Video Game
Play and Trait Verbal Aggressiveness: An Application of the General
Aggression Model, 24 Communications Research Reports 113
(2007).
Cicchirillo & Chory-Assad, Effects of Affective Orientation
and Video Game Play on Aggressive Thoughts and Behaviors, 49 J.
Broadcasting & Electronic Media 435 (2005).
Colwell & Payne, Negative Correlates of Computer Game Play
in Adolescents, 91 British J. Psychology 295 (2000).
Cooper & Mackie, Video Games and Aggression in Children, 16
J. Applied Soc. Psychology 726 (1986).
Deselms & Altman, Immediate and Prolonged Effects of
Videogame Violence, 33 J. Applied Soc. Psychology 1553 (2003).
Dill & Dill, Video Game Violence: A Review of the Empirical
Literature, 3 Aggression & Violent Behavior 407 (1998).
Do&dsign;an, Video Games and Children: Violence in Video
Games, 44 Yeni Symposium 161 (2006).
Eastin, Video Game Violence and the Female Game Player: Self-
and Opponent Gender Effects on Presence and Aggressive Thoughts, 32
Human Communication Research 351 (2006).
Emes, Is Mr Pac Man Eating Our Children? A Review of the Effect
of Video Games on Children, 42 Canadian J. Psychiatry 409
(1997).
Farrar, Krcmar, & Nowak, Contextual Features of Violent
Video Games, Mental Models, and Aggression, 56 J. Communication 387
(2006).
Fischer, Kastenmüller, & Greitemeyer, Media Violence and the
Self: The Impact of Personalized Gaming Characters in Aggressive
Video Games on Aggressive Behavior, 46 J. Experimental Soc.
Psychology 192 (2010).
Funk, Children’s Exposure to Violent Video Games and
Desensitization to Violence, 14 Child & Adolescent Psychiatric
Clinics North Am. 387 (2005).
Funk, Video Games, 16 Adolescent Med. Clinics 395 (2005).
Funk, Baldacci, Pasold, & Baumgardner, Violence Exposure in
Real-Life, Video Games, Television, Movies, and the Internet: Is
There Desensitization? 27 J. Adolescence 23 (2004).
Funk, Buchman, Jenks, & Bechtoldt, Playing Violent Video
Games, Desensitization, and Moral Evaluation in Children, 24 J.
Applied Developmental Psychology 413 (2003).
Funk et al., Aggression and Psychopathology in Adolescents
with a Preference for Violent Electronic Games, 28 Aggressive
Behavior 134 (2002).
Funk, Buchman, Jenks, & Bechtoldt, An Evidence-Based
Approach to Examining the Impact of Playing Violent Video and
Computer Games, SIMILE: Studies in Media & Information Literacy
Educ., vol. 2, no. 4, p. 1 (Nov. 2002).
Gentile & Stone, Violent Video Game Effects on Children and
Adolescents: A Review of the Literature, 57 Minerva Pediatrica 337
(2005).
Gentile et al., The Effects of Prosocial Video Games on
Prosocial Behaviors: International Evidence From Correlational,
Longitudinal, and Experimental Studies, 35 Personality & Soc.
Psychology Bull. 752 (2009).
Gentile, Lynch, Linder, & Walsh, The Effects of Violent
Video Game Habits on Adolescent Hostility, Aggressive Behaviors,
and School Performance, 27 J. Adolescence 5 (2004).
Gentile & Gentile, Violent Video Games as Exemplary
Teachers: A Conceptual Analysis, 37 J. Youth & Adolescence 127
(2008).
Giumetti & Markey, Violent Video Games and Anger as
Predictors of Aggression, 41 J. Research in Personality 1234
(2007).
Graybill, Kirsch, & Esselman, Effects of Playing Violent
Versus Nonviolent Video Games on the Aggressive Ideation of
Aggressive and Nonaggressive Children, 15 Child Study J. 199
(1985).
Grigoryan, Stepanyan, Stepanyan, & Agababyan, Influence of
Aggressive Computer Games on the Brain Cortex Activity Level in
Adolescents, 33 Human Physiology 34 (2007).
Hastings et al., Young Children’s Video/Computer Game Use:
Relations With School Performance and Behavior, 30 Issues in Mental
Health Nursing 638 (2009).
Huesmann, Nailing the Coffin Shut on Doubts That Violent Video
Games Stimulate Aggression: Comment on Anderson et al., 136
Psychological Bull. 179 (2010).
Huesmann, The Impact of Electronic Media Violence: Scientific
Theory and Research, 41 J. Adolescent Health S6 (2007).
Huesmann & Taylor, The Role of Media Violence in Violent
Behavior, 27 Annual Rev. Public Health 393 (2006).
Hummer et al., Short-Term Violent Video Game Play by
Adolescents Alters Prefrontal Activity During Cognitive Inhibition,
13 Media Psychology 136 (2010).
Irwin & Gross, Cognitive Temp, Violent Video Games, and
Aggressive Behavior in Young Boys, 10 J. Family Violence 337
(1995).
Kirsh & Mounts, Violent Video Game Play impacts Facial
Emotion Recognition, 33 Aggressive Behavior 353 (2007).
Kirsh, Mounts, & Olczak, Violent Media Consumption and the
Recognition of Dynamic Facial Expressions, 21 J. Interpersonal
Violence 571 (2006).
Kirsh, Olczak, & Mounts, Violent Video Games Induce an
Affect Processing Bias, 7 Media Psychology 239 (2005).
Kirsh, The Effects of Violent Video Games on Adolescents: The
Overlooked Influence of Development, 8 Aggression & Violent
Behavior 377 (2003).
Kirsh, Seeing the World Through Mortal Kombat-Colored Glasses:
Violent Video Games and the Development of a Short-term Hostile
Attribution Bias, 5 Childhood 177 (1998).
Konijn, Bijvank, & Bushman, I Wish I Were a Warrior: The
Role of Wishful Identification in the Effects of Violent Video
Games on Aggression in Adolescent Boys, 43 Developmental Psychology
1038 (2007).
Krahé & Möller, Playing Violent Electronic Games, Hostile
Attributional Style, and Aggression-related Norms in German
Adolescents, 27 J. Adolescence 53 (2004).
Krcmar, Farrar, & McGloin, The Effects of Video Game Realism
on Attention, Retention and Aggressive Outcomes, 27 Computers in
Human Behavior 432 (2011).
Krcmar & Lachlan, Aggressive Outcomes and Videogame Play:
The Role of Length of Play and the Mechanisms at Work, 12 Media
Psychology 249 (2009).
Krcmar & Farrar, Retaliatory Aggression and the Effects of
Point of View and Blood in Violent Video Games, 12 Mass
Communication & Society 115 (2009).
Kronenberger et al., Media Violence Exposure in Aggressive and
Control Adolescents: Differences in Self- and Parent-Reported
Exposure to Violence on Television and in Video Games, 31
Aggressive Behavior 201 (2005).
Kronenberger et al., Media Violence Exposure and Executive
Functioning in Aggressive and Control Adolescents, 61 J. Clinical
Psychology 725 (2005).
Kuntsche, Hostility Among Adolescents in Switzerland?
Multivariate Relations Between Excessive Media Use and Forms of
Violence, 34 J. Adolescent Health 230 (2004).
Lee, Peng, & Klein, Will the Experience of Playing a Violent
Role in a Video Game Influence People’s Judgments of Violent
Crimes? 26 Computers in Human Behavior 1019 (2010).
Lemmens & Bushman, The Appeal of Violent Video Games to
Lower Educated Aggressive Adolescent Boys From Two Countries, 9
CyberPsychology & Behavior 638 (2006).
Mathiak & Weber, Toward Brain Correlates of Natural
Behavior: fMRI During VIolent Video Games, 27 Human Brain Mapping
948 (2006).
Möller & Krahé, Exposure to Violent Video Games and
Aggression in German Adolescents: A Longitudinal Analysis, 35
Aggressive Behavior 75 (2009).
Nowak, Krcmar, & Farrar, The Causes and Consequences of
Presence: Considering the Influence of Violent Video Games on
Presence and Aggression, 17 Presence: Teleoperators & Virtual
Environments 256 (2008).
Olson et al., M-Rated Video Games and Aggressive or Problem
Behavior Among Young Adolescents, 13 Applied Developmental Science
188 (2009).
Panee & Ballard, High Versus Low Aggressive Priming During
Video-Game Training: Effects on Violent Action During Game Play,
Hostility, Heart Rate, and Blood Pressure, 32 J. Applied Soc.
Psychology 2458 (2002).
Persky & Blascovich, Immersive Virtual Environments Versus
Traditional Platforms: Effects of Violent and Nonviolent Video Game
Play, 10 Media Psychology 135 (2007).
Persky & Blascovich, Immersive Virtual Video Game Play and
Presence: Influences on Aggressive Feelings and Behavior, 17
Presence: Teleoperators & Virtual Environments 57 (2008).
Polman, de Castro, & van Aken, Experimental Study of the
Differential Effects of Playing Versus Watching Violent Video Games
on Children’s Aggressive Behavior, 34 Aggressive Behavior 256
(2008).
Potera, Sex and Violence in the Media Influence Teen Behavior:
Three Studies Show a Correlation, 109 American J. Nursing 20
(2009).
Richmond & Wilson, Are Graphic Media Violence, Aggression,
and Moral Disengagement Related? 15 Psychiatry, Psychology &
Law 350 (2008).
Schaefer & Harrison, The Effects of Violent Fantasy on
Children’s Aggressive Behavior, 41 Psychology & Educ. 35
(2004).
Schmierbach, “Killing Spree”: Exploring the Connection Between
Competitive Game Play and Aggressive Cognition, 37 Communication
Research 256 (2010).
Sheese & Graziano, Deciding to Defect: The Effects of
Video-Game Violence on Cooperative Behavior, 16 Psychological
Science: J. Am. Psychological Society 354 (2005).
Sherry, The Effects of Violent Video Games on Aggression. A
Meta-Analysis, 27 Human Communication Research 409 (2001).
Shibuya, Sakamoto, Ihori, & Yukawa, The Effects of the
Presence and Contexts of Video Game Violence on Children: A
Longitudinal Study in Japan, 39 Simulation & Gaming 528
(2008).
Sigurdsson, Gudjonsson, Bragason, Kristjansdottir, &
Sigfusdottir, The Role of Violent Cognition in the Relationship
Between Personality and the Involvement in Violent Films and
Computer Games, 41 Personality & Individual Differences 381
(2006).
Silvern & Williamson, The Effects of Video Game Play on
Young Children’s Aggression, Fantasy, and Prosocial behavior, 8 J.
Applied Developmental Psychology 453 (1987).
Slater, Henry, Swaim, & Cardador, Vulnerable Teens,
Vulnerable Times: How Sensation Seeking, Alienation, and
Victimization Moderate the Violent Media Content—Aggressiveness
Relation, 31 Communication Research 642 (2004).
Slater, Henry, Swaim, & Anderson, Violent Media Content and
Aggressiveness in Adolescents: A Downward Spiral Model, 30
Communication Research 713 (2003).
Staude-Müller, Bliesener, & Luthman, Hostile and Hardened?
An Experimental Study on (De-)sensitization to Violence and
Suffering Through Playing Video Games, 67 Swiss J. Psychology 41
(2008).
Steward & Follina, Informing Policies in Forensic Settings:
A Review of Research Investigating the Effects of Exposure to Media
Violence on Challenging/Offending Behaviour, 8 British J. Forensic
Prac. 31 (2006).
Swing & Anderson, The Unintended Negative Consequences of
Exposure to Violent Video games, 12 Int. J. Cognitive Tech. 3
(2007).
Tamborini et al., Violent Virtual Video Games and Hostile
Thoughts, 48 J. Broadcasting & Electronic Media 335 (2004).
Uhlmann & Swanson, Exposure to Violent Video Games Increases
Automatic Aggressiveness, 27 J. Adolescence 41 (2004).
Vaughan, Inadvertent Script Change and Increased Propensity for
Violence: The Danger of Interactive Video Games, 34 Transactional
Analysis J. 30 (2004).
Wallenius & Punamäki, Digital Game Violence and Direct
Aggression in Adolescence: A Longitudinal Study of the Roles of
Sex, Age, and Parent-Child Communication, 29 J. Applied
Developmental Psychology 286 (2008).
Wallenius, Punamäki, & Rimpelä, Digital Game Playing and
Direct and Indirect Aggression in Early Adolescence: The Roles of
Age, Social Intelligence, and Parent-Child Communication, 36 J.
Youth and Adolescence 325 (2007).
Wang et al., Short Term Exposure to a Violent Video Game
Induces Changes in Frontolimbic Circuitry in Adolescents, 3 Brain
Imaging & Behavior 38 (2009).
Weber, Ritterfeld, & Mathiak, Does Playing Violent Video
Games Induce Aggression? Empirical Evidence of a Functional
Magnetic Resonance Imaging Study, 8 Media Psychology 39 (2006).
Wiegman & van Schie, Video Game Playing and its Relations
With Aggressive and Prosocial Behaviour, 37 British J. Soc.
Psychology 367 (1998).
Williams, The Effects of Frustration, Violence, and Trait
Hostility After Playing a Video Game, 12 Mass Communication &
Society 291 (2009).
Ybarra et al., Linkages Between Internet and Other Media
Violence With Seriously Violent Behavior by Youth, 122 Pediatrics
929 (2008).
B
Bensley & Van Eenwyk, Video Games and Real-Life Aggression:
Review of the Literature, 29 J. Adolescent Health 244 (2001).
Bösche, Violent Content Enhances Video Game Performance, 21 J.
Media Psychology: Theories, Methods, and Applications 145
(2009).
Colwell & Kato, Video Game Play in British and Japanese
Adolescents, 36 Simulation & Gaming 518 (2005).
Colwell & Kato, Investigation of the Relationship Between
Social Isolation, Self-Esteem, Aggression and Computer Game Play in
Japanese Adolescents, 6 Asian J. Soc. Psychology 149 (2003).
Dominick, Videogames, Television Violence, and Aggression in
Teenagers, 34 J. Communication 136 (1984).
Ferguson, Blazing Angels or Resident Evil? Can Violent Video
Games be a Force For Good? 14 Rev. Gen. Psychology 68 (2010).
Ferguson, Violent Video Games: Dogma, Fear, Pseudoscience, 33
Skeptical Inquirer 38 (2009).
Ferguson, The Good, The Bad and the Ugly: A Meta-analytic Review
of Positive and Negative Effects of Violent Video Games, 78
Psychiatric Q. 309 (2007).
Ferguson & Meehan, Saturday Night’s Alright for Fighting:
Antisocial Traits, Fighting, and Weapons Carrying in a Large Sample
of Youth, 81 Psychiatric Q. 293 (2010).
Ferguson et al., Violent Video Games and Aggression, 35
Crim. Justice & Behavior 311 (2008).
Ferguson, Research on the Effects of Violent Video Games: A
Critical Analysis, 3 Soc. & Personality Psychology Compass 351
(2009).
Ferguson & Rueda, The Hitman Study: Violent Video Game
Exposure Effects on Aggressive Behavior, Hostile Feelings, and
Depression, 15 European Psychologist 99 (2010).
Ferguson, San Miguel, & Hartley, A Multivariate Analysis of
Youth Violence and Aggression: The Influence of Family, Peers,
Depression, and Media Violence, 155 J. Pediatrics 904 (2009).
Ferguson, Evidence for Publication Bias in Video Game Violence
Effects Literature: A Meta-Analytic Review, 12 Aggression &
Violent Behavior 470 (2007).
Ferguson, The School Shooting/Violent Video Game Link: Causal
Relationship or Moral Panic? 5 J. Investigative Psychology &
Offender Profiling 25 (2008).
Ferguson et al., Personality, Parental, and Media
Influences on Aggressive Personality and Violent Crime in Young
Adults, 17 J. Aggression, Maltreatment & Trauma 395 (2008).
Ferguson & Kilburn, Much Ado About Nothing: The
Misestimation and Overinterpretation of Violent Video Game Effects
in Eastern and Western Nations: Comment on Anderson et al. (2010),
136 Psychological Bull. 174 (2010).
Fleming & Rickwood, Effects of Violent Versus Nonviolent
Video Games on Children's Arousal, Aggressive Mood, and Positive
Mood, 31 J. Applied Soc. Psychology 2047 (2001).
Griffiths, Violent Video Games and Aggression: A Review of the
Literature, 4 Aggression & Violent Behavior 203 (1999).
Griffiths, Video Games and Aggression, 10 The Psychologist 397
(1997).
Ivory & Kalyanaraman, The Effects of Technological
Advancement and Violent Content in Video Games on Players' Feelings
of Presence, Involvement, Physiological Arousal, and Aggression, 57
J. Communication 532 (2007).
Kestenbaum & Weinstein, Personality, Psychopathology, and
Developmental Issues in Male Adolescent Video Game Use, 24 J. Am.
Academy Child Psychology 329 (1985).
Markey & Markey, Vulnerability to Violent Video Games: A
Review and Integration of Personality Research, 14 Rev. Gen.
Psychology 82 (2010).
Markey & Scherer, An Examination of Psychoticism and Motion
Capture Controls as Moderators of the Effects of Violent Video
Games, 25 Computers in Human Behavior 407 (2009).
Mitrofan, Paul, & Spencer, Is Aggression in Children With
Behavioural and Emotional Difficulties Associated With Television
Viewing and Video Game Playing? A Systematic Review, 35 Child:
Care, Health & Development 5 (2009).
Olson, Media Violence Research and Youth Violence Data: Why Do
They Conflict? 28 Academic Psychiatry 144 (2004).
Porter & Starcevic, Are Violent Video Games Harmful? 15
Australasian Psychiatry 422 (2007).
Regenbogen, Herrmann, & Fehr, The Neural Processing of
Voluntary Completed, Real and Virtual Violent and NonViolent
Computer Game Scenarios Displaying Predefined Actions in Gamers and
Nongamers, 5 Soc. Neuroscience 221 (2010).
Scott, The Effect of Video Games on Feelings of Aggression, 129
J. Psychology 121 (1995).
Sestir & Bartholow, Violent and Nonviolent Video Games
Produce Opposing Effects on Aggressive and Prosocial Outcomes, 46
J. Experimental Soc. Psychology 934 (2010).
Unsworth, Devilly, & Ward, The Effect of Playing Violent
Video Games on Adolescents: Should Parents be Quaking in Their
Boots? 13 Psychology, Crime & Law 383 (2007).
Unsworth & Ward, Video Games and Aggressive Behavior. 36
Australian Psychologist 184 (2001).
Williams & Skoric, Internet Fantasy Violence: A Test of
Aggression in an Online Game, 72 Communication Monographs 217
(2005).
Winkel, Novak, & Hopson, Personality Factors, Subject
Gender, and the Effects of Aggressive Video Games on Aggression in
Adolescents, 21 J. Research in Personality 211 (1987). | The Supreme Court ruled that video games are protected under the First Amendment, striking down a California law that restricted the sale of violent video games to minors. |
Free Speech | Minnesota Voters Alliance v. Mansky | https://supreme.justia.com/cases/federal/us/585/16-1435/ | NOTICE: This opinion is subject to
formal revision before publication in the preliminary print of the
United States Reports. Readers are requested to notify the Reporter
of Decisions, Supreme Court of the United States, Washington,
D. C. 20543, of any typographical or other formal errors, in
order that corrections may be made before the preliminary print
goes to press.
SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES
_________________
No. 16–1435
_________________
MINNESOTA VOTERS ALLIANCE, et al.,
PETITIONERS v. JOE MANSKY, et al.
on writ of certiorari to the united states
court of appeals for the eighth circuit
[June 14, 2018]
Chief Justice Roberts delivered the opinion of
the Court.
Under Minnesota law, voters may not wear a
political badge, political button, or anything bearing political
insignia inside a polling place on Election Day. The question
presented is whether this ban violates the Free Speech Clause of
the First Amendment.
I
A
Today, Americans going to their polling places
on Election Day expect to wait in a line, briefly interact with an
election official, enter a private voting booth, and cast an
anonymous ballot. Little about this ritual would have been familiar
to a voter in the mid-to-late nineteenth century. For one thing,
voters typically deposited pri- vately prepared ballots at the
polls instead of completing official ballots on-site. These
pre-made ballots often took the form of “party tickets”—printed
slates of candidate selections, often distinctive in appearance,
that political parties distributed to their supporters and pressed
upon others around the polls. See E. Evans, A History of the
Australian Ballot System in the United States 6–11 (1917) (Evans);
R. Bensel, The American Ballot Box in the Mid-Nineteenth Century
14–15 (2004) (Bensel).
The physical arrangement confronting the voter
was also different. The polling place often consisted simply of a
“voting window” through which the voter would hand his ballot to an
election official situated in a separate room with the ballot box.
Bensel 11, 13; see, e.g., C. Rowell, Digest of
Contested-Election Cases in the Fifty-First Congress 224 (1891)
(report of Rep. Lacey) (considering whether “the ability to reach
the window and actually tender the ticket to the [election] judges”
is “essential in all cases to constitute a good offer to vote”);
Holzer, Election Day 1860, Smithsonian Magazine (Nov. 2008), pp.
46, 52 (describing the interior voting window on the third floor of
the Springfield, Illinois courthouse where Abraham Lincoln voted).
As a result of this arrangement, “the actual act of voting was
usually performed in the open,” frequently within view of
interested onlookers. Rusk, The Effect of the Australian Ballot
Reform on Split Ticket Voting: 1876–1908, Am. Pol. Sci. Rev. 1220,
1221 (1970) (Rusk); see Evans 11–13.
As documented in Burson v. Freeman , 504 U. S. 191 (1992), “[a]pproaching the
polling place under this system was akin to entering an open
auction place.” Id., at 202 (plurality opinion). The room
containing the ballot boxes was “usually quiet and orderly,” but
“[t]he public space outside the window . . . was
chaotic.” Bensel 13. Electioneering of all kinds was permitted. See id. , at 13, 16–17; R. Dinkin, Election Day: A Documentary
History 19 (2002). Crowds would gather to heckle and harass voters
who appeared to be supporting the other side. Indeed, “[u]nder the
informal conventions of the period, election etiquette required
only that a ‘man of ordinary courage’ be able to make his way to
the voting window.” Bensel 20–21. “In short, these early elections
were not a very pleasant spectacle for those who believed in
democratic government.” Burson, 504 U. S., at 202
(plurality opinion) (internal quotation marks omitted).
By the late nineteenth century, States began
implementing reforms to address these vulnerabilities and improve
the reliability of elections. Between 1888 and 1896, nearly every
State adopted the secret ballot. See id., at 203–205.
Because voters now needed to mark their state-printed ballots
on-site and in secret, voting moved into a sequestered space where
the voters could “deliberate and make a decision in . . .
privacy.” Rusk 1221; see Evans 35; 1889 Minn. Stat. ch. 3, §§27–28,
p. 21 (regulating, as part of Minnesota’s secret ballot law, the
arrangement of voting compartments inside the polling place). In
addition, States enacted “viewpoint-neutral restrictions on
election-day speech” in the immediate vicinity of the polls. Burson, 504 U. S., at 214–215 (Scalia, J., concurring
in judgment) (by 1900, 34 of 45 States had such restrictions).
Today, all 50 States and the District of Columbia have laws curbing
various forms of speech in and around polling places on Election
Day.
Minnesota’s such law contains three
prohibitions, only one of which is challenged here. See Minn. Stat.
§211B.11(1) (Supp. 2017). The first sentence of §211B.11(1) forbids
any person to “display campaign material, post signs, ask, solicit,
or in any manner try to induce or persuade a voter within a polling
place or within 100 feet of the building in which a polling place
is situ- ated” to “vote for or refrain from voting for a candidate
or ballot question.” The second sentence prohibits the distribution
of “political badges, political buttons, or other political
insignia to be worn at or about the polling place.” The third
sentence—the “political apparel ban”—states that a “political
badge, political button, or other political insignia may not be
worn at or about the polling place.” Versions of all three
prohibitions have been on the books in Minnesota for over a
century. See 1893 Minn. Laws ch. 4, §108, pp. 51–52; 1912 Minn.
Laws, 1st Spec. Sess., ch. 3, p. 24; 1988 Minn. Laws ch. 578, Art.
3, §11, p. 594 (reenacting the prohibitions as part of
§211B.11).
There is no dispute that the political apparel
ban applies only within the polling place, and covers
articles of clothing and accessories with “political insignia” upon
them. Minnesota election judges—temporary government employees
working the polls on Election Day—have the authority to decide
whether a particular item falls within the ban. App. to Pet. for
Cert. I–1. If a voter shows up wearing a prohibited item, the
election judge is to ask the individual to conceal or remove it. Id., at I–2. If the individual refuses, the election judge
must allow him to vote, while making clear that the incident “will
be recorded and referred to appropriate authorities.” Ibid. Violators are subject to an administrative process before the
Minnesota Office of Administrative Hearings, which, upon finding a
violation, may issue a reprimand or impose a civil penalty. Minn.
Stat. §§211B.32, 211B.35(2) (2014). That administrative body may
also refer the complaint to the county attorney for prosecution as
a petty misdemeanor; the maximum penalty is a $300 fine.
§§211B.11(4) (Supp. 2017), 211B.35(2) (2014), 609.02(4a)
(2016).
B
Petitioner Minnesota Voters Alliance (MVA) is
a nonprofit organization that “seeks better government through
election reforms.” Pet. for Cert. 5. Petitioner Andrew Cilek
is a registered voter in Hennepin County and the executive director
of MVA; petitioner Susan Jeffers served in 2010 as a Ramsey County
election judge. Five days before the November 2010 election, MVA,
Jeffers, and other likeminded groups and individuals filed a
lawsuit in Federal District Court challenging the political apparel
ban on First Amendment grounds. The groups—calling themselves
“Election Integrity Watch” (EIW)—planned to have supporters wear
buttons to the polls printed with the words “Please I. D. Me,” a
picture of an eye, and a telephone number and web address for EIW.
(Minnesota law does not require individuals to show identification
to vote.) One of the individual plaintiffs also planned to wear a
“Tea Party Patriots” shirt. The District Court denied the
plaintiffs’ request for a temporary restraining order and
preliminary injunction and allowed the apparel ban to remain in
effect for the upcoming election.
In response to the lawsuit, officials for
Hennepin and Ramsey Counties distributed to election judges an
“Election Day Policy,” providing guidance on the enforcement of the
political apparel ban. The Minnesota Secretary of State also
distributed the Policy to election officials throughout the State.
The Policy specified that examples of apparel falling within the
ban “include, but are not limited to”:
“• Any item including the name of a political
party in Minnesota, such as the Republican,
[Democratic-Farmer-Labor], Independence, Green or Libertar- ian
parties.
• Any item including the name of a candidate at
any election.
• Any item in support of or opposition to a
ballot question at any election.
• Issue oriented material designed to influence
or impact voting (including specifically the ‘Please I. D. Me’
buttons).
• Material promoting a group with recognizable
political views (such as the Tea Party, MoveOn.org, and so on).”
App. to Pet. for Cert. I–1 to I–2.
As alleged in the plaintiffs’ amended complaint
and supporting declarations, some voters associated with EIW ran
into trouble with the ban on Election Day. One individual was asked
to cover up his Tea Party shirt. Another refused to conceal his
“Please I. D. Me” button, and an election judge recorded his name
and address for possible referral. And petitioner Cilek—who was
wearing the same button and a T-shirt with the words “Don’t Tread
on Me” and the Tea Party Patriots logo—was twice turned away from
the polls altogether, then finally permitted to vote after an
election judge recorded his information.
Back in court, MVA and the other plaintiffs (now
joined by Cilek) argued that the ban was unconstitutional both on
its face and as applied to their apparel. The District Court
granted the State’s motions to dismiss, and the Court of Appeals
for the Eighth Circuit affirmed in part and reversed in part. Minnesota Majority v. Mansky , 708 F. 3d 1051
(2013). In evaluating MVA’s facial challenge, the Court of Appeals
observed that this Court had previously upheld a state law
restricting speech “related to a political campaign” in a 100-foot
zone outside a polling place; the Court of Appeals determined that
Minnesota’s law likewise passed constitutional muster. Id., at 1056–1058 (quoting Burson , 504 U. S., at 197
(plurality opinion)). The Court of Appeals reversed the dismissal
of the plaintiffs’ as-applied challenge, however, finding that the
District Court had improperly considered matters outside the
pleadings. 708 F. 3d, at 1059. Judge Shepherd concurred in
part and dissented in part. In his view, Minnesota’s broad
restriction on political apparel did not “rationally and
reasonably” serve the State’s asserted interests. Id., at
1062. On remand, the District Court granted summary judgment for
the State on the as-applied challenge, and this time the Court of
Appeals affirmed. Minnesota Majority v. Mansky , 849
F. 3d 749 (2017).
MVA, Cilek, and Jeffers (hereinafter MVA)
petitioned for review of their facial First Amendment claim only.
We granted certiorari. 583 U. S. ___ (2017).
II
The First Amendment prohibits laws “abridging
the freedom of speech.” Minnesota’s ban on wearing any “political
badge, political button, or other political insignia” plainly
restricts a form of expression within the protection of the First
Amendment.
But the ban applies only in a specific location:
the interior of a polling place. It therefore implicates our
“ ‘forum based’ approach for assessing restrictions that the
government seeks to place on the use of its property.” International Soc. for Krishna Consciousness, Inc. v. Lee , 505 U. S. 672, 678 (1992) ( ISKCON ).
Generally speaking, our cases recognize three types of
government-controlled spaces: traditional public forums, designated
public forums, and nonpublic forums. In a traditional public
forum—parks, streets, sidewalks, and the like—the government may
impose reasonable time, place, and manner restrictions on private
speech, but restrictions based on content must satisfy strict
scrutiny, and those based on viewpoint are prohibited. See Pleasant Grove City v. Summum , 555 U. S. 460,
469 (2009). The same standards apply in designated public
forums—spaces that have “not traditionally been regarded as a
public forum” but which the government has “intentionally opened up
for that purpose.” Id., at 469–470. In a nonpublic forum, on
the other hand—a space that “is not by tradition or designation a
forum for public communication”—the government has much more
flexibility to craft rules limiting speech. Perry Ed. Assn. v. Perry Local Educators’ Assn. , 460 U. S. 37, 46
(1983). The government may reserve such a forum “for its intended
purposes, communicative or otherwise, as long as the regulation on
speech is reasonable and not an effort to suppress expression
merely because public officials oppose the speaker’s view.” Ibid. This Court employs a distinct standard of review
to assess speech restrictions in nonpublic forums because the
government, “no less than a private owner of property,” retains the
“power to preserve the property under its control for the use to
which it is lawfully dedicated.” Adderley v. Florida ,
385 U. S. 39, 47 (1966). “Nothing in the Constitution requires
the Government freely to grant access to all who wish to exercise
their right to free speech on every type of Government property
without regard to the nature of the property or to the disruption
that might be caused by the speaker’s activities.” Cornelius v. NAACP Legal Defense & Ed. Fund, Inc. , 473 U. S.
788, 799–800 (1985). Accordingly, our decisions have long
recognized that the government may impose some content-based
restrictions on speech in nonpublic forums, including restrictions
that exclude political advocates and forms of political advocacy.
See id., at 806–811; Greer v. Spock , 424
U. S. 828, 831–833, 838–839 (1976); Lehman v. Shaker
Heights , 418 U. S. 298, 303–304 (1974) (plurality opin-
ion); id., at 307–308 (Douglas, J., concurring in
judgment).
A polling place in Minnesota qualifies as a
nonpublic forum. It is, at least on Election Day,
government-controlled property set aside for the sole purpose of
voting. The space is “a special enclave, subject to greater
restriction.” ISKCON , 505 U. S., at 680. Rules strictly
govern who may be present, for what purpose, and for how long. See
Minn. Stat. §204C.06 (2014). And while the four-Justice plurality
in Burson and Justice Scalia’s concurrence in the judgment
parted ways over whether the public sidewalks and streets surrounding a polling place qualify as a nonpublic forum,
neither opinion suggested that the interior of the building was
anything but. See 504 U. S., at 196–197, and n. 2
(plurality opinion); id. , at 214–216 (opinion of Scalia,
J.).
We therefore evaluate MVA’s First Amendment
challenge under the nonpublic forum standard. The text of the
apparel ban makes no distinction based on the speaker’s political
persuasion, so MVA does not claim that the ban discriminates on the
basis of viewpoint on its face. The question accordingly is whether
Minnesota’s ban on political apparel is “reasonable in light of the
purpose served by the forum”: voting. Cornelius , 473
U. S., at 806.
III
A
We first consider whether Minnesota is
pursuing a permissible objective in prohibiting voters from wearing
particular kinds of expressive apparel or accessories while inside
the polling place. The natural starting point for evaluating a
First Amendment challenge to such a restriction is this Court’s
decision in Burson , which upheld a Tennessee law imposing a
100-foot campaign-free zone around polling place entrances. Under
the Tennessee law—much like Minnesota’s buffer-zone provision—no
person could solicit votes for or against a candidate, party, or
ballot measure, distribute campaign materials, or
“display . . . campaign posters, signs or other
campaign materials” within the restricted zone. 504 U. S., at
193–194 (plurality opinion). The plurality found that the law
withstood even the strict scrutiny applicable to speech
restrictions in traditional public forums. Id., at 211. In
his opinion concurring in the judgment, Justice Scalia argued that
the less rigorous “reasonableness” standard of review should apply,
and found the law “at least reasonable” in light of the plurality’s
analysis. Id. , at 216.
That analysis emphasized the problems of fraud,
voter intimidation, confusion, and general disorder that had
plagued polling places in the past. See id., at 200–204
(plurality opinion). Against that historical backdrop, the
plurality and Justice Scalia upheld Tennessee’s determination,
supported by overwhelming consensus among the States and “common
sense,” that a campaign-free zone outside the polls was “necessary”
to secure the advantages of the secret ballot and protect the right
to vote. Id., at 200, 206–208, 211. As the plurality
explained, “[t]he State of Tennessee has decided that [the] last 15
seconds before its citizens enter the polling place should be their
own, as free from interference as possible.” Id., at 210.
That was not “an unconstitutional choice.” Ibid. MVA disputes the relevance of Burson to
Minnesota’s apparel ban. On MVA’s reading, Burson considered
only “active campaigning” outside the polling place by campaign
workers and others trying to engage voters approaching the polls.
Brief for Petitioners 36–37. Minne- sota’s law, by contrast,
prohibits what MVA characterizes as “passive, silent”
self-expression by voters themselves when voting. Reply Brief 17.
MVA also points out that the plurality focused on the extent to
which the restricted zone combated “voter intimidation and election
fraud,” 504 U. S., at 208—concerns that, in MVA’s view, have
little to do with a prohibition on certain types of voter
apparel.
Campaign buttons and apparel did come up in the Burson briefing and argument, but neither the plurality nor
Justice Scalia expressly addressed such applications of the
law.[ 1 ] Nor did either opinion
specifically consider the interior of the polling place as opposed
to its environs, and it is true that the plurality’s reasoning
focused on campaign activities of a sort not likely to occur in an
area where, for the most part, only voters are permitted while
voting. At the same time, Tennessee’s law swept broadly to ban even
the plain “display” of a campaign-related message, and the Court
upheld the law in full. The plurality’s conclusion that the State
was warranted in designating an area for the voters as “their own”
as they enter the polling place suggests an interest more
significant, not less, within that place. Id., at
210.
In any event, we see no basis for rejecting
Minnesota’s determination that some forms of advocacy should be
excluded from the polling place, to set it aside as “an island of
calm in which voters can peacefully contemplate their choices.”
Brief for Respondents 43. Casting a vote is a weighty civic act,
akin to a jury’s return of a verdict, or a representative’s vote on
a piece of legislation. It is a time for choosing, not campaigning.
The State may reasonably decide that the interior of the polling
place should reflect that distinction.
To be sure, our decisions have noted the
“nondisruptive” nature of expressive apparel in more mundane
settings. Board of Airport Comm’rs of Los Angeles v. Jews
for Jesus, Inc. , 482 U. S. 569, 576 (1987) (so
characterizing “the wearing of a T-shirt or button that contains a
political message” in an airport); Tinker v. Des Moines
Independent Community School Dist. , 393 U. S. 503, 508
(1969) (students wearing black armbands to protest the Vietnam War
engaged in “silent, passive expression of opinion, unaccompanied by
any disorder or disturbance”). But those observations do not speak
to the unique context of a polling place on Election Day. Members
of the public are brought together at that place, at the end of
what may have been a divisive election season, to reach considered
decisions about their government and laws. The State may reasonably
take steps to ensure that partisan discord not follow the voter up
to the voting booth, and distract from a sense of shared civic
obligation at the moment it counts the most. That interest may be
thwarted by displays that do not raise significant concerns in
other situations.
Other States can see the matter differently, and
some do.[ 2 ] The majority,
however, agree with Minnesota that at least some kinds of
campaign-related clothing and accessories should stay
outside. [ 3 ] That broadly
shared judgment is entitled to respect. Cf. Burson , 504
U. S., at 206 (plurality opinion) (finding that a “widespread
and time-tested consensus” supported the constitutionality of
campaign buffer zones).
Thus, in light of the special purpose of the
polling place itself, Minnesota may choose to prohibit certain
apparel there because of the message it conveys, so that voters may
focus on the important decisions immediately at hand.
B
But the State must draw a reasonable line.
Although there is no requirement of narrow tailoring in a nonpublic
forum, the State must be able to articulate some sensible basis for
distinguishing what may come in from what must stay out. See Cornelius , 473 U. S., at 808–809. Here, the unmoored
use of the term “political” in the Minnesota law, combined with
haphazard interpretations the State has provided in official
guidance and representations to this Court, cause Minnesota’s
restriction to fail even this forgiving test.
Again, the statute prohibits wearing a
“political badge, political button, or other political insignia.”
It does not define the term “political.” And the word can be
expansive. It can encompass anything “of or relating to government,
a government, or the conduct of governmental affairs,” Webster’s
Third New International Dictionary 1755 (2002), or anything “[o]f,
relating to, or dealing with the structure or affairs of
government, politics, or the state,” American Heritage Dictionary
1401 (3d ed. 1996). Under a literal reading of those definitions, a
button or T-shirt merely imploring others to “Vote!” could
qualify.
The State argues that the apparel ban should not
be read so broadly. According to the State, the statute does not
prohibit “any conceivably ‘political’ message” or cover “all
‘political’ speech, broadly construed.” Brief for Respondents 21,
23. Instead, the State interprets the ban to proscribe “only words
and symbols that an objectively reasonable observer would perceive
as conveying a message about the electoral choices at issue in
[the] polling place.” Id., at 13; see id., at 19 (the
ban “applies not to any message regarding government or its
affairs, but to messages relating to questions of governmental
affairs facing voters on a given election day”).
At the same time, the State argues that the
category of “political” apparel is not limited to campaign
apparel. After all, the reference to “campaign material” in the
first sentence of the statute—describing what one may not “display”
in the buffer zone as well as inside the polling place—implies that
the distinct term “political” should be understood to cover a
broader class of items. As the State’s counsel explained to the
Court, Minnesota’s law “expand[s] the scope of what is prohibited
from campaign speech to additional political speech.” Tr. of Oral
Arg. 50.
We consider a State’s “authoritative
constructions” in interpreting a state law. Forsyth County v. Nationalist Movement , 505 U. S. 123, 131 (1992). But
far from clarifying the indeterminate scope of the political
apparel provision, the State’s “electoral choices” construction
introduces confusing line-drawing problems. Cf. Jews for
Jesus, 482 U. S., at 575–576 (a resolution banning all “
First Amendment activities” in an airport could not be saved by a
“murky” construction excluding “airport-related” activity).
For specific examples of what is banned under
its standard, the State points to the 2010 Election Day Pol-
icy—which it continues to hold out as authoritative guidance
regarding implementation of the statute. See Brief for Respondents
22–23. The first three examples in the Policy are clear enough:
items displaying the name of a political party, items displaying
the name of a candidate, and items demonstrating “support of or
opposition to a ballot question.” App. to Pet. for Cert. I–2.
But the next example—“[i]ssue oriented material
designed to influence or impact voting,” id., at I–2—raises
more questions than it answers. What qualifies as an “issue”? The
answer, as far as we can tell from the State’s briefing and
argument, is any subject on which a political candidate or party
has taken a stance. See Tr. of Oral Arg. 37 (explaining that the
“electoral choices” test looks at the “issues that have been
raised” in a campaign “that are relevant to the election”). For
instance, the Election Day Policy specifically notes that the
“Please I. D. Me” buttons are prohibited. App. to Pet. for Cert.
I–2. But a voter identification requirement was not on the ballot
in 2010, see Brief for Respondents 47, n. 24, so a Minnesotan
would have had no explicit “electoral choice” to make in that
respect. The buttons were nonetheless covered, the State tells us,
because the Republican candidates for Governor and Secretary of
State had staked out positions on whether photo identification
should be required. Ibid. ; see App. 58–60.[ 4 ]
A rule whose fair enforcement requires an
election judge to maintain a mental index of the platforms and
positions of every candidate and party on the ballot is not reason-
able. Candidates for statewide and federal office and major
political parties can be expected to take positions on a wide array
of subjects of local and national import. See, e.g., Democratic Platform Committee, 2016 Democratic Party Platform
(approved July 2016) (stating positions on over 90 issues);
Republican Platform Committee, Republican Platform 2016 (approved
July 2016) (similar). Would a “Support Our Troops” shirt be banned,
if one of the candidates or parties had expressed a view on
military funding or aid for veterans? What about a “#MeToo” shirt,
referencing the movement to increase awareness of sexual harassment
and assault? At oral argument, the State indicated that the ban
would cover such an item if a candidate had “brought up” the topic.
Tr. of Oral Arg. 64–65.
The next broad category in the Election Day
Policy—any item “promoting a group with recognizable political
views,” App. to Pet. for Cert. I–2—makes matters worse. The State
construes the category as limited to groups with “views” about “the
issues confronting voters in a given election.” Brief for
Respondents 23. The State does not, however, confine that category
to groups that have endorsed a candidate or taken a position on a
ballot question.
Any number of associations, educational
institutions, businesses, and religious organizations could have an
opinion on an “issue[ ] confronting voters in a given
election.” For instance, the American Civil Liberties Union, the
AARP, the World Wildlife Fund, and Ben & Jerry’s all have
stated positions on matters of public concern.[ 5 ] If the views of those groups align or conflict
with the position of a candidate or party on the ballot, does that
mean that their insignia are banned? See id., at 24,
n. 15 (representing that “AFL–CIO or Chamber of Commerce
apparel” would be banned if those organizations “had objectively
recognizable views on an issue in the election at hand”). Take
another example: In the run-up to the 2012 election, Presidential
candidates of both major parties issued public statements regarding
the then-existing policy of the Boy Scouts of America to exclude
members on the basis of sexual orientation.[ 6 ] Should a Scout leader in 2012 stopping to vote on
his way to a troop meeting have been asked to cover up his
uniform?
The State emphasizes that the ban covers only
apparel promoting groups whose political positions are sufficiently
“well-known.” Tr. of Oral Arg. 37. But that requirement, if
anything, only increases the potential for erratic application.
Well known by whom? The State tells us the lodestar is the “typical
observer” of the item. Brief for Respondents 21. But that measure
may turn in significant part on the background knowledge and media
consumption of the particular election judge applying it.
The State’s “electoral choices” standard,
considered together with the nonexclusive examples in the Election
Day Policy, poses riddles that even the State’s top lawyers
struggle to solve. A shirt declaring “All Lives Matter,” we are
told, could be “perceived” as political. Tr. of Oral Arg. 41. How
about a shirt bearing the name of the National Rifle Association?
Definitely out. Id. , at 39–40. That said, a shirt displaying
a rainbow flag could be worn “ unless there was an issue on
the ballot” that “related somehow . . . to gay rights.” Id. , at 38 (emphasis added). A shirt simply displaying the
text of the Second Amendment? Prohibited. Id. , at 40. But a
shirt with the text of the First Amendment? “It would be
allowed.” Ibid. “[P]erfect clarity and precise guidance have
never been required even of regulations that restrict expressive
activ- ity.” Ward v. Rock Against Racism , 491
U. S. 781, 794 (1989). But the State’s difficulties with its
restriction go beyond close calls on borderline or fanciful cases.
And that is a serious matter when the whole point of the exercise
is to prohibit the expression of political views.
It is “self-evident” that an indeterminate
prohibition carries with it “[t]he opportunity for abuse,
especially where [it] has received a virtually open-ended
interpretation.” Jews for Jesus , 482 U. S., at 576; see Heffron v. International Soc. for Krishna Consciousness,
Inc. , 452 U. S. 640, 649 (1981) (warning of the “more
covert forms of discrimination that may result when arbitrary
discretion is vested in some governmental authority”). Election
judges “have the authority to decide what is political” when
screening individuals at the entrance to the polls. App. to Pet.
for Cert. I–1. We do not doubt that the vast majority of election
judges strive to enforce the statute in an evenhanded manner, nor
that some degree of discretion in this setting is necessary. But
that discretion must be guided by objective, workable standards.
Without them, an election judge’s own politics may shape his views
on what counts as “political.” And if voters experience or witness
episodes of unfair or inconsistent enforcement of the ban, the
State’s interest in maintaining a polling place free of distraction
and disruption would be undermined by the very measure intended to
further it.
That is not to say that Minnesota has set upon
an impossible task. Other States have laws proscribing displays
(including apparel) in more lucid terms. See, e.g., Cal.
Elec. Code Ann. §319.5 (West Cum. Supp. 2018) (prohibiting “the
visible display . . . of information that advocates for
or against any candidate or measure,” including the “display of a
candidate’s name, likeness, or logo,” the “display of a ballot
measure’s number, title, subject, or logo,” and “[b]uttons, hats,”
or “shirts” containing such information); Tex. Elec. Code Ann.
§61.010(a) (West 2010) (prohibiting the wearing of “a badge,
insignia, emblem, or other similar communicative device relating to
a candidate, measure, or political party appearing on the ballot,
or to the conduct of the election”). We do not suggest that such
provisions set the outer limit of what a State may proscribe, and
do not pass on the constitutionality of laws that are not before
us. But we do hold that if a State wishes to set its polling places
apart as areas free of partisan discord, it must employ a more
discernible approach than the one Minnesota has offered
here.[ 7 ]
* * *
Cases like this “present[ ] us with a
particularly difficult reconciliation: the accommodation of the
right to engage in political discourse with the right to vote.” Burson , 504 U. S., at 198 (plurality opinion).
Minnesota, like other States, has sought to strike the balance in a
way that affords the voter the opportunity to exercise his civic
duty in a setting removed from the clamor and din of
electioneering. While that choice is generally worthy of our
respect, Minnesota has not supported its good intentions with a law
capable of reasoned application.
The judgment of the Court of Appeals is
reversed, and the case is remanded for further proceedings
consistent with this opinion.
It is so ordered.
APPENDIX
State Laws Prohibiting Accessories or Apparel in
the Polling Place[ 8 ]* Notes 1 The State of Tennessee
represented that its prohibition on campaign displays extended both
to items of apparel and to voters. Tr. of Oral Arg. in No. 90–1056,
p. 33 (argument of Atty. Gen. Burson) (explaining that the statute
banned “[t]ee-shirts,” “campaign buttons,” and “hats” because such
items “implicate and invite the same problems,” and that voters
would be “asked to take campaign button[s] off as they go in”); see
Brief for State of Tennessee et al. as Amici Curiae 3,
28–30, and n. 3 (making the same representation in the present
case). The Burson plaintiff also emphasized that the
Tennessee law would cover apparel, including apparel worn by
voters, see Brief for Respondent in No. 90–1056, p. 3; Tr. of
Oral Arg. in No. 90–1056, p. 21, and Justice Stevens in
dissent referred to the application of the law to campaign buttons,
see Burson, 504 U. S., at 218–219, 224. 2 See, e.g., Ala.
Secretary of State, 2018 Alabama Voter Guide 14 (voters may wear
“campaign buttons or T-shirts with political advertisements”); 2018
Va. Acts ch. 700, §1 (prohibitions on exhibiting campaign material
“shall not be construed” to prohibit a voter “from wearing a shirt,
hat, or other apparel on which a candidate’s name or a political
slogan appears or from having a sticker or button attached to his
apparel on which a candidate’s name or a political slogan
appears”); R. I. Bd. of Elections, Rules and Regulations for
Polling Place Conduct 3 (2016) (voters may “display or wear any
campaign or political party button, badge or other document or item
designed or tending to aid, injure or defeat any candidate for
public office or any political party or any question,” but they
must “immediately exit the polling location without unreasonable
delay” after voting). 3 See Appendix, infra . 4 The State also maintains
that the “Please I. D. Me” buttons were properly banned because the
buttons were designed to confuse other voters about whether they
needed photo identification to vote. Brief for Respondents 46–47.
We do not doubt that the State may prohibit messages intended to
mislead voters about voting requirements and procedures. But that
interest does not align with the State’s construction of
“political” to refer to messages “about the electoral choices at
issue in [the] polling place.” Id., at 13. 5 See, e.g., American Civil Liberties Union, Campaign for Smart Justice (2018),
online at
http://www.aclu.org/issues/mass-incarceration/smart-justice/campaign-smart-justice
(taking positions on criminal justice reform) (all Internet
materials as last visited June 11, 2018); AARP, Government &
Elections, online at
https://www.aarp.org/politics-society/government-elections/
(listing positions on Social Secu-rity and health care); World
Wildlife Fund, A Win on Capitol Hill (Apr. 17, 2018), online at
https://www.worldwildlife.org/stories/a-win-on-capitol-hill
(describing the organization’s position on federal funding for
international conservation programs); Ben & Jerry’s, Issues We
Care About, online at
https://www.benjerry.com/values/issues-we-care-about (sharing the
corporation’s views on campaign finance reform, international
conflict, and civil rights). 6 C. Camia, Obama, Romney
Opposed to Boy Scouts Ban on Gays, USA Today OnPolitics (updated
Aug. 08, 2012), online at
http : / / content.usatoday.com/communities/onpolitics/post/2012/08/barack-obama-boy-scouts-gays-mitt-romney-/1. 7 The State argues that, in
the event this Court concludes that there is a “substantial
question” about the proper interpretation of §211B.11(1), we should
postpone our decision and certify that issue to the Minnesota
Supreme Court. Brief for Respondents 57; see Minn. Stat.
§480.065(3) (2016). The dissent takes up this cause as well. See post, at 1 (opinion of Sotomayor, J.). The decision to
certify, however, “rests in the sound discretion of the federal
court.” Expressions Hair Design v. Schneiderman , 581
U. S. ___, ___ (2017) (Sotomayor, J., concurring in judgment)
(slip op., at 8). We decline to exercise that discretion in this
instance. Minnesota’s request for certification comes very late in
the day: This litigation had been ongoing in the federal courts for
over seven years before the State made its certification request in
its merits brief before this Court. See Stenberg v. Carhart , 530 U. S. 914, 945 (2000) (noting, in denying
certification, that the State had never asked the lower federal
courts to certify). And the State has not offered sufficient reason
to believe that certification would obviate the need to address the
constitutional question. Our analysis today reflects the State’s
proffered interpretation; nothing in that analysis would change if
the State’s interpretation were also adopted by the Minnesota
Supreme Court. Nor has the State (or the dissent) suggested a
viable alternative construction that the Minnesota Supreme Court
might adopt instead. See Brief for Respondents 56–58; post, at 5–8. 8 * Based on statutory or
regulatory language and official resources, where
available. SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES
_________________
No. 16–1435
_________________
MINNESOTA VOTERS ALLIANCE, et al.,
PETITIONERS v. JOE MANSKY, et al.
on writ of certiorari to the united states
court of appeals for the eighth circuit
[June 14, 2018]
Justice Sotomayor, with whom Justice Breyer
joins, dissenting.
I agree with the Court that “[c]asting a vote is
a weighty civic act” and that “State[s] may reasonably take steps
to ensure that partisan discord not follow the voter up to the
voting booth,” including by “prohibit[ing] certain apparel [in
polling places] because of the message it conveys.” Ante, at
11–12. I disagree, however, with the Court’s decision to declare
Minnesota’s political apparel ban unconstitutional on its face
because, in its view, the ban is not “capable of reasoned
application,” ante, at 19, when the Court has not first
afforded the Minnesota state courts “ ‘a reasonable
opportunity to pass upon’ ” and construe the statute, Babbitt v. Farm Workers , 442 U. S. 289, 308
(1979). I would certify this case to the Minnesota Supreme Court
for a definitive interpretation of the political apparel ban under
Minn. Stat. §211B.11(1) (Supp. 2017), which likely would obviate
the hypothetical line-drawing problems that form the basis of the
Court’s decision today.
I
As the Court acknowledges, Minnesota adopted
its political apparel ban late in the 19th century against the
backdrop of often “ ‘chaotic’ ” voting conditions where
“[c]rowds would gather to heckle and harass voters who appeared to
be supporting the other side.” Ante, at 2. Polling places
became “highly charged ethnic, religious, and ideological
battleground[s] in which individuals were stereotyped as friend or
foe,” even “on the basis of clothing.” R. Bensel, The American
Ballot Box in the Mid-Nineteenth Century 21 (2004). As a result,
States began adopting reforms “to address these vulnerabilities and
improve the reliability of elections.” Ante, at 3.
Minnesota thus enacted the political apparel ban
at issue in this case, which prohibits an individual from wearing
“[a] political badge, political button, or other political insignia
. . . at or about the polling place.” §211B.11(1).
Respondents maintain that this prohibition, together with other
election-day regulations, furthers Minnesota’s compelling interests
in (1) “maintaining peace, order and decorum in the polling place,”
(2) “protecting voters from confusion and undue influence such as
intimidation,” and (3) “preserving the integrity of its election
process.” Brief for Respondents 41 (internal quotation marks and
alterations omitted); see Burson v. Freeman , 504
U. S. 191, 193, 199 (1992) (plurality opinion) (recognizing
such interests as compelling).
The majority accords due respect to the weight
of these state interests in concluding that there is “no basis for
rejecting Minnesota’s determination that some forms of advocacy
should be excluded from the polling place, to set it aside as ‘an
island of calm in which voters can peacefully contemplate their
choices.’ ” Ante, at 11. Polling places today may not
much resemble the chaotic scenes of the turn of the 20th century,
but they remain vulnerable to interpersonal conflicts and partisan
efforts to influence voters.[ 1 ]
Even acts of interference that are “undetected or less than blatant
. . . may nonetheless drive the voter away before
remedial action can be taken.” Burson , 504 U. S., at
207; see also Brief for Campaign Legal Center as Amicus
Curiae 9 (noting that, “[a]bsent a ban on political
paraphernalia, [poll] workers might unintentionally exhibit
unconscious bias against voters who wear the ‘wrong’
paraphernalia”).
In holding that a polling place constitutes a
nonpublic forum and that a State must establish only that its
limitations on speech inside the polling place are reasonable, see ante, at 8–9, the Court goes a long way in preserving
States’ discretion to determine what measures are appropriate to
further important interests in maintaining order and decorum,
preventing confusion and intimidation, and protecting the integrity
of the voting process. The Court errs, however, in declaring
Minnesota’s political apparel ban unconstitutional under that
standard, without any guidance from the State’s highest court on
the proper interpretation of that state law. Ante, at 13,
19, n. 7.
II
The Court invalidates Minnesota’s political
apparel ban based on its inability to define the term “political”
in §211B.11(1), so as to discern “some sensible basis for
distinguishing what may come in from what must stay out” of a
polling place. Ante, at 12–13. The majority believes that
the law is not “capable of reasoned application,” ante, at
19, but it reaches that conclusion without taking the preferential
step of first asking the state courts to provide “an accurate
picture of how, exactly, the statute works,” Expressions Hair
Design v. Schneiderman , 581 U. S. ___, ___ (2017)
(Sotomayor, J., concurring in judgment) (slip op., at 5). It is a
“cardinal principle” that, “when confronting a challenge to the
constitutionality of a . . . statute,” courts “will first
ascertain whether a construction . . . is fairly possible
that will contain the statute within constitutional bounds,” and in
the context of a challenge to a state statute, federal courts
should be particularly hesitant to speculate as to possible
constructions of the state law when “the state courts stand willing
to address questions of state law on certification.” Arizonans
for Official English v. Arizona , 520 U. S. 43,
78–79 (1997) (internal quotation marks omitted); see Minn. Stat.
§480.065(3) (2016) (authorizing the Minnesota Supreme Court to
answer certified questions). Certification “save[s] time, energy,
and resources and helps build a cooperative judicial federalism.” Lehman Brothers v. Schein , 416 U. S. 386, 391
(1974). Neither of the majority’s proffered reasons for declining
to certify this case justifies its holding.
First, the Court notes that respondents’
“request for certification comes very late in the day,” as the
litigation already had been ongoing for more than seven years
before the request. Ante, at 19, n. 7. But
certification is not an argument subject to forfeiture by the
parties. It is a tool of the federal courts that serves to avoid
“friction-generating error” where a federal court attempts to
construe a statute “not yet reviewed by the State’s highest court.” Arizonans for Official English , 520 U. S., at 79. This
Court has certified questions to a state court “sua sponte,
even though the parties had not sought such relief and even though
the district court and the court of appeals previously had resolved
the disputed point of state law.” S. Shapiro, K. Geller, T. Bishop,
E. Hartnett, & D. Himmelfarb, Supreme Court Practice §9.4,
p. 611 (10th ed. 2013) (citing Elkins v. Moreno ,
435 U. S. 647, 660–663, 668–669 (1978)); see also Massachusetts v. Feeney , 429 U. S. 66 (1976)
( per curiam ) (certifying a question to the Supreme Judicial
Court of the Commonwealth of Massachusetts “on [the Court’s] own
motion”). Respondents’ delay in asking for certification does
nothing to alter this Court’s responsibility as a matter of
state-federal comity to give due deference to the state courts in
interpreting their own laws.
Second, the majority maintains that respondents
have “not offered sufficient reason to believe that certification
would obviate the need to address the constitutional question,” as
“nothing in [its] analysis would change if [respondents’]
interpretation were also adopted by the Minnesota Supreme Court.” Ante, at 19, n. 7. The majority also relies on its view
that respondents have not “suggested a viable alternative
construction that the Minnesota Supreme Court might adopt instead.” Ibid. To presume that the Minnesota Supreme Court would
adopt respondents’ interpretation wholesale or that it could not
provide a construction of its own that is “capable of reasoned
application,” ante, at 19, however, reflects precisely the
“gratuitous” “ ‘[s]peculation . . . about the
meaning of a state statute’ ” that this Court has discouraged, Arizonans for Official English , 520 U. S., at 79.
It is at least “fairly possible” that the state
court could “ascertain . . . a construction
. . . that will contain the statute within constitutional
bounds.” Id., at 78 (internal quotation marks omitted).
Ultimately, the issue comes down to the meaning of the adjective
“political,” as used to describe what constitutes a “political
badge, political button, or other political insignia.” §211B.11(1).
The word “political” is, of course, not inherently incapable of
definition. This Court elsewhere has encountered little difficulty
discerning its meaning in the context of statutes subject to First
Amendment challenges. See, e.g., Civil Service Comm’n v. Letter Carriers , 413 U. S. 548, 550–551 (1973)
(rejecting First Amendment overbreadth and vagueness challenge to
§9(a) of the Hatch Act, then codified at 5 U. S. C.
§7324(a)(2), which prohibited federal employees from taking
“ ‘an active part in political management or in political
campaigns’ ”); Broadrick v. Oklahoma , 413
U. S. 601, 602 (1973) (rejecting First Amendment overbreadth
and vagueness challenge to a similar Oklahoma law that “restricts
the political activities of the State’s classified civil
servants”).
Even here, the majority recognizes a substantial
amount of speech that “clear[ly]” qualifies as “political,” such as
“items displaying the name of a political party, items displaying
the name of a candidate, and items demonstrating support of or
opposition to a ballot question.” Ante, at 14 (internal
quotation marks omitted). The fact that the majority has some
difficulty deciphering guidance to §211B.11(1) that also proscribes
“[i]ssue oriented material designed to influence or impact voting”
and “[m]aterial promoting a group with recognizable political
views,” App. to Pet. for Cert. I–2; see ante, at 14–17, does
not mean that the statute as a whole is not subject to a
construction that falls within constitutional bounds. As this Court
has made clear in the context of the First Amendment overbreadth
doctrine, the “mere fact” that petitioners “can conceive of some
impermissible applications of [the] statute is not sufficient to
render it” unconstitutional. United States v. Williams , 553 U. S. 285, 303 (2008) (internal quotation
marks omitted). That is especially so where the state court is
capable of clarifying the boundaries of state law in a manner that
would permit the Court to engage in a comprehensive constitutional
analysis. See, e.g., Virginia v. American
Booksellers Assn., Inc. , 484 U. S. 383 (1988) (certifying
questions to the Virginia Supreme Court for clarification as to
whether a state statute was readily susceptible to a narrowing
construction that would not violate the First Amendment); Commonwealth v. American Booksellers Assn., Inc. , 236
Va. 168, 372 S. E. 2d 618 (1988) (responding to certification
with such a narrowing construction).
Furthermore, the Court also should consider the
history of Minnesota’s “implementation” of the statute in
evaluating the facial challenge here. Forsyth County v. Nationalist Movement , 505 U. S. 123, 131 (1992). That
history offers some assurance that the statute has not been
interpreted or applied in an unreasonable manner. There is no
evidence that any individual who refused to remove a political item
has been prohibited from voting, and respondents maintain that no
one has been referred for prosecution for violating the provision.
See Brief for Respondents 4, n. 2. Since the political apparel
ban was enacted in the late 19th century, this is the first time
the statute has been challenged on the basis that certain speech is
not “political.” Tr. of Oral Arg. 44. Even then, petitioners’
as-applied challenge was rejected by the District Court and the
Court of Appeals for the Eighth Circuit. See Minnesota
Majority v. Mansky , 62 F. Supp. 3d 870, 878 (Minn.
2014); Minnesota Majority v. Mansky , 2015 WL
13636675, *12 (D Minn., Mar. 23, 2015); Minnesota Majority v. Mansky , 849 F. 3d 749, 752–753 (CA8 2017).
Petitioners did not seek review of those claims in this Court. See
Pet. for Cert. i. On the whole, the historical application of the
law helps illustrate that the statute is not so “indeterminate” so
as to “carr[y] with it ‘[t]he opportunity for abuse.’ ” Ante, at 17.
III
Especially where there are undisputedly many
constitutional applications of a state law that further weighty
state interests, the Court should be wary of invalidating a law
without giving the State’s highest court an opportunity to pass
upon it. See Babbitt , 442 U. S., at 309; Arizonans
for Official English , 520 U. S., at 79. Because the Court
declines to take the obvious step of certification in this case, I
respectfully dissent. Notes 1 See, e.g., J.
Johnson, Fight Breaks Out at Polling Place (Nov. 8, 2016)
(describing a fight in which a voter sprayed pepper spray at a
campaign volunteer who allegedly had been handing out campaign
materials),
http://www.wpbf.com/article/fight-breaks-out-at-polling-place/8258506
(all Internet materials as last visited June 8, 2018); R. Reilly, A
Guy in a Trump Shirt Carried a Gun Outside of a Virginia Polling
Place. Authorities Say That’s Fine (Nov. 4, 2016) (describing a man
wearing a shirt bearing the name of a candidate and carrying a
weapon outside of a polling place),
https://www.huffingtonpost.com/entry/trump-supporter - gun -voter-intimidation-virginia_us_581cf16ee4b0aac624846eb5;
Houston Chronicle, Nov. 5, 2012, p. 2 (reporting that
individuals wearing shirts bearing the name of a racial equality
organization allegedly were “disruptive,” “took over” a polling
place, and were “electioneering and voicing support” for a
particular candidate); Orlando Sentinel, Nov. 8, 2006, p. A5
(reporting arrest of a poll worker who was “charged with assault
and interfering with an election after allegedly choking a voter
and pushing him out the door”); Orlando Sentinel, Mar. 2, 2005,
p. B1 (reporting “[s]houting matches and rowdy behavior” and
“harass[ment] and intimidat[ion] at the polls”). | The Supreme Court of the United States ruled that a Minnesota law banning voters from wearing political badges, buttons, or insignia inside polling places on Election Day violates the Free Speech Clause of the First Amendment. The Court found that the law was overly broad and could be interpreted to prohibit a wide range of expression, including non-political speech. The Court also noted that there are other ways to maintain order and decorum in polling places without restricting voters' freedom of expression. |
Free Speech | City of Austin v. Reagan National Advertising of Austin | https://supreme.justia.com/cases/federal/us/596/20-1029/ | NOTICE: This opinion is subject to
formal revision before publication in the preliminary print of the
United States Reports. Readers are requested to notify the Reporter
of Decisions, Supreme Court of the United States, Washington,
D. C. 20543, of any typographical or other formal errors, in
order that corrections may be made before the preliminary print
goes to press.
SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES
_________________
No. 20–1029
_________________
City of Austin, Texas, PETITIONER v. Reagan National Advertising of Austin, LLC, et al.
on writ of certiorari to the united states
court of appeals for the fifth circuit
[April 21, 2022]
Justice Sotomayor delivered the opinion of the
Court.
Like thousands of jurisdictions around the
country, the City of Austin, Texas (City), regulates signs that
advertise things that are not located on the same premises as the
sign, as well as signs that direct people to offsite locations.
These are known as off-premises signs, and they include, most
notably, billboards. The question presented is whether, under this
Court’s precedents interpreting the Free Speech Clause of the First
Amendment, the City’s regulation is subject to strict scrutiny. We
hold that it is not.
I
A
American jurisdictions have regulated outdoor
advertisements for well over a century. See C. Taylor & W.
Chang, The History of Outdoor Advertising Regulation in the United
States, 15 J. of Macromarketing 47, 48 (Spring 1995). By some
accounts, the proliferation of conspicuous patent-medicine
advertisements on rocks and barns prompted States to begin
regulating outdoor advertising in the late 1860s. Ibid. ; F.
Presbrey, The History and Development of Advertising 500–501
(1929). As part of this regulatory tradition, federal, state, and
local governments have long distinguished between signs (such as
billboards) that promote ideas, products, or services located
elsewhere and those that promote or identify things located onsite.
For example, this Court in 1932 reviewed and approved of a Utah
statute that prohibited signs advertising cigarettes and related
products, but allowed businesses selling such products to post
onsite signs identifying themselves as dealers. Packer Corp. v. Utah , 285 U.S.
105 , 107, 110.
On-/off-premises distinctions, like the one at
issue here, proliferated following the enactment of the Highway
Beautification Act of 1965 (Act), 23 U. S. C. §131. In
the Act, Congress directed States receiving federal highway funding
to regulate outdoor signs in proximity to federal highways, in part
by limiting off-premises signs. See §§131(b)–(c) (allowing
exceptions for “signs, displays, and devices advertising the sale
or lease of property upon which they are located” and “signs,
displays, and devices . . . advertising activities
conducted on the property on which they are located”). Under the
Act, approximately two-thirds of States have implemented similar
on-/off-premises distinctions. See App. A to Reply to Brief in
Opposition (collecting statutes); Brief for State of Florida
et al. as Amici Curiae 7, n. 3 (same). The City
represents, and respondents have not disputed, that “tens of
thousands of municipalities nationwide” have adopted analogous
on-/off-premises distinctions in their sign codes. Brief for
Petitioner 19; see also App. B to Reply to Brief in Opposition
(collecting examples of ordinances); Brief for State of Florida
et al. as Amici Curiae 8, n. 4 (same).
The City of Austin is one such municipality. The
City distinguishes between on-premises and off-premises signs in
its sign code, and specially regulates the latter, in order to
“protect the aesthetic value of the city and to protect public
safety.” App. 39.
During the time period relevant to this dispute,
the City’s sign code defined the term “off-premise sign” to mean “a
sign advertising a business, person, activity, goods, products, or
services not located on the site where the sign is installed, or
that directs persons to any location not on that site.” Austin,
Tex., City Code §25–10–3(11) (2016). This definition was materially
analogous to the one used in the federal Highway Beautification Act
and many other state and local codes referenced above. The code
prohibited the construction of any new off-premises signs,
§25–10–102(1), but allowed existing off-premises signs to remain as
grandfathered “non-conforming signs,” §25–10–3(10). An owner of a
grandfathered off-premises sign could “continue or maintain [it] at
its existing location” and could change the “face of the sign,” but
could not “increase the degree of the existing nonconformity,”
“change the method or technology used to convey a message,” or
“increase the illumination of the sign.” §§25–10–152(A)–(B). By
contrast, the code permitted the digitization of on-premises signs.
§25–10–102(6) (permitting “electronically controlled
changeable-copy sign[s]”).[ 1 ]
B
Respondents, Reagan National Advertising of
Austin, LLC (Reagan), and Lamar Advantage Outdoor Company,
L. P. (Lamar), are outdoor-advertising companies that own
billboards in Austin. In April and June of 2017, Reagan sought
permits from the City to digitize some of its off-premises
billboards. The City denied the applications. Reagan filed suit
against the City in state court alleging that the code’s
prohibition against digitizing off-premises signs, but not
on-premises signs, violated the Free Speech Clause of the First
Amendment. The City removed the case to federal court, and Lamar
intervened as a plaintiff.[ 2 ]
After the parties stipulated to the pertinent
facts, the District Court held a bench trial and entered judgment
in favor of the City. 377 F. Supp. 3d 670, 673, 683 (WD Tex.
2019). As relevant, the court held that the challenged sign code
provisions were content neutral under Reed v. Town of
Gilbert , 576 U.S. 155 (2015). The court explained that “the
on/off premises distinction [did] not impose greater restrictions
for political messages, religious messages, or any other subject
matter,” and “d[id] not require a viewer to evaluate the topic,
idea, or viewpoint on the sign”; instead, it required the viewer
only “to determine whether the subject matter is located on the
same property as the sign.” 377 F. Supp. 3d, at 681. The court
therefore held that the distinction was a facially content-neutral
“regulation based on location.” Ibid. The court further
found “no evidence in the record” that the City had applied the
sign code provisions “differently for different messages or
speakers” or that its stated concern for esthetics and safety was
“pretext for any other purpose.” Id., at 681–682.
Accordingly, the court reviewed the City’s on-/off-premises
distinction under the standard of intermediate scrutiny applicable
to content-neutral regulations of speech. Id., at 682. The
court found that the distinction satisfied this standard. Id., at 682–683.
The Court of Appeals reversed. 972 F.3d 696, 699
(CA5 2020). The court opined that because the City’s
on-/off-premises distinction required a reader to inquire “who is
the speaker and what is the speaker saying,” “both hallmarks of a
content-based inquiry,” the distinction was content based. Id., at 706. It reasoned that “[t]he fact that a government
official ha[s] to read a sign’s message to determine the sign’s
purpose [i]s enough to” render a regulation content based and
“subject [it] to strict scrutiny.” Ibid. (citing Thomas v. Bright , 937 F.3d 721, 730–731 (CA6 2019));
see also 972 F. 3d, at 704 (“To determine whether a sign is
on-premises or off-premises, one must read the sign . . .
”). The court acknowledged that its interpretation of Reed was “broad,” but reasoned that the consequences were “not
. . . unforeseen,” given the concerns raised by Justices
who did not join the opinion of the Court. 972 F. 3d, at
707.
Because the Court of Appeals determined that the
City’s on-/off-premises distinction imposed a content-based
restriction on speech, it reviewed that distinction under the
onerous standard of strict scrutiny. Recognizing that strict
scrutiny “is, understandably, a hard standard to meet” and that it
“leads to almost certain legal condemnation,” id., at 709,
the court held that the City’s justifications for the distinction
could not meet that standard, rendering it unconstitutional, id., at 709–710.[ 3 ]
This Court granted certiorari. 594 U. S.
___ (2021).
II
A regulation of speech is facially content
based under the First Amendment if it “target[s] speech based on
its communicative content”—that is, if it “applies to particular
speech because of the topic discussed or the idea or message
expressed.” Reed , 576 U. S., at 163. The Court of
Appeals interpreted Reed to mean that if “[a] reader must
ask: who is the speaker and what is the speaker saying” to apply a
regulation, then the regulation is automatically content based. 972
F. 3d, at 706. This rule, which holds that a regulation cannot
be content neutral if it requires reading the sign at issue, is too
extreme an interpretation of this Court’s precedent. Unlike the
regulations at issue in Reed , the City’s off-premises
distinction requires an examination of speech only in service of
drawing neutral, location-based lines. It is agnostic as to
content. Thus, absent a content-based purpose or justification, the
City’s distinction is content neutral and does not warrant the
application of strict scrutiny.
A
The Reed Court confronted a very
different regulatory scheme than the one at issue here: a
comprehensive sign code that “single[d] out specific subject matter
for differential treatment.” 576 U. S., at 169. The town of
Gilbert, Arizona, had adopted a code that applied distinct size,
placement, and time restrictions to 23 different categories of
signs. Id., at 159. The Court focused its analysis on three
categories defined by whether the signs displayed ideological,
political, or certain temporary directional messages. The code gave
the most favorable treatment to “ ‘Ideological
Sign[s],’ ” defined as those “ ‘communicating a message
or ideas for noncommercial purposes’ ” with certain
exceptions. Id., at 159–160 (alteration in original). It
offered less favorable treatment to “ ‘Political
Sign[s],’ ” defined as those “ ‘designed to influence the
outcome of an election.’ ” Id., at 160 (alteration in
original). Most restricted of all were “ ‘Temporary
Directional Signs Relating to a Qualifying Event,’ ” with
qualifying events defined as gatherings “ ‘sponsored,
arranged, or promoted by a religious, charitable, community
service, educational, or other similar non-profit
organization.’ ” Id., at 160–161.
The Reed Court determined that these
restrictions were facially content based. Id., at 164–165.
Rejecting the contention that the restrictions were content neutral
because they did not discriminate on the basis of viewpoint, the
Court explained: “[I]t is well established that ‘[t]he First
Amendment’s hostility to content-based regulation extends not only
to restrictions on particular viewpoints, but also to prohibition
of public discussion of an entire topic.’ ” Id., at 169
(quoting Consolidated Edison Co. of N. Y. v. Public
Serv. Comm’n of N. Y. , 447 U.S.
530 , 537 (1980)); accord, e.g., Police Dept. of
Chicago v. Mosley , 408 U.S.
92 , 95 (1972) (explaining that “[t]he central problem” with a
municipality’s effort to exempt labor picketing from a prohibition
on picketing near public schools was “that it describes permissible
picketing in terms of its subject matter”); Carey v. Brown , 447 U.S.
455 , 460–461 (1980) (subjecting a similar statute that
“accord[ed] preferential treatment to the expression of views on
one particular subject” to strict scrutiny).[ 4 ] Applying these principles, the Court reasoned
that “a speech regulation targeted at specific subject matter is
content based even if it does not discriminate among viewpoints
within that subject matter. . . . For example, a law
banning the use of sound trucks for political speech—and only
political speech—would be a content-based regulation, even if it
imposed no limits on the political viewpoints that could be
expressed.” 576 U. S., at 169. By treating ideological
messages more favorably than political messages, and both more
favorably than temporary directional messages, “[t]he Town’s Sign
Code likewise single[d] out specific subject matter for
differential treatment, even if it [did] not target viewpoints
within that subject matter.” Ibid. In this case, enforcing the City’s challenged
sign code provisions requires reading a billboard to determine
whether it directs readers to the property on which it stands or to
some other, offsite location. Unlike the sign code at issue in Reed , however, the City’s provisions at issue here do not
single out any topic or subject matter for differential treatment.
A sign’s substantive message itself is irrelevant to the
application of the provisions; there are no content-discriminatory
classifications for political messages, ideological messages, or
directional messages concerning specific events, including those
sponsored by religious and nonprofit organizations. Rather, the
City’s provisions distinguish based on location: A given sign is
treated differently based solely on whether it is located on the
same premises as the thing being discussed or not. The message on
the sign matters only to the extent that it informs the sign’s
relative location. The on-/off-premises distinction is therefore
similar to ordinary time, place, or manner restrictions. Reed does not require the application of strict scrutiny to
this kind of location-based regulation. Cf. Frisby v. Schultz , 487 U.S.
474 , 482 (1988) (sustaining an ordinance that prohibited “only
picketing focused on, and taking place in front of, a particular
residence” as content neutral).
B
This Court’s First Amendment precedents and
doctrines have consistently recognized that restrictions on speech
may require some evaluation of the speech and nonetheless remain
content neutral.
Most relevant here, the First Amendment allows
for regulations of solicitation—that is, speech “requesting or
seeking to obtain something” or “[a]n attempt or effort to gain
business.” Black’s Law Dictionary 1677 (11th ed. 2019). To identify
whether speech entails solicitation, one must read or hear it
first. Even so, the Court has reasoned that restrictions on
solicitation are not content based and do not inherently present
“the potential for becoming a means of suppressing a particular
point of view,” so long as they do not discriminate based on topic,
subject matter, or viewpoint. Heffron v. International
Soc. for Krishna Consciousness, Inc. , 452
U.S. 640 , 649 (1981).
Thus, in 1940, the Court invalidated a statute
prohibiting solicitation for religious causes but observed that
States were “free to regulate the time and manner of solicitation
generally, in the interest of public safety, peace, comfort or
convenience.” Cantwell v. Connecticut , 310 U.S.
296 , 306–307. Decades later, the Court reviewed just such a
time, place, and manner regulation restricting all solicitation at
the Minnesota State Fair, as well as all sale or distribution of
merchandise, to a specific location. Heffron , 452
U. S., at 643–644. The State had applied the restriction
against a religious practice that included “solicit[ing] donations
for the support of the Krishna religion.” Id., at 645. As a
result, members of the religion were free to roam the fairgrounds
and discuss their beliefs, but they were prohibited from asking for
donations for their cause outside of a designated location. Id., at 646, 655. The Court upheld the State’s application
of this restriction as content neutral, emphasizing that it
“applie[d] evenhandedly to all who wish[ed] . . . to
solicit funds,” whether for “commercial or charitable” reasons. Id., at 649.
Consistent with these precedents, the Court has
previously understood distinctions between on-premises and
off-premises signs, like the one at issue in this case, to be
content neutral. In 1978, the Court summarily dismissed an appeal
“for want of a substantial federal question” where a state court
had approved of an on-/off-premises distinction as a permissible
time, place, and manner restriction under the Free Speech Clause. Suffolk Outdoor Advertising Co. v. Hulse , 439 U.S.
808 (1978). Three years later, the Court upheld in relevant part an
ordinance that prohibited all off-premises commercial advertising
but allowed on-premises commercial advertising. Metromedia,
Inc. v. San Diego , 453 U.S.
490 , 503–512 (1981) (plurality opinion).[ 5 ] The Metromedia Court did not need to
decide whether the off-premises prohibition was content based, as
it regulated only commercial speech and so was subject to
intermediate scrutiny in any event. See id., at 507–512
(citing Central Hudson Gas & Elec. Corp. v. Public
Serv. Comm’n of N. Y. , 447 U.S.
557 (1980)). Shortly thereafter, however, the Court applied the
relevant portion of Metromedia and described the
off-premises prohibition as “a content-neutral prohibition
against the use of billboards.” Members of City Council of Los
Angeles v. Taxpayers for Vincent , 466 U.S.
789 , 807 (1984) (emphasis added).
Underlying these cases and others is a rejection
of the view that any examination of speech or expression
inherently triggers heightened First Amendment concern. Rather, it
is regulations that discriminate based on “the topic discussed or
the idea or message expressed” that are content based. Reed ,
576 U. S., at 171. The sign code provisions challenged here do
not discriminate on those bases.
C
Reagan does not claim Reed expressly or
implicitly overturned the precedents discussed above. Its argument
relies primarily on one sentence in Reed recognizing that
“[s]ome facial distinctions based on a message are obvious,
defining regulated speech by particular subject matter, and others
are more subtle, defining regulated speech by its function or
purpose.” Id., at 163. Seizing on this reference, Reagan
asserts that the City’s sign code “defines off- premises signs
based on their ‘function or purpose.’ ” Brief for Respondent
Reagan 20 (quoting Reed , 576 U. S., at 163). It asks
the Court to “reaffirm that, where a regulation ‘define[s]
regulated speech by its function or purpose,’ it is content-based
on its face and thus subject to strict scrutiny.” Brief for
Respondent Reagan 34 (quoting Reed , 576 U. S., at
163).
The argument stretches Reed ’s “function
or purpose” language too far. The principle the Reed Court
articulated is more straightforward. While overt subject-matter
discrimination is facially content based (for example,
“ ‘Ideological Sign[s],’ ” defined as those
“ ‘communicating a message or ideas for noncommercial
purposes’ ”), so, too, are subtler forms of discrimination
that achieve identical results based on function or purpose (for
example, “ ‘Political Sign[s],’ ” defined as those
“ ‘designed to influence the outcome of an election’ ”). Id., at 159, 160, 163–164 (alterations in original). In
other words, a regulation of speech cannot escape classification as
facially content based simply by swapping an obvious subject-matter
distinction for a “function or purpose” proxy that achieves the
same result. That does not mean that any classification that
considers function or purpose is always content based. Such
a reading of “function or purpose” would contravene numerous
precedents, including many of those discussed above. Reed did not purport to cast doubt on these cases.
Nor did Reed cast doubt on the Nation’s
history of regulating off-premises signs. Off-premises billboards
of the sort that predominate today were not present in the founding
era, but as large outdoor advertisements proliferated in the 1800s,
regulation followed. As early as 1932, the Court had already
approved a location-based differential for advertising signs. See Packer Corp. , 285 U. S., at 107, 110. Thereafter, for
the last 50-plus years, federal, state, and local jurisdictions
have repeatedly relied upon on-/off- premises distinctions to
address the distinct safety and esthetic challenges posed by
billboards and other methods of outdoor advertising. See supra, at 2. The unbroken tradition of on-/off-premises
distinctions counsels against the adoption of Reagan’s novel rule.
See Williams-Yulee v. Florida Bar , 575 U.S. 433, 446
(2015) (recognizing “history and tradition of regulation” as
relevant when considering the scope of the First
Amendment).[ 6 ]
D
Tellingly, even today’s dissent appears
reluctant to embrace the read-the-sign rule adopted by the court
below. Instead, the dissent attacks a straw man. Contrary to its
accusations, we do not “nullif[y]” Reed ’s protections,
“resuscitat[e]” a decision that we do not cite, or fashion a novel
“specificity test” simply by quoting the standard repeatedly
enunciated in Reed . Post, at 9, 11, 21 (opinion of
Thomas, J.). Nor do we cast doubt on any of our precedents
recognizing examples of topic or subject-matter discrimination as
content based. See, e.g., post, at 9–10. We merely
apply those precedents to reach the “commonsense” result that a
location-based and content-agnostic on-/off-premises distinction
does not, on its face, “singl[e] out specific subject matter for
differential treatment.” Reed , 576 U. S., at 163,
169.
It is the dissent that would upend settled
understandings of the law. Where we adhere to the teachings of
history, experience, and precedent, the dissent would hold that
tens of thousands of jurisdictions have presumptively violated the
First Amendment, some for more than half a century, and that they
have done so by use of an on-/off-premises distinction this Court
has repeatedly reviewed and never previously questioned. For the
reasons we have explained, the Constitution does not require that
bizarre result.
III
This Court’s determination that the City’s
ordinance is facially content neutral does not end the First
Amendment inquiry. If there is evidence that an impermissible
purpose or justification underpins a facially content-neutral
restriction, for instance, that restriction may be content based.
See Reed , 576 U. S., at 164. Moreover, to survive
intermediate scrutiny, a restriction on speech or expression must
be “ ‘narrowly tailored to serve a significant governmental
interest.’ ” Ward v. Rock Against Racism , 491 U.S.
781 , 791 (1989).
The parties dispute whether the City can satisfy
these requirements. This Court, however, is “a court of final
review and not first view,” and it does not “[o]rdinarily
. . . decide in the first instance issues not decided
below.” Zivotofsky v. Clinton , 566 U.S.
189 , 201 (2012) (internal quotation marks omitted). “In
particular, when we reverse on a threshold question, we typically
remand for resolution of any claims the lower courts’ error
prevented them from addressing.” Ibid. Because the Court of
Appeals did not address these issues, the Court leaves them for
remand and expresses no view on the matters.
* * *
For these reasons, the judgment of the Court
of Appeals for the Fifth Circuit is reversed, and the case is
remanded for further proceedings consistent with this opinion.
It is so ordered. Notes 1 The City subsequently
amended its sign code. The parties agree that the amendments do not
affect this dispute. Reply to Brief in Opposition 11–12; Brief for
Respondent Reagan 9. 2 Lamar did not participate
in the proceedings on the merits before this Court. Brief for
Respondent Reagan II. 3 The Court of Appeals
further considered the possibility that the code provisions
regulated only commercial speech, such that only intermediate
scrutiny would apply even if the provisions were content based. 972
F. 3d, at 707–709; see Central Hudson Gas & Elec.
Corp. v. Public Serv. Comm’n of N. Y. , 447 U.S.
557 , 566 (1980). The court rejected this view because the
provisions “applie[d] with equal force to both commercial and
noncommercial messages.” 972 F. 3d, at 709. Before this Court,
the City makes a similar argument, claiming that “[a]s applied to
billboards like those owned by respondents,” the contested code
provisions regulate commercial speech and so are subject to
intermediate scrutiny. Brief for Petitioner 49. It is undisputed,
however, that Reagan’s billboards also display noncommercial
messages, meaning that the City’s denial of Reagan’s applications
for digitization implicated Reagan’s commercial and noncommercial
speech alike. See Brief for Respondent Reagan 45–46; App. 130–141.
More importantly, as the Court of Appeals explained, the contested
code provisions admit of no exception for noncommercial speech. The
only way in which they differentiate speech is by distinguishing
between on-premises and off-premises signs. The Court thus must
determine which level of scrutiny applies to the manner in which
the provisions actually regulate speech. 4 The concurrence in Reed , which spoke for three of the six Justices in the
majority, similarly explained that “[c]ontent-based laws merit
th[e] protection” of strict scrutiny “because they present, albeit
sometimes in a subtler form, the same dangers as laws that regulate
speech based on viewpoint. Limiting speech based on its ‘topic’ or
‘subject’ favors those who do not want to disturb the status quo.
Such regulations may interfere with democratic self-government and
the search for truth.” 576 U. S., at 174 (Alito, J.,
concurring) (quoting Consolidated Edison Co. of N. Y. , 447
U. S., at 537). 5 Although the opinion in Metromedia was labeled a plurality for four Justices, the
relevant portion of the opinion was also joined by a fifth. See 453
U. S., at 541 (Stevens, J., dissenting in part) (“join[ing]
Parts I through IV of Justice White’s opinion”). 6 The Court of Appeals, for
its part, understood Reed to have deemed a regulation
content based solely because “it ‘single[d] out signs bearing a
particular message: the time and location of a specific
event.’ ” 972 F.3d 696, 706 (CA5 2020) (quoting Reed ,
576 U. S., at 171). Reagan does not rely as heavily on this
language, and for good reason. As a preliminary matter, the Reed Court found that the provisions at issue in that case
did not, in fact, “hinge on ‘whether and when an event is
occurring.’ ” Id., at 170. More fundamentally, those
provisions did not target all events generally, regardless of
topic; they targeted “a specific event” (an election) “because of
the topic discussed or the idea or message expressed” (political
speech). Id., at 171. The Court of Appeals’ contrary reading
would render the majority opinion in Reed irreconcilable
with the concurrence, which recognized that “[r]ules imposing time
restrictions on signs advertising a one-time event,” which “do not
discriminate based on topic or subject,” would be content neutral. Id., at 174, 175 (Alito, J., concurring). SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES
_________________
No. 20–1029
_________________
City of Austin, Texas, PETITIONER v. Reagan National Advertising of Austin, LLC, et al.
on writ of certiorari to the united states
court of appeals for the fifth circuit
[April 21, 2022]
Justice Breyer, concurring. Reed v. Town of Gilbert , 576 U.S.
155 (2015), is binding precedent here. Given that precedent, I join
the majority’s opinion. I write separately because I continue to
believe that the Court’s reasoning in Reed was wrong. The
Court there struck down a city’s sign ordinance under the First
Amendment. It wrote that the First Amendment requires strict
scrutiny whenever a regulation “target[s] speech based on its
communicative content.” Id., at 163. It therefore concluded
that “[c]ontent-based laws . . . are presumptively
unconstitutional and may be justified only if the government proves
that they are narrowly tailored to serve compelling state
interests.” Ibid. But the First Amendment is not the Tax Code. Its
purposes are often better served when judge-made categories (like
“content discrimination”) are treated, not as bright-line rules,
but instead as rules of thumb. And, where strict scrutiny’s harsh
presumption of unconstitutionality is at issue, it is particularly
important to avoid jumping to such presumptive conclusions without
first considering “whether the regulation at issue works harm to
First Amendment interests that is disproportionate in light of the
relevant regulatory objectives.” Id., at 179 (Breyer, J.,
concurring in judgment); Barr v. American Assn. of
Political Consultants, Inc. , 591 U. S. ___, ___–___ (2020)
(Breyer, J., concurring in judgment and dissenting in part) (slip
op., at 9–10); Sorrell v. IMS Health Inc. , 564 U.S.
552 , 582 (2011) (Breyer, J., dissenting). Here, I would
conclude that the City of Austin’s (City’s) regulation of
off-premises signs works no such disproportionate harm. I therefore
agree with the majority’s conclusion that strict scrutiny and its
attendant presumption of unconstitutionality are unwarranted. The
majority reaches this conclusion by applying Reed ’s formal
framework, as stare decisis requires. I would add that Reed ’s strict formalism can sometimes disserve the very
First Amendment interests it was designed to protect.
I
The First Amendment helps to safeguard what
Justice Holmes described as a marketplace of ideas. Abrams v. United States, 250 U.S.
616 , 630 (1919) (dissenting opinion). A democratic people must
be able to freely “generate, debate, and discuss both general and
specific ideas, hopes, and experiences.” Barr , 591
U. S., at ___ (opinion of Breyer, J.) (slip op., at 3). They
“must then be able to transmit their resulting views and
conclusions to their elected representatives, which they may do
directly, or indirectly through the shaping of public opinion.” Ibid. Those representatives can respond by turning the
people’s ideas into policies. The First Amendment, by protecting
the “marketplace” and the “transmission” of ideas, thereby helps to
protect the basic workings of democracy itself. See Meyer v. Grant , 486 U.S.
414 , 421 (1988) (“The First Amendment was ‘fashioned to assure
unfettered interchange of ideas for the bringing about of political
and social changes desired by the people’ ”).
Courts help to protect these democratic values
in part by strictly scrutinizing certain categories of laws that
threaten to “ ‘drive certain ideas or viewpoints from the
marketplace.’ ” R. A. V. v. St. Paul , 505 U.S.
377 , 387 (1992). We have recognized, for example, that First
Amendment values are in danger when the government imposes
restrictions upon “ ‘core political speech,’ ” Buckley v. American Constitutional Law Foundation,
Inc. , 525 U.S.
182 , 186–187 (1999); when it discriminates against “particular
views taken by speakers on a subject,” Rosenberger v. Rector and Visitors of Univ. of Va. , 515
U.S. 819 , 829–830 (1995); and, in some contexts, when it
removes “an entire topic” of discussion from public debate, Consolidated Edison Co. of N. Y. v. Public Serv.
Comm’n of N. Y. , 447 U.S.
530 , 537–538 (1980).
But not all laws that distinguish between speech
based on its content fall into a category of this kind. That is in
part because many ordinary regulatory programs may well turn on the
content of speech without posing any “realistic possibility that
official suppression of ideas is afoot.” R. A. V. ,
505 U. S., at 390. Those regulations, rather than hindering
the ability of the people to transmit their thoughts to their
elected representatives, may constitute the very product of that
transmission. Barr , 591 U. S., at ___ (opinion of
Breyer, J.) (slip op., at 4).
The U. S. Code (as well as its state and
local equivalents) is filled with regulatory laws that turn, often
necessarily, on the content of speech. Consider laws regulating
census reporting requirements, e.g., 13 U. S. C.
§224; securities- related disclosures, e.g., 15
U. S. C. §78 l ; copyright infringement, e.g., 17 U. S. C. §102; labeling of prescription
drugs, e.g., 21 U. S. C. §353(b)(4)(A), or
consumer electronics, e.g., 42 U. S. C. §6294;
highway signs, e.g., 23 U. S. C. §131(c); tax
disclosures, e.g., 26 U. S. C. §6039F;
confidential medical records, e.g., 38 U. S. C.
§7332; robocalls, e.g., 47 U. S. C. §227;
workplace safety warnings, e.g., 29 CFR §1910.145 (2021);
panhandling, e.g., Ala. Code §13A–11–9(a) (2022);
solicitation on behalf of charities, e.g., N. Y. Exec.
Law Ann. §174–b (West 2019); signs at petting zoos, e.g., N. Y. Gen. Bus. Law Ann. §399–ff(3) (West 2015); and many
more.
If Reed is taken as setting forth a
formal rule that courts must strictly scrutinize regulations simply
because they refer to particular content, we have good reason to
fear the consequences of that decision. One possibility is that
courts will strike down “ ‘entirely reasonable’ ”
regulations that reflect the will of the people. Reed , 576
U. S., at 171; e.g., Barr , 591 U. S., at
___ (slip op., at 9) (striking down the Telephone Consumer
Protection Act’s exception allowing robocalls that collect
government debt); IMDB.com v. Becerra , 962 F.3d 1111,
1125–1127 (CA9 2020) (striking down a California law prohibiting
certain websites from publishing the birthdates of entertainment
professionals). If so, the Court’s content-based line-drawing will
“substitut[e] judicial for democratic decisionmaking” and threaten
the ability of the people to translate their ideas into policy. Sorrell , 564 U. S., at 603 (Breyer, J.,
dissenting).
A second possibility is that courts instead will
(perhaps unconsciously) dilute the stringent strict scrutiny
standard in an effort to avoid striking down reasonable
regulations. Doing so would “weaken the First Amendment’s
protection in instances where ‘strict scrutiny’ should apply in
full force.” Reed , 576 U. S., at 178 (opinion of
Breyer, J.) . A third possibility is that courts will develop
a matrix of formal subsidiary rules and exceptions that seek to
distinguish between reasonable and unreasonable content-based
regulations. Such a patchwork, however, may prove overly complex,
unwieldy, or unworkable. And it may make it more difficult for
ordinary Americans to understand the importance of First Amendment
values and to live their lives in accord with those values.
For these reasons, as I have said before, I
would reject Reed’s approach, which too rigidly ties content
discrimination to strict scrutiny (and, consequently, to “almost
certain legal condemnation”). Id. , at 176. Instead, I would
treat content discrimination as a rule of thumb to be applied with
what Justice Kagan has called “a dose of common sense.” Id., at 183 (opinion concurring in judgment). Where content-based
regulations are at issue, I would ask a more basic First Amendment
question: Does “the regulation at issue wor[k] harm to First
Amendment interests that is disproportionate in light of the
relevant regulatory objectives”? Id., at 179 (opinion of
Breyer, J.). I believe we should answer that question by examining
“the seriousness of the harm to speech, the importance of the
countervailing objectives, the extent to which the law will achieve
those objectives, and whether there are other, less restrictive
ways of doing so.” Ibid. II
The regulation at issue in this case is the
City of Austin’s sign code, which regulates billboards and other
“off- premises” signs. The City defines an “off-premises” sign as
“a sign advertising a business, person, activity, goods, products,
or services not located on the site where the sign is installed, or
that directs persons to any location not on that site.” Austin,
Tex., City Code §25–10–3(11) (2016).
Some years ago, the City forbid construction of
new off-premises signs. §25–10–102(1). At the same time, it
grandfathered in existing off-premises signs, allowing them to
remain but subjecting them to regulation. §§25–10–3(10),
25–10–152(A), (B). Owners of grandfathered off-premises signs are
allowed to change the face of their signs, but not to digitize
them. Ibid. In the case before us, owners who wanted to
digitize their off-premises signs challenged the City’s regulation
on the ground that it violates the First Amendment.
The Court remands for the lower courts to assess
the constitutionality of this regulation in the first instance, so
I need not answer that question conclusively now. I wish only to
illustrate why I believe a strong presumption of unlawfulness is
out of place here.
Billboards and other roadside signs can
generally be categorized as a form of outdoor advertising.
Regulation of outdoor advertising in order to protect the public’s
interest in “avoiding visual clutter,” Members of City Council
of Los Angeles v. Taxpayers for Vincent , 466 U.S.
789 , 806 (1984), or minimizing traffic risks, Metromedia,
Inc. v. San Diego , 453 U.S.
490 , 507–508 (1981), is unlikely to interfere significantly
with the “marketplace of ideas.” In this case, for example, there
is no evidence that the City regulated off-premises signs in order
to censor a particular viewpoint or topic, or that its regulations
have had that effect in practice. There is consequently little
reason to apply a presumption of unconstitutionality to this kind
of regulation.
Without such a presumption, I would weigh the
First Amendment harms that a regulation imposes against the
regulatory objectives that it serves. The City’s regulation here
appears to work at most a limited, niche-like harm to First
Amendment interests. Respondents own a number of grandfathered
off-premises signs. They can use those signs to communicate
whatever messages they choose. They complain only that they cannot
digitize the signs, which would allow them to display several
messages in rapid succession. Perhaps digitization would enable
them to make more effective use of their billboard space. But their
inability to maximize the use of their space in this way is
unlikely to meaningfully interfere with their participation in the
“marketplace of ideas.”
At the same time, the City has asserted a
legitimate interest in maintaining the regulation. As I have said,
the public has an interest in ensuring traffic safety and
preserving an esthetically pleasing environment, supra this
page, and the City here has reasonably explained how its regulation
of off-premises signs in general, and digitization in particular,
serves those interests. Amici tell us that billboards,
especially digital ones, can distract drivers and cause accidents.
See, e.g., Brief for United States as Amicus Curiae 21 (citing a study of 450 crashes in Alabama and Florida that
“revealed that the presence of digital billboards increased the
overall crash rates in areas of billboard influence”); Brief for
National League of Cities et al. as Amici Curiae 22
(“ ‘The Wisconsin Department of Transport found a 35% increase
in collisions near a variable message sign’ ” (alteration
omitted)). They add that on-premises signs are less likely to cause
accidents. Id., at 23 (“[A] 2014 study found no evidence
that on premises digital signs led to an increase in crashes”). The
City further says that billboards cause more visual clutter than
on-premises signs because the latter are “typically ‘small in size’
and integrated into the premises.” Reply Brief 19.
I would leave for the courts below to weigh
these harms and interests, and any alternatives, in the first
instance, without a strong presumption of unconstitutionality. SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES
_________________
No. 20–1029
_________________
City of Austin, Texas, PETITIONER v. Reagan National Advertising of Austin, LLC, et al.
on writ of certiorari to the united states
court of appeals for the fifth circuit
[April 21, 2022]
Justice Alito, concurring in the judgment in
part and dissenting in part.
I agree with the majority that we must reverse
the decision of the Court of Appeals holding that the provisions of
the Austin City Code regulating on- and off-premises signs are
facially unconstitutional. Ante , at 6. The Court of Appeals
reasoned that those provisions impose content-based restrictions
and that they cannot satisfy strict scrutiny, but the Court of
Appeals did not apply the tests that must be met before a law is
held to be facially unconstitutional. “Normally, a plaintiff
bringing a facial challenge must ‘establish that no set of
circumstances exists under which the [law] would be valid,’ or show
that the law lacks ‘a plainly legitimate sweep.’ ” Americans for Prosperity Foundation v. Bonta , 594
U. S. ___, ___ (2021) (slip op., at 15) (citation omitted). A
somewhat less demanding test applies when a law affects freedom of
speech. Under our First Amendment “overbreadth” doctrine, a law
restricting speech is unconstitutional “if a substantial number of
its applications are unconstitutional, judged in relation to the
statute’s plainly legitimate sweep.” United States v. Stevens , 559 U.S.
460 , 473 (2010) (internal quotation marks omitted).
In this case, the Court of Appeals did not apply
either of those tests, and it is doubtful that they can be met.
Many (and possibly the great majority) of the situations in which
the relevant provisions may apply involve commercial speech, and
under our precedents, regulations of commercial speech are analyzed
differently. See Sorrell v. IMS Health Inc. , 564 U.S.
552 , 571–572 (2011).
It is also questionable whether those code
provisions are unconstitutional as applied to most of respondents’
billboards. It appears that most if not all of those billboards are
located off-premises in both the usual sense of that term,[ 1 ] and in the sense in which the term
is used in the Austin code. See Austin, Tex., City Code
§25–10–3(11) (2016) (a sign is off-premises if it “advertis[es] a
business, person, activity, goods, products, or services not
located on the site where the sign is installed” or if it “directs
persons to any location not on that site”). The record contains
photos of some of these billboards, see App. 130–147, and all but
one appears to be located on otherwise vacant land. Thus, they are
clearly off-premises signs, and because they were erected before
the enactment of the code provisions at issue, the only relevant
restriction they face is that they cannot be digitized.[ 2 ] The distinction between a digitized
and non-digitized sign is not based on content, topic, or subject
matter. Even if the message on a billboard were written in a secret
code, an observer would have no trouble determining whether it had
been digitized.
Because the Court of Appeals erred in holding
that the code provisions are facially unconstitutional, I agree
that we should reverse that decision. On remand, the lower courts
should determine whether those provisions are unconstitutional as
applied to each of the billboards at issue.
Today’s decision, however, goes further and
holds flatly that “[t]he sign code provisions challenged here do
not discriminate” on the basis of “ ‘the topic discussed or
the idea or message expressed,’ ” ante , at 10, and that
categorical statement is incorrect. The provisions defining on- and
off-premises signs clearly discriminate on those grounds, and at
least as applied in some situations, strict scrutiny should be
required.
As the Court notes, under the provisions in
effect when petitioner’s applications were denied, a sign was
considered to be off-premises if it “advertis[ed],” among other
things, a “person, activity, . . . or servic[e] not
located on the site where the sign is installed” or if it
“direct[ed] persons to any location not on that site.” Austin,
Tex., City Code §25–10–3(11). Consider what this definition would
mean as applied to signs posted in the front window of a commercial
establishment, say, a little coffee shop. If the owner put up a
sign advertising a new coffee drink, the sign would be classified
as on-premises, but suppose the owner instead mounted a sign in the
same location saying: “Contribute to X’s legal defense fund” or
“Free COVID tests available at Y pharmacy” or “Attend City Council
meeting to speak up about Z.” All those signs would appear to fall
within the definition of an off-premises sign and would thus be
disallowed. See also post , at 3–4 (Thomas, J., dissenting).
Providing disparate treatment for the sign about a new drink and
the signs about social and political matters constitutes
discrimination on the basis of topic or subject matter. The code
provisions adopted in 2017 are worded differently, but the new
wording may not rule out similar results.[ 3 ]
For these reasons, I would simply hold that the
provisions at issue are not facially unconstitutional, and I would
refrain from making any broader pronouncements. Notes 1 In ordinary usage, a sign
that is attached to or located in close proximity to a building is
not described as located “off-premises.” The distinction between
on- and off-premises signs is based solely on location, and that is
why such a classification is not content-based. See Reed v. Town of Gilbert , 576 U.S. 155, 175 (2015) (Alito, J.,
concurring). 2 A grandfathered sign can
be maintained at its existing location, but the owner cannot
“increase the degree of the existing nonconformity,” “change the
method or technology used to convey a message,” or “increase the
illumination of the sign.” Austin, Tex., City Code
§§25–10–152(A)–(B). 3 The amended code now
defines “off-premise[s] sign” as “a sign that displays any message
directing attention to a business, product, service, profession,
commodity, activity, event, person, institution, or other
commercial message which is generally conducted, sold,
manufactured, produced, offered, or occurs elsewhere than on the
premises where the sign is located,” and defines an “on-premise[s]
sign” as “a sign that is not an off-premise[s] sign.” Austin, Tex.,
City Code §§25–10–4(9)–(10) (2021). It is not clear that the
inclusion of “other commercial message” modifies the terms
“activity,” “event,” “person,” or “institution” such that the
provision would not draw topic-based distinctions as applied to
non-commercial speech. SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES
_________________
No. 20–1029
_________________
City of Austin, Texas, PETITIONER v. Reagan National Advertising of Austin, LLC, et al.
on writ of certiorari to the united states
court of appeals for the fifth circuit
[April 21, 2022]
Justice Thomas, with whom Justice Gorsuch and
Justice Barrett join, dissenting.
In Reed v. Town of Gilbert , 576
U.S. 155 (2015), we held that a speech regulation is content
based—and thus presumptively invalid—if it “draws distinctions
based on the message a speaker conveys.” Id. , at 163. Here,
the city of Austin imposes special restrictions on “off-premise[s]
sign[s],” defined as signs that “advertis[e] a business, person,
activity, goods, products, or services not located on the site
where the sign is installed, or that direc[t] persons to any
location not on that site.” Austin, Tex., City Code §25–10–3(11)
(2016). Under Reed , Austin’s off-premises restriction is
content based. It discriminates against certain signs based on the
message they convey— e.g. , whether they promote an on- or
off-site event, activity, or service.
The Court nevertheless holds that the
off-premises restriction is content neutral because it proscribes a
sufficiently broad category of communicative content and,
therefore, does not target a specific “topic or subject matter.” Ante , at 8. This misinterprets Reed ’s clear rule for
content-based restrictions and replaces it with an incoherent and
malleable standard. In so doing, the majority’s reasoning is
reminiscent of this Court’s erroneous decision in Hill v. Colorado , 530 U.S.
703 (2000), which upheld a blatantly content-based prohibition
on “counseling” near abortion clinics on the ground that it
discriminated against “an extremely broad category of
communications.” Id. , at 723. Because I would adhere to Reed rather than echo Hill ’s long-discredited
approach, I respectfully dissent.
I
A
The First Amendment, applicable to the States
through the Fourteenth, prohibits laws “abridging the freedom of
speech.” U. S. Const., Amdt. 1; see also Stromberg v. California , 283 U.S.
359 , 368 (1931). “When enforcing this prohibition, our
precedents distinguish between content-based and content-neutral
regulations.” National Institute of Family and Life
Advocates v. Becerra , 585 U. S. ___, ___ (2018)
(slip op., at 6). A content-based law is “presumptively invalid,” United States v. Playboy Entertainment Group , Inc. , 529 U.S.
803 , 817 (2000) (internal quotation marks omitted), and may
generally be upheld only if the government proves that the
regulation is narrowly tailored to serve compelling state
interests, R. A. V. v. St. Paul , 505 U.S.
377 , 395 (1992).[ 1 ]
In Reed v. Town of Gilbert , we
held that courts should identify content-based restrictions by
applying a “commonsense” test: A speech regulation is content based
if it
“target[s] speech based on its communicative
content.” 576 U. S., at 163. Put another way, a law is content
based “ ‘on its face’ [if it] draws distinctions based on the
message a speaker conveys.” Ibid. While we noted that
“[s]ome facial distinctions based on a message are obvious,” we
emphasized that others could be “more subtle, defining regulated
speech by its function or purpose.” Ibid . In all events,
whether a law is characterized as targeting a “topic,” “idea,”
“subject matter,” or “communicative content,” the law is content
based if it draws distinctions based in any way “on the message a
speaker conveys.” Id. , at 163–164.[ 2 ]
Applying this standard, we held that the town of
Gilbert’s sign code was “a paradigmatic example of content-based
discrimination” because it classified “various categories of signs
based on the type of information they convey[ed], [and] then
subject[ed] each category to different restrictions.” Id. ,
at 169, 159. For instance, Gilbert defined “ ‘Temporary
Directional Signs’ ” as any sign that “convey[ed] the message
of directing the public to [a] ‘qualifying event,’ ” and
permitted their display for no more than 12 hours before and 1 hour
after the event occurred. Id. , at 164, 161. Meanwhile,
“ ‘Ideological Sign[s],’ ” defined as any sign (not
covered by another category) that “ ‘communicat[ed] a message
or ideas for noncommercial purposes,’ ” were subject to no
temporal limitations. Id. , at 159–160. In short, the
restrictions on any given sign depended “on the communicative
content of the sign.” Id. , at 164. Gilbert’s sign code was
thus facially content based and presumptively unlawful. See id. , at 159.
In contrast to Reed ’s “commonsense” test,
Gilbert urged us to define “content based” as a “term of art that
‘should be applied flexibly’ with the goal of protecting
‘viewpoints and ideas from government censorship or
favoritism.’ ” Id. , at 168. Such a functionalist test,
Gilbert argued, could ferret out illicit government motives while
obviating the need to subject reasonable laws to strict scrutiny.
See ibid. We rejected Gilbert’s attempt to cast the phrase
“content based” as a “term of art” because “[i]nnocent motives do
not eliminate the danger of censorship presented by a facially
content-based statute.” Id. , at 167. We noted that “one
could easily imagine a Sign Code compliance manager who disliked
[a] Church’s substantive teachings deploying the Sign Code to make
it more difficult for the Church to inform the public of the
location of its services.” Id. , at 167–168. Thus, we
concluded that “a clear and firm rule governing content neutrality
is an essential means of protecting the freedom of speech, even if
laws that might seem entirely reasonable will sometimes be struck
down because of their content-based nature.” Id. , at 171
(internal quotation marks omitted).
We also rejected the Ninth Circuit’s reasoning
that Gilbert’s sign restrictions were content neutral because they
depended on “the content-neutral elements of . . .
whether and when an event is occurring.” Id. , at 169
(internal quotation marks omitted). That is, whether a temporary
directional sign was permissible depended, in part, on its temporal
proximity to a “ ‘qualifying event.’ ” Id. , at
164. This partial dependence on content-neutral elements was
immaterial, we explained, because the restrictions also depended on
the signs’ communicative content. Gilbert officials still had to
examine a sign’s message to determine what type of sign it was, and
this “obvious content-based inquiry d[id] not evade strict scrutiny
simply because an event [was] involved.” Id. , at 170.
B
Under Reed ’s approach for identifying
content-based regulations, Austin’s off-premises sign restriction
is content based. As relevant to this suit, Austin’s sign code
imposes stringent restrictions on a category of “off-premise[s]
sign[s].” §25–10–3(11). The code defines “off-premise[s] sign[s]”
as those “advertising a business, person, activity, goods,
products, or services not located on the site where the sign is
installed,” or as signs “direct[ing] persons to any location not on
that site.” Ibid. This broad definition sweeps in a wide
swath of signs, from 14- by 48-foot billboards to 24- by 18-inch
yard signs. The sign code prohibits new off-premises signs and
makes it difficult (or impossible) to change existing off-premises
signs, including by digitizing them. See ante , at 3.
Like the town of Gilbert in Reed , Austin
has identified a “categor[y] of signs based on the type of
information they convey, [and] then subject[ed that] category to
different restrictions.” 576 U. S., at 159. A sign that
conveys a message about off-premises activities is restricted,
while one that conveys a message about on-premises activities is
not. See id. , at 171 (regulating signs based on “a
particular message” about “the time and location of a specific
event” is content based). And, per Reed , it does not matter
that Austin’s code “defin[es] regulated speech by its function or
purpose”— i.e. , advertising or directing passersby elsewhere. Id. , at 163. Again, all that matters is that the regulation
“draws distinctions based on” a sign’s “communicative content,”
which the off-premises restriction plainly does. Ibid .
This conclusion is not undermined because the
off- premises sign restriction depends in part on a content-
neutral element: the location of the sign. Much like in Reed , that an Austin official applying the sign code must
know where the sign is does not negate the fact that he also
must know what the sign says. Take, for instance, a sign
outside a Catholic bookstore. If the sign says, “Visit the Holy
Land,” it is likely an off-premises sign because it conveys a
message directing people elsewhere (unless the name of the
bookstore is “Holy Land Books”). But if the sign instead says, “Buy
More Books,” it is likely a permissible on- premises sign (unless
the sign also contains the address of another bookstore across
town). Finally, suppose the sign says, “Go to Confession.” After
examining the sign’s message, an official would need to inquire
whether a priest ever hears confessions at that location. If one
does, the sign could convey a permissible “on-premises” message. If
not, the sign conveys an impermissible off-premises message.
Because enforcing the sign code in any of these instances “requires
[Austin] officials to determine whether a sign” conveys a
particular message, the sign code is content based under Reed . Id. , at 170.
In sum, the off-premises rule is content based
and thus invalid unless Austin can satisfy strict scrutiny. See Playboy Entertainment Group , 529 U. S., at 813. Because
Austin has offered nothing to make that showing, the Court of
Appeals did not err in holding that the off-premises rule violates
the First Amendment.
II
To reach the opposite result, the majority
implicitly rewrites Reed ’s bright-line rule for
content-based restrictions. In the majority’s view, the
off-premises restriction is not content based because it does not
target a specific “topic or subject matter.” Ante , at 8. The
upshot of the majority’s reasoning appears to be that a regulation
based on a sufficiently general or broad category of communicative
content is not actually content based.
Such a rule not only conflicts with Reed and many pre- Reed precedents but is also incoherent and
unworkable. Tellingly, the only decision that even remotely
supports the majority’s rule is one it does not cite: Hill v. Colorado . There, the Court held that an undeniably
content-based law was nonetheless content neutral because it
discriminated against “an extremely broad category of
communications,” supposedly without regard to “subject matter.” 530
U. S., at 723. The majority’s decision today is erroneous for
the same reasons that Hill is an aberration in our case
law.
A
The majority concedes that “[t]he message on
the sign matters” when applying Austin’s sign code. Ante , at
8. That concession should end the inquiry under Reed . But
the majority nonetheless finds the sign code to be content neutral
by recasting facially content-based restrictions as only those that
target sufficiently specific categories of communicative content
and not as those that depend on communicative content simpliciter .
For example, while Reed defined
content-based restrictions as those that “dra[w] distinctions based
on the message a speaker conveys,” 576 U. S., at 163
(emphasis added), the majority decides that Austin’s sign code is
not content based because it draws no distinctions based on “[a]
sign’s substantive message,” ante , at 8 (emphasis
added). Elsewhere, the majority speaks not of “substantive
message[s]” but of “topic[s] or subject matter[s],” which the
majority thinks are sufficiently specific categories of
communicative content. Ibid. As a result, the majority
contends that a law targeting directional messages concerning
“events generally, regardless of topic,” would not be content
based, but one targeting “directional messages concerning specific events” ( e.g. , “religious” or “political”
events) would be. Ante , at 12, n. 6, 8 (emphasis
added).[ 3 ] Regardless of the
label, the majority today excises, without a word of explanation, a
subset of supposedly non-substantive or unspecific messages from
the First Amendment’s protection against content-based
restrictions.
This understanding of content-based restrictions
contravenes Reed , which held that a law is content based if
it “target[s] speech based on its communicative content”—not
“specific” or “substantive” categories of communicative content.
576 U. S., at 163; see also, e.g. , Norton v. Springfield , 806 F.3d 411, 412 (CA7 2015) (“ Reed effectively abolishes any distinction between content regulation
and subject-matter regulation. Any law distinguishing one kind of
speech from another by reference to its meaning now requires a
compelling justification”). Only by jettisoning Reed ’s
“commonsense” definition of what it means to be content based can
the majority assert that the off-premises rule is strictly
“location-based” and “agnostic as to content,” ante , at 6,
even though the law undeniably depends on both location and communicative content, supra , at 5–6.
Moreover, the majority’s suggestion that laws
targeting broad categories of communicative content are not content
based is hard to square with the sign categories that Reed invalidated. For instance, we found Gilbert’s expansive definition
of “Ideological Sign[s]” to be content based even though it broadly
covered any “sign communicating a message or ideas for
noncommercial purposes” that did not already fall into one of the
other categories. 576 U. S., at 159 (internal quotation marks
omitted). Nor did we suggest that the outcome in Reed would
have been different if the sign categories were defined even more
generally.
The majority answers that it is not
“fashion[ing] a novel ‘specificity test,’ ” but instead
“simply” “quoting the standard repeatedly enunciated in Reed .” Ante , at 13. The majority finds this alleged
specificity test in a paragraph near the end of Reed , where
we noted that a law “targeted at specific subject matter is content
based even if it does not discriminate among viewpoints within that
subject matter,” and then affirmed that Gilbert’s sign code
“single[d] out specific subject matter for differential treatment.”
576 U. S., at 169.
These statements never purported to endorse a
specificity test of the sort now suggested by the majority. Read in
context, Reed ’s two references to “specific subject matter”
naturally address laws that target a “subject matter,” however
broadly defined, as opposed to some other subject matter; they did
not refer only to laws targeting some sufficiently “specific”
category of “subject matter.” Moreover, the concept of
“specificity” or “generality” appears nowhere in the part of Reed that set forth its “commonsense” test for content
neutrality. See id. , at 163–164. If Reed ’s
content-neutrality test turned on specificity, we would have said
so explicitly when stating the test. Finally, even crediting the
majority’s strained reading of Reed ’s passing references to
“specific subject matter,” the paragraph where they appear made
clear that it was describing only “a paradigmatic example of
content-based discrimination.” Id. , at 169 (emphasis added).
That part of Reed never professed to announce a
comprehensive rule with respect to all laws targeting speech based
on its communicative content.
Our pre- Reed precedents likewise
foreclose a construction of “content based” that applies only to
some content. We have held many capacious speech regulations to be
content based, including restrictions on “ ‘advice or
assistance derived from scientific, technical or other specialized
knowledge,’ ” Holder v. Humanitarian Law
Project , 561 U.S.
1 , 12–13 (2010); “ ‘advertising, promotion, or any
activity . . . used to influence sales or the market
share of a prescription drug,’ ” Sorrell v. IMS
Health Inc. , 564 U.S.
552 , 559 (2011); “editorializing,” FCC v. League of
Women Voters of Cal. , 468 U.S.
364 , 382–383, and n. 14 (1984); “ ‘[publication] for
philatelic, numismatic, educational, historical, or newsworthy
purposes,’ ” Regan v. Time , Inc. , 468 U.S.
641 , 644 (1984); and “anonymous speech,” McIntyre v. Ohio Elections Comm’n , 514 U.S.
334 , 348, 357 (1995). These speech categories are no more
“specific” or “substantive” than messages regarding off-premises
activities. And some of these examples, like “editorializing” or
publishing “newsworthy” information, are clearly less so.
What unites these speech restrictions is that their application
turns “on the nature of the message being conveyed,” Carey v. Brown , 447 U.S.
455 , 461 (1980), not whether they regulate specific or general
categories of speech, or whether they address substantive or
non-substantive categories of speech.
We have defined content-based restrictions to
include all content-based distinctions because any other
rule would be incoherent. After all, off-premises advertising could
be considered a “subject” or a “topic” as those words are
ordinarily used. See L. D. Management Co. v. Gray , 988 F.3d 836, 839 (CA6 2021) (off-premises billboard
restriction “turns on the ‘ topic discussed’ ” (emphasis
added)). And, in any event, there is no principled way to decide
whether a category of communicative content is “substantive” or
“specific” enough for the majority to deem it a “topic” or
“subject” worthy of heightened protection. Although off-premises
advertising is a more general category of speech than some
( e.g. , off-premises advertising of religious events), it is
a more specific category than others ( e.g. , advertising
generally). The majority offers only its own ipse dixit to
explain why off-premises advertising is insufficiently specific to
qualify as content based under Reed . Worse still, the
majority does not explain how courts should draw the line between a
sufficiently substantive or specific content-based classification
and one that is insufficiently substantive or specific.
On this point, Austin suggests there is no need
to worry because our cases provide “guideposts” from which one can
divine what “level of generality” renders a speech regulation
content based. Tr. of Oral Arg. 18, 24. To be sure, that is the
sort of inquiry the majority’s opaque test invites. But Reed directed us elsewhere—to the text of the law in question and
whether that law “ ‘on its face’ draws distinctions based on
the message a speaker conveys.” 576 U. S., at 163. The
majority’s holding that some rules based on content are not, as it
turns out, content based nullifies Reed ’s clear test.
B
The majority offers several reasons why its
approach is consistent with Reed and other cases. None of
these arguments is persuasive. Instead, they only serve to
underscore the Court’s ill-advised departure from our doctrine.
1
The majority first suggests that deeming
Austin’s sign code content based would require us to adopt an
“extreme” reinterpretation of Reed . Ante , at 6.
Specifically, the majority faults the Court of Appeals for
concluding that Austin’s regulation was content based because, to
enforce the off-premises rule, “ ‘[a] reader must ask: who is
the speaker and what is the speaker saying’ ”? Ibid. (quoting 972 F.3d 696, 706 (CA5 2020)). In the majority’s view, Reed cannot stand for such a simplistic read-the-sign
test.
The majority’s skepticism is misplaced. We have
often acknowledged that the need to examine the content of a
message is a strong indicator that a speech regulation is content
based. One year before Reed , for example, we stated that an
abortion clinic buffer-zone law “would be content based if it
required enforcement authorities to examine the content of the
message that is conveyed to determine whether a violation has
occurred.” McCullen v. Coakley , 573 U.S.
464 , 479 (2014) (internal quotation marks omitted). That
statement was not an outlier. See, e.g. , Arkansas
Writers’ Project , Inc. v. Ragland , 481 U.S.
221 , 230 (1987) (tax exemption for periodicals “uniformly
devoted to religion or sports” was content based because it
required state officials to “examine the content of the message”
(internal quotation marks omitted)); Forsyth County v. Nationalist Movement , 505 U.S.
123 , 134 (1992) (regulation requiring parade organizers to pay
a fee depending on the security costs anticipated for the event was
content based because “[i]n order to assess accurately the cost of
security for parade participants, the administrator must
necessarily examine the content of the message that is conveyed”
(internal quotation marks omitted)); League of Women Voters ,
468 U. S., at 366, 383 (law forbidding public broadcasting
stations from “engag[ing] in editorializing” was content based
because it required “enforcement authorities [to] necessarily
examine the content of the message that is conveyed” (internal
quotation marks omitted)).
Ultimately, the majority’s objection to the
Court of Appeals’ reliance on a read-the-sign test is a red
herring; its real objection is to Reed ’s rule that any law
that draws distinctions based on communicative content is content
based.
2
The majority next argues that Austin’s sign
code is content neutral under our precedents. See ante , at
8–10. But none of the cases the majority cites supports its crabbed
view of what constitutes a content-based restriction.
First, in Heffron v. International
Soc. for Krishna Consciousness , Inc. , 452 U.S.
640 (1981), the Court upheld, as content neutral, an ordinance
providing that the “[s]ale or distribution of any merchandise,
including printed or written material,” could occur only from
certain booths at the fairgrounds. Id. , at 643 (internal
quotation marks omitted). Such a statute is facially content
neutral under Reed because it does not “ ‘on its face’
dra[w] distinctions based on the message a speaker conveys” when
selling or distributing merchandise subject to the ordinance. 576
U. S., at 163. True, the Court construed the ordinance also to
limit “fund solicitation operations,” 452 U. S., at 644, but
that was not, as the majority claims, a prohibition on “asking for
donations,” ante , at 9. Rather, anyone was free to “as[k]
for donations” wherever he liked, because the ordinance did “not
prevent respondents from wandering throughout the fairgrounds and
directing interested donors or purchasers to their booth.” 452
U. S., at 664, n. 2 (Blackmun, J., concurring in part and
dissenting in part). Then, once “at the booth,” the donor could
“make a contribution.” Ibid. Second, in Cantwell v. Connecticut , 310 U.S.
296 (1940), the Court invalidated a licensing system for
religious and charitable solicitation while acknowledging in dicta
that a State could regulate the time, place, and manner of
solicitation. Id. , at 304, 307. But here, we are not faced
with a true time, place, or manner restriction, as even the
majority concedes. See ante , at 8.[ 4 ] And, in any event, Cantwell did not suggest
that a content-based restriction could be sustained as a time,
place, or manner restriction; its analysis focused predominantly on
the plaintiff ’s free exercise claim; and the case predated
our modern content-neutrality doctrine by nearly three decades.
Thus, nothing in Heffron or Cantwell supports the
majority’s narrow approach to identifying content-based
restrictions.
Finally, the majority argues that we have
“previously understood distinctions between on-premises and
off-premises signs . . . to be content neutral.” Ante , at 9–10. To be sure, in both Suffolk Outdoor Adv.
Co. v. Hulse , 439 U.S. 808 (1978), and Metromedia , Inc. v. San Diego , 453 U.S.
490 , 503–512 (1981) (plurality opinion), this Court suggested
that some restrictions on off-premises advertising were
constitutional. And later, in Members of City Council of Los
Angeles v. Taxpayers for Vincent , 466 U.S.
789 (1984), the Court described Metromedia as upholding
“a content- neutral prohibition against the use of
billboards.” 466 U. S., at 807 (emphasis added). But the
statement in Vincent was dictum, and, as the majority
concedes, both our summary decision in Suffolk and the
plurality opinion in Metromedia sanctioned off-premises
restrictions only insofar as they applied to commercial speech. Ante , at 10. That is, the “Court did not need to
decide”—and did not decide—“whether the off-premises prohibition
was content based” because restrictions on commercial speech are
“subject to intermediate scrutiny in any event.” Ibid. 3
The majority also claims that finding Austin’s
sign code to be content based “would render the majority opinion in Reed irreconcilable with” Justice Alito’s Reed concurrence. Ante , at 12, n. 6. In particular, Justice
Alito identified nine different types of sign regulations that he
believed “would not be content based,” including “[r]ules
distinguishing between on-premises and off-premises signs” and
“[r]ules imposing time restrictions on signs advertising a one-time
event.” 576 U. S., at 174–175. The majority evidently believes
that these two types of sign regulations necessarily turn on a
sign’s communicative content, like the off-premises sign
restriction at issue here.
That reading of the Reed concurrence
makes little sense. First, there is no reason to interpret the
concurrence as referring to off-premises or one-time-event rules
that turn on a sign’s communicative content. Doing so would make
those two rules categorically different from the other seven, none
of which would ever turn on message content. See, e.g. , id. , at 174 (“Rules distinguishing between lighted and
unlighted signs”). And although off-premises and one-time-event
rules could be drafted in terms of a sign’s communicative
content, as is true here, they need not be. “There might be many
formulations of an on/off-premises distinction that are
content-neutral.” Thomas v. Bright , 937 F.3d 721, 733
(CA6 2019); see also ante , at 2, n. 1 (Alito, J.,
concurring in judgment in part and dissenting in part) (explaining
that “[i]n ordinary usage” an “off- premises” sign is one that is
not “attached to or located in close proximity to a building”). For
instance, a city could define “ ‘an o[n]-premise[s] sign as
any sign within 500 feet of a building,’ ” 937 F. 3d, at
732, or a sign that is installed by “ ‘a business
. . . licensed to occupy . . . the premises
where the sign is located,’ ” Brief for Summus Outdoor as Amicus Curiae 10. As for regulations of one-time-event
signs, Austin itself amended its sign code, at the behest of its
lawyers, specifically to make its ordinance content neutral. See
Austin, Tex., City Code §25–10–102(D) (2021); App. 152. Thus,
interpreting Justice Alito’s concurrence as referring to rules that
turn on communicative content, as opposed to rules that are content
neutral, is unwarranted.
Second, it would be strange to interpret the
concurrence as proclaiming that all off-premises sign
restrictions are content neutral considering the longstanding
dispute over that question. In fact, 20 years before Reed ,
then-Judge Alito opined that there was “no easy answer to [the]
question” whether “exceptions for ‘for sale’ signs and signs
relating to on-site activities” would render a sign code content
based. Rappa v. New Castle County , 18 F.3d 1043 , 1080 (CA3 1994) (concurring opinion); see also, e.g. , Ackerly Communications of Mass. , Inc. v. Cambridge , 88 F.3d 33 , 36, n. 7 (CA1 1996) (“In ‘commonsense’ terms,
the distinction surely is content-based because determining whether
a sign must stay up or must come down requires consideration of the
message it carries”); Norton Outdoor Adv. , Inc. v. Arlington Heights , 69 Ohio St. 2d 539, 541, 433 N.E.2d
198, 200 (1982) (“In prohibiting all forms of offsite billboard
advertising, the ordinance is thus inescapably directed to the
content of protected speech”). Ultimately, it seems quite unlikely
that Justice Alito’s quick recital of some content-neutral rules
purported to pre-emptively decide an issue that had long perplexed
federal and state courts.
4
Near the end of its analysis, the majority
invokes an allegedly “unbroken tradition of on-/off-premises
distinctions” that it claims “counsels against” faithful
application of Reed . Ante , at 12. To be sure, history
and tradition are relevant to identifying and defining those “few
limited areas” where, “[f ]rom 1791 to the present,” “the
First Amendment has permitted restrictions upon the content of
speech.” Brown v. Entertainment Merchants Assn. , 564 U.S.
786 , 791 (2011) (internal quotation marks omitted); see supra , at 2, n. 1. But the majority openly admits that
off-premises regulations “were not present [at] the founding.” Ante , at 12. And while it asserts that “large outdoor
advertisements proliferated in the 1800s,” ibid. , it offers
no evidence of any content-based restrictions from that period, let
alone off-premises restrictions on noncommercial speech. The earliest example of an off-premises restriction that the
majority cites arose in Packer Corp. v. Utah , 285 U.S.
105 (1932), but that case involved a restriction on commercial advertising and did not even feature a First
Amendment claim. See id. , at 108–112.
Ultimately, the majority’s only “historical”
support is that regulations like Austin’s “proliferated following
the enactment of the Highway Beautification Act of 1965.” Ante , at 2. The majority’s suggestion that the First
Amendment should yield to a speech restriction that “proliferated”—
under pressure from the Federal Government—some two centuries after
the founding is both “startling and dangerous.” United
States v. Stevens , 559
U.S. 460 , 470 (2010). This Court has never hinted that the
government can, with a few decades of regulation, subject “new
categories of speech” to less exacting First Amendment scrutiny. Id. , at 472.
Regardless, even if this allegedly “unbroken
tradition” did not fall short by a century or two, the majority
offers no explanation why historical regulation is relevant to the
question whether the off-premises restriction is content based
under Reed and our modern content-neutrality jurisprudence.
If Austin had met its burden of identifying a historical tradition
of analogous regulation—as can be done, say, for obscenity or
defamation—that would not make the off-premises rule content
neutral. It might simply mean that the off-premises rule is a
constitutional form of content-based discrimination. But content
neutrality under Reed is an empirical question, not a
historical one. Thus, the majority’s historical argument is not
only meritless but misguided.
C
Despite asserting that the Court of Appeals’
analysis under Reed would “contravene numerous precedents,” ante , at 11, the majority identifies no decision of this
Court supporting the idea that a speech restriction is not content
based so long as it regulates a sufficiently broad or non-
substantive category of communicative content. In fact, there is
only one case that could possibly validate the majority’s aberrant
analysis: Hill v. Colorado . That Hill is the
majority’s only support underscores the danger that today’s
decision poses to the First Amendment. Hill involved a law that prohibited
persons outside abortion clinics from knowingly approaching within
eight feet of another person without consent “for the purpose of
. . . engaging in oral protest, education, or
counseling.” 530 U. S., at 707 (internal quotation marks
omitted). Hill concluded, implausibly, that this regulation
was content neutral.
The majority’s reasoning in this case is just as
implausible. The majority asserts that the off-premises rule is not
content based because it does not target a sufficiently “specific”
or “substantive” category of communications. Ante , at 8. Hill correspondingly held that restrictions on “protest,
education, or counseling” were not content-based classifications
because they cover “an extremely broad category of communications.”
530 U. S., at 723. The majority also tries to disguise its
redefinition of content neutrality by characterizing Austin’s rule
as a “neutral, location-based” restriction. Ante , at 6. So
too did Hill try to conceal its doctrinal innovation by
characterizing the buffer-zone law as a neutral “place
restriction.” 530 U. S., at 723. Finally, the majority finds
it immaterial that Austin’s rule can be enforced only by “reading a
[sign] to determine whether it” contains an off-premises message. Ante , at 8. Hill likewise found it irrelevant that
“the content of the oral statements” would need to “be examined to
determine whether” the prohibition applied. 530 U. S., at
720.
The parallel between the majority’s opinion and Hill should be discomforting given that Hill represented “an unprecedented departure” from this Court’s First
Amendment jurisprudence. Id. , at 772 (Kennedy, J.,
dissenting). Its content-neutrality analysis was, as Justice Scalia
explained, “absurd” given that the buffer-zone law was “obviously
and undeniably content based.” Id. , at 742–743 (dissenting
opinion). First Amendment scholars from across the ideological
spectrum agree. See, e.g. , M. McConnell, Professor Michael
W. McConnell’s Response, in K. Sullivan, Sex, Money, and Groups:
Free Speech and Association Decisions in the October 1999 Term, 28
Pepperdine L. Rev. 723, 748 (2001) (“The Court said that this
statute is content-neutral. I just literally cannot see how they
could possibly come to that conclusion”); Colloquium, id .,
at 750 (Laurence Tribe stating Hill “was slam-dunk simple
and slam-dunk wrong”); R. Fallon, Strict Judicial Scrutiny, 54 UCLA
L. Rev. 1267, 1298, and n. 174 (2007) ( Hill “unconvincingly . . . maintain[ed] that a content-based
restriction on speech [was] not really content-based”). And, since Hill , this Court has all but interred its flawed
content-neutrality analysis in both McCullen , see supra , at 11, and Reed . See Price v. Chicago , 915 F.3d 1107, 1118 (CA7 2019) (“In the wake of McCullen and Reed , it’s not too strong to say that
what Hill explicitly rejected is now prevailing law”).
The majority’s refusal to acknowledge Hill simply underscores the decision’s defunct status.
Again, Hill is the only case that could support the
majority’s ill-conceived content-neutrality analysis, and yet the
majority disclaims reliance on it. Lower courts should take the
majority’s disclaimer at face value: Hill is “a decision
that we do not cite.” Ante , at 13. And today’s decision
amounts to little more than an ad hoc exemption for the
“location-based” and supposedly “content-agnostic on-/off-premises
distinction.” Ibid .
Even so, the majority’s approach should offer
little comfort because arbitrary carveouts from Reed undermine the “clear and firm rule governing content neutrality”
that we understood to be “an essential means of protecting the
freedom of speech.” 576 U. S., at 171. The majority’s
deviation from that “clear and firm rule” poses two serious threats
to the First Amendment’s protections.
First, transforming Reed ’s clear
definition of “content based regulation” back into an opaque and
malleable “term of art” turns the concept of content neutrality
into a “vehicl[e] for the implementation of individual judges’
policy preferences.” Tennessee v. Lane , 541 U.S.
509 , 556 (2004) (Scalia, J., dissenting). Hill exemplifies this danger. See 530 U. S., at 742 (Scalia, J.,
dissenting) (“I have no doubt that this regulation would be deemed
content based in an instant if the case before us involved
antiwar protesters, or union members seeking to ‘educate’ the
public about the reasons for their strike”). The majority’s
approach in this case is cut from the same cloth. As the majority
transparently admits, it seeks to “apply [our] precedents to reach
the ‘commonsense’ result ” and avoid what it perceives as a
“bizarre result .” Ante , at 13 (emphasis added). But Reed mandates a “commonsense” test for content neutrality
even if the result is that “laws that might seem entirely
reasonable will sometimes be struck down.” 576 U. S., at 163,
171 (internal quotation marks omitted).
Second, sanctioning certain content-based
classifications but not others ignores that even seemingly
reasonable content-based restrictions are ready tools for those who
would “suppress disfavored speech.” Id ., at 167; see also Hill , 530 U. S., at 743 (Scalia, J., dissenting)
(“ ‘The vice of content-based legislation . . . is
not that it is always used for invidious, thought-control purposes,
but that it lends itself to use for those purposes’ ”). This
is because “the responsibility for distinguishing between”
permissible and impermissible content “carries with it the
potential for invidious discrimination of disfavored subjects.” Cincinnati v. Discovery Network , Inc. , 507 U.S.
410 , 423–424, n. 19 (1993). That danger only grows when
the content-based distinctions are “by no means clear,” giving more
leeway for government officials to punish disfavored speakers and
ideas. Ibid. The content-based distinction drawn by Austin’s
off-premises speech restriction is “by no means clear,” ibid. , and plainly lends itself “to suppress[ing] disfavored
speech,” Reed , 576 U. S., at 167. As the Court of
Appeals noted, Austin’s “prepared counsel” “struggled to answer
whether” signs conveying messages like “ ‘God Loves
You,’ ” “ ‘Vote for Kathy,’ ” or “ ‘Sally makes
quilts here and sells them at 3200 Main Street’ ” would be
regulated as off- premises signs. 972 F. 3d, at 706. Before
us, Austin’s counsel had similar difficulties, and amici have proposed dozens of religious and political messages that would
be next to impossible to categorize under Austin’s rule. See, e.g. , Brief for Alliance Defending Freedom et. al. as Amici Curiae 15–19; Brief for Institute for Justice as Amicus Curiae 3–9. These pervasive ambiguities offer
enforcement officials ample opportunity to suppress disfavored
views. And they underscore Reed ’s warning that “[i]nnocent
motives do not eliminate the danger of censorship presented by a
facially content-based statute.” 576 U. S., at 167.
* * *
Because Reed provided a clear and
neutral rule that protected the freedom of speech from governmental
caprice and viewpoint discrimination, I would adhere to that
precedent rather than risk resuscitating Hill . I
respectfully dissent. Notes 1 For several categories of
historically unprotected speech, including obscenity, defamation,
fraud, incitement, and speech integral to criminal conduct, the
government ordinarily may enact content-based restrictions without
satisfying strict scrutiny. See United States v. Stevens , 559 U.S.
460 , 468–469 (2010). This Court’s precedents have also declined
to apply strict scrutiny to several other types of content-based
restrictions, including laws targeting “commercial speech.” Central Hudson Gas & Elec. Corp. v. Public Serv.
Comm’n of N. Y. , 447 U.S.
557 , 561–566 (1980). But see Lorillard Tobacco Co. v. Reilly , 533 U.S.
525 , 572 (2001) (Thomas, J., concurring in part and concurring
in judgment). As the Court recognizes, Austin’s off-premises sign
rule is not limited to any of these categories of speech. See ante, at 5, n. 3. 2 In Reed , we
acknowledged that some prior decisions had skipped over this facial
analysis and applied a justification-focused test. See 576
U. S., at 165–167. But we explained that the
justification-focused test implicated a “separate and additional
category of laws that, though facially content neutral, [are]
content-based regulations [because they] cannot be
‘ “justified without reference to the content of the regulated
speech,” ’ or . . . were adopted by the government
‘because of disagreement with the message [the speech]
conveys.’ ” Id., at 164 (quoting Ward v. Rock
Against Racism , 491 U.S.
781 , 791 (1989)). All agree that this second type of
content-based regulation is not at issue here. 3 On this point, the
majority’s analysis tracks the position advanced byAustin, which
asserted that content neutrality was a “question of generality.”
Tr. of Oral Arg. 14; see also id., at 19 (explaining that
whether a law is content based turns on the “level of specificity”
at which the government regulates speech). 4 The majority says only
that Austin’s sign code is “similar” to a time-place-manner
restriction, citing Frisby v. Schultz , 487 U.S.
474 (1988). Ante, at 8. But Frisby upheld an
ordinance that regulated only where picketing may take place
and not what message the picketers could communicate. See
487 U. S., at 477 (ordinance made it “unlawful for any person
to engage in picketing before or about the residence or dwelling of
any individual” (internal quotation marks omitted)); cf. Hill v. Colorado , 530 U.S.
703 , 766 (2000) (Kennedy, J., dissenting) (“[n]o examination of
the content of a speaker’s message is required to determine whether
an individual is picketing”). | The City of Austin, Texas, regulates off-premises signs, including billboards, and allows onsite signs. The Supreme Court held that this regulation is not subject to strict scrutiny under the First Amendment's Free Speech Clause. Justice Sotomayor delivered the opinion, citing historical precedent and the Highway Beautification Act of 1965, which allowed states to limit off-premises signs near federal highways. The Court's decision protects against governmental caprice and viewpoint discrimination. |
Free Speech | Lindke v. Freed | https://supreme.justia.com/cases/federal/us/601/22-611/ | NOTICE: This opinion is subject to
formal revision before publication in the United States Reports.
Readers are requested to notify the Reporter of Decisions, Supreme
Court of the United States, Washington, D. C. 20543,
[email protected], of any typographical or other formal
errors.
SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES
_________________
No. 22–611
_________________
KEVIN LINDKE, PETITIONER v. JAMES R.
FREED
on writ of certiorari to the united states
court of appeals for the sixth circuit
[March 15, 2024]
Justice Barrett delivered the opinion of the
Court.
Like millions of Americans, James Freed
maintained a Facebook account on which he posted about a wide range
of topics, including his family and his job. Like most of those
Americans, Freed occasionally received unwelcome comments on his
posts. In response, Freed took a step familiar to Facebook users:
He deleted the comments and blocked those who made them.
For most people with a Facebook account, that
would have been the end of it. But Kevin Lindke, one of the
unwelcome commenters, sued Freed for violating his right to free
speech. Because the First Amendment binds only the government, this
claim is a nonstarter if Freed posted as a private citizen. Freed,
however, is not only a private citizen but also the city manager of
Port Huron, Michigan—and while Freed insists that his Facebook
account was strictly personal, Lindke argues that Freed acted in
his official capacity when he silenced Lindke’s speech.
When a government official posts about
job-related topics on social media, it can be difficult to tell
whether the speech is official or private. We hold that such speech
is attributable to the State only if the official
(1) possessed actual authority to speak on the State’s behalf,
and (2) purported to exercise that authority when he spoke on
social media.
I
A
Sometime before 2008, while he was a college
student, James Freed created a private Facebook profile that he
shared only with “friends.” In Facebook lingo, “friends” are not
necessarily confidants or even real-life acquaintances. Users
become “friends” when one accepts a “friend request” from another;
after that, the two can generally see and comment on one another’s
posts and photos. When Freed, an avid Facebook user, began nearing
the platform’s 5,000-friend limit, he converted his profile to a
public “page.” This meant that anyone could see and comment
on his posts. Freed chose “public figure” for his page’s category,
“James Freed” for its title, and “JamesRFreed1” as his username.
Facebook did not require Freed to satisfy any special criteria
either to convert his Facebook profile to a public page or to
describe himself as a public figure.
In 2014, Freed was appointed city manager of
Port Huron, Michigan, and he updated his Facebook page to reflect
the new job. For his profile picture, Freed chose a photo of
himself in a suit with a city lapel pin. In the “About” section,
Freed added his title, a link to the city’s website, and the city’s
general email address. He described himself as “Daddy to Lucy,
Husband to Jessie and City Manager, Chief Administrative Officer
for the citizens of Port Huron, MI.”
As before his appointment, Freed operated his
Facebook page himself. And, as before his appointment, Freed posted
prolifically (and primarily) about his personal life. He uploaded
hundreds of photos of his daughter. He shared about outings like
the Daddy Daughter Dance, dinner with his wife, and a family nature
walk. He posted Bible verses, updates on home-improvement projects,
and pictures of his dog, Winston.
Freed also posted information related to his
job. He described mundane activities, like visiting local high
schools, as well as splashier ones, like starting reconstruction of
the city’s boat launch. He shared news about the city’s efforts to
streamline leaf pickup and stabilize water intake from a local
river. He highlighted communications from other city officials,
like a press release from the fire chief and an annual financial
report from the finance department. On occasion, Freed solicited
feedback from the public—for instance, he once posted a link to a
city survey about housing and encouraged his audience to complete
it.
Freed’s readers frequently commented on his
posts, sometimes with reactions (for example, “Good job it takes
skills” on a picture of his sleeping daughter) and sometimes with
questions (for example, “Can you allow city residents to have
chickens?”). Freed often replied to the comments, including by
answering inquiries from city residents. (City residents can have
chickens and should “call the Planning Dept for details.”) He
occasionally deleted comments that he thought were “derogatory” or
“stupid.”
After the COVID–19 pandemic began, Freed posted
about that. Some posts were personal, like pictures of his family
spending time at home and outdoors to “[s]tay safe” and “[s]ave
lives.” Some contained general information, like case counts and
weekly hospitalization numbers. Others related to Freed’s job, like
a description of the city’s hiring freeze and a screenshot of a
press release about a relief package that he helped prepare.
Enter Kevin Lindke. Unhappy with the city’s
approach to the pandemic, Lindke visited Freed’s page and said so.
For example, in response to one of Freed’s posts, Lindke commented
that the city’s pandemic response was “abysmal” and that “the city
deserves better.” When Freed posted a photo of himself and the
mayor picking up takeout from a local restaurant, Lindke complained
that while “residents [we]re suffering,” the city’s leaders were
eating at an expensive restaurant “instead of out talking to the
community.” Initially, Freed deleted Lindke’s comments; ultimately,
he blocked him. Once blocked, Lindke could see Freed’s posts but
could no longer comment on them.
B
Lindke sued Freed under 42 U. S. C.
§1983, alleging that Freed had violated his First Amendment rights.
As Lindke saw it, he had the right to comment on Freed’s Facebook
page, which he characterized as a public forum. Freed, Lindke
claimed, had engaged in impermissible viewpoint discrimination by
deleting unfavorable comments and blocking the people who made
them.
The District Court granted summary judgment to
Freed. Because only state action can give rise to liability under
§1983, Lindke’s claim depended on whether Freed acted in a
“private” or “public” capacity. 563 F. Supp. 3d 704, 714 (ED
Mich. 2021). The “prevailing personal quality of Freed’s post[s],”
the absence of “government involvement” with his account, and the
lack of posts conducting official business led the court to
conclude that Freed managed his Facebook page in his private
capacity, so Lindke’s claim failed. Ibid .
The Sixth Circuit affirmed. It noted that “the
caselaw is murky as to when a state official acts personally and
when he acts officially” for purposes of §1983. 37 F. 4th
1199, 1202 (2022). To sort the personal from the official, that
court “asks whether the official is ‘performing an actual or
apparent duty of his office,’ or if he could not have behaved as he
did ‘without the authority of his office.’ ” Id ., at
1203 (quoting Waters v. Morristown , 242 F.3d 353 , 359 (CA6 2001)). Applying this precedent to the
social-media context, the Sixth Circuit held that an official’s
activity is state action if the “text of state law requires an
officeholder to maintain a social-media account,” the official
“use[s] . . . state resources” or “government
staff ” to run the account, or the “accoun[t] belong[s] to an
office, rather than an individual officeholder.” 37 F. 4th, at
1203–1204. These situations, the Sixth Circuit explained, make an
official’s social-media activity “ ‘fairly
attributable’ ” to the State. Id ., at 1204 (quoting Lugar v. Edmondson Oil Co. , 457
U.S. 922 , 937 (1982)). And it concluded that Freed’s activity
was not.
The Sixth Circuit’s approach to state action in
the social-media context differs from that of the Second and Ninth
Circuits, which focus less on the connection between the official’s
authority and the account and more on whether the account’s
appearance and content look official. See, e . g ., Garnier v. O’Connor-Ratcliff , 41 F. 4th 1158,
1170–1171 (CA9 2022); Knight First Amdt. Inst. at Columbia
Univ. v. Trump , 928 F.3d 226, 236 (CA2 2019), vacated as
moot sub nom . Biden v. Knight First Amdt.
Inst. at Columbia Univ ., 593 U. S. ___ (2021). We granted
certiorari. 598 U. S. ___ (2023).
II
Section 1983 provides a cause of action
against “[e]very person who, under color of any statute,
ordinance, regulation, custom, or usage, of any State ” deprives
someone of a federal constitutional or statutory right. (Emphasis
added.) As its text makes clear, this provision protects against
acts attributable to a State, not those of a private person. This
limit tracks that of the Fourteenth Amendment, which obligates States to honor the constitutional rights that §1983
protects. §1 (“No State shall . . . nor shall any State deprive . . . ” (emphasis added)); see also Lugar , 457 U. S., at 929 (“[T]he statutory requirement
of action ‘under color of state law’ and the ‘state action’
requirement of the Fourteenth Amendment are identical”). The need
for governmental action is also explicit in the Free Speech Clause,
the guarantee that Lindke invokes in this case. Amdt. 1
(“ Congress shall make no law . . . abridging the
freedom of speech . . . ” (emphasis added)); see also Manhattan Community Access Corp. v. Halleck , 587 U.S.
802, 808 (2019) (“[T]he Free Speech Clause prohibits only governmental abridgment of speech,” not “ private abridgment of speech”). In short, the state-action requirement is
both well established and reinforced by multiple sources.[ 1 ]
In the run-of-the-mill case, state action is
easy to spot. Courts do not ordinarily pause to consider whether
§1983 applies to the actions of police officers, public schools, or
prison officials. See, e . g ., Graham v. Connor , 490 U.S.
386 , 388 (1989) (police officers); Tinker v. Des
Moines Independent Community School Dist. , 393 U.S.
503 , 504–505 (1969) (public schools); Estelle v. Gamble , 429 U.S.
97 , 98 (1976) (prison officials). And, absent some very unusual
facts, no one would credit a child’s assertion of free speech
rights against a parent, or a plaintiff ’s complaint that a
nosy neighbor unlawfully searched his garage.
Sometimes, however, the line between private
conduct and state action is difficult to draw. Griffin v. Maryland is a good example. 378 U.S.
130 (1964). There, we held that a security guard at a privately
owned amusement park engaged in state action when he enforced the
park’s policy of segregation against black protesters. Id .,
at 132–135. Though employed by the park, the guard had been
“deputized as a sheriff of Montgomery County” and possessed
“ ‘the same power and authority’ ” as any other deputy
sheriff. Id ., at 132, and n. 1. The State had therefore
allowed its power to be exercised by someone in the private sector.
And the source of the power, not the identity of the employer,
controlled.
By and large, our state-action precedents have
grappled with variations of the question posed in Griffin :
whether a nominally private person has engaged in state action for
purposes of §1983. See, e.g. , Marsh v. Alabama , 326 U.S.
501 , 502–503 (1946) (company town); Adickes v. S. H.
Kress & Co. , 398 U.S.
144 , 146–147 (1970) (restaurant); Flagg Bros., Inc. v. Brooks , 436 U.S.
149 , 151–152 (1978) (warehouse company). Today’s case, by
contrast, requires us to analyze whether a state official engaged in state action or functioned as a private citizen. This
Court has had little occasion to consider how the state-action
requirement applies in this circumstance.
The question is difficult, especially in a case
involving a state or local official who routinely interacts with
the public. Such officials may look like they are always on the
clock, making it tempting to characterize every encounter as part
of the job. But the state-action doctrine avoids such broad-brush
assumptions—for good reason. While public officials can act on
behalf of the State, they are also private citizens with their own
constitutional rights. By excluding from liability “acts of
officers in the ambit of their personal pursuits,” Screws v. United States , 325 U.S.
91 , 111 (1945) (plurality opinion), the state-action
requirement “protects a robust sphere of individual liberty” for
those who serve as public officials or employees, Halleck ,
587 U. S., at 808.
The dispute between Lindke and Freed illustrates
this dynamic. Freed did not relinquish his First Amendment rights
when he became city manager. On the contrary, “the First Amendment
protects a public employee’s right, in certain circumstances, to
speak as a citizen addressing matters of public concern.” Garcetti v. Ceballos , 547 U.S.
410 , 417 (2006). This right includes the ability to speak about
“information related to or learned through public employment,” so
long as the speech is not “itself ordinarily within the scope of
[the] employee’s duties.” Lane v. Franks , 573 U.S.
228 , 236, 240 (2014). Where the right exists, “editorial
control over speech and speakers on [the public employee’s]
properties or platforms” is part and parcel of it. Halleck ,
587 U. S., at 816. Thus, if Freed acted in his private
capacity when he blocked Lindke and deleted his comments, he did
not violate Lindke’s First Amendment rights—instead, he exercised
his own.
So Lindke cannot hang his hat on Freed’s status
as a state employee. The distinction between private conduct and
state action turns on substance, not labels: Private parties can
act with the authority of the State, and state officials have
private lives and their own constitutional rights. Categorizing
conduct, therefore, can require a close look.
III
A close look is definitely necessary in the
context of a public official using social media. There are
approximately 20 million state and local government employees
across the Nation, with an extraordinarily wide range of job
descriptions—from Governors, mayors, and police chiefs to teachers,
healthcare professionals, and transportation workers. Many use
social media for personal communication, official communication, or
both—and the line between the two is often blurred. Moreover,
social media involves a variety of different and rapidly changing
platforms, each with distinct features for speaking, viewing, and
removing speech. The Court has frequently emphasized that the
state-action doctrine demands a fact-intensive inquiry. See, e.g. , Reitman v. Mulkey , 387 U.S.
369 , 378 (1967); Gilmore v. Montgomery , 417 U.S.
556 , 574 (1974). We repeat that caution here.
That said, our precedent articulates principles
that govern cases analogous to this one. For the reasons we explain
below, a public official’s social-media activity constitutes state
action under §1983 only if the official (1) possessed actual
authority to speak on the State’s behalf, and (2) purported to
exercise that authority when he spoke on social media. The
appearance and function of the social-media activity are relevant
at the second step, but they cannot make up for a lack of state
authority at the first.
A
The first prong of this test is grounded in
the bedrock requirement that “the conduct allegedly causing the
deprivation of a federal right be fairly attributable to the
State .” Lugar , 457 U. S., at 937 (emphasis added).
An act is not attributable to a State unless it is traceable to the
State’s power or authority. Private action—no matter how “official”
it looks—lacks the necessary lineage.
This rule runs through our cases. Griffin stresses that the security guard was “possessed of state authority”
and “purport[ed] to act under that authority.” 378 U. S., at
135. West v. Atkins states that the “traditional
definition” of state action “requires that the defendant
. . . have exercised power ‘possessed by virtue of state
law and made possible only because the wrongdoer is clothed with
the authority of state law.’ ” 487 U.S.
42 , 49 (1988) (quoting United States v. Classic , 313 U.S.
299 , 326 (1941)). Lugar emphasizes that state action
exists only when “the claimed deprivation has resulted from the
exercise of a right or privilege having its source in state
authority.” 457 U. S., at 939; see also, e . g ., Edmonson v. Leesville Concrete Co. , 500 U.S.
614 , 620 (1991) (describing state action as the “exercise of a
right or privilege having its source in state authority”); Screws , 325 U. S., at 111 (plurality opinion)
(police-officer defendants “were authorized to make an arrest and
to take such steps as were necessary to make the arrest
effective”). By contrast, when the challenged conduct “entail[s]
functions and obligations in no way dependent on state authority,”
state action does not exist. Polk County v. Dodson , 454 U.S.
312 , 318–319 (1981) (no state action because criminal defense
“is essentially a private function . . . for which state
office and authority are not needed”); see also Jackson v. Metropolitan Edison Co. , 419 U.S.
345 , 358–359 (1974).
Lindke’s focus on appearance skips over this
crucial step. He insists that Freed’s social-media activity
constitutes state action because Freed’s Facebook page looks and
functions like an outlet for city updates and citizen concerns. But
Freed’s conduct is not attributable to the State unless he was
“possessed of state authority” to post city updates and register
citizen concerns. Griffin , 378 U. S., at 135. If the
State did not entrust Freed with these responsibilities, it cannot
“fairly be blamed” for the way he discharged them. Lugar ,
457 U. S., at 936. Lindke imagines that Freed can conjure the
power of the State through his own efforts. Yet the presence of
state authority must be real, not a mirage.
Importantly, Lindke must show more than that
Freed had some authority to communicate with residents on
behalf of Port Huron. The alleged censorship must be connected to
speech on a matter within Freed’s bailiwick. For example, imagine
that Freed posted a list of local restaurants with health-code
violations and deleted snarky comments made by other users. If
public health is not within the portfolio of the city manager, then
neither the post nor the deletions would be traceable to Freed’s
state authority—because he had none. For state action to exist, the
State must be “responsible for the specific conduct of which the
plaintiff complains.” Blum v. Yaretsky , 457 U.S.
991 , 1004 (1982) (emphasis deleted). There must be a tie
between the official’s authority and “the gravamen of the
plaintiff ’s complaint.” Id ., at 1003.
To be clear, the “[ m ] isuse of
power, possessed by virtue of state law,” constitutes state action. Classic , 313 U. S., at 326 (emphasis added); see also, e . g ., Screws , 325 U. S., at 110
(plurality opinion) (state action where “the power which [state
officers] were authorized to exercise was misused”). While the
state-action doctrine requires that the State have granted an
official the type of authority that he used to violate
rights— e . g ., the power to arrest—it encompasses cases
where his “particular action”— e.g. , an arrest made with
excessive force—violated state or federal law. Griffin , 378
U. S., at 135; see also Home Telephone & Telegraph
Co. v. Los Angeles , 227 U.S.
278 , 287–288 (1913) (the Fourteenth Amendment encompasses
“abuse by a state officer . . . of the powers
possessed”). Every §1983 suit alleges a misuse of power, because no
state actor has the authority to deprive someone of a federal
right. To misuse power, however, one must possess it in the first
place.
Where does the power come from? Section 1983
lists the potential sources: “statute, ordinance, regulation,
custom, or usage.” Statutes, ordinances, and regulations refer to
written law through which a State can authorize an official to
speak on its behalf. “Custom” and “usage” encompass “persistent
practices of state officials” that are “so permanent and well
settled” that they carry “the force of law.” Adickes , 398
U. S., at 167–168. So a city manager like Freed would be
authorized to speak for the city if written law like an ordinance
empowered him to make official announcements. He would also have
that authority even in the absence of written law if, for instance,
prior city managers have purported to speak on its behalf and have
been recognized to have that authority for so long that the
manager’s power to do so has become “permanent and well settled.” Id. , at 168. And if an official has authority to speak for
the State, he may have the authority to do so on social media even
if the law does not make that explicit.
Determining the scope of an official’s power
requires careful attention to the relevant statute, ordinance,
regulation, custom, or usage. In some cases, a grant of authority
over particular subject matter may reasonably encompass authority
to speak about it officially. For example, state law might grant a
high-ranking official like the director of the state department of
transportation broad responsibility for the state highway system
that, in context, includes authority to make official announcements
on that subject. At the same time, courts must not rely on
“ ‘excessively broad job descriptions’ ” to conclude that
a government employee is authorized to speak for the State. Kennedy v. Bremerton School Dist. , 597 U.S. 507, 529
(2022) (quoting Garcetti , 547 U. S., at 424). The
inquiry is not whether making official announcements could fit within the job description; it is whether making official
announcements is actually part of the job that the State
entrusted the official to do.
In sum, a defendant like Freed must have actual
authority rooted in written law or longstanding custom to speak for
the State. That authority must extend to speech of the sort that
caused the alleged rights deprivation. If the plaintiff cannot make
this threshold showing of authority, he cannot establish state
action.
B
For social-media activity to constitute state
action, an official must not only have state authority—he must also
purport to use it. Griffin , 378 U. S., at 135. State
officials have a choice about the capacity in which they choose to
speak. “[G]enerally, a public employee” purports to speak on behalf
of the State while speaking “in his official capacity or” when he
uses his speech to fulfill “his responsibilities pursuant to state
law.” West , 487 U. S., at 50. If the public employee
does not use his speech in furtherance of his official
responsibilities, he is speaking in his own voice.
Consider a hypothetical from the offline world.
A school board president announces at a school board meeting that
the board has lifted pandemic-era restrictions on public schools.
The next evening, at a backyard barbecue with friends whose
children attend public schools, he shares that the board has lifted
the pandemic-era restrictions. The former is state action taken in
his official capacity as school board president; the latter is
private action taken in his personal capacity as a friend and
neighbor. While the substance of the announcement is the same, the
context—an official meeting versus a private event—differs. He
invoked his official authority only when he acted as school board
president.
The context of Freed’s speech is hazier than
that of the hypothetical school board president. Had Freed’s
account carried a label ( e.g. , “this is the personal page of
James R. Freed”) or a disclaimer ( e.g. , “the views expressed
are strictly my own”), he would be entitled to a heavy (though not
irrebuttable) presumption that all of the posts on his page were
personal. Markers like these give speech the benefit of clear
context: Just as we can safely presume that speech at a backyard
barbeque is personal, we can safely presume that speech on a
“personal” page is personal (absent significant evidence indicating
that a post is official).[ 2 ]
Conversely, context can make clear that a social-media account
purports to speak for the government—for instance, when an account
belongs to a political subdivision ( e.g. , a “City of Port
Huron” Facebook page) or is passed down to whomever occupies a
particular office ( e.g. , an “@PHuronCityMgr” Instagram
account). Freed’s page, however, was not designated either
“personal” or “official,” raising the prospect that it was “mixed
use”—a place where he made some posts in his personal capacity and
others in his capacity as city manager.
Categorizing posts that appear on an ambiguous
page like Freed’s is a fact-specific undertaking in which the
post’s content and function are the most important considerations.
In some circumstances, the post’s content and function might make
the plaintiff ’s argument a slam dunk. Take a mayor who makes
the following announcement exclusively on his Facebook page:
“Pursuant to Municipal Ordinance 22.1, I am temporarily suspending
enforcement of alternate-side parking rules.” The post’s express
invocation of state authority, its immediate legal effect, and the
fact that the order is not available elsewhere make clear that the
mayor is purporting to discharge an official duty. If, by contrast,
the mayor merely repeats or shares otherwise available
information—for example, by linking to the parking announcement on
the city’s webpage—it is far less likely that he is purporting to
exercise the power of his office. Instead, it is much more likely
that he is engaging in private speech “relate[d] to his public
employment” or “concern[ing] information learned during that
employment.” Lane , 573 U. S., at 238.
Hard-to-classify cases require awareness that an
official does not necessarily purport to exercise his authority
simply by posting about a matter within it. He might post
job-related information for any number of personal reasons, from a
desire to raise public awareness to promoting his prospects for
reelection. Moreover, many public officials possess a broad
portfolio of governmental authority that includes routine
interaction with the public, and it may not be easy to discern a
boundary between their public and private lives. Yet these
officials too have the right to speak about public affairs in their
personal capacities. See, e . g ., id ., at
235–236. Lest any official lose that right, it is crucial for the
plaintiff to show that the official is purporting to exercise state
authority in specific posts. And when there is doubt, additional
factors might cast light—for example, an official who uses
government staff to make a post will be hard pressed to deny that
he was conducting government business.
One last point: The nature of the technology
matters to the state-action analysis. Freed performed two actions
to which Lindke objected: He deleted Lindke’s comments and blocked
him from commenting again. So far as deletion goes, the only
relevant posts are those from which Lindke’s comments were removed.
Blocking, however, is a different story. Because blocking operated
on a page-wide basis, a court would have to consider whether Freed
had engaged in state action with respect to any post on which
Lindke wished to comment. The bluntness of Facebook’s blocking tool
highlights the cost of a “mixed use” social-media account: If
page-wide blocking is the only option, a public official might be
unable to prevent someone from commenting on his personal posts
without risking liability for also preventing comments on his
official posts.[ 3 ] A public
official who fails to keep personal posts in a clearly designated
personal account therefore exposes himself to greater potential
liability.
* * *
The state-action doctrine requires Lindke to
show that Freed (1) had actual authority to speak on behalf of
the State on a particular matter, and (2) purported to
exercise that authority in the relevant posts. To the extent that
this test differs from the one applied by the Sixth Circuit, we
vacate its judgment and remand the case for further proceedings
consistent with this opinion.
It is so ordered. Notes 1 Because local governments
are subdivisions of the State, actions taken under color of a local
government’s law, custom, or usage count as “state” action for
purposes of §1983. See Monell v. New York City Dept. of
Social Servs. , 436 U.S.
658 , 690–691 (1978). And when a state or municipal employee
violates a federal right while acting “under color of law,” he can
be sued in an individual capacity, as Freed was here. 2 An official cannot
insulate government business from scrutiny by conducting it on a
personal page. The Solicitor General offers the particularly clear
example of an official who designates space on his nominally
personal page as the official channel for receiving comments on a
proposed regulation. Because the power to conduct
notice-and-comment rulemaking belongs exclusively to the State, its
exercise is necessarily governmental. Similarly, a mayor would
engage in state action if he hosted a city council meeting online
by streaming it only on his personalFacebook page. By contrast, a
post that is compatible with either a “personal capacity” or
“official capacity” designation is “personal” if it appears on a
personal page. 3 On some platforms, a
blocked user might be unable even to see the blocker’s
posts. See, e . g ., Garnier v. O’Connor-Ratcliff , 41 F. 4th, 1158, 1164 (CA9 2022)
(noting that “on Twitter, once a user has been ‘blocked,’ the
individual can neither interact with nor view the blocker’s Twitter
feed”); Knight First Amdt. Inst. at Columbia
Univ . v. Trump , 928 F.3d 226, 231 (CA2 2019) (noting
that a blocked user is unable to see, reply to, retweet, or like
the blocker’s tweets). | The Supreme Court held that when a government official posts about job-related topics on social media, their speech is attributable to the state only if the official had the authority to speak on the state's behalf and purported to exercise that authority when speaking on social media. In this case, James Freed, the city manager of Port Huron, Michigan, deleted comments and blocked users on his Facebook page, including Kevin Lindke, who sued Freed for violating his right to free speech. The Court ruled that Freed's actions were not state action and that Lindke must show that Freed had the authority to speak for the state and intended to do so when silencing Lindke's speech. The case was sent back to the lower court to apply this test. |
Free Speech | Counterman v. Colorado | https://supreme.justia.com/cases/federal/us/600/22-138/ | NOTICE: This opinion is subject to
formal revision before publication in the United States Reports.
Readers are requested to notify the Reporter of Decisions, Supreme
Court of the United States, Washington, D. C. 20543,
[email protected], of any typographical or other formal
errors.
SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES
_________________
No. 22–138
_________________
BILLY RAYMOND COUNTERMAN, PETITIONER v. COLORADO
on writ of certiorari to the court of appeals
of colorado
[June 27, 2023]
Justice Kagan delivered the opinion of the
Court.
True threats of violence are outside the bounds
of First Amendment protection and punishable as crimes. Today we
consider a criminal conviction for communications falling within
that historically unprotected category. The question presented is
whether the First Amendment still requires proof that the defendant
had some subjective understanding of the threatening nature of his
statements. We hold that it does, but that a mental state of
recklessness is sufficient. The State must show that the defendant
consciously disregarded a substantial risk that his communications
would be viewed as threatening violence. The State need not prove
any more demanding form of subjective intent to threaten
another.
I
From 2014 to 2016, petitioner Billy Counterman
sent hundreds of Facebook messages to C. W., a local singer and
musician. The two had never met, and C. W. never responded. In
fact, she repeatedly blocked Counterman. But each time, he created
a new Facebook account and resumed his contacts. Some of his
messages were utterly prosaic (“Good morning sweetheart”; “I am
going to the store would you like anything?”)—except that they were
coming from a total stranger. 3 App. 465. Others suggested that
Counterman might be surveilling C. W. He asked “[w]as that you
in the white Jeep?”; referenced “[a] fine display with your
partner”; and noted “a couple [of] physical sightings.” 497 P.3d
1039, 1044 (Colo. App. 2021). And most critically, a number
expressed anger at C. W. and envisaged harm befalling her: “Fuck
off permanently.” Ibid. “Staying in cyber life is going to
kill you.” Ibid. “You’re not being good for human relations.
Die.” Ibid. The messages put C. W. in fear and upended her
daily existence. She believed that Counterman was “threat[ening
her] life”; “was very fearful that he was following” her; and was
“afraid [she] would get hurt.” 2 App. 177, 181, 193. As a result,
she had “a lot of trouble sleeping” and suffered from severe
anxiety. Id. , at 200; see id. , at 194–198. She
stopped walking alone, declined social engagements, and canceled
some of her performances, though doing so caused her financial
strain. See id. , at 182–183, 199, 201–206, 238–239.
Eventually, C. W. decided that she had to contact the
authorities. Id. , at 184.
Colorado charged Counterman under a statute
making it unlawful to “[r]epeatedly . . . make[ ]
any form of communication with another person” in “a manner that
would cause a reasonable person to suffer serious emotional
distress and does cause that person . . . to suffer
serious emotional distress.” Colo. Rev. Stat. §18–3–602(1)(c)
(2022). The only evidence the State proposed to introduce at trial
were his Facebook messages.[ 1 ]
Counterman moved to dismiss the charge on First
Amendment grounds, arguing that his messages were not “true
threats” and therefore could not form the basis of a criminal
prosecution. In line with Colorado law, the trial court assessed
the true-threat issue using an “objective ‘reasonable person’
standard.” People v. Cross , 127 P.3d 71 , 76 (Colo. 2006). Under that standard, the State
had to show that a reasonable person would have viewed the Facebook
messages as threatening. By contrast, the State had no need to
prove that Counterman had any kind of “subjective intent to
threaten” C. W. In re R. D. , 464 P.3d 717,
731, n. 21 (Colo. 2020). The court decided, after “consider[ing]
the totality of the circumstances,” that Counterman’s statements
“r[o]se to the level of a true threat.” 497 P. 3d, at 1045. Because
that was so, the court ruled, the First Amendment posed no bar to
prosecution. The court accordingly sent the case to the jury, which
found Counterman guilty as charged.
The Colorado Court of Appeals affirmed.
Counterman had urged the court to hold that the First Amendment
required the State to show that he was aware of the threatening
nature of his statements. Relying on its precedent, the court
turned the request down: It “decline[d] today to say that a
speaker’s subjective intent to threaten is necessary” under the
First Amendment to procure a conviction for threatening
communications. Id. , at 1046 (quoting R. D. , 464
P. 3d, at 731, n. 21). Using the established objective
standard, the court then approved the trial court’s ruling that
Counterman’s messages were “true threats” and so were not protected
by the First Amendment. 497 P. 3d, at 1050. The Colorado Supreme
Court denied review.
Courts are divided about (1) whether the First
Amendment requires proof of a defendant’s subjective mindset in
true-threats cases, and (2) if so, what mens rea standard is
sufficient. We therefore granted certiorari. 598 U. S. ___
(2023).
II
True threats of violence, everyone agrees, lie
outside the bounds of the First Amendment’s protection. And a
statement can count as such a threat based solely on its objective
content. The first dispute here is about whether the First
Amendment nonetheless demands that the State in a true-threats case
prove that the defendant was aware in some way of the threatening
nature of his communications.[ 2 ] Colorado argues that there is no such requirement.
Counterman contends that there is one, based mainly on the
likelihood that the absence of such a mens rea requirement
will chill protected, non-threatening speech. Counterman’s view, we
decide today, is the more consistent with our precedent. To combat
the kind of chill he references, our decisions have often insisted
on protecting even some historically unprotected speech through the
adoption of a subjective mental-state element. We follow the same
path today, holding that the State must prove in true-threats cases
that the defendant had some understanding of his statements’
threatening character. The second issue here concerns what precise mens rea standard suffices for the First Amendment purpose
at issue. Again guided by our precedent, we hold that a
recklessness standard is enough. Given that a subjective standard
here shields speech not independently entitled to protection—and
indeed posing real dangers—we do not require that the State prove
the defendant had any more specific intent to threaten the
victim.
A
“From 1791 to the present,” the First
Amendment has “permitted restrictions upon the content of speech in
a few limited areas.” United States v. Stevens , 559 U.S.
460 , 468 (2010). These “historic and traditional categories”
are “long familiar to the bar” and perhaps, too, the general
public. Ibid. One is incitement—statements “directed [at]
producing imminent lawless action,” and likely to do so. Brandenburg v. Ohio , 395 U.S.
444 , 447 (1969) ( per curiam ). Another is
defamation—false statements of fact harming another’s reputation.
See Gertz v. Robert Welch, Inc. , 418 U.S.
323 , 340, 342 (1974). Still a third is obscenity—valueless
material “appeal[ing] to the prurient interest” and describing
“sexual conduct” in “a patently offensive way.” Miller v. California , 413 U.S.
15 , 24 (1973). This Court has “often described [those]
historically unprotected categories of speech as being of such
slight social value as a step to truth that any benefit that may be
derived from them is clearly outweighed by the social interest” in
their proscription. Stevens , 559 U. S., at 470
(internal quotation marks omitted; emphasis deleted).
“True threats” of violence is another
historically unprotected category of communications. Virginia v. Black , 538
U.S. 343 , 359 (2003); see United States v. Alvarez , 567 U.S.
709 , 717–718 (2012) (plurality opinion). The “true” in that
term distinguishes what is at issue from jests, “hyperbole,” or
other statements that when taken in context do not convey a real
possibility that violence will follow (say, “I am going to kill you
for showing up late”). Watts v. United States , 394 U.S.
705 , 708 (1969) ( per curiam ). True threats are “serious
expression[s]” conveying that a speaker means to “commit an act of
unlawful violence.” Black , 538 U. S., at 359. Whether
the speaker is aware of, and intends to convey, the threatening
aspect of the message is not part of what makes a statement a
threat, as this Court recently explained. See Elonis v. United States , 575 U.S. 723, 733 (2015). The existence of a
threat depends not on “the mental state of the author,” but on
“what the statement conveys” to the person on the other end. Ibid. When the statement is understood as a true threat, all
the harms that have long made threats unprotected naturally follow.
True threats subject individuals to “fear of violence” and to the
many kinds of “disruption that fear engenders.” Black , 538
U. S., at 360 (internal quotation marks omitted). The facts of
this case well illustrate how.[ 3 ]
Yet the First Amendment may still demand a
subjective mental-state requirement shielding some true threats
from liability. The reason relates to what is often called a
chilling effect. Prohibitions on speech have the potential to
chill, or deter, speech outside their boundaries. A speaker may be
unsure about the side of a line on which his speech falls. Or he
may worry that the legal system will err, and count speech that is
permissible as instead not. See Philadelphia Newspapers,
Inc. v. Hepps , 475 U.S.
767 , 777 (1986). Or he may simply be concerned about the
expense of becoming entangled in the legal system. The result is
“self-censorship” of speech that could not be proscribed—a
“cautious and restrictive exercise” of First Amendment freedoms. Gertz , 418 U. S., at 340. And an important tool to
prevent that outcome—to stop people from steering “wide[ ] of
the unlawful zone”—is to condition liability on the State’s showing
of a culpable mental state. Speiser v. Randall , 357 U.S.
513 , 526 (1958). Such a requirement comes at a cost: It will
shield some otherwise proscribable (here, threatening) speech
because the State cannot prove what the defendant thought. But the
added element reduces the prospect of chilling fully protected
expression. As this Court has noted, the requirement lessens “the
hazard of self-censorship” by “compensat[ing]” for the law’s
uncertainties. Mishkin v. New York , 383 U.S.
502 , 511 (1966). Or said a bit differently: “[B]y reducing an
honest speaker’s fear that he may accidentally [or erroneously]
incur liability,” a mens rea requirement “provide[s]
‘breathing room’ for more valuable speech.” Alvarez , 567
U. S., at 733 (Breyer, J., concurring in judgment).
That kind of “strategic protection” features in
our precedent concerning the most prominent categories of
historically unprotected speech. Gertz , 418 U. S., at
342. Defamation is the best known and best theorized example. False
and defamatory statements of fact, we have held, have “no
constitutional value.” Id. , at 340; see Alvarez , 567
U. S., at 718–719 (plurality opinion). Yet a public figure
cannot recover for the injury such a statement causes unless the
speaker acted with “knowledge that it was false or with reckless
disregard of whether it was false or not.” New York Times
Co. v. Sullivan , 376 U.S.
254 , 280 (1964); see Garrison v. Louisiana , 379 U.S.
64 , 74 (1964) (using the same standard for criminal libel).
That rule is based on fear of “self-censorship”—the worry that
without such a subjective mental-state requirement, the
uncertainties and expense of litigation will deter speakers from
making even truthful statements. Sullivan , 376 U. S.,
at 279. The First Amendment, we have concluded, “requires that we
protect some falsehood in order to protect speech that matters.” Gertz , 418 U. S., at 341.
The same idea arises in the law respecting
obscenity and incitement to unlawful conduct. Like threats,
incitement inheres in particular words used in particular contexts:
Its harm can arise even when a clueless speaker fails to grasp his
expression’s nature and consequence. But still, the First Amendment
precludes punishment, whether civil or criminal, unless the
speaker’s words were “intended” (not just likely) to produce
imminent disorder. Hess v. Indiana , 414 U.S.
105 , 109 (1973) ( per curiam ); see Brandenburg ,
395 U. S., at 447; NAACP v. Claiborne Hardware
Co. , 458 U.S.
886 , 927–929 (1982). That rule helps prevent a law from
deterring “mere advocacy” of illegal acts—a kind of speech falling
within the First Amendment’s core. Brandenburg , 395
U. S., at 449. And for a similar reason, the First Amendment
demands proof of a defendant’s mindset to make out an obscenity
case. Obscenity is obscenity, whatever the purveyor’s mental state.
But we have repeatedly recognized that punishment depends on a
“vital element of scienter”—often described as the defendant’s
awareness of “the character and nature” of the materials he
distributed. Hamling v. United States , 418 U.S.
87 , 122–123 (1974); see Elonis , 575 U. S., at 739
(reiterating Hamling ). The rationale should by now be
familiar. Yes, “obscene speech and writings are not protected.” Smith v. California , 361 U.S.
147 , 152 (1959). But punishing their distribution without
regard to scienter would “have the collateral effect of inhibiting”
protected expression. Id. , at 151. Given “the ambiguities
inherent in the definition of obscenity,” the First Amendment
“requires proof of scienter to avoid the hazard of
self-censorship.” Mishkin , 383 U. S., at 511.[ 4 ]
The same reasoning counsels in favor of
requiring a subjective element in a true-threats case. This Court
again must consider the prospect of chilling non-threatening
expression, given the ordinary citizen’s predictable tendency to
steer “wide[ ] of the unlawful zone.” Speiser , 357
U. S., at 526. The speaker’s fear of mistaking whether a
statement is a threat; his fear of the legal system getting that
judgment wrong; his fear, in any event, of incurring legal
costs—all those may lead him to swallow words that are in fact not
true threats. Some 50 years ago, Justice Marshall made the point
when reviewing a true-threats prosecution arguably involving only
political hyperbole. See Rogers v. United States , 422 U.S.
35 (1975). The Court in Rogers reversed the conviction
on other grounds, but Justice Marshall focused on the danger of
deterring non-threatening speech. An objective standard, turning
only on how reasonable observers would construe a statement in
context, would make people give threats “a wide berth.” Id. ,
at 47 (concurring opinion). And so use of that standard would
discourage the “uninhibited, robust, and wide-open debate that the
First Amendment is intended to protect.” Id. , at 48 (quoting Sullivan , 376 U. S., at 270).
The reasoning—and indeed some of the words—came
straight from this Court’s decisions insisting on a subjective
element in other unprotected-speech cases, whether involving
defamation, incitement, or obscenity. No doubt, the approach in all
of those cases has a cost: Even as it lessens chill of protected
speech, it makes prosecution of otherwise proscribable, and often
dangerous, communications harder. And the balance between those two
effects may play out differently in different contexts, as the next
part of this opinion discusses. But the ban on an objective
standard remains the same, lest true-threats prosecutions chill too
much protected, non-threatening expression.
B
The next question concerns the type of
subjective standard the First Amendment requires. The law of mens rea offers three basic choices. Purpose is the most
culpable level in the standard mental-state hierarchy, and the
hardest to prove. A person acts purposefully when he “consciously
desires” a result—so here, when he wants his words to be received
as threats. United States v. Bailey , 444 U.S.
394 , 404 (1980). Next down, though not often distinguished from
purpose, is knowledge. Ibid. A person acts knowingly when
“he is aware that [a] result is practically certain to follow”—so
here, when he knows to a practical certainty that others will take
his words as threats. Ibid. (internal quotation marks
omitted). A greater gap separates those two from recklessness. A
person acts recklessly, in the most common formulation, when he
“consciously disregard[s] a substantial [and unjustifiable] risk
that the conduct will cause harm to another.” Voisine v. United States , 579 U.S. 686, 691 (2016) (internal quotation
marks omitted). That standard involves insufficient concern with
risk, rather than awareness of impending harm. See Borden v. United States , 593 U. S. ___, ___ (2021) (plurality
opinion) (slip op., at 5). But still, recklessness is morally
culpable conduct, involving a “deliberate decision to endanger
another.” Voisine , 579 U. S., at 694. In the threats
context, it means that a speaker is aware “that others could regard
his statements as” threatening violence and “delivers them anyway.” Elonis , 575 U. S., at 746 (Alito, J., concurring in
part and dissenting in part).[ 5 ]
Among those standards, recklessness offers the
right path forward. We have so far mostly focused on the
constitutional interest in free expression, and on the correlative
need to take into account threat prosecutions’ chilling effects.
But the precedent we have relied on has always recognized—and
insisted on “accommodat[ing]”—the “competing value[ ]” in
regulating historically unprotected expression. Gertz , 418
U. S., at 348. Here, as we have noted, that value lies in
protecting against the profound harms, to both individuals and
society, that attend true threats of violence—as evidenced in this
case. See supra , at 2, 6. The injury associated with those
statements caused history long ago to place them outside the First
Amendment’s bounds. When despite that judgment we require use of a
subjective mental-state standard, we necessarily impede some
true-threat prosecutions. And as we go up the subjective mens
rea ladder, that imposition on States’ capacity to counter true
threats becomes still greater—and, presumably, with diminishing
returns for protected expression. In advancing past recklessness,
we make it harder for a State to substantiate the needed inferences
about mens rea (absent, as is usual, direct evidence). And
of particular importance, we prevent States from convicting morally
culpable defendants. See Elonis , 575 U. S., at 745
(opinion of Alito, J.). For reckless defendants have done more than
make a bad mistake. They have consciously accepted a substantial
risk of inflicting serious harm.
Using a recklessness standard also fits with the
analysis in our defamation decisions. As noted earlier, the Court
there adopted a recklessness rule, applicable in both civil and
criminal contexts, as a way of accommodating competing interests.
See supra , at 7–8. In the more than half-century in which
that standard has governed, few have suggested that it needs to be
higher—in other words, that still more First Amendment “breathing
space” is required. Gertz , 418 U. S., at 342. And we
see no reason to offer greater insulation to threats than to
defamation. See Elonis , 575 U. S., at 748 (opinion of
Alito, J.). The societal interests in countering the former are at
least as high. And the protected speech near the borderline of true
threats (even though sometimes political, as in Rogers ) is,
if anything, further from the First Amendment’s central concerns
than the chilled speech in Sullivan -type cases ( i.e. ,
truthful reputation-damaging statements about public officials and
figures).
It is true that our incitement decisions demand
more—but the reason for that demand is not present here. When
incitement is at issue, we have spoken in terms of specific intent,
presumably equivalent to purpose or knowledge. See Hess , 414
U. S., at 109; supra , at 8. In doing so, we recognized
that incitement to disorder is commonly a hair’s-breadth away from
political “advocacy”—and particularly from strong protests against
the government and prevailing social order. Brandenburg , 395
U. S., at 447. Such protests gave rise to all the cases in
which the Court demanded a showing of intent. See ibid. ; Hess , 414 U. S., at 106; Claiborne Hardware Co. ,
458 U. S., at 888, 928. And the Court decided those cases
against a resonant historical backdrop: the Court’s failure, in an
earlier era, to protect mere advocacy of force or lawbreaking from
legal sanction. See, e.g. , Whitney v. California , 274 U.S.
357 (1927); Gitlow v. New York , 268 U.S.
652 (1925); Abrams v. United States , 250 U.S.
616 (1919). A strong intent requirement was, and remains, one
way to guarantee history was not repeated. It was a way to ensure
that efforts to prosecute incitement would not bleed over, either
directly or through a chilling effect, to dissenting political
speech at the First Amendment’s core. But the potency of that
protection is not needed here. For the most part, the speech on the
other side of the true-threats boundary line—as compared with the
advocacy addressed in our incitement decisions—is neither so
central to the theory of the First Amendment nor so vulnerable to
government prosecutions. It is not just that our incitement
decisions are distinguishable; it is more that they compel the use
of a distinct standard here.[ 6 ]
That standard, again, is recklessness. It offers
“enough ‘breathing space’ for protected speech,” without
sacrificing too many of the benefits of enforcing laws against true
threats. Elonis , 575 U. S., at 748 (opinion of Alito,
J.). As with any balance, something is lost on both sides: The rule
we adopt today is neither the most speech-protective nor the most
sensitive to the dangers of true threats. But in declining one of
those two alternative paths, something more important is gained:
Not “having it all”—because that is impossible—but having much of
what is important on both sides of the scale.[ 7 ]
III
It is time to return to Counterman’s case,
though only a few remarks are necessary. Counterman, as described
above, was prosecuted in accordance with an objective standard. See supra , at 3. The State had to show only that a reasonable
person would understand his statements as threats. It did not have
to show any awareness on his part that the statements could be
understood that way. For the reasons stated, that is a violation of
the First Amendment.
We accordingly vacate the judgment of the
Colorado Court of Appeals and remand the case for further
proceedings not inconsistent with this opinion.
It is so ordered. Notes 1 The statute Counterman
was charged with violating is titled a “stalking” statute and also
prohibits “[r]epeatedly follow[ing], approach[ing], contact[ing],
[or] plac[ing] under surveillance” another person. §18–3–602(1)(c).
But the State had no evidence, beyond what Counterman claimed, that
he actually had followed or surveilled C. W. For example, C.
W. had never noticed anything of that kind. So the prosecution
based its case solely on Counterman’s “[r]epeated[ ]
. . . communication[s]” with C. W. Ibid. 2 A preliminary
clarification may be useful, concerning the difference between
awareness of a communication’s contents and awareness of its
threatening nature. Everyone agrees, again, that the State must
prove the former—and Colorado law appears to hold as much. See
Colo. Rev. Stat. §18–3–602(1)(c); Brief for Respondent 18. So, for
example, if a defendant delivers a sealed envelope without knowing
that a threatening letter is inside, he cannot be liable for the
communication. So too (though this common example seems fairly
preposterous) if a “foreigner, ignorant of the English language,
who would not know the meaning of the words,” somehow manages to
convey an English-language threat. Elonis v. United
States , 575 U.S. 723, 738 (2015) (internal quotation marks
omitted). The question in this case arises when the defendant
(unlike in those hypotheticals) understands the content of the
words, but may not grasp that others would find them threatening.
Must he do so, under the First Amendment, for a true-threats
prosecution to succeed? 3 The concurrence relies on Virginia v. Black , 538 U.S.
343 (2003), to argue that the category of true threats itself
incorporates a mens rea element. See post , at 9–11,
14 (Sotomayor, J., concurring in part and concurring in judgment).
But that claim is based on a misreading. The statements the
concurrence quotes merely reflect that the statute involved in the
case required a showing of intent. Black did not address
whether the First Amendment demands such a showing, or why it might
do so. See United States v. Jeffries , 692 F.3d 473,
479–480 (CA6 2012) (Sutton, J.); see also post , at 9–10, and
n. 4 (Barrett, J., dissenting) (explaining that Black concerned a different part of the statute, preventing consideration
of contextual factors in assessing whether a statement was a
threat). 4 The dissent, in urging an
objective standard here, reads the obscenity decisions as requiring
merely that the defendant know “what the material depicts” (as a
speaker must know a communication’s contents). Post , at 5–6
(opinion of Barrett, J.) (relying on Hamling , 418
U. S., at 120–123). But see the statements quoted above: That
is not what they say. And indeed, this Court recently rejected the
dissent’s revisionist reading, explaining in detail—and in response
to a near-identical argument—that the obscenity decisions demand
awareness of “the character of [the materials,] not simply
[their] contents.” Elonis , 575 U. S., at 739–740
(discussing Hamling , 418 U. S., at 120–123, and Mishkin , 383 U. S., at 510). The dissent’s use of two
other First Amendment categories—fighting words and false
commercial speech—to support an objective test also falls flat. See post , at 3–4 (opinion of Barrett, J.). This Court has not
upheld a conviction under the fighting-words doctrine in 80 years.
At the least, that doctrine is today a poor candidate for spinning
off other First Amendment rules. False commercial speech is also a
poor analog, though for different reasons. Put aside that the line
of cases the dissent invokes has never been listed among the
historically unprotected categories of speech. See, e.g. , United States v. Stevens , 559
U.S. 460 , 468 (2010); see supra , at 5. Yet more
relevant, the Court has often noted that commercial speech is less
vulnerable to chill than most other speech is. See, e.g. , Board of Trustees of State Univ. of N. Y. v. Fox , 492 U.S.
469 , 481 (1989). And it is the fear of chill that has led to
state-of-mind requirements in the context of unprotected
speech. 5 Just to complete the mens rea hierarchy, the last level is negligence—but that is
an objective standard, of the kind we have just rejected. A person
acts negligently if he is not but should be aware of a substantial
risk—here , that others will understand his words as threats.
See Borden , 593 U. S., at ___ (plurality opinion) (slip
op., at 5). That makes liability depend not on what the speaker
thinks, but instead on what a reasonable person would think about
whether his statements are threatening in nature. See Elonis , 575 U. S., at 738 (“Having liability turn on
whether a reasonable person regards the communication as a
threat—regardless of what the defendant thinks—reduces culpability
. . . to negligence” (internal quotation marks
omitted)). 6 Our obscenity decisions
are of no help in this inquiry, because the Court has never
determined the precise mens rea needed to impose punishment.
In arguing to the contrary, the concurrence relies mainly on Hamling . Post , at 18–19 (opinion of Sotomayor, J.).
But if the dissent is wrong in saying that Hamling (and
other obscenity decisions) allowed an objective inquiry, see supra , at 9, n. 4, the concurrence is wrong in suggesting
that it required use of a purpose or knowledge standard. As to the
concurrence’s claim, Hamling held only that a statute with
that standard was “constitutionally sufficient.” 418 U. S., at
123. The decision said nothing about whether it was
constitutionally necessary, or instead whether a recklessness
standard would suffice as well. 7 The dissent accuses the
Court of making a “Goldilocks judgment” in favoring a recklessness
standard. Post , at 13 (opinion of Barrett, J.). But in law,
as in life, there are worse things than being “just
right.” SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES
_________________
No. 22–138
_________________
BILLY RAYMOND COUNTERMAN, PETITIONER v. COLORADO
on writ of certiorari to the court of appeals
of colorado
[June 27, 2023]
Justice Sotomayor, with whom Justice Gorsuch
joins as to Parts I, II, III–A, and III–B, concurring in part and
concurring in the judgment.
When the government seeks to punish speech based
on its content, the First Amendment typically imposes stringent
requirements. This ensures that the government, even when pursuing
compelling objectives, does not unduly burden our Nation’s
commitment to free expression. “From 1791 to the present, however,
the First Amendment has permitted restrictions upon the content of
speech in a few limited areas.” United States v. Stevens , 559 U.S.
460 , 468 (2010) (internal quotation marks omitted). These
categories must be “well-defined and narrowly limited” in light of
the serious consequences that flow from carving out speech from
ordinary First Amendment protections. Chaplinsky v. New
Hampshire , 315 U.S.
568 , 571 (1942).
“True threats” are one such category, and there
is a tradition of criminalizing threats stretching back centuries.
This includes punishing single utterances based on the message
conveyed. One paradigmatic example of this would be writing and
mailing a letter threatening to assassinate the President. Such
laws are plainly important. There is no longstanding tradition,
however, of punishing speech merely because it is unintentionally
threatening. Instead, this Court’s precedent, along with historical
statutes and cases, reflect a commonsense understanding that
threatening someone is an intentional act. As to what intent is
needed, “[t]raditionally, one intends certain consequences when he
desires that his acts cause those consequences or knows that those
consequences are substantially certain to result from his acts.” Tison v. Arizona , 481 U.S.
137 , 150 (1987) (internal quotation marks omitted). This does
not require showing that an individual intends to carry through
with the threat. But it does require showing that an individual
desires to threaten or is substantially certain that her statements
will be understood as threatening.
Today, unfortunately, the Court unnecessarily
departs from this traditional understanding. That is not to say
that I disagree with the Court on everything. Far from it. I join
the Court’s conclusion that some subjective mens rea is
required in true-threats cases. I also agree that in this
particular case, where petitioner was prosecuted for stalking that
involved threatening statements, a mens rea of recklessness
is amply sufficient. Where I part ways with the Court is that I
would not reach the distinct and more complex question whether a mens rea of recklessness is sufficient for true-threats
prosecutions generally. Further, requiring nothing more than a mens rea of recklessness is inconsistent with precedent,
history, and the commitment to even harmful speech that the First
Amendment enshrines. I therefore respectfully concur only in part
and in the judgment.
I
As an initial matter, I do not believe that
this Court should reach the question whether recklessness is
sufficient for true-threats prosecutions. A key conceptual
distinction is helpful for explaining why. On the one hand, there
are statements that are objectively threatening. In some cases,
such statements can be punished because they fall into the
unprotected category of “true threats.” Yet such statements can
also be punished if they fall into another category of unprotected
speech, such as speech integral to criminal conduct. Or they might
warrant less First Amendment protection for other reasons. On the
other hand, there is the question of what constitutes the
well-defined and longstanding category of unprotected true threats.
It is with this latter question that I do not see the need to
address whether a mens rea of recklessness is sufficient
across the board.
First, the courts below did not address whether
recklessness was sufficient to prosecute true threats and neither
of the actual parties have advocated a recklessness standard.
Colorado disclaimed the idea that recklessness was required, and
petitioner asserted, correctly, that recklessness had not been
raised under traditional principles of party presentation. The
briefing on recklessness consists almost entirely of a few pages of
an argument in the alternative at the tail end of an amicus brief filed by the United States.
Second, because petitioner was prosecuted for
stalking involving threatening speech, this case does not require
resort to the true-threats exemption to the First Amendment.
True-threats doctrine covers content-based
prosecutions for single utterances of “pure speech,” which need not
even be communicated to the subject of the threat. Watts v. United States , 394 U.S.
705 , 707 (1969) ( per curiam ). The First Amendment
would normally place strict limits on such prosecutions. So there
is typically a need to determine whether the speech in question
falls within the traditionally unprotected category of true
threats.
This is not such a case, however. Petitioner was
convicted for “stalking [causing] serious emotional distress” for a
combination of threatening statements and repeated, unwanted,
direct contact with C. W. 497 P.3d 1039, 1043 (Colo. App.
2021).[ 1 ] This kind of
prosecution raises fewer First Amendment concerns for a variety of
reasons. Stalking can be carried out through speech but need not
be, which requires less First Amendment scrutiny when speech is
swept in. See, e.g. , Rumsfeld v. Forum for
Academic and Institutional Rights, Inc. , 547 U.S.
47 , 62 (2006). The content of the repeated communications can
sometimes be irrelevant, such as persistently calling someone and
hanging up, or a stream of “utterly prosaic” communications. Ante , at 1. Repeatedly forcing intrusive communications
directly into the personal life of “an unwilling recipient” also
enjoys less protection. Rowan v. Post Office Dept. , 397 U.S.
728 , 738 (1970). Finally, while there is considerable risk with
a single intemperate utterance that a speaker will “accidentally or
erroneously incur liability,” ante , at 7 (internal quotation
marks and alterations omitted), that risk is far reduced with a
course of repeated unwanted contact. Take, for example, petitioner
continuously contacting C. W. despite her blocking him.
Given this, prosecuting threatening statements
made as part of a course of stalking does not squarely present the
hardest questions about the mens rea required to prosecute
isolated utterances based solely on their content.[ 2 ] True-threats doctrine came up below only
because of the lower courts’ doubtful assumption that petitioner
could be prosecuted only if his actions fell under the true-threats
exception. I do not think that is accurate, given the lessened
First Amendment concerns at issue. In such cases, recklessness is
amply sufficient. And I would stop there. There is simply no need
to reach out in this stalking case to determine whether anything
more than recklessness is needed for punishing true threats
generally.
II
Lest there be any doubt, the First Amendment
stakes around the definition of “true threats” are high indeed. The
First Amendment’s mantle covers speech that is “vituperative,
abusive and inexact.” Watts , 394 U. S., at 708. “It
might be tempting to dismiss” seemingly low-value speech “as
unworthy of . . . robust First Amendment protections.” Mahanoy Area School Dist. v. B. L. , 594 U. S.
___, ___ (2021) (slip op., at 11). Yet “[m]ost of what we say to
one another lacks ‘religious, political, scientific, educational,
journalistic, historical, or artistic value’ (let alone serious
value), but it is still sheltered from Government regulation.” Stevens , 559 U. S., at 479 (emphasis deleted). First
Amendment vigilance is especially important when speech is
disturbing, frightening, or painful, because the undesirability of
such speech will place a heavy thumb in favor of silencing it. In
response, the Court has upheld First Amendment rights in the
context of gruesome animal cruelty videos, id ., at 472;
cross burning, Virginia v. Black , 538
U.S. 343 , 347–348 (2003); hateful rhetoric in protests of the
funerals of fallen soldiers, Snyder v. Phelps , 562 U.S.
443 , 448–449, 458 (2011); and computer-generated images of
child pornography, Ashcroft v. Free Speech Coalition , 535 U.S.
234 , 239–240, 258 (2002).
The risk of overcriminalizing upsetting or
frightening speech has only been increased by the internet. Our
society’s discourse occurs more and more in “the ‘vast democratic
forums of the Internet’ in general, and social media in
particular.” Packingham v. North Carolina , 582 U.S.
98, 104 (2017) (citation omitted). “Rapid changes in the dynamics
of communication and information transmission” have led to equally
rapid and ever-evolving changes “in what society accepts as proper
behavior.” Ontario v. Quon , 560
U.S. 746 , 759 (2010). Different corners of the internet have
considerably different norms around appropriate speech. Online
communication can also lack many normal contextual clues, such as
who is speaking, tone of voice, and expression. Moreover, it is
easy for speech made in a one context to inadvertently reach a
larger audience.
Without sufficient protection for
unintentionally threatening speech, a high school student who is
still learning norms around appropriate language could easily go to
prison for sending another student violent music lyrics, or for
unreflectingly using language he read in an online forum. “[A]
drunken joke” in bad taste can lead to criminal prosecution. Perez v. Florida , 580 U.S. 1187 (2016) (Sotomayor,
J., concurring in denial of certiorari). In the heat of the moment,
someone may post an enraged comment under a news story about a
controversial topic. Another person might reply equally heatedly.
In a Nation that has never been timid about its opinions, political
or otherwise, this is commonplace.
Many of this Court’s true-threats cases involve
such charged political speech. See Black , 538 U. S., at
348–349 (Ku Klux Klan rally); Watts , 394 U. S., at 707
(antiwar protest); Rogers v. United States , 422 U.S.
35 , 41–42, 47–48 (1975) (Marshall, J., concurring) (opposition
to Nixon’s policies toward China). Amici give further
contemporary examples of such speech from across the political
spectrum. See, e.g. , Brief for American Civil Liberties
Union et al. as Amici Curiae 24–29. Much of this speech
exists in a gray area where it will be quite hard to predict
whether a jury would find it threatening. And the ubiquity of such
speech raises the possibility of highly discretionary
enforcement.
The burdens of overcriminalization will fall
hardest on certain groups. A jury’s determination of when angry
hyperbole crosses the line will depend on amorphous norms around
language, which will vary greatly from one discursive community to
another. Juries’ decisions will reflect their “background knowledge
and media consumption.” Minnesota Voters Alliance v. Mansky , 585 U. S. ___, ___ (2018) (slip op., at 17).
“[S]peakers whose ideas or views occupy the fringes of our society
have more to fear, for their violent and extreme rhetoric, even if
intended simply to convey an idea or express displeasure, is more
likely to strike a reasonable person as threatening.” United
States v. White , 670 F.3d 498, 525 (CA4 2012) (Floyd,
J., concurring in part and dissenting in part). Members of certain
groups, including religious and cultural minorities, can also use
language that is more susceptible to being misinterpreted by
outsiders. And unfortunately yet predictably, racial and cultural
stereotypes can also influence whether speech is perceived as
dangerous. See, e.g. , A. Dunbar, C. Kubrin, & N.
Scurich, The Threatening Nature of “Rap” Music, 22 J. Psychol. Pub.
Pol’y & L. 281, 281–282, 288–290 (2016).
On the other hand, the internet has also made
stalking and harassment even easier. Stalking can be devastating
and dangerous. See Brief for First Amendment Scholars as Amici
Curiae 7–8. Lives can be ruined, and in the most tragic
instances, lives are lost. Ibid. Harassers can hide behind
online anonymity while tormenting others. This happens in the
context of intimate relationships and it happens with strangers.
Overly constraining our society’s ability to respond to stalking
would come at a real cost. For the reasons given, however, a mens rea standard for true threats would not hinder stalking
prosecutions. See supra, at 3–5.
Even isolated threatening speech can do real
harm. Such speech not only disrupts lives, it can silence the
speech of others who become afraid to speak out. A mens rea require- ment would not, however, present an uncommon or
insurmountable barrier to true-threats prosecutions.[ 3 ] Nonetheless, under such a standard, there
will be some speech that some find threatening that will not and
should not land anyone in prison.
III
These high First Amendment stakes are further
reason for caution when delineating the boundaries of what
constitutes a true threat. In undertaking that analysis, the Court
and I part ways on the order of operations. The Court begins by
defining true threats as all objectively threatening speech,
entirely independent of whether the speaker intended to be
threatening, ante , at 6, and the lead dissent agrees, post , at 2–3 (opinion of Barrett, J.). The Court gets there
by relying on this Court’s interpretation of the word “threat” in a
federal statute. Ante , at 6 (citing Elonis v. United States , 575 U.S. 723, 733 (2015)). The Court declares
all such speech categorically unprotected, and then asks what
“buffer zone” is needed in order to protect other, unthreatening
speech. See ante , at 4–7.
Respectfully, I see the analysis differently.
The first step in the analysis should instead be to ask about the
scope of the well-defined and narrow category of “true threats” as
a constitutional matter. This Court has already warned about the
danger of creating new categories of “unprotected speech” exempt
from the ordinary First Amendment framework for balancing our
society’s commitment to free expression with other interests. Stevens , 559 U. S., at 470. If courts were at liberty
to redefine what counts as a “threat” or “defamation” at will, this
would achieve the same results as creating new categories of
unprotected speech.
Thus, the Court must first ask whether there is
a long-standing tradition of punishing inadvertent threats as “true
threats.” This Court’s prior definition of the word “threat” in a
federal statute, looking primarily to dictionaries, Elonis ,
575 U. S., at 733, does not tell us the scope of “true
threats” for First Amendment purposes. Elonis itself made
clear that it did “not . . . consider any First Amendment
issues.” Id. , at 740. Instead, a careful examination of this
Court’s true-threats precedent and the history of threat crimes
does not support a long-settled tradition of punishing
inadvertently threatening speech.
A
A natural place to begin, one might think,
would be with this Court’s most recent decision involving the First
Amendment, mens rea , and true threats. Yet to read the
Court’s decision, one would have little idea that in a seminal 2003
decision, this Court held that a threat conviction could not stand
because of an insufficient mens rea requirement. See Black , 538
U.S. 343 . Black plainly sets out a conception of true
threats as including a mens rea requirement.
In Black , the Court confronted the
constitutionality of a Virginia statute that prohibited burning a
cross with intent to intimidate. Only part of the decision in Black is contained in a five-Justice majority opinion. The
other relevant parts of the decision were written by the Members of
that majority, who split into a four-Justice plurality and Justice
Scalia’s partial concurrence in judgment.
The majority explained why a prohibition on
cross burning with intent to threaten was constitutional, beginning
by defining the category of true threats. “ ‘True
threats,’ ” the majority explained “encompass those statements
where the speaker means to communicate a serious expression
of an intent to commit an act of unlawful violence.” Id. , at
359 (emphasis added). However, “[t]he speaker need not actually
intend to carry out the threat,” as true threats also include
intimidation alone. Id. , at 359–360. And “[i]ntimidation in
the constitutionally proscribable sense of the word is a type of
true threat, where a speaker directs a threat to a person or group
of persons with the intent of placing the victim in fear of
bodily harm or death.” Id. , at 360 (emphasis added).
To the extent the Virginia statute covered
intentionally threatening cross burning, it was thus tailored to
cover only true threats. Critically, however, the statute also
provided that “ ‘[a]ny such burning of a cross shall be prima
facie evidence of an intent to intimidate.’ ” Id. , at
348. In other words, the all-important intent requirement could be
satisfied by the mere conduct itself.
Consistent with the majority’s definition of
true threats, both the plurality and Justice Scalia agreed that the
lack of a sufficient intent requirement meant that a conviction
under the statute could not stand. Id. , at 367, 379. For the
plurality, the intent requirement was “the very reason why a State
may ban cross burning” because it “distinguish[ed]” between the
constitutionally unprotected true threat of burning a cross with
intent to intimidate and “cross burning [as] a statement of
ideology.” Id. , at 365–366.[ 4 ] For Justice Scalia, the “plurality [was] correct in all
of this.” Id. , at 372 (opinion concurring in part,
concurring in judgment in part, and dissenting in part). There was
a constitutional need for a distinction between cross burning
“ ‘intended to intimidate’ ” and cross burning as
“ ‘a statement of ideology.’ ” Ibid . The plurality
and Justice Scalia only parted ways as to whether to hold that the
statute was “facially invalid,” id. , at 367 (plurality
opinion), or just that the jury instructions made it unclear
“whether the jury has rendered its verdict ( as it must )”
with sufficient consideration of “intent to intimidate,” id. , at 380 (opinion of Scalia, J.) (emphasis added).
The through-line is not hard to discern. First,
unprotected true threats include a subjective mens rea requirement. Id ., at 360 (majority opinion). Second, as a
result, “Virginia’s statute does not run afoul of the First
Amendment insofar as it bans cross burning with intent to
intimidate.” Id. , at 362 (majority opinion). Third, a
conviction could not stand if it had categorically dispensed with
that intent requirement, id. , at 365–366 (plurality
opinion), or if the jury had insufficiently considered “intent to
intimidate,” id. , at 380 (opinion of Scalia, J.).
In sum, all five Justices in the Black majority agreed that a true-threats prosecution could not stand
under the First Amendment without a sufficient subjective mens
rea requirement.[ 5 ]
B
In defining true threats as “statements where
the speaker means to communicate a serious expression of an intent
to commit an act of unlawful violence,” id ., at 359, the
Court in Black echoed the traditional understanding of
threats. Historically, threat crimes covered the same kind of
subjectively threatening speech Black invoked.
In reviewing this history, it is also vital to
keep in mind the nature of the inquiry. Removing speech from normal
First Amendment scrutiny is a major shift in the balance of
expression and public interest that our Constitution generally
strikes. The inquiry is therefore whether there is a “long-settled
tradition” of prohibiting inadvertently threatening speech. Stevens , 559 U. S., at 469. None of the other opinions,
however, identify a historical case that expressly raised the
question whether a subjective mens rea is required and held
that it is not. That is a remarkable thing when one considers that
the sample size consists of decisions from both sides of the
Atlantic across centuries.
There was a long tradition of crimes for
threatening another person in order to extort them. See, e.g. , 1796 N. J. Laws §57, p. 108. Colorado and the
United States admit that this core category of threat crimes
required intent.
Even beyond that, a subjective mens rea remained a key component of threat offenses. An 18th-century
English statute made it a capital offense to “knowingly send any
letter . . . threatening to kill or murder any of his
Majesty’s subject or subjects” or to threaten arson. 27 Geo. II, c.
15, in 21 Eng. Stat. at Large 184 (1754). A leading treatise
explained that the statute was “levelled against such whose intention it was [to] obtain their object by creating terror
in [the victim’s] mind.” 2 W. Russell & D. Davis, Crimes &
Misdemeanors *1845 (emphasis added).
Consistent with this, defendants were convicted
of “knowingly, wilfully, and feloniously” sending threatening
letters. Rex v. Tyler , 1 Mood. 428, 168 Eng. Rep.
1330 (1835); Rex v. Paddle , Russ. & Ry. 484, 168
Eng. Rep. 910 (1822) (indictment for “knowingly, unlawfully,
wickedly, and feloniously” sending a threatening letter); see also King v. Girdwood , 1 Leach 142, 168 Eng. Rep. 173
(1776) (indictment for “feloniously” sending a threatening letter).
“ ‘[K]nowingly and wilfully’ effecting any result applies to
those who know that the acts performed will have that effect, and
perform them with the intention that such shall be their
operation.” 12 American and English Encyclopaedia of Law 522–524
(J. Merrill ed. 1890); see also J. Boag, Imperial Lexicon of the
English Language 530 (1850) (defining “felonious” as “with the
deliberate purpose to commit a crime”).
The necessary mens rea could sometimes be
inferred from the content of the letter, but could be rebutted by
other evidence. See King v. Philipps , 6 East 464,
475, 102 Eng. Rep. 1365, 1369 (1805). Courts thus considered “the
threat intended to be made by the prisoner” and “what he meant by
what he had written” in determining whether he had violated the
statute. Regina v. Hill , 5 Cox 233, 235 (Crim. Cas.
1851); see also King v. John and Mary Hammond , 1
Leach 444, 446, 168 Eng. Rep. 324, 325 (1787) (describing the
offense of sending a threatening letter “to the party whose fears
the threat it contains was calculated to alarm”).
Threat laws in the United States were of a
piece. Some state laws about threats expressly required
maliciousness. See Me. Rev. Stat., Tit. 12, ch. 154, §26 (1840);
1884 La. Acts No. 64, §1, p. 86. Courts more generally emphasized
the importance of a mens rea requirement. See, e.g. , State v. Benedict , 11 Vt. 236, 239 (1839). The North
Carolina Su- preme Court, for example, singled out threats as
quintessential examples of offenses where it is “necessary” to
prove the “ intent of the particular letter.” State v. Murphy , 84 N. C. 742, 743–744 (1881). And where state
statutes may have been silent on intent to threaten, courts read
such requirements in. See Commonwealth v. Morton , 140
Ky. 628, 631, 131 S.W. 506, 507–508 (1910) (letter must be
“calculated to alarm, disturb, intimidate, or injure”); see also State v. Stewart , 90 Mo. 507, 512, 2 S.W. 790, 792
(1887) (jury instruction requiring that “ ‘defendant intended
to threaten’ ”).
Leading treatises also explained the importance
of mens rea . See 25 American and English Encyclopaedia of
Law 1071 (C. Williams ed. 1894) (when there is a question as to
“whether or not the letter contains the threat alleged, the intent
is a question for the jury”); see also 2 R. Anderson, Wharton’s
Criminal Law and Procedure §803, pp. 659–660 (1957) (threats must
be “intended to put the person threatened in fear of bodily harm”);
2 J. Bishop, Commentaries on the Criminal Law §1201, p. 664 (6th
ed. 1877) (“The intent, both under the unwritten law and under the
statutes, must be evil”).
Against that backdrop, I return to the inquiry
at hand: whether there is a “long-settled” or “well-established”
history of prosecuting inadvertently threatening speech. There is
no line of cases or pattern of statutes affirmatively stating that
an objective standard is sufficient.
C
Put together, Black and the history
point to an intent requirement. When Black defined and
analyzed true threats in terms of intent, there is no reason to
think the Court used intent to mean anything less than its
traditional definition of purpose or knowledge. See, e.g. , Tison , 481 U. S., at 150. Nor would a recklessness
standard play the necessary role of distinguishing between cross
burning that is “ ‘intended to intimidate’ . . . and
nonintimidating cross burning [that] cannot be prohibited.” 538
U. S., at 372 (opinion of Scalia, J.). Given the violent
history of the symbol, it is hard to imagine that any politically
motivated cross burning done within view of the public could be
carried out without awareness of some risk a reasonable spectator
would feel threatened. See id. , at 388–391 (Thomas, J.,
dissenting). Recklessness, which turns so heavily on an objective
person standard, would not have been enough.
As to the history, it is true that over time
courts have often used a wide variety of terms to describe mental
states. See, e.g. , Morissette v. United
States , 342 U.S.
246 , 252 (1952). Yet “[t]he element of intent in the criminal
law has traditionally been viewed as a bifurcated concept embracing
either the specific requirement of purpose or the more general one
of knowledge or awareness.” United States v. United
States Gypsum Co. , 438 U.S.
422 , 445 (1978); see also Tison , 481 U. S., at 150; Carter v. United States , 530
U.S. 255 , 270 (2000) (describing “feloniously” as equivalent to
“ ‘intent’ ”). And at the very least, there is no
well-settled history showing that it is enough for a defendant to
be merely aware of some risk that their statements could be
threatening. See, e.g. , Borden v. United
States , 593 U. S. ___, ___ (2021) (plurality opinion)
(slip op., at 5) (recklessness requires awareness of a level of
risk that “need not come anywhere close to a likelihood”). The
history is, instead, replete with the enduring and commonsense
pairing of threats and intent.
D
The Court, eschewing Black and history,
instead reaches its result based on the need for a “buffer zone”
drawn by analogy to other categories of unprotected speech. Ante , at 4. For the reasons above, I do not think we can
leap ahead to this question. With that caveat, I agree with the
Court that precedent in other areas of unprotected speech and
concerns about chilling support a subjective mens rea requirement for true threats. Yet these same chilling concerns only
further buttress the conclusion that true threats should be limited
to intentionally threatening speech. Indeed, in the concurrence by
Justice Marshall that the Court invokes, ante , at 9–10, he
advocated “requir[ing] proof that the speaker intended his
statement to be taken as a threat,” based on concerns about
punishing “pure speech.” Rogers , 422 U. S., at 47–48.
In determining the appropriate mens rea , the Court
analogizes to three categories of traditionally unprotected speech:
incitement, obscenity, and defamation. None of these warrants
expanding the narrow boundaries of true threats.
1
Speech inciting harm is the closest cousin to
speech threatening harm. Both incitement and threats put other
people at risk, and both “sprin[g] from [Justice] Holmes’s ‘clear
and present danger’ test.” G. Blakey & B. Murray, Threats, Free
Speech, and the Jurisprudence of the Federal Criminal Law, 2002 B.
Y. U. L. Rev. 829, 1069 (2002). Like true threats, incitement’s
scope is defined in terms of both intention and effect, covering
speech “[1] intended to produce, and [2] likely to produce, imminent disorder.” Hess v. Indiana , 414 U.S.
105 , 109 (1973) ( per curiam ).
Despite their similar nature and source, the
Court today draws a hard line between the two. Incitement requires
“ ‘inten[t].’ ” Ante , at 8. While for threats, the
speaker need only be “aware that others could regard his statements
as threatening violence and delive[r] them anyway.” Ante , at
11 (internal quotation marks omitted). The Court justifies this
asymmetry by the idea “that incitement to disorder is commonly a
hair’s-breadth away from political ‘advocacy,’ ” ante ,
at 13, and the lead dissent says much the same, post , at 7
(opinion of Barrett, J.). These opinions offer little basis for
distinguishing threats on this ground, as this Court’s own cases
show time and again how true-threats prosecutions sweep in
political speech. See Black , 538 U. S., at 348–349; Watts , 394 U. S., at 707 (antiwar protest); Rogers , 422 U. S., at 41–42 (Marshall, J., concurring)
(opposition to Nixon’s policies toward China).[ 6 ] Not only that, but incitement itself is often
only a hair’s-breadth away from threats.
Take the seminal incitement case NAACP v. Claiborne Hardware Co. , 458 U.S.
886 (1982). During a civil rights boycott, NAACP leader Charles
Evers, brother of the murdered civil rights hero Medgar Evers, gave
a series of heated speeches. See id. , at 898–902. He intoned
that “boycott violators would be ‘disciplined’ ” and that
“ ‘[i]f we catch any of you going in any of them racist
stores, we’re gonna break your damn neck.’ ” Id. , at
902. The Court acknowledged that in this charged context, these
speeches “might have been understood as inviting an unlawful form
of discipline or, at least, as intending to create a fear of
violence.” Id. , at 927. Yet inflammatory and threatening as
these speeches were, they did not constitute incitement. That was
because “there [was] no evidence—apart from the speeches
themselves—that Evers authorized, ratified, or directly threatened
acts of violence.” Id ., at 929. His speeches were thus not
“ ‘directed to inciting or producing imminent lawless
action’ ” and he had not “specifically intended to further an
unlawful goal.” Id. , at 925, n. 68, 928.
Under a recklessness rule, Claiborne would have come out the other way. So long as Evers had some
subjective awareness of some risk that a reasonable person could
re- gard his statements as threatening, that would be sufficient.
It would be quite troubling indeed to adopt a rule rendering this
Court’s admirable defense of the First Amendment wrongly decided.
Nor is Claiborne the only example. The foundational
incitement case, Brandenburg v. Ohio , 395 U.S.
444 (1969) ( per curiam ), extended First Amendment
protections to armed Klan members uttering racial slurs, a warning
that “there might have to be some revengeance taken,” and plans for
a “ ‘four hundred thousand strong’ ” march in two cities. Id ., at 446. Then, as now, there would be at least some risk
that a reasonable resident of those cities could feel
threatened.
These concrete examples illustrate a more
general principle. Speech inciting imminent and dangerous unlawful
activity will reasonably be threatening to those who would be
harmed by that illegality. In all such cases, whether seminal
decisions by this Court or guilty pleas that barely see the inside
of a courtroom, the Court’s decision effectively downgrades to
recklessness the mens rea required for incitement of
unlawful force; prosecutors could now simply charge such offenses
as true threats. This is particularly worrisome because the
standard for recklessness decreases the lower the “social utility”
of the conduct. 1 W. LaFave, Substantive Criminal Law §5.4(f )
(3d ed. 2018). That is a troubling standard for juries in a
polarized nation to apply in cases involving heated political
speech. This collateral damage can be avoided, however, if intent
to threaten is understood as part of a true threat, just like
intent to incite is part of incitement.
2
While obscenity is a step further afield of
true threats and incitement, examination of this Court’s obscenity
case law further supports an intent requirement for prosecutions of
true threats.
The Constitution “ ‘requires proof of
scienter’ ” in part “ ‘to compensate for the ambiguities
inherent in the definition of obscenity.’ ” Hamling v. United States , 418 U.S.
87 , 123 (1974). This is in line with this Court’s more general
observation that “vagueness” of “content-based regulation of
speech” is of “special concern” when it comes to “criminal
statute[s].” Reno v. American Civil Liberties Union , 521 U.S.
844 , 871–872 (1997).[ 7 ]
Specifically, the Court has held that a
“knowledge” mens rea is sufficient for obscenity: “It is
constitutionally sufficient that the prosecution show that a
defendant had knowledge of the contents of the materials he
distributed, and that he knew the character and nature of the
materials.” Hamling , 418 U. S., at 123. This ensures
that “not innocent but calculated purveyance of filth
. . . is exorcised.” Id. , at 122 (internal
quotation marks omitted). While the Court today asserts that this
Court has “never determined the precise mens rea ” for
obscenity, ante , at 13, n. 6, the Court has cited a
knowledge standard approvingly for half a century, see Hamling , 418 U. S., at 123; Elonis , 575
U. S., at 739.[ 8 ] Applying
that standard to threats, the “ ‘calculated purveyance’ of a
threat would require that [a defendant] know the threatening nature
of his communication.” Id ., at 739.
The considerations that drove this Court to
approve a higher mens rea for obscenity apply here as well.
With obscenity, the ambiguity comes partly from the reliance on
“ ‘contemporary community standards’ ” to define what is
obscene. Hamling , 418 U. S., at 129. Such a standard is
notoriously amorphous, and will change a great deal between
communities and over time. The same chilling concerns apply to true
threats. A recklessness standard based on what a reasonable person
could find threatening will depend on ever-shifting community norms
around language and when heated speech crosses the line from overly
aggressive to criminal. See supra , at 5–7.[ 9 ]
3
Finally, the Court relies heavily upon this
Court’s framework for defamation. Specifically, the Court
analogizes to the “reckless disregard” standard for defamation of
public figures or punitive damages for certain claims involving
private figures. New York Times Co. v. Sullivan , 376 U.S.
254 , 279–280 (1964).
Yet while civil defamation may be “the best
known and best theorized example” of unprotected speech, ante , at 8, the same does not go for criminal prosecution of
defamation. It is true that this Court in 1964 invalidated a
prosecution for criminal libel for failing to apply the Sullivan standard, which covers “only those false statements
made with a high degree of awareness of their probable falsity.” Garrison v. Louisiana , 379 U.S.
64 , 75 (1964). Yet the Court expressed strong skepticism of the
very concept of criminal prosecutions for libel and noted the
salutary trend of its “virtual disappearance.” Id. , at
69–70 . The Court approvingly cited the Model Penal Code’s
recommendation that criminal libel be limited to speech likely to
cause a breach of the peace and “calculated” to do so. Id. ,
at 70. This is not a promising theoretical springboard for
determining the mens rea required to criminalize other
speech.
If the Court were correct that the Sullivan standard is the appropriate analogy, however, then
this standard should guide how to analyze recklessness in
true-threats prosecutions. The generic formulation of recklessness
requires that an individual disregard a relatively unspecified
level of risk that the harm in question will occur. See Borden , 593 U. S., at ___ (plurality opinion) (slip
op., at 5). Within that potentially broad range, Sullivan provides a more definite and demanding level of risk, reflecting
the First Amendment concerns at stake. The Court has “made clear
that the defendant must have made the false publication with a high
degree of awareness of probable falsity or must have entertained
serious doubts as to the truth.” Harte-Hanks Communications,
Inc. v. Connaughton , 491 U.S.
657 , 667 (1989) (internal quotation marks and ellipsis
omitted). This makes sense. Allowing liability for awareness of a
small chance that a story may be false would undermine the very
shield Sullivan erects.
For similar reasons, after today’s ruling,
future courts grappling with how to articulate the appropriate
level of recklessness in true-threats cases would be well served to
consult the Sullivan standard. The equivalent to Sullivan for true threats would require a high degree of
awareness that a statement was probably threatening or serious
doubts as to the threatening nature of the statement. This could
avoid the chilling that would arise from a more amorphous and
easily satisfied standard.
4
This Court’s various frameworks for
unprotected speech do not speak with one voice, as perhaps befits
the First Amendment. The above survey does not, however, give
reason to depart from the traditional understanding of true
threats. To the contrary, this case law supports keeping true
threats within their traditional bounds. Incitement similarly
requires intent. The same chilling concerns that have led this
Court to approve a knowledge requirement for obscenity are present
with true threats. And to the extent the civil defamation context
is relevant, at the very least, it points to a precise and
demanding form of recklessness.[ 10 ]
IV
Maintaining true threats doctrine within its
traditional boundaries will guard against the overcriminalization
of a wide range of political, artistic, and everyday speech based
on its content alone. This does not mean that unintentionally
threatening communications are exempt from regulation, far from it.
As explained above, there are far fewer First Amendment concerns
with stalking laws that punish repeated, targeted, unwanted conduct
and accompanying speech. For that reason, recklessness is quite
sufficient. As to true threats, intent is neither an unusual nor an
insurmountable bar. “[C]ourts and juries every day pass upon
knowledge, belief and intent . . . having before them no
more than evidence of . . . words and conduct, from
which, in ordinary human experience, mental condition can be
inferred.” American Communications Assn. v. Douds , 339 U.S.
382 , 411 (1950).
* * *
I agree with the Court’s conclusion that the
First Amendment requires a subjective mens rea in
true-threats cases, and I also agree that recklessness is amply
sufficient for this case. Yet I would stop there, leaving for
another day the question of the specific mens rea required
to prosecute true threats generally. If that question is reached,
however, the answer is that true threats encompass a narrow band of
intentional threats. Especially in a climate of intense
polarization, it is dangerous to allow criminal prosecutions for
heated words based solely on an amorphous recklessness standard.
Our society has often concluded that an intent standard sets a
proper balance between safety and the need for a guilty mind, even
in cases that do not involve the First Amendment. Surely when the
power of the State is called upon to imprison someone based on the
content of their words alone, this standard cannot be considered
excessive. Because I part ways with the Court on this score, I
respectfully concur only in part and in the judgment. Notes 1 The statute of conviction
applies to someone who “[r]epeatedly follows, approaches, contacts,
places under surveillance, or makes any form of communication with
another person . . . in a manner that would cause a
reasonable person to suffer serious emotional distress and does
cause that person . . . serious emotional distress.”
Colo. Rev. Stat. §18–3–602(1)(c) (2022). 2 For these reasons,
stalking prosecutions that do not rely on the content of
communications would raise even fewer First Amendment
concerns. 3 Intent requirements are
common, including for incitement that results in actual violence,
not just the threat of it. See infra , at 15–17. For that
reason there are longstanding frameworks for determining when
someone is not guilty by reason of insanity, and when delusions do
(and do not) defeat a showing of intent. See, e.g. , 1 W.
LaFave, Substantive Criminal Law §§7.1(a), (b) (3d ed. 2018); 2 id. , §9.2. 4 The lead dissent asserts
that the Black plurality’s decision was based on how the
statute “ ‘ignore[d] all of the contextual factors that are
necessary to decide whether a particular cross burning’ was covered
by the statute.” Post , at 9 (opinion of Barrett, J.)
(quoting 538 U. S., at 367 (plurality opinion)). But some
context is missing from this reading itself. The full sentence is
“all of the contextual factors that are necessary to decide whether
a particular cross burning is intended to intimidate .” Id. , at 367 (emphasis added). The plurality was thus
concerned with context to the extent it was relevant to the mens
rea requirement needed to render the statute constitutional. Id. , at 365–366. 5 According to the Court
today and the lead dissent, however, Black somehow managed
not to say anything about the First Amendment mens rea requirement for true-threats prosecutions—while striking down a
true-threat conviction under the First Amendment for an
insufficient mens rea requirement. On this reading, Black only discussed intent because “the statute involved in
the case required a showing of intent.” Ante , at 6,
n. 3; post , at 9, n. 4 (discussion of intent was
“a reference to the statutory requirements for a conviction,
not the constitutional requirements”). This puzzling
interpretation does not explain why an illusory mens rea requirement in a Virginia law would pose any First Amendment
problems if the Amendment did not impose a mens rea requirement of this kind. After all, “[w]hy would the First
Amendment care how a jury goes about finding an [intent] element
that is a matter of indifference to the Amendment?” United
States v. Heineman , 767 F.3d 970, 980 (CA10 2014). The
obvious answer, from Black ’s reasoning to its holding, is
that such a mens rea requirement was necessary for the
statute to target true threats. 6 Nor is this limited to
decisions by this Court. Threats cases sweep in political speech.
See, e.g. , State v. Taylor , 379 N. C.
589, 590, 866 S.E.2d 740, 744 (2021). Incitement cases can sweep in
nonpolitical speech. See, e.g. , Rice v. Paladin
Enterprises, Inc. , 128 F.3d 233 , 264, n. 11, 267 (CA4 1997). And still other
cases show how incitement and threats can often go hand in hand.
See, e.g. , State v. Caroll , 456 N. J.
Super. 520, 544–545, 196 A.3d 106, 120–121 (App. Div.
2018). 7 Analogously, the Court’s
civil defamation case law recognizes that heightened liability can
require a heightened mens rea ; even as to nonpublic figures,
a higher standard must be met for punitive damages in certain
cases. See, e.g. , Gertz v. Robert Welch, Inc. , 418 U.S.
323 , 349–350 (1974). 8 The Court has held,
however, that recklessness is sufficient for child pornography. See Osborne v. Ohio , 495 U.S.
103 , 115 (1990). This Court has emphasized time and again how
child pornography is “a special case” because “[t]he market for
child pornography [is] ‘intrinsically related’ to the underlying
abuse” and thus “ ‘an integral part of the production of such
materials, an activity illegal throughout the Nation.’ ” United States v. Stevens, 559
U.S. 460 , 471 (2010) (quoting New York v. Ferber , 458 U.S.
747 , 759, 761 (1982)); see also Osborne , 495 U. S.,
at 110–111. Child pornography, with its integral ties to separate
criminal conduct, is not a strong analogue for threats, which can
be fleeting statements in total isolation from any other
criminality (though it is a stronger analogy to threats as part of
an unlawful course of stalking). Yet the Court’s decision today
puts child pornography on a First Amendment par with overheated
political speech or violent song lyrics. 9 There is a further
safeguard in obscenity cases. Something is obscene if “taken as a
whole, [it] lacks serious literary, artistic, political, or
scientific value.” Ashcroft v. American Civil Liberties
Union , 535 U.S.
564 , 574 (2002) (internal quotation marks omitted). An intent
requirement can provide a similar safeguard for threats. As Virginia v. Black , 538
U.S. 343 (2003), explained, requiring intent distinguishes
between speech intended to intimidate and speech intended to
express a political statement. Id. , at 365–366 (plurality
opinion); id. , at 372 (opinion of Scalia, J.). 10 The
lead dissent headlines its analysis by pointing to this Court’s
case law on “fighting words.” Post , at 3–4 (opinion of
Barrett, J.). This is an unlikely candidate for a broader theory of
the First Amendment. For “nearly three-quarters of a century
. . . the Court has never . . . upheld a
fighting words conviction” and “[t]he cumulative impact of [the
Court’s] decisions is to make it unlikely that a fighting words law
could survive.” E. Chemerinsky, The First Amendment 1094 (6th ed.
2019). It is not hard to see why such convictions would be unlikely
to pass First Amendment muster; the leading case involved a
Jehovah’s Witness distributing literature who was arrested for
breach of the peace for calling a public official a “ ‘damned
Fascist.’ ” Chaplinsky v. New Hampshire , 315 U.S.
568 , 569, 573–574 (1942). Drawing upon a conviction like the
one in Chaplinksy as the proper model for criminalizing
political speech is proof itself of the serious risks with the lead
dissent’s approach. In any event, as to the question at hand, when
such breach of the peace offenses involved threats, intent to
threaten was required. See 2 R. Anderson, Wharton’s Criminal Law
and Procedure §803, pp. 659–660 (1957). SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES
_________________
No. 22–138
_________________
BILLY RAYMOND COUNTERMAN, PETITIONER v. COLORADO
on writ of certiorari to the court of appeals
of colorado
[June 27, 2023]
Justice Thomas, dissenting.
I join Justice Barrett’s dissent in full. I
write separately to address the majority’s surprising and misplaced
reliance on New York Times Co. v. Sullivan , 376 U.S.
254 (1964). In New York Times , this Court held that the
First Amendment bars public figures from recovering damages for
defamation unless they can show that the statement at issue was
made with “ ‘actual malice’—that is, with knowledge that it
was false or with reckless disregard of whether it was false or
not.” Id. , at 280. Like the majority’s decision today,
“ New York Times and the Court’s decisions extending it were
policy-driven decisions masquerading as constitutional law.” McKee v. Cosby , 586 U. S. ___, ___ (2019)
(Thomas, J., concurring in denial of certiorari) (slip op., at 2).
Instead of simply applying the First Amendment as it was understood
at the time of the Founding, “the Court fashioned its own
‘ “federal rule[s]” ’ by balancing the ‘competing values
at stake in defamation suits.’ ” Ibid. (quoting Gertz v. Robert Welch, Inc. , 418
U.S. 323 , 334, 348 (1974)); see also Bose Corp. v. Consumers Union of United States, Inc. , 466 U.S.
485 , 501–502 (1984) (acknowledging that “the rule enunciated in
the New York Times case” is “largely a judge-made rule of
law,” the “content” of which is “given meaning through the
evolutionary process of common-law adjudication”). “The
constitutional libel rules adopted by this Court in New York
Times and its progeny broke sharply from the common law of
libel, and there are sound reasons to question whether the First
and Fourteenth Amendments displaced this body of common law.” McKee , 586 U. S., at ___ (opinion of Thomas, J.) (slip
op., at 6). Thus, as I have previously noted, “[w]e should
reconsider our jurisprudence in this area.” Id. , at ___
(slip op., at 14); see also Berisha v. Lawson , 594
U. S. ___ (2021) (Thomas, J., dissenting from denial of
certiorari).
I am far from alone. Many Members of this Court
have questioned the soundness of New York Times and its
numerous extensions. See, e.g. , Berisha , 594
U. S., at ___–___ (Gorsuch, J., dissenting from denial of
certiorari) (slip op., at 5–8); Coughlin v. Westinghouse
Broadcasting & Cable, Inc ., 476 U.S.
1187 (1986) (Burger, C. J., joined by Rehnquist, J.,
dissenting from denial of certiorari); Gertz , 418
U. S., at 370 (White, J., dissenting); Rosenbloom v. Metromedia, Inc ., 403 U.S.
29 , 62 (1971) (Harlan, J., dissenting); id ., at 78
(Marshall, J., dissenting); Rosenblatt v. Baer , 383 U.S.
75 , 92 (1966) (Stewart, J., concurring); see also E. Kagan, A
Libel Story: Sullivan Then and Now, 18 L. & Soc. Inquiry
197, 207 (1993); J. Lewis & B. Ottley, New York Times v. Sullivan at 50, 64 DePaul L. Rev. 1, 35–36 (2014)
(collecting statements from Justice Scalia); cf. Tah v. Global Witness Publishing, Inc ., 991 F.3d 231, 251–256 (CADC
2021) (Silberman, J., dissenting in part) (questioning the
doctrine). It is thus unfortunate that the majority chooses not
only to prominently and uncritically invoke New York Times ,
but also to extend its flawed, policy-driven First Amendment
analysis to true threats, a separate area of this Court’s
jurisprudence. SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES
_________________
No. 22–138
_________________
BILLY RAYMOND COUNTERMAN, PETITIONER v. COLORADO
on writ of certiorari to the court of appeals
of colorado
[June 27, 2023]
Justice Barrett, with whom Justice Thomas
joins, dissenting.
Billy Counterman was convicted under a Colorado
law that prohibits true threats. As everyone agrees, the statute
requires that the speaker understand the meaning of his words. Ante , at 4, n. 1. The question is what more the First
Amendment requires. Colorado maintains that an objective standard is enough—that is, the government must show that a
reasonable person would regard the statement as a threat of
violence. Counterman, however, argues that the First Amendment
requires a subjective test—that is, the speaker himself must
intend or know the threatening nature of the statement.
It should be easy to choose between these
positions. True threats do not enjoy First Amendment protection,
and nearly every other category of unprotected speech may be
restricted using an objective standard. Nonetheless, the Court
adopts a subjective standard, though not quite the one advanced by
Counterman. The Court holds that speakers must recklessly disregard
the threatening nature of their speech to lose constitutional
protection. Because this unjustifiably grants true threats
preferential treatment, I respectfully dissent.
I
Since the founding, the First Amendment has
allowed the government to regulate certain “areas of speech”
“because of their constitutionally proscribable content.” R. A. V. v. St. Paul , 505 U.S.
377 , 382–383 (1992) (emphasis deleted). This includes true
threats, which are “serious expression[s] of an intent to commit an
act of unlawful violence to a particular individual or group of
individuals.” Virginia v. Black , 538 U.S.
343 , 359 (2003); see also R. A. V. , 505
U. S., at 388 (“[T]hreats of violence are outside the First
Amendment”). True threats carry little value and impose great cost.
See Chaplinsky v. New Hampshire , 315 U.S.
568 , 572 (1942) (“[A]ny benefit that may be derived from [true
threats] is clearly outweighed by the social interest in order and
morality”). “[B]y their very utterance,” true threats “inflict
injury.” Ibid. They provoke “the fear of violence,” create
“disruption,” give rise to “the possibility that the threatened
violence will occur”—and the list goes on. Black , 538 U. S.,
at 360 (internal quotation marks omitted).[ 1 ]
The nature of a true threat points to an
objective test for determining the scope of First Amendment
protection: Neither its “social value” nor its potential for
“injury” depends on the speaker’s subjective intent. Chaplinsky , 315 U. S., at 572. They can relate, of
course—a speaker who does not intend to threaten is less likely to
utter a statement that could be taken that way. But the
Constitution ultimately declines to protect true threats for
objective reasons, not subjective ones. So an objective test
“complements the explanation for excluding threats of violence from
First Amendment protection in the first place.” United
States v. Jeffries , 692 F.3d 473, 480 (CA6 2012).
II
The Court agrees that “[t]he existence of a
threat depends not on ‘the mental state of the author,’ but on
‘what the statement conveys’ to the person on the other end.” Ante , at 6. And it acknowledges that “[w]hen the statement
is understood as a true threat, all the harms that have long made
threats unprotected naturally follow.” Ibid. Nonetheless,
the Court holds Colorado’s statute unconstitutional. Why? Because
the Court installs a prophylactic buffer zone to avoid chilling
protected speech—a buffer zone that protects true threats unless
the speaker “consciously disregarded a substantial risk that his
communications would be viewed as threatening violence.” Ante , at 1, 4–5. That reasoning is flawed.
A
The Court’s first error is awarding true
threats “pride of place among unprotected speech.” Elonis v. United States , 575 U.S. 723, 767 (2015) (Thomas, J.,
dissenting). We have held that nearly every category of unprotected
speech may be regulated using an objective test. In concluding
otherwise, the Court neglects certain cases and misreads
others.
Start with fighting words—a category of
unprotected speech that the Court skips past. Fighting words are
“personally abusive epithets” that are “inherently likely to
provoke violent reaction.” Cohen v. California , 403 U.S.
15 , 20 (1971). Under our precedent, legislatures may regulate
fighting words even when the speaker does not intend to provoke the
listener (or does not recklessly disregard that possibility). Chaplinsky , 315 U. S., at 572–573 (rejecting First
Amendment challenge to a state law punishing “fighting words”
according to a reasonable-person standard); Cantwell v. Connecticut , 310 U.S.
296 , 309–310 (1940) (statements unprotected when they are
“likely to provoke violence and disturbance of good order, even
though no such eventuality be intended”). Instead, we ask only
whether “the ordinary citizen,” using her “common knowledge,” would
reasonably understand the statement as a “direct personal insult.” Cohen , 403 U. S., at 20; see also Texas v. Johnson , 491 U.S.
397 , 409 (1989).
The Court similarly overlooks the category of
“false, deceptive, or misleading” commercial speech. Zauderer v. Office of Disciplinary Counsel of Supreme
Court of Ohio , 471 U.S.
626 , 638 (1985); In re R. M. J. , 455 U.S.
191 , 203 (1982) (“Truthful advertising . . . is
entitled to the protections of the First Amendment,” but
“[m]isleading advertising may be prohibited entirely”); Ibanez v. Florida Dept. of Business and Professional
Regulation , Bd. of Accountancy , 512
U.S. 136 , 142 (1994) (“[F]alse, deceptive, or misleading
commercial speech may be banned”). Here, too, our cases suggest
that First Amendment protection depends on objective falsity rather
than the speaker’s intention. See In re R. M. J. ,
455 U. S., at 202 (“[R]egulation—and imposition of
discipline—are permissible where the particular advertising is inherently likely to deceive or where the record indicates
that a particular form or method of advertising has in fact been
deceptive ” (emphasis added)); see also Milavetz , Gallop & Milavetz , P. A. v. United
States , 559 U.S.
229 , 250–253 (2010). Thus, the government is “free to prevent
the dissemination of commercial speech that is false, deceptive, or
misleading,” without regard to whether the speaker knew that the
recipient would be deceived or misled. Zauderer , 471
U. S., at 638.
Or take obscenity, which we have long held is
“not protected by the freedoms of speech and press.” Roth v. United States , 354 U.S.
476 , 481 (1957). Speech qualifies as obscene if the
“ ‘average person, applying contemporary community
standards,’ ” would conclude that “the work, taken as a whole,
appeals to the prurient interest.” Miller v. California , 413 U.S.
15 , 24 (1973). The jury must also make an objective judgment
about whether the speech “depicts or describes” sexual conduct “in
a patently offensive way,” and whether it “lacks serious literary,
artistic, political, or scientific value.” Ibid. The
speaker’s “ ‘belief as to the obscenity or non-obscenity of
the material is irrelevant.’ ” Hamling v. United
States , 418 U.S.
87 , 120–121 (1974). So long as the defendant has “knowledge of
the contents of the materials,” her speech may be constitutionally
regulated. Id. , at 123. An objective, reasonable-person
standard applies.
In an effort to bolster its position, the Court
floats a different standard for obscenity laws, asserting that “the
First Amendment demands proof of a defendant’s mindset to make out
an obscenity case.” Ante , at 8. By “mindset,” the Court
apparently means that the defendant must have some awareness that
an average person would consider the materials obscene. But the
Court draws this conclusion from cases rejecting a strict
liability standard—for example, we have held that the
proprietor of a bookstore cannot be liable for possessing an
obscene book unless he knew what was in it. Smith v. California , 361 U.S.
147 , 149, 155 (1959); Mishkin v. New York , 383 U.S.
502 , 510–512 (1966); see also Ginsberg v. New
York , 390 U.S.
629 , 643–644 (1968).[ 2 ]
Knowing what the material depicts is not the same as knowing how
the average person would react to it—just as there is an important
difference between Counterman’s knowledge of what his words meant
and his knowledge of how they would be perceived. Though the Court
conflates the two, our obscenity cases have repeatedly refused to
require the latter as a matter of constitutional law. Hamling , 418 U. S., at 120–123; Rosen v. United States , 161 U.S.
29 , 41–42 (1896). So obscenity doctrine does not help
Counterman.
The Court leans hardest on defamation law, but
its argument depends on a single, cherry-picked strand of the
doctrine. Yes, New York Times Co. v. Sullivan requires public figures and public officials to show “actual
malice” on a defamation claim, and we have defined “actual malice”
as “knowledge that [the statement] was false” or “reckless
disregard of whether it was false or not.” 376
U.S. 254 , 279–280 (1964). But that is not the full story. A
private person need only satisfy an objective standard to recover
actual damages for defamation. Gertz v. Robert Welch , Inc. , 418 U.S.
323 , 347–350 (1974). And if the defamatory speech does not
involve a matter of public concern, she may recover punitive
damages with the same showing. Dun & Bradstreet , Inc. v. Greenmoss Builders , Inc. , 472 U.S.
749 , 760–761 (1985) (plurality opinion). We have justified that
distinction on the ground that public-figure defamation claims may
deter “would-be critics of official conduct . . . from
voicing their criticism,” which would “dampe[n] the vigor and limit
the variety of public debate.” Sullivan , 376 U. S., at
279. Not only that, but “the state interest in protecting” public
figures is weaker, since they tend to “enjoy significantly greater
access to the channels of effective communication and hence have a
more realistic opportunity to counteract false statements.” Gertz , 418 U. S., at 344. So, despite what the Court
says, Sullivan does not stand for the broad proposition that
the First Amendment “demand[s] a subjective mental-state
requirement.” Ante , at 6. Instead, it simply raises the bar
for borderline unprotected speech with high social value (because
of its proximity to public discourse) and low potential for injury
(because public figures can engage in counterspeech). Sullivan ’s rationale does not justify a
heightened mens rea for true threats. Because true threats
are not typically proximate to debate on matters of public concern,
the Court’s newly erected buffer zone does not serve the end of
protecting heated political commentary. Nor can public figures use
counterspeech in the public square to protect themselves from
serious threats of physical violence. And perversely, private
individuals now have less protection from true threats than from
defamation—even though they presumably value their lives more than
their reputations. See Gertz , 418 U. S., at 347–350.
The Court has therefore extended Sullivan in a way that
makes no sense on Sullivan ’s own terms.
I will give the Court this much: Speakers must
specifically intend to incite violence before they lose First
Amendment protection. Brandenburg v. Ohio , 395 U.S.
444 , 447 (1969) ( per curiam ) (defining incitement
as “advocacy . . . directed to inciting or producing
imminent lawless action and likely to incite or produce such
action”); see also Hess v. Indiana , 414 U.S.
105 , 108–109 (1973) ( per curiam ). Once more, however,
our precedent itself explains the difference. Incitement, as a form
of “advocacy,” often arises in the political arena. See Brandenburg , 395 U. S., at 447 (Ku Klux Klan rally held
to plan a “ ‘marc[h] on Congress’ ”); Hess , 414
U. S., at 106 (antiwar demonstration); Abrams v. United States , 250 U.S.
616 , 620 (1919) (pamphlets about the President’s
“ ‘shameful, cowardly silence about the intervention in
Russia’ ”). A specific intent requirement helps draw the line
between incitement and “political rhetoric lying at the core of the
First Amendment.” NAACP v. Claiborne Hardware Co. , 458 U.S.
886 , 926–927 (1982). The Court does not contend that targeted
threats and political commentary share a similarly close
relationship.
In sum, our First Amendment precedent does not
set a “baseline ban on an objective standard.” Ante , at 10.
Precedent does more than allow an objective test for true threats;
on balance, it affirmatively supports one.
B
The Court’s analysis also gives short shrift
to how an objective test works in practice. Two key features of
true threats already guard against the risk of silencing protected
speech. Thus, there is no need to go further and adopt the Court’s
heightened standard.
First, only a very narrow class of statements
satisfies the definition of a true threat. To make a true threat,
the speaker must express “an intent to commit an act of unlawful
violence .” Black , 538 U. S., at 359 (emphasis
added). Speech that is merely “offensive,” “ ‘poorly
chosen,’ ” or “unpopular” does not qualify. Brief for
Petitioner 31, 36, 42. The statement must also threaten violence
“to a particular individual or group of individuals”—not just in
general. Black , 538 U. S., at 359. These tight
guardrails distinguish true threats from public-figure defamation,
the model for the Court’s rule. While defamatory statements can
cover an infinite number of topics, true threats target one:
unlawful violence.
Second, the statement must be deemed threatening
by a reasonable listener who is familiar with the “entire factual
context” in which the statement occurs. State v. Taveras , 342 Conn. 563, 572, 271 A.3d 123, 129 (2022). This
inquiry captures (among other things) the speaker’s tone, the
audience, the medium for the communication, and the broader
exchange in which the statement occurs.[ 3 ] Each consideration helps weed out protected speech from
true threats.
Our decision in Black illustrates the
point. There, the Court considered a Virginia law that prohibited
cross burning “ ‘with the intent of intimidating any person or
group of persons.’ ” 538 U. S., at 348. Notably, the
statute included a presumption: “ ‘Any such burning of a cross
shall be prima facie evidence of an intent to intimidate.’ ” Ibid. After three men were convicted under the statute, they
challenged it as facially unconstitutional. We upheld the general
prohibition on cross burning, concluding that the First Amendment
allows the government to ban “a particular type of threat.” Id. , at 362–363. A plurality then went on to address the
statutory presumption. While cross burning “may mean that a person
is engaging in constitutionally proscribable intimidation,” the
plurality reasoned, the act is not monolithic. Id. , at 365.
Cross burning could be directed “at an individual” or “at a group
of like-minded believers”; it could be done “on a neighbor’s lawn”
or “at a public rally”; it could be done with the property owner’s
“permission” or without it. Id. , at 366 . The
presumption “blur[red] the line” between these different situations
and “ignore[d] all of the contextual factors that are necessary to
decide whether a particular cross burning” was covered by the
statute or not.[ 4 ] Id. ,
at 365, 367. Thus, the presumption was unconstitutionally
overbroad.
The Black plurality’s reasoning can be
boiled down to the following insight: When context is ignored, true
threats cannot be reliably distinguished from protected speech. The
reverse also holds: When context is properly considered,
constitutional concerns abate. See, e.g. , Watts v. United States , 394 U.S.
705 , 708 (1969) ( per curiam ) (concluding that a
statement was “political hyperbole” instead of a true threat based
on “context,” “the expressly conditional nature of the statement,”
and the “reaction of the listeners”).
One more point: Many States have long had
statutes like Colorado’s on the books. See Brief for Illinois et
al. as Amici Curiae 16–17. Before we took this case, the
vast majority of Courts of Appeals and state high courts had upheld
these statutes as constitutional. So objective tests are
effectively the status quo today, yet Counterman still struggles to
identify past prosecutions that came close to infringing on
protected speech. Tr. of Oral Arg. 28–30. The silence is
telling.
C
So is the silence in the historical record.
Since 1791, true threats have been excluded from the “speech”
protected by the First Amendment. R. A.V. , 505
U. S., at 382–383, 388. If Counterman could show that a
subjective requirement has been inherent in the definition of “true
threat” since the founding, he would have a compelling case. But
Counterman cannot make that showing.
For starters, he produces no evidence directly
addressing the meaning of the First Amendment—nothing from state
ratifying conventions, political commentary, or even early debates
about efforts to regulate threats in ways that might threaten
speech. That is not surprising at the federal level, because the
Federal Government did not prohibit threats until the early 20th
century. Elonis , 575 U. S., at 760 (Thomas, J.,
dissenting). Some States, however, both regulated threats and
guaranteed the right to free speech in their own constitutions. Id. , at 760–761 . Yet even at the state level, there
was apparently no discussion about the implications of these
statutes for the constitutional right.
That void notwithstanding, the state threat
statutes are the evidence on which Counterman seizes. He argues
that they imposed a subjective mens rea , demonstrating that
the founding generation thought that threats could be punished on
no less. But as Justice Thomas has already discussed in detail,
this is incorrect. See id. , at 760–765. Rather than a
subjective mens rea , these statutes used an objective
standard resembling Colorado’s.
Even if they did require a heightened mens
rea , though, these statutes would not carry the day for
Counterman. The enactment of a statute against the backdrop of a
free speech guarantee tends to show that the legislature thought
the statute consistent with that guarantee. Thus, if the question
were whether such statutes violated the First Amendment,
their existence would be evidence to the contrary. But the question
here is whether a subjective intent requirement is the
constitutional floor. And because the legislature is always free to
exceed the floor, the enactment of legislation does not necessarily
reflect the legislature’s view of the constitutional minimum.
At the end of the day, then, the best historical
case for Counterman does not add up to much. He is plainly not
asking the Court to enforce a historically sanctioned rule, but
rather to fashion a new one.
D
Even if a subjective test had a historical
pedigree, the Court’s chosen standard of recklessness certainly
does not. Where does recklessness come from? It was not raised by
the parties. Only the Solicitor General noted this possibility—and
briefly at that. Brief for United States as Amicus Curiae 28–31. Nor did the courts below address recklessness; indeed, very
few courts (of the many that have taken up the question) have
settled on recklessness as the constitutional floor for true
threats. See, e.g. , State v. Mrozinski , 971
N.W.2d 233, 243–245 (Minn. 2022); In re
J. J. M. , 265 A.3d 246, 269–270 (Pa. 2021). Still,
the Court adopts recklessness as “the right path forward.” Ante , at 11. Its rationale is, at best, unclear.
The Court begins by acknowledging the
“ ‘competing value[s]’ ” of “free expression” on one
hand, and “profound harms . . . to both individuals and
society” on the other. Ante , at 11–12. But why do these
considerations point to recklessness? A knowledge or purpose
standard would allow more free expression, so maybe we should go
higher. See ante , at 16 (Sotomayor, J., concurring in part
and concurring in judgment) (“chilling concerns only further
buttress the conclusion that true threats should be limited to
intentionally threatening speech”). An objective standard would
cause less harm to victims, so perhaps lower is better. The optimal
balance strikes me as a question best left to the legislature,
which could calibrate the mens rea to the circumstance—for
example, higher for the criminal context and lower for the civil.
See Brief for Illinois et al. as Amici Curiae 28–30
(States “have a range of policy reasons for using subjective
standards for penalizing threats of violence” and many “choose to
require proof of a speaker’s subjective mental state” in some
situations but not others).
Nor does our First Amendment precedent buttress
the Court’s preferred standard. A recklessness requirement
currently applies only to public-figure defamation claims.
Incitement to violence calls for more. Fighting words,
private-figure defamation, false commercial speech, and obscenity
require less. I fail to see why, of all these categories of
unprotected speech, public-figure defamation is the best analog for
true threats. The reality is that recklessness is not grounded in
law, but in a Goldilocks judgment: Recklessness is not too much,
not too little, but instead “just right.”
III
Some may find Colorado’s statute harsh, and
the Court’s decision seems driven in no small part by the heavy
hammer of criminal punishment. See ante , at 12; ante ,
at 14–15, 20–21 (opinion of Sotomayor, J.). While an objective test
is “a familiar feature of civil liability in tort law,” the
“ ‘conventional requirement for criminal conduct’ ” is
“ ‘ awareness of some wrongdoing.’ ” Elonis ,
575 U. S., at 737–738. In keeping with this convention, we
generally presume that “federal criminal statutes that are silent
on the required mental state” nonetheless impose the “ mens
rea which is necessary to separate wrongful conduct from
otherwise innocent conduct.” Id. , at 736 (internal quotation
marks omitted). That is why we rejected an objective standard for
the federal threat prohibition, 18 U. S. C. §875(c). 575
U. S., at 737–739. It is “the threatening nature of the
communication” that “makes the conduct ‘wrongful’ ”; thus, the
statute is best interpreted to require that the defendant be aware
of the impact of his speech. Id. , at 737.
But this case is about the scope of the First
Amendment, not the interpretation of a criminal statute.
Accordingly, the Court’s holding affects the civil consequences for true threats just as much as it restricts criminal
liability. And the civil context underscores the danger of adopting
a Sullivan -style buffer zone for true threats.
Consider, for example, threat victims who seek
restraining orders to protect themselves from their harassers. See, e.g. , United States v. Elonis , 841 F.3d 589,
593 (CA3 2016) (defendant’s wife sought a restraining order after
he wrote on Facebook, “I’m not going to rest until your body is a
mess, soaked in blood and dying from all the little cuts”). Civil
orders can also keep individuals away from particular geographic
areas. Imagine someone who threatens to bomb an airport, State v. Johnston , 156 Wash. 2d 355, 358–359, 127 P.3d 707 , 708–709 (2006), or “shoot up [a] courthous[e],” State v. Draskovich , 2017 S. D. 76, ¶3, 904
N.W.2d 759, 761. The speaker might well end up barred from the
location in question—for good reason. Yet after today, such orders
cannot be obtained without proof—not necessarily easy to
secure—that the person who issued the threat anticipated that it
would elicit fear. See Tr. of Oral Arg. 92–93.
The government can also opt to counteract true
threats by means of civil enforcement actions. For instance, 18
U. S. C. §248 prohibits “threat[s] of force” against any
person “obtaining or providing reproductive health services” or
“seeking to exercise the First Amendment right of religious freedom
at a place of religious worship.” The statute imposes a range of
civil penalties, and it allows enforcement suits by both private
persons and government officials. See, e.g. , United
States v. Dillard , 795 F.3d 1191, 1196–1197 (CA10 2015)
(Government brought §248 action after defendant warned a health
provider, “[y]ou will be checking under your car everyday—because
maybe today is the day someone places an explosive under it”); McCullen v. Coakley , 573 U.S.
464 , 491 (2014) (noting that several States have similar laws).
After today, these civil enforcement actions face a higher
constitutional hurdle.
In addition, employers and school administrators
often discipline individuals who make true threats. Consider the
student who was expelled after “draft[ing] two violent, misogynic,
and obscenity-laden rants expressing a desire to molest, rape, and
murder” his ex-girlfriend. Doe v. Pulaski Cty. Special
School Dist. , 306 F.3d 616 , 619 (CA8 2002) (en banc). Or the one who was
suspended after “ ‘talking about taking a gun to school’ to
‘shoot everyone he hates.’ ” D. J. M. v. Hannibal Public School Dist. No. 60 , 647 F.3d 754, 758 (CA8
2011); Lovell v. Poway Unified School District , 90 F.3d 367 , 369, 372–373 (CA9 1996) (similar); Haughwout v. Tordenti , 332 Conn. 559, 561–562, 211
A.3d 1, 3–4 (2019) (similar). True threats can also be expressed by
a parent, a teacher, or an employee in another context altogether.
See, e.g. , Taveras , 342 Conn., at 567–569, 578, 271
A. 3d, at 126–128, 133 (parent); Smith v. New York
City Dept. of Ed. , 109 App. Div. 3d 701, 702–703, 972 N.Y.S.2d
221, 222 (2013) (teacher); Diggs v. St. Louis ,
613 S.W.3d 858, 862, 864 (Mo. App. 2020) (correctional
officer).
Barring some reason why the speech receives
lesser constitutional protection, e.g. , Mahanoy Area
School Dist. v. B. L. , 594 U. S. ___, ___–___
(2021) (slip op., at 4–5), the Court’s new rule applies to all of
these situations. That can make all the difference in some cases. A
delusional speaker may lack awareness of the threatening nature of
her speech; a devious speaker may strategically disclaim such
awareness; and a lucky speaker may leave behind no evidence of
mental state for the government to use against her. The Court’s
decision thus sweeps much further than it lets on.
* * *
The bottom line is this: Counterman
communicated true threats, which, “everyone agrees, lie outside the
bounds of the First Amendment’s protection.” Ante , at 4. He
knew what the words meant. Those threats caused the victim to fear
for her life, and they “upended her daily existence.” Ante ,
at 2. Nonetheless, the Court concludes that Counterman can prevail
on a First Amendment defense. Nothing in the Constitution compels
that result. I respectfully dissent. Notes 1 Indeed, the Colorado
Legislature considered these very harms when it enacted the statute
at issue here. The statutory findings explain that stalking,
harassment, and threats have “an immediate and long-lasting impact
on quality of life as well as risks to security and safety of the
victim and persons close to the victim.” Colo. Rev. Stat.
§§18–3–601(1)(f), 18–3–602(1) (2022). So the legislature passed the
statute to “encourag[e] and authoriz[e] effective intervention”
before the covered conduct could “escalate into behavior that has
even more serious consequences.” §18–3–601(2). 2 The Court also cites Elonis v. United States , ante , at 8, 9,
n. 4, which Counterman argues puts a “gloss” on obscenity
doctrine, Tr. of Oral Arg. 6–7. While Elonis briefly
discusses the necessary mens rea for a conviction under a
federal obscenity statute, it does so only in dicta. 575 U.S. 723,
739–740 (2015). Elonis does not alter the doctrinal
framework for assessing the constitutionality of obscenity laws:
That case involves true threats, not obscenity, and it interprets a
federal statute, not the Constitution. 3 Colorado’s test provides
a good example. Juries must apply the following nonexhaustive
factors to determine whether a statement is a true threat: “(1) the
statement’s role in a broader exchange, if any, including
surrounding events; (2) the medium or platform through which the
statement was communicated, including any distinctive conventions
or architectural features; (3) the manner in which the statement
was conveyed ( e.g. , anonymously or not, privately or
publicly); (4) the relationship between the speaker and
recipient(s); and (5) the subjective reaction of the statement’s
intended or foreseeable recipient(s).” People in the Interest of
R. D. , 464 P.3d 717, 721–722 (Colo. 2020). 4 As Justice Sotomayor
emphasizes, ante , at 10, n. 4, the plurality said that
context informs “whether a particular cross burning is intended
to intimidate ,” 538 U. S., at 367 (emphasis added). But
this was a reference to the statutory requirements for a
conviction, not the constitutional requirements—the Virginia
statute covered only threats made “ ‘with the intent of
intimidating any person or group of persons.’ ” Id. , at
348. At no point did the Court hold that the First Amendment
demands specific intent; on the contrary, it recognized that a
statement made “with the intent of placing the victim in fear of
bodily harm or death” is “ a type of true threat.” Id. , at 360 (emphasis added). | The Supreme Court ruled that true threats of violence are not protected by the First Amendment and are punishable as crimes. In the case of Billy Counterman, who sent threatening messages to a local singer, the Court held that the First Amendment requires proof that the defendant had a subjective understanding of the threatening nature of his statements, with a mental state of recklessness being sufficient. The Court also emphasized the impact of such threats on the victim, noting that they caused fear and significantly disrupted her life. However, Justice Sotomayor dissented, arguing that the majority's decision allowed Counterman to prevail on a First Amendment defense despite communicating true threats. |
Equal Protection | Pace v. Alabama | https://supreme.justia.com/cases/federal/us/106/583/ | U.S. Supreme Court Pace v. Alabama, 106
U.S. 583 (1883) Pace v. Alabama Decided January 29,
1883 106
U.S. 583 ERROR TO THE SUPREME
COURT OF THE STATE OF
ALABAMA Syllabus Section 4189 of the Code of Alabama, prohibiting a white person
and a negro from living with each other in adultery or fornication,
is not in conflict with the Constitution of the United States,
although it prescribes penalties more severe than those to which
the parties would be subject, were they of the same race and
color.
Section 4184 of the Code of Alabama provides that
"If any man and woman live together in adultery or fornication,
each of them must, on the first conviction of the offense, be fined
not less than one hundred dollars, and may also be imprisoned in
the county jail or sentenced to hard labor for the county for not
more than six months. On the second conviction for the offense with
the same person, the offender must be fined not less than three
hundred dollars, and may be imprisoned in the county jail, or
sentenced to hard labor for the county for not more than twelve
months, and for a third or any subsequent conviction with the same
person, must be imprisoned in the penitentiary, or sentenced to
hard labor for the county for two years."
Section 4189 of the same code declares that
"If any white person and any negro, or the descendant of any
negro to the third generation, inclusive, though one ancestor of
each generation was a white person, intermarry or live in adultery
or fornication with each other, each of them must, on conviction,
be imprisoned in the penitentiary or sentenced to hard labor for
the county for not less than two nor more than seven years. " Page 106 U. S. 584 In November, 1881, the plaintiff in error, Tony Pace, a negro
man, and Mary J. Cox, a white woman, were indicted under sec. 4189
in a circuit court of Alabama for living together in a state of
adultery or fornication, and were tried, convicted, and sentenced,
each to two years' imprisonment in the state penitentiary. On
appeal to the supreme court of the state, the judgment was affirmed
and he brought the case here on writ of error, insisting that the
act under which he was indicted and convicted is in conflict with
the concluding clause of the first section of the Fourteenth
Amendment of the Constitution, which declares that no state shall
"deny to any person the equal protection of the laws."
MR. JUSTICE FIELD delivered the opinion of the Court, and after
stating the case as above, proceeded as follows:
The counsel of the plaintiff in error compares secs. 4184 and
4189 of the Code of Alabama, and assuming that the latter relates
to the same offense as the former and prescribes a greater
punishment for it because one of the parties is a negro or of negro
descent, claims that a discrimination is made against the colored
person in the punishment designated which conflicts with the clause
of the Fourteenth Amendment prohibiting a state from denying to any
person within its jurisdiction the equal protection of the
laws.
The counsel is undoubtedly correct in his view of the purpose of
the clause of the amendment in question -- that it was to prevent
hostile and discriminating state legislation against any person or
class of persons. Equality of protection under the laws implies not
only accessibility by each one, whatever his race, on the same
terms with others to the courts of the country for the security of
his person and property, but that in the administration of criminal
justice, he shall not be subjected for the same offense to any
greater or different punishment. Such was the view of Congress in
the reenactment of the Civil Rights Act of May 31, 1870, c. 114,
after the adoption of the amendment. That act, after providing that
all persons within Page 106 U. S. 585 the jurisdiction of the United States shall have the same right,
in every state and territory, to make and enforce contracts, to
sue, be parties, give evidence, and to the full and equal benefit
of all laws and proceedings for the security of person and property
as is enjoyed by white citizens, declares, in sec. 16, that they
shall be subject
"to like punishment, pains, penalties, taxes, licenses, and
exactions of every kind, and none other, any law, statute,
ordinance, regulation, or custom to the contrary
notwithstanding."
The defect in the argument of counsel consists in his assumption
that any discrimination is made by the laws of Alabama in the
punishment provided for the offense for which the plaintiff in
error was indicted when committed by a person of the African race
and when committed by a white person. The two sections of the Code
cited are entirely consistent. The one prescribes generally a
punishment for an offense committed between persons of different
sexes; the other prescribes a punishment for an offense which can
only be committed where the two sexes are of different races. There
is in neither section any discrimination against either race.
Section 4184 equally includes the offense when the persons of the
two sexes are both white and when they are both black. Section 4189
applies the same punishment to both offenders, the white and the
black. Indeed, the offense against which this latter section is
aimed cannot be committed without involving the persons of both
races in the same punishment. Whatever discrimination is made in
the punishment prescribed in the two sections is directed against
the offense designated, and not against the person of any
particular color or race. The punishment of each offending person,
whether white or black, is the same. Judgment affirmed. | The Supreme Court upheld an Alabama law that prohibited interracial adultery or fornication and prescribed harsher penalties compared to similar laws for same-race couples. The Court reasoned that the law did not violate the Fourteenth Amendment's Equal Protection Clause because it applied equally to both races involved in the interracial relationship, with both the white and black individuals receiving the same punishment. The Court emphasized that the law targeted a specific offense that could only occur between races, and the harsher punishment was due to the nature of the offense, not racial discrimination. |
Free Speech | 303 Creative LLC v. Elenis | https://supreme.justia.com/cases/federal/us/600/21-476/ | NOTICE: This opinion is subject to
formal revision before publication in the United States Reports.
Readers are requested to notify the Reporter of Decisions, Supreme
Court of the United States, Washington, D. C. 20543,
[email protected], of any typographical or other formal
errors.
SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES
_________________
No. 21–476
_________________
303 CREATIVE LLC, et al., PETITIONERS v. AUBREY ELENIS, et al.
on writ of certiorari to the united states
court of appeals for the tenth circuit
[June 30, 2023]
Justice Gorsuch delivered the opinion of the
Court.
Like many States, Colorado has a law forbidding
businesses from engaging in discrimination when they sell goods and
services to the public. Laws along these lines have done much to
secure the civil rights of all Americans. But in this particular
case Colorado does not just seek to ensure the sale of goods or
services on equal terms. It seeks to use its law to compel an
individual to create speech she does not believe. The question we
face is whether that course violates the Free Speech Clause of the
First Amendment.
I
A
Through her business, 303 Creative LLC, Lorie
Smith offers website and graphic design, marketing advice, and
social media management services. Recently, she decided to expand
her offerings to include services for couples seeking websites for
their weddings. As she envisions it, her websites will provide
couples with text, graphic arts, and videos to “celebrate” and
“conve[y ]” the “details” of their “unique love story.” App.
to Pet. for Cert. 182a, 187a, 198a. The websites will discuss how
the couple met, explain their backgrounds, families, and future
plans, and provide information about their upcoming wedding. All of
the text and graphics on these websites will be “original,”
“customized,” and “tailored” creations. Id. , at 187a. The
websites will be “expressive in nature,” designed “to communicate a
particular message.” Id. , at 181a. Viewers will know, too,
“that the websites are [Ms. Smith’s] original artwork,” for the
name of the company she owns and operates by herself will be
displayed on every one. Id. , at 187a.
While Ms. Smith has laid the groundwork for her
new venture, she has yet to carry out her plans. She worries that,
if she does so, Colorado will force her to express views with which
she disagrees. Ms. Smith provides her website and graphic services
to customers regardless of their race, creed, sex, or sexual
orientation. Id. , at 184a. But she has never created
expressions that contradict her own views for anyone—whether that
means generating works that encourage violence, demean another
person, or defy her religious beliefs by, say, promoting atheism.
See ibid. ; see also Tr. of Oral Arg. 19–20. Ms. Smith does
not wish to do otherwise now, but she worries Colorado has
different plans. Specifically, she worries that, if she enters the
wedding website business, the State will force her to convey
messages inconsistent with her belief that marriage should be
reserved to unions between one man and one woman. App. to Pet. for
Cert. 177a–190a. Ms. Smith acknowledges that her views about
marriage may not be popular in all quarters. But, she asserts, the
First Amendment’s Free Speech Clause protects her from being
compelled to speak what she does not believe. The Constitution, she
insists, protects her right to differ.
B
To clarify her rights, Ms. Smith filed a
lawsuit in federal district court. In that suit, she sought an
injunction to prevent the State from forcing her to create wedding
websites celebrating marriages that defy her beliefs. App. 303–305.
To secure relief, Ms. Smith first had to establish her standing to
sue. That required her to show “a credible threat” existed that
Colorado would, in fact, seek to compel speech from her that she
did not wish to produce. Susan B. Anthony List v. Driehaus , 573 U.S.
149 , 159 (2014).
Toward that end, Ms. Smith began by directing
the court to the Colorado Anti-Discrimination Act (CADA). That law
defines a “public accommodation” broadly to include almost every
public-facing business in the State. Colo. Rev. Stat. §24–34–601(1)
(2022). In what some call its “Accommodation Clause,” the law
prohibits a public accommodation from denying “the full and equal
enjoyment” of its goods and services to any customer based on his
race, creed, disability, sexual orientation, or other statutorily
enumerated trait. §24–34–601(2)(a). Either state officials or
private citizens may bring actions to enforce the law. §§24–34–306,
24–34–602(1). And a variety of penalties can follow. Courts can
order fines up to $500 per violation. §24–34–602(1)(a). The
Colorado Commission on Civil Rights can issue cease-and-desist
orders, §24–34–306(9), and require violators to take various other
“affirmative action[s].” §24–34–605; §24–34–306(9). In the past,
these have included participation in mandatory educational programs
and the submission of ongoing compliance reports to state
officials. See Masterpiece Cakeshop, Ltd. v. Colorado
Civil Rights Comm’n , 584 U. S. ___, ___ (2018) (slip op.,
at 8).[ 1 ]
In her lawsuit, Ms. Smith alleged that, if she
enters the wedding website business to celebrate marriages she does
endorse, she faces a credible threat that Colorado will seek to use
CADA to compel her to create websites celebrating marriages she
does not endorse. 6 F. 4th 1160, 1173–1174 (CA10 2021). As
evidence, Ms. Smith pointed to Colorado’s record of past
enforcement actions under CADA, including one that worked its way
to this Court five years ago. See Masterpiece Cakeshop , 584
U. S., at ___ (slip op., at 9); see also App. 25–155
(discussing Colorado’s other past enforcement actions).
To facilitate the district court’s resolution of
the merits of her case, Ms. Smith and the State stipulated to a
number of facts:
bullet10Ms. Smith is “willing to work with all
people regardless of classifications such as race, creed, sexual
orientation, and gender,” and she “will gladly create custom
graphics and websites” for clients of any sexual orientation. App.
to Pet. for Cert. 184a.
bullet10She will not produce content that
“contradicts biblical truth” regardless of who orders it. Ibid. bullet10Her belief that marriage is a union
between one man and one woman is a sincerely held religious
conviction. Id. , at 179a.
bullet10All of the graphic and website design
services Ms. Smith provides are “expressive.” Id. , at
181a.
bullet10The websites and graphics Ms. Smith
designs are “original, customized” creations that “contribut[e] to
the overall messages” her business conveys “through the websites”
it creates. Id. , at 181a–182a.
bullet10Just like the other services she
provides, the wedding websites Ms. Smith plans to create “will be
expressive in nature.” Id. , at 187a.
bullet10Those wedding websites will be
“customized and tailored” through close collaboration with
individual couples, and they will “express Ms. Smith’s and 303
Creative’s message celebrating and promoting” her view of marriage. Id. , at 186a–187a.
bullet10Viewers of Ms. Smith’s websites “will
know that the websites are [Ms. Smith’s and 303 Creative’s]
original artwork.” Id. , at 187a.
bullet10To the extent Ms. Smith may not be able
to provide certain services to a potential customer, “[t]here are
numerous companies in the State of Colorado and across the nation
that offer custom website design services.” Id. , at
190a.
C
Ultimately, the district court ruled against
Ms. Smith. 405 F. Supp. 3d 907, 912 (Colo. 2019). So did the
Tenth Circuit. 6 F. 4th, at 1168. For its part, the Tenth
Circuit held that Ms. Smith had standing to sue. In that court’s
judgment, she had established a credible threat that, if she
follows through on her plans to offer wedding website services,
Colorado will invoke CADA to force her to create speech she does
not believe or endorse. Id ., at 1172–1175. The court pointed
to the fact that “Colorado has a history of past enforcement
against nearly identical conduct— i.e. , Masterpiece
Cakeshop ”; that anyone in the State may file a complaint
against Ms. Smith and initiate “a potentially burdensome
administrative hearing” process; and that “Colorado [has]
decline[d] to disavow future enforcement” proceedings against her. Id. , at 1174. Before us, no party challenges these
conclusions.
Turning to the merits, however, the Tenth
Circuit held that Ms. Smith was not entitled to the injunction she
sought. The court acknowledged that Ms. Smith’s planned wedding
websites qualify as “pure speech” protected by the First Amendment. Id ., at 1176. As a result, the court reasoned, Colorado had
to satisfy “strict scrutiny” before compelling speech from her that
she did not wish to create. Id ., at 1178. Under that
standard, the court continued, the State had to show both that
forcing Ms. Smith to create speech would serve a compelling
governmental interest and that no less restrictive alternative
exists to secure that interest. Ibid . Ultimately, a divided
panel concluded that the State had carried these burdens. As the
majority saw it, Colorado has a compelling interest in ensuring
“equal access to publicly available goods and services,” and no
option short of coercing speech from Ms. Smith can satisfy that
interest because she plans to offer “unique services” that are, “by
definition, unavailable elsewhere.” Id. , at 1179–1180
(internal quotation marks omitted).
Chief Judge Tymkovich dissented. He observed
that “ensuring access to a particular person’s” voice,
expression, or artistic talent has never qualified as “a compelling
state interest” under this Court’s precedents. Id. , at 1203.
Nor, he submitted, should courts depart from those precedents now.
“Taken to its logical end,” Chief Judge Tymkovich warned, his
colleagues’ approach would permit the government to “regulate the
messages communicated by all artists”—a result he called
“unprecedented.” Id ., at 1204.
We granted certiorari to review the Tenth
Circuit’s disposition. 595 U. S. ___ (2022).
II
The framers designed the Free Speech Clause of
the First Amendment to protect the “freedom to think as you will
and to speak as you think.” Boy Scouts of America v. Dale , 530 U.S.
640 , 660–661 (2000) (internal quotation marks omitted). They
did so because they saw the freedom of speech “both as an end and
as a means.” Whitney v. California , 274 U.S.
357 , 375 (1927) (Brandeis, J., concurring); see also 12 The
Papers of James Madison 193–194 (C. Hobson & R. Rutland eds.
1979). An end because the freedom to think and speak is among our
inalienable human rights. See, e.g. , 4 Annals of Cong. 934
(1794) (Rep. Madison). A means because the freedom of thought and
speech is “indispensable to the discovery and spread of political
truth.” Whitney , 274 U. S., at 375 (Brandeis, J.,
concurring). By allowing all views to flourish, the framers
understood, we may test and improve our own thinking both as
individuals and as a Nation. For all these reasons, “[i]f there is
any fixed star in our constitutional constellation,” West
Virginia Bd. of Ed. v. Barnette , 319
U.S. 624 , 642 (1943), it is the principle that the government
may not interfere with “an uninhibited marketplace of ideas,” McCullen v. Coakley , 573 U.S.
464 , 476 (2014) (internal quotation marks omitted).
From time to time, governments in this country
have sought to test these foundational principles. In Barnette , for example, the Court faced an effort by the
State of West Virginia to force schoolchildren to salute the
Nation’s flag and recite the Pledge of Allegiance. If the students
refused, the State threatened to expel them and fine or jail their
parents. Some families objected on the ground that the State sought
to compel their children to express views at odds with their faith
as Jehovah’s Witnesses. When the dispute arrived here, this Court
offered a firm response. In seeking to compel students to salute
the flag and recite a pledge, the Court held, state authorities had
“transcend[ed] constitutional limitations on their powers.” 319
U. S., at 642. Their dictates “invade[d] the sphere of
intellect and spirit which it is the purpose of the First Amendment
. . . to reserve from all official control.” Ibid. A similar story unfolded in Hurley v. Irish-American Gay, Lesbian and Bisexual Group of Boston,
Inc. , 515 U.S.
557 (1995). There, veterans organizing a St. Patrick’s Day
parade in Boston refused to include a group of gay, lesbian, and
bisexual individuals in their event. The group argued that
Massachusetts’s public accommodations statute entitled it to
participate in the parade as a matter of law. Id. , at
560–561. Lower courts agreed. Id. , at 561–566. But this
Court reversed. Id. , at 581. Whatever state law may demand,
this Court explained, the parade was constitutionally protected
speech and requiring the veterans to include voices they wished to
exclude would impermissibly require them to “alter the expressive
content of their parade.” Id. , at 572–573. The veterans’
choice of what to say (and not say) might have been unpopular, but
they had a First Amendment right to present their message undiluted
by views they did not share.
Then there is Boy Scouts of America v. Dale . In that case, the Boy Scouts excluded James Dale, an
assistant scoutmaster, from membership after learning he was gay.
Mr. Dale argued that New Jersey’s public accommodations law
required the Scouts to reinstate him. 530 U. S., at 644–645.
The New Jersey Supreme Court sided with Mr. Dale, id. , at
646–647, but again this Court reversed, id. , at 661. The
decision to exclude Mr. Dale may not have implicated pure speech,
but this Court held that the Boy Scouts “is an expressive
association” entitled to First Amendment protection. Id. , at
656. And, the Court found, forcing the Scouts to include Mr. Dale
would “interfere with [its] choice not to propound a point of view
contrary to its beliefs.” Id. , at 654.
As these cases illustrate, the First Amendment
protects an individual’s right to speak his mind regardless of
whether the government considers his speech sensible and well
intentioned or deeply “misguided,” Hurley , 515 U. S.,
at 574, and likely to cause “anguish” or “incalculable grief,” Snyder v. Phelps , 562 U.S.
443 , 456 (2011). Equally, the First Amendment protects acts of
expressive association. See, e.g. , Dale , 530
U. S., at 647–656; Hurley , 515 U. S., at 568–570,
579. Generally, too, the government may not compel a person to
speak its own preferred messages. See Tinker v. Des
Moines Independent Community School Dist. , 393 U.S.
503 , 505–506 (1969); see also, e.g. , Miami Herald
Publishing Co. v. Tornillo , 418
U.S. 241 , 256 (1974); Wooley v. Maynard , 430 U.S.
705 , 714 (1977); National Institute of Family and Life
Advocates v. Becerra , 585 U. S. ___, ___ (2018)
( NIFLA ) (slip op., at 8). Nor does it matter whether the
government seeks to compel a person to speak its message when he
would prefer to remain silent or to force an individual to include
other ideas with his own speech that he would prefer not to
include. See Hurley, 515 U. S., at 568–570, 576; see
also Rumsfeld v. Forum for Academic & Institutional
Rights, Inc. , 547 U.S.
47 , 63–64 (2006) ( FAIR ) (discussing cases). All that
offends the First Amendment just the same.
III
Applying these principles to this case, we
align ourselves with much of the Tenth Circuit’s analysis. The
Tenth Circuit held that the wedding websites Ms. Smith seeks to
create qualify as “pure speech” under this Court’s precedents. 6
F. 4th, at 1176. We agree. It is a conclusion that flows
directly from the parties’ stipulations. They have stipulated that
Ms. Smith’s websites promise to contain “images, words, symbols,
and other modes of expression.” App. to Pet. for Cert. 181a. They
have stipulated that every website will be her “original,
customized” creation. Id. , at 181a–182a. And they have
stipulated that Ms. Smith will create these websites to communicate
ideas—namely, to “celebrate and promote the couple’s wedding and
unique love story” and to “celebrat[e] and promot[e]” what Ms.
Smith understands to be a true marriage. Id. , at
186a–187a.
A hundred years ago, Ms. Smith might have
furnished her services using pen and paper. Those services are no
less protected speech today because they are conveyed with a “voice
that resonates farther than it could from any soapbox.” Reno v. American Civil Liberties Union , 521
U.S. 844 , 870 (1997). All manner of speech—from “pictures,
films, paintings, drawings, and engravings,” to “oral utterance and
the printed word”—qualify for the First Amendment’s protections; no
less can hold true when it comes to speech like Ms. Smith’s
conveyed over the Internet. Kaplan v. California , 413 U.S.
115 , 119–120 (1973); see also Shurtleff v. Boston , 596 U. S. ___, ___–___ (2022) (slip op., at
7–8) (flags); Brown v. Entertainment Merchants Assn. , 564 U.S.
786 , 790 (2011) (video games); Hurley , 515 U. S.,
at 568–570 (parades); Ward v. Rock Against Racism , 491 U.S.
781 , 790 (1989) (music); Joseph Burstyn, Inc. v. Wilson , 343 U.S.
495 , 501–502 (1952) (movies).
We further agree with the Tenth Circuit that the
wedding websites Ms. Smith seeks to create involve her speech. 6 F. 4th, at 1181, and n. 5. Again, the parties’
stipulations lead the way to that conclusion. See App. to Pet. for
Cert. 181a, 187a. As the parties have described it, Ms. Smith
intends to “ve[t]” each prospective project to determine whether it
is one she is willing to endorse. Id. , at 185a. She will
consult with clients to discuss “their unique stories as source
material.” Id. , at 186a. And she will produce a final story
for each couple using her own words and her own “original artwork.” Id. , at 182a–183a. Of course, Ms. Smith’s speech may combine
with the couple’s in the final product. But for purposes of the
First Amendment that changes nothing. An individual “does not
forfeit constitutional protection simply by combining multifarious
voices” in a single communication. Hurley , 515 U. S.,
at 569.
As surely as Ms. Smith seeks to engage in
protected First Amendment speech, Colorado seeks to compel speech
Ms. Smith does not wish to provide. As the Tenth Circuit observed,
if Ms. Smith offers wedding websites celebrating marriages she
endorses, the State intends to “forc[e her] to create custom
websites” celebrating other marriages she does not. 6 F. 4th,
at 1178. Colorado seeks to compel this speech in order to “excis[e]
certain ideas or viewpoints from the public dialogue.” Turner
Broadcasting System, Inc. v. FCC , 512 U.S. 633, 642
(1994). Indeed, the Tenth Circuit recognized that the coercive
“[e]liminati[on]” of dissenting “ideas” about marriage constitutes
Colorado’s “very purpose” in seeking to apply its law to Ms. Smith.
6 F. 4th, at 1178.
We part ways with the Tenth Circuit only when it
comes to the legal conclusions that follow. While that court
thought Colorado could compel speech from Ms. Smith consistent with
the Constitution, our First Amendment precedents laid out above
teach otherwise. In Hurley , the Court found that
Massachusetts impermissibly compelled speech in violation of the
First Amendment when it sought to force parade organizers to accept
participants who would “affec[t] the[ir] message.” 515 U. S.,
at 572. In Dale , the Court held that New Jersey intruded on
the Boy Scouts’ First Amendment rights when it tried to require the
group to “propound a point of view contrary to its beliefs” by
directing its membership choices. 530 U. S., at 654. And in Barnette , this Court found impermissible coercion when West
Virginia required schoolchildren to recite a pledge that
contravened their convictions on threat of punishment or expulsion.
319 U. S., at 626–629. Here, Colorado seeks to put Ms. Smith
to a similar choice: If she wishes to speak, she must either speak
as the State demands or face sanctions for expressing her own
beliefs, sanctions that may include compulsory participation in
“remedial . . . training,” filing periodic compliance
reports as officials deem necessary, and paying monetary fines.
App. 120; supra , at 3. Under our precedents, that “is
enough,” more than enough, to represent an impermissible abridgment
of the First Amendment’s right to speak freely. Hurley , 515
U. S., at 574.
Consider what a contrary approach would mean.
Under Colorado’s logic, the government may compel anyone who speaks
for pay on a given topic to accept all commissions on that same
topic—no matter the underlying message—if the topic somehow
implicates a customer’s statutorily protected trait. 6 F. 4th,
at 1198 (Tymkovich, C. J., dissenting). Taken seriously, that
principle would allow the government to force all manner of
artists, speechwriters, and others whose services involve speech to
speak what they do not believe on pain of penalty. The government
could require “an unwilling Muslim movie director to make a film
with a Zionist message,” or “an atheist muralist to accept a
commission celebrating Evangelical zeal,” so long as they would
make films or murals for other members of the public with different
messages. Id ., at 1199. Equally, the government could force
a male website designer married to another man to design websites
for an organization that advocates against same-sex marriage. See
Brief for Petitioners 26–27. Countless other creative
professionals, too, could be forced to choose between remaining
silent, producing speech that violates their beliefs, or speaking
their minds and incurring sanctions for doing so. See, e.g. ,
Brief for Creative Professionals et al. as Amici Curiae 5–10; Brief for First Amendment Scholars as Amici Curiae 19–22. As our precedents recognize, the First Amendment tolerates
none of that.
In saying this much, we do not question the
vital role public accommodations laws play in realizing the civil
rights of all Americans. This Court has recognized that governments
in this country have a “compelling interest” in eliminating
discrimination in places of public accommodation. Roberts v. United States Jaycees , 468
U.S. 609 , 628 (1984); see also Hurley , 515 U. S.,
at 571–572. This Court has recognized, too, that public
accommodations laws “vindicate the deprivation of personal dignity
that surely accompanies denials of equal access to public
establishments.” Heart of Atlanta Motel, Inc. v. United
States , 379 U.S.
241 , 250 (1964) (internal quotation marks omitted); see also, e.g. , Katzenbach v. McClung , 379 U.S.
294 (1964); Newman v. Piggie Park Enterprises,
Inc. , 390 U.S.
400 (1968) ( per curiam ).
Over time, governments in this country have
expanded public accommodations laws in notable ways too. Statutes
like Colorado’s grow from nondiscrimination rules the common law
sometimes imposed on common carriers and places of traditional
public accommodation like hotels and restaurants. Dale , 530
U. S., at 656–657. Often, these enterprises exercised
something like monopoly power or hosted or transported others or
their belongings much like bailees. See, e.g., Liverpool
& Great Western Steam Co. v. Phenix Ins. Co. , 129 U.S.
397 , 437 (1889); Primrose v. Western Union Telegraph
Co. , 154 U.S.
1 , 14 (1894). Over time, some States, Colorado included, have
expanded the reach of these nondiscrimination rules to cover
virtually every place of business engaged in any sales to the
public. Compare 1885 Colo. Sess. Laws pp. 132–133 (a short list of
entities originally bound by the State’s public accommodations law)
with Colo. Rev. Stat. §24–34–601(1) (currently defining a public
accommodation to include “any place of business engaged in any
sales to the public”).
Importantly, States have also expanded their
laws to prohibit more forms of discrimination. Today, for example,
approximately half the States have laws like Colorado’s that
expressly prohibit discrimination on the basis of sexual
orientation.[ 2 ] And, as we have
recognized, this is entirely “unexceptional.” Masterpiece
Cakeshop , 584 U. S., at ___ (slip op., at 10). States may
“protect gay persons, just as [they] can protect other classes of
individuals, in acquiring whatever products and services they
choose on the same terms and conditions as are offered to other
members of the public. And there are no doubt innumerable goods and
services that no one could argue implicate the First Amendment.” Ibid. ; see also Hurley , 515 U. S., at 571–572; 6
F. 4th, at 1203 (Tymkovich, C. J., dissenting). Consistent
with all of this, Ms. Smith herself recognizes that Colorado and
other States are generally free to apply their public
accommodations laws, including their provisions protecting gay
persons, to a vast array of businesses. Reply Brief 15; see Tr. of
Oral Arg. 45–46.
At the same time, this Court has also recognized
that no public accommodations law is immune from the demands of the
Constitution. In particular, this Court has held, public
accommodations statutes can sweep too broadly when deployed to
compel speech. In Hurley , the Court commented favorably on
Massachusetts’ public accommodations law, but made plain it could
not be “applied to expressive activity” to compel speech. 515
U. S., at 571, 578. In Dale , the Court observed that
New Jersey’s public accommodations law had many lawful applications
but held that it could “not justify such a severe intrusion on the
Boy Scouts’ rights to freedom of expressive association.” 530
U. S., at 659. And, once more, what was true in those cases
must hold true here. When a state public accommodations law and the
Constitution collide, there can be no question which must prevail.
U. S. Const., Art. VI, cl. 2.
Nor is it any answer, as the Tenth Circuit
seemed to suppose, that Ms. Smith’s services are “unique.” 6
F. 4th, at 1180. In some sense, of course, her voice is
unique; so is everyone’s. But that hardly means a State may coopt
an individual’s voice for its own purposes. In Hurley , the
veterans had an “enviable” outlet for speech; after all, their
parade was a notable and singular event. 515 U. S., at 560,
577–578. In Dale , the Boy Scouts offered what some might
consider a unique experience. 530 U. S., at 649–650. But in
both cases this Court held that the State could not use its public
accommodations statute to deny speakers the right “to choose the
content of [their] own message[s].” Hurley , 515 U. S.,
at 573; see Dale , 530 U. S., at 650–656. Were the rule
otherwise, the better the artist, the finer the writer, the more
unique his talent, the more easily his voice could be conscripted
to disseminate the government’s preferred messages. That would not
respect the First Amendment; more nearly, it would spell its
demise.
IV
Before us, Colorado appears to distance itself
from the Tenth Circuit’s reasoning. Now, the State seems to
acknowledge that the First Amendment does forbid it from
coercing Ms. Smith to create websites endorsing same-sex marriage
or expressing any other message with which she disagrees. See Brief
for Respondents 12 (disclaiming any interest in “interfer[ing] with
[Ms. Smith’s] choice to offer only websites of [her] own design”);
see also Brief for United States as Amicus Curiae 19
(conceding that “constitutional concerns” would arise if Colorado
“require[d] petitione[r] to design a website” that she “would not
create or convey for any client”). Instead, Colorado devotes most
of its efforts to advancing an alternative theory for
affirmance.
The State’s alternative theory runs this way. To
comply with Colorado law, the State says, all Ms. Smith must do is
repurpose websites she will create to celebrate marriages she does endorse for marriages she does not . She sells a
product to some, the State reasons, so she must sell the same
product to all. Brief for Respondents 15, 20. At bottom, Colorado’s
theory rests on a belief that the Tenth Circuit erred at the outset
when it said this case implicates pure speech. Id. , at 19.
Instead, Colorado says, this case involves only the sale of an
ordinary commercial product and any burden on Ms. Smith’s speech is
purely “incidental.” Id. , at 18, 25–28; see Tr. of Oral Arg.
65, 97–98. On the State’s telling, then, speech more or less
vanishes from the picture—and, with it, any need for First
Amendment scrutiny. In places, the dissent seems to advance the
same line of argument. Post , at 29 (opinion of Sotomayor,
J.).
This alternative theory, however, is difficult
to square with the parties’ stipulations. As we have seen, the
State has stipulated that Ms. Smith does not seek to sell an
ordinary commercial good but intends to create “customized and
tailored” speech for each couple. App. to Pet. for Cert. 181a,
187a. The State has stipulated that “[e]ach website 303 Creative
designs and creates is an original, customized creation for each
client.” Id ., at 181a. The State has stipulated, too, that
Ms. Smith’s wedding websites “will be expressive in nature, using
text, graphics, and in some cases videos to celebrate and promote
the couple’s wedding and unique love story.” Id. , at 187a.
As the case comes to us, then, Colorado seeks to compel just the
sort of speech that it tacitly concedes lies beyond the reach of
its powers.
Of course, as the State emphasizes, Ms. Smith
offers her speech for pay and does so through 303 Creative LLC, a
company in which she is “the sole member-owner.” Id. , at
181a; see also post , at 33 (opinion of Sotomayor, J.)
(emphasizing Ms. Smith’s “commercial” activity). But none of that
makes a difference. Does anyone think a speechwriter loses his
First Amendment right to choose for whom he works if he accepts
money in return? Or that a visual artist who accepts commissions
from the public does the same? Many of the world’s great works of
literature and art were created with an expectation of
compensation. Nor, this Court has held, do speakers shed their
First Amendment protections by employing the corporate form to
disseminate their speech. This fact underlies our cases involving
everything from movie producers to book publishers to newspapers.
See, e.g., Joseph Burstyn, Inc. , 343 U. S., at
497–503; Simon & Schuster, Inc. v. Members of
N. Y. State Crime Victims Bd. , 502
U.S. 105 , 114–116 (1991); Grosjean v. American Press
Co. , 297 U.S.
233 , 240–241, 249 (1936).
Colorado next urges us to focus on the reason Ms. Smith refuses to offer the speech it seeks to
compel. She refuses, the State insists, because she objects to the
“protected characteristics” of certain customers. Brief for
Respondents 16; see also post , at 26–27, 31–32 (opinion of
Sotomayor, J.) (reciting the same argument). But once more, the
parties’ stipulations speak differently. The parties agree that Ms.
Smith “will gladly create custom graphics and websites for gay,
lesbian, or bisexual clients or for organizations run by gay,
lesbian, or bisexual persons so long as the custom graphics and
websites” do not violate her beliefs. App. to Pet. for Cert. 184a.
That is a condition, the parties acknowledge, Ms. Smith applies to
“all customers.” Ibid. Ms. Smith stresses, too, that she has
not and will not create expressions that defy any of her beliefs
for any customer, whether that involves encouraging violence,
demeaning another person, or promoting views inconsistent with her
religious commitments. See Tr. of Oral Arg. 18–20. Nor, in any
event, do the First Amendment’s protections belong only to speakers
whose motives the government finds worthy; its protections belong
to all, including to speakers whose motives others may find
misinformed or offensive. See Federal Election Comm’n v. Wisconsin Right to Life, Inc. , 551 U.S.
449 , 468–469 (2007) (opinion of Roberts, C. J.) (observing
that “a speaker’s motivation is entirely irrelevant” (internal
quotation marks omitted)); National Socialist Party of
America v. Skokie , 432 U.S.
43 , 43–44 (1977) ( per curiam ) (upholding
free-speech rights of participants in a Nazi parade); Snyder , 562 U. S., at 456–457 (same for protestors of a
soldier’s funeral).[ 3 ]
Failing all else, Colorado suggests that this
Court’s decision in FAIR supports affirmance. See also post , at 25–26 (opinion of Sotomayor, J.) (making the same
argument). In FAIR , a group of schools challenged a law
requiring them, as a condition of accepting federal funds, to
permit military recruiters space on campus on equal terms with
other potential employers. 547 U. S., at 51–52, 58. The only
expressive activity required of the law schools, the Court found,
involved the posting of logistical notices along these lines:
“ ‘The U. S. Army recruiter will meet interested students in
Room 123 at 11 a.m.’ ” Id ., at 61–62. And, the Court
reasoned, compelled speech of this sort was “incidental” and a “far
cry” from the speech at issue in our “leading First Amendment
precedents [that] have established the principle that freedom of
speech prohibits the government from telling people what they must
say.” Ibid. ; see also NIFLA , 585 U. S., at ___
(slip op., at 8).
It is a far cry from this case too. To be sure,
our cases have held that the government may sometimes “requir[e]
the dissemination of purely factual and uncontroversial
information,” particularly in the context of “commercial
advertising.” Hurley , 515 U. S., at 573 (internal
quotation marks omitted); see also NIFLA , 585 U. S., at
___ (slip op., at 8); Riley v. National Federation of
Blind of N. C., Inc. , 487 U.S.
781 , 795–796 (1988). But this case involves nothing like that.
Here, Colorado does not seek to impose an incidental burden on
speech. It seeks to force an individual to “utter what is not in
[her] mind” about a question of political and religious
significance. Barnette , 319 U. S., at 634. And that, FAIR reaffirmed, is something the First Amendment does not
tolerate. No government, FAIR recognized, may affect a
“speaker’s message” by “forc[ing]” her to “accommodate” other
views, 547 U. S., at 63; no government may
“ ‘alter’ ” the “ ‘expressive content’ ” of her
message, id. , at 63–64 (alteration omitted); and no
government may “interfer[e] with” her “desired message,” id. , at 64.
V
It is difficult to read the dissent and
conclude we are looking at the same case. Much of it focuses on the
evolution of public accommodations laws, post , at 7–13, and
the strides gay Americans have made towards securing equal justice
under law, post , at 14–17. And, no doubt, there is much to
applaud here. But none of this answers the question we face today:
Can a State force someone who provides her own expressive services
to abandon her conscience and speak its preferred message
instead?
When the dissent finally gets around to that
question—more than halfway into its opinion—it reimagines the facts
of this case from top to bottom. The dissent claims that Colorado
wishes to regulate Ms. Smith’s “conduct,” not her speech. Post , at 24–29. Forget Colorado’s stipulation that Ms.
Smith’s activities are “expressive,” App. to Pet. for Cert. 181a,
and the Tenth Circuit’s conclusion that the State seeks to compel
“pure speech,” 6 F. 4th, at 1176. The dissent chides us for
deciding a pre-enforcement challenge. Post , at 23. But it
ignores the Tenth Circuit’s finding that Ms. Smith faces a credible
threat of sanctions unless she conforms her views to the State’s. 6
F. 4th, at 1172–1175. The dissent suggests (over and over
again) that any burden on speech here is “incidental.” Post ,
at 24, 26–30, 32–33. All despite the Tenth Circuit’s finding that
Colorado intends to force Ms. Smith to convey a message she does
not believe with the “very purpose” of “[e]liminating
. . . ideas” that differ from its own. 6 F. 4th, at
1178.[ 4 ]
Nor does the dissent’s reimagination end there.
It claims that, “for the first time in its history,” the Court
“grants a business open to the public” a “right to refuse to serve
members of a protected class.” Post , at 1; see also id. , at 26, n. 10, 35. Never mind that we do no such
thing and Colorado itself has stipulated Ms. Smith will (as
CADA requires) “work with all people regardless of . . .
sexual orientation.” App. to Pet. for Cert. 184a. Never mind, too,
that it is the dissent that would have this Court do something
truly novel by allowing a government to coerce an individual to
speak contrary to her beliefs on a significant issue of personal
conviction, all in order to eliminate ideas that differ from its
own.
There is still more. The dissent asserts that we
“sweep under the rug petitioners’ challenge to CADA’s Communication
Clause.” Post , at 26. This despite the fact the parties and
the Tenth Circuit recognized that Ms. Smith’s Communication Clause
challenge hinges on her Accommodation Clause challenge. (So much so
that Colorado devoted less than two pages at the tail end of its
brief to the Communication Clause and the Tenth Circuit afforded it
just three paragraphs in its free-speech analysis. See Brief for
Respondents 44–45; 6 F. 4th, at 1182–1183.)[ 5 ] The dissent even suggests that our
decision today is akin to endorsing a “separate but equal” regime
that would allow law firms to refuse women admission into
partnership, restaurants to deny service to Black Americans, or
businesses seeking employees to post something like a “White
Applicants Only” sign. Post , at 1, 16–21, 26, 28–29, 32, and
n. 13, 37. Pure fiction all.
In some places, the dissent gets so turned
around about the facts that it opens fire on its own position. For
instance: While stressing that a Colorado company cannot refuse
“the full and equal enjoyment of [its] services” based on a
customer’s protected status, post , at 27, the dissent
assures us that a company selling creative services “to the public” does have a right “to decide what messages to include or not
to include,” post , at 28. But if that is true, what are we
even debating?
Instead of addressing the parties’ stipulations
about the case actually before us, the dissent spends much of its
time adrift on a sea of hypotheticals about photographers,
stationers, and others, asking if they too provide expressive
services covered by the First Amendment. Post , at 27–29,
31–32, 37. But those cases are not this case. Doubtless,
determining what qualifies as expressive activity protected by the
First Amendment can sometimes raise difficult questions. But this
case presents no complication of that kind. The parties have stipulated that Ms. Smith seeks to engage in expressive
activity. And the Tenth Circuit has recognized her services involve
“pure speech.” See supra , at 6, 9. Nothing the dissent says
can alter this—nor can it displace the First Amendment protections
that follow.
The dissent’s treatment of precedent parallels
its handling of the facts. Take its remarkable suggestion that a
government forcing an individual to create speech on weighty issues
with which she disagrees—all, as the Tenth Circuit found, with the
goal of “[e]liminating” views it does not share, 6 F. 4th, at
1178—only “incidental[ly]” burdens First Amendment liberties. Post , at 26–35 . Far from embracing a notion like
that, our cases have rejected it time after time—including in the
context of public accommodations laws. See Parts II–IV, supra ; FAIR , 547 U. S., at 61–64 (no government
may affect a “speaker’s own message” by “forc[ing]” her to
“accommodate” views she does not hold); Hurley , 515
U. S., at 563, 566 (using a public accommodations law to
compel parade organizers to include speech they did not believe was
no mere “ ‘incidental’ ” infringement on First Amendment
rights); Dale , 530 U. S., at 659 (employing a public
accommodations law to require the Boy Scouts to alter their
admissions policies had more than “an incidental effect on
protected speech”).[ 6 ]
When it finally gets around to discussing these
controlling precedents, the dissent offers a wholly unpersuasive
attempt to distinguish them. The First Amendment protections
furnished in Barnette , Hurley , and Dale , the
dissent declares, were limited to schoolchildren and
“nonprofit[s],” and it is “dispiriting” to think they might also
apply to Ms. Smith’s “commercial” activity. Post , at 32–35.
But our precedents endorse nothing like the limits the dissent
would project on them. Instead, as we have seen, the First
Amendment extends to all persons engaged in expressive conduct,
including those who seek profit (such as speechwriters, artists,
and website designers). See supra , at 16–17. If anything is
truly dispiriting here, it is the dissent’s failure to take
seriously this Court’s enduring commitment to protecting the speech
rights of all comers, no matter how controversial—or even
repugnant—many may find the message at hand.
Finally, the dissent comes out and says what it
really means: Once Ms. Smith offers some speech, Colorado “would
require [her] to create and sell speech, notwithstanding [her]
sincere objection to doing so”—and the dissent would force her to
comply with that demand. Post , at 29–30. Even as it does so,
however, the dissent refuses to acknowledge where its reasoning
leads. In a world like that, as Chief Judge Tymkovich highlighted,
governments could force “an unwilling Muslim movie director to make
a film with a Zionist message,” they could compel “an atheist
muralist to accept a commission celebrating Evangelical zeal,” and
they could require a gay website designer to create websites for a
group advocating against same-sex marriage, so long as these
speakers would accept commissions from the public with different
messages. 6 F. 4th, at 1199 (dissenting opinion). Perhaps the
dissent finds these possibilities untroubling because it trusts
state governments to coerce only “enlightened” speech. But if that
is the calculation, it is a dangerous one indeed.[ 7 ]
The dissent is right about one thing—“[w]hat a
difference” time can make. See post , at 2 (internal
quotation marks omitted). Eighty years ago in Barnette , this
Court affirmed that “no official, high or petty, can prescribe what
shall be orthodox in politics, nationalism, religion, or other
matters of opinion.” 319 U. S., at 642. The Court did so
despite the fact that the speech rights it defended were deeply
unpopular; at the time, the world was at war and many thought
respect for the flag and the pledge “essential for the welfare of
the state.” Id ., at 662–663 (Frankfurter, J., dissenting);
see also id. , at 636, 640 (majority opinion). Fifty years
ago, this Court protected the right of Nazis to march through a
town home to many Holocaust survivors and along the way espouse
ideas antithetical to those for which this Nation stands. See Skokie , 432 U. S., at 43–44; supra , at 17–18.
Five years ago, in a case the dissenters highlight at the outset of
their opinion, the Court stressed that “it is not . . .
the role of the State or its officials to prescribe what shall be
offensive.” Masterpiece Cakeshop , 584 U. S., at ___
(slip op., at 16). And just days ago, Members of today’s dissent
joined in holding that the First Amendment restricts how States may
prosecute stalkers despite the “harm[ful],” “low-value,” and
“upsetting” nature of their speech. Counterman v. Colorado , 600 U. S. ___, ___ (2023) (slip op., at 6); id. , at ___ (Sotomayor, J., concurring in part and
concurring in judgment) (slip op., at 5).
Today, however, the dissent abandons what this
Court’s cases have recognized time and time again: A commitment to
speech for only some messages and some persons is no
commitment at all. By approving a government’s effort to
“[e]liminat[e]” disfavored “ideas,” 6 F. 4th, at 1178, today’s
dissent is emblematic of an unfortunate tendency by some to defend
First Amendment values only when they find the speaker’s message
sympathetic. But “[i]f liberty means anything at all, it means the
right to tell people what they do not want to hear.” 6 F. 4th,
at 1190 (Tymkovich, C. J., dissenting) (quoting G.
Orwell).
*
In this case, Colorado seeks to force an
individual to speak in ways that align with its views but defy her
conscience about a matter of major significance. In the past, other
States in Barnette , Hurley , and Dale have
similarly tested the First Amendment’s boundaries by seeking to
compel speech they thought vital at the time. But, as this Court
has long held, the opportunity to think for ourselves and to
express those thoughts freely is among our most cherished liberties
and part of what keeps our Republic strong. Of course, abiding the
Constitution’s commitment to the freedom of speech means all of us
will encounter ideas we consider “unattractive,” post , at 38
(opinion of Sotomayor, J.), “misguided, or even hurtful,” Hurley , 515 U. S., at 574. But tolerance, not coercion,
is our Nation’s answer. The First Amendment envisions the United
States as a rich and complex place where all persons are free to
think and speak as they wish, not as the government demands.
Because Colorado seeks to deny that promise, the judgment is Reversed. Notes 1 In addition to the
Accommodation Clause, CADA contains a “Com-munication Clause” that
prohibits a public accommodation from “publish[ing] . . .
any written . . . communication” indicating that a person
will be denied “the full and equal enjoyment” of services or that
he will be “unwelcome, objectionable, unacceptable, or undesirable”
based on a pro-tected classification. Colo. Rev. Stat.
§24–34–601(2)(a) (2022). The Communication Clause, Ms. Smith notes,
prohibits any speech inconsistent with the Accommodation Clause.
Because Colorado concedes that its authority to apply the
Communication Clause to Ms. Smith stands or falls with its
authority to apply the Accommodation Clause, see Brief for
Respondents 44–45, we focus our attention on the Accommodation
Clause. 2 Besides Colorado, this includes
Cal. Civ. Code Ann. §51 (West 2020); Conn. Gen. Stat. §46a–81d
(2021); Del. Code Ann., Tit. 6, §4504 (2019); Haw. Rev. Stat.
§489–3 (Cum. Supp. 2021); Ill. Comp. Stat., ch. 775, §5/1–102 (West
2021); Iowa Code §216.7 (2022); Me. Rev. Stat. Ann., Tit. 5,
§4591 (2013); Md. State Govt. Code Ann. §20–304 (2021); Mass. Gen.
Laws, ch. 272, §98 (2021); Mich. Comp. Laws Ann. §37.2302 (West
2013); Minn. Stat. §363 A. 11 (2022); Nev. Rev. Stat. §651.070
(2017); N. H. Rev. Stat. Ann. §354–A:17 (2022); N. J. Stat. Ann.
§10:5–12 (West 2013); N. M. Stat. Ann. §28–1–7 (2022); N. Y.
Exec. Law Ann. §291(2) (West 2019); Ore. Rev. Stat. §659 A. 403
(2021); R. I. Gen. Laws §11–24–2 (2002); Vt. Stat. Ann., Tit. 9,
§4502(a) (2020); Va. Code Ann. §2.2–3904 (2022); Wash. Rev. Code
§49.60.215 (2022); Wis. Stat. §106.52 (2019–2020). See also Brief
for Local Governments et al. as Amici Curiae 5 (noting that
many local governments have enacted similar rules). 3 The dissent labels the
distinction between status and message “amusing” and
“embarrassing.” Post , at 32. But in doing so, the dissent
ignores a fundamental feature of the Free Speech Clause. While it
does not protect status-based discrimination unrelated to
expression, generally it does protect a speaker’s right to
control her own message—even when we may disapprove of the
speaker’s motive or the message itself. The dissent’s derision is
no answer to any of this. It ignores, too, the fact that Colorado itself has, in other contexts, distinguished status-based
discrimination (forbidden) from the right of a speaker to control
his own message (protected). See App. 131, 137, 140, 143–144, 149,
152, 154. (Truth be told, even the dissent acknowledges “th[is]
distinction” elsewhere in its opinion. Post , at 31,
n. 11.) Nor is the distinction unusual in societies committed
both to nondiscrimination rules and free expression. See, e.g. , Lee v. Ashers Baking Co. Ltd. , [2018]
UKSC 49, p. 14 (“The less favourable treatment was afforded to the
message not to the man.”). Does the dissent really find all that
amusing and embarrassing? 4 Perplexingly, too, the dissent
suggests that, by recounting the Tenth Circuit’s conclusion on this
score, we “misunderstan[d] this case” and “invo[ke] . . .
Orwellian thought policing.” Post , at 34, n.
14. 5 Why does the dissent try to
refocus this case around the Communication Clause? Perhaps because
the moment one acknowledges the parties’ stipulations—and the fact
Colorado seeks to use its Accommodation Clause to compel speech in
order to ensure conformity to its own views on a topic of major
significance—the First Amendment implications become obvious. As
does the fact that our case is nothing like a typical application
of a public accommodations law requiring an ordinary,
non-expressive business to serve all customers or consider all
applicants. Our decision today does not concern—much less
endorse—anything like the “ ‘straight couples only’ ”
notices the dissent conjures out of thin air. Post , at 26,
n. 10. Nor do the parties discuss anything of the sort in
their stipulations. 6 The dissent observes that
public accommodations laws may sometimes touch on speech
incidentally as they work to ensure ordinary, non-expressive goods
and services are sold on equal terms. Cf. post , at 24–27
(citing Sorrell v. IMS Health Inc. , 564 U.S.
552 (2011); Rumsfeld v. FAIR , 547 U.S.
47 (2006); United States v. O’Brien , 391 U.S.
367 (1968)). But as Hurley observed, there is nothing
“incidental” about an infringement on speech when a public
accommodations law is applied “peculiar[ly]” to compel expressive
activity. Hurley v. Irish-American Gay, Lesbian and
Bisexual Group of Boston, Inc. , 515 U.S.
557 , 572 (1995).The dissent notes that our case law has not
sustained every First Amendment objection to an antidiscrimination
rule, as with a law firm that sought to exclude women from
partnership. Post , at 19–21 (citing Hishon v. King
& Spalding , 467 U.S.
69 (1984); Roberts v. United States Jaycees , 468 U.S.
609 (1984)). But the dissent disregards Dale ’s holding
that context matters and that very different considerations come
into play when a law is used to force individuals to toe the
government’s preferred line when speaking (or associating to
express themselves) on matters of significance. Boy Scouts of
America v. Dale , 530 U.S.
640 , 648–653 (2000). 7 Perhaps the dissent finds these
possibilities untroubling for another reason. It asserts that CADA
does not apply to “[m]any filmmakers, visual artists, and writers”
because they do not “hold out” their services to the public. Post , at 27. But the dissent cites nothing to support its
claim and instead, once more, fights the facts. As we have seen,
Colorado’s law today applies to “ any place of business
engaged in any sales to the public.” Colo. Rev. Stat.
§24–34–601(1) (emphasis added); see also Part III, supra .
And the dissent can hardly dispute that many artists and writers
accept commissions from the public. Brief for Creative
Professionals et al. as Amici Curiae 5–21. Certainly,
Colorado does not advance anything like the dissent’s argument; it
calls any exemption to its law for “artists” and others who provide
“custom” services “unworkable.” Brief for Respondents 28–31
(internal quotation marks omitted). SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES
_________________
No. 21–476
_________________
303 CREATIVE LLC, et al., PETITIONERS v. AUBREY ELENIS, et al.
on writ of certiorari to the united states
court of appeals for the tenth circuit
[June 30, 2023]
Justice Sotomayor, with whom Justice Kagan and
Justice Jackson join, dissenting.
Five years ago, this Court recognized the
“general rule” that religious and philosophical objections to gay
marriage “do not allow business owners and other actors in the
economy and in society to deny protected persons equal access to
goods and services under a neutral and generally applicable public
accommodations law.” Masterpiece Cakeshop, Ltd. v. Colorado Civil Rights Comm’n , 584 U. S. ___, ___ (2018)
(slip op., at 9). The Court also recognized the “serious stigma”
that would result if “purveyors of goods and services who object to
gay marriages for moral and religious reasons” were “allowed to put
up signs saying ‘no goods or services will be sold if they will be
used for gay marriages.’ ” Id. , at ___ (slip op., at
12).
Today, the Court, for the first time in its
history, grants a business open to the public a constitutional
right to refuse to serve members of a protected class.
Specifically, the Court holds that the First Amendment exempts a
website-design company from a state law that prohibits the company
from denying wedding websites to same-sex couples if the company
chooses to sell those websites to the public. The Court also holds
that the company has a right to post a notice that says, “ ‘no
[wedding websites] will be sold if they will be used for gay
marriages.’ ” Ibid. “What a difference five years makes.” Carson v. Makin , 596 U. S. ___, ___ (2022)
(Sotomayor, J., dissenting) (slip op., at 5). And not just at the
Court. Around the country, there has been a backlash to the
movement for liberty and equality for gender and sexual minorities.
New forms of inclusion have been met with reactionary exclusion.
This is heartbreaking. Sadly, it is also familiar. When the civil
rights and women’s rights movements sought equality in public life,
some public establishments refused. Some even claimed, based on
sincere religious beliefs, constitutional rights to discriminate.
The brave Justices who once sat on this Court decisively rejected
those claims.
Now the Court faces a similar test. A business
open to the public seeks to deny gay and lesbian customers the full
and equal enjoyment of its services based on the owner’s religious
belief that same-sex marriages are “false.” The business argues,
and a majority of the Court agrees, that because the business
offers services that are customized and expressive, the Free Speech
Clause of the First Amendment shields the business from a generally
applicable law that prohibits discrimination in the sale of
publicly available goods and services. That is wrong. Profoundly
wrong. As I will explain, the law in question targets conduct, not
speech, for regulation, and the act of discrimination has
never constituted protected expression under the First Amendment.
Our Constitution contains no right to refuse service to a
disfavored group. I dissent.
I
A
A “public accommodations law” is a law that
guarantees to every person the full and equal enjoyment of places
of public accommodation without unjust discrimination. The American
people, through their elected representatives, have enacted such
laws at all levels of government: The federal Civil Rights Act of
1964 and the Americans with Disabilities Act of 1990 prohibit
discrimination by places of public accommodation on the basis of
race, color, religion, national origin, or disability.[ 1 ] All but five States have analogous
laws that prohibit discrimination on the basis of these and other
traits, such as age, sex, sexual orientation, and gender
identity.[ 2 ] And numerous local
laws offer similar protections.
The people of Colorado have adopted the Colorado
Anti-Discrimination Act (CADA), which provides:
“It is a discriminatory practice and
unlawful for a person, directly or indirectly, to refuse, withhold
from, or deny to an individual or a group, because of disability,
race, creed, color, sex, sexual orientation, gender identity,
gender expression, marital status, national origin, or ancestry,
the full and equal enjoyment of the goods, services, facilities,
privileges, advantages, or accommodations of a place of public
accommodation.” Colo. Rev. Stat. §24–34–601(2)(a).
This provision, known as the Act’s
“Accommodation Clause,” applies to any business engaged in sales
“to the public.” §24–34–601(1). The Accommodation Clause does not
apply to any “church, synagogue, mosque, or other place that is
principally used for religious purposes.” Ibid. In addition, CADA contains what is referred to
as the Act’s “Communication Clause,” which makes it unlawful to
advertise that services “will be refused, withheld from, or
denied,” or that an individual is “unwelcome” at a place of public
accommodation, based on the same protected traits.
§24–34–601(2)(a). In other words, just as a business open to the
public may not refuse to serve customers based on race, religion,
or sexual orientation, so too the business may not hang a sign that
says, “No Blacks, No Muslims, No Gays.”
A public accommodations law has two core
purposes. First, the law ensures “ equal access to publicly
available goods and services.” Roberts v. United States
Jaycees , 468
U.S. 609 , 624 (1984) (emphasis added). For social groups that
face discrimination, such access is vital. All the more so if the
group is small in number or if discrimination against the group is
widespread. Equal access is mutually beneficial: Protected persons
receive “equally effective and meaningful opportunity to benefit
from all aspects of life in America,” 135 Cong. Rec. 8506 (1989)
(remarks of Sen. Harkin) (Americans with Disabilities Act), and
“society,” in return, receives “the benefits of wide participation
in political, economic, and cultural life.” Roberts , 468
U. S., at 625.
Second, a public accommodations law ensures equal dignity in the common market. Indeed, that is the
law’s “fundamental object”: “to vindicate ‘the deprivation of
personal dignity that surely accompanies denials of equal access to
public establishments.’ ” Heart of Atlanta Motel, Inc. v. United States , 379 U.S.
241 , 250 (1964) (quoting S. Rep. No. 872, 88th Cong., 2d
Sess., 16 (1964)). This purpose does not depend on whether
goods or services are otherwise available. “ ‘Discrimination
is not simply dollars and cents, hamburgers and movies; it is the
humiliation, frustration, and embarrassment that a person must
surely feel when he is told that he is unacceptable as a member of
the public because of his [social identity]. It is equally the
inability to explain to a child that regardless of education,
civility, courtesy, and morality he will be denied the right to
enjoy equal treatment.’ ” 379 U. S., at 292 (Goldberg,
J., concurring). When a young Jewish girl and her parents come
across a business with a sign out front that says, “ ‘No dogs
or Jews allowed,’ ”[ 3 ] the
fact that another business might serve her family does not redress
that “stigmatizing injury,” Roberts , 468 U. S., at 625.
Or, put another way, “the hardship Jackie Robinson suffered when on
the road” with his baseball team “was not an inability to find some hotel that would have him; it was the indignity of not
being allowed to stay in the same hotel as his white
teammates.” J. Oleske, The Evolution of Accommodation, 50 Harv.
Civ. Rights-Civ. Lib. L. Rev. 99, 138 (2015).
To illustrate, imagine a funeral home in rural
Mississippi agrees to transport and cremate the body of an elderly
man who has passed away, and to host a memorial lunch. Upon
learning that the man’s surviving spouse is also a man, however,
the funeral home refuses to deal with the family. Grief stricken,
and now isolated and humiliated, the family desperately searches
for another funeral home that will take the body. They eventually
find one more than 70 miles away. See First Amended Complaint in Zawadski v. Brewer Funeral Services, Inc. , No.
55CI1–17–cv–00019 (C. C. Pearl River Cty., Miss., Mar. 7,
2017), pp. 4–7.[ 4 ] This
ostracism, this otherness, is among the most distressing feelings
that can be felt by our social species. K. Williams,
Ostracism, 58 Ann. Rev. Psychology 425, 432–435 (2007).
Preventing the “unique evils” caused by “acts of
invidious discrimination in the distribution of publicly available
goods, services, and other advantages” is a compelling state
interest “of the highest order.” Roberts , 468 U. S., at
624, 628; see Board of Directors of Rotary Int’l v. Rotary Club of Duarte , 481 U.S.
537 , 549 (1987). Moreover, a law that prohibits only such acts
by businesses open to the public is narrowly tailored to achieve
that compelling interest. The law “responds precisely to the
substantive problem which legitimately concerns the State”: the
harm from status-based discrimination in the public marketplace. Roberts , 468 U. S., at 629 (internal quotation marks
omitted).
This last aspect of a public accommodations law
deserves special emphasis: The law regulates only businesses that
choose to sell goods or services “to the general public,” e.g. , Va. Code Ann. §2.2–3904, or “to the public,” e.g. , Mich. Comp. Laws §37.2301. Some public accommodations
laws, such as the federal Civil Rights Act, list establishments
that qualify, but these establishments are ones open to the public
generally. See, e.g. , 42 U. S. C. §2000a(b)
(hotels, restaurants, gas stations, movie theaters, concert halls,
sports arenas, stadiums). A public accommodations law does not
force anyone to start a business, or to hold out the business’s
goods or services to the public at large. The law also does not
compel any business to sell any particular good or service. But if
a business chooses to profit from the public market, which is
established and maintained by the state, the state may require the
business to abide by a legal norm of nondiscrimination. In
particular, the state may ensure that groups historically marked
for second-class status are not denied goods or services on equal
terms.
The concept of a public accommodation thus
embodies a simple, but powerful, social contract: A business that
chooses to sell to the public assumes a duty to serve the public
without unjust discrimination. J. Singer, No Right To Exclude:
Public Accommodations and Private Property, 90 Nw. U. L. Rev.
1283, 1298 (1996) (Singer).
B
The legal duty of a business open to the
public to serve the public without unjust discrimination is deeply
rooted in our history. The true power of this principle, however,
lies in its capacity to evolve, as society comes to understand more
forms of unjust discrimination and, hence, to include more persons
as full and equal members of “the public.”
1
“At common law, innkeepers, smiths, and others
who ‘made profession of a public employment,’ were prohibited from
refusing, without good reason, to serve a customer.” Hurley v. Irish-American Gay, Lesbian and Bisexual Group of Boston,
Inc. , 515 U.S.
557 , 571 (1995) (quoting Lane v. Cotton , 12 Mod.
472, 485, 88 Eng. Rep. 1458, 1465 (K. B. 1701) (Holt,
C. J.)). “Public employment” meant a business “in which the
owner has held himself out as ready to serve the public by
exercising his trade.” Singer 1307; see, e.g. , Gisbourn v. Hurst , 1 Salk. 249, 91 Eng. Rep. 220
(K. B. 1710). Take, for example, Lane v. Cotton ,
“[t]he leading English case” on the subject “cited over and over
again in the nineteenth century in the United States.” Singer 1304.
There, Lord Chief Justice Holt explained:
“[W]here-ever any subject takes upon
himself a public trust for the benefit of the rest of his
fellow-subjects, he is eo ipso bound to serve the subject in
all the things that are within the reach and comprehension of such
an office, under pain of an action against him. . . . If
on the road a shoe fall off my horse, and I come to a smith to have
one put on, and the smith refuse to do it, an action will lie
against him, because he has made profession of a trade which is for
the public good, and has thereby exposed and vested an interest of
himself in all the King’s subjects that will employ him in the way
of his trade.” Lane v. Cotton , 12 Mod., at 484, 88
Eng. Rep., at 1464.
That is to say, a business’s duty to serve all
comers derived from its choice to hold itself out as ready to serve
the public. This holding-out rationale became firmly established in
early American law. See 2 J. Kent, Commentaries on American Law
464–465 (1827); J. Story, Commentaries on the Law of Bailments
§§495, 591 (1832); see also, e.g. , Markham v. Brown , 8 N. H. 523, 528 (1837); Jencks v. Coleman , 13 F. Cas. 442, 443 (No. 7,258) (CC RI 1835)
(Story, J.); Dwight v. Brewster , 18 Mass. 50, 53
(1822).
The majority is therefore mistaken to suggest
that public accommodations or common carriers historically assumed
duties to serve all comers because they enjoyed monopolies or
otherwise had market power. Ante , at 13. Tellingly, the
majority cites no common-law case espousing the monopoly
rationale.[ 5 ] That is because
nowhere in the relevant case law “is monopoly suggested as the
distinguishing characteristic.” E. Adler, Business Jurisprudence,
28 Harv. L. Rev. 135, 156 (1914) (“A distinction based on
monopoly would require proof that the common carrier had some kind
of a monopoly which the private carrier did not have, or that
‘common’ was synonymous with ‘monopoly.’ The plain meaning of the
cases is [instead that] the common was the public, the
professional, the business carrier or other trader”).[ 6 ]
2
After the Civil War, some States codified the
common-law duty of public accommodations to serve all comers. See
M. Konvitz & T. Leskes, A Century of Civil Rights 155–157
(1961). Early state public accommodations statutes prohibited
discrimination based on race or color. Yet the principle was at
times stated more broadly: to provide “a remedy against any unjust
discrimination to the citizen in all public places.” Ferguson v. Gies , 82 Mich. 358, 365, 46 N.W. 718, 720
(1890). In 1885, Colorado adopted “ ‘An Act to Protect All
Citizens in Their Civil Rights,’ which guaranteed ‘full and equal
enjoyment’ of certain public facilities to ‘all citizens,’
‘regardless of race, color or previous condition of
servitude.’ ” Masterpiece Cakeshop , 584 U. S., at
___–___ (slip op., at 4–5) (quoting 1885 Colo. Sess. Laws p. 132).
“A decade later, the [State] expanded the requirement to apply to
‘all other places of public accommodation.’ ” 584 U. S.,
at ___ (slip op., at 5) (quoting 1895 Colo. Sess. Laws ch. 61, p.
139). Congress, too, passed the Civil Rights Act of 1875, which
established “[t]hat all persons within the jurisdiction of the
United States shall be entitled to the full and equal enjoyment of
the accommodations, advantages, facilities, and privileges of inns,
public conveyances on land or water, theaters, and other places of
public amusement . . . applicable alike to citizens of
every race and color, regardless of any previous condition of
servitude.” Act of Mar. 1, 1875, §1, 18Stat. 336.
This Court, however, struck down the federal
Civil Rights Act of 1875 as unconstitutional. Civil Rights
Cases , 109 U.S.
3 , 25 (1883). Southern States repealed public accommodations
statutes and replaced them with Jim Crow laws. And state courts
construed any remaining right of access in ways that furthered de jure and de facto racial
segregation.[ 7 ] Full and equal
enjoyment came to mean “separate but equal” enjoyment. The result
of this backsliding was “the replacement of a general right of
access with a general right to exclude . . . in order to
promote a racial caste system.” Singer 1295.
In time, the civil rights movement of the
mid-20th century again demanded racial equality in public places.
In 1963, two decades after then–Howard University law student Pauli
Murray organized sit-ins at cafeterias in Washington, D. C., a
diverse group of students and faculty from Tougaloo College sat at
Woolworth’s lunch counter in Jackson, Mississippi. For doing so,
they were violently attacked by a white mob. See A. Moody, Coming
of Age in Mississippi 235–240 (1992). Around the country, similar
acts of protest against racial injustice, some big and some small,
sought “to create such a crisis and foster such a tension” that the
country would be “forced to confront the issue.” M. King, Letter
from a Birmingham Jail, Apr. 16, 1963. That year, Congress once
more set out to eradicate “discrimination . . . in places
of accommodation and public facilities,” Heart of Atlanta
Motel , 379 U. S., at 246, notwithstanding this Court’s
previous declaration of a federal public accommodations law to be
unconstitutional.
Congress believed, rightly, that discrimination
in places of public accommodation—“the injustice of being
arbitrarily denied equal access to those facilities and
accommodations which are otherwise open to the general public”—had
“no place” in this country, the country “of the melting pot, of
equal rights, of one nation and one people.” S. Rep. No. 872,
at 8–9 (quoting President Kennedy, June 19, 1963). It therefore
passed Title II of the Civil Rights Act of 1964, which declares:
“All persons shall be entitled to the full and equal enjoyment of
the goods, services, facilities, privileges, advantages, and
accommodations of any place of public accommodation . . .
without discrimination . . . on the ground of race,
color, religion, or national origin.” 42 U. S. C. §2000a.
In enacting this landmark civil rights statute, Congress invoked
the holding-out rationale from antebellum common law: “one who
employed his private property for purposes of commercial gain by
offering goods or services to the public must stick to his
bargain.” S. Rep. No. 872, at 22; see also id. , at 9–10
(endorsing Lord Holt’s view in Lane v. Cotton ).
This bargain, America would soon realize, had
long excluded half of society. Women, though having won the right
to vote half a century earlier, were not equal in public. Instead,
a “separate-spheres ideology” had “assigned women to the home and
men to the market.” E. Sepper & D. Dinner, Sex in Public, 129
Yale L. J. 78, 83, 88–90 (2019) (Sepper & Dinner). Women
were excluded from restaurants, bars, civic and professional
organizations, financial institutions, and sports. “Just as it did
for the civil rights struggle, public accommodations served as
kindling for feminist mobilization.” Id. , at 83, 97–104; cf.
S. Mayeri, Reasoning From Race: Feminism, Law, and the Civil Rights
Revolution 9–40 (2011). In response to a movement for women’s
liberation, numerous States banned discrimination in public
accommodations on the basis of “sex.” See Sepper & Dinner 104,
nn. 145–147 (collecting statutes). Colorado was the first State to
do so. See 1969 Colo. Sess. Laws ch. 74, p. 200.
In the decades that followed, the Nation opened
its eyes to another injustice. People with disabilities, though
inherently full and equal members of the public, had been excluded
from many areas of public life. This exclusion worked harms not
only to disabled people’s standards of living, but to their dignity
too. So Congress, responding once again to a social movement, this
time against the subordination of people with disabilities, banned
discrimination on that basis and secured by law disabled people’s
equal access to public spaces. See S. Bagenstos, Law and the
Contradictions of the Disability Rights Movement 13–20 (2009); R.
Colker, The Disability Pendulum 22–68 (2005). The centerpiece of
this political and social action was the Americans with
Disabilities Act of 1990 (ADA). Title III of the ADA provides that
“[n]o individual shall be discriminated against on the basis of
disability in the full and equal enjoyment of the goods, services,
facilities, privileges, advantages, or accommodations of any place
of public accommodation.” 42 U. S. C. §12182(a).
Not only have public accommodations laws
expanded to recognize more forms of unjust discrimination, such as
discrimination based on race, sex, and disability, such laws have
also expanded to include more goods and services as “public
accommodations.” What began with common inns, carriers, and smiths
has grown to include restaurants, bars, movie theaters, sports
arenas, retail stores, salons, gyms, hospitals, funeral homes, and
transportation networks. See nn. 1–2, supra ; L. Lerman &
A. Sanderson, Discrimination in Access to Public Places: A Survey
of State and Federal Public Accommodations Laws, 7
N. Y. U. Rev. L. & Soc. Change 215, 217 (1978)
(“ ‘Public accommodations’ is a term of art which was
developed by the drafters of discrimination laws to refer to
[public] places other than schools, work places, and homes”).
Today, laws like Colorado’s cover “any place of business engaged in
any sales to the public and any place offering services
. . . to the public.” Colo. Rev. Stat. §24–34–601(1); see
also, e.g. , Ohio Rev. Code Ann. §4112.01(9). Numerous other
States extend such protections to businesses offering goods or
services to “the general public.” Ariz. Rev. Stat. Ann.
§41–1441(2); see also, e.g. , Mass. Gen. Laws, ch. 272,
§92A.
This broader scope, though more inclusive than
earlier state public accommodations laws, is in keeping with the
fundamental principle—rooted in the common law, but alive and
blossoming in statutory law—that the duty to serve without unjust
discrimination is owed to everyone, and it extends to any business
that holds itself out as ready to serve the public. If you have
ever taken advantage of a public business without being denied
service because of who you are, then you have come to enjoy the
dignity and freedom that this principle protects.
3
Lesbian, gay, bisexual, and transgender (LGBT)
people, no less than anyone else, deserve that dignity and freedom.
The movement for LGBT rights, and the resulting expansion of state
and local laws to secure gender and sexual minorities’ full and
equal enjoyment of publicly available goods and services, is the
latest chapter of this great American story.
LGBT people have existed for all of human
history. And as sure as they have existed, others have sought to
deny their existence, and to exclude them from public life. Those
who would subordinate LGBT people have often done so with the
backing of law. For most of American history, there were laws
criminalizing same-sex intimacy. Obergefell v. Hodges , 576 U.S. 644, 660–661 (2015). “Gays and lesbians
were [also] prohibited from most government employment, barred from
military service, excluded under immigration laws, targeted by
police, and burdened in their rights to associate.” Id. , at
661. “These policies worked to create and reinforce the belief that
gay men and lesbians” constituted “an inferior class.” Brief for
Organization of American Historians as Amicus Curiae in Obergefell v. Hodges , O. T. 2014, No. 14–556,
p. 3.
State-sponsored discrimination was compounded by
discrimination in public accommodations, though the two often went
hand in hand. The police raided bars looking for gays and lesbians
so often that some bars put up signs saying, “ ‘We Do Not
Serve Homosexuals.’ ” Id. , at 13 (quoting G. Chauncey,
Why Marriage 8 (2004)). LGBT discrimination in public
accommodations has continued well into the 21st century. See UCLA
School of Law Williams Institute, C. Mallory & B. Sears,
Evidence of Discrimination in Public Accommodations Based on Sexual
Orientation and Gender Identity (2016).
A social system of discrimination created an
environment in which LGBT people were unsafe. Who could forget the
brutal murder of Matthew Shepard? Matthew was targeted by two men,
tortured, tied to a buck fence, and left to die for who he was. See
K. Drake, Gay Man Beaten, Burned and Left Tied to Fence, Casper
Star-Tribune, Oct. 10, 1998, p. A1. Or the Pulse nightclub
massacre, the second-deadliest mass shooting in U. S. history?
See S. Stolberg, For Gays Across America, a Massacre Punctuates
Fitful Gains, N. Y. Times, June 13, 2016, p. A1. Rates of
violent victimization are still significantly higher for LGBT
people, with transgender persons particularly vulnerable to attack.
See Dept. of Justice, J. Truman & R. Morgan, Violent
Victimization by Sexual Orientation and Gender Identity, 2017–2020
(2022).
Determined not to live as “social outcasts,” Masterpiece Cakeshop , 584 U. S., at ___ (slip op., at
9), LGBT people have risen up. The social movement for LGBT rights
has been long and complex. See L. Faderman, The Gay Revolution
(2015) (Faderman). But if there ever was an “earthquake,” it
occurred in the final days of June in 1969 at the Stonewall Inn in
Greenwich Village. Id. , at 169. The Stonewall Inn was a gay
bar with a “varied and lively clientele.” Id. , at 171. Its
“ ‘unruly’ element” made it “an especially inviting target”
for police raids. J. D’Emilio, Sexual Politics, Sexual Communities
231 (1983) (D’Emilio). “Patrons of the Stonewall tended to be young
and nonwhite. Many were drag queens. . . . ” Ibid. Just before midnight on June 27, the New York police’s
Public Morals Squad showed up to the bar and started making
arrests. Drag queens, for example, were arrested for offenses like
being “disguised” in “unnatural attire.” N. Y. Penal Law Ann.
§240.35(4) (West 1967).
What started out as a fairly routine police
raid, however, became anything but. Outside the Stonewall Inn,
patrons who had been thrown out started to form a crowd. “Jeers and
catcalls arose from the onlookers when a paddy wagon departed with
the bartender, the Stonewall’s bouncer, and three drag queens.”
D’Emilio 231. “A few minutes later, an officer attempted to steer
the last of the patrons, a lesbian, through the bystanders to a
nearby patrol car.” Id. , at 231–232. When she started to
struggle, protests erupted. They lasted into the night and
continued into the next. News of the Stonewall protests “spread
rapidly,” and “within a year gay liberation groups had sprung into
existence on college campuses and in cities around the nation.” Id. , at 233. From there, the path to LGBT rights has not
been quick or easy. Nor is it over. Still, change has come: change
in social attitudes, in representation, and in legal institutions.
Faderman 535–629.
One significant change has been the addition of
sexual orientation and gender identity to public accommodations
laws. State and local legislatures took note of the failure of such
laws to protect LGBT people and, in response, acted to guarantee
them “all the privileges . . . of any other member of
society.” Hearings on S. B. 200 before the House Judiciary
Committee, 66th Gen. Assem., 2d Reg. Sess., 4, 11–12 (Colo. 2008)
(remarks of Sen. Judd). Colorado thus amended its
antidiscrimination law in 2008 to prohibit the denial of publicly
available goods or services on the basis of “sexual orientation.”
2008 Colo. Sess. Laws. ch. 341, pp. 1596–1597. About half of the
States now provide such protections.[ 8 ] It is “ ‘unexceptional’ ” that they may do
so. Ante , at 13 (quoting Masterpiece Cakeshop , 584
U. S., at ___ (slip op., at 10)). “These are protections taken
for granted by most people either because they already have them or
do not need them; these are protections against exclusion from an
almost limitless number of transactions and endeavors that
constitute ordinary civic life in a free society.” Romer v. Evans , 517 U.S.
620 , 631 (1996). LGBT people do not seek any special treatment.
All they seek is to exist in public. To inhabit public spaces on
the same terms and conditions as everyone else.
C
Yet for as long as public accommodations laws
have been around, businesses have sought exemptions from them. The
civil rights and women’s liberation eras are prominent examples of
this. Backlashes to race and sex equality gave rise to legal claims
of rights to discriminate, including claims based on First
Amendment freedoms of expression and association. This Court was
unwavering in its rejection of those claims, as invidious
discrimination “has never been accorded affirmative constitutional
protections.” Norwood v. Harrison , 413 U.S.
455 , 470 (1973). In particular, the refusal to deal with or to
serve a class of people is not an expressive interest protected by
the First Amendment.
1
Opponents of the Civil Rights Act of 1964
objected that the law would force business owners to defy their
beliefs. Cf. ante , at 3. They argued that the Act would deny
them “any freedom to speak or to act on the basis of their
religious convictions or their deep-rooted preferences for
associating or not associating with certain classifications of
people.” 110 Cong. Rec. 7778 (1964) (remarks of Sen. Tower).
Congress rejected those arguments. Title II of the Act, in
particular, did not invade “rights of privacy [or] of free
association,” Congress concluded, because the establishments
covered by the law were “those regularly held open to the public in
general.” H. R. Rep. No. 914, 88th Cong., 1st Sess., pt. 2, p.
9 (1963); see also S. Rep. No. 872, at 92.
Having failed to persuade Congress, opponents of
Title II turned to the federal courts. In Heart of Atlanta
Motel , one of several arguments made by the plaintiff motel
owner was that Title II violated his Fifth Amendment due process
rights by “tak[ing] away the personal liberty of an individual to
run his business as he sees fit with respect to the selection and
service of his customers.” Brief for Appellant, O. T. 1964,
No. 515, p. 32. This Court disagreed, based on “a long line of
cases” holding that “prohibition of racial discrimination in public
accommodations” did not “interfer[e] with personal liberty.” 379
U. S., at 260.
In Katzenbach v. McClung , 379 U.S.
294 (1964), the owner of Ollie’s Barbecue (Ollie McClung)
likewise argued that Title II’s application to his business
violated the “personal rights of persons in their personal
convictions” to deny services to Black people. Brief for Appellees,
O. T. 1964, No. 543, p. 33 (citing, inter alia , West Virginia Bd. of Ed. v. Barnette , 319 U.S.
624 (1943)). Note that McClung did not refuse to transact with Black people. Oh, no. He was willing to offer
them take-out service at a separate counter. See Brief for NAACP
Legal Defense and Educational Fund, Inc., as Amicus Curiae in Katzenbach v. McClung , p. 4, n. 5. Only
integrated table service, you see, violated McClung’s core beliefs.
So he claimed a constitutional right to offer Black people a
limited menu of his services. This Court rejected that claim,
citing its decision in Heart of Atlanta Motel . See 379
U. S., at 298, n. 1.
Next is Newman v. Piggie Park
Enterprises, Inc. , 390 U.S.
400 (1968) ( per curiam ), in which the owner of a
chain of drive-in establishments asserted that requiring him to
“contribut[e]” to racial integration in any way violated the First
Amendment by interfering with his religious liberty. App. to Pet.
for Cert., O. T. 1967, No. 339, p. 21a. Title II could
not be applied to his business, he argued, because that would
“ ‘controven[e] the will of God.’ ” 390 U. S., at
402–403, n. 5. The Court found this argument “patently
frivolous.” Ibid. Last but not least is Runyon v. McCrary , 427 U.S.
160 (1976), a case the majority studiously avoids. In Runyon , the Court confronted the question whether
“commercially operated” schools had a First Amendment right to
exclude Black children, notwithstanding a federal law against
racial discrimination in contracting. Id. , at 168; see 42
U. S. C. §1981. The schools in question offered
“educational services” for sale to “the general public.” 427
U. S., at 172. They argued that the law, as applied to them,
violated their First Amendment rights of “freedom of speech, and
association.” Pet. for Cert., O. T. 1976, No. 75–62,
p. 6; see also Brief for Petitioners, O. T. 1976, No.
75–62, p. 12 (“Freedom to teach, to express ideas”). The
Court, however, reasoned that the schools’ “ practice ” of
denying educational services to racial minorities was not shielded
by the First Amendment, for two reasons: First, “the Constitution
places no value on discrimination.” 427 U. S., at 176
(alterations and internal quotations marks omitted). Second, the
government’s regulation of conduct did not “inhibit” the schools’
ability to teach its preferred “ideas or dogma.” Ibid. (internal quotation marks omitted). Requiring the schools to abide
by an antidiscrimination law was not the same thing as compelling
the schools to express teachings contrary to their sincerely held
“belief that racial segregation is desirable.” Ibid .
2
First Amendment rights of expression and
association were also raised to challenge laws against sex
discrimination. In Roberts v. United States Jaycees ,
the United States Jaycees sought an exemption from a Minnesota
law that forbids discrimination on the basis of sex in public
accommodations. The U. S. Jaycees was a civic organization,
which until then had denied admission to women. The organization
alleged that applying the law to require it to include women would
violate its “members’ constitutional rights of free speech and
association.” 468 U. S., at 615. “The power of the state to
change the membership of an organization is inevitably the power to change the way in which it speaks ,” the Jaycees argued.
Brief for Appellee, O. T. 1983, No. 83–724, p. 19
(emphasis added). Thus, “the right of the Jaycees to decide its own
membership” was “inseparable,” in its view, “from its ability to
freely express itself.” Ibid. This Court took a different view. The Court held
that the “application of the Minnesota statute to compel the
Jaycees to accept women” did not infringe the organization’s First
Amendment “freedom of expressive association.” Roberts , 468
U. S., at 622. That was so because the State’s public
accommodations law did “not aim at the suppression of speech” and
did “not distinguish between prohibited and permitted activity on
the basis of viewpoint.” Id. , at 623–624. If the State had
applied the law “for the purpose of hampering the
organization’s ability to express its views,” that would be a
different matter. Id. , at 624 (emphasis added). “Instead,”
the law’s purpose was “eliminating discrimination and assuring [the
State’s] citizens equal access to publicly available goods and
services.” Ibid. “That goal,” the Court reasoned, “was
unrelated to the suppression of expression” and “plainly serves
compelling state interests of the highest order.” Ibid. Justice O’Connor concurred in part and concurred
in the judgment. See id. , at 631. She stressed that the
U. S. Jaycees was a predominantly commercial entity open to
the public. And she took the view that there was a First Amendment
“dichotomy” between rights of commercial and expressive
association. Id. , at 634. The State, for example, was “free
to impose any rational regulation” on commercial transactions
themselves. “A shopkeeper,” Justice O’Connor explained, “has no
constitutional right to deal only with persons of one sex.” Ibid. To wit, the Court had just decided in Hishon v. King & Spalding , 467 U.S.
69 , 78 (1984), that a law partnership had no constitutional
right to discriminate on the basis of sex in violation of Title
VII. The law partnership was an act of association. Its services
(legal advocacy) were expressive; indeed, they consisted of speech.
So the law firm argued that requiring it to consider a woman for
the partnership violated its First Amendment rights “of free
expression” and “of commercial association.” Brief for Respondent,
O. T. 1983, No. 82–940, pp. 14–18. This Court rejected that
argument. The application of Title VII did not “infringe
constitutional rights of expression or association,” the Court
held, because compliance with Title VII did not “inhibi[t]” the
partnership’s ability to advocate for certain “ideas and beliefs.”
467 U. S., at 78 (internal quotation marks omitted); see also supra , at 19 (discussing Runyon , 427 U. S., at
176). The Court reiterated: “ ‘[I]nvidious private
discrimination . . . has never been accorded affirmative
constitutional protections.’ ” 467 U. S., at 78 (quoting Norwood , 413 U. S., at 470).
II
Battling discrimination is like “battling the
Hydra.” Shelby County v. Holder , 570 U.S.
529 , 560 (2013) (Ginsburg, J., dissenting). Whenever you defeat
“one form of . . . discrimination,” another “spr[ings] up
in its place.” Ibid. Time and again, businesses and other
commercial entities have claimed constitutional rights to
discriminate. And time and again, this Court has courageously stood
up to those claims—until today. Today, the Court shrinks. A
business claims that it would like to sell wedding websites to the
general public, yet deny those same websites to gay and lesbian
couples. Under state law, the business is free to include, or not
to include, any lawful message it wants in its wedding websites.
The only thing the business may not do is deny whatever websites it
offers on the basis of sexual orientation. This Court, however,
grants the business a broad exemption from state law and allows the
business to post a notice that says: Wedding websites will be
refused to gays and lesbians. The Court’s decision, which conflates
denial of service and protected expression, is a grave error.
A
303 Creative LLC is a limited liability
company that sells graphic and website designs for profit. Lorie
Smith is the company’s founder and sole member-owner. Smith
believes same-sex marriages are “false,” because “ ‘God’s true
story of marriage’ ” is a story of a “ ‘union between one
man and one woman.’ ” Brief for Petitioners 4, 6–7 (quoting
App. to Pet. for Cert. 188a, 189a); Tr. of Oral Arg. 36, 40–41.
Same-sex marriage, according to her, “violates God’s will” and
“harms society and children.” App. to Pet. for Cert. 186a.
303 Creative has never sold wedding websites.
Smith now believes, however, that “God is calling her ‘to explain
His true story about marriage.’ ” Brief for Petitioners 7
(quoting App. to Pet. for Cert. 188a). For that reason, she says,
she wants her for-profit company to enter the wedding website
business. There is only one thing: Smith would like her company to
sell wedding websites “to the public,” App. to Pet. for Cert. 189a;
Colo. Rev. Stat. §24–34–601(1), but not to same-sex couples. She
also wants to post a notice on the company’s website announcing
this intent to discriminate. App. to Pet. for Cert. 188a–189a. In
Smith’s view, “it would violate [her] sincerely held religious
beliefs to create a wedding website for a same-sex wedding because,
by doing so, [she] would be expressing a message celebrating and
promoting a conception of marriage that [she] believe[s] is
contrary to God’s design.” Id. , at 189a.
Again, Smith’s company has never sold a wedding
website to any customer. Colorado, therefore, has never had to
enforce its antidiscrimination laws against the company. As the
majority puts it, however, Smith “worries that, if she enters the
wedding website business, the State will force her to convey
messages inconsistent with her belief that marriage should be
reserved to unions between one man and one woman.” Ante , at
2. So Smith and her company, the petitioners here, sued the State
in federal court. They sought a court decree giving them a special
exemption from CADA’s Accommodation Clause (which, remember, makes
it unlawful for a business to hold itself out to the public yet
deny to any individual, because of sexual orientation, the full and
equal enjoyment of the business’s goods or services, see supra , at 3–4) and CADA’s Communication Clause (which makes
it unlawful to advertise that goods or services will be denied
because of sexual orientation, see supra , at 4). App.
303–304.
The breadth of petitioners’ pre-enforcement
challenge is astounding. According to Smith, the Free Speech Clause
of the First Amendment entitles her company to refuse to sell any “websites for same-sex weddings,” even though the
company plans to offer wedding websites to the general public. Ibid. ; see also Brief for Petitioners 22–23, and n. 2;
Tr. of Oral Arg. 37–38. In other words, the company claims a
categorical exemption from a public accommodations law simply
because the company sells expressive services. The sweeping nature
of this claim should have led this Court to reject it.
B
The First Amendment does not entitle
petitioners to a special exemption from a state law that simply
requires them to serve all members of the public on equal terms.
Such a law does not directly regulate petitioners’ speech at all,
and petitioners may not escape the law by claiming an expressive
interest in discrimination. The First Amendment likewise does not
exempt petitioners from the law’s prohibition on posting a notice
that they will deny goods or services based on sexual
orientation.
1
This Court has long held that “the First
Amendment does not prevent restrictions directed at commerce or
conduct from imposing incidental burdens on speech.” Sorrell v. IMS Health Inc. , 564 U.S.
552 , 567 (2011). “Congress, for example, can prohibit employers
from discriminating in hiring on the basis of race. The fact that
this will require an employer to take down a sign reading ‘White
Applicants Only’ hardly means that the law should be analyzed as
one regulating the employer’s speech rather than conduct.” Rumsfeld v. Forum for Academic and Institutional Rights,
Inc. , 547 U.S.
47 , 62 (2006) ( FAIR ). This principle explains “why an
ordinance against outdoor fires might forbid burning a flag and why
antitrust laws can prohibit agreements in restraint of trade.” Sorrell , 564 U. S., at 567 (citation and internal
quotation marks omitted).
Consider United States v. O’Brien , 391 U.S.
367 (1968). In that case, the Court upheld the application of a
law against the destruction of draft cards to a defendant who had
burned his draft card to protest the Vietnam War. The protester’s
conduct was indisputably expressive. Indeed, it was political
expression, which lies at the heart of the First Amendment. Whitney v. California , 274 U.S.
357 , 375 (1927) (Brandeis, J., concurring). Yet the O’Brien Court focused on whether the Government’s interest
in regulating the conduct was to burden expression. Because it was
not, the regulation was subject to lesser constitutional scrutiny.
391 U. S., at 376–377, 381–382; Clark v. Community
for Creative Non-Violence , 468 U.S.
288 , 294, 299 (1984). The O’Brien standard is satisfied
if a regulation is unrelated to the suppression of expression and
“ ‘promotes a substantial government interest that would be
achieved less effectively absent the regulation.’ ” FAIR , 547 U. S., at 67 (quoting United States v. Albertini , 472 U.S.
675 , 689 (1985)).[ 9 ] FAIR confronted the interaction between
this principle and an equal-access law. The law at issue was the
Solomon Amendment, which prohibits an institution of higher
education in receipt of federal funding from denying a military
recruiter “the same access to its campus and students that it
provides to the nonmilitary recruiter receiving the most favorable
access.” 547 U. S., at 55; see 10 U. S. C. §983(b). A
group of law schools challenged the Solomon Amendment based on
their sincere objection to the military’s “Don’t Ask, Don’t Tell”
policy. For those who are too young to know, “Don’t Ask, Don’t
Tell” was a homophobic policy that barred openly LGBT people from
serving in the military. LGBT people could serve only if they kept
their identities secret. The idea was that their open existence was
a threat to the military.
The law schools in FAIR claimed that the
Solomon Amendment infringed the schools’ First Amendment freedom of
speech. The schools provided recruiting assistance in the form of
emails, notices on bulletin boards, and flyers. 547 U. S., at
60–61. As the Court acknowledged, those services “clearly involve
speech.” Id. , at 60. And the Solomon Amendment required
“schools offering such services to other recruiters” to provide
them equally “on behalf of the military,” even if the school deeply
objected to creating such speech. Id. , at 61. But that did
not transform the equal provision of services into “compelled
speech” of the kind barred by the First Amendment, because the
school’s speech was “only ‘compelled’ if, and to the extent, the
school provides such speech for other recruiters.” Id. , at
62. Thus, any speech compulsion was “plainly incidental to the
Solomon Amendment’s regulation of conduct.” Ibid. 2
The same principle resolves this case. The
majority tries to sweep under the rug petitioners’ challenge to
CADA’s Communication Clause, so I will start with it. Recall that
Smith wants to post a notice on her company’s homepage that the
company will refuse to sell any website for a same-sex couple’s
wedding. This Court, however, has already said that “a ban on
race-based hiring may require employers to remove ‘White Applicants
Only’ signs.” Sorrell , 564 U. S., at 567 (quoting FAIR , 547 U. S., at 62; some internal quotation marks
omitted); see Pittsburgh Press Co. v. Pittsburgh Comm’n
on Human Relations , 413 U.S.
376 , 389 (1973). So petitioners concede that they are not
entitled to an exemption from the Communication Clause unless they
are also entitled to an exemption from the Accommodation Clause.
Brief for Petitioners 34–35. That concession is all but fatal to
their argument, because it shows that even “pure speech” may be
burdened incident to a valid regulation of conduct.[ 10 ]
CADA’s Accommodation Clause and its application
here are valid regulations of conduct. It is well settled that a
public accommodations law like the Accommodation Clause does not
“target speech or discriminate on the basis of its content.” Hurley , 515 U. S., at 572. Rather, “the focal point of
its prohibition” is “on the act of discriminating against
individuals in the provision of publicly available goods,
privileges, and services.” Ibid. (emphasis added). The State
confirms this reading of CADA. The law applies only to status-based
refusals to provide the full and equal enjoyment of whatever
services petitioners choose to sell to the public. See Brief for
Respondents 15–18.
Crucially, the law “does not dictate the content
of speech at all, which is only ‘compelled’ if, and to the extent,”
the company offers “such speech” to other customers. FAIR ,
547 U. S., at 62. Colorado does not require the company to
“speak [the State’s] preferred message.” Ante , at 19. Nor
does it prohibit the company from speaking the company’s preferred
message. The company could, for example, offer only wedding
websites with biblical quotations describing marriage as between
one man and one woman. Brief for Respondents 15. (Just as it could
offer only t-shirts with such quotations.) The company could also
refuse to include the words “Love is Love” if it would not provide
those words to any customer. All the company has to do is offer its
services without regard to customers’ protected characteristics. Id. , at 15–16. Any effect on the company’s speech is
therefore “incidental” to the State’s content-neutral regulation of
conduct. FAIR , 547 U. S., at 62; see Hurley , 515
U. S., at 572–573.
Once these features of the law are understood,
it becomes clear that petitioners’ freedom of speech is not
abridged in any meaningful sense, factual or legal. Petitioners
remain free to advocate the idea that same-sex marriage betrays
God’s laws. FAIR , 547 U. S., at 60; Hishon , 467
U. S., at 78; Runyon , 427 U. S., at 176. Even if
Smith believes God is calling her to do so through her for-profit
company, the company need not hold out its goods or services to the
public at large. Many filmmakers, visual artists, and writers never
do. (That is why the law does not require Steven Spielberg or
Banksy to make films or art for anyone who asks. But cf. ante , at 12, 23–24.) Finally, and most importantly, even if
the company offers its goods or services to the public, it remains
free under state law to decide what messages to include or not to
include. To repeat (because it escapes the majority): The company
can put whatever “harmful” or “low-value” speech it wants on its
websites. It can “tell people what they do not want to hear.” Ante , at 25 (internal quotation marks and brackets omitted).
All the company may not do is offer wedding websites to the public
yet refuse those same websites to gay and lesbian couples. See Runyon , 427 U. S., at 176 (distinguishing between
schools’ ability to express their bigoted view “that racial
segregation is desirable” and the schools’ proscribable
“ practice of excluding racial minorities”).
Another example might help to illustrate the
point. A professional photographer is generally free to choose her
subjects. She can make a living taking photos of flowers or
celebrities. The State does not regulate that choice. If the
photographer opens a portrait photography business to the public,
however, the business may not deny to any person, because of race,
sex, national origin, or other protected characteristic, the full
and equal enjoyment of whatever services the business chooses to
offer. That is so even though portrait photography services are
customized and expressive. If the business offers school photos, it
may not deny those services to multiracial children because the
owner does not want to create any speech indicating that
interracial couples are acceptable. If the business offers
corporate headshots, it may not deny those services to women
because the owner believes a woman’s place is in the home. And if
the business offers passport photos, it may not deny those services
to Mexican Americans because the owner opposes immigration from
Mexico.
The same is true for sexual-orientation
discrimination. If a photographer opens a photo booth outside of
city hall and offers to sell newlywed photos captioned with the
words “Just Married,” she may not refuse to sell that service to a
newlywed gay or lesbian couple, even if she believes the couple is
not, in fact, just married because in her view their marriage is
“false.” Tr. of Oral Arg. 36, 40–41.
3
Because any burden on petitioners’ speech is
incidental to CADA’s neutral regulation of commercial conduct, the
regulation is subject to the standard set forth in O’Brien .
That standard is easily satisfied here because the law’s
application “promotes a substantial government interest that would
be achieved less effectively absent the regulation.” FAIR ,
547 U. S., at 67 (internal quotation marks omitted). Indeed,
this Court has already held that the State’s goal of “eliminating
discrimination and assuring its citizens equal access to publicly
available goods and services” is “unrelated to the suppression of
expression” and “plainly serves compelling state interests of the
highest order.” Roberts , 468 U. S., at 624. The Court
has also held that by prohibiting only “ acts of invidious
discrimination in the distribution of publicly available goods, services, and other advantages,” the law “responds precisely
to the substantive problem which legitimately concerns the State
and abridges no more speech . . . than is necessary to
accomplish that purpose.” Id. , at 628–629 (emphasis added;
internal quotation marks omitted); see supra , at 4–7.
C
The Court reaches the wrong answer in this
case because it asks the wrong questions. The question is not
whether the company’s products include “elements of speech.” FAIR , 547 U. S., at 61. (They do.) The question is not
even whether CADA would require the company to create and sell
speech, notwithstanding the owner’s sincere objection to doing so,
if the company chooses to offer “such speech” to the public. Id. , at 62. (It would.) These questions do not resolve the
First Amendment inquiry any more than they did in FAIR .
Instead, the proper focus is on the character of state action and
its relationship to expression. Because Colorado seeks to apply
CADA only to the refusal to provide same-sex couples the full and
equal enjoyment of the company’s publicly available services, so
that the company’s speech “is only ‘compelled’ if, and to the
extent,” the company chooses to offer “such speech” to the public,
any burden on speech is “plainly incidental” to a content-neutral
regulation of conduct. Ibid. The majority attempts to distinguish this clear
holding of FAIR by suggesting that the compelled speech in FAIR was “incidental” because it was “logistical”
( e.g. , “The U. S. Army recruiter will meet interested
students in Room 123 at 11 a.m.”). Ante , at 18 (internal
quotation marks omitted). This attempt fails twice over. First, the
law schools in FAIR alleged that the Solomon Amendment
required them to create and disseminate speech propagating the
military’s message, which they deeply objected to, and to include
military speakers in on- and off-campus forums (if the schools
provided equally favorable services to other recruiters). 547
U. S., at 60–61; App. 27 and Brief for Respondents 5–8 in Rumsfeld v. Forum for Academic and Institutional Rights,
Inc. , O. T. 2005, No. 04–1152. The majority simply skips
over the Court’s key reasoning for why any speech compulsion was
nevertheless “incidental” to the Amendment’s regulation of conduct:
It would occur only “if, and to the extent,” the regulated entity
provided “such speech” to others. FAIR , 547 U. S., at
62. Likewise in O’Brien , the reason the burden on O’Brien’s
expression was incidental was not because his message was factual
or uncontroversial. But cf. ante , at 19. O’Brien burned his
draft card to send a political message, and the burden on his
expression was substantial. Still, the burden was “incidental”
because it was ancillary to a regulation that did not aim at
expression. 391 U. S., at 377.
Second, the majority completely ignores the
categorical nature of the exemption claimed by petitioners.
Petitioners maintain, as they have throughout this litigation, that
they will refuse to create any wedding website for a
same-sex couple. Even an announcement of the time and place of a
wedding (similar to the majority’s example from FAIR )
abridges petitioners’ freedom of speech, they claim, because “the
announcement of the wedding itself is a concept that [Smith]
believes to be false.” Tr. of Oral Arg. 41. Indeed, petitioners
here concede that if a same-sex couple came across an opposite-sex
wedding website created by the company and requested an identical
website, with only the names and date of the wedding changed,
petitioners would refuse. Id. , at 37–38.[ 11 ] That is status-based discrimination,
plain and simple.
Oblivious to this fact, the majority insists
that petitioners discriminate based on message, not status. The
company, says the majority, will not sell same-sex wedding websites
to anyone. Ante , at 17. It will sell only opposite-sex
wedding websites; that is its service. Petitioners, however,
“cannot define their service as ‘opposite-sex wedding [websites]’
any more than a hotel can recast its services as ‘whites-only
lodgings.’ ” Telescope Media Group v. Lucero ,
936 F.3d 740, 769 (CA8 2019) (Kelly, J., concurring in part and
dissenting in part). To allow a business open to the public to
define the expressive quality of its goods or services to exclude a
protected group would nullify public accommodations laws. It would
mean that a large retail store could sell “passport photos for
white people.”
The majority protests that Smith will gladly
sell her goods and services to anyone, including same-sex couples . Ante , at 2, 17. She just will not sell
websites for same-sex weddings . Apparently, a gay or lesbian
couple might buy a wedding website for their straight friends. This
logic would be amusing if it were not so embarrassing.[ 12 ] I suppose the Heart of Atlanta
Motel could have argued that Black people may still rent rooms for
their white friends. Smith answers that she will sell other
websites for gay or lesbian clients. But then she, like Ollie
McClung, who would serve Black people take-out but not table
service, discriminates against LGBT people by offering them a
limited menu.[ 13 ] This is
plain to see, for all who do not look the other way.
The majority, however, analogizes this case to Hurley and Boy Scouts of America v. Dale , 530 U.S.
640 (2000). The law schools in FAIR likewise relied on Hurley and Dale to argue that the Solomon Amendment
violated their free-speech rights. FAIR confirmed, however,
that a neutral regulation of conduct imposes an incidental burden
on speech when the regulation grants a right of equal access that
requires the regulated party to provide speech only if, and to the
extent, it provides such speech for others. Supra , at 25–26,
29–30. Hurley and Dale , by contrast,
involved “peculiar” applications of public accommodations laws, not
to “the act of discriminating . . . in the provision of
publicly available goods” by “clearly commercial entities,” but
rather to private, nonprofit expressive associations in ways that
directly burdened speech. Hurley , 515 U. S., at 572
(private parade); Dale , 530 U. S., at 657 (Boy Scouts).
The Court in Hurley and Dale stressed that the speech
burdens in those cases were not incidental to prohibitions on
status-based discrimination because the associations did not assert
that “mere acceptance of a member from a particular group would
impair [the association’s] message.” Dale , 530 U. S.,
at 653; see also ibid. (reasoning that Dale was excluded for
being a gay rights activist, not for being gay); ibid. (explaining that in Hurley , “the parade organizers did not
wish to exclude the GLIB [Irish-American gay, lesbian, and bisexual
group] members because of their sexual orientations, but because
they wanted to march behind a GLIB banner”); Hurley , 515
U. S., at 572–573.
Here, the opposite is true. 303 Creative LLC is
a “clearly commercial entit[y].” Dale , 530 U. S., at
657. The company comes under the regulation of CADA only if it
sells services to the public, and only if it denies the equal
enjoyment of such services because of sexual orientation. The State
confirms that the company is free to include or not to include any
message in whatever services it chooses to offer. Supra , at
26–28. And the company confirms that it plans to engage in
status-based discrimination. Supra , at 22–23, 31–32.
Therefore, any burden on the company’s expression is incidental to
the State’s content-neutral regulation of commercial conduct.
Frustrated by this inescapable logic, the
majority dials up the rhetoric, asserting that “Colorado seeks to
compel [the company’s] speech in order to excise certain ideas or
viewpoints from the public dialogue.” The State’s “very purpose in
seeking to apply its law,” in the majority’s view, is “the coercive
elimination of dissenting ideas about marriage.” Ante , at
10–11 (internal quotation marks and brackets omitted).[ 14 ] That is an astonishing view of
the law. It is contrary to the fact that a law requiring
public-facing businesses to accept all comers “is textbook
viewpoint neutral,” Christian Legal Soc. Chapter of Univ. of
Cal., Hastings College of Law v. Martinez , 561 U.S.
661 , 695 (2010); contrary to the fact that the Accommodation
Clause and the State’s application of it here allows Smith to
include in her company’s goods and services whatever “dissenting
views about marriage” she wants; and contrary to this Court’s clear
holdings that the purpose of a public accommodations law, as
applied to the commercial act of discrimination in the sale of
publicly available goods and services, is to ensure equal access to
and equal dignity in the public marketplace, supra , at
4–6.
So it is dispiriting to read the majority
suggest that this case resembles West Virginia Bd. of Ed. v. Barnette , 319 U.S.
624 (1943). A content-neutral equal-access policy is “a far
cry” from a mandate to “endorse” a pledge chosen by the Government. FAIR , 547 U. S., at 62. This Court has said “it
trivializes the freedom protected in Barnette ” to equate the
two. Ibid. Requiring Smith’s company to abide by a law
against invidious discrimination in commercial sales to the public
does not conscript her into espousing the government’s message. It
does not “invad[e]” her “sphere of intellect” or violate her
constitutional “right to differ.” Ante , at 2, 7 (internal
quotation marks omitted). All it does is require her to stick to
her bargain: “The owner who hangs a shingle and offers her services
to the public cannot retreat from the promise of open service; to
do so is to offer the public marked money. It is to convey the
promise of a free and open society and then take the prize away
from the despised few.” J. Singer, We Don’t Serve Your Kind Here:
Public Accommodations and the Mark of Sodom, 95 B. U.
L. Rev. 929, 949 (2015).
III
Today is a sad day in American constitutional
law and in the lives of LGBT people. The Supreme Court of the
United States declares that a particular kind of business, though
open to the public, has a constitutional right to refuse to serve
members of a protected class. The Court does so for the first time
in its history. By issuing this new license to discriminate in a
case brought by a company that seeks to deny same-sex couples the
full and equal enjoyment of its services, the immediate, symbolic
effect of the decision is to mark gays and lesbians for
second-class status. In this way, the decision itself inflicts a
kind of stigmatic harm, on top of any harm caused by denials of
service. The opinion of the Court is, quite literally, a notice
that reads: “Some services may be denied to same-sex couples.”
“The truth is,” these “affronts and denials”
“are intensely human and personal.” S. Rep. No. 872,
at 15 (internal quotation marks omitted). Sometimes they may
“harm the physical body, but always they strike at the root of the
human spirit, at the very core of human dignity.” Ibid. To
see how, imagine a same-sex couple browses the public market with
their child. The market could be online or in a shopping mall. Some
stores sell products that are customized and expressive. The family
sees a notice announcing that services will be refused for same-sex
weddings. What message does that send? It sends the message that we
live in a society with social castes. It says to the child of the
same-sex couple that their parents’ relationship is not equal to
others’. And it reminds LGBT people of a painful feeling that they
know all too well: There are some public places where they can be
themselves, and some where they cannot. K. Yoshino, Covering 61–66
(2006). Ask any LGBT person, and you will learn just how often they
are forced to navigate life in this way. They must ask themselves:
If I reveal my identity to this co-worker, or to this shopkeeper,
will they treat me the same way? If I hold the hand of my partner
in this setting, will someone stare at me, harass me, or even hurt
me? It is an awful way to live. Freedom from this way of life is
the very object of a law that declares: All members of the public
are entitled to inhabit public spaces on equal terms.
This case cannot be understood outside of the
context in which it arises. In that context, the outcome is even
more distressing. The LGBT rights movement has made historic
strides, and I am proud of the role this Court recently played in
that history. Today, however, we are taking steps backward. A slew
of anti-LGBT laws have been passed in some parts of the
country,[ 15 ] raising the
specter of a “bare . . . desire to harm a politically
unpopular group.” Romer , 517 U. S., at 634 (internal
quotation marks omitted). This is especially unnerving when “for
centuries there have been powerful voices to condemn” this small
minority. Lawrence v. Texas , 539
U.S. 558 , 571 (2003). In this pivotal moment, the Court had an
opportunity to reaffirm its commitment to equality on behalf of all
members of society, including LGBT people. It does not do so.
Although the consequences of today’s decision
might be most pressing for the LGBT community, the decision’s logic
cannot be limited to discrimination on the basis of sexual
orientation or gender identity. The decision threatens to balkanize
the market and to allow the exclusion of other groups from many
services. A website designer could equally refuse to create a
wedding website for an interracial couple, for example. How quickly
we forget that opposition to interracial marriage was often because
“ ‘Almighty God . . . did not intend for the races
to mix.’ ” Loving v. Virginia , 388 U.S.
1 , 3 (1967). Yet the reason for discrimination need not even be
religious, as this case arises under the Free Speech Clause. A
stationer could refuse to sell a birth announcement for a disabled
couple because she opposes their having a child. A large retail
store could reserve its family portrait services for “traditional”
families. And so on.[ 16 ]
Wedding websites, birth announcements, family
portraits, epitaphs. These are not just words and images. They are
the most profound moments in a human’s life. They are the moments
that give that life personal and cultural meaning. You already
heard the story of Bob and Jack, the elderly gay couple forced to
find a funeral home more than an hour away. Supra , at 5–6,
and n. 4. Now hear the story of Cynthia and Sherry, a lesbian
couple of 13 years until Cynthia died from cancer at age 35. When
Cynthia was diagnosed, she drew up a will, which authorized Sherry
to make burial arrangements. Cynthia had asked Sherry to include an
inscription on her headstone, listing the relationships that were
important to her, for example, “daughter, granddaughter, sister,
and aunt.” After Cynthia died, the cemetery was willing to include
those words, but not the words that described Cynthia’s
relationship to Sherry: “ ‘beloved life partner.’ ” N.
Knauer, Gay and Lesbian Elders 102 (2011). There are many such
stories, too many to tell here. And after today, too many to
come.
I fear that the symbolic damage of the Court’s
opinion is done. But that does not mean that we are powerless in
the face of the decision. The meaning of our Constitution is found
not in any law volume, but in the spirit of the people who live
under it. Every business owner in America has a choice whether to
live out the values in the Constitution. Make no mistake: Invidious
discrimination is not one of them. “[D]iscrimination in any form
and in any degree has no justifiable part whatever in our
democratic way of life.” Korematsu v. United States , 323 U.S.
214 , 242 (1944) (Murphy, J., dissenting). “It is unattractive
in any setting but it is utterly revolting among a free people who
have embraced the principles set forth in the Constitution of the
United States.” Ibid. The unattractive lesson of the majority opinion
is this: What’s mine is mine, and what’s yours is yours. The lesson
of the history of public accommodations laws is altogether
different. It is that in a free and democratic society, there can
be no social castes. And for that to be true, it must be true in
the public market. For the “promise of freedom” is an empty one if
the Government is “powerless to assure that a dollar in the hands
of [one person] will purchase the same thing as a dollar in the
hands of a[nother].” Jones v. Alfred H. Mayer Co. , 392 U.S.
409 , 443 (1968). Because the Court today retreats from that
promise, I dissent. Notes 1 See 42 U. S. C. §2000a et seq. (Title II of Civil Rights Act of 1964); 42
U. S. C. §12181 et seq. (Title III of Americans
with Disabilities Act of 1990). 2 See Alaska Stat.
§18.80.230 (2023); Ariz. Rev. Stat. Ann. §41–1442 (2017); Ark. Code
Ann. §16–123–107 (Supp. 2021); Cal. Civ. Code Ann. §51 (West 2020);
Colo. Rev. Stat. §24–34–601 (2022); Conn. Gen. Stat. §§46a–64,
46a–81d (Cum. Supp. 2023); Del. Code Ann., Tit. 6, §4504 (Cum.
Supp. 2022); Fla. Stat. §§413.08, 760.08 (2022); Haw. Rev. Stat.
§489–3 (Cum. Supp. 2021); Idaho Code Ann. §67–5909 (2020); Ill.
Comp. Stat., ch. 775, §5/1–102 (West Supp. 2021); Ind. Code
§22–9–1–2 (2022); Iowa Code §216.7 (2023); Kan. Stat. Ann. §44–1001
(2021); Ky. Rev. Stat. Ann. §§344.120, 344.145 (West 2018); La.
Rev. Stat. Ann. §51:2247 (West Cum. Supp. 2023); Me. Rev. Stat.
Ann., Tit. 5, §4591 (Cum. Supp. 2023); Md. State Govt. Code Ann.
§20–304 (2021); Mass. Gen. Laws, ch. 272, §98 (2020); Mich. Comp.
Laws §§37.1102, 37.2302 (1981), as amended, 2023 Mich. Pub. Acts
no. 6 ( sine die ); Minn. Stat. §363 A. 11 (2022); Mo.
Rev. Stat. §213.065 (Cum. Supp. 2021); Mont. Code Ann. §49–2–304
(2021); Neb. Rev. Stat. §20–134 (2022); Nev. Rev. Stat. §651.070
(2017); N. H. Rev. Stat. Ann. §354–A:17 (2022); N. J.
Stat. Ann. §10:5–12 (West Cum. Supp. 2023); N. M. Stat. Ann.
§28–1–7 (2022); N. Y. Civ. Rights Law Ann. §40 (West 2019);
N. D. Cent. Code Ann. §14–02.4–14 (2017); Ohio Rev. Code Ann.
§4112.02 (Lexis Supp. 2023); Okla. Stat., Tit. 25, §1402 (2011);
Ore. Rev. Stat. §659 A. 403 (2021); Pa. Stat. Ann., Tit. 43, §953
(Purdon 2020); R. I. Gen. Laws §11–24–2 (2002); S. C.
Code Ann. §45–9–10 (2016); S. D. Codified Laws §20–13–23
(2016); Tenn. Code Ann. §4–21–501 (2021); Utah Code §13–7–3 (2022);
Vt. Stat. Ann., Tit. 9, §4502 (2020); Va. Code Ann. §2.2–3904
(2022); Wash. Rev. Code §49.60.215 (2022); W. Va. Code Ann.
§5–11–2 (Lexis 2022); Wis. Stat. §106.52 (2019–2020); Wyo. Stat.
Ann. §6–9–101 (2021). 3 Hearings on the
Nomination of Ruth Bader Ginsburg To Be Associate Justice of the
Supreme Court of the United States before the Senate Committee on
the Judiciary, 103d Cong., 1st Sess., 139 (1993). 4 The men in this story are
Robert “Bob” Huskey and John “Jack” Zawadski. Bob and Jack were a
loving couple of 52 years. They moved from California to Colorado
to care for Bob’s mother, then to Wisconsin to farm apples and
teach special education, and then to Mississippi to retire. Within
weeks of this Court’s decision in Obergefell v. Hodges , 576 U.S. 644 (2015), Bob and Jack got married. They
were 85 and 81 years old on their wedding day. A few months later,
Bob’s health took a turn. He died the following spring. When Bob’s
family was forced to find an alternative funeral home more than an
hour from where Bob and Jack lived, the lunch in Bob’s memory had
to be canceled. Jack died the next year. 5 For example, a case on
which the majority relies found that it could “shortly dispos[e]”
of the question whether a steamship company was a common carrier
because the company was “the owner of a general ship, carrying
goods for hire . . . and perform[ing]” that service
“regular[ly].” Liverpool & Great Western Steam Co. v. Phenix Ins. Co. , 129 U.S.
397 , 437 (1889). No showing of market power was required. Ibid. 6 Nor does “host[ing] or
transport[ing] others and their belongings,” ante , at 13,
explain the right of access. Smiths, for instance, did not always
practice their trade by holding property for others. And even when
they did, any duty of care resulting from such bailment cannot
explain the duty to serve all comers, which logically must be
assumed beforehand. See Lane v. Cotton , 12 Mod. 472,
484, 88 Eng. Rep. 1458, 1464 (K. B. 1701) (Holt, C. J.).
That duty instead came from somewhere else, and the weight of
authority indicates that it came from a business’s act of holding
itself out to the public as ready to serve anyone who would hire
it. Singer 1304–1330; 3 W. Blackstone, Commentaries on the Laws of
England 164 (1768); J. Story, Commentaries on the Law of Bailments
§§495, 591 (1837); 1 T. Parsons, Law of Contracts 639, 643, 649
(1853). 7 Compare, e.g. , Chesapeake, O. & S. R. Co. v. Wells , 85 Tenn.
613, 615, 4 S.W. 5 (1887) (rejecting Ida B. Wells’s claim that she
was denied “ ‘accommodations equal in all respects,’ ”
when she tried to enter a train car “set apart for white ladies and
their gentlemen” on account of tobacco smoke in her car, and was
forcibly removed), with Memphis & C. R. Co. v. Benson , 85 Tenn. 627, 632, 4 S.W. 5, 7 (1887) (accepting
that a white man would be permitted to ride standing in the ladies’
car on account of tobacco smoke in his car). 8 See Cal. Civ. Code Ann.
§51; Colo. Rev. Stat. §24–34–601; Conn. Gen. Stat. §46a–81d; Del.
Code Ann., Tit. 6, §4504; Haw. Rev. Stat. §489–3; Ill. Comp. Stat.,
ch. 775, §5/1–102; Iowa Code §216.7; Me. Rev. Stat. Ann., Tit. 5,
§4591; Md. State Govt. Code Ann. §20–304; Mass. Gen. Laws, ch. 272,
§98; Mich. Comp. Laws §37.2302, as amended; Minn. Stat. §363 A. 11;
Nev. Rev. Stat. §651.070; N. H. Rev. Stat. Ann. §354–A:17;
N. J. Stat. Ann. §10:5–12; N. M. Stat. Ann. §28–1–7;
N. Y. Civ. Rights Law Ann. §40; Ore. Rev. Stat. §659 A. 403;
R. I. Gen. Laws §11–24–2; Vt. Stat. Ann., Tit. 9, §4502; Va.
Code Ann. §2.2–3904; Wash. Rev. Code §49.60.215; Wis. Stat.
§106.52. 9 The majority commits a
fundamental error in suggesting that a law does not regulate
conduct if it ever applies to expressive activities. See ante , at 19, 22. This would come as a great surprise to the O’Brien Court. 10 The
majority appears to find this discussion of the Communication
Clause upsetting. See ante , at 20–21, and n. 5. It is
easy to understand why: The Court’s prior First Amendment cases
clearly explain that a ban on discrimination may require a business
to take down a sign that expresses the business owner’s intent to
discriminate. See, e.g. , FAIR , 547 U. S., at 62.
This principle is deeply inconsistent with the majority’s position.
Thus, a “straight couples only” notice, like the one the Court
today allows, see App. to Pet. for Cert. 188a–189a, is itself a
devastating indictment of the majority’s logic. 11 Because petitioners have never sold a
wedding website to anyone, the record contains only a mockup
website. The mockup confirms what you would expect: The website
provides details of the event, a form to RSVP, a gift registry,
etc. See App. 51–72. The customization of these elements pursuant
to a content-neutral regulation of conduct does not
unconstitutionally intrude upon any protected expression of the
website designer. Yet Smith claims a First Amendment right to
refuse to provide any wedding website for a same-sex couple.
Her claim therefore rests on the idea that her act of service is
itself a form of protected expression. In granting Smith’s claim,
the majority collapses the distinction between status-based and
message-based refusals of service. The history shows just how
profoundly wrong that is. See Runyon v. McCrary , 427 U.S.
160 , 176 (1976); Hishon v. King & Spalding , 467 U.S.
69 , 78 (1984); Roberts v. United States Jaycees , 468 U.S.
609 , 622–629 (1984). 12 The
majority tacitly acknowledges the absurdity. At the start of its
opinion, it explains that Smith “decided to expand her offerings to
include services for couples seeking websites for their weddings.” Ante , at 1 (emphasis added). 13 What
is “ ‘embarrassing’ ” about this reasoning is not, as the
Court claims, the “distinction between status and message.” Ante , at 18, n. 3. It is petitioners’ contrivance,
embraced by the Court, that a prohibition on status-based
discrimination can be avoided by asserting that a group can always
buy services on behalf of others, or else that the group can access
a “separate but equal” subset of the services made available to
everyone else. 14 The
majority’s repeated invocation of this Orwellian thought policing
is revealing of just how much it misunderstands this case. See ante , at 10–12, 19–20, 24–25 (claiming that the State seeks
to “eliminate ideas” and that it will punish Smith unless she
“conforms her views to the State’s”). 15 These
laws variously censor discussion of sexual orientation and gender
identity in schools, see, e.g. , 2023 Ky. Acts pp. 775–779,
and ban drag shows in public, see 2023 Tenn. Pub. Acts ch. 2. Yet
we are told that the real threat to free speech is that a
commercial business open to the public might have to serve all
members of the public. 16 The
potential implications of the Court’s logic are deeply troubling.
Would Runyon v. McCrary have come out differently if
the schools had argued that accepting Black children would have
required them to create original speech, like lessons, report
cards, or diplomas, that they deeply objected to? What if the law
firm in Hishon v. King & Spalding had argued that
promoting a woman to the partnership would have required it to
alter its speech, like letterhead or court filings, in ways that it
would rather not? Once you look closely, “compelled speech” (in the
majority’s facile understanding of that concept) is
everywhere. | The Supreme Court case 303 Creative LLC v. Elenis considers the conflict between Colorado's anti-discrimination law and the First Amendment right to free speech. Lorie Smith, the owner of 303 Creative LLC, offers website and graphic design services and wanted to expand into creating wedding websites for couples. She refused to serve same-sex couples, citing her religious beliefs, and challenged Colorado's anti-discrimination law on free speech grounds. The Court ruled in favor of Smith, arguing that Colorado's law compelled her to create speech that contradicted her beliefs, thus violating her right to free speech. This case sets a precedent for businesses to potentially override anti-discrimination laws by claiming that serving certain customers would require them to create speech contrary to their beliefs. Dissenting opinions highlight the potential implications for protecting minority groups from discrimination and the distinction between regulating conduct and compelling speech. |
Free Speech | National Rifle Association of America v. Vullo | https://supreme.justia.com/cases/federal/us/602/22-842/ | NOTICE: This opinion is subject to
formal revision before publication in the United States Reports.
Readers are requested to notify the Reporter of Decisions, Supreme
Court of the United States, Washington, D. C. 20543,
[email protected], of any typographical or other formal
errors.
SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES
_________________
No. 22–842
_________________
NATIONAL RIFLE ASSOCIATION OF AMERICA,
PETITIONER v. MARIA T. VULLO
on writ of certiorari to the united states
court of appeals for the second circuit
[May 30, 2024]
Justice Sotomayor delivered the opinion of the
Court.
Six decades ago, this Court held that a
government entity’s “threat of invoking legal sanctions and other
means of coercion” against a third party “to achieve the
suppression” of disfavored speech violates the First Amendment. Bantam Books, Inc. v. Sullivan , 372 U.S.
58 , 67 (1963). Today, the Court reaffirms what it said then:
Government officials cannot attempt to coerce private parties in
order to punish or suppress views that the government disfavors.
Petitioner National Rifle Association (NRA) plausibly alleges that
respondent Maria Vullo did just that. As superintendent of the New
York Department of Financial Services, Vullo allegedly pressured
regulated entities to help her stifle the NRA’s pro-gun advocacy by
threatening enforcement actions against those entities that refused
to disassociate from the NRA and other gun-promotion advocacy
groups. Those allegations, if true, state a First Amendment
claim.
I
A
Because this case comes to us at the
motion-to-dismiss stage, the Court assumes the truth of
“well-pleaded factual allegations” and “reasonable inference[s]”
therefrom. Ashcroft v. Iqbal , 556
U.S. 662 , 678–679 (2009). Unless stated otherwise, the
allegations aver as follows:
The New York Department of Financial Services
(DFS) oversees insurance companies and financial services
institutions doing business in the State. See N. Y. Fin.
Servs. Law Ann. §201(a) (West 2012). DFS can initiate
investigations and civil enforcement actions against regulated
entities, and can refer potential criminal violations to the
State’s attorney general for prosecution. §§301(b), (c)(4). The
DFS-regulated entities in this case are insurers that had business
relationships with the NRA.
Since 2000, the NRA has offered a variety of
insurance programs as a benefit to its members. The NRA contracted
with affiliates of Lockton Companies, LLC (Lockton), to administer
the various policies of these affinity insurance programs, which
Chubb Limited (Chubb) and Lloyd’s of London (Lloyd’s) would then
underwrite. In return, the NRA received a percentage of its
members’ premium payments. One of the NRA’s affinity products,
Carry Guard, covered personal-injury and criminal-defense costs
related to licensed firearm use, and “insured New York residents
for intentional, reckless, and criminally negligent acts with a
firearm that injured or killed another person.” 49 F. 4th 700, 707
(CA2 2022).
In September 2017, a gun-control advocacy group
contacted the New York County District Attorney’s office to tip
them off to “compliance infirmities in Carry Guard.” App. to Pet.
for Cert. 206, Second Amended Complaint ¶34. That office then
passed on the allegations to DFS. The next month,
then-Superintendent of DFS Vullo began investigating Carry Guard,
focusing on Chubb and Lockton. The investigation revealed at least
two kinds of violations of New York law: that Carry Guard insured
intentional criminal acts, and the NRA promoted Carry Guard without
an insurance producer license. By mid-November, upon finding out
about the investigation following DFS information requests, Lockton
and Chubb suspended Carry Guard. Vullo then expanded her
investigation into the NRA’s other affinity insurance programs,
many of which were underwritten by Lloyd’s and administered by
Lockton. These NRA-endorsed programs provided similar coverage and
suffered from the same legal infirmities.
In the midst of the investigation, tragedy
struck Parkland, Florida. On February 14, 2018, a gunman opened
fire at Marjory Stoneman Douglas High School, murdering 17 students
and staff members. Following the shooting, the NRA and other
gun-advocacy groups experienced “intense backlash” across the
country. 49 F. 4th, at 708. Major business institutions, including
DFS-regulated entities, spoke out against the NRA, and some even
cut ties with the organization. App. to Pet. for Cert. 244.
MetLife, for example, ended a discount program it offered with the
NRA. On February 25, 2018, Lockton’s chairman “placed a distraught
telephone call to the NRA,” in which he privately shared that
Lockton would sever all ties with the NRA to avoid “ ‘losing
[its] license’ to do business in New York.” Id ., at 298,
Complaint ¶42. Lockton publicly announced its decision the next
day. Following Lockton’s decision, the NRA’s corporate insurance
carrier also severed ties with the organization and refused to
renew coverage at any price. The NRA contends that Lockton and the
corporate insurance carrier took these steps not because of the
Parkland shooting but because they feared “reprisa[l]” from Vullo. Id ., at 210, ¶44; see id ., at 209–210, ¶¶41–43.
Around that time, Vullo also began to meet with
executives at the insurance companies doing business with the NRA.
On February 27, Vullo met with senior executives at Lloyd’s. There,
speaking on behalf of DFS and then-Governor Andrew Cuomo, Vullo
“presented [their] views on gun control and their desire to
leverage their powers to combat the availability of firearms,
including specifically by weakening the NRA.” Id ., at 221,
¶67. She also “discussed an array of technical regulatory
infractions plaguing the affinity-insurance marketplace” in New
York. Id ., at 199, ¶21. Vullo told the Lloyd’s executives
“that DFS was less interested in pursuing the[se] infractions”
unrelated to any NRA business “so long as Lloyd’s ceased providing
insurance to gun groups, especially the NRA.” Id ., at
199–200, ¶21; accord, id ., at 223, ¶69 (alleging that Vullo
made it clear to Lloyd’s that it “could avoid liability for
infractions relating to other, similarly situated insurance
policies, so long as it aided DFS’s campaign against gun
groups”).[ 1 ] Vullo and Lloyd’s
struck a deal: Lloyd’s “would instruct its syndicates to cease
underwriting firearm-related policies and would scale back its
NRA-related business,” and “in exchange, DFS would focus its
forthcoming affinity-insurance enforcement action solely on those
syndicates which served the NRA, and ignore other syndicates
writing similar policies.” Ibid ., ¶69.
On April 19, 2018, Vullo issued two virtually
identical guidance letters on DFS letterhead entitled, “Guidance on
Risk Management Relating to the NRA and Similar Gun Promotion
Organizations.” Id ., at 246–251 (Guidance Letters). Vullo
sent one of the letters to insurance companies and the other to
financial services institutions. In the letters, Vullo pointed to
the “social backlash” against the NRA and other groups “that
promote guns that lead to senseless violence” following “several
recent horrific shootings, including in Parkland, Florida.” Id ., at 246, 249. Vullo then cited recent instances of
businesses severing their ties with the NRA as examples of
companies “fulfilling their corporate social responsibility.” Id ., at 247, 250.
In the Guidance Letters’ final paragraph, Vullo
“encourage[d]” DFS-regulated entities to: (1) “continue evaluating
and managing their risks, including reputational risks, that may
arise from their dealings with the NRA or similar gun promotion
organizations”; (2) “review any relationships they have with the
NRA or similar gun promotion organizations”; and (3) “take prompt
actions to manag[e] these risks and promote public health and
safety.” Id ., at 248, 251.[ 2 ]
The same day that DFS issued the Guidance
Letters, Vullo and Governor Cuomo issued a joint press release that
echoed many of the letters’ statements. The press release included
a quote from Vullo “ ‘urg[ing] all insurance companies and
banks doing business in New York’ ” to join those “ ‘that
have already discontinued their arrangements with the NRA.’ ” Id ., at 244. The press release cited Chubb’s decision to
stop underwriting Carry Guard as an example to emulate. The next
day, Cuomo tweeted: “ ‘The NRA is an extremist organization. I
urge companies in New York State to revisit any ties they have to
the NRA and consider their reputations, and responsibility to the
public.’ ” Id ., at 213, Complaint ¶51.
Less than two weeks after the Guidance Letters
and press release went out, DFS entered into consent decrees with
Lockton (on May 2), and Chubb (on May 7). The decrees stipulated
that Carry Guard violated New York insurance law because it
provided insurance coverage for intentional criminal acts, and
because the NRA promoted Carry Guard, along with other NRA-endorsed
programs, without an insurance producer license. The decrees also
listed other infractions of the State’s insurance law. Both Lockton
and Chubb admitted liability, agreed not to provide any
NRA-endorsed insurance programs (even if lawful) but were permitted
to sell corporate insurance to the NRA, and agreed to pay fines of
$7 million and $1.3 million respectively. On May 9, Lloyd’s
officially instructed its syndicates to terminate existing
agreements with the NRA and not to insure new ones. It publicly
announced its decision to cut ties with the NRA that same day. On
December 20, 2018, DFS and Lloyd’s entered into their own consent
decree, which imposed similar terms and a $5 million fine.
B
The NRA sued Cuomo, Vullo, and DFS. The only
claims before the Court today are those against Vullo—namely,
claims that Vullo violated the First Amendment by coercing
DFS-regulated parties to punish or suppress “the NRA’s pro- Second
Amendment viewpoint” and “core political speech.” Id ., at
231, ¶91, 234, ¶101. The complaint asserts both censorship and
retaliation First Amendment claims, which the parties and lower
courts have analyzed together. Vullo moved to dismiss, arguing that
the alleged conduct did not constitute impermissible coercion and
that, in the alternative, she was entitled to qualified immunity
because she did not violate clearly established law.
The District Court denied Vullo’s motion to
dismiss the NRA’s First-Amendment damages claims. The court held
that the NRA plausibly alleged that “the combination of [Vullo’s
and Cuomo’s] actions . . . could be interpreted as a
veiled threat to regulated industries to disassociate with the NRA
or risk DFS enforcement action.” NRA of Am. v. Cuomo ,
525 F. Supp. 3d 382, 402–403 (NDNY 2021). That threat, the
court said, crossed a First Amendment line. The District Court
concluded that Vullo was not entitled to qualified immunity at the
motion-to-dismiss stage.
The Second Circuit reversed. It concluded that
Vullo’s alleged actions constituted permissible government speech
and legitimate law enforcement, and not unconstitutional coercion.
The Second Circuit determined that the Guidance Letters and
accompanying press release were not unconstitutionally coercive
because they “were written in an even-handed, nonthreatening tone
and employed words intended to persuade rather than intimidate.” 49
F. 4th, at 717. The court found it significant that Vullo “did not
refer to any pending investigations or possible regulatory action”
and alluded only to business-related risks “amid growing public
concern over gun violence.” Ibid. As for Vullo’s meeting
with the Lloyd’s executives, the court admitted that the
allegations presented a “closer call.” Id ., at 718.
Nonetheless, just as with the consent decrees, it found that Vullo
“was merely carrying out her regulatory responsibilities.” Id., at 718–719. The Second Circuit also held that, even if
the complaint stated a First Amendment violation, the law was not
clearly established, and so Vullo was entitled to qualified
immunity.
The NRA filed a petition for a writ of
certiorari, seeking either summary reversal or review of the First
Amendment and qualified immunity holdings. This Court granted
certiorari on only the first question presented whether the
complaint states a First Amendment claim against Vullo. See 601
U. S. ___ (2023).[ 3 ]
II
As discussed below, Vullo was free to
criticize the NRA and pursue the conceded violations of New York
insurance law. She could not wield her power, however, to threaten
enforcement actions against DFS-regulated entities in order to
punish or suppress the NRA’s gun-promotion advocacy. Because the
complaint plausibly alleges that Vullo did just that, the Court
holds that the NRA stated a First Amendment violation.
A
At the heart of the First Amendment’s Free
Speech Clause is the recognition that viewpoint discrimination is
uniquely harmful to a free and democratic society. The Clause
prohibits government entities and actors from “abridging the
freedom of speech.” When government officials are “engaging in
their own expressive conduct,” though, “the Free Speech Clause has
no application.” Pleasant Grove City v. Summum , 555 U.S.
460 , 467 (2009). The government can “ ‘say what it
wishes’ ” and “select the views that it wants to express.” Id. , at 467–468 (quoting Rosenberger v. Rector and
Visitors of Univ. of Va. , 515 U.S.
819 , 833 (1995)). That makes sense; the government could barely
function otherwise. “When a government entity embarks on a course
of action, it necessarily takes a particular viewpoint and rejects
others,” and thus does not need to “maintain viewpoint-neutrality
when its officers and employees speak about that venture.” Matal v. Tam , 582 U.S. 218, 234 (2017).
A government official can share her views freely
and criticize particular beliefs, and she can do so forcefully in
the hopes of persuading others to follow her lead. In doing so, she
can rely on the merits and force of her ideas, the strength of her
convictions, and her ability to inspire others. What she cannot do,
however, is use the power of the State to punish or suppress
disfavored expression. See Rosenberger , 515 U. S., at
830 (explaining that governmental actions seeking to suppress a
speaker’s particular views are presumptively unconstitutional). In
such cases, it is “the application of state power which we are
asked to scrutinize.” NAACP v. Alabama ex rel.
Patterson , 357 U.S.
449 , 463 (1958).
In Bantam Books , this Court explored the
distinction between permissible attempts to persuade and
impermissible attempts to coerce. There, a state commission used
its power to investigate and recommend criminal prosecution to
censor publications that, in its view, were
“ ‘objectionable’ ” because they threatened “youthful
morals.” 372 U. S., at 59–62, 71. The commission sent official
notices to a distributor for blacklisted publications that
highlighted the commission’s “duty to recommend to the Attorney
General” violations of the State’s obscenity laws. Id ., at
62–63, and n. 5. The notices also informed the distributor
that the lists of blacklisted publications “were circulated to
local police departments,” and that the distributor’s cooperation
in removing the publications from the shelves would
“ ‘eliminate the necessity’ ” of any referral for
prosecution. Ibid. A local police officer also conducted
followup visits to ensure compliance. In response, the distributor
took “steps to stop further circulation of copies of the listed
publications” out of fear of facing “ ‘a court action.’ ” Id ., at 63.
The publishers of the blacklisted publications
sued the commission, alleging that this scheme of informal
censorship violated their First Amendment rights. The commission
responded that “it d[id] not regulate or suppress obscenity but
simply exhort[ed] booksellers and advise[d] them of their legal
rights.” Id ., at 66. This Court sided with the publishers,
holding that the commission violated their free-speech rights by
coercing the distributor to stop selling and displaying the listed
publications.
The Court explained that the First Amendment
prohibits government officials from relying on the “threat of
invoking legal sanctions and other means of coercion
. . . to achieve the suppression” of disfavored speech. Id ., at 67. Although the commission lacked the “power to
apply formal legal sanctions,” the distributor “reasonably
understood” the commission to threaten adverse action, and thus the
distributor’s “compliance with the [c]ommission’s directives was
not voluntary.” Id ., at 66–68. To reach this conclusion, the
Court considered things like: the commission’s coordination with
law enforcement and its authority to refer matters for prosecution;
the notices themselves, which were “phrased virtually as orders”
containing “thinly veiled threats to institute criminal
proceedings” if the distributor did not come around; and the
distributor’s reaction to the notices and followup visits. Id., at 68.
Since Bantam Books , the Courts of Appeals
have considered similar factors to determine whether a challenged
communication is reasonably understood to be a coercive threat.
Take the decision below, for example. The Second Circuit purported
to consider: “(1) word choice and tone; (2) the existence of
regulatory authority; (3) whether the speech was perceived as a
threat; and, perhaps most importantly, (4) whether the speech
refers to adverse consequences.” 49 F. 4th, at 715 (citations
omitted).[ 4 ] Other Circuits
have taken similarly fact-intensive approaches, utilizing a
multifactor test or a totality-of-the-circumstances analysis. See, e . g ., Missouri v. Biden , 83 F. 4th 350,
380 (CA5 2023) (“[T]o help distinguish permissible persuasion from
impermissible coercion, we turn to the Second (and Ninth) Circuit’s
four-factor test”); Kennedy v. Warren , 66 F. 4th
1199, 1207 (CA9 2023) (applying the Second Circuit’s “useful
non-exclusive four-factor framework”); Backpage.com, LLC v. Dart , 807 F.3d 229, 230–232 (CA7 2015) (considering the same
factors as part of a totality-of-the-circumstances analysis); R. C. Maxwell Co. v. New Hope , 735 F.2d 85, 88
(CA3 1984) (same). The Courts of Appeals that employ a multifactor
test agree that “[n]o one factor is dispositive.” 49 F. 4th, at
715; accord, Kennedy , 66 F. 4th, at 1210 (explaining that
the absence of direct regulatory authority is not dispositive).
Ultimately, Bantam Books stands for the
principle that a government official cannot do indirectly what she
is barred from doing directly: A government official cannot coerce
a private party to punish or suppress disfavored speech on her
behalf. See, e . g ., 372 U. S., at 67–69; see also Backpage.com , 807 F. 3d, at 231 (holding that the First
Amendment barred a sheriff from “using the power of his office to
threaten legal sanctions against . . . credit-card
companies for facilitating future speech”); Okwedy v. Molinari , 333 F.3d 339 , 344 (CA2 2003) ( per curiam ) (holding
that a religious group stated a First Amendment claim against a
borough president who wrote a letter “contain[ing] an implicit
threat of retaliation” against a billboard company displaying the
group’s disfavored message); cf. Penthouse Int’l, Ltd. v. Meese , 939 F. 2d, 1011, 1016 (CADC 1991) (“[W]hen the
government threatens no sanction—criminal or otherwise—we very much
doubt that the government’s criticism or effort to embarrass the
[intermediary] threatens anyone’s First Amendment rights”).
B
The parties and the Solicitor General, who
filed an amicus brief supporting vacatur, agree that Bantam Books provides the right analytical framework for
claims that the government has coerced a third party to violate the
First Amendment rights of another. They also embrace the lower
courts’ multifactor test as a useful, though nonexhaustive, guide.
Rightly so. Considerations like who said what and how, and what
reaction followed, are just helpful guideposts in answering the
question whether an official seeks to persuade or, instead, to
coerce. Where the parties differ is on the application of the Bantam Books framework. The NRA and the Solicitor General
reject the Second Circuit’s application of the framework, while
Vullo defends it. The Court now agrees with the NRA and the
Solicitor General.
To state a claim that the government violated
the First Amendment through coercion of a third party, a plaintiff
must plausibly allege conduct that, viewed in context, could be
reasonably understood to convey a threat of adverse government
action in order to punish or suppress the plaintiff ’s speech.
See 372 U. S., at 67–68. Accepting the well-pleaded factual
allegations in the complaint as true, the NRA plausibly alleged
that Vullo violated the First Amendment by coercing DFS-regulated
entities into disassociating with the NRA in order to punish or
suppress the NRA’s gun-promotion advocacy.
Consider first Vullo’s authority, which serves
as a backdrop to the NRA’s allegations of coercion. The power that
a government official wields, while certainly not dispositive, is
relevant to the objective inquiry of whether a reasonable person
would perceive the official’s communication as coercive. See id ., at 66–67. Generally speaking, the greater and more
direct the government official’s authority, the less likely a
person will feel free to disregard a directive from the official.
For example, imagine a local affinity group in New York that
receives a strongly worded letter. One would reasonably expect that
organization to react differently if the letter came from, say, the
U. S. Attorney for the Southern District of New York than if
it came from an out-of-state school board.
As DFS superintendent, Vullo had direct
regulatory and enforcement authority over all insurance companies
and financial service institutions doing business in New York. See
N. Y. Fin. Servs. Law Ann. §§202, 301. Just like the
commission in Bantam Books , Vullo could initiate
investigations and refer cases for prosecution. Indeed, she could
do much more than that. Vullo also had the power to notice civil
charges and, as this case shows, enter into consent decrees that
impose significant monetary penalties.
Against this backdrop, consider Vullo’s
communications with the DFS-regulated entities, particularly with
Lloyd’s. According to the NRA, Vullo brought a variety of
insurance-law violations to the Lloyd’s executives’ attention
during a private meeting in February 2018. The violations included
technical infractions that allegedly plagued the affinity insurance
market in New York and that were unrelated to any NRA business.
App. to Pet. for Cert. 199–200, Complaint ¶21; accord, id., at 207–208, ¶¶36–37; id ., at 223, ¶69. Vullo allegedly said
she would be “less interested in pursuing the[se] infractions
. . . so long as Lloyd’s ceased providing insurance to
gun groups, especially the NRA.” Id ., at 199–200, ¶21. Vullo
therefore wanted Lloyd’s to disassociate from all gun groups,
although there was no indication that such groups had unlawful
insurance policies similar to the NRA’s. Vullo also told the
Lloyd’s executives she would “focus” her enforcement actions
“solely” on the syndicates with ties to the NRA, “and ignore other
syndicates writing similar policies.” Id ., at 223, ¶69. The
message was therefore loud and clear: Lloyd’s “could avoid
liability for [unrelated] infractions” if it “aided DFS’s campaign
against gun groups” by terminating its business relationships with
them. Ibid. As alleged, Vullo’s communications with Lloyd’s
can be reasonably understood as a threat or as an inducement.
Either of those can be coercive. As Vullo concedes, the “threat
need not be explicit,” Brief for Respondent 47, and as the
Solicitor General explains, “[t]he Constitution does not
distinguish between ‘comply or I’ll prosecute’ and ‘comply and I’ll
look the other way,’ ” Brief for United States as Amicus
Curiae 18, n. 7. So, whether analyzed as a threat or as an
inducement, the conclusion is the same: Vullo allegedly coerced
Lloyd’s by saying she would ignore unrelated infractions and focus
her enforcement efforts on NRA-related business alone, if Lloyd’s
ceased underwriting NRA policies and disassociated from
gun-promotion groups.
The reaction from Lloyd’s further confirms the
communications’ coercive nature. Cf. Bantam Books , 372
U. S., at 63, 68 (noting that the distributor’s “reaction on
receipt of a notice was to take steps to stop further circulation
of copies of the listed publications”). At the meeting itself,
Lloyd’s “agreed that it would instruct its syndicates to cease
underwriting firearm-related policies and would scale back its
NRA-related business.” App. to Pet. for Cert. 223, Complaint ¶69.
Minutes from a subsequent board of directors’ meeting reveal that
Lloyd’s thought “the DFS investigation had transformed the gun
issue into ‘a regulatory, legal[,] and compliance matter.’ ” 2
App. to Pet. for Cert. 29 (Sealed). That reaction is consistent
with Lloyd’s public announcement that it had directed its
syndicates to “terminate all insurance related to the NRA and not
to provide any insurance to the NRA in the future.” App. to Pet.
for Cert. 224, Complaint ¶72; accord, id ., at 306, ¶20
(consent decree memorializing commitment not to underwrite, or
participate in, NRA-endorsed programs).
Other allegations, viewed in context, reinforce
the NRA’s First Amendment claim. Consider the April 2018 Guidance
Letters and accompanying press release, which Vullo issued on
official letterhead. Cf. Bantam Books , 372 U. S., at
61–63, and n. 5 (discussing notice issued in “official
Commission stationery”). Just like in her meeting with the Lloyd’s
executives, here too Vullo singled out the NRA and other
gun-promotion organizations as the targets of her call to action.
This time, the Guidance Letters reminded DFS-regulated entities of
their obligation to consider their “reputational risks,” and then
tied that obligation to an encouragement for “prompt actio[n] to
manag[e] these risks.” App. to Pet. for Cert. 248, 251. Evocative
of Vullo’s private conversation with the Lloyd’s executives a few
weeks earlier, the press release revealed how to manage the risks
by encouraging DFS-regulated entities to “ ‘discontinu[e]
their arrangements with the NRA,’ ” just like Chubb did when
it stopped underwriting Carry Guard. App. to Pet. for Cert. 244. A
follow-on tweet from Cuomo reaffirmed the message: Businesses in
New York should “ ‘consider their reputations’ ” and
“ ‘revisit any ties they have to the NRA,’ ” which he
called “ ‘an extremist organization.’ ” Id ., at
213, ¶51.
In sum, the complaint, assessed as a whole,
plausibly alleges that Vullo threatened to wield her power against
those refusing to aid her campaign to punish the NRA’s
gun-promotion advocacy. If true, that violates the First
Amendment.
C
In holding otherwise, the Second Circuit found
that: (1) the “Guidance Letters and Press Release are clear
examples of permissible government speech”; and (2) the Lloyd’s
meeting was “legitimate enforcement action” in which Vullo was
“merely carrying out her regulatory responsibilities” by offering
“leniency in the course of negotiating a resolution of the apparent
insurance law violations.” 49 F. 4th, at 717–719. The Second
Circuit could only reach this conclusion by taking the allegations
in isolation and failing to draw reasonable inferences in the NRA’s
favor in violation of this Court’s precedents. Cf. Iqbal ,
556 U. S., at 678–679; Bell Atlantic Corp. v. Twombly , 550 U.S.
544 , 570 (2007).
For example, the Second Circuit failed to
analyze the Guidance Letters and press release against the backdrop
of other allegations in the complaint, including the Lloyd’s
meeting. Moreover, as discussed above, the complaint alleges that
Vullo made a not-so-subtle, sanctions-backed threat to Lloyd’s to
cut all business ties with the NRA and other gun-promotion groups,
although there was no sign that other gun groups also had unlawful
insurance policies. See supra , at 13. It is also relevant
that Vullo made this alleged threat in a meeting where she
presented her “desire to leverage [her] powers to combat the
availability of firearms, including specifically by weakening the
NRA.” App. to Pet. for Cert. 221, Complaint ¶67; id ., at
223, ¶69 (alleging Vullo hoped to enlist DFS-regulated entities in
“aid[ing] DFS’s campaign against gun groups”). Given the obligation
to draw reasonable inferences in the NRA’s favor and consider the
allegations as a whole, the Second Circuit erred in reading the
complaint as involving only individual instances of “permissible
government speech” and the execution of Vullo’s “regulatory
responsibilities.” 49 F. 4th, at 717–719.
For the same reasons, this Court cannot simply
credit Vullo’s assertion that “pursuing conceded violations of the
law,” Brief for Respondent 29, is an “ ‘obvious alternative
explanation’ ” for her actions that defeats the plausibility
of any coercive threat raising First Amendment concerns, id ., at 37, 40, 42 (quoting Iqbal , 556 U. S., at
682). Of course, discovery in this case might show that the
allegations of coercion are false, or that certain actions should
be understood differently in light of newly disclosed evidence. At
this stage, though, the Court must assume the well-pleaded factual
allegations in the complaint are true.[ 5 ]
Moreover, the conceded illegality of the
NRA-endorsed insurance programs does not insulate Vullo from First
Amendment scrutiny under the Bantam Books framework. Indeed,
the commission in that case targeted the distribution and display
of material that, in its view, violated the State’s obscenity laws.
Nothing in that case turned on the distributor’s compliance with
state law. On the contrary, Bantam Books held that the
commission violated the First Amendment by invoking legal sanctions
to suppress disfavored publications, some of which may or may not
contain protected speech ( i . e ., nonobscene material).
See 372 U. S., at 64, 67. Here, too, although Vullo can pursue
violations of state insurance law, she cannot do so in order to
punish or suppress the NRA’s protected expression. So, the
contention that the NRA and the insurers violated New York law does
not excuse Vullo from allegedly employing coercive threats to
stifle gun-promotion advocacy.
Vullo next argues that this case does not
involve unconstitutional coercion because her challenged actions in
fact targeted business practices and relationships, which qualify
as “nonexpressive activity.” Brief for Respondent 32. The argument
is misplaced. That Vullo “regulate[d]” business activities stemming
from the NRA’s “relationships with insurers and banks,” ibid. , does not change the allegations that her actions were
aimed at punishing or suppressing speech. In Bantam Books ,
the commission interfered with the business relationship between
the distributor and the publishers in order to suppress the
publishers’ disfavored speech. 372 U. S., at 66–71. Similarly,
in Backpage.com , a sheriff interfered with a website’s
business relationships with payments-service providers in order to
eliminate the website’s “adult section” (if not the website
itself ). 807 F. 3d, at 230–232, 235–236. In that case,
the sheriff wanted to “suffocat[e]” the website, “depriving the
company of ad revenues by scaring off its payments-service
providers.” Id ., at 231. “The analogy,” the Seventh Circuit
explained, “is to killing a person by cutting off his oxygen supply
rather than by shooting him.” Ibid. So too here. One can
reasonably infer from the complaint that Vullo coerced
DFS-regulated entities to cut their ties with the NRA in order to
stifle the NRA’s gun-promotion advocacy and advance her views on
gun control. See, e . g ., supra , at 12–15; App.
to Pet. for Cert. 221, 230–235, Complaint ¶¶67, 87–105. Vullo knew,
after all, that the NRA relied on insurance and financing “to
disseminate its message.” Id ., at 231, ¶92; see id .,
at 203–204, ¶¶28–29.[ 6 ]
Lastly, Vullo falls back on the argument that a
ruling in the NRA’s favor would interfere with the government’s
ability to function properly. She claims that the NRA’s position,
if accepted, would stifle government speech and hamper legitimate
enforcement efforts. This argument falls flat for the simple reason
that it requires the Court to accept Vullo’s limited reading of the
complaint. The Court does not break new ground in deciding this
case. It only reaffirms the general principle from Bantam
Books that where, as here, the complaint plausibly alleges
coercive threats aimed at punishing or suppressing disfavored
speech, the plaintiff states a First Amendment claim.
III
The NRA’s allegations, if true, highlight the
constitutional concerns with the kind of intermediary strategy that
Vullo purportedly adopted to target the NRA’s advocacy. Such a
strategy allows government officials to “expand their regulatory
jurisdiction to suppress the speech of organizations that they have
no direct control over.” Brief for First Amendment Scholars as Amici Curiae Supporting Petitioner 8. It also allows
government officials to be more effective in their
speech-suppression efforts “[b]ecause intermediaries will often be
less invested in the speaker’s message and thus less likely to risk
the regulator’s ire.” Ibid. The allegations here bear this
out. Although “the NRA was not even the directly regulated party,”
Brief for Respondent 32, Vullo allegedly used the power of her
office to target gun promotion by going after the NRA’s business
partners. Insurers in turn followed Vullo’s lead, fearing
regulatory hostility.
Nothing in this case gives advocacy groups like
the NRA a “right to absolute immunity from [government]
investigation,” or a “right to disregard [state or federal] laws.” Patterson , 357 U. S., at 463. Similarly, nothing here
prevents government officials from forcefully condemning views with
which they disagree. For those permissible actions, the
Constitution “relies first and foremost on the ballot box, not on
rules against viewpoint discrimination, to check the government
when it speaks.” Shurtleff v. Boston , 596 U.S. 243,
252 (2022). Yet where, as here, a government official makes
coercive threats in a private meeting behind closed doors, the
“ballot box” is an especially poor check on that official’s
authority. Ultimately, the critical takeaway is that the First
Amendment prohibits government officials from wielding their power
selectively to punish or suppress speech, directly or (as alleged
here) through private intermediaries.
* * *
For the reasons discussed above, the Court
holds that the NRA plausibly alleged that Vullo violated the First
Amendment by coercing DFS-regulated entities to terminate their
business relationships with the NRA in order to punish or suppress
the NRA’s advocacy.
The judgment of the U. S. Court of Appeals
for the Second Circuit is vacated, and the case remanded for
further proceedings consistent with this opinion.[ 7 ]
It is so ordered. Notes 1 According to the
complaint, other affinity organizations offered similar insurance
policies, including the New York State Bar Association, the New
York City Bar, and the New York State Psychological Association,
among others. See App. to Pet. for Cert. 207–208, Complaint
¶36. 2 The financial-regulatory
term “reputational risk” is “ ‘the risk to current or
projected financial condition and resilience arising from negative
public opinion,’ which ‘may impair a bank’s competitiveness by
affecting its ability to establish new relationships or services or
continue servicing existing relationships.’ ” Brief for United
States as Amicus Curiae 27–28, and n. 10 (quoting
Office of the Comptroller of the Currency, Comptroller’s Handbook,
Examination Process, Bank Supervision Process 28 (Sept. 2019)). DFS
monitors the reputational risk of regulated institutions because of
its potential effect on market stability. See Brief for Respondent
6. 3 Vullo argues that the
Court must dismiss the case as improvidently granted because the
Court deprived itself of jurisdiction by limiting its review to the
First Amendment question and declining to review the Second
Circuit’s alternative holding that Vullo is entitled to qualified
immunity. See Brief for Respondent 21–24. Not so. In this case,
“[a]n order limiting the grant of certiorari does not operate as a
jurisdictional bar.” Piper Aircraft Co. v. Reyno , 454 U.S.
235 , 247, n. 12 (1981). Because the Second Circuit is free
to revisit the qualified immunity question in light of this Court’s
opinion, the NRA still could obtain “ ‘effectual
relief ’ ” on remand. Chafin v. Chafin , 568 U.S.
165 , 172 (2013). In such circumstances, it cannot be said that
the resolution of the First Amendment question is merely
advisory. 4 The NRA posits a
three-factor test that looks to: (1) the actor’s authority; (2) the
content and purpose of the actor’s communications; and (3) the
reactions of the recipient. Brief for Petitioner 26. The NRA
concedes, however, that its test is the same as the Second
Circuit’s, as it considers the fourth factor in the Second
Circuit’s test of “ ‘whether the speech refers to adverse
consequences’ ” to be an “aspect of the inquiry into the
content and purpose of the communication.” Id ., at 27,
n. 8. 5 Vullo also argues that
she is entitled to absolute prosecutorial immunity for her
enforcement actions. See Brief for Respondent 25–28. Putting aside
whether a financial regulator like Vullo is entitled to such
immunity in the administrative context, because Vullo did not raise
this defense below with respect to the First Amendment claim (or
even with respect to allegations unrelated to the consent decrees),
the Court declines to consider that argument here in the first
instance. 6 Vullo’s boss, Governor
Cuomo, also urged businesses to disassociate with the NRA to put
the organization “into financial jeopardy” and “shut them down.”
App. 21 (Aug. 3, 2018, tweet). 7 On remand, the Second
Circuit is free to reconsider whether Vullo is entitled to
qualified immunity. SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES
_________________
No. 22–842
_________________
NATIONAL RIFLE ASSOCIATION OF AMERICA,
PETITIONER v. MARIA T. VULLO
on writ of certiorari to the united states
court of appeals for the second circuit
[May 30, 2024]
Justice Gorsuch, concurring.
I write separately to explain my understanding
of the Court’s opinion, which I join in full. Today we reaffirm a
well-settled principle: “A government official cannot coerce a
private party to punish or suppress disfavored speech on her
behalf.” Ante, at 11. As the Court mentions, many lower
courts have taken to analyzing this kind of coercion claim under a
four-pronged “multifactor test.” Ibid . These tests, the
Court explains, might serve “as a useful, though nonexhaustive,
guide.” Ante, at 12. But sometimes they might not. Cf. Axon Enterprise, Inc. v. FTC , 598 U.S. 175, 205–207
(2023) (Gorsuch, J., concurring in judgment). Indeed, the Second
Circuit’s decision to break up its analysis into discrete parts and
“tak[e] the [complaint’s] allegations in isolation” appears only to
have contributed to its mistaken conclusion that the National Rifle
Association failed to state a claim. Ante, at 15. Lower
courts would therefore do well to heed this Court’s directive:
Whatever value these “guideposts” serve, they remain “just” that
and nothing more. Ante, at 12. “Ultimately, the critical”
question is whether the plaintiff has “plausibly allege[d] conduct
that, viewed in context, could be reasonably understood to convey a
threat of adverse government action in order to punish or suppress
the plaintiff ’s speech.” Ante, at 12, 19. SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES
_________________
No. 22–842
_________________
NATIONAL RIFLE ASSOCIATION OF AMERICA,
PETITIONER v. MARIA T. VULLO
on writ of certiorari to the united states
court of appeals for the second circuit
[May 30, 2024]
Justice Jackson, concurring.
Applying our decision in Bantam Books,
Inc. v. Sullivan , 372 U.S.
58 (1963), the Court today explains that a “government official
cannot coerce a private party to punish or suppress disfavored
speech on her behalf.” Ante, at 11. I agree. I write
separately to stress the important distinction between government
coercion, on the one hand, and a violation of the First Amendment,
on the other.
I
Coercion of a third party can be the means by
which the government violates the First Amendment rights of
another. But the fact of coercion, without more, does not state a
First Amendment claim. Rather, in addition to finding that the
government has crossed a line from persuasion to coercion, courts
must assess how that coercion actually violates a speaker’s First
Amendment rights.
Our decision in Bantam Books provides one
example of how government coercion of a third party can indirectly
bring about a First Amendment violation. As the majority explains, ante, at 9–10, Bantam Books held that a Rhode Island
commission’s efforts to coerce intermediary book distributors into
pulling certain publications from circulation violated the First
Amendment rights of the books’ publishers, 372 U. S., at
61–62, 66–67. Even though the state commission had not itself
“seized or banned” any books, “the threat of invoking legal
sanctions and other means of coercion, persuasion, and
intimidation” against the distributors “directly and designedly
stopped the circulation of publications in many parts of Rhode
Island.” Id ., at 67–68. Essentially, the State’s threats to
third parties—the distributors—erected through private hands an
“effective state regulation . . . of obscenity.” Id ., at 69. And the government could not escape
responsibility for the distributors’ actions merely because the
commission did not itself seize any books. See id ., at
66–67.
Notably, however, the government’s coercion of
the distributors into doing its bidding was not—in and of
itself—what offended the First Amendment. Rather, by threatening
those third-party conduits of speech, the state commission had
effectively “subject[ed] the distribution of publications to a
system of prior administrative restraints” lacking the requisite
constitutional safeguards. Id ., at 70. Put another way, by
exerting pressure on a third party, the State had constructed a
“system of informal censorship.” Id ., at 71.
The lesson of Bantam Books is that “a
government official cannot do indirectly what she is barred from
doing directly.” Ante, at 11. That case does not hold
that government coercion alone violates the First Amendment. And
recognizing the distinction between government coercion and a First
Amendment violation is important because our democracy can function
only if the government can effectively enforce the rules embodied
in legislation; by its nature, such enforcement often involves
coercion in the form of legal sanctions. The existence of an
allegation of government coercion of a third party thus merely
invites, rather than answers, the question whether that coercion
indirectly worked a violation of the plaintiff’s First Amendment
rights.
II
Whether and how government coercion of a third
party might violate another party’s First Amendment rights will
depend on the facts of the case. Indeed, under our precedents,
determining whether government action violates the First Amendment
requires application of different doctrines that vary depending on
the circumstances. Different circumstances—who is being coerced to
do what, and why—may implicate different First Amendment
inquiries.
In Bantam Books and many cases applying
it, the coercion and First Amendment inquiries practically merge.
This is because those cases tend to follow a similar fact pattern:
The plaintiff claims that the government coerced a distributor,
purveyor, or conduit of expression—like a billboard company,
television station, or book retailer—to shut down the speech of
another party that relies on that distributor, purveyor, or conduit
to spread its message.[ 1 ]*
Coercing an entity in the business of disseminating speech to stop
disseminating someone else’s speech obviously implicates the First
Amendment, insofar as it may result in censorship similar to the
prior restraint identified in Bantam Books .
But, in my view, that censorship theory is an
awkward fit with the facts of this case. According to the
complaint, Vullo coerced various regulated entities to cut business
ties with the National Rifle Association (NRA). See ante, at
3–5. The NRA does not contend that its (concededly unlawful)
insurance products offered through those business relationships
were themselves “speech,” akin to a billboard, a television ad, or
a book. Nor does the complaint allege that Vullo pressured the
printer of American Rifleman (a longstanding NRA periodical) to
stop printing the magazine, or coerced a convention center into
canceling the NRA’s annual meeting. See VDARE Foundation v. Colorado Springs , 11 F. 4th 1151, 1157 (CA10 2021). In
other words, the effect of Vullo’s alleged coercion of regulated
entities on the NRA’s speech is significantly more attenuated here
than in Bantam Books or most decisions applying it. It is,
for instance, far from obvious that Vullo’s conduct toward
regulated entities established “a system of prior administrative
restraints” against the NRA’s expression. Bantam Books , 372
U. S., at 70.
Of course, as the majority correctly observes,
none of that means that Vullo may target with impunity the NRA’s
“ ‘nonexpressive’ ” activity if she is doing so to punish
the NRA for its expression. See ante, at 17. But it does
suggest that our First Amendment retaliation cases might provide a
better framework for analyzing these kinds of
allegations— i . e ., coercion claims that are not
directly related to the publication or distribution of speech. And,
fortunately for the NRA, the complaint in this case alleges both
censorship and retaliation theories for how Vullo violated the
First Amendment—theories that, in my opinion, deserve separate
analyses.
“ ‘[A]s a general matter,’ the First
Amendment prohibits government officials from subjecting
individuals to ‘retaliatory actions’ after the fact for having
engaged in protected speech.” Houston Community College
System v. Wilson , 595 U.S. 468, 474 (2022) (quoting Nieves v. Bartlett , 587 U.S. 391, 398 (2019)). “[A]
plaintiff pursuing a First Amendment retaliation claim must show,
among other things, that the government took an ‘adverse action’ in
response to his speech that ‘would not have been taken absent the
retaliatory motive.’ ” Wilson , 595 U. S., at 477
(quoting Nieves , 587 U. S., at 399). Although our
analysis has varied by context, see Lozman v. Riviera
Beach , 585 U.S. 87, 96–99 (2018), we have generally required
plaintiffs claiming First Amendment retaliation to “establish a
‘causal connection’ between the government defendant’s ‘retaliatory
animus’ and the plaintiff’s ‘subsequent injury,’ ” Nieves , 587 U. S., at 398 (quoting Hartman v. Moore , 547 U.S.
250 , 259 (2006)).
Requiring that causal connection to a
retaliatory motive is important, because “[s]ome official actions
adverse to . . . a speaker might well be unexceptionable
if taken on other grounds.” Id. , at 256. In this case, for
example, analyzing causation matters because much of Vullo’s
alleged conduct, if not done for retaliatory reasons, might
otherwise be legitimate enforcement of New York’s insurance
regulations.
How a retaliation analysis should proceed in
this case was not addressed below, so the Court rightly leaves that
question unanswered today. But, importantly, any such analysis
requires more than asking simply whether the government’s actions
crossed the threshold from permissible persuasion to impermissible
coercion. The NRA concedes that, at the very least, our
burden-shifting framework from Mt. Healthy City Bd. of Ed. v. Doyle , 429 U.S.
274 (1977), likely applies. See Reply Brief 16–17. Should that
test govern, the NRA would have to plausibly allege that a
retaliatory motive was a “ ‘substantial’ ” or
“ ‘motivating factor’ ” in Vullo’s targeting of the
regulated entities doing business with the NRA. Mt. Healthy ,
429 U. S., at 287. Vullo, in turn, could rebut that allegation
by showing that she would have taken the same action “even in the
absence of the [NRA’s] protected conduct.” Ibid. ; see Lozman , 585 U. S., at 96 (“[E]ven if retaliation might
have been a substantial motive for the board’s action, still there
was no liability unless the alleged constitutional violation was a
but-for cause of the employment termination”).
* * *
The NRA’s complaint advances both censorship
and retaliation claims, yet the lower courts in this case lumped
these claims together and ultimately focused almost exclusively on
whether Vullo’s conduct was coercive. See ante, at 6–7.
Consequently, the strength of the NRA’s claim under the Mt.
Healthy framework has received little attention thus far. On
remand, the parties and lower courts should consider the censorship
and retaliation theories independently, mindful of the distinction
between government coercion and the ways in which such coercion
might (or might not) have violated the NRA’s constitutional rights.
That analysis can and should likewise consider which First
Amendment framework best captures the NRA’s allegations in this
case. See, e . g ., VDARE , 11 F. 4th, at
1159–1175 (separately analyzing censorship and retaliation
claims). Notes 1 *See, e . g ., Okwedy v. Molinari , 333 F.3d 339 , 340, 342–344 (CA2 2003) ( per curiam )
(billboard company); R. C. Maxwell Co. v. New
Hope , 735 F.2d 85, 85–88 (CA3 1984) (same); American Family
Assn., Inc. v. City and County of San Francisco , 277 F.3d 1114 , 1119–1120 (CA9 2002) (television stations); Kennedy v. Warren , 66 F. 4th 1199, 1204–1205 (CA9
2023) (online book retailer); Penthouse Int’l, Ltd. v. Meese , 939 F.2d 1011, 1013–1016 (CADC 1991) (convenience
stores carrying pornographic magazines); Hammerhead Enterprises,
Inc. v. Brezenoff , 707 F.2d 33, 34–38 (CA2 1983)
(department stores carrying satirical board game); VDARE
Foundation v. Colorado Springs , 11 F. 4th 1151,
1156–1157 (CA10 2021) (resort hosting advocacy group
conference). | Here is a summary of the National Rifle Association of America v. Maria T. Vullo case:
The Supreme Court ruled that government officials cannot coerce private parties to suppress or punish views they disagree with, reaffirming a previous decision from six decades ago. The Court sent the case back to lower courts to determine if the NRA's allegations of retaliation by Maria Vullo, the superintendent of the New York Department of Financial Services, were true. The NRA claimed Vullo threatened enforcement actions against insurers with ties to the NRA to stifle its pro-gun advocacy. The Court emphasized the distinction between government coercion and retaliation, stating that the lower courts should analyze the NRA's censorship and retaliation claims independently. |
Equal Protection | Gong Lum v. Rice | https://supreme.justia.com/cases/federal/us/275/78/ | U.S. Supreme Court Gong Lum v. Rice, 275 U.S.
78 (1927) Gong Lum v. Rice No. 29 Submitted October 12,
1927 Decided November 21,
1927 275 U.S.
78 ERROR TO THE SUPREME
COURT OF THE STATE OF
MISSISSIPPI Syllabus A child of Chinese blood, born in and a citizen of the United
States, is not denied the equal protection of the law by being
classed by the state among the colored races who are assigned to
public schools separate from those provided for the whites when
equal facilities for education are afforded to both classes. P. 275 U. S.
85 .
139 Miss. 760 affirmed.
Error to a judgment of the Supreme Court of Mississippi
reversing a judgment awarding the writ of mandamus. The writ was
applied for in the interest of Martha Lum, a child of Chinese
blood, born in the United States, and was directed to the trustees
of a high school district and the state Superintendent of
Education, commanding them to cease discriminating against her and
to admit her to the privileges of the high school specified, which
was assigned to white children exclusively. Page 275 U. S. 79 MR. CHIEF JUSTICE TAFT delivered the opinion of the Court.
This was a petition for mandamus filed in the state circuit
court of Mississippi for the First judicial district of Bolivar
County.
Gong Lum is a resident of Mississippi, resides in the Rosedale
Consolidated High School District, and is the father of Martha Lum.
He is engaged in the mercantile business. Neither he nor she was
connected with the consular service, or any other service, of the
government of China, or any other government at the time of her
birth. Page 275 U. S. 80 She was nine years old when the petition was filed, having been
born January 21, 1915, and she sued by her next friend, Chew How,
who is a native-born citizen of the United States and the State of
Mississippi. The petition alleged that she was of good moral
character, between the ages of 5 and 21 years, and that, as she was
such a citizen and an educable child, it became her father's duty
under the law to send her to school; that she desired to attend the
Rosedale Consolidated High School; that, at the opening of the
school, she appeared as a pupil, but at the noon recess she was
notified by the superintendent that she would not be allowed to
return to the school; that an order had been issued by the board of
trustees, who are made defendants, excluding her from attending the
school solely on the ground that she was of Chinese descent, and
not a member of the white or Caucasian race, and that their order
had been made in pursuance to instructions from the State
Superintendent of Education of Mississippi, who is also made a
defendant.
The petitioners further show that there is no school maintained
in the district for the education of children of Chinese descent,
and none established in Bolivar County where she could attend.
The Constitution of Mississippi requires that there shall be a
county common school fund, made up of poll taxes from the various
counties, to be retained in the counties where the same is
collected, and a state common school fund to be taken from the
general fund in the state treasury, which together shall be
sufficient to maintain a common school for a term of four months in
each scholastic year, but that any county or separate school
district may levy an additional tax to maintain schools for a
longer time than a term of four months, and that the said common
school fund shall be distributed among the several counties and
separate school districts in proportion to the number of educable
children in each, to be collected Page 275 U. S. 81 from the data in the office of the State Superintendent of
Education in the manner prescribed by law; that the legislature
encourage by all suitable means the promotion of intellectual,
scientific, moral, and agricultural improvement by the
establishment of a uniform system of free public schools by
taxation or otherwise, for all children between the ages of 5 and
21 years, and. as soon as practicable, establish schools of higher
grade.
The petition alleged that, in obedience to this mandate of the
constitution, the legislature has provided for the establishment
and for the payment of the expenses of the Rosedale Consolidated
High School, and that the plaintiff, Gong Lum, the petitioner's
father, is a taxpayer and helps to support and maintain the school;
that Martha Lum is an educable child, is entitled to attend the
school as a pupil, and that this is the only school conducted in
the district available for her as a pupil; that the right to attend
it is a valuable right; that she is not a member of the colored
race, nor is she of mixed blood, but that she is pure Chinese; that
she is, by the action of the board of trustees and the state
superintendent, discriminated against directly, and denied her
right to be a member of the Rosedale school; that the school
authorities have no discretion under the law as to her admission as
a pupil in the school, but that they continue without authority of
law to deny her the right to attend it as a pupil. For these
reasons, the writ of mandamus is prayed for against the defendants,
commanding them and each of them to desist from discriminating
against her on account of her race or ancestry, and to give her the
same rights and privileges that other educable children between the
ages of 5 and 21 are granted in the Rosedale Consolidated High
School.
The petition was demurred to by the defendants on the ground,
among others, that the bill showed on its face that plaintiff is a
member of the Mongolian or yellow race, and Page 275 U. S. 82 therefore not entitled to attend the schools provided by law in
the State of Mississippi for children of the white or Caucasian
race.
The trial court overruled the demurrer and ordered that a writ
of mandamus issue to the defendants as prayed in the petition.
The defendants then appealed to the Supreme Court of
Mississippi, which heard the case. Rice v. Gong Lum, 139
Miss. 760. In its opinion, it directed its attention to the proper
construction of § 207 of the state constitution of 1890, which
provides: "Separate schools shall be maintained for children of the
white and colored races."
The court held that this provision of the constitution divided
the educable children into those of the pure white or Caucasian
race, on the one hand, and the brown, yellow, and black races, on
the other, and therefore that Martha Lum, of the Mongolian or
yellow race, could not insist on being classed with the whites
under this constitutional division. The court said:
"The legislature is not compelled to provide separate schools
for each of the colored races, and unless and until it does provide
such schools, and provide for segregation of the other races, such
races are entitled to have the benefit of the colored public
schools. Under our statutes, a colored public school exists in
every county and in some convenient district, in which every
colored child is entitled to obtain an education. These schools are
within the reach of all the children of the state, and the
plaintiff does not show by her petition that she applied for
admission to such schools. On the contrary, the petitioner takes
the position that, because there are no separate public schools for
Mongolians, she is entitled to enter the white public schools in
preference to the colored public schools. A consolidated school in
this state is simply a common school conducted as other common
schools are conducted; Page 275 U. S. 83 the only distinction being that two or more school districts
have been consolidated into one school. Such consolidation is
entirely discretionary with the county school board, having
reference to the condition existing in the particular territory.
Where a school district has an unusual amount of territory, with an
unusual valuation of property therein, it may levy additional
taxes. But the other common schools under similar statutes have the
same power."
"If the plaintiff desires, she may attend the colored public
schools of her district, or, if she does not so desire, she may go
to a private school. The compulsory school law of this state does
not require the attendance at a public school, and a parent under
the decisions of the Supreme Court of the United States has a right
to educate his child in a private school if he so desires. But
plaintiff is not entitled to attend a white public school."
As we have seen, the plaintiffs aver that the Rosedale
Consolidated High School is the only school conducted in that
district available for Martha Lum as a pupil. They also aver that
there is no school maintained in the district of Bolivar County for
the education of Chinese children, and none in the county. How are
these averments to be reconciled with the statement of the state
supreme court that colored schools are maintained in every county
by virtue of the constitution? This seems to be explained, in the
language of the state supreme court, as follows:
"By statute it is provided that all the territory of each county
of the state shall be divided into school districts separately for
the white and colored races -- that is to say, the whole territory
is to be divided into white school districts, and then a new
division of the county for colored school districts. In other
words, the statutory scheme is to make the districts, outside of
the separate school districts, districts for the particular race,
white or colored, so that the territorial limits of the school
districts need Page 275 U. S. 84 not be the same, but the territory embraced in a school district
for the colored race may not be the same territory embraced in the
school district for the white race, and vice versa, which system of
creating the common school districts for the two races, white and
colored, do not require schools for each race as such to be
maintained in each district, but each child, no matter from what
territory, is assigned to some school district, the school
buildings being separately located and separately controlled, but
each having the same curriculum, and each having the same number of
months of school term, if the attendance is maintained for the said
statutory period, which school district of the common or public
schools has certain privileges, among which is to maintain a public
school by local taxation for a longer period of time than the said
term of four months under named conditions which apply alike to the
common schools for the white and colored races."
We must assume, then, that there are school districts for
colored children in Bolivar County, but that no colored school is
within the limits of the Rosedale Consolidated High School
District. This is not inconsistent with there being at a place
outside of that district and in a different district, a colored
school which the plaintiff Martha Lum may conveniently attend. If
so, she is not denied, under the existing school system, the right
to attend and enjoy the privileges of a common school education in
a colored school. If it were otherwise, the petition should have
contained an allegation showing it. Had the petition alleged
specifically that there was no colored school in Martha Lum's
neighborhood to which she could conveniently go, a different
question would have been presented, and this without regard to the
state supreme court's construction of the state constitution as
limiting the white schools provided for the education of children
of the white or Caucasian race. But we do not find the petition to
present such a situation. Page 275 U. S. 85 The case then reduces itself to the question whether a state can
be said to afford to a child of Chinese ancestry, born in this
country and a citizen of the United States, the equal protection of
the laws by giving her the opportunity for a common school
education in a school which receives only colored children of the
brown, yellow, or black races.
The right and power of the state to regulate the method of
providing for the education of its youth at public expense is
clear. In Cumming v. Richmond County Board of Education, 175 U. S. 528 , 175 U. S. 545 ,
persons of color sued the board of education to enjoin it from
maintaining a high school for white children without providing a
similar school for colored children, which had existed and had been
discontinued. Mr. Justice Harlan, in delivering the opinion of the
Court, said:
"Under the circumstances disclosed, we cannot say that this
action of the state court was, within the meaning of the Fourteenth
Amendment, a denial by the state to the plaintiffs and to those
associated with them of the equal protection of the laws, or of any
privileges belonging to them as citizens of the United States. We
may add that, while all admit that the benefits and burdens of
public taxation must be shared by citizens without discrimination
against any class on account of their race, the education of the
people in schools maintained by state taxation is a matter
belonging to the respective states, and any interference on the
part of federal authority with the management of such schools
cannot be justified, except in the case of a clear and unmistakable
disregard of rights secured by the supreme law of the land."
The question here is whether a Chinese citizen of the United
States is denied equal protection of the laws when he is classed
among the colored races and furnished facilities for education
equal to that offered to all, whether white, brown, yellow, or
black. Were this a new question, Page 275 U. S. 86 it would call for very full argument and consideration; but we
think that it is the same question which has been many times
decided to be within the constitutional power of the state
legislature to settle, without intervention of the federal courts
under the federal Constitution. Roberts v. City of Boston, 5 Cush. 198, 206, 208, 209; State ex rel. Garnes v.
McCann, 21 Ohio St.198, 210; People ex rel. King v.
Gallagher, 93 N.Y. 438; People ex rel. Cisco v. School
Board, 161 N.Y. 598; Ward v. Flood, 48 Cal. 36; Wysinger v. Crookshank, 82 Cal. 588, 590; Reynolds v.
Board of Education, 66 Kan. 672; McMillan v. School
Committee, 107 N.C. 609; Cory v. Carter, 48 Ind. 327; Lehew v. Brummell, 103 Mo. 546; Dameron v.
Bayless, 14 Ariz. 180; State ex rel. Stoutmeyer v.
Duffy, 7 Nev. 342, 348, 355; Bertonneau v. Board, 3
Woods, 177, 3 Fed.Cas. 294, Case No. 1,361; United States v.
Buntin, 10 F. 730, 735; Wong Him v. Callahan, 119 F.
381.
In Plessy v. Ferguson, 163 U.
S. 537 , 163 U. S.
544 -545, in upholding the validity under the Fourteenth
Amendment of a statute of Louisiana requiring the separation of the
white and colored races in railway coaches, a more difficult
question than this, this Court, speaking of permitted race
separation, said:
"The most common instance of this is connected with the
establishment of separate schools for white and colored children,
which has been held to be a valid exercise of the legislative power
even by courts of states where the political rights of the colored
race have been longest and most earnestly enforced."
The case of Roberts v. City of Boston, supra, in which
Chief Justice Shaw, of the Supreme Judicial Court of Massachusetts,
announced the opinion of that court upholding the separation of
colored and white schools under Page 275 U. S. 87 a state constitutional injunction of equal protection, the same
as the Fourteenth Amendment, was then referred to, and this Court
continued:
"Similar laws have been enacted by Congress under its general
power of legislation over the District of Columbia, Rev.Stat.D.C.
§§ 281, 282, 283, 310, 319, as well as by the legislatures of many
of the states, and have been generally, if not uniformly, sustained
by the courts"
-- citing many of the cases above named.
Most of the cases cited arose, it is true, over the
establishment of separate schools as between white pupils and black
pupils, but we cannot think that the question is any different, or
that any different result can be reached, assuming the cases above
cited to be rightly decided, where the issue is as between white
pupils and the pupils of the yellow races. The decision is within
the discretion of the state in regulating its public schools, and
does not conflict with the Fourteenth Amendment.
The judgment of the Supreme Court of Mississippi is Affirmed. | In Gong Lum v. Rice, the U.S. Supreme Court ruled that a child of Chinese descent, born in the United States, was not denied equal protection under the law when they were classified as "colored" and assigned to a public school for non-whites, as long as equal educational facilities were provided for both white and non-white students. The Court upheld the power of states to separate students by race in public schools, as long as equal facilities were offered to both races. This decision reflected the Court's stance on racial segregation at the time, which allowed for separate but equal facilities for different races, as previously established in Plessy v. Ferguson. |
Equal Protection | Civil Rights Cases | https://supreme.justia.com/cases/federal/us/109/3/ | U.S. Supreme Court Civil Rights Cases, 109 U.S. 3 (1883) Civil Rights Cases Submitted October Term,
1882 Decided October 16th,
1888 109 U.S.
3 ON CERTIFICATE OF DIVISION FROM THE
CIRCUIT COURT OF THE UNITED STATES FOR THE
DISTRICT OF KANSAS Syllabus 1. The 1st and 2d sections of the Civil Rights Act passed March
1st, 1876, are unconstitutional enactments as applied to the
several States, not being authorized either by the XIIIth or XIVth
Amendments of the Constitution.
2. The XIVth Amendment is prohibitory upon the States only, and
the legislation authorized to be adopted by Congress for enforcing
it is not direct legislation on the matters respecting which the
States are prohibited from making or enforcing certain laws, or
doing certain acts, but is corrective legislation such as may be
necessary or proper for counteracting and redressing the effect of
such laws or acts. Page 109 U. S. 4 The XIIIth Amendment relates only to slavery and involuntary
servitude (which it abolishes), and, although, by its reflex
action, it establishes universal freedom in the United States, and
Congress may probably pass laws directly enforcing its provisions,
yet such legislative power extends only to the subject of slavery
and its incidents, and the denial of equal accommodations in inns,
public conveyances, and places of public amusement (which is
forbidden by the sections in question), imposes no badge of slavery
or involuntary servitude upon the party but at most, infringes
rights which are protected from State aggression by the XIVth
Amendment.
4. Whether the accommodations and privileges sought to be
protected by the 1st and 2d sections of the Civil Rights Act are or
are not rights constitutionally demandable, and if they are, in
what form they are to be protected, is not now decided.
5. Nor is it decided whether the law, as it stands, is operative
in the Territories and District of Columbia, the decision only
relating to its validity as applied to the States.
6. Nor is it decided whether Congress, under the commercial
power, may or may not pass a law securing to all persons equal
accommodations on lines of public conveyance between two or more
States.
These cases were all founded on the first and second sections of
the Act of Congress known as the Civil Rights Act, passed March
1st, 1875, entitled "An Act to protect all citizens in their civil
and legal rights." 18 Stat. 335. Two of the cases, those against
Stanley and Nichols, were indictments for denying to persons of
color the accommodations and privileges of an inn or hotel; two of
them, those against Ryan and Singleton, were, one on information,
the other an indictment, for denying to individuals the privileges
and accommodations of a theatre, the information against Ryan being
for refusing a colored person a seat in the dress circle of
Maguire's theatre in San Francisco, and the indictment against
Singleton was for denying to another person, whose color was not
stated, the full enjoyment of the accommodations of the theatre
known as the Grand Opera House in New York,
"said denial not being made for any reasons by law applicable to
citizens of every race and color, and regardless of any previous
condition of servitude."
The case of Robinson and wife against the Memphis &
Charleston R.R. Company was an action brought in the Circuit Court
of the United States for the Western District of Tennessee to
recover the penalty of five hundred dollars Page 109 U. S. 5 given by the second section of the act, and the gravamen was the
refusal by the conductor of the railroad company to allow the wife
to ride in the ladies' car, for the reason, as stated in one of the
counts, that she was a person of African descent. The jury rendered
a verdict for the defendants in this case upon the merits, under a
charge of the court to which a bill of exceptions was taken by the
plaintiffs. The case was tried on the assumption by both parties of
the validity of the act of Congress, and the principal point made
by the exceptions was that the judge allowed evidence to go to the
jury tending to show that the conductor had reason to suspect that
the plaintiff, the wife, was an improper person because she was in
company with a young man whom he supposed to be a white man, and,
on that account, inferred that there was some improper connection
between them, and the judge charged the jury, in substance, that,
if this was the conductor's bona fide reason for excluding
the woman from the car, they might take it into consideration on
the question of the liability of the company. The case was brought
here by writ of error at the suit of the plaintiffs. The cases of
Stanley, Nichols, and Singleton came up on certificates of division
of opinion between the judges below as to the constitutionality of
the first and second sections of the act referred to, and the case
of Ryan on a writ of error to the judgment of the Circuit Court for
the District of California sustaining a demurrer to the
information.
The Stanley, Ryan, Nichols, and Singleton cases were submitted
together by the solicitor general at the last term of court, on the
7th day of November, 1882. There were no appearances, and no briefs
filed for the defendants.
The Robinson case was submitted on the briefs at the last term,
on the 9th day of arch, 1883. Page 109 U. S. 8 MR. JUSTICE BRADLEY delivered the opinion of the court. After
stating the facts in the above language, he continued:
It is obvious that the primary and important question in all Page 109 U. S. 9 the cases is the constitutionality of the law, for if the law is
unconstitutional, none of the prosecutions can stand.
The sections of the law referred to provide as follows:
"SEC. 1. That all persons within the jurisdiction of the United
States shall be entitled to the full and equal enjoyment of the
accommodations, advantages, facilities, and privileges of inns,
public conveyances on land or water, theatres, and other places of
public amusement, subject only to the conditions and limitations
established by law and applicable alike to citizens of every race
and color, regardless of any previous condition of servitude."
"SEC. 2. That any person who shall violate the foregoing section
by denying to any citizen, except for reasons by law applicable to
citizens of every race and color, and regardless of any previous
condition of servitude, the full enjoyment of any of the
accommodations, advantages, facilities, or privileges in said
section enumerated, or by aiding or inciting such denial, shall for
every such offence, forfeit and pay the sum of five hundred dollars
to the person aggrieved thereby, to be recovered in an action of
debt, with full costs, and shall also, for every such offence, be
deemed guilty of a misdemeanor, and, upon conviction thereof, shall
be fined not less than five hundred nor more than one thousand
dollars, or shall be imprisoned not less than thirty days nor more
than one year, Provided, That all persons may elect to sue
for the penalty aforesaid, or to proceed under their rights at
common law and by State statutes, and having so elected to proceed
in the one mode or the other, their right to proceed in the other
jurisdiction shall be barred. But this provision shall not apply to
criminal proceedings, either under this act or the criminal law of
any State; and provided further, that a judgment for the
penalty in favor of the party aggrieved, or a judgment upon an
indictment, shall be a bar to either prosecution respectively."
Are these sections constitutional? The first section, which is
the principal one, cannot be fairly understood without attending to
the last clause, which qualifies the preceding part.
The essence of the law is not to declare broadly that all
persons shall be entitled to the full and equal enjoyment of the
accommodations, advantages, facilities, and privileges of inns, Page 109 U. S. 10 public conveyances, and theatres, but that such enjoyment shall
not be subject to any conditions applicable only to citizens of a
particular race or color, or who had been in a previous condition
of servitude. In other words, it is the purpose of the law to
declare that, in the enjoyment of the accommodations and privileges
of inns, public conveyances, theatres, and other places of public
amusement, no distinction shall be made between citizens of
different race or color or between those who have, and those who
have not, been slaves. Its effect is to declare that, in all inns,
public conveyances, and places of amusement, colored citizens,
whether formerly slaves or not, and citizens of other races, shall
have the same accommodations and privileges in all inns, public
conveyances, and places of amusement as are enjoyed by white
citizens, and vice versa. The second section makes it a penal
offence in any person to deny to any citizen of any race or color,
regardless of previous servitude, any of the accommodations or
privileges mentioned in the first section.
Has Congress constitutional power to make such a law? Of course,
no one will contend that the power to pass it was contained in the
Constitution before the adoption of the last three amendments. The
power is sought, first, in the Fourteenth Amendment, and the views
and arguments of distinguished Senators, advanced whilst the law
was under consideration, claiming authority to pass it by virtue of
that amendment, are the principal arguments adduced in favor of the
power. We have carefully considered those arguments, as was due to
the eminent ability of those who put them forward, and have felt,
in all its force, the weight of authority which always invests a
law that Congress deems itself competent to pass. But the
responsibility of an independent judgment is now thrown upon this
court, and we are bound to exercise it according to the best lights
we have.
The first section of the Fourteenth Amendment (which is the one
relied on), after declaring who shall be citizens of the United
States, and of the several States, is prohibitory in its character,
and prohibitory upon the States. It declares that: Page 109 U. S. 11 "No State shall make or enforce any law which shall abridge the
privileges or immunities of citizens of the United States; nor
shall any State deprive any person of life, liberty, or property
without due process of law; nor deny to any person within its
jurisdiction the equal protection of the laws."
It is State action of a particular character that is prohibited.
Individual invasion of individual rights is not the subject matter
of the amendment. It has a deeper and broader scope. It nullifies
and makes void all State legislation, and State action of every
kind, which impairs the privileges and immunities of citizens of
the United States or which injures them in life, liberty or
property without due process of law, or which denies to any of them
the equal protection of the laws. It not only does this, but, in
order that the national will, thus declared, may not be a mere brutum fulmen, the last section of the amendment invests
Congress with power to enforce it by appropriate legislation. To
enforce what? To enforce the prohibition. To adopt appropriate
legislation for correcting the effects of such prohibited State
laws and State acts, and thus to render them effectually null,
void, and innocuous. This is the legislative power conferred upon
Congress, and this is the whole of it. It does not invest Congress
with power to legislate upon subjects which are within the domain
of State legislation, but to provide modes of relief against State
legislation, or State action, of the kind referred to. It does not
authorize Congress to create a code of municipal law for the
regulation of private rights, but to provide modes of redress
against the operation of State laws and the action of State
officers executive or judicial when these are subversive of the
fundamental rights specified in the amendment. Positive rights and
privileges are undoubtedly secured by the Fourteenth Amendment, but
they are secured by way of prohibition against State laws and State
proceedings affecting those rights and privileges, and by power
given to Congress to legislate for the purpose of carrying such
prohibition into effect, and such legislation must necessarily be
predicated upon such supposed State laws or State proceedings, and
be directed to the correction Page 109 U. S. 12 of their operation and effect. A quite full discussion of this
aspect of the amendment may be found in United Sates v.
Cruikshank, 92 U. S. 542 ; Virginia v. Rives, 100 U. S. 313 , and Ex parte Virginia, 100 U. S. 339 .
An apt illustration of this distinction may be found in some of
the provisions of the original Constitution. Take the subject of
contracts, for example. The Constitution prohibited the States from
passing any law impairing the obligation of contracts. This did not
give to Congress power to provide laws for the general enforcement
of contracts, nor power to invest the courts of the United States
with jurisdiction over contracts, so as to enable parties to sue
upon them in those courts. It did, however, give the power to
provide remedies by which the impairment of contracts by State
legislation might be counteracted and corrected, and this power was
exercised. The remedy which Congress actually provided was that
contained in the 25th section of the Judiciary Act of 1789, 1 Stat.
8, giving to the Supreme Court of the United States jurisdiction by
writ of error to review the final decisions of State courts
whenever they should sustain the validity of a State statute or
authority alleged to be repugnant to the Constitution or laws of
the United States. By this means, if a State law was passed
impairing the obligation of a contract and the State tribunals
sustained the validity of the law, the mischief could be corrected
in this court. The legislation of Congress, and the proceedings
provided for under it, were corrective in their character. No
attempt was made to draw into the United States courts the
litigation of contracts generally, and no such attempt would have
been sustained. We do not say that the remedy provided was the only
one that might have been provided in that case. Probably Congress
had power to pass a law giving to the courts of the United States
direct jurisdiction over contracts alleged to be impaired by a
State law, and under the broad provisions of the act of March 3d
1875, ch. 137, 18 Stat. 470, giving to the circuit courts
jurisdiction of all cases arising under the Constitution and laws
of the United States, it is possible that such jurisdiction now
exists. But under that, or any other law, it must appear as Page 109 U. S. 13 well by allegation, as proof at the trial, that the Constitution
had been violated by the action of the State legislature. Some
obnoxious State law passed, or that might be passed, is necessary
to be assumed in order to lay the foundation of any federal remedy
in the case, and for the very sufficient reason that the
constitutional prohibition is against State laws impairing
the obligation of contracts.
And so, in the present case, until some State law has been
passed, or some State action through its officers or agents has
been taken, adverse to the rights of citizens sought to be
protected by the Fourteenth Amendment, no legislation of the United
States under said amendment, nor any proceeding under such
legislation, can be called into activity, for the prohibitions of
the amendment are against State laws and acts done under State
authority. Of course, legislation may, and should, be provided in
advance to meet the exigency when it arises, but it should be
adapted to the mischief and wrong which the amendment was intended
to provide against, and that is State laws, or State action of some
kind, adverse to the rights of the citizen secured by the
amendment. Such legislation cannot properly cover the whole domain
of rights appertaining to life, liberty and property, defining them
and providing for their vindication. That would be to establish a
code of municipal law regulative of all private rights between man
and man in society. It would be to make Congress take the place of
the State legislatures and to supersede them. It is absurd to
affirm that, because the rights of life, liberty, and property
(which include all civil rights that men have) are, by the
amendment, sought to be protected against invasion on the part of
the State without due process of law, Congress may therefore
provide due process of law for their vindication in every case, and
that, because the denial by a State to any persons of the equal
protection of the laws is prohibited by the amendment, therefore
Congress may establish laws for their equal protection. In fine,
the legislation which Congress is authorized to adopt in this
behalf is not general legislation upon the rights of the citizen,
but corrective legislation, that is, such as may be necessary and
proper for counteracting such laws as the States may Page 109 U. S. 14 adopt or enforce, and which, by the amendment, they are
prohibited from making or enforcing, or such acts and proceedings
as the States may commit or take, and which, by the amendment, they
are prohibited from committing or taking. It is not necessary for
us to state, if we could, what legislation would be proper for
Congress to adopt. It is sufficient for us to examine whether the
law in question is of that character.
An inspection of the law shows that it makes no reference
whatever to any supposed or apprehended violation of the Fourteenth
Amendment on the part of the States. It is not predicated on any
such view. It proceeds ex directo to declare that certain
acts committed by individuals shall be deemed offences, and shall
be prosecuted and punished by proceedings in the courts of the
United States. It does not profess to be corrective of any
constitutional wrong committed by the States; it does not make its
operation to depend upon any such wrong committed. It applies
equally to cases arising in States which have the justest laws
respecting the personal rights of citizens, and whose authorities
are ever ready to enforce such laws, as to those which arise in
States that may have violated the prohibition of the amendment. In
other words, it steps into the domain of local jurisprudence, and
lays down rules for the conduct of individuals in society towards
each other, and imposes sanctions for the enforcement of those
rules, without referring in any manner to any supposed action of
the State or its authorities.
If this legislation is appropriate for enforcing the
prohibitions of the amendment, it is difficult to see where it is
to stop. Why may not Congress, with equal show of authority, enact
a code of laws for the enforcement and vindication of all rights of
life, liberty, and property? If it is supposable that the States
may deprive persons of life, liberty, and property without due
process of law (and the amendment itself does suppose this), why
should not Congress proceed at once to prescribe due process of law
for the protection of every one of these fundamental rights, in
every possible case, as well as to prescribe equal privileges in
inns, public conveyances, and theatres? The truth is that the
implication of a power to legislate in this manner is based Page 109 U. S. 15 upon the assumption that, if the States are forbidden to
legislate or act in a particular way on a particular subject, and
power is conferred upon Congress to enforce the prohibition, this
gives Congress power to legislate generally upon that subject, and
not merely power to provide modes of redress against such State
legislation or action. The assumption is certainly unsound. It is
repugnant to the Tenth Amendment of the Constitution, which
declares that powers not delegated to the United States by the
Constitution, nor prohibited by it to the States, are reserved to
the States respectively or to the people.
We have not overlooked the fact that the fourth section of the
act now under consideration has been held by this court to be
constitutional. That section declares
"that no citizen, possessing all other qualifications which are
or may be prescribed by law, shall be disqualified for service as
grand or petit juror in any court of the United States, or of any
State, on account of race, color, or previous condition of
servitude, and any officer or other person charged with any duty in
the selection or summoning of jurors who shall exclude or fail to
summon any citizen for the cause aforesaid, shall, on conviction
thereof, be deemed guilty of a misdemeanor, and be fined not more
than five thousand dollars."
In Ex parte Virginia, 100 U. S. 339 , it
was held that an indictment against a State officer under this
section for excluding persons of color from the jury list is
sustainable. But a moment's attention to its terms will show that
the section is entirely corrective in its character.
Disqualifications for service on juries are only created by the
law, and the first part of the section is aimed at certain
disqualifying laws, namely, those which make mere race or color a
disqualification, and the second clause is directed against those
who, assuming to use the authority of the State government, carry
into effect such a rule of disqualification. In the Virginia case,
the State, through its officer, enforced a rule of disqualification
which the law was intended to abrogate and counteract. Whether the
statute book of the State actually laid down any such rule of
disqualification or not, the State, through its officer, enforced
such a rule, and it is against such State action, through its
officers and agents, that the last clause of the section is
directed. Page 109 U. S. 16 This aspect of the law was deemed sufficient to divest it of any
unconstitutional character, and makes it differ widely from the
first and second sections of the same act which we are now
considering.
These sections, in the objectionable features before referred
to, are different also from the law ordinarily called the "Civil
Rights Bill," originally passed April 9th, 1866, 14 Stat. 27, ch.
31, and reenacted with some modifications in sections 16, 17, 18,
of the Enforcement Act, passed ay 31st, 1870, 16 Stat. 140, ch.
114. That law, as reenacted, after declaring that all persons
within the jurisdiction of the United States shall have the same
right in every State and Territory to make and enforce contracts,
to sue, be parties, give evidence, and to the full and equal
benefit of all laws and proceedings for the security of persons and
property as is enjoyed by white citizens, and shall be subject to
like punishment, pains, penalties, taxes, licenses and exactions of
every kind, and none other, any law, statute, ordinance, regulation
or custom to the contrary notwithstanding, proceeds to enact that
any person who, under color of any law, statute, ordinance,
regulation or custom, shall subject, or cause to be subjected, any
inhabitant of any State or Territory to the deprivation of any
rights secured or protected by the preceding section (above
quoted), or to different punishment, pains, or penalties, on
account of such person's being an alien, or by reason of his color
or race, than is prescribed for the punishment of citizens, shall
be deemed guilty of a misdemeanor, and subject to fine and
imprisonment as specified in the act. This law is clearly
corrective in its character, intended to counteract and furnish
redress against State laws and proceedings, and customs having the
force of law, which sanction the wrongful acts specified. In the
Revised Statutes, it is true, a very important clause, to-wit, the
words "any law, statute, ordinance, regulation or custom to the
contrary notwithstanding," which gave the declaratory section its
point and effect, are omitted; but the penal part, by which the
declaration is enforced, and which is really the effective part of
the law, retains the reference to State laws by making the penalty
apply only to those who should subject Page 109 U. S. 17 parties to a deprivation of their rights under color of any
statute, ordinance, custom, etc., of any State or Territory, thus
preserving the corrective character of the legislation. Rev. St. §§
177, 1978, 1979, 5510. The Civil Rights Bill here referred to is
analogous in its character to what a law would have been under the
original Constitution, declaring that the validity of contracts
should not be impaired, and that, if any person bound by a contract
should refuse to comply with it, under color or pretence that it
had been rendered void or invalid by a State law, he should be
liable to an action upon it in the courts of the United States,
with the addition of a penalty for setting up such an unjust and
unconstitutional defence.
In this connection, it is proper to state that civil rights,
such as are guaranteed by the Constitution against State
aggression, cannot be impaired by the wrongful acts of individuals,
unsupported by State authority in the shape of laws, customs, or
judicial or executive proceedings. The wrongful act of an
individual, unsupported by any such authority, is simply a private
wrong, or a crime of that individual; an invasion of the rights of
the injured party, it is true, whether they affect his person, his
property, or his reputation; but if not sanctioned in some way by
the State, or not done under State authority, his rights remain in
full force, and may presumably be vindicated by resort to the laws
of the State for redress. An individual cannot deprive a man of his
right to vote, to hold property, to buy and sell, to sue in the
courts, or to be a witness or a juror; he may, by force or fraud,
interfere with the enjoyment of the right in a particular case; he
may commit an assault against the person, or commit murder, or use
ruffian violence at the polls, or slander the good name of a fellow
citizen; but, unless protected in these wrongful acts by some
shield of State law or State authority, he cannot destroy or injure
the right; he will only render himself amenable to satisfaction or
punishment, and amenable therefor to the laws of the State where
the wrongful acts are committed. Hence, in all those cases where
the Constitution seeks to protect the rights of the citizen against
discriminative and unjust laws of the State by prohibiting such
laws, it is not individual offences, but abrogation and Page 109 U. S. 18 denial of rights, which it denounces and for which it clothes
the Congress with power to provide a remedy. This abrogation and
denial of rights for which the States alone were or could be
responsible was the great seminal and fundamental wrong which was
intended to be remedied. And the remedy to be provided must
necessarily be predicated upon that wrong. It must assume that, in
the cases provided for, the evil or wrong actually committed rests
upon some State law or State authority for its excuse and
perpetration.
Of course, these remarks do not apply to those cases in which
Congress is clothed with direct and plenary powers of legislation
over the whole subject, accompanied with an express or implied
denial of such power to the States, as in the regulation of
commerce with foreign nations, among the several States, and with
the Indian tribes, the coining of money, the establishment of post
offices and post roads, the declaring of war, etc. In these cases,
Congress has power to pass laws for regulating the subjects
specified in every detail, and the conduct and transactions of
individuals in respect thereof. But where a subject is not
submitted to the general legislative power of Congress, but is only
submitted thereto for the purpose of rendering effective some
prohibition against particular State legislation or State action in
reference to that subject, the power given is limited by its
object, and any legislation by Congress in the matter must
necessarily be corrective in its character, adapted to counteract
and redress the operation of such prohibited State laws or
proceedings of State officers.
If the principles of interpretation which we have laid down are
correct, as we deem them to be (and they are in accord with the
principles laid down in the cases before referred to, as well as in
the recent case of United States v. Harris, 106 U.
S. 629 ), it is clear that the law in question cannot be
sustained by any grant of legislative power made to Congress by the
Fourteenth Amendment. That amendment prohibits the States from
denying to any person the equal protection of the laws, and
declares that Congress shall have power to enforce, by appropriate
legislation, the provisions of the amendment. The law in question,
without any reference to adverse State legislation on the
subject, Page 109 U. S. 19 declares that all persons shall be entitled to equal
accommodations and privileges of inns, public conveyances, and
places of public amusement, and imposes a penalty upon any
individual who shall deny to any citizen such equal accommodations
and privileges. This is not corrective legislation; it is primary
and direct; it takes immediate and absolute possession of the
subject of the right of admission to inns, public conveyances, and
places of amusement. It supersedes and displaces State legislation
on the same subject, or only allows it permissive force. It ignores
such legislation, and assumes that the matter is one that belongs
to the domain of national regulation. Whether it would not have
been a more effective protection of the rights of citizens to have
clothed Congress with plenary power over the whole subject is not
now the question. What we have to decide is whether such plenary
power has been conferred upon Congress by the Fourteenth Amendment,
and, in our judgment, it has not.
We have discussed the question presented by the law on the
assumption that a right to enjoy equal accommodation and privileges
in all inns, public conveyances, and places of public amusement is
one of the essential rights of the citizen which no State can
abridge or interfere with. Whether it is such a right or not is a
different question which, in the view we have taken of the validity
of the law on the ground already stated, it is not necessary to
examine.
We have also discussed the validity of the law in reference to
cases arising in the States only, and not in reference to cases
arising in the Territories or the District of Columbia, which are
subject to the plenary legislation of Congress in every branch of
municipal regulation. Whether the law would be a valid one as
applied to the Territories and the District is not a question for
consideration in the cases before us, they all being cases arising
within the limits of States. And whether Congress, in the exercise
of its power to regulate commerce amongst the several States, might
or might not pass a law regulating rights in public conveyances
passing from one State to another is also a question which is not
now before us, as the sections in question are not conceived in any
such view. Page 109 U. S. 20 But the power of Congress to adopt direct and primary, as
distinguished from corrective, legislation on the subject in hand
is sought, in the second place, from the Thirteenth Amendment,
which abolishes slavery. This amendment declares
"that neither slavery, nor involuntary servitude, except as a
punishment for crime, whereof the party shall have been duly
convicted, shall exist within the United States, or any place
subject to their jurisdiction,"
and it gives Congress power to enforce the amendment by
appropriate legislation.
This amendment, as well as the Fourteenth, is undoubtedly
self-executing, without any ancillary legislation, so far as its
terms are applicable to any existing state of circumstances. By its
own unaided force and effect, it abolished slavery and established
universal freedom. Still, legislation may be necessary and proper
to meet all the various cases and circumstances to be affected by
it, and to prescribe proper modes of redress for its violation in
letter or spirit. And such legislation may be primary and direct in
its character, for the amendment is not a mere prohibition of State
laws establishing or upholding slavery, but an absolute declaration
that slavery or involuntary servitude shall not exist in any part
of the United States.
It is true that slavery cannot exist without law, any more than
property in lands and goods can exist without law, and, therefore,
the Thirteenth Amendment may be regarded as nullifying all State
laws which establish or uphold slavery. But it has a reflex
character also, establishing and decreeing universal civil and
political freedom throughout the United States, and it is assumed
that the power vested in Congress to enforce the article by
appropriate legislation clothes Congress with power to pass all
laws necessary and proper for abolishing all badges and incidents
of slavery in the United States, and, upon this assumption ,it is
claimed that this is sufficient authority for declaring by law that
all persons shall have equal accommodations and privileges in all
inns, public conveyances, and places of amusement, the argument
being that the denial of such equal accommodations and privileges
is, in itself, a subjection to a species of servitude within the
meaning of the amendment. Conceding the major proposition to be
true, that Page 109 U. S. 21 Congress has a right to enact all necessary and proper laws for
the obliteration and prevention of slavery with all its badges and
incidents, is the minor proposition also true, that the denial to
any person of admission to the accommodations and privileges of an
inn, a public conveyance, or a theatre does subject that person to
any form of servitude, or tend to fasten upon him any badge of
slavery? If it does not, then power to pass the law is not found in
the Thirteenth Amendment.
In a very able and learned presentation of the cognate question
as to the extent of the rights, privileges and immunities of
citizens which cannot rightfully be abridged by state laws under
the Fourteenth Amendment, made in a former case, a long list of
burdens and disabilities of a servile character, incident to feudal
vassalage in France, and which were abolished by the decrees of the
National Assembly, was presented for the purpose of showing that
all inequalities and observances exacted by one man from another
were servitudes or badges of slavery which a great nation, in its
effort to establish universal liberty, made haste to wipe out and
destroy. But these were servitudes imposed by the old law, or by
long custom, which had the force of law, and exacted by one man
from another without the latter's consent. Should any such
servitudes be imposed by a state law, there can be no doubt that
the law would be repugnant to the Fourteenth, no less than to the
Thirteenth, Amendment, nor any greater doubt that Congress has
adequate power to forbid any such servitude from being exacted.
But is there any similarity between such servitudes and a denial
by the owner of an inn, a public conveyance, or a theatre of its
accommodations and privileges to an individual, even though the
denial be founded on the race or color of that individual? Where
does any slavery or servitude, or badge of either, arise from such
an act of denial? Whether it might not be a denial of a right
which, if sanctioned by the state law, would be obnoxious to the
prohibitions of the Fourteenth Amendment is another question. But
what has it to do with the question of slavery?
It may be that, by the Black Code (as it was called), in the
times when slavery prevailed, the proprietors of inns and
public Page 109 U. S. 22 conveyances were forbidden to receive persons of the African
race because it might assist slaves to escape from the control of
their masters. This was merely a means of preventing such escapes,
and was no part of the servitude itself. A law of that kind could
not have any such object now, however justly it might be deemed an
invasion of the party's legal right as a citizen, and amenable to
the prohibitions of the Fourteenth Amendment.
The long existence of African slavery in this country gave us
very distinct notions of what it was and what were its necessary
incidents. Compulsory service of the slave for the benefit of the
master, restraint of his movements except by the master's will,
disability to hold property, to make contracts, to have a standing
in court, to be a witness against a white person, and such like
burdens and incapacities were the inseparable incidents of the
institution. Severer punishments for crimes were imposed on the
slave than on free persons guilty of the same offences. Congress,
as we have seen, by the Civil Rights Bill of 1866, passed in view
of the Thirteenth Amendment before the Fourteenth was adopted,
undertook to wipe out these burdens and disabilities, the necessary
incidents of slavery constituting its substance and visible form,
and to secure to all citizens of every race and color, and without
regard to previous servitude, those fundamental rights which are
the essence of civil freedom, namely, the same right to make and
enforce contracts, to sue, be parties, give evidence, and to
inherit, purchase, lease, sell and convey property as is enjoyed by
white citizens. Whether this legislation was fully authorized by
the Thirteenth Amendment alone, without the support which it
afterward received from the Fourteenth Amendment, after the
adoption of which it was reenacted with some additions, it is not
necessary to inquire. It is referred to for the purpose of showing
that, at that time (in 1866), Congress did not assume, under the
authority given by the Thirteenth Amendment, to adjust what may be
called the social rights of men and races in the community, but
only to declare and vindicate those fundamental rights which
appertain to the essence of citizenship, and the enjoyment or
deprivation of which constitutes the essential distinction between
freedom and slavery. Page 109 U. S. 23 We must not forget that the province and scope of the Thirteenth
and Fourteenth amendments are different: the former simply
abolished slavery; the latter prohibited the States from abridging
the privileges or immunities of citizens of the United States, from
depriving them of life, liberty, or property without due process of
law, and from denying to any the equal protection of the laws. The
amendments are different, and the powers of Congress under them are
different. What Congress has power to do under one it may not have
power to do under the other. Under the Thirteenth Amendment, it has
only to do with slavery and its incidents. Under the Fourteenth
Amendment, it has power to counteract and render nugatory all State
laws and proceedings which have the effect to abridge any of the
privileges or immunities of citizens of the United States, or to
deprive them of life, liberty or property without due process of
law, or to deny to any of them the equal protection of the laws.
Under the Thirteenth Amendment, the legislation, so far as
necessary or proper to eradicate all forms and incidents of slavery
and involuntary servitude, may be direct and primary, operating
upon the acts of individuals, whether sanctioned by State
legislation or not; under the Fourteenth, as we have already shown,
it must necessarily be, and can only be, corrective in its
character, addressed to counteract and afford relief against State
regulations or proceedings.
The only question under the present head, therefore, is whether
the refusal to any persons of the accommodations of an inn or a
public conveyance or a place of public amusement by an individual,
and without any sanction or support from any State law or
regulation, does inflict upon such persons any manner of servitude
or form of slavery as those terms are understood in this country?
Many wrongs may be obnoxious to the prohibitions of the Fourteenth
Amendment which are not, in any just sense, incidents or elements
of slavery. Such, for example, would be the taking of private
property without due process of law, or allowing persons who have
committed certain crimes (horse stealing, for example) to be seized
and hung by the posse comitatus without regular trial, or
denying to any person, or class of persons, the right to pursue any
peaceful Page 109 U. S. 24 avocations allowed to others. What is called class legislation
would belong to this category, and would be obnoxious to the
prohibitions of the Fourteenth Amendment, but would not necessarily
be so to the Thirteenth, when not involving the idea of any
subjection of one man to another. The Thirteenth Amendment has
respect not to distinctions of race or class or color, but to
slavery. The Fourteenth Amendment extends its protection to races
and classes, and prohibits any State legislation which has the
effect of denying to any race or class, or to any individual, the
equal protection of the laws.
Now, conceding for the sake of the argument that the admission
to an inn, a public conveyance, or a place of public amusement on
equal terms with all other citizens is the right of every man and
all classes of men, is it any more than one of those rights which
the states, by the Fourteenth Amendment, are forbidden to deny to
any person? And is the Constitution violated until the denial of
the right has some State sanction or authority? Can the act of a
mere individual, the owner of the inn, the public conveyance or
place of amusement, refusing the accommodation, be justly regarded
as imposing any badge of slavery or servitude upon the applicant,
or only as inflicting an ordinary civil injury, properly cognizable
by the laws of the State and presumably subject to redress by those
laws until the contrary appears?
After giving to these questions all the consideration which
their importance demands, we are forced to the conclusion that such
an act of refusal has nothing to do with slavery or involuntary
servitude, and that, if it is violative of any right of the party,
his redress is to be sought under the laws of the State, or, if
those laws are adverse to his rights and do not protect him, his
remedy will be found in the corrective legislation which Congress
has adopted, or may adopt, for counteracting the effect of State
laws or State action prohibited by the Fourteenth Amendment. It
would be running the slavery argument into the ground to make it
apply to every act of discrimination which a person may see fit to
make as to the guests he will entertain, or as to the people he
will take into his coach or cab or car, or admit to his concert or
theatre, or deal with in Page 109 U. S. 25 other matters of intercourse or business. Innkeepers and public
carriers, by the laws of all the States, so far as we are aware,
are bound, to the extent of their facilities, to furnish proper
accommodation to all unobjectionable persons who in good faith
apply for them. If the laws themselves make any unjust
discrimination amenable to the prohibitions of the Fourteenth
Amendment, Congress has full power to afford a remedy under that
amendment and in accordance with it.
When a man has emerged from slavery, and, by the aid of
beneficent legislation, has shaken off the inseparable concomitants
of that state, there must be some stage in the progress of his
elevation when he takes the rank of a mere citizen and ceases to be
the special favorite of the laws, and when his rights as a citizen
or a man are to be protected in the ordinary modes by which other
men's rights are protected. There were thousands of free colored
people in this country before the abolition of slavery, enjoying
all the essential rights of life, liberty and property the same as
white citizens, yet no one at that time thought that it was any
invasion of his personal status as a freeman because he was not
admitted to all the privileges enjoyed by white citizens, or
because he was subjected to discriminations in the enjoyment of
accommodations in inns, public conveyances and places of amusement.
Mere discriminations on account of race or color were not regarded
as badges of slavery. If, since that time, the enjoyment of equal
rights in all these respects has become established by
constitutional enactment, it is not by force of the Thirteenth
Amendment (which merely abolishes slavery), but by force of the
Thirteenth and Fifteenth Amendments.
On the whole, we are of opinion that no countenance of authority
for the passage of the law in question can be found in either the
Thirteenth or Fourteenth Amendment of the Constitution, and no
other ground of authority for its passage being suggested, it must
necessarily be declared void, at least so far as its operation in
the several States is concerned.
This conclusion disposes of the cases now under consideration.
In the cases of the United States v. Michael Ryan, and of Richard A. Robinson and Wife v. The Memphis &
Charleston Page 109 U. S. 26 Railroad Company, the judgments must be affirmed. In
the other cases, the answer to be given will be that the first and
second sections of the act of Congress of March 1st, 1875, entitled
"An Act to protect all citizens in their civil and legal rights,"
are unconstitutional and void, and that judgment should be rendered
upon the several indictments in those cases accordingly. And it is so ordered. MR. JUSTICE HARLAN dissenting.
The opinion in these cases proceeds, it seems to me, upon
grounds entirely too narrow and artificial. I cannot resist the
conclusion that the substance and spirit of the recent amendments
of the Constitution have been sacrificed by a subtle and ingenious
verbal criticism.
"It is not the words of the law, but the internal sense of it
that makes the law; the letter of the law is the body; the sense
and reason of the law is the soul."
Constitutional provisions, adopted in the interest of liberty
and for the purpose of securing, through national legislation, if
need be, rights inhering in a state of freedom and belonging to
American citizenship have been so construed as to defeat the ends
the people desired to accomplish, which they attempted to
accomplish, and which they supposed they had accomplished by
changes in their fundamental law. By this I do not mean that the
determination of these cases should have been materially controlled
by considerations of mere expediency or policy. I mean only, in
this form, to express an earnest conviction that the court has
departed from the familiar rule requiring, in the interpretation of
constitutional provisions, that full effect be given to the intent
with which they were adopted.
The purpose of the first section of the act of Congress of March
1, 1875, was to prevent race discrimination in respect of the
accommodations and facilities of inns, public conveyances, and
places of public amusement. It does not assume to define the
general conditions and limitations under which inns, public
conveyances, and places of public amusement may be conducted, but
only declares that such conditions and limitations, whatever they
may be, shall not be applied so as to work a Page 109 U. S. 27 discrimination solely because of race, color, or previous
condition of servitude. The second section provides a penalty
against anyone denying, or aiding or inciting the denial, of any
citizen, of that equality of right given by the first section
except for reasons by law applicable to citizens of every race or
color and regardless of any previous condition of servitude.
There seems to be no substantial difference between my brethren
and myself as to the purpose of Congress, for they say that the
essence of the law is not to declare broadly that all persons shall
be entitled to the full and equal enjoyment of the accommodations,
advantages, facilities, and privileges of inns, public conveyances,
and theatres, but that such enjoyment shall not be subject to
conditions applicable only to citizens of a particular race or
color, or who had been in a previous condition of servitude. The
effect of the statute, the court says, is that colored citizens,
whether formerly slaves or not, and citizens of other races shall
have the same accommodations and privileges in all inns, public
conveyances, and places of amusement as are enjoyed by white
persons, and vice versa.
The court adjudges, I think erroneously, that Congress is
without power, under either the Thirteenth or Fourteenth Amendment,
to establish such regulations, and that the first and second
sections of the statute are, in all their parts, unconstitutional
and void.
Whether the legislative department of the government has
transcended the limits of its constitutional powers, "is at all
times," said this court in Fletcher v. Peck, 6 Cr.
128,
"a question of much delicacy which ought seldom, if ever, to be
decided in the affirmative in a doubtful case. . . . The opposition
between the Constitution and the law should be such that the judge
feels a clear and strong conviction of their incompatibility with
each other."
More recently, in Sinking Fund Cases, 99 U.
S. 718 , we said:
"It is our duty, when required in the regular course of judicial
proceedings, to declare an act of Congress void if not within the
legislative power of the United States, but this declaration should
never be made except in a clear case. Every possible presumption
is Page 109 U. S. 28 in favor of the validity of a statute, and this continues until
the contrary is shown beyond a rational doubt. One branch of the
government cannot encroach on the domain of another without danger.
The safety of our institutions depends in no small degree on a
strict observance of this salutary rule."
Before considering the language and scope of these amendments,
it will be proper to recall the relations subsisting, prior to
their adoption, between the national government and the institution
of slavery, as indicated by the provisions of the Constitution, the
legislation of Congress, and the decisions of this court. In this
mode, we may obtain keys with which to open the mind of the people
and discover the thought intended to be expressed.
In section 2 of article IV of the Constitution, it was provided
that
"no person held to service or labor in one State, under the laws
thereof, escaping into another, shall, in consequence of any law or
regulation therein, be discharged from such service or labor, but
shall be delivered up on claim of the party to whom such service or
labor may be due."
Under the authority of this clause, Congress passed the Fugitive
Slave Law of 1793, establishing a mode for the recovery of fugitive
slaves and prescribing a penalty against any person who should
knowingly and willingly obstruct or hinder the master, his agent,
or attorney in seizing, arresting, and recovering the fugitive, or
who should rescue the fugitive from him, or who should harbor or
conceal the slave after notice that he was a fugitive.
In Prigg v. Commonwealth of
Pennsylvania , 16 Pet. 539, this court had occasion
to define the powers and duties of Congress in reference to
fugitives from labor. Speaking by MR. JUSTICE STORY, it laid down
these propositions:
That a clause of the Constitution conferring a right should not
be so construed as to make it shadowy or unsubstantial, or leave
the citizen without a remedial power adequate for its protection
when another construction equally accordant with the words and the
sense in which they were used would enforce and protect the right
granted;
That Congress is not restricted to legislation for the
execution Page 109 U. S. 29 of its expressly granted powers, but, for the protection of
rights guaranteed by the Constitution, may employ such means, not
prohibited, as are necessary and proper, or such as are
appropriate, to attain the ends proposed;
That the Constitution recognized the master's right of property
in his fugitive slave, and, as incidental thereto, the right of
seizing and recovering him, regardless of any State law or
regulation or local custom whatsoever; and,
That the right of the master to have his slave, thus escaping,
delivered up on claim, being guaranteed by the Constitution, the
fair implication was that the national government was clothed with
appropriate authority and functions to enforce it.
The court said
"The fundamental principle, applicable to all cases of this
sort, would seem to be that, when the end is required the means are
given, and when the duty is enjoined, the ability to perform it is
contemplated to exist on the part of the functionary to whom it is
entrusted."
Again,
"It would be a strange anomaly and forced construction to
suppose that the national government meant to rely for the due
fulfillment of its own proper duties, and the rights which it
intended to secure, upon State legislation, and not upon that of
the Union. A fortiori, it would be more objectionable to
suppose that a power which was to be the same throughout the Union
should be confided to State sovereignty, which could not rightfully
act beyond its own territorial limits "
The act of 1793 was, upon these grounds, adjudged to be a
constitutional exercise of the powers of Congress.
It is to be observed from the report of Priggs' case that
Pennsylvania, by her attorney general, pressed the argument that
the obligation to surrender fugitive slaves was on the States and
for the States, subject to the restriction that they should not
pass laws or establish regulations liberating such fugitives; that
the Constitution did not take from the States the right to
determine the status of all persons within their respective
jurisdictions; that it was for the State in which the alleged
fugitive was found to determine, through her courts or in such
modes as she prescribed, whether the person arrested was, in fact,
a freeman or a fugitive slave; that the sole power Page 109 U. S. 30 of the general government in the premises was, by judicial
instrumentality, to restrain and correct, not to forbid and prevent
in the absence of hostile State action, and that, for the general
government to assume primary authority to legislate on the subject
of fugitive slaves, to the exclusion of the States, would be a
dangerous encroachment on State sovereignty. But to such
suggestions, this court turned a deaf ear, and adjudged that
primary legislation by Congress to enforce the master's right was
authorized by the Constitution.
We next come to the Fugitive Slave Act of 1850, the
constitutionality of which rested, as did that of 1793, solely upon
the implied power of Congress to enforce the master's rights. The
provisions of that act were far in advance of previous legislation.
They placed at the disposal of the master seeking to recover his
fugitive slave substantially the whole power of the nation. It
invested commissioners, appointed under the act, with power to
summon the posse comitatus for the enforcement of its
provisions, and commanded all good citizens to assist in its prompt
and efficient execution whenever their services were required as
part of the posse comitatus. Without going into the
details of that act, it is sufficient to say that Congress omitted
from it nothing which the utmost ingenuity could suggest as
essential to the successful enforcement of the master's claim to
recover his fugitive slave. And this court, in Ableman v.
Booth , 21 How. 506, adjudged it to be "in all of
its provisions, fully authorized by the Constitution of the United
States."
The only other case, prior to the adoption of the recent
amendments, to which reference will be made, is that of Dred Scott v.
Sanford , 19 How. 399. That case was instituted in a
circuit court of the United States by Dred Scott, claiming to be a
citizen of Missouri, the defendant being a citizen of another
State. Its object was to assert the title of himself and family to
freedom. The defendant pleaded in abatement that Scott -- being of
African descent, whose ancestors, of pure African blood, were
brought into this country and sold as slaves -- was not a citizen.
The only matter in issue, said the court, was whether the
descendants of slaves thus imported Page 109 U. S. 31 and sold, when they should be emancipated, or who were born of
parents who had become free before their birth, are citizens of a
State in the sense in which the word "citizen" is used in the
Constitution of the United States.
In determining that question, the court instituted an inquiry as
to who were citizens of the several States at the adoption of the
Constitution and who at that time were recognized as the people
whose rights and liberties had been violated by the British
government. The result was a declaration by this court, speaking by
Chief Justice Taney, that the legislation and histories of the
times, and the language used in the Declaration of Independence,
showed
"that neither the class of persons who had been imported as
slaves nor their descendants, whether they had become free or not,
were then acknowledged as a part of the people, nor intended to be
included in the general words used in that instrument;"
that
"they had for more than a century before been regarded as beings
of an inferior race, and altogether unfit to associate with the
white race either in social or political relations, and so far
inferior that they had no rights which the white man was bound to
respect, and that the negro might justly and lawfully be reduced to
slavery for his benefit;"
that he was "bought and sold, and treated as an ordinary article
of merchandise and traffic, whenever a profit could be made by it;"
and, that
"this opinion was at that time fixed and universal in the
civilized portion of the white race. It was regarded as an axiom in
morals, as well as in politics, which no one thought of disputing,
or supposed to be open to dispute, and men in every grade and
position in society daily and habitually acted upon it in their
private pursuits, as well as in matters of public concern, without
for a moment doubting the correctness of this opinion."
The judgment of the court was that the words "people of the
United States" and "citizens" meant the same thing, both
describing
"the political body who, according to our republican
institutions, form the sovereignty and hold the power and conduct
the government through their representatives;"
that
"they are what we familiarly call the 'sovereign people,'
and Page 109 U. S. 32 every citizen is one of this people and a constituent member of
this sovereignty;"
but that the class of persons described in the plea in abatement
did not compose a portion of this people, were not "included, and
were not intended to be included, under the word citizens' in
the Constitution;" that, therefore, they could "claim none of the
rights and privileges which that instrument provides for and
secures to citizens of the United States;" that, "on the contrary, they were at that time considered as a
subordinate and inferior class of beings who had been subjugated by
the dominant race and, whether emancipated or not, yet remained
subject to their authority, and had no rights or privileges but
such as those who held the power and the government might choose to
grant them."
Such were the relations which formerly existed between the
government, whether national or state, and the descendants, whether
free or in bondage, of those of African blood who had been imported
into this country and sold as slaves.
The first section of the Thirteenth Amendment provides that
"neither slavery nor involuntary servitude, except as a
punishment for crime, whereof the party shall have been duly
convicted, shall exist within the United States, or any place
subject to their jurisdiction."
Its second section declares that "Congress shall have power to
enforce this article by appropriate legislation." This amendment
was followed by the Civil Rights Act of April 9, 1866, which, among
other things, provided that
"all persons born in the United States, and not subject to any
foreign power, excluding Indians not taxed, are hereby declared to
be citizens of the United States."
14 Stat. 27. The power of Congress, in this mode, to elevate the
enfranchised race to national citizenship was maintained by the
supporters of the act of 1866 to be as full and complete as its
power, by general statute, to make the children, being of full age,
of persons naturalized in this country, citizens of the United
States without going through the process of naturalization. The act
of 1866 in this respect was also likened to that of 1843, in which
Congress declared
"that the Stockbridge tribe of Indians, and each and every one
of them, shall be deemed to be and are hereby declared to be,
citizens of the United States to Page 109 U. S. 33 all intents and purposes, and shall be entitled to all the
rights, privileges, and immunities of such citizens, and shall in
all respects be subject to the laws of the United States."
If the act of 1866 was valid in conferring national citizenship
upon all embraced by its terms, then the colored race, enfranchised
by the Thirteenth Amendment, became citizens of the United States
prior to the adoption of the Fourteenth Amendment. But, in the view
which I take of the present case, it is not necessary to examine
this question.
The terms of the Thirteenth Amendment are absolute and
universal. They embrace every race which then was, or might
thereafter be, within the United States. No race, as such, can be
excluded from the benefits or rights thereby conferred. Yet it is
historically true that that amendment was suggested by the
condition, in this country, of that race which had been declared by
this court to have had -- according to the opinion entertained by
the most civilized portion of the white race at the time of the
adoption of the Constitution -- "no rights which the white man was
bound to respect," none of the privileges or immunities secured by
that instrument to citizens of the United States. It had reference,
in peculiar sense, to a people which (although the larger part of
them were in slavery) had been invited by an act of Congress to aid
in saving from overthrow a government which, theretofore, by all of
its departments, had treated them as an inferior race, with no
legal rights or privileges except such as the white race might
choose to grant them.
These are the circumstances under which the Thirteenth Amendment
was proposed for adoption. They are now recalled only that we may
better understand what was in the minds of the people when that
amendment was considered, and what were the mischiefs to be
remedied and the grievances to be redressed by its adoption.
We have seen that the power of Congress, by legislation, to
enforce the master's right to have his slave delivered up on claim
was implied from the recognition of that right in the
national Constitution. But the power conferred by the Thirteenth
Amendment does not rest upon implication or Page 109 U. S. 34 inference. Those who framed it were not ignorant of the
discussion, covering many years of our country's history, as to the
constitutional power of Congress to enact the Fugitive Slave Laws
of 1793 and 1850. When, therefore, it was determined, by a change
in the fundamental law, to uproot the institution of slavery
wherever it existed in the land and to establish universal freedom,
there was a fixed purpose to place the authority of Congress in the
premises beyond the possibility of a doubt. Therefore, ex
industria, power to enforce the Thirteenth Amendment by
appropriate legislation was expressly granted. Legislation for that
purpose, my brethren concede, may be direct and primary. But to
what specific ends may it be directed? This court has uniformly
held that the national government has the power, whether expressly
given or not, to secure and protect rights conferred or guaranteed
by the Constitution. United States v. Reese, 92 U. S.
214 ; Strauder v. West Virginia, 100 U.
S. 303 . That doctrine ought not now to be abandoned when
the inquiry is not as to an implied power to protect the master's
rights, but what may Congress, under powers expressly granted, do
for the protection of freedom and the rights necessarily inhering
in a state of freedom.
The Thirteenth Amendment, it is conceded, did something more
than to prohibit slavery as an institution resting upon
distinctions of race and upheld by positive law. My brethren admit
that it established and decreed universal civil freedom throughout the United States. But did the freedom thus established
involve nothing more than exemption from actual slavery? Was
nothing more intended than to forbid one man from owning another as
property? Was it the purpose of the nation simply to destroy the
institution, and then remit the race, theretofore held in bondage,
to the several States for such protection, in their civil rights,
necessarily growing out of freedom, as those States, in their
discretion, might choose to provide? Were the States against whose
protest the institution was destroyed to be left free, so far as
national interference was concerned, to make or allow
discriminations against that race, as such, in the enjoyment of
those fundamental rights which, by universal concession, inhere in
a state of freedom? Page 109 U. S. 35 Had the Thirteenth Amendment stopped with the sweeping
declaration in its first section against the existence of slavery
and involuntary servitude except for crime, Congress would have had
the power, by implication, according to the doctrines of Prigg
v. Commonwealth of Pennsylvania, repeated in Strauder v.
West Virginia, to protect the freedom established, and
consequently, to secure the enjoyment of such civil rights as were
fundamental in freedom. That it can exert its authority to that
extent is made clear, and was intended to be made clear, by the
express grant of power contained in the second section of the
Amendment.
That there are burdens and disabilities which constitute badges
of slavery and servitude, and that the power to enforce by
appropriate legislation the Thirteenth Amendment may be exerted by
legislation of a direct and primary character for the eradication
not simply of the institution, but of its badges and incidents, are
propositions which ought to be deemed indisputable. They lie at the
foundation of the Civil Rights Act of 1866. Whether that act was
authorized by the Thirteenth Amendment alone, without the support
which it subsequently received from the Fourteenth Amendment, after
the adoption of which it was reenacted with some additions, my
brethren do not consider it necessary to inquire. But I submit,
with all respect to them, that its constitutionality is
conclusively shown by their opinion. They admit, as I have said,
that the Thirteenth Amendment established freedom; that there are
burdens and disabilities, the necessary incidents of slavery, which
constitute its substance and visible form; that Congress, by the
act of 1866, passed in view of the Thirteenth Amendment, before the
Fourteenth was adopted, undertook to remove certain burdens and
disabilities, the necessary incidents of slavery, and to secure to
all citizens of every race and color, and without regard to
previous servitude, those fundamental rights which are the essence
of civil freedom, namely, the same right to make and enforce
contracts, to sue, be parties, give evidence, and to inherit,
purchase, lease, sell, and convey property as is enjoyed by white
citizens; that, under the Thirteenth Amendment, Congress has to do
with slavery and Page 109 U. S. 36 its incidents, and that legislation, so far as necessary or
proper to eradicate all forms and incidents of slaver and
involuntary servitude, may be direct and primary, operating upon
the acts of individuals, whether sanctioned by State legislation or
not. These propositions being conceded, it is impossible, as it
seems to me, to question the constitutional validity of the Civil
Rights Act of 1866. I do not contend that the Thirteenth Amendment
invests Congress with authority, by legislation, to define and
regulate the entire body of the civil rights which citizens enjoy,
or may enjoy, in the several States. But I hold that, since
slavery, as the court has repeatedly declared, Slaughterhouse
Cases , 16 Wall. 36; Strauder West
Virginia, 100 U. S. 303 , was
the moving or principal cause of the adoption of that amendment,
and since that institution rested wholly upon the inferiority, as a
race, of those held in bondage, their freedom necessarily involved
immunity from, and protection against, all discrimination against
them, because of their race, in respect of such civil rights as
belong to freemen of other races. Congress, therefore, under its
express power to enforce that amendment by appropriate legislation,
may enact laws to protect that people against the deprivation, because of their race, of any civil rights granted to
other freemen in the same State, and such legislation may be of a
direct and primary character, operating upon States, their officers
and agents, and also upon at least such individuals and
corporations as exercise public functions and wield power and
authority under the State.
To test the correctness of this position, let us suppose that,
prior to the adoption of the Fourteenth Amendment, a State had
passed a statute denying to freemen of African descent, resident
within its limits, the same right which was accorded to white
persons of making and enforcing contracts and of inheriting,
purchasing, leasing, selling and conveying property; or a statute
subjecting colored people to severer punishment for particular
offences than was prescribed for white persons, or excluding that
race from the benefit of the laws exempting homesteads from
execution. Recall the legislation of 1865-1866 in some of the
States, of which this court in the Slaughterhouse Page 109 U. S. 37 Cases said that it imposed upon the colored race
onerous disabilities and burdens; curtailed their rights in the
pursuit of life, liberty and property to such an extent that their
freedom was of little value; forbade them to appear in the towns in
any other character than menial servants; required them to reside
on and cultivate the soil, without the right to purchase or own it;
excluded them from many occupations of gain, and denied them the
privilege of giving testimony in the courts where a white man was a
party. 16 Wall. 83 U. S. 57 . Can
there be any doubt that all such enactments might have been reached
by direct legislation upon the part of Congress under its express
power to enforce the Thirteenth Amendment? Would any court have
hesitated to declare that such legislation imposed badges of
servitude in conflict with the civil freedom ordained by that
amendment? That it would have been also in conflict with the
Fourteenth Amendment because inconsistent with the fundamental
rights of American citizenship does not prove that it would have
been consistent with the Thirteenth Amendment.
What has been said is sufficient to show that the power of
Congress under the Thirteenth Amendment is not necessarily
restricted to legislation against slavery as an institution upheld
by positive law, but may be exerted to the extent, at least, of
protecting the liberated race against discrimination in respect of
legal rights belonging to freemen where such discrimination is
based upon race.
It remains now to inquire what are the legal rights of colored
persons in respect of the accommodations, privileges and facilities
of public conveyances, inns, and places of public amusement? First, as to public conveyances on land and water. In New Jersey Steam Navigation
Co. v. Merchants' Bank , 6 How. 344, this court,
speaking by Mr. Justice Nelson, said that a common carrier is
"in the exercise of a sort of public office, and has public
duties to perform, from which he should not be permitted to
exonerate himself without the assent of the parties concerned."
To the same effect is Munn v. Illinois, 94 U. S.
113 . In Olcott v.
Supervisor , 16 Wall. 678, it was ruled that Page 109 U. S. 38 railroads are public highways, established by authority of the
State for the public use; that they are nonetheless public highways
because controlled and owned by private corporations; that it is a
part of the function of government to make and maintain highways
for the convenience of the public; that no matter who is the agent,
or what is the agency, the function performed is that of the
State; that, although the owners may be private companies,
they may be compelled to permit the public to use these works in
the manner in which they can be used; that, upon these grounds
alone have the courts sustained the investiture of railroad
corporations with the State's right of eminent domain, or the right
of municipal corporations, under legislative authority, to assess,
levy and collect taxes to aid in the construction of railroads. So
in Township of Queensbury v.
Culver , 19 Wall. 83, it was said that a municipal
subscription of railroad stock was in aid of the construction and
maintenance of a public highway, and for the promotion of a public
use. Again, in Township of Pine Grove v.
Talcott , 19 Wall. 666: "Though the corporation
[railroad] was private, its work was public, as much so as if it
were to be constructed by the State." To the like effect are
numerous adjudications in this and the State courts with which the
profession is familiar. The Supreme Judicial Court of
Massachusetts, in Inhabitants of Worcester v. The Western R.R.
Corporation, 4 Met. 564, said in reference to a railroad:
"The establishment of that great thoroughfare is regarded as a
public work, established by public authority, intended for the
public use and benefit, the use of which is secured to the whole
community, and constitutes, therefore, like a canal, turnpike, or
highway, a public easement. . . . It is true that the real and
personal property, necessary to the establishment and management of
the railroad is vested in the corporation, but it is in trust for
the public."
In Erie, Etc., R.R. Co. v. Casey, 26 Penn. St. 287, the
court, referring to an act repealing the charter of a railroad, and
under which the State took possession of the road, said:
"It is a public highway, solemnly devoted to public use. When
the lands were taken, it was for such use, or they could not have
been taken at all. . . . Railroads established Page 109 U. S. 39 upon land taken by the right of eminent domain by authority of
the commonwealth, created by her laws as thoroughfares for
commerce, are her highways. No corporation has property in them,
though it may have franchises annexed to and exercisable within
them."
In many courts it has been held that, because of the public
interest in such a corporation, the land of a railroad company
cannot be levied on and sold under execution by a creditor. The sum
of the adjudged cases is that a railroad corporation is a
governmental agency, created primarily for public purposes and
subject to be controlled for the public benefit. Upon this ground,
the State, when unfettered by contract, may regulate, in its
discretion, the rates of fares of passengers and freight. And upon
this ground, too, the State may regulate the entire management of
railroads in all matters affecting the convenience and safety of
the public, as, for example, by regulating speed, compelling stops
of prescribed length at stations, and prohibiting discriminations
and favoritism. If the corporation neglect or refuse to discharge
its duties to the public, it may be coerced to do so by appropriate
proceedings in the name or in behalf of the State.
Such being the relations these corporations hold to the public,
it would seem that the right of a colored person to use an improved
public highway upon the terms accorded to freemen of other races is
as fundamental, in the state of freedom established in this
country, as are any of the rights which my brethren concede to be
so far fundamental as to be deemed the essence of civil freedom.
"Personal liberty consists," says Blackstone,
"in the power of locomotion, of changing situation, or removing
one's person to whatever places one's own inclination may direct,
without restraint unless by due course of law."
But of what value is this right of locomotion if it may be
clogged by such burdens as Congress intended by the act of 1875 to
remove? They are burdens which lay at the very foundation of the
institution of slavery as it once existed. They are not to be
sustained except upon the assumption that there is, in this land of
universal liberty, a class which may still be discriminated
against, even in respect of rights of a character Page 109 U. S. 40 so necessary and supreme that, deprived of their enjoyment in
common with others, a freeman is not only branded as one inferior
and infected, but, in the competitions of life, is robbed of some
of the most essential means of existence, and all this solely
because they belong to a particular race which the nation has
liberated. The Thirteenth Amendment alone obliterated the race line
so far as all rights fundamental in a state of freedom are
concerned. Second, as to inns. The same general observations which
have been made as to railroads are applicable to inns. The word
"inn" has a technical legal signification. It means, in the act of
1875, just what it meant at common law. A mere private boarding
house is not an inn, nor is its keeper subject to the
responsibilities, or entitled to the privileges, of a common
innkeeper.
"To constitute one an innkeeper within the legal force of that
term, he must keep a house of entertainment or lodging for all
travelers or wayfarers who might choose to accept the same, being
of good character or conduct."
Redfield on Carriers, etc., § 7. Says Judge Story:
"An innkeeper may be defined to be the keeper of a common inn
for the lodging and entertainment of travelers and passengers,
their horses and attendants. An innkeeper is bound to take in all
travelers and wayfaring persons, and to entertain them, if he can
accommodate them, for a reasonable compensation, and he must guard
their goods with proper diligence. . . . If an innkeeper improperly
refuses to receive or provide for a guest, he is liable to be
indicted therefor. . . . They (carriers of passengers) are no more
at liberty to refuse a passenger, if they have sufficient room and
accommodations, than an innkeeper is to refuse suitable room and
accommodations to a guest."
"Story on Bailments §§ 475-476."
In Rex v. Ivens, 7 Carrington & Payne 213, 32
E.C.L. 49, the court, speaking by Mr. Justice Coleridge, said:
"An indictment lies against an innkeeper who refuses to receive
a guest, he having at the time room in his house and either the
price of the guest's entertainment being tendered to him or such
circumstances occurring as will dispense with that Page 109 U. S. 41 tender. This law is founded in good sense. The innkeeper is not
to select his guest. He has no right to say to one, you shall come
to my inn, and to another, you shall not, as everyone coming and
conducting himself in a proper manner has a right to be received,
and, for this purpose innkeepers are a sort of public servants,
they having, in return a kind of privilege of entertaining
travelers and supplying them with what they want."
These authorities are sufficient to show that a keeper of an inn
is in the exercise of a quasi -public employment. The law
gives him special privileges. and he is charged with certain duties
and responsibilities to the public. The public nature of his
employment forbids him from discriminating against any person
asking admission as a guest on account of the race or color of that
person. Third. As to places of public amusement. It may be
argued that the managers of such places have no duties to perform
with which the public are, in any legal sense, concerned, or with
which the public have any right to interfere, and that the
exclusion of a black man from a place of public amusement on
account of his race, or the denial to him on that ground of equal
accommodations at such places, violates no legal right for the
vindication of which he may invoke the aid of the courts. My answer
is that places of public amusement, within the meaning of the act
of 1875, are such as are established and maintained under direct
license of the law. The authority to establish and maintain them
comes from the public. The colored race is a part of that public.
The local government granting the license represents them as well
as all other races within its jurisdiction. A license from the
public to establish a place of public amusement imports in law
equality of right at such places among all the members of that
public. This must be so unless it be -- which I deny -- that the
common municipal government of all the people may, in the exertion
of its powers, conferred for the benefit of all, discriminate or
authorize discrimination against a particular race solely because
of its former condition of servitude.
I also submit, whether it can be said -- in view of the
doctrines of this court as announced in Munn v.
State of Illinois , Page 109 U. S. 42 94 U. S. 113 , and
reaffirmed in Peik v. Chicago & N.W. Railway Co., 94 U. S. 164 , 169
[argument of counsel -- omitted], that the management of places of
public amusement is a purely private matter, with which government
has no rightful concern? In the Munn case, the question
was whether the State of Illinois could fix, by law, the maximum of
charges for the storage of grain in certain warehouses in that
State -- the private property of individual citizens. After quoting a remark attributed to Lord Chief Justice Hale, to
the effect that, when private property is "affected with a public
interest, it ceases to be juris privati only," the court
says:
"Property does become clothed with a public interest when used
in a manner to make it of public consequence and affect the
community at large. When, therefore, one devotes his property to a
use in which the public has an interest, he, in effect, grants to
the public an interest in that use, and must submit to be
controlled by the public for the common good to the extent of the
interest he has thus created. He may withdraw his grant by
discontinuing the use, but, so long as he maintains the use, he
must submit to the control."
The doctrines of Munn v. Illinois have never been
modified by this court, and I am justified upon the authority of
that case in saying that places of public amusement, conducted
under the authority of the law, are clothed with a public interest
because used in a manner to make them of public consequence and to
affect the community at large. The law may therefore regulate, to
some extent, the mode in which they shall be conducted, and,
consequently, the public have rights in respect of such places
which may be vindicated by the law. It is consequently not a matter
purely of private concern.
Congress has not, in these matters, entered the domain of State
control and supervision. It does not, as I have said, assume to
prescribe the general conditions and limitations under which inns,
public conveyances, and places of public amusement shall be
conducted or managed. It simply declares, in effect, that, since
the nation has established universal freedom in this country for
all time, there shall be no discrimination, based merely upon race
or color, in respect of the accommodations Page 109 U. S. 43 and advantages of public conveyances, inns, and places of public
amusement.
I am of the opinion that such discrimination practised by
corporations and individuals in the exercise of their public or quasi -public functions is a badge of servitude the
imposition of which Congress may prevent under its power, by
appropriate legislation, to enforce the Thirteenth Amendment; and
consequently, without reference to its enlarged power under the
Fourteenth Amendment, the act of March 1, 1875, is not, in my
judgment, repugnant to the Constitution.
It remains now to consider these cases with reference to the
power Congress has possessed since the adoption of the Fourteenth
Amendment. Much that has been said as to the power of Congress
under the Thirteenth Amendment is applicable to this branch of the
discussion, and will not be repeated.
Before the adoption of the recent amendments, it had become, as
we have seen, the established doctrine of this court that negroes,
whose ancestors had been imported and sold as slaves, could not
become citizens of a State, or even of the United States, with the
rights and privileges guaranteed to citizens by the national
Constitution; further, that one might have all the rights and
privileges of a citizen of a State without being a citizen in the
sense in which that word was used in the national Constitution, and
without being entitled to the privileges and immunities of citizens
of the several States. Still further, between the adoption of the
Thirteenth Amendment and the proposal by Congress of the Fourteenth
Amendment, on June 16, 1866, the statute books of several of the
States, as we have seen, had become loaded down with enactments
which, under the guise of Apprentice, Vagrant, and contract
regulations, sought to keep the colored race in a condition,
practically, of servitude. It was openly announced that whatever
might be the rights which persons of that race had as freemen,
under the guarantees of the national Constitution, they could not
become citizens of a State, with the privileges belonging to
citizens, except by the consent of such State; consequently, that
their civil rights as citizens of the State depended entirely upon
State legislation. To meet this new peril to the black race, that
the Page 109 U. S. 44 purposes of the nation might not be doubted or defeated, and by
way of further enlargement of the power of Congress, the Fourteenth
Amendment was proposed for adoption.
Remembering that this court, in the Slaughterhouse
Cases, declared that the one pervading purpose found in all
the recent amendments, lying at the foundation of each and without
which none of them would have been suggested, was
"the freedom of the slave race, the security and firm
establishment of that freedom, and the protection of the newly made
freeman and citizen from the oppression of those who had formerly
exercised unlimited dominion over him"
-- that each amendment was addressed primarily to the grievances
of that race -- let us proceed to consider the language of the
Fourteenth Amendment.
Its first and fifth sections are in these words:
"SEC. 1. All persons born or naturalized in the United States,
and subject to the jurisdiction thereof, are citizens of the United
States and of the State wherein they reside. No State shall make or
enforce any law which shall abridge the privileges or immunities of
citizens of the United States; nor shall any State deprive any
person of life, liberty, or property, without due process of law;
nor deny to any person within its jurisdiction the equal protection
of the laws."
" * * * *" "SEC. 5. That Congress shall have power to enforce, by
appropriate legislation, the provisions of this article."
It was adjudged in Strauder v. West Virginia, 100 U. S. 303 , and Ex parte Virginia, 100 U. S. 339 , and
my brethren concede, that positive rights and privileges were
intended to be secured, and are, in fact, secured, by the
Fourteenth Amendment.
But when, under what circumstances, and to what extent may
Congress, by means of legislation, exert its power to enforce the
provisions of this amendment? The theory of the opinion of the
majority of the court -- the foundation upon which their reasoning
seems to rest -- is that the general government cannot, in advance
of hostile State laws or hostile State Page 109 U. S. 45 proceedings, actively interfere for the protection of my of the
rights, privileges, and immunities secured by the Fourteenth
Amendment. It is said that such rights, privileges, and immunities
are secured by way of prohibition against State laws and
State proceedings affecting such rights and privileges, and by
power given to Congress to legislate for the purpose of carrying such prohibition into effect; also, that congressional
legislation must necessarily be predicated upon such supposed State
laws or State proceedings, and be directed to the correction of
their operation and effect.
In illustration of its position, the court refers to the clause
of the Constitution forbidding the passage by a State of any law
impairing the obligation of contracts. That clause does not, I
submit, furnish a proper illustration of the scope and effect of
the fifth section of the Fourteenth Amendment. No express power is
given Congress to enforce, by primary direct legislation, the
prohibition upon State laws impairing the obligation of contracts.
Authority is, indeed, conferred to enact all necessary and proper
laws for carrying into execution the enumerated powers of Congress
and all other powers vested by the Constitution in the government
of the United States or in any department or officer thereof. And,
as heretofore shown, there is also, by necessary implication, power
in Congress, by legislation, to protect a right derived from the
national Constitution. But a prohibition upon a State is not a
power in Congress or in the national government. It is simply a denial of power to the State. And the only
mode in which the inhibition upon State laws impairing the
obligation of contracts can be enforced is indirectly, through the
courts in suits where the parties raise some question as to the
constitutional validity of such laws. The judicial power of the
United States extends to such suits for the reason that they are
suits arising under the Constitution. The Fourteenth Amendment
presents the first instance in our history of the investiture of
Congress with affirmative power, by legislation, to enforce an express prohibition upon the States. It is not
said that the judicial power of the nation may be exerted
for the enforcement of that amendment. No enlargement of the
judicial power was required, for it is clear Page 109 U. S. 46 that, had the fifth section of the Fourteenth Amendment been
entirely omitted, the judiciary could have stricken down all State
laws and nullified all State proceedings in hostility to rights and
privileges secured or recognized by that amendment. The power given
is, in terms, by congressional legislation, to enforce the
provisions of the amendment.
The assumption that this amendment consists wholly of
prohibitions upon State laws and State proceedings in hostility to
its provisions is unauthorized by its language. The first clause of
the first section --
"All persons born or naturalized in the United States, and
subject to the jurisdiction thereof, are citizens of the United
States, and of the State wherein they reside"
-- is of a distinctly affirmative character. In its application
to the colored race, previously liberated, it created and granted
as well citizenship of the United States as citizenship of the
State in which they respectively resided. It introduced all of that
race whose ancestors had been imported and sold as slaves at once
into the political community known as the "People of the United
States." They became instantly citizens of the United States and of
their respective States. Further, they were brought by this supreme
act of the nation within the direct operation of that provision of
the Constitution which declares that "the citizens of each State
shall be entitled to all privileges and immunities of citizens in
the several States." Art. 4, § 2.
The citizenship thus acquired by that race in virtue of an
affirmative grant from the nation may be protected not alone by the
judicial branch of the government, but by congressional legislation
of a primary direct character, this because the power of Congress
is not restricted to the enforcement of prohibitions upon State
laws or State action. It is, in terms distinct and positive, to
enforce "the provisions of this article " of amendment; not
simply those of a prohibitive character, but the provisions -- all of the provisions -- affirmative and prohibitive, of
the amendment. It is, therefore, a grave misconception to suppose
that the fifth section of the amendment has reference exclusively
to express prohibitions upon State laws or State action. If any
right was created by that amendment, the Page 109 U. S. 47 grant of power through appropriate legislation to enforce its
provisions authorizes Congress, by means of legislation operating
throughout the entire Union, to guard, secure, and protect that
right.
It is therefore an essential inquiry what, if any, right,
privilege or immunity was given, by the nation to colored persons
when they were made citizens of the State in which they reside? Did
the constitutional grant of State citizenship to that race, of its
own force, invest them with any rights, privileges and immunities
whatever? That they became entitled, upon the adoption of the
Fourteenth Amendment, "to all privileges and immunities of citizens
in the several States," within the meaning of section 2 of article
4 of the Constitution, no one, I suppose, will for a moment
question. What are the privileges and immunities to which, by that
clause of the Constitution, they became entitled? To this it may be
answered generally, upon the authority of the adjudged cases, that
they are those which are fundamental in citizenship in a free
republican government, such as are "common to the citizens in the
latter States under their constitutions and laws by virtue of their
being citizens." Of that provision it has been said, with the
approval of this court, that no other one in the Constitution has
tended so strongly to constitute the citizens of the United States
one people. Ward v.
Maryland , 12 Wall. 418; Corfield v.
Coryell, 4 Wash.C.C. 371; Paul v.
Virginia , 8 Wall. 168; Slaughterhouse
Cases , 16 id. 36.
Although this court has wisely forborne any attempt by a
comprehensive definition to indicate all of the privileges and
immunities to which the citizen of a State is entitled of right
when within the jurisdiction of other States, I hazard nothing, in
view of former adjudications, in saying that no State can sustain
her denial to colored citizens of other States, while within her
limits, of privileges or immunities fundamental in republican
citizenship upon the ground that she accords such privileges and
immunities only to her white citizens, and withholds them from her
colored citizens. The colored citizens of other States, within the
jurisdiction of that State, could claim, in virtue of section 2 of
article 4 of the Constitution, every privilege and immunity Page 109 U. S. 48 which that State secures to her white citizens. Otherwise it
would be in the power of any State, by discriminating class
legislation against its own citizens of a particular race or color,
to withhold from citizens of other States belonging to that
proscribed race, when within her limits, privileges and immunities
of the character regarded by all courts as fundamental in
citizenship, and that too when the constitutional guaranty is that
the citizens of each State shall be entitled to "all privileges and
immunities of citizens of the several States." No State may, by
discrimination against a portion of its own citizens of a
particular race, in respect of privileges and immunities
fundamental in citizenship, impair the constitutional right of
citizens of other States, of whatever race, to enjoy in that State
all such privileges and immunities as are there accorded to her
most favored citizens. A colored citizen of Ohio or Indiana, while
in the jurisdiction of Tennessee, is entitled to enjoy any
privilege or immunity, fundamental in citizenship, which is given
to citizens of the white race in the latter State. It is not to be
supposed that anyone will controvert this proposition.
But what was secured to colored citizens of the United States --
as between them and their respective States -- by the national
grant to them of State citizenship? With what rights, privileges,
or immunities did this grant invest them? There is one, if there be
no other -- exemption from race discrimination in respect of any
civil right belonging to citizens of the white race in the same
State. That, surely, is their constitutional privilege when within
the jurisdiction of other States. And such must be their
constitutional right in their own State, unless the recent
amendments be splendid baubles thrown out to delude those who
deserved fair and generous treatment at the hands of the nation.
Citizenship in this country necessarily imports at least equality
of civil rights among citizens of every race in the same State. It
is fundamental in American citizenship that, in respect of such
rights, there shall be no discrimination by the State, or its
officers, or by individuals or corporations exercising public
functions or authority, against any citizen because of his race or
previous condition of servitude. In United States v.
Cruikshank, 92 U. S. 542 , it
was said at page 92 U. S. 555 ,
that the Page 109 U. S. 49 rights of life and personal liberty are natural rights of man,
and that "the equality of the rights of citizens is a principle of
republicanism." And in Ex parte Virginia, 100
U. S. 334 , the emphatic language of this court is
that
"one great purpose of these amendments was to raise the colored
race from that condition of inferiority and servitude in which most
of them had previously stood into perfect equality of civil rights
with all other persons within the jurisdiction of the States."
So, in Strauder v. West Virginia, 100 U.S. at 100 U. S. 306 ,
the court, alluding to the Fourteenth Amendment, said:
"This is one of a series of constitutional provisions having a
common purpose, namely, securing to a race recently emancipated, a
race that, through many generations, had been held in slavery, all
the civil rights that the superior race enjoy."
Again, in Neal v. Delaware, 103
U. S. 386 , it was ruled that this amendment was designed
primarily
"to secure to the colored race, thereby invested with the
rights, privileges, and responsibilities of citizenship, the
enjoyment of all the civil rights that, under the law, are enjoyed
by white persons."
The language of this court with reference to the Fifteenth
Amendment adds to the force of this view. In United States v.
Cruikshank, it was said:
"In United States v. Reese, 92 U. S.
214 , we held that the Fifteenth Amendment has invested
the citizens of the United States with a new constitutional right,
which is exemption from discrimination in tho exercise of the
elective franchise, on account of race, color, or previous
condition of servitude. From this it appears that the right of
suffrage is not a necessary attribute of national citizenship, but
that exemption from discrimination in the exercise of that right on
account of race, &c., is. The right to vote in the States comes
from the States, but the right of exemption from the prohibited
discrimination comes from the United States. The first has not been
granted or secured by the Constitution of the United States, but
the last has been."
Here, in language at once clear and forcible, is stated the
principle for which I contend. It can scarcely be claimed that
exemption from race discrimination, in respect of civil rights,
against those to whom State citizenship was granted by the Page 109 U. S. 50 nation, is any less, for the colored race, a new constitutional
right, derived from and secured by the national Constitution, than
is exemption from such discrimination in the exercise of the
elective franchise. It cannot be that the latter is an attribute of
national citizenship, while the other is not essential in national
citizenship or fundamental in State citizenship.
If, then, exemption from discrimination in respect of civil
rights is a new constitutional right, secured by the grant of State
citizenship to colored citizens of the United States -- and I do
not see how this can now be questioned -- why may not the nation,
by means of its own legislation of a primary direct character,
guard, protect, and enforce that right? It is a right and privilege
which the nation conferred. It did not come from the States in
which those colored citizens reside. It has been the established
doctrine of this court during all its history, accepted as
essential to the national supremacy, that Congress, in the absence
of a positive delegation of power to the State legislatures, may,
by its own legislation, enforce and protect any right derived from
or created by the national Constitution. It was so declared in Prigg v. Commonwealth of Pennsylvania. It was reiterated
in United States v. Reese, 92 U. S.
214 , where the court said that
"rights and immunities created by and dependent upon the
Constitution of the United States can be protected by Congress. The
form and manner of the protection may be such as Congress, in the
legitimate exercise of its discretion, shall provide. These may be
varied to meet the necessities of the particular right to be
protected."
It was distinctly reaffirmed in Strauder v. West
Virginia, 100 U.S. at 100 U. S. 310 , where we said that
"a right or immunity created by the Constitution or only
guaranteed by it, even without any express delegation of power, may
be protected by Congress."
How then can it be claimed, in view of the declarations of this
court in former cases, that exemption of colored citizens, within
their States, from race discrimination in respect of the civil
rights of citizens is not an immunity created or derived from the
national Constitution?
This court has always given a broad and liberal construction to
the Constitution, so as to enable Congress, by legislation, to Page 109 U. S. 51 enforce rights secured by that instrument. The legislation which
Congress may enact in execution of its power to enforce the
provisions of this amendment is such as may be appropriate to
protect the right granted. The word appropriate was undoubtedly
used with reference to its meaning, as established by repeated
decisions of this court. Under given circumstances, that which the
court characterizes as corrective legislation might be deemed by
Congress appropriate and entirely sufficient. Under other
circumstances, primary direct legislation may be required. But it
is for Congress, not the judiciary, to say that legislation is
appropriate -- that is, best adapted to the end to be attained. The
judiciary may not, with safety to our institutions, enter the
domain of legislative discretion and dictate the means which
Congress shall employ in the exercise of its granted powers. That
would be sheer usurpation of the functions of a coordinate
department, which, if often repeated, and permanently acquiesced
in, would work a radical change in our system of government. In United States v. Fisher, 2 Cr. 38, the court said that
"Congress must possess the choice of means, and must be
empowered to use any means which are, in fact, conducive to the
exercise of a power granted by the Constitution. . . . The sound
construction of the Constitution,"
said Chief Justice Marshall,
"must allow to the national legislature that discretion, with
respect to the means by which the powers it confers are to be
carried into execution, which will enable that body to perform the
high duties assigned to it in the manner most beneficial to the
people. Let the end be legitimate, let it be within the scope of
the Constitution, and all means which are appropriate, which are
plainly adapted to that end, which are not prohibited, but consist
with the letter and spirit of the Constitution, are
constitutional." McCulloch v.
Maryland , 4 Wheat. 421.
Must these rules of construction be now abandoned? Are the
powers of the national legislature to be restrained in proportion
as the rights and privileges, derived from the nation, are
valuable? Are constitutional provisions, enacted to secure the
dearest rights of freemen and citizens, to be subjected to that
rule of construction, applicable to private instruments, Page 109 U. S. 52 which requires that the words to be interpreted must be taken
most strongly against those who employ them? Or shall it be
remembered that
"a constitution of government, founded by the people for
themselves and their posterity and for objects of the most
momentous nature -- for perpetual union, for the establishment of
justice, for the general welfare, and for a perpetuation of the
blessings of liberty -- necessarily requires that every
interpretation of its powers should have a constant reference to
these objects? No interpretation of the words in which those powers
are granted can be a sound one which narrows down their ordinary
import so as to defeat those objects."
Story Const. § 422.
The opinion of the court, as I have said, proceeds upon the
ground that the power of Congress to legislate for the protection
of the rights and privileges secured by the Fourteenth Amendment
cannot be brought into activity except with the view, and as it may
become necessary, to correct and annul State laws and State
proceedings in hostility to such rights and privileges. In the
absence of State laws or State action adverse to such rights and
privileges, the nation may not actively interfere for their
protection and security, even against corporations and individuals
exercising public or quasi -public functions. Such I
understand to be the position of my brethren. If the grant to
colored citizens of the United States of citizenship in their
respective States imports exemption from race discrimination in
their States in respect of such civil rights as belong to
citizenship, then to hold that the amendment remits that right to
the States for their protection, primarily, and stays the hands of
the nation until it is assailed by State laws or State proceedings
is to adjudge that the amendment, so far from enlarging the powers
of Congress -- as we have heretofore said it did -- not only
curtails them, but reverses the policy which the general government
has pursued from its very organization. Such an interpretation of
the amendment is a denial to Congress of the power, by appropriate
legislation, to enforce one of its provisions. In view of the
circumstances under which the recent amendments were incorporated
into the Constitution, and especially in view of the peculiar
character of the new Page 109 U. S. 53 rights they created and secured, it ought not to be presumed
that the general government has abdicated its authority, by
national legislation, direct and primary in its character, to guard
and protect privileges and immunities secured by that instrument.
Such an interpretation of the Constitution ought not to be accepted
if it be possible to avoid it. Its acceptance would lead to this
anomalous result: that, whereas, prior to the amendments, Congress,
with the sanction of this court, passed the most stringent laws --
operating directly and primarily upon States and their officers and
agents, as well as upon individuals -- in vindication of slavery
and the right of the master, it may not now, by legislation of a
like primary and direct character, guard, protect, and secure the
freedom established, and the most essential right of the
citizenship granted, by the constitutional amendments. With all
respect for the opinion of others, I insist that the national
legislature may, without transcending the limits of the
Constitution, do for human liberty and the fundamental rights of
American citizenship what it did, with the sanction of this court,
for the protection of slavery and the rights of the masters of
fugitive slaves. If fugitive slave laws, providing modes and
prescribing penalties whereby the master could seize and recover
his fugitive slave, were legitimate exercises of an implied power
to protect and enforce a right recognized by the Constitution, why
shall the hands of Congress be tied so that -- under an express
power, by appropriate legislation, to enforce a constitutional
provision granting citizenship -- it may not, by means of direct
legislation, bring the whole power of this nation to bear upon
States and their officers and upon such individuals and
corporations exercising public functions as assume to abridge,
impair, or deny rights confessedly secured by the supreme law of
the land?
It does not seem to me that the fact that, by the second clause
of the first section of the Fourteenth Amendment, the States are
expressly prohibited from making or enforcing laws abridging the
privileges and immunities of citizens of the United States
furnishes any sufficient reason for holding or maintaining that the
amendment was intended to deny Congress the power, by general,
primary, and direct legislation, of Page 109 U. S. 54 protecting citizens of the several States, being also citizens
of the United States, against all discrimination in respect of
their rights as citizens which is founded on race, color, or
previous condition of servitude.
Such an interpretation of the amendment is plainly repugnant to
its fifth section, conferring upon Congress power, by appropriate
legislation, to enforce not merely the provisions containing
prohibitions upon the States, but all of the provisions of the
amendment, including the provisions, express and implied, in the
first clause of the first section of the article granting
citizenship. This alone is sufficient for holding that Congress is
not restricted to the enactment of laws adapted to counteract and
redress the operation of State legislation, or the action of State
officers, of the character prohibited by the amendment. It was
perfectly well known that the great danger to the equal enjoyment
by citizens of their rights as citizens was to be apprehended not
altogether from unfriendly State legislation, but from the hostile
action of corporations and individuals in the States. And it is to
be presumed that it was intended by that section to clothe Congress
with power and authority to meet that danger. If the rights
intended to be secured by the act of 1875 are such as belong to the
citizen in common or equally with other citizens in the same State,
then it is not to be denied that such legislation is peculiarly
appropriate to the end which Congress is authorized to accomplish, viz., to protect the citizen, in respect of such rights,
against discrimination on account of his race. Recurring to the
specific prohibition in the Fourteenth Amendment upon the making or
enforcing of State laws abridging the privileges of citizens of the
United States, I remark that if, as held in the Slaughterhouse
Cases, the privileges here referred to were those which
belonged to citizenship of the United States, as distinguished from
those belonging to State citizenship, it was impossible for any
State prior to the adoption of that amendment to have enforced laws
of that character. The judiciary could have annulled all such
legislation under the provision that the Constitution shall be the
supreme law of the land, anything in the constitution or laws of
any State to the contrary notwithstanding. The States were Page 109 U. S. 55 already under an implied prohibition not to abridge any
privilege or immunity belonging to citizens of the United States as
such. Consequently, the prohibition upon State laws in hostility to
rights belonging to citizens of the United States was intended --
in view of the introduction into the body of citizens of a race
formerly denied the essential rights of citizenship -- only as an
express limitation on the powers of the States, and was not
intended to diminish in the slightest degree the authority which
the nation has always exercised of protecting, by means of its own
direct legislation, rights created or secured by the Constitution.
Any purpose to diminish the national authority in respect of
privileges derived from the nation is distinctly negatived by the
express grant of power by legislation to enforce every provision of
the amendment, including that which, by the grant of citizenship in
the State, secures exemption from race discrimination in respect of
the civil rights of citizens.
It is said that any interpretation of the Fourteenth Amendment
different from that adopted by the majority of the court would
imply that Congress had authority to enact a municipal code for all
the States covering every matter affecting the life, liberty, and
property of the citizens of the several States. Not so. Prior to
the adoption of that amendment, the constitutions of the several
States, without perhaps an exception, secured all persons against deprivation of life, liberty, or property otherwise than by
due process of law, and, in some form, recognized the right of all persons to the equal protection of the laws. Those rights
therefore existed before that amendment was proposed or adopted,
and were not created by it. If, by reason of that fact, it be
assumed that protection in these rights of persons still rests
primarily with the States, and that Congress may not interfere
except to enforce, by means of corrective legislation, the
prohibitions upon State laws or State proceedings inconsistent with
those rights, it does not at all follow that privileges which have
been granted by the nation may not be protected by primary
legislation upon the part of Congress. The personal rights and
immunities recognized in the prohibitive clauses of the amendment
were, prior to its adoption, Page 109 U. S. 56 under the protection, primarily, of the States, while rights,
created by or derived from the United States have always been and,
in the nature of things, should always be, primarily under the
protection of the general government. Exemption from race
discrimination in respect of the civil rights which are fundamental
in citizenship in a republican government, is, as we have
seen, a new right, created by the nation, with express power in
Congress, by legislation, to enforce the constitutional provision
from which it is derived. If, in some sense, such race
discrimination is, within the letter of the last clause of the
first section, a denial of that equal protection of the laws which
is secured against State denial to all persons, whether citizens or
not, it cannot be possible that a mere prohibition upon such State
denial, or a prohibition upon State laws abridging the privileges
and immunities of citizens of the United States, takes from the
nation the power which it has uniformly exercised of protecting, by
direct primary legislation, those privileges and immunities which
existed under the Constitution before the adoption of the
Fourteenth Amendment or have been created by that amendment in
behalf of those thereby made citizens of their respective
States.
This construction does not in any degree intrench upon the just
rights of the States in the control of their domestic affairs. It
simply recognizes the enlarged powers conferred by the recent
amendments upon the general government. In the view which I take of
those amendments, the States possess the same authority which they
have always had to define and regulate the civil rights which their
own people, in virtue of State citizenship, may enjoy within their
respective limits, except that its exercise is now subject to the
expressly granted power of Congress, by legislation, to enforce the
provisions of such amendments -- a power which necessarily carries
with it authority, by national legislation, to protect and secure
the privileges and immunities which are created by or are derived
from those amendments. That exemption of citizens from
discrimination based on race or color, in respect of civil rights,
is one of those privileges or immunities can no longer be deemed an
open question in this court. Page 109 U. S. 57 It was said of the case of Dred Scott v. Sandford that
this court there overruled the action of two generations, virtually
inserted a new clause in the Constitution, changed its character,
and made a new departure in the workings of the federal government.
I may be permitted to say that, if the recent amendments are so
construed that Congress may not, in its own discretion and
independently of the action or nonaction of the States, provide by
legislation of a direct character for the security of rights
created by the national Constitution, if it be adjudged that the
obligation to protect the fundamental privileges and immunities
granted by the Fourteenth Amendment to citizens residing in the
several States rests primarily not on the nation, but on the
States, if it be further adjudged that individuals and corporations
exercising public functions or wielding power under public
authority may, without liability to direct primary legislation on
the part of Congress, make the race of citizens the ground for
denying them that equality of civil rights which the Constitution
ordains as a principle of republican citizenship, then not only the
foundations upon which the national supremacy has always securely
rested will be materially disturbed, but we shall enter upon an era
of constitutional law when the rights of freedom and American
citizenship cannot receive from the nation that efficient
protection which heretofore was unhesitatingly accorded to slavery
and the rights of the master.
But if it were conceded that the power of Congress could not be
brought into activity until the rights specified in the act of 1875
had been abridged or denied by some State law or State action, I
maintain that the decision of the court is erroneous. There has
been adverse State action within the Fourteenth Amendment as
heretofore interpreted by this court. I allude to Ex parte
Virginia, supra. It appears in that case that one Cole, judge
of a county court, was charged with the duty by the laws of
Virginia of selecting grand and petit jurors. The law of the State
did not authorize or permit him, in making such selections, to
discriminate against colored citizens because of their race. But he
was indicted in the federal court, under the act of 1875, for
making such discriminations. Page 109 U. S. 58 The attorney general of Virginia contended before us that the
State had done its duty, and had not authorized or directed that
county judge to do what he was charged with having done; that the
State had not denied to the colored race the equal protection of
the laws, and that consequently the act of Cole must be deemed his
individual act, in contravention of the will of the State.
Plausible as this argument was, it failed to convince this court,
and after saying that the Fourteenth Amendment had reference to the
political body denominated a State "by whatever instruments or in
whatever modes that action may be taken," and that a State acts by
its legislative, executive, and judicial authorities, and can act
in no other way, we proceeded:
"The constitutional provision, therefore, must mean that no
agency of the State or of the officers or agents by whom its powers
are exerted shall deny to any person within its jurisdiction the
equal protection of the laws. Whoever, by virtue of public position
under a State government, deprives another of property, life, or
liberty without due process of law, or denies or takes away the
equal protection of the laws, violates the constitutional
inhibition; and, as he acts under the name and for the State, and
is clothed with the State's power, his act is that of the State.
This must be so, or the constitutional prohibition has no meaning.
Then the State has clothed one of its agents with power to annul or
evade it. But the constitutional amendment was ordained for a
purpose. It was to secure equal rights to all persons, and, to
insure to all persons the enjoyment of such rights, power was given
to Congress to enforce its provisions by appropriate legislation.
Such legislation must act upon persons, not upon the abstract thing
denominated a State, but upon the persons who are the agents of the
State in the denial of the rights which were intended to be
secured." Ex parte Virginia, 100 U. S.
346 -347.
In every material sense applicable to the practical enforcement
of the Fourteenth Amendment, railroad corporations, keepers of
inns, and managers of places of public amusement are agents or
instrumentalities of the State, because they are charged with Page 109 U. S. 59 duties to the public and are amenable, in respect of their
duties and functions, to governmental regulation. It seems to me
that, within the principle settled in Ex parte Virginia, a
denial by these instrumentalities of the State to the citizen,
because of his race, of that equality of civil rights secured to
him by law is a denial by the State within the meaning of the
Fourteenth Amendment. If it be not, then that race is left, in
respect of the civil rights in question, practically at the mercy
of corporations and individuals wielding power under the
States.
But the court says that Congress did not, in the act of 1866,
assume, under the authority given by the Thirteenth Amendment, to
adjust what may be called the social rights of men and races in the
community. I agree that government has nothing to do with social,
as distinguished from technically legal, rights of individuals. No
government ever has brought, or ever can bring, its people into
social intercourse against their wishes. Whether one person will
permit or maintain social relations with another is a matter with
which government has no concern. I agree that, if one citizen
chooses not to hold social intercourse with another, he is not and
cannot be made amenable to the law for his conduct in that regard,
for even upon grounds of race, no legal right of a citizen is
violated by the refusal of others to maintain merely social
relations with him. What I affirm is that no State, nor the
officers of any State, nor any corporation or individual wielding
power under State authority for the public benefit or the public
convenience, can, consistently either with the freedom established
by the fundamental law or with that equality of civil rights which
now belongs to every citizen, discriminate against freemen or
citizens in those rights because of their race, or because they
once labored under the disabilities of slavery imposed upon them as
a race. The rights which Congress, by the act of 1875, endeavored
to secure and protect are legal, not social, rights. The right, for
instance, of a colored citizen to use the accommodations of a
public highway upon the same terms as are permitted to white
citizens is no more a social right than his right under the law to
use the public streets of a city or a town, or a turnpike road, or
a public market, or a post office, or his right to sit Page 109 U. S. 60 in a public building with others, of whatever race, for the
purpose of hearing the political questions of the day discussed.
Scarcely a day passes without our seeing in this courtroom citizens
of the white and black races sitting side by side, watching the
progress of our business. It would never occur to anyone that the
presence of a colored citizen in a courthouse, or courtroom, was an
invasion of the social rights of white persons who may frequent
such places. And yet such a suggestion would be quite as sound in
law -- I say it with all respect -- as is the suggestion that the
claim of a colored citizen to use, upon the same terms as is
permitted to white citizens, the accommodations of public highways,
or public inns, or places of public amusement, established under
the license of the law, is an invasion of the social rights of the
white race.
The court, in its opinion, reserves the question whether
Congress, in the exercise of its power to regulate commerce amongst
the several States, might or might not pass a law regulating rights
in public conveyances passing from one State to another. I beg to
suggest that that precise question was substantially presented here
in the only one of these cases relating to railroads -- Robinson and Wife v. Memphis & Charleston Railroad
Company. In that case, it appears that Mrs. Robinson, a
citizen of Mississippi, purchased a railroad ticket entitling her
to be carried from Grand Junction, Tennessee, to Lynchburg,
Virginia. Might not the act of 1875 be maintained in that case as
applicable at least to commerce between the States, notwithstanding
it does not, upon its face, profess to have been passed in
pursuance of the power of Congress to regulate commerce? Has it
ever been held that the judiciary should overturn a statute because
the legislative department did not accurately recite therein the
particular provision of the Constitution authorizing its enactment?
We have often enforced municipal bonds in aid of railroad
subscriptions where they failed to recite the statute authorizing
their issue, but recited one which did not sustain their validity.
The inquiry in such cases has been was there, in any statute,
authority for the execution of the bonds? Upon this branch of the
case, it may be remarked that the State of Louisiana, in 1869,
passed a statute Page 109 U. S. 61 giving to passengers, without regard to race or color, equality
of right in the accommodations of railroad and street cars,
steamboats or other watercrafts, stage coaches, omnibuses, or other
vehicles. But in Hall v. De Cuir, 95 U.
S. 487 , that act was pronounced unconstitutional so far
as it related to commerce between the States, this court saying
that, "if the public good requires such legislation, it must come
from Congress, and not from the States." I suggest, that it may
become a pertinent inquiry whether Congress may, in the exertion of
its power to regulate commerce among the States, enforce among
passengers on public conveyances equality of right, without regard
to race, color or previous condition of servitude, if it be true --
which I do not admit -- that such legislation would be an
interference by government with the social rights of the
people.
My brethren say that, when a man has emerged from slavery, and
by the aid of beneficent legislation has shaken off the inseparable
concomitants of that state, there must be some stage in the
progress of his elevation when he takes the rank of a mere citizen,
and ceases to be the special favorite of the laws, and when his
rights as a citizen or a man are to be protected in the ordinary
modes by which other men's rights are protected. It is, I submit,
scarcely just to say that the colored race has been the special
favorite of the laws. The statute of 1875, now adjudged to be
unconstitutional, is for the benefit of citizens of every race and
color. What the nation, through Congress, has sought to accomplish
in reference to that race is what had already been done in every
State of the Union for the white race -- to secure and protect
rights belonging to them as freemen and citizens, nothing more. It
was not deemed enough "to help the feeble up, but to support him
after." The one underlying purpose of congressional legislation has
been to enable the black race to take the rank of mere citizens.
The difficulty has been to compel a recognition of the legal right
of the black race to take the rank of citizens, and to secure the
enjoyment of privileges belonging, under the law, to them as a
component part of the people for whose welfare and happiness
government is ordained. Page 109 U. S. 62 At every step in this direction, the nation has been confronted
with class tyranny, which a contemporary English historian says is,
of all tyrannies, the most intolerable,
"for it is ubiquitous in its operation and weighs perhaps most
heavily on those whose obscurity or distance would withdraw them
from the notice of a single despot."
Today it is the colored race which is denied, by corporations
and individuals wielding public authority, rights fundamental in
their freedom and citizenship. At some future time, it may be that
some other race will fall under the ban of race discrimination. If
the constitutional amendments be enforced according to the intent
with which, as I conceive, they were adopted, there cannot be, in
this republic, any class of human beings in practical subjection to
another class with power in the latter to dole out to the former
just such privileges as they may choose to grant. The supreme law
of the land has decreed that no authority shall be exercised in
this country upon the basis of discrimination, in respect of civil
rights, against freemen and citizens because of their race, color,
or previous condition of servitude. To that decree -- for the due
enforcement of which, by appropriate legislation, Congress has been
invested with express power -- everyone must bow, whatever may have
been, or whatever now are, his individual views as to the wisdom or
policy either of the recent changes in the fundamental law or of
the legislation which has been enacted to give them effect.
For the reasons stated, I feel constrained to withhold my assent
to the opinion of the court. | In the Civil Rights Cases of 1883, the U.S. Supreme Court ruled that the Civil Rights Act of 1875, which prohibited discrimination in public accommodations, was unconstitutional as applied to the states. The Court interpreted the Fourteenth Amendment as prohibiting state action that discriminated against individuals but did not authorize Congress to regulate the conduct of private individuals or entities.
The Court's decision effectively limited the reach of federal anti-discrimination laws and left the regulation of private discrimination to the states. This ruling was a significant setback for civil rights and contributed to the continued segregation and discrimination faced by racial minorities in the United States. |
Equal Protection | U.S. v. Carolene Products Co. | https://supreme.justia.com/cases/federal/us/304/144/ | U.S. Supreme Court United States v. Carolene Products
Co., 304
U.S. 144 (1938) United States v. Carolene Products
Co. No. 640 Argued April 6, 1938 Decided April 25,
1938 304
U.S. 144 APPEAL FROM THE DISTRICT COURT OF
THE UNITED STATES FOR THE SOUTHERN DISTRICT OF
ILLINOIS Syllabus The Filled Milk Act of Congress of Mar. 4, 1923, defines the
term Filled Milk as meaning any milk, cream, or skimmed milk,
whether or not condensed or dried, etc., to which has been added,
or which has been blended or compounded with, any fat or oil other
than milk fat, so that the resulting product is in imitation or
semblance of milk, cream, or skimmed milk, whether or not
condensed, dried, etc.; it declares that Filled Milk, as so
defined, "is an adulterated article of food, injurious to the
public health, and its sale constitutes a fraud upon the public",
and it forbids and penalizes the shipment of such Filled Milk in
interstate commerce. Defendant was indicted for shipping interstate
certain packages of an article described in the indictment as a
compound of condensed skimmed milk and coconut oil made in the
imitation or semblance of condensed milk or cream, and further
characterized by the indictment in the words of the statute, as "an
adulterated article of food, injurious to the public health." Held: Page 304 U. S. 145 1. That upon its face, and as supported by judicial knowledge,
including facts found in the reports of the congressional
committees, the Act is presumptively within the scope of the power
to regulate interstate commerce and consistent with due process.
Demurrer to the indictment should have been overruled. Hebe Co.
v. Shaw, 248 U. S. 297 . P. 304 U. S.
147 .
2. It is no valid objection that the prohibition of the Act does
not extend to oleomargarine or other butter substitutes in which
vegetable fats or oils replace butter. P. 304 U. S.
151 .
3. The statutory characterization of filled milk as injurious to
health and as a fraud upon the public may, for the purposes of this
case, be considered as a declaration of legislative findings deemed
to support the Act as a constitutional exertion of the legislative
power, aiding informed judicial review by revealing the rationale
of the legislation, as do the reports of legislative committees. P. 304 U. S.
152 . 7 F. Supp.
500 , reversed.
APPEAL under the Criminal Appeals Act from a judgment sustaining
a demurrer to an indictment.
MR. JUSTICE STONE delivered the opinion of the Court
The question for decision is whether the "Filled Milk Act" of
Congress of March 4, 1923 (c. 262, 42 Stat. 1486, 21 U.S.C. §
61-63), [ Footnote 1 ] which
prohibits the shipment in Page 304 U. S. 146 interstate commerce of skimmed milk compounded with any fat or
oil other than milk fat, so as to resemble milk or cream,
transcends the power of Congress to regulate interstate commerce or
infringes the Fifth Amendment.
Appellee was indicted in the district court for southern
Illinois for violation of the Act by the shipment in interstate
commerce of certain packages of "Milnut," a compound of condensed
skimmed milk and coconut oil made in imitation or semblance of
condensed milk or cream. The indictment states, in the words of the
statute, that Milnut "is an adulterated article of food, injurious
to the public health," and that it is not a prepared food product
of the type excepted from the prohibition of the Act. The trial
court sustained a demurrer to the indictment on the authority of an
earlier case in the same court, United States v. Carolene
Products Co., 7 F. Supp.
500 . The case was brought here on appeal under the Criminal
Appeals Act of March 2, 1907, 34 Stat. 1246, 18 U.S.C. § 682. The
Court of Appeals for the Seventh Circuit has meanwhile, in another
case, upheld the Filled Milk Act as an appropriate exercise of the
commerce power in Carolene Products Co. v. Evaporated Milk
Assn., 93 F. (2d) 202.
Appellee assails the statute as beyond the power of Congress
over interstate commerce, and hence an invasion of a field of
action said to be reserved to the states by the Tenth Amendment.
Appellee also complains that the Page 304 U. S. 147 statute denies to it equal protection of the laws and, in
violation of the Fifth Amendment, deprives it of its property
without due process of law, particularly in that the statute
purports to make binding and conclusive upon appellee the
legislative declaration that appellee's product "is an adulterated
article of food injurious to the public health and its sale
constitutes a fraud on the public." First. The power to regulate commerce is the power "to
prescribe the rule by which commerce is to be governed," Gibbons v.
Ogden , 9 Wheat. 1, 22 U. S. 196 , and
extends to the prohibition of shipments in such commerce. Reid
v. Colorado, 187 U. S. 137 ; Lottery Case, 188 U. S. 321 ; United States v. Delaware & Hudson Co., 213 U.
S. 366 ; Hope v. United States, 227 U.
S. 308 ; Clark Distilling Co. v. Western Maryland R.
Co., 242 U. S. 311 ; United States v. Hill, 248 U. S. 420 ; McCormick & Co. v. Brown, 286 U.
S. 131 . The power "is complete in itself, may be
exercised to its utmost extent, and acknowledges no limitations
other than are prescribed by the Constitution." Gibbons v.
Ogden, supra, 22 U. S. 196 .
Hence, Congress is free to exclude from interstate commerce
articles whose use in the states for which they are destined it may
reasonably conceive to be injurious to the public health, morals or
welfare, Reid v. Colorado, supra; Lottery Case, supra; Hipolite
Egg Co. v. United States, 220 U. S. 45 ; Hope v. United States, supra, or which contravene the
policy of the state of their destination. Kentucky Whip &
Collar Co. v. Illinois Central R. Co., 299 U.
S. 334 . Such regulation is not a forbidden invasion of
state power either because its motive or its consequence is to
restrict the use of articles of commerce within the states of
destination, and is not prohibited unless by the due process clause
of the Fifth Amendment. And it is no objection to the exertion of
the power to regulate interstate commerce that its exercise is
attended by the same incidents which attend the exercise of the
police power of the states. Seven Cases v. United States, 239 U. S. 510 , 239 U. S. 514 ; Hamilton v.
Kentucky Page 304 U. S. 148 Distilleries & Warehouse Co., 251 U.
S. 146 , 251 U. S. 156 .
The prohibition of the shipment of filled milk in interstate
commerce is a permissible regulation of commerce, subject only to
the restrictions of the Fifth Amendment. Second. The prohibition of shipment of appellee's
product in interstate commerce does not infringe the Fifth
Amendment. Twenty years ago, this Court, in Hebe Co. v.
Shaw, 248 U. S. 297 ,
held that a state law which forbids the manufacture and sale of a
product assumed to be wholesome and nutritive, made of condensed
skimmed milk, compounded with coconut oil, is not forbidden by the
Fourteenth Amendment. The power of the legislature to secure a
minimum of particular nutritive elements in a widely used article
of food and to protect the public from fraudulent substitutions was
not doubted, and the Court thought that there was ample scope for
the legislative judgment that prohibition of the offending article
was an appropriate means of preventing injury to the public.
We see no persuasive reason for departing from that ruling here,
where the Fifth Amendment is concerned, and since none is
suggested, we might rest decision wholly on the presumption of
constitutionality. But affirmative evidence also sustains the
statute. In twenty years, evidence has steadily accumulated of the
danger to the public health from the general consumption of foods
which have been stripped of elements essential to the maintenance
of health. The Filled Milk Act was adopted by Congress after
committee hearings, in the course of which eminent scientists and
health experts testified. An extensive investigation was made of
the commerce in milk compounds in which vegetable oils have been
substituted for natural milk fat, and of the effect upon the public
health of the use of such compounds as a food substitute for milk.
The conclusions drawn from evidence presented at the hearings were
embodied in reports of the Page 304 U. S. 149 House Committee on Agriculture, H.R. No. 365, 67th Cong., 1st
Sess., and the Senate Committee on Agriculture and Forestry,
Sen.Rep. No. 987, 67th Cong., 4th Sess. Both committees concluded,
as the statute itself declares, that the use of filled milk as a
substitute for pure milk is generally injurious to health and
facilitates fraud on the public. [ Footnote 2 ]
There is nothing in the Constitution which compels a
legislature, either national or state, to ignore such evidence, nor
need it disregard the other evidence which amply supports the
conclusions of the Congressional committees that the danger is
greatly enhanced where an inferior product, like appellee's, is
indistinguishable from Page 304 U. S. 150 a valuable food of almost universal use, thus making fraudulent
distribution easy and protection of the consumer difficult.
[ Footnote 3 ] Page 304 U. S. 151 Here, the prohibition of the statute is inoperative unless the
product is "in imitation or semblance milk, cream, or skimmed milk,
whether or not condensed." Whether in such circumstances the public
would be adequately protected by the prohibition of false labels
and false branding imposed by the Pure Food and Drugs Act, or
whether it was necessary to go farther and prohibit a substitute
food product thought to be injurious to health if used as a
substitute when the two are not distinguishable, was a matter for
the legislative Judgment, and not that of courts. Hebe Co. v.
Shaw, supra; South Carolina v. Barnwell Bros. Inc., 303 U. S. 177 . It
was upon this ground that the prohibition of the sale of
oleomargarine made in imitation of butter was held not to infringe
the Fourteenth Amendment in Powell v. Pennsylvania, 127 U. S. 678 ; Capital City Dairy Co. v. Ohio, 183 U.
S. 238 . Compare McCray v. United States, 195 U. S. 27 , 195 U. S. 63 ; Purity Extract & Tonic Co. v. Lynch, 226 U.
S. 192 .
Appellee raises no valid objection to the present statute by
arguing that its prohibition has not been extended to oleomargarine
or other butter substitutes in which vegetable fats or oils are
substituted for butter fat. The Fifth Amendment has no equal
protection clause, and even that of the Fourteenth, applicable only
to the states, does not compel their legislatures to prohibit all
like evils, or none. A legislature may hit at an abuse which it has
found, even though it has failed to strike at another. Central
Lumber Co. v. South Dakota, 226 U. S. 157 , 226 U. S. 160 ; Miller v. Wilson, 236 U. S. 373 , 236 U. S. 384 ; Hall v. Geiger-Jones Co., 242 U.
S. 539 , 242 U. S. 556 ; Farmers & Merchants Bank v. Federal Reserve Bank, 262 U. S. 649 , 262 U. S.
661 . Page 304 U. S. 152 Third. We may assume for present purposes that no
pronouncement of a legislature can forestall attack upon the
constitutionality of the prohibition which it enacts by applying
opprobrious epithets to the prohibited act, and that a statute
would deny due process which precluded the disproof in judicial
proceedings of all facts which would show or tend to show that a
statute depriving the suitor of life, liberty or property had a
rational basis.
But such we think is not the purpose or construction of the
statutory characterization of filled milk as injurious to health
and as a fraud upon the public. There is no need to consider it
here as more than a declaration of the legislative findings deemed
to support and justify the action taken as a constitutional
exertion of the legislative power, aiding informed judicial review,
as do the reports of legislative committees, by revealing the
rationale of the legislation. Even in the absence of such aids, the
existence of facts supporting the legislative judgment is to be
presumed, for regulatory legislation affecting ordinary commercial
transactions is not to be pronounced unconstitutional unless, in
the light of the facts made known or generally assumed, it is of
such a character as to preclude the assumption that it rests upon
some rational basis within the knowledge and experience of the
legislators. [ Footnote 4 ] See Metropolitan Casualty Ins.
Co. v. Page 304 U. S. 153 Brownell, 294 U. S. 580 , 294 U. S. 584 ,
and cases cited. The present statutory findings affect appellee n
more than the reports of the Congressional committees, and since,
in the absence of the statutory findings, they would be presumed,
their incorporation in the statute is no more prejudicial than
surplusage.
Where the existence of a rational basis for legislation whose
constitutionality is attacked depends upon facts beyond the sphere
of judicial notice, such facts may properly be male the subject of
judicial inquiry, Boren's Farm Products Co. v. Baldwin, 293 U. S. 194 , and
the constitutionality of a statute predicated upon the existence of
a particular state of facts may be challenged by showing to the
court that those facts have ceased to exist. Chastleton
Corporation v. Sinclair, 264 U. S. 543 .
Similarly we recognize that the constitutionality of a statute,
valid on its face, may be assailed by proof of facts tending to
show that the statute as applied to a particular Page 304 U. S. 154 article is without support in reason because the article,
although within the prohibited class, is so different from others
of the class as to be without the reason for the prohibition, Railroad Retirement Board v. Alton R. Co., 295 U.
S. 330 , 295 U. S. 349 , 295 U. S. 351 , 295 U. S. 352 ; see Whitney v. California, 274 U.
S. 357 , 274 U. S. 379 ; cf. Morf v. Bingaman, 298 U. S. 407 , 298 U. S. 413 ,
though the effect of such proof depends on the relevant
circumstances of each case, as, for example, the administrative
difficulty of excluding the article from the regulated class. Carmichael v. Southern Coal & Coke Co., 301 U.
S. 495 , 301 U. S.
511 -512; South Carolina v. Barnwell Bros., 303 U. S. 177 , 303 U. S.
192 -193. But, by their very nature, such inquiries,
where the legislative judgment is drawn in question, must be
restricted to the issue whether any state of facts either known or
which could reasonably be assumed affords support for it. Here, the
demurrer challenges the validity of the statute on its face, and it
is evident from all the considerations presented to Congress, and
those of which we may take judicial notice, that the question is at
least debatable whether commerce in filled milk should be left
unregulated, or in some measure restricted, or wholly prohibited.
As that decision was for Congress, neither the finding of a court
arrived at by weighing the evidence nor the verdict of a jury can
be substituted for it. Price v. Illinois, 238 U.
S. 446 , 238 U. S. 452 ; Hebe Co. v. Shaw, supra, 248 U. S. 303 ; Standard Oil Co. v. Marysville, 279 U.
S. 582 , 279 U. S. 584 ; South Carolina v. Barnwell Bros., Inc., supra, 303 U. S. 191 ,
citing Worcester County Trust Co. v. Riley, 302 U.
S. 292 , 302 U. S.
299 .
The prohibition of shipment in interstate commerce of appellee's
product, as described in the indictment, is a constitutional
exercise of the power to regulate interstate commerce. As the
statute is not unconstitutional on its face the demurrer should
have been overruled, and the judgment will be Reversed. Page 304 U. S. 155 MR. JUSTICE BLACK concurs in the result and in all of the
opinion except the part marked " Third. "
MR. JUSTICE McREYNOLDS thinks that the judgment should be
affirmed.
MR. JUSTICE CARDOZO and MR. JUSTICE REED took no part in the
consideration or decision of this case.
[ Footnote 1 ]
The relevant portions of the statute are as follows:
"Section 61. . . . (c) The term 'filled milk' means any milk
cream, or skimmed milk, whether or not condensed, evaporated,
concentrated, powdered, dried, or desiccated, to which has been
added, or which has been blended or compounded with, any fat or oil
other than milk fat, so that the resulting product is in imitation
or semblance of milk, cream, or skimmed milk, whether or not
condensed, evaporated, concentrated, powdered, dried, or
desiccated."
"Section 62. . . . It is hereby declared that filled milk, as
herein defined, is an adulterated article of food, injurious to the
public health, and its sale constitutes a fraud upon the public. It
shall be unlawful for any person to . . . ship or deliver for
shipment in interstate or foreign commerce, any filled milk."
Section 63 imposes as penalties for violations "a fine of not
more than $1,000 or imprisonment of not more than one year, or both
. . ."
[ Footnote 2 ]
The reports may be summarized as follows: there is an extensive
commerce in milk compounds made of condensed milk from which the
butter fat has been extracted and an equivalent amount of vegetable
oil, usually coconut oil, substituted. These compounds resemble
milk in taste and appearance, and are distributed in packages
resembling those in which pure condensed milk is distributed. By
reason of the extraction of the natural milk fat, the compounded
product can be manufactured and sold at a lower cost than pure
milk. Butter fat, which constitutes an important part of the food
value of pure milk, is rich in vitamins, food elements which are
essential to proper nutrition and are wanting in vegetable oils.
The use of filled milk as a dietary substitute for pure milk
results, especially in the case of children, in undernourishment,
and induces diseases which attend malnutrition. Despite compliance
with the branding and labeling requirements of the Pure Food and
Drugs Act, there is widespread use of filled milk as a food
substitute for pure milk. This is aided by their identical taste
and appearance, by the similarity of the containers in which they
are sold, by the practice of dealers in offering the inferior
product to customers as being as good as or better than pure
condensed milk sold at a higher price, by customers' ignorance of
the respective food values of the two products, and, in many
sections of the country, by their inability to read the labels
placed on the containers. Large amounts of filled milk, much of it
shipped and sold in bulk, are purchased by hotels and boarding
houses, and by manufacturers of food products, such as ice cream,
to whose customers labeling restrictions afford no protection.
[ Footnote 3 ]
There is now an extensive literature indicating wide recognition
by scientists and dietitians of the great importance to the public
health of butter fat and whole milk as the prime source of
vitamins, which are essential growth producing and disease
preventing elements in the diet. See Dr. Henry C. Sherman,
The Meaning of Vitamin A, in Science, Dec. 21, 1928, p. 619; Dr. E.
V. McCollum et al., The Newer Knowledge of Nutrition (1929
ed.), pp. 134, 170, 176, 177; Dr. A. S. Root, Food Vitamins (N.Car.
State Board of Health, May 1931), p. 2; Dr. Henry C. Sherman,
Chemistry of Food and Nutrition (1932), p. 367; Dr. Mary S. Rose,
The Foundations of Nutrition (1933), p. 237.
When the Filled Milk Act was passed, eleven states had rigidly
controlled the exploitation of filled milk, or forbidden it
altogether. H.R. 365, 67th Cong., 1st Sess. Some thirty-five states
have now adopted laws which, in terms or by their operation,
prohibit the sale of filled milk. Ala.Agri.Code, 1927, § 51, Art.
8; Ariz.Rev.Code, 1936 Supp., § 943y; Pope's Ark.Dig.1937, § 3103;
Deering's Cal.Code, 1933 Supp., Tit. 149, Act 1943, p. 1302;
Conn.Gen.Stat., 1930, § 2487, c. 135; Del.Rev.Code, 1935, § 649;
Fla.Comp.Gen.Laws, 1927, §§ 3216, 7676; Ga.Code, 1933, § 42-511;
Idaho Code, 1932, Tit. 36, §§ 502-504; Jones Ill.Stat.Ann., 1937
Supp., § 53.020(1), (2), (3); Burns Ind.Stat., 1933, § 35-1203;
Iowa Code, 1935, § 3062; Kan.Gen.Stat., 1935, c. 65, § 707;
Md.Ann.Code, Art. 27, § 281; Mass.Ann.Laws, 1933, § 17-A, c. 94;
Mich.Comp.Laws, 1929, § 5358; Mason's Minn.Stat., 1927, § 3926;
Mo.Rev.Stat., 1929, §§ 12408-12413; Mont.Rev.Code, Anderson and
McFarland, 1935, c. 240, § 2620.39; Neb.Comp.Stat., 1929, §
81-1022; N.H.Pub.L.1926 v. 1, c. 163, § 37, p. 619; N.J.Comp.Stat.,
1911-1924, § 8l-8j, p. 1400; Cahill's N.Y.Cons.Laws, 1930, § 60, c.
1; N.D. Comp.Laws, 1913-1925, Pol.Code, c. 38, § 2855(a) 1; Page's
Ohio Gen.Code, § 12725; Purdon's Penna.Stat., 1936, Tit. 31, §§
553, 582; S.D.Comp.Laws, 1929, c.192, § 7926-O, p. 2493; Williams
Tenn.Code, 1934, c. 15, §§ 6549, 6551; Vernon's Tex.Pen.Code, Tit.
12, c. 2, Art. 713a; Utah Rev.Stat., 1933, §§ 3-10-59, 3-10-60;
Vt.Pub.L., 1933, Tit. 34, c. 303, § 7724, p. 1288; Va.1936 Code, §
1197c; W.Va.1932 Code, § 2036; Wis.Stat., 11th ed.1931, c. 98, §
98.07, p. 1156; cf. N.Mex.Ann.Stat., 1929, §§ 25-104,
25-108. Three others have subjected its sale to rigid regulations.
Colo.L.1921, c. 30, § 1007, p. 440; Ore.1930 Code v. 2, c. XII, §§
41-1208 to 41-1210; Remington's Wash.Rev.Stat. v. 7, Tit. 40, c.
13, §§ 6206, 6207, 6713, 6714, p. 360, et seq. [ Footnote 4 ]
There may be narrower scope for operation of the presumption of
constitutionality when legislation appears on its face to be within
a specific prohibition of the Constitution, such as those of the
first ten amendments, which are deemed equally specific when held
to be embraced within the Fourteenth. See Stromberg v.
California, 283 U. S. 359 , 283 U. S.
369 -370; Lovell v. Griffin, 303 U.
S. 444 , 303 U. S.
452 .
It is unnecessary to consider now whether legislation which
restricts those political processes which can ordinarily be
expected to bring about repeal of undesirable legislation is to be
subjected to more exacting judicial scrutiny under the general
prohibitions of the Fourteenth Amendment than are most other types
of legislation. On restrictions upon the right to vote, see
Nixon v. Herndon, 273 U. S. 536 ; Nixon v. Condon, 286 U. S. 73 ; on
restraints upon the dissemination of information, see Near v.
Minnesota ex rel. Olson, 283 U. S. 697 , 283 U. S.
713 -714, 283 U. S.
718 -720, 283 U. S. 722 ; Grosjean v. American Press Co., 297 U.
S. 233 ; Lovell v. Griffin, supra; on
interferences with political organizations, see Stromberg v.
California, supra, 283 U. S. 369 ; Fiske v. Kansas, 274 U. S. 380 ; Whitney v. California, 274 U. S. 357 , 274 U. S.
373 -378; Herndon v. Lowry, 301 U.
S. 242 , and see Holmes, J., in Gitlow v.
New York, 268 U. S. 652 , 268 U. S. 673 ;
as to prohibition of peaceable assembly, see De Jonge v.
Oregon, 299 U. S. 353 , 299 U. S.
365 .
Nor need we enquire whether similar considerations enter into
the review of statutes directed at particular religious, Pierce
v. Society of Sisters, 268 U. S. 510 , or
national, Meyer v. Nebraska, 262 U.
S. 390 ; Bartels v. Iowa, 262 U.
S. 404 ; Farrington v. Tokushige, 273 U.
S. 284 , or racial minorities, Nixon v. Herndon,
supra; Nixon v. Condon, supra: whether prejudice against
discrete and insular minorities may be a special condition, which
tends seriously to curtail the operation of those political
processes ordinarily to be relied upon to protect minorities, and
which may call for a correspondingly more searching judicial
inquiry. Compare 17 U. S. Maryland, 4 Wheat. 316, 17 U. S. 428 ; South Carolina v. Barnwell Bros., 303 U.
S. 177 , 303 U. S. 184 ,
n 2, and cases cited.
MR. JUSTICE BUTLER.
I concur in the result. Prima facie, the facts alleged
in the indictment are sufficient to constitute a violation of the
statute. But they are not sufficient conclusively to establish
guilt of the accused. At the trial, it may introduce evidence to
show that the declaration of the Act that the described product is
injurious to public health and that the sale of it is a fraud upon
the public are without any substantial foundation. Mobile, J.
& K.C. R. Co. v. Turnipseed, 219 U. S.
35 , 219 U. S. 43 . Manley v. Georgia, 279 U. S. 1 , 279 U. S. 6 . The
provisions on which the indictment rests should, if possible, be
construed to avoid the serious question of constitutionality. Federal Trade Comm'n v. American Tobacco Co., 264 U.
S. 298 , 264 U. S. 307 . Panama R. Co. v. Johnson, 264 U.
S. 375 , 264 U. S. 390 . Missouri Pacific R. Co. v. Boone, 270 U.
S. 466 , 270 U. S. 472 . Richmond Co. v. United States, 275 U.
S. 331 , 275 U. S. 346 .
If construed to exclude from interstate commerce wholesome food
products that demonstrably are neither injurious to health nor
calculated to deceive, they are repugnant to the Fifth Amendment. Weaver v. Palmer Bros. Co., 270 U.
S. 402 , 270 U. S.
412 -13. See People v. Carolene Products Co., 345 Ill. 166. Carolene Products Co. v. McLaughlin, 365
Ill. 62, 5 N.E.2d 447. Carolene Products Co. v. Thomson, 276 Mich. 172, 267 N.W. 608. Carolene Products Co. v.
Banning, 131 Neb. 429, 268 N.W. 313. The allegation of the
indictment that Milnut "is an adulterated article of food,
injurious to the public health," tenders an issue of fact to be
determined upon evidence. | The Supreme Court upheld the Filled Milk Act of 1923, which prohibited the shipment of skimmed milk compounded with non-milk fats in interstate commerce, as a valid exercise of Congress's power to regulate interstate commerce. The Court found that the Act was presumptively constitutional and that the legislative findings supported it as a constitutional exertion of legislative power. The Court also noted that similar products, such as oleomargarine, were not included in the Act, but this did not invalidate the prohibition on filled milk. Justice Stone's opinion included a footnote suggesting that stricter judicial review may be warranted when laws target "discrete and insular minorities." |
Free Speech | Moody v. NetChoice, LLC | https://supreme.justia.com/cases/federal/us/603/22-277/ | NOTICE: This opinion is subject to formal
revision before publication in the United States Reports. Readers
are requested to notify the Reporter of Decisions, Supreme Court of
the United States, Washington, D. C. 20543,
[email protected], of any typographical or other formal
errors.
SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES
_________________
Nos. 22–277 and 22–555
_________________
ASHLEY MOODY, ATTORNEY GENERAL OF
FLORIDA, et al., PETITIONERS
22–277 v. NETCHOICE, LLC, dba NETCHOICE, et
al.
on writ of certiorari to the united states
court of appeals for the eleventh circuit
NETCHOICE, LLC, dba NETCHOICE, et al.,
PETITIONERS
22–555 v. KEN PAXTON, ATTORNEY GENERAL OF
TEXAS
on writ of certiorari to the united states
court of appeals for the fifth circuit
[July 1, 2024]
Justice Kagan delivered the opinion of the
Court.[ 1 ]*
Not even thirty years ago, this Court felt the
need to explain to the opinion-reading public that the “Internet is
an international network of interconnected computers.” Reno v. American Civil Liberties Union , 521
U.S. 844 , 849 (1997). Things have changed since then. At the
time, only 40 million people used the internet. See id. , at
850. Today, Facebook and YouTube alone have over two billion users
each. See App. in No. 22–555, p. 67a. And the public likely no
longer needs this Court to define the internet.
These years have brought a dizzying
transformation in how people communicate, and with it a raft of
public policy issues. Social-media platforms, as well as other
websites, have gone from unheard-of to inescapable. They structure
how we relate to family and friends, as well as to businesses,
civic organizations, and governments. The novel services they offer
make our lives better, and make them worse—create unparalleled
opportunities and unprecedented dangers. The questions of whether,
when, and how to regulate online entities, and in particular the
social-media giants, are understandably on the front-burner of many
legislatures and agencies. And those government actors will
generally be better positioned than courts to respond to the
emerging challenges social-media entities pose.
But courts still have a necessary role in
protecting those entities’ rights of speech, as courts have
historically protected traditional media’s rights. To the extent
that social-media platforms create expressive products, they
receive the First Amendment’s protection. And although these cases
are here in a preliminary posture, the current record suggests that
some platforms, in at least some functions, are indeed engaged in
expression. In constructing certain feeds, those platforms make
choices about what third-party speech to display and how to display
it. They include and exclude, organize and prioritize—and in making
millions of those decisions each day, produce their own distinctive
compilations of expression. And while much about social media is
new, the essence of that project is something this Court has seen
before. Traditional publishers and editors also select and shape
other parties’ expression into their own curated speech products.
And we have repeatedly held that laws curtailing their editorial
choices must meet the First Amendment’s requirements. The principle
does not change because the curated compilation has gone from the
physical to the virtual world. In the latter, as in the former,
government efforts to alter an edited compilation of third-party
expression are subject to judicial review for compliance with the
First Amendment.
Today, we consider whether two state laws
regulating social-media platforms and other websites facially
violate the First Amendment. The laws, from Florida and Texas,
restrict the ability of social-media platforms to control whether
and how third-party posts are presented to other users. Or
otherwise put, the laws limit the platforms’ capacity to engage in
content moderation—to filter, prioritize, and label the varied
messages, videos, and other content their users wish to post. In
addition, though far less addressed in this Court, the laws require
a platform to provide an individualized explanation to a user if it
removes or alters her posts. NetChoice, an internet trade
association, challenged both laws on their face—as a whole, rather
than as to particular applications. The cases come to us at an
early stage, on review of preliminary injunctions. The Court of
Appeals for the Eleventh Circuit upheld such an injunction, finding
that the Florida law was not likely to survive First Amendment
review. The Court of Appeals for the Fifth Circuit reversed a
similar injunction, primarily reasoning that the Texas law does not
regulate any speech and so does not implicate the First
Amendment.
Today, we vacate both decisions for reasons
separate from the First Amendment merits, because neither Court of
Appeals properly considered the facial nature of NetChoice’s
challenge. The courts mainly addressed what the parties had focused
on. And the parties mainly argued these cases as if the laws
applied only to the curated feeds offered by the largest and most
paradigmatic social-media platforms—as if, say, each case presented
an as-applied challenge brought by Facebook protesting its loss of
control over the content of its News Feed. But argument in this
Court revealed that the laws might apply to, and differently
affect, other kinds of websites and apps. In a facial challenge,
that could well matter, even when the challenge is brought under
the First Amendment. As explained below, the question in such a
case is whether a law’s unconstitutional applications are
substantial compared to its constitutional ones. To make that
judgment, a court must determine a law’s full set of applications,
evaluate which are constitutional and which are not, and compare
the one to the other. Neither court performed that necessary
inquiry.
To do that right, of course, a court must
understand what kind of government actions the First Amendment
prohibits. We therefore set out the relevant constitutional
principles, and explain how one of the Courts of Appeals failed to
follow them. Contrary to what the Fifth Circuit thought, the
current record indicates that the Texas law does regulate speech
when applied in the way the parties focused on below—when applied,
that is, to prevent Facebook (or YouTube) from using its
content-moderation standards to remove, alter, organize,
prioritize, or disclaim posts in its News Feed (or homepage). The
law then prevents exactly the kind of editorial judgments this
Court has previously held to receive First Amendment protection. It
prevents a platform from compiling the third-party speech it wants
in the way it wants, and thus from offering the expressive product
that most reflects its own views and priorities. Still more, the
law—again, in that specific application—is unlikely to withstand
First Amendment scrutiny. Texas has thus far justified the law as
necessary to balance the mix of speech on Facebook’s News Feed and
similar platforms; and the record reflects that Texas officials
passed it because they thought those feeds skewed against
politically conservative voices. But this Court has many times
held, in many contexts, that it is no job for government to decide
what counts as the right balance of private expression—to “un-bias”
what it thinks biased, rather than to leave such judgments to
speakers and their audiences. That principle works for social-media
platforms as it does for others.
In sum, there is much work to do below on both
these cases, given the facial nature of NetChoice’s challenges. But
that work must be done consistent with the First Amendment, which
does not go on leave when social media are involved.
I
As commonly understood, the term “social media
platforms” typically refers to websites and mobile apps that allow
users to upload content—messages, pictures, videos, and so on—to
share with others. Those viewing the content can then react to it,
comment on it, or share it themselves. The biggest social-media
companies—entities like Facebook and YouTube—host a staggering
amount of content. Facebook users, for example, share more than 100
billion messages every day. See App. in No. 22–555, at 67a. And
YouTube sees more than 500 hours of video uploaded every minute.
See ibid. In the face of that deluge, the major platforms
cull and organize uploaded posts in a variety of ways. A user does
not see everything—even everything from the people she follows—in
reverse-chronological order. The platforms will have removed some
content entirely; ranked or otherwise prioritized what remains; and
sometimes added warnings or labels. Of particular relevance here,
Facebook and YouTube make some of those decisions in conformity
with content-moderation policies they call Community Standards and
Community Guidelines. Those rules list the subjects or messages the
platform prohibits or discourages—say, pornography, hate speech, or
misinformation on select topics. The rules thus lead Facebook and
YouTube to remove, disfavor, or label various posts based on their
content.
In 2021, Florida and Texas enacted statutes
regulating internet platforms, including the large social-media
companies just mentioned. The States’ laws differ in the entities
they cover and the activities they limit. But both contain
content-moderation provisions, restricting covered platforms’
choices about whether and how to display user- generated content to
the public. And both include individualized-explanation provisions,
requiring platforms to give reasons for particular
content-moderation choices.
Florida’s law regulates “social media
platforms,” as defined expansively, that have annual gross revenue
of over $100 million or more than 100 million monthly active users.
Fla. Stat. §501.2041(1)(g) (2023).[ 2 ] The statute restricts varied ways of “censor[ing]” or
otherwise disfavoring posts—including deleting, altering, labeling,
or deprioritizing them—based on their content or source.
§501.2041(1)(b). For example, the law prohibits a platform from
taking those actions against “a journalistic enterprise based on
the content of its publication or broadcast.” §501.2041(2)(j).
Similarly, the law prevents deprioritizing posts by or about
political candidates. See §501.2041(2)(h). And the law requires
platforms to apply their content-moderation practices to users “in
a consistent manner.” §501.2041(2)(b).
In addition, the Florida law mandates that a
platform provide an explanation to a user any time it removes or
alters any of her posts. See §501.2041(2)(d)(1). The requisite
notice must be delivered within seven days, and contain both a
“thorough rationale” for the action and an account of how the
platform became aware of the targeted material. §501.2041(3).
The Texas law regulates any social-media
platform, having over 50 million monthly active users, that allows
its users “to communicate with other users for the primary purpose
of posting information, comments, messages, or images.” Tex. Bus.
& Com. Code Ann. §§120.001(1), 120.002(b) (West Cum. Supp.
2023).[ 3 ] With several
exceptions, the statute prevents platforms from “censor[ing]” a
user or a user’s expression based on viewpoint. Tex. Civ. Prac.
& Rem. Code Ann. §§143A.002(a), 143 A. 006 (West Cum. Supp.
2023). That ban on “censor[ing]” covers any action to “block, ban,
remove, deplatform, demonetize, de-boost, restrict, deny equal
access or visibility to, or otherwise discriminate against
expression.” §143A.001(1). The statute also requires that
“concurrently with the removal” of user content, the platform shall
“notify the user” and “explain the reason the content was removed.”
§120.103(a)(1). The user gets a right of appeal, and the platform
must address an appeal within 14 days. See §§120.103(a)(2),
120.104.
Soon after Florida and Texas enacted those
statutes, NetChoice LLC and the Computer & Communications
Industry Association (collectively, NetChoice)—trade associations
whose members include Facebook and YouTube—brought facial First
Amendment challenges against the two laws. District courts in both
States entered preliminary injunctions, halting the laws’
enforcement. See 546 F. Supp. 3d 1082, 1096 (ND Fla. 2021);
573 F. Supp. 3d 1092, 1117 (WD Tex. 2021). Each court held
that the suit before it is likely to succeed because the statute
infringes on the constitutionally protected “editorial judgment” of
NetChoice’s members about what material they will display. See 546
F. Supp. 3d, at 1090; 573 F. Supp. 3d, at 1107.
The Eleventh Circuit upheld the injunction of
Florida’s law, as to all provisions relevant here. The court held
that the State’s restrictions on content moderation trigger First
Amendment scrutiny under this Court’s cases protecting “editorial
discretion.” 34 F. 4th 1196, 1209, 1216 (2022). When a
social-media platform “removes or deprioritizes a user or post,”
the court explained, it makes a “judgment rooted in the platform’s
own views about the sorts of content and viewpoints that are
valuable and appropriate for dissemination.” Id. , at 1210.
The court concluded that the content-moderation provisions are
unlikely to survive “intermediate—let alone strict—scrutiny,”
because a State has no legitimate interest in counteracting
“private ‘censorship’ ” by “tilt[ing] public debate in a
preferred direction.” Id. , at 1227–1228. Similarly, the
Eleventh Circuit thought the statute’s individualized-explanation
requirements likely to fall. Applying the standard from Zauderer v. Office of Disciplinary Counsel of Supreme
Court of Ohio , 471 U.S.
626 (1985), the court held that the obligation to explain
“millions of [decisions] per day” is “unduly burdensome and likely
to chill platforms’ protected speech.” 34 F. 4th, at 1230.
The Fifth Circuit disagreed across the board,
and so reversed the preliminary injunction before it. In that
court’s view, the platforms’ content-moderation activities are “not
speech” at all, and so do not implicate the First Amendment. 49
F. 4th 439, 466, 494 (2022). But even if those activities were
expressive, the court continued, the State could regulate them to
advance its interest in “protecting a diversity of ideas.” Id. , at 482 (emphasis deleted). The court further held that
the statute’s individualized- explanation provisions would likely
survive, again even assuming that the platforms were engaged in
speech. Those requirements, the court maintained, are not unduly
burdensome under Zauderer because the platforms needed only
to “scale up” a “complaint-and-appeal process” they already used.
49 F. 4th, at 487.
We granted certiorari to resolve the split
between the Fifth and Eleventh Circuits. 600 U. S. ___
(2023).
II
NetChoice chose to litigate these cases as
facial challenges, and that decision comes at a cost. For a host of
good reasons, courts usually handle constitutional claims case by
case, not en masse. See Washington State Grange v. Washington State Republican Party , 552
U.S. 442 , 450–451 (2008). “Claims of facial invalidity often
rest on speculation” about the law’s coverage and its future
enforcement. Id. , at 450. And “facial challenges threaten to
short circuit the democratic process” by preventing duly enacted
laws from being implemented in constitutional ways. Id. , at
451. This Court has therefore made facial challenges hard to
win.
That is true even when a facial suit is based on
the First Amendment, although then a different standard applies. In
other cases, a plaintiff cannot succeed on a facial challenge
unless he “establish[es] that no set of circumstances exists under
which the [law] would be valid,” or he shows that the law lacks a
“plainly legitimate sweep.” United States v. Salerno , 481 U.S.
739 , 745 (1987); Washington State Grange , 552
U. S., at 449. In First Amendment cases, however, this Court
has lowered that very high bar. To “provide[ ] breathing room
for free expression,” we have substituted a less demanding though
still rigorous standard. United States v. Hansen , 599
U.S. 762, 769 (2023). The question is whether “a substantial number
of [the law’s] applications are unconstitutional, judged in
relation to the statute’s plainly legitimate sweep.” Americans
for Prosperity Foundation v. Bonta , 594 U.S. 595, 615
(2021); see Hansen , 599 U. S., at 770 (likewise asking
whether the law “prohibits a substantial amount of protected speech
relative to its plainly legitimate sweep”). So in this singular
context, even a law with “a plainly legitimate sweep” may be struck
down in its entirety. But that is so only if the law’s
unconstitutional applications substantially outweigh its
constitutional ones.
So far in these cases, no one has paid much
attention to that issue. In the lower courts, NetChoice and the
States alike treated the laws as having certain heartland
applications, and mostly confined their battle to that terrain.
More specifically, the focus was on how the laws applied to the
content-moderation practices that giant social-media platforms use
on their best-known services to filter, alter, or label their
users’ posts. Or more specifically still, the focus was on how the
laws applied to Facebook’s News Feed and YouTube’s homepage.
Reflecting the parties’ arguments, the Eleventh and Fifth Circuits
also mostly confined their analysis in that way. See 34
F. 4th, at 1210, 1213 (considering “platforms like Facebook,
Twitter, YouTube, and TikTok” and content moderation in “viewers’
feeds”); 49 F. 4th, at 445, 460, 478, 492 (considering
platforms “such as Facebook, Twitter, and YouTube” and referencing
users’ feeds); see also id. , at 501 (Southwick, J.,
concurring in part and dissenting in part) (analyzing a curated
feed). On their way to opposing conclusions, they concentrated on
the same issue: whether a state law can regulate the
content-moderation practices used in Facebook’s News Feed (or near
equivalents). They did not address the full range of activities the
laws cover, and measure the constitutional against the
unconstitutional applications. In short, they treated these cases
more like as-applied claims than like facial ones.
The first step in the proper facial analysis is
to assess the state laws’ scope. What activities, by what actors,
do the laws prohibit or otherwise regulate? The laws of course
differ one from the other. But both, at least on their face, appear
to apply beyond Facebook’s News Feed and its ilk. Members of this
Court asked some of the relevant questions at oral argument.
Starting with Facebook and the other giants: To what extent, if at
all, do the laws affect their other services, like direct messaging
or events management? See Tr. of Oral Arg. in No. 22–555,
pp. 62–63; Tr. of Oral Arg. in No. 22–277, pp. 24–25;
App. in No. 22–277, pp. 129, 159. And beyond those
social-media entities, what do the laws have to say, if anything,
about how an email provider like Gmail filters incoming messages,
how an online marketplace like Etsy displays customer reviews, how
a payment service like Venmo manages friends’ financial exchanges,
or how a ride-sharing service like Uber runs? See Tr. of Oral Arg.
in No. 22–277, at 74–79, 95–98; see also id. , at 153
(Solicitor General) (“I have some sympathy [for the Court] here. In
preparation for this argument, I’ve been working with my team to
say, does this even cover direct messaging? Does this even cover
Gmail?”). Those are examples only. The online world is variegated
and complex, encompassing an ever-growing number of apps, services,
functionalities, and methods for communication and connection. Each
might (or might not) have to change because of the provisions, as
to either content moderation or individualized explanation, in
Florida’s or Texas’s law. Before a court can do anything else with
these facial challenges, it must address that set of issues—in
short, must “determine what [the law] covers.” Hansen , 599
U. S., at 770.
The next order of business is to decide which of
the laws’ applications violate the First Amendment, and to measure
them against the rest. For the content-moderation provisions, that
means asking, as to every covered platform or function, whether
there is an intrusion on protected editorial discretion. See infra , at 13–19. And for the individualized-explanation
provisions, it means asking, again as to each thing covered,
whether the required disclosures unduly burden expression. See Zauderer , 471 U. S., at 651. Even on a preliminary
record, it is not hard to see how the answers might differ as
between regulation of Facebook’s News Feed (considered in the
courts below) and, say, its direct messaging service (not so
considered). Curating a feed and transmitting direct messages, one
might think, involve different levels of editorial choice, so that
the one creates an expressive product and the other does not. If
so, regulation of those diverse activities could well fall on
different sides of the constitutional line. To decide the facial
challenges here, the courts below must explore the laws’ full range
of applications—the constitutionally impermissible and permissible
both—and compare the two sets. Maybe the parties treated the
content-moderation choices reflected in Facebook’s News Feed and
YouTube’s homepage as the laws’ heartland applications because they are the principal things regulated, and should have just
that weight in the facial analysis. Or maybe not: Maybe the
parties’ focus had all to do with litigation strategy, and there is
a sphere of other applications—and constitutional ones—that would
prevent the laws’ facial invalidation.
The problem for this Court is that it cannot
undertake the needed inquiries. “[W]e are a court of review, not of
first view.” Cutter v. Wilkinson , 544 U.S.
709 , 718, n. 7 (2005). Neither the Eleventh Circuit nor
the Fifth Circuit performed the facial analysis in the way just
described. And even were we to ignore the value of other courts
going first, we could not proceed very far. The parties have not
briefed the critical issues here, and the record is underdeveloped.
So we vacate the decisions below and remand these cases. That will
enable the lower courts to consider the scope of the laws’
applications, and weigh the unconstitutional as against the
constitutional ones.
III
But it is necessary to say more about how the
First Amendment relates to the laws’ content-moderation provisions,
to ensure that the facial analysis proceeds on the right path in
the courts below. That need is especially stark for the Fifth
Circuit. Recall that it held that the content choices the major
platforms make for their main feeds are “not speech” at all, so
States may regulate them free of the First Amendment’s restraints.
49 F. 4th, at 494; see supra , at 8. And even if those
activities were expressive, the court held, Texas’s interest in
better balancing the marketplace of ideas would satisfy First
Amendment scrutiny. See 49 F. 4th, at 482. If we said nothing
about those views, the court presumably would repeat them when it
next considers NetChoice’s challenge. It would thus find that
significant applications of the Texas law—and so significant inputs
into the appropriate facial analysis—raise no First Amendment
difficulties. But that conclusion would rest on a serious
misunderstanding of First Amendment precedent and principle. The
Fifth Circuit was wrong in concluding that Texas’s restrictions on
the platforms’ selection, ordering, and labeling of third-party
posts do not interfere with expression. And the court was wrong to
treat as valid Texas’s interest in changing the content of the
platforms’ feeds. Explaining why that is so will prevent the Fifth
Circuit from repeating its errors as to Facebook’s and YouTube’s
main feeds. (And our analysis of Texas’s law may also aid the
Eleventh Circuit, which saw the First Amendment issues much as we
do, when next considering NetChoice’s facial challenge.) But a
caveat: Nothing said here addresses any of the laws’ other
applications, which may or may not share the First Amendment
problems described below.[ 4 ]
A
Despite the relative novelty of the technology
before us, the main problem in this case—and the inquiry it calls
for—is not new. At bottom, Texas’s law requires the platforms to
carry and promote user speech that they would rather discard or
downplay. The platforms object that the law thus forces them to
alter the content of their expression—a particular edited
compilation of third-party speech. See Brief for NetChoice in No.
22–555, pp. 18–34. That controversy sounds a familiar note. We
have repeatedly faced the question whether ordering a party to
provide a forum for someone else’s views implicates the First
Amendment. And we have repeatedly held that it does so if, though
only if, the regulated party is engaged in its own expressive
activity, which the mandated access would alter or disrupt. So too
we have held, when applying that principle, that expressive
activity includes presenting a curated compilation of speech
originally created by others. A review of the relevant precedents
will help resolve the question here.
The seminal case is Miami Herald Publishing
Co. v. Tornillo , 418 U.S.
241 (1974). There, a Florida law required a newspaper to give a
political candidate a right to reply when it published “criticism
and attacks on his record.” Id. , at 243. The Court held the
law to violate the First Amendment because it interfered with the
newspaper’s “exercise of editorial control and judgment.” Id. , at 258. Forcing the paper to print what “it would not
otherwise print,” the Court explained, “intru[ded] into the
function of editors.” Id. , at 256, 258. For that function
was, first and foremost, to make decisions about the “content of
the paper” and “[t]he choice of material to go into” it. Id. , at 258. In protecting that right of editorial control,
the Court recognized a possible downside. It noted the access
advocates’ view (similar to the States’ view here) that “modern
media empires” had gained ever greater capacity to “shape” and even
“manipulate popular opinion.” Id. , at 249–250. And the Court
expressed some sympathy with that diagnosis. See id. , at
254. But the cure proposed, it concluded, collided with the First
Amendment’s antipathy to state manipulation of the speech
market. Florida, the Court explained, could not substitute
“governmental regulation” for the “crucial process” of editorial
choice. Id. , at 258.
Next up was Pacific Gas & Elec. Co. v. Public Util. Comm’n of Cal. , 475 U.S.
1 (1986) ( PG&E ), which the Court thought to follow
naturally from Tornillo . See 475 U. S., at 9–12
(plurality opinion); id. , at 21 (Burger, C. J.,
concurring). A private utility in California regularly put a
newsletter in its billing envelopes expressing its views of energy
policy. The State directed it to include as well material from a
consumer-advocacy group giving a different perspective. The utility
objected, and the Court held again that the interest in “offer[ing]
the public a greater variety of views” could not justify the
regulation. Id. , at 12. California was compelling the
utility (as Florida had compelled a newspaper) “to carry speech
with which it disagreed” and thus to “alter its own message.” Id. , at 11, n. 7, 16.
In Turner Broadcasting System, Inc. v. FCC , 512 U.S.
622 (1994) ( Turner I ), the Court further
underscored the constitutional protection given to editorial
choice. At issue were federal “must-carry” rules, requiring cable
operators to allocate some of their channels to local broadcast
stations. The Court had no doubt that the First Amendment was
implicated, because the operators were engaging in expressive
activity. They were, the Court explained, “exercising editorial
discretion over which stations or programs to include in [their]
repertoire.” Id. , at 636. And the rules “interfere[d]” with
that discretion by forcing the operators to carry stations they
would not otherwise have chosen. Id. , at 643–644. In a later
decision, the Court ruled that the regulation survived First
Amendment review because it was necessary to prevent the demise of
local broadcasting. See Turner Broadcasting System, Inc. v. FCC , 520 U.S.
180 , 185, 189–190 (1997) ( Turner II ); see infra , at 28, n. 10. But for purposes of today’s cases,
the takeaway of Turner is this holding: A private party’s
collection of third-party content into a single speech product (the
operators’ “repertoire” of programming) is itself expressive, and
intrusion into that activity must be specially justified under the
First Amendment.
The capstone of those precedents came in Hurley v. Irish-American Gay, Lesbian and Bisexual Group
of Boston, Inc. , 515 U.S.
557 (1995), when the Court considered (of all things) a parade.
The question was whether Massachusetts could require the organizers
of a St. Patrick’s Day parade to admit as a participant a gay and
lesbian group seeking to convey a message of “pride.” Id. ,
at 561. The Court held unanimously that the First Amendment
precluded that compulsion. The “selection of contingents to make a
parade,” it explained, is entitled to First Amendment protection,
no less than a newspaper’s “presentation of an edited compilation
of [other persons’] speech.” Id. , at 570 (citing Tornillo , 418 U. S., at 258). And that meant the State
could not tell the parade organizers whom to include. Because
“every participating unit affects the message,” said the Court,
ordering the group’s admittance would “alter the expressive content
of the[ ] parade.” Hurley , 515 U. S., at 572–573.
The parade’s organizers had “decided to exclude a message [they]
did not like from the communication [they] chose to make,” and that
was their decision alone. Id. , at 574.
On two other occasions, the Court distinguished Tornillo and its progeny for the flip-side reason—because in
those cases the compelled access did not affect the
complaining party’s own expression. First, in PruneYard Shopping
Center v. Robins , 447 U.S.
74 (1980), the Court rejected a shopping mall’s First Amendment
challenge to a California law requiring it to allow members of the
public to distribute handbills on its property. The mall owner did
not claim that he (or the mall) was engaged in any expressive
activity. Indeed, as the PG&E Court later noted, he “did
not even allege that he objected to the content of the pamphlets”
passed out at the mall. 475 U. S., at 12. Similarly, in Rumsfeld v. Forum for Academic and Institutional Rights,
Inc. , 547 U.S.
47 (2006) ( FAIR ), the Court reiterated that a First
Amendment claim will not succeed when the entity objecting to
hosting third-party speech is not itself engaged in expression. The
statute at issue required law schools to allow the military to
participate in on-campus recruiting. The Court held that the
schools had no First Amendment right to exclude the military based
on its hiring policies, because the schools “are not speaking when
they host interviews.” Id. , at 64. Or stated again, with
reference to the just-described precedents: Because a “law school’s
recruiting services lack the expressive quality of a parade, a
newsletter, or the editorial page of a newspaper,” the required
“accommodation of a military recruiter[ ]” did not “interfere
with any message of the school.” Ibid. That is a slew of individual cases, so consider
three general points to wrap up. Not coincidentally, they will
figure in the upcoming discussion of the First Amendment problems
the statutes at issue here likely present as to Facebook’s News
Feed and similar products.
First, the First Amendment offers protection
when an entity engaging in expressive activity, including compiling
and curating others’ speech, is directed to accommodate messages it
would prefer to exclude. “[T]he editorial function itself is an
aspect of speech.” Denver Area Ed. Telecommunications
Consortium, Inc. v. FCC , 518 U.S.
727 , 737 (1996) (plurality opinion). Or said just a bit
differently: An entity “exercis[ing] editorial discretion in the
selection and presentation” of content is “engage[d] in speech
activity.” Arkansas Ed. Television Comm’n v. Forbes , 523 U.S.
666 , 674 (1998). And that is as true when the content comes
from third parties as when it does not. (Again, think of a
newspaper opinion page or, if you prefer, a parade.) Deciding on
the third-party speech that will be included in or excluded from a
compilation—and then organizing and presenting the included
items—is expressive activity of its own. And that activity results
in a distinctive expressive product. When the government interferes
with such editorial choices—say, by ordering the excluded to be
included—it alters the content of the compilation. (It creates a
different opinion page or parade, bearing a different message.) And
in so doing—in overriding a private party’s expressive choices—the
government confronts the First Amendment.[ 5 ]
Second, none of that changes just because a
compiler includes most items and excludes just a few. That was the
situation in Hurley . The St. Patrick’s Day parade at issue
there was “eclectic”: It included a “wide variety of patriotic,
commercial, political, moral, artistic, religious, athletic, public
service, trade union, and eleemosynary themes, as well as
conflicting messages.” 515 U. S., at 562. Or otherwise said,
the organizers were “rather lenient in admitting participants.” Id. , at 569. No matter. A “narrow, succinctly articulable
message is not a condition of constitutional protection.” Ibid. It “is enough” for a compiler to exclude the handful
of messages it most “disfavor[s].” Id. , at 574. Suppose, for
example, that the newspaper in Tornillo had granted a right
of reply to all but one candidate. It would have made no
difference; the Florida statute still could not have altered the
paper’s policy. Indeed, that kind of focused editorial choice packs
a peculiarly powerful expressive punch.
Third, the government cannot get its way just by
asserting an interest in improving, or better balancing, the
marketplace of ideas. Of course, it is critically important to have
a well-functioning sphere of expression, in which citizens have
access to information from many sources. That is the whole project
of the First Amendment. And the government can take varied
measures, like enforcing competition laws, to protect that access.
Cf., e.g. , Turner I , 512 U. S., at 647
(protecting local broadcasting); Hurley , 515 U. S., at
577 (discussing Turner I ). But in case after case, the
Court has barred the government from forcing a private speaker to
present views it wished to spurn in order to rejigger the
expressive realm. The regulations in Tornillo , PG&E , and Hurley all were thought to promote
greater diversity of expression. See supra , at 14–16. They
also were thought to counteract advantages some private parties
possessed in controlling “enviable vehicle[s]” for speech. Hurley , 515 U. S., at 577. Indeed, the Tornillo Court devoted six pages of its opinion to recounting a critique of
the then-current media environment—in particular, the
disproportionate “influen[ce]” of a few speakers—similar to one
heard today (except about different entities). 418 U. S., at
249; see id. , at 248–254; supra , at 14–15. It made no
difference. However imperfect the private marketplace of ideas,
here was a worse proposal—the government itself deciding when
speech was imbalanced, and then coercing speakers to provide more
of some views or less of others.
B
“[W]hatever the challenges of applying the
Constitution to ever-advancing technology, the basic principles” of
the First Amendment “do not vary.” Brown v. Entertainment
Merchants Assn. , 564 U.S.
786 , 790 (2011). New communications media differ from old ones
in a host of ways: No one thinks Facebook’s News Feed much
resembles an insert put in a billing envelope. And similarly,
today’s social media pose dangers not seen earlier: No one ever
feared the effects of newspaper opinion pages on adolescents’
mental health. But analogies to old media, even if imperfect, can
be useful. And better still as guides to decision are settled
principles about freedom of expression, including the ones just
described. Those principles have served the Nation well over many
years, even as one communications method has given way to another.
And they have much to say about the laws at issue here. These
cases, to be sure, are at an early stage; the record is incomplete
even as to the major social-media platforms’ main feeds, much less
the other applications that must now be considered. See supra , at 12. But in reviewing the District Court’s
preliminary injunction, the Fifth Circuit got its
likelihood-of-success finding wrong. Texas is not likely to succeed
in enforcing its law against the platforms’ application of their
content-moderation policies to the feeds that were the focus of the
proceedings below. And that is because of the core teaching
elaborated in the above-summarized decisions: The government may
not, in supposed pursuit of better expressive balance, alter a
private speaker’s own editorial choices about the mix of speech it
wants to convey.
Most readers are likely familiar with Facebook’s
News Feed or YouTube’s homepage; assuming so, feel free to skip
this paragraph (and maybe a couple more). For the uninitiated,
though, each of those feeds presents a user with a continually
updating stream of other users’ posts. For Facebook’s News Feed,
any user may upload a message, whether verbal or visual, with
content running the gamut from “vacation pictures from friends” to
“articles from local or national news outlets.” App. in No. 22–555,
at 139a. And whenever a user signs on, Facebook delivers a
personalized collection of those stories. Similarly for YouTube.
Its users upload all manner of videos. And any person opening the
website or mobile app receives an individualized list of video
recommendations.
The key to the scheme is prioritization of
content, achieved through the use of algorithms. Of the billions of
posts or videos (plus advertisements) that could wind up on a
user’s customized feed or recommendations list, only the tiniest
fraction do. The selection and ranking is most often based on a
user’s expressed interests and past activities. But it may also be
based on more general features of the communication or its creator.
Facebook’s Community Standards and YouTube’s Community Guidelines
detail the messages and videos that the platforms disfavor. The
platforms write algorithms to implement those standards—for
example, to prefer content deemed particularly trustworthy or to
suppress content viewed as deceptive (like videos promoting
“conspiracy theor[ies]”). Id. , at 113a.
Beyond rankings lie labels. The platforms may
attach “warning[s], disclaimers, or general commentary”—for
example, informing users that certain content has “not been
verified by official sources.” Id. , at 75a. Likewise, they
may use “information panels” to give users “context on content
relating to topics and news prone to misinformation, as well as
context about who submitted the content.” Id. , at 114a. So,
for example, YouTube identifies content submitted by
state-supported media channels, including those funded by the
Russian Government. See id. , at 76a.
But sometimes, the platforms decide, providing
more information is not enough; instead, removing a post is the
right course. The platforms’ content-moderation policies also say
when that is so. Facebook’s Standards, for example, proscribe
posts—with exceptions for “newsworth[iness]” and other “public
interest value”—in categories and subcategories including: Violence
and Criminal Behavior ( e.g. , violence and incitement,
coordinating harm and publicizing crime, fraud and deception);
Safety ( e.g. , suicide and self-injury, sexual exploitation,
bullying and harassment); Objectionable Content ( e.g. , hate
speech, violent and graphic content); Integrity and Authenticity
( e.g. , false news, manipulated media). Id. , at
412a–415a, 441a–442a. YouTube’s Guidelines similarly target videos
falling within categories like: hate speech, violent or graphic
content, child safety, and misinformation (including about
elections and vaccines). See id. , at 430a–432a. The
platforms thus unabashedly control the content that will appear to
users, exercising authority to remove, label or demote messages
they disfavor.[ 6 ]
Except that Texas’s law limits their power to do
so. As noted earlier, the law’s central provision prohibits the
large social-media platforms (and maybe other
entities [ 7 ]) from
“censor[ing]” a “user’s expression” based on its “viewpoint.”
§143A.002(a)(2); see supra , at 7. The law defines
“expression” broadly, thus including pretty much anything that
might be posted. See §143A.001(2). And it defines “censor” to mean
“block, ban, remove, deplatform, demonetize, de-boost, restrict,
deny equal access or visibility to, or otherwise discriminate
against expression.” §143A.001(1).[ 8 ] That is a long list of verbs, but it comes down to
this: The platforms cannot do any of the things they typically do
(on their main feeds) to posts they disapprove—cannot demote,
label, or remove them—whenever the action is based on the post’s
viewpoint.[ 9 ] And what does
that “based on viewpoint” requirement entail? Doubtless some of the
platforms’ content-moderation practices are based on
characteristics of speech other than viewpoint ( e.g. , on
subject matter). But if Texas’s law is enforced, the platforms
could not—as they in fact do now—disfavor posts because they:
support Nazi ideology;
advocate for terrorism;
espouse racism, Islamophobia, or
anti-Semitism;
glorify rape or other gender-based
violence;
encourage teenage suicide and self-injury;
discourage the use of vaccines;
advise phony treatments for diseases;
advance false claims of election fraud.
The list could continue for a while.[ 10 ] The point of it is not that the
speech environment created by Texas’s law is worse than the ones to
which the major platforms aspire on their main feeds. The point is
just that Texas’s law profoundly alters the platforms’ choices
about the views they will, and will not, convey.
And we have time and again held that type of
regulation to interfere with protected speech. Like the editors,
cable operators, and parade organizers this Court has previously
considered, the major social-media platforms are in the business,
when curating their feeds, of combining “multifarious voices” to
create a distinctive expressive offering. Hurley , 515
U. S., at 569. The individual messages may originate with
third parties, but the larger offering is the platform’s. It is the
product of a wealth of choices about whether—and, if so, how—to
convey posts having a certain content or viewpoint. Those choices
rest on a set of beliefs about which messages are appropriate and
which are not (or which are more appropriate and which less so).
And in the aggregate they give the feed a particular expressive
quality. Consider again an opinion page editor, as in Tornillo , who wants to publish a variety of views, but
thinks some things off-limits (or, to change the facts, worth only
a couple of column inches). “The choice of material,” the
“decisions made [as to] content,” the “treatment of public
issues”—“whether fair or unfair”—all these “constitute the exercise
of editorial control and judgment.” Tornillo , 418
U. S., at 258. For a paper, and for a platform too. And the
Texas law (like Florida’s earlier right-of-reply statute) targets
those expressive choices—in particular, by forcing the major
platforms to present and promote content on their feeds that they
regard as objectionable.
That those platforms happily convey the lion’s
share of posts submitted to them makes no significant First
Amendment difference. Contra, 49 F. 4th, at 459–461 (arguing
otherwise). To begin with, Facebook and YouTube exclude (not to
mention, label or demote) lots of content from their News Feed and
homepage. The Community Standards and Community Guidelines set out
in copious detail the varied kinds of speech the platforms want no
truck with. And both platforms appear to put those manuals to work.
In a single quarter of 2021, Facebook removed from its News Feed
more than 25 million pieces of “hate speech content” and almost 9
million pieces of “bullying and harassment content.” App. in No.
22–555, at 80a. Similarly, YouTube deleted in one quarter more than
6 million videos violating its Guidelines. See id. , at 116a.
And among those are the removals the Texas law targets. What is
more, this Court has already rightly declined to focus on the ratio
of rejected to accepted content. Recall that in Hurley , the
parade organizers welcomed pretty much everyone, excluding only
those who expressed a message of gay pride. See supra , at
18. The Court held that the organizers’ “lenient” admissions
policy—and their resulting failure to express a “particularized
message”—did “not forfeit” their right to reject the few messages
they found harmful or offensive. 515 U. S., at 569, 574. So
too here, though the excluded viewpoints differ. That Facebook and
YouTube convey a mass of messages does not license Texas to
prohibit them from deleting posts with, say, “hate speech” based on
“sexual orientation.” App. in No. 22–555, at 126a, 155a; see id. , at 431a. It is as much an editorial choice to convey
all speech except in select categories as to convey only speech
within them.
Similarly, the major social-media platforms do
not lose their First Amendment protection just because no one will
wrongly attribute to them the views in an individual post. Contra,
49 F. 4th, at 462 (arguing otherwise). For starters, users may
well attribute to the platforms the messages that the posts convey in toto . Those messages—communicated by the feeds as a
whole—derive largely from the platforms’ editorial decisions about
which posts to remove, label, or demote. And because that is so,
the platforms may indeed “own” the overall speech environment. In
any event, this Court has never hinged a compiler’s First Amendment
protection on the risk of misattribution. The Court did not think
in Turner —and could not have thought in Tornillo or PG&E —that anyone would view the entity conveying the
third-party speech at issue as endorsing its content. See Turner
I , 512 U. S., at 655 (“[T]here appears little risk” of
such misattribution). Yet all those entities, the Court held, were
entitled to First Amendment protection for refusing to carry the
speech. See supra , at 14–16. To be sure, the Court noted in PruneYard and FAIR , when denying such protection,
that there was little prospect of misattribution. See 447
U. S., at 87; 547 U. S., at 65. But the key fact in those
cases, as noted above, was that the host of the third-party speech
was not itself engaged in expression. See supra , at 16–17.
The current record suggests the opposite as to Facebook’s News Feed
and YouTube’s homepage. When the platforms use their Standards and
Guidelines to decide which third-party content those feeds will
display, or how the display will be ordered and organized, they are
making expressive choices. And because that is true, they receive
First Amendment protection.
C
And once that much is decided, the interest
Texas relies on cannot sustain its law. In the usual First
Amendment case, we must decide whether to apply strict or
intermediate scrutiny. But here we need not. Even assuming that the
less stringent form of First Amendment review applies, Texas’s law
does not pass. Under that standard, a law must further a
“substantial governmental interest” that is “unrelated to the
suppression of free expression.” United States v. O’Brien , 391 U.S.
367 , 377 (1968). Many possible interests relating to social
media can meet that test; nothing said here puts regulation of
NetChoice’s members off-limits as to a whole array of subjects. But
the interest Texas has asserted cannot carry the day: It is very
much related to the suppression of free expression, and it is not
valid, let alone substantial.
Texas has never been shy, and always been
consistent, about its interest: The objective is to correct the mix
of speech that the major social-media platforms present. In this
Court, Texas described its law as “respond[ing]” to the platforms’
practice of “favoring certain viewpoints.” Brief for Texas 7; see id. , at 27 (explaining that the platforms’ “discrimination”
among messages “led to [the law’s] enactment”). The large
social-media platforms throw out (or encumber) certain messages;
Texas wants them kept in (and free from encumbrances), because it
thinks that would create a better speech balance. The current
amalgam, the State explained in earlier briefing, was “skewed” to
one side. 573 F. Supp. 3d, at 1116. And that assessment
mirrored the stated views of those who enacted the law, save that
the latter had a bit more color. The law’s main sponsor explained
that the “West Coast oligarchs” who ran social-media companies were
“silenc[ing] conservative viewpoints and ideas.” Ibid. The
Governor, in signing the legislation, echoed the point: The
companies were fomenting a “dangerous movement” to “silence”
conservatives. Id. , at 1108; see id. , at 1099
(“[S]ilencing conservative views is un- American, it’s un-Texan and
it’s about to be illegal in Texas”).
But a State may not interfere with private
actors’ speech to advance its own vision of ideological balance.
States (and their citizens) are of course right to want an
expressive realm in which the public has access to a wide range of
views. That is, indeed, a fundamental aim of the First Amendment.
But the way the First Amendment achieves that goal is by preventing the government from “tilt[ing] public debate in a preferred
direction.” Sorrell v. IMS Health Inc. , 564 U.S.
552 , 578–579 (2011). It is not by licensing the government to
stop private actors from speaking as they wish and
preferring some views over others. And that is so even when those
actors possess “enviable vehicle[s]” for expression. Hurley ,
515 U. S., at 577. In a better world, there would be fewer
inequities in speech opportunities; and the government can take
many steps to bring that world closer. But it cannot prohibit
speech to improve or better balance the speech market. On the
spectrum of dangers to free expression, there are few greater than
allowing the government to change the speech of private actors in
order to achieve its own conception of speech nirvana. That is why
we have said in so many contexts that the government may not
“restrict the speech of some elements of our society in order to
enhance the relative voice of others.” Buckley v. Valeo , 424 U.S.
1 , 48–49 (1976) ( per curiam ). That unadorned interest is
not “unrelated to the suppression of free expression,” and the
government may not pursue it consistent with the First
Amendment.
The Court’s decisions about editorial control,
as discussed earlier, make that point repeatedly. See supra ,
at 18–19. Again, the question those cases had in common was whether
the government could force a private speaker, including a compiler
and curator of third-party speech, to convey views it disapproved.
And in most of those cases, the government defended its regulation
as yielding greater balance in the marketplace of ideas. But the
Court—in Tornillo , in PG&E , and again in Hurley —held that such an interest could not support the
government’s effort to alter the speaker’s own expression. “Our
cases establish,” the PG&E Court wrote, “that the State
cannot advance some points of view by burdening the expression of
others.” 475 U. S., at 20. So the newspaper, the public
utility, the parade organizer—whether acting “fair[ly] or
unfair[ly]”—could exclude the unwanted message, free from
government interference. Tornillo , 418 U. S., at 258;
see United States Telecom Assn. v. FCC , 855 F.3d
381, 432 (CADC 2017) (Kavanaugh, J., dissenting from denial of
rehearing en banc) (“[E]xcept in rare circumstances, the First
Amendment does not allow the Government to regulate the content
choices of private editors just so that the Government may enhance
certain voices and alter the content available to the
citizenry”).[ 11 ]
The case here is no different. The interest
Texas asserts is in changing the balance of speech on the major
platforms’ feeds, so that messages now excluded will be included.
To describe that interest, the State borrows language from this
Court’s First Amendment cases, maintaining that it is preventing
“viewpoint discrimination.” Brief for Texas 19; see supra ,
at 26–27. But the Court uses that language to say what governments
cannot do: They cannot prohibit private actors from expressing
certain views. When Texas uses that language, it is to say what
private actors cannot do: They cannot decide for themselves what
views to convey. The innocent-sounding phrase does not redeem the
prohibited goal. The reason Texas is regulating the content-
moderation policies that the major platforms use for their feeds is
to change the speech that will be displayed there. Texas does not
like the way those platforms are selecting and moderating content,
and wants them to create a different expressive product,
communicating different values and priorities. But under the First
Amendment, that is a preference Texas may not impose.
IV
These are facial challenges, and that matters.
To succeed on its First Amendment claim, NetChoice must show that
the law at issue (whether from Texas or from Florida) “prohibits a
substantial amount of protected speech relative to its plainly
legitimate sweep.” Hansen , 599 U. S., at 770. None of
the parties below focused on that issue; nor did the Fifth or
Eleventh Circuits. But that choice, unanimous as it has been,
cannot now control. Even in the First Amendment context, facial
challenges are disfavored, and neither parties nor courts can
disregard the requisite inquiry into how a law works in all of its
applications. So on remand, each court must evaluate the full scope
of the law’s coverage. It must then decide which of the law’s
applications are constitutionally permissible and which are not,
and finally weigh the one against the other. The need for NetChoice
to carry its burden on those issues is the price of its decision to
challenge the laws as a whole.
But there has been enough litigation already to
know that the Fifth Circuit, if it stayed the course, would get
wrong at least one significant input into the facial analysis. The
parties treated Facebook’s News Feed and YouTube’s homepage as the
heartland applications of the Texas law. At least on the current
record, the editorial judgments influencing the content of those
feeds are, contrary to the Fifth Circuit’s view, protected
expressive activity. And Texas may not interfere with those
judgments simply because it would prefer a different mix of
messages. How that matters for the requisite facial analysis is for
the Fifth Circuit to decide. But it should conduct that analysis in
keeping with two First Amendment precepts. First, presenting a
curated and “edited compilation of [third party] speech” is itself
protected speech. Hurley , 515 U. S., at 570. And
second, a State “cannot advance some points of view by burdening
the expression of others.” PG&E , 475 U. S., at 20.
To give government that power is to enable it to control the
expression of ideas, promoting those it favors and suppressing
those it does not. And that is what the First Amendment protects
all of us from.
We accordingly vacate the judgments of the
Courts of Appeals for the Fifth and Eleventh Circuits and remand
the cases for further proceedings consistent with this opinion.
It is so ordered. Notes 1 *Justice Jackson joins Parts I,
II, and III–A of this opinion. 2 The definition of
“social-media platforms” covers “any information service, system,
Internet search engine, or access software provider” that
“[p]rovides or enables computer access by multiple users to a
computer server, including an Internet platform or a social media
site.” Fla. Stat. §501.2041(1)(g)(1). 3 The statute further
clarifies that it does not cover internet service providers, email
providers, and any online service, website, or app consisting
“primarily of news, sports, entertainment, or other information or
content that is not user generated but is preselected by the
provider.” §120.001(1). 4 Although the discussion
below focuses on Texas’s content-moderation provisions, it also
bears on how the lower courts should address the
individualized-explanation provisions in the upcoming facial
inquiry. As noted, requirements of that kind violate the First
Amendment if they unduly burden expressive activity. See Zauderer v. Office of Disciplinary Counsel of Supreme
Court of Ohio , 471 U.S.
626 , 651 (1985); supra , at 11. So our explanation of why
Facebook and YouTube are engaged in expression when they make
content-moderation choices in their main feeds should inform the
courts’ further consideration of that issue. 5 Of course, an entity
engaged in expressive activity when performing one function may not
be when carrying out another. That is one lesson of FAIR .
The Court ruled as it did because the law schools’ recruiting
services were not engaged in expression. See 547 U.S.
47 , 64 (2006). The case could not have been resolved on that
ground if the regulation had affected what happened in law school
classes instead. 6 We therefore do not deal
here with feeds whose algorithms respond solely to how users act
online—giving them the content they appear to want, without any
regard to independent content standards. See post , at 2
(Barrett, J., concurring). Like them or loathe them, the Community
Standards and Community Guidelines make a wealth of user-agnostic
judgments about what kinds of speech, including what viewpoints,
are not worthy of promotion. And those judgments show up in
Facebook’s and YouTube’s main feeds. 7 The scope of the Texas
law, a matter crucial to the facial inquiry, is unsettled, as
previously discussed. See supra , at 10–11. The Texas
solicitor general at oral argument stated that he understood the
law to cover Facebook and YouTube, but “d[id]n’t know” whether it
also covered other platforms and applications. Tr. of Oral Arg. in
No. 22–555, pp. 61–62. 8 In addition to barring
“censor[ship]” of “expression,” the law bars “censor[ship]” of
people. More specifically, it prohibits taking the designated
“censor[ial]” actions against any “user” based on his “viewpoint,”
regardless of whether that “viewpoint is expressed on a social
media platform.” §§143A.002(a)(1), (b); see supra , at 7.
Because the Fifth Circuit did not focus on that provision, instead
confining its analysis to the law’s ban on “censor[ing]” a “user’s
expression” on the platform, we do the same. 9 The Texas solicitor
general explained at oral argument that the Texas law allows the
platforms to remove “categories” of speech, so long as they are not
based on viewpoint. See Tr. of Oral Arg. in No. 22–555, at 69–70;
§120.052 (Acceptable Use Policy). The example he gave was speech
about Al-Qaeda. Under the law, a platform could remove all posts
about Al-Qaeda, regardless of viewpoint. But it could not stop the
“pro-Al-Qaeda” speech alone; it would have to stop the
“anti-Al-Qaeda” speech too. Tr. of Oral Arg. in No. 22–555, at 70.
So again, the law, as described by the solicitor general, prevents
the platforms from disfavoring posts because they express one view
of a subject. 10 Details on both the enumerated
examples and similar ones are found in Facebook’s Community
Standards and YouTube’s Community Guidelines. See
https://transparency.meta.com/policies/community-standards;
https://support.google.com/youtube/answer/9288567. 11 Texas
claims Turner as a counter-example, but that decision offers
no help to speak of. Turner did indeed hold that the FCC’s
must-carry provisions, requiring cable operators to give some of
their channel space to local broadcast stations, passed First
Amendment muster. See supra , at 15. But the interest there
advanced was not to balance expressive content; rather, the
interest was to save the local-broadcast industry, so that it could
continue to serve households without cable. That interest, the
Court explained, was “unrelated to the content of expression”
disseminated by either cable or broadcast speakers. Turner
I , 512 U.S.
622 , 647 (1994). And later, the Hurley Court again noted
the difference. It understood the Government interest in Turner as one relating to competition policy: The FCC needed
to limit the cable operators’ “monopolistic,” gatekeeping position
“in order to allow for the survival of broadcasters.” 515
U. S., at 577. Unlike in regulating the parade—or here in
regulating Facebook’s News Feed or YouTube’s homepage—the
Government’s interest was “not the alteration of speech.” Ibid . And when that is so, the prospects of permissible
regulation are entirely different. SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES
_________________
Nos. 22–277 and 22–555
_________________
ASHLEY MOODY, ATTORNEY GENERAL OF
FLORIDA, et al., PETITIONERS
22–277 v. NETCHOICE, LLC, dba NETCHOICE, et
al.
on writ of certiorari to the united states
court of appeals for the eleventh circuit
NETCHOICE, LLC, dba NETCHOICE, et al.,
PETITIONERS
22–555 v. KEN PAXTON, ATTORNEY GENERAL OF
TEXAS
on writ of certiorari to the united states
court of appeals for the fifth circuit
[July 1, 2024]
Justice Jackson, concurring in part and
concurring in the judgment.
These cases present a complex clash between two
novel state laws and the alleged First Amendment rights of several
of the largest social media platforms. Some things are already
clear. Not every potential action taken by a social media company
will qualify as expression protected under the First Amendment. But
not every hypothesized regulation of such a company’s operations
will necessarily be able to withstand the force of the First
Amendment’s protections either. Beyond those broadest of
statements, it is difficult to say much more at this time. With
these records and lower court decisions, we are not able to
adequately evaluate whether the challenged state laws are facially
valid.
That is in no small part because, as all Members
of the Court acknowledge, plaintiffs bringing a facial challenge
must clear a high bar. See ante, at 9–10 (majority opinion); post , at 13–14 (Alito, J., concurring in judgment). The
Eleventh Circuit failed to appreciate the nature of this challenge,
and the Fifth Circuit did not adequately evaluate it. That said, I
agree with Justice Barrett that the Eleventh Circuit at least
fairly stated our First Amendment precedent, whereas the Fifth
Circuit did not. See ante , at 1 (concurring opinion); see
also ante, at 13–19 (majority opinion). On remand, then,
both courts will have to undertake their legal analyses anew.
In doing so, the lower courts must address these
cases at the right level of specificity. The question is not
whether an entire category of corporations (like social media
companies) or a particular entity (like Facebook) is generally
engaged in expression. Nor is it enough to say that a given
activity (say, content moderation) for a particular service (the
News Feed, for example) seems roughly analogous to a more familiar
example from our precedent. Cf. Red Lion Broadcasting Co. v. FCC , 395 U.S.
367 , 386 (1969) (positing that “differences in the
characteristics of new media justify differences in the First
Amendment standards applied to them”). Even when evaluating a broad
facial challenge, courts must make sure they carefully parse not
only what entities are regulated, but how the regulated activities actually function before deciding if the activity in
question constitutes expression and therefore comes within the
First Amendment’s ambit. See Brief for Knight First Amendment
Institute at Columbia University as Amicus Curiae 11–12.
Thus, further factual development may be necessary before either of
today’s challenges can be fully and fairly addressed.
In light of the high bar for facial challenges
and the state of these cases as they come to us, I would not go on
to treat either like an as-applied challenge and preview our
potential ruling on the merits. Faced with difficult constitutional
issues arising in new contexts on undeveloped records, this Court
should strive to avoid deciding more than is necessary. See Ashwander v. TVA , 297 U.S.
288 , 346–347 (1936) (Brandeis, J., concurring). In my view,
such restraint is warranted today. SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES
_________________
Nos. 22–277 and 22–555
_________________
ASHLEY MOODY, ATTORNEY GENERAL OF
FLORIDA, et al., PETITIONERS
22–277 v. NETCHOICE, LLC, dba NETCHOICE, et
al.
on writ of certiorari to the united states
court of appeals for the eleventh circuit
NETCHOICE, LLC, dba NETCHOICE, et al.,
PETITIONERS
22–555 v. KEN PAXTON, ATTORNEY GENERAL OF
TEXAS
on writ of certiorari to the united states
court of appeals for the fifth circuit
[July 1, 2024]
Justice Thomas, concurring in the
judgment.
I agree with the Court’s decision to vacate and
remand because NetChoice and the Computer and Communications
Industry Association (together, the trade associations) have not
established that Texas’s H. B. 20 and Florida’s S. B.
7072 are facially unconstitutional.
I cannot agree, however, with the Court’s
decision to opine on certain applications of those statutes. The
Court’s discussion is unnecessary to its holding. See Jama v. Immigration and Customs Enforcement , 543 U.S.
335 , 351, n. 12 (2005) (“Dictum settles nothing, even in the
court that utters it”). Moreover, the Court engages in the exact
type of analysis that it chastises the Courts of Appeals for
performing. It faults the Courts of Appeals for focusing on only
one subset of applications, rather than determining whether each
statute’s “full range of applications” are constitutional. See ante, at 10, 12. But, the Court repeats that very same
error. Out of the sea of “variegated and complex” functions that
platforms perform, ante , at 11, the Court plucks out two
(Facebook’s News Feed and YouTube’s homepage), and declares that
they may be protected by the First Amendment. See ante, at
26 (opining on what the “current record suggests”). The Court does
so on a record that it itself describes as “incomplete” and
“underdeveloped,” ante, at 12, 20, and by sidestepping
several pressing factual and legal questions, see post , at
29–32 (Alito, J., concurring in judgment). As Justice Alito
explains, the Court’s approach is both unwarranted and mistaken.
See ibid .
I agree with Justice Alito’s analysis and join
his opinion in full. I write separately to add two observations on
the merits and to highlight a more fundamental jurisdictional
problem. The trade associations have brought facial challenges
alleging that H. B. 20 and S. B. 7072 are
unconstitutional in many or all of their applications. But,
Art-icle III of the Constitution permits federal courts to
exercise judicial power only over “Cases” and “Controversies.”
Accordingly, federal courts can decide whether a statute is
constitutional only as applied to the parties before them—they lack
authority to deem a statute “facially” unconstitutional.
I
As Justice Alito explains, the trade
associations have failed to provide many of the basic facts
necessary to evaluate their challenges to H. B. 20 and
S. B. 7072. See post , at 22–29. I make two additional
observations.
First, with respect to certain provisions of
H. B. 20 and S. B. 7072, the Court assumes that the
framework outlined in Zauderer v. Office of Disciplinary
Counsel of Supreme Court of Ohio , 471 U.S.
626 (1985), applies. See ante , at 11. In that case, the
Court held that laws requiring the disclosure of factual
information in commercial advertising may satisfy the First
Amendment if the disclosures are “reasonably related” to the
Government’s interest in preventing consumer deception. 471
U. S., at 651. Because the trade associations did not contest Zauderer ’s applicability before the Eleventh Circuit and
both lower courts applied its framework, I agree with the Court’s
decision to rely upon Zauderer at this stage. However, I
think we should reconsider Zauderer and its progeny. “I am
skeptical of the premise on which Zauderer rests—that, in
the commercial-speech context, the First Amendment interests
implicated by disclosure requirements are substantially weaker than
those at stake when speech is actually suppressed.” Milavetz,
Gallop & Milavetz, P. A. v. United States , 559 U.S.
229 , 255 (2010) (Thomas, J., concurring in part and concurring
in judgment) (internal quotation marks omitted).
Second, the common-carrier doctrine should
continue to guide the lower courts’ examination of the trade
associations’ claims on remand. See post , at 18, and
n. 17, 30 (opinion of Alito, J.). “[O]ur legal system and its
British predecessor have long subjected certain businesses, known
as common carriers, to special regulations, including a general
requirement to serve all comers.” Biden v. Knight First
Amendment Institute at Columbia Univ. , 593 U. S. ___, ___
(2021) (Thomas, J., concurring in grant of certiorari) (slip op.,
at 3). Moreover, “there is clear historical precedent for
regulating transportation and communications networks in a similar
manner as traditional common carriers” given their many
similarities. Id ., at ___ (slip op., at 5). Though they
reached different conclusions, both the Fifth Circuit and the
Eleventh Circuit appropriately strove to apply the common-carrier
doctrine in assessing the constitutionality of H. B. 20 and
S. B. 7072 respectively. See 49 F. 4th 439, 469–480 (CA5
2022); NetChoice v. Attorney Gen., Fla ., 34
F. 4th 1196, 1219–1222 (CA11 2022).
The common-carrier doctrine may have weighty
implications for the trade associations’ claims. But, the same
factual barriers that preclude the Court from assessing the trade
associations’ claims under our First Amendment precedents also
prevent us from applying the common-carrier doctrine in this
posture. At a minimum, we would need to pinpoint the regulated
parties and specific conduct being regulated. On remand, however,
both lower courts should continue to consider the common-carrier
doctrine.
II
The opinions in these cases detail many of the
considerable hurdles that currently preclude resolution of the
trade associations’ claims. See ante, at 9–10; ante ,
at 1–4 (Barrett, J., concurring); post , at 22–32 (opinion of
Alito, J.). The most significant problem of all, however, has yet
to be addressed: Federal courts lack authority to adjudicate the
trade associations’ facial challenges.
Rather than allege that the statutes
impermissibly regulate them, the trade associations assert that
H. B. 20 and S. B. 7072 are actually unconstitutional in
most or all of their applications. This type of challenge, called a
facial challenge, is “an attack on a statute itself as opposed to a
particular application.” Los Angeles v. Patel , 576 U.S.
409 , 415 (2015).
Facial challenges are fundamentally at odds with
Article III. Because Article III limits federal courts’ judicial
power to cases or controversies, federal courts “lac[k] the power
to pronounce that [a] statute is unconstitutional” as applied to
nonparties. Americans for Prosperity Foundation v. Bonta , 594 U.S. 595, 621 (2021) (Thomas, J., concurring in
part and concurring in judgment) (internal quotation marks
omitted). Entertaining facial challenges in spite of that
limitation arrogates powers reserved to the political branches and
disturbs the relationship between the Federal Government and the
States. The practice of adjudicating facial challenges creates
practical concerns as well. Facial challenges’ dubious historical
roots further confirm that the doctrine should have no place in our
jurisprudence.
A
1
Article III empowers federal courts to
exercise “judicial Power” only over “Cases” and “Controversies.”
This Court has long recognized that those terms impose substantive
constraints on the authority of federal courts. See Muskrat v. United States , 219 U.S.
346 , 356–358 (1911); see also Steel Co. v. Citizens
for Better Environment , 523 U.S.
83 , 102 (1998). One corollary of the case-or-controversy
requirement is that while federal courts can judge the
constitutionality of statutes, they may do so only to the extent
necessary to resolve the case at hand. “It is emphatically the
province and duty of the judicial department to say what the law
is,” but only because “[t]hose who apply the rule to particular
cases, must of necessity expound and interpret that rule.” Marbury v. Madison , 1 Cranch 137, 177 (1803); see Liverpool, New York & Philadelphia S. S. Co. v. Commissioners of Emigration , 113 U.S.
33 , 39 (1885) (“[The Court] has no jurisdiction to pronounce
any statute . . . irreconcilable with the Constitution,
except as it is called upon to adjudge the legal rights of
litigants in actual controversies”). Accordingly, “[e]xcept when
necessary” to resolve a case or controversy, “courts have no
charter to review and revise legislative and executive action.” Summers v. Earth Island Institute , 555 U.S.
488 , 492 (2009); see United States v. Raines , 362 U.S.
17 , 20–21 (1960).
These limitations on the power of judicial
review play an essential role in preserving our constitutional
structure. Our Constitution sets forth a “tripartite allocation of
power,” separating different types of powers across three co-equal
branches. DaimlerChrysler Corp. v. Cuno , 547 U.S.
332 , 341 (2006) (internal quotation marks omitted). “[E]ach
branch [is vested] with an exclusive form of power,” and “no branch
can encroach upon the powers confided to the others.” Patchak v. Zinke , 583 U.S. 244, 250 (2018) (plurality
opinion) (internal quotation marks omitted). In the Judicial
Branch’s case, it is vested with the “ultimate and supreme” power
of judicial review. Chicago & Grand Trunk R. Co. v. Wellman , 143 U.S.
339 , 345 (1892). That power includes the authority to refuse to
apply a statute enacted and approved by the other two branches of
the Federal Government. But, the power of judicial review can be
wielded only in specific circumstances and to limited ends—to
resolve cases and controversies. Without that limitation, the
Judiciary would have an unchecked ability to enjoin duly enacted
statutes. Respecting the case-or-controversy requirement is
therefore necessary to “preven[t] the Federal Judiciary from
intruding upon the powers given to the other branches, and
confin[e] the federal courts to a properly judicial role.” Town
of Chester v. Laroe Estates, Inc. , 581 U.S. 433, 438
(2017) (internal quotation marks and alteration omitted).
2
Facial challenges conflict with Article III’s
case-or-controversy requirement because they ask a federal court to
decide whether a statute might conflict with the Constitution in
cases that are not before the court.
To bring a facial challenge under our
precedents, a plaintiff must ordinarily “establish that no set of
circumstances exists under which the Act would be valid.” United
States v. Salerno , 481 U.S.
739 , 745 (1987). In the First Amendment context, we have
sometimes applied an even looser standard, called the overbreadth
doctrine. The overbreadth doctrine requires a plaintiff to
establish only that a statute “prohibits a substantial amount of
protected speech,” “relative to [its] plainly legitimate sweep.” United States v. Williams , 553
U.S. 285 , 292 (2008).
Facial challenges ask courts to issue holdings
that are rarely, if ever, required to resolve a single case or
controversy. The only way a plaintiff gets into a federal court is
by showing that he “personally has suffered some actual or
threatened injury as a result of the putatively illegal conduct of
the defendant.” Blum v. Yaretsky , 457 U.S.
991 , 999 (1982) (internal quotation marks omitted). And, the
only remedy a plaintiff should leave a federal court with is one
“limited to the inadequacy that produced the injury in fact that
the plaintiff has established.” Lewis v. Casey , 518 U.S.
343 , 357 (1996). Accordingly, once a court decides whether a
statute can be validly enforced against the plaintiff who
challenges it, that case or controversy is resolved. Either the
court remedies the plaintiff ’s injury, or it determines that
the statute may be constitutionally applied to the plaintiff.
Proceeding to decide the merits of possible
constitutional challenges that could be brought by other plaintiffs is not necessary to resolve that case. Instead, any
holding with respect to potential future plaintiffs would be “no
more than an advisory opinion—which a federal court should never
issue at all, and especially should not issue with regard to
a constitutional question, as to which we seek to avoid even non advisory opinions.” Chicago v. Morales , 527 U.S.
41 , 77 (1999) (Scalia, J., dissenting) (citation omitted).
Unsurprisingly, facial challenges are at odds
with doctrines enforcing the case-or-controversy requirement.
Pursuant to standing doctrine, for example, a plaintiff can
maintain a suit in a federal court—and thus invoke judicial
power—only if he has suffered an “injury” with a “traceable
connection” to the “complained-of conduct of the defendant.” Steel Co. , 523 U. S., at 103. Facial challenges
significantly relax those rules. Start with the injury requirement.
Facial challenges allow a plaintiff to challenge applications of a
statute that have not injured him. But see Acheson Hotels,
LLC v. Laufer , 601 U.S. 1, 10 (2023) (Thomas, J.,
concurring in judgment) (“To have standing, a plaintiff must assert
a violation of his [own] rights”). In fact, under our First
Amendment overbreadth doctrine, a plaintiff need not be injured at
all; he can challenge a statute that lawfully applies to him
so long as it would be unlawful to enforce it against others. See United States v. Hansen , 599 U.S. 762, 769
(2023).
Facial challenges also distort standing
doctrine’s redressability requirement. The Court has held that a
plaintiff has standing to sue only when his “requested relief will
redress the alleged injury.” Steel Co. , 523 U. S., at
103. With a facial challenge, however, a plaintiff seeks to enjoin
every application of a statute—including ones that have nothing to
do with his injury. A plaintiff can ask, “Do [I] just want [the
court] to say that this statute cannot constitutionally be applied
to [me] in this case, or do [I] want to go for broke and try to get
the statute pronounced void in all its applications?” Morales , 527 U. S., at 77 (opinion of Scalia, J.). In
this sense, the remedy sought by a facial challenge is akin to a
universal injunction—a practice that is itself “inconsistent with
longstanding limits on equitable relief and the power of Article
III courts.” Trump v. Hawaii , 585 U.S. 667, 713
(2018) (Thomas, J., concurring); see Department of Homeland
Security v. New York , 589 U. S. ___, ___–___ (2020)
(Gorsuch, J., concurring in grant of stay) (slip op., at 2–3); FDA v. Alliance for Hippocratic Medicine , 602 U.S.
367, 402 (2024) (Thomas, J., concurring).
Because deciding the constitutionality of a
statute as applied to nonparties is not necessary to resolve a case
or controversy, it is beyond a federal court’s constitutional
authority. Federal courts have “no power per se to review
and annul acts of Congress on the ground that they are
unconstitutional. That question may be considered only when the
justification for some direct injury suffered or threatened,
presenting a justiciable issue, is made to rest upon such an act.” Massachusetts v. Mellon , 262
U.S. 447 , 488 (1923). Resolving facial challenges thus violates
Article III.[ 1 ]
3
Adjudicating facial challenges also intrudes
upon powers reserved to the Legislative and Executive Branches and
the States. When a federal court decides an issue unnecessary for
resolving a case or controversy, the Judiciary assumes authority
beyond what the Constitution granted. Supra , at 5–6. That
necessarily alters the balance of powers: When one branch exceeds
its vested power, it becomes stronger relative to the other
branches. See Free Enterprise Fund v. Public Company
Accounting Oversight Bd ., 561 U.S.
477 , 500 (2010).
Moreover, by exceeding their Article III powers,
federal courts risk interfering with the executive and legislative
functions. Facial challenges enable federal courts to review the
constitutionality of a statute in many or all of its
applications—often before the statute has even been enforced. In
practice, this provides federal courts a “general veto power
. . . upon the legislation of Congress.” Muskrat ,
219 U. S., at 357. But, the Judicial Branch has no such
constitutional role in lawmaking. When courts take on the
supervisory role of judging statutes in the abstract, they thus
“assume a position of authority over the governmental acts of
another and co-equal department, an authority which plainly [they]
do not possess.” Mellon , 262 U. S., at 489.
Comparing the effects of as-applied challenges
and facial challenges makes this point clear. With an as-applied
challenge, the Judiciary intrudes only as much as necessary on the
will “ ‘of the elected representatives of the people.’ ” Washington State Grange v. Washington State Republican
Party , 552 U.S.
442 , 451 (2008). Assuming a court adheres to traditional
remedial limits, a successful as-applied challenge only prevents
application of the statute against that plaintiff. The Executive
Branch remains free to enforce the statute in all of its other
applications. And, the court’s decision provides some notice to the
political branches, enabling the Executive Branch to tailor future
enforcement of the statute to avoid violating the Constitution or
Congress to amend the statute.
Facial challenges, however, force the Judiciary
to take a maximalist approach. A single plaintiff can immediately
call upon a federal court to declare an entire statute
unconstitutional, even before it has been applied to him. The
political branches have no opportunity to correct course, making
legislation an all-or-nothing proposition. The end result is that
“the democratic process” is “short circuit[ed]” and “laws embodying
the will of the people [are prevented] from being implemented in a
manner consistent with the Constitution.” Ibid. In a similar vein, facial challenges distort the
relationship between the Federal Government and the States. The
Constitution “establishes a system of dual sovereignty between the
States and the Federal Government.” Gregory v. Ashcroft , 501 U.S.
452 , 457 (1991). The States retain all powers “not delegated”
to the Federal Government and not “prohibited by [the Constitution]
to the States.” Amdt. 10. Facial challenges can upset this division
by shifting power from the States to the Federal Judiciary. Most
obviously, when a state law is challenged, a facial challenge
prevents that State from applying its own statute in a
constitutional manner. But, facial challenges can also force
federal courts to appropriate the role of state courts. To analyze
whether a statute is valid on its face, a court must determine the
statute’s scope. If a state court has yet to determine the scope of
its statute (a common occurrence with facial challenges), the
federal court must do so in the first instance. Facial challenges
thus increase the likelihood that federal courts must interpret
novel state-law questions—a role typically and appropriately
reserved for state courts.
B
In addition to their constitutional
infirmities, facial challenges also create practical problems. The
case-or-controversy requirement serves as the foundation of our
adversarial system. Rather than “ ‘sit[ting] as self-directed
boards of legal inquiry and research,’ ” federal courts serve
as “ ‘arbiters of legal questions presented and argued by the
parties before them.’ ” NASA v. Nelson , 562 U.S.
134 , 147, n. 10 (2011) (quoting Carducci v. Regan , 714 F.2d 171, 177 (CADC 1983) (opinion for the court
by Scalia, J.)). This system “assure[s] that the legal questions
presented to the court will be resolved . . . in a
concrete factual context conducive to a realistic appreciation of
the consequences of judicial action.” Valley Forge Christian
College v. Americans United for Separation of Church and
State, Inc. , 454 U.S.
464 , 472 (1982).
Facial challenges disrupt the adversarial system
and increase the risk of judicial error as a result. A plaintiff
raising a facial challenge need not have any direct knowledge of
how the statute applies to others. In fact, since a facial
challenge may be brought before a statute has been enforced against
anyone, a plaintiff often can only guess how the statute
operates—even in his own case. For this reason, “[c]laims of facial
invalidity often rest on speculation,” Washington State
Grange , 552 U. S., at 450, and “factually barebones
records,” Sabri v. United States , 541 U.S.
600 , 609 (2004). Federal courts are often called to give
“premature interpretations of statutes in areas where their
constitutional application might be cloudy.” Raines , 362
U. S., at 22. In short, facial challenges ask courts to
resolve potentially thorny constitutional questions with little
factual background and briefing by a party who may not be affected
by the outcome.
C
The problems with facial challenges are
particularly evident in the two cases before us. Even though the
trade associations challenge two state laws, the state actors have
been left out of the picture. State officials had no opportunity to
tailor the laws’ enforcement. Nor could the legislatures amend the
statutes before they were preliminarily enjoined. In addition,
neither set of state courts had a chance to interpret their own
State’s law or “accord [that] law a limiting construction to avoid
constitutional questions.” Washington State Grange , 552
U. S., at 450. Instead, federal courts construed these novel
state laws in the first instance. And, they did so with little
factual record to assist them. The trade associations’ reliance on
our questionable associational-standing doctrine is partially to
blame.[ 2 ] But, the fact that
the trade associations raise facial challenges has undeniably
played a significant role. With even simple fact patterns, a court
has little chance of determining whether a novel,
never-before-enforced state law can be constitutionally enforced
against nonparties without resorting to mere speculation. For cases
such as these, where the constitutional analysis depends on
complex, fact-specific questions, the task becomes impossible.
D
Facial challenges are particularly suspect
given their origins. They appear to be the product of two doctrines
that are themselves constitutionally questionable, vagueness and
overbreadth.
At the time of the founding, it was well
understood that federal courts could hold a statute
unconstitutional only insofar as necessary to resolve a particular
case or controversy. See supra , at 5–6. The Founders were
certainly familiar with alternative systems that provided for the
free-floating review of duly enacted statutes. For example, the New
York Constitution of 1777 created a Council of Revision, composed
of the Governor, Chancellor, and New York Supreme Court. See Hansen , 599 U. S., at 786 (Thomas, J., concurring). The
Council of Revision could object to “any measure of a [prospective]
bill” based on “not only [its] constitutionality . . .
but also [its] policy.” Id ., at 787. If the Council lodged
an objection, the Legislature’s only options were to “conform to
[the Council’s] objections, override them by a two-thirds vote of
both Houses, or simply let the bill die.” Ibid. (internal
quotation marks omitted).
In our Constitution, the Founders refused to
create a council of revision or involve the Federal Judiciary in
the business of reviewing statutes in the abstract. “Despite the
support of respected delegates . . . the Convention voted
against creating a federal council of revision on four different
occasions. No other proposal was considered and rejected so many
times.” Id ., at 789 (citation omitted). Instead, the
Founders created a Judiciary with “only the authority to resolve
private disputes between particular parties, rather than matters
affecting the general public.” Ibid. (internal quotation
marks omitted). They considered judges “of all men the most unfit
to have a veto on laws before their enactment.” Ibid .
(internal quotation marks omitted). Therefore, they refused to
enlist judges in the business of reviewing statutes other than “as
an issue for decision in a concrete case or controversy.”[ 3 ] Ibid .
For more than a century following the founding,
the Court generally adhered to the original understanding of the
narrow scope of judicial review. When the Court first discussed the
concept of judicial review in Marbury v. Madison , it
made clear that such review is limited to what is necessary for
resolving “a particular cas[e]” before a court. 1 Cranch, at 177;
see also supra , at 5–6. And, in case after case that
followed Marbury , the Court reiterated that federal courts
have no authority to reach beyond the parties before them to
facially invalidate a statute.[ 4 ]
As best I can tell, the Court’s first departure
from those principles was the development of the vagueness
doctrine. See Johnson v. United States , 576 U.S.
591 , 616–620 (2015) (Thomas, J., concurring in judgment)
(describing history of vagueness doctrine). Before and at the time
of the founding, American and English courts dealt with vague laws
by “simply refus[ing] to apply them in individual cases.” Id ., at 615. After the unfortunate rise of “substantive” due
process, however, American courts began striking down statutes
wholesale as “unconstitutionally indefinite.” Id ., at 617.
This Court first adopted that approach in 1914, see International Harvester Co. of America v. Kentucky , 234 U.S.
216 , and has since repeatedly used the vagueness doctrine “to
strike down democratically enacted laws” in the name of substantive
due process, Sessions v. Dimaya , 584 U.S. 148, 210
(2018) (Thomas, J., dissenting); see Johnson , 576
U. S., at 618–621 (opinion of Thomas, J.). As I have
explained, I doubt that “our practice of striking down statutes as
unconstitutionally vague is consistent with the original meaning of
the Due Process Clause.” Dimaya , 584 U. S., at 206
(opinion of Thomas, J.); see Johnson , 576 U. S., at 622
(opinion of Thomas, J.).
The vagueness doctrine was the direct ancestor
of one subset of modern facial challenges, the overbreadth
doctrine. See United States v. Sineneng-Smith , 590
U.S. 371, 385 (2020) (Thomas, J., concurring) (noting that the
overbreadth doctrine “developed as a result of the vagueness
doctrine’s application in the First Amendment context”). In Thornhill v. Alabama , 310 U.S.
88 (1940), the Court deemed an antipicketing statute “invalid
on its face” due to its “sweeping proscription of freedom of
discussion.” Id., at 101–106. The Thornhill Court did
so “[w]ithout considering whether the defendant’s actual conduct
was entitled to First Amendment protection,” instead invalidating
the law because it “ ‘swept within its ambit . . .
activities that in ordinary circumstances constitute an exercise of
freedom of speech or of the press.’ ” Sineneng-Smith ,
590 U. S., at 383 (opinion of Thomas, J.) (quoting Thornhill , 310 U. S., at 97; alteration omitted). Thornhill ’s approach quickly gained
traction in the First Amendment context. In the years to follow,
the Court “invoked [its] rationale to facially invalidate a wide
range of laws” concerning First Amendment rights—a practice that
became known as the overbreadth doctrine. Sineneng-Smith ,
590 U. S., at 383. Under that doctrine, a court can invalidate
a statute if it “prohibits a substantial amount of protected
speech,” “relative to the statute’s plainly legitimate
sweep.”[ 5 ] Williams , 553
U. S., at 292. The Court has never attempted to ground the
overbreadth doctrine “in the text or history of the First
Amendment.” Sineneng-Smith , 590 U. S., at 384 (opinion
of Thomas, J.). Instead, the Court has supplied only “policy
considerations and value judgments.” Ibid .
The overbreadth and vagueness doctrines’ method
of facial invalidation eventually spread to other areas of law,
setting in motion our modern facial challenge doctrine. For several
decades after Thornhill , the Court continued to resist the
broad use of facial challenges. For example, in Broadrick v. Oklahoma , 413 U.S.
601 (1973), the Court emphasized that “[c]onstitutional
judgments, as Mr. Chief Justice Marshall recognized, are justified
only out of the necessity of adjudicating rights in particular
cases between the litigants brought before the Court.” Id., at 611. In that vein, the Court characterized “facial overbreadth
adjudication [as] an exception to our traditional rules of
practice.” Id ., at 615. But, the Court eventually
entertained facial challenges more broadly where a plaintiff
established that “no set of circumstances exists under which the
Act would be valid.” [ 6 ] Salerno , 481 U. S., at 745. Just as with the
overbreadth doctrine, the Court has yet to explain how facial
challenges are consistent with the Constitution’s text or
history.
Given how our facial challenge doctrine seems to
have developed—with one doctrinal mistake leading to another—it is
no wonder that facial challenges create a host of constitutional
and practical issues. See supra , at 6–13. Rather than
perpetuate our mistakes, the Court should end them. “No principle
is more fundamental to the judiciary’s proper role in our system of
government than the constitutional limitation of federal-court
jurisdiction to actual cases or controversies.” Simon v. Eastern Ky. Welfare Rights Organization , 426 U.S.
26 , 37 (1976). Because that requirement precludes courts from
judging and enjoining statutes as applied to nonparties, the Court
should discontinue the practice of facial challenges.
* * *
The Court has recognized the problems that
facial challenges pose, emphasizing that they are “disfavored,” Washington State Grange , 552 U. S., at 450, and “best
when infrequent,” Sabri , 541 U. S., at 608. The Court
reiterates those sentiments today. Ante, at 9, 30. But,
while sidelining facial challenges provides some measure of relief,
it ignores the real problem. Because federal courts are bound by
Article III’s case-or-controversy requirement, holding a statute
unconstitutional as applied to nonparties is not simply
disfavored—it exceeds the authority granted to federal courts. It
is high time the Court reconsiders its facial challenge
doctrine. Notes 1 This is not to say that
federal courts can never adjudicate a constitutional claim if a
plaintiff styles it as a facial challenge. Whenever a plaintiff
alleges a statute is unconstitutional in many or all of its
applications, that argument nearly always includes an allegation
that the statute is unconstitutional as applied to the plaintiff.
Federal courts are free to consider challenged statutes as applied
to the plaintiff before them and limit any relief accordingly. See
generally Americans for Prosperity Foundation v. Bonta , 594 U.S. 595, 618–619 (2021); id ., at 621
(Thomas, J., concurring in part and concurring in
judgment). 2 The trade associations do
not allege that they are subject to H. B. 20 and S. B.
7072, but have brought suit to vindicate the rights of their
members. There is thus not a single party in these suits that is
actually regulated by the challenged statutes and can explain how
specific provisions will infringe on their First Amendment rights.
Instead, the trade associations assert their understanding of how
the challenged statutes will regulate nonparties. As I have
recently explained, “[a]ssociational standing raises constitutional
concerns.” See FDA v. Alliance for Hippocratic
Medicine , 602 U.S. 367, 399 (2024) (concurring opinion).
Associational standing appears to conflict with Article III’s
injury and redressability requirements in many of the same ways as
facial challenges. I have serious doubts that either trade
association has standing to vicariously assert a member’s injury.
See id ., at 400. 3 “The later history of the
New York Council of Revision demonstrates the wisdom of the
Framers’ decision.” United States v. Hansen , 599 U.S.
762, 790 (2023) (Thomas, J., concurring). The Council’s ability to
lodge objections proved significant: “Over the course of its
existence, [the Council] returned 169 bills to the legislature; the
legislature, in turn, overrode only 51 of those vetoes and
reenacted at least 26 bills with modifications.” Ibid . The
Council did not shy away from controversial or weighty matters
either. It vetoed, among other things, “a bill barring those
convicted of adultery from remarrying” and a bill “declar[ing]
Loyalists aliens.” Ibid . In fact, the bill authorizing the
Erie Canal’s construction—“one of the most important measures in
the Nation’s history—survived the Council’s review only because
Chancellor James Kent changed his deciding vote at the last minute,
seemingly on a whim.” Ibid. Concerns over the Council’s
“intrusive involvement in the legislative process” eventually led
to its abolition in 1820. Ibid. 4 See, e . g ., Austin v. Aldermen , 7 Wall. 694, 699 (1869) (holding
that the Court could “only consider the statute in connection with
the case before” it and thus “our jurisdiction [wa]s at an end”
once it “ascertained that [the case] wrought no effect which the
act forbids”); Liverpool, New York & Philadelphia S. S.
Co. v. Commissioners of Emigration , 113 U.S.
33 , 39 (1885) (the Court “has no jurisdiction to pronounce any
statute . . . irreconcilable with the Constitution,
except as it is called upon to adjudge the legal rights of
litigants in actual controversies”); Chicago & Grand Trunk
R. Co. v. Wellman , 143 U.S.
339 , 345 (1892) (explaining that judicial review of a statute’s
constitutionality “is legitimate only in the last resort, and as a
necessity in the determination of real, earnest, and vital
controversy between individuals”); Muskrat v. United
States , 219 U.S.
346 , 357 (1911) (“[T]here [i]s no general veto power in the
court upon the legislation of Congress”); Yazoo &
Mississippi Valley R. Co. v. Jackson Vinegar Co. , 226 U.S.
217 , 219 (1912) (rejecting argument that statute was “void in toto ,” because the Court “must deal with the case in
hand and not with imaginary ones”); Dahnke-Walker Milling
Co. v. Bondurant , 257 U.S.
282 , 289 (1921) (“[A] litigant can be heard to question a
statute’s validity only when and so far as it is being or is about
to be applied to his disadvantage”); Massachusetts v .
Mellon , 262 U.S.
447 , 488 (1923) (Federal courts “have no power per se to review and annul acts of Congress on the
ground that they are unconstitutional. That question may be
considered only when the justification for some direct injury
suffered or threatened, presenting a justiciable issue, is made to
rest upon such an act”). 5 Although the Court’s
precedents describe an unconstitutionally overbroad statute as
facially “invalid,” “federal courts have no authority to erase a
duly enacted law from the statute books.” J. Mitchell, The
Writ-of-Erasure Fallacy, 104 Va. L. Rev. 933, 936 (2018); see Sineneng-Smith , 590 U. S., at 387 (opinion of Thomas,
J.). 6 Some Members of the Court
subsequently sought to apply a more lenient standard to all facial
challenges. See Washington State Grange v. Washington
State Republican Party , 552 U.S.
442 , 449 (2008) (noting that “some Members of the Court have
criticized the Salerno formulation”); United States v. Stevens , 559 U.S.
460 , 472 (2010) (reserving the question of which standard
applies to “a typical facial attack”). SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES
_________________
Nos. 22–277 and 22–555
_________________
ASHLEY MOODY, ATTORNEY GENERAL OF
FLORIDA, et al., PETITIONERS
22–277 v. NETCHOICE, LLC, dba NETCHOICE, et
al.
on writ of certiorari to the united states
court of appeals for the eleventh circuit
NETCHOICE, LLC, dba NETCHOICE, et al.,
PETITIONERS
22–555 v. KEN PAXTON, ATTORNEY GENERAL OF
TEXAS
on writ of certiorari to the united states
court of appeals for the fifth circuit
[July 1, 2024]
Justice Alito, with whom Justice Thomas and
Justice Gorsuch join, concurring in the judgment.
The holding in these cases is narrow: NetChoice
failed to prove that the Florida and Texas laws they challenged are
facially unconstitutional. Everything else in the opinion of the
Court is nonbinding dicta.
I agree with the bottom line of the majority’s
central holding. But its description of the Florida and Texas laws,
as well as the litigation that shaped the question before us,
leaves much to be desired. Its summary of our legal precedents is
incomplete. And its broader ambition of providing guidance on
whether one part of the Texas law is unconstitutional as applied to
two features of two of the many platforms that it reaches—namely,
Facebook’s News Feed and YouTube’s homepage—is unnecessary and
unjustified.
But given the incompleteness of this record,
there is no need and no good reason to decide anything other than
the facial unconstitutionality question actually before us. After
all, we do not know how the platforms “moderate” their users’
content, much less whether they do so in an inherently expressive
way under the First Amendment. Nevertheless, the majority is
undeterred. It inexplicably singles out a few provisions and a
couple of platforms for special treatment. And it unreflectively
assumes the truth of NetChoice’s unsupported assertion that
social-media platforms—which use secret algorithms to review and
moderate an almost unimaginable quantity of data today—are just as
expressive as the newspaper editors who marked up typescripts in
blue pencil 50 years ago.
These as-applied issues are important, and we
may have to decide them before too long. But these cases do not
provide the proper occasion to do so. For these reasons, I am
therefore compelled to provide a more complete discussion of those
matters than is customary in an opinion that concurs only in the
judgment.
I
As the Court has recognized, social-media
platforms have become the “modern public square.” Packingham v. North Carolina , 582 U.S. 98, 107 (2017). In just a few
years, they have transformed the way in which millions of Americans
communicate with family and friends, perform daily chores, conduct
business, and learn about and comment on current events. The vast
majority of Americans use social media,[ 1 ] and the average person spends more than two hours a day
on various platforms.[ 2 ] Young
people now turn primarily to social media to get the news,[ 3 ] and for many of them, life without
social media is unimaginable.[ 4 ] Social media may provide many benefits—but not without
drawbacks. For example, some research suggests that social media
are having a devastating effect on many young people, leading to
depression, isolation, bullying, and intense pressure to endorse
the trend or cause of the day.[ 5 ]
In light of these trends, platforms and
governments have implemented measures to minimize the harms unique
to the social-media context. Social-media companies have created
user guidelines establishing the kinds of content that users may
post and the consequences of violating those guidelines, which
often include removing nonconforming posts or restricting
noncompliant users’ access to a platform.
Such enforcement decisions can sometimes have
serious consequences. Restricting access to social media can impair
users’ ability to speak to, learn from, and do business with
others. Deleting the account of an elected official or candidate
for public office may seriously impair that individual’s efforts to
reach constituents or voters, as well as the ability of voters to
make a fully informed electoral choice. And what platforms call
“content moderation” of the news or user comments on public affairs
can have a substantial effect on popular views.
Concerned that social-media platforms could
abuse their enormous power, Florida and Texas enacted laws that
prohibit them from disfavoring particular viewpoints and speakers.
See S. B. 7072, 2021 Reg. Sess., §1(9) (Fla. 2021) (finding
that “[s]ocial media platforms have unfairly censored
. . . Floridians”); H. B. 20, 87th Leg., Called
Sess. (Tex. 2021) (prohibiting the “censorship of . . .
expression on social media platforms” in Texas). Both statutes have
a broad reach, and it is impossible to determine whether they are
unconstitutional in all their applications without surveying those
applications. The majority, however, provides only a cursory
outline of the relevant provisions of these laws and the litigation
challenging their constitutionality. To remedy this deficiency, I
will begin with a more complete summary.
A
1
I start with Florida’s law, S. B. 7072,
which regulates any internet platform that does “business in the
state” and has either “annual gross revenues in excess of $100
million” or “at least 100 million monthly individual platform
participants globally.” Fla. Stat. §501.2041(1)(g) (2023). This
definition is broad. There is no dispute that it covers large
social-networking websites like Facebook, X, YouTube, and
Instagram, but it may also reach e-commerce and other
non-social-networking websites that allow users to leave reviews,
ask and answer questions, or communicate with others online. These
may include Uber, Etsy, PayPal, Yelp, Wikipedia, and Gmail. See, e.g. , Tr. of Oral Arg. in No. 22–555, pp. 54–56, 69, 76–79,
155; Brief for Wikimedia Foundation as Amicus Curiae 6;
Brief for Yelp Inc. as Amicus Curiae 4, n. 4.
To prevent covered platforms from unfairly
treating Floridians, S. B. 7072 imposes the following
“content- moderation” and disclosure requirements: Content-moderation provisions . “Content
moderation” is the gentle-sounding term used by internet platforms
to denote actions they take purportedly to ensure that user-
provided content complies with their terms of service and
“community standards.” The Florida law eschews this neologism and
instead uses the old-fashioned term “censorship.” To prevent
platforms from discriminating against certain views or speakers,
that law requires each regulated platform to enforce its
“censorship . . . standards in a consistent manner among
its users on the platform.” Fla. Stat. §501.2041(2)(b). The law
defines “censorship” as any action taken to: “delete, regulate,
restrict, edit, alter, [or] inhibit” users from posting their own
content; “post an addendum to any content or material posted by a
user”; or “inhibit the ability of a user to be viewable by or to
interact with another user.” §501.2041(1)(b).
To prevent platforms from attempting to evade
this restriction by regularly modifying their practices, the law
prohibits platforms from changing their censorship “rules, terms,
and agreements . . . more than once every 30 days.”
§501.2041(2)(c). And to give Floridians more control over how they
view content on social-media websites, the law requires each
platform to give its users the ability to “opt out” of its
content-sorting “algorithms” and instead view posts sequentially or
chronologically. §501.2041(2)(f ).[ 6 ]
Although some platforms still have employees who
monitor and organize social-media feeds, for most platforms, “the
incredible volume of content shared each day makes human review of
each new post impossible.” Brief for Developers Alliance et al. as Amici Curiae 4. Consequently, platforms rely heavily on
algorithms to organize and censor content. Ibid. And it is
likely that they will increasingly rely on artificial intelligence
(AI), a machine learning tool that arranges, deletes, and modifies
content and learns from its own choices.
In addition to barring censorship, the Florida
law attempts to prevent platforms from unfairly influencing
elections or distorting public discourse. To do this, it requires
platforms to host candidates for public office and journalistic
enterprises.[ 7 ]
§§501.2041(2)(h), (j). For the same reasons, the law also prohibits
platforms from censoring posts made by or about candidates for
public office. §501.2041(2)(h). Disclosure provisions . S. B. 7072
requires platforms to make both general and individual disclosures
about how and when they censor the speech of Floridians. The law
requires platforms to publish their content-moderation standards
and to inform users of any changes. §§501.2041(2)(a), (c). And
whenever a platform censors a user, S. B. 7072 requires it to:
(1) notify the user of the censorship decision in writing
within seven days; (2) provide “a thorough” explanation of the
action and how the platform became aware of the affected content;
and (3) allow the user “to access or retrieve all of the
user’s information, content, material, and data for at least 60
days.” §§501.2041(2)(d), (i), (3).
To ensure compliance with these provisions,
S. B. 7072 authorizes the Florida attorney general to bring
civil and administrative actions against noncomplying platforms.
§501.2041(5). The law allows the Florida Elections Commission to
fine platforms that fail to host candidates for public office. Fla.
Stat. §106.072(3) (2023). And the law permits aggrieved users to
sue and recover up to $100,000 for each violation of the
content-moderation and disclosure provisions, along with actual
damages, equitable relief, punitive damages, and attorney’s fees.
§501.2041(6).
To protect platforms, the law provides that it
“may only be enforced to the extent not inconsistent with federal
law,” including §203 of the Communications Decency Act of 1996.
§501.2041(9). Section 230(c)(2)(A) of that Act shields internet
platforms from liability for voluntary, good-faith efforts to
restrict or remove content that is “obscene, lewd, lascivious,
filthy, excessively violent, harassing, or otherwise
objectionable.” 47 U. S. C. §230(c)(2)(A).
2
Days after S. B. 7072’s enactment,
NetChoice filed suit in federal court, alleging that the new law
violates the First Amendment in all its applications.[ 8 ] As a result, NetChoice asked the District
Court to enter a preliminary injunction against any enforcement of
any of its provisions before the law took effect.
Florida defended the constitutionality of
S. B. 7072. It argued that the law’s prohibition of censorship
does not violate the freedom of speech because the First Amendment
permits the regulation of the conduct of entities that do not
express their own views but simply provide the means for others to
communicate. See Record in No. 4:21–CV–00220 (ND Fla.), Doc. 106,
p. 22 (citing Rumsfeld v. Forum for Academic and
Institutional Rights, Inc. , 547 U.S.
47 , 64 (2006) ( FAIR )). And, in any event, Florida argued
that NetChoice’s facial challenge was likely to fail at the
threshold because NetChoice had not identified which of its members
were required to comply with the new law or how each of its
members’ presentation of third-party speech expressed that
platform’s own message. Record, Doc. 106, at 30, 58–59; id .,
Doc. 118, pp. 5, 24–25. Without this information, Florida
said, it could not properly respond to NetChoice’s facial claim. Id ., Doc. 122, pp. 4–5. Florida requested a “meaningful
opportunity to take discovery.” Tr. of Oral Arg. in No. 22–277,
p. 154. NetChoice objected. Record, Doc. 122.
Despite these arguments, the District Court
enjoined S. B. 7072 in its entirety before the law could go
into effect. Florida appealed, maintaining, among other things,
that NetChoice was “unlikely to prevail on the merits of [its]
facial First Amendment challenge.” Brief for Appellants in No.
21–12355 (CA11), p. 20; Reply Brief in No. 21–12355 (CA11), p.
15.
With just one exception, the Eleventh Circuit
affirmed. It first held that all the regulated platforms’
decisions about “whether, to what extent, and in what manner to
disseminate third-party created content to the public” were
constitutionally protected expression. NetChoice v. Attorney Gen., Fla. , 34 F. 4th 1196, 1212 (2022). Under
that framing, the court found that the moderation and individual-
disclosure provisions likely failed intermediate scrutiny,
obviating the need to determine whether strict scrutiny applied. Id., at 1227.[ 9 ] But the
court held that the general-disclosure provisions, which require
only that platforms publish their censorship policies, met the
intermediate-scrutiny standard set forth in Zauderer v. Office of Disciplinary Counsel of Supreme Court of Ohio , 471 U.S.
626 (1985). 34 F. 4th, at 1230. The Eleventh Circuit
therefore vacated the portion of the District Court’s order that
enjoined the enforcement of those general-disclosure provisions,
while affirming all the rest of the injunction. Id., at
1231.
B
1
Around the same time as the enactment of the
Florida law, Texas adopted a similar measure, H. B. 20, which
covers “social media platform[s]” with more than 50 million monthly
users in the United States. Tex. Bus. & Com. Code Ann.
§120.002(b) (West 2023). The statute defines a “ ‘[s]ocial
media platform’ ” as an “[i]nternet website or application
that is open to the public, allows a user to create an account, and
enables users to communicate with other users for the primary
purpose of posting information, comments, messages, or images.”
§120.001(l). Unlike Florida’s broader law, however, Texas’s statute
does not cover internet-service providers, email providers, and
websites that “consis[t] primarily of news, sports, entertainment,
or other information or content that is not user generated but is
preselected by the provider.” §120.001(1)(C)(i).
To ensure “the free exchange of ideas and
information,” H. B. 20 requires regulated platforms to abide
by the following content-moderation and disclosure requirements.
Act of Sept. 2, 2021, 87th Leg., 2d Called Sess., ch. 3. Content-moderation provisions . H. B.
20 prevents social-media companies from “censoring” users—that is,
acting to “block, ban, remove, deplatform, demonetize, de-boost,
restrict, deny equal access or visibility to, or otherwise
discriminate against”—based on their viewpoint or geographic
location within Texas.[ 10 ],[ 11 ],[ 12 ] Tex. Civ. Prac. & Rem. Code
Ann. §§143A.001(1), 143A.002(a)(1)–(3) (West Cum. Supp. 2023).
However, the law allows platforms to censor speech that: federal
law “specifically authorize[s]” them to censor; speech that the
platform is told sexually exploits children or survivors of sexual
abuse; speech that “directly incites criminal activity or consists
of specific threats of violence targeted against a person or group
because of race, color, disability, religion, national origin or
ancestry, age, sex or status as peace officer or judge”; and speech
that is otherwise unlawful or has been the subject of a user’s
request for removal from his or her feed or profile.
§§143A.006(a)–(b). Disclosure provisions . Like the Florida
law, H. B. 20 also requires platforms to make general and
individual disclosures about their censorship practices.
Specifically, the law obligates each platform to tell the public
how it “targets,” “promotes,” and “moderates” content.
§§120.051(a)(1)–(3). And whenever a platform censors a user, the
law requires it to inform the user why that was done.
§120.103(a)(1).[ 13 ]
Platforms must allow users to appeal removal decisions through “an
easily accessible complaint system;” resolve such appeals within 14
business days (unless an enumerated exception applies); and, if the
appeal is successful, provide “the reason for the reversal.”
§§120.101, 120.103(a)(2), (a)(3)(B)–(b), 120.104.
Users may sue any platform that violates these
provisions, as may the Texas attorney general. §143A.007(d). But
unlike the Florida law, H. B. 20 authorizes only injunctive
relief. §§143A.007(a), 143 A. 008. It contains a strong
severability provision, §8(a), which reaches “every provision,
section, subsection, sentence, clause, phrase, or word in th[e]
Act, and every application of [its] provisions.”
2
As it did in the Florida case, NetChoice
sought a preliminary injunction in federal court, claiming that
H. B. 20 violates the First Amendment in its entirety. In
response, Texas argued that because H. B. 20 regulates
NetChoice’s members “in their operation as publicly accessible
conduits for the speech of others” rather than “as authors or
editors” of their own speech, NetChoice could not prevail. Record
in No. 1:21–CV–00840 (WD Tex.), Doc. 39, p. 23. But even if
the platforms might have the right to use algorithms to censor
their users’ speech, the State argued, the question of “ what these algorithms are doing is a critical, and so far, unexplained,
aspect of this case.” Id ., at 24. This deficiency mattered,
Texas contended, because the platforms could succeed on their
facial challenge only by showing that “ all algorithms used
by the Platforms are for the purposes of expressing viewpoints of
those Platforms.” Id., at 27. And because NetChoice had not
even explained what its members’ algorithms did, much less whether
they did so in an expressive way, Texas argued that NetChoice had
not shown that “all applications of H.B. 20 are unconstitutional.” Ibid. ; see also id ., Doc. 53, at 13 (arguing that
NetChoice had failed to show that “H. B. 20 is . . .
unconstitutional in all its applications” because “a number” of
NetChoice’s members had conceded that the law did “ not burden or chill their speech”).
To clarify these and other “threshold issues,”
Texas moved for expedited discovery. Id ., Doc. 20, at 1. The
District Court granted Texas’s motion in part, but after one month
of discovery, it sided with NetChoice and enjoined H. B. 20 in
its entirety before it could go into effect. Texas appealed,
arguing that despite the District Court’s judgment to the contrary,
“[l]aws requiring commercial entities to neutrally host speakers
generally do not even implicate the First Amendment because they do
not regulate the host’s speech at all—they regulate its conduct.”
Brief for Appellant in No. 21–51178 (CA5), p. 16. The State also
emphasized NetChoice’s alleged failure to show that H. B. 20
was unconstitutional in even a “ ‘substantial number of its
applications,’ ” the “bare minimum” showing that NetChoice
needed to make to prevail on its facial challenge. E.g., Reply Brief in No. 21–51178 (CA5), p. 8 (quoting Americans for
Prosperity Foundation v. Bonta , 594 U.S. 595, 615
(2021)).
A divided Fifth Circuit panel reversed, focusing
primarily on NetChoice’s failure to “even try to show that HB 20 is
‘unconstitutional in all of its applications.’ ” 49
F. 4th 439, 449 (2022) (quoting Washington State Grange v. Washington State Republican Party , 552 U.S.
442 , 449 (2008)). The court also accepted Texas’s argument that
H. B. 20 “does not regulate the Platforms’ speech at all”
because “the Platforms are not ‘speaking’ when they host other
people’s speech.” 49 F. 4th, at 448. Finally, the court upheld
the law’s disclosure requirements on the ground that they involve
the disclosure of the type of purely factual and uncontroversial
information that may be compelled under Zauderer . 49 F. 4th,
at 485.
II
NetChoice contends that the Florida and Texas
statutes facially violate the First Amendment, meaning that they
cannot be applied to anyone at any time under any circumstances
without violating the Constitution. Such challenges are strongly
disfavored. See Washington State Grange , 552 U. S., at
452. They often raise the risk of “ ‘premature
interpretatio[n] of statutes’ on the basis of factually barebones
records.” Sabri v. United States , 541 U.S.
600 , 609 (2004). They clash with the principle that courts
should neither “ ‘anticipate a question of constitutional law
in advance of the necessity of deciding it’ ” nor
“ ‘formulate a rule of constitutional law broader than is
required by the precise facts to which it is to be applied.’ ” Ashwander v. TVA , 297 U.S.
288 , 346–347 (1936) (Brandeis, J., concurring). And they
“threaten to short circuit the democratic process by preventing
laws embodying the will of the people from being implemented in a
manner consistent with the Constitution.” Washington State
Grange , 552 U. S., at 451.
Facial challenges also strain the limits of the
federal courts’ constitutional authority to decide only actual
“Cases” and “Controversies.” Art. III, §2. “[L]itigants typically
lack standing to assert the constitutional rights of third
parties.” United States v. Hansen , 599 U.S. 762, 769
(2023). But when a court holds that a law cannot be enforced
against anyone under any circumstances, it effectively grants
relief with respect to unknown parties in disputes that have not
yet materialized.
For these reasons, we have insisted that parties
mounting facial attacks satisfy demanding requirements. In United States v. Salerno , 481
U.S. 739 , 745 (1987), we held that a facial challenger must
“establish that no set of circumstances exists under which the
[law] would be valid.” “While some Members of the Court have
criticized the Salerno formulation,” all have agreed “that a
facial challenge must fail where the statute has a “ ‘plainly
legitimate sweep.” ’ ” Washington State Grange ,
552 U. S., at 449. In First Amendment cases, we have sometimes
phrased the requirement as an obligation to show that a law
“ ‘prohibits a substantial amount of protected speech’ ”
relative to its ‘ “plainly legitimate sweep.’ ” Hansen , 599 U. S., at 770; Bonta , 594
U. S., at 615; United States v. Williams , 553 U.S.
285 , 292–293 (2008).[ 14 ]
NetChoice and the Federal Government urge us not
to apply any of these demanding tests because, they say, the States
disputed only the “threshold question” whether their laws “cover
expressive activity at all.” Tr. of Oral Arg. in No. 22–277, at 76;
see also id., at 84, 125; Tr. of Oral Arg. in No. 22–555, at
92. The Court unanimously rejects that argument—and for good
reason.
First, the States did not “put all their
eggs in [one] basket.” Tr. of Oral Arg. in No. 22–277, at 76. To be
sure, they argued that their newly enacted laws were valid in all
their applications. Ibid. Both the Federal Government and
the States almost always defend the constitutionality of all
provisions of their laws. But Florida and Texas did not stop there.
Rather, as noted above, they went on to argue that NetChoice had
failed to make the showing required for a facial
challenge.[ 15 ] Therefore,
the record does not support NetChoice’s attempt to use “the party
presentation rules” as grounds for blocking our consideration of
the question whether it satisfied the facial constitutionality
test. Tr. of Oral Arg. in No. 22–555, at 92.
Second, even if the States had not asked the
lower courts to reject NetChoice’s request for blanket relief, it
would have been improper for those courts to enjoin all
applications of the challenged laws unless that test was met. “It
is one thing to allow parties to forfeit claims, defenses, or lines
of argument; it would be quite another to allow parties to
stipulate or bind [a court] to the application of an incorrect
legal standard.” Gardner v. Galetka , 568 F.3d 862,
879 (CA10 2009); see also Kairys v. Southern Pines
Trucking, Inc ., 75 F. 4th 153, 160 (CA3 2023) (“But
parties cannot forfeit the application of ‘controlling
law’ ”); United States v. Escobar , 866 F.3d 333,
339, n. 13 (CA5 2017) ( per curiam ) (“ ‘A party cannot
waive, concede, or abandon the applicable standard of
review’ ” (quoting Ward v. Stephens , 777 F.3d
250, 257, n. 3 (CA5 2015)).
Represented by sophisticated counsel, NetChoice
made the deliberate choice to mount a facial challenge to both
laws, and in doing so, it obviously knew what it would have to show
in order to prevail. NetChoice decided to fight these laws on these
terms, and the Court properly holds it to that decision.
III
I therefore turn to the question whether
NetChoice established facial unconstitutionality, and I begin with
the States’ content-moderation requirements. To show that these
provisions are facially invalid, NetChoice had to demonstrate that
they lack a plainly legitimate sweep under the First Amendment. Our
precedents interpreting that Amendment provide the numerator (the
number of unconstitutional applications) and denominator (the total
number of possible applications) that NetChoice was required to
identify in order to make that showing. Estimating the numerator
requires an understanding of the First Amendment principles that
must be applied here, and I therefore provide a brief review of
those principles.
A
The First Amendment protects “the freedom of
speech,” and most of our cases interpreting this right have
involved government efforts to forbid, restrict, or compel a
party’s own oral or written expression. Agency for Int’l
Development v. Alliance for Open Society Int’l, Inc. , 570 U.S.
205 , 213 (2013); Wooley v. Maynard , 430 U.S.
705 , 714 (1977); West Virginia Bd. of Ed. v. Barnette , 319 U.S.
624 , 642 (1943). Some cases, however, have involved another
aspect of the free speech right, namely, the right to “presen[t]
. . . an edited compilation of speech generated by other
persons” for the purpose of expressing a particular message. See Hurley v. Irish-American Gay, Lesbian and Bisexual Group
of Boston, Inc. , 515 U.S.
557 , 570 (1995). As used in this context, the term
“compilation” means any effort to present the expression of others
in some sort of organized package. See ibid. An example such as the famous Oxford Book of
English Poetry illustrates why a compilation may constitute
expression on the part of the compiler. The editors’ selection of
the poems included in this volume expresses their view about the
poets and poems that most deserve the attention of their
anticipated readers. Forcing the editors to exclude or include a
poem could alter the expression that the editors wish to
convey.
Not all compilations, however, have this
expressive characteristic. Suppose that the head of a neighborhood
group prepares a directory consisting of contact information
submitted by all the residents who want to be listed. This
directory would not include any meaningful expression on the part
of the compiler.
Because not all compilers express a message of
their own, not all compilations are protected by the First
Amendment. Instead, the First Amendment protects only those
compilations that are “inherently expressive” in their own right,
meaning that they select and present speech created by other
persons in order “to spread [the compiler’s] own message.” FAIR , 547 U. S., at 66; Pacific Gas & Elec.
Co. v. Public Util. Comm’n of Cal. , 475 U.S.
1 , 10 (1986) ( PG&E ) (plurality opinion). If a
compilation is inherently expressive, then the compiler may have
the right to refuse to accommodate a particular speaker or message.
See Hurley , 515 U. S., at 573. But if a compilation is
not inherently expressive, then the government can require the
compiler to host a message or speaker because the accommodation
does not amount to compelled speech. Id. , at 578–581.
To show that a hosting requirement would compel
speech and thereby trigger First Amendment scrutiny, a claimant
must generally show three things.
1
First, a claimant must establish that its
practice is to exercise “editorial discretion in the selection and
presentation” of the content it hosts. Arkansas Ed. Television
Comm’n v. Forbes , 523 U.S.
666 , 674 (1998); Hurley , 515 U. S., at 574; ante, at 14. NetChoice describes this process as content
“curation.” But whatever you call it, not all compilers do this, at
least in a way that is inherently expressive. Some may serve as
“passive receptacle[s]” of third-party speech or as “dumb
pipes”[ 16 ] that merely emit
what they are fed. Such entities communicate no message of their
own, and accordingly, their conduct does not merit First Amendment
protection.[ 17 ] Miami
Herald Publishing Co. v. Tornillo , 418
U.S. 241 , 258 (1974).
Determining whether an entity should be viewed
as a “curator” or a “dumb pipe” may not always be easy because
different aspects of an entity’s operations may take different
approaches with respect to hosting third-party speech. The typical
newspaper regulates the content and presentation of articles
authored by its employees or others, PG&E , 475
U. S., at 8, but that same paper might also run nearly all the
classified advertisements it receives, regardless of their content
and without adding any expression of its own. Compare Tornillo , 418 U.S.
241 , with Pittsburgh Press Co. v. Pittsburgh Comm’n
on Human Relations , 413
U.S. 376 (1973). These differences may be significant for First
Amendment purposes.
The same may be true for a parade organizer. For
example, the practice of a parade organizer may be to select the groups that are admitted, but not the individuals who
are allowed to march as members of admitted groups. Hurley ,
515 U. S., at 572–574. In such a case, each of these practices
would have to be analyzed separately.
2
Second, the host must use the compilation of
speech to express “some sort of collective point”—even if only at a
fairly abstract level. Id. , at 568. Thus, a parade organizer
who claims a First Amendment right to exclude certain groups or
individuals would need to show at least that the message conveyed
by the groups or individuals who are allowed to march comport with
the parade’s theme. Id., at 560, 574. A parade comprising
“unrelated segments” that lumber along together willy-nilly would
likely not express anything at all. Id. , at 576. And
although “a narrow, succinctly articulable message is not a
condition of constitutional protection,” compilations that organize
the speech of others in a non-expressive way ( e.g., chronologically) fall “beyond the realm of expressi[on].” Id., at 569; contra, ante, at 17–18 . Our decision in PruneYard illustrates
this point. In that case, the Court held that a mall could be
required to host third-party speech ( i.e. , to admit
individuals who wanted to distribute handbills or solicit
signatures on petitions) because the mall’s admission policy did
not express any message, and because the mall was “open to the
public at large.” PruneYard Shopping Center v. Robins , 447 U.S.
74 , 83, 87–88 (1980); 303 Creative LLC v. Elenis ,
600 U.S. 570, 590 (2023). In such circumstances, we held that the
First Amendment is not implicated merely because a host objects to
a particular message or viewpoint. See PG&E , 475
U. S., at 12.
3
Finally, a compiler must show that its “own
message [is] affected by the speech it [is] forced to accommodate.” FAIR , 547 U. S., at 63. In core examples of expressive
compilations, such as a book containing selected articles,
chapters, stories, or poems, this requirement is easily satisfied.
But in other situations, it may be hard to identify any message
that would be affected by the inclusion of particular third-party
speech.
Two precedents that the majority tries to
downplay, if not forget, are illustrative. The first is PruneYard , which I have already discussed. The PruneYard Court rejected the mall’s First Amendment claim
because “[t]he views expressed by members of the public in passing
out pamphlets or seeking signatures for a petition [were] not
likely [to] be identified with those of the owner.” 447 U. S.,
at 87. And if those who perused the handbills or petitions were not
likely to make that connection, any message that the mall owner
intended to convey would not be affected.
The decision in FAIR rested on similar
reasoning. In that case, the Court did not dispute the proposition
that the law schools’ refusal to host military recruiters expressed
the message that the military should admit and retain gays and
lesbians. But the Court found no First Amendment violation because,
as in PruneYard , it was unlikely that the views of the
military recruiters “would be identified with” those of the schools
themselves, and consequently, hosting the military recruiters did
not “sufficiently interfere with any message of the school.” 547
U. S., at 64–65; contra, ante , at 25 (“[T]his Court has never hinged a compiler’s First Amendment protection on the
risk of misattribution.”).[ 18 ]
B
A party that challenges government
interference with its curation of content cannot win without making
the three-part showing just outlined, but such a showing does not
guarantee victory. To prevail, the party must go on and show that
the challenged regulation of its curation practices violates the
applicable level of First Amendment scrutiny.
Our decision in Turner makes that clear.
Although the television cable operators in that case made the
showing needed to trigger First Amendment scrutiny, they did not
ultimately prevail on their facial challenge to the Cable Act.
After a remand and more than 18 months of additional factual
development, the Court held that the law was adequately tailored to
serve legitimate and important government interests, including
“promoting the widespread dissemination of information from a
multiplicity of sources.” Turner Broadcasting System, Inc. v. FCC , 520 U.S.
180 , 189 (1997). Here, the States assert a similar interest in
fostering a free and open marketplace of ideas.[ 19 ]
C
With these standards in mind, I proceed to the
question whether the content-moderation provisions are facially
valid. For the following three reasons, NetChoice failed to meet
its burden.
1
First, NetChoice did not establish which
entities the statutes cover. This failure is critical because
it is “impossible to determine whether a statute reaches too far
without first knowing what the statute covers.” Williams ,
553 U. S., at 293. When it sued Florida, NetChoice was
reluctant to disclose which of its members were covered by
S. B. 7072. Instead, it filed declarations revealing only that
the law reached “Etsy, Facebook, and YouTube.” Tr. of Oral Arg. in
No. 22–277, at 32. In this Court, NetChoice was a bit more
forthcoming, representing that S. B. 7072 also covers In-
stagram, X, Pinterest, Reddit, Gmail, Uber, and other e-commerce
websites. Id., at 69, 76; Brief for Respondents in No.
22–277, at 7, 38, 49.[ 20 ] But NetChoice has still not provided a complete
list.
NetChoice was similarly reluctant to identify
its affected members in the Texas case. At first, NetChoice
“represented . . . that only Facebook, YouTube, and [X]
are affected by the Texas law.” Brief for Appellant in No. 21–51178
(CA5), at 1, n. 1. But in its brief in this Court, NetChoice
told us that H. B. 20 also regulates “some of the Internet’s
most popular websites, including Facebook, Instagram, Pinterest,
TikTok, Vimeo, X (formerly known as Twitter), and YouTube.” Brief
for Petitioners in No. 22–555, p. 1. And websites such as
Discord,[ 21 ]
Reddit,[ 22 ]
Wikipedia,[ 23 ] and
Yelp[ 24 ] have filed amicus briefs claiming that they may be covered by both the
Texas and Florida laws.
It is a mystery how NetChoice could expect to
prevail on a facial challenge without candidly disclosing the
platforms that it thinks the challenged laws reach or the nature of
the content moderation they practice. Without such information, we
have no way of knowing whether the laws at issue here “cover
websites that engage in primarily non- expressive conduct.” Tr. of
Oral Arg. in No. 22–277, at 34; see also id., at 126.
For example, among other things, NetChoice has not stated whether
the challenged laws reach websites like WhatsApp[ 25 ] and Gmail,[ 26 ] which carry messages instead of curating them to create an independent speech product. Both
laws also appear to cover Reddit[ 27 ] and BeReal,[ 28 ] and websites like Parler,[ 29 ] which claim to engage in little or no content
moderation at all. And Florida’s law, which is even broader than
Texas’s, plainly applies to e-commerce platforms like Etsy that
make clear in their terms of service that they are “not a curated
marketplace.”[ 30 ]
In First Amendment terms, this means that these
laws—in at least some of their applications—appear to regulate the
kind of “passive receptacle[s]” of third-party speech that receive
no First Amendment protection. Tornillo , 418 U. S., at
258. Given such uncertainty, it is impossible for us to determine
whether these laws have a “plainly legitimate sweep.” Williams , 553 U. S., at 292; Washington State
Grange , 552 U. S., at 449.
2
Second, NetChoice has not established what kinds of content appear on all the regulated platforms,
and we cannot determine whether these platforms create an
“inherently expressive” compilation of third-party speech until we
know what is being compiled.
We know that social-media platforms generally allow their users to create accounts; send direct
messages through private inboxes; post written messages, photos,
and videos; and comment on, repost, or otherwise interact with
other users’ posts. And NetChoice acknowledges in fairly general
terms that its members engage in most—though not all—of these
functions. But such generalities are insufficient.
For one thing, the ways in which users post,
send direct messages, or interact with content may differ in
meaningful ways from platform to platform. And NetChoice’s failure
to account for these differences may be decisive. To see how,
consider X and Yelp. Both platforms allow users to post comments
and photos, but they differ in other respects.[ 31 ] X permits users to post (or “Tweet”) on a
broad range of topics because its “purpose is to serve the public
conversation,”[ 32 ] and as a
result, many elected officials use X to communicate with
constituents. Yelp, by contrast, allows users to post comments and
pictures only for the purpose of advertising local businesses or
providing “firsthand accounts” that reflect their “consumer
experience” with businesses.[ 33 ] It does not permit “rants about political ideologies,
a business’s employment practices, extraordinary circumstances, or
other matters that don’t address the core of the consumer
experience.”[ 34 ]
As this example shows, X’s content is more
political than Yelp’s, and Yelp’s content is more commercial than
X’s. That difference may be significant for First Amendment
purposes. See Pittsburgh Press , 413
U.S. 376 . But NetChoice has not developed the record on that
front. Nor has it shown what kinds of content appear across the
diverse array of regulated platforms.
Social-media platforms are diverse, and each may
be unique in potentially significant ways. On the present record,
we are ill-equipped to account for the many platform-specific
features that allow users to do things like sell or purchase
goods,[ 35 ] live-stream
events,[ 36 ] request a
ride,[ 37 ] arrange a
date,[ 38 ] create a
discussion forum,[ 39 ] wire
money to friends,[ 40 ] play a
video game,[ 41 ] hire an
employee,[ 42 ] log a
run,[ 43 ] or agree to watch a
dog.[ 44 ] The challenged laws
may apply differently to these different functions, which may
present different First Amendment issues. A court cannot invalidate
the challenged laws if it has to speculate about their
applications.
3
Third, NetChoice has not established how websites moderate content. NetChoice alleges that
“[c]overed websites” generally use algorithms to organize and
censor content appearing in “search results, comments, or in
feeds.” Brief for Petitioners in No. 22–555, at 4, 6. But at this
stage and on this record, we have no way of confirming whether all
of the regulated platforms use algorithms to organize all of their
content, much less whether these algorithms are expressive. See Hurley , 515 U. S., at 568. Facebook and Reddit, for
instance, both allow their users to post about a wide range of
topics.[ 45 ] But while
Facebook uses algorithms to arrange and moderate its users’ posts,
Reddit asserts that its content is moderated by Reddit users, “not
by centralized algorithms.” Brief for Reddit, Inc., as Amicus
Curiae 2. If Reddit and other platforms entirely outsource
curation to others, they can hardly claim that their compilations
express their own views.
Perhaps recognizing this, NetChoice argues in
passing that it cannot tell us how its members moderate content
because doing so would embolden “malicious actors” and divulge
“proprietary and closely held” information. E.g., Brief for
Petitioners in No. 22–555, at 11. But these harms are far from
inevitable. Various platforms already make similar disclosures—both
voluntarily and to comply with the European Union’s Digital
Services Act[ 46 ]—yet the sky
has not fallen. And on remand, NetChoice will have the opportunity
to contest whether particular disclosures are necessary and whether
any relevant materials should be filed under seal.
Various NetChoice members already disclose in
broad strokes how they use algorithms to curate content. Many
platforms claim to use algorithms to identify and remove violent,
obscene, sexually explicit, and false posts that violate their
community guidelines. Brief for Developers Alliance et al. as Amici Curiae 11. Some platforms—like X, for instance—say
they use algorithms, not for the purpose of removing all
nonconforming speech, but to “promot[e] counterspeech” that
“presents facts to correct misstatements” or “denounces hateful or
dangerous speech.”[ 47 ] Still
others, like Parler,[ 48 ]
Reddit,[ 49 ] and Signal
Messenger,[ 50 ] say they
engage in little or no content moderation.
Some platforms have also disclosed that they use
algorithms to help their users find relevant content. The
e-commerce platform Etsy, for instance, uses an algorithm that
matches a user’s search terms to the “attributes” that a seller
ascribes to its wares.[ 51 ]
Etsy’s algorithm also accounts for things like the date of the
seller’s listing, the proximity of the seller and buyer, and the
quality of the seller’s customer-service ratings. Ibid. YouTube says it answers search queries based on
“relevance, engagement and quality”—taking into account how well a
search query matches a video title, the kinds of videos a
particular user viewed in the past, and each creator’s “expertise,
authoritativeness, and trustworthiness on a given topic.”[ 52 ]
These disclosures suggest that platforms can say
something about their content-moderation practices without enabling
malicious actors or disclosing proprietary information. They also
suggest that not all platforms curate all third-party content in an
inherently expressive way. Without more information about how
regulated platforms moderate content, it is not possible to
determine whether these laws lack “a ‘ “plainly legitimate
sweep.” ’ ” Washington State Grange , 552
U. S., at 449.
For all these reasons, NetChoice failed to
establish whether the content-moderation provisions violate the
First Amendment on their face.
D
Although the only question the Court must
decide today is whether NetChoice showed that the Florida and Texas
laws are facially unconstitutional, much of the majority opinion
addresses a different question: whether the Texas law’s
content-moderation provisions are constitutional as applied to two
features of two platforms—Facebook’s News Feed and YouTube’s
homepage. The opinion justifies this discussion on the ground that
the Fifth Circuit cannot apply the facial constitutionality test
without resolving that question, see, e.g., ante, at
13, 30, but that is not necessarily true. Especially in light of
the wide reach of the Texas law, NetChoice may still fall far short
of establishing facial unconstitutionality—even if it is assumed
for the sake of argument that the Texas law is unconstitutional as
applied to Facebook’s News Feed and YouTube’s homepage.[ 53 ]
For this reason, the majority’s “guidance” on
this issue may well be superfluous. Yet superfluity is not its most
egregious flaw. The majority’s discussion also rests on wholly
conclusory assumptions that lack record support. For example, the
majority paints an attractive, though simplistic, picture of what
Facebook’s News Feed and YouTube’s homepage do behind the scenes.
Taking NetChoice at its word, the majority says that the platforms’
use of algorithms to enforce their community standards is per se expressive. But the platforms have refused to
disclose how these algorithms were created and how they actually
work. And the majority fails to give any serious consideration to
key arguments pressed by the States. Most notable is the majority’s
conspicuous failure to address the States’ contention that
platforms like YouTube and Facebook—which constitute the 21st
century equivalent of the old “public square”—should be viewed as
common carriers. See Biden v. Knight First Amendment
Institute at Columbia University , 593 U. S. ___, ___
(2021) (Thomas, J., concurring) (slip op., at 6). Whether or not
the Court ultimately accepts that argument, it deserves serious
treatment.
Instead of seriously engaging with this and
other arguments, the majority rests on NetChoice’s dubious
assertion that there is no constitutionally significant difference
between what newspaper editors did more than a half-century ago at
the time of Tornillo and what Facebook and YouTube do
today.
Maybe that is right—but maybe it is not. Before
mechanically accepting this analogy, perhaps we should take a
closer look.
Let’s start with size. Currently, Facebook and
YouTube each produced—on a daily basis—more than four petabytes
(4,000,000,000,000,000 bytes) of data.[ 54 ] By my calculation, that is roughly 1.3 billion
times as many bytes as there are in an issue of the New York
Times.[ 55 ]
No human being could possibly review even a tiny
fraction of this gigantic outpouring of speech, and it is therefore
hard to see how any shared message could be discerned. And even if
someone could view all this data and find such a message, how
likely is it that the addition of a small amount of discordant
speech would change the overall message?
Now consider how newspapers and social-media
platforms edit content. Newspaper editors are real human beings,
and when the Court decided Tornillo (the case that the
majority finds most instructive), editors assigned articles to
particular reporters, and copyeditors went over typescript with a
blue pencil. The platforms, by contrast, play no role in selecting
the billions of texts and videos that users try to convey to each
other. And the vast bulk of the “curation” and “content moderation”
carried out by platforms is not done by human beings. Instead,
algorithms remove a small fraction of nonconforming posts post hoc and prioritize content based on factors that
the platforms have not revealed and may not even know. After all,
many of the biggest platforms are beginning to use AI algorithms to
help them moderate content. And when AI algorithms make a decision,
“even the researchers and programmers creating them don’t really
understand why the models they have built make the decisions they
make.”[ 56 ] Are such
decisions equally expressive as the decisions made by humans?
Should we at least think about this?
Other questions abound. Maybe we should think
about the enormous power exercised by platforms like Facebook and
YouTube as a result of “network effects.” Cf. Ohio v. American Express Co. , 585 U.S. 529 (2018). And maybe we
should think about the unique ways in which social-media platforms
influence public thought. To be sure, I do not suggest that we
should decide at this time whether the Florida and Texas laws are
constitutional as applied to Facebook’s News Feed or YouTube’s
homepage. My argument is just the opposite. Such questions should
be resolved in the context of an as-applied challenge. But no
as-applied question is before us, and we do not have all the facts
that we need to tackle the extraneous matters reached by the
majority.
Instead, when confronted with the application of
a constitutional requirement to new technology, we should proceed
with caution. While the meaning of the Constitution remains
constant, the application of enduring principles to new technology
requires an understanding of that technology and its effects.
Premature resolution of such questions creates the risk of
decisions that will quickly turn into embarrassments.
IV
Just as NetChoice failed to make the showing
necessary to demonstrate that the States’ content-moderation
provisions are facially unconstitutional, NetChoice’s facial
attacks on the individual-disclosure provisions also fell short.
Those provisions require platforms to explain to affected users the
basis of each content-censorship decision. Because these
regulations provide for the disclosure of “purely factual and
uncontroversial information,” they must be reviewed under Zauderer ’s framework, which requires only that such laws be
“reasonably related to the State’s interest in preventing deception
of consumers” and not “unduly burde[n]” speech. 471 U. S., at
651.[ 57 ]
For Zauderer purposes, a law is “unduly
burdensome” if it threatens to “chil[l] protected commercial
speech.” Ibid. Here, NetChoice claims that these disclosures
have that effect and lead platforms to “conclude that the safe
course is to . . . not exercis[e] editorial discretion at
all” rather than explain why they remove “millions of posts per
day.” Brief for Respondents in No. 22–277, at 39–40 (internal
quotation marks omitted).
Our unanimous agreement regarding NetChoice’s
failure to show that a sufficient number of its members engage in
constitutionally protected expression prevents us from accepting
NetChoice’s argument regarding these provisions. In the lower
courts, NetChoice did not even try to show how these disclosure
provisions chill each platform’s speech. Instead, NetChoice merely
identified one subset of one platform’s content that would be
affected by these laws: billions of nonconforming comments that
YouTube removes each year. 49 F. 4th, at 487; see also Brief
for Appellees in No. 21–12355 (CA11), p. 13. But if YouTube uses
automated processes to flag and remove these comments, it is not
clear why having to disclose the bases of those processes would
chill YouTube’s speech. And even if having to explain each removal
decision would unduly burden YouTube’s First Amendment rights, the
same does not necessarily follow with regard to all of NetChoice’s
members.
NetChoice’s failure to make this broader showing
is especially problematic since NetChoice does not dispute the
States’ assertion that many platforms already provide a
notice-and-appeal process for their removal decisions. In fact,
some have even advocated for such disclosure requirements.
Before its change in ownership, the previous Chief Executive
Officer of the platform now known as X went as far as to say that
“all companies” should be required to explain censorship decisions
and “provide a straightforward process to appeal decisions made by
humans or algorithms.”[ 58 ]
Moreover, as mentioned, many platforms are already providing
similar disclosures pursuant to the European Union’s Digital
Services Act. Yet complying with that law does not appear to have
unduly burdened each platform’s speech in those countries. On
remand, the courts might consider whether compliance with EU law
chilled the platforms’ speech.
* * *
The only binding holding in these decisions is
that NetChoice has yet to prove that the Florida and Texas laws
they challenged are facially unconstitutional. Because the majority
opinion ventures far beyond the question we must decide, I concur
only in the judgment. Notes 1 J. Gottfried, Pew
Research Center, Americans’ Social Media Use 3 (2024). As platforms
incorporate new features and technology, the number of Americans
who use social media is expected to grow. S. Dixon, Statista,
Social Media Users in the United States 2020–2029 (Jan. 30, 2024),
https://www.statista.com/statistics/278409/number-of-social-network-users-in-the-united-states. 2 V. Filak, Exploring Mass
Communication: Connecting With the World of Media 210
(2024). 3 Social Media and News
Platform Fact Sheet, Pew Research Center (Nov. 15, 2023),
https://www.pewresearch.org/journalism/fact-sheet/social-media-and-news-fact-sheet. 4 M. Anderson, M. Faverio,
& J. Gottfried, Pew Research Center, Teens, Social Media and
Technology 2023 (Dec. 11, 2023),
https://www.pewresearch.org/internet/2023/12/11/teens-social-media-and-technology-2023. 5 Ibid. ; see also J.
Twenge, J. Haidt, J. Lozano, & K. Cummins, Specification Curve
Analysis Shows That Social Media Use Is Linked to Poor Mental
Health, Especially Among Girls, 224 Acta Psychologica 1, 8–12
(2022). 6 As relevant here, an
“algorithm” is a program that platforms use to automatically
“censor” or “moderate” content that violates their terms or
conditions, to organize the results of a search query, or to
display posts in a feed. 7 A “journalistic
enterprise” is defined as any entity doing business in Florida
that: (1) has published more than 100,000 words online and has at
least 50,000 paid subscribers or 100,000 monthly users; (2) has
published at least 100 hours of audio or video online and has at
least 100 million annual viewers; (3) operates a cable channel that
produces more than 40 hours of content per week to at least 100,000
subscribers; or (4) operates under a Federal Communications
Commission broadcast license. Fla. Stat.
§501.2041(1)(d). 8 NetChoice also argued
that S. B. 7072 is preempted by 47 U. S. C. §230(c)
and is unconstitutionally vague. Those arguments are not before us
because the District Court did not rule on the vagueness issue, 546
F. Supp. 3d 1082, 1095 (ND Fla. 2021), and the Eleventh
Circuit declined to reach the preemption issue, NetChoice v. Attorney Gen., Fla. , 34 F. 4th 1196, 1209
(2022). 9 See also id. , at
1214 (“unless posts and users are removed randomly , those
sorts of actions necessarily convey some sort of
message—most obviously, the platforms’ disagreement with
. . . certain content”); id. , at 1223 (“S.B.
7072’s disclosure provisions implicate the First
Amendment”). 10 In
general, to “deplatform” means “to remove and ban a registered user
from a mass communication medium (such as a social networking or
blogging website).” Merriam-Webster’s Collegiate Dictionary (10th
ed. 2024), (defining “deplatform”; some punctuation omitted),
https://unabridged.merriam-webster.com/collegiate/deplatform
(unless otherwise noted, all internet sites last accessed May 22,
2024). 11 “[D]emonetization” often refers to
the act of preventing “online content from earning revenue (as from
advertisements).” Ibid. (defining“demonetize”; some
punctuation omitted),
https://unabridged.merriam-webster.com/collegiate/demonetize. 12 “Boosting on social media means
[paying] a platform to amplify . . . posts for more
reach.” C. Williams, HubSpot, Social Media Definitions: The
Ultimate Glossary of Terms You Should Know (June 23, 2023),
https://blog.hubspot.com/marketing/social-media-terms. De-boosting
thus usually refers to when platforms refuse to continue increasing
a post’s or user’s visibility to other users. 13 Texas
has represented that a brief computer-generated notification to an
affected user would satisfy the provision’s notification
requirement. Brief for Respondent in No. 22–555, p.
44. 14 At
oral argument, NetChoice represented that “it’s the plainly
legitimate sweep test, which is not synonymous with overbreadth,”
that governs these cases. See Tr. of Oral Arg. in No. 22–277, p.
70; contra, ante, at 9 (suggesting that the overbreadth
doctrine applies to all facial challenges brought under the First
Amendment, including these cases). This representation makes sense
given that the overbreadth doctrine applies only when there is “a
realistic danger that the statute itself will significantly
compromise recognized First Amendment protections of parties not
before the Court.” Members of City Council of Los Angeles v. Taxpayers for Vincent , 466 U.S.
789 , 801 (1984). And here, NetChoice appears to represent
all—or nearly all—regulated parties. 15 See
Reply Brief in No. 21–12355 (CA11), p. 15 (“Plaintiffs—in
their facial challenge—have failed to demonstrate that even a
significant subset of covered social media platforms engages in
[expressive] conduct.” See also Brief for Appellants in No.
21–12355 (CA11), p. 20 (NetChoice is “unlikely to prevail on the
merits of [its] facial First Amendment challenge”); Record in No.
4:21–CV–00220 (ND Fla.), Doc. 106, p. 30 (“Plaintiffs have not
demonstrated that their members actually [express a message],” so
there is “not a basis for sustaining Plaintiffs’ facial
constitutional challenge”); Reply Brief in No. 21–51178 (CA5), p. 8
(arguing that NetChoice failed “to show at a bare minimum that [S.
B. 20] is unconstitutional in a ‘substantial number of its
applications’ ” (quoting Americans for Prosperity
Foundation v. Bonta , 594 U.S. 595, 615 (2021))); Record
in No. 1:21–CV–00840 (WD Tex.), Doc. 39, p. 27 (because “not
all applications of H.B. 20 are unconstitutional,” “Plaintiffs’
delayed facial challenge [can]not succeed”). 16 American Broadcasting Cos. v. Aereo, Inc. , 573 U.S.
431 , 458 (2014) (Scalia, J., dissenting). 17 The
majority states that it is irrelevant whether “a compiler includes
most items and excludes just a few.” Ante , at 18. That may
be true if the compiler carefully reviews, edits, and selects a
large proportion of the items it receives. But if an entity, like
some “sort of community billboard, regularly carr[ies] the messages
of third parties” instead of selecting only those that contribute
to a common theme, then this information becomes highly relevant. PG&E , 475 U.S.
1 , 23 (1986) (Marshall, J., concurring in judgment). Entities
that have assumed the role of common carriers fall into this
category, for example. And the States defend portions of their laws
on the ground that at least some social-media platforms have taken
on that role. The majority brushes aside that argument without
adequate consideration. 18 To be
sure, in Turner Broadcasting System, Inc. v. FCC , 512 U.S.
622 , 655 (1994), we held that the First Amendment applied even
though there was “little risk” of misattribution in that case. But
that is only because the claimants in that case had already shown
that the Cable Act affected the quantity or reach of the messages
that they communicated through “original programming” or television
programs produced by others. Id. , at 636 (internal quotation
marks omitted). In cases not involving core examples of expressive
compilations, such as in PruneYard and FAIR , a
compiler’s First Amendment protection has very much turned on the
risk of misattribution. 19 Contrary to the majority’s
suggestion, ante , at 27, this is not the only interest that
Texas asserted. Texas has also invoked its interest in preventing
platforms from discriminating against speakers who reside in Texas
or engage in certain forms of off-platform speech. Brief for
Respondent in No. 22–555, at 15. The majority opinion does not
mention these features, much less the interests that Texas claims
they serve. Texas also asserts an interest in preventing common
carriers from engaging in “ ‘invidious discrimination in the
distribution of publicly available goods, services, and other
advantages.’ ” Id. , at 18. These are “compelling state
interests of the highest order” too. Roberts v. United
States Jaycees , 468 U.S.
609 , 624 (1984). 20 This
concession suggests that S. B. 7072 may “cover websites that
engage in primarily non-expressive conduct.” Tr. of Oral Arg. in
No. 22–277, at 34. 21 Brief
for Discord Inc. as Amicus Curiae 2, 21–27. “Discord is a
real time messaging service with over 150 million active monthly
users who communicate within a huge variety of interest-based
communities, or ‘servers.’ ” Id., at 1. 22 Brief
for Reddit, Inc., as Amicus Curiae 2. Reddit is an online
forum that allows its “users to establish and enforce their own
rules governing what topics are acceptable and how those topics may
be discussed . . . . The display of content on Reddit is
thus primarily driven by humans—not by centralized algorithms.” Ibid. 23 Brief
for Wikimedia Foundation as Amicus Curiae 2. 24 Brief
for Yelp Inc. as Amicus Curiae 3–4. 25 About
WhatsApp, WhatsApp, https://whatsapp.com/about (last accessed Apr.
23, 2024). 26 Secure, Smart, and Easy To Use Email,
Gmail, https://google.com/gmail/about (last accessed Apr. 23,
2024). 27 Reddit Content Policy, Reddit,
https://www.redditinc.com/policies/content-policy (last accessed
Apr. 23, 2024) (describing Reddit as a platform that is run and
moderated by its users). 28 BeReal, which appears to have enough
monthly users to be covered by the Texas law, allows users to share
a photo with their friends once during a randomly selected 2-minute
window each day. Time To BeReal,
https://help.bereal.com/hc/en-us/articles/7350386715165--Time-to-BeReal
(last accessed Apr. 23, 2024). Twenty-four hours later, those
photos disappear. Because BeReal posts thus appear and disappear
“ randomly ,” even the Eleventh Circuit would agree that
BeReal likely is not an expressive compilation. 34 F. 4th, at
1214. 29 Community Guidelines, Parler,
https://www.parler.com/community-guidelines (May 31, 2024) (“We
honor the ability of all users to freely express themselves without
interference from oppressive censorship or manipulation”). Parler
probably does not have a sufficient number of monthly users to be
covered by these statutes. But it is possible that other covered
websites use a similar business model. 30 Our
House Rules, Etsy, https://etsy.com/legal/prohibited (last accessed
Apr. 23, 2024). 31 Yelp
and X are both covered by S. B. 7072 and H. B. 20. See Brief for
Yelp Inc. as Amicus Curiae 4, n. 4. 32 The X
Rules, X, https://help.x.com/en/rules-and-policies/x-rules (last
accessed Apr. 23, 2024). 33 Content Guidelines, Yelp,
https://www.yelp.com/guidelines (last accessed Apr. 23,
2024). 34 Ibid. 35 E.g., Facebook Marketplace,
Etsy. 36 E.g., X Live,
Twitch. 37 E.g., Uber, Lyft. 38 E.g., Facebook Dating,
Tinder. 39 E.g., Reddit,
Quora. 40 E.g., Meta Pay, Venmo,
PayPal. 41 E.g., Metaverse,
Discord. 42 E.g., Indeed,
LinkedIn. 43 E.g., Strava. 44 E.g., Rover. 45 Community Standards, Facebook,
https://transparency.meta.com/policies/community-standards
(“[Facebook] wants people to be able to talk openly about the
issues that matter to them, whether through written comments,
photos, music, or other artistic mediums”); Brief for Reddit, Inc.,
as Amicus Curiae 12 (“[T]he Reddit platform as a whole
accommodates a wide range of communities and modes of
discourse”). 46 Comm’n Reg. 2022/2065, Art. 17, 2022
O. J. (L. 277) 51–52. NetChoice does not dispute the States’
assertion that the regulated platforms are required to comply with
this law. Compare Brief for Petitioners in No. 22–277, p. 49, with
Reply Brief in No. 22–277, p. 24; Tr. of Oral Arg. in No.
22–555, pp. 20–21. If, on remand, the States show that the
platforms have been able to comply with this law in Europe without
having to forgo “exercising editorial discretion at all,” Brief for
Respondents in No. 22–277, p. 40, then that might help them prove
that their disclosure laws are not “unduly burdensome” under Zauderer v. Office of Disciplinary Counsel of Supreme
Court of Ohio , 471 U.S.
626 (1985). 47 Our
Approach to Policy Development and Enforcement Philosophy, X,
http://www.help.x.com/en/rules-and-policies/enforcement-philosophy. 48 Community Guidelines, Parler,
https://www.parler.com/community-guidelines. 49 Reddit Content Policy, Reddit,
https://www.redditinc.com/policies/content-policy. 50 Signal Terms & Privacy Policy,
Signal Messenger (May 25, 2018),
https://www.signal.org/legal. 51 How
Etsy Search Works, Etsy Help Center,
https://help.etsy.com/hc/en-us/articles/115015745428–How-Etsy-Search-Works?segment=selling
(visited Apr. 9, 2024). 52 YouTube Search,
https://www.youtube.com/howyoutubeworks/product-features/search
(last accessed Apr. 23, 2024). Unlike many other platforms, YouTube
does not accept payment for better placement within organic
search 53 This
problem is even more pronounced for the Florida law, which covers
more platforms and conduct than the Texas law. 54 Breaking Down the Numbers: How Much
Data Does the World Create Daily in 2024? Edge Delta (Mar. 11,
2024), https://www.
edgedelta.com/company/blog/how-much-data-is-created-per-day. 55 The
average issue of the New York Times, excluding ads, contains about
150,000 words. A typical word consists of 10 to 20 bytes.
Therefore, the average issue of the New York Times contains around
3 million bytes. 56 T.
Xu, AI Makes Decisions We Don’t Understand—That’s a Pro-blem, (Jul.
19, 2021),
https://builtin.com/artificial-intelligence/ai-right-explanation. 57 Both
lower courts reviewed these provisions under the Zauderer test. And in the Florida case in particular, NetChoice did not
contest—and accordingly forfeited—whether Zauderer applies
here. See Brief for Appellants in No. 21–12355 (CA11), at 21; Brief
for Appellees in No. 21–12355 (CA11), p. 44. 58 Does
Section 230’s Sweeping Immunity Enable Big Tech Bad Behavior?
Hearing before the Senate Committee on Commerce, Science, and
Transportation, 116th Cong., 2d Sess., 2 (2020) (statement of Jack
Dorsey, CEO, Twitter, Inc.). SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES
_________________
Nos. 22–277 and 22–555
_________________
ASHLEY MOODY, ATTORNEY GENERAL OF
FLORIDA, et al., PETITIONERS
22–277 v. NETCHOICE, LLC, dba NETCHOICE, et
al.
on writ of certiorari to the united states
court of appeals for the eleventh circuit
NETCHOICE, LLC, dba NETCHOICE, et al.,
PETITIONERS
22–555 v. KEN PAXTON, ATTORNEY GENERAL OF
TEXAS
on writ of certiorari to the united states
court of appeals for the fifth circuit
[July 1, 2024]
Justice Barrett, concurring.
I join the Court’s opinion, which correctly
articulates and applies our First Amendment precedent. In this
respect, the Eleventh Circuit’s understanding of the First
Amendment’s protection of editorial discretion was generally
correct; the Fifth Circuit’s was not.
But for the reasons the Court gives, these cases
illustrate the dangers of bringing a facial challenge. If
NetChoice’s members are concerned about preserving their editorial
discretion with respect to the services on which they have focused
throughout this litigation— e . g ., Facebook’s Newsfeed
and YouTube’s homepage—they would be better served by bringing a
First Amendment challenge as applied to those functions. Analyzing
how the First Amendment bears on those functions is complicated
enough without simultaneously analyzing how it bears on a
platform’s other functions— e.g. , Facebook Messenger and
Google Search—much less to distinct platforms like Uber and Etsy.
In fact, dealing with a broad swath of varied platforms and
functions in a facial challenge strikes me as a daunting, if not
impossible, task. A function qualifies for First Amendment
protection only if it is inherently expressive. Hurley v. Irish-American Gay, Lesbian and Bisexual Group of Boston,
Inc. , 515 U.S.
557 , 568 (1995). Even for a prototypical social-media feed,
making this determination involves more than meets the eye.
Consider, for instance, how platforms use
algorithms to prioritize and remove content on their feeds. Assume
that human beings decide to remove posts promoting a particular
political candidate or advocating some position on a public-health
issue. If they create an algorithm to help them identify and delete
that content, the First Amendment protects their exercise of
editorial judgment—even if the algorithm does most of the deleting
without a person in the loop. In that event, the algorithm would
simply implement human beings’ inherently expressive choice “to
exclude a message [they] did not like from” their speech
compilation. Id. , at 574.
But what if a platform’s algorithm just presents
automatically to each user whatever the algorithm thinks the user
will like— e . g ., content similar to posts with which
the user previously engaged? See ante , at 22, n. 5. The
First Amendment implications of the Florida and Texas laws might be
different for that kind of algorithm. And what about AI, which is
rapidly evolving? What if a platform’s owners hand the reins to an
AI tool and ask it simply to remove “hateful” content? If the AI
relies on large language models to determine what is “hateful” and
should be removed, has a human being with First Amendment rights
made an inherently expressive “choice . . . not to
propound a particular point of view”? Hurley , 515
U. S., at 575. In other words, technology may attenuate the
connection between content-moderation actions ( e . g ., removing posts) and human beings’
constitutionally protected right to “ decide for
[themselves] the ideas and beliefs deserving of expression,
consideration, and adherence.” Turner Broadcasting System,
Inc. v. FCC , 512 U.S.
622 , 641 (1994) (emphasis added). So the way platforms use this
sort of technology might have constitutional significance.
There can be other complexities too. For
example, the corporate structure and ownership of some platforms
may be relevant to the constitutional analysis. A speaker’s right
to “decide ‘what not to say’ ” is “enjoyed by business
corporations generally.” Hurley , 515 U. S., at 573–574
(quoting Pacific Gas & Elec. Co. v. Public Util.
Comm’n of Cal. , 475 U.S.
1 , 16 (1986)). Corporations, which are composed of human beings
with First Amendment rights, possess First Amendment rights
themselves. See Citizens United v. Federal Election
Comm’n , 558 U.S.
310 , 365 (2010); cf. Burwell v. Hobby Lobby Stores,
Inc. , 573 U.S.
682 , 706–707 (2014). But foreign persons and corporations
located abroad do not. Agency for Int’l Development v. Alliance for Open Society Int’l, Inc. , 591 U.S. 430, 433–436
(2020). So a social-media platform’s foreign ownership and control
over its content-moderation decisions might affect whether laws
overriding those decisions trigger First Amendment scrutiny. What
if the platform’s corporate leadership abroad makes the policy
decisions about the viewpoints and content the platform will
disseminate? Would it matter that the corporation employs Americans
to develop and implement content- moderation algorithms if they do
so at the direction of foreign executives? Courts may need to
confront such questions when applying the First Amendment to
certain platforms.
These are just a few examples of questions that
might arise in litigation that more thoroughly exposes the relevant
facts about particular social-media platforms and functions. The
answers in any given case might cast doubt on—or might vindicate—a
social-media company’s invocation of its First Amendment rights.
Regardless, the analysis is bound to be fact intensive, and it will
surely vary from function to function and platform to platform. And
in a facial challenge, answering all of those questions isn’t even
the end of the story: The court must then find a way to measure the
unconstitutional relative to the constitutional applications to
determine whether the law “prohibits a substantial amount of
protected speech relative to its plainly legitimate sweep.” United States v. Hansen , 599 U.S. 762, 770 (2023)
(internal quotation marks omitted).
A facial challenge to either of these laws
likely forces a court to bite off more than it can chew. An
as-applied challenge, by contrast, would enable courts to home in
on whether and how specific functions—like feeds versus direct
messaging—are inherently expressive and answer platform- and
function-specific questions that might bear on the First Amendment
analysis. While the governing constitutional principles are
straightforward, applying them in one fell swoop to the entire
social-media universe is not. | The Supreme Court's decision addresses the complex and evolving nature of social media platforms and their impact on public policy and communication. The Court acknowledges the need for legislative and agency responses to the challenges posed by these platforms while also emphasizing the role of courts in protecting the free speech rights of these entities. The Court suggests that social media platforms engage in expressive activities and possess First Amendment rights, but the extent of these rights depends on various factors, including the platform's functions, corporate structure, and ownership. The Court highlights the complexity of applying the First Amendment to social media platforms, especially in a facial challenge, and suggests that an as-applied challenge would be more appropriate to address specific functions and platform-related questions. The Court concludes that while the governing constitutional principles are clear, their application to the diverse and dynamic social media landscape is challenging and requires a fact-intensive analysis. |
Equal Protection | Missouri ex rel. Gaines v. Canada | https://supreme.justia.com/cases/federal/us/305/337/ | U.S. Supreme Court Missouri ex rel. Gaines v. Canada, 305
U.S. 337 (1938) Missouri ex rel. Gaines v.
Canada No. 57 Argued November 9,
1938 Decided December 12,
1938 305
U.S. 337 CERTIORARI TO THE SUPREME COURT OF
MISSOURI Syllabus 1. The State of Missouri provides separate schools and
universities for whites and negroes. At the state university,
attended by whites, there is a course in law; at the Lincoln
University, attended by negroes, there is as yet none, but it is
the duty of the curators of that institution to establish one there
whenever in their opinion this shall be necessary and practicable,
and pending such development, they are authorized to arrange for
legal education of Missouri negroes, and to pay the tuition charges
therefor, at law schools in adjacent States where negroes are
accepted and where the training is equal to that obtainable at the
Missouri State University. Pursuant to the State's policy of
separating the races in its educational institutions, the curators
of the state university refused to admit a negro as a student in
the law school there because of his race; whereupon he sought a
mandamus, in the state courts, which was denied. Held: (1) That inasmuch as the curators of the state university
represented the State, in carrying out its policy, their action in
denying the negro admission to the law school was state action
within the meaning of the Fourteenth Amendment. P. 305 U. S.
343 .
(2) The action of the State in furnishing legal education within
the State to whites while not furnishing legal education within the
State to negroes was a discrimination repugnant to the Fourteenth
Amendment. P. 305 U. S.
344 .
If a State furnishes higher education to white residents, it is
bound to furnish substantially equal advantages to negro residents,
though not necessarily in the same schools.
(3) The unconstitutional discrimination is not avoided by the
purpose of the State to establish a law school for negroes whenever
necessary and practicable in the opinion of the curators of the
University provided for negroes. P. 305 U. S.
346 .
(4) Nor are the requirements of the equal protection clause
satisfied by the opportunities afforded by Missouri to its negro
citizens for legal education in other States. P. 305 U. S.
348 .
The basic consideration here is not as to what sort of
opportunities other States provide, or whether they are as good as
those Page 305 U. S. 338 in Missouri, but as to what opportunities Missouri itself
furnishes to white students and denies to negroes solely upon the
ground of color. The admissibility of laws separating the races in
the enjoyment of privileges afforded by the State rests wholly upon
the equality of the privileges which the laws give to the separated
groups within the State. By the operation of the laws of Missouri,
a privilege has been created for white law students which is denied
to negroes by reason of their race. The white resident is afforded
legal education within the State; the negro resident having the
same qualifications is refused it there, and must go outside the
State to obtain it. That is a denial of the equality of legal right
to the enjoyment of the privilege which the State has set up, and
the provision for the payment of tuition fees in another State does
not remove the discrimination. P. 305 U. S.
348 .
(5) The obligation of the State to give the protection of equal
laws can be performed only where its laws operate, that is, within
its own jurisdiction. It is there that the equality of legal right
must be maintained. That obligation is imposed by the Constitution
upon the States severally as governmental entities each responsible
for its own laws establishing the rights and duties of persons
within its borders. P. 305 U. S.
350 .
(6) The fact that there is but a limited demand in Missouri for
the legal education of negroes does not excuse the discrimination
in favor of whites. P. 305 U. S.
350 .
(7) Inasmuch as the discrimination may last indefinitely -- so
long as the curators find it unnecessary and impracticable to
provide facilities for the legal education of negroes within the
State, the alternative of attendance at law schools in other States
being provided meanwhile -- it cannot be excused as a temporary
discrimination. P. 305 U. S.
351 .
2. The state court decided this case upon the merits of the
federal question, and not upon the propriety of remedy by mandamus.
P. 305 U. S.
352 .
342 Mo. 121; 113 S.W.2d 783, reversed.
CERTIORARI, post, p. 580, to review a judgment
affirming denial of a writ of mandamus. Page 305 U. S. 342 MR. CHIEF JUSTICE HUGHES delivered the opinion of the Court.
Petitioner Lloyd Gaines, a negro, was refused admission to the
School of Law at the State University of Missouri. Asserting that
this refusal constituted a denial by the State of the equal
protection of the laws in violation of the Fourteenth Amendment of
the Federal Constitution, petitioner brought this action for
mandamus to compel the curators of the University to admit him. On
final hearing, an alternative writ was quashed and a peremptory
writ was denied by the Circuit Court. The Supreme Court of the
State affirmed the judgment. 113 S.W.2d 783. We granted certiorari,
October 10, 1938.
Petitioner is a citizen of Missouri. In August, 1935, he was
graduated with the degree of Bachelor of Arts at the Lincoln
University, an institution maintained by the State of Missouri for
the higher education of negroes. That University has no law school.
Upon the filing of his application for admission to the law school
of the University of Missouri, the registrar advised him to
communicate with the president of Lincoln University, and the
latter directed petitioner's attention to § 9622 of the Revised
Statutes of Missouri (1929), providing as follows:
"Sec. 9622. May arrange for attendance at university of any
adjacent state -- Tuition fees. -- Pending the full
development of the Lincoln university, the board of Page 305 U. S. 343 curators shall have the authority to arrange for the attendance
of negro residents of the state of Missouri at the university of
any adjacent state to take any course or to study any subjects
provided for at the state university of Missouri, and which are not
taught at the Lincoln university and to pay the reasonable tuition
fees for such attendance; provided that, whenever the
board of curators deem it advisable, they shall have the power to
open any necessary school or department. (Laws 1921, p. 86, §
7.)"
Petitioner was advised to apply to the State Superintendent of
Schools for aid under that statute. It was admitted on the trial
that petitioner's
"work and credits at the Lincoln University would qualify him
for admission to the School of Law of the University of Missouri if
he were found otherwise eligible."
He was refused admission upon the ground that it was "contrary
to the constitution, laws and public policy of the State to admit a
negro as a student in the University of Missouri." It appears that
there are schools of law in connection with the state universities
of four adjacent States, Kansas, Nebraska, Iowa and Illinois, where
nonresident negroes are admitted.
The clear and definite conclusions of the state court in
construing the pertinent state legislation narrow the issue. The
action of the curators, who are representatives of the State in the
management of the state university (R.S.Mo. § 9625), must be
regarded as state action. [ Footnote
1 ] The state constitution provides that separate free public
schools shall be established for the education of children of
African descent (Art. XI, § 3), and, by statute, separate high
school facilities are supplied for colored students equal to those
provided for white students (R.S.Mo. Page 305 U. S. 344 §§ 9346-9349). While there is no express constitutional
provision requiring that the white and negro races be separated for
the purpose of higher education, the state court, on a
comprehensive review of the state statutes, held that it was
intended to separate the white and negro races for that purpose
also. Referring in particular to Lincoln University, the court
deemed it to be clear
"that the Legislature intended to bring the Lincoln University
up to the standard of the University of Missouri, and give to the
whites and negroes an equal opportunity for higher education -- the
whites at the University of Missouri, and the negroes at Lincoln
University."
Further, the court concluded that the provisions of § 9622
(above-quoted) to the effect that negro residents "may attend the
university of any adjacent State with their tuition paid, pending
the full development of Lincoln University," made it evident "that
the Legislature did not intend that negroes and whites should
attend the same university in this State." In that view, it
necessarily followed that the curators of the University of
Missouri acted in accordance with the policy of the State in
denying petitioner admission to its School of Law upon the sole
ground of his race.
In answering petitioner's contention that this discrimination
constituted a denial of his constitutional right, the state court
has fully recognized the obligation of the State to provide negroes
with advantages for higher education substantially equal to the
advantages afforded to white students. The State has sought to
fulfill that obligation by furnishing equal facilities in separate
schools, a method the validity of which has been sustained by our
decisions. Plessy v. Ferguson, 163 U.
S. 537 , 163 U. S. 544 ; McCabe v. Atchison, T. & S.F. Ry. Co., 235 U.
S. 151 , 235 U. S. 160 ; Gong Lum v. Rice, 275 U. S. 78 , 275 U. S. 85 , 275 U. S. 86 . Compare Cumming v. Board of Education, 175 U.
S. 528 , 175 U. S. 544 , 175 U. S. 545 .
Respondents' counsel have appropriately emphasized the special Page 305 U. S. 345 solicitude of the State for the higher education of negroes as
shown in the establishment of Lincoln University, a state
institution well conducted on a plane with the University of
Missouri so far as the offered courses are concerned. It is said
that Missouri is a pioneer in that field and is the only State in
the Union which has established a separate university for negroes
on the same basis as the state university for white students. But,
commendable as is that action, the fact remains that instruction in
law for negroes is not now afforded by the State, either at Lincoln
University or elsewhere within the State, and that the State
excludes negroes from the advantages of the law school it has
established at the University of Missouri.
It is manifest that this discrimination, if not relieved by the
provisions we shall presently discuss, would constitute a denial of
equal protection. That was the conclusion of the Court of Appeals
of Maryland in circumstances substantially similar in that aspect. University of Maryland v. Murray, 169 Md. 478, 182 A. 590.
It there appeared that the State of Maryland had "undertaken the
function of education in the law," but had "omitted students of one
race from the only adequate provision made for it, and omitted them
solely because of their color"; that, if those students were to be
offered "equal treatment in the performance of the function, they
must, at present, be admitted to the one school provided." Id., p. 489. A provision for scholarships to enable
negroes to attend colleges outside the State, mainly for the
purpose of professional studies, was found to be inadequate
( Id. pp. 485, 486), and the question "whether with aid in
any amount it is sufficient to send the negroes outside the State
for legal education" the Court of Appeals found it unnecessary to
discuss. Accordingly, a writ of mandamus to admit the applicant was
issued to the officers and Page 305 U. S. 346 regents of the University of Maryland as the agents of the State
entrusted with the conduct of that institution.
The Supreme Court of Missouri in the instant case has
distinguished the decision in Maryland upon the grounds -- (1)
that, in Missouri, but not in Maryland, there is "a legislative
declaration of a purpose to establish a law school for negroes at
Lincoln University whenever necessary or practical", and (2)
that,
"pending the establishment of such a school, adequate provision
has been made for the legal education of negro students in
recognized schools outside of this State."
113 S.W.2d p. 791.
As to the first ground, it appears that the policy of
establishing a law school at Lincoln University has not yet ripened
into an actual establishment, and it cannot be said that a mere
declaration of purpose, still unfulfilled, is enough. The provision
for legal education at Lincoln is at present entirely lacking.
Respondents' counsel urge that, if, on the date when petitioner
applied for admission to the University of Missouri, he had instead
applied to the curators of Lincoln University, it would have been
their duty to establish a law school; that this "agency of the
State," to which he should have applied, was "specifically charged
with the mandatory duty to furnish him what he seeks." We do not
read the opinion of the Supreme Court as construing the state
statute to impose such a "mandatory duty" as the argument seems to
assert. The state court quoted the language of § 9618, R.S.Mo.1929,
set forth in the margin, [ Footnote
2 ] making it the mandatory Page 305 U. S. 347 duty of the board of curators to establish a law school in
Lincoln University "whenever necessary and practicable in their
opinion." This qualification of their duty, explicitly stated in
the statute, manifestly leaves it to the judgment of the curators
to decide when it will be necessary and practicable to establish a
law school, and the state court so construed the statute.
Emphasizing the discretion of the curators, the court said:
"The statute was enacted in 1921. Since its enactment, no negro,
not even appellant, has applied to Lincoln University for a law
education. This fact demonstrates the wisdom of the legislature in
leaving it to the judgment of the board of curators to determine
when it would be necessary or practicable to establish a law school
for negroes at Lincoln University. Pending that time, adequate
provision is made for the legal education of negroes in the
university of some adjacent State, as heretofore pointed out."
113 S.W.2d p. 791.
The state court has not held that it would have been the duty of
the curators to establish a law school at Lincoln University for
the petitioner on his application. Their duty, as the court defined
it, would have been either to supply a law school at Lincoln
University as provided in § 9618 or to furnish him the opportunity
to obtain his legal training in another State, as provided in §
9622
Thus, the law left the curators free to adopt the latter course.
The state court has not ruled or intimated that their failure or
refusal to establish a law school for a very few students, still
less for one student, would have been an abuse of the discretion
with which the curators were entrusted. And, apparently, it was
because of that discretion, Page 305 U. S. 348 and of the postponement which its exercise in accordance with
the terms of the statute would entail until necessity and
practicability appeared, that the state court considered and upheld
as adequate the provision for the legal education of negroes, who
were citizens of Missouri, in the universities of adjacent States.
We may put on one side respondent's contention that there were
funds available at Lincoln University for the creation of a law
department and the suggestions with respect to the number of
instructors who would be needed for that purpose and the cost of
supplying them. The president of Lincoln University did not advert
to the existence or prospective use of funds for that purpose when
he advised petitioner to apply to the State Superintendent of
Schools for aid under § 9622. At best, the evidence to which
argument as to available funds is addressed admits of conflicting
inferences, and the decision of the state court did not hinge on
any such matter. In the light of its ruling, we must regard the
question whether the provision for the legal education in other
States of negroes resident in Missouri is sufficient to satisfy the
constitutional requirement of equal protection as the pivot upon
which this case turns.
The state court stresses the advantages that are afforded by the
law schools of the adjacent States -- Kansas, Nebraska, Iowa and
Illinois -- which admit nonresident negroes. The court considered
that these were schools of high standing where one desiring to
practice law in Missouri can get "as sound, comprehensive, valuable
legal education" as in the University of Missouri; that the system
of education in the former is the same as that in the latter, and
is designed to give the students a basis for the practice of law in
any State where the Anglo-American system of law obtains; that the
law school of the University of Missouri does not specialize in
Missouri law, and that the course of study and the case books
used Page 305 U. S. 349 in the five schools are substantially identical. Petitioner
insists that, for one intending to practice in Missouri, there are
special advantages in attending a law school there, both in
relation to the opportunities for the particular study of Missouri
law and for the observation of the local courts [ Footnote 3 ] and also in view of the prestige
of the Missouri law school among the citizens of the State, his
prospective clients. Proceeding with its examination of relative
advantages, the state court found that the difference in distances
to be traveled afforded no substantial ground of complaint, and
that there was an adequate appropriation to meet the full tuition
fees which petitioner would have to pay.
We think that these matters are beside the point. The basic
consideration is not as to what sort of opportunities other States
provide, or whether they are as good as those in Missouri, but as
to what opportunities Missouri itself furnishes to white students
and denies to negroes solely upon the ground of color. The
admissibility of laws separating the races in the enjoyment of
privileges afforded by the State rests wholly upon the equality of
the privileges which the laws give to the separated groups within
the State. The question here is not of a duty of the State to
supply legal training, or of the quality of the training which it
does supply, but of its duty when it provides such training to
furnish it to the residents of the State upon the basis of an
equality of right. By the operation of the laws of Missouri, a
privilege has been created for white law students which is denied
to negroes by reason of their race. The white resident is afforded
legal education within the State; the negro resident having the
same qualifications is refused it there, and must go outside the
State to obtain it. That is a denial of the equality of legal right
to the enjoyment of the privilege Page 305 U. S. 350 which the State has set up, and the provision for the payment of
tuition fees in another State does not remove the
discrimination.
The equal protection of the laws is "a pledge of the protection
of equal laws." Yick Wo v. Hopkins, 118 U.
S. 356 , 118 U. S. 369 .
Manifestly, the obligation of the State to give the protection of
equal laws can be performed only where its laws operate, that is,
within its own jurisdiction. It is there that the equality of legal
right must be maintained. That obligation is imposed by the
Constitution upon the States severally as governmental entities --
each responsible for its own laws establishing the rights and
duties of persons within its borders. It is an obligation the
burden of which cannot be cast by one State upon another, and no
State can be excused from performance by what another State may do
or fail to do. That separate responsibility of each State within
its own sphere is of the essence of statehood maintained under our
dual system. It seems to be implicit in respondents' argument that,
if other States did not provide courses for legal education, it
would nevertheless be the constitutional duty of Missouri, when it
supplied such courses for white students, to make equivalent
provision for negroes. But that plain duty would exist because it
rested upon the State independently of the action of other States.
We find it impossible to conclude that what otherwise would be an
unconstitutional discrimination, with respect to the legal right to
the enjoyment of opportunities within the State, can be justified
by requiring resort to opportunities elsewhere. That resort may
mitigate the inconvenience of the discrimination, but cannot serve
to validate it.
Nor can we regard the fact that there is but a limited demand in
Missouri for the legal education of negroes as excusing the
discrimination in favor of whites. We had occasion to consider a
cognate question in the case Page 305 U. S. 351 of McCabe v. Atchison, T. & S.F. Ry. Co., supra. There, the argument was advanced, in relation to the provision by a
carrier of sleeping cars, dining, and chair cars, that the limited
demand by negroes justified the State in permitting the furnishing
of such accommodations exclusively for white persons. We found that
argument to be without merit. It made, we said, the constitutional
right
"depend upon the number of persons who may be discriminated
against, whereas the essence of the constitutional right is that it
is a personal one. Whether or not particular facilities shall be
provided may doubtless be conditioned upon there being a reasonable
demand therefor, but, if facilities are provided, substantial
equality of treatment of persons traveling under like conditions
cannot be refused. It is the individual who is entitled to the
equal protection of the laws, and if he is denied by a common
carrier, acting in the matter under the authority of a state law, a
facility or convenience in the course of his journey which under
substantially the same circumstances is furnished to another
traveler, he may properly complain that his constitutional
privilege has been invaded." Id. pp. 235 U. S. 161 , 235 U. S.
162 .
Here, petitioner's right was a personal one. It was as an
individual that he was entitled to the equal protection of the
laws, and the State was bound to furnish him within its borders
facilities for legal education substantially equal to those which
the State there afforded for persons of the white race, whether or
not other negroes sought the same opportunity.
It is urged, however, that the provision for tuition outside the
State is a temporary one -- that it is intended to operate merely
pending the establishment of a law department for negroes at
Lincoln University. While, in that sense, the discrimination may be
termed temporary, it may nevertheless continue for an indefinite
period by reason of the discretion given to the curators of
Lincoln Page 305 U. S. 352 University and the alternative of arranging for tuition in other
States, as permitted by the state law as construed by the state
court, so long as the curators find it unnecessary and
impracticable to provide facilities for the legal instruction of
negroes within the State. In that view, we cannot regard the
discrimination as excused by what is called its temporary
character.
We do not find that the decision of the state court turns on any
procedural question. The action was for mandamus, but it does not
appear that the remedy would have been deemed inappropriate if the
asserted federal right had been sustained. In that situation, the
remedy by mandamus was found to be a proper one in University
of Maryland v. Murray, supra. In the instant case, the state
court did note that petitioner had not applied to the management of
Lincoln University for legal training. But, as we have said, the
state court did not rule that it would have been the duty of the
curators to grant such an application, but, on the contrary, took
the view, as we understand it, that the curators were entitled
under the state law to refuse such an application and, in its
stead, to provide for petitioner's tuition in an adjacent State.
That conclusion presented the federal question as to the
constitutional adequacy of such a provision while equal opportunity
for legal training within the State was not furnished, and this
federal question the state court entertained and passed upon. We
must conclude that, in so doing, the court denied the federal right
which petitioner set up and the question as to the correctness of
that decision is before us. We are of the opinion that the ruling
was error, and that petitioner was entitled to be admitted to the
law school of the State University in the absence of other and
proper provision for his legal training within the State.
The judgment of the Supreme Court of Missouri is reversed, and
the cause is remanded for further proceedings not inconsistent with
this opinion. Reversed. Page 305 U. S. 353 [ Footnote 1 ] Ex parte Virginia, 100 U. S. 339 , 100 U. S. 346 ,
347; Neal v. Delaware, 103 U. S. 370 , 103 U. S. 397 ; Carter v. Texas, 177 U. S. 442 , 177 U. S. 447 ; Norris v. Alabama, 294 U. S. 587 , 294 U. S.
589 .
[ Footnote 2 ]
Section 9618, R.S.Mo.1929, is as follows:
"Sec. 9618. Board of curators authorized to reorganize. -- The board of curators of the Lincoln university shall be
authorized and required to reorganize said institution so that it
shall afford to the negro people of the state opportunity for
training up to the standard furnished at the state university of
Missouri whenever necessary and practicable in their opinion. To
this end the board of curators shall be authorized to purchase
necessary additional land, erect necessary additional buildings, to
provide necessary additional equipment, and to locate, in the
county of Cole the respective units of the university where, in
their opinion, the various schools will most effectively promote
the purposes of this article. (Laws of 1921, p. 86, § 3.)"
[ Footnote 3 ] See University of Maryland v. Murray, 169 Md. 478,
486.
Separate opinion of MR. JUSTICE McREYNOLDS.
Considering the disclosures of the record, the Supreme Court of
Missouri arrived at a tenable conclusion, and its judgment should
be affirmed. That court well understood the grave difficulties of
the situation, and rightly refused to upset the settled legislative
policy of the State by directing a mandamus.
In Cummming v. Richmond County Board of Education, 175 U. S. 528 , 175 U. S. 545 ,
this Court, through Mr. Justice Harlan, declared:
"The education of the people in schools maintained by state
taxation is a matter belonging to the respective States, and any
interference on the part of Federal authority with the management
of such schools cannot be justified except in the case of a clear
and unmistakable disregard of rights secured by the supreme law of
the land." Gong Lum v. Rice, 275 U. S. 78 , 275 U. S. 85 --
opinion by Mr. Chief Justice Taft -- asserts: "The right and power
of the state to regulate the method of providing for the education
of its youth at public expense is clear."
For a long time, Missouri has acted upon the view that the best
interest of her people demands separation of whites and negroes in
schools. Under the opinion just announced, I presume she may
abandon her law school, and thereby disadvantage her white citizens
without improving petitioner's opportunities for legal instruction;
or she may break down the settled practice concerning separate
schools and thereby, as indicated by experience, damnify both
races. Whether by some other course it may be possible for her to
avoid condemnation is matter for conjecture.
The State has offered to provide the negro petitioner
opportunity for study of the law -- if perchance that is the thing
really desired -- by paying his tuition at some nearby school of
good standing. This is far from unmistakable disregard of his
rights, and, in the circumstances, Page 305 U. S. 354 is enough to satisfy any reasonable demand for specialized
training. It appears that never before has a negro applied for
admission to the Law School, and none has ever asked that Lincoln
University provide legal instruction.
The problem presented obviously is a difficult and highly
practical one. A fair effort to solve it has been made by offering
adequate opportunity for study when sought in good faith. The State
should not be unduly hampered through theorization inadequately
restrained by experience.
This proceeding commenced in April, 1936. Petitioner, then
twenty-four years old, asked mandamus to compel his admission to
the University in September, 1936, notwithstanding plain
legislative inhibition. Mandamus is not a writ of right, but is
granted only in the court's discretion upon consideration of all
the circumstances. Duncan Townsite Co. v. Lane, 245 U. S. 308 , 245 U. S. 311 ; United States ex rel. Arant v. Lane, 249 U.
S. 367 , 249 U. S.
371 .
The Supreme Court of Missouri did not consider the propriety of
granting the writ under the theory of the law now accepted here.
That, of course, will be matter open for its consideration upon
return of the cause. | In Missouri ex rel. Gaines v. Canada, the U.S. Supreme Court ruled that Missouri's policy of providing separate schools for whites and negroes was unconstitutional under the Fourteenth Amendment. The Court held that if a state provides higher education to white residents, it must also provide substantially equal advantages to negro residents, even if they are not in the same schools. The Court found that Missouri's denial of admission to a negro student at the state university's law school solely based on race was state action and violated the equal protection clause. The Court also rejected the state's argument that its plans to establish a law school for negroes or its offer to pay tuition for negro students to study law in other states satisfied the requirements of the Fourteenth Amendment. |
Equal Protection | Plessy v. Ferguson | https://supreme.justia.com/cases/federal/us/163/537/ | U.S. Supreme Court Plessy v. Ferguson, 163
U.S. 537 (1896) Plessy v. Ferguson No. 210 Argued April 18, 1896 Decided May 18, 1896 163
U.S. 537 ERROR TO THE SUPREME COURT OF THE
STATE OF LOUISIANA Syllabus The statute of Louisiana, acts of 1890, c. 111, requiring
railway companies carrying passengers in their coaches in that
State, to provide equal, but separate, accommodations for the white
and colored races, by providing two or more passenger coaches for
each passenger train, or by dividing the passenger coaches by a
partition so as to secure separate accommodations; and providing
that no person shall be permitted to occupy seats in coaches other
than the ones assigned to them, on account Page 163 U. S. 538 of the race they belong to; and requiring the officer of the
passenger train to assign each passenger to the coach or
compartment assigned for the race to which he or she belong; and
imposing fines or imprisonment upon passengers insisting on going
into a coach or compartment other than the one set aide for the
race to which he or she belongs; and conferring upon officers of
the train power to refuse to carry on the train passengers refusing
to occupy the coach or compartment assigned to them, and exempting
the railway company from liability for such refusal, are not in
conflict with the provisions either of the Thirteenth Amendment or
of the Fourteenth Amendment to the Constitution of the United
States.
This was a petition for writs of prohibition and certiorari,
originally filed in the Supreme Court of the State by Plessy, the
plaintiff in error, against the Hon. John H. Ferguson, judge of the
criminal District Court for the parish of Orleans, and setting
forth in substance the following facts:
That petitioner was a citizen of the United States and a
resident of the State of Louisiana, of mixed descent, in the
proportion of seven eighths Caucasian and one eighth African blood;
that the mixture of colored blood was not discernible in him, and
that he was entitled to every recognition, right, privilege and
immunity secured to the citizens of the United States of the white
race by its Constitution and laws; that, on June 7, 1892, he
engaged and paid for a first class passage on the East Louisiana
Railway from New Orleans to Covington, in the same State, and
thereupon entered a passenger train, and took possession of a
vacant seat in a coach where passengers of the white race were
accommodated; that such railroad company was incorporated by the
laws of Louisiana as a common carrier, and was not authorized to
distinguish between citizens according to their race. But,
notwithstanding this, petitioner was required by the conductor,
under penalty of ejection from said train and imprisonment, to
vacate said coach and occupy another seat in a coach assigned by
said company for persons not of the white race, and for no other
reason than that petitioner was of the colored race; that, upon
petitioner's refusal to comply with such order, he was, with the
aid of a police officer, forcibly ejected from said coach and
hurried off to and imprisoned in the parish jail of Page 163 U. S. 539 New Orleans, and there held to answer a charge made by such
officer to the effect that he was guilty of having criminally
violated an act of the General Assembly of the State, approved July
10, 1890, in such case made and provided.
That petitioner was subsequently brought before the recorder of
the city for preliminary examination and committed for trial to the
criminal District Court for the parish of Orleans, where an
information was filed against him in the matter above set forth,
for a violation of the above act, which act the petitioner affirmed
to be null and void, because in conflict with the Constitution of
the United States; that petitioner interposed a plea to such
information based upon the unconstitutionality of the act of the
General Assembly, to which the district attorney, on behalf of the
State, filed a demurrer; that, upon issue being joined upon such
demurrer and plea, the court sustained the demurrer, overruled the
plea, and ordered petitioner to plead over to the facts set forth
in the information, and that, unless the judge of the said court be
enjoined by a writ of prohibition from further proceeding in such
case, the court will proceed to fine and sentence petitioner to
imprisonment, and thus deprive him of his constitutional rights set
forth in his said plea, notwithstanding the unconstitutionality of
the act under which he was being prosecuted; that no appeal lay
from such sentence, and petitioner was without relief or remedy
except by writs of prohibition and certiorari. Copies of the
information and other proceedings in the criminal District Court
were annexed to the petition as an exhibit.
Upon the filing of this petition, an order was issued upon the
respondent to show cause why a writ of prohibition should not issue
and be made perpetual, and a further order that the record of the
proceedings had in the criminal cause be certified and transmitted
to the Supreme Court.
To this order the respondent made answer, transmitting a
certified copy of the proceedings, asserting the constitutionality
of the law, and averring that, instead of pleading or admitting
that he belonged to the colored race, the said Plessy declined and
refused, either by pleading or otherwise, to admit Page 163 U. S. 540 that he was in any sense or in any proportion a colored man.
The case coming on for a hearing before the Supreme Court, that
court was of opinion that the law under which the prosecution was
had was constitutional, and denied the relief prayed for by the
petitioner. Ex parte Plessy, 45 La.Ann. 80. Whereupon
petitioner prayed for a writ of error from this court, which was
allowed by the Chief Justice of the Supreme Court of Louisiana.
MR. JUSTICE BROWN, after stating the case, delivered the opinion
of the court.
This case turns upon the constitutionality of an act of the
General Assembly of the State of Louisiana, passed in 1890,
providing for separate railway carriages for the white and colored
races. Acts 1890, No. 111, p. 152.
The first section of the statute enacts
"that all railway companies carrying passengers in their coaches
in this State shall provide equal but separate accommodations for
the white and colored races by providing two or more passenger
coaches for each passenger train, or by dividing the passenger
coaches by a partition so as to secure separate accommodations: Provided, That this section shall not be construed to
apply to street railroads. No person or persons, shall be admitted
to occupy seats in coaches other than the ones assigned to them on
account of the race they belong to."
By the second section, it was enacted
"that the officers of such passenger trains shall have power and
are hereby required Page 163 U. S. 541 to assign each passenger to the coach or compartment used for
the race to which such passenger belongs; any passenger insisting
on going into a coach or compartment to which by race he does not
belong shall be liable to a fine of twenty-five dollars, or in lieu
thereof to imprisonment for a period of not more than twenty days
in the parish prison, and any officer of any railroad insisting on
assigning a passenger to a coach or compartment other than the one
set aside for the race to which said passenger belongs shall be
liable to a fine of twenty-five dollars, or in lieu thereof to
imprisonment for a period of not more than twenty days in the
parish prison; and should any passenger refuse to occupy the coach
or compartment to which he or she is assigned by the officer of
such railway, said officer shall have power to refuse to carry such
passenger on his train, and for such refusal neither he nor the
railway company which he represents shall be liable for damages in
any of the courts of this State."
The third section provides penalties for the refusal or neglect
of the officers, directors, conductors, and employees of railway
companies to comply with the act, with a proviso that "nothing in
this act shall be construed as applying to nurses attending
children of the other race." The fourth section is immaterial.
The information filed in the criminal District Court charged in
substance that Plessy, being a passenger between two stations
within the State of Louisiana, was assigned by officers of the
company to the coach used for the race to which he belonged, but he
insisted upon going into a coach used by the race to which he did
not belong. Neither in the information nor plea was his particular
race or color averred. The petition for the writ of prohibition
averred that petitioner was seven-eighths Caucasian and one eighth
African blood; that the mixture of colored blood was not
discernible in him, and that he was entitled to every right,
privilege and immunity secured to citizens of the United States of
the white race; and that, upon such theory, he took possession of a
vacant seat in a coach where passengers of the white race were
accommodated, and was ordered by the conductor to vacate Page 163 U. S. 542 said coach and take a seat in another assigned to persons of the
colored race, and, having refused to comply with such demand, he
was forcibly ejected with the aid of a police officer, and
imprisoned in the parish jail to answer a charge of having violated
the above act.
The constitutionality of this act is attacked upon the ground
that it conflicts both with the Thirteenth Amendment of the
Constitution, abolishing slavery, and the Fourteenth Amendment,
which prohibits certain restrictive legislation on the part of the
States.
1. That it does not conflict with the Thirteenth Amendment,
which abolished slavery and involuntary servitude, except as a
punishment for crime, is too clear for argument. Slavery implies
involuntary servitude -- a state of bondage; the ownership of
mankind as a chattel, or at least the control of the labor and
services of one man for the benefit of another, and the absence of
a legal right to the disposal of his own person, property and
services. This amendment was said in the Slaughterhouse
Cases , 16 Wall. 36, to have been intended primarily
to abolish slavery as it had been previously known in this country,
and that it equally forbade Mexican peonage or the Chinese coolie
trade when they amounted to slavery or involuntary servitude, and
that the use of the word "servitude" was intended to prohibit the
use of all forms of involuntary slavery, of whatever class or name.
It was intimated, however, in that case that this amendment was
regarded by the statesmen of that day as insufficient to protect
the colored race from certain laws which had been enacted in the
Southern States, imposing upon the colored race onerous
disabilities and burdens and curtailing their rights in the pursuit
of life, liberty and property to such an extent that their freedom
was of little value; and that the Fourteenth Amendment was devised
to meet this exigency.
So, too, in the Civil Rights Cases, 109 U. S.
3 , 109 U. S. 24 , it
was said that the act of a mere individual, the owner of an inn, a
public conveyance or place of amusement, refusing accommodations to
colored people cannot be justly regarded as imposing any badge of
slavery or servitude upon the applicant, but Page 163 U. S. 543 only as involving an ordinary civil injury, properly cognizable
by the laws of the State and presumably subject to redress by those
laws until the contrary appears. "It would be running the slavery
argument into the ground," said Mr. Justice Bradley,
"to make it apply to every act of discrimination which a person
may see fit to make as to the guests he will entertain, or as to
the people he will take into his coach or cab or car, or admit to
his concert or theatre, or deal with in other matters of
intercourse or business."
A statute which implies merely a legal distinction between the
white and colored races -- a distinction which is founded in the
color of the two races and which must always exist so long as white
men are distinguished from the other race by color -- has no
tendency to destroy the legal equality of the two races, or
reestablish a state of involuntary servitude. Indeed, we do not
understand that the Thirteenth Amendment is strenuously relied upon
by the plaintiff in error in this connection.
2. By the Fourteenth Amendment, all persons born or naturalized
in the United States and subject to the jurisdiction thereof are
made citizens of the United States and of the State wherein they
reside, and the States are forbidden from making or enforcing any
law which shall abridge the privileges or immunities of citizens of
the United States, or shall deprive any person of life, liberty, or
property without due process of law, or deny to any person within
their jurisdiction the equal protection of the laws.
The proper construction of this amendment was first called to
the attention of this court in the Slaughterhouse
Cases , 16 Wall. 36, which involved, however, not a
question of race, but one of exclusive privileges. The case did not
call for any expression of opinion as to the exact rights it was
intended to secure to the colored race, but it was said generally
that its main purpose was to establish the citizenship of the
negro, to give definitions of citizenship of the United States and
of the States, and to protect from the hostile legislation of the
States the privileges and immunities of citizens of the United
States, as distinguished from those of citizens of the States. Page 163 U. S. 544 The object of the amendment was undoubtedly to enforce the
absolute equality of the two races before the law, but, in the
nature of things, it could not have been intended to abolish
distinctions based upon color, or to enforce social, as
distinguished from political, equality, or a commingling of the two
races upon terms unsatisfactory to either. Laws permitting, and
even requiring, their separation in places where they are liable to
be brought into contact do not necessarily imply the inferiority of
either race to the other, and have been generally, if not
universally, recognized as within the competency of the state
legislatures in the exercise of their police power. The most common
instance of this is connected with the establishment of separate
schools for white and colored children, which has been held to be a
valid exercise of the legislative power even by courts of States
where the political rights of the colored race have been longest
and most earnestly enforced.
One of the earliest of these cases is that of Roberts v.
City of Boston, 5 Cush. 19, in which the Supreme Judicial
Court of Massachusetts held that the general school committee of
Boston had power to make provision for the instruction of colored
children in separate schools established exclusively for them, and
to prohibit their attendance upon the other schools. "The great
principle," said Chief Justice Shaw, p. 206, "advanced by the
learned and eloquent advocate for the plaintiff" (Mr. Charles
Sumner),
"is that, by the constitution and laws of Massachusetts, all
persons without distinction of age or sex, birth or color, origin
or condition, are equal before the law. . . . But when this great
principle comes to be applied to the actual and various conditions
of persons in society, it will not warrant the assertion that men
and women are legally clothed with the same civil and political
powers, and that children and adults are legally to have the same
functions and be subject to the same treatment, but only that the
rights of all, as they are settled and regulated by law, are
equally entitled to the paternal consideration and protection of
the law for their maintenance and security."
It was held that the powers of the committee extended to the
establishment Page 163 U. S. 545 of separate schools for children of different ages, sexes and
colors, and that they might also establish special schools for poor
and neglected children, who have become too old to attend the
primary school and yet have not acquired the rudiments of learning
to enable them to enter the ordinary schools. Similar laws have
been enacted by Congress under its general power of legislation
over the District of Columbia, Rev.Stat.D.C. §§ 281, 282, 283, 310,
319, as well as by the legislatures of many of the States, and have
been generally, if not uniformly, sustained by the courts. State v. McCann, 21 Ohio St. 198; Lehew v.
Brummell, 15 S.W.Rep. 765; Ward v. Flood, 48
California 36; Bertonneau v. School Directors, 3 Woods
177; People v. Gallagher, 93 N.Y. 438; Cory v.
Carter, 48 Indiana 897; Dawson v. Lee, 3 Kentucky
49.
Laws forbidding the intermarriage of the two races may be said
in a technical sense to interfere with the freedom of contract, and
yet have been universally recognized as within the police power of
the State. State v. Gibson, 36 Indiana 389.
The distinction between laws interfering with the political
equality of the negro and those requiring the separation of the two
races in schools, theatres and railway carriages has been
frequently drawn by this court. Thus, in Strauder v. West
Virginia, 100 U. S. 303 , it
was held that a law of West Virginia limiting to white male
persons, 21 years of age and citizens of the State, the right to
sit upon juries was a discrimination which implied a legal
inferiority in civil society, which lessened the security of the
right of the colored race, and was a step toward reducing them to a
condition of servility. Indeed, the right of a colored man that, in
the selection of jurors to pass upon his life, liberty and
property, there shall be no exclusion of his race and no
discrimination against them because of color has been asserted in a
number of cases. Virginia v. Rives, 100 U.
S. 313 ; Neal v. Delaware, 103 U.
S. 370 ; Bush v. Kentucky, 107 U.
S. 110 ; Gibson v. Mississippi, 162 U.
S. 565 . So, where the laws of a particular locality or
the charter of a particular railway corporation has provided that
no person shall be excluded from the cars on account of Page 163 U. S. 546 color, we have held that this meant that persons of color should
travel in the same car as white ones, and that the enactment was
not satisfied by the company's providing cars assigned exclusively
to people of color, though they were as good as those which they
assigned exclusively to white persons. Railroad
Company v. Brown , 17 Wall. 445.
Upon the other hand, where a statute of Louisiana required those
engaged in the transportation of passengers among the States to
give to all persons traveling within that State, upon vessels
employed in that business, equal rights and privileges in all parts
of the vessel, without distinction on account of race or color, and
subjected to an action for damages the owner of such a vessel, who
excluded colored passengers on account of their color from the
cabin set aside by him for the use of whites, it was held to be, so
far as it applied to interstate commerce, unconstitutional and
void. Hall v. De Cuir, 95 U. S. 48 . The
court in this case, however, expressly disclaimed that it had
anything whatever to do with the statute as a regulation of
internal commerce, or affecting anything else than commerce among
the States.
In the Civil Rights Case, 109 U. S.
3 , it was held that an act of Congress entitling all
persons within the jurisdiction of the United States to the full
and equal enjoyment of the accommodations, advantages, facilities
and privileges of inns, public conveyances, on land or water,
theatres and other places of public amusement, and made applicable
to citizens of every race and color, regardless of any previous
condition of servitude, was unconstitutional and void upon the
ground that the Fourteenth Amendment was prohibitory upon the
States only, and the legislation authorized to be adopted by
Congress for enforcing it was not direct legislation on matters
respecting which the States were prohibited from making or
enforcing certain laws, or doing certain acts, but was corrective
legislation such as might be necessary or proper for counteracting
and redressing the effect of such laws or acts. In delivering the
opinion of the court, Mr. Justice Bradley observed that the
Fourteenth Amendment
"does not invest Congress with power to legislate upon subjects
that are within the Page 163 U. S. 547 domain of state legislation, but to provide modes of relief
against state legislation or state action of the kind referred to.
It does not authorize Congress to create a code of municipal law
for the regulation of private rights, but to provide modes of
redress against the operation of state laws and the action of state
officers, executive or judicial, when these are subversive of the
fundamental rights specified in the amendment. Positive rights and
privileges are undoubtedly secured by the Fourteenth Amendment, but
they are secured by way of prohibition against state laws and state
proceedings affecting those rights and privileges, and by power
given to Congress to legislate for the purpose of carrying such
prohibition into effect, and such legislation must necessarily be
predicated upon such supposed state laws or state proceedings, and
be directed to the correction of their operation and effect."
Much nearer, and, indeed, almost directly in point is the case
of the Louisville, New Orleans &c. Railway v.
Mississippi, 133 U. S. 587 ,
wherein the railway company was indicted for a violation of a
statute of Mississippi enacting that all railroads carrying
passengers should provide equal but separate accommodations for the
white and colored races by providing two or more passenger cars for
each passenger train, or by dividing the passenger cars by a
partition so as to secure separate accommodations. The case was
presented in a different aspect from the one under consideration,
inasmuch as it was an indictment against the railway company for
failing to provide the separate accommodations, but the question
considered was the constitutionality of the law. In that case, the
Supreme Court of Mississippi, 66 Mississippi 662, had held that the
statute applied solely to commerce within the State, and that,
being the construction of the state statute by its highest court,
was accepted as conclusive. "If it be a matter," said the court, p.
591,
"respecting commerce wholly within a State, and not interfering
with commerce between the States, then obviously there is no
violation of the commerce clause of the Federal Constitution. . . .
No question arises under this section as to the power of the State
to separate in different compartments interstate passengers Page 163 U. S. 548 or affect in any manner the privileges and rights of such
passengers. All that we can consider is whether the State has the
power to require that railroad trains within her limits shall have
separate accommodations for the two races; that affecting only
commerce within the State is no invasion of the power given to
Congress by the commerce clause."
A like course of reasoning applies to the case under
consideration, since the Supreme Court of Louisiana in the case of
the State ex rel. Abbott v. Hicks, Judge, et al., 44
La.Ann. 770, held that the statute in question did not apply to
interstate passengers, but was confined in its application to
passengers traveling exclusively within the borders of the State.
The case was decided largely upon the authority of Railway Co.
v. State, 66 Mississippi 662, and affirmed by this court in 133 U. S. 587 . In
the present case, no question of interference with interstate
commerce can possibly arise, since the East Louisiana Railway
appears to have been purely a local line, with both its termini
within the State of Louisiana. Similar statutes for the separation
of the to races upon public conveyances were held to be
constitutional in West Chester &c. Railroad v. Miles, 55 Penn.St. 209; Day v. Owen, 5 Michigan 520; Chicago
&c. Railway v. Williams, 5 Illinois 185; Chesapeake
&c. Railroad v. Wells, 85 Tennessee 613; Memphis
&c. Railroad v. Benson, 85 Tennessee 627; The
Sue, 22 Fed.Rep. 83; Logwood v. Memphis &c.
Railroad, 23 Fed.Rep. 318; McGuinn v. Forbes, 37
Fed.Rep. 639; People v. King, 18 N.E.Rep. 245; Houck
v. South Pac. Railway, 38 Fed.Rep. 226; Heard v. Georgia
Railroad Co., 3 Int.Com.Com'n 111; S.C., 1 Ibid. 428.
While we think the enforced separation of the races, as applied
to the internal commerce of the State, neither abridges the
privileges or immunities of the colored man, deprives him of his
property without due process of law, nor denies him the equal
protection of the laws within the meaning of the Fourteenth
Amendment, we are not prepared to say that the conductor, in
assigning passengers to the coaches according to their race, does
not act at his peril, or that the provision of the second section
of the act that denies to the passenger compensation Page 163 U. S. 549 in damages for a refusal to receive him into the coach in which
he properly belongs is a valid exercise of the legislative power.
Indeed, we understand it to be conceded by the State's Attorney
that such part of the act as exempts from liability the railway
company and its officers is unconstitutional. The power to assign
to a particular coach obviously implies the power to determine to
which race the passenger belongs, as well as the power to determine
who, under the laws of the particular State, is to be deemed a
white and who a colored person. This question, though indicated in
the brief of the plaintiff in error, does not properly arise upon
the record in this case, since the only issue made is as to the
unconstitutionality of the act so far as it requires the railway to
provide separate accommodations and the conductor to assign
passengers according to their race.
It is claimed by the plaintiff in error that, in any mixed
community, the reputation of belonging to the dominant race, in
this instance the white race, is property in the same sense that a
right of action or of inheritance is property. Conceding this to be
so for the purposes of this case, we are unable to see how this
statute deprives him of, or in any way affects his right to, such
property. If he be a white man and assigned to a colored coach, he
may have his action for damages against the company for being
deprived of his so-called property. Upon the other hand, if he be a
colored man and be so assigned, he has been deprived of no
property, since he is not lawfully entitled to the reputation of
being a white man.
In this connection, it is also suggested by the learned counsel
for the plaintiff in error that the same argument that will justify
the state legislature in requiring railways to provide separate
accommodations for the two races will also authorize them to
require separate cars to be provided for people whose hair is of a
certain color, or who are aliens, or who belong to certain
nationalities, or to enact laws requiring colored people to walk
upon one side of the street and white people upon the other, or
requiring white men's houses to be painted white and colored men's
black, or their vehicles or business signs to be of different
colors, upon the theory that one side Page 163 U. S. 550 of the street is as good as the other, or that a house or
vehicle of one color is as good as one of another color. The reply
to all this is that every exercise of the police power must be
reasonable, and extend only to such laws as are enacted in good
faith for the promotion for the public good, and not for the
annoyance or oppression of a particular class. Thus, in Yick Wo
v. Hopkins, 118 U. S. 356 , it
was held by this court that a municipal ordinance of the city of
San Francisco to regulate the carrying on of public laundries
within the limits of the municipality violated the provisions of
the Constitution of the United States if it conferred upon the
municipal authorities arbitrary power, at their own will and
without regard to discretion, in the legal sense of the term, to
give or withhold consent as to persons or places without regard to
the competency of the persons applying or the propriety of the
places selected for the carrying on of the business. It was held to
be a covert attempt on the part of the municipality to make an
arbitrary and unjust discrimination against the Chinese race. While
this was the case of a municipal ordinance, a like principle has
been held to apply to acts of a state legislature passed in the
exercise of the police power. Railroad Company v. Husen, 95 U. S. 465 ; Louisville & Nashville Railroad v. Kentucky, 161 U. S. 677 , and
cases cited on p. 161 U. S. 700 ; Duggett v. Hudson, 43 Ohio St. 548; Capen v.
Foster, 12 Pick. 48; State ex rel. Wood v. Baker, 38
Wisconsin 71; Monroe v. Collins, 17 Ohio St. 66; Hulseman v. Rems, 41 Penn. St. 396; Orman v.
Riley, 1 California 48.
So far, then, as a conflict with the Fourteenth Amendment is
concerned, the case reduces itself to the question whether the
statute of Louisiana is a reasonable regulation, and, with respect
to this, there must necessarily be a large discretion on the part
of the legislature. In determining the question of reasonableness,
it is at liberty to act with reference to the established usages,
customs, and traditions of the people, and with a view to the
promotion of their comfort and the preservation of the public peace
and good order. Gauged by this standard, we cannot say that a law
which authorizes or even requires the separation of the two races
in public conveyances Page 163 U. S. 551 is unreasonable, or more obnoxious to the Fourteenth Amendment
than the acts of Congress requiring separate schools for colored
children in the District of Columbia, the constitutionality of
which does not seem to have been questioned, or the corresponding
acts of state legislatures.
We consider the underlying fallacy of the plaintiff's argument
to consist in the assumption that the enforced separation of the
two races stamps the colored race with a badge of inferiority. If
this be so, it is not by reason of anything found in the act, but
solely because the colored race chooses to put that construction
upon it. The argument necessarily assumes that if, as has been more
than once the case and is not unlikely to be so again, the colored
race should become the dominant power in the state legislature, and
should enact a law in precisely similar terms, it would thereby
relegate the white race to an inferior position. We imagine that
the white race, at least, would not acquiesce in this assumption.
The argument also assumes that social prejudices may be overcome by
legislation, and that equal rights cannot be secured to the negro
except by an enforced commingling of the two races. We cannot
accept this proposition. If the two races are to meet upon terms of
social equality, it must be the result of natural affinities, a
mutual appreciation of each other's merits, and a voluntary consent
of individuals. As was said by the Court of Appeals of New York in People v. Gallagher, 93 N.Y. 438, 448,
"this end can neither be accomplished nor promoted by laws which
conflict with the general sentiment of the community upon whom they
are designed to operate. When the government, therefore, has
secured to each of its citizens equal rights before the law and
equal opportunities for improvement and progress, it has
accomplished the end for which it was organized, and performed all
of the functions respecting social advantages with which it is
endowed."
Legislation is powerless to eradicate racial instincts or to
abolish distinctions based upon physical differences, and the
attempt to do so can only result in accentuating the difficulties
of the present situation. If the civil and political rights of both
races be equal, one cannot be inferior to the other civilly Page 163 U. S. 552 or politically. If one race be inferior to the other socially,
the Constitution of the United States cannot put them upon the same
plane.
It is true that the question of the proportion of colored blood
necessary to constitute a colored person, as distinguished from a
white person, is one upon which there is a difference of opinion in
the different States, some holding that any visible admixture of
black blood stamps the person as belonging to the colored race
( State v. Chaver, 5 Jones [N.C.] 1, p. 11); others that it
depends upon the preponderance of blood ( Gray v. State, 4
Ohio 354; Monroe v. Collins, 17 Ohio St. 665); and still
others that the predominance of white blood must only be in the
proportion of three-fourths. ( People v. Dean, 4 Michigan
406; Jones v. Commonwealth, 80 Virginia 538). But these
are questions to be determined under the laws of each State, and
are not properly put in issue in this case. Under the allegations
of his petition, it may undoubtedly become a question of importance
whether, under the laws of Louisiana, the petitioner belongs to the
white or colored race.
The judgment of the court below is, therefore, Affirmed. MR. JUSTICE HARLAN, dissenting.
By the Louisiana statute the validity of which is here involved,
all railway companies (other than street railroad companies)
carrying passengers in that State are required to have separate but
equal accommodations for white and colored persons
"by providing two or more passenger coaches for each passenger
train, or by dividing the passenger coaches by a partition so as to
secure separate accommodations."
Under this statute, no colored person is permitted to occupy a
seat in a coach assigned to white persons, nor any white person to
occupy a seat in a coach assigned to colored persons. The managers
of the railroad are not allowed to exercise any discretion in the
premises, but are required to assign each passenger to some coach
or compartment set apart for the exclusive use of his race. If a
passenger insists upon going into a coach or compartment not set
apart for persons of his race, Page 163 U. S. 553 he is subject to be fined or to be imprisoned in the parish
jail. Penalties are prescribed for the refusal or neglect of the
officers, directors, conductors and employees of railroad companies
to comply with the provisions of the act.
Only "nurses attending children of the other race " are excepted
from the operation of the statute. No exception is made of colored
attendants traveling with adults. A white man is not permitted to
have his colored servant with him in the same coach, even if his
condition of health requires the constant, personal assistance of
such servant. If a colored maid insists upon riding in the same
coach with a white woman whom she has been employed to serve, and
who may need her personal attention while traveling, she is subject
to be fined or imprisoned for such an exhibition of zeal in the
discharge of duty.
While there may be in Louisiana persons of different races who
are not citizens of the United States, the words in the act "white
and colored races" necessarily include all citizens of the United
States of both races residing in that State. So that we have before
us a state enactment that compels, under penalties, the separation
of the two races in railroad passenger coaches, and makes it a
crime for a citizen of either race to enter a coach that has been
assigned to citizens of the other race.
Thus, the State regulates the use of a public highway by
citizens of the United States solely upon the basis of race.
However apparent the injustice of such legislation may be, we
have only to consider whether it is consistent with the
Constitution of the United States.
That a railroad is a public highway, and that the corporation
which owns or operates it is in the exercise of public functions,
is not, at this day, to be disputed. Mr. Justice Nelson, speaking
for this court in New Jersey Steam Navigation
Co. v. Merchants' Bank , 6 How. 344, 47 U. S. 382 ,
said that a common carrier was in the exercise
"of a sort of public office, and has public duties to perform,
from which he should not be permitted to exonerate himself without
the assent of the parties concerned."
Mr. Justice Strong, delivering the judgment of Page 163 U. S. 554 this court in Olcott v. The
Supervisors , 16 Wall. 678, 83 U. S. 694 ,
said:
"That railroads, though constructed by private corporations and
owned by them, are public highways has been the doctrine of nearly
all the courts ever since such conveniences for passage and
transportation have had any existence. Very early the question
arose whether a State's right of eminent domain could be exercised
by a private corporation created for the purpose of constructing a
railroad. Clearly it could not unless taking land for such a
purpose by such an agency is taking land for public use. The right
of eminent domain nowhere justifies taking property for a private
use. Yet it is a doctrine universally accepted that a state
legislature may authorize a private corporation to take land for
the construction of such a road, making compensation to the owner.
What else does this doctrine mean if not that building a railroad,
though it be built by a private corporation, is an act done for a
public use."
So, in Township of Pine Grove v.
Talcott , 19 Wall. 666, 86 U. S. 676 :
"Though the corporation [a railroad company] was private, its work
was public, as much so as if it were to be constructed by the
State." So, in Inhabitants of Worcester v. Western Railroad
Corporation, 4 Met. 564:
"The establishment of that great thoroughfare is regarded as a
public work, established by public authority, intended for the
public use and benefit, the use of which is secured to the whole
community, and constitutes, therefore, like a canal, turnpike or
highway, a public easement. It is true that the real and personal
property necessary to the establishment and management of the
railroad is vested in the corporation, but it is in trust for the
public."
In respect of civil rights common to all citizens, the
Constitution of the United States does not, I think, permit any
public authority to know the race of those entitled to be protected
in the enjoyment of such rights. Every true man has pride of race,
and, under appropriate circumstances, when the rights of others,
his equals before the law, are not to be affected, it is his
privilege to express such pride and to take such action based upon
it as to him seems proper. But I deny that any legislative body or
judicial tribunal may have regard to the Page 163 U. S. 555 race of citizens when the civil rights of those citizens are
involved. Indeed, such legislation as that here in question is
inconsistent not only with that equality of rights which pertains
to citizenship, National and State, but with the personal liberty
enjoyed by everyone within the United States.
The Thirteenth Amendment does not permit the withholding or the
deprivation of any right necessarily inhering in freedom. It not
only struck down the institution of slavery as previously existing
in the United States, but it prevents the imposition of any burdens
or disabilities that constitute badges of slavery or servitude. It
decreed universal civil freedom in this country. This court has so
adjudged. But that amendment having been found inadequate to the
protection of the rights of those who had been in slavery, it was
followed by the Fourteenth Amendment, which added greatly to the
dignity and glory of American citizenship and to the security of
personal liberty by declaring that
"all persons born or naturalized in the United States, and
subject to the jurisdiction thereof, are citizens of the United
States and of the State wherein they reside,"
and that
"no State shall make or enforce any law which shall abridge the
privileges or immunities of citizens of the United States; nor
shall any State deprive any person of life, liberty or property
without due process of law, nor deny to any person within its
jurisdiction the equal protection of the laws."
These two amendments, if enforced according to their true intent
and meaning, will protect all the civil rights that pertain to
freedom and citizenship. Finally, and to the end that no citizen
should be denied, on account of his race, the privilege of
participating in the political control of his country, it as
declared by the Fifteenth Amendment that
"the right of citizens of the United States to vote shall not be
denied or abridged by the United States or by any State on account
of race, color or previous condition of servitude."
These notable additions to the fundamental law were welcomed by
the friends of liberty throughout the world. They removed the race
line from our governmental systems. They had, as this court has
said, a common purpose, namely to secure
"to a race recently emancipated, a race that through Page 163 U. S. 556 many generations have been held in slavery, all the civil rights
that the superior race enjoy."
They declared, in legal effect, this court has further said,
"that the law in the States shall be the same for the black as
for the white; that all persons, whether colored or white, shall
stand equal before the laws of the States, and, in regard to the
colored race, for whose protection the amendment was primarily
designed, that no discrimination shall be made against them by law
because of their color."
We also said:
"The words of the amendment, it is true, are prohibitory, but
they contain a necessary implication of a positive immunity, or
right, most valuable to the colored race -- the right to exemption
from unfriendly legislation against them distinctively as colored
-- exemption from legal discriminations, implying inferiority in
civil society, Lessening the security of their enjoyment of the
rights which others enjoy, and discriminations which are steps
towards reducing them to the condition of a subject race."
It was, consequently, adjudged that a state law that excluded
citizens of the colored race from juries, because of their race and
however well qualified in other respects to discharge the duties of
jurymen, was repugnant to the Fourteenth Amendment. Strauder v.
West Virginia, 100 U. S. 303 , 100 U. S. 306 , 100 U. S. 307 ; Virginia v. Rives, 100 U. S. 313 ; Ex parte Virginia, 100 U. S. 339 ; Neal v. Delaware, 103 U. S. 370 , 103 U. S. 386 ; Bush v. Kentucky, 107 U. S. 110 , 107 U. S. 116 .
At the present term, referring to the previous adjudications, this
court declared that
"underlying all of those decisions is the principle that the
Constitution of the United States, in its present form, forbids, so
far as civil and political rights are concerned, discrimination by
the General Government or the States against any citizen because of
his race. All citizens are equal before the law." Gibson v. Mississippi, 162 U.S.
565 .
The decisions referred to show the scope of the recent
amendments of the Constitution. They also show that it is not
within the power of a State to prohibit colored citizens, because
of their race, from participating as jurors in the administration
of justice.
It as said in argument that the statute of Louisiana does Page 163 U. S. 557 not discriminate against either race, but prescribes a rule
applicable alike to white and colored citizens. But this argument
does not meet the difficulty. Everyone knows that the statute in
question had its origin in the purpose not so much to exclude white
persons from railroad cars occupied by blacks as to exclude colored
people from coaches occupied by or assigned to white persons.
Railroad corporations of Louisiana did not make discrimination
among whites in the matter of accommodation for travelers. The
thing to accomplish was, under the guise of giving equal
accommodation for whites and blacks, to compel the latter to keep
to themselves while traveling in railroad passenger coaches. No one
would be so wanting in candor a to assert the contrary. The
fundamental objection, therefore, to the statute is that it
interferes with the personal freedom of citizens. "Personal
liberty," it has been well said,
"consists in the power of locomotion, of changing situation, or
removing one's person to whatsoever places one's own inclination
may direct, without imprisonment or restraint unless by due course
of law."
1 Bl.Com. *134. If a white man and a black man choose to occupy
the same public conveyance on a public highway, it is their right
to do so, and no government, proceeding alone on grounds of race,
can prevent it without infringing the personal liberty of each.
It is one thing for railroad carriers to furnish, or to be
required by law to furnish, equal accommodations for all whom they
are under a legal duty to carry. It is quite another thing for
government to forbid citizens of the white and black races from
traveling in the same public conveyance, and to punish officers of
railroad companies for permitting persons of the two races to
occupy the same passenger coach. If a State can prescribe, as a
rule of civil conduct, that whites and blacks shall not travel as
passengers in the same railroad coach, why may it not so regulate
the use of the streets of its cities and towns as to compel white
citizens to keep on one side of a street and black citizens to keep
on the other? Why may it not, upon like grounds, punish whites and
blacks who ride together in streetcars or in open vehicles on a
public road Page 163 U. S. 558 or street? Why may it not require sheriffs to assign whites to
one side of a courtroom and blacks to the other? And why may it not
also prohibit the commingling of the two races in the galleries of
legislative halls or in public assemblages convened for the
consideration of the political questions of the day? Further, if
this statute of Louisiana is consistent with the personal liberty
of citizens, why may not the State require the separation in
railroad coaches of native and naturalized citizens of the United
States, or of Protestants and Roman Catholics?
The answer given at the argument to these questions was that
regulations of the kind they suggest would be unreasonable, and
could not, therefore, stand before the law. Is it meant that the
determination of questions of legislative power depends upon the
inquiry whether the statute whose validity is questioned is, in the
judgment of the courts, a reasonable one, taking all the
circumstances into consideration? A statute may be unreasonable
merely because a sound public policy forbade its enactment. But I
do not understand that the courts have anything to do with the
policy or expediency of legislation. A statute may be valid and
yet, upon grounds of public policy, may well be characterized as
unreasonable. Mr. Sedgwick correctly states the rule when he says
that, the legislative intention being clearly ascertained,
"the courts have no other duty to perform than to execute the
legislative will, without any regard to their views as to the
wisdom or justice of the particular enactment."
Stat. & Const.Constr. 324. There is a dangerous tendency in
these latter days to enlarge the functions of the courts by means
of judicial interference with the will of the people as expressed
by the legislature. Our institutions have the distinguishing
characteristic that the three departments of government are
coordinate and separate. Each must keep within the limits defined
by the Constitution. And the courts best discharge their duty by
executing the will of the lawmaking power, constitutionally
expressed, leaving the results of legislation to be dealt with by
the people through their representatives. Statutes must always have
a reasonable construction. Sometimes they are to be construed
strictly; sometimes liberally, in order to carry out the
legislative Page 163 U. S. 559 will. But however construed, the intent of the legislature is to
be respected, if the particular statute in question is valid,
although the courts, looking at the public interests, may conceive
the statute to be both unreasonable and impolitic. If the power
exists to enact a statute, that ends the matter so far as the
courts are concerned. The adjudged cases in which statutes have
been held to be void because unreasonable are those in which the
means employed by the legislature were not at all germane to the
end to which the legislature was competent.
The white race deems itself to be the dominant race in this
country. And so it is in prestige, in achievements, in education,
in wealth and in power. So, I doubt not, it will continue to be for
all time if it remains true to its great heritage and holds fast to
the principles of constitutional liberty. But in view of the
Constitution, in the eye of the law, there is in this country no
superior, dominant, ruling class of citizens. There is no caste
here. Our Constitution is color-blind, and neither knows nor
tolerates classes among citizens. In respect of civil rights, all
citizens are equal before the law. The humblest is the peer of the
most powerful. The law regards man as man, and takes no account of
his surroundings or of his color when his civil rights as
guaranteed by the supreme law of the land are involved. It is
therefore to be regretted that this high tribunal, the final
expositor of the fundamental law of the land, has reached the
conclusion that it is competent for a State to regulate the
enjoyment by citizens of their civil rights solely upon the basis
of race.
In my opinion, the judgment this day rendered will, in time,
prove to be quite as pernicious as the decision made by this
tribunal in the Dred Scott Case. It was adjudged in that
case that the descendants of Africans who were imported into this
country and sold as slaves were not included nor intended to be
included under the word "citizens" in the Constitution, and could
not claim any of the rights and privileges which that instrument
provided for and secured to citizens of the United States; that, at
the time of the adoption of the Constitution, they were
"considered as a subordinate and inferior class of beings, who
had been subjugated by the dominant Page 163 U. S. 560 race, and, whether emancipated or not, yet remained subject to
their authority, and had no rights or privileges but such as those
who held the power and the government might choose to grant
them."
19 How. 60 U. S. 393 , 60 U. S. 404 .
The recent amendments of the Constitution, it was supposed, had
eradicated these principles from our institutions. But it seems
that we have yet, in some of the States, a dominant race -- a
superior class of citizens, which assumes to regulate the enjoyment
of civil rights, common to all citizens, upon the basis of race.
The present decision, it may well be apprehended, will not only
stimulate aggressions, more or less brutal and irritating, upon the
admitted rights of colored citizens, but will encourage the belief
that it is possible, by means of state enactments, to defeat the
beneficent purposes which the people of the United States had in
view when they adopted the recent amendments of the Constitution,
by one of which the blacks of this country were made citizens of
the United States and of the States in which they respectively
reside, and whose privileges and immunities, as citizens, the
States are forbidden to abridge. Sixty millions of whites are in no
danger from the presence here of eight millions of blacks. The
destinies of the two races in this country are indissolubly linked
together, and the interests of both require that the common
government of all shall not permit the seeds of race hate to be
planted under the sanction of law. What can more certainly arouse
race hate, what more certainly create and perpetuate a feeling of
distrust between these races, than state enactments which, in fact,
proceed on the ground that colored citizens are so inferior and
degraded that they cannot be allowed to sit in public coaches
occupied by white citizens. That, as all will admit, is the real
meaning of such legislation as was enacted in Louisiana.
The sure guarantee of the peace and security of each race is the
clear, distinct, unconditional recognition by our governments,
National and State, of every right that inheres in civil freedom,
and of the equality before the law of all citizens of the United
States, without regard to race. State enactments regulating the
enjoyment of civil rights upon the basis of race, and cunningly
devised to defeat legitimate results of the Page 163 U. S. 561 war under the pretence of recognizing equality of rights, can
have no other result than to render permanent peace impossible and
to keep alive a conflict of races the continuance of which must do
harm to all concerned. This question is not met by the suggestion
that social equality cannot exist between the white and black races
in this country. That argument, if it can be properly regarded as
one, is scarcely worthy of consideration, for social equality no
more exists between two races when traveling in a passenger coach
or a public highway than when members of the same races sit by each
other in a street car or in the jury box, or stand or sit with each
other in a political assembly, or when they use in common the
street of a city or town, or when they are in the same room for the
purpose of having their names placed on the registry of voters, or
when they approach the ballot box in order to exercise the high
privilege of voting.
There is a race so different from our own that we do not permit
those belonging to it to become citizens of the United States.
Persons belonging to it are, with few exceptions, absolutely
excluded from our country. I allude to the Chinese race. But, by
the statute in question, a Chinaman can ride in the same passenger
coach with white citizens of the United States, while citizens of
the black race in Louisiana, many of whom, perhaps, risked their
lives for the preservation of the Union, who are entitled, by law,
to participate in the political control of the State and nation,
who are not excluded, by law or by reason of their race, from
public stations of any kind, and who have all the legal rights that
belong to white citizens, are yet declared to be criminals, liable
to imprisonment, if they ride in a public coach occupied by
citizens of the white race. It is scarcely just to say that a
colored citizen should not object to occupying a public coach
assigned to his own race. He does not object, nor, perhaps, would
he object to separate coaches for his race if his rights under the
law were recognized. But he objecting, and ought never to cease
objecting, to the proposition that citizens of the white and black
race can be adjudged criminals because they sit, or claim the right
to sit, in the same public coach on a public highway. Page 163 U. S. 562 The arbitrary separation of citizens on the basis of race while
they are on a public highway is a badge of servitude wholly
inconsistent with the civil freedom and the equality before the law
established by the Constitution. It cannot be justified upon any
legal grounds.
If evils will result from the commingling of the two races upon
public highways established for the benefit of all, they will be
infinitely less than those that will surely come from state
legislation regulating the enjoyment of civil rights upon the basis
of race. We boast of the freedom enjoyed by our people above all
other peoples. But it is difficult to reconcile that boast with a
state of the law which, practically, puts the brand of servitude
and degradation upon a large class of our fellow citizens, our
equals before the law. The thin disguise of "equal" accommodations
for passengers in railroad coaches will not mislead anyone, nor
atone for the wrong this day done.
The result of the whole matter is that, while this court has
frequently adjudged, and at the present term has recognized the
doctrine, that a State cannot, consistently with the Constitution
of the United States, prevent white and black citizens, having the
required qualifications for jury service, from sitting in the same
jury box, it is now solemnly held that a State may prohibit white
and black citizens from sitting in the same passenger coach on a
public highway, or may require that they be separated by a
"partition," when in the same passenger coach. May it not now be
reasonably expected that astute men of the dominant race, who
affect to be disturbed at the possibility that the integrity of the
white race may be corrupted, or that its supremacy will be
imperiled, by contact on public highways with black people, will
endeavor to procure statutes requiring white and black jurors to be
separated in the jury box by a "partition," and that, upon retiring
from the courtroom to consult as to their verdict, such partition,
if it be a moveable one, shall be taken to their consultation room
and set up in such way as to prevent black jurors from coming too
close to their brother jurors of the white race. If the "partition"
used in the courtroom happens to be stationary, provision could be
made for screens with openings through Page 163 U. S. 563 which jurors of the two races could confer as to their verdict
without coming into personal contact with each other. I cannot see
but that, according to the principles this day announced, such
state legislation, although conceived in hostility to, and enacted
for the purpose of humiliating, citizens of the United States of a
particular race, would be held to be consistent with the
Constitution.
I do not deem it necessary to review the decisions of state
courts to which reference was made in argument. Some, and the most
important, of them are wholly inapplicable because rendered prior
to the adoption of the last amendments of the Constitution, when
colored people had very few rights which the dominant race felt
obliged to respect. Others were made at a time when public opinion
in many localities was dominated by the institution of slavery,
when it would not have been safe to do justice to the black man,
and when, so far as the rights of blacks were concerned, race
prejudice was, practically, the supreme law of the land. Those
decisions cannot be guides in the era introduced by the recent
amendments of the supreme law, which established universal civil
freedom, gave citizenship to all born or naturalized in the United
States and residing here, obliterated the race line from our
systems of governments, National and State, and placed our free
institutions upon the broad and sure foundation of the equality of
all men before the law.
I am of opinion that the statute of Louisiana is inconsistent
with the personal liberty of citizens, white and black, in that
State, and hostile to both the spirit and letter of the
Constitution of the United States. If laws of like character should
be enacted in the several States of the Union, the effect would be
in the highest degree mischievous. Slavery, as an institution
tolerated by law would, it is true, have disappeared from our
country, but there would remain a power in the States, by sinister
legislation, to interfere with the full enjoyment of the blessings
of freedom to regulate civil rights, common to all citizens, upon
the basis of race, and to place in a condition of legal inferiority
a large body of American citizens now constituting a part of the
political community called the Page 163 U. S. 564 People of the United States, for whom and by whom, through
representatives, our government is administered. Such a system is
inconsistent with the guarantee given by the Constitution to each
State of a republican form of government, and may be stricken down
by Congressional action, or by the courts in the discharge of their
solemn duty to maintain the supreme law of the land, anything in
the constitution or laws of any State to the contrary
notwithstanding.
For the reasons stated, I am constrained to withhold my assent
from the opinion and judgment of the majority.
MR. JUSTICE BREWER did not hear the argument or participate in
the decision of this case. | In the case of Plessy v. Ferguson, the Supreme Court of the United States upheld the constitutionality of racial segregation laws for public facilities, establishing the "separate but equal" doctrine that would persist for decades. Homer Plessy, a person of mixed race, challenged a Louisiana law requiring separate accommodations for white and non-white passengers on trains. The Court, in an infamous decision, ruled that such segregation did not violate the Thirteenth and Fourteenth Amendments as long as the separate facilities were equal in quality. This ruling entrenched racial segregation and legitimized the notion that racial inequality could be legally sanctioned. Dissenting opinions highlighted the inherent injustice and conflict of such laws with the Constitution's guarantee of equal rights and freedoms. |
Equal Protection | Skinner v. Oklahoma ex rel. Williamson | https://supreme.justia.com/cases/federal/us/316/535/ | U.S. Supreme Court Skinner v. Oklahoma ex rel.
Williamson, 316
U.S. 535 (1942) Skinner v. Oklahoma ex rel.
Williamson No. 782 Argued May 6, 1942 Decided June 1, 1942 316
U.S. 535 CERTIORARI TO THE SUPREME COURT OF
OKLAHOMA Syllabus 1. A statute of Oklahoma provides for the sterilization, by
vasectomy or salpingectomy, of "habitual criminals" -- an habitual
criminal being defined therein as any person who, having been
convicted two or more times, in Oklahoma or in any other State, of
"felonies involving moral turpitude," is thereafter convicted and
sentenced to imprisonment in Oklahoma for such a crime. Expressly
excepted from the terms of the statute are certain offenses,
including embezzlement. As applied to one who was convicted once of
stealing chickens and twice of robbery, held that the
statute violated the equal protection clause of the Fourteenth
Amendment. P. 316 U. S.
537 .
2. The State Supreme Court having sustained the Act, as applied
to the petitioner here, without reference to a severability clause,
the question whether that clause would be so applied as to remove
the particular constitutional objection is one which may
appropriately be left for adjudication by the state court. P. 316 U. S.
542 . 189 Okla. 235 , 115 P.2d 123 ,
reversed. Page 316 U. S. 536 CERTIORARI, 315 U.S. 789, to review the affirmance of a judgment
in a proceeding under the Oklahoma Habitual Criminal Sterilization
Act, wherein it was ordered that the defendant (petitioner here) be
made sterile.
MR. JUSTICE DOUGLAS delivered the opinion of the Court.
This case touches a sensitive and important area of human
rights. Oklahoma deprives certain individuals of a right which is
basic to the perpetuation of a race the right to have offspring.
Oklahoma has decreed the enforcement of its law against petitioner,
overruling his claim that it violated the Fourteenth Amendment.
Because that decision raised grave and substantial constitutional
questions, we granted the petition for certiorari.
The statute involved is Oklahoma's Habitual Criminal
Sterilization Act. Okla.Stat.Ann. Tit. 57, §§ 171, et
seq.; L.1935, pp. 94 et seq. That Act defines an
"habitual criminal" as a person who, having been convicted two or
more times for crimes "amounting to felonies involving moral
turpitude," either in an Oklahoma court or in a court of any other
State, is thereafter convicted of such a felony in Oklahoma and is
sentenced to a term of imprisonment in an Oklahoma penal
institution. § 173. Machinery is provided for the institution by
the Attorney General of a proceeding against such a person in the
Oklahoma courts for a judgment that such person shall be rendered
sexually sterile. §§ 176, 177. Notice, an opportunity to be heard,
and the right to a jury trial are provided. §§ 177-181. The issues
triable in such a proceeding are narrow and confined. Page 316 U. S. 537 If the court or jury finds that the defendant is an "habitual
criminal" and that he "may be rendered sexually sterile without
detriment to his or her general health," then the court "shall
render judgment to the effect that said defendant be rendered
sexually sterile" (§ 182) by the operation of vasectomy in case of
a male, and of salpingectomy in case of a female. § 174. Only one
other provision of the Act is material here, and that is § 195,
which provides that
"offenses arising out of the violation of the prohibitory laws,
revenue acts, embezzlement, or political offenses, shall not come
or be considered within the terms of this Act."
Petitioner was convicted in 1926 of the crime of stealing
chickens, and was sentenced to the Oklahoma State Reformatory. In
1929 he was convicted of the crime of robbery with firearms, and
was sentenced to the reformatory. In 1934, he was convicted again
of robbery with firearms, and was sentenced to the penitentiary. He
was confined there in 1935 when the Act was passed. In 1936, the
Attorney General instituted proceedings against him. Petitioner, in
his answer, challenged the Act as unconstitutional by reason of the
Fourteenth Amendment. A jury trial was had. The court instructed
the jury that the crimes of which petitioner had been convicted
were felonies involving moral turpitude, and that the only question
for the jury was whether the operation of vasectomy could be
performed on petitioner without detriment to his general health.
The jury found that it could be. A judgment directing that the
operation of vasectomy be performed on petitioner was affirmed by
the Supreme Court of Oklahoma by a five-to-four decision. 189 Okla. 235 , 115 P.2d
123 .
Several objections to the constitutionality of the Act have been
pressed upon us. It is urged that the Act cannot be sustained as an
exercise of the police power, in view Page 316 U. S. 538 of the state of scientific authorities respecting inheritability
of criminal traits. [ Footnote
1 ] It is argued that due process is lacking because, under this
Act, unlike the Act [ Footnote
2 ] upheld in Buck v. Bell, 274 U.
S. 200 , the defendant is given no opportunity to be
heard on the issue as to whether he is the probable potential
parent of socially undesirable offspring. See Davis v.
Berry, 216 F. 413; Williams v. Smith, 190 Ind. 526,
131 N.E. 2. It is also suggested that the Act is penal in
character, and that the sterilization provided for is cruel and
unusual punishment and violative of the Fourteenth Amendment. See Davis v. Berry, supra. Cf. State v. Felen, 70
Wash. 65, 126 P. 75; Mickle v. Henrichs, 262 F. 687. We
pass those points without intimating an opinion on them, for there
is a feature of the Act which clearly condemns it. That is its
failure to meet the requirements of the equal protection clause of
the Fourteenth Amendment.
We do not stop to point out all of the inequalities in this Act.
A few examples will suffice. In Oklahoma, grand larceny is a
felony. Okla.Stats.Ann. Tit. 21, §§ 1705, 5. Larceny is grand
larceny when the property taken exceeds $20 in value. Id., § 1704. Embezzlement is punishable "in the manner prescribed for
feloniously stealing property of the value of that embezzled." Id., § 1462. Hence, he who embezzles property worth more
than $20 is guilty of a felony. A clerk who appropriates over $20
from his employer's till ( id. § 1456) and a stranger who
steals the same Page 316 U. S. 539 amount are thus both guilty of felonies. If the latter repeats
his act and is convicted three times, he may be sterilized. But the
clerk is not subject to the pains and penalties of the Act no
matter how large his embezzlements nor how frequent his
convictions. A person who enters a chicken coop and steals chickens
commits a felony ( id., § 1719), and he may be sterilized
if he is thrice convicted. If, however, he is a bailee of the
property and fraudulently appropriates it, he is an embezzler. Id., § 1455. Hence, no matter how habitual his
proclivities for embezzlement are, and no matter how often his
conviction, he may not be sterilized. Thus, the nature of the two
crimes is intrinsically the same, and they are punishable in the
same manner. Furthermore, the line between them follows close
distinctions -- distinctions comparable to those highly technical
ones which shaped the common law as to "trespass" or "taking."
Bishop, Criminal Law (9th ed.) Vol. 2, §§ 760, 799, et
seq. There may be larceny by fraud, rather than embezzlement
even where the owner of the personal property delivers it to the
defendant, if the latter has, at that time, "a fraudulent intention
to make use of the possession as a means of converting such
property to his own use, and does so convert it." Bivens v.
State, 6 Okla.Cr. 521, 529, 120 P. 1033, 1036. If the
fraudulent intent occurs later, and the defendant converts the
property, he is guilty of embezzlement. Bivens v. State, supra;
Flohr v. Territory, 14 Okla. 477 ,
78 P. 565. Whether a particular act is larceny by fraud or
embezzlement thus turns not on the intrinsic quality of the act,
but on when the felonious intent arose -- a question for the jury
under appropriate instructions. Bivens v. State, supra; Riley
v. State, 64 Okla.Cr. 183, 78 P.2d
712 .
It was stated in Buck v. Bell, supra, that the claim
that state legislation violates the equal protection clause of the
Fourteenth Amendment is "the usual last resort of constitutional
arguments." 274 U.S. p. 274 U. S. 208 .
Under our constitutional Page 316 U. S. 540 system, the States, in determining the reach and scope of
particular legislation, need not provide "abstract symmetry." Patsone v. Pennsylvania, 232 U. S. 138 , 232 U. S. 144 .
They may mark and set apart the classes and types of problems
according to the needs and as dictated or suggested by experience. See Bryant v. Zimmerman, 278 U. S. 63 , and
cases cited. It was in that connection that Mr. Justice Holmes,
speaking for the Court in Bain Peanut Co. v. Pinson, 282 U. S. 499 , 282 U. S. 501 ,
stated, "We must remember that the machinery of government would
not work if it were not allowed a little play in its joints." Only
recently, we reaffirmed the view that the equal protection clause
does not prevent the legislature from recognizing "degrees of evil"
( Truax v. Raich, 239 U. S. 33 , 239 U. S. 43 ) by
our ruling in Tigner v. Texas, 310 U.
S. 141 , 310 U. S. 147 ,
that "the Constitution does not require things which are different,
in fact, or opinion to be treated in law as though they were the
same." And see Nashville, C. & St.L. Ry. v. Browning, 310 U. S. 362 .
Thus, if we had here only a question as to a State's classification
of crimes, such as embezzlement or larceny, no substantial federal
question would be raised. See Moore v. Missouri, 159 U. S. 673 ; Hawker v. New York, 170 U. S. 189 ; Finley v. California, 222 U. S. 28 ; Patsone v. Pennsylvania, supra. For a State is not
constrained in the exercise of its police power to ignore
experience which marks a class of offenders or a family of offenses
for special treatment. Nor is it prevented by the equal protection
clause from confining "its restrictions to those classes of cases
where the need is deemed to be clearest." Miller v.
Wilson, 236 U. S. 373 , 236 U. S. 384 . And see McLean v. Arkansas, 211 U.
S. 539 . As stated in Buck v. Bell, supra, p. 274 U. S. 208 ,
". . . the law does all that is needed when it does all that it
can, indicates a policy, applies it to all within the lines, and
seeks to bring within the lines all similarly situated so far and
so fast as its means allow. " Page 316 U. S. 541 But the instant legislation runs afoul of the equal protection
clause, though we give Oklahoma that large deference which the rule
of the foregoing cases requires. We are dealing here with
legislation which involves one of the basic civil rights of man.
Marriage and procreation are fundamental to the very existence and
survival of the race. The power to sterilize, if exercised, may
have subtle, far-reaching and devastating effects. In evil or
reckless hands, it can cause races or types which are inimical to
the dominant group to wither and disappear. There is no redemption
for the individual whom the law touches. Any experiment which the
State conducts is to his irreparable injury. He is forever deprived
of a basic liberty. We mention these matters not to reexamine the
scope of the police power of the States. We advert to them merely
in emphasis of our view that strict scrutiny of the classification
which a State makes in a sterilization law is essential, lest
unwittingly, or otherwise, invidious discriminations are made
against groups or types of individuals in violation of the
constitutional guaranty of just and equal laws. The guaranty of
"equal protection of the laws is a pledge of the protection of
equal laws." Yick Wo v. Hopkins, 118 U.
S. 356 , 118 U. S. 369 .
When the law lays an unequal hand on those who have committed
intrinsically the same quality of offense and sterilizes one and
not the other, it has made as invidious a discrimination as if it
had selected a particular race or nationality for oppressive
treatment. Yick Wo v. Hopkins, supra; Gaines v. Canada, 305 U. S. 337 .
Sterilization of those who have thrice committed grand larceny,
with immunity for those who are embezzlers, is a clear, pointed,
unmistakable discrimination. Oklahoma makes no attempt to say that
he who commits larceny by trespass or trick or fraud has
biologically inheritable traits which he who commits embezzlement
lacks. Oklahoma's line between larceny by fraud and embezzlement is
determined, as we have noted, "with reference to the time when
the Page 316 U. S. 542 fraudulent intent to convert the property to the taker's own
use" arises. Riley v. State, supra, 64 Okla.Cr. at p. 189,
78 P.2d p. 715. We have not the slightest basis for inferring that
that line has any significance in eugenics, nor that the
inheritability of criminal traits follows the neat legal
distinctions which the law has marked between those two offenses.
In terms of fines and imprisonment, the crimes of larceny and
embezzlement rate the same under the Oklahoma code. Only when it
comes to sterilization are the pains and penalties of the law
different. The equal protection clause would indeed be a formula of
empty words if such conspicuously artificial lines could be drawn. See Smith v. Wayne Probate Judge, 231 Mich. 409, 420-421,
204 N.W. 40. In Buck v. Bell, supra, the Virginia statute
was upheld though it applied only to feeble-minded persons in
institutions of the State. But it was pointed out that,
"so far as the operations enable those who otherwise must be
kept confined to be returned to the world, and thus open the asylum
to others, the equality aimed at will be more nearly reached."
274 U.S. p. 274 U. S. 208 .
Here there is no such saving feature. Embezzlers are forever free.
Those who steal or take in other ways are not. If such a
classification were permitted, the technical common law concept of
a "trespass" (Bishop, Criminal Law, 9th ed., vol. 1, §§ 566, 567)
based on distinctions which are "very largely dependent upon
history for explanation" (Holmes, The Common Law, p. 73) could
readily become a rule of human genetics.
It is true that the Act has a broad severability clause.
[ Footnote 3 ] But we will not
endeavor to determine whether its application Page 316 U. S. 543 would solve the equal protection difficulty. The Supreme Court
of Oklahoma sustained the Act without reference to the severability
clause. We have therefore a situation where the Act, as construed
and applied to petitioner, is allowed to perpetuate the
discrimination which we have found to be fatal. Whether the
severability clause would be so applied as to remove this
particular constitutional objection is a question which may be more
appropriately left for adjudication by the Oklahoma court. Dorchy v. Kansas, 264 U. S. 286 .
That is reemphasized here by our uncertainty as to what excision,
if any, would be made as a matter of Oklahoma law. Cf. Smith v.
Cahoon, 283 U. S. 553 . It
is by no means clear whether, if an excision were made, this
particular constitutional difficulty might be solved by enlarging,
on the one hand, or contracting, on the other ( cf. Mr.
Justice Brandeis dissenting, National Life Ins. Co. v. United
States, 277 U. S. 508 , 277 U. S.
534 -535) the class of criminals who might be
sterilized. Reversed. [ Footnote 1 ]
Healy, The Individual Delinquent (1915), pp. 188-200;
Sutherland, Criminology (1924), pp. 112-118, 621-622; Gillin,
Criminology and Penology (1926), c. IX; Popenoe, Sterilization and
Criminality, 53 Rep.Am.Bar Assoc. 575; Myerson et al., Eugenical Sterilization (1936), c. VIII; Landman, Human
Sterilization (1932), c. IX; Summary of the Report of the American
Neurological Association Committee for the Investigation of
Sterilization, 1 Am.Journ.Med.Jur. 253 (1938).
[ Footnote 2 ] And see State v. Troutman, 50 Ida. 673, 299 P. 668;
Chamberlain, Eugenics in Legislatures and Courts, 15 Am.Bar
Assn.Journ. 165; Castle, The Law and Human Sterilization, 53
Rep.Am.Bar Assoc., 556, 572; 2 Bill of Rights Review 54.
[ Footnote 3 ]
Sec.194 provides:
"If any section, subsection, paragraph, sentence, clause or
phrase of this Act shall be declared unconstitutional, or void for
any other reason by any court of final jurisdiction, such fact
shall not in any manner invalidate or affect any other or the
remaining portions of this Act, but the same shall continue in full
force and effect. The Legislature hereby declares that it would
have passed this Act, and each section, subsection, paragraph,
sentence, clause or phrase thereof, irrespective of the fact that
any one or more other sections, sub-sections, paragraphs,
sentences, clauses or phrases be declared unconstitutional."
MR. CHIEF JUSTICE STONE, concurring:
I concur in the result, but I am not persuaded that we are aided
in reaching it by recourse to the equal protection clause.
If Oklahoma may resort generally to the sterilization of
criminals on the assumption that their propensities are
transmissible to future generations by inheritance, I seriously
doubt that the equal protection clause requires it to apply the
measure to all criminals in the first instance, or to none. See
Rosenthal v. New York, 226 U. S. 260 , 226 U. S.
271 ; Page 316 U. S. 544 Keokee Coke Co. v. Taylor, 234 U.
S. 224 , 234 U. S. 227 ; Patsone v. Pennsylvania, 232 U. S. 138 , 232 U. S.
144 .
Moreover, if we must presume that the legislature knows -- what
science has been unable to ascertain -- that the criminal
tendencies of any class of habitual offenders are transmissible
regardless of the varying mental characteristics of its
individuals, I should suppose that we must likewise presume that
the legislature, in its wisdom, knows that the criminal tendencies
of some classes of offenders are more likely to be transmitted than
those of others. And so I think the real question we have to
consider is not one of equal protection, but whether the wholesale
condemnation of a class to such an invasion of personal liberty,
without opportunity to any individual to show that his is not the
type of case which would justify resort to it, satisfies the
demands of due process.
There are limits to the extent to which the presumption of
constitutionality can be pressed, especially where the liberty of
the person is concerned ( see United States v. Carolene Products
Co., 304 U. S. 144 , 304 U. S. 152 ,
n. 4) and where the presumption is resorted to only to dispense
with a procedure which the ordinary dictates of prudence would seem
to demand for the protection of the individual from arbitrary
action. Although petitioner here was given a hearing to ascertain
whether sterilization would be detrimental to his health, he was
given none to discover whether his criminal tendencies are of an
inheritable type. Undoubtedly, a state may, after appropriate
inquiry, constitutionally interfere with the personal liberty of
the individual to prevent the transmission by inheritance of his
socially injurious tendencies. Buck v. Bell, 274 U.
S. 200 . But, until now, we have not been called upon to
say that it may do so without giving him a hearing and opportunity
to challenge the existence as to him of the only facts which could
justify so drastic a measure. Page 316 U. S. 545 Science has found, and the law has recognized, that there are
certain types of mental deficiency associated with delinquency
which are inheritable. But the State does not contend -- nor can
there be any pretense -- that either common knowledge or
experience, or scientific investigation, * has given
assurance that the criminal tendencies of any class of habitual
offenders are universally, or even generally, inheritable. In such
circumstances, inquiry whether such is the fact in the case of any
particular individual cannot rightly be dispensed with. Whether the
procedure by which a statute carries its mandate into execution
satisfies due process is a matter of judicial cognizance. A law
which condemns, without hearing, all the individuals of a class to
so harsh a measure as the present because some or even many merit
condemnation is lacking in the first principles of due process. Morrison v. California, 291 U. S. 82 , 291 U. S. 90 ,
and cases cited; Taylor v. Georgia, 315 U. S.
25 . And so, while the state may protect itself from the
demonstrably inheritable tendencies of the individual which are
injurious to society, the most elementary notions of due process
would seem to require it to take appropriate steps to safeguard the
liberty of the individual by affording him, before he is condemned
to an irreparable injury in his person, some opportunity to show
that he is without such inheritable tendencies. The state is called
on to sacrifice no permissible end when it is required to reach its
objective by a reasonable and just procedure adequate to safeguard
rights of the individual which concededly the Constitution
protects. Page 316 U. S. 546 * See Eugenical Sterilization, A Report of the
Committee of the American Neurological Association (1936),
pp.150-52; Myerson, Summary of the Report, 1 American Journal of
Medical Jurisprudence 253; Popenoe, Sterilization and Criminality,
53 American Bar Assn. Reports 575; Jennings, Eugenics, 5
Encyclopedia of the Social Sciences 617, 6221; Montagu, The
Biologist Looks at Crime, 217 Annals of American Academy of
Political and Social Science 46.
MR JUSTICE JACKSON concurring:
I join the CHIEF JUSTICE in holding that the hearings provided
are too limited in the context of the present Act to afford due
process of law. I also agree with the opinion of MR. JUSTICE
DOUGLAS that the scheme of classification set forth in the Act
denies equal protection of the law. I disagree with the opinion of
each insofar as it rejects or minimizes the grounds taken by the
other.
Perhaps to employ a broad and loose scheme of classification
would be permissible if accompanied by the individual hearings
indicated by the CHIEF JUSTICE. On the other hand, narrow
classification with reference to the end to be accomplished by the
Act might justify limiting individual hearings to the issue whether
the individual belonged to a class so defined. Since this Act does
not present these questions, I reserve judgment on them.
I also think the present plan to sterilize the individual in
pursuit of a eugenic plan to eliminate from the race
characteristics that are only vaguely identified and which, in our
present state of knowledge, are uncertain as to transmissibility
presents other constitutional questions of gravity. This Court has
sustained such an experiment with respect to an imbecile, a person
with definite and observable characteristics, where the condition
had persisted through three generations and afforded grounds for
the belief that it was transmissible, and would continue to
manifest itself in generations to come. Buck v. Bell, 274 U. S. 200 .
There are limits to the extent to which a legislatively
represented majority may conduct biological experiments at the
expense of the dignity and personality and natural powers of a
minority -- even those who have been guilty of what the majority
define as crimes. But this Act falls down before reaching this
problem, which I mention only to Page 316 U. S. 547 avoid the implication that such a question may not exist because
not discussed. On it, I would also reserve judgment. | In Skinner v. Oklahoma, the U.S. Supreme Court ruled that an Oklahoma law allowing for the sterilization of "habitual criminals" violated the Equal Protection Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment. The Court held that the right to have offspring is fundamental, and the law's classification scheme was not sufficiently narrow to justify such an infringement on individual liberty. The Court also raised concerns about the due process protections afforded by the law's hearing procedures. |
Equal Protection | McLaurin v. Oklahoma State Regents | https://supreme.justia.com/cases/federal/us/339/637/ | U.S. Supreme Court McLaurin v. Oklahoma State Regents, 339
U.S. 637 (1950) McLaurin v. Oklahoma State Regents
for Higher Education No. 34 Argued April 3-4,
1950 Decided June 5, 1950 339
U.S. 637 APPEAL FROM THE UNITED STATES
DISTRICT COURT FOR THE WESTERN DISTRICT OF
OKLAHOMA Syllabus Appellant, a Negro citizen of Oklahoma possessing a master's
degree, was admitted to the Graduate School of the state supported
University of Oklahoma as a candidate for a doctorate in education
and was permitted to use the same classroom, library and cafeteria
as white students. Pursuant to a requirement of state law that the
instruction of Negroes in institutions of higher education be "upon
a segregated basis," however, he was assigned to a seat in the
classroom in a row specified for Negro students, was assigned to a
special table in the library, and, although permitted to eat in the
cafeteria at the same time as other students, was assigned to a
special table there. Held: the conditions under which appellant is required
to receive his education deprive him of his personal and present
right to the equal protection of the laws, and the Fourteenth
Amendment precludes such differences in treatment by the State
based upon race. Pp. 339 U. S.
638 -642.
(a) The restrictions imposed upon appellant impair and inhibit
his ability to study, to engage in discussions and exchange views
with other students, and, in general, to learn his profession. Pp. 339 U. S.
640 -641.
(b) That appellant may still be set apart by his fellow students
and may be in no better position when these restrictions are
removed is irrelevant, for there is a constitutional difference
between restrictions imposed by the State which prohibit the
intellectual commingling of students and the refusal of students to
commingle where the State presents no such bar. P. 339 U. S.
641 .
(c) Having been admitted to a state supported graduate school,
appellant must receive the same treatment at the hands of the State
as students of other races. P. 339 U. S.
642 . 87 F.
Supp. 528 reversed.
The proceedings below are stated in the opinion. The judgment
below is reversed, p. 339 U. S.
642 . Page 339 U. S. 638 MR. CHIEF JUSTICE VINSON delivered the opinion of the Court.
In this case, we are faced with the question whether a state
may, after admitting a student to graduate instruction in its state
university, afford him different treatment from other students
solely because of his race. We decide only this issue; see
Sweatt v. Painter, ante, p. 339 U. S. 629 .
Appellant is a Negro citizen of Oklahoma. Possessing a Master's
degree, he applied for admission to the University of Oklahoma in
order to pursue studies and courses leading to a Doctorate in
Education. At that time, his application was denied, solely because
of his race. The school authorities were required to exclude him by
the Oklahoma statutes, 70 Okl.Stat. (1941) §§ 455, 456, 457, which
made it a misdemeanor to maintain or operate, teach or attend a
school at which both whites and Negroes are enrolled or taught.
Appellant filed a complaint requesting injunctive relief, alleging
that the action of the school authorities and the statutes upon
which their action was based were unconstitutional and deprived
him Page 339 U. S. 639 of the equal protection of the laws. Citing our decisions in Missouri ex rel. Gaines v. Canada, 305 U.
S. 337 (1938), and Sipuel v. Board of Regents, 332 U. S. 631 (1948), a statutory three-judge District Court held, 87 F. Supp.
526 , that the State had a constitutional duty to provide him
with the education he sought as soon as it provided that education
for applicants of any other group. It further held that, to the
extent the Oklahoma statutes denied him admission, they were
unconstitutional and void. On the assumption, however, that the
State would follow the constitutional mandate, the court refused to
grant the injunction, retaining jurisdiction of the cause with full
power to issue any necessary and proper orders to secure McLaurin
the equal protection of the laws.
Following this decision, the Oklahoma legislature amended these
statutes to permit the admission of Negroes to institutions of
higher learning attended by white students, in cases where such
institutions offered courses not available in the Negro schools.
The amendment provided, however, that, in such cases the program of
instruction "shall be given at such colleges or institutions of
higher education upon a segregated basis." * Appellant Page 339 U. S. 640 was thereupon admitted to the University of Oklahoma Graduate
School. In apparent conformity with the amendment, his admission
was made subject to
"such rules and regulations as to segregation as the President
of the University shall consider to afford Mr. G. W. McLaurin
substantially equal educational opportunities as are afforded to
other persons seeking the same education in the Graduate
College,"
a condition which does not appear to have been withdrawn. Thus,
he was required to sit apart at a designated desk in an anteroom
adjoining the classroom; to sit at a designated desk on the
mezzanine floor of the library, but not to use the desks in the
regular reading room, and to sit at a designated table and to eat
at a different time from the other students in the school
cafeteria.
To remove these conditions, appellant filed a motion to modify
the order and judgment of the District Court. That court held that
such treatment did not violate the provisions of the Fourteenth
Amendment, and denied the motion. 87 F.
Supp. 528 . This appeal followed.
In the interval between the decision of the court below and the
hearing in this Court, the treatment afforded appellant was
altered. For some time, the section of the classroom in which
appellant sat was surrounded by a rail on which there was a sign
stating, "Reserved For Colored," but these have been removed. He is
now assigned to a seat in the classroom in a row specified for
colored students; he is assigned to a table in the library on the
main floor, and he is permitted to eat at the same time in the
cafeteria as other students, although here again he is assigned to
a special table.
It is said that the separations imposed by the State in this
case are in form merely nominal. McLaurin uses the same classroom,
library, and cafeteria as students of other races; there is no
indication that the seats to which he is assigned in these rooms
have any disadvantage Page 339 U. S. 641 of location. He may wait in line in the cafeteria and there
stand and talk with his fellow students, but, while he eats, he
must remain apart.
These restrictions were obviously imposed in order to comply, as
nearly as could be, with the statutory requirements of Oklahoma.
But they signify that the State, in administering the facilities it
affords for professional and graduate study, sets McLaurin apart
from the other students. The result is that appellant is
handicapped in his pursuit of effective graduate instruction. Such
restrictions impair and inhibit his ability to study, to engage in
discussions and exchange views with other students, and, in
general, to learn his profession.
Our society grows increasingly complex, and our need for trained
leaders increases correspondingly. Appellant's case represents
perhaps the epitome of that need, for he is attempting to obtain an
advanced degree in education, to become, by definition, a leader
and trainer of others. Those who will come under his guidance and
influence must be directly affected by the education he receives.
Their own education and development will necessarily suffer to the
extent that his training is unequal to that of his classmates.
State-imposed restrictions which produce such inequalities cannot
be sustained.
It may be argued that appellant will be in no better position
when these restrictions are removed, for he may still be set apart
by his fellow students. This we think irrelevant. There is a vast
difference -- a Constitutional difference -- between restrictions
imposed by the state which prohibit the intellectual commingling of
students and the refusal of individuals to commingle where the
state presents no such bar. Shelley v. Kraemer, 334 U. S. 1 , 334 U. S. 13 -14
(1948). The removal of the state restrictions will not necessarily
abate individual and group predilections, prejudices, and choices.
But, at the very least, the state will not be depriving appellant
of the opportunity Page 339 U. S. 642 to secure acceptance by his fellow students on his own
merits.
We conclude that the conditions under which this appellant is
required to receive his education deprive him of his personal and
present right to the equal protection of the laws. See Sweatt
v. Painter, ante, p. 339 U. S. 629 . We
hold that, under these circumstances, the Fourteenth Amendment
precludes differences in treatment by the state based upon race.
Appellant, having been admitted to a state-supported graduate
school, must receive the same treatment at the hands of the state
as students of other races. The judgment is Reversed. * The amendment adds the following proviso to each of the
sections relating to mixed schools:
"Provided, that the provisions of this Section shall not apply
to programs of instruction leading to a particular degree given at
State owned or operated colleges or institutions of higher
education of this State established for and/or used by the white
race where such programs of instruction leading to a particular
degree are not given at colleges or institutions of higher
education of this State established for and/or used by the colored
race; provided further, that said programs of instruction leading
to a particular degree shall be given at such colleges or
institutions of higher education upon a segregated basis."
70 Okla.Stat.Ann. (1950) §§ 455, 456, 457. Segregated basis is
defined as "classroom instruction given in separate classrooms, or
at separate times." Id., § 455. | In *McLaurin v. Oklahoma State Regents* (1950), the Supreme Court ruled that a state-supported university could not impose racial segregation on a black student, as it violated the Fourteenth Amendment's guarantee of equal protection under the law. The Court held that the conditions, such as separate seating in classrooms and libraries, impaired the student's ability to learn and engage with peers. The state must provide equal treatment regardless of individual or group prejudices. |
Equal Protection | Sipuel v. Board of Regents of the University of Oklahoma | https://supreme.justia.com/cases/federal/us/332/631/ | U.S. Supreme Court Sipuel v. Board of Regents, 332
U.S. 631 (1948) Sipuel v. Board of Regents of the
University of Oklahoma No. 369 Argued January 7-8,
1948 Decided January 12,
1948 332
U.S. 631 CERTIORARI TO THE SUPREME COURT OF
OKLAHOMA Syllabus A Negro, concededly qualified to receive professional legal
education offered by a State, cannot be denied such education
because of her color. The State must provide such education for her
in conformity with the equal protection clause of the Fourteenth
Amendment, and provide it as soon as it does for applicants of any
other group. Pp. 332 U. S.
632 -633. 199 Okla. 36 , 180 P.2d 135 ,
reversed.
The Supreme Court of Oklahoma affirmed a denial by an inferior
state court of a writ of mandamus to require Page 332 U. S. 632 admission of a qualified Negro applicant to a state law school. 199 Okla. 36 , 180 P.2d 135 .
This Court granted certiorari. 332 U.S. 814. Reversed, p. 332 U. S. 633 .
PER CURIAM.
On January 14, 1946, the petitioner, a Negro, concededly
qualified to receive the professional legal education offered by
the State, applied for admission to the School of Law of the
University of Oklahoma, the only institution for legal education
supported and maintained by the taxpayers of the Oklahoma.
Petitioner's application for admission was denied solely because of
her color.
Petitioner then made application for a writ of mandamus in the
District Court of Cleveland County, Oklahoma. The writ of mandamus
was refused, and the Supreme Court of the Oklahoma affirmed the
judgment of the District Court. 180 P.2d 135 .
We brought the case here for review.
The petitioner is entitled to secure legal education afforded by
a state institution. To this time, it has been denied her although,
during the same period, many Page 332 U. S. 633 white applicants have been afforded legal education by the
State. The State must provide it for her in conformity with the
equal protection clause of the Fourteenth Amendment, and provide it
as soon as it does for applicants of any other group. Missouri
ex rel. Gaines v. Canada, 305 U. S. 337 .
The judgment of the Supreme Court of Oklahoma is reversed, and
the cause is remanded to that court for proceedings not
inconsistent with this opinion.
The mandate shall issue forthwith. Reversed. | In *Sipuel v. Board of Regents of the University of Oklahoma* (1948), the U.S. Supreme Court ruled that a qualified applicant cannot be denied admission to a state law school solely based on their race, as per the Fourteenth Amendment's Equal Protection Clause. The Court ordered the state to provide legal education to the applicant, a Negro, as soon as it would for applicants of any other race, reversing the Oklahoma Supreme Court's decision. |
Equal Protection | Bolling v. Sharpe | https://supreme.justia.com/cases/federal/us/347/497/ | U.S. Supreme Court Bolling v. Sharpe, 347
U.S. 497 (1954) Bolling v. Sharpe No. 8 Argued December 10-11,
1952 Reargued December 9,
1953 Decided May 17, 1954 347
U.S. 497 CERTIORARI TO THE UNITED STATES
COURT OF APPEALS FOR THE DISTRICT OF COLUMBIA
CIRCUIT Syllabus Racial segregation in the public schools of the District of
Columbia is a denial to Negro children of the due process of law
guaranteed by the Fifth Amendment. Pp. 347 U. S.
498 -500.
(a) Though the Fifth Amendment does not contain an equal
protection clause, as does the Fourteenth Amendment, which applies
only to the States, the concepts of equal protection and due
process are not mutually exclusive. P. 347 U. S.
499 .
(b) Discrimination may be so unjustifiable as to be violative of
due process. P. 347 U. S.
499 .
(c) Segregation in public education is not reasonably related to
any proper governmental objective, and thus it imposes on Negro
children of the District of Columbia a burden that constitutes an
arbitrary deprivation of their liberty in violation of the Due
Process Clause. Pp. 347 U. S.
499 -500.
(d) In view of this Court's decision in Brown v. Board of
Education, ante, p. 347 U. S. 483 ,
that the Constitution prohibits the States from maintaining
racially segregated public schools, it would be unthinkable that
the same Constitution would impose a lesser duty on the Federal
Government. P. 347 U. S.
500 .
(e) The case is restored to the docket for further argument on
specified questions relating to the form of the decree. P. 347 U. S.
500 . Page 347 U. S. 498 MR. CHIEF JUSTICE WARREN delivered the opinion of the Court.
This case challenges the validity of segregation in the public
schools of the District of Columbia. The petitioners, minors of the
Negro race, allege that such segregation deprives them of due
process of law under the Fifth Amendment. They were refused
admission to a public school attended by white children solely
because of their race. They sought the aid of the District Court
for the District of Columbia in obtaining admission. That court
dismissed their complaint. The Court granted a writ of certiorari
before judgment in the Court of Appeals because of the importance
of the constitutional question presented. 344 U.S. 873.
We have this day held that the Equal Protection Clause of the
Fourteenth Amendment prohibits the states from maintaining racially
segregated public schools. [ Footnote 1 ] The legal problem in the District of Columbia
is somewhat Page 347 U. S. 499 different, however. The Fifth Amendment, which is applicable in
the District of Columbia, does not contain an equal protection
clause, as does the Fourteenth Amendment, which applies only to the
states. But the concepts of equal protection and due process, both
stemming from our American ideal of fairness, are not mutually
exclusive. The "equal protection of the laws" is a more explicit
safeguard of prohibited unfairness than "due process of law," and
therefore we do not imply that the two are always interchangeable
phrases. But, as this Court has recognized, discrimination may be
so unjustifiable as to be violative of due process. [ Footnote 2 ]
Classifications based solely upon race must be scrutinized with
particular care, since they are contrary to our traditions, and
hence constitutionally suspect. [ Footnote 3 ] As long ago as 1896, this Court declared the
principle
"that the constitution of the United States, in its present
form, forbids, so far as civil and political rights are concerned,
discrimination by the general government, or by the states, against
any citizen because of his race. [ Footnote 4 ]"
And in Buchanan v. Warley, 245 U. S.
60 , the Court held that a statute which limited the
right of a property owner to convey his property to a person of
another race was, as an unreasonable discrimination, a denial of
due process of law.
Although the Court has not assumed to define "liberty" with any
great precision, that term is not confined to mere freedom from
bodily restraint. Liberty under law extends to the full range of
conduct which the individual is free to pursue, and it cannot be
restricted except for a Page 347 U. S. 500 proper governmental objective. Segregation in public education
is not reasonably related to any proper governmental objective, and
thus it imposes on Negro children of the District of Columbia a
burden that constitutes an arbitrary deprivation of their liberty
in violation of the Due Process Clause.
In view of our decision that the Constitution prohibits the
states from maintaining racially segregated public schools, it
would be unthinkable that the same Constitution would impose a
lesser duty on the Federal Government. [ Footnote 5 ] We hold that racial segregation in the public
schools of the District of Columbia is a denial of the due process
of law guaranteed by the Fifth Amendment to the Constitution.
For the reasons set out in Brown v. Board of Education, this case will be restored to the docket for reargument on
Questions 4 and 5 previously propounded by the Court. 345 U.S.
972. It is so ordered. [ Footnote 1 ] Brown v. Board of Education, ante, p. 347 U. S. 483 .
[ Footnote 2 ] Detroit Bank v. United States, 317 U.
S. 329 ; Currin v. Wallace, 306 U. S.
1 , 306 U. S. 13 -14; Steward Machine Co. v. Davis, 301 U.
S. 548 , 301 U. S.
585 .
[ Footnote 3 ] Korematsu v. United States, 323 U.
S. 214 , 323 U. S. 216 ; Hirabayashi v. United States, 320 U. S.
81 , 320 U. S.
100 .
[ Footnote 4 ] Gibson v. Mississippi, 162 U.
S. 565 , 162 U. S. 591 . Cf. Steele v. Louisville & Nashville R. Co., 323 U. S. 192 , 323 U. S.
198 -199.
[ Footnote 5 ] Cf. Hurd v. Hodge, 334 U. S. 24 . | In Bolling v. Sharpe, the U.S. Supreme Court ruled that racial segregation in public schools within the District of Columbia violated the due process clause of the Fifth Amendment. While the Fifth Amendment does not contain an equal protection clause like the Fourteenth Amendment, the Court argued that the concepts of equal protection and due process are linked and that discrimination can violate due process. The Court emphasized that classifications based solely on race are constitutionally suspect and that segregation in public education is not justifiable by any proper governmental objective. This decision extended the principles established in Brown v. Board of Education, which prohibited racial segregation in state schools, to the federal level. |
Equal Protection | Railway Express Agency, Inc. v. New York | https://supreme.justia.com/cases/federal/us/336/106/ | U.S. Supreme Court Railway Express Agency, Inc. v. New
York, 336
U.S. 106 (1949) Railway Express Agency, Inc. v. New
York No. 51 Argued December 6,
1948 Decided January 31,
1949 336
U.S. 106 APPEAL FROM THE COURT OF APPEALS OF
NEW YORK Syllabus A New York City traffic regulation forbids the operation of any
advertising vehicle on the streets, but excepts vehicles which have
upon them business notices or advertisements of the products of the
owner and which are not used merely or mainly for advertising. An
express company, which sold space on the exterior sides of its
trucks for advertising and which operated such trucks on the
streets, was convicted and fined for violating the ordinance. Upon
review here of the state court judgment, held: 1. The regulation does not violate the due process clause of the
Fourteenth Amendment. Pp. 336 U. S.
108 -109.
(a) The function of this Court upon such review is not to weigh
evidence on the due process issue in order to determine whether the
regulation is sound or appropriate, nor to pass judgment on the
wisdom of the regulation. P. 336 U. S.
109 .
(b) This Court can not say that the regulation has no relation
to the trnffic problem of the City. P. 109.
2. The exemption of vehicles having upon them advertisements of
products sold by the owner does not render the regulation a denial
of the equal protection of the laws. Pp. 336 U. S.
109 -110. Page 336 U. S. 107 (a) This Court can not say that the advertising which is
forbidden has less incidence on traffic than that which is
exempted. P. 336 U. S.
110 .
(b) The regulation is not rendered invalid by the fact that it
does not extend to what may be even greater distractions affecting
traffic safety, such as the spectacular displays at Times Square.
P. 336 U. S.
110 .
3. The regulation does not burden interstate commerce in
violation of Art. I, § 8 of the Federal Constitution. P. 336 U. S.
111 .
(a) Where traffic control and the use of highways are involved,
and where there is no conflicting federal regulation, great leeway
is allowed local authorities, even though the local regulation
materially interferes with interstate commerce. P. 336 U. S.
111 .
297 N.Y. 703, 77 N.E.2d 13, affirmed.
Appellant was convicted and fined for violation of a traffic
regulation of the City of New York. The conviction was sustained by
the Court of Special Sessions. 188 Misc. 342, 67 N.Y.S.2d 732. The
Court of Appeals affirmed. 297 N Y. 703, 77 N.E.2d 13. On appeal to
this Court, affirmed, p. 336 U. S.
111 .
MR. JUSTICE DOUGLAS delivered the opinion of the Court.
Section 124 of the Traffic Regulations of the City of New York
[ Footnote 1 ] promulgated by the
Police Commissioner provides:
"No person shall operate, or cause to be operated, in or upon
any street an advertising vehicle; provided Page 336 U. S. 108 that nothing herein contained shall prevent the putting of
business notices upon business delivery vehicles, so long as such
vehicles are engaged in the usual business or regular work of the
owner, and not used merely or mainly for advertising."
Appellant is engaged in a nationwide express business. It
operates about 1,900 trucks in New York City, and sells the space
on the exterior sides of these trucks for advertising. That
advertising is, for the most part, unconnected with its own
business. [ Footnote 2 ] It was
convicted in the magistrates court and fined. The judgment of
conviction was sustained in the Court of Special Sessions. 188
Misc. 342, 67 N.Y.S.2d 732. The Court of Appeals affirmed without
opinion by a divided vote. 297 N.Y. 703, 77 N.E.2d 13. The case is
here on appeal. Judicial Code § 237(a), 28 U.S.C. § 344(a), as
amended, now 28 U.S.C. § 1257.
The Court, in Fifth Ave. Coach Co. v. New York, 221 U. S. 467 ,
sustained the predecessor ordinance to the present regulation over
the objection that it violated the due process and equal protection
clauses of the Fourteenth Amendment. It is true that that was a
municipal Page 336 U. S. 109 ordinance resting on the broad base of the police power, while
the present regulation stands or falls merely as a traffic
regulation. But we do not believe that distinction warrants a
different result in the two cases.
The Court of Special Sessions concluded that advertising on
vehicles using the streets of New York City constitutes a
distraction to vehicle drivers and to pedestrians alike, and
therefore affects the safety of the public in the use of the
streets. [ Footnote 3 ] We do not
sit to weigh evidence on the due process issue in order to
determine whether the regulation is sound or appropriate; nor is it
our function to pass judgment on its wisdom. See Olsen v.
Nebraska, 313 U. S. 236 . We
would be trespassing on one of the most intensely local and
specialized of all municipal problems if we held that this
regulation had no relation to the traffic problem of New York City.
It is the judgment of the local authorities that it does have such
a relation. And nothing has been advanced which shows that to be
palpably false.
The question of equal protection of the laws is pressed more
strenuously on us. It is pointed out that the regulation draws the
line between advertisements of products sold by the owner of the
truck and general advertisements. It is argued that unequal
treatment on the basis of such a distinction is not justified by
the aim and purpose of the regulation. It is said, for example,
that one of appellant's trucks carrying the advertisement of a
commercial house would not cause any greater distraction of
pedestrians and vehicle drivers than if the Page 336 U. S. 110 commercial house carried the same advertisement on its own
truck. Yet the regulation allows the latter to do what the former
is forbidden from doing. It is therefore contended that the
classification which the regulation makes has no relation to the
traffic problem, since a violation turns not on what kind of
advertisements are carried on trucks, but on whose trucks they are
carried.
That, however, is a superficial way of analyzing the problem,
even if we assume that it is premised on the correct construction
of the regulation. The local authorities may well have concluded
that those who advertised their own wares on their trucks do not
present the same traffic problem in view of the nature or extent of
the advertising which they use. It would take a degree of
omniscience which we lack to say that such is not the case. If that
judgment is correct, the advertising displays that are exempt have
less incidence on traffic than those of appellants.
We cannot say that that judgment is not an allowable one. Yet,
if it is, the classification has relation to the purpose for which
it is made, and does not contain the kind of discrimination against
which the Equal Protection Clause affords protection. It is by such
practical considerations based on experience, rather than by
theoretical inconsistencies, that the question of equal protection
is to be answered. Patsone v. Pennsylvania, 232 U.
S. 138 , 232 U. S. 144 ; Marcus Brown Holding Co. v. Feldman, 256 U.
S. 170 , 256 U. S.
198 -199; Metropolitan Casualty Co. of New York v.
Brownell, 294 U. S. 580 , 294 U. S.
585 -586. And the fact that New York City sees fit to
eliminate from traffic this kind of distraction, but does not touch
what may be even greater ones in a different category, such as the
vivid displays on Times Square, is immaterial. It is no requirement
of equal protection that all evils of the same genus be eradicated
or none at all. Central Lumber Co. v. South Dakota, 226 U. S. 157 , 226 U. S.
160 . Page 336 U. S. 111 It is finally contended that the regulation is a burden on
interstate commerce in violation of Art. I, § 8 of the
Constitution. Many of these trucks are engaged in delivering goods
in interstate commerce from New Jersey to New York. Where traffic
control and the use of highways are involved, and where there is no
conflicting federal regulation, great leeway is allowed local
authorities, even though the local regulation materially interferes
with interstate commerce. The case in that posture is controlled by South Carolina Hwy. Dept. v. Barnwell Bros., 303 U.
S. 177 , 303 U. S. 187 et seq. . And see Maurer v. Hamilton, 309 U.
S. 598 . Affirmed. MR. JUSTICE RUTLEDGE acquiesces in the Court's opinion and
judgment, dubitante on the question of equal protection of
the laws.
[ Footnote 1 ]
This regulation was promulgated by the Police Commissioner
pursuant to the power granted the police department under § 435 of
the New York City Charter, which provides as follows:
"The police department and force shall have the power and it
shall be their duty to . . . regulate, direct, control and restrict
the movement of vehicular and pedestrian traffic for the
facilitation of traffic, and the convenience of the public as well
as the proper protection of human life and health; . . . The
commissioner shall make such rules and regulations for the conduct
of pedestrian and vehicular traffic in the use of the public
streets, squares and avenues as he may deem necessary. . . ."
[ Footnote 2 ]
The advertisements for which appellant was convicted consisted
of posters from three by seven feet to four by ten feet portraying
Camel Cigarettes, Ringling Brothers and Barnum & Bailey Circus,
and radio station WOR. Drivers of appellant's trucks carrying
advertisements of Prince Albert Smoking Tobacco and U.S. Navy were
also convicted.
[ Footnote 3 ]
The element of safety was held to be one of the standards by
which the regulations of the Police Commissioner were to be judged.
We accept that construction of the authority of the Police
Commissioner under § 435 of the Charter, note 1 supra. See Price v. Illinois, 238 U. S. 446 , 238 U. S. 451 ; Hartford Accident & Indemnity Co. v. N. O. Nelson Co., 291 U. S. 352 , 291 U. S. 358 ; Central Hanover Bank & Trust Co. v. Kelly, 319 U. S. 94 , 310 U. S.
97 .
MR. JUSTICE JACKSON, concurring.
There are two clauses of the Fourteenth Amendment which this
Court may invoke to invalidate ordinances by which municipal
governments seek to solve their local problems. One says that no
state shall "deprive any person of life, liberty, or property,
without due process of law." The other declares that no state shall
"deny to any person within its jurisdiction the equal protection of
the laws."
My philosophy as to the relative readiness with which we should
resort to these two clauses is almost diametrically opposed to the
philosophy which prevails on this Court. While claims of denial of
equal protection are frequently asserted, they are rarely
sustained. But the Court frequently uses the due process clause to
strike down measures taken by municipalities to deal with
activities in their streets and public places which the local Page 336 U. S. 112 authorities consider to create hazards, annoyances or
discomforts to their inhabitants. And I have frequently dissented
when I thought local power was improperly denied. See, for
example, opinion in Douglas v. Jeannette and
companion cases, 319 U. S. 157 , 319 U. S.
166 ,; and dissents in Saia v. New York, 334 U. S. 558 , 334 U. S. 566 ; Prince v. Massachusetts, 321 U. S. 158 , 321 U. S.
176 .
The burden should rest heavily upon one who would persuade us to
use the due process clause to strike down a substantive law or
ordinance. Even its provident use against municipal regulations
frequently disables all government -- state, municipal and federal
-- from dealing with the conduct in question because the
requirement of due process is also applicable to State and Federal
Governments. Invalidation of a statute or an ordinance on due
process grounds leaves ungoverned and ungovernable conduct which
many people find objectionable.
Invocation of the equal protection clause, on the other hand,
does not disable any governmental body from dealing with the
subject at hand. It merely means that the prohibition or regulation
must have a broader impact. I regard it as a salutary doctrine that
cities, states and the Federal Government must exercise their
powers so as not to discriminate between their inhabitants except
upon some reasonable differentiation fairly related to the object
of regulation. This equality is not merely abstract justice. The
framers of the Constitution knew, and we should not forget today,
that there is no more effective practical guaranty against
arbitrary and unreasonable government than to require that the
principles of law which officials would impose upon a minority must
be imposed generally. Conversely, nothing opens the door to
arbitrary action so effectively as to allow those officials to pick
and choose only a few to whom they will apply legislation, and thus
to escape the political retribution that might be visited upon them
if larger numbers were affected. Page 336 U. S. 113 Courts can take no better measure to assure that laws will be
just than to require that laws be equal in operation.
This case affords an illustration. Even casual observations from
the sidewalks of New York will show that an ordinance which would
forbid all advertising on vehicles would run into conflict with
many interests, including some, if not all, of the great
metropolitan newspapers, which use that advertising extensively.
Their blandishment of the latest sensations is not less a cause of
diverted attention and traffic hazard than the commonplace
cigarette advertisement which this truck owner is forbidden to
display. But any regulation applicable to all such advertising
would require much clearer justification in local conditions to
enable its enactment than does some regulation applicable to a few.
I do not mention this to criticize the motives of those who enacted
this ordinance, but it dramatizes the point that we are much more
likely to find arbitrariness in the regulation of the few than of
the many. Hence, for my part, I am more receptive to attack on
local ordinances for denial of equal protection than for denial of
due process, while the Court has more often used the latter
clause.
In this case, if the City of New York should assume that display
of any advertising on vehicles tends and intends to distract the
attention of persons using the highways and to increase the dangers
of its traffic, I should think it fully within its constitutional
powers to forbid it all. The same would be true if the City should
undertake to eliminate or minimize the hazard by any generally
applicable restraint, such as limiting the size, color, shape or
perhaps to some extent the contents of vehicular advertising.
Instead of such general regulation of advertising, however, the
City seeks to reduce the hazard only by saying that while some may,
others may not exhibit such appeals. The same display, for
example, Page 336 U. S. 114 advertising cigarettes, which this appellant is forbidden to
carry on its trucks, may be carried on the trucks of a cigarette
dealer and might on the trucks of this appellant if it dealt in
cigarettes. And almost an identical advertisement, certainly one of
equal size, shape, color, and appearance, may be carried by this
appellant if it proclaims its own offer to transport cigarettes.
But it may not be carried so long as the message is not its own,
but a cigarette dealer's offer to sell the same cigarettes.
The City urges that this applies equally to all persons of a
permissible classification, because all that it does is (1) forbid
all inhabitants of New York City from engaging in the business of
selling advertising space on trucks which move as part of the city
traffic; (2) forbid all truck owners from incidentally employing
their vehicles for such purpose, with the exception that all truck
owners can advertise their own business on their own trucks. It is
argued that, while this does not eliminate vehicular advertising,
it does eliminate such advertising for hire, and, to this extent,
cuts down the hazard sought to be controlled.
That the difference between carrying on any business for hire
and engaging in the same activity on one's own is a sufficient one
to sustain some types of regulations of the one that is not applied
to the other is almost elementary. But it is usual to find such
regulations applied to the very incidents wherein the two classes
present different problems, such as in charges, liability and
quality of service.
The difference, however, is invoked here to sustain a
discrimination in a problem in which the two classes present
identical dangers. The courts of New York have declared that the
sole nature and purpose of the regulation before us is to reduce
traffic hazards. There is not even a pretense here that the traffic
hazard created Page 336 U. S. 115 by the advertising which is forbidden is in any manner or degree
more hazardous than that which is permitted. It is urged with
considerable force that this local regulation does not comply with
the equal protection clause, because it applies unequally upon
classes whose differentiation is in no way relevant to the objects
of the regulation.
As a matter of principle, and in view of my attitude toward the
equal protection clause, I do not think differences of treatment
under law should be approved on classification because of
differences unrelated to the legislative purpose. The equal
protection clause ceases to assure either equality or protection if
it is avoided by any conceivable difference that can be pointed out
between those bound and those left free. This Court has often
announced the principle that the differentiation must have an
appropriate relation to the object of the legislation or ordinance. See, for example, Mayflower Farms v. Ten Eyck, 297 U. S. 266 ; Smith v. Cahoon, 283 U. S. 553 . In
the latter case, a motor vehicle regulation was struck down upon
citation of many authorities because "such a classification is not
based on anything having relation to the purpose for which it is
made." 283 U. S. 283 U.S.
553, 283 U. S. 567 .
If that were the situation here, I should think we should reach a
similar conclusion.
The question in my mind comes to this. Where individuals
contribute to an evil or danger in the same way and to the same
degree, may those who do so for hire be prohibited, while those who
do so for their own commercial ends but not for hire be allowed to
continue? I think the answer has to be that the hireling may be put
in a class by himself, and may be dealt with differently than those
who act on their own. But this is not merely because such a
discrimination will enable the lawmaker to diminish the evil. That
might be done by many classifications, which I should think wholly
unsustainable. Page 336 U. S. 116 It is, rather, because there is a real difference between doing
in self-interest and doing for hire, so that it is one thing to
tolerate action from those who act on their own, and it is another
thing to permit the same action to be promoted for a price.
Certainly the presence of absence of hire has been the hook by
which much highway regulations has been supported. Rights usual to
passengers may be denied to the nonpaying guest in an automobile to
limit vexatious litigation. Silver v. Silver, 280 U.
S. 117 . A state may require security against injuries
from one using the highways for hire that it does not exact from
others because, as Mr. Justice Sutherland put it,
"The streets belong to the public, and are primarily for the use
of the public in the ordinary way. Their use for the purposes of
gain is special and extraordinary, and, generally at least, may be
prohibited or conditioned as the Legislature deems proper." Packard v. Banton, 264 U. S. 140 , 264 U. S. 144 .
In the case of those who let out automobiles to those who drive
them, the Court, through Mr. Justice Butler, said of the State, "It
may prohibit or condition as it deems proper the use of city
streets as a place for the carrying on of private business." Hodge Co. v. Cincinnati, 284 U. S. 335 , 284 U. S. 337 . See also Sproles v. Binford, 286 U.
S. 374 , 286 U. S. 393 ; Stephenson v. Binford, 287 U. S. 251 , 287 U. S. 278 ; Hicklin v. Coney, 290 U. S. 169 ; Stanley v. Public Utilities Commission, 295 U. S.
76 ; Aero Mayflower Transit Co. v. Georgia
Commission, 295 U. S. 285 ; Dixie Ohio Express Co. v. State Revenue Commission, 306 U. S. 72 . The
rule was flatly stated for the Court by Mr. Justice Brandeis:
"In dealing with the problem of safety of the highways, as in
other problems of motor transportation, the state may adopt
measures which favor vehicles used solely in the business of their
owners, as distinguished from those which are operated for hire by
carriers who use the highways as their place of business." Bradley v. Public Utilities
Commission , 289 Page 336 U. S. 117 U.S. 92, 289 U. S. 97 .
However, it is otherwise if the discriminations within the
regulates class are based on arbitrary differences as to
commodities carried having no relation to the object of the
regulation. Smith v. Cahoon, 283 U.
S. 553 . See also Quaker City Cab Co. v.
Pennsylvania, 277 U. S. 389 .
Of course, this appellant did not hold itself out to carry or
display everybody's advertising, and its rental of space on the
sides of its trucks was only incidental to the main business which
brought its trucks into the streets. But it is not difficult to see
that, in a day of extravagant advertising more or less subsidized
by tax deduction, the rental of truck space could become an
obnoxious enterprise. While I do not think highly of this type of
regulation, that is not my business, and in view of the control I
would concede to cities to protect citizens in quiet and orderly
use for their proper purposes of the highways and public places, see dissent in Saia v. New York, 334 U.
S. 558 , I think the judgment below must be affirmed. | The U.S. Supreme Court upheld a New York City traffic regulation prohibiting the operation of advertising vehicles on streets, with an exemption for vehicles displaying advertisements for the owner's products. The Court found that the regulation did not violate due process, equal protection, or burden interstate commerce. It allowed local authorities significant discretion in traffic control and highway use, recognizing the unique challenges of urban transportation. |
Equal Protection | Brown v. Board of Education of Topeka | https://supreme.justia.com/cases/federal/us/347/483/ | U.S. Supreme Court Brown v. Board of Education of Topeka, 347
U.S. 483 (1954) Brown v. Board of Education of Topeka Argued December 9, 1952 Reargued December 8, 1953 Decided May 17, 1954* APPEAL FROM THE UNITED STATES DISTRICT COURT FOR THE DISTRICT OF KANSAS MR. CHIEF JUSTICE WARREN delivered the opinion of the Court.
These cases come to us from the States of Kansas, South
Carolina, Virginia, and Delaware. They are premised on different
facts and different local conditions, but a common legal question
justifies their consideration together in this consolidated
opinion. [ Footnote 1 ] [487 ]
In each of the cases, minors of the Negro race, through their
legal representatives, seek the aid of the courts in obtaining
admission to the public schools of their community on a
nonsegregated basis. In each instance, [488 ]
they had been denied admission to schools attended by white
children under laws requiring or permitting segregation according
to race. This segregation was alleged to deprive the plaintiffs of
the equal protection of the laws under the Fourteenth Amendment. In
each of the cases other than the Delaware case, a three-judge
federal district court denied relief to the plaintiffs on the
so-called "separate but equal" doctrine announced by this Court in Plessy v. Fergson, 163 U. S. 537 .
Under that doctrine, equality of treatment is accorded when the
races are provided substantially equal facilities, even though
these facilities be separate. In the Delaware case, the Supreme
Court of Delaware adhered to that doctrine, but ordered that the
plaintiffs be admitted to the white schools because of their
superiority to the Negro schools.
The plaintiffs contend that segregated public schools are not
"equal" and cannot be made "equal," and that hence they are
deprived of the equal protection of the laws. Because of the
obvious importance of the question presented, the Court took
jurisdiction. [ Footnote 2 ]
Argument was heard in the 1952 Term, and reargument was heard this
Term on certain questions propounded by the Court. [ Footnote 3 ] [489 ]
Reargument was largely devoted to the circumstances surrounding
the adoption of the Fourteenth Amendment in 1868. It covered
exhaustively consideration of the Amendment in Congress,
ratification by the states, then-existing practices in racial
segregation, and the views of proponents and opponents of the
Amendment. This discussion and our own investigation convince us
that, although these sources cast some light, it is not enough to
resolve the problem with which we are faced. At best, they are
inconclusive. The most avid proponents of the post-War Amendments
undoubtedly intended them to remove all legal distinctions among
"all persons born or naturalized in the United States." Their
opponents, just as certainly, were antagonistic to both the letter
and the spirit of the Amendments and wished them to have the most
limited effect. What others in Congress and the state legislatures
had in mind cannot be determined with any degree of certainty.
An additional reason for the inconclusive nature of the
Amendment's history with respect to segregated schools is the
status of public education at that time. [ Footnote 4 ] In the South, the movement toward free
common schools, supported [490 ]
by general taxation, had not yet taken hold. Education of white
children was largely in the hands of private groups. Education of
Negroes was almost nonexistent, and practically all of the race
were illiterate. In fact, any education of Negroes was forbidden by
law in some states. Today, in contrast, many Negroes have achieved
outstanding success in the arts and sciences, as well as in the
business and professional world. It is true that public school
education at the time of the Amendment had advanced further in the
North, but the effect of the Amendment on Northern States was
generally ignored in the congressional debates. Even in the North,
the conditions of public education did not approximate those
existing today. The curriculum was usually rudimentary; ungraded
schools were common in rural areas; the school term was but three
months a year in many states, and compulsory school attendance was
virtually unknown. As a consequence, it is not surprising that
there should be so little in the history of the Fourteenth
Amendment relating to its intended effect on public education.
In the first cases in this Court construing the Fourteenth
Amendment, decided shortly after its adoption, the Court
interpreted it as proscribing all state-imposed discriminations
against the Negro race. [ Footnote
5 ] The doctrine of [491 ]
"separate but equal" did not make its appearance in this Court
until 1896 in the case of Plessy v. Ferguson, supra, involving not education but transportation. [ Footnote 6 ] American courts have since labored with
the doctrine for over half a century. In this Court, there have
been six cases involving the "separate but equal" doctrine in the
field of public education. [ Footnote 7 ] In Cumming v. County Board of
Education, 175 U. S. 528 , and Gong Lum v. Rice, 275 U. S. 78 , the
validity of the doctrine itself was not challenged. [ Footnote 8 ] In more recent cases, all on
the graduate school [492 ]
level, inequality was found in that specific benefits enjoyed by
white students were denied to Negro students of the same
educational qualifications. Missouri ex rel. Gaines v.
Canada, 305 U. S. 337 ; Sipuel v. Oklahoma, 332 U. S. 631 ; Sweatt v. Painter, 339 U. S. 629 ; McLaurin v. Oklahoma State Regents, 339 U.
S. 637 . In none of these cases was it necessary to
reexamine the doctrine to grant relief to the Negro plaintiff. And
in Sweatt v. Painter, supra, the Court expressly reserved
decision on the question whether Plessy v. Ferguson should
be held inapplicable to public education.
In the instant cases, that question is directly presented. Here,
unlike Sweatt v. Painter, there are findings below that
the Negro and white schools involved have been equalized, or are
being equalized, with respect to buildings, curricula,
qualifications and salaries of teachers, and other "tangible"
factors. [ Footnote 9 ] Our
decision, therefore, cannot turn on merely a comparison of these
tangible factors in the Negro and white schools involved in each of
the cases. We must look instead to the effect of segregation itself
on public education.
In approaching this problem, we cannot turn the clock back to
1868, when the Amendment was adopted, or even to 1896, when Plessy v. Ferguson was written. We must consider public
education in the light of its full development and its present
place in American life throughout [493 ]
the Nation. Only in this way can it be determined if segregation
in public schools deprives these plaintiffs of the equal protection
of the laws.
Today, education is perhaps the most important function of state
and local governments. Compulsory school attendance laws and the
great expenditures for education both demonstrate our recognition
of the importance of education to our democratic society. It is
required in the performance of our most basic public
responsibilities, even service in the armed forces. It is the very
foundation of good citizenship. Today it is a principal instrument
in awakening the child to cultural values, in preparing him for
later professional training, and in helping him to adjust normally
to his environment. In these days, it is doubtful that any child
may reasonably be expected to succeed in life if he is denied the
opportunity of an education. Such an opportunity, where the state
has undertaken to provide it, is a right which must be made
available to all on equal terms.
We come then to the question presented: does segregation of
children in public schools solely on the basis of race, even though
the physical facilities and other "tangible" factors may be equal,
deprive the children of the minority group of equal educational
opportunities? We believe that it does.
In Sweatt v. Painter, supra, in finding that a
segregated law school for Negroes could not provide them equal
educational opportunities, this Court relied in large part on
"those qualities which are incapable of objective measurement but
which make for greatness in a law school." In McLaurin v.
Oklahoma State Regents, supra, the Court, in requiring that a
Negro admitted to a white graduate school be treated like all other
students, again resorted to intangible considerations: ". . . his
ability to study, to engage in discussions and exchange views with
other students, and, in general, to learn his profession." [494 ]
Such considerations apply with added force to children in grade
and high schools. To separate them from others of similar age and
qualifications solely because of their race generates a feeling of
inferiority as to their status in the community that may affect
their hearts and minds in a way unlikely ever to be undone. The
effect of this separation on their educational opportunities was
well stated by a finding in the Kansas case by a court which
nevertheless felt compelled to rule against the Negro
plaintiffs:
"Segregation of white and colored children in public schools has
a detrimental effect upon the colored children. The impact is
greater when it has the sanction of the law, for the policy of
separating the races is usually interpreted as denoting the
inferiority of the negro group. A sense of inferiority affects the
motivation of a child to learn. Segregation with the sanction of
law, therefore, has a tendency to [retard] the educational and
mental development of negro children and to deprive them of some of
the benefits they would receive in a racial[ly] integrated school
system. [ Footnote 10 ]"
Whatever may have been the extent of psychological knowledge at
the time of Plessy v. Ferguson, this finding is amply
supported by modern authority. [ Footnote 11 ] Any language [495 ]
in Plessy v. Ferguson contrary to this finding is
rejected.
We conclude that, in the field of public education, the doctrine
of "separate but equal" has no place. Separate educational
facilities are inherently unequal. Therefore, we hold that the
plaintiffs and others similarly situated for whom the actions have
been brought are, by reason of the segregation complained of,
deprived of the equal protection of the laws guaranteed by the
Fourteenth Amendment. This disposition makes unnecessary any
discussion whether such segregation also violates the Due Process
Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment. [ Footnote 12 ]
Because these are class actions, because of the wide
applicability of this decision, and because of the great variety of
local conditions, the formulation of decrees in these cases
presents problems of considerable complexity. On reargument, the
consideration of appropriate relief was necessarily subordinated to
the primary question -- the constitutionality of segregation in
public education. We have now announced that such segregation is a
denial of the equal protection of the laws. In order that we may
have the full assistance of the parties in formulating decrees, the
cases will be restored to the docket, and the parties are requested
to present further argument on Questions 4 and 5 previously
propounded by the Court for the reargument this Term. [ Footnote 13 ] The Attorney General [496 ]
of the United States is again invited to participate. The
Attorneys General of the states requiring or permitting segregation
in public education will also be permitted to appear as amici
curiae upon request to do so by September 15, 1954, and
submission of briefs by October 1, 1954. [ Footnote 14 ] It is so ordered. * Together with No. 2, Briggs et al. v. Elliott et al., on appeal from the United States District Court for the Eastern
District of South Carolina, argued December 9-10, 1952, reargued
December 7-8, 1953; No. 4, Davis et al. v. County School Board
of Prince Edward County, Virginia, et al., on appeal from the
United States District Court for the Eastern District of Virginia,
argued December 10, 1952, reargued December 7-8, 1953, and No. 10, Gebhart et al. v. Belton et al., on certiorari to the
Supreme Court of Delaware, argued December 11, 1952, reargued
December 9, 1953.
[ Footnote 1 ]
In the Kansas case, Brown v. Board of Education, the
plaintiffs are Negro children of elementary school age residing in
Topeka. They brought this action in the United States District
Court for the District of Kansas to enjoin enforcement of a Kansas
statute which permits, but does not require, cities of more than
15,000 population to maintain separate school facilities for Negro
and white students. Kan.Gen.Stat. § 72-1724 (1949). Pursuant to
that authority, the Topeka Board of Education elected to establish
segregated elementary schools. Other public schools in the
community, however, are operated on a nonsegregated basis. The
three-judge District Court, convened under 28 U.S.C. §§ 2281 and
2284, found that segregation in public education has a detrimental
effect upon Negro children, but denied relief on the ground that
the Negro and white schools were substantially equal with respect
to buildings, transportation, curricula, and educational
qualifications of teachers. 98 F. Supp.
797 . The case is here on direct appeal under 28 U.S.C. §
1253.
In the South Carolina case, Briggs v. Elliott, the
plaintiffs are Negro children of both elementary and high school
age residing in Clarendon County. They brought this action in the
United States District Court for the Eastern District of South
Carolina to enjoin enforcement of provisions in the state
constitution and statutory code which require the segregation of
Negroes and whites in public schools. S.C.Const., Art. XI, § 7;
S.C.Code § 5377 (1942). The three-judge District Court, convened
under 28 U.S.C. §§ 2281 and 2284, denied the requested relief. The
court found that the Negro schools were inferior to the white
schools, and ordered the defendants to begin immediately to
equalize the facilities. But the court sustained the validity of
the contested provisions and denied the plaintiffs admission to the
white schools during the equalization program. 98 F. Supp.
529 . This Court vacated the District Court's judgment and
remanded the case for the purpose of obtaining the court's views on
a report filed by the defendants concerning the progress made in
the equalization program. 342 U. S. 350 . On
remand, the District Court found that substantial equality had been
achieved except for buildings and that the defendants were
proceeding to rectify this inequality as well. 103 F.
Supp. 920 . The case is again here on direct appeal under 28
U.S.C. § 1253.
In the Virginia case, Davis v. County School Board, the
plaintiffs are Negro children of high school age residing in Prince
Edward County. They brought this action in the United States
District Court for the Eastern District of Virginia to enjoin
enforcement of provisions in the state constitution and statutory
code which require the segregation of Negroes and whites in public
schools. Va.Const., § 140; Va.Code § 22-221 (1950). The three-judge
District Court, convened under 28 U.S.C. §§ 2281 and 2284, denied
the requested relief. The court found the Negro school inferior in
physical plant, curricula, and transportation, and ordered the
defendants forthwith to provide substantially equal curricula and
transportation and to "proceed with all reasonable diligence and
dispatch to remove" the inequality in physical plant. But, as in
the South Carolina case, the court sustained the validity of the
contested provisions and denied the plaintiffs admission to the
white schools during the equalization program. 103 F.
Supp. 337 . The case is here on direct appeal under 28 U.S.C. §
1253.
In the Delaware case, Gebhart v. Belton, the plaintiffs
are Negro children of both elementary and high school age residing
in New Castle County. They brought this action in the Delaware
Court of Chancery to enjoin enforcement of provisions in the state
constitution and statutory code which require the segregation of
Negroes and whites in public schools. Del.Const., Art. X, § 2;
Del.Rev.Code § 2631 (1935). The Chancellor gave judgment for the
plaintiffs and ordered their immediate admission to schools
previously attended only by white children, on the ground that the
Negro schools were inferior with respect to teacher training,
pupil-teacher ratio, extracurricular activities, physical plant,
and time and distance involved in travel. 87
A.2d 862 . The Chancellor also found that segregation itself
results in an inferior education for Negro children ( see note 10 infra ), but
did not rest his decision on that ground. Id. at 865. The
Chancellor's decree was affirmed by the Supreme Court of Delaware,
which intimated, however, that the defendants might be able to
obtain a modification of the decree after equalization of the Negro
and white schools had been accomplished. 91 A.2d
137 , 152. The defendants, contending only that the Delaware
courts had erred in ordering the immediate admission of the Negro
plaintiffs to the white schools, applied to this Court for
certiorari. The writ was granted, 344 U.S. 891. The plaintiffs, who
were successful below, did not submit a cross-petition.
[ Footnote 2 ] 344 U. S. 1 , 141,
891.
[ Footnote 3 ]
345 U.S. 972. The Attorney General of the United States
participated both Terms as amicus curiae. [ Footnote 4 ]
For a general study of the development of public education prior
to the Amendment, see Butts and Cremin, A History of
Education in American Culture (1953), Pts. I, II; Cubberley, Public
Education in the United States (1934 ed.), cc. II-XII. School
practices current at the time of the adoption of the Fourteenth
Amendment are described in Butts and Cremin, supra, at
269-275; Cubberley, supra, at 288-339, 408-431; Knight,
Public Education in the South (1922), cc. VIII, IX. See
also H. Ex.Doc. No. 315, 41st Cong., 2d Sess. (1871). Although
the demand for free public schools followed substantially the same
pattern in both the North and the South, the development in the
South did not begin to gain momentum until about 1850, some twenty
years after that in the North. The reasons for the somewhat slower
development in the South ( e.g., the rural character of the
South and the different regional attitudes toward state assistance)
are well explained in Cubberley, supra, at 408-423. In the
country as a whole, but particularly in the South, the War
virtually stopped all progress in public education. Id. at
427-428. The low status of Negro education in all sections of the
country, both before and immediately after the War, is described in
Beale, A History of Freedom of Teaching in American Schools (1941),
112-132, 175-195. Compulsory school attendance laws were not
generally adopted until after the ratification of the Fourteenth
Amendment, and it was not until 1918 that such laws were in force
in all the states. Cubberley, supra, at 563-565.
[ Footnote 5 ] Slaughter-House
Cases , 16 Wall. 36, 67-72 (1873); Strauder v.
West Virginia, 100 U. S. 303 ,
307-308 (1880):
"It ordains that no State shall deprive any person of life,
liberty, or property, without due process of law, or deny to any
person within its jurisdiction the equal protection of the laws.
What is this but declaring that the law in the States shall be the
same for the black as for the white; that all persons, whether
colored or white, shall stand equal before the laws of the States,
and, in regard to the colored race, for whose protection the
amendment was primarily designed, that no discrimination shall be
made against them by law because of their color? The words of the
amendment, it is true, are prohibitory, but they contain a
necessary implication of a positive immunity, or right, most
valuable to the colored race -- the right to exemption from
unfriendly legislation against them distinctively as colored --
exemption from legal discriminations, implying inferiority in civil
society, lessening the security of their enjoyment of the rights
which others enjoy, and discriminations which are steps towards
reducing them to the condition of a subject race." See also Virginia v. Rives, 100 U.
S. 313 , 318 (1880); Ex parte Virginia, 100 U. S. 339 ,
344-345 (1880).
[ Footnote 6 ]
The doctrine apparently originated in Roberts v. City of
Boston, 59 Mass.198, 206 (1850), upholding school segregation
against attack as being violative of a state constitutional
guarantee of equality. Segregation in Boston public schools was
eliminated in 1855. Mass.Acts 1855, c. 256. But elsewhere in the
North, segregation in public education has persisted in some
communities until recent years. It is apparent that such
segregation has long been a nationwide problem, not merely one of
sectional concern.
[ Footnote 7 ] See also Berea College v. Kentucky, 211 U. S.
45 (1908).
[ Footnote 8 ]
In the Cummin case, Negro taxpayers sought an
injunction requiring the defendant school board to discontinue the
operation of a high school for white children until the board
resumed operation of a high school for Negro children. Similarly,
in the Gong Lum case, the plaintiff, a child of Chinese
descent, contended only that state authorities had misapplied the
doctrine by classifying him with Negro children and requiring him
to attend a Negro school.
[ Footnote 9 ]
In the Kansas case, the court below found substantial equality
as to all such factors. 98 F. Supp.
797 , 798. In the South Carolina case, the court below found
that the defendants were proceeding "promptly and in good faith to
comply with the court's decree." 103 F.
Supp. 920 , 921. In the Virginia case, the court below noted
that the equalization program was already "afoot and progressing"
( 103 F.
Supp. 337 , 341); since then, we have been advised, in the
Virginia Attorney General's brief on reargument, that the program
has now been completed. In the Delaware case, the court below
similarly noted that the state's equalization program was well
under way. 91 A.2d 137 ,
149.
[ Footnote 10 ]
A similar finding was made in the Delaware case:
"I conclude from the testimony that, in our Delaware society,
State-imposed segregation in education itself results in the Negro
children, as a class, receiving educational opportunities which are
substantially inferior to those available to white children
otherwise similarly situated." 87 A.2d
862 , 865.
[ Footnote 11 ]
K.B. Clark, Effect of Prejudice and Discrimination on
Personality Development (Mid-century White House Conference on
Children and Youth, 1950); Witmer and Kotinsky, Personality in the
Making (1952), c. VI; Deutscher and Chein, The Psychological
Effects of Enforced Segregation A Survey of Social Science Opinion,
26 J.Psychol. 259 (1948); Chein, What are the Psychological Effects
of Segregation Under Conditions of Equal Facilities?, 3
Int.J.Opinion and Attitude Res. 229 (1949); Brameld, Educational
Costs, in Discrimination and National Welfare (MacIver, ed., 1949),
44-48; Frazier, The Negro in the United States (1949), 674-681. And see generally Myrdal, An American Dilemma (1944).
[ Footnote 12 ] See Bolling v. Sharpe, post, p. 497, concerning the Due
Process Clause of the Fifth Amendment.
[ Footnote 13 ]
"4. Assuming it is decided that segregation in public schools
violates the Fourteenth Amendment"
"( a ) would a decree necessarily follow providing that,
within the limits set by normal geographic school districting,
Negro children should forthwith be admitted to schools of their
choice, or"
"( b ) may this Court, in the exercise of its equity
powers, permit an effective gradual adjustment to be brought about
from existing segregated systems to a system not based on color
distinctions?"
"5. On the assumption on which questions 4( a ) and
( b ) are based, and assuming further that this Court will
exercise its equity powers to the end described in question
4( b ),"
"( a ) should this Court formulate detailed decrees in
these cases;"
"( b ) if so, what specific issues should the decrees
reach;"
"( c ) should this Court appoint a special master to hear
evidence with a view to recommending specific terms for such
decrees;"
"( d ) should this Court remand to the courts of first
instance with directions to frame decrees in these cases and, if
so, what general directions should the decrees of this Court
include and what procedures should the courts of first instance
follow in arriving at the specific terms of more detailed
decrees?"
[ Footnote 14 ] See Rule 42, Revised Rules of this Court (effective
July 1, 1954). | Here is a summary of the key points from the case:
- The case, Brown v. Board of Education of Topeka, was a consolidation of several cases from different states, all involving racial segregation in public schools.
- The plaintiffs, minors of the Negro race, sought admission to white schools, arguing that segregated schools were inherently unequal and violated the Equal Protection Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment.
- The lower courts in all but one case upheld segregation under the "separate but equal" doctrine established in Plessy v. Ferguson. The Delaware court ordered admission to white schools due to their superiority over Negro schools.
- The Supreme Court took jurisdiction due to the importance of the question presented and heard rearguments focused on the historical context of the Fourteenth Amendment.
- The Court concluded that racial segregation in public education violated the Equal Protection Clause, overturning Plessy v. Ferguson and ending legal segregation in US public schools.
- The Court recognized the negative psychological impact of segregation and the inherent inequality of separate educational facilities.
- The Court considered the implementation of desegregation, including the potential for gradual adjustment and the formulation of detailed decrees.
This case was a landmark decision that played a crucial role in the civil rights movement, ending legal segregation in public schools and setting a precedent for further challenges to racial segregation in other areas of American life. |
Equal Protection | Hernandez v. Texas | https://supreme.justia.com/cases/federal/us/347/475/ | U.S. Supreme Court Hernandez v. Texas, 347
U.S. 475 (1954) Hernandez v. Texas No. 406 Argued January 11,
1954 Decided May 3, 1954 347
U.S. 475 CERTIORARI TO THE COURT OF CRIMINAL
APPEALS OF TEXAS Syllabus The systematic exclusion of persons of Mexican descent from
service as jury commissioners, grand jurors, and petit jurors in
the Texas county in which petitioner was indicted and tried for
murder, although there were a substantial number of such persons in
the county fully qualified to serve, deprived petitioner, a person
of Mexican descent, of the equal protection of the laws guaranteed
by the Fourteenth Amendment, and his conviction in a state court is
reversed. Pp. 347 U. S.
476 -482.
(a) The constitutional guarantee of equal protection of the laws
is not directed solely against discrimination between whites and
Negroes. Pp. 347 U. S.
477 -478.
(b) When the existence of a distinct class is demonstrated, and
it is shown that the laws, as written or as applied, single out
that class for different treatment not based on some reasonable
classification, the guarantees of the Constitution have been
violated. P. 347 U. S.
478 .
(c) The exclusion of otherwise eligible persons from jury
service solely because of their ancestry or national origin is
discrimination prohibited by the Fourteenth Amendment. Pp. 347 U. S.
478 -479.
(d) The evidence in this case was sufficient to prove that, in
the county in question, persons of Mexican descent constitute a
separate class, distinct from "whites." Pp. 347 U. S.
479 -480.
(e) A prima facie case of denial of the equal
protection of the laws was established in this case by evidence
that there were in the county a substantial number of persons of
Mexican descent with the qualifications required for jury service,
but that none of them had served on a jury commission, grand jury
or petit jury for 25 years. Pp. 347 U. S.
480 -481.
(f) The testimony of five jury commissioners that they had not
discriminated against persons of Mexican descent in selecting
jurors, and that their only objective had been to select those whom
they thought best qualified, was not enough to overcome
petitioner's prima facie case of denial of the equal
protection of the laws. Pp. 347 U. S.
481 -482.
(g) Petitioner had the constitutional right to be indicted and
tried by juries from which all members of his class were not
systematically excluded. P. 347 U. S.
482 .
___ Tex.Cr.R. ___, 251
S.W.2d 531 , reversed. Page 347 U. S. 476 MR. CHIEF JUSTICE WARREN delivered the opinion of the Court.
The petitioner, Pete Hernandez, was indicted for the murder of
one Joe Espinosa by a grand jury in Jackson County, Texas. He was
convicted and sentenced to life imprisonment. The Texas Court of
Criminal Appeals affirmed the judgment of the trial court. 251
S.W.2d 531 . Prior to the trial, the petitioner, by his counsel,
offered timely motions to quash the indictment and the jury panel.
He alleged that persons of Mexican descent were systematically
excluded from service as jury commissioners, [ Footnote 1 ] grand jurors, and petit jurors,
although there were such persons fully Page 347 U. S. 477 qualified to serve residing in Jackson County. The petitioner
asserted that exclusion of this class deprived him, as a member of
the class, of the equal protection of the laws guaranteed by the
Fourteenth Amendment of the Constitution. After a hearing, the
trial court denied the motions. At the trial, the motions were
renewed, further evidence taken, and the motions again denied. An
allegation that the trial court erred in denying the motions was
the sole basis of petitioner's appeal. In affirming the judgment of
the trial court, the Texas Court of Criminal Appeals considered and
passed upon the substantial federal question raised by the
petitioner. We granted a writ of certiorari to review that
decision. 346 U.S. 811.
In numerous decisions, this Court has held that it is a denial
of the equal protection of the laws to try a defendant of a
particular race or color under an indictment issued by a grand
jury, or before a petit jury, from which all persons of his race or
color have, solely because of that race or color, been excluded by
the State, whether acting through its legislature, its courts, or
its executive or administrative officers. [ Footnote 2 ] Although the Court has had little occasion
to rule on the question directly, it has been recognized since Strauder v. West Virginia, 100 U.
S. 303 , that the exclusion of a class of persons from
jury service on grounds other than race or color may also deprive a
defendant who is a member of that class of the constitutional
guarantee of equal protection of the laws. [ Footnote 3 ] The State of Texas would have us hold that
there are only two classes -- white and Negro -- within the
contemplation of the Fourteenth Amendment. The decisions of this
Court Page 347 U. S. 478 do not support that view. [ Footnote 4 ] And, except where the question presented
involves the exclusion of persons of Mexican descent from juries,
[ Footnote 5 ] Texas courts have
taken a broader view of the scope of the equal protection clause.
[ Footnote 6 ]
Throughout our history, differences in race and color have
defined easily identifiable groups which have at times required the
aid of the courts in securing equal treatment under the laws. But
community prejudices are not static, and, from time to time, other
differences from the community norm may define other groups which
need the same protection. Whether such a group exists within a
community is a question of fact. When the existence of a distinct
class is demonstrated, and it is further shown that the laws, as
written or as applied, single out that class for different
treatment not based on some reasonable classification, the
guarantees of the Constitution have been violated. The Fourteenth
Amendment is not directed solely against discrimination due to a
"two-class theory" -- that is, based upon differences between
"white" and Negro.
As the petitioner acknowledges, the Texas system of selecting
grand and petit jurors by the use of jury commissions is fair on
its face and capable of being utilized Page 347 U. S. 479 without discrimination. [ Footnote 7 ] But, as this Court has held, the system is
susceptible to abuse, and can be employed in a discriminatory
manner. [ Footnote 8 ] The
exclusion of otherwise eligible persons from jury service solely
because of their ancestry or national origin is discrimination
prohibited by the Fourteenth Amendment. The Texas statute makes no
such discrimination, but the petitioner alleges that those
administering the law do.
The petitioner's initial burden in substantiating his charge of
group discrimination was to prove that persons of Mexican descent
constitute a separate class in Jackson County, distinct from
"whites." [ Footnote 9 ] One
method by which this may be demonstrated is by showing the attitude
of the community. Here, the testimony of responsible officials and
citizens contained the admission that residents of the community
distinguished between "white" and "Mexican." The participation of
persons of Mexican descent in business and community groups was
shown to be slight. Until very recent times, children of Mexican
descent were required to attend a segregated school for the first
four grades. [ Footnote 10 ]
At least one restaurant in town prominently displayed a sign
announcing "No Mexicans Served." On the courthouse grounds at the
time of the Page 347 U. S. 480 hearing, there were two men's toilets, one unmarked, and the
other marked "Colored Men" and "Hombres Aqui" ("Men Here"). No
substantial evidence was offered to rebut the logical inference to
be drawn from these facts, and it must be concluded that petitioner
succeeded in his proof.
Having established the existence of a class, petitioner was then
charged with the burden of proving discrimination. To do so, he
relied on the pattern of proof established by Norris v.
Alabama, 294 U. S. 587 . In
that case, proof that Negroes constituted a substantial segment of
the population of the jurisdiction, that some Negroes were
qualified to serve as jurors, and that none had been called for
jury service over an extended period of time, was held to
constitute prima facie proof of the systematic exclusion
of Negroes from jury service. This holding, sometimes called the
"rule of exclusion," has been applied in other cases, [ Footnote 11 ] and it is available in
supplying proof of discrimination against any delineated class.
The petitioner established that 14% of the population of Jackson
County were persons with Mexican or Latin American surnames, and
that 11% of the males over 21 bore such names. [ Footnote 12 ] The County Tax Assessor
testified Page 347 U. S. 481 that 6 or 7 percent of the freeholders on the tax rolls of the
County were persons of Mexican descent. The State of Texas
stipulated that,
"for the last twenty-five years, there is no record of any
person with a Mexican or Latin American name having served on a
jury commission, grand jury or petit jury in Jackson County.
[ Footnote 13 ]"
The parties also stipulated that
"there are some male persons of Mexican or Latin American
descent in Jackson County who, by virtue of being citizens,
freeholders, and having all other legal prerequisites to jury
service, are eligible to serve as members of a jury commission,
grand jury and/or petit jury. [ Footnote 14 ]"
The petitioner met the burden of proof imposed in Norris v.
Alabama, supra. To rebut the strong prima facie case
of the denial of the equal protection of the laws guaranteed by the
Constitution thus established, the State offered the testimony of
five jury commissioners that they had no discriminated against
persons of Mexican or Latin American descent in selecting jurors.
They stated that their only objective had been to select those whom
they thought were best qualified. This testimony is not enough to
overcome the petitioner's case. As the Court said in Norris v.
Alabama: "That showing as to the long-continued exclusion of negroes from
jury service, and as to the many negroes qualified for that
service, could not be met by mere generalities. If, in the presence
of such testimony as defendant adduced, the mere general assertions
by officials of their performance of duty were to be accepted as an
adequate justification for Page 347 U. S. 482 the complete exclusion of negroes from jury service, the
constitutional provision . . . would be but a vain and illusory
requirement. [ Footnote
15 ]"
The same reasoning is applicable to these facts.
Circumstances or chance may well dictate that no persons in a
certain class will serve on a particular jury or during some
particular period. But it taxes our credulity to say that mere
chance resulted in their being no members of this class among the
over six thousand jurors called in the past 25 years. The result
bespeaks discrimination, whether or not it was a conscious decision
on the part of any individual jury commissioner. The judgment of
conviction must be reversed.
To say that this decision revives the rejected contention that
the Fourteenth Amendment requires proportional representation of
all the component ethnic groups of the community on every jury
[ Footnote 16 ] ignores the
facts. The petitioner did not seek proportional representation, nor
did he claim a right to have persons of Mexican descent sit on the
particular juries which he faced. [ Footnote 17 ] His only claim is the right to be indicted
and tried by juries from which all members of his class are not
systematically excluded -- juries selected from among all qualified
persons regardless of national origin or descent. To this much he
is entitled by the Constitution. Reversed. [ Footnote 1 ]
Texas law provides that, at each term of court, the judge shall
appoint three to five jury commissioners. The judge instructs these
commissioners as to their duties. After taking an oath that they
will not knowingly select a grand juror they believe unfit or
unqualified, the commissioners retire to a room in the courthouse
where they select from the county assessment roll the names of 16
grand jurors from different parts of the county. These names are
placed in a sealed envelope and delivered to the clerk. Thirty days
before court meets, the clerk delivers a copy of the list to the
sheriff who summons the jurors. Vernon's Tex.Code Crim.Proc. arts.
333-350.
The general jury panel is also selected by the jury commission.
Vernon's Tex.Civ.Stat. art. 2107. In capital cases, a special
venire may be selected from the list furnished by the
commissioners. Vernon's Tex.Code Crim.Proc. art. 592.
[ Footnote 2 ] See Carter v. State of Texas, 177 U.
S. 442 , 177 U. S.
447 .
[ Footnote 3 ]
"Nor, if a law should be passed excluding all naturalized Celtic
Irishmen [from jury service], would there be any doubt of its
inconsistency with the spirit of the amendment."
100 U.S. at 100 U. S. 308 . Cf. American Sugar Refining Co. v. Louisiana, 179 U. S.
89 , 179 U. S.
92 .
[ Footnote 4 ] See Truax v. Raich, 239 U. S. 33 ; Takahaski v. Fish & Game Commission, 334 U.
S. 410 ; cf. Hirabayashi v. United States, 320 U. S. 81 , 320 U. S.
100 :
"Distinctions between citizens solely because of their ancestry
are, by their very nature, odious to a free people whose
institutions are founded upon the doctrine of equality."
[ Footnote 5 ] Sanchez v. State, 147 Tex.Cr.R. 436, 181 S.W.2d 87; Salazar v. State, 149 Tex.Cr.R. 260, 193 S.W.2d 211; Sanchez v. State, Tex.Cr.App., 243
S.W.2d 700 .
[ Footnote 6 ]
In Juarez v. State, 102 Tex.Cr.R. 297, 277 S.W. 1091,
the Texas court held that the systematic exclusion of Roman
Catholics from juries was barred by the Fourteenth Amendment. In Clifton v. Puente, Tex.Civ.App., 218 S.W.2d 272, the Texas
court ruled that restrictive covenants prohibiting the sale of land
to persons of Mexican descent were unenforceable.
[ Footnote 7 ] Smith v. Texas, 311 U. S. 128 , 311 U. S.
130 .
[ Footnote 8 ]
[ Footnote 9 ]
We do not have before us the question whether or not the Court
might take judicial notice that persons of Mexican descent are
there considered as a separate class. See Marden,
Minorities in American Society; McDonagh & Richards, Ethnic
Relations in the United States.
[ Footnote 10 ]
The reason given by the school superintendent for this
segregation was that these children needed special help in learning
English. In this special school, however, each teacher taught two
grades, while, in the regular school, each taught only one in most
instances. Most of the children of Mexican descent left school by
the fifth or sixth grade.
[ Footnote 11 ] See note 8 supra. [ Footnote 12 ]
The 1950 census report shows that, of the 12,916 residents of
Jackson County, 1,865, or about 14% had Mexican or Latin American
surnames. U.S. Census of Population, 1950, Vol. II, pt. 43, p. 180;
id., Vol. IV, pt. 3, c. C, p. 45. Of these 1,865, 1,738 were native
born American citizens and 65 were naturalized citizens. Id., Vol. IV, pt. 3, c. C, p. 45. Of the 3,754 males over
21 years of age in the County, 408, or about 11%, had Spanish
surnames. Id., Vol. II, pt. 43, p. 180; id., Vol. IV, pt.
3, c. C, p. 67. The State challenges any reliance on names as
showing the descent of persons in the County. However, just as
persons of a different race are distinguished by color, these
Spanish names provide ready identification of the members of this
class. In selecting jurors, the jury commissioners work from a list
of names.
[ Footnote 13 ]
R. 34.
[ Footnote 14 ]
R. 55. The parties also stipulated that there were no persons of
Mexican or Latin American descent on the list of talesmen. R. 83.
Each item of each stipulation was amply supported by the testimony
adduced at the hearing.
[ Footnote 15 ]
294 U.S. at 294 U. S.
598 .
[ Footnote 16 ] See Akins v. Texas, 325 U. S. 398 , 325 U. S. 403 ; Cassell v. Texas, 339 U. S. 282 , 339 U. S.
286 -287.
[ Footnote 17 ] See Akins v. Texas, supra, note 16, at 325 U. S.
403 . | In Hernandez v. Texas (1954), the U.S. Supreme Court ruled that the systematic exclusion of individuals of Mexican descent from jury service violated the Fourteenth Amendment's guarantee of equal protection under the law. The Court held that the constitutional right to equal protection applies to all racial groups, not just whites and African Americans.
The Court found that in Jackson County, Texas, individuals of Mexican descent constituted a distinct class and were treated differently due to their ancestry or national origin. Despite comprising a substantial portion of the county's population, no person of Mexican descent had served on a jury commission, grand jury, or petit jury for 25 years.
The Court concluded that the petitioner, Pete Hernandez, had been denied his constitutional right to be indicted and tried by juries from which members of his class were not systematically excluded. The Court reversed Hernandez's murder conviction, stating that the exclusion of individuals from jury service based solely on their ancestry or national origin was prohibited by the Fourteenth Amendment. |
Equal Protection | Sweatt v. Painter | https://supreme.justia.com/cases/federal/us/339/629/ | U.S. Supreme Court Sweatt v. Painter, 339
U.S. 629 (1950) Sweatt v. Painter No. 44 Argued April 4, 1950 Decided June 5, 1950 339
U.S. 629 CERTIORARI TO THE SUPREME COURT OF
TEXAS Syllabus Petitioner was denied admission to the state supported
University of Texas Law School, solely because he is a Negro and
state law forbids the admission of Negroes to that Law School. He
was offered, but he refused, enrollment in a separate law school
newly established by the State for Negroes. The University of Texas
Law School has 16 full-time and three part-time professors, 850
students, a library of 65,000 volumes, a law review, moot court
facilities, scholarship funds, an Order of the Coif affiliation,
many distinguished alumni, and much tradition and prestige. The
separate law school for Negroes has five full-time professors, 23
students, a library of 16,500 volumes, a practice court, a legal
aid association, and one alumnus admitted to the Texas Bar, but it
excludes from its student body members of racial groups which
number 85% of the population of the State and which include most of
the lawyers, witnesses, jurors, judges, and other officials with
whom petitioner would deal as a member of the Texas Bar. Held: The legal education offered petitioner is not
substantially equal to that which he would receive if admitted to
the University of Texas Law School, and the Equal Protection Clause
of the Fourteenth Amendment requires that he be admitted to the
University of Texas Law School. Pp. 343 U. S.
631 -636. Reversed. A Texas trial court found that a newly established state law
school for Negroes offered petitioner "privileges, advantages, and
opportunities for the study of law substantially equivalent to
those offered by the State to white students at the University of
Texas," and denied mandamus to compel his admission to the
University of Texas Law School. The Court of Civil Appeals
affirmed. 210 S.W.2d 442. The Texas Supreme Court denied writ of
error. This Court granted certiorari. 338 U.S. 865. Reversed, p. 339 U. S.
636 . Page 339 U. S. 631 MR. CHIEF JUSTICE VINSON delivered the opinion of the Court.
This case and McLaurin v. Oklahoma State Regents, post, p. 339 U. S. 637 ,
present different aspects of this general question: to what extent
does the Equal Protection Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment limit
the power of a state to distinguish between students of different
races in professional and graduate education in a state university?
Broader issues have been urged for our consideration, but we adhere
to the principle of deciding constitutional questions only in the
context of the particular case before the Court. We have frequently
reiterated that this Court will decide constitutional questions
only when necessary to the disposition of the case at hand, and
that such decisions will be drawn as narrowly as possible. Rescue Army v. Municipal Court, 331 U.
S. 549 (1947), and cases cited therein. Because of this
traditional reluctance to extend constitutional interpretations to
situations or facts which are not before the Court, much of the
excellent research and detailed argument presented in these cases
is unnecessary to their disposition.
In the instant case, petitioner filed an application for
admission to the University of Texas Law School for the February,
1946, term. His application was rejected solely because he is a
Negro. [ Footnote 1 ] Petitioner
thereupon brought this suit for mandamus against the appropriate
school officials, respondents here, to compel his admission. At
that time, there was no law school in Texas which admitted
Negroes.
The state trial court recognized that the action of the State in
denying petitioner the opportunity to gain Page 339 U. S. 632 a legal education while granting it to others deprived him of
the equal protection of the laws guaranteed by the Fourteenth
Amendment. The court did not grant the relief requested, however,
but continued the case for six months to allow the State to supply
substantially equal facilities. At the expiration of the six
months, in December, 1946, the court denied the writ on the showing
that the authorized university officials had adopted an order
calling for the opening of a law school for Negroes the following
February. While petitioner's appeal was pending, such a school was
made available, but petitioner refused to register therein. The
Texas Court of Civil Appeals set aside the trial court's judgment
and ordered the cause "remanded generally to the trial court for
further proceedings without prejudice to the rights of any party to
this suit."
On remand, a hearing was held on the issue of the equality of
the educational facilities at the newly established school as
compared with the University of Texas Law School. Finding that the
new school offered petitioner
"privileges, advantages, and opportunities for the study of law
substantially equivalent to those offered by the State to white
students at the University of Texas,"
the trial court denied mandamus. The Court of Civil Appeals
affirmed. 210 S.W.2d 442 (1948). Petitioner's application for a
writ of error was denied by the Texas Supreme Court. We granted
certiorari, 338 U.S. 865 (1949), because of the manifest importance
of the constitutional issues involved.
The University of Texas Law School, from which petitioner was
excluded, was staffed by a faculty of sixteen full-time and three
part-time professors, some of whom are nationally recognized
authorities in their field. Its student body numbered 850. The
library contained over 65,000 volumes. Among the other facilities
available to the students were a law review, moot court
facilities, Page 339 U. S. 633 scholarship funds, and Order of the Coif affiliation. The
school's alumni occupy the most distinguished positions in the
private practice of the law and in the public life of the State. It
may properly be considered one of the nation's ranking law
schools.
The law school for Negroes which was to have opened in February,
1947, would have had no independent faculty or library. The
teaching was to be carried on by four members of the University of
Texas Law School faculty, who were to maintain their offices at the
University of Texas while teaching at both institutions. Few of the
10,000 volumes ordered for the library had arrived, [ Footnote 2 ] nor was there any full-time
librarian. The school lacked accreditation.
Since the trial of this case, respondents report the opening of
a law school at the Texas State University for Negroes. It is
apparently on the road to full accreditation. It has a faculty of
five full-time professors; a student body of 23; a library of some
16,500 volumes serviced by a full-time staff; a practice court and
legal aid association, and one alumnus who has become a member of
the Texas Bar.
Whether the University of Texas Law School is compared with the
original or the new law school for Negroes, we cannot find
substantial equality in the educational opportunities offered white
and Negro law students by the State. In terms of number of the
faculty, variety of courses and opportunity for specialization,
size of the student body, scope of the library, availability of
law Page 339 U. S. 634 review and similar activities, the University of Texas Law
School is superior. What is more important, the University of Texas
Law School possesses to a far greater degree those qualities which
are incapable of objective measurement but which make for greatness
in a law school. Such qualities, to name but a few, include
reputation of the faculty, experience of the administration,
position and influence of the alumni, standing in the community,
traditions and prestige. It is difficult to believe that one who
had a free choice between these law schools would consider the
question close.
Moreover, although the law is a highly learned profession, we
are well aware that it is an intensely practical one. The law
school, the proving ground for legal learning and practice, cannot
be effective in isolation from the individuals and institutions
with which the law interacts. Few students and no one who has
practiced law would choose to study in an academic vacuum, removed
from the interplay of ideas and the exchange of views with which
the law is concerned. The law school to which Texas is willing to
admit petitioner excludes from its student body members of the
racial groups which number 85% of the population of the State and
include most of the lawyers, witnesses, jurors, judges and other
officials with whom petitioner will inevitably be dealing when he
becomes a member of the Texas Bar. With such a substantial and
significant segment of society excluded, we cannot conclude that
the education offered petitioner is substantially equal to that
which he would receive if admitted to the University of Texas Law
School.
It may be argued that excluding petitioner from that school is
no different from excluding white students from the new law school.
This contention overlooks realities. It is unlikely that a member
of a group so decisively in the majority, attending a school with
rich traditions and Page 339 U. S. 635 prestige which only a history of consistently maintained
excellence could command, would claim that the opportunities
afforded him for legal education were unequal to those held open to
petitioner. That such a claim, if made, would be dishonored by the
State is no answer. "Equal protection of the laws is not achieved
through indiscriminate imposition of inequalities." Shelley v.
Kraemer, 334 U. S. 1 , 334 U. S. 22 (1948).
It is fundamental that these cases concern rights which are
personal and present. This Court has stated unanimously that
"The State must provide [legal education] for [petitioner] in
conformity with the equal protection clause of the Fourteenth
Amendment and provide it as soon as it does for applicants of any
other group." Sipuel v. Board of Regents, 332 U.
S. 631 , 332 U. S. 633 (1948). That case
"did not present the issue whether a state might not satisfy the
equal protection clause of the Fourteenth Amendment by establishing
a separate law school for Negroes." Fisher v. Hurst, 333 U. S. 147 , 333 U. S. 150 (1948). In Missouri ex rel. Gaines v. Canada, 305 U.
S. 337 , 305 U. S. 351 (1938), the Court, speaking through Chief Justice Hughes, declared
that
"petitioner's right was a personal one. It was as an individual
that he was entitled to the equal protection of the laws, and the
State was bound to furnish him within its borders facilities for
legal education substantially equal to those which the State there
afforded for persons of the white race, whether or not other
negroes sought the same opportunity."
These are the only cases in this Court which present the issue
of the constitutional validity of race distinctions in state
supported graduate and professional education.
In accordance with these cases, petitioner may claim his full
constitutional right: legal education equivalent to that offered by
the State to students of other races. Such education is not
available to him in a separate law school as offered by the State.
We cannot, therefore, Page 339 U. S. 636 agree with respondents that the doctrine of Plessy v.
Ferguson, 163 U. S. 537 (1896), requires affirmance of the judgment below. Nor need we
reach petitioner's contention that Plessy v. Ferguson should be reexamined in the light of contemporary knowledge
respecting the purposes of the Fourteenth Amendment and the effects
of racial segregation. See supra, p. 339 U. S.
631 .
We hold that the Equal Protection Clause of the Fourteenth
Amendment requires that petitioner be admitted to the University of
Texas Law School. The judgment is reversed, and the cause is
remanded for proceedings not inconsistent with this opinion. Reversed. [ Footnote 1 ]
It appears that the University has been restricted to white
students, in accordance with the State law. See Tex.Const., Art. VII, §§ 7, 14; Tex.Rev.Civ.Stat. (Vernon, 1925),
Arts. 2643b (Supp. 1949), 2719, 2900.
[ Footnote 2 ]
"Students of the interim School of Law of the Texas State
University for Negroes [located in Austin, whereas the permanent
School was to be located at Houston] shall have use of the State
Law Library in the Capitol Building. . . ."
Tex.Laws 1947, c. 29, § 11, Tex.Rev.Civ.Stat. (Vernon, 1949
Supp.), note to Art. 2643b. It is not clear that this privilege was
anything more than was extended to all citizens of the State. | The Supreme Court ruled that Heman Marion Sweatt, a black man, must be admitted to the University of Texas Law School, as the separate law school established for black students did not offer substantially equal educational opportunities. The Court found that the educational benefits of the University of Texas Law School, including its faculty, student body, library, and other resources, were significantly superior to those of the separate law school for black students. The Court held that the Equal Protection Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment requires states to provide equal educational opportunities for students of all races and that separate educational facilities are inherently unequal. This ruling contributed to the dismantling of racial segregation in education and set a precedent for future civil rights cases. |
Equal Protection | Brown v. Board of Education | https://supreme.justia.com/cases/federal/us/344/141/ | U.S. Supreme Court Brown v. Board of Education, 344
U.S. 141 (1952) Brown v. Board of
Education No. 8 November 24, 1952 344
U.S. 141 APPEAL FROM THE UNITED STATES
DISTRICT COURT FOR THE DISTRICT OF
KANSAS Syllabus This is an appeal from a decision of the District Court
sustaining the constitutionality of a state statute which
authorized racial segregation in the public schools of Kansas. In
the District Court, the State intervened and defended the
constitutionality of the statute, but neither the State nor any of
the other appellees has entered an appearance or filed a brief
here. Because of the importance of the issue, this Court requests
that the State present its views at the oral argument. If the State
does not desire to appear, the Attorney General of the State is
requested to advise this Court whether the State's default shall be
construed as a concession of the invalidity of the statute. Pp. 344 U. S.
141 -142.
The decision below is reported in 98 F. Supp.
797 .
PER CURIAM.
This action was instituted by the appellants attacking a Kansas
statute which authorized segregation in the schools of that State.
It was urged that the Kansas was without power to enact such
legislation, claimed by appellants to be in contravention of the
Fourteenth Amendment.
In the District Court, the State, by its Governor and Attorney
General, intervened and defended the constitutionality of the
statute. The court upheld its validity, 98 F.
Supp. 797 .
In this Court, the appellants continue their constitutional
attack. No appearance has been entered here by Page 344 U. S. 142 the State of Kansas, the Board of Education of Topeka, and the
other appellees; nor have they presented any brief in support of
the statute's validity. The Court has been advised by counsel for
the Board of Education that it does not propose to appear in oral
argument or present a brief.
Because of the national importance of the issue presented and
because of its importance to the Kansas, we request that the State
present its views at oral argument. If the State does not desire to
appear, we request the Attorney General to advise whether the
State's default shall be construed as a concession of
invalidity.
Order accordingly. | In Brown v. Board of Education (1952), the U.S. Supreme Court addressed the constitutionality of racial segregation in public schools, inviting the state of Kansas to present its views during oral arguments. The case challenged a Kansas statute authorizing school segregation, with the state defending its validity in the District Court. However, neither the state nor other appellees entered an appearance or filed briefs in the Supreme Court, leading the Court to request the state's participation in oral arguments and guidance on the implications of its absence. |
Equal Protection | Loving v. Virginia | https://supreme.justia.com/cases/federal/us/388/1/ | U.S. Supreme Court Loving v. Virginia, 388 U.S. 1 (1967) Loving v. Virginia No. 395 Argued April 10, 1967 Decided June 12, 1967 388 U.S.
1 APPEAL FROM THE SUPREME COURT OF APPEALS OF
VIRGINIA Syllabus Virginia's statutory scheme to prevent marriages between persons
solely on the basis of racial classifications held to violate the
Equal Protection and Due Process Clauses of the Fourteenth
Amendment. Pp. 388 U. S.
4 -12.
206 Va. 924, 147 S.E.2d 78, reversed. Page 388 U. S. 2 MR. CHIEF JUSTICE WARREN delivered the opinion of the Court.
This case presents a constitutional question never addressed by
this Court: whether a statutory scheme adopted by the State of
Virginia to prevent marriages between persons solely on the basis
of racial classifications violates the Equal Protection and Due
Process Clauses of the Fourteenth Amendment. [ Footnote 1 ] For reasons which seem to us to reflect the
central meaning of those constitutional commands, we conclude that
these statutes cannot stand consistently with the Fourteenth
Amendment.
In June, 1958, two residents of Virginia, Mildred Jeter, a Negro
woman, and Richard Loving, a white man, were married in the
District of Columbia pursuant to its laws. Shortly after their
marriage, the Lovings returned to Virginia and established their
marital abode in Caroline County. At the October Term, 1958, of the
Circuit Court Page 388 U. S. 3 of Caroline County, a grand jury issued an indictment charging
the Lovings with violating Virginia's ban on interracial marriages.
On January 6, 1959, the Lovings pleaded guilty to the charge, and
were sentenced to one year in jail; however, the trial judge
suspended the sentence for a period of 25 years on the condition
that the Lovings leave the State and not return to Virginia
together for 25 years. He stated in an opinion that:
"Almighty God created the races white, black, yellow, malay and
red, and he placed them on separate continents. And, but for the
interference with his arrangement, there would be no cause for such
marriage. The fact that he separated the races shows that he did
not intend for the races to mix."
After their convictions, the Lovings took up residence in the
District of Columbia. On November 6, 1963, they filed a motion in
the state trial court to vacate the judgment and set aside the
sentence on the ground that the statutes which they had violated
were repugnant to the Fourteenth Amendment. The motion not having
been decided by October 28, 1964, the Lovings instituted a class
action in the United States District Court for the Eastern District
of Virginia requesting that a three-judge court be convened to
declare the Virginia anti-miscegenation statutes unconstitutional
and to enjoin state officials from enforcing their convictions. On
January 22, 1965, the state trial judge denied the motion to vacate
the sentences, and the Lovings perfected an appeal to the Supreme
Court of Appeals of Virginia. On February 11, 1965, the three-judge
District Court continued the case to allow the Lovings to present
their constitutional claims to the highest state court.
The Supreme Court of Appeals upheld the constitutionality of the
anti-miscegenation statutes and, after Page 388 U. S. 4 modifying the sentence, affirmed the convictions. [ Footnote 2 ] The Lovings appealed this decision, and we
noted probable jurisdiction on December 12, 1966, 385 U.S. 986.
The two statutes under which appellants were convicted and
sentenced are part of a comprehensive statutory scheme aimed at
prohibiting and punishing interracial marriages. The Lovings were
convicted of violating § 258 of the Virginia Code:
" Leaving State to evade law. -- If any white person and
colored person shall go out of this State, for the purpose of being
married, and with the intention of returning, and be married out of
it, and afterwards return to and reside in it, cohabiting as man
and wife, they shall be punished as provided in § 20-59, and the
marriage shall be governed by the same law as if it had been
solemnized in this State. The fact of their cohabitation here as
man and wife shall be evidence of their marriage."
Section 259, which defines the penalty for miscegenation,
provides:
" Punishment for marriage. -- If any white person
intermarry with a colored person, or any colored person intermarry
with a white person, he shall be guilty of a felony and shall be
punished by confinement in the penitentiary for not less than one
nor more than five years."
Other central provisions in the Virginia statutory scheme are §
20-57, which automatically voids all marriages between "a white
person and a colored person" without any judicial proceeding,
[ Footnote 3 ] and §§ 20-54 and 1-14 which, Page 388 U. S. 5 respectively, define "white persons" and "colored persons and
Indians" for purposes of the statutory prohibitions. [ Footnote 4 ] The Lovings have never disputed in the course
of this litigation that Mrs. Loving is a "colored person" or that
Mr. Loving is a "white person" within the meanings given those
terms by the Virginia statutes. Page 388 U. S. 6 Virginia is now one of 16 States which prohibit and punish
marriages on the basis of racial classifications. [ Footnote 5 ] Penalties for miscegenation arose as an
incident to slavery, and have been common in Virginia since the
colonial period. [ Footnote 6 ] The present
statutory scheme dates from the adoption of the Racial Integrity
Act of 1924, passed during the period of extreme nativism which
followed the end of the First World War. The central features of
this Act, and current Virginia law, are the absolute prohibition of
a "white person" marrying other than another "white person,"
[ Footnote 7 ] a prohibition against issuing
marriage licenses until the issuing official is satisfied that Page 388 U. S. 7 the applicants' statements as to their race are correct,
[ Footnote 8 ] certificates of "racial composition"
to be kept by both local and state registrars, [ Footnote 9 ] and the carrying forward of earlier
prohibitions against racial intermarriage. [ Footnote
10 ] I In upholding the constitutionality of these provisions in the
decision below, the Supreme Court of Appeals of Virginia referred
to its 1965 decision in Naim v. Naim, 197 Va. 80, 87
S.E.2d 749, as stating the reasons supporting the validity of these
laws. In Naim, the state court concluded that the State's
legitimate purposes were "to preserve the racial integrity of its
citizens," and to prevent "the corruption of blood," "a mongrel
breed of citizens," and "the obliteration of racial pride,"
obviously an endorsement of the doctrine of White Supremacy. Id. at 90, 87 S.E.2d at 756. The court also reasoned that
marriage has traditionally been subject to state regulation without
federal intervention, and, consequently, the regulation of marriage
should be left to exclusive state control by the Tenth
Amendment.
While the state court is no doubt correct in asserting that
marriage is a social relation subject to the State's police power, Maynard v. Hill, 125 U. S. 190 (1888), the State does not contend in its argument before this
Court that its powers to regulate marriage are unlimited
notwithstanding the commands of the Fourteenth Amendment. Nor could
it do so in light of Meyer v. Nebraska, 262 U.
S. 390 (1923), and Skinner v. Oklahoma, 316 U. S. 535 (1942). Instead, the State argues that the meaning of the Equal
Protection Clause, as illuminated by the statements of the Framers,
is only that state penal laws containing an interracial element Page 388 U. S. 8 as part of the definition of the offense must apply equally to
whites and Negroes in the sense that members of each race are
punished to the same degree. Thus, the State contends that, because
its miscegenation statutes punish equally both the white and the
Negro participants in an interracial marriage, these statutes,
despite their reliance on racial classifications, do not constitute
an invidious discrimination based upon race. The second argument
advanced by the State assumes the validity of its equal application
theory. The argument is that, if the Equal Protection Clause does
not outlaw miscegenation statutes because of their reliance on
racial classifications, the question of constitutionality would
thus become whether there was any rational basis for a State to
treat interracial marriages differently from other marriages. On
this question, the State argues, the scientific evidence is
substantially in doubt and, consequently, this Court should defer
to the wisdom of the state legislature in adopting its policy of
discouraging interracial marriages.
Because we reject the notion that the mere "equal application"
of a statute containing racial classifications is enough to remove
the classifications from the Fourteenth Amendment's proscription of
all invidious racial discriminations, we do not accept the State's
contention that these statutes should be upheld if there is any
possible basis for concluding that they serve a rational purpose.
The mere fact of equal application does not mean that our analysis
of these statutes should follow the approach we have taken in cases
involving no racial discrimination where the Equal Protection
Clause has been arrayed against a statute discriminating between
the kinds of advertising which may be displayed on trucks in New
York City, Railway Express Agency, Inc. v. New York, 336 U. S. 106 (1949), or an exemption in Ohio's ad valorem tax for
merchandise owned by a nonresident in a storage warehouse, Allied Stores of
Ohio , Page 388 U. S. 9 Inc. v. Bowers, 358 U. S. 522 (1959). In these cases, involving distinctions not drawn according
to race, the Court has merely asked whether there is any rational
foundation for the discriminations, and has deferred to the wisdom
of the state legislatures. In the case at bar, however, we deal
with statutes containing racial classifications, and the fact of
equal application does not immunize the statute from the very heavy
burden of justification which the Fourteenth Amendment has
traditionally required of state statutes drawn according to
race.
The State argues that statements in the Thirty-ninth Congress
about the time of the passage of the Fourteenth Amendment indicate
that the Framers did not intend the Amendment to make
unconstitutional state miscegenation laws. Many of the statements
alluded to by the State concern the debates over the Freedmen's
Bureau Bill, which President Johnson vetoed, and the Civil Rights
Act of 1866, 14 Stat. 27, enacted over his veto. While these
statements have some relevance to the intention of Congress in
submitting the Fourteenth Amendment, it must be understood that
they pertained to the passage of specific statutes, and not to the
broader, organic purpose of a constitutional amendment. As for the
various statements directly concerning the Fourteenth Amendment, we
have said in connection with a related problem that, although these
historical sources "cast some light" they are not sufficient to
resolve the problem;
"[a]t best, they are inconclusive. The most avid proponents of
the post-War Amendments undoubtedly intended them to remove all
legal distinctions among 'all persons born or naturalized in the
United States.' Their opponents, just as certainly, were
antagonistic to both the letter and the spirit of the Amendments,
and wished them to have the most limited effect." Brown v. Board of Education, 347 U.
S. 483 , 347 U. S. 489 (1954). See also Strauder Page 388 U. S. 10 v. West Virginia, 100 U. S. 303 , 100 U. S. 310 (1880). We have rejected the proposition that the debates in the
Thirty-ninth Congress or in the state legislatures which ratified
the Fourteenth Amendment supported the theory advanced by the
State, that the requirement of equal protection of the laws is
satisfied by penal laws defining offenses based on racial
classifications so long as white and Negro participants in the
offense were similarly punished. McLaughlin v. Florida, 379 U. S. 184 (1964).
The State finds support for its "equal application" theory in
the decision of the Court in Pace v. Alabama, 106 U.
S. 583 (1883). In that case, the Court upheld a
conviction under an Alabama statute forbidding adultery or
fornication between a white person and a Negro which imposed a
greater penalty than that of a statute proscribing similar conduct
by members of the same race. The Court reasoned that the statute
could not be said to discriminate against Negroes because the
punishment for each participant in the offense was the same.
However, as recently as the 1964 Term, in rejecting the reasoning
of that case, we stated " Pace represents a limited view of
the Equal Protection Clause which has not withstood analysis in the
subsequent decisions of this Court." McLaughlin v. Florida,
supra, at 379 U. S. 188 .
As we there demonstrated, the Equal Protection Clause requires the
consideration of whether the classifications drawn by any statute
constitute an arbitrary and invidious discrimination. The clear and
central purpose of the Fourteenth Amendment was to eliminate all
official state sources of invidious racial discrimination in the
States. Slaughter-House
Cases , 16 Wall. 36, 83 U. S. 71 (1873); Strauder v. West Virginia, 100 U.
S. 303 , 100 U. S.
307 -308 (1880); Ex parte Virginia, 100 U.
S. 339 , 100 U. S.
334 -335 (1880); Shelley v. Kraemer, 334 U. S. 1 (1948); Burton v. Wilmington Parking Authority, 365 U.
S. 715 (1961). Page 388 U. S. 11 There can be no question but that Virginia's miscegenation
statutes rest solely upon distinctions drawn according to race. The
statutes proscribe generally accepted conduct if engaged in by
members of different races. Over the years, this Court has
consistently repudiated "[d]istinctions between citizens solely
because of their ancestry" as being "odious to a free people whose
institutions are founded upon the doctrine of equality." Hirabayashi v. United States, 320 U. S.
81 , 320 U. S. 100 (1943). At the very least, the Equal Protection Clause demands that
racial classifications, especially suspect in criminal statutes, be
subjected to the "most rigid scrutiny," Korematsu v. United
States, 323 U. S. 214 , 323 U. S. 216 (1944), and, if they are ever to be upheld, they must be shown to
be necessary to the accomplishment of some permissible state
objective, independent of the racial discrimination which it was
the object of the Fourteenth Amendment to eliminate. Indeed, two
members of this Court have already stated that they
"cannot conceive of a valid legislative purpose . . . which
makes the color of a person's skin the test of whether his conduct
is a criminal offense." McLaughlin v. Florida, supra, at 379 U. S. 198 (STEWART, J., joined by DOUGLAS, J., concurring).
There is patently no legitimate overriding purpose independent
of invidious racial discrimination which justifies this
classification. The fact that Virginia prohibits only interracial
marriages involving white persons demonstrates that the racial
classifications must stand on their own justification, as measures
designed to maintain White Supremacy. [ Footnote
11 ] We have consistently denied Page 388 U. S. 12 the constitutionality of measures which restrict the rights of
citizens on account of race. There can be no doubt that restricting
the freedom to marry solely because of racial classifications
violates the central meaning of the Equal Protection Clause. II These statutes also deprive the Lovings of liberty without due
process of law in violation of the Due Process Clause of the
Fourteenth Amendment. The freedom to marry has long been recognized
as one of the vital personal rights essential to the orderly
pursuit of happiness by free men.
Marriage is one of the "basic civil rights of man," fundamental
to our very existence and survival. Skinner v. Oklahoma, 316 U. S. 535 , 316 U. S. 541 (1942). See also Maynard v. Hill, 125 U.
S. 190 (1888). To deny this fundamental freedom on so
unsupportable a basis as the racial classifications embodied in
these statutes, classifications so directly subversive of the
principle of equality at the heart of the Fourteenth Amendment, is
surely to deprive all the State's citizens of liberty without due
process of law. The Fourteenth Amendment requires that the freedom
of choice to marry not be restricted by invidious racial
discriminations. Under our Constitution, the freedom to marry, or
not marry, a person of another race resides with the individual,
and cannot be infringed by the State.
These convictions must be reversed. It is so ordered. Page 388 U. S. 13 [ Footnote 1 ]
Section 1 of the Fourteenth Amendment provides:
"All persons born or naturalized in the United States and
subject to the jurisdiction thereof, are citizens of the United
States and of the State wherein they reside. No State shall make or
enforce any law which shall abridge the privileges or immunities of
citizens of the United States; nor shall any State deprive any
person of life, liberty, or property, without due process of law;
nor deny to any person within its jurisdiction the equal protection
of the laws."
[ Footnote 2 ]
206 Va. 924, 147 S.E.2d 78 (1966).
[ Footnote 3 ]
Section 257 of the Virginia Code provides:
" Marriages void without decree. -- All marriages
between a white person and a colored person shall be absolutely
void without any decree of divorce or other legal process."
Va.Code Ann. § 20-57 (1960 Repl. Vol.).
[ Footnote 4 ]
Section 20-54 of the Virginia Code provides:
" Intermarriage prohibited; meaning of term 'white
persons.' -- It shall hereafter be unlawful for any white
person in this State to marry any save a white person, or a person
with no other admixture of blood than white and American Indian.
For the purpose of this chapter, the term 'white person' shall
apply only to such person as has no trace whatever of any blood
other than Caucasian; but persons who have one-sixteenth or less of
the blood of the American Indian and have no other non-Caucasic
blood shall be deemed to be white persons. All laws heretofore
passed and now in effect regarding the intermarriage of white and
colored persons shall apply to marriages prohibited by this
chapter."
Va.Code Ann. § 20-54 (1960 Repl. Vol.).
The exception for persons with less than one-sixteenth "of the
blood of the American Indian" is apparently accounted for, in the
words of a tract issued by the Registrar of the State Bureau of
Vital Statistics, by "the desire of all to recognize as an integral
and honored part of the white race the descendants of John Rolfe
and Pocathontas. . . ." Plecker, The New Family and Race
Improvement, 17 Va.Health Bull., Extra No. 12, at 25-26 (New Family
Series No. 5, 1925), cited in Wadlington, The Loving Case:
Virginia's Anti-Miscegenation Statute in Historical Perspective, 52
Va.L.Rev. 1189, 1202, n. 93 (1966).
Section 1-14 of the Virginia Code provides:
" Colored persons and Indians defined. -- Every person
in whom there is ascertainable any Negro blood shall be deemed and
taken to be a colored person, and every person not a colored person
having one fourth or more of American Indian blood shall be deemed
an American Indian; except that members of Indian tribes existing
in this Commonwealth having one fourth or more of Indian blood and
less than one sixteenth of Negro blood shall be deemed tribal
Indians."
Va.Code Ann. § 1-14 (1960 Repl. Vol.).
[ Footnote 5 ]
After the initiation of this litigation, Maryland repealed its
prohibitions against interracial marriage, Md.Laws 1967, c. 6,
leaving Virginia and 15 other States with statutes outlawing
interracial marriage: Alabama, Ala.Const., Art. 4, § 102, Ala.Code,
Tit. 14, § 360 (1958); Arkansas, Ark.Stat.Ann. § 55-104 (1947);
Delaware, Del.Code Ann., Tit. 13, § 101 (1953); Florida,
Fla.Const., Art. 16, § 24, Fla.Stat. § 741.11 (1965); Georgia,
Ga.Code Ann. § 53-106 (1961); Kentucky, Ky.Rev.Stat.Ann. § 402.020
(Supp. 1966); Louisiana, La.Rev.Stat. § 14:79 (1950); Mississippi,
Miss.Const., Art. 14, § 263, Miss.Code Ann. § 459 (1956); Missouri,
Mo.Rev.Stat. § 451.020 (Supp. 1966); North Carolina, N.C.Const.,
Art. XIV, § 8, N.C.Gen.Stat. § 14-181 (1953); Oklahoma, Okla.Stat.,
Tit. 43, § 12 (Supp. 1965); South Carolina, S.C.Const., Art. 3, §
33, S.C.Code Ann. § 20-7 (1962); Tennessee, Tenn.Const., Art. 11, §
14, Tenn.Code Ann. § 36-402 (1955); Texas, Tex.Pen.Code, Art. 492
(1952); West Virginia, W.Va.Code Ann. § 4697 (1961).
Over the past 15 years, 14 States have repealed laws outlawing
interracial marriages: Arizona, California, Colorado, Idaho,
Indiana, Maryland, Montana, Nebraska, Nevada, North Dakota, Oregon,
South Dakota, Utah, and Wyoming.
The first state court to recognize that miscegenation statutes
violate the Equal Protection Clause was the Supreme Court of
California. Perez v. Sharp, 32 Cal. 2d
711 , 198 P.2d 17 (1948).
[ Footnote 6 ]
For a historical discussion of Virginia's miscegenation
statutes, see Wadlington, supra, n 4.
[ Footnote 7 ]
Va.Code Ann. § 20-54 (1960 Repl. Vol.).
[ Footnote 8 ]
Va.Code Ann. § 20-53 (1960 Repl. Vol.).
[ Footnote 9 ]
Va.Code Ann. § 20-50 (1960 Repl. Vol.).
[ Footnote 10 ]
Va.Code Ann. § 254 (1960 Repl. Vol.).
[ Footnote 11 ]
Appellants point out that the State's concern in these statutes,
as expressed in the words of the 1924 Act's title, "An Act to
Preserve Racial Integrity," extends only to the integrity of the
white race. While Virginia prohibits whites from marrying any
nonwhite (subject to the exception for the descendants of
Pocahontas), Negroes, Orientals, and any other racial class may
intermarry without statutory interference. Appellants contend that
this distinction renders Virginia's miscegenation statutes
arbitrary and unreasonable even assuming the constitutional
validity of an official purpose to preserve "racial integrity." We
need not reach this contention, because we find the racial
classifications in these statutes repugnant to the Fourteenth
Amendment, even assuming an even-handed state purpose to protect
the "integrity" of all races.
MR. JUSTICE STEWART, concurring.
I have previously expressed the belief that "it is simply not
possible for a state law to be valid under our Constitution which
makes the criminality of an act depend upon the race of the actor." McLaughlin v. Florida, 379 U. S. 184 , 379 U. S. 198 (concurring opinion). Because I adhere to that belief, I concur in
the judgment of the Court. | In the case of Loving v. Virginia (1967), the U.S. Supreme Court ruled that laws prohibiting interracial marriage violate the Equal Protection and Due Process Clauses of the Fourteenth Amendment. The Court struck down Virginia's anti-miscegenation laws, which had prevented interracial couples from marrying solely based on racial classifications. The ruling ended the enforcement of such laws across the United States, affirming the right of individuals to marry regardless of race. |
Equal Protection | Swann v. Charlotte-Mecklenburg Board of Education | https://supreme.justia.com/cases/federal/us/402/1/ | U.S. Supreme Court Swann v. Charlotte-Mecklenburg Bd. of
Educ., 402 U.S. 1 (1971) Swann v. Charlotte-Mecklenburg Board
of Education No. 281 Argued October 12,
1970 Decided April 20, 1971 402 U.S.
1 ast|>* 402 U.S.
1 CERTIORARI TO THE UNITED STATES
COURT OF APPEALS FOR THE FOURTH
CIRCUIT Syllabus The Charlotte-Mecklenburg school system, which includes the city
of Charlotte, North Carolina, had more than 84,000 students in 107
schools in the 1968-1969 school year. Approximately 29% (24,000) of
the pupils were Negro, about 14,000 of whom attended 21 schools
that were at least 99% Negro. This resulted from a desegregation
plan approved by the District Court in 1965, at the commencement of
this litigation. In 1968, petitioner Swann moved for further relief
based on Green v. County School Board, 391 U.
S. 430 , which required school boards to
"come forward with a plan that promises realistically to work .
. . now . . . until it is clear that state-imposed segregation has
been completely removed."
The District Court ordered the school board in April 1969 to
provide a plan for faculty and student desegregation. Finding the
board's submission unsatisfactory, the District Court appointed an
expert to submit a desegregation plan. In February 1970, the expert
and the board presented plans, and the court adopted the board's
plan, as modified, for the junior and senior high schools, and the
expert's proposed plan for the elementary schools. The Court of
Appeals affirmed the District Court's order as to faculty
desegregation and the secondary school plans, Page 402 U. S. 2 but vacated the order respecting elementary schools, fearing
that the provisions for pairing and grouping of elementary schools
would unreasonably burden the pupils and the board. The case was
remanded to the District Court for reconsideration and submission
of further plans. This Court granted certiorari and directed
reinstatement of the District Court's order pending further
proceedings in that court. On remand the District Court received
two new plans, and ordered the board to adopt a plan, or the
expert's plan would remain in effect. After the board "acquiesced"
in the expert's plan, the District Court directed that it remain in
effect. Held: 1. Today's objective is to eliminate from the public schools all
vestiges of state-imposed segregation that was held violative of
equal protection guarantees by Brown v. Board of
Education, 347 U. S. 483 , in
1954. P. 402 U. S. 15 .
2. In default by the school authorities of their affirmative
obligation to proffer acceptable remedies, the district courts have
broad power to fashion remedies that will assure unitary school
systems. P. 402 U. S. 16 .
3. Title IV of the Civil Rights Act of 1964 does not restrict or
withdraw from the federal courts their historic equitable remedial
powers. The proviso in 42 U.S.C. § 2000c-6 was designed simply to
foreclose any interpretation of the Act as expanding the existing
powers of the federal courts to enforce the Equal Protection
Clause. Pp. 402 U. S.
16 -18.
4. Policy and practice with regard to faculty, staff,
transportation, extracurricular activities, and facilities are
among the most important indicia of a segregated system, and the
first remedial responsibility of school authorities is to eliminate
invidious racial distinctions in those respects. Normal
administrative practice should then produce schools of like
quality, facilities, and staffs. Pp. 402 U. S.
18 -19.
5. The Constitution does not prohibit district courts from using
their equity power to order assignment of teachers to achieve a
particular degree of faculty desegregation. United States v.
Montgomery County Board of Education, 395 U.
S. 225 , was properly followed by the lower courts in
this case. Pp. 402 U. S.
19 -20.
6. In devising remedies to eliminate legally imposed
segregation, local authorities and district courts must see to it
that future school construction and abandonment are not used and do
not serve to perpetuate or reestablish a dual system. Pp. 402 U. S.
20 -21. Page 402 U. S. 3 7. Four problem areas exist on the issue of student
assignment:
(1) Racial quotas. The constitutional command to
desegregate schools does not mean that every school in the
community must always reflect the racial composition of the system
as a whole; here the District Court's very limited use of the
racial ratio -- not as an inflexible requirement, but as a starting
point in shaping a remedy -- was within its equitable discretion.
Pp. 402 U. S.
22 -25.
(2) One-race schools. While the existence of a small
number of one-race, or virtually one-race, schools does not, in
itself, denote a system that still practices segregation by law,
the court should scrutinize such schools and require the school
authorities to satisfy the court that the racial composition does
not result from present or past discriminatory action on their
part. Pp. 402 U. S.
25 -26.
An optional majority-to-minority transfer provision has long
been recognized as a useful part of a desegregation plan, and to be
effective such arrangement must provide the transferring student
free transportation and available space in the school to which he
desires to move. Pp. 402 U. S.
26 -27.
(3) Attendance zones. The remedial altering of
attendance zones is not, as an interim corrective measure, beyond
the remedial powers of a district court. A student assignment plan
is not acceptable merely because it appears to be neutral, for such
a plan may fail to counteract the continuing effects of past school
segregation. The pairing and grouping of noncontiguous zones is a
permissible tool; judicial steps going beyond contiguous zones
should be examined in light of the objectives to be sought. No
rigid rules can be laid down to govern conditions in different
localities. Pp. 402 U. S.
27 -29.
(4) Transportation. The District Court's conclusion
that assignment of children to the school nearest their home
serving their grade would not effectively dismantle the dual school
system is supported by the record, and the remedial technique of
requiring bus transportation as a tool of school desegregation was
within that court's power to provide equitable relief. An objection
to transportation of students may have validity when the time or
distance of travel is so great as to risk either the health of the
children or significantly impinge on the educational process;
limits on travel time will vary with many factors, but probably
with none more than the age of the students. Pp. 402 U. S.
29 -31. Page 402 U. S. 4 8. Neither school authorities nor district courts are
constitutionally required to make year-by-year adjustments of the
racial composition of student bodies once a unitary system has been
achieved. Pp. 402 U. S.
31 -32.
431 F.2d 138, affirmed as to those parts in which it affirmed
the District Court's judgment. The District Court's order of August
7, 1970, is also affirmed.
BURGER, C.J., delivered the opinion for a unanimous Court. Page 402 U. S. 5 MR. CHIEF JUSTICE BURGER delivered the opinion of the Court.
We granted certiorari in this case to review important issues as
to the duties of school authorities and the scope of powers of
federal courts under this Court's mandates to eliminate racially
separate public schools established and maintained by state action. Brown v. Board of Education, 347 U.
S. 483 (1954) ( Brown I ).
This case and those argued with it [ Footnote 1 ] arose in States having a long history of
maintaining two sets of schools in a Page 402 U. S. 6 single school system deliberately operated to carry out a
governmental policy to separate pupils in schools solely on the
basis of race. That was what Brown v. Board of Education was all about. These cases present us with the problem of defining
in more precise terms than heretofore the scope of the duty of
school authorities and district courts in implementing Brown
I and the mandate to eliminate dual systems and establish
unitary systems at once. Meanwhile, district courts and courts of
appeals have struggled in hundreds of cases with a multitude and
variety of problems under this Court's general directive.
Understandably, in an area of evolving remedies, those courts had
to improvise and experiment without detailed or specific
guidelines. This Court, in Brown I, appropriately dealt
with the large constitutional principles; other federal courts had
to grapple with the flinty, intractable realities of day-to-day
implementation of those constitutional commands. Their efforts, of
necessity, embraced a process of "trial and error," and our effort
to formulate guidelines must take into account their
experience. I The Charlotte-Mecklenburg school system, the 43d largest in the
Nation, encompasses the city of Charlotte and surrounding
Mecklenburg County, North Carolina. The area is large -- 550 square
miles --spanning roughly 22 miles east-west and 36 miles
north-south. During the 1968-1969 school year, the system served
more than 84,000 pupils in 107 schools. Approximately 71% of the
pupils were found to be white, and 29% Negro. As of Page 402 U. S. 7 June, 1969, there were approximately 24,000 Negro students in
the system, of whom 21,000 attended schools within the city of
Charlotte. Two-thirds of those 21,000 -- approximately 14,000 Negro
students -- attended 21 schools which were either totally Negro or
more than 99% Negro.
This situation came about under a desegregation plan approved by
the District Court at the commencement of the present litigation in
1965, 243 F.
Supp. 667 (WDNC), aff'd, 369 F.2d 29 (CA4 1966), based
upon geographic zoning with a free transfer provision. The present
proceedings were initiated in September, 1968, by petitioner
Swann's motion for further relief based on Green v. County
School Board, 391 U. S. 430 (1968), and its companion cases. [ Footnote 2 ] All parties now agree that in 1969 the system
fell short of achieving the unitary school system that those cases
require.
The District Court held numerous hearings and received
voluminous evidence. In addition to finding certain actions of the
school board to be discriminatory, the court also found that
residential patterns in the city and county resulted in part from
federal, state, and local government action other than school board
decisions. School board action based on these patterns, for
example, by locating schools in Negro residential areas and fixing
the size of the schools to accommodate the needs of immediate
neighborhoods, resulted in segregated education. These findings
were subsequently accepted by the Court of Appeals.
In April, 1969, the District Court ordered the school board to
come forward with a plan for both faculty and student
desegregation. Proposed plans were accepted by the court in June
and August, 1969, on an interim basis Page 402 U. S. 8 only, and the board was ordered to file a third plan by
November, 1969. In November, the board moved for an extension of
time until February, 1970, but when that was denied the board
submitted a partially completed plan. In December, 1969, the
District Court held that the board's submission was unacceptable
and appointed an expert in education administration, Dr. John
Finger, to prepare a desegregation plan. Thereafter in February,
1970, the District Court was presented with two alternative pupil
assignment plan the finalized "board plan" and the "Finger
plan." The Board Plan. As finally submitted, the school board
plan closed seven schools and reassigned their pupils. It
restructured school attendance zones to achieve greater racial
balance but maintained existing grade structures and rejected
techniques such as pairing and clustering as part of a
desegregation effort. The plan created a single athletic league,
eliminated the previously racial basis of the school bus system,
provided racially mixed faculties and administrative staffs, and
modified its free-transfer plan into an optional
majority-to-minority transfer system.
The board plan proposed substantial assignment of Negroes to
nine of the system's 10 high schools, producing 17% to 36% Negro
population in each. The projected Negro attendance at the 10th
school, Independence, was 2%. The proposed attendance zones for the
high schools were typically shaped like wedges of a pie, extending
outward from the center of the city to the suburban and rural areas
of the county in order to afford residents of the center city area
access to outlying schools.
As for junior high schools, the board plan rezoned the 21 school
areas so that, in 20, the Negro attendance would range from 0% to
38%. The other school, located in the heart of the Negro
residential area, was left with an enrollment of 90% Negro. Page 402 U. S. 9 The board plan with respect to elementary schools relied
entirely upon gerrymandering of geographic zones. More than half of
the Negro elementary pupils were left in nine schools that were 86%
to 100% Negro; approximately half of the white elementary pupils
were assigned to schools 86% to 100% white. The Finger Plan. The plan submitted by the
court-appointed expert, Dr. Finger, adopted the school board zoning
plan for senior high schools with one modification: it required
that an additional 300 Negro students be transported from the Negro
residential area of the city to the nearly all-white Independence
High School.
The Finger plan for the junior high schools employed much of the
rezoning plan of the board, combined with the creation of nine
"satellite" zones. [ Footnote 3 ]
Under the satellite plan, inner-city Negro students were assigned
by attendance zones to nine outlying predominately white junior
high schools, thereby substantially desegregating every junior high
school in the system.
The Finger plan departed from the board plan chiefly in its
handling of the system's 76 elementary schools. Rather than relying
solely upon geographic zoning, Dr. Finger proposed use of zoning,
pairing, and grouping techniques, with the result that student
bodies throughout the system would range from 9% to 38% Negro.
[ Footnote 4 ]
The District Court described the plan thus:
"Like the board plan, the Finger plan does as much by rezoning
school attendance lines as can reasonably Page 402 U. S. 10 be accomplished. However, unlike the board plan, it does not
stop there. It goes further and desegregates all the rest of the
elementary schools by the technique of grouping two or three
outlying schools with one black inner city school; by transporting
black students from grades one through four to the outlying white
schools; and by transporting white students from the fifth and
sixth grades from the outlying white schools to the inner city
black school."
Under the Finger plan, nine inner-city Negro schools were
grouped in this manner with 24 suburban white schools.
On February 5, 1970, the District Court adopted the board plan,
as modified by Dr. Finger, for the junior and senior high schools.
The court rejected the board elementary school plan and adopted the
Finger plan as presented. Implementation was partially stayed by
the Court of Appeals for the Fourth Circuit on March 5, and this
Court declined to disturb the Fourth Circuit's order, 397 U.S. 978
(1970).
On appeal, the Court of Appeals affirmed the District Court's
order as to faculty desegregation and the secondary school plans,
but vacated the order respecting elementary schools. While agreeing
that the District Court properly disapproved the board plan
concerning these schools, the Court of Appeals feared that the
pairing and grouping of elementary schools would place an
unreasonable burden on the board and the system's pupils. The case
was remanded to the District Court for reconsideration and
submission of further plans. 431 F.2d Page 402 U. S. 11 138. This Court granted certiorari, 399 U.S. 926, and directed
reinstatement of the District Court's order pending further
proceedings in that court.
On remand, the District Court received two new plans for the
elementary schools: a plan prepared by the United States Department
of Health, Education, and Welfare (the HEW plan) based on
contiguous grouping and zoning of schools, and a plan prepared by
four members of the nine-member school board (the minority plan)
achieving substantially the same results as the Finger plan but
apparently with slightly less transportation. A majority of the
school board declined to amend its proposal. After a lengthy
evidentiary hearing, the District Court concluded that its own plan
(the Finger plan), the minority plan, and an earlier draft of the
Finger plan were all reasonable and acceptable. It directed the
board to adopt one of the three or, in the alternative, to come
forward with a new, equally effective plan of its own; the court
ordered that the Finger plan would remain in effect in the event
the school board declined to adopt a new plan. On August 7, the
board indicated it would "acquiesce" in the Finger plan,
reiterating its view that the plan was unreasonable. The District
Court, by order dated August 7, 1970, directed that the Finger plan
remain in effect. II Nearly 17 years ago, this Court held, in explicit terms, that
state-imposed segregation by race in public schools denies equal
protection of the laws. At no time has the Court deviated in the
slightest degree from that holding or its constitutional
underpinnings. None of the parties before us challenges the Court's
decision of May 17, 1954, that,
"in the field of public education, the doctrine of 'separate but
equal' has no place. Separate educational facilities are inherently
unequal. Therefore, Page 402 U. S. 12 we hold that the plaintiffs and others similarly situated . . .
are, by reason of the segregation complained of, deprived of the
equal protection of the laws guaranteed by the Fourteenth
Amendment. . . ."
"Because these are class actions, because of the wide
applicability of this decision, and because of the great variety of
local conditions, the formulation of decrees in these cases
presents problems of considerable complexity." Brown v. Board of Education, supra, at 347 U. S.
495 .
None of the parties before us questions the Court's 1955 holding
in Brown II, that
"School authorities have the primary responsibility for
elucidating, assessing, and solving these problems; courts will
have to consider whether the action of school authorities
constitutes good faith implementation of the governing
constitutional principles. Because of their proximity to local
conditions and the possible need for further hearings, the courts
which originally heard these cases can best perform this judicial
appraisal. Accordingly, we believe it appropriate to remand the
cases to those courts."
"In fashioning and effectuating the decrees, the courts will be
guided by equitable principles. Traditionally, equity has been
characterized by a practical flexibility in shaping its remedies
and by a facility for adjusting and reconciling public and private
needs. These cases call for the exercise of these traditional
attributes of equity power. At stake is the personal interest of
the plaintiffs in admission to public schools as soon as
practicable on a nondiscriminatory basis. To effectuate this
interest may call for elimination of a variety of obstacles in
making the transition to school systems operated in accordance with
the constitutional principles set forth in our May 17, 1954,
decision. Courts of Page 402 U. S. 13 equity may properly take into account the public interest in the
elimination of such obstacles in a systematic and effective manner.
But it should go without saying that the vitality of these
constitutional principles cannot be allowed to yield simply because
of disagreement with them." Brown v. Board of Education, 349 U.
S. 294 , 349 U. S.
299 -300 (1955).
Over the 16 years since Brown II, many difficulties
were encountered in implementation of the basic constitutional
requirement that the State not discriminate between public school
children on the basis of their race. Nothing in our national
experience prior to 1955 prepared anyone for dealing with changes
and adjustments of the magnitude and complexity encountered since
then. Deliberate resistance of some to the Court's mandates has
impeded the good faith efforts of others to bring school systems
into compliance. The detail and nature of these dilatory tactics
have been noted frequently by this Court and other courts.
By the time the Court considered Green v. County School
Board, 391 U. S. 430 , in
1968, very little progress had been made in many areas where dual
school systems had historically been maintained by operation of
state laws. In Green, the Court was confronted with a
record of a freedom of choice program that the District Court had
found to operate, in fact, to preserve a dual system more than a
decade after Brown II. While acknowledging that a freedom
of choice concept could be a valid remedial measure in some
circumstances, its failure to be effective in Green required that:
"The burden on a school board today is to come forward with a
plan that promises realistically to work . . . now . . .
until it is clear that state-imposed segregation has been
completely removed." Green, supra, at 391 U. S.
439 . Page 402 U. S. 14 This was plain language, yet the 1969 Term of Court brought
fresh evidence of the dilatory tactics of many school authorities. Alexander v. Holmes County Board of Education, 396 U. S. 19 ,
restated the basic obligation asserted in Griffin v. School
Board, 377 U. S. 218 , 377 U. S. 234 (1964), and Green, supra, that the remedy must be
implemented forthwith.
The problems encountered by the district courts and courts of
appeals make plain that we should now try to amplify guidelines,
however incomplete and imperfect, for the assistance of school
authorities and courts. [ Footnote
5 ] The failure of local authorities to meet their
constitutional obligations aggravated the massive problem of
converting from the state-enforced discrimination of racially
separate school systems. This process has been rendered more
difficult by changes since 1954 in the structure and patterns of
communities, the growth of student population, [ Footnote 6 ] movement of families, and other
changes, some of which had marked impact on school planning,
sometimes neutralizing or negating remedial action before it was
fully implemented. Rural areas accustomed for half a century to the
consolidated school systems implemented by bus transportation could
make adjustments more readily than metropolitan areas with dense
and shifting population, numerous schools, congested and complex
traffic patterns. Page 402 U. S. 15 III The objective today remains to eliminate from the public schools
all vestiges of state-imposed segregation. Segregation was the evil
struck down by Brown I as contrary to the equal protection
guarantees of the Constitution. That was the violation sought to be
corrected by the remedial measures of Brown II. That was
the basis for the holding in Green that school authorities
are
"clearly charged with the affirmative duty to take whatever
steps might be necessary to convert to a unitary system in which
racial discrimination would be eliminated root and branch."
391 U.S. at 391 U. S.
437 -438.
If school authorities fail in their affirmative obligations
under these holdings, judicial authority may be invoked. Once a
right and a violation have been shown, the scope of a district
court's equitable powers to remedy past wrongs is broad, for
breadth and flexibility are inherent in equitable remedies.
"The essence of equity jurisdiction has been the power of the
Chancellor to do equity and to mould each decree to the necessities
of the particular case. Flexibility, rather than rigidity, has
distinguished it. The qualities of mercy and practicality have made
equity the instrument for nice adjustment and reconciliation
between the public interest and private needs as well as between
competing private claims." Hecht Co. v. Bowles, 321 U. S. 321 , 321 U. S.
329 -330 (1944), cited in Brown II, supra, at 347 U. S.
300 .
This allocation of responsibility once made, the Court attempted
from time to time to provide some guidelines for the exercise of
the district judge's discretion and for the reviewing function of
the courts of appeals. However, a school desegregation case does
not differ fundamentally from other cases involving the framing
of Page 402 U. S. 16 equitable remedies to repair the denial of a constitutional
right. The task is to correct, by a balancing of the individual and
collective interests, the condition that offends the
Constitution.
In seeking to define even in broad and general terms how far
this remedial power extends, it is important to remember that
judicial powers may be exercised only on the basis of a
constitutional violation. Remedial judicial authority does not put
judges automatically in the shoes of school authorities whose
powers are plenary. Judicial authority enters only when local
authority defaults.
School authorities are traditionally charged with broad power to
formulate and implement educational policy, and might well
conclude, for example, that, in order to prepare students to live
in a pluralistic society, each school should have a prescribed
ratio of Negro to white students reflecting the proportion for the
district as a whole. To do this as an educational policy is within
the broad discretionary powers of school authorities; absent a
finding of a constitutional violation, however, that would not be
within the authority of a federal court. As with any equity case,
the nature of the violation determines the scope of the remedy. In
default by the school authorities of their obligation to proffer
acceptable remedies, a district court has broad power to fashion a
remedy that will assure a unitary school system.
The school authorities argue that the equity powers of federal
district courts have been limited by Title IV of the Civil Rights
Act of 1964, 42 U.S.C. § 2000c. The language and the history of
Title IV show that it was enacted not to limit, but to define, the
role of the Federal Government in the implementation of the Brown I decision. It authorizes the Commissioner of
Education to provide technical assistance to local boards in the
preparation of desegregation plans, to arrange "training
institutes" Page 402 U. S. 17 for school personnel involved in desegregation efforts, and to
make grants directly to schools to ease the transition to unitary
systems. It also authorizes the Attorney General, in specified
circumstances, to initiate federal desegregation suits. Section
2000c(b) defines "desegregation" as it is used in Title IV:
"'Desegregation' means the assignment of students to public
schools and within such schools without regard to their race,
color, religion, or national origin, but 'desegregation' shall not
mean the assignment of students to public schools in order to
overcome racial imbalance."
Section 2000c-6, authorizing the Attorney General to institute
federal suits, contains the following proviso:
"nothing herein shall empower any official or court of the
United States to issue any order seeking to achieve a racial
balance in any school by requiring the transportation of pupils or
students from one school to another or one school district to
another in order to achieve such racial balance, or otherwise
enlarge the existing power of the court to insure compliance with
constitutional standard."
On their face, the sections quoted purport only to insure that
the provisions of Title IV of the Civil Rights Act of 1964 will not
be read as granting new powers. The proviso in § 2000c-6 is, in
terms, designed to foreclose any interpretation of the Act as
expanding the existing powers of federal courts to enforce the
Equal Protection Clause. There is no suggestion of an intention to
restrict those powers or withdraw from courts their historic
equitable remedial powers. The legislative history of Title IV
indicates that Congress was concerned that the Act might be read as
creating a right of action under the Fourteenth Amendment in the
situation of so-called " de facto segregation," where
racial imbalance exists in the Page 402 U. S. 18 schools but with no showing that this was brought about by
discriminatory action of state authorities. In short, there is
nothing in the Act that provides us material assistance in
answering the question of remedy for state-imposed segregation in
violation of Brown I. The basis of our decision must be
the prohibition of the Fourteenth Amendment that no State shall
"deny to any person within its jurisdiction the equal protection of
the laws." IV We turn now to the problem of defining with more particularity
the responsibilities of school authorities in desegregating a
state-enforced dual school system in light of the Equal Protection
Clause. Although the several related cases before us are primarily
concerned with problems of student assignment, it may be helpful to
begin with a brief discussion of other aspects of the process.
In Green, we pointed out that existing policy and
practice with regard to faculty, staff, transportation,
extracurricular activities, and facilities were among the most
important indicia of a segregated system. 391 U.S. at 391 U. S. 435 .
Independent of student assignment, where it is possible to identify
a "white school" or a "Negro school" simply by reference to the
racial composition of teachers and staff, the quality of school
buildings and equipment, or the organization of sports activities,
a prima facie case of violation of substantive
constitutional rights under the Equal Protection Clause is
shown.
When a system has been dual in these respects, the first
remedial responsibility of school authorities is to eliminate
invidious racial distinctions. With respect to such matters as
transportation, supporting personnel, and extracurricular
activities, no more than this may be necessary. Similar corrective
action must be taken with regard to the maintenance of buildings
and the distribution of equipment. In these areas, normal
administrative Page 402 U. S. 19 practice should produce schools of like quality, facilities, and
staffs. Something more must be said, however, as to faculty
assignment and new school construction.
In the companion Davis case, post, p. 402 U. S. 33 , the
Mobile school board has argued that the Constitution requires that
teachers be assigned on a "color blind" basis. It also argues that
the Constitution prohibits district courts from using their equity
power to order assignment of teachers to achieve a particular
degree of faculty desegregation. We reject that contention.
In United States v. Montgomery County Board of
Education, 395 U. S. 225 (1969), the District Court set as a goal a plan of faculty
assignment in each school with a ratio of white to Negro faculty
members substantially the same throughout the system. This order
was predicated on the District Court finding that:
"The evidence does not reflect any real administrative problems
involved in immediately desegregating the substitute teachers, the
student teachers, the night school faculties, and in the evolvement
of a really legally adequate program for the substantial
desegregation of the faculties of all schools in the system
commencing with the school year 1968-69."
Quoted at 395 U.S. at 395 U. S.
232 .
The District Court, in Montgomery, then proceeded to
set an initial ratio for the whole system of at least two Negro
teachers out of each 12 in any given school. The Court of Appeals
modified the order by eliminating what it regarded as "fixed
mathematical" ratios of faculty and substituted an initial
requirement of "substantially or approximately" a five-to-one
ratio. With respect to the future, the Court of Appeals held that
the numerical ratio should be eliminated and that compliance should
not be tested solely by the achievement of specified proportions. Id. at 234. Page 402 U. S. 20 We reversed the Court of Appeals and restored the District
Court's order in its entirety, holding that the order of the
District Judge
"was adopted in the spirit of this Court's opinion in Green . . . in that his plan 'promises realistically to
work, and promises realistically to work now. ' The
modifications ordered by the panel of the Court of Appeals, while
of course not intended to do so, would, we think, take from the
order some of its capacity to expedite, by means of specific
commands, the day when a completely unified, unitary,
nondiscriminatory school system becomes a reality instead of a
hope. . . . We also believe that, under all the circumstances of
this case, we follow the original plan outlined in Brown
II . . . by accepting the more specific and expeditious order
of [District] Judge Johnson. . . ."
395 U.S. at 395 U. S.
235 -236 (emphasis in original). The principles of Montgomery have been properly followed by the District
Court and the Court of Appeals in this case.
The construction of new schools and the closing of old ones are
two of the most important functions of local school authorities and
also two of the most complex. They must decide questions of
location and capacity in light of population growth, finances, land
values, site availability, through an almost endless list of
factors to be considered. The result of this will be a decision
which, when combined with one technique or another of student
assignment, will determine the racial composition of the student
body in each school in the system. Over the long run, the
consequences of the choices will be far-reaching. People gravitate
toward school facilities, just as schools are located in response
to the needs of people. The location of schools may thus
influence Page 402 U. S. 21 the patterns of residential development of a metropolitan area
and have important impact on composition of inner-city
neighborhoods.
In the past, choices in this respect have been used as a potent
weapon for creating or maintaining a state-segregated school
system. In addition to the classic pattern of building schools
specifically intended for Negro or white students, school
authorities have sometimes, since Brown, closed schools
which appeared likely to become racially mixed through changes in
neighborhood residential patterns. This was sometimes accompanied
by building new schools in the areas of white suburban expansion
farthest from Negro population centers in order to maintain the
separation of the races with a minimum departure from the formal
principles of "neighborhood zoning." Such a policy does more than
simply influence the short-run composition of the student body of a
new school. It may well promote segregated residential patterns
which, when combined with "neighborhood zoning," further lock the
school system into the mold of separation of the races. Upon a
proper showing, a district court may consider this in fashioning a
remedy.
In ascertaining the existence of legally imposed school
segregation, the existence of a pattern of school construction and
abandonment is thus a factor of great weight. In devising remedies
where legally imposed segregation has been established, it is the
responsibility of local authorities and district courts to see to
it that future school construction and abandonment are not used and
do not serve to perpetuate or reestablish the dual system. When
necessary, district courts should retain jurisdiction to assure
that these responsibilities are carried out. Cf. United States
v. Board of Public Instruction, 395 F.2d 66 (CA5 1968); Brewer v. School Board, 397 F.2d 37 (CA4 1968). Page 402 U. S. 22 V The central issue in this case is that of student assignment,
and there are essentially four problem areas:
(1) to what extent racial balance or racial quotas may be used
as an implement in a remedial order to correct a previously
segregated system;
(2) whether every all-Negro and all-white school must be
eliminated as an indispensable part of a remedial process of
desegregation;
(3) what the limits are, if any, on the rearrangement of school
districts and attendance zones, as a remedial measure; and
(4) what the limits are, if any, on the use of transportation
facilities to correct state-enforced racial school segregation.
(1) Racial Balances or Racial Quotas. The constant theme and thrust of every holding from Brown
I to date is that state-enforced separation of races in public
schools is discrimination that violates the Equal Protection
Clause. The remedy commanded was to dismantle dual school
systems.
We are concerned in these cases with the elimination of the
discrimination inherent in the dual school systems, not with myriad
factors of human existence which can cause discrimination in a
multitude of ways on racial, religious, or ethnic grounds. The
target of the cases from Brown I to the present was the
dual school system. The elimination of racial discrimination in
public schools is a large task, and one that should not be retarded
by efforts to achieve broader purposes lying beyond the
jurisdiction of school authorities. One vehicle can carry only a
limited amount of baggage. It would not serve the important
objective of Brown I to seek to use school desegregation
cases for purposes beyond their scope, although desegregation of
schools ultimately will have Page 402 U. S. 23 impact on other forms of discrimination. We do not reach in this
case the question whether a showing that school segregation is a
consequence of other types of state action, without any
discriminatory action by the school authorities, is a
constitutional violation requiring remedial action by a school
desegregation decree. This case does not present that question and
we therefore do not decide it.
Our objective in dealing with the issues presented by these
cases is to see that school authorities exclude no pupil of a
racial minority from any school, directly or indirectly, on account
of race; it does not and cannot embrace all the problems of racial
prejudice, even when those problems contribute to disproportionate
racial concentrations in some schools.
In this case, it is urged that the District Court has imposed a
racial balance requirement of 71%-29% on individual schools. The
fact that no such objective was actually achieved -- and would
appear to be impossible -- tends to blunt that claim, yet in the
opinion and order of the District Court of December 1, 1969, we
find that court directing
"that efforts should be made to reach a 71-29 ratio in the
various schools so that there will be no basis for contending that
one school is racially different from the others . . . , [t]hat no
school [should] be operated with an all-black or predominantly
black student body, [and] [t]hat pupils of all grades [should] be
assigned in such a way that as nearly as practicable the various
schools at various grade levels have about the same proportion of
black and white students."
The District Judge went on to acknowledge that variation "from
that norm may be unavoidable." This contains intimations that the
"norm" is a fixed mathematical Page 402 U. S. 24 racial balance reflecting the pupil constituency of the system.
If we were to read the holding of the District Court to require, as
a matter of substantive constitutional right, any particular degree
of racial balance or mixing, that approach would be disapproved and
we would be obliged to reverse. The constitutional command to
desegregate schools does not mean that every school in every
community must always reflect the racial composition of the school
system as a whole.
As the voluminous record in this case shows, [ Footnote 7 ] the predicate for the District
Court's use of the 71%-29% ratio was twofold: first, its express
finding, approved by the Court of Appeals and not challenged here,
that a dual school system had been maintained by the school
authorities at least until 1969; second, its finding, also approved
by the Court of Appeals, that the school board had totally
defaulted in its acknowledged duty to come forward with an
acceptable plan of its own, notwithstanding the patient efforts of
the District Judge who, on at least three occasions, urged the
board to submit plans. [ Footnote
8 ] As the statement of facts shows, these findings are
abundantly Page 402 U. S. 25 supported by the record. It was because of this total failure of
the school board that the District Court was obliged to turn to
other qualified sources, and Dr. Finger was designated to assist
the District Court to do what the board should have done.
We see therefore that the use made of mathematical ratios was no
more than a starting point in the process of shaping a remedy,
rather than an inflexible requirement. From that starting point,
the District Court proceeded to frame a decree that was within its
discretionary powers, as an equitable remedy for the particular
circumstances. [ Footnote 9 ] As
we said in Green, a school authority's remedial plan or a
district court's remedial decree is to be judged by its
effectiveness. Awareness of the racial composition of the whole
school system is likely to be a useful starting point in shaping a
remedy to correct past constitutional violations. In sum, the very
limited use made of mathematical ratios was within the equitable
remedial discretion of the District Court.
(2) One-race Schools. The record in this case reveals the familiar phenomenon that, in
metropolitan areas, minority groups are often found concentrated in
one part of the city. In some circumstances, certain schools may
remain all or largely of one race until new schools can be provided
or neighborhood patterns change. Schools all or predominately Page 402 U. S. 26 of one race in a district of mixed population will require close
scrutiny to determine that school assignments are not part of
state-enforced segregation.
In light of the above, it should be clear that the existence of
some small number of one-race, or virtually one-race, schools
within a district is not, in and of itself, the mark of a system
that still practices segregation by law. The district judge or
school authorities should make every effort to achieve the greatest
possible degree of actual desegregation, and will thus necessarily
be concerned with the elimination of one-race schools. No per
se rule can adequately embrace all the difficulties of
reconciling the competing interests involved; but, in a system with
a history of segregation, the need for remedial criteria of
sufficient specificity to assure a school authority's compliance
with its constitutional duty warrants a presumption against schools
that are substantially disproportionate in their racial
composition. Where the school authority's proposed plan for
conversion from a dual to a unitary system contemplates the
continued existence of some schools that are all or predominately
of one race, they have the burden of showing that such school
assignments are genuinely nondiscriminatory. The court should
scrutinize such schools, and the burden upon the school authorities
will be to satisfy the court that their racial composition is not
the result of present or past discriminatory action on their
part.
An optional majority-to-minority transfer provision has long
been recognized as a useful part of every desegregation plan.
Provision for optional transfer of those in the majority racial
group of a particular school to other schools where they will be in
the minority is an indispensable remedy for those students willing
to transfer to other schools in order to lessen the impact on them
of the state-imposed stigma of segregation. In order to be
effective, such a transfer arrangement must grant Page 402 U. S. 27 the transferring student free transportation and space must be
made available in the school to which he desires to move. Cf.
Ellis v. Board of Public Instruction, 423 F.2d 203, 206 (CA5
1970). The court orders in this and the companion Davis case now provide such an option.
(3) Remedial Altering of Attendance Zones. The maps submitted in these cases graphically demonstrate that
one of the principal tools employed by school planners and by
courts to break up the dual school system has been a frank -- and
sometimes drastic -- gerrymandering of school districts and
attendance zones. An additional step was pairing, "clustering," or
"grouping" of schools with attendance assignments made deliberately
to accomplish the transfer of Negro students out of formerly
segregated Negro schools and transfer of white students to formerly
all-Negro schools. More often than not, these zones are neither
compact [ Footnote 10 ] nor
contiguous; indeed they may be on opposite ends of the city. As an
interim corrective measure, this cannot be said to be beyond the
broad remedial powers of a court. Page 402 U. S. 28 Absent a constitutional violation, there would be no basis for
judicially ordering assignment of students on a racial basis. All
things being equal, with no history of discrimination, it might
well be desirable to assign pupils to schools nearest their homes.
But all things are not equal in a system that has been deliberately
constructed and maintained to enforce racial segregation. The
remedy for such segregation may be administratively awkward,
inconvenient, and even bizarre in some situations, and may impose
burdens on some; but all awkwardness and inconvenience cannot be
avoided in the interim period when remedial adjustments are being
made to eliminate the dual school systems.
No fixed or even substantially fixed guidelines can be
established as to how far a court can go, but it must be recognized
that there are limits. The objective is to dismantle the dual
school system. "Racially neutral" assignment plans proposed by
school authorities to a district court may be inadequate; such
plans may fail to counteract the continuing effects of past school
segregation resulting from discriminatory location of school sites
or distortion of school size in order to achieve or maintain an
artificial racial separation. When school authorities present a
district court with a "loaded game board," affirmative action in
the form of remedial altering of attendance zones is proper to
achieve truly nondiscriminatory assignments. In short, an
assignment plan is not acceptable simply because it appears to be
neutral.
In this area, we must of necessity rely to a large extent, as
this Court has for more than 16 years, on the informed judgment of
the district courts in the first instance and on courts of
appeals.
We hold that the pairing and grouping of noncontiguous school
zones is a permissible tool, and such action is to be considered in
light of the objectives sought. Judicial Page 402 U. S. 29 steps in shaping such zones going beyond combinations of
contiguous areas should be examined in light of what is said in
subdivisions (1), (2), and (3) of this opinion concerning the
objectives to be sought. Maps do not tell the whole story, since
noncontiguous school zones may be more accessible to each other in
terms of the critical travel time, because of traffic patterns and
good highways, than schools geographically closer together.
Conditions in different localities will vary so widely that no
rigid rules can be laid down to govern all situations.
(4) Transportation of Students. The scope of permissible transportation of students as an
implement of a remedial decree has never been defined by this
Court, and, by the very nature of the problem, it cannot be defined
with precision. No rigid guidelines as to student transportation
can be given for application to the infinite variety of problems
presented in thousands of situations. Bus transportation has been
an integral part of the public education system for years, and was
perhaps the single most important factor in the transition from the
one-room schoolhouse to the consolidated school. Eighteen million
of the Nation's public school children, approximately 39%, were
transported to their schools by bus in 1969-1970 in all parts of
the country.
The importance of bus transportation as a normal and accepted
tool of educational policy is readily discernible in this and the
companion case, Davis, supra. [ Footnote 11 ] The Page 402 U. S. 30 Charlotte school authorities did not purport to assign students
on the basis of geographically drawn zones until 1965, and then
they allowed almost unlimited transfer privileges. The District
Court's conclusion that assignment of children to the school
nearest their home serving their grade would not produce an
effective dismantling of the dual system is supported by the
record.
Thus, the remedial techniques used in the District Court's order
were within that court's power to provide equitable relief;
implementation of the decree is well within the capacity of the
school authority.
The decree provided that the buses used to implement the plan
would operate on direct routes. Students would be picked up at
schools near their homes and transported to the schools they were
to attend. The trips for elementary school pupils average about
seven miles, and the District Court found that they would take "not
over 35 minutes, at the most." [ Footnote 12 ] This system compares favorably with the
transportation plan previously operated in Charlotte, under which,
each day, 23,600 students on all grade levels were transported an
average of 15 miles one way for an average trip requiring over an
hour. In these circumstances, we find no basis for holding that the
local school authorities may not be required to employ bus
transportation as one tool of school desegregation. Desegregation
plans cannot be limited to the walk-in school.
An objection to transportation of students may have validity
when the time or distance of travel is so great as to either risk
the health of the children or significantly Page 402 U. S. 31 impinge on the educational process. District courts must weigh
the soundness of any transportation plan in light of what is said
in subdivisions (1), (2), and (3) above. It hardly needs stating
that the limits on time of travel will vary with many factors, but
probably with none more than the age of the students. The
reconciliation of competing values in a desegregation case is, of
course, a difficult task with many sensitive facets, but
fundamentally no more so than remedial measures courts of equity
have traditionally employed. VI The Court of Appeals, searching for a term to define the
equitable remedial power of the district courts, used the term
"reasonableness." In Green, supra, this Court used the
term "feasible," and, by implication, "workable," "effective," and
"realistic" in the mandate to develop "a plan that promises
realistically to work, and . . . to work now. " On the
facts of this case, we are unable to conclude that the order of the
District Court is not reasonable, feasible and workable. However,
in seeking to define the scope of remedial power or the limits on
remedial power of courts in an area as sensitive as we deal with
here, words are poor instruments to convey the sense of basic
fairness inherent in equity. Substance, not semantics, must govern,
and we have sought to suggest the nature of limitations without
frustrating the appropriate scope of equity.
At some point, these school authorities and others like them
should have achieved full compliance with this Court's decision in Brown I. The systems would then be "unitary" in the sense
required by our decisions in Green and Alexander. It does not follow that the communities served by such systems
will remain demographically stable, for, in a growing, mobile
society, few will do so. Neither Page 402 U. S. 32 school authorities nor district courts are constitutionally
required to make year-by-year adjustments of the racial composition
of student bodies once the affirmative duty to desegregate has been
accomplished and racial discrimination through official action is
eliminated from the system. This does not mean that federal courts
are without power to deal with future problems; but, in the absence
of a showing that either the school authorities or some other
agency of the State has deliberately attempted to fix or alter
demographic patterns to affect the racial composition of the
schools, further intervention by a district court should not be
necessary.
For the reasons herein set forth, the judgment of the Court of
Appeals is affirmed as to those parts in which it affirmed the
judgment of the District Court. The order of the District Court,
dated August 7, 1970, is also affirmed. It is so ordered. * Together with No. 349, Charlotte-Mecklenburg Board of
Education et al. v. Swann et al., also on certiorari to the
same court.
[ Footnote 1 ] McDaniel v. Barresi, No. 420, post, p. 402 U. S. 39 ; Davis v. Board of School Commissioners of Mobile County, No. 436, post, p. 402
U. S. 33 ; Moore v. Charlotte-Mecklenburg Board of
Education, No. 444, post, p. 402 U. S. 47 ; North Carolina State Board of Education v. Swann, No. 498, post, p. 402 U. S. 43 . For
purposes of this opinion the cross-petitions in Nos. 281 and 349
are treated as a single case, and will be referred to as "this
case."
[ Footnote 2 ] Raney v. Board of Education, 391 U.
S. 443 (1968), and Monroe v. Board of
Commissioners, 391 U. S. 450 (1968).
[ Footnote 3 ]
A "satellite zone" is an area which is not contiguous with the
main attendance zone surrounding the school.
[ Footnote 4 ]
In its opinion and order of December 1, 1969, later incorporated
in the order appointing Dr. Finger as consultant, the District
Court stated:
"Fixed ratios of pupils in particular schools will not be set.
If the board in one of its three tries had presented a plan for
desegregation, the court would have sought ways to approve
variations in pupil ratios. In default of any such plan from the
school board, the court will start with the thought . . . that
efforts should be made to reach a 71-29 ratio in the various
schools so that there will be no basis for contending that one
school is racially different from the others, but to understand
that variations from that norm may be unavoidable." 306 F.
Supp. 1299 , 1312.
[ Footnote 5 ]
The necessity for this is suggested by the situation in the
Fifth Circuit where 166 appeals in school desegregation cases were
heard between December 2, 1969, and September 24, 1970.
[ Footnote 6 ]
Elementary public school population (grades 1-6) grew from
17,447,000 in 1954 to 23, 103,000 in 1969; secondary school
population (beyond grade 6) grew from 11, 183,000 in 1954 to
20,775,000 in 1969. Digest of Educational Statistics, Table 3,
Office of Education Pub. 10024-64; Digest of Educational
Statistics, Table 28, Office of Education Pub. 10024-70.
[ Footnote 7 ]
It must be remembered that the District Court entered nearly a
score of orders and numerous sets of findings; and, for the most
part, each was accompanied by a memorandum opinion. Considering the
pressure under which the court was obliged to operate, we would not
expect that all inconsistencies and apparent inconsistencies could
be avoided. Our review, of course, is on the orders of February 5,
1970, as amended, and August 7, 1970.
[ Footnote 8 ]
The final board plan left 10 schools 86% to 100% Negro, and yet
categorically rejected the techniques of pairing and clustering as
part of the desegregation effort. As discussed below, the Charlotte
board was under an obligation to exercise every reasonable effort
to remedy the violation, once it was identified, and the suggested
techniques are permissible remedial devices. Additionally, as noted
by the District Court and Court of Appeals, the board plan did not
assign white students to any school unless the student population
of that school was at least 60% white. This was an arbitrary
limitation negating reasonable remedial steps.
[ Footnote 9 ]
In its August 3, 1970, memorandum holding that the District
Court plan was,"reasonable" under the standard laid down by the
Fourth Circuit on appeal, the District Court explained the approach
taken as follows:
"This court has not ruled, and does not rule, that 'racial
balance' is required under the Constitution; nor that all black
schools in all cities are unlawful; nor that all school boards must
bus children or violate the Constitution; nor that the
particular order entered in this case would be correct in other
circumstances not before this court. "
(Emphasis in original.)
[ Footnote 10 ]
The reliance of school authorities on the reference to the
"revision of . . . attendance areas into compact units," Brown II, at 349 U. S. 300 (emphasis supplied), is misplaced. The enumeration in that opinion
of considerations to be taken into account by district courts was
patently intended to be suggestive, rather than exhaustive. The
decision in Brown II to remand the cases decided in Brown I to local courts for the framing of specific
decrees was premised on a recognition that this Court could not at
that time foresee the particular means which would be required to
implement the constitutional principles announced. We said in Green, supra, at 391 U. S.
439 :
"The obligation of the district courts, as it always has been,
is to assess the effectiveness of a proposed plan in achieving
desegregation. There is no universal answer to complex problems of
desegregation; there is obviously no one plan that will do the job
in every case. The matter must be assessed in light of the
circumstances present and the options available in each
instance."
[ Footnote 11 ]
During 1967-1968, for example, the Mobile board used 207 buses
to transport 22,094 students daily for an average round trip of 31
miles. During 1966-1967, 7,116 students in the metropolitan area
were bused daily. In Charlotte-Mecklenburg, the system as a whole,
without regard to desegregation plans, planned to bus approximately
23,000 students this year, for an average daily round trip of 15
miles. More elementary school children than high school children
were to be bused, and four- and five-year-olds travel the longest
routes in the system.
[ Footnote 12 ]
The District Court found that the school system would have to
employ 138 more buses than it had previously operated. But 105 of
those buses were already available, and the others could easily be
obtained. Additionally, it should be noted that North Carolina
requires provision of transportation for all students who are
assigned to schools more than one and one-half miles from their
homes. N.C.Gen.Stat. § 115-186(b) (1966). | Here is a summary of the key points from the Supreme Court case Swann v. Charlotte-Mecklenburg Board of Education:
**Background:**
- The case concerns the desegregation of the Charlotte-Mecklenburg school system in North Carolina, which had a significant number of racially segregated schools.
- Petitioner Swann sought further relief based on the Green v. County School Board case, which required school boards to take active steps to desegregate.
**Lower Court Decisions:**
- The District Court ordered the school board to provide a plan for faculty and student desegregation, but found their proposal unsatisfactory.
- An expert was appointed and proposed plans for both junior/senior high schools and elementary schools.
- The Court of Appeals affirmed the District Court's order regarding faculty desegregation and secondary school plans but vacated the order for elementary schools, concerned about the burden on pupils and the board.
**Supreme Court Decision:**
- The Supreme Court granted certiorari and directed the reinstatement of the District Court's order pending further proceedings.
- The objective is to eliminate all vestiges of state-imposed segregation that violate equal protection guarantees.
- School authorities have an affirmative obligation to propose acceptable remedies, and district courts have broad power to fashion remedies for unitary school systems if authorities default.
- The Civil Rights Act of 1964 does not restrict federal courts' equitable remedial powers.
- The Court affirmed the District Court's plan, which included busing and the pairing and grouping of schools to achieve desegregation.
The case affirmed the power of federal courts to implement remedies to achieve desegregation and ensure equal protection under the law in public education. |
Equal Protection | Frontiero v. Richardson | https://supreme.justia.com/cases/federal/us/411/677/ | U.S. Supreme Court Frontiero v. Richardson, 411
U.S. 677 (1973) Frontiero v.
Richardson No. 71-1694 Argued January 17,
1973 Decided May 14, 1973 411
U.S. 677 APPEAL FROM THE UNITED STATES
DISTRICT COURT FOR THE MIDDLE DISTRICT OF ALABAMA Syllabus A married woman Air Force officer (hereafter appellant) sought
increased benefits for her husband as a "dependent" under 37 U.S.C.
§§ 401, 403, and 10 U.S.C. §§ 1072, 1076. Those statutes provide,
solely for administrative convenience, that spouses of male members
of the uniformed services are dependents for purposes of obtaining
increased quarters allowances and medical and dental benefits, but
that spouses of female members are not dependents unless they are
in fact, dependent for over one-half of their support. When her
application was denied for failure to satisfy the statutory
dependency standard, appellant and her husband brought this suit in
District Court, contending that the statutes deprived servicewomen
of due process. From that Court's adverse ruling, they took a
direct appeal. Held: The judgment is reversed. Pp. 411 U. S.
682 -691; 411 U. S.
691 -692. 341 F.
Supp. 201 , reversed.
MR. JUSTICE BRENNAN, joined by MR. JUSTICE DOUGLAS, MR. JUSTICE
WHITE, and MR. JUSTICE MARSHALL, concluded that 37 U.S.C. §§ 401,
403 and 10 U.S.C. §§ 1072, 1076, as inherently suspect statutory
classifications based on sex, are so unjustifiably discriminatory
as to violate the Due Process Clause of the Fifth Amendment. Pp. 411 U. S.
682 -691.
MR. JUSTICE STEWART concluded that the challenged statutes work
an invidious discrimination in violation of the Constitution. Reed v. Reed, 404 U. S. 71 . P. 411 U. S.
691 .
MR. JUSTICE POWELL, joined by THE CHIEF JUSTICE and MR. JUSTICE
BLACKMUN, while agreeing that the statutes deprive servicewomen of
due process, concluded that, in the light of Reed v. Reed, 404 U. S. 71 , and
the fact that the Equal Rights Amendment has been submitted to the
States for ratification, it is inappropriate to decide at this time
whether sex is a suspect classification. Pp. 411 U. S.
691 -692. Page 411 U. S. 678 BRENNAN, J., announced the Court's judgment and delivered an
opinion, in which DOUGLAS, WHITE, and MARSHALL, JJ., joined.
STEWART, J., filed a statement concurring in the judgment, post, p. 411 U. S. 691 .
POWELL, J., filed an opinion concurring in the judgment, in which
BURGER, C.J., and BLACKMUN, J., joined, post, p. 411 U. S. 691 .
REHNQUIST, J., filed a dissenting statement, post, p. 411 U. S.
691 .
MR. JUSTICE BRENNAN announced the judgment of the Court and an
opinion in which MR. JUSTICE DOUGLAS, MR. JUSTICE WHITE, and MR.
JUSTICE MARSHALL join.
The question before us concerns the right of a female member of
the uniformed services [ Footnote
1 ] to claim her spouse as a "dependent" for the purposes of
obtaining increased quarters allowances and medical and dental
benefits under 37 U.S.C. §§ 401, 403, and 10 U.S.C. §§ 1072, 1076,
on an equal footing with male members. Under these statutes, a
serviceman may claim his wife as a "dependent" without regard to
whether she is in fact, dependent upon him for any part of her
support. 37 U.S.C.§ 401(1); 10 U.S.C.§ 1072(2)(A). A servicewoman,
on the other hand, may not claim her husband as a "dependent" under
these programs unless he is in fact, dependent upon her for over
one-half of his support. Page 411 U. S. 679 37 U.S.C. § 401; 10 U.S.C. § 1072(2)(C). [ Footnote 2 ] Thus, the question for decision is
whether this difference in treatment constitutes an
unconstitutional discrimination against servicewomen in violation
of the Due Process Clause of the Fifth Amendment. A three-judge
District Court for the Middle District of Alabama, one judge
dissenting, rejected this contention and sustained the
constitutionality of the provisions of the statutes making this
distinction. 341 F.
Supp. 201 (1972). We noted probable jurisdiction. 409 U.S. 840
(1972). We reverse. I In an effort to attract career personnel through reenlistment,
Congress established, in 37 U.S.C. § 401 et seq., and 10
U.S.C. § 1071 et seq., a scheme for the provision of
fringe benefits to members of the uniformed services on a
competitive basis with business and industry. [ Footnote 3 ] Thus, under 37 U.S.C. § 403, a member
of the uniformed services with dependents is entitled to an Page 411 U. S. 680 increased "basic allowance for quarters" and, under 10 U.S.C. §
1076, a member's dependents are provided comprehensive medical and
dental care.
Appellant Sharron Frontiero, a lieutenant in the United States
Air Force, sought increased quarters allowances, and housing and
medical benefits for her husband, appellant Joseph Frontiero, on
the ground that he was her "dependent." Although such benefits
would automatically have been granted with respect to the wife of a
male member of the uniformed services, appellant's application was
denied because she failed to demonstrate that her husband was
dependent on her for more than one-half of his support. [ Footnote 4 ] Appellants then commenced
this suit, contending that, by making this distinction, the
statutes unreasonably discriminate on the basis of sex in violation
of the Due Process Clause of the Fifth Amendment. [ Footnote 5 ] In essence, appellants asserted
that the discriminatory impact of the statutes is twofold: first,
as a procedural matter, a female member is required to demonstrate
her spouse's dependency, while no such burden is imposed upon male
members; and, second, as a substantive matter, a male member who
does not provide more than one-half of his wife's support receives
benefits, while a similarly situated female member is denied such
benefits. Appellants therefore sought a permanent injunction Page 411 U. S. 681 against the continued enforcement of these statutes and an order
directing the appellees to provide Lieutenant Frontiero with the
same housing and medical benefits that a similarly situated male
member would receive.
Although the legislative history of these statutes sheds
virtually no light on the purposes underlying the differential
treatment accorded male and female members, [ Footnote 6 ] a majority of the three-judge District
Court surmised that Congress might reasonably have concluded that,
since the husband in our society is generally the "breadwinner" in
the family -- and the wife typically the "dependent" partner --
"it would be more economical to require married female members
claiming husbands to prove actual dependency than to extend the
presumption of dependency to such members."
341 F. Supp. at 207. Indeed, given the fact that approximately
99% of all members of the uniformed services are male, the
District Page 411 U. S. 682 Court speculated that such differential treatment might
conceivably lead to a "considerable saving of administrative
expense and manpower." Ibid. II At the outset, appellants contend that classifications based
upon sex, like classifications based upon race, [ Footnote 7 ] alienage, [ Footnote 8 ] and national origin, [ Footnote 9 ] are inherently suspect, and must
therefore be subjected to close judicial scrutiny. We agree, and,
indeed, find at least implicit support for such an approach in our
unanimous decision only last Term in Reed v. Reed, 404 U. S. 71 (1971).
In Reed, the Court considered the constitutionality of
an Idaho statute providing that, when two individuals are otherwise
equally entitled to appointment as administrator of an estate, the
male applicant must be preferred to the female. Appellant, the
mother of the deceased, and appellee, the father, filed competing
petitions for appointment as administrator of their son's estate.
Since the parties, as parents of the deceased, were members of the
same entitlement class, the statutory preference was invoked, and
the father's petition was therefore granted. Appellant claimed that
this statute, by giving a mandatory preference to males over
females without regard to their individual qualifications, violated
the Equal Protection Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment.
The Court noted that the Idaho statute
"provides that different treatment be accorded to the applicants
on the basis of their sex; it thus establishes a classification
subject Page 411 U. S. 683 to scrutiny under the Equal Protection Clause."
404 U.S. at 404 U. S. 75 .
Under "traditional" equal protection analysis, a legislative
classification must be sustained unless it is "patently arbitrary"
and bears no rational relationship to a legitimate governmental
interest. See Jefferson v. Hackney, 406 U.
S. 535 , 406 U. S. 546 (1972); Richardson v. Belcher, 404 U. S.
78 , 404 U. S. 81 (1971); Flemming v. Nestor, 363 U.
S. 603 , 363 U. S. 611 (1960); McGowan v. Maryland, 366 U.
S. 420 , 366 U. S. 426 (1961); Dandridge v. Williams, 397 U.
S. 471 , 397 U. S. 485 (1970).
In an effort to meet this standard, appellee contended that the
statutory scheme was a reasonable measure designed to reduce the
workload on probate courts by eliminating one class of contests.
Moreover, appellee argued that the mandatory preference for male
applicants was, in itself, reasonable, since "men [are], as a rule,
more conversant with business affairs than . . . women." [ Footnote 10 ] Indeed, appellee
maintained that
"it is a matter of common knowledge that women still are not
engaged in politics, the professions, business or industry to the
extent that men are. [ Footnote
11 ]"
And the Idaho Supreme Court, in upholding the constitutionality
of this statute, suggested that the Idaho Legislature might
reasonably have "concluded that, in general, men are better
qualified to act as an administrator than are women." [ Footnote 12 ]
Despite these contentions, however, the Court held the statutory
preference for male applicants unconstitutional. In reaching this
result, the Court implicitly rejected appellee's apparently
rational explanation of the statutory scheme, and concluded that,
by ignoring the individual qualifications of particular applicants,
the challenged statute provided "dissimilar treatment for men and
women who are . . . similarly situated." 404 U.S. Page 411 U. S. 684 at 404 U. S. 77 .
The Court therefore held that, even though the State's interest in
achieving administrative efficiency "is not without some
legitimacy,"
"[t]o give a mandatory preference to members of either sex over
members of the other merely to accomplish the elimination of
hearings on the merits is to make the very kind of arbitrary
legislative choice forbidden by the [Constitution]. . . ." Id. at 404 U. S. 76 .
This departure from "traditional" rational basis analysis with
respect to sex-based classifications is clearly justified.
There can be no doubt that our Nation has had a long and
unfortunate history of sex discrimination. [ Footnote 13 ] Traditionally, such discrimination
was rationalized by an attitude of "romantic paternalism" which, in
practical effect, put women not on a pedestal, but in a cage.
Indeed, this paternalistic attitude became so firmly rooted in our
national consciousness that, 100 years ago, a distinguished Member
of this Court was able to proclaim:
"Man is, or should be, woman's protector and defender. The
natural and proper timidity and delicacy which belongs to the
female sex evidently unfits it for many of the occupations of civil
life. The constitution of the family organization, which is founded
in the divine ordinance as well as in the nature of things,
indicates the domestic sphere as that which properly belongs to the
domain and functions of womanhood. The harmony, not to say
identity, of interests and views which belong, or should belong, to
the family institution is repugnant to the idea of a woman adopting
a distinct and Page 411 U. S. 685 independent career from that of her husband. . . ."
". . . The paramount destiny and mission of woman are to fulfil
the noble and benign offices of wife and mother. This is the law of
the Creator." Bradwell v.
State , 16 Wall. 130, 83 U. S. 141 (1873) (Bradley, J., concurring).
As a result of notions such as these, our statute books
gradually became laden with gross, stereotyped distinctions between
the sexes, and, indeed, throughout much of the 19th century, the
position of women in our society was, in many respects, comparable
to that of blacks under the pre-Civil War slave codes. Neither
slaves nor women could hold office, serve on juries, or bring suit
in their own names, and married women traditionally were denied the
legal capacity to hold or convey property or to serve as legal
guardians of their own children. See generally L.
Kanowitz, Women and the Law: The Unfinished Revolution 5-6 (1969);
G. Myrdal, An American Dilemma 1073 (20th anniversary ed.1962). And
although blacks were guaranteed the right to vote in 1870, women
were denied even that right -- which is itself "preservative of
other basic civil and political rights" [ Footnote 14 ] -- until adoption of the Nineteenth
Amendment half a century later.
It is true, of course, that the position of women in America has
improved markedly in recent decades. [ Footnote 15 ] Page 411 U. S. 686 Nevertheless, it can hardly be doubted that, in part because of
the high visibility of the sex characteristic, [ Footnote 16 ] women still face pervasive,
although at times more subtle, discrimination in our educational
institutions, in the job market and, perhaps most conspicuously, in
the political arena. [ Footnote
17 ] See generally K. Amundsen, The Silenced Majority:
Women and American Democracy (1971); The President's Task Force on
Women's Rights and Responsibilities, A Matter of Simple Justice
(1970).
Moreover, since sex, like race and national origin, is an
immutable characteristic determined solely by the accident of
birth, the imposition of special disabilities upon the members of a
particular sex because of their sex would seem to violate "the
basic concept of our system that legal burdens should bear some
relationship to individual responsibility. . . ." Weber v.
Aetna Casualty & Surety Co., 406 U.
S. 164 , 406 U. S. 175 (1972). And what differentiates sex from such nonsuspect statuses
as intelligence or physical disability, and aligns it with the
recognized suspect criteria, is that the sex characteristic
frequently bears no relation to ability to perform or contribute to
society. [ Footnote 18 ] As a
result, statutory distinctions Page 411 U. S. 687 between the sexes often have the effect of invidiously
relegating the entire class of females to inferior legal status
without regard to the actual capabilities of its individual
members.
We might also note that, over the past decade, Congress has
itself manifested an increasing sensitivity to sex-based
classifications. In Tit. VII of the Civil Rights Act of 1964, for
example, Congress expressly declared that no employer, labor union,
or other organization subject to the provisions of the Act shall
discriminate against any individual on the basis of "race, color,
religion, sex, or national origin." [ Footnote 19 ] Similarly, the Equal Pay Act of
1963 provides that no employer covered by the Act "shall
discriminate . . . between employees on the basis of sex. "
[ Footnote 20 ] And § 1 of the
Equal Rights Amendment, passed by Congress on March 22, 1972, and
submitted to the legislatures of the States for ratification,
declares that "[e]quality of rights under the law shall not be
denied or abridged by the United States or by any State on account
of sex." [ Footnote 21 ] Thus,
Congress itself has concluded that classifications based upon sex
are inherently invidious, and this conclusion of a coequal Page 411 U. S. 688 branch of Government is not without significance to the question
presently under consideration. Cf. Oregon v. Mitchell, 400 U. S. 112 , 400 U. S. 240 , 400 U. S.
248 -249 (1970) (opinion of BRENNAN, WHITE, and MARSHALL,
JJ.); Katzenbach v. Moran, 384 U.
S. 641 , 384 U. S.
648 -649 (1966).
With these considerations in mind, we can only conclude that
classifications based upon sex, like classifications based upon
race, alienage, or national origin, are inherently suspect, and
must therefore be subjected to strict judicial scrutiny. Applying
the analysis mandated by that stricter standard of review, it is
clear that the statutory scheme now before us is constitutionally
invalid. III The sole basis of the classification established in the
challenged statutes is the sex of the individuals involved. Thus,
under 37 U.S.C. §§ 401, 403, and 10 U.S.C. §§ 1072, 1076, a female
member of the uniformed services seeking to obtain housing and
medical benefits for her spouse must prove his dependency in fact,
whereas no such burden is imposed upon male members. In addition,
the statutes operate so as to deny benefits to a female member,
such as appellant Sharron Frontiero, who provides less than
one-half of her spouse's support, while at the same time granting
such benefits to a male member who likewise provides less than
one-half of his spouse's support. Thus, to this extent, at least,
it may fairly be said that these statutes command "dissimilar
treatment for men and women who are . . . similarly situated." Reed v. Reed, 404 U.S. at 404 U. S.
77 .
Moreover, the Government concedes that the differential
treatment accorded men and women under these statutes serves no
purpose other than mere "administrative convenience." In essence,
the Government maintains that, as an empirical matter, wives in our
society frequently are dependent upon their husbands, while
husbands Page 411 U. S. 689 rarely are dependent upon their wives. Thus, the Government
argues that Congress might reasonably have concluded that it would
be both cheaper and easier simply conclusively to presume that
wives of male members are financially dependent upon their
husbands, while burdening female members with the task of
establishing dependency in fact. [ Footnote 22 ]
The Government offers no concrete evidence, however, tending to
support its view that such differential treatment in fact saves the
Government any money. In order to satisfy the demands of strict
judicial scrutiny, the Government must demonstrate, for example,
that it is actually cheaper to grant increased benefits with
respect to all male members than it is to determine which male
members are, in fact, entitled to such benefits, and to grant
increased benefits only to those members whose wives actually meet
the dependency requirement. Here, however, there is substantial
evidence that, if put to the test, many of the wives of male
members would fail to qualify for benefits. [ Footnote 23 ] And in light of the fact that
the Page 411 U. S. 690 dependency determination with respect to the husbands of female
members is presently made solely on the basis of affidavits, rather
than through the more costly hearing process, [ Footnote 24 ] the Government's explanation of the
statutory scheme is, to say the least, questionable.
In any case, our prior decisions make clear that, although
efficacious administration of governmental programs is not without
some importance, "the Constitution recognizes higher values than
speed and efficiency." Stanley v. Illinois, 405 U.
S. 645 , 405 U. S. 656 (1972). And when we enter the realm of "strict judicial scrutiny,"
there can be no doubt that "administrative convenience" is not a
shibboleth, the mere recitation of which dictates
constitutionality. See Shapiro v. Thompson, 394 U.
S. 618 (1969); Carrington v. Rash, 380 U. S.
89 (1965). On the contrary, any statutory scheme which
draws a sharp line between the sexes, solely for the purpose of
achieving administrative convenience, necessarily commands
"dissimilar treatment for men and women who are . . . similarly
situated," and therefore involves the "very kind of arbitrary
legislative choice forbidden by the [Constitution]. . . ." Reed
v. Reed, 404 U.S. at 404 U. S. 77 , 404 U. S. 76 . We
therefore conclude that, by according differential treatment to
male and female members of the uniformed services for the sole
purpose of achieving administrative Page 411 U. S. 691 convenience, the challenged statutes violate the Due Process
Clause of the Fifth Amendment insofar as they require a female
member to prove the dependency of her husband. [ Footnote 25 ] Reversed. MR. JUSTICE STEWART concurs in the judgment, agreeing that the
statutes before us work an invidious discrimination in violation of
the Constitution. Reed v. Reed, 404 U. S.
71 .
MR. JUSTICE REHNQUIST dissents for the reasons stated by Judge
Rives in his opinion for the District Court, Frontiero v.
Laird, 341 F.
Supp. 201 (1972).
[ Footnote 1 ]
The "uniformed services" include the Army, Navy, Air Force,
Marine Corps, Coast Guard, Environmental Science Services
Administration, and Public Health Service. 37 U.S.C. § 101(3); 10
U.S.C. § 1072(1).
[ Footnote 2 ]
Title 37 U.S.C. § 401 provides in pertinent part:
"In this chapter, 'dependent,' with respect to a member of a
uniformed service, means --"
"(1) his spouse;"
" * * * *" "However, a person is not a dependent of a female member unless
he is in fact, dependent on her for over one-half of his support. .
. ."
Title 10 U.S.C. § 1072(2) provides in pertinent part:
"'Dependent,' with respect to a member . . . of a uniformed
service, means --"
"(A) the wife;"
" * * * *" "(C) the husband, if he is in fact, dependent on the member . .
. for over one-half of his support. . . ."
[ Footnote 3 ] See 102 Cong.Rec. 3849-3850 (Cong. Kilday), 8043 (Sen.
Saltonstall); 95 Cong.Rec. 7662 (Cong. Kilday), 7664 (Cong. Short),
7666 (Cong. Havenner), 7667 (Cong. Bates), 7671 (Cong. Price). See also 10 U.S.C. § 1071.
[ Footnote 4 ]
Appellant Joseph Frontiero is a full-time student at Huntingdon
College in Montgomery, Alabama. According to the agreed stipulation
of facts, his living expenses, including his share of the household
expenses, total approximately $354 per month. Since he receives
$205 per month in veterans' benefits, it is clear that he is not
dependent upon appellant Sharron Frontiero for more than one-half
of his support.
[ Footnote 5 ]
"[W]hile the Fifth Amendment contains no equal protection
clause, it does forbid discrimination that is 'so unjustifiable as
to be violative of due process.'" Schneider v. Rusk, 377 U. S. 163 , 377 U. S. 168 (1964); see Shapiro v. Thompson, 394 U.
S. 618 , 394 U. S.
641 -642 (1969); Bolling v. Sharpe, 347 U.
S. 497 (1954).
[ Footnote 6 ]
The housing provisions, set forth in 37 U.S.C. § 401 et
seq., were enacted as part of the Career Compensation Act of
1949, which established a uniform pattern of military pay and
allowances, consolidating and revising the piecemeal legislation
that had been developed over the previous 40 years. See H.R.Rep. No. 779, 81st Cong., 1st Sess.; S.Rep. No. 733, 81st
Cong., 1st Sess. The Act apparently retained in substance the
dependency definitions of § 4 of the Pay Readjustment Act of 1942
(56 Stat. 361), as amended by § 6 of the Act of September 7, 1944
(58 Stat. 730), which required a female member of the service to
demonstrate her spouse's dependency. It appears that this provision
was itself derived from unspecified earlier enactments. See S.Rep. No. 917, 78th Cong., 2d Sess., 4.
The medical benefits legislation, 10 U.S.C. § 1071 et
seq., was enacted as the Dependents' Medical Care Act of 1956.
As such, it was designed to revise and make uniform the existing
law relating to medical services for military personnel. It, too,
appears to have carried forward, without explanation, the
dependency provisions found in other military pay and allowance
legislation. See H.R.Rep. No. 1805, 84th Cong., 2d Sess.;
S.Rep. No. 1878, 84th Cong., 2d Sess.
[ Footnote 7 ] See Loving v. Virginia, 388 U. S.
1 , 388 U. S. 11 (1967); McLaughlin v. Florida, 379 U.
S. 184 , 379 U. S.
191 -192 (1964); Bolling v. Sharpe, supra, at 347 U. S.
499 .
[ Footnote 8 ] See Graham v. Richardson, 403 U.
S. 365 , 403 U. S. 372 (1971).
[ Footnote 9 ] See Oyama v. California, 332 U.
S. 633 , 332 U. S.
644 -646 (1948); Korematsu v. United States, 323 U. S. 214 , 323 U. S. 216 (1944); Hirabayashi v. United States, 320 U. S.
81 , 320 U. S. 100 (1943).
[ Footnote 10 ]
Brief for Appellee in No. 70-4, O.T. 1971, Reed v.
Reed, p. 12.
[ Footnote 11 ] Id. at 12-13.
[ Footnote 12 ] Reed v. Reed, 93 Idaho 511, 514, 465 P.2d 635, 638
(1970).
[ Footnote 13 ]
Indeed, the position of women in this country at its inception
is reflected in the view expressed by Thomas Jefferson that women
should be neither seen nor heard in society's decisionmaking
councils. See M. Gruberg, Women in American Politics 4
(1968). See also 2 A. de Tocqueville, Democracy in America
(Reeves trans.1948).
[ Footnote 14 ] Reynolds v. Sims, 377 U. S. 533 , 377 U. S. 562 (1964); see Dunn v. Blumstein, 405 U.
S. 330 , 405 U. S. 336 (1972); Kramer v. Union Free School District, 395 U.
S. 621 , 395 U. S. 626 (1969); Yick Wo v. Hopkins, 118 U.
S. 356 , 118 U. S. 370 (1886).
[ Footnote 15 ] See generally The President's Task Force on Women's
Rights and Responsibilities, A Matter of Simple Justice (1970); L.
Kanowitz, Women and the Law: The Unfinished Revolution (1969); A.
Montagu, Man's Most Dangerous Myth (4th ed.1964); The President's
Commission on the Status of Women, American Women (1963).
[ Footnote 16 ] See, e.g., Note, Sex Discrimination and Equal
Protection: Do We Need a Constitutional Amendment?, 84 Harv.L.Rev.
1499, 1507 (1971).
[ Footnote 17 ]
It is true, of course, that, when viewed in the abstract, women
do not constitute a small and powerless minority. Nevertheless, in
part because of past discrimination, women are vastly
underrepresented in this Nation's decisionmaking councils. There
has never been a female President, nor a female member of this
Court. Not a single woman presently sits in the United States
Senate, and only 14 women hold seats in the House of
Representatives. And, as appellants point out, this
underrepresentation is present throughout all levels of our State
and Federal Government. See Joint Reply Brief of
Appellants and American Civil Liberties Union ( Amicus
Curiae ) 9.
[ Footnote 18 ] See, e.g., Developments in the Law -- Equal Protection,
82 Harv.L.Rev. 1065, 1173-1174 (1969).
[ Footnote 19 ]
42 U.S.C. §§ 2000e-2(a), (b), (c) (emphasis added). See
generally Sape & Hart, Title VII Reconsidered: The Equal
Employment Opportunity Act of 1972, 40 Geo.Wash.L.Rev. 824 (1972);
Developments in the Law -- Employment Discrimination and Title VII
of the Civil Rights Act of 1964, 84 Harv.L.Rev. 1109 (1971).
[ Footnote 20 ]
29 U.S.C. § 206(d) (emphasis added). See generally Murphy, Female Wage Discrimination: A Study of the Equal Pay Act
1963-1970, 39 U.Cin.L.Rev. 615 (1970).
[ Footnote 21 ]
H.R.J.Res. No. 208, 92d Cong., 2d Sess. (1972). In conformity
with these principles, Congress in recent years has amended various
statutory schemes similar to those presently under consideration so
as to eliminate the differential treatment of men and women. See 5 U.S.C. § 2108, as amended, 85 Stat. 644; 5 U.S.C. §
7152, as amended, 85 Stat. 644; 5 U.S.C. § 8341, as amended, 84
Stat. 1961; 38 U.S.C. § 102(b), as amended, 86 Stat. 1092.
[ Footnote 22 ]
It should be noted that these statutes are not in any sense
designed to rectify the effects of past discrimination against
women. See Gruenwald v. Gardner, 390 F.2d 591 (CA2), cert. denied, 393 U.S. 982 (1968); cf. Jones v. Alfred
H. Mayer Co., 392 U. S. 409 (1968); South Carolina v. Katzenbach, 383 U.
S. 301 (1966). On the contrary, these statutes seize
upon a group -- women -- who have historically suffered
discrimination in employment, and rely on the effects of this past
discrimination as a justification for heaping on additional
economic disadvantages. Cf. Gaston County v. United
States, 395 U. S. 285 , 395 U. S.
296 -297 (1969).
[ Footnote 23 ]
In 1971, 43% of all women over the age of 16 were in the labor
force, and 18% of all women worked full-time 12 months per year. See U.S. Women's Bureau, Dept. of Labor, Highlights of
Women's Employment & Education 1 (W.B.Pub. No. 72-191,
Mar.1972). Moreover, 41.5% of all married women are employed. See U.S. Bureau of Labor Statistics, Dept. of Labor, Work
Experience of the Population in 1971, p. 4 (Summary Special Labor
Force Report, Aug.1972). It is also noteworthy that, while the
median income of a male member of the armed forces is approximately
$3,686, see The Report of the President's Commission on an
All-Volunteer Armed Force 51, 181 (1970), the median income for all
women over the age of 14, including those who are not employed, is
approximately $2,237. See Statistical Abstract of the
United States Table No. 535 (1972) Source: U.S. Bureau of the
Census, Current Population Reports Series P-60, No. 80. Applying
the statutory definition of "dependency" to these statistics, it
appears that, in the "median" family, the wife of a male member
must have personal expenses of approximately $4,474, or about 75%
of the total family income, in order to qualify as a
"dependent."
[ Footnote 24 ]
Tr. of Oral Arg. 27-28.
[ Footnote 25 ]
As noted earlier, the basic purpose of these statutes was to
provide fringe benefits to members of the uniformed services in
order to establish a compensation pattern which would attract
career personnel through reenlistment. See n 3, supra, and accompanying text.
Our conclusion in no wise invalidates the statutory schemes except
insofar as they require a female member to prove the dependency of
her spouse. See Weber v. Aetna Casualty & Surety Co., 406 U. S. 164 (1972); Levy v. Louisiana, 391 U. S.
68 (1968); Moritz v. Commissioner of Internal
Revenue, 469 F.2d 466 (CA10 1972). See also 1 U.S.C.
§ 1.
MR. JUSTICE POWELL, with whom THE CHIEF JUSTICE and MR. JUSTICE
BLACKMUN join, concurring in the judgment.
I agree that the challenged statutes constitute an
unconstitutional discrimination against servicewomen in violation
of the Due Process Clause of the Fifth Amendment, but I cannot join
the opinion of MR. JUSTICE BRENNAN, which would hold that all
classifications based upon sex, "like classifications based upon
race, alienage, and national origin," are "inherently suspect, and
must therefore be subjected to close judicial scrutiny." Ante at 411 U. S. 682 .
It is unnecessary for the Court in this case to Page 411 U. S. 692 characterize sex as a suspect classification, with all of the
far-reaching implications of such a holding. Reed v. Reed, 404 U. S. 71 (1971), which abundantly supports our decision today, did not add
sex to the narrowly limited group of classifications which are
inherently suspect. In my view, we can and should decide this case
on the authority of Reed, and reserve for the future any
expansion of its rationale.
There is another, and I find compelling, reason for deferring a
general categorizing of sex classifications as invoking the
strictest test of judicial scrutiny. The Equal Rights Amendment,
which if adopted will resolve the substance of this precise
question, has been approved by the Congress and submitted for
ratification by the States. If this Amendment is duly adopted, it
will represent the will of the people accomplished in the manner
prescribed by the Constitution. By acting prematurely and
unnecessarily, as I view it, the Court has assumed a decisional
responsibility at the very time when state legislatures,
functioning within the traditional democratic process, are debating
the proposed Amendment. It seems to me that this reaching out to
preempt by judicial action a major political decision which is
currently in process of resolution does not reflect appropriate
respect for duly prescribed legislative processes.
There are times when this Court, under our system, cannot avoid
a constitutional decision on issues which normally should be
resolved by the elected representatives of the people. But
democratic institutions are weakened, and confidence in the
restraint of the Court is impaired, when we appear unnecessarily to
decide sensitive issues of broad social and political importance at
the very time they are under consideration within the prescribed
constitutional processes. | In *Frontiero v. Richardson*, the Supreme Court ruled that laws providing benefits to military spouses based on gender are unconstitutional, violating the Due Process Clause of the Fifth Amendment. The Court found that classifications based on sex are inherently suspect and must be closely scrutinized, with some justices reserving judgment on whether sex is a suspect classification until the Equal Rights Amendment is ratified. The decision ensured that female service members could claim their spouses as dependents, receiving equal quarters, medical, and dental benefits as their male counterparts. |
Free Speech | Reed v. Town of Gilbert | https://supreme.justia.com/cases/federal/us/576/13-502/ | NOTICE: This opinion is subject to
formal revision before publication in the preliminary print of the
United States Reports. Readers are requested to notify the Reporter
of Decisions, Supreme Court of the United States, Washington,
D. C. 20543, of any typographical or other formal errors, in
order that corrections may be made before the preliminary print
goes to press.
SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES
_________________
No. 13–502
_________________
CLYDE REED, et al., PETITIONERS v. TOWN OF GILBERT, ARIZONA, et al.
on writ of certiorari to the united states
court of appeals for the ninth circuit
[June 18, 2015]
Justice Thomas delivered the opinion of the
Court.
The town of Gilbert, Arizona (or Town), has
adopted a comprehensive code governing the manner in which people
may display outdoor signs. Gilbert, Ariz., Land Development Code
(Sign Code or Code), ch. 1, §4.402 (2005).[ 1 ] The Sign Code identifies various categories of signs
based on the type of information they convey, then subjects each
category to different restrictions. One of the categories is
“Temporary Directional Signs Relating to a Qualifying Event,”
loosely defined as signs directing the public to a meeting of a
nonprofit group. §4.402(P). The Code imposes more stringent
restrictions on these signs than it doeson signs conveying other
messages. We hold that these provisions are content-based
regulations of speech that cannot survive strict scrutiny.
I
A
The Sign Code prohibits the display of outdoor
signs anywhere within the Town without a permit, but it then
exempts 23 categories of signs from that requirement. These
exemptions include everything from bazaar signs to flying banners.
Three categories of exempt signs are particularly relevant
here.
The first is “Ideological Sign[s].” This
category includes any “sign communicating a message or ideas for
noncommercial purposes that is not a Construction Sign, Directional
Sign, Temporary Directional Sign Relating to a Qualifying Event,
Political Sign, Garage Sale Sign, or a sign owned or required by a
governmental agency.” Sign Code, Glossary of General Terms
(Glossary), p. 23 (emphasis deleted). Of the three categories
discussed here, the Code treats ideological signs most favorably,
allowing them to be up to 20 square feet in area and to be placed
in all “zoning districts” without time limits. §4.402(J).
The second category is “Political Sign[s].” This
includes any “temporary sign designed to influence the outcome of
an election called by a public body.” Glossary 23.[ 2 ] The Code treats these signs less favorably
than ideological signs. The Code allows the placement of political
signs up to 16 square feet on residential property and up to 32
square feet on nonresidential property, undeveloped municipal
property, and “rights-of-way.” §4.402(I).[ 3 ] These signs may be displayed up to 60 days before a
primary election and up to 15 days following a general election. Ibid. The third category is “Temporary Directional
Signs Relating to a Qualifying Event.” This includes any “Temporary
Sign intended to direct pedestrians, motorists, and other passersby
to a ‘qualifying event.’ ” Glossary 25 (emphasis deleted). A
“qualifying event” is defined as any “assembly, gathering,
activity, or meeting sponsored, arranged, or promoted by a
religious, charitable, community service, educational, or other
similar non-profit organization.” Ibid. The Code treats
temporary directional signs even less favorably than political
signs.[ 4 ] Temporary directional
signs may be no larger than six square feet. §4.402(P). They may be
placed on private property or on a public right-of-way, but no more
than four signs may be placed on a single property at any time. Ibid . And, they may be displayed no more than 12 hours
before the “qualifying event” and no more than 1 hour afterward. Ibid. B
Petitioners Good News Community Church
(Church) and its pastor, Clyde Reed, wish to advertise the time and
location of their Sunday church services. The Church is a small,
cash-strapped entity that owns no building, so it holds its
services at elementary schools or other locations in or near the
Town. In order to inform the public about its services, which are
held in a variety of different locations, the Church began placing
15 to 20 temporary signs around the Town, frequently in the public
right-of-way abutting the street. The signs typically displayed the
Church’s name, along with the time and location of the upcoming
service. Church members would post the signs early in the day on
Saturday and then remove them around midday on Sunday. The display
of these signs requires little money and manpower, and thus has
proved to be an economical and effective way for the Church to let
the community know where its services are being held each week.
This practice caught the attention of the Town’s
Sign Code compliance manager, who twice cited the Church for
violating the Code. The first citation noted that the Church
exceeded the time limits for displaying its temporary directional
signs. The second citation referred to the same problem, along with
the Church’s failure to include the date of the event on the signs.
Town officials even confiscated one of the Church’s signs, which
Reed had to retrieve from the municipal offices.
Reed contacted the Sign Code Compliance
Department in an attempt to reach an accommodation. His efforts
proved unsuccessful. The Town’s Code compliance manager informed
the Church that there would be “no leni-ency under the Code” and
promised to punish any futureviolations.
Shortly thereafter, petitioners filed a
complaint in the United States District Court for the District of
Arizona, arguing that the Sign Code abridged their freedom of
speech in violation of the First and Fourteenth Amendments. The
District Court denied the petitioners’ motion for a preliminary
injunction. The Court of Appeals for the Ninth Circuit affirmed,
holding that the Sign Code’s provision regulating temporary
directional signs did not regulate speech on the basis of content.
587 F. 3d 966, 979 (2009). It reasoned that, even though an
enforcement officer would have to read the sign to determine what
provisions of the Sign Code applied to it, the “ ‘kind of
cursory examination’ ” that would be necessary for an officer
to classify it as a temporary directional sign was “not akin to an
officer synthesizing the expressive content of the sign.” Id. , at 978. It then remanded for the District Court to
determine in the first instance whether the Sign Code’s
distinctions among temporary directional signs, political signs,
and ideological signs nevertheless constituted a content-based
regulation of speech.
On remand, the District Court granted summary
judgment in favor of the Town. The Court of Appeals again affirmed,
holding that the Code’s sign categories were content neutral. The
court concluded that “the distinctions between Temporary
Directional Signs, Ideological Signs, and Political Signs
. . . are based on objective factors relevant to
Gilbert’s creation of the specific exemption from the permit
requirement and do not otherwise consider the substance of the
sign.” 707 F. 3d 1057, 1069 (CA9 2013). Relying on this
Court’s decision in Hill v. Colorado , 530 U. S.
703 (2000) , the Court of Appeals concluded that the Sign Code is
content neutral. 707 F. 3d, at 1071–1072. As the court
explained, “Gilbert did not adopt its regulation of speech because
it disagreed with the message conveyed” and its “interests in
regulat[ing] temporary signs are unrelated to the content of the
sign.” Ibid. Accord-ingly, the court believed that the Code
was “content-neutral as that term [has been] defined by the Supreme
Court.” Id., at 1071. In light of that determination, it
applied a lower level of scrutiny to the Sign Code and concluded
that the law did not violate the First Amendment. Id. , at
1073–1076.
We granted certiorari, 573 U. S. ___
(2014), and now reverse.
II
A
The First Amendment, applicable to the States
through the Fourteenth Amendment, prohibits the enactment of laws
“abridging the freedom of speech.” U. S. Const., Amdt. 1.
Under that Clause, a government, including a municipal government
vested with state authority, “has no power to restrict expression
because of its message, its ideas, its subject matter, or its
content.” Police Dept. of Chicago v. Mosley , 408
U. S. 92, 95 (1972) . Content-based laws—those that target
speech based on its communicative content—are presumptively
unconstitutional and may be justified only if the government proves
that they are narrowly tailored to serve compelling state
interests. R. A. V. v. St. Paul , 505
U. S. 377, 395 (1992) ; Simon & Schuster, Inc. v. Members of N. Y. State Crime Victims Bd. , 502
U. S. 105, 115, 118 (1991) .
Government regulation of speech is content based
if a law applies to particular speech because of the topic
discussed or the idea or message expressed. E.g., Sorrell v. IMS Health, Inc. , 564 U. S. ___, ___–___ (2011) (slip
op., at 8–9); Carey v. Brown , 447 U. S. 455, 462
(1980) ; Mosley , supra, at 95. This commonsense
meaning of the phrase “content based” requires a court to consider
whether a regulation of speech “on its face” draws distinctions
based on the message a speaker conveys. Sorrell , supra, at ___ (slip op., at 8). Some facial distinctions
based on a message are obvious, defining regulated speech by
particular subject matter, and others are more subtle, defining
regulated speech by its function or purpose. Both are distinctions
drawn based on the message a speaker conveys, and, therefore, are
subject to strict scrutiny.
Our precedents have also recognized a separate
and additional category of laws that, though facially content
neutral, will be considered content-based regulations of speech:
laws that cannot be “ ‘justified without reference to the
content of the regulated speech,’ ” or that were adopted by
the government “because of disagreement with the message [the
speech] conveys,” Ward v. Rock Against Racism , 491
U. S. 781, 791 (1989) . Those laws, like those that are
content based on their face, must also satisfy strict scrutiny.
B
The Town’s Sign Code is content based on its
face. It defines “Temporary Directional Signs” on the basis of
whether a sign conveys the message of directing the public to
church or some other “qualifying event.” Glossary 25. It defines
“Political Signs” on the basis of whether a sign’s message is
“designed to influence the outcome of an election.” Id., at
24. And it defines “Ideological Signs” on the basis of whether a
sign “communicat[es] a message or ideas” that do not fit within the
Code’s other categories. Id., at 23. It then subjects each
of these categories to different restrictions.
The restrictions in the Sign Code that apply to
any given sign thus depend entirely on the communicative content of
the sign. If a sign informs its reader of the time and place a book
club will discuss John Locke’s Two Treatises of Government, that
sign will be treated differently from a sign expressing the view
that one should vote for one of Locke’s followers in an upcoming
election, and both signs will be treated differently from a sign
expressing an ideological view rooted in Locke’s theory of
government. More to the point, the Church’s signs inviting people
to attend its worship services are treated differently from signs
conveying other types of ideas. On its face, the Sign Code is a
content-based regulation of speech. We thus have no need to
consider the government’s justifications or purposes for enacting
the Code to determine whether it is subject to strict scrutiny.
C
In reaching the contrary conclusion, the Court
of Appeals offered several theories to explain why the Town’s Sign
Code should be deemed content neutral. None is persuasive.
1
The Court of Appeals first determined that the
Sign Code was content neutral because the Town “did not adopt its
regulation of speech [based on] disagree[ment] with the message
conveyed,” and its justifications for regulating temporary
directional signs were “unrelated to the content of the sign.” 707
F. 3d, at 1071–1072. In its brief to this Court, the United
States similarly contends that a sign regulation is content
neutral—even if it expressly draws distinctions based on the sign’s
communicative content—if those distinctions can be
“ ‘justified without reference to the content of the regulated
speech.’ ” Brief for United States as Amicus Curiae 20,
24 (quoting Ward, supra , at 791; emphasis
deleted).
But this analysis skips the crucial first step
in thecontent-neutrality analysis: determining whether the law is
content neutral on its face. A law that is content based on its
face is subject to strict scrutiny regardless of the government’s
benign motive, content-neutral justification, or lack of “animus
toward the ideas contained” in the regulated speech. Cincinnati v. Discovery Network , Inc., 507
U. S. 410, 429 (1993) . We have thus made clear that
“ ‘[i]llicit legislative intent is not the sine qua non of a violation of the First Amendment,’ ” and a party opposing
the government “need adduce ‘no evidence of an improper censorial
motive.’ ” Simon & Schuster, supra, at 117.
Although “a content-based purpose may be sufficient in certain
circumstances to show that a regulation is content based, it is not
necessary.” Turner Broadcasting System, Inc. v. FCC ,
512 U. S. 622, 642 (1994) . In other words, an innocuous
justification cannot transform a facially content-based law into
one that is content neutral.
That is why we have repeatedly considered
whether a law is content neutral on its face before turning
to the law’s justification or purpose. See, e.g., Sorrell , supra, at ___–___ (slip op., at 8–9)
(statute was content based “on its face,” and there was also
evidence of an impermissible legislative motive); United
States v. Eichman , 496 U. S. 310, 315 (1990)
(“Although the [statute] contains no ex-plicit content-based
limitation on the scope of prohibited conduct, it is nevertheless
clear that the Government’s asserted interest is related to
the suppression of free expression” (internal quotation marks
omitted)); Members of City Council of Los Angeles v. Taxpayers for Vincent , 466 U. S. 789, 804 (1984) (“The
text of the ordinance is neutral,” and “there is not even a hint of
bias or censorship in the City’s enactment or enforcement of this
ordinance”); Clark v. Community for Creative
Non-Violence , 468 U. S. 288, 293 (1984) (requiring that a
facially content-neutral ban on camping must be “justified without
reference to the content of the regulated speech”); United
States v. O’Brien , 391 U. S. 367, 375, 377 (1968)
(noting that the statute “on its face deals with conduct having no
connection with speech,” but examining whether the “the
governmental interest is unrelated to the suppression of free
expression”). Because strict scrutiny applies either when a law is
content based on its face or when the purpose and justification for
the law are content based, a court must evaluate each question
before it concludes that the law is content neutral and thus
subject to a lower level of scrutiny.
The Court of Appeals and the United States
misunderstand our decision in Ward as suggesting that a
government’s purpose is relevant even when a law is content based
on its face. That is incorrect. Ward had nothing to say
about facially content-based restrictions because it involved a
facially content- neutral ban on the use, in a city-owned
music venue, of sound amplification systems not provided by the
city. 491 U. S., at 787, and n. 2. In that context, we
looked to governmental motive, including whether the government had
regulated speech “because of disagreement” with its message, and
whether the regulation was “ ‘justified without reference to
the content of the speech.’ ” Id., at 791. But Ward ’s framework “applies only if a statute is content
neutral.” Hill , 530 U. S., at 766 (Kennedy, J.,
dissenting). Its rules thus operate “to protect speech,” not “to
restrict it.” Id., at 765.
The First Amendment requires no less. Innocent
motives do not eliminate the danger of censorship presented by a
facially content-based statute, as future government officials may
one day wield such statutes to suppress disfavored speech. That is
why the First Amendment expressly targets the operation of the
laws— i.e., the “abridg[ement] of speech”—rather than merely
the motives of those who enacted them. U. S. Const., Amdt. 1.
“ ‘The vice of content-based legislation . . . is
not that it is always used for invidious, thought-control purposes,
but that it lends itself to use for those purposes.’ ” Hill, supra, at 743 (Scalia, J., dissenting).
For instance, in NAACP v. Button ,
371 U. S. 415 (1963) , the Court encountered a State’s attempt
to use a statute prohibiting “ ‘improper solicitation’ ”
by attorneys to outlaw litigation-related speech of the National
Association for the Advancement of Colored People. Id., at
438. Although Button predated our more recent formulations
of strict scrutiny, the Court rightly rejected the State’s claim
that its interest in the “regulation of professional conduct”
rendered the statute consistent with the First Amendment, observing
that “it is no answer . . . to say . . . that
the purpose of these regulations was merely to insure high
professional standards and not to curtail free expression.” Id., at 438–439. Likewise, one could easily imagine a Sign
Code compliance manager who disliked the Church’s substantive
teachings deploying the Sign Code to make it more difficult for the
Church to inform the public of the location of its services.
Accordingly, we have repeatedly “rejected the argument that
‘discriminatory . . . treatment is suspect under the
First Amendment only when the legislature intends to suppress
certain ideas.’ ” Discovery Network, 507 U. S., at
429. We do so again today.
2
The Court of Appeals next reasoned that the
Sign Code was content neutral because it “does not mention any idea
or viewpoint, let alone single one out for differential treatment.”
587 F. 3d, at 977. It reasoned that, for the purpose of the
Code provisions, “[i]t makes no difference which candidate is
supported, who sponsors the event, or what ideological perspective
is asserted.” 707 F. 3d, at 1069.
The Town seizes on this reasoning, insisting
that “content based” is a term of art that “should be applied
flexibly” with the goal of protecting “viewpoints and ideas from
government censorship or favoritism.” Brief for Respondents 22. In
the Town’s view, a sign regulation that “does not censor or favor
particular viewpoints or ideas” cannot be content based. Ibid . The Sign Code allegedly passes this test because its
treatment of temporary directional signs does not raise any
concerns that the government is “endorsing or suppressing ‘ideas or
viewpoints,’ ” id. , at 27, and the provisions for
political signs and ideological signs “are neutral as to particular
ideas or viewpoints” within those categories. Id. , at
37.
This analysis conflates two distinct but related
limitations that the First Amendment places on government
regulation of speech. Government discrimination among viewpoints—or
the regulation of speech based on “the specific motivating ideology
or the opinion or perspective of the speaker”—is a “more blatant”
and “egregious form of content discrimination.” Rosenberger v. Rector and Visitors of Univ. of Va. , 515 U. S. 819,
829 (1995) . But it is well established that “[t]he First
Amendment’s hostility to content-based regulation extends not only
to restrictions on particular viewpoints, but also to prohibition
of public discussion of an entire topic.” Consolidated Edison
Co. of N. Y. v. Public Serv. Comm’n of N. Y. ,
447 U. S. 530, 537 (1980) .
Thus, a speech regulation targeted at specific
subject matter is content based even if it does not discriminate
among viewpoints within that subject matter. Ibid. For
example, a law banning the use of sound trucks for political
speech—and only political speech—would be a content-based
regulation, even if it imposed no limits on the political
viewpoints that could be expressed. See Discovery Network,
supra, at 428. The Town’s Sign Code likewise singles out
specific subject matter for differential treatment, even if it does
not target viewpoints within that subject matter. Ideological
messages are given more favorable treatment than messages
concerning a political candidate, which are themselves given more
favorable treatment than messages announcing an assembly of
like-minded individuals. That is a paradigmatic example of
content-based discrimination.
3
Finally, the Court of Appeals characterized
the Sign Code’s distinctions as turning on “ ‘the
content-neutral elements of who is speaking through the sign and
whether and when an event is occurring.’ ” 707 F. 3d, at
1069. That analysis is mistaken on both factual and legal
grounds.
To start, the Sign Code’s distinctions are not
speaker based. The restrictions for political, ideological, and
temporary event signs apply equally no matter who sponsors them. If
a local business, for example, sought to put up signs advertising
the Church’s meetings, those signs would be subject to the same
limitations as such signs placed by the Church. And if Reed had
decided to dis-play signs in support of a particular candidate, he
could have made those signs far larger—and kept them up for far
longer—than signs inviting people to attend hischurch services. If
the Code’s distinctions were truly speaker based, both types of
signs would receive the same treatment.
In any case, the fact that a distinction is
speaker based does not, as the Court of Appeals seemed to believe,
automatically render the distinction content neutral. Because
“[s]peech restrictions based on the identity of the speaker are all
too often simply a means to control content,” Citizens
United v. Federal Election Comm’n , 558 U. S. 310,
340 (2010) , we have insisted that “laws favoring some speakers
over others demand strict scrutiny when the legislature’s speaker
preference reflects a content preference,” Turner, 512
U. S., at 658. Thus, a law limiting the content of newspapers,
but only newspapers, could not evade strict scrutiny simply because
it could be characterized as speaker based. Likewise, a
content-based law that restricted the political speech of all
corporations would not become content neutral just because it
singled out corporations as a class of speakers. See Citizens
United, supra , at 340–341. Characterizing a distinction as
speaker based is only the beginning—not the end—of the inquiry.
Nor do the Sign Code’s distinctions hinge on
“whether and when an event is occurring.” The Code does not permit
citizens to post signs on any topic whatsoever within a set period
leading up to an election, for example. Instead, come election
time, it requires Town officials to determine whether a sign is
“designed to influence the outcome of an election” (and thus
“political”) or merely “communicating a message or ideas for
noncommercial purposes” (and thus “ideological”). Glossary 24. That
obvious content-based inquiry does not evade strict scrutiny review
simply because an event ( i.e., an election) is involved.
And, just as with speaker-based laws, the fact
that a distinction is event based does not render it content
neutral. The Court of Appeals cited no precedent from this Court
supporting its novel theory of an exception from the
content-neutrality requirement for event-based laws. As we have
explained, a speech regulation is content based if the law applies
to particular speech because of the topic discussed or the idea or
message expressed. Supra, at 6. A regulation that targets a
sign because it conveys an idea about a specific event is no less
content based than a regulation that targets a sign because it
conveys some other idea. Here, the Code singles out signs bearing a
particular message: the time and location of a specific event. This
type of ordinance may seem like a perfectly rational way to
regulate signs, but a clear and firm rule governing content
neutrality is an essential means of protecting the freedom of
speech, even if laws that might seem “entirely reasonable” will
sometimes be “struck down because of their content-based nature.” City of Ladue v. Gilleo , 512 U. S. 43, 60 (1994)
(O’Connor, J., concurring).
III
Because the Town’s Sign Code imposes
content-based restrictions on speech, those provisions can stand
only if they survive strict scrutiny, “ ‘which requires the
Government to prove that the restriction furthers a compelling
interest and is narrowly tailored to achieve that interest,’ ” Arizona Free Enterprise Club’s Freedom Club PAC v. Bennett , 564 U. S. ___, ___ (2011) (slip op., at 8)
(quoting Citizens United , 558 U. S. , at 340).
Thus, it is the Town’s burden to demonstrate that the Code’s
differentiation between temporary directional signs and other types
of signs, such as political signs and ideological signs, furthers a
compelling governmental interest and is narrowly tailored to that
end. See ibid .
The Town cannot do so. It has offered only two
governmental interests in support of the distinctions the Sign Code
draws: preserving the Town’s aesthetic appeal and traffic safety.
Assuming for the sake of argument that those are compelling
governmental interests, the Code’s distinctions fail as hopelessly
underinclusive.
Starting with the preservation of aesthetics,
temporary directional signs are “no greater an eyesore,” Discovery Network , 507 U. S. , at 425, than
ideological or political ones. Yet the Code allows unlimited
proliferation of larger ideological signs while strictly limiting
the number, size, and duration of smaller directional ones. The
Town cannot claim that placing strict limits on temporary
directional signs is necessary to beautify the Town while at the
same time allowing unlimited numbers of other types of signs that
create the same problem.
The Town similarly has not shown that limiting
temporary directional signs is necessary to eliminate threats to
traffic safety, but that limiting other types of signs is not. The
Town has offered no reason to believe that directional signs pose a
greater threat to safety than do ideological or political signs. If
anything, a sharply worded ideological sign seems more likely to
distract a driver than a sign directing the public to a nearby
church meeting.
In light of this underinclusiveness, the Town
has not met its burden to prove that its Sign Code is narrowly
tailored to further a compelling government interest. Because a
“ ‘law cannot be regarded as protecting an interest of the
highest order, and thus as justifying a restriction on truthful
speech, when it leaves appreciable damage to that supposedly vital
interest unprohibited,’ ” Republican Party of Minn. v. White , 536 U. S. 765, 780 (2002) , the Sign Code fails
strict scrutiny.
IV
Our decision today will not prevent
governments from enacting effective sign laws. The Town asserts
that an “ ‘absolutist’ ” content-neutrality rule would
render “virtually all distinctions in sign laws . . .
subject to strict scrutiny,” Brief for Respondents 34–35, but that
is not the case. Not “all distinctions” are subject to strict
scrutiny, only content-based ones are. Laws that are content neutral are instead subject to lesser scrutiny. See Clark , 468 U. S., at 295.
The Town has ample content-neutral options
available to resolve problems with safety and aesthetics. For
example, its current Code regulates many aspects of signs that have
nothing to do with a sign’s message: size, building materials,
lighting, moving parts, and portability. See, e.g., §4.402(R). And on public property, the Town may go a long way
toward entirely forbidding the posting of signs, so long as it does
so in an evenhanded, content-neutral manner. See Taxpayers for
Vincent , 466 U. S., at 817 (upholding content-neutral ban
against posting signs on public property). Indeed, some lower
courts have long held that similar content-based sign laws receive
strict scrutiny, but there is no evidence that towns in those
jurisdictions have suffered catastrophic effects. See, e.g., Solantic, LLC v. Neptune Beach , 410 F. 3d 1250,
1264–1269 (CA11 2005) (sign categories similar to the town of
Gilbert’s were content based and subject to strict scru-tiny); Matthews v. Needham , 764 F. 2d 58, 59–60 (CA1
1985) (law banning political signs but not commercial signs was
content based and subject to strict scrutiny).
We acknowledge that a city might reasonably view
the general regulation of signs as necessary because signs “take up
space and may obstruct views, distract motorists, displace
alternative uses for land, and pose other problems that
legitimately call for regulation.” City of Ladue , 512
U. S., at 48. At the same time, the presence of certain signs
may be essential, both for vehicles and pedestrians, to guide
traffic or to identify hazards and ensure safety. A sign ordinance
narrowly tailored to the challenges of protecting the safety of
pedestrians, drivers, and passengers—such as warning signs marking
hazards on private property, signs directing traffic, or street
numbers associated with private houses—well might survive strict
scrutiny. The signs at issue in this case, including political and
ideological signs and signs for events, are far removed from those
purposes. As discussed above, they are facially content based and
are neither justified by traditional safety concerns nor narrowly
tailored.
* * *
We reverse the judgment of the Court of
Appeals and remand the case for proceedings consistent with this
opinion.
It is so ordered. Notes 1 The Town’s Sign Code is
available online at
http://www.gilbertaz.gov/departments / development - service / planning - development / land -development-code
(as visited June 16, 2015, and available in Clerk of Court’s case
file). 2 A “Temporary Sign” is a
“sign not permanently attached to the ground, a wall or a building,
and not designed or intended for permanent display.” Glossary
25. 3 The Code defines
“Right-of-Way” as a “strip of publicly owned land occupied by or
planned for a street, utilities, landscaping, sidewalks, trails,
and similar facilities.” Id., at 18. 4 The Sign Code has been
amended twice during the pendency of this case. When litigation
began in 2007, the Code defined the signs at issue as “Religious
Assembly Temporary Direction Signs.” App. 75. The Code entirely
prohibited placement of those signs in the public right-of-way, and
it forbade posting them in any location for more than two hours
before the religious assembly or more than one hour afterward. Id., at 75–76. In 2008, the Town redefined the category as
“Temporary Directional Signs Related to a Qualifying Event,” and it
expanded the time limit to 12 hours before and 1 hour after the
“qualifying event.” Ibid. In 2011, the Town amended the Code
to authorize placement of temporary directional signs in the public
right-of-way. Id., at 89. SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES
_________________
No. 13–502
_________________
CLYDE REED, et al., PETITIONERS v. TOWN OF GILBERT, ARIZONA, et al.
on writ of certiorari to the united states
court of appeals for the ninth circuit
[June 18, 2015]
Justice Alito, with whom Justice Kennedy and
Justice Sotomayor join, concurring.
I join the opinion of the Court but add a few
words of further explanation.
As the Court holds, what we have termed
“content-based” laws must satisfy strict scrutiny. Content-based
laws merit this protection because they present, albeit sometimes
in a subtler form, the same dangers as laws that regulate speech
based on viewpoint. Limiting speech based on its “topic” or
“subject” favors those who do not want to disturb the status quo.
Such regulations may interfere with democratic self-government and
the search for truth. See Consolidated Edison Co. of N. Y. v. Public Serv. Comm’n of N. Y. , 447 U. S. 530, 537 (1980)
.
As the Court shows, the regulations at issue in
this case are replete with content-based distinctions, and as a
result they must satisfy strict scrutiny. This does not mean,
however, that municipalities are powerless to enact and enforce
reasonable sign regulations. I will not attempt to provide anything
like a comprehensive list, but here are some rules that would not
be content based:
Rules regulating the size of signs. These rules
may distinguish among signs based on any content-neutral criteria,
including any relevant criteria listed below.
Rules regulating the locations in which signs
may be placed. These rules may distinguish between free-standing
signs and those attached to buildings.
Rules distinguishing between lighted and
unlighted signs.
Rules distinguishing between signs with fixed
messages and electronic signs with messages that change.
Rules that distinguish between the placement of
signs on private and public property.
Rules distinguishing between the placement of
signs on commercial and residential property.
Rules distinguishing between on-premises and
off-premises signs.
Rules restricting the total number of signs
allowed per mile of roadway.
Rules imposing time restrictions on signs
advertising a one-time event. Rules of this nature do not
discriminate based on topic or subject and are akin to rules
restricting the times within which oral speech or music is
allowed.[ 1 ]*
In addition to regulating signs put up by
private actors, government entities may also erect their own signs
consistent with the principles that allow governmental speech. See Pleasant Grove City v. Summum , 555 U. S. 460 –469
(2009). They may put up all manner of signs to promote safety, as
well as directional signs and signs pointing out historic sites and
scenic spots.
Properly understood, today’s decision will not
prevent cities from regulating signs in a way that fully protects
public safety and serves legitimate esthetic objectives. Notes 1 * Of course,
content-neutral restrictions on speech are not necessarily
consistent with the First Amendment. Time, place, and manner
restrictions “must be narrowly tailored to serve the government’s
legitimate, content-neutral interests.” Ward v. Rock
Against Racism , 491 U. S. 781, 798 (1989) . But they need not
meet the high standard imposed on viewpoint- and content-based
restrictions. SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES
_________________
No. 13–502
_________________
CLYDE REED, et al., PETITIONERS v. TOWN OF GILBERT, ARIZONA, et al.
on writ of certiorari to the united states
court of appeals for the ninth circuit
[June 18, 2015]
Justice Breyer, concurring in the
judgment.
I join Justice Kagan’s separate opinion. Like
Justice Kagan I believe that categories alone cannot satisfactorily
resolve the legal problem before us. The First Amendment requires
greater judicial sensitivity both to the Amendment’s expressive
objectives and to the public’s legitimate need for regulation than
a simple recitation of categories, such as “content discrimination”
and “strict scrutiny,” would permit. In my view, the category
“content discrimination” is better considered in many contexts,
including here, as a rule of thumb, rather than as an automatic
“strict scrutiny” trigger, leading to almost certain legal
condemnation.
To use content discrimination to trigger strict
scrutiny sometimes makes perfect sense. There are cases in which
the Court has found content discrimination an unconstitutional
method for suppressing a viewpoint. E.g., Rosenberger v. Rector and Visitors of Univ. of Va. , 515 U. S.
819 –829 (1995); see also Boos v. Barry , 485
U. S. 312 –319 (1988) (plurality opinion) (applying strict
scrutiny where the line between subject matter and viewpoint was
not obvious). And there are cases where the Court has found content
discrimination to reveal that rules governing a traditional public
forum are, in fact, not a neutral way of fairly managing the forum
in the interest of all speakers. Police Dept. of Chicago v. Mosley , 408 U. S. 92, 96 (1972) (“Once a forum is
opened up to assembly or speaking by some groups, government may
not prohibit others from assembling or speaking on the basis of
what they intend to say”). In these types of cases, strict
scru-tiny is often appropriate, and content discrimination has thus
served a useful purpose.
But content discrimination, while helping courts
to identify unconstitutional suppression of expression, cannot and
should not always trigger strict scrutiny. To say that it is
not an automatic “strict scrutiny” trigger is not to argue against
that concept’s use. I readily concede, for example, that content
discrimination, as a conceptual tool, can sometimes reveal
weaknesses in the government’s rationale for a rule that limits
speech. If, for example, a city looks to litter prevention as the
rationale for a prohibition against placing newsracks dispensing
free advertisements on public property, why does it exempt other
newsracks causing similar litter? Cf. Cincinnati v. Discovery Network, Inc. , 507 U. S. 410 (1993) . I also
concede that, whenever government disfavors one kind of speech, it
places that speech at a disadvantage, potentially interfering with
the free marketplace of ideas and with an individual’s ability to
express thoughts and ideas that can help that individual determine
the kind of society in which he wishes to live, help shape that
society, and help define his place within it.
Nonetheless, in these latter instances to use
the presence of content discrimination automatically to trigger
strict scrutiny and thereby call into play a strong presumption
against constitutionality goes too far. That is because virtually
all government activities involve speech, many of which involve the
regulation of speech. Regula-tory programs almost always require
content discrimination. And to hold that such content
discrimination triggers strict scrutiny is to write a recipe for
judicial management of ordinary government regulatory activity.
Consider a few examples of speech regulated by
government that inevitably involve content discrimination, but
where a strong presumption against constitutionality has no place.
Consider governmental regulation of securities, e.g., 15
U. S. C. §78 l (requirements for content that must
be included in a registration statement); of energy conservation
labeling-practices, e.g., 42 U. S. C. §6294
(requirements for content that must be included on labels of
certain consumer electronics); of prescription drugs, e.g., 21 U. S. C. §353(b)(4)(A) (requiring a prescription drug
label to bear the symbol “Rx only”); of doctor-patient
confidentiality, e.g., 38 U. S. C. §7332
(requiring confidentiality of certain medical records, but allowing
a physician to disclose that the patient has HIV to the patient’s
spouse or sexual partner); of income tax statements, e.g., 26 U. S. C. §6039F (requiring taxpayers to furnish
information about foreign gifts received if the aggregate amount
exceeds $10,000); of commercial airplane briefings, e.g., 14
CFR §136.7 (2015) (requiring pilots to ensure that each passenger
has been briefed on flight procedures, such as seatbelt fastening);
of signs at petting zoos, e.g., N. Y. Gen. Bus. Law
Ann. §399–ff(3) (West Cum. Supp. 2015) (requiring petting zoos to
post a sign at every exit “ ‘strongly recommend[ing] that
persons wash their hands upon exiting the petting zoo
area’ ”); and so on.
Nor can the majority avoid the application of
strict scrutiny to all sorts of justifiable governmental
regulations by relying on this Court’s many subcategories and
exceptions to the rule. The Court has said, for example, that we
should apply less strict standards to “commercial speech.” Central Hudson Gas & Elec. Corp. v. Public Service
Comm’n of N. Y. , 447 U. S. 557 –563 (1980). ButI
have great concern that many justifiable instancesof
“content-based” regulation are noncommercial. And, worse than that,
the Court has applied the heightened “strict scrutiny” standard
even in cases where the less stringent “commercial speech” standard
was appropriate. See Sorrell v. IMS Health Inc. , 564
U. S. ___, ___ (2011) (Breyer, J., dissenting) (slip op., at
___ ) . The Court has also said that “government speech”
escapes First Amendment strictures. See Rust v. Sullivan , 500 U. S. 173 –194 (1991). But regulated
speech is typically private speech, not government speech. Further,
the Court has said that, “[w]hen the basis for the content
discrimination consists entirely of the very reason the entire
class of speech at issue is proscribable, no significant danger of
idea or viewpoint discrimination exists.” R. A. V. v. St. Paul , 505 U. S. 377, 388 (1992) . But this
exception accounts for only a few of the instances in which content
discrimination is readily justifiable.
I recognize that the Court could escape the
problem by watering down the force of the presumption against
constitutionality that “strict scrutiny” normally carries with it.
But, in my view, doing so will weaken the First Amendment’s
protection in instances where “strict scru-tiny” should apply in
full force.
The better approach is to generally treat
content discrimination as a strong reason weighing against the
constitutionality of a rule where a traditional public forum, or
where viewpoint discrimination, is threatened, but elsewhere treat
it as a rule of thumb, finding it a helpful, but not determinative
legal tool, in an appropriate case, to determine the strength of a
justification. I would use content discrimination as a supplement
to a more basic analysis, which, tracking most of our First
Amendment cases, asks whether the regulation at issue works harm to
First Amendment interests that is disproportionate in light of the
relevant regulatory objectives. Answering this question requires
examining the seriousness of the harm to speech, the importance of
the countervailing objectives, the extent to which the law will
achieve those objectives, and whether there are other, less
restrictive ways of doing so. See, e.g., United States v. Alvarez , 567 U. S. ___, ___–___ (2012) (Breyer, J.,
concurring in judgment) (slip op., at 1–3); Nixon v. Shrink Missouri Government PAC , 528 U. S. 377 –403
(2000) (Breyer, J., concurring). Admittedly, this approach does not
have the simplicity of a mechanical use of categories. But it does
permit the government to regulate speech in numerous instances
where the voters have authorized the government to regulate and
where courts should hesitate to substitute judicial judgment for
that of administrators.
Here, regulation of signage along the roadside,
for purposes of safety and beautification is at issue. There is no
traditional public forum nor do I find any general effort to censor
a particular viewpoint. Consequently, the specific regulation at
issue does not warrant “strict scrutiny.” Nonetheless, for the
reasons that Justice Kagan sets forth, I believe that the Town of
Gilbert’s regulatory rules violate the First Amendment. I
consequently concur in the Court’s judgment only. SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES
_________________
No. 13–502
_________________
CLYDE REED, et al., PETITIONERS v. TOWN OF GILBERT, ARIZONA, et al.
on writ of certiorari to the united states
court of appeals for the ninth circuit
[June 18, 2015]
Justice Kagan, with whom Justice Ginsburg and
Justice Breyer join, concurring in the judgment.
Countless cities and towns across America have
adopted ordinances regulating the posting of signs, while exempting
certain categories of signs based on their subject matter. For
example, some municipalities generally prohibit illuminated signs
in residential neighborhoods, but lift that ban for signs that
identify the address of a home or the name of its owner or
occupant. See, e.g. , City of Truth or Consequences,
N. M., Code of Ordinances, ch. 16, Art. XIII, §§11–13–2.3,
11–13–2.9(H)(4) (2014). In other municipalities, safety signs such
as “Blind Pedestrian Crossing” and “Hidden Driveway” can be posted
without a permit, even as other permanent signs require one. See, e.g. , Code of Athens-Clarke County, Ga., Pt. III, §7–4–7(1)
(1993). Elsewhere, historic site markers—for example, “George
Washington Slept Here”—are also exempt from general regulations.
See, e.g. , Dover, Del., Code of Ordinances, Pt. II, App. B,
Art. 5, §4.5(F) (2012). And simi-larly, the federal Highway
Beautification Act limits signs along interstate highways unless,
for instance, they direct travelers to “scenic and historical
attractions” or advertise free coffee. See 23 U. S. C. §§131(b),
(c)(1), (c)(5).
Given the Court’s analysis, many sign ordinances
of that kind are now in jeopardy. See ante , at 14
(acknowledging that “entirely reasonable” sign laws “will sometimes
be struck down” under its approach (internal quotation marks
omitted)). Says the majority: When laws “single[ ] out
specific subject matter,” they are “facially content based”; and
when they are facially content based, they are automatically
subject to strict scrutiny. Ante , at 12, 16–17. And although
the majority holds out hope that some sign laws with subject-matter
exemptions “might survive” that stringent review, ante , at
17, the likelihood is that most will be struck down. After all, it
is the “rare case[ ] in which a speech restriction withstands
strict scrutiny.” Williams-Yulee v. Florida Bar , 575
U. S. ___, ___ (2015) (slip op., at 9). To clear that high bar, the
government must show that a content-based distinction “is necessary
to serve a compelling state interest and is narrowly drawn to
achieve that end.” Arkansas Writers’ Project, Inc. v. Ragland , 481 U. S. 221, 231 (1987) . So on the
majority’s view, courts would have to determine that a town has a
compelling interest in informing passersby where George Washington
slept. And likewise, courts would have to find that a town has no
other way to prevent hidden-driveway mishaps than by specially
treating hidden-driveway signs. (Well-placed speed bumps? Lower
speed limits? Or how about just a ban on hidden driveways?) The
consequence—unless courts water down strict scrutiny to something
unrecognizable—is that our communities will find themselves in an
unenviable bind: They will have to either repeal the exemptions
that allow for helpful signs on streets and sidewalks, or else lift
their sign restrictions altogether and resign themselves to the
resulting clutter.[ 1 ]*
Although the majority insists that applying
strict scrutiny to all such ordinances is “essential” to protecting
First Amendment freedoms, ante , at 14, I find it challenging
to understand why that is so. This Court’s decisions articulate two
important and related reasons for subjecting content-based speech
regulations to the most exacting standard of review. The first is
“to preserve an uninhib-ited marketplace of ideas in which truth
will ultimately prevail.” McCullen v. Coakley , 573 U.
S. ___, ___–___ (2014) (slip op., at 8–9) (internal quotation marks
omitted). The second is to ensure that the government has not
regulated speech “based on hostility—or favoritism—towards the
underlying message expressed.” R. A. V. v. St. Paul ,
505 U. S. 377, 386 (1992) . Yet the subject-matter exemptions
included in many sign ordinances do not implicate those concerns.
Allowing residents, say, to install a light bulb over “name and
address” signs but no others does not distort the marketplace of
ideas. Nor does that different treatment give rise to an inference
of impermissible government motive.
We apply strict scrutiny to facially
content-based regulations of speech, in keeping with the rationales
just described, when there is any “realistic possibility that
official suppression of ideas is afoot.” Davenport v. Washington Ed. Assn. , 551 U. S. 177, 189 (2007)
(quoting R. A. V. , 505 U. S., at 390). That
is always the case when the regulation facially differentiates on
the basis of viewpoint. See Rosenberger v. Rector and
Visitors of Univ. of Va. , 515 U. S. 819, 829 (1995) . It
is also the case (except in non-public or limited public forums)
when a law restricts “discussion of an entire topic” in public
debate. Consolidated Edison Co. of N. Y. v. Public
Serv. Comm’n of N. Y. , 447 U. S. 530 –540 (1980)
(invalidating a limitation on speech about nuclear power). We have
stated that “[i]f the marketplace of ideas is to remain free and
open, governments must not be allowed to choose ‘which issues are
worth discussing or debating.’ ” Id. , at 537–538
(quoting Police Dept. of Chicago v. Mosley , 408 U. S.
92, 96 (1972) ). And we have recognized that such subject-matter
restrictions, even though viewpoint-neutral on their face, may
“suggest[ ] an attempt to give one side of a debatable public
question an advantage in expressing its views to the people.” First Nat. Bank of Boston v. Bellotti , 435 U. S.
765, 785 (1978) ; accord, ante , at 1 (Alito, J., concurring)
(limiting all speech on one topic “favors those who do not want to
disturb the status quo”). Subject-matter regulation, in other
words, may have the intent or effect of favoring some ideas over
others. When that is realistically possible—when the restriction
“raises the specter that the Government may effectively drive
certain ideas or viewpoints from the marketplace”—we insist that
the law pass the most demanding constitutional test. R. A. V. , 505 U. S., at 387 (quoting Simon
& Schuster, Inc. v. Members of N. Y. State Crime Victims
Bd. , 502 U. S. 105, 116 (1991) ).
But when that is not realistically possible, we
may do well to relax our guard so that “entirely reasonable” laws
imperiled by strict scrutiny can survive. Ante , at 14. This
point is by no means new. Our concern with content-based regulation
arises from the fear that the government will skew the public’s
debate of ideas—so when “that risk is inconsequential,
. . . strict scrutiny is unwarranted.” Davenport ,
551 U. S., at 188; see R. A. V. , 505 U. S.,
at 388 (approving certain content-based distinctions when there is
“no significant danger of idea or viewpoint discrimination”). To do
its intended work, of course, the category of content-based
regulation triggering strict scrutiny must sweep more broadly than
the actual harm; that category exists to create a buffer zone
guaranteeing that the government cannot favor or disfavor certain
viewpoints. But that buffer zone need not extend forever. We can
administer our content-regulation doctrine with a dose of common
sense, so as to leave standing laws that in no way implicate its
intended function.
And indeed we have done just that: Our cases
have been far less rigid than the majority admits in applying
strict scrutiny to facially content-based laws—including in cases
just like this one. See Davenport , 551 U. S., at 188
(noting that “we have identified numerous situations in which [the]
risk” attached to content-based laws is “attenuated”). In Members of City Council of Los Angeles v. Taxpayers for
Vincent , 466 U. S. 789 (1984) , the Court declined to
apply strict scrutiny to a municipal ordinance that exempted
address numbers and markers commemorating “historical, cultural, or
artistic event[s]” from a generally applicable limit on sidewalk
signs. Id. , at 792, n. 1 (listing exemptions); see id. , at 804–810 (upholding ordinance under intermediate
scrutiny). After all, we explained, the law’s enactment and
enforcement revealed “not even a hint of bias or censorship.” Id. , at 804; see also Renton v. Playtime Theatres,
Inc. , 475 U. S. 41, 48 (1986) (applying intermediate
scrutiny to a zoning law that facially distinguished among movie
theaters based on content because it was “designed to prevent
crime, protect the city’s retail trade, [and] maintain property
values . . . , not to suppress the expression of
unpopular views”). And another decision involving a similar law
provides an alternative model. In City of Ladue v. Gilleo , 512 U. S. 43 (1994) , the Court assumed arguendo that a sign ordinance’s exceptions for address
signs, safety signs, and for-sale signs in residential areas did
not trigger strict scrutiny. See id. , at 46–47, and
n. 6 (listing exemptions); id. , at 53 (noting this
assumption). We did not need to, and so did not, decide the
level-of-scrutiny question because the law’s breadth made it
unconstitutional under any standard.
The majority could easily have taken Ladue ’s tack here. The Town of Gilbert’s defense of its sign
ordinance—most notably, the law’s distinctions between directional
signs and others—does not pass strict scrutiny, or intermediate
scrutiny, or even the laugh test. See ante , at 14–15
(discussing those distinctions). The Town, for example, provides no
reason at all for prohibiting more than four directional signs on a
property while placing no limits on the number of other types of
signs. See Gilbert, Ariz., Land Development Code, ch. I,
§§4.402(J), (P)(2) (2014). Similarly, the Town offers no coherent
justification for restricting the size of directional signs to 6
square feet while allowing other signs to reach 20 square feet. See
§§4.402(J), (P)(1). The best the Town could come up with at oral
argument was that directional signs “need to be smaller because
they need to guide travelers along a route.” Tr. of Oral Arg. 40.
Why exactly a smaller sign better helps travelers get to where they
are going is left a mystery. The absence of any sensible basis for
these and other distinctions dooms the Town’s ordinance under even
the intermediate scrutiny that the Court typically applies to
“time, place, or manner” speech regulations. Accordingly, there is
no need to decide in this case whether strict scrutiny applies to
every sign ordinance in every town across this country containing a
subject-matter exemption.
I suspect this Court and others will regret the
majority’s insistence today on answering that question in the
affirmative. As the years go by, courts will discover that
thousands of towns have such ordinances, many of them “entirely
reasonable.” Ante , at 14. And as the challenges to them
mount, courts will have to invalidate one after the other. (This
Court may soon find itself a veritable Supreme Board of Sign
Review.) And courts will strike down those democratically enacted
local laws even though no one—certainly not the majority—has ever
explained why the vindication of First Amendment values requires
that result. Because I see no reason why such an easy case calls
for us to cast a constitutional pall on reasonable regulations
quite unlike the law before us, I concur only in the judgment. Notes 1 * Even in trying
(commendably) to limit today’s decision, Justice Alito’s
concurrence highlights its far-reaching effects. According to
Justice Alito, the majority does not subject to strict scrutiny
regulations of “signs advertising a one-time event.” Ante ,
at 2 (Alito, J., concurring). But of course it does. On the
majority’s view, a law with an exception for such signs “singles
out specific subject matter for differential treatment” and
“defin[es] regulated speech by particular subject matter.” Ante , at 6, 12 (majority opinion). Indeed, the precise
reason the majority applies strict scrutiny here is that “the Code
singles out signs bearing a particular message: the time and
location of a specific event.” Ante , at 14. | The Supreme Court ruled that the town of Gilbert, Arizona's sign code, which imposed more restrictions on "Temporary Directional Signs Relating to a Qualifying Event" than on other types of signs, was a content-based regulation of speech that could not withstand strict scrutiny. The Court held that the code's distinctions between different types of signs based on the messages they conveyed were subject to strict scrutiny and that the town's defense of the ordinance did not pass strict scrutiny or even intermediate scrutiny. The Court found that the town's sign code violated the First Amendment by unfairly restricting certain types of speech over others. |
Equal Protection | San Antonio Independent School District v. Rodriguez | https://supreme.justia.com/cases/federal/us/411/1/ | U.S. Supreme Court San Antonio Indep. Sch. Dist. v.
Rodriguez, 411 U.S. 1 (1973) San Antonio Independent School
District v. Rodriguez No. 71-1332 Argued October 12,
1972 Decided March 21,
1973 411 U.S.
1 APPEAL FROM THE UNITED STATES
DISTRICT COURT FOR THE WESTERN DISTRICT OF
TEXAS Syllabus The financing of public elementary and secondary schools in
Texas is a product of state and local participation. Almost half of
the revenues are derived from a largely state-funded program
designed to provide a basic minimum educational offering in every
school. Each district supplements state aid through an ad
valorem tax on property within its jurisdiction. Appellees
brought this class action on behalf of school children said to be
members of poor families who reside in school districts having a
low property tax base, making the claim that the Texas system's
reliance on local property taxation favors the more affluent and
violates equal protection requirements because of substantial
inter-district disparities in per-pupil expenditures resulting
primarily from differences in the value of assessable property
among the districts. The District Court, finding that wealth is a
"suspect" classification and that education is a "fundamental"
right, concluded that the system could be upheld only upon a
showing, which appellants failed to make, that there was a
compelling state interest for the system. The court also concluded
that appellants failed even to Page 412 U. S. 2 demonstrate a reasonable or rational basis for the State's
system. Held: 1. This is not a proper case in which to examine a State's laws
under standards of strict judicial scrutiny, since that test is
reserved for cases involving laws that operate to the disadvantage
of suspect classes or interfere with the exercise of fundamental
rights and liberties explicitly or implicitly protected by the
Constitution. Pp. 411 U. S.
18 -44.
(a) The Texas system does not disadvantage any suspect class. It
has not been shown to discriminate against any definable class of
"poor" people or to occasion discriminations depending on the
relative wealth of the families in any district. And, insofar as
the financing system disadvantages those who, disregarding their
individual income characteristics, reside in comparatively poor
school districts, the resulting class cannot be said to be suspect.
Pp. 411 U. S.
18 -28.
(b) Nor does the Texas school financing system impermissibly
interfere with the exercise of a "fundamental" right or liberty.
Though education is one of the most important services performed by
the State, it is not within the limited category of rights
recognized by this Court as guaranteed by the Constitution. Even if
some identifiable quantum of education is arguably entitled to
constitutional protection to make meaningful the exercise of other
constitutional rights, here there is no showing that the Texas
system fails to provide the basic minimal skills necessary for that
purpose. Pp. 411 U. S.
29 -39.
(c) Moreover, this is an inappropriate case in which to invoke
strict scrutiny, since it involves the most delicate and difficult
questions of local taxation, fiscal planning, educational policy,
and federalism, considerations counseling a more restrained form of
review. Pp. 411 U. S.
40 -44.
2. The Texas system does not violate the Equal Protection Clause
of the Fourteenth Amendment. Though concededly imperfect, the
system bears a rational relationship to a legitimate state purpose.
While assuring a basic education for every child in the State, it
permits and encourages participation in and significant control of
each district's schools at the local level. Pp. 411 U. S.
44 -53. 337 F.
Supp. 280 , reversed.
POWELL, J., delivered the opinion of the Court, in which BURGER,
C.J., and STEWART, BLACKMUN, and REHNQUIST, JJ., joined. Page 411 U. S. 3 STEWART, J., filed a concurring opinion, post, p. 411 U. S. 59 .
BRENNAN, J., filed a dissenting opinion, post, p. 411 U. S. 62 .
WHITE, J., filed a dissenting opinion, in which DOUGLAS and
BRENNAN, JJ., joined, post, p. 411 U. S. 63 .
MARSHALL, J., filed a dissenting opinion, in which DOUGLAS, J.,
joined, post, p. 411 U. S. 70 . Page 411 U. S. 4 MR. JUSTICE POWELL delivered the opinion of the Court.
This suit attacking the Texas system of financing public
education was initiated by Mexican-American parents whose children
attend the elementary and secondary Page 411 U. S. 5 schools in the Edgewood Independent School District, an urban
school district in San Antonio, Texas. [ Footnote 1 ] They brought a class action on behalf of
school children throughout the State who are members of minority
groups or who are poor and reside in school districts having a low
property tax base. Named as defendants [ Footnote 2 ] were the State Board of Education, the
Commissioner of Education, the State Attorney General, and the
Bexar County (San Antonio) Board of Trustees. The complaint Page 411 U. S. 6 was filed in the summer of 1968, and a three-judge court was
impaneled in January, 1969. [ Footnote 3 ] In December, 1971, [ Footnote 4 ] the panel rendered its judgment in a per
curiam opinion holding the Texas school finance system
unconstitutional under the Equal Protection Clause of the
Fourteenth Amendment. [ Footnote
5 ] The State appealed, and we noted probable jurisdiction to
consider the far-reaching constitutional questions presented. 406
U.S. 966 (1972). For the reasons stated in this opinion, we reverse
the decision of the District Court. I The first Texas State Constitution, promulgated upon Texas'
entry into the Union in 1845, provided for the establishment of a
system of free schools. [ Footnote
6 ] Early in its history, Texas adopted a dual approach to the
financing of its schools, relying on mutual participation by the
local school districts and the State. As early as 1883, the
state Page 411 U. S. 7 constitution was amended to provide for the creation of local
school districts empowered to levy ad valorem taxes with
the consent of local taxpayers for the "erection . . . of school
buildings" and for the "further maintenance of public free
schools." [ Footnote 7 ] Such
local funds as were raised were supplemented by funds distributed
to each district from the State's Permanent and Available School
Funds. [ Footnote 8 ] The
Permanent School Fund, its predecessor established in 1854 with
$2,000,000 realized from an annexation settlement, [ Footnote 9 ] was thereafter endowed with
millions of acres of public land set aside to assure a continued
source of income for school support. [ Footnote 10 ] The Available School Fund, which received
income from the Permanent School Fund as well as from a state ad valorem property tax and other designated taxes,
[ Footnote 11 ] served as the
disbursing arm for most state educational funds throughout the late
1800's and first half of this century. Additionally, in 1918, an
increase in state property taxes was used to finance a program
providing free textbooks throughout the State. [ Footnote 12 ]
Until recent times, Texas was a predominantly rural State, and
its population and property wealth were spread Page 411 U. S. 8 relatively evenly across the State. [ Footnote 13 ] Sizable differences in the value of
assessable property between local school districts became
increasingly evident as the State became more industrialized and as
rural-to-urban population shifts became more pronounced. [ Footnote 14 ] The location of
commercial and industrial property began to play a significant role
in determining the amount of tax resources available to each school
district. These growing disparities in population and taxable
property between districts were responsible in part for
increasingly notable differences in levels of local expenditure for
education. [ Footnote 15 ] In
due time, it became apparent to those concerned with financing
public education that contributions from the Available School Fund
were not sufficient to ameliorate these disparities. [ Footnote 16 ] Prior to 1939, the
Available School Fund contributed money to every school district at
a rate of $17.50 per school-age child. [ Footnote 17 ] Although the amount was increased several
times in the early 1940's, [ Footnote 18 ] Page 411 U. S. 9 the Fund was providing only $46 per student by 1945. [ Footnote 19 ]
Recognizing the need for increased state funding to help offset
disparities in local spending and to meet Texas' changing
educational requirements, the state legislature, in the late
1940's, undertook a thorough evaluation of public education with an
eye toward major reform. In 1947, an 18-member committee, composed
of educators and legislators, was appointed to explore alternative
systems in other States and to propose a funding scheme that would
guarantee a minimum or basic educational offering to each child and
that would help overcome inter-district disparities in taxable
resources. The Committee's efforts led to the passage of the
Gilmer-Aikin bills, named for the Committee's co-chairmen,
establishing the Texas Minimum Foundation School Program. [ Footnote 20 ] Today, this Program
accounts for approximately half of the total educational
expenditures in Texas. [ Footnote
21 ]
The Program calls for state and local contributions to a fund
earmarked specifically for teacher salaries, operating expenses,
and transportation costs. The State, supplying funds from its
general revenues, finances approximately 80% of the Program, and
the school districts are responsible -- as a unit -- for providing
the remaining 20%. The districts' share, known as the Local Fund
Assignment, is apportioned among the school districts Page 411 U. S. 10 under a formula designed to reflect each district's relative
taxpaying ability. The Assignment is first divided among Texas' 254
counties pursuant to a complicated economic index that takes into
account the relative value of each county's contribution to the
State's total income from manufacturing, mining, and agricultural
activities. It also considers each county's relative share of all
payrolls paid within the State and, to a lesser extent, considers
each county's share of all property in the State. [ Footnote 22 ] Each county's assignment is
then divided among its school districts on the basis of each
district's share of assessable property within the county.
[ Footnote 23 ] The district,
in turn, finances its share of the Assignment out of revenues from
local property taxation.
The design of this complex system was twofold. First, it was an
attempt to assure that the Foundation Program would have an
equalizing influence on expenditure levels between school districts
by placing the heaviest burden on the school districts most capable
of paying. Second, the Program's architects sought to establish a
Local Fund Assignment that would force every school district to
contribute to the education of its children, [ Footnote 24 ] but that would not, by itself,
exhaust any district's resources. [ Footnote 25 ] Today every school district does impose a
property tax from which it derives locally expendable Page 411 U. S. 11 funds in excess of the amount necessary to satisfy its Local
Fund Assignment under the Foundation Program.
In the years since this program went into operation in 1949,
expenditures for education -- from state as well as local sources
-- have increased steadily. Between 1949 and 1967, expenditures
increased approximately 500%. [ Footnote 26 ] In the last decade alone, the total public
school budget rose from $750 million to $2.1 billion, [ Footnote 27 ] and these increases
have been reflected in consistently rising per-pupil expenditures
throughout the State. [ Footnote
28 ] Teacher salaries, by far the largest item in any school's
budget, have increased dramatically -- the state supported minimum
salary for teachers possessing college degrees has risen from
$2,400 to $6,000 over the last 20 years. [ Footnote 29 ]
The school district in which appellees reside, the Edgewood
Independent School District, has been compared throughout this
litigation with the Alamo Heights Independent School District. This
comparison between the least and most affluent districts in the San
Antonio area serves to illustrate the manner in which the dual
system of finance operates, and to indicate the extent to which
substantial disparities exist despite the State's impressive
progress in recent years. Edgewood is one of seven public school
districts in the metropolitan area. Approximately 22,000 students
are enrolled in its 25 elementary Page 411 U. S. 12 and secondary schools. The district is situated in the core-city
sector of San Antonio in a residential neighborhood that has little
commercial or industrial property. The residents are predominantly
of Mexican-American descent: approximately 90% of the student
population is Mexican-American and over 6% is Negro. The average
assessed property value per pupil is $5,960 -- the lowest in the
metropolitan area -- and the median family income ($4,686) is also
the lowest. [ Footnote 30 ] At
an equalized tax rate of $1.05 per $100 of assessed property -- the
highest in the metropolitan area -- the district contributed $26 to
the education of each child for the 1967-1968 school year above its
Local Fund Assignment for the Minimum Foundation Program. The
Foundation Program contributed $222 per pupil for a state-local
total of $248. [ Footnote 31 ]
Federal funds added another $108, for a total of $356 per pupil.
[ Footnote 32 ]
Alamo Heights is the most affluent school district in San
Antonio. Its six schools, housing approximately 5,000 students, are
situated in a residential community quite unlike the Edgewood
District. The school population is predominantly "Anglo," having
only 18% Mexican-Americans Page 411 U. S. 13 and less than 1% Negroes. The assessed property value per pupil
exceeds $49,000, [ Footnote
33 ] and the median family income is $8,001. In 1967-1968 the
local tax rate of $.85 per $100 of valuation yielded $333 per pupil
over and above its contribution to the Foundation Program. Coupled
with the $225 provided from that Program, the district was able to
supply $558 per student. Supplemented by a $36 per-pupil grant from
federal sources, Alamo Heights spent $594 per pupil.
Although the 1967-1968 school year figures provide the only
complete statistical breakdown for each category of aid, [ Footnote 34 ] more recent partial
statistics indicate that the previously noted trend of increasing
state aid has been significant. For the 1970-1971 school year, the
Foundation School Program allotment for Edgewood was $356 per
pupil, a 62% increase over the 1967-1968 school year. Indeed, state
aid alone in 1970-1971 equaled Edgewood's entire 1967-1968 school
budget from local, state, and federal sources. Alamo Heights
enjoyed a similar increase under the Foundation Program, netting
$491 per pupil in 1970-1971. [ Footnote 35 ] These recent figures Page 411 U. S. 14 also reveal the extent to which these two districts' allotments
were funded from their own required contributions to the Local Fund
Assignment. Alamo Heights, because of its relative wealth, was
required to contribute out of its local property tax collections
approximately $100 per pupil, or about 20% of its Foundation grant.
Edgewood, on the other hand, paid only $8.46 per pupil, which is
about 2.4% of its grant. [ Footnote 36 ] It appears then that, at least as to these
two districts, the Local Fund Assignment does reflect a rough
approximation of the relative taxpaying potential of each.
[ Footnote 37 ] Page 411 U. S. 15 Despite these recent increases, substantial inter-district
disparities in school expenditures found by the District Court to
prevail in San Antonio and in varying degrees throughout the State
[ Footnote 38 ] still exist.
And it was Page 411 U. S. 16 these disparities, largely attributable to differences in the
amounts of money collected through local property taxation, that
led the District Court to conclude that Texas' dual system of
public school financing violated the Equal Protection Clause. The
District Court held that the Texas system discriminates on the
basis of wealth in the manner in which education is provided for
its people. 337 F. Supp. at 282. Finding that wealth is a "suspect"
classification, and that education is a "fundamental" interest, the
District Court held that the Texas system could be sustained only
if the State could show that it was premised upon some compelling
ate interest. Id. at 282-284. On this issue the court
concluded that
"[n]ot only are defendants unable to demonstrate compelling
state interests . . . they fail even to establish a reasonable
basis for these classifications." Id. at 284.
Texas virtually concedes that its historically rooted dual
system of financing education could not withstand the strict
judicial scrutiny that this Court has found appropriate in
reviewing legislative judgments that interfere with fundamental
constitutional rights [ Footnote
39 ] or that involve suspect classifications. [ Footnote 40 ] If, as previous decisions have
indicated, strict scrutiny means that the State's system is not
entitled to the usual presumption of validity, that the State,
rather than the complainants, must carry a "heavy burden of
justification," that the State must Page 411 U. S. 17 demonstrate that its educational system has been structured with
"precision," and is "tailored" narrowly to serve legitimate
objectives, and that it has selected the "less drastic means" for
effectuating its objectives, [ Footnote 41 ] the Texas financing system and its
counterpart in virtually every other State will not pass muster.
The State candidly admits that "[n]o one familiar with the Texas
system would contend that it has yet achieved perfection."
[ Footnote 42 ] Apart from its
concession that educational financing in Texas has "defects"
[ Footnote 43 ] and
"imperfections," [ Footnote
44 ] the State defends the system's rationality with vigor, and
disputes the District Court's finding that it lacks a "reasonable
basis."
This, then, establishes the framework for our analysis. We must
decide, first, whether the Texas system of financing public
education operates to the disadvantage of some suspect class or
impinges upon a fundamental right explicitly or implicitly
protected by the Constitution, thereby requiring strict judicial
scrutiny. If so, the judgment of the District Court should be
affirmed. If not, the Texas scheme must still be examined to
determine whether it rationally furthers some legitimate,
articulated state purpose, and therefore does not constitute an
invidious discrimination in violation of the Equal Protection
Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment. II The District Court's opinion does not reflect the novelty and
complexity of the constitutional questions posed by appellees'
challenge to Texas' system of school financing. In concluding that
strict judicial scrutiny was required, Page 411 U. S. 18 that court relied on decisions dealing with the rights of
indigents to equal treatment in the criminal trial and appellate
processes, [ Footnote 45 ] and
on cases disapproving wealth restrictions on the right to vote.
[ Footnote 46 ] Those cases,
the District Court concluded, established wealth as a suspect
classification. Finding that the local property tax system
discriminated on the basis of wealth, it regarded those precedents
as controlling. It then reasoned, based on decisions of this Court
affirming the undeniable importance of education, [ Footnote 47 ] that there is a fundamental
right to education, and that, absent some compelling state
justification, the Texas system could not stand.
We are unable to agree that this case, which in significant
aspects is sui generis, may be so neatly fitted into the
conventional mosaic of constitutional analysis under the Equal
Protection Clause. Indeed, for the several reasons that follow, we
find neither the suspect classification nor the fundamental
interest analysis persuasive. A The wealth discrimination discovered by the District Court in
this case, and by several other courts that have recently struck
down school financing laws in other States, [ Footnote 48 ] is quite unlike any of the forms of
wealth discrimination Page 411 U. S. 19 heretofore reviewed by this Court. Rather than focusing on the
unique features of the alleged discrimination, the courts in these
cases have virtually assumed their findings of a suspect
classification through a simplistic process of analysis: since,
under the traditional systems of financing public schools, some
poorer people receive less expensive educations than other more
affluent people, these systems discriminate on the basis of wealth.
This approach largely ignores the hard threshold questions,
including whether it makes a difference, for purposes of
consideration under the Constitution, that the class of
disadvantaged "poor" cannot be identified or defined in customary
equal protection terms, and whether the relative -- rather than
absolute -- nature of the asserted deprivation is of significant
consequence. Before a State's laws and the justifications for the
classifications they create are subjected to strict judicial
scrutiny, we think these threshold considerations must be analyzed
more closely than they were in the court below.
The case comes to us with no definitive description of the
classifying facts or delineation of the disfavored class.
Examination of the District Court's opinion and of appellees'
complaint, briefs, and contentions at oral argument suggests,
however, at least three ways in which the discrimination claimed
here might be described. The Texas system of school financing might
be regarded as discriminating (1) against "poor" persons whose
incomes fall below some identifiable level of poverty or who might
be characterized as functionally "indigent," [ Footnote 49 ] or Page 411 U. S. 20 (2) against those who are relatively poorer than others
[ Footnote 50 ] or (3) against
all those who, irrespective of their personal incomes, happen to
reside in relatively poorer school districts. [ Footnote 51 ] Our task must be to ascertain
whether, in fact, the Texas system has been shown to discriminate
on any of these possible bases and, if so, whether the resulting
classification may be regarded as suspect.
The precedents of this Court provide the proper starting point.
The individuals, or groups of individuals, who constituted the
class discriminated against in our prior cases shared two
distinguishing characteristics: because of their impecunity, they
were completely unable to pay for some desired benefit, and, as a
consequence, they sustained an absolute deprivation of a meaningful
opportunity to enjoy that benefit. In Griffin v.
Illinois , Page 411 U. S. 21 351 U. S. 12 (1956), and its progeny, [ Footnote 52 ] the Court invalidated state laws that
prevented an indigent criminal defendant from acquiring a
transcript, or an adequate substitute for a transcript, for use at
several stages of the trial and appeal process. The payment
requirements in each case were found to occasion de facto discrimination against those who, because of their indigency, were
totally unable to pay for transcripts. And the Court in each case
emphasized that no constitutional violation would have been shown
if the State had provided some "adequate substitute" for a full
stenographic transcript. Britt v. North Carolina, 404 U. S. 226 , 404 U. S. 228 (1971); Gardner v. California, 393 U.
S. 367 (1969); Draper v. Washington, 372 U. S. 487 (1963); Eskridge v. Washington Prison Board, 357 U.
S. 214 (1958).
Likewise, in Douglas v. California, 372 U.
S. 353 (1963), a decision establishing an indigent
defendant's right to court-appointed counsel on direct appeal, the
Court dealt only with defendants who could not pay for counsel from
their own resources and who had no other way of gaining
representation. Douglas provides no relief for those on
whom the burdens of paying for a criminal defense are, relatively
speaking, great but not insurmountable. Nor does it deal with
relative differences in the quality of counsel acquired by the less
wealthy. Williams v. Illinois, 399 U. S. 235 (1970), and Tate v. Short, 401 U.
S. 395 (1971), struck down criminal penalties that
subjected indigents to incarceration simply because Page 411 U. S. 22 of their inability to pay a fine. Again, the disadvantaged class
was composed only of persons who were totally unable to pay the
demanded sum. Those cases do not touch on the question whether
equal protection is denied to persons with relatively less money on
whom designated fines impose heavier burdens. The Court has not
held that fines must be structured to reflect each person's ability
to pay in order to avoid disproportionate burdens. Sentencing
judges may, and often do, consider the defendant's ability to pay,
but, in such circumstances, they are guided by sound judicial
discretion, rather than by constitutional mandate.
Finally, in Bullock v. Carter, 405 U.
S. 134 (1972), the Court invalidated the Texas filing
fee requirement for primary elections. Both of the relevant
classifying facts found in the previous cases were present there.
The size of the fee, often running into the thousands of dollars
and, in at least one case, as high as $8,900, effectively barred
all potential candidates who were unable to pay the required fee.
As the system provided "no reasonable alternative means of access
to the ballot" ( id. at 405 U. S.
149 ), inability to pay occasioned an absolute denial of
a position on the primary ballot.
Only appellees' first possible basis for describing the class
disadvantaged by the Texas school financing system --
discrimination against a class of definably "poor" persons -- might
arguably meet the criteria established in these prior cases. Even a
cursory examination, however, demonstrates that neither of the two
distinguishing characteristics of wealth classifications can be
found here. First, in support of their charge that the system
discriminates against the "poor," appellees have made no effort to
demonstrate that it operates to the peculiar disadvantage of any
class fairly definable as indigent, or as composed of persons whose
incomes are beneath any Page 411 U. S. 23 designated poverty level. Indeed, there is reason to believe
that the poorest families are not necessarily clustered in the
poorest property districts. A recent and exhaustive study of school
districts in Connecticut concluded that
"[i]t is clearly incorrect . . . to contend that the 'poor' live
in 'poor' districts. . . . Thus, the major factual assumption of Serrano -- that the educational financing system
discriminates against the 'poor' -- is simply false in Connecticut.
[ Footnote 53 ]"
Defining "poor" families as those below the Bureau of the Census
"poverty level," [ Footnote
54 ] the Connecticut study found, not surprisingly, that the
poor were clustered around commercial and industrial areas -- those
same areas that provide the most attractive sources of property tax
income for school districts. [ Footnote 55 ] Whether a similar pattern would be
discovered in Texas is not known, but there is no basis on the
record in this case for assuming that the poorest people -- defined
by reference to any level of absolute impecunity -- are
concentrated in the poorest districts.
Second, neither appellees nor the District Court addressed the
fact that, unlike each of the foregoing cases, lack of personal
resources has not occasioned an absolute deprivation of the desired
benefit. The argument here is not that the children in districts
having relatively low assessable property values are receiving no
public education; rather, it is that they are receiving a poorer
quality education than that available to children in districts
having more assessable wealth. Apart from the unsettled and
disputed question whether the quality of education may be
determined by the amount of money Page 411 U. S. 24 expended for it, [ Footnote
56 ] a sufficient answer to appellees' argument is that, at
least where wealth is involved, the Equal Protection Clause does
not require absolute equality or precisely equal advantages.
[ Footnote 57 ] Nor, indeed,
in view of the infinite variables affecting the educational
process, can any system assure equal quality of education except in
the most relative sense. Texas asserts that the Minimum Foundation
Program provides an "adequate" education for all children in the
State. By providing 12 years of free public school education, and
by assuring teachers, books, transportation, and operating funds,
the Texas Legislature has endeavored to
"guarantee, for the welfare of the state as a whole, that all
people shall have at least an adequate program of education. This
is what is meant by 'A Minimum Foundation Program of Education.'
[ Footnote 58 ]"
The State repeatedly asserted in its briefs in this Court that
it has fulfilled this desire, and that it now assures "every child
in every school district an adequate education." [ Footnote 59 ] No proof was offered at trial
persuasively discrediting or refuting the State's assertion. Page 411 U. S. 25 For these two reasons -- the absence of any evidence that the
financing system discriminates against any definable category of
"poor" people or that it results in the absolute deprivation of
education -- the disadvantaged class is not susceptible of
identification in traditional terms. [ Footnote 60 ]
As suggested above, appellees and the District Court may have
embraced a second or third approach, the second of which might be
characterized as a theory of relative or comparative discrimination
based on family income. Appellees sought to prove that a direct
correlation exists between the wealth of families within each
district and the expenditures therein for education. That is, along
a continuum, the poorer the family, the lower the dollar amount of
education received by the family's children.
The principal evidence adduced in support of this comparative
discrimination claim is an affidavit submitted by Professor Joel S.
Berke of Syracuse University's Educational Finance Policy
Institute. The District Court, relying in major part upon this
affidavit and apparently accepting the substance of appellees'
theory, Page 411 U. S. 26 noted, first, a positive correlation between the wealth of
school districts, measured in terms of assessable property per
pupil, and their levels of per-pupil expenditures. Second, the
court found a similar correlation between district wealth and the
personal wealth of its residents, measured in terms of median
family income. 337 F. Supp. at 282 n. 3.
If, in fact, these correlations could be sustained, then it
might be argued that expenditures on education -- equated by
appellees to the quality of education -- are dependent on personal
wealth. Appellees' comparative discrimination theory would still
face serious unanswered questions, including whether a bare
positive correlation or some higher degree of correlation [ Footnote 61 ] is necessary to provide
a basis for concluding that the financing system is designed to
operate to the peculiar disadvantage of the comparatively poor,
[ Footnote 62 ] and whether a
class of this size and diversity could ever claim the special
protection accorded "suspect" classes. These questions need not be
addressed in this case, however, since appellees' proof fails to
support their allegations or the District Court's conclusions.
Professor Berke's affidavit is based on a survey of
approximately 10% of the school districts in Texas. His findings,
previously set out in the margin, [ Footnote 63 ] show only Page 411 U. S. 27 that the wealthiest few districts in the sample have the highest
median family incomes and spend the most on education, and that the
several poorest districts have the lowest family incomes and devote
the least amount of money to education. For the remainder of the
districts -- 96 districts composing almost 90% of the sample -- the
correlation is inverted, i.e., the districts that spend
next to the most money on education are populated by families
having next to the lowest median family incomes, while the
districts spending the least have the highest median family
incomes. It is evident that, even if the conceptual questions were
answered favorably to appellees, no factual basis exists upon which
to found a claim of comparative wealth discrimination. [ Footnote 64 ]
This brings us, then, to the third way in which the
classification scheme might be defined -- district wealth
discrimination. Since the only correlation indicated by the
evidence is between district property wealth and expenditures, it
may be argued that discrimination might be found without regard to
the individual income characteristics of district residents.
Assuming a perfect correlation between district property wealth and
expenditures from top to bottom, the disadvantaged class might
be Page 411 U. S. 28 viewed as encompassing every child in every district except the
district that has the most assessable wealth and spends the most on
education. [ Footnote 65 ]
Alternatively, as suggested in MR. JUSTICE MARSHALL's dissenting
opinion, post at 411 U. S. 96 , the
class might be defined more restrictively to include children in
districts with assessable property which falls below the state-wide
average, or median, or below some other artificially defined
level.
However described, it is clear that appellees' suit asks this
Court to extend its most exacting scrutiny to review a system that
allegedly discriminates against a large, diverse, and amorphous
class, unified only by the common factor of residence in districts
that happen to have less taxable wealth than other districts.
[ Footnote 66 ] The system of
alleged discrimination and the class it defines have none of the
traditional indicia of suspectness: the class is not saddled with
such disabilities, or subjected to such a history of purposeful
unequal treatment, or relegated to such a position of political
powerlessness as to command extraordinary protection from the
majoritarian political process.
We thus conclude that the Texas system does not operate to the
peculiar disadvantage of any suspect class. Page 411 U. S. 29 But in recognition of the fact that this Court has never
heretofore held that wealth discrimination alone provides an
adequate basis for invoking strict scrutiny, appellees have not
relied solely on this contention. [ Footnote 67 ] They also assert that the State's system
impermissibly interferes with the exercise of a "fundamental"
right, and that, accordingly, the prior decisions of this Court
require the application of the strict standard of judicial review. Graham v. Richardson, 403 U. S. 365 , 403 U. S.
375 -376 (1971); Kramer v. Union School
District, 395 U. S. 621 (1969); Shapiro v. Thompson, 394 U.
S. 618 (1969). It is this question -- whether education
is a fundamental right, in the sense that it is among the rights
and liberties protected by the Constitution -- which has so
consumed the attention of courts and commentators in recent years.
[ Footnote 68 ] B In Brown v. Board of Education, 347 U.
S. 483 (1954), a unanimous Court recognized that
"education is perhaps the most important function of state and
local governments." Id. at 347 U. S. 493 .
What was said there in the context of racial discrimination has
lost none of its vitality with the passage of time:
"Compulsory school attendance laws and the great expenditures
for education both demonstrate our Page 411 U. S. 30 recognition of the importance of education to our democratic
society. It is required in the performance of our most basic public
responsibilities, even service in the armed forces. It is the very
foundation of good citizenship. Today it is a principal instrument
in awakening the child to cultural values, in preparing him for
later professional training, and in helping him to adjust normally
to his environment. In these days, it is doubtful that any child
may reasonably be expected to succeed in life if he is denied the
opportunity of an education. Such an opportunity, where the state
has undertaken to provide it, is a right which must be made
available to all on equal terms." Ibid. This theme, expressing an abiding respect for the
vital role of education in a free society, may be found in numerous
opinions of Justices of this Court writing both before and after Brown was decided. Wisconsin v. Yoder, 406 U. S. 205 , 406 U. S. 213 (BURGER, C.J.), 406 U. S. 237 , 406 U. S.
238 -239 (WHITE, J.), (1972); Abington School Dist.
v. Schempp, 374 U. S. 203 , 374 U. S. 230 (1963) (BRENNAN, J.); McCollum v. Board of Education, 333 U. S. 203 212
(1948) (Frankfurter, J.); Pierce v. Society of Sisters, 268 U. S. 510 (1925); Meyer v. Nebraska, 262 U.
S. 390 (1923); Interstate Consolidated Street R. Co.
v. Massachusetts, 207 U. S. 79 (1907).
Nothing this Court holds today in any way detracts from our
historic dedication to public education. We are in complete
agreement with the conclusion of the three-judge panel below that
"the grave significance of education both to the individual and to
our society" cannot be doubted. [ Footnote 69 ] But the importance of a service performed by
the State does not determine whether it must be regarded as
fundamental for purposes of examination under the Equal Protection
Clause. Mr. Justice Page 411 U. S. 31 Harlan, dissenting from the Court's application of strict
scrutiny to a law impinging upon the right of interstate travel,
admonished that "[v]irtually every state statute affects important
rights." Shapiro v. Thompson, 394 U.S. at 394 U. S. 655 , 394 U. S. 661 .
In his view, if the degree of judicial scrutiny of state
legislation fluctuated, depending on a majority's view of the
importance of the interest affected, we would have gone "far toward
making this Court a super-legislature.'" Ibid. We
would, indeed, then be assuming a legislative role, and one for
which the Court lacks both authority and competence. But MR.
JUSTICE STEWART s response in Shapiro to Mr. Justice
Harlan's concern correctly articulates the limits of the
fundamental rights rationale employed in the Court's equal
protection decisions: "The Court today does not "pick out particular human
activities, characterize them as fundamental,' and give them
added protection. . . ." To the contrary, the Court simply
recognizes, as it must, an established constitutional right, and
gives to that right no less protection than the Constitution itself
demands." Id. at 394 U. S. 642 .
(Emphasis in original.)
MR. JUSTICE STEWART's statement serves to underline what the
opinion of the Court in Shapiro makes clear. In subjecting
to strict judicial scrutiny state welfare eligibility statutes that
imposed a one-year durational residency requirement as a
precondition to receiving AFDC benefits, the Court explained:
"[I]n moving from State to State . . . appellees were exercising
a constitutional right, and any classification which serves to
penalize the exercise of that right, unless shown to be necessary
to promote a compelling governmental interest, is
unconstitutional." Id. at 394 U. S. 634 .
(Emphasis in original.) Page 411 U. S. 32 The right to interstate travel had long been recognized as a
right of constitutional significance, [ Footnote 70 ] and the Court's decision, therefore, did
not require an ad hoc determination as to the social or
economic importance of that right. [ Footnote 71 ] Lindsey v. Normet, 405 U. S. 56 (1972), decided only last Term, firmly reiterates that social
importance is not the critical determinant for subjecting state
legislation to strict scrutiny. The complainants in that case,
involving a challenge to the procedural limitations imposed on
tenants in suits brought by landlords under Oregon's Forcible Entry
and Wrongful Detainer Law, urged the Court to examine the operation
of the statute under "a more stringent standard than mere
rationality." Id. at 405 U. S. 73 .
The tenants argued that the statutory limitations implicated
"fundamental interests which are particularly important to the
poor," such as the " need for decent shelter'" and the "`right
to retain peaceful possession of one's home." Ibid. MR.
JUSTICE WHITE's analysis, in his opinion for the Court, is
instructive: "We do not denigrate the importance of decent, safe, and
sanitary housing. But the Constitution does not provide judicial
remedies for every social and economic ill. We are unable to
perceive in that document any constitutional guarantee of
access Page 411 U. S. 33 to dwellings of a particular quality or any recognition of the
right of a tenant to occupy the real property of his landlord
beyond the term of his lease, without the payment of rent. . . . Absent constitutional mandate, the assurance of adequate
housing and the definition of landlord-tenant relationships are
legislative, not judicial, functions." Id. at 74. (Emphasis supplied.)
Similarly, in Dandridge v. Williams, 397 U.
S. 471 (1970), the Court's explicit recognition of the
fact that the "administration of public welfare assistance . . .
involves the most basic economic needs of impoverished human
beings," id. at 397 U. S. 485 ,
[ Footnote 72 ] provided no
basis for departing from the settled mode of constitutional
analysis of legislative classifications involving questions of
economic and social policy. As in the case of housing, the central
importance of welfare benefits to the poor was not an adequate
foundation for requiring the State to justify its law by showing
some compelling state interest. See also Jefferson v.
Hackney, 406 U. S. 535 (1972); Richardson v. Belcher, 404 U. S.
78 (1971).
The lesson of these cases in addressing the question now before
the Court is plain. It is not the province of this Court to create
substantive constitutional rights in the name of guaranteeing equal
protection of the laws. Thus, the key to discovering whether
education is "fundamental" is not to be found in comparisons of the
relative societal significance of education, as opposed to
subsistence or housing. Nor is it to be found by weighing whether
education is as important as the right to travel. Rather, the
answer lies in assessing whether there is a right to education
explicitly or implicitly guaranteed by the Constitution. Page 411 U. S. 34 Eisenstadt v. Baird, 405 U. S. 438 (1972); [ Footnote 73 ] Dunn v. Blumstein, 405 U. S. 330 (1972); [ Footnote 74 ] Police Dept. of Chicago v. Mosley, 408 U. S.
92 (197); [ Footnote
75 ] Skinner v. Oklahoma, 316 U.
S. 535 (1942). [ Footnote 76 ] Page 411 U. S. 35 Education, of course, is not among the rights afforded explicit
protection under our Federal Constitution. Nor do we find any basis
for saying it is implicitly so protected. As we have said, the
undisputed importance of education will not, alone, cause this
Court to depart from the usual standard for reviewing a State's
social and economic legislation. It is appellees' contention,
however, that education is distinguishable from other services and
benefits provided by the State, because it bears a peculiarly close
relationship to other rights and liberties accorded protection
under the Constitution. Specifically, they insist that education is
itself a fundamental personal right, because it is essential to the
effective exercise of First Amendment freedoms and to intelligent
utilization of the right to vote. In asserting a nexus between
speech and education, appellees urge that the right to speak is
meaningless unless the speaker is capable of articulating his
thoughts intelligently and persuasively. The "marketplace of ideas"
is an empty forum for those lacking basic communicative tools.
Likewise, they argue that the corollary right to receive
information [ Footnote 77 ]
becomes little more than a hollow privilege when the recipient has
not been taught to read, assimilate, and utilize available
knowledge.
A similar line of reasoning is pursued with respect to the right
to vote. [ Footnote 78 ]
Exercise of the franchise, it is contended, cannot be divorced from
the educational foundation Page 411 U. S. 36 of the voter. The electoral process, if reality is to conform to
the democratic ideal, depends on an informed electorate: a voter
cannot cast his ballot intelligently unless his reading skills and
thought processes have been adequately developed.
We need not dispute any of these propositions. The Court has
long afforded zealous protection against unjustifiable governmental
interference with the individual's rights to speak and to vote. Yet
we have never presumed to possess either the ability or the
authority to guarantee to the citizenry the most effective speech
or the most informed electoral choice. That these may be desirable
goals of a system of freedom of expression and of a representative
form of government is not to be doubted. [ Footnote 79 ] These are indeed goals to be pursued by a
people whose thoughts and beliefs are freed from governmental
interference. But they are not values to be implemented by judicial
intrusion into otherwise legitimate state activities.
Even if it were conceded that some identifiable quantum of
education is a constitutionally protected prerequisite to the
meaningful exercise of either right, we have no indication that the
present levels of educational expenditures Page 411 U. S. 37 in Texas provide an education that falls short. Whatever merit
appellees' argument might have if a State's financing system
occasioned an absolute denial of educational opportunities to any
of its children, that argument provides no basis for finding an
interference with fundamental rights where only relative
differences in spending levels are involved and where -- as is true
in the present case -- no charge fairly could be made that the
system fails to provide each child with an opportunity to acquire
the basic minimal skills necessary for the enjoyment of the rights
of speech and of full participation in the political process.
Furthermore, the logical limitations on appellees' nexus theory
are difficult to perceive. How, for instance, is education to be
distinguished from the significant personal interests in the basics
of decent food and shelter? Empirical examination might well
buttress an assumption that the ill-fed, ill-clothed, and
ill-housed are among the most ineffective participants in the
political process, and that they derive the least enjoyment from
the benefits of the First Amendment. [ Footnote 80 ] If so, appellees' thesis would cast serious
doubt on the authority of Dandridge v. Williams, supra, and Lindsey v. Normet, supra. We have carefully considered each of the arguments supportive of
the District Court's finding that education is a fundamental right
or liberty, and have found those arguments unpersuasive. In one
further respect, we find this a particularly inappropriate case in
which to subject state action to strict judicial scrutiny. The
present case, in another basic sense, is significantly different
from any of the cases in which the Court has Page 411 U. S. 38 applied strict scrutiny to state or federal legislation touching
upon constitutionally protected rights. Each of our prior cases
involved legislation which "deprived," "infringed," or "interfered"
with the free exercise of some such fundamental personal right or
liberty. See Skinner v. Oklahoma, supra, at 316 U. S. 536 ; Shapiro v. Thompson, supra at 394 U. S. 634 ; Dunn v. Blumstein, supra, at 405 U. S.
338 -343. A critical distinction between those cases and
the one now before us lies in what Texas is endeavoring to do with
respect to education. MR. JUSTICE BRENNAN, writing for the Court in Katzenbach v. Morgan, 384 U. S. 641 (1966), expresses well the salient point: [ Footnote 81 ]
"This is not a complaint that Congress . . . has
unconstitutionally denied or diluted anyone's right to vote, but
rather that Congress violated the Constitution by not extending the
relief effected [to others similarly situated]. . . ."
"[The federal law in question] does not restrict or deny the
franchise, but, in effect, extends the franchise to persons who
otherwise would be denied it by state law. . . . We need only
decide whether the challenged limitation on the relief effected . .
. was permissible. In deciding that question, the principle that
calls for the closest scrutiny of distinctions in laws denying fundamental rights . . . is Page 411 U. S. 39 inapplicable; for the distinction challenged by appellees is
presented only as a limitation on a reform measure aimed at
eliminating an existing barrier to the exercise of the franchise.
Rather, in deciding the constitutional propriety of the limitations
in such a reform measure we are guided by the familiar principles
that a 'statute is not invalid under the Constitution because it
might have gone farther than it did,' . . . that a legislature need
not 'strike at all evils at the same time,' . . . and that 'reform
may take one step at a time, addressing itself to the phase of the
problem which seems most acute to the legislative mind. . . .'" Id. at 384 U. S.
656 -657. (Emphasis in original.) The Texas system of
school financing is not unlike the federal legislation involved in Katzenbach in this regard. Every step leading to the
establishment of the system Texas utilizes today -- including the
decisions permitting localities to tax and expend locally, and
creating and continuously expanding state aid -- was implemented in
an effort to extend public education and to improve its quality.
[ Footnote 82 ] Of course,
every reform that benefits some more than others may be criticized
for what it fails to accomplish. But we think it plain that, in
substance, the thrust of the Texas system is affirmative and
reformatory, and, therefore, should be scrutinized under judicial
principles sensitive to the nature of the State's efforts and to
the rights reserved to the States under the Constitution. [ Footnote 83 ] Page 411 U. S. 40 C It should be clear, for the reasons stated above and in accord
with the prior decisions of this Court, that this is not a case in
which the challenged state action must be subjected to the
searching judicial scrutiny reserved for laws that create suspect
classifications or impinge upon constitutionally protected
rights.
We need not rest our decision, however, solely on the
inappropriateness of the strict scrutiny test. A century of Supreme
Court adjudication under the Equal Protection Clause affirmatively
supports the application of the traditional standard of review,
which requires only that the State's system be shown to bear some
rational relationship to legitimate state purposes. This case
represents far more than a challenge to the manner in which Texas
provides for the education of its children. We have here nothing
less than a direct attack on the way in which Texas has chosen to
raise and disburse state and local tax revenues. We are asked to
condemn the State's judgment in conferring on political
subdivisions the power to tax local property to supply revenues for
local interests. In so doing, appellees would have the Court
intrude in an area in which it has traditionally deferred to state
legislatures. [ Footnote 84 ]
This Court has often admonished against such interferences with the
State's fiscal policies under the Equal Protection Clause:
"The broad discretion as to classification possessed by a
legislature in the field of taxation has long been recognized. . .
. [T]he passage of time has only served to underscore the wisdom of
that recognition of the large area of discretion which is needed by
a legislature in formulating sound tax policies. . . . Page 411 U. S. 41 It has . . . been pointed out that in taxation, even more than
in other fields, legislatures possess the greatest freedom in
classification. Since the members of a legislature necessarily
enjoy a familiarity with local conditions which this Court cannot
have, the presumption of constitutionality can be overcome only by
the most explicit demonstration that a classification is a hostile
and oppressive discrimination against particular persons and
classes. . . ." Madden v. Kentucky, 309 U. S. 83 , 309 U. S. 87 -88
(1940). See also Lehnhausen v. Lake Shore Auto Parts Co., 410 U. S. 356 (1973); Wisconsin v. J. C. Penney Co., 311 U.
S. 435 , 311 U. S. 445 (1940).
Thus, we stand on familiar ground when we continue to
acknowledge that the Justices of this Court lack both the expertise
and the familiarity with local problems so necessary to the making
of wise decisions with respect to the raising and disposition of
public revenues. Yet we are urged to direct the States either to
alter drastically the present system or to throw out the property
tax altogether in favor of some other form of taxation. No scheme
of taxation, whether the tax is imposed on property, income, or
purchases of goods and services, has yet been devised which is free
of all discriminatory impact. In such a complex arena in which no
perfect alternatives exist, the Court does well not to impose too
rigorous a standard of scrutiny lest all local fiscal schemes
become subjects of criticism under the Equal Protection Clause.
[ Footnote 85 ] Page 411 U. S. 42 In addition to matters of fiscal policy, this case also involves
the most persistent and difficult questions of educational policy,
another area in which this Court's lack of specialized knowledge
and experience counsels against premature interference with the
informed judgments made at the state and local levels. Education,
perhaps even more than welfare assistance, presents a myriad of
"intractable economic, social, and even philosophical problems." Dandridge v. Williams, 397 U.S. at 397 U. S. 487 .
The very complexity of the problems of financing and managing a
state-wide public school system suggests that "there will be more
than one constitutionally permissible method of solving them," and
that, within the limits of rationality, "the legislature's efforts
to tackle the problems" should be entitled to respect. Jefferson v. Hackney, 406 U.S. at 406 U. S.
546 -547. On even the most basic questions in this area,
the scholars and educational experts are divided. Indeed, one of
the major Page 411 U. S. 43 sources of controversy concerns the extent to which there is a
demonstrable correlation between educational expenditures and the
quality of education [ Footnote
86 ] -- an assumed correlation underlying virtually every legal
conclusion drawn by the District Court in this case. Related to the
questioned relationship between cost and quality is the equally
unsettled controversy as to the proper goals of a system of public
education. [ Footnote 87 ] And
the question regarding the most effective relationship between
state boards of education and local school boards, in terms of
their respective responsibilities and degrees of control, is now
undergoing searching reexamination. The ultimate wisdom as to these
and related problems of education is not likely to be divined for
all time even by the scholars who now so earnestly debate the
issues. In such circumstances, the judiciary is well advised to
refrain from imposing on the States inflexible constitutional
restraints that could circumscribe or handicap the continued
research and experimentation so vital to finding even partial
solutions to educational problems and to keeping abreast of
ever-changing conditions. Page 411 U. S. 44 It must be remembered, also, that every claim arising under the
Equal Protection Clause has implications for the relationship
between national and state power under our federal system.
Questions of federalism are always inherent in the process of
determining whether a State's laws are to be accorded the
traditional presumption of constitutionality, or are to be
subjected instead to rigorous judicial scrutiny. While
"[t]he maintenance of the principles of federalism is a foremost
consideration in interpreting any of the pertinent constitutional
provisions under which this Court examines state action, [ Footnote 88 ]"
it would be difficult to imagine a case having a greater
potential impact on our federal system than the one now before us,
in which we are urged to abrogate systems of financing public
education presently in existence in virtually every State.
The foregoing considerations buttress our conclusion that Texas'
system of public school finance is an inappropriate candidate for
strict judicial scrutiny. These same considerations are relevant to
the determination whether that system, with its conceded
imperfections, nevertheless bears some rational relationship to a
legitimate state purpose. It is to this question that we next turn
our attention. III The basic contours of the Texas school finance system have been
traced at the outset of this opinion. We will now describe in more
detail that system and how it operates, as these facts bear
directly upon the demands of the Equal Protection Clause.
Apart from federal assistance, each Texas school receives its
funds from the State and from its local school Page 411 U. S. 45 district. On a state-wide average, a roughly comparable amount
of funds is derived from each source. [ Footnote 89 ] The State's contribution, under the
Minimum Foundation Program, was designed to provide an adequate
minimum educational offering in every school in the State. Funds
are distributed to assure that there will be one teacher --
compensated at the state supported minimum salary -- for every 25
students. [ Footnote 90 ] Each
school district's other supportive personnel are provided for: one
principal for every 30 teachers; [ Footnote 91 ] one "special service" teacher -- librarian,
nurse, doctor, etc. -- for every 20 teachers; [ Footnote 92 ] superintendents, vocational
instructors, counselors, and educators for exceptional children are
also provided. [ Footnote 93 ]
Additional funds are earmarked for current operating expenses, for
student transportation, [ Footnote 94 ] and for free textbooks. [ Footnote 95 ]
The program is administered by the State Board of Education and
by the Central Education Agency, which also have responsibility for
school accreditation [ Footnote
96 ] and for monitoring the statutory teacher-qualification
standards. [ Footnote 97 ] As
reflected by the 62 increase in funds allotted to the Edgewood
School District over the last three years, [ Footnote 98 ] the State's financial contribution
to education is steadily increasing. None of Texas' school
districts, however, Page 411 U. S. 46 has been content to rely alone on funds from the Foundation
Program.
By virtue of the obligation to fulfill its Local Fund
Assignment, every district must impose an ad valorem tax
on property located within its borders. The Fund Assignment was
designed to remain sufficiently low to assure that each district
would have some ability to provide a more enriched educational
program. [ Footnote 99 ] Every
district supplements its Foundation grant in this manner. In some
districts, the local property tax contribution is insubstantial, as
in Edgewood, where the supplement was only $26 per pupil in 1967.
In other districts, the local share may far exceed even the total
Foundation grant. In part, local differences are attributable to
differences in the rates of taxation or in the degree to which the
market value for any category of property varies from its assessed
value. [ Footnote 100 ] The
greatest inter-district disparities, however, are attributable to
differences in the amount of assessable property available within
any district. Those districts that have more property, or more
valuable property, have a greater capability for supplementing
state funds. In large measure, these additional local revenues are
devoted to paying higher salaries to more teachers. Therefore, the
primary distinguishing attributes of schools in property-affluent
districts are lower pupil-teacher ratios and higher salary
schedules. [ Footnote
101 ] Page 411 U. S. 47 This, then, is the basic outline of the Texas school financing
structure. Because of differences in expenditure levels occasioned
by disparities in property tax income, appellees claim that
children in less affluent districts have been made the subject of
invidious discrimination. The District Court found that the State
had failed even "to establish a reasonable basis" for a system that
results in different levels of per-pupil expenditure. 337 F. Supp.
at 284. We disagree.
In its reliance on state, as well as local, resources, the Texas
system is comparable to the systems employed Page 411 U. S. 48 in virtually every other State. [ Footnote 102 ] The power to tax local property for
educational purposes has been recognized in Texas at least since
1883. [ Footnote 103 ] When
the growth of commercial and industrial centers and accompanying
shifts in population began to create disparities in local
resources, Texas undertook a program calling for a considerable
investment of state funds.
The "foundation grant" theory upon which Texas legislators and
educators based the Gilmer-Aikin bills was a product of the
pioneering work of two New York educational reformers in the
1920's, George D. Strayer and Robert M. Haig. [ Footnote 104 ] Their efforts were devoted
to establishing a means of guaranteeing a minimum state-wide
educational program without sacrificing the vital element of local
participation. The Strayer-Haig thesis Page 411 U. S. 49 represented an accommodation between these two competing forces.
As articulated by Professor Coleman:
"The history of education since the industrial revolution shows
a continual struggle between two forces: the desire by members of
society to have educational opportunity for all children and the
desire of each family to provide the best education it can afford
for its own children. [ Footnote 105 ]"
The Texas system of school finance is responsive to these two
forces. While assuring a basic education for every child in the
State, it permits and encourages a large measure of participation
in and control of each district's schools at the local level. In an
era that has witnessed a consistent trend toward centralization of
the functions of government, local sharing of responsibility for
public education has survived. The merit of local control was
recognized last Term in both the majority and dissenting opinions
in Wright v. Council of the City of Emporia, 407 U.
S. 451 (1972). MR. JUSTICE STEWART stated there that
"[d]irect control over decisions vitally affecting the education of
one's children is a need that is strongly felt in our society." Id. at 407 U. S. 469 .
THE CHIEF JUSTICE, in his dissent, agreed that
"[l]ocal control is not only vital to continued public support
of the schools, but it is of overriding importance from an
educational standpoint as well." Id. at 407 U. S.
478 .
The persistence of attachment to government at the lowest level
where education is concerned reflects the depth of commitment of
its supporters. In part, local control means, as Professor Coleman
suggests, the freedom to devote more money to the education of
one's children. Equally important, however, is the opportunity Page 411 U. S. 50 it offers for participation in the decisionmaking process that
determines how those local tax dollars will be spent. Each locality
is free to tailor local programs to local needs. Pluralism also
affords some opportunity for experimentation, innovation, and a
healthy competition for educational excellence. An analogy to the
Nation-State relationship in our federal system seems uniquely
appropriate. Mr. Justice Brandeis identified as one of the peculiar
strengths of our form of government each State's freedom to "serve
as a laboratory; and try novel social and economic experiments."
[ Footnote 106 ] No area of
social concern stands to profit more from a multiplicity of
viewpoints and from a diversity of approaches than does public
education.
Appellees do not question the propriety of Texas' dedication to
local control of education. To the contrary, they attack the school
financing system precisely because, in their view, it does not
provide the same level of local control and fiscal flexibility in
all districts. Appellees suggest that local control could be
preserved and promoted under other financing systems that resulted
in more equality in educational expenditures. While it is no doubt
true that reliance on local property taxation for school revenues
provides less freedom of choice with respect to expenditures for
some districts than for others, [ Footnote 107 ] Page 411 U. S. 51 the existence of "some inequality" in the manner in which the
State's rationale is achieved is not alone a sufficient basis for
striking down the entire system. McGowan v. Maryland, 366 U. S. 420 , 366 U. S.
425 -426 (1961). It may not be condemned simply because
it imperfectly effectuates the State's goals. Dandridge v.
Williams, 397 U.S. at 397 U. S. 485 . Nor must the financing system fail
because, as appellees suggest, other methods of satisfying the
State's interest, which occasion "less drastic" disparities in
expenditures, might be conceived. Only where state action impinges
on the exercise of fundamental constitutional rights or liberties
must it be found to have chosen the least restrictive alternative. Cf. Dunn v. Blumstein, 405 U.S. at 405 U. S. 343 ; Shelton v. Tucker, 364 U. S. 479 , 364 U. S. 488 (1960). It is also well to remember that even those districts that
have reduced ability to make free decisions with respect to how
much they spend on education still retain, under the present
system, a large measure of authority as to how available funds will
be allocated. They further enjoy the power to make numerous other
decisions with respect to the operation of the schools. [ Footnote 108 ] The people of Texas
may be Page 411 U. S. 52 justified in believing that other systems of school financing,
which place more of the financial responsibility in the hands of
the State, will result in a comparable lessening of desired local
autonomy. That is, they may believe Page 411 U. S. 53 that along with increased control of the purse strings at the
state level will go increased control over local policies.
[ Footnote 109 ]
Appellees further urge that the Texas system is
unconstitutionally arbitrary because it allows the availability of
local taxable resources to turn on "happenstance." They see no
justification for a system that allows, as they contend, the
quality of education to fluctuate on the basis of the fortuitous
positioning of the boundary lines of political subdivisions and the
location of valuable commercial and industrial property. But any
scheme of Page 411 U. S. 54 local taxation -- indeed the very existence of identifiable
local governmental units -- requires the establishment of
jurisdictional boundaries that are inevitably arbitrary. It is
equally inevitable that some localities are going to be blessed
with more taxable assets than others. [ Footnote 110 ] Nor is local wealth a static quantity.
Changes in the level of taxable wealth within any district may
result from any number of events, some of which local residents can
and do influence. For instance, commercial and industrial
enterprises may be encouraged to locate within a district by
various actions -- public and private.
Moreover, if local taxation for local expenditures were an
unconstitutional method of providing for education, then it might
be an equally impermissible means of providing other necessary
services customarily financed largely from local property taxes,
including local police and fire protection, public health and
hospitals, and public utility facilities of various kinds. We
perceive no justification for such a severe denigration of local
property taxation and control as would follow from appellees'
contentions. It has simply never been within the constitutional
prerogative of this Court to nullify state-wide measures for
financing public services merely because the burdens or benefits
thereof fall unevenly depending upon the relative wealth of the
political subdivisions in which citizens live.
In sum, to the extent that the Texas system of school financing
results in unequal expenditures between children Page 411 U. S. 55 who happen to reside in different districts, we cannot say that
such disparities are the product of a system that is so irrational
as to be invidiously discriminatory. Texas has acknowledged its
shortcomings, and has persistently endeavored -- not without some
success -- to ameliorate the differences in levels of expenditures
without sacrificing the benefits of local participation. The Texas
plan is not the result of hurried, ill-conceived legislation. It
certainly is not the product of purposeful discrimination against
any group or class. On the contrary, it is rooted in decades of
experience in Texas and elsewhere, and, in major part, is the
product of responsible studies by qualified people. In giving
substance to the presumption of validity to which the Texas system
is entitled, Lindsley v. Natural Carbonic Gas Co., 220 U. S. 61 , 220 U. S. 78 (1911), it is important to remember that, at every stage of its
development, it has constituted a "rough accommodation" of
interests in an effort to arrive at practical and workable
solutions. Metropolis Theatre Co. v. City of Chicago, 228 U. S. 61 , 228 U. S. 69 -70
(1913). One also must remember that the system here challenged is
not peculiar to Texas or to any other State. In its essential
characteristics, the Texas plan for financing public education
reflects what many educators for a half century have thought was an
enlightened approach to a problem for which there is no perfect
solution. We are unwilling to assume for ourselves a level of
wisdom superior to that of legislators, scholars, and educational
authorities in 50 States, especially where the alternatives
proposed are only recently conceived and nowhere yet tested. The
constitutional standard under the Equal Protection Clause is
whether the challenged state action rationally furthers a
legitimate state purpose or interest. McGinnis v. Royster, 410 U. S. 263 , 410 U. S. 270 (1973). We hold that the Texas plan abundantly satisfies this
standard. Page 411 U. S. 56 IV In light of the considerable attention that has focused on the
District Court opinion in this case and on its California
predecessor, Serrano v. Priest, 5 Cal. 3d 584 ,
487 P.2d 1241 (1971), a cautionary postscript seems appropriate. It
cannot be questioned that the constitutional judgment reached by
the District Court and approved by our dissenting Brothers today
would occasion in Texas and elsewhere an unprecedented upheaval in
public education. Some commentators have concluded that, whatever
the contours of the alternative financing programs that might be
devised and approved, the result could not avoid being a beneficial
one. But, just as there is nothing simple about the constitutional
issues involved in these cases, there is nothing simple or certain
about predicting the consequences of massive change in the
financing and control of public education. Those who have devoted
the most thoughtful attention to the practical ramifications of
these cases have found no clear or dependable answers, and their
scholarship reflects no such unqualified confidence in the
desirability of completely uprooting the existing system.
The complexity of these problems is demonstrated by the lack of
consensus with respect to whether it may be said with any assurance
that the poor, the racial minorities, or the children in
overburdened core-city school districts would be benefited by
abrogation of traditional modes of financing education. Unless
there is to be a substantial increase in state expenditures on
education across the board -- an event the likelihood of which is
open to considerable question [ Footnote 111 ] -- these groups stand to Page 411 U. S. 57 realize gains in terms of increased per-pupil expenditures only
if they reside in districts that presently spend at relatively low
levels, i.e., in those districts that would benefit from
the redistribution of existing resources. Yet recent studies have
indicated that the poorest families are not invariably clustered in
the most impecunious school districts. [ Footnote 112 ] Nor does it now appear that there is
any more than a random chance that racial minorities are
concentrated in property-poor districts. [ Footnote 113 ] Additionally, Page 411 U. S. 58 several research projects have concluded that any financing
alternative designed to achieve a greater equality of expenditures
is likely to lead to higher taxation and lower educational
expenditures in the major urban centers, [ Footnote 114 ] a result that would exacerbate,
rather than ameliorate, existing conditions in those areas.
These practical considerations, of course, play no role in the
adjudication of the constitutional issues presented here. But they
serve to highlight the wisdom of the traditional limitations on
this Court's function. The consideration and initiation of
fundamental reforms with respect to state taxation and education
are matters reserved for the legislative processes of the various
States, and we do no violence to the values of federalism and
separation of powers by staying our hand. We hardly need add that
this Court's action today is not to be viewed as placing its
judicial imprimatur on the status quo. The need is
apparent for reform in tax systems which may well have relied too
long and too heavily on the local property tax. And certainly
innovative thinking as to public education, its methods, and its
funding is necessary to assure both a higher level of quality and
greater uniformity of opportunity. These matters merit the
continued attention of the scholars who already Page 411 U. S. 59 have contributed much by their challenges. But the ultimate
solutions must come from the lawmakers and from the democratic
pressures of those who elect them. Reversed. [ Footnote 1 ]
Not all of the children of these complainants attend public
school. One family's children are enrolled in private school
"because of the condition of the schools in the Edgewood
Independent School District." Third Amended Complaint, App. 14.
[ Footnote 2 ]
The San Antonio Independent School District, whose name this
case still bears, was one of seven school districts in the San
Antonio metropolitan area that were originally named as defendants.
After a pretrial conference, the District Court issued an order
dismissing the school districts from the case. Subsequently, the
San Antonio Independent School District joined in the plaintiffs'
challenge to the State's school finance system and filed an amicus curiae brief in support of that position in this
Court.
[ Footnote 3 ]
A three-judge court was properly convened, and there are no
questions as to the District Court's jurisdiction or the direct
appealability of its judgment. 28 U.S.C. §§ 1253, 2281.
[ Footnote 4 ]
The trial was delayed for two years to permit extensive pretrial
discovery and to allow completion of a pending Texas legislative
investigation concerning the need for reform of its public school
finance system. 337 F.
Supp. 280 , 285 n. 11 (WD Tex.1971).
[ Footnote 5 ] 337 F.
Supp. 280 . The District Court stayed its mandate for two years
to provide Texas an opportunity to remedy the inequities found in
its financing program. The court, however, retained jurisdiction to
fashion its own remedial order if the State failed to offer an
acceptable plan. Id. at 286.
[ Footnote 6 ]
Tex.Const., Art. X, § 1 (1845):
"A general diffusion of knowledge being essential to the
preservation of the rights and liberties of the people, it shall be
the duty of the Legislature of this State to make suitable
provision for the support and maintenance of public schools." Id. § 2:
"The Legislature shall as early as practicable establish free
schools throughout the State, and shall furnish means for their
support, by taxation on property. . . ."
[ Footnote 7 ]
Tex.Const. of 1876, Art. 7, § 3, as amended, Aug. 14, 1883.
[ Footnote 8 ] Id. Art. 7, §§ 3, 4, 5.
[ Footnote 9 ]
3 Gammel's Laws of Texas 1847-1854, p. 1461. See Tex.Const. Art. 7, §§ 1, 2, 5 (interpretive commentaries); 1 Report
of Governor's Committee on Public School Education, The Challenge
and the Chance 27 (1969) (hereinafter Governor's Committee
Report).
[ Footnote 10 ]
Tex.Const., Art. 7, § 5 ( see also the interpretive
commentary); 5 Governor's Committee Report 11-12.
[ Footnote 11 ]
The various sources of revenue for the Available School Fund are
cataloged in A Report of the Adequacy of Texas Schools, prepared by
Texas State Board of Education, 7-15 (1938) (hereinafter Texas
State Bd. of Educ.).
[ Footnote 12 ]
Tex.Const., Art. 7, § 3, as amended, Nov. 5, 1918 ( see interpretive commentary).
[ Footnote 13 ]
l Governor's Committee Report 35; Texas State Bd. of Educ., supra, n 11, at
5-7; J. Coons, W. Clune, & S. Sugarman, Private Wealth and
Public Education 48-49 (1970); E. Cubberley, School Funds and Their
Apportionment 21-27 (1905).
[ Footnote 14 ]
By 1940, one-half of the State's population was clustered in its
metropolitan centers. 1 Governor's Committee Report 35.
[ Footnote 15 ]
Gilmer-Aikin Committee, To Have What We Must 13 (1948).
[ Footnote 16 ]
R. Still, The Gilmer-Aikin Bills 11-13 (1950); Texas State Bd.
of Educ., supra, n 11.
[ Footnote 17 ]
Still, supra, n. 16 at 12. It should be noted that, during this period,
the median per-pupil expenditure for all schools with an enrollment
of more than 200 was approximately $50 per year. During this same
period, a survey conducted by the State Board of Education
concluded that,
"in Texas, the best educational advantages offered by the State
at present may be had for the median cost of $52.67 per year per
pupil in average daily attendance."
Texas State Bd. of Educ., supra, n 11, at 56.
[ Footnote 18 ]
General Laws of Texas, 46th Legis., Reg.Sess.1939, c. 7, pp.
274-275 ($22.50 per student); General & Spec.Laws of Texas,
48th Legis., Reg.Sess.1943, c. 161, pp. 262-263 ($25 per
student).
[ Footnote 19 ]
General & Spec.Laws of Texas, 49th Legis., Reg.Sess.1945, c.
52, pp. 74-75; Still, supra, n 16, at 12.
[ Footnote 20 ]
For a complete history of the adoption in Texas of a foundation
program, see Still, supra, n 16. See also 5 Governor's Committee
Report 14; Texas Research League, Public School Finance Problems in
Texas 9 (Interim Report 1972).
[ Footnote 21 ]
For the 1970-1971 school year, this state aid program accounted
for 48% of all public school funds. Local taxation contributed
41.1%, and 10.9% was provided in federal funds. Texas Research
League, supra, n 20, at 9.
[ Footnote 22 ]
5 Governor's Committee Report 44-48.
[ Footnote 23 ]
At present, there are 1,161 school districts in Texas. Texas
Research League, supra, n 20, at 12.
[ Footnote 24 ]
In 1948, the Gilmer-Aikin Committee found that some school
districts were not levying any local tax to support education.
Gilmer-Aikin Committee, supra, n 15, at 16. The Texas State Board of Education Survey
found that over 400 common and independent school districts were
levying no local property tax in 1935-1936. Texas State Bd. of
Educ., supra, n 11,
at 392.
[ Footnote 25 ]
Gilmer-Aikin Committee, supra, n 15, at 15.
[ Footnote 26 ]
1 Governor's Committee Report 51-53.
[ Footnote 27 ]
Texas Research League, supra, n 20, at 2.
[ Footnote 28 ]
In the years between 1949 and 1967, the average per-pupil
expenditure for all current operating expenses increased from $206
to $493. In that same period, capital expenditures increased from
$44 to $102 per pupil. 1 Governor's Committee Report 53-54.
[ Footnote 29 ]
Acts 1949, 51st Legis., p. 625, c. 334, Art. 4, Tex.Educ.Code
Ann. § 16.302 (1972); see generally 3 Governor's Committee
Report 113-146; Berke, Carnevale, Morgan & White, The Texas
School Finance Case: A Wrong in Search of a Remedy, 1 J. of L.Educ.
659, 681-682 (1972).
[ Footnote 30 ]
The family income figures are based on 1960 census
statistics.
[ Footnote 31 ]
The Available School Fund, technically, provides a second source
of state money. That Fund has continued as in years past (see text
accompanying nn 16-19, supra ) to distribute uniform per-pupil grants to every
district in the State. In 1968, this Fund allotted $98 per pupil.
However, because the Available School Fund contribution is always
subtracted from a district's entitlement under the Foundation
Program, it plays no significant role in educational finance
today.
[ Footnote 32 ]
While federal assistance has an ameliorating effect on the
difference in school budgets between wealthy and poor districts,
the District Court rejected an argument made by the State in that
court that it should consider the effect of the federal grant in
assessing the discrimination claim. 337 F. Supp. at 284. The State
has not renewed that contention here.
[ Footnote 33 ]
A map of Bexar County included in the record shows that Edgewood
and Alamo Heights are among the smallest districts in the county,
and are of approximately equal size. Yet, as the figures above
indicate, Edgewood's student population is more than four times
that of Alamo Heights. This factor obviously accounts for a
significant percentage of the differences between the two districts
in per-pupil property values and expenditures. If Alamo Heights had
as many students to educate as Edgewood does (22,000) its per pupil
assessed property value would be approximately $11,100 rather than
$49,000, and its per-pupil expenditures would therefore have been
considerably lower.
[ Footnote 34 ]
The figures quoted above vary slightly from those utilized in
the District Court opinion. 337 F. Supp. at 282. These trivial
differences are apparently a product of that court's reliance on
slightly different statistical data than we have relied upon.
[ Footnote 35 ]
Although the Foundation Program has made significantly greater
contributions to both school districts over the last several years,
it is apparent that Alamo Heights has enjoyed a larger gain. The
sizable difference between the Alamo Heights and Edgewood grants is
due to the emphasis in the State's allocation formula on the
guaranteed minimum salaries for teachers. Higher salaries are
guaranteed to teachers having more years of experience and
possessing more advanced degrees. Therefore, Alamo Heights, which
has a greater percentage of experienced personnel with advanced
degrees, receives more state support. In this regard, the Texas
Program is not unlike that presently in existence in a number of
other States. Coons, Clune & Sugarman, supra, n 13, at 63-125. Because more
dollars have been given to districts that already spend more per
pupil, such Foundation formulas have been described as
"anti-equalizing." Ibid. The formula, however, is
anti-equalizing only if viewed in absolute terms. The percentage
disparity between the two Texas districts is diminished
substantially by state aid. Alamo Heights derived in 1967-1968
almost 13 times as much money from local taxes as Edgewood did. The
state aid grants to each district in 1970-1971 lowered the ratio to
approximately two to one, i.e., Alamo Heights had a little
more than twice as much money to spend per pupil from its combined
state and local resources.
[ Footnote 36 ]
Texas Research League, supra, n 20, at 13.
[ Footnote 37 ]
The Economic Index, which determines each county's share of the
total Local Fund Assignment, is based on a complex formula
conceived in 1949 when the Foundation Program was instituted. See text, supra at 411 U. S. 9 -10. It
has frequently been suggested by Texas researchers that the formula
be altered in several respects to provide a more accurate
reflection of local taxpaying ability, especially of urban school
districts. 5 Governor's Committee Report 48; Texas Research League,
Texas Public School Finance: A Majority of Exceptions 31-32 (2d
Interim Report 1972); Berke, Carnevale, Morgan White, supra, n 29, at
680-681.
[ Footnote 38 ]
The District Court relied on the findings presented in an
affidavit submitted by Professor Berke of Syracuse University. His
sampling of 110 Texas school districts demonstrated a direct
correlation between the amount of a district's taxable property and
it level of per-pupil expenditures. But his study found only a
partial correlation between a district's median family income and
per-pupil expenditures. The study also shows, in the relatively few
districts at the extremes, an inverse correlation between
percentage of minorities and expenditures.
Categorized by Equalized Property Values,
Median Family Income, and State-Local Revenue
Market Value Median State &
of Taxable Family Per Cent Local
Property Income Minority Revenues
Per Pupil From 1960 Pupils Per Pupil
Above $100,000 $5,900 8% $815
(10 districts)
$100,000-$50,000 $4,425 32% $544
(26 districts)
$50,00$30,000 $4,900 23% $483
(30 districts)
$30,000-$10,000 $5,050 31% $462
(40 districts)
Below $10,000 $3,325 79% $305
(4 districts)
Although the correlations with respect to family income and race
appear only to exist at the extremes, and although the affiant's
methodology has been questioned ( see Goldstein,
Inter-district Inequalities in School Financing: A Critical
Analysis of Serrano v. Priest and its Progeny, 120
U.Pa.L.Rev. 504, 523-525, nn. 67, 71 (1972)), insofar as any of
these correlations is relevant to the constitutional thesis
presented in this case, we may accept its basic thrust. But see
infra at 411 U. S. 25 -27.
For a defense of the reliability of the affidavit, see Berke, Carnevale, Morgan & White, supra, n 29.
[ Footnote 39 ] E.g., Police Dept. of Chicago v. Mosley, 408 U. S.
92 (1972); Dunn v. Blumstein, 405 U.
S. 330 (1972); Shapiro v. Thompson, 394 U. S. 618 (1969).
[ Footnote 40 ] E.g., Graham v. Richardson, 403 U.
S. 365 (1971); Loving v. Virginia, 388 U. S.
1 (1967); McLaughlin v. Florida, 379 U.
S. 184 (1964).
[ Footnote 41 ] See Dunn v. Blumstein, supra, at 405 U. S. 343 ,
and the cases collected therein.
[ Footnote 42 ]
Brief for Appellants 11.
[ Footnote 43 ] Ibid. [ Footnote 44 ]
Tr. of Oral Arg. 3; Reply Brief for Appellants 2.
[ Footnote 45 ] E.g., Griffin v. Illinois, 351 U. S.
12 (1956); Douglas v. California, 372 U.
S. 353 (1963).
[ Footnote 46 ] Harper v. Virginia Bd. of Elections, 383 U.
S. 663 (1966); McDonald v. Board of Election
Comm'rs, 394 U. S. 802 (1969); Bullock v. Carter, 405 U.
S. 134 (1972); Goosby v. Osser, 409 U.
S. 512 (1973).
[ Footnote 47 ] See cases cited in text, infra at 411 U. S.
29 -30.
[ Footnote 48 ] Serrano v. Priest, 5 Cal. 3d 584 ,
487 P.2d 1241 (1971); Van Dusartz v.
Hatfield, 334 F.
Supp. 870 (Minn.1971); Robinson v. Cahill, 118
N.J.Super. 223, 287 A.2d 187 (1972); Milliken v. Green, 389 Mich. 1, 203 N.W.2d
457 (1972), rehearing granted, Jan., 1973.
[ Footnote 49 ]
In their complaint, appellees purported to represent a class
composed of persons who are "poor" and who reside in school
districts having a "low value of . . . property." Third Amended
Complaint, App. 15. Yet appellees have not defined the term "poor"
with reference to any absolute or functional level of impecunity. See text, infra at 411 U. S. 22 -23. See also Brief for Appellees 1, 3; Tr. of Oral Arg.
221.
[ Footnote 50 ]
Appellees' proof at trial focused on comparative differences in
family incomes between residents of wealthy and poor districts.
They endeavored, apparently, to show that there exists a direct
correlation between personal family income and educational
expenditures. See text, infra at 411 U. S. 25 -27.
The District Court may have been relying on this notion of relative
discrimination based on family wealth. Citing appellees'
statistical proof, the court emphasized that "those districts most
rich in property also have the highest median family income .
.while the poor property districts are poor in income. . . ." 337
F. Supp. at 282.
[ Footnote 51 ]
At oral argument, and in their brief, appellees suggest that
description of the personal status of the residents in districts
that spend less on education is not critical to their case. In
their view, the Texas system is impermissibly discriminatory even
if relatively poor districts do not contain poor people. Brief for
Appellees 43-44; Tr. of Oral Arg. 20-21. There are indications in
the District Court opinion that it adopted this theory of district
discrimination. The opinion repeatedly emphasizes the comparative
financial status of districts, and, early in the opinion, it
describes appellees' class as being composed of "all . . . children
throughout Texas who live in school districts with low property
valuations." 337 F. Supp. at 281.
[ Footnote 52 ] Mayer v. City of Chicago, 404 U.
S. 189 (1971); Williams v. Oklahoma City, 395 U. S. 458 (1969); Gardner v. California, 393 U.
S. 367 (1969); Roberts v. LaVallee, 389 U. S. 40 (1967); Long v. District Court of Iowa, 385 U.
S. 192 (1966); Draper v. Washington, 372 U. S. 487 (1963); Eskridge v. Washington Prison Board, 357 U.
S. 214 (1958).
[ Footnote 53 ]
Note, A Statistical Analysis of the School Finance Decisions: On
Winning Battles and Losing Wars, 81 Yale L.J. 1303, 1328-1329
(1972).
[ Footnote 54 ] Id. at 1324 and n. 102
[ Footnote 55 ] Id. at 1328
[ Footnote 56 ]
Each of appellees' possible theories of wealth discrimination is
founded on the assumption that the quality of education varies
directly with the amount of funds expended on it, and that,
therefore, the difference in quality between two schools can be
determined simplistically by looking at the difference in per-pupil
expenditures. This is a matter of considerable dispute among
educators and commentators. See nn. 86 and | 86
and S. 1fn101|>101, infra. [ Footnote 57 ] E.g., Bullock v. Carter, 405 U.S. at 405 U. S. 137 ,
149; Mayer v. City of Chicago, 404 U.S. at 404 U. S. 194 ; Draper v. Washington, 372 U.S. at 372 U. S.
495 -496; Douglas v. California, 372 U.S. at 372 U. S.
367 .
[ Footnote 58 ]
Gilmer-Aikin Committee, supra, n 15, at 13. Indeed, even though local funding
has long been a significant aspect of educational funding, the
State has always viewed providing an acceptable education as one of
its primary functions. See Texas State Bd. of Educ., supra, n 11, at 1,
7.
[ Footnote 59 ]
Brief for Appellants 35; Reply Brief for Appellants 1.
[ Footnote 60 ]
An educational financing system might be hypothesized, however,
in which the analogy to the wealth discrimination cases would be
considerably closer. If elementary and secondary education were
made available by the State only to those able to pay a tuition
assessed against each pupil, there would be a clearly defined class
of "poor" people -- definable in terms of their inability to pay
the prescribed sum -- who would be absolutely precluded from
receiving an education. That case would present a far more
compelling set of circumstances for judicial assistance than the
case before us today. After all, Texas has undertaken to do a good
deal more than provide an education to those who can afford it. It
has provided what it considers to be an adequate base education for
all children, and has attempted, though imperfectly, to ameliorate
by state funding and by the local assessment program the
disparities in local tax resources.
[ Footnote 61 ]
Also it should be recognized that median income statistics may
not define with any precision the status of individual families
within any given district. A more dependable showing of comparative
wealth discrimination would also examine factors such as the
average income, the mode, and the concentration of poor families in
any district.
[ Footnote 62 ] Cf. Jefferson v. Hackney, 406 U.
S. 535 , 406 U. S.
547 -549 (1972); Ely, Legislative and Administrative
Motivation in Constitutional Law 79 Yale L.J. 1205, 1258-1259
(1970); Simon, The School Finance Decisions: Collective Bargaining
and Future Finance Systems, 82 Yale L.J. 409, 439-440 (1973).
[ Footnote 63 ] Supra at 411 U. S. 15 n.
38.
[ Footnote 64 ]
Studies in other States have also questioned the existence of
any dependable correlation between a district's wealth measured in
terms of assessable property and the collective wealth of families
residing in the district measured in terms of median family income.
Ridenour & Ridenour, Serrano v. Priest: Wealth and
Kansas School Finance, 20 Kan.L.Rev. 213, 225 (1972) ("it can be
argued that there exists in Kansas almost an inverse correlation:
districts with highest income per pupil have low assessed value per
pupil, and districts with high assessed value per pupil have low
income per pupil"); Davis, Taxpaying Ability: A Study of the
Relationship Between Wealth and Income in California Counties, in
The Challenge of Change in School Finance, 10th Nat. Educational
Assn. Conf. on School Finance 199 (1967). Note, 81 Yale L.J., supra, n 53. See also Goldstein, supra, n 38, at 522-527.
[ Footnote 65 ]
Indeed, this is precisely how the plaintiffs in Serrano v.
Priest defined the class they purported to represent:
"Plaintiff children claim to represent a class consisting of all
public school pupils in California, 'except children in that school
district . . . which . . . affords the greatest educational
opportunity of all school districts within California.'"
5 Cal. 3d at 589, 487 P.2d at 1244. See also Van Dusartz v.
Hatfield, 334 F. Supp. at 873.
[ Footnote 66 ]
Appellees, however, have avoided describing the Texas system as
one resulting merely in discrimination between districts per
se, since this Court has never questioned the State's power to
draw reasonable distinctions between political subdivisions within
its borders. Griffin v. County School Board of Prince Edward
County, 377 U. S. 218 , 377 U. S.
230 -231 (1964); McGowan v. Maryland, 366 U. S. 420 , 366 U. S. 427 (1961); Salsbury v. Maryland, 346 U.
S. 545 , 346 U. S. 552 (1954).
[ Footnote 67 ] E.g., Harper v. Virginia Bd. of Elections, 383 U.
S. 663 (1966); United States v. Kras, 409 U. S. 434 (1973). See MR. JUSTICE MARSHALL's dissenting opinion, post at 411 U. S.
121 .
[ Footnote 68 ] See Serrano v. Priest, supra; Van Dusartz v. Hatfield,
supra; Robinson v. Cahill, 118 N.J.Super. 223, 287 A.2d 187 (1972); Coons, Clune & Sugarman, supra, n 13, at
339-393; Goldstein, supra, n 38, at 534-541; Vieira, Unequal Educational
Expenditures: Some Minority Views on Serrano v. Priest, 37
Mo.L.Rev. 617, 618-624 (1972); Comment, Educational Financing,
Equal Protection of the Laws, and the Supreme Court, 70 Mich.L.Rev.
1324, 1335-1342 (1972); Note, The Public School Financing Cases:
Inter-district Inequalities and Wealth Discrimination, 14
Ariz.L.Rev. 88, 120-124 (1972).
[ Footnote 69 ]
337 F. Supp. at 283.
[ Footnote 70 ] E.g., United States v. Guest, 383 U.
S. 745 , 383 U. S.
757 -759 (1966); Oregon v. Mitchell, 400 U. S. 112 , 400 U. S. 229 , 400 U. S.
237 -238 (1970) (opinion of BRENNAN, WHITE, and MARSHALL,
JJ.).
[ Footnote 71 ]
After Dandridge v. Williams, 397 U.
S. 471 (1970), there could be no lingering question
about the constitutional foundation for the Court's holding in Shapiro. In Dandridge, the Court applied the
rational basis test in reviewing Maryland's maximum family grant
provision under its AFDC program. A federal district court held the
provision unconstitutional, applying a stricter standard of review.
In the course of reversing the lower court, the Court distinguished Shapiro properly on the ground that, in that case, "the
Court found state interference with the constitutionally protected
freedom of interstate travel." Id. at 397 U. S. 484 n. 16.
[ Footnote 72 ]
The Court refused to apply the strict scrutiny test despite its
contemporaneous recognition in Goldberg v. Kelly, 397 U. S. 254 , 397 U. S. 264 (1970) that "welfare provides the means to obtain essential food,
clothing, housing, and medical care."
[ Footnote 73 ]
In Eisenstadt, the Court struck down a Massachusetts
statute that prohibited the distribution of contraceptive devices,
finding that the law failed "to satisfy even the more lenient equal
protection standard." 405 U.S. at 405 U. S. 447 n. 7. Nevertheless, in dictum, the Court recited the
correct form of equal protection analysis:
"[I]f we were to conclude that the Massachusetts statute
impinges upon fundamental freedoms under Griswold [v.
Connecticut, 381 U. S. 479 (1965)], the
statutory classification would have to be not merely rationally
related to a valid public purpose, but necessary to
the achievement of a compelling state interest." Ibid. (emphasis in original).
[ Footnote 74 ] Dunn fully canvasses this Court's voting rights cases,
and explains that
"this Court has made clear that a citizen has a constitutionally protected right to participate in
elections on an equal basis with other citizens in the
jurisdiction."
405 U.S. at 405 U. S. 336 (emphasis supplied). The constitutional underpinnings of the right
to equal treatment in the voting process can no longer be doubted,
even though, as the Court noted in Harper v. Virginia Bd. of
Elections, 383 U.S. at 383 U. S. 665 ,
"the right to vote in state elections is nowhere expressly
mentioned." See Oregon v. Mitchell, 400 U.S. at 400 U. S. 135 , 400 U. S.
138 -44 (DOUGLAS, J.), 400 U. S. 229 , 400 U. S.
241 -242 (BRENNAN, WHITE, and MARSHALL, JJ.); Bullock
v. Carter, 405 U.S. at 405 U. S.
140 -144; Kramer v. Union School District, 395 U. S. 621 , 395 U. S.
625 -630 (1969); Williams v. Rhodes, 393 U. S. 23 , 393 U. S. 29 , 393 U. S. 30 -31
(1968); Reynolds v. Sims, 377 U.
S. 533 , 377 U. S.
554 -562 (1964); Gray v. Sanders, 372 U.
S. 368 , 372 U. S.
379 -381 (1963).
[ Footnote 75 ]
In Mosley, the Court struck down a Chicago
anti-picketing ordinance that exempted labor picketing from its
prohibitions. The ordinance was held invalid under the Equal
Protection Clause after subjecting it to careful scrutiny and
finding that the ordinance was not narrowly drawn. The stricter
standard of review was appropriately applied, since the ordinance
was one "affecting First Amendment interests." 408 U.S. at 408 U. S.
101 .
[ Footnote 76 ] Skinner applied the standard of close scrutiny to a
state law permitting forced sterilization of "habitual criminals."
Implicit in the Court's opinion is the recognition that the right
of procreation is among the rights of personal privacy protected
under the Constitution. See Roe v. Wade, 410 U.
S. 113 , 410 U. S. 152 (1973).
[ Footnote 77 ] See, e.g., Red Lion Broadcasting Co. v. FCC, 395 U. S. 367 , 395 U. S.
389 -390 (1969); Stanley v.Georgia, 394 U.
S. 557 , 394 U. S. 564 (1969); Lamont v. Postmaster General, 381 U.
S. 301 , 381 U. S.
306 -307 (1965).
[ Footnote 78 ]
Since the right to vote, per se, is not a
constitutionally protected right, we assume that appellees'
references to that right are simply shorthand references to the
protected right, implicit in our constitutional system, to
participate in state elections on an equal basis with other
qualified voters whenever the State has adopted an elective process
for determining who will represent any segment of the State's
population. See n 74, supra.
[ Footnote 79 ]
The States have often pursued their entirely legitimate interest
in assuring "intelligent exercise of the franchise," Katzenbach
v. Morgan, 384 U. S. 641 , 384 U. S. 655 (1966), through such devices as literacy tests and age restrictions
on the right to vote. See ibid.; Oregon v. Mitchell, 400 U. S. 112 (1970). And, where those restrictions have been found to promote
intelligent use of the ballot without discriminating against those
racial and ethnic minorities previously deprived of an equal
educational opportunity, this Court has upheld their use. Compare Lassiter v. Northampton County Bd. of Elections, 360 U. S. 45 (1959), with Oregon v. Mitchell, supra, at 400 U. S. 133 (Black, J.), 400 U. S. 135 , 400 U. S.
144 -147 (DOUGLAS, J.), 400 U. S. 152 , 400 U. S.
216 -217 (Harlan, J.), 400 U. S. 229 , 400 U. S.
231 -236 (BRENNAN, WHITE, and MARSHALL, JJ.), 400 U. S. 281 , 400 U. S.
282 -284 (STEWART, J.), and Gaston County v. United
States, 395 U. S. 285 (1969).
[ Footnote 80 ] See Schoettle, The Equal Protection Clause in Public
Education, 71 Col.L.Rev. 1355, 1389-1390 (1971); Vieira, supra, 411 U. S. 68,
at 622-623; Comment, Tenant Interest Representation: Proposal for a
National Tenants' Association, 47 Tex.L.Rev. 1160, 1172-1173, n. 61
(1969).
[ Footnote 81 ] Katzenbach v. Morgan involved a challenge by registered
voters in New York City to a provision of the Voting Rights Act of
1965 that prohibited enforcement of a state law calling for English
literacy tests for voting. The law was suspended as to residents
from Puerto Rico who had completed at least six years of education
at an "American-flag" school in that country even though the
language of instruction was other than English. This Court upheld
the questioned provision of the 1965 Act over the claim that it
discriminated against those with a sixth-grade education obtained
in non-English-speaking schools other than the ones designated by
the federal legislation.
[ Footnote 82 ] Cf. Meyer v. Nebraska, 262 U.
S. 390 (1923); Pierce v. Society of Sisters, 268 U. S. 510 (1925); Hargrave v. Kirk, 313 F.
Supp. 944 (MD Fla.1970), vacated, 401 U.
S. 476 (1971).
[ Footnote 83 ] See Schilb v. Kuebel, 404 U. S. 357 (1971); McDonald v. Board of Election Comm'rs, 394 U. S. 802 (1969).
[ Footnote 84 ] See, e.g., Bell's Gap R. Co. v. Pennsylvania, 134 U. S. 232 (1890); Carmichael v. Southern Coal & Coke Co., 301 U. S. 495 , 301 U. S.
508 -509 (1937); Allied Stores of Ohio v.
Bowers, 358 U. S. 522 (1959).
[ Footnote 85 ]
Those who urge that the present system be invalidated offer
little guidance as to what type of school financing should replace
it. The most likely result of rejection of the existing system
would be state-wide financing of all public education with funds
derived from taxation of property or from the adoption or expansion
of sale and income taxes. See Simon, supra, n 62. The authors of Private
Wealth and Public Education, supra, n 13, at 201-242, suggest an alternative scheme,
known as "district power equalizing." In simplest terms, the State
would guarantee that, at any particular rate of property taxation
the district would receive a stated number of dollars regardless of
the district's tax base. To finance the subsidies to "poorer"
districts, funds would be taken away from the "wealthier" districts
that, because of their higher property values, collect more than
the stated amount at any given rate. This is not the place to weigh
the arguments for and against "district power equalizing," beyond
noting that commentators are in disagreement as to whether it is
feasible, how it would work, and indeed whether it would violate
the equal protection theory underlying appellees' case. President's
Commission on School Finance, Schools, People & Money 32-33
(1972); Bateman & Brown, Some Reflections on Serrano v.
Priest, 49 J. Urban L. 701, 706-708 (1972); Brest, Book
Review, 23 Stan.L.Rev. 591, 594-596 (1971); Goldstein, supra, n 38, at
542-543; Wise, School Finance Equalization Lawsuits: A Model
Legislative Response, 2 Yale Rev. of L. & Soc.Action 123, 125
(1971); Silard & White, Intrastate Inequalities in Public
Education: The Case for Judicial Relief Under the Equal Protection
Clause, 1970 Wis.L.Rev. 7, 29-30.
[ Footnote 86 ]
The quality-cost controversy has received considerable
attention. Among the notable authorities on both sides are the
following: C. Jencks, Inequality (1972); C. Silberman, Crisis in
the Classroom (1970); U.S. Office of Education, Equality of
Educational Opportunity (1966) (the Coleman Report); On Equality of
Educational Opportunity (F. Mosteller 8 D. Moynihan eds.1972); J.
Guthrie, G. Kleindorfer, H. Levin R. Stout, Schools and Inequality
(1971); President's Commission on School Finance, supra, n. 85; Swanson, The Cost-Quality Relationship, in The Challenge of
Change in School Finance, 10th Nat. Educational Assn. Conf. on
School Finance 151 (1967).
[ Footnote 87 ] See the results of the Texas Governor's Committee's
state-wide survey on the goals of education in that State. 1
Governor's Committee Report 59-68. See also Goldstein, supra, n 38, at
519-522; Schoettle, supra, n 80, authorities cited in n 86, supra. [ Footnote 88 ] Allied Stores of Ohio v. Bowers, 358 U.
S. 522 , 358 U. S. 530 , 358 U. S. 532 (1959) (BRENNAN, J., concurring); Katzenbach v. Morgan, 384 U.S. at 384 U. S. 659 , 384 U. S. 661 (Harlan, J., dissenting).
[ Footnote 89 ]
In 1970 Texas expended approximately $2.1 billion for education
and a little over $1 billion came from the Minimum Foundation
Program. Texas Research League, supra, n 20, at 2
[ Footnote 90 ]
Tex.Educ.Code Ann. § 16.13 (1972).
[ Footnote 91 ] Id. § 16.18.
[ Footnote 92 ] Id., § 16.15.
[ Footnote 93 ] Id. §§ 16.16, 16.17, 16.19.
[ Footnote 94 ] Id., §§ 16.45, 16.51-16.63.
[ Footnote 95 ] Id. §§ 12.01-12.04.
[ Footnote 96 ] Id. § 11.26(5).
[ Footnote 97 ] Id. § 16.301 et seq. [ Footnote 98 ] See supra at 411 U. S.
13 -14.
[ Footnote 99 ]
Gilmer-Aikin Committee, supra, n 15, at 15.
[ Footnote 100 ]
There is no uniform state-wide assessment practice in Texas.
Commercial property, for example, might be assessed at 30% of
market value in one county and at 50% in another. 5 Governor'
Committee Report 25-26; Berke, Carnevale, Morgan & White, supra, n 29, at
666-667, n. 16.
[ Footnote 101 ]
Texas Research League, supra, n 20, at 18. Texas, in this regard, is not unlike most
other States. One commentator has observed that "disparities in
expenditures appear to be largely explained by variations in
teacher salaries." Simon, supra, n 62, at 413.
As previously noted, see text accompanying n 86, supra, the extent to
which the quality of education varies with expenditure per pupil is
debated inconclusively by the most thoughtful students of public
education. While all would agree that there is a correlation up to
the point of providing the recognized essentials in facilities and
academic opportunities, the issues of greatest disagreement include
the effect on the quality of education of pupil-teacher ratios and
of higher teacher salary schedules. E.g., Office of
Education, supra, n 86, at 316-319. The state funding in Texas is designed to assure,
on the average, one teacher for every 25 students, which is
considered to be a favorable ratio by most standards. Whether the
minimum salary of $6,000 per year is sufficient in Texas to attract
qualified teachers may be more debatable, depending in major part
upon the location of the school district. But there appear to be
few empirical data that support the advantage of any particular
pupil-teacher ratio or that document the existence of a dependable
correlation between the level of public school teachers' salaries
and the quality of their classroom instruction. An intractable
problem in dealing with teachers' salaries is the absence, up to
this time, of satisfactory techniques for judging their ability or
performance. Relatively few school systems have merit plans of any
kind, with the result that teachers' salaries are usually increased
across the board in a way which tends to reward the least deserving
on the same basis as the most deserving. Salaries are usually
raised automatically on the basis of length of service and
according to predetermined "steps," extending over 10- to 12-year
periods.
[ Footnote 102 ]
President's Commission on School Finance, supra, n 85, at 9. Until recently,
Hawaii was the only State that maintained a purely state-funded
educational program. In 1968, however, that State amended its
educational finance statute to permit counties to collect
additional funds locally and spend those amounts on its schools.
The rationale for that recent legislative choice is instructive on
the question before the Court today:
"Under existing law, counties are precluded from doing anything
in this area, even to spend their own funds if they so desire. This
corrective legislation is urgently needed in order to allow
counties to go above and beyond the State's standards and provide
educational facilities as good as the people of the counties want
and are willing to pay for. Allowing local communities to go above
and beyond established minimums to provide for their people
encourages the best features of democratic government."
Haw.Sess.Laws 1968, Act 38, § 1.
[ Footnote 103 ] See text accompanying n 7, supra. [ Footnote 104 ]
G. Strayer & R. Haig, The Financing of Education in the
State of New York (1923). For a thorough analysis of the
contribution of these reformers and of the prior and subsequent
history of educational finance, see Coons, Clune &
Sugarman, supra, n 13, at 39-95.
[ Footnote 105 ]
J. Coleman, Foreword to Strayer & Haig, supra, at
vii.
[ Footnote 106 ] New State Ice Co. v. Liebmann, 285 U.
S. 262 , 285 U. S. 280 , 285 U. S. 311 (1932) (Brandeis, J., dissenting).
[ Footnote 107 ]
MR. JUSTICE WHITE suggests in his dissent that the Texas system
violates the Equal Protection Clause because the means it has
selected to effectuate its interest in local autonomy fail to
guarantee complete freedom of choice to every district. He places
special emphasis on the statutory provision that establishes a
maximum rate of $1.50 per $100 valuation at which a local school
district may tax for school maintenance. Tex.Educ.Code Ann. §
20.04(d) (1972). The maintenance rate in Edgewood when this case
was litigated in the District Court was $.55 per $100, barely
one-third of the allowable rate. (The tax rate of $1.05 per $100, see supra at 411 U. S. 12 , is
the equalized rate for maintenance and for the retirement of
bonds.) Appellees do not claim that the ceiling presently bars
desired tax increases in Edgewood or in any other Texas district.
Therefore, the constitutionality of that statutory provision is not
before us, and must await litigation in a case in which it is
properly presented. Cf. Hargrave v. Kirk, 313 F.
Supp. 944 (MD Fla.1970), vacated, 401 U.
S. 476 (1971).
[ Footnote 108 ]
MR. JUSTICE MARSHALL states in his dissenting opinion that the
State's asserted interest in local control is a "mere
sham," post, at 411 U. S. 130 ,
and that it has been offered not as a legitimate justification, but
"as an excuse . . . for inter-district inequality." Id. at 411 U. S. 126 .
In addition to asserting that local control would be preserved and
possibly better served under other systems -- a consideration that
we find irrelevant for the purpose of deciding whether the system
may be said to be supported by a legitimate and reasonable basis --
the dissent suggests that Texas' lack of good faith may be
demonstrated by examining the extent to which the State already
maintains considerable control. The State, we are told, regulates
"the most minute details of local public education," ibid., including textbook selection, teacher
qualifications, and the length of the school day. This assertion,
that genuine local control does not exist in Texas, simply cannot
be supported. It is abundantly refuted by the elaborate statutory
division of responsibilities set out in the Texas Education Code.
Although policy decisionmaking and supervision in certain areas are
reserved to the State, the day-to-day authority over the
"management and control" of all public elementary and secondary
schools is squarely placed on the local school boards.
Tex.Educ.Code Ann. §§ 17.01, 23.26 (1972). Among the innumerable
specific powers of the local school authorities are the following:
the power of eminent domain to acquire land for the construction of
school facilities, id. §§ 17.26, 23.26; the power to hire
and terminate teachers and other personnel, id. §§
13.101-13.103; the power to designate conditions of teacher
employment and to establish certain standards of educational
policy, id. § 13.901; the power to maintain order and
discipline, id. § 21.305, including the prerogative to
suspend students for disciplinary reasons, id. § 21.301;
the power to decide whether to offer a kindergarten program, id. §§ 21.131-21.135, or a vocational training program, id. § 21.111, or a program of special education for the
handicapped, id. § 11.16; the power to control the
assignment and transfer of students, id. §§ 21.074-21.080;
and the power to operate and maintain a school bus program, id. § 16.52. See also Pervis v. LaMarque Ind. School
Dist., 328 F.
Supp. 638 , 642-643 (SD Tex.1971), reversed, 466 F.2d
1054 (CA5 1972); Nichols v. Aldine Ind. School Dist., 356
S.W.2d 182 (Tex.Civ.App. 1962). Local school boards also determine
attendance zones, location of new schools, closing of old ones,
school attendance hours (within limits), grading and promotion
policies subject to general guidelines, recreational and athletic
policies, and a myriad of other matters in the routine of school
administration. It cannot be seriously doubted that, in Texas,
education remains largely a local function, and that the
preponderating bulk of all decisions affecting the schools is made
and executed at the local level, guaranteeing the greatest
participation by those most directly concerned.
[ Footnote 109 ]
This theme -- that greater state control over funding will lead
to greater state power with respect to local educational programs
and policies -- is a recurrent one in the literature on financing
public education. Professor Simon, in his thoughtful analysis of
the political ramifications of this case, states that one of the
most likely consequences of the District Court's decision would be
an increase in the centralization of school finance and an increase
in the extent of collective bargaining by teacher unions at the
state level. He suggests that the subjects for bargaining may
include many "non-salary" items, such as teaching loads, class
size, curricular and program choices, questions of student
discipline, and selection of administrative personnel -- matters
traditionally decided heretofore at the local level. Simon, supra, n 62, at
434-436. See, e.g., Coleman, The Struggle for Control of
Education, in Education and Social Policy: Local Control of
Education 64, 77-79 (C. Bowers, I. Housego & D. Dyke eds.1970);
J. Conant, The Child, The Parent, and The State 27 (1959) ("Unless
a local community, through its school board, has some control over
the purse, there can be little real feeling in the community that
the schools are in fact, local schools. . . ."); Howe, Anatomy of a
Revolution, in Saturday Review 84, 88 (Nov. 20, 1971) ("It is an
axiom of American politics that control and power follow money. . .
."); R. Hutchinson, State-Administered Locally Shared Taxes 21
(1931) ("[S]tate administration of taxation is the first step
toward state control of the functions supported by these taxes. . .
."). Irrespective of whether one regards such prospects as
detrimental or whether he agrees that the consequence is
inevitable, it certainly cannot be doubted that there is a rational
basis for this concern on the part of parents, educators, and
legislators.
[ Footnote 110 ]
This Court has never doubted the propriety of maintaining
political subdivisions within the States and has never found in the
Equal Protection Clause any per se rule of "territorial
uniformity." McGowan v. Maryland, 366 U.S. at 366 U. S. 427 . See also Griffin v. County School Board of Prince Edward
County, 377 U.S. at 377 U. S.
230 -231; Salsbury v. Maryland, 346 U.
S. 545 (1954). Cf. Board of Education of Muskogee v.
Oklahoma, 409 F.2d 665, 668 (CA10 1969).
[ Footnote 111 ]
Any alternative that calls for significant increases in
expenditures for education, whether financed through increases in
property taxation or through other sources of tax dollars, such as
income and sales taxes, is certain to encounter political barriers.
At a time when nearly every State and locality is suffering from
fiscal undernourishment, and with demands for services of all kinds
burgeoning and with weary taxpayers already resisting tax
increases, there is considerable reason to question whether a
decision of this Court nullifying present state taxing systems
would result in a marked increase in the financial commitment to
education. See Senate Select Committee on Equal
Educational Opportunity, 92d Cong., 2d Sess., Toward Equal
Educational Opportunity 339-345 (Comm.Print 1972); Berke &
Callahan, Serrano v. Priest: Milestone or Millstone for
School Finance, 21 J.Pub.L. 23, 25-26 (1972); Simon, supra, n. 62 at
420-421. In Texas, it has been calculated that $2.4 billion of
additional school funds would be required to bring all schools in
that State up to the present level of expenditure of all but the
wealthiest districts -- an amount more than double that currently
being spent on education. Texas Research League, supra, n 20, at 16-18. An amicus curiae brief filed on behalf of almost 30 States,
focusing on these practical consequences, claims with some
justification that "each of the undersigned states . . . would
suffer severe financial stringency." Brief of Amici Curiae in Support of Appellants 2 (filed by Montgomery County, Md. et
al.).
[ Footnote 112 ] See Note, supra, n 53. See also authorities cited n 114, infra. [ Footnote 113 ] See Goldstein, supra, n 38, at 526; Jencks, supra, n 86, at 27; U.S. Comm'n on Civil
Rights, Inequality in School Financing: The Role of the Law 37
(1972). Coons, Clune & Sugarman, supra, n 13, at 356-357, n. 47, have noted that,
in California, for example, "[f]ifty-nine percent . . . of minority
students live in districts above the median [average valuation per
pupil.]" In Bexar County, the largest district by far -- the San
Antonio Independent School District -- is above the local average
in both the amount of taxable wealth per pupil and in median family
income. Yet 72% of its students are Mexican-Americans. And, in
1967-1968, it spent only a very few dollars less per pupil than the
North East and North Side Independent School Districts, which have
only 7% and 18% Mexican-American enrollment respectively. Berke,
Carnevale, Morgan & White, supra, n 29, at 673.
[ Footnote 114 ] See Senate Select Committee on Equal Educational
Opportunity, 92d Cong., 2d Sess., Issues in School Finance 129
(Comm.Print 1972) (monograph entitled Inequities in School Finance
prepared by Professors Berke and Callahan); U.S. Office of
Education, Finances of Large-City School Systems: A Comparative
Analysis (1972) (HEW publication); U.S. Comm'n on Civil Rights, supra, n 113 at
33-36; Simon, supra, n 62, at 410-411, 418.
MR. JUSTICE STEWART, concurring.
The method of financing public schools in Texas, as in almost
every other State, has resulted in a system of public education
that can fairly be described as chaotic and unjust. [ Footnote 2/1 ] It does not follow, however,
and I cannot find, that this system violates the Constitution of
the United States. I join the opinion and judgment of the Court
because I am convinced that any other course would mark an
extraordinary departure from principled adjudication under the
Equal Protection Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment. The uncharted
directions of such a departure are suggested, I think, by the
imaginative dissenting opinion my Brother MARSHALL has filed
today.
Unlike other provisions of the Constitution, the Equal
Protection Clause confers no substantive rights and creates no
substantive liberties. [ Footnote
2/2 ] The function of the Equal Protection Clause, rather, is
simply to measure the validity of classifications created
by state laws. Page 411 U. S. 60 There is hardly a law on the books that does not affect some
people differently from others. But the basic concern of the Equal
Protection Clause is with state legislation whose purpose or effect
is to create discrete and objectively identifiable classes.
[ Footnote 2/3 ] And, with respect to
such legislation, it has long been settled that the Equal
Protection Clause is offended only by laws that are invidiously
discriminatory -- only by classifications that are wholly arbitrary
or capricious. See, e.g., Rinaldi v. Yeager, 384 U.
S. 305 . This settled principle of constitutional law was
compendiously stated in Mr. Chief Justice Warren's opinion for the
Court in McGowan v. Maryland, 366 U.
S. 420 , 366 U. S.
425 -426, in the following words:
"Although no precise formula has been developed, the Court has
held that the Fourteenth Amendment permits the States a wide scope
of discretion in enacting laws which affect some groups of citizens
differently than others. The constitutional safeguard is offended
only if the classification rests on grounds wholly irrelevant to
the achievement of the State's objective. State legislatures are
presumed to have acted within their constitutional power despite
the fact that, in practice, their laws result in some inequality. A
statutory discrimination will not be set aside if any state of
facts reasonably may be conceived to justify it."
This doctrine is no more than a specific application of one of
the first principles of constitutional adjudication -- the basic
presumption of the constitutional validity of a duly enacted state
or federal law. See Thayer, The Origin and Scope of the
American Doctrine of Constitutional Law, 7 Harv.L.Rev. 129
(1893). Page 411 U. S. 61 Under the Equal Protection Clause, this presumption of
constitutional validity disappears when a State has enacted
legislation whose purpose or effect is to create classes based upon
criteria that, in a constitutional sense, are inherently "suspect."
Because of the historic purpose of the Fourteenth Amendment, the
prime example of such a "suspect" classification is one that is
based upon race. See, e.g., Brown v. Board of Education, 347 U. S. 483 ; McLaughlin v. Florida, 379 U. S. 184 . But
there are other classifications that, at least in some settings,
are also "suspect" -- for example, those based upon national
origin, [ Footnote 2/4 ] alienage,
[ Footnote 2/5 ] indigency, [ Footnote 2/6 ] or illegitimacy. [ Footnote 2/7 ]
Moreover, quite apart from the Equal Protection Clause, a state
law that impinges upon a substantive right or liberty created or
conferred by the Constitution is, of course, presumptively invalid,
whether or not the law's purpose or effect is to create any
classifications. For example, a law that provided that newspapers
could be published only by people who had resided in the State for
five years could be superficially viewed as invidiously
discriminating against an identifiable class in violation of the
Equal Protection Clause. But, more basically, such a law would be
invalid simply because it abridged the freedom of the press.
Numerous cases in this Court illustrate this principle. [ Footnote 2/8 ] Page 411 U. S. 62 In refusing to invalidate the Texas system of financing its
public schools, the Court today applies with thoughtfulness and
understanding the basic principles I have so sketchily summarized.
First, as the Court points out, the Texas system has hardly created
the kind of objectively identifiable classes that are cognizable
under the Equal Protection Clause. [ Footnote 2/9 ] Second, even assuming the existence of
such discernible categories, the classifications are in no sense
based upon constitutionally "suspect" criteria. Third, the Texas
system does not rest "on grounds wholly irrelevant to the
achievement of the State's objective." Finally, the Texas system
impinges upon no substantive constitutional rights or liberties. It
follows, therefore, under the established principle reaffirmed in
Mr. Chief Justice Warren's opinion for the Court in McGowan v.
Maryland, supra, that the judgment of the District Court must
be reversed.
[ Footnote 2/1 ] See New York Times, Mar. 11, 1973, p. 1, col. 1.
[ Footnote 2/2 ]
There is one notable exception to the above statement: it has
been established in recent years that the Equal Protection Clause
confers the substantive right to participate on an equal basis with
other qualified voters whenever the State has adopted an electoral
process for determining who will represent any segment of the
State's population. See, e.g., Reynolds v. Sims, 377 U. S. 533 ; Kramer v. Union School District, 395 U.
S. 621 ; Dunn v. Blumstein, 405 U.
S. 330 , 405 U. S. 336 .
But there is no constitutional right to vote, as such. Minor v.
Happersett , 21 Wall. 162. If there were such a
right, both the Fifteenth Amendment and the Nineteenth Amendment
would have been wholly unnecessary.
[ Footnote 2/3 ] But see Bullock v. Carter, 405 U.
S. 134 .
[ Footnote 2/4 ] See Oyama v. California, 332 U.
S. 633 , 332 U. S.
644 -646.
[ Footnote 2/5 ] See Graham v. Richardson, 403 U.
S. 365 , 403 U. S.
372 .
[ Footnote 2/6 ] See Griffin v. Illinois, 351 U. S.
12 . "Indigency" means actual or functional indigency; it
does not mean comparative poverty vis-a-vis comparative
affluence. See James v. Valtierra, 402 U.
S. 137 .
[ Footnote 2/7 ] See Gomez v. Perez, 409 U. S. 535 ; Weber v. Aetna Casualty & Surety Co., 406 U.
S. 164 .
[ Footnote 2/8 ] See, e.g., Police Dept. of Chicago v. Mosley, 408 U. S. 92 (free
speech); Shapiro v. Thompson, 394 U.
S. 618 (freedom of interstate travel); Williams v.
Rhodes, 393 U. S. 23 (freedom of association); Skinner v. Oklahoma, 316 U. S. 535 ("liberty" conditionally protected by Due Process Clause of
Fourteenth Amendment).
[ Footnote 2/9 ] See Katzenbach v. Morgan, 384 U.
S. 641 , 384 U. S. 660 (Harlan, J., dissenting).
MR. JUSTICE BRENNAN, dissenting.
Although I agree with my Brother WHITE that the Texas statutory
scheme is devoid of any rational basis, and, for that reason, is
violative of the Equal Protection Clause, I also record my
disagreement with the Court's rather distressing assertion that a
right may be deemed "fundamental" for the purposes of equal
protection analysis only if it is "explicitly or implicitly
guaranteed by the Constitution." Ante at 411 U. S. 33 -34.
As my Brother MARSHALL convincingly demonstrates, our prior cases
stand for the proposition that "fundamentality" is, in large
measure, a function of the right's importance in terms of the
effectuation of those rights which are in fact, constitutionally
guaranteed. Thus,
"[a]s the nexus between the specific constitutional guarantee
and the nonconstitutional Page 411 U. S. 63 interest draws closer, the nonconstitutional interest becomes
more fundamental and the degree of judicial scrutiny applied when
the interest is infringed on a discriminatory basis must be
adjusted accordingly." Post at 411 U. S.
102 -103.
Here, there can be no doubt that education is inextricably
linked to the right to participate in the electoral process and to
the rights of free speech and association guaranteed by the First
Amendment. See post at 411 U. S.
111 -115. This being so, any classification affecting
education must be subjected to strict judicial scrutiny, and since
even the State concedes that the statutory scheme now before us
cannot pass constitutional muster under this stricter standard of
review, I can only conclude that the Texas school-financing scheme
is constitutionally invalid.
MR. JUSTICE WHITE, with whom MR. JUSTICE DOUGLAS and MR. JUSTICE
BRENNAN join, dissenting.
The Texas public schools are financed through a combination of
state funding, local property tax revenue, and some federal funds.
[ Footnote 3/1 ] Concededly, the
system yields wide disparity in per-pupil revenue among the various
districts. In a typical year, for example, the Alamo Heights
district had total revenues of $594 per pupil, while the Edgewood
district had only $356 per pupil. [ Footnote 3/2 ] The majority and the State concede, as
they must, the existence Page 411 U. S. 64 of major disparities in spendable funds. But the State contends
that the disparities do not invidiously discriminate against
children and families in districts such as Edgewood, because the
Texas scheme is designed
"to provide an adequate education for all, with local autonomy
to go beyond that as individual school districts desire and are
able. . . . It leaves to the people of each district the choice
whether to go beyond the minimum and, if so, by how much. [ Footnote 3/3 ]"
The majority advances this rationalization:
"While assuring a basic education for every child in the State,
it permits and encourages a large measure of participation in and
control of each district's schools at the local level."
I cannot disagree with the proposition that local control and
local decisionmaking play an important part in our democratic
system of government. Cf. James v. Valtierra, 402 U.
S. 137 (1971). Much may be left to local option, and
this case would be quite different if it were true that the Texas
system, while insuring minimum educational expenditures in every
district through state funding, extended a meaningful option to all
local districts to increase their per-pupil expenditures, and so to
improve their children's education to the extent that increased
funding would achieve that goal. The system would then arguably
provide a rational and sensible method of achieving the stated aim
of preserving an area for local initiative and decision.
The difficulty with the Texas system, however, is that it
provides a meaningful option to Alamo Heights and like school
districts, but almost none to Edgewood and those other districts
with a low per-pupil real estate tax base. In these latter
districts, no matter how desirous parents are of supporting their
schools with greater revenues, it is impossible to do so through
the use of the Page 411 U. S. 65 real estate property tax. In these districts, the Texas system
utterly fails to extend a realistic choice to parents because the
property tax, which is the only revenue-raising mechanism extended
to school districts, is practically and legally unavailable. That
this is the situation may be readily demonstrated.
Local school districts in Texas raise their portion of the
Foundation School Program -- the Local Fund Assignment -- by
levying ad valorem taxes on the property located within
their boundaries. In addition, the districts are authorized, by the
state constitution and by statute, to levy ad valorem property taxes in order to raise revenues to support educational
spending over and above the expenditure of Foundation School
Program funds.
Both the Edgewood and Alamo Heights districts are located in
Bexar County, Texas. Student enrollment in Alamo Heights is 5,432,
in Edgewood 22,862. The per-pupil market value of the taxable
property in Alamo Heights is $49,078, in Edgewood $5,960. In a
typical, relevant year, Alamo Heights had a maintenance tax rate of
$1.20 and a debt service (bond) tax rate of 20� per $100 assessed
evaluation, while Edgewood had a maintenance rate of 52� and a bond
rate of 67�. These rates, when applied to the respective tax bases,
yielded Alamo Heights $1,433,473 in maintenance dollars and
$236,074 in bond dollars, and Edgewood $223,034 in maintenance
dollars and $279,023 in bond dollars. As is readily apparent,
because of the variance in tax bases between the districts,
results, in terms of revenues, do not correlate with effort, in
terms of tax rate. Thus, Alamo Heights, with a tax base
approximately twice the size of Edgewood's base, realized
approximately six times as many maintenance dollars as Edgewood by
using a tax rate only approximately two and one-half times larger.
Similarly, Alamo Heights realized slightly fewer bond Page 411 U. S. 66 dollars by using a bond tax rate less than one-third of that
used by Edgewood.
Nor is Edgewood's revenue-raising potential only deficient when
compared with Alamo Heights. North East District has taxable
property with a per-pupil market value of approximately $31,000,
but total taxable property approximately four and one-half times
that of Edgewood. Applying a maintenance rate of $1, North East
yielded $2,818,148. Thus, because of its superior tax base, North
East was able to apply a tax rate slightly less than twice that
applied by Edgewood and yield more than 10 times the maintenance
dollars. Similarly, North East, with a bond rate of 45�, yielded
$1,249,159 -- more than four times Edgewood's yield with two-thirds
the rate.
Plainly, were Alamo Heights or North East to apply the Edgewood
tax rate to its tax base, it would yield far greater revenues than
Edgewood is able to yield applying those same rates to its base.
Conversely, were Edgewood to apply the Alamo Heights or North East
rates to its base, the yield would be far smaller than the Alamo
Heights or North East yields. The disparity is, therefore,
currently operative, and its impact on Edgewood is undeniably
serious. It is evident from statistics in the record that show
that, applying an equalized tax rate of 85� per $100 assessed
valuation, Alamo Heights was able to provide approximately $330 per
pupil in local revenues over and above the Local Fund Assignment.
In Edgewood, on the other hand, with an equalized tax rate of $1.05
per $100 of assessed valuation, $26 per pupil was raised beyond the
Local Fund Assignment. [ Footnote
3/4 ] As previously noted, in Alamo Heights, Page 411 U. S. 67 total per-pupil revenues from local, state, and federal funds
was $594 per pupil, in Edgewood $356. [ Footnote 3/5 ]
In order to equal the highest yield in any other Bexar County
district, Alamo Heights would be required to tax at the rate of 68�
per $100 of assessed valuation. Edgewood would be required to tax
at the prohibitive rate of $5.76 per $100. But state law places a
$1.50 per $100 ceiling on the maintenance tax rate, a limit that
would surely be reached long before Edgewood attained an equal
yield. Edgewood is thus precluded in law, as well a in fact, from
achieving a yield even close to that of some other district.
The Equal Protection Clause permits discriminations between
classes, but requires that the classification bear some rational
relationship to a permissible object sought to be attained by the
statute. It is not enough that the Texas system before us seeks to
achieve the valid, rational purpose of maximizing local initiative;
the means chosen by the State must also be rationally related to
the end sought to be achieved. As the Court stated just last Term
in Weber v. Aetna Casualty & Surety Co., 406 U.
S. 164 , 406 U. S. 172 (1972):
"The tests to determine the validity of state statutes under the
Equal Protection Clause have been variously expressed, but this
Court requires, at a minimum, that a statutory classification bear
some rational relationship to a legitimate state purpose. Morey
v. Doud, 354 U. S. 457 (1957); Williamson v. Lee Optical Co., 348 U. S.
483 (1955); Gulf, Colorado & Santa Fe R. Co. v.
Ellis, 165 U. S. 150 (1897); Yick
Wo v. Hopkins, 118 U. S. 356 (1886). " Page 411 U. S. 68 Neither Texas nor the majority heeds this rule. If the State
aims at maximizing local initiative and local choice, by permitting
school districts to resort to the real property tax if they choose
to do so, it utterly fails in achieving its purpose in districts
with property tax bases so low that there is little if any
opportunity for interested parents, rich or poor, to augment school
district revenues. Requiring the State to establish only that
unequal treatment is in furtherance of a permissible goal, without
also requiring the State to show that the means chosen to
effectuate that goal are rationally related to its achievement,
makes equal protection analysis no more than an empty gesture.
[ Footnote 3/6 ] In my view, the
parents and children in Edgewood, and in like districts, suffer
from an invidious discrimination violative of the Equal Protection
Clause. This does not, of course, mean that local control may not
be a legitimate goal of a school financing system. Nor does it mean
that the State must guarantee each district an equal per-pupil
revenue from the state school financing system. Nor does it mean,
as the majority appears to believe, that, by affirming the decision
below, Page 411 U. S. 69 this Court would be
"imposing on the States inflexible constitutional restraints
that could circumscribe or handicap the continued research and
experimentation so vital to finding even partial solutions to
educational problems and to keeping abreast of ever-changing
conditions."
On the contrary, it would merely mean that the State must
fashion a financing scheme which provides a rational basis for the
maximization of local control, if local control is to remain a goal
of the system, and not a scheme with
"different treatment be[ing] accorded to persons placed by a
statute into different classes on the basis of criteria wholly
unrelated to the objective of that statute." Reed v. Reed, 404 U. S. 71 , 404 U. S. 75 -76
(1971).
Perhaps the majority believes that the major disparity in
revenues provided and permitted by the Texas system is
inconsequential. I cannot agree, however, that the difference of
the magnitude appearing in this case can sensibly be ignored,
particularly since the State itself considers it so important to
provide opportunities to exceed the minimum state educational
expenditures.
There is no difficulty in identifying the class that is subject
to the alleged discrimination and that is entitled to the benefits
of the Equal Protection Clause. I need go no farther than the
parents and children in the Edgewood district, who are plaintiffs
here and who assert that they are entitled to the same choice as
Alamo Heights to augment local expenditures for schools but are
denied that choice by state law. This group constitutes a class
sufficiently definite to invoke the protection of the Constitution.
They are as entitled to the protection of the Equal Protection
Clause as were the voters in allegedly underrepresented counties in
the reapportionment case. See, e.g., Baker v. Carr, 369 U. S. 186 , 369 U. S.
204 -208 (1962); Gray v. Sanders, 372 U.
S. 368 , 372 U. S. 375 (1963); Reynolds v. Sims, 377 U.
S. 533 , 377 U. S.
654 -556 (1964). And in Bullock v. Carter, 405 U. S. 134 (1972), where a challenge to the Page 411 U. S. 70 Texas candidate filing fee on equal protection grounds was
upheld, we noted that the victims of alleged discrimination wrought
by the filing fee
"cannot be described by reference to discrete and precisely
defined segments of the community as is typical of inequities
challenged under the Equal Protection Clause,"
but concluded that
"we would ignore reality were we not to recognize that this
system falls with unequal weight on voters, as well as candidates,
according to their economic status." Id. at 405 U. S. 144 .
Similarly, in the present case, we would blink reality to ignore
the fact that school districts, and students in the end, are
differentially affected by the Texas school financing scheme with
respect to their capability to supplement the Minimum Foundation
School Program. At the very least, the law discriminates against
those children and their parents who live in districts where the
per-pupil tax base is sufficiently low to make impossible the
provision of comparable school revenues by resort to the real
property tax which is the only device the State extends for this
purpose.
[ Footnote 3/1 ]
The heart of the Texas system is embodied in an intricate series
of statutory provisions which make up Chapter 16 of the Texas
Education Code, Tex.Educ.Code Ann. § 16.01 et seq. See
also Tex.Educ.Code Ann. § 15.01 et seq., and § 20.10 et seq. [ Footnote 3/2 ]
The figures discussed are from Plaintiffs' Exhibits 7, 8, and
12. The figures are from the 1967-1968 school year. Because the
various exhibits relied upon different attendance totals, the
per-pupil results do not precisely correspond to the gross figures
quoted. The disparity between districts, rather than the actual
figures, is the important factor.
[ Footnote 3/3 ]
Brief for Appellants 11-13, 35.
[ Footnote 3/4 ]
Variable assessment practices are also revealed in this record.
Appellants do not, however, contend that this factor accounts, even
to a small extent, for the inter-district disparities.
[ Footnote 3/5 ]
The per-pupil funds received from state, federal, and other
sources, while not precisely equal, do not account for the large
differential and are not directly attacked in the present case.
[ Footnote 3/6 ]
The State of Texas appears to concede that the choice of whether
or not to go beyond the state-provided minimum
"is easier for some districts than for others. Those districts
with large amounts of taxable property can produce more revenue at
a lower tax rate and will provide their children with a more
expensive education."
Brief for Appellants 35. The State nevertheless insists that
districts have a choice and that the people in each district have
exercised that choice by providing some real property tax money
over and above the minimum funds guaranteed by the State. Like the
majority, however, the State fails to explain why the Equal
Protection Clause is not violated, or how its goal of providing
local government with realistic choices as to how much money should
be expended on education is implemented, where the system makes it
much more difficult for some than for others to provide additional
educational funds and where, as a practical and legal matter, it is
impossible for some districts to provide the educational budgets
that other districts can make available from real property tax
revenues.
MR. JUSTICE MARSHALL, with whom MR. JUSTICE DOUGLAS concurs,
dissenting.
The Court today decides, in effect, that a State may
constitutionally vary the quality of education which it offers its
children in accordance with the amount of taxable wealth located in
the school districts within which they reside. The majority's
decision represents an abrupt departure from the mainstream of
recent state and federal court decisions concerning the
unconstitutionality of state educational financing schemes
dependent upon taxable local wealth. [ Footnote 4/1 ] More unfortunately, though, the Page 411 U. S. 71 majority's holding can only be seen as a retreat from our
historic commitment to equality of educational opportunity and as
unsupportable acquiescence in a system which deprives children in
their earliest years of the chance to reach their full potential as
citizens. The Court does this despite the absence of any
substantial justification for a scheme which arbitrarily channels
educational resources in accordance with the fortuity of the amount
of taxable wealth within each district.
In my judgment, the right of every American to an equal start in
life, so far as the provision of a state service as important as
education is concerned, is far too vital to permit state
discrimination on grounds as tenuous as those presented by this
record. Nor can I accept the notion that it is sufficient to remit
these appellees to the vagaries of the political process which,
contrary to the majority's suggestion, has proved singularly
unsuited to the task of providing a remedy for this discrimination.
[ Footnote 4/2 ] I, for one, am
unsatisfied with the hope of an ultimate "political" solution
sometime in the indefinite future while, in the meantime, countless
children unjustifiably receive inferior educations that "may affect
their hearts Page 411 U. S. 72 and minds in a way unlikely ever to be undone." Brown v.
Board of Education, 347 U. S. 483 , 347 U. S. 494 (1954). I must therefore respectfully dissent. I The Court acknowledges that "substantial inter-district
disparities in school expenditures" exist in Texas, ante at 411 U. S. 15 , and
that these disparities are "largely attributable to differences in
the amounts of money collected through local property taxation," ante at 411 U. S. 16 . But
instead of closely examining the seriousness of these disparities
and the invidiousness of the Texas financing scheme, the Court
undertakes an elaborate exploration of the efforts Texas has
purportedly made to close the gaps between its districts in terms
of levels of district wealth and resulting educational funding. Yet
however praiseworthy Texas' equalizing efforts, the issue in this
case is not whether Texas is doing its best to ameliorate the worst
features of a discriminatory scheme, but rather whether the scheme
itself is, in fact, unconstitutionally discriminatory in the face
of the Fourteenth Amendment's guarantee of equal protection of the
laws. When the Texas financing scheme is taken as a whole, I do not
think it can be doubted that it produces a discriminatory impact on
substantial numbers of the school-age children of the State of
Texas. A Funds to support public education in Texas are derived from
three sources: local ad valorem property taxes; the
Federal Government; and the state government. [ Footnote 4/3 ] It is enlightening to consider these
in order. Page 411 U. S. 73 Under Texas law, the only mechanism provided the local school
district for raising new, unencumbered revenues is the power to tax
property located within its boundaries. [ Footnote 4/4 ] At the same time, the Texas financing
scheme effectively restricts the use of monies raised by local
property taxation to the support of public education within the
boundaries of the district in which they are raised, since any such
taxes must be approved by a majority of the property-taxpaying
voters of the district. [ Footnote
4/5 ]
The significance of the local property tax element of the Texas
financing scheme is apparent from the fact that it provides the
funds to meet some 40% of the cost of public education for Texas as
a whole. [ Footnote 4/6 ] Yet the
amount of revenue that any particular Texas district can raise is
dependent on two factors -- its tax rate and its amount of taxable
property. The first factor is determined by the property-taxpaying
voters of the district. [ Footnote
4/7 ] But, regardless of the enthusiasm of the local voters for
public Page 411 U. S. 74 education, the second factor -- the taxable property wealth of
the district -- necessarily restricts the district's ability to
raise funds to support public education. [ Footnote 4/8 ] Thus, even though the voters of two Texas
districts may be willing to make the same tax effort, the results
for the districts will be substantially different if one is
property rich, while the other is property poor. The necessary
effect of the Texas local property tax is, in short, to favor
property-rich districts and to disfavor property-poor ones.
The seriously disparate consequences of the Texas local property
tax, when that tax is considered alone, are amply illustrated by
data presented to the District Court by appellees. These data
included a detailed study of a sample of 110 Texas school districts
[ Footnote 4/9 ] for the 1967-1968
school year conducted by Professor Joel S. Berke of Syracuse
University's Educational Finance Policy Institute. Among other
things, this study revealed that the 10 richest districts examined,
each of which had more than $100,000 in taxable property per pupil,
raised through local effort an average of $610 per pupil, whereas
the four poorest districts studied, each of which had less than
$10,000 in taxable property per pupil, were able Page 411 U. S. 75 to raise only an average of $63 per pupil. [ Footnote 4/10 ] And, as the Court effectively
recognizes, ante at 411 U. S. 27 ,
this correlation between the amount of taxable property per pupil
and the amount of local revenues per pupil holds true for the 96
districts in between the richest and poorest districts. [ Footnote 4/11 ]
It is clear, moreover, that the disparity of per-pupil revenues
cannot be dismissed as the result of lack of local effort -- that
is, lower tax rates by property-poor districts. To the contrary,
the data presented below indicate that the poorest districts tend
to have the highest tax rates and the richest districts tend to
have the lowest tax rates. [ Footnote
4/12 ] Yet, despite the apparent extra effort being made by the
poorest districts, they are unable even to begin to match the
richest districts in terms of the production of local revenues. For
example, the 10 richest districts studied by Professor Berke were
able to produce $585 per pupil with an equalized tax rate of
31� Page 411 U. S. 76 on $100 of equalized valuation, but the four poorest districts
studied, with an equalized rate of 70� on $100 of equalized
valuation, were able to produce only $60 per pupil. [ Footnote 4/13 ] Without more, this
state-imposed system of educational funding presents a serious
picture of widely varying treatment of Texas school districts, and
thereby of Texas school children, in terms of the amount of funds
available for public education.
Nor are these funding variations corrected by the other aspects
of the Texas financing scheme. The Federal Government provides
funds sufficient to cover only some 10% of the total cost of public
education in Texas. [ Footnote
4/14 ] Furthermore, while these federal funds are not
distributed in Texas solely on a per-pupil basis, appellants do not
here contend that they are used in such a way as to ameliorate
significantly the widely varying consequences for Texas school
districts and school children of the local property tax element of
the state financing scheme. [ Footnote
4/15 ]
State funds provide the remaining some 50% of the monies spent
on public education in Texas. [ Footnote 4/16 ] Technically, they are distributed under
two programs. The first is the Available School Fund, for which
provision is made in the Texas Constitution. [ Footnote 4/17 ] The Available Page 411 U. S. 77 School Fund is composed of revenues obtained from a number of
sources, including receipts from the state ad valorem property tax, one-fourth of all monies collected by the occupation
tax, annual contributions by the legislature from general revenues,
and the revenues derived from the Permanent School Fund. [ Footnote 4/18 ] For the 1970-1971 school
year, the Available School Fund contained $296,000,000. The Texas
Constitution requires that this money be distributed annually on a
per capita basis [ Footnote 4/19 ]
to the local school districts. Obviously, such a flat grant could
not alone eradicate the funding differentials attributable to the
local property tax. Moreover, today the Available School Fund is in
reality simply one facet of the second state financing program, the
Minimum Foundation School Program, [ Footnote 4/20 ] since each district's annual share of
the Fund is deducted from the sum to which the district is entitled
under the Foundation Program. [ Footnote 4/21 ]
The Minimum Foundation School Program provides funds for three
specific purposes: professional salaries, current operating
expenses, and transportation expenses. [ Footnote 4/22 ] The State pays, on an overall basis, for
approximately 80% of the cost of the Program; the remaining 20% is
distributed among the local school districts under the Page 411 U. S. 78 Local Fund Assignment. [ Footnote
4/23 ] Each district's share of the Local Fund Assignment is
determined by a complex "economic index" which is designed to
allocate a larger share of the costs to property-rich districts
than to property-poor districts. [ Footnote 4/24 ] Each district pays its share with
revenues derived from local property taxation.
The stated purpose of the Minimum Foundation School Program is
to provide certain basic funding for each local Texas school
district. [ Footnote 4/25 ] At the
same time, the Program was apparently intended to improve, to some
degree, the financial position of property-poor districts relative
to property-rich districts, since -- through the use of the
economic index -- an effort is made to charge a disproportionate
share of the costs of the Program to rich districts. [ Footnote 4/26 ] It bears noting, however,
that substantial criticism has been leveled at the practical
effectiveness of the economic index system of local cost
allocation. [ Footnote 4/27 ] In
theory, the index is designed to ascertain the relative ability of
each district to contribute to the Local Fund Assignment from local
property taxes. Yet the index is not developed simply on the basis
of each district's taxable wealth. It also takes into account the
district's relative income from manufacturing, mining, and
agriculture, its payrolls, and its scholastic population. [ Footnote 4/28 ] Page 411 U. S. 79 It is difficult to discern precisely how these latter factors
are predictive of a district's relative ability to raise revenues
through local property taxes. Thus, in 1966, one of the consultants
who originally participated in the development of the Texas
economic index adopted in 1949 told the Governor's Committee on
Public School Education: "The Economic Index approach to evaluating
local ability offers a little better measure than sheer chance, but
not much." [ Footnote 4/29 ]
Moreover, even putting aside these criticisms of the economic
index as a device for achieving meaningful district wealth
equalization through cost allocation, poor districts still do not
necessarily receive more state aid than property-rich districts.
For the standards which currently determine the amount received
from the Foundation School Program by any particular district
[ Footnote 4/30 ] favor
property-rich districts. [ Footnote
4/31 ] Thus, focusing on the same Page 411 U. S. 80 Edgewood Independent and Alamo Heights School Districts which
the majority uses for purposes of illustration, we find that, in
1967-1968, property-rich Alamo Heights, [ Footnote 4/32 ] which raised $333 per pupil on an
equalized tax rate of 85� per $100 valuation, received $225 per
pupil from the Foundation School Program, while property-poor
Edgewood, [ Footnote 4/33 ] which
raised only $26 per pupil with an equalized tax rate of $1.05 per
$100 valuation, received only $222 per pupil from the Foundation
School Program. [ Footnote 4/34 ]
And, more recent data, which indicate that, for the 1970-1971
school year, Alamo Heights received $491 per pupil from Page 411 U. S. 81 the Program while Edgewood received only $356 per pupil, hardly
suggest that the wealth gap between the districts is being narrowed
by the State Program. To the contrary, whereas, in 1967-1968, Alamo
Heights received only $3 per pupil, or about 1%, more than Edgewood
in state aid, by 1970-1971, the gap had widened to a difference of
$135 per pupil, or about 38%. [ Footnote 4/35 ] It was data of this character that
prompted the District Court to observe that "the current [state
aid] system tends to subsidize the rich at the expense of the poor,
rather than the other way around." [ Footnote 4/36 ] 337 F.
Supp. 280 , 282. And even the appellants go no further here than
to venture that the Minimum Foundation School Program has "a mildly
equalizing effect." [ Footnote
4/37 ]
Despite these facts, the majority continually emphasizes how
much state aid has, in recent years, been given Page 411 U. S. 82 to property-poor Texas school districts. What the Court fails to
emphasize is the cruel irony of how much more state aid is being
given to property-rich Texas school districts on top of their
already substantial local property tax revenues. [ Footnote 4/38 ] Under any view, then, it is
apparent that the state aid provided by the Foundation School
Program fails to compensate for the large funding variations
attributable to the local property tax element of the Texas
financing scheme. And it is these stark differences in the
treatment of Texas school districts and school children inherent in
the Texas financing scheme, not the absolute amount of state aid
provided to any particular school district, that are the crux of
this case. There can, moreover, be no escaping the conclusion that
the local property tax which is dependent upon taxable district
property wealth is an essential feature of the Texas scheme for
financing public education. [ Footnote
4/39 ] B The appellants do not deny the disparities in educational
funding caused by variations in taxable district property wealth.
They do contend, however, that whatever the differences in
per-pupil spending among Texas districts, there are no
discriminatory consequences for the children of the disadvantaged
districts. They recognize that what is at stake in this case is the
quality of the Page 411 U. S. 83 public education provided Texas children in the districts in
which they live. But appellants reject the suggestion that the
quality of education in any particular district is determined by
money -- beyond some minimal level of funding which they believe to
be assured every Texas district by the Minimum Foundation School
Program. In their view, there is simply no denial of equal
educational opportunity to any Texas school children as a result of
the widely varying per-pupil spending power provided districts
under the current financing scheme.
In my view, though, even an unadorned restatement of this
contention is sufficient to reveal its absurdity. Authorities
concerned with educational quality no doubt disagree as to the
significance of variations in per-pupil spending. [ Footnote 4/40 ] Indeed, conflicting expert
testimony was presented to the District Court in this case
concerning the effect of spending variations on educational
achievement. [ Footnote 4/41 ] We
sit, however, not to resolve disputes over educational theory, but
to enforce our Constitution. It is an inescapable fact that, if one
district has more funds available per pupil than another district,
the Page 411 U. S. 84 former will have greater choice in educational planning than
will the latter. In this regard, I believe the question of
discrimination in educational quality must be deemed to be an
objective one that looks to what the State provides its children,
not to what the children are able to do with what they receive.
That a child forced to attend an underfunded school with poorer
physical facilities, less experienced teachers, larger classes, and
a narrower range of courses than a school with substantially more
funds -- and thus with greater choice in educational planning --
may nevertheless excel is to the credit of the child, not the
State, cf. Missouri ex rel. Gaines v. Canada, 305 U.
S. 337 , 305 U. S. 349 (1938). Indeed, who can ever measure for such a child the
opportunities lost and the talents wasted for want of a broader,
more enriched education? Discrimination in the opportunity to learn
that is afforded a child must be our standard.
Hence, even before this Court recognized its duty to tear down
the barriers of state-enforced racial segregation in public
education, it acknowledged that inequality in the educational
facilities provided to students may be discriminatory state action
as contemplated by the Equal Protection Clause. As a basis for
striking down state-enforced segregation of a law school, the Court
in Sweatt v. Painter, 339 U. S. 629 , 339 U. S.
633 -634 (1950), stated:
"[W]e cannot find substantial equality in the educational
opportunities offered white and Negro law students by the State. In
terms of number of the faculty, variety of courses and opportunity
for specialization, size of the student body, scope of the library,
availability of law review and similar activities, the
[whites-only] Law School is superior. . . . It is difficult to
believe that one who had a free choice between these law schools
would consider the question close. " Page 411 U. S. 85 See also McLaurin v. Oklahoma State Regents for Higher
Education, 339 U. S. 637 (1950). Likewise, it is difficult to believe that, if the children
of Texas had a free choice, they would choose to be educated in
districts with fewer resources, and hence with more antiquated
plants, less experienced teachers, and a less diversified
curriculum. In fact, if financing variations are so insignificant
to educational quality, it is difficult to understand why a number
of our country's wealthiest school districts, which have no legal
obligation to argue in support of the constitutionality of the
Texas legislation, have nevertheless zealously pursued its cause
before this Court. [ Footnote
4/42 ]
The consequences, in terms of objective educational input, of
the variations in district funding caused by the Texas financing
scheme are apparent from the data introduced before the District
Court. For example, in 1968-1969, 100% of the teachers in the
property-rich Alamo Heights School District had college degrees.
[ Footnote 4/43 ] By contrast,
during the same school year, only 80.02% of the teachers had
college degrees in the property poor Edgewood Independent school
District. [ Footnote 4/44 ] Also,
in 1968-1969, approximately 47% of the teachers in the Edgewood
District were on emergency teaching permits, whereas only 11% of
the teachers in Alamo Heights were on such permits. [ Footnote 4/45 ] This is undoubtedly a
reflection of the fact that the top of Edgewood's teacher salary
scale was Page 411 U. S. 86 approximately 80% of Alamo Heights'. [ Footnote 4/46 ] And, not surprisingly, the
teacher-student ratio varies significantly between the two
districts. [ Footnote 4/47 ] In
other wards, as might be expected, a difference in the funds
available to districts results in a difference in educational
inputs available for a child's public education in Texas. For
constitutional purposes, I believe this situation, which is
directly attributable to the Texas financing scheme, raises a grave
question of state-created discrimination in the provision of public
education. Cf. Gaston County v. United States, 395 U. S. 285 , 395 U. S.
293 -294 (1969).
At the very least, in view of the substantial inter-district
disparities in funding and in resulting educational inputs shown by
appellees to exist under the Texas financing scheme, the burden of
proving that these disparities do not, in fact, affect the quality
of children's education must fall upon the appellants. Cf.
Hobson v. Hansen, 327 F.
Supp. 844 , 860-861 (DC 1971). Yet appellants made no effort in
the District Court to demonstrate that educational quality is not
affected by variations in funding and in resulting inputs. And, in
this Court, they have argued no more than that the relationship is
ambiguous. This is hardly sufficient to overcome appellees' prima facie showing of state-created discrimination
between the school children of Texas with respect to objective
educational opportunity.
Nor can I accept the appellants' apparent suggestion that the
Texas Minimum Foundation School Program effectively eradicates any
discriminatory effects otherwise resulting from the local property
tax element of the Page 411 U. S. 87 Texas financing scheme. Appellants assert that, despite its
imperfections, the Program "does guarantee an adequate education to
every child." [ Footnote 4/48 ] The
majority, in considering the constitutionality of the Texas
financing scheme, seems to find substantial merit in this
contention, for it tells us that the Foundation Program "was
designed to provide an adequate minimum educational offering in
every school in the State," ante at 411 U. S. 45 , and
that the Program "assur[es] a basic education for every child," ante at 411 U. S. 49 . But
I fail to understand how the constitutional problems inherent in
the financing scheme are eased by the Foundation Program. Indeed,
the precise thrust of the appellants' and the Court's remarks are
not altogether clear to me.
The suggestion may be that the state aid received via the
Foundation Program sufficiently improves the position of
property-poor districts vis-a-vis property-rich districts
-- in terms of educational funds -- to eliminate any claim of
inter-district discrimination in available educational resources
which might otherwise exist if educational funding were dependent
solely upon local property taxation. Certainly the Court has
recognized that to demand precise equality of treatment is normally
unrealistic, and thus minor differences inherent in any practical
context usually will not make out a substantial equal protection
claim. See, e.g., Mayer v. City of Chicago, 404 U.
S. 189 , 404 U. S.
194 -195 (1971); Draper v. Washington, 372 U. S. 487 , 372 U. S.
495 -496 (1963); Bain Peanut Co. v. Pinson, 282 U. S. 499 , 282 U. S. 501 (1931). But, as has already been seen, we are hardly presented here
with some de minimis claim of discrimination resulting
from the play necessary in any functioning system; to the contrary,
it is clear that the Foundation Program utterly fails to Page 411 U. S. 88 ameliorate the seriously discriminatory effects of the local
property tax. [ Footnote 4/49 ]
Alternatively, the appellants and the majority may believe that
the Equal Protection Clause cannot be offended by substantially
unequal state treatment of persons who are similarly situated so
long as the State provides everyone with some unspecified amount of
education which evidently is "enough." [ Footnote 4/50 ] The basis for such a novel view is far
from clear. It is, of course, true that the Constitution does not
require precise equality in the treatment of all persons. As Mr.
Justice Frankfurter explained:
"The equality at which the 'equal protection' clause aims is not
a disembodied equality. The Fourteenth Amendment enjoins 'the equal
protection of the laws,' and laws are not abstract propositions. .
. . The Constitution does not require things which are different in
fact or opinion to be treated in law as though they were the
same." Tigner v. Texas, 310 U. S. 141 , 310 U. S. 147 (1940). See also Douglas v. California, 372 U.
S. 353 , 372 U. S. 357 (1963); Goesaert v. Cleary, 335 U.
S. 464 , 335 U. S. 466 (1948). Page 411 U. S. 89 But this Court has never suggested that, because some "adequate"
level of benefits is provided to all, discrimination in the
provision of services is therefore constitutionally excusable. The
Equal Protection Clause is not addressed to the minimal
sufficiency, but rather to the unjustifiable inequalities of state
action. It mandates nothing less than that "all persons similarly
circumstanced shall be treated alike." F. S. Royster Guano Co.
v. Virginia, 253 U. S. 412 , 253 U. S. 415 (1920).
Even if the Equal Protection Clause encompassed some theory of
constitutional adequacy, discrimination in the provision of
educational opportunity would certainly seem to be a poor candidate
for its application. Neither the majority nor appellants inform us
how judicially manageable standards are to be derived for
determining how much education is "enough" to excuse constitutional
discrimination. One would think that the majority would heed its
own fervent affirmation of judicial self-restraint before
undertaking the complex task of determining at large what level of
education is constitutionally sufficient. Indeed, the majority's
apparent reliance upon the adequacy of the educational opportunity
assured by the Texas Minimum Foundation School Program seems
fundamentally inconsistent with its own recognition that
educational authorities are unable to agree upon what makes for
educational quality, see ante at 411 U. S. 42 -43
and n. 86 and at 411 U. S. 47 n.
101. If, as the majority stresses, such authorities are uncertain
as to the impact of various levels of funding on educational
quality, I fail to see where it finds the expertise to divine that
the particular levels of funding provided by the Program assure an
adequate educational opportunity -- much less an education
substantially equivalent in quality to that which a higher level of
funding might provide. Certainly appellants' mere assertion before
this Court of the adequacy of the education guaranteed by the
Minimum Page 411 U. S. 90 Foundation School Program cannot obscure the constitutional
implications of the discrimination in educational funding and
objective educational inputs resulting from the local property tax
-- particularly since the appellees offered substantial
uncontroverted evidence before the District Court impugning the now
much-touted "adequacy" of the education guaranteed by the
Foundation Program. [ Footnote
4/51 ]
In my view, then, it is inequality -- not some notion of gross
inadequacy -- of educational opportunity that raises a question of
denial of equal protection of the laws. I find any other approach
to the issue unintelligible, and without directing principle. Here,
appellees have made a substantial showing of wide variations in
educational funding and the resulting educational opportunity
afforded to the school children of Texas. This discrimination is,
in large measure, attributable to significant disparities in the
taxable wealth of local Texas school districts. This is a
sufficient showing to raise a substantial question of
discriminatory state action in violation of the Equal Protection
Clause. [ Footnote 4/52 ] Page 411 U. S. 91 C Despite the evident discriminatory effect of the Texas financing
scheme, both the appellants and the majority raise substantial
questions concerning the precise character of the disadvantaged
class in this case. The District Court concluded that the Texas
financing scheme draws "distinction between groups of citizens
depending upon the wealth of the district in which they live," and
thus creates a disadvantaged class composed of persons living in
property-poor districts. See 337 F. Supp. at 282. See
also id. at 281. In light of the data introduced before the
District Court, the conclusion that the school children of
property-poor districts constitute a sufficient class for our
purposes seems indisputable to me.
Appellants contend, however, that, in constitutional terms, this
case involves nothing more than discrimination against local school
districts, not against individuals, since, on its face, the state
scheme is concerned only with the provision of funds to local
districts. The result of the Texas financing scheme, appellants
suggest, is merely that some local districts have more available
revenues for education; others have less. In that respect, Page 411 U. S. 92 they point out, the States have broad discretion in drawing
reasonable distinctions between their political subdivisions. See Griffin v. County School Board of Prince Edward
County, 377 U. S. 218 , 377 U. S. 231 (1964); McGowan v. Maryland, 366 U.
S. 420 , 366 U. S. 427 (1961); Salsbury v. Maryland, 346 U.
S. 545 , 346 U. S.
550 -554 (1954).
But this Court has consistently recognized that, where there is,
in fact, discrimination against individual interests, the
constitutional guarantee of equal protection of the laws is not
inapplicable simply because the discrimination is based upon some
group characteristic such as geographic location. See Gordon v.
Lance, 403 U. S. 1 , 403 U. S. 4 (1971); Reynolds v. Sims, 377 U.
S. 533 , 377 U.S.
565 -566 (1964); Gray v. Sanders, 372 U.
S. 368 , 372 U. S. 379 (1963). Texas has chosen to provide free public education for all
its citizens, and it has embodied that decision in its
constitution. [ Footnote 4/53 ]
Yet, having established public education for its citizens, the
State, as a direct consequence of the variations in local property
wealth endemic to Texas' financing scheme, has provided some Texas
school children with substantially less resources for their
education than others. Thus, while, on its face, the Texas scheme
may merely discriminate between local districts, the impact of that
discrimination falls directly upon the children whose educational
opportunity is dependent upon where they happen to live.
Consequently, the District Court correctly concluded that the Texas
financing scheme discriminates, from a constitutional perspective,
between school children on the basis of the amount of taxable
property located within their local districts.
In my Brother STEWART's view, however, such a description of the
discrimination inherent in this case is apparently not sufficient,
for it fails to define the "kind of objectively identifiable
classes" that he evidently perceives Page 411 U. S. 93 to be necessary for a claim to be "cognizable under the Equal
Protection Clause," ante at 411 U. S. 62 . He
asserts that this is also the view of the majority, but he is
unable to cite, nor have I been able to find, any portion of the
Court's opinion which remotely suggests that there is no
objectively identifiable or definable class in this case. In any
event, if he means to suggest that an essential predicate to equal
protection analysis is the precise identification of the particular
individuals who compose the disadvantaged class, I fail to find the
source from which he derives such a requirement. Certainly such
precision is not analytically necessary. So long as the basis of
the discrimination is clearly identified, it is possible to test it
against the State's purpose for such discrimination -- whatever the
standard of equal protection analysis employed. [ Footnote 4/54 ] This is clear from our decision
only last Term in Bullock v. Carter, 405 U.
S. 134 (1972), where the Court, in striking down Texas'
primary filing fees as violative of equal protection, found no
impediment to equal protection analysis in the fact that the
members of the disadvantaged class could not be readily identified.
The Court recognized that the filing fee system tended
"to deny some voters the opportunity to vote for a candidate of
their choosing; at the same time it gives the affluent the power to
place on the ballot their own names or the names of persons they
favor." Id. at 405 U. S. 144 .
The Page 411 U. S. 94 Court also recognized that
"[t]his disparity in voting power based on wealth cannot be
described by reference to discrete and precisely defined segments
of the community as is typical of inequities challenged under the
Equal Protection Clause. . . ." Ibid. Nevertheless it concluded that
"we would ignore reality were we not to recognize that this
system falls with unequal weight on voters . . . according to their
economic status." Ibid. The nature of the classification in Bullock was clear, although the precise membership of the
disadvantaged class was not. This was enough in Bullock for purposes of equal protection analysis. It is enough here.
It may be, though, that my Brother STEWART is not in fact,
demanding precise identification of the membership of the
disadvantaged class for purposes of equal protection analysis, but
is merely unable to discern with sufficient clarity the nature of
the discrimination charged in this case. Indeed, the Court itself
displays some uncertainty as to the exact nature of the
discrimination and the resulting disadvantaged class alleged to
exist in this case. See ante at 411 U. S. 120 .
It is, of course, essential to equal protection analysis to have a
firm grasp upon the nature of the discrimination at issue. In fact,
the absence of such a clear, articulable understanding of the
nature of alleged discrimination in a particular instance may well
suggest the absence of any real discrimination. But such is hardly
the case here.
A number of theories of discrimination have, to be sure, been
considered in the course of this litigation. Thus, the District
Court found that, in Texas, the poor and minority group members
tend to live in property-poor districts, suggesting discrimination
on the basis of both personal wealth and race. See 337 F.
Supp. at 282 and n. 3. The Court goes to great lengths to discredit
the data upon which the District Court relied, and thereby its
conclusion that poor people live in property-poor districts.
[ Footnote 4/55 ] Page 411 U. S. 95 Although I have serious doubts as to the correctness of the
Court's analysis in rejecting the data submitted below, [ Footnote 4/56 ] I have no need to join
issue on these factual disputes. Page 411 U. S. 96 I believe it is sufficient that the overarching form of
discrimination in this case is between the school children of Texas
on the basis of the taxable property wealth of the districts in
which they happen to live. To understand both the precise nature of
this discrimination and the parameters of the disadvantaged class,
it is sufficient to consider the constitutional principle which
appellees contend is controlling in the context of educational
financing. In their complaint, appellees asserted that the
Constitution does not permit local district wealth to be
determinative of educational opportunity. [ Footnote 4/57 ] This is simply another way of saying, as
the District Court concluded, that, consistent with the guarantee
of equal protection of the laws, "the quality of public education
may not be a function of wealth, other than the wealth of the state
as a whole." 337 F. Supp. at 284. Under such a principle, the
children of a district are excessively advantaged if that district
has more taxable property per pupil than the average amount of
taxable property per pupil considering the State as a whole. By
contrast, the children of a district are disadvantaged if that
district has less taxable property per pupil than the state
average. The majority attempts to disparage such a definition of
the disadvantaged class as the product of an "artificially defined
level" of district wealth. Ante at 411 U. S. 28 . But
such is clearly not the case, for this is the Page 411 U. S. 97 definition unmistakably dictated by the constitutional principle
for which appellees have argued throughout the course of this
litigation. And I do not believe that a clearer definition of
either the disadvantaged class of Texas school children or the
allegedly unconstitutional discrimination suffered by the members
of that class under the present Texas financing scheme could be
asked for, much less needed. [ Footnote 4/58 ] Whether this discrimination, against the
school children of property-poor districts, inherent in the Texas
financing scheme, is violative of the Equal Protection Clause is
the question to which we must now turn. II To avoid having the Texas financing scheme struck down because
of the inter-district variations in taxable property wealth, the
District Court determined that it was insufficient for appellants
to show merely that the State's scheme was rationally related to
some legitimate state purpose; rather, the discrimination inherent
in the scheme had to be shown necessary to promote a "compelling
state interest" in order to withstand constitutional scrutiny. The
basis for this determination was twofold: first, the financing
scheme divides citizens on a wealth basis, a classification which
the District Court viewed as highly suspect; and second, the
discriminatory scheme directly affects what it considered to be a
"fundamental interest," namely, education.
This Court has repeatedly held that state discrimination which
either adversely affects a "fundamental interest," see, e.g.,
Dunn v. Blumstein, 405 U. S. 330 , 405 U. S.
336 -342 (1972); Shapiro v. Thompson, 394 U. S. 618 , 394 U. S.
629 -631 (1969), or is based on a distinction of a
suspect character, see, e.g., Graham v. Richardson, 403 U. S. 365 , 403 U. S.
372 Page 411 U. S. 98 (1971); McLaughlin v. Florida, 379 U.
S. 184 , 379 U. S.
191 -192 (1964), must be carefully scrutinized to ensure
that the scheme is necessary to promote a substantial, legitimate
state interest. See, e.g., Dunn v. Blumstein, supra, at 405 U. S.
342 -343; Shapiro v. Thompson, supra, at 394 U. S. 634 .
The majority today concludes, however, that the Texas scheme is not
subject to such a strict standard of review under the Equal
Protection Clause. Instead, in its view, the Texas scheme must be
tested by nothing more than that lenient standard of rationality
which we have traditionally applied to discriminatory state action
in the context of economic and commercial matters. See, e.g.,
McGowan v. Maryland, 366 U.S. at 366 U. S.
425 -426; Morey v. Doud, 354 U.
S. 457 , 354 U. S.
465 -466 (1957); F. S. Royster Guano Co. v.
Virginia, 253 U.S. at 253 U. S. 415 ; Lindsley v. Natural Carbonic Gas
Co., 220 U. S. 61 , 220 U. S. 78 -79
(1911). By so doing, the Court avoids the telling task of searching
for a substantial state interest which the Texas financing scheme,
with its variations in taxable district property wealth, is
necessary to further. I cannot accept such an emasculation of the
Equal Protection Clause in the context of this case. A To begin, I must once more voice my disagreement with the
Court's rigidified approach to equal protection analysis. See
Dandridge v. Williams, 397 U. S. 471 , 397 U. S.
519 -521 (1970) (dissenting opinion); Richardson v.
Belcher, 404 U. S. 78 , 404 U. S. 90 (1971) (dissenting opinion). The Court apparently seeks to
establish today that equal protection cases fall into one of two
neat categories which dictate the appropriate standard of review --
strict scrutiny or mere rationality. But this Court's decisions in
the field of equal protection defy such easy categorization. A
principled reading of what this Court has done reveals that it has
applied a spectrum of standards in reviewing discrimination
allegedly violative of the Equal Protection Page 411 U. S. 99 Clause. This spectrum clearly comprehends variations in the
degree of care with which the Court will scrutinize particular
classifications, depending, I believe, on the constitutional and
societal importance of the interest adversely affected and the
recognized invidiousness of the basis upon which the particular
classification is drawn. I find, in fact, that many of the Court's
recent decisions embody the very sort of reasoned approach to equal
protection analysis for which I previously argued -- that is, an
approach in which
"concentration [is] placed upon the character of the
classification in question, the relative importance to individuals
in the class discriminated against of the governmental benefits
that they do not receive, and the asserted state interests in
support of the classification." Dandridge v. Williams, supra, at 397 U. S.
520 -521 (dissenting opinion).
I therefore cannot accept the majority's labored efforts to
demonstrate that fundamental interests, which call for strict
scrutiny of the challenged classification, encompass only
established rights which we are somehow bound to recognize from the
text of the Constitution itself. To be sure, some interests which
the Court has deemed to be fundamental for purposes of equal
protection analysis are themselves constitutionally protected
rights. Thus, discrimination against the guaranteed right of
freedom of speech has called for strict judicial scrutiny. See
Police Dept. of Chicago v. Mosley, 408 U. S.
92 (1972). Further, every citizen's right to travel
interstate, although nowhere expressly mentioned in the
Constitution, has long been recognized as implicit in the premises
underlying that document: the right "was conceived from the
beginning to be a necessary concomitant of the stronger Union the
Constitution created." United States v. Guest, 383 U. S. 745 , 383 U. S. 758 (1966). See also Crandall v.
Nevada , 6 Wall. 35, 73 U. S. 48 (1868). Consequently, the Court has required that a state
classification affecting the constitutionally Page 411 U. S. 100 protected right to travel must be "shown to be necessary to
promote a compelling governmental interest." Shapiro v.
Thompson, 394 U.S. at 394 U. S. 634 . But it will not do to suggest that the
"answer" to whether an interest is fundamental for purposes of
equal protection analysis is always determined by whether that
interest "is a right . . . explicitly or implicitly guaranteed by
the Constitution," ante at 411 U. S. 33 -34.
[ Footnote 4/59 ]
I would like to know where the Constitution guarantees the right
to procreate, Skinner v. Oklahoma, 316 U.
S. 535 541 (1942) or the right to vote in state
elections, e.g., Reynolds v. Sims, 377 U.
S. 533 (1964) or the right to an appeal from a criminal
conviction, e.g., Griffin v. Illinois, 351 U. S.
12 (1956). These are instances in which, due to the
importance of the interests at stake, the Court has displayed a
strong concern with the existence of discriminatory state
treatment. But the Court has never said or indicated that these are
interests which independently enjoy full-blown constitutional
protection.
Thus, in Buck v. Bell, 274 U.
S. 200 (1927), the Court refused to recognize a
substantive constitutional guarantee of the right to procreate.
Nevertheless, in Skinner v. Oklahoma, supra, at 316 U. S. 541 the Court, without impugning the continuing validity of Buck v.
Bell, held that "strict scrutiny" of state discrimination
affecting procreation "is essential," for "[m]arriage and
procreation are fundamental to the very existence and survival of
the race." Recently, in Roe v. Wade, 410 U.
S. 113 , 410 U. S.
152 -154 (1973), Page 411 U. S. 101 the importance of procreation has, indeed, been explained on the
basis of its intimate relationship with the constitutional right of
privacy which we have recognized. Yet the limited stature thereby
accorded any "right" to procreate is evident from the fact that, at
the same time, the Court reaffirmed its initial decision in Buck v. Bell. See Roe v. Wade, supra, at 410 U. S.
154 .
Similarly, the right to vote in state elections has been
recognized as a "fundamental political right," because the Court
concluded very early that it is "preservative of all rights." Yick Wo v. Hopkins, 118 U. S. 356 , 118 U. S. 370 (1886); see, e.g., Reynolds v. Sims, supra, at 377 U. S.
561 -562. For this reason,
"this Court has made clear that a citizen has a constitutionally protected right to participate in elections on
an equal basis with other citizens in the jurisdiction. " Dunn v. Blumstein, 405 U.S. at 405 U. S. 336 (emphasis added). The final source of such protection from
inequality in the provision of the state franchise is, of course,
the Equal Protection Clause. Yet it is clear that whatever degree
of importance has been attached to the state electoral process when
unequally distributed, the right to vote in state elections has
itself never been accorded the stature of an independent
constitutional guarantee. [ Footnote
4/60 ] See Oregon v. Mitchell, 400 U.
S. 112 (1970); Kramer v. Union School District, 395 U. S. 621 , 395 U. S.
626 -629 (1969); Harper v. Virginia Bd. of
Elections, 383 U. S. 663 , 383 U. S. 665 (1966). Page 411 U. S. 102 Finally, it is likewise "true that a State is not required by
the Federal Constitution to provide appellate courts or a right to
appellate review at all." Griffin v. Illinois, 351 U.S. at 351 U. S. 18 .
Nevertheless, discrimination adversely affecting access to an
appellate process which a State has chosen to provide has been
considered to require close judicial scrutiny. See, e.g.,
Griffin v. Illinois, supra; Douglas v. California, 372 U. S. 353 (1963). [ Footnote 4/61 ]
The majority is, of course, correct when it suggests that the
process of determining which interests are fundamental is a
difficult one. But I do not think the problem is insurmountable.
And I certainly do not accept the view that the process need
necessarily degenerate into an unprincipled, subjective
"picking-and-choosing" between various interests, or that it must
involve this Court in creating "substantive constitutional rights
in the name of guaranteeing equal protection of the laws," ante at 411 U. S. 33 .
Although not all fundamental interests are constitutionally
guaranteed, the determination of which interests are fundamental
should be firmly rooted in the text of the Constitution. The task
in every case should be to determine the extent to which
constitutionally guaranteed rights are dependent on interests not
mentioned in the Constitution. As the nexus between the specific
constitutional guarantee and the nonconstitutional interest draws
closer, the nonconstitutional interest becomes Page 411 U. S. 103 more fundamental and the degree of judicial scrutiny applied
when the interest is infringed on a discriminatory basis must be
adjusted accordingly. Thus, it cannot be denied that interests such
as procreation, the exercise of the state franchise, and access to
criminal appellate processes are not fully guaranteed to the
citizen by our Constitution. But these interests have nonetheless
been afforded special judicial consideration in the face of
discrimination because they are, to some extent, interrelated with
constitutional guarantees. Procreation is now understood to be
important because of its interaction with the established
constitutional right of privacy. The exercise of the state
franchise is closely tied to basic civil and political rights
inherent in the First Amendment. And access to criminal appellate
processes enhances the integrity of the range of rights [ Footnote 4/62 ] implicit in the Fourteenth
Amendment guarantee of due process of law. Only if we closely
protect the related interests from state discrimination do we
ultimately ensure the integrity of the constitutional guarantee
itself. This is the real lesson that must be taken from our
previous decisions involving interests deemed to be
fundamental.
The effect of the interaction of individual interests with
established constitutional guarantees upon the degree of care
exercised by this Court in reviewing state discrimination affecting
such interests is amply illustrated by our decision last Term in Eisenstadt v. Baird, 405 U. S. 438 (1972). In Baird, the Court struck down as violative of
the Equal Protection Clause a state statute which denied unmarried
persons access to contraceptive devices on the same basis as
married persons. The Court Page 411 U. S. 104 purported to test the statute under its traditional standard
whether there is some rational basis for the discrimination
effected. Id. at 405 U. S.
446 -447. In the context of commercial regulation, the
Court has indicated that the Equal Protection Clause "is offended
only if the classification rests on grounds wholly irrelevant to
the achievement of the State's objective." See, e.g., McGowan
v. Maryland, 366 U.S. at 366 U. S. 425 ; Kotch v. Board of River Port Pilot Comm'rs, 330 U.
S. 552 , 330 U. S. 557 (1947). And this lenient standard is further weighted in the
State's favor by the fact that "[a] statutory discrimination will
not be set aside if any state of facts reasonably may be conceived
[by the Court] to justify it." McGowan v. Maryland, supra, at 366 U. S. 426 .
But, in Baird, the Court clearly did not adhere to these
highly tolerant standards of traditional rational review. For
although there were conceivable state interests intended to be
advanced by the statute -- e.g., deterrence of premarital
sexual activity and regulation of the dissemination of potentially
dangerous articles -- the Court was not prepared to accept these
interests on their face, but instead proceeded to test their
substantiality by independent analysis. See 405 U.S. at 405 U. S.
449 -454. Such close scrutiny of the State's interests
was hardly characteristic of the deference shown state
classifications in the context of economic interests. See,
e.g., Goesaert v. Cleary, 335 U. S. 464 (1948); Kotch v. Board of River Port Pilot Comm'rs, supra. Yet I think the Court's action was entirely appropriate, for access
to and use of contraceptives bears a close relationship to the
individual's constitutional right of privacy. See 405 U.S.
at 405 U. S.
453 -454; id. at 405 U. S.
463 -464 (WHITE, J., concurring in result). See also
Roe v. Wade, 410 U.S. at 410 U. S.
152 -153.
A similar process of analysis with respect to the invidiousness
of the basis on which a particular classification is drawn has also
influenced the Court as to the Page 411 U. S. 105 appropriate degree of scrutiny to be accorded any particular
case. The highly suspect character of classifications based on
race, [ Footnote 4/63 ]
nationality, [ Footnote 4/64 ] or
alienage [ Footnote 4/65 ] is well
established. The reasons why such classifications call for close
judicial scrutiny are manifold. Certain racial and ethnic groups
have frequently been recognized as "discrete and insular
minorities" who are relatively powerless to protect their interests
in the political process. See Graham v. Richardson, 403
U.S. at 403 U. S. 372 ; cf. United States v. Carolene Products Co., 304 U.
S. 144 , 304 U. S.
152 -153, n. 4 (1938). Moreover, race, nationality, or
alienage is,
"'in most circumstances, irrelevant' to any constitutionally
acceptable legislative purpose, Hirabayashi v. United
States, 320 U. S. 81 , 320 U. S.
100 ." McLaughlin v. Florida, 379 U.S. at 379 U. S. 192 .
Instead, lines drawn on such bases are frequently the reflection of
historic prejudices, rather than legislative rationality. It may be
that all of these considerations, which make for particular
judicial solicitude in the face of discrimination on the basis of
race, nationality, or alienage, do not coalesce -- or at least not
to the same degree -- in other forms of discrimination.
Nevertheless, these considerations have undoubtedly influenced the
care with which the Court has scrutinized other forms of
discrimination.
In James v. Strange, 407 U. S. 128 (1972), the Court held unconstitutional a state statute which
provided for recoupment from indigent convicts of legal defense
fees paid by the State. The Court found that the statute
impermissibly differentiated between indigent criminals in debt to
the State and civil judgment debtors, since criminal debtors were
denied various protective exemptions Page 411 U. S. 106 afforded civil judgment debtors. [ Footnote 4/66 ] The Court suggested that, in reviewing
the statute under the Equal Protection Clause, it was merely
applying the traditional requirement that there be " some
rationality'" in the line drawn between the different types of
debtors. I.d. at 407 U. S. 140 .
Yet it then proceeded to scrutinize the statute with less than
traditional deference and restraint. Thus, the Court recognized
"that state recoupment statutes may betoken legitimate state
interests" in recovering expenses and discouraging fraud.
Nevertheless, MR. JUSTICE POWELL, speaking for the Court, concluded
that "these interests are not thwarted by requiring more even
treatment of indigent criminal defendants with other classes of
debtors to whom the statute itself repeatedly makes reference.
State recoupment laws, notwithstanding the state interests they may
serve, need not blight in such discriminatory fashion the hopes of
indigents for self-sufficiency and self-respect." Id. at 407 U. S.
141 -142. The Court, in short, clearly did not consider
the problems of fraud and collection that the state legislature
might have concluded were peculiar to indigent criminal defendants
to be either sufficiently important or at least sufficiently
substantiated to justify denial of the protective exemptions
afforded to all civil judgment debtors, to a class composed
exclusively of indigent criminal debtors.
Similarly, in Reed v. Reed, 404 U. S.
71 (1971), the Court, in striking down a state statute
which gave men Page 411 U. S. 107 preference over women when persons of equal entitlement apply
for assignment as an administrator of a particular estate, resorted
to a more stringent standard of equal protection review than that
employed in cases involving commercial matters. The Court indicated
that it was testing the claim of sex discrimination by nothing more
than whether the line drawn bore "a rational relationship to a
state objective," which it recognized as a legitimate effort to
reduce the work of probate courts in choosing between competing
applications for letters of administration. Id. at 404 U. S. 76 .
Accepting such a purpose, the Idaho Supreme Court had thought the
classification to be sustainable on the basis that the legislature
might have reasonably concluded that, as a rule, men have more
experience than women in business matters relevant to the
administration of an estate. 93 Idaho 511, 514, 465 P.2d 635, 638
(1970). This Court, however, concluded that
"[t]o give a mandatory preference to members of either sex over
members of the other merely to accomplish the elimination of
hearings on the merits is to make the very kind of arbitrary
legislative choice forbidden by the Equal Protection Clause of the
Fourteenth Amendment. . . ."
404 U.S. at 404 U. S. 76 .
This Court, in other words, was unwilling to consider a theoretical
and unsubstantiated basis for distinction -- however reasonable it
might appear -- sufficient to sustain a statute discriminating on
the basis of sex. James and Reed can only be understood as
instances in which the particularly invidious character of the
classification caused the Court to pause and scrutinize with more
than traditional care the rationality of state discrimination.
Discrimination on the basis of past criminality and on the basis of
sex posed for the Court the specter of forms of discrimination
which it implicitly recognized to have deep social and legal roots
without necessarily having any basis in actual differences.
Still, Page 411 U. S. 108 the Court's sensitivity to the invidiousness of the basis for
discrimination is perhaps most apparent in its decisions protecting
the interests of children born out of wedlock from discriminatory
state action. See Weber v. Aetna Casualty & Surety
Co., 406 U. S. 164 (1972); Levy v. Louisiana, 391 U. S.
68 (1968).
In Weber, the Court struck down a portion of a state
workmen's compensation statute that relegated unacknowledged
illegitimate children of the deceased to a lesser status with
respect to benefits than that occupied by legitimate children of
the deceased. The Court acknowledged the true nature of its inquiry
in cases such as these: "What legitimate state interest does the
classification promote? What fundamental personal rights might the
classification endanger?" Id. at 406 U. S. 173 .
Embarking upon a determination of the relative substantiality of
the State's justifications for the classification, the Court
rejected the contention that the classifications reflected what
might be presumed to have been the deceased's preference of
beneficiaries as "not compelling . . . where dependency on the
deceased is a prerequisite to anyone's recovery. . . ." Ibid. Likewise, it deemed the relationship between the
State's interest in encouraging legitimate family relationships and
the burden placed on the illegitimates too tenuous to permit the
classification to stand. Ibid. A clear insight into the
basis of the Court's action is provided by its conclusion:
"[I]mposing disabilities on the illegitimate child is contrary
to the basic concept of our system that legal burdens should bear
some relationship to individual responsibility or wrongdoing.
Obviously, no child is responsible for his birth and penalizing the
illegitimate child is an ineffectual -- as well as an unjust -- way
of deterring the parent. Courts are powerless to prevent the social
opprobrium suffered by these hapless children, but the Equal
Protection Page 411 U. S. 109 Clause does enable us to strike down discriminatory laws
relating to status of birth. . . ." Id. at 406 U. S.
175 -176. Status of birth, like the color of one's skin,
is something which the individual cannot control, and should
generally be irrelevant in legislative considerations. Yet
illegitimacy has long been stigmatized by our society. Hence,
discrimination on the basis of birth -- particularly when it
affects innocent children -- warrants special judicial
consideration.
In summary, it seems to me inescapably clear that this Court has
consistently adjusted the care with which it will review state
discrimination in light of the constitutional significance of the
interests affected and the invidiousness of the particular
classification. In the context of economic interests, we find that
discriminatory state action is almost always sustained, for such
interests are generally far removed from constitutional guarantees.
Moreover,
"[t]he extremes to which the Court has gone in dreaming up
rational bases for state regulation in that area may in many
instances be ascribed to a healthy revulsion from the Court's
earlier excesses in using the Constitution to protect interests
that have more than enough power to protect themselves in the
legislative halls." Dandridge v. Williams, 397 U.S. at 397 U. S. 520 (dissenting opinion). But the situation differs markedly when
discrimination against important individual interests with
constitutional implications and against particularly disadvantaged
or powerless classes is involved. The majority suggests, however,
that a variable standard of review would give this Court the
appearance of a "super-legislature." Ante at 411 U. S. 31 . I
cannot agree. Such an approach seems to me a part of the guarantees
of our Constitution and of the historic experiences with oppression
of and discrimination against discrete, powerless minorities which
underlie that document. In truth, Page 411 U. S. 110 the Court itself will be open to the criticism raised by the
majority so long as it continues on its present course of
effectively selecting in private which cases will be afforded
special consideration without acknowledging the true basis of its
action. [ Footnote 4/67 ] Opinions
such as those in Reed and James seem drawn more
as efforts to shield, rather than to reveal, the true basis of the
Court's decisions. Such obfuscated action may be appropriate to a
political body such as a legislature, but it is not appropriate to
this Court. Open debate of the bases for the Court's action is
essential to the rationality and consistency of our decisionmaking
process. Only in this way can we avoid the label of legislature and
ensure the integrity of the judicial process.
Nevertheless, the majority today attempts to force this case
into the same category for purposes of equal protection analysis as
decisions involving discrimination affecting commercial interests.
By so doing, the majority ingles this case out for analytic
treatment at odds with what seems to me to be the clear trend of
recent decisions in this Court, and thereby ignores the
constitutional importance of the interest at stake and the
invidiousness of the particular classification, factors that call
for far more than the lenient scrutiny of the Texas financing
scheme which the majority pursues. Yet if the discrimination
inherent in the Texas scheme is scrutinized with the care demanded
by the interest and classification present in this case, the
unconstitutionality of that scheme is unmistakable. B Since the Court now suggests that only interests guaranteed by
the Constitution are fundamental for purposes of equal protection
analysis, and since it rejects Page 411 U. S. 111 the contention that public education is fundamental, it follows
that the Court concludes that public education is not
constitutionally guaranteed. It is true that this Court has never
deemed the provision of free public education to be required by the
Constitution. Indeed, it has on occasion suggested that
state-supported education is a privilege bestowed by a State on its
citizens. See Missouri ex rel. Gaines v. Canada, 305 U.S.
at 305 U. S. 349 .
Nevertheless, the fundamental importance of education is amply
indicated by the prior decisions of this Court, by the unique
status accorded public education by our society, and by the close
relationship between education and some of our most basic
constitutional values.
The special concern of this Court with the educational process
of our country is a matter of common knowledge. Undoubtedly, this
Court's most famous statement on the subject is that contained in Brown v. Board of Education, 347 U.S. at 347 U. S.
493 :
"Today, education is perhaps the most important function of
state and local governments. Compulsory school attendance laws and
the great expenditures for education both demonstrate our
recognition of the importance of education to our democratic
society. It is required in the performance of our most basic public
responsibilities, even service in the armed forces. It is the very
foundation of good citizenship. Today it is a principal instrument
in awakening the child to cultural values, in preparing him for
later professional training, and in helping him to adjust normally
to his environment. . . ."
Only last Term, the Court recognized that "[p]roviding public
schools ranks at the very apex of the function of a State." Wisconsin v. Yoder, 406 U. S. 205 , 406 U. S. 213 (1972). This is clearly borne out by the fact that, in 48 Page 411 U. S. 112 of our 50 States, the provision of public education is mandated
by the state constitution. [ Footnote
4/68 ] No other state function is so uniformly recognized
[ Footnote 4/69 ] as an essential
element of our society's wellbeing. In large measure, the
explanation for the special importance attached to education must
rest, as the Court recognized in Yoder, id. at 406 U. S. 221 ,
on the facts that "some degree of education is necessary to prepare
citizens to participate effectively and intelligently in our open
political system . . . ," and that "education prepares individuals
to be self-reliant and self-sufficient participants in society."
Both facets of this observation are suggestive of the substantial
relationship which education bears to guarantees of our
Constitution.
Education directly affects the ability of a child to exercise
his First Amendment rights, both as a source and as a receiver of
information and ideas, whatever interests he may pursue in life.
This Court's decision in Sweezy v. New Hampshire, 354 U. S. 234 , 354 U. S. 250 (1957), speaks of the right of students "to inquire, to study and
to evaluate, to gain new maturity and understanding. . . ." Thus,
we have not casually described the classroom as the
" marketplace of ideas.'" Keyishian v. Board of
Regents, 385 U. S. 589 , 385 U. S. 603 (1967). The opportunity for formal education may not necessarily be
the essential determinant of an individual's ability to enjoy
throughout his life the rights of free speech and
association Page 411 U. S. 113 guaranteed to him by the First Amendment. But such an
opportunity may enhance the individual's enjoyment of those rights
not only during, but also following, school attendance. Thus, in
the final analysis,
"the pivotal position of education to success in American
society and its essential role in opening up to the individual the
central experiences of our culture lend it an importance that is
undeniable. [ Footnote 4/70 ]"
Of particular importance is the relationship between education
and the political process. "Americans regard the public schools as
a most vital civic institution for the preservation of a democratic
system of government." Abington School Dist. v. Schempp, 374 U. S. 203 , 374 U. S. 230 (1963) (BRENNAN, J., concurring). Education serves the essential
function of instilling in our young an understanding of and
appreciation for the principles and operation of our governmental
processes. [ Footnote 4/71 ]
Education may instill the interest and provide the tools necessary
for political discourse and debate. Indeed, it has frequently been
suggested that education is the dominant factor affecting political
consciousness and participation. [ Footnote 4/72 ] A system of
"[c]ompetition in ideas and governmental Page 411 U. S. 114 policies is at the core of our electoral process and of the
First Amendment freedoms." Williams v. Rhodes, 393 U. S. 23 , 393 U. S. 32 (1968). But of most immediate and direct concern must be the
demonstrated effect of education on the exercise of the franchise
by the electorate. The right to vote in federal elections is
conferred by Art. I, § 2, and the Seventeenth Amendment of the
Constitution, and access to the state franchise has been afforded
special protection because it is "preservative of other basic civil
and political rights," Reynolds v. Sims, 377 U.S. at 377 U. S. 562 .
Data from the Presidential Election of 1968 clearly demonstrate a
direct relationship between participation in the electoral process
and level of educational attainment, [ Footnote 4/73 ] and, as this Court recognized in Gaston County v. United States, 395 U.
S. 285 , 395 U. S. 296 (1969), the quality of education offered may Page 411 U. S. 115 influence a child's decision to "enter or remain in school." It
is this very sort of intimate relationship between a particular
personal interest and specific constitutional guarantees that has
heretofore caused the Court to attach special significance, for
purposes of equal protection analysis, to individual interests such
as procreation and the exercise of the state franchise. [ Footnote 4/74 ]
While ultimately disputing little of this, the majority seeks
refuge in the fact that the Court has
"never presumed to possess either the ability or the authority
to guarantee to the citizenry the most effective speech or
the most informed electoral choice." Ante at 411 U. S. 36 .
This serves only to blur what is in fact, at stake. With due
respect, the issue is neither provision of the most effective
speech nor of the most informed vote. Appellees Page 411 U. S. 116 do not now seek the best education Texas might provide. They do
seek, however, an end to state discrimination resulting from the
unequal distribution of taxable district property wealth that
directly impairs the ability of some districts to provide the same
educational opportunity that other districts can provide with the
same or even substantially less tax effort. The issue is, in other
words, one of discrimination that affects the quality of the
education which Texas has chosen to provide its children; and, the
precise question here is what importance should attach to education
for purposes of equal protection analysis of that discrimination.
As this Court held in Brown v. Board of Education, 347
U.S. at 347 U. S. 493 ,
the opportunity of education, "where the state has undertaken to
provide it, is a right which must be made available to all on equal
terms." The factors just considered, including the relationship
between education and the social and political interests enshrined
within the Constitution, compel us to recognize the fundamentality
of education and to scrutinize with appropriate care the bases for
state discrimination affecting equality of educational opportunity
in Texas' school districts [ Footnote
4/75 ] -- a conclusion Page 411 U. S. 117 which is only strengthened when we consider the character of the
classification in this case. C The District Court found that, in discriminating between Texas
school children on the basis of the amount of taxable property
wealth located in the district in which they live, the Texas
financing scheme created a form of wealth discrimination. This
Court has frequently recognized that discrimination on the basis of
wealth may create a classification of a suspect character, and
thereby call for exacting judicial scrutiny. See, e.g., Griffin
v. Illinois, 351 U. S. 12 (1956); Douglas v. California, 372 U.
S. 353 (1963); McDonald v. Board of Election Comm'rs
of Chicago, 394 U. S. 802 , 394 U. S. 807 (1969). The majority, however, considers any wealth classification
in this case to lack certain essential characteristics which it
contends are common to the instances of wealth discrimination that
this Court has heretofore recognized. We are told that, in every
prior case involving a wealth classification, the members of the
disadvantaged class have
"shared two distinguishing characteristics: because Page 411 U. S. 118 of their impecunity, they were completely unable to pay for some
desired benefit, and as a consequence, they sustained an absolute
deprivation of a meaningful opportunity to enjoy that benefit." Ante at 411 U. S. 20 . I
cannot agree. The Court's distinctions may be sufficient to explain
the decisions in Williams v. Illinois, 399 U.
S. 235 (1970); Tate v. Short, 401 U.
S. 395 (1971); and even Bullock v. Carter, 405 U. S. 134 (1972). But they are not, in fact, consistent with the decisions in Harper v. Virginia Bd. of Elections, 383 U.
S. 663 (1966), or Griffin v. Illinois, supra, or Douglas v. California, supra. In Harper, the Court struck down, as violative of the
Equal Protection Clause, an annual Virginia poll tax of $1.50,
payment of which by persons over the age of 21 was a prerequisite
to voting in Virginia elections. In part, the Court relied on the
fact that the poll tax interfered with a fundamental interest --
the exercise of the state franchise. In addition, though, the Court
emphasized that "[l]ines drawn on the basis of wealth or property .
. . are traditionally disfavored." 383 U.S. at 383 U. S. 668 .
Under the first part of the theory announced by the majority, the
disadvantaged class in Harper, in terms of a wealth
analysis, should have consisted only of those too poor to afford
the $1.50 necessary to vote. But the Harper Court did not
see it that way. In its view, the Equal Protection Clause "bars a
system which excludes [from the franchise] those unable to pay a
fee to vote or who fail to pay. " Ibid. (Emphasis
added.) So far as the Court was concerned, the "degree of the
discrimination [was] irrelevant." Ibid. Thus, the Court
struck down the poll tax in toto; it did not order merely
that those too poor to pay the tax be exempted; complete impecunity
clearly was not determinative of the limits of the disadvantaged
class, nor was it essential to make an equal protection claim. Page 411 U. S. 119 Similarly, Griffin and Douglas refute the
majority's contention that we have in the past required an absolute
deprivation before subjecting wealth classifications to strict
scrutiny. The Court characterizes Griffin as a case
concerned simply with the denial of a transcript or an adequate
substitute therefor, and Douglas as involving the denial
of counsel. But, in both cases, the question was, in fact, whether
"a State that [grants] appellate review can do so in a way
that discriminates against some convicted defendants on account of
their poverty." Griffin v. Illinois, supra, at 351 U. S. 18 (emphasis added). In that regard, the Court concluded that
inability to purchase a transcript denies "the poor an adequate appellate review accorded to all who have money enough to
pay the costs in advance," ibid. (emphasis added), and
that "the type of an appeal a person is afforded . . .
hinges upon whether or not he can pay for the assistance of
counsel," Douglas v. California, supra, at 372 U. S.
355 -356 (emphasis added). The right of appeal itself was
not absolutely denied to those too poor to pay, but, because of the
cost of a transcript and of counsel, the appeal was a substantially
less meaningful right for the poor than for the rich. [ Footnote 4/76 ] It was on these terms that
the Court found a denial of equal protection, and those terms
clearly encompassed degrees of discrimination on the Page 411 U. S. 120 basis of wealth which do not amount to outright denial of the
affected right or interest. [ Footnote
4/77 ]
This is not to say that the form of wealth classification in
this case does not differ significantly from those recognized in
the previous decisions of this Court. Our prior eases have dealt
essentially with discrimination on the basis of personal wealth.
[ Footnote 4/78 ] Here, by
contrast, the Page 411 U. S. 121 children of the disadvantaged Texas school districts are being
discriminated against not necessarily because of their personal
wealth or the wealth of their families, but because of the taxable
property wealth of the residents of the district in which they
happen to live. The appropriate question, then, is whether the same
degree of judicial solicitude and scrutiny that has previously been
afforded wealth classifications is warranted here.
As the Court points out, ante at 411 U. S. 28 -29,
no previous decision has deemed the presence of just a wealth
classification to be sufficient basis to call forth rigorous
judicial scrutiny of allegedly discriminatory state action. Compare, e.g., Harper v. Virginia Bd. of Elections, supra,
with, e.g., James v. Valtierra, 402 U.
S. 137 (1971). That wealth classifications alone have
not necessarily been considered to bear the same high degree of
suspectness as have classifications based on, for instance, race or
alienage may be explainable on a number of grounds. The "poor" may
not be seen as politically powerless as certain discrete and
insular minority groups. [ Footnote
4/79 ] Personal poverty may entail much the same social stigma
as historically attached to certain racial or ethnic groups.
[ Footnote 4/80 ] But personal
poverty is not a permanent disability; its shackles may be escaped.
Perhaps most importantly, though, personal wealth may not
necessarily share the general irrelevance as a basis for
legislative action that race or nationality is recognized to have.
While the "poor" have frequently been a Page 411 U. S. 122 legally disadvantaged group, [ Footnote 4/81 ] it cannot be ignored that social
legislation must frequently take cognizance of the economic status
of our citizens. Thus, we have generally gauged the invidiousness
of wealth classifications with an awareness of the importance of
the interests being affected and the relevance of personal wealth
to those interests. See Harper v. Virginia Bd. of Elections,
supra. When evaluated with these considerations in mind, it seems to me
that discrimination on the basis of group wealth in this case
likewise calls for careful judicial scrutiny. First, it must be
recognized that, while local district wealth may serve other
interests, [ Footnote 4/82 ] it
bears no relationship whatsoever to the interest of Texas school
children in the educational opportunity afforded them by the State
of Texas. Given the importance of that interest, we must be
particularly sensitive to the invidious characteristics of any form
of discrimination that is not clearly intended to serve it, as
opposed to some other distinct state interest. Discrimination on
the basis of group wealth may not, to be sure, reflect the social
stigma frequently attached to personal poverty. Nevertheless,
insofar as group wealth discrimination involves wealth over which
the disadvantaged individual has no significant control, [ Footnote 4/83 ] it represents in fact, a
more serious basis of discrimination than does personal wealth. For
such discrimination Page 411 U. S. 123 is no reflection of the individual's characteristics or his
abilities. And thus -- particularly in the context of a
disadvantaged class composed of children -- we have previously
treated discrimination on a basis which the individual cannot
control as constitutionally disfavored. Cf. Weber v. Aetna
Casualty & Surety Co., 406 U. S. 164 (1972); Levy v. Louisiana, 391 U. S.
68 (1968).
The disability of the disadvantaged class in this case extends
as well into the political processes upon which we ordinarily rely
a adequate for the protection and promotion of all interests. Here
legislative reallocation of the State's property wealth must be
sought in the face of inevitable opposition from significantly
advantaged districts that have a strong vested interest in the
preservation of the status quo, a problem not completely
dissimilar to that faced by underrepresented districts prior to the
Court's intervention in the process of reapportionment, [ Footnote 4/84 ] see Baker v.
Carr, 369 U. S. 186 , 369 U. S.
191 -192 (1962).
Nor can we ignore the extent to which, in contrast to our prior
decisions, the State is responsible for the wealth discrimination
in this instance. Griffin, Douglas, Williams, Tate, and
our other prior cases have dealt with discrimination on the basis
of indigency which was attributable to the operation of the private
sector. But we have no such simple de facto wealth
discrimination here. The means for financing public education in
Texas are selected and specified by the State. It is the State that
has created local school districts, and tied educational funding to
the local property tax, and thereby to local district wealth. At
the same time, governmentally Page 411 U. S. 124 imposed land use controls have undoubtedly encouraged and
rigidified natural trends in the allocation of particular areas for
residential or commercial use, [ Footnote 4/85 ] and thus determined each district's
amount of taxable property wealth. In short, this case, in contrast
to the Court's previous wealth discrimination decisions, can only
be seen as "unusual in the extent to which governmental action is
the cause of the wealth classifications." [ Footnote 4/86 ]
In the final analysis, then, the invidious characteristics of
the group wealth classification present in this case merely serve
to emphasize the need for careful judicial scrutiny of the State's
justifications for the resulting inter-district discrimination in
the educational opportunity afforded to the school children of
Texas. D The nature of our inquiry into the justifications for state
discrimination is essentially the same in all equal protection
cases: we must consider the substantiality of the state interests
sought to be served, and we must scrutinize the reasonableness of
the means by which the State has sought to advance its interests. See Police Dept. of Chicago v. Mosley, 408 U.S. at 408 U. S. 95 .
Differences in the application of this test are, in my view, a
function of the constitutional importance of the interests at stake
and the invidiousness of the particular classification. In terms of
the asserted state interests, the Court has indicated that it will
require, for instance, a "compelling," Shapiro v.
Thompson, 394 U.S. at 394 U. S. 634 , or a "substantial" Page 411 U. S. 125 or "important," Dunn v. Blumstein, 405 U.S. at 405 U. S. 343 ,
state interest to justify discrimination affecting individual
interests of constitutional significance. Whatever the differences,
if any, in these descriptions of the character of the state
interest necessary to sustain such discrimination, basic to each
is, I believe, a concern with the legitimacy and the reality of the
asserted state interests. Thus, when interests of constitutional
importance are at stake, the Court does not stand ready to credit
the State's classification with any conceivable legitimate purpose,
[ Footnote 4/87 ] but demands a
clear showing that there are legitimate state interests which the
classification was in fact, intended to serve. Beyond the question
of the adequacy of the State's purpose for the classification, the
Court traditionally has become increasingly sensitive to the means
by which a State chooses to act as its action affects more directly
interests of constitutional significance. See, e.g., United
States v. Robel, 389 U. S. 258 , 389 U. S. 265 (1967); Shelton v. Tucker, 364 U.
S. 479 , 364 U. S. 488 (1960). Thus, by now, "less restrictive alternatives" analysis is
firmly established in equal protection jurisprudence. See Dunn
v. Blumstein, supra, at 405 U. S. 343 ; Kramer v. Union School District, 395 U.S. at 395 U. S. 627 .
It seems to me that the range of choice we are willing to accord
the State in selecting the means by which it will act, and the care
with which we scrutinize the effectiveness of the means which the
State selects, also must reflect the constitutional importance of
the interest affected and the invidiousness of the particular
classification. Here, both the nature of the interest and the
classification dictate close judicial scrutiny of the purposes
which Texas seeks to serve with its present educational
financing Page 411 U. S. 126 scheme and of the means it has selected to serve that
purpose.
The only justification offered by appellants to sustain the
discrimination in educational opportunity caused by the Texas
financing scheme is local educational control. Presented with this
justification, the District Court concluded that
"[n]ot only are defendants unable to demonstrate compelling
state interests for their classifications based upon wealth, they
fail even to establish a reasonable basis for these
classifications."
337 F. Supp. at 284. I must agree with this conclusion.
At the outset, I do not question that local control of public
education, as an abstract matter, constitutes a very substantial
state interest. We observed only last Term that "[d]irect control
over decisions vitally affecting the education of one's children is
a need that is strongly felt in our society." Wright v. Council
of the City of Emporia, 407 U. S. 451 , 407 U. S. 469 (1972). See also id. at 407 U. S.
477 -478 (BURGER, C.J., dissenting). The State's interest
in local educational control -- which certainly includes questions
of educational funding -- has deep roots in the inherent benefits
of community support for public education. Consequently, true state
dedication to local control would present, I think, a substantial
justification to weigh against simply inter-district variations in
the treatment of a State's school children. But I need not now
decide how I might ultimately strike the balance were we confronted
with a situation where the State's sincere concern for local
control inevitably produced educational inequality. For, on this
record, it is apparent that the State's purported concern with
local control is offered primarily as an excuse, rather than as a
justification for inter-district inequality.
In Texas, state-wide laws regulate in fact, the most minute
details of local public education. For example, Page 411 U. S. 127 the State prescribes required courses. [ Footnote 4/88 ] All textbooks must be submitted for
state approval, [ Footnote 4/89 ]
and only approved textbooks may be used. [ Footnote 4/90 ] The State has established the
qualifications necessary for teaching in Texas public schools and
the procedures for obtaining certification. [ Footnote 4/91 ] The State has even legislated on the
length of the school day. [ Footnote
4/92 ] Texas' own courts have said:
"As a result of the acts of the Legislature, our school system
is not of mere local concern, but it is state-wide. While a school
district is local in territorial limits, it is an integral part of
the vast school system which is coextensive with the confines of
the State of Texas." Treadaway v. Whitney Independent School District, 205
S.W.2d 97, 99 Tex.Ct. Civ.App. (1947). See also El Dorado
Independent School District v. Tisdale, 3 S.W.2d 420, 422
(Tex. Comm'n App. 1928).
Moreover, even if we accept Texas' general dedication to local
control in educational matters, it is difficult to find any
evidence of such dedication with respect to fiscal matters. It
ignores reality to suggest -- as the Court does, ante at 411 U. S. 49 -50
-- that the local property tax element of the Texas financing
scheme reflects a conscious legislative effort to provide school
districts with local fiscal control. If Texas had a system truly
dedicated to local fiscal control, one would expect the quality of
the educational opportunity provided in each district to vary with
the decision of the voters in that district as Page 411 U. S. 128 to the level of sacrifice they wish to make for public
education. In fact, the Texas scheme produces precisely the
opposite result. Local school districts cannot choose to have the
best education in the State by imposing the highest tax rate.
Instead, the quality of the educational opportunity offered by any
particular district is largely determined by the amount of taxable
property located in the district -- a factor over which local
voters can exercise no control.
The study introduced in the District Court showed a direct
inverse relationship between equalized taxable district property
wealth and district tax effort with the result that the
property-poor districts making the highest tax effort obtained the
lowest per-pupil yield. [ Footnote
4/93 ] The implications of this situation for local choice are
illustrated by again comparing the Edgewood and Alamo Heights
School Districts. In 1967-1968, Edgewood, after contributing its
share to the Local Fund Assignment, raised only $26 per pupil
through its local property tax, whereas Alamo Heights was able to
raise $333 per pupil. Since the funds received through the Minimum
Foundation School Program are to be used only for minimum
professional salaries, transportation costs, and operating
expenses, it is not hard to see the lack of local choice with
respect to higher teacher salaries to attract more and better
teachers, physical facilities, library books, and facilities,
special courses, or participation in special state and federal
matching funds programs -- under which a property-poor district
such as Edgewood is forced to labor. [ Footnote 4/94 ] In fact, because of the difference in
taxable local property wealth, Edgewood would have to tax itself
almost nine times as heavily to obtain the same Page 411 U. S. 129 yield as Alamo Heights. [ Footnote
4/95 ] At present, then, local control is a myth for many of the
local school districts in Texas. As one district court has
observed,
"rather than reposing in each school district the economic power
to fix its own level of per pupil expenditure, the State has so
arranged the structure as to guarantee that some districts will
spend low (with high taxes) while others will spend high (with low
taxes)." Van Dusatz v. Hatfield, 334 F.
Supp. 870 , 876 (Minn.1971).
In my judgment, any substantial degree of scrutiny of the
operation of the Texas financing scheme reveals that the State has
selected means wholly inappropriate to secure its purported
interest in assuring its school districts local fiscal control.
[ Footnote 4/96 ] At the same time,
appellees have pointed out a variety of alternative financing
schemes which may serve the State's purported interest in local
control as well as, if not better than, the present scheme without
the current impairment of the educational opportunity of vast
numbers of Texas school children. [ Footnote 4/97 ] I see no need, however, to explore the
practical or constitutional merits of those suggested alternatives
at this time, for, whatever their positive or negative features,
experience Page 411 U. S. 130 with the present financing scheme impugns any suggestion that it
constitutes a serious effort to provide local fiscal control. If,
for the sake of local education control, this Court is to sustain
inter-district discrimination in the educational opportunity
afforded Texas school children, it should require that the State
present something more than the mere sham now before us. III In conclusion, it is essential to recognize that an end to the
wide variations in taxable district property wealth inherent in the
Texas financing scheme would entail none of the untoward
consequences suggested by the Court or by the appellants.
First, affirmance of the District Court's decisions would hardly
sound the death knell for local control of education. It would mean
neither centralized decisionmaking nor federal court intervention
in the operation of public schools. Clearly, this suit has nothing
to do with local decisionmaking with respect to educational policy
or even educational spending. It involves only a narrow aspect of
local control -- namely, local control over the raising of
educational funds. In fact, in striking down inter-district
disparities in taxable local wealth, the District Court took the
course which is most likely to make true local control over
educational decisionmaking a reality for all Texas school
districts.
Nor does the District Court's decision even necessarily
eliminate local control of educational funding. The District Court
struck down nothing more than the continued inter-district wealth
discrimination inherent in the present property tax. Both
centralized and decentralized plans for educational funding not
involving such inter-district discrimination have been put forward.
[ Footnote 4/98 ] The choice Page 411 U. S. 131 among these or other alternatives would remain with the State,
not with the federal courts. In this regard, it should be evident
that the degree of federal intervention Page 411 U. S. 132 in matters of local concern would be substantially less in this
context than in previous decisions in which we have been asked
effectively to impose a particular scheme upon the States under the
guise of the Equal Protection Clause. See, e.g., Dandridge v.
Williams, 397 U. S. 471 (1970); cf. Richardson v. Belcher, 404 U. S.
78 (1971).
Still, we are told that this case requires us "to condemn the
State's judgment in conferring on political subdivisions the power
to tax local property to supply revenues for local interests." Ante at 411 U. S. 40 . Yet
no one in the course of this entire litigation has ever questioned
the constitutionality of the local property tax as a device for
raising educational funds. The District Court's decision, at most,
restricts the power of the State to make educational funding
dependent exclusively upon local property taxation so long as there
exists inter-district disparities in taxable property wealth. But
it hardly eliminates the local property tax as a source of
educational funding or as a means of providing local fiscal
control. [ Footnote 4/99 ]
The Court seeks solace for its action today in the possibility
of legislative reform. The Court's suggestions of legislative
redress and experimentation will doubtless be of great comfort to
the school children of Texas' disadvantaged districts, but,
considering the vested interests of wealthy school districts in the
preservation of the status quo, they are worth little
more. The possibility of legislative action is, in all events, no
answer to this Court's duty under the Constitution to eliminate
unjustified state discrimination. In this case, we have been
presented with an instance of such discrimination, in a
particularly invidious form, against an individual interest of
large constitutional and practical importance. To support the
demonstrated discrimination in the provision Page 411 U. S. 133 of educational opportunity the State has offered a justification
which, on analysis, takes on, at best, an ephemeral character.
Thus, I believe that the wide disparities in taxable district
property wealth inherent in the local property tax element of the
Texas financing scheme render that scheme violative of the Equal
Protection Clause. [ Footnote
4/100 ]
I would therefore affirm the judgment of the District Court. Page 411 U. S. 134 | 411 U.S.
1 app1|
bwm:
APPENDIX I TO OPINION OF MARSHALL, J., DISSENTING
REVENUES OF TEXAS SCHOOL DISTRICTS CATEGORIZED
BY EQUALIZED PROPERTY VALUES AND SOURCE OF FUNDS
CATEGORIES Total Revenues
State and Local Per Pupil
Market Value of Revenues Per Federal (State-Local-
Taxable Property Local Revenues State Revenues Pupil (Columns
Revenues Federal, Columns
Per Pupil Per Pupil Per Pupil 1 and 2) Per Pupil 1, 2 and 4)
Above $100,000 $610 $205 $815 $ 41 $856
(10 districts)
$100,000-$50,000 287 257 544 66 610
(26 districts)
$50,000-$30,000 224 260 484 45 529
(30 districts)
$30,000-$10,000 166 295 461 85 546
(40 districts)
Below $10,000 63 243 306 135 441
(4 districts)
ewm:
Based on Table V to affidavit of Joel S. Berke, App. 208, which
was prepared on the basis of a sample of 110 selected Texas school
districts from data for the 1967-1968 school year. Page 411 U. S. 135 | 411 U.S.
1 app2|
APPENDIX II TO OPINION OF MARSHALL, J., DISSENTING
TEXAS SCHOOL DISTRICTS CATEGORIZED BY
EQUALIZED PROPERTY VALUES, EQUALIZED
TAX RATES, AND YIELD OF RATES
CATEGORIES EQUALIZED YIELD PER PUPIL
Market Value of TAX (Equalized Rate
Taxable Property RATES Applied to District
Per Pupil ON $100 Market Value)
Above $100,000 $.31 $585
(10 districts)
$100,000-$50,000 .38 262
(26 districts)
$50,000-$30,000 .55 213
(30 districts)
$30,000-$10,000 .72 162
(40 districts)
Below $10,000 .70 60
(4 districts)
Based on Table II to affidavit of Joel S. Berke, App. 205, which
was prepared on the basis of a sample of 110 selected Texas school
districts from data for the 1967-1968 school year. Page 411 U. S. 136 | 411 U.S.
1 app3|
bwm:
APPENDIX III TO OPINION OF MARSHALL, J., DISSENTING
SELECTED BEXAR COUNTY, TEXAS, SCHOOL DISTRICTS
CATEGORIZED BY EQUALIZED PROPERTY VALUATION AND
SELECTED INDICATORS OF EDUCATIONAL QUALITY
Selected Districts Per Cent of Per Cent of
From High to Low by Professional Teachers With Total Staff
Student- Professional
Market Valuation Salaries Per College Masters With Emergen-
Counselor Personnel
Per Pupil Pupil Degrees Degrees cy Permits Ratios Per 100
Pupils
ALAMO HEIGHTS $372 100% 40% 11% 645 4.80
NORTH EAST 288 99 24 7 1,516 4.50
SAN ANTONIO 251 98 29 17 2,320 4.00
NORTH SIDE 258 99 20 17 1,493 4.30
HARLANDALE 243 94 21 22 1,800 4.00
EDGEWOOD 209 96 15 47 3,098 4.06
ewm:
Based on Table XI to affidavit of Joel S. Berke,App. 220, which
was prepared on the basis of a sample of six selected school
districts located in Bexar County, Texas, from data for the
1967-1968 school year. Page 411 U. S. 137 | 411 U.S.
1 app4|
APPENDIX IV TO OPINION OF MARSHALL, J., DISSENTING
BEXAR COUNTY, TEXAS, SCHOOL DISTRICTS RANKED BY
EQUALIZED PROPERTY VALUE AND TAX RATE REQUIRED TO
GENERATE HIGHEST YIELD IN ALL DISTRICTS
Districts Ranked from Tax Rate Per $100
High to Low Market Needed to Equal
Valuation Per Pupil Highest Yield
ALAMO HEIGHTS $0.68
JUDSON 1.04
EAST CENTRAL 1.17
NORTH EAST 1.21
SOMERSET 1.32
SAN ANTONIO 1.56
NORTH SIDE 1.65
SOUTH WEST 2.10
SOUTH SIDE 3.03
HARLANDALE 3.20
SOUTH SAN ANTONIO 5.77
EDGEWOOD 5.76
Based on Table IX to affidavit of Joel S. Berke, App. 218, which
was prepared on the basis of the 12 school districts located in
Bexar County, Texas, from data from the 1967-1968 school year.
[ Footnote 4/1 ] See Van Dusartz v. Hatfield, 334 F.
Supp. 870 (Minn.1971); Milliken v. Green, 389 Mich. 1, 203 N.W.2d
457 (1972), rehearing granted, Jan.1973; Serrano
v. Priest, 5 Cal. 3d 584 ,
487 P.2d 1241 (1971); Robinson v. Cahill, 118 N.J.Super.
223, 287 A.2d 187 , 119 N.J.Super. 40, 289 A.2d 569 (1972); Hollins v. Shofstall, Civil No.
C-253652 (Super.Ct. Maricopa County, Ariz. July 7, 1972). See
also Sweetwater County Planning Com. for the Organization of School
Districts v. Hinkle, 491 P.2d 1234 (Wyo.1971), juris. relinquished, 493 P.2d 1050 (Wyo.1972).
[ Footnote 4/2 ]
The District Court in this case postponed decision for some two
years in the hope that the Texas Legislature would remedy the gross
disparities in treatment inherent in the Texas financing scheme. It
was only after the legislature failed to act in its 1971 Regular
Session that the District Court, apparently recognizing the lack of
hope for self-initiated legislative reform, rendered its decision. See Texas Research League, Public School Finance Problems
in Texas 13 (Interim Report 1972). The strong vested interest of
property-rich districts in the existing property tax scheme poses a
substantial barrier to self-initiated legislative reform in
educational financing. See N.Y. Times, Dec.19, 1972, p. 1,
col. 1.
[ Footnote 4/3 ]
Texas provides its school districts with extensive bonding
authority to obtain capital both for the acquisition of school
sites and "the construction and equipment of school buildings,"
Tex.Educ.Code Ann. § 20.01 (1972), and for the acquisition,
construction, and maintenance of "gymnasia, stadia, or other
recreational facilities," id. §§ 20.21-20.22. While such
private capital provides a fourth source of revenue, it is, of
course, only temporary in nature, since the principal and interest
of all bonds must ultimately be paid out of the receipts of the
local ad valorem property tax, see id. §§ 20.01,
20.04, except to the extent that outside revenues derived from the
operation of certain facilities, such as gymnasia, are employed to
repay the bonds issued thereon, see id. §§ 20.22,
20.25.
[ Footnote 4/4 ] See Tex.Const., Art. 7, § 3; Tex.Educ.Code Ann. §§
20.01-20.02. As a part of the property tax scheme, bonding
authority is conferred upon the local school districts, see 411 U.S.
1 fn4/3|>n. 3, supra. [ Footnote 4/5 ] See Tex.Educ.Code Ann. § 20.04.
[ Footnote 4/6 ]
For the 1970-1971 school year, the precise figure was 41.1%. See Texas Research League, supra, 411 U.S.
1 fn4/2|>n. 2, at 9.
[ Footnote 4/7 ] See Tex.Educ.Code Ann. § 20.04.
Theoretically, Texas law limits the tax rate for public school
maintenance, see id. § 20.02, to $1.50 per $100 valuation, see id. § 20.04(d). However, it does not appear that any
Texas district presently taxes itself at the highest rate
allowable, although some poor districts are approaching it, see App. 174.
[ Footnote 4/8 ]
Under Texas law, local districts are allowed to employ differing
bases of assessment -- a fact that introduces a third variable into
the local funding. See Tex.Educ.Code Ann. § 20.03. But
neither party has suggested that this factor is responsible for the
disparities in revenues available to the various districts.
Consequently, I believe we must deal with this case on the
assumption that differences in local methods of assessment do not
meaningfully affect the revenue-raising power of local districts
relative to one another. The Court apparently admits as much. See ante at 411 U. S. 46 . It
should be noted, moreover, that the main set of data introduced
before the District Court to establish the disparities at issue
here was based upon "equalized taxable property" values which had
been adjusted to correct for differing methods of assessment. See App. C to Affidavit of Professor Joel S. Berke.
[ Footnote 4/9 ]
Texas has approximately 1,200 school districts.
[ Footnote 4/10 ] See Appendix I, post, p. 411 U. S.
134 .
[ Footnote 4/11 ] See ibid. Indeed, appellants acknowledge that the
relevant data from Professor Berke's affidavit show "a very
positive correlation, 0.973, between market value of taxable
property per pupil and state and local revenues per pupil." Reply
Brief for Appellants 6 n. 9.
While the Court takes issue with much of Professor Berke's data
and conclusions, ante at 411 U. S. 15 -16,
n. 38, and 411 U. S. 25 -27,
I do not understand its criticism to run to the basic finding of a
correlation between taxable district property per pupil and local
revenues per pupil. The critique of Professor Berke's methodology
upon which the Court relies, see Goldstein, Inter-district
Inequalities in School Financing: A Critical Analysis of Serrano v. Priest and its Progeny, 120 U.Pa.L.Rev. 504,
523-525, nn. 67, 71 (1972), is directed only at the suggested
correlations between family income and taxable district wealth and
between race and taxable district wealth. Obviously, the appellants
do not question the relationship in Texas between taxable district
wealth and per-pupil expenditures; and there is no basis for the
Court to do so, whatever the criticisms that may be leveled at
other aspects of Professor Berke's study, see infra, 411 U.S.
1 fn4/56|>n. 56.
[ Footnote 4/12 ] See Appendix II, post, p. 411 U. S.
135 .
[ Footnote 4/13 ] See ibid. [ Footnote 4/14 ]
For the 1970-1971 school year, the precise figure was 10.9%. See Texas Research League, supra, 411 U.S.
1 fn4/2|>n. 2, at 9.
[ Footnote 4/15 ]
Appellants made such a contention before the District Court but
apparently have abandoned it in this Court. Indeed, data introduced
in the District Court simply belie the argument that federal funds
have a significant equalizing effect. See Appendix I, post, p. 411 U. S. 134 .
And, as the District Court observed, it does not follow that
remedial action by the Federal Government would excuse any
unconstitutional discrimination effected by the state financing
scheme. 337 F.
Supp. 280 , 284.
[ Footnote 4/16 ]
For the 1970-1971 school year, the precise figure was 48%. See Texas Research League, supra, 411 U.S.
1 fn4/2|>n. 2, at 9.
[ Footnote 4/17 ] See Tex.Const., Art. 7, § 5 (Supp. 1972). See
also Tex.Educ.Code Ann. § 15.01(b).
[ Footnote 4/18 ] See Tex.Educ.Code Ann. § 15.01(b).
The Permanent School Fund is, in essence, a public trust
initially endowed with vast quantities of public land, the sale of
which has provided an enormous corpus that, in turn, produces
substantial annual revenues which are devoted exclusively to public
education. See Tex.Const., Art. 7, § 5 (Supp. 1972). See also 5 Report of Governor's Committee on Public School
Education, The Challenge and the Chance 11 (1969) (hereinafter
Governor's Committee Report).
[ Footnote 4/19 ]
This is determined from the average daily attendance within each
district for the preceding year. Tex.Educ.Code Ann. § 15.01(c).
[ Footnote 4/20 ] See id. §§ 16.01-16.975.
[ Footnote 4/21 ] See id. §§ 16.71(2), 16.79.
[ Footnote 4/22 ] See id. §§ 16.301-16.316, 16.45, 16.51-16.63.
[ Footnote 4/23 ] See id., §§ 16.72-16.73, 16.76-16.77.
[ Footnote 4/24 ] See id. §§ 16.74-16.76. The formula for calculating
each district's share is described in 5 Governor's Committee Report
448.
[ Footnote 4/25 ] See Tex.Educ.Code Ann. § 16.01.
[ Footnote 4/26 ] See 5 Governor's Committee Report 401.
[ Footnote 4/27 ] See id. at 45 67; Texas Research League, Texas Public
Schools Under the Minimum Foundation Program -- An Evaluation:
1949-1954, pp.67-68 (1954).
[ Footnote 4/28 ]
Technically, the economic index involves a two-step calculation.
First, on the basis of the factors mentioned above, each Texas
county's share of the Local Fund Assignment is determined. Then
each county's share is divided among its school districts on the
basis of their relative shares of the county's assessable wealth. See Tex.Educ.Code Ann. §§ 16.74-16.76; 5 Governor's
Committee Report 43-44; Texas Research League, Texas Public School
Finance: A Majority of Exceptions 6-8 (2d Interim Report 1972).
[ Footnote 4/29 ]
5 Governor's Committee Report 48, quoting statement of Dr. Edgar
Morphet.
[ Footnote 4/30 ]
The extraordinarily complex standards are summarized in 5
Governor's Committee Report 41-43.
[ Footnote 4/31 ]
The key element of the Minimum Foundation School Program is the
provision of funds for professional salaries -- more particularly,
for teacher salaries. The Program provides each district with funds
to pay its professional payroll as determined by certain state
standards. See Tex.Educ.Code Ann. §§ 16.301-16.316. If the
district fails to pay its teachers at the levels determined by the
state standards, it receives nothing from the Program. See
id. § 16.301(c). At the same time, districts are free to pay
their teachers salaries in excess of the level set by the state
standards, using local revenues -- that is, property tax revenue --
to make up the difference, see id. § 16.301(a).
The state salary standards focus upon two factors: the
educational level and the experience of the district's teachers. See id. §§ 16.30116.316. The higher these two factors are,
the more funds the district will receive from the Foundation
Program for professional salaries.
It should be apparent that the net effect of this scheme is to
provide more assistance to property-rich districts than to
property-poor ones. For rich districts are able to pay their
teachers, out of local funds, salary increments above the state
minimum levels. Thus, the rich districts are able to attract the
teachers with the best education and the most experience. To
complete the circle, this then means, given the state standards,
that the rich districts receive more from the Foundation Program
for professional salaries than do poor districts. A portion of
Professor Berke's study vividly illustrates the impact of the
State's standards on districts of varying wealth. See Appendix III, post, p. 411 U. S.
136 .
[ Footnote 4/32 ]
In 1967-1968, Alamo Heights School District had $49,478 in
taxable property per pupil. See Berke Affidavit, Table
VII, App. 216.
[ Footnote 4/33 ]
In 1967-1968, Edgewood Independent School District had $5,960 in
taxable property per pupil. Ibid. [ Footnote 4/34 ]
I fail to understand the relevance for this case of the Court's
suggestion that, if Alamo Heights School District, which is
approximately the same physical size as Edgewood Independent School
District but which has only one-fourth as many students, had the
same number of students as Edgewood, the former's per-pupil
expenditure would be considerably closer to the latter's. Ante at 411 U. S. 13 n.
33. Obviously this is true, but it does not alter the simple fact
that Edgewood does have four times as many students but
not four times as much taxable property wealth. From the
perspective of Edgewood's school children then -- the perspective
that ultimately counts here -- Edgewood is clearly a much poorer
district than Alamo Heights. The question here is not whether
districts have equal taxable property wealth in absolute terms, but
whether districts have differing taxable wealth given their
respective school-age populations.
[ Footnote 4/35 ]
In the face of these gross disparities in treatment which
experience with the Texas financing scheme has revealed, I cannot
accept the Court's suggestion that we are dealing here with a
remedial scheme to which we should accord substantial deference
because of its accomplishments, rather than criticize it for its
failures. Ante at 411 U. S. 38 -39. Moreover, Texas' financing scheme is
hardly remedial legislation of the type for which we have
previously shown substantial tolerance. Such legislation may in
fact, extend the vote to "persons who otherwise would be denied it
by state law," Katzenbach v. Morgan, 384 U.
S. 641 , 384 U. S. 657 (1966), or it may eliminate the evils of the private bail bondsman, Schilb v. Kuebel, 404 U. S. 357 (1971). But those are instances in which a legislative body has
sought to remedy problems for which it cannot be said to have been
directly responsible. By contrast, public education is the function
of the State in Texas, and the responsibility for any defect in the
financing scheme must ultimately rest with the State. It is the
State's own scheme which has caused the funding problem, and, thus
viewed, that scheme can hardly be deemed remedial.
[ Footnote 4/36 ] Cf. Appendix I, post, p. 411 U. S.
134 .
[ Footnote 4/37 ]
Brief for Appellants 3.
[ Footnote 4/38 ]
Thus, in 1967-1968, Edgewood had a total of $248 per pupil in
state and local funds, compared with a total of $558 per pupil for
Alamo Heights. See Berke Affidavit, Table X, App. 219. For
1970-1971, the respective totals were $418 and $913. See Texas Research League, supra, 411 U.S.
1 fn4/2|>n. 2, at 14.
[ Footnote 4/39 ]
Not only does the local property tax provide approximately 40%
of the funds expended on public education, but it is the only source of funds for such essential aspects of
educational financing as the payment of school bonds, see 411 U.S.
1 fn4/3|>n. 3, supra, and the payment of the
district's share of the Local Fund Assignment, as well as for
nearly all expenditures above the minimums established by the
Foundation School Program.
[ Footnote 4/40 ] Compare, e.g., J. Coleman et al., Equality of
Educational Opportunity 290-330 (1966); Jencks, The Coleman Report
and the Conventional Wisdom, in On Equality of Educational
Opportunity 69, 91-104 (F. Mosteller & D. Moynihan eds.1972), with, e.g., J. Guthrie, G. Kleindorfer, H. Levin, & R.
Stout, Schools and Inequality 79-90 (1971); Kiesling, Measuring a
Local Government Service: A Study of School Districts in New York
State, 49 Rev.Econ. & Statistics 356 (1967).
[ Footnote 4/41 ] Compare Berke Answers to Interrogatories 10 ("Dollar
expenditures are probably the best way of measuring the quality of
education afforded students . . ."), with Graham
Deposition 39 ("[I]t is not just necessarily the money, no. It is
how wisely you spend it"). It warrants noting that even appellants'
witness, Mr. Graham, qualified the importance of money only by the
requirement of wise expenditure. Quite obviously, a district which
is property poor is powerless to match the education provided by a
property-rich district, assuming each district allocates its funds
with equal wisdom.
[ Footnote 4/42 ] See Brief of amici curiae, inter alia, San
Marino Unified School District; Beverly Hills Unified School
District; Brief of amici curiae, inter alia, Bloomfield
Hills, Michigan, School District; Dearborn City, Michigan, School
District; Grosse Pointe, Michigan, Public School System.
[ Footnote 4/43 ]
Answers to Plaintiffs' Interrogatories, App. 115.
[ Footnote 4/44 ] Ibid. Moreover, during the same period, 37.17% of the
teachers in Alamo Heights had advanced degrees, while only 14.98%
of Edgewood's faculty had such degrees. See id. at
116.
[ Footnote 4/45 ] Id. at 117.
[ Footnote 4/46 ] Id. at 118.
[ Footnote 4/47 ]
In the 1967-1968 school year, Edgewood had 22,862 students and
864 teachers, a ratio of 26.5 to 1. See id. at 110, 114.
In Alamo Heights, for the same school year, there were 5,432
students and 265 teachers, for a ratio of 20.5 to 1. Ibid. [ Footnote 4/48 ]
Reply Brief for Appellant 17. See also id. at 5,
15-16.
[ Footnote 4/49 ]
Indeed, even apart from the differential treatment inherent in
the local property tax, the significant inter-district disparities
in state aid received under the Minimum Foundation School Program
would seem to raise substantial equal protection questions.
[ Footnote 4/50 ]
I find particularly strong intimations of such a view in the
majority's efforts to denigrate the constitutional significance of
children in property-poor districts "receiving a poorer quality
education than that available to children in districts having more
assessable wealth" with the assertion "that, at least where wealth
is involved, the Equal Protection Clause does not require absolute
equality or precisely equal advantages." Ante at 411 U. S. 23 , 411 U. S. 24 . The
Court, to be sure, restricts its remark to "wealth" discrimination.
But the logical basis for such a restriction is not explained by
the Court, nor is it otherwise apparent, see infra at 411 U. S.
117 -120 and n. 77.
[ Footnote 4/51 ] See Answers to Interrogatories by Dr. Joel S. Berke,
Ans. 17, p. 9; Ans. 48-51, pp. 22-24; Ans. 88-89, pp. 41-42;
Deposition of Dr. Daniel C. Morgan, Jr., at 52-55; Affidavit of Dr.
Daniel C. Morgan, Jr., App. 242-243.
[ Footnote 4/52 ]
It is true that, in two previous cases, this Court has summarily
affirmed district court dismissals of constitutional attacks upon
other state educational financing schemes. See McInnis v.
Shapiro, 293 F.
Supp. 327 (ND Ill.1968), aff'd per curiam sub nom. McInnis
v. Ogilvie, 394 U. S. 322 (1969); Burruss v. Wilkerson, 310 F.
Supp. 572 (WD Va.1969), aff'd per curiam, 397 U. S.
44 (1970). But those decisions cannot be considered
dispositive of this action, for the thrust of those suits differed
materially from that of the present case. In McInnis, the
plaintiffs asserted that
"only a financing system which apportions public funds according
to the educational needs of the students satisfies the Fourteenth
Amendment."
293 F. Supp. at 331. The District Court concluded that
"(1) the Fourteenth Amendment does not require that public
school expenditures be made only on the basis of pupils'
educational needs, and (2) the lack of judicially manageable
standards makes this controversy nonjusticiable." Id. at 329. The Burruss District Court
dismissed that suit essentially in reliance on McInnis, which it found to be "scarcely distinguishable." 310 F. Supp. at
574. This suit involves no effort to obtain an allocation of school
funds that considers only educational need. The District Court
ruled only that the State must remedy the discrimination resulting
from the distribution of taxable local district wealth which has
heretofore prevented many districts from truly exercising local
fiscal control. Furthermore, the limited holding of the District
Court presents none of the problems of judicial management which
would exist if the federal courts were to attempt to ensure the
distribution of educational funds solely on the basis of
educational need, see infra at 411 U. S.
130 -132.
[ Footnote 4/53 ]
Tex.Const., Art. 7, § 1.
[ Footnote 4/54 ]
Problems of remedy may be another matter. If provision of the
relief sought in a particular case required identification of each
member of the affected class, as in the case of monetary relief,
the need for clarity in defining the class is apparent. But this
involves the procedural problems inherent in class action
litigation, not the character of the elements essential to equal
protection analysis. We are concerned here only with the latter.
Moreover, it is evident that, in cases such as this, provision of
appropriate relief, which takes the injunctive form, is not a
serious problem, since it is enough to direct the action of
appropriate officials. Cf. Potts v. Flax, 313 F.2d 284,
288-290 (CA5 1963).
[ Footnote 4/55 ]
I assume the Court would lodge the same criticism against the
validity of the finding of a correlation between poor districts and
racial minorities.
[ Footnote 4/56 ]
The Court rejects the District Court's finding of a correlation
between poor people and poor districts with the assertion that
"there is reason to believe that the poorest families are not
necessarily clustered in the poorest property districts" in Texas. Ante at 411 U. S. 23 . In
support of its conclusion, the Court offers absolutely no data --
which it cannot on this record -- concerning the distribution of
poor people in Texas to refute the data introduced below by
appellees; it relies instead on a recent law review note concerned
solely with the State of Connecticut, Note, A Statistical Analysis
of the School Finance Decisions: On Winning Battles and Losing
Wars, 81 Yale L.J. 1303 (1972). Common sense suggests that the
basis for drawing a demographic conclusion with respect to a
geographically large, urban-rural, industrial-agricultural State
such as Texas from a geographically small, densely populated,
highly industrialized State such as Connecticut is doubtful, at
best.
Furthermore, the article upon which the Court relies to
discredit the statistical procedures employed by Professor Berke to
establish the correlation between poor people and poor districts, see 411 U.S.
1 fn4/11|>n. 11, supra, based its criticism
primarily on the fact that only four of the 110 districts studied
were in the lowest of the five categories, which were determined by
relative taxable property per pupil, and most districts clustered
in the middle three groups. See Goldstein, Inter-district
Inequalities in School Financing: A Critical Analysis of Serrano v. Priest and its Progeny, 120 U.Pa.L.Rev. 504,
524 n. 67 (1972). See also ante at 411 U. S. 26 -27.
But the Court fails to note that the four poorest districts in the
sample had over 50,000 students, which constituted 10% of the
students in the entire sample. It appears, moreover, that even when
the richest and the poorest categories are enlarged to include in
each category 20% of the students in the sample, the correlation
between district and individual wealth holds true. See Brief for the Governors of Minnesota, Maine, South Dakota,
Wisconsin, and Michigan as amici curiae 17 n. 21.
Finally, it cannot be ignored that the data introduced by
appellees went unchallenged in the District Court. The majority's
willingness to permit appellants to litigate the correctness of
those data for the first time before this tribunal -- where
effective response by appellees is impossible -- is both unfair and
judicially unsound.
[ Footnote 4/57 ]
Third Amended Complaint App. 23. Consistent with this theory,
appellees purported to represent, among others, a class composed
of
"all . . . school children in independent school districts . . .
who . . . have been deprived of the equal protection of the law
under the Fourteenth Amendment with regard to public school
education because of the low value of the property lying within the
independent school districts in which they reside." Id. at 15.
[ Footnote 4/58 ]
The degree of judicial scrutiny that this particular
classification demands is a distinct issue which I consider in 411 U. S. infra. [ Footnote 4/59 ]
Indeed, the Court's theory would render the established concept
of fundamental interests in the context of equal protection
analysis superfluous, for the substantive constitutional right
itself requires that this Court strictly scrutinize any asserted
state interest for restricting or denying access to any particular
guaranteed right, see, e.g., United States v. O'Brien, 391 U. S. 367 , 391 U. S. 377 (1968); Cox v. Louisiana, 379 U.
S. 536 , 379 U. S.
545 -551 (1965).
[ Footnote 4/60 ]
It is interesting that, in its effort to reconcile the state
voting rights cases with its theory of fundamentality, the majority
can muster nothing more than the contention that "[t]he
constitutional underpinnings of the right to equal treatment in
the voting process can no longer be doubted. . . ." Ante at 411 U. S. 34 n.
74 (emphasis added). If, by this, the Court intends to recognize a
substantive constitutional "right to equal treatment in the voting
process" independent of the Equal Protection Clause, the source of
such a right is certainly a mystery to me.
[ Footnote 4/61 ]
It is true that Griffin and Douglas also
involved discrimination against indigents, that is, wealth
discrimination. But, as the majority points out, ante at 411 U. S. 28 -29,
the Court has never deemed wealth discrimination alone to be
sufficient to require strict judicial scrutiny; rather, such review
of wealth classifications has been applied only where the
discrimination affects an important individual interest, see,
e.g., Harper v. Virginia Bd. of Elections, 383 U.
S. 663 (1966). Thus, I believe Griffin and Douglas can only be understood as premised on a
recognition of the fundamental importance of the criminal appellate
process.
[ Footnote 4/62 ] See, e.g., Duncan v. Louisiana, 391 U.
S. 145 (1968) (right to jury trial); Washington v.
Texas, 388 U. S. 14 (1967)
(right to compulsory process); Pointer v. Texas, 380 U. S. 400 (1965) (right to confront one's accusers).
[ Footnote 4/63 ] See, e.g., McLaughlin v. Florida, 379 U.
S. 184 , 379 U. S.
191 -192 (1964); Loving v. Virginia, 388 U. S. 1 , 388 U. S. 9 (1967).
[ Footnote 4/64 ] See Oyama v. California, 332 U.
S. 633 , 332 U. S.
644 -646 (1948); Korematsu v. United States, 323 U. S. 214 , 323 U. S. 216 (1944).
[ Footnote 4/65 ] See Graham v. Richardson, 403 U.
S. 365 , 403 U. S. 372 (1971).
[ Footnote 4/66 ]
The Court noted that the challenged
"provision strips from indigent defendants the array of
protective exemptions Kansas has erected for other civil judgment
debtors, including restrictions on the amount of disposable
earnings subject to garnishment, protection of the debtor from wage
garnishment at times of severe personal or family sickness, and
exemption from attachment and execution on a debtor's personal
clothing, books, and tools of trade."
407 U.S. at 407 U. S.
135 .
[ Footnote 4/67 ] See generally Gunther, The Supreme Court, 1971 Term,
Foreword: In Search of Evolving Doctrine on a Changing Court: A
Model for a Newer Equal Protection, 86 Harv.L.Rev. 1 (1972).
[ Footnote 4/68 ] See Brief of the National Education Association et
al. as Amici Curiae App. A. All 48 of the 50 States
which mandate public education also have compulsory attendance laws
which require school attendance for eight years or more. Id. at 20-21.
[ Footnote 4/69 ]
Prior to this Court's decision in Brown v. Board of
Education, 347 U. S. 483 (1954), every State had a constitutional provision directing the
establishment of a system of public schools. But after Brown, South Carolina repealed its constitutional
provision, and Mississippi made its constitutional provision
discretionary with the state legislature.
[ Footnote 4/70 ]
Developments in the Law -- Equal Protection, 82 Harv.L.Rev.
1065, 1129 (1969).
[ Footnote 4/71 ]
The President's Commission on School Finance, Schools, People,
& Money: The Need for Educational Reform 11 (1972), concluded
that "[l]iterally, we cannot survive as a nation or as individuals
without [education]." It further observed that:
"[I]n a democratic society, public understanding of public
issues is necessary for public support. Schools generally include
in their courses of instruction a wide variety of subjects related
to the history, structure and principles of American government at
all levels. In so doing, schools provide students with a background
of knowledge which is deemed an absolute necessity for responsible
citizenship." Id. at 13-14.
[ Footnote 4/72 ] See J. Guthrie, G. Kleindorfer, H. Levin, & R.
Stout, Schools and Inequality 103-105 (1971); R. Hess & J.
Torney, The Development of Political Attitudes in Children 217-218
(1967); Campbell, The Passive Citizen, in 6 Acta Sociologica, Nos.
1-2, p. 9, at 20-21 (1962).
That education is the dominant factor in influencing political
participation and awareness is sufficient, I believe, to dispose of
the Court's suggestion that, in all events, there is no indication
that Texas is not providing all of its children with a sufficient
education to enjoy the right of free speech and to participate
fully in the political process. Ante at 411 U. S. 36 -37.
There is, in short, no limit on the amount of free speech or
political participation that the Constitution guarantees. Moreover,
it should be obvious that the political process, like most other
aspects of social intercourse, is to some degree competitive. It is
thus of little benefit to an individual from a property-poor
district to have "enough" education if those around him have more
than "enough." Cf. Sweatt v. Painter, 339 U.
S. 629 , 339 U. S.
633 -634 (1950).
[ Footnote 4/73 ] See United States Department of Commerce, Bureau of the
Census, Voting and Registration in the Election of November 1968,
Current Population Reports, Series P-20, No.192, Table 4, p. 17. See also Senate Select Committee on Equal Educational
Opportunity, 92d Cong., 2d Sess., Levin, The Costs to the Nation of
Inadequate Education 46-47 (Comm.Print 1972).
[ Footnote 4/74 ]
I believe that the close nexus between education and our
established constitutional values with respect to freedom of speech
and participation in the political process makes this a different
case from our prior decisions concerning discrimination affecting
public welfare, see, e.g., Dandridge v. Williams, 397 U. S. 471 (1970), or housing, see, e.g., Lindsey v. Normet, 405 U. S. 56 (1972). There can be no question that, as the majority suggests,
constitutional rights may be less meaningful for someone without
enough to eat or without decent housing. Ante at 411 U. S. 37 . But
the crucial difference lies in the closeness of the relationship.
Whatever the severity of the impact of insufficient food or
inadequate housing on a person's life, they have never been
considered to bear the same direct and immediate relationship to
constitutional concerns for free speech and for our political
processes as education has long been recognized to bear. Perhaps
the best evidence of this fact is the unique status which has been
accorded public education as the single public service nearly
unanimously guaranteed in the constitutions of our States, see
supra at 411 U. S.
111 -112 and n. 68. Education, in terms of constitutional
values, is much more analogous, in my judgment, to the right to
vote in state elections than to public welfare or public housing.
Indeed, it is not without significance that we have long recognized
education as an essential step in providing the disadvantaged with
the tools necessary to achieve economic self-sufficiency.
[ Footnote 4/75 ]
The majority's reliance on this Court's traditional deference to
legislative bodies in matters of taxation falls wide of the mark in
the context of this particular case. See ante at 411 U. S. 40 -41.
The decisions on which the Court relies were simply taxpayer suits
challenging the constitutionality of a tax burden in the face of
exemptions or differential taxation afforded to others. See,
e.g., Allied Stores of Ohio v. Bowers, 358 U.
S. 522 (1959), Madden v. Kentucky, 309 U. S.
83 (1940); Carmichael v. Southern Coal & Coke
Co., 301 U. S. 495 (1937); Bell's Gap R. Co. v. Pennsylvania, 134 U.
S. 232 (1890). There is no question that, from the
perspective of the taxpayer, the Equal Protection Clause
"imposes no iron rule of equality, prohibiting the flexibility
and variety that are appropriate to reasonable schemes of state
taxation. The State may impose different specific taxes upon
different trades and professions, and may vary the rate of excise
upon various products." Allied Stores of Ohio v. Bowers, supra, at 358 U. S.
526 -527. But, in this case, we are presented with a
claim of discrimination of an entirely different nature -- a claim
that the revenue-producing mechanism directly discriminates against
the interests of some of the intended beneficiaries; and, in
contrast to the taxpayer suits, the interest adversely affected is
of substantial constitutional and societal importance. Hence, a
different standard of equal protection review than has been
employed in the taxpayer suits is appropriate here. It is true that
affirmance of the District Court decision would to some extent
intrude upon the State's taxing power insofar as it would be
necessary for the State to at least equalize taxable district
wealth. But, contrary to the suggestions of the majority,
affirmance would not impose a strait-jacket upon the
revenue-raising powers of the State, and would certainly not spell
the end of the local property tax. See infra at 411 U. S.
132 .
[ Footnote 4/76 ]
This does not mean that the Court has demanded precise equality
in the treatment of the indigent and the person of means in the
criminal process. We have never suggested, for instance, that the
Equal Protection Clause requires the best lawyer money can buy for
the indigent. We are hardly equipped with the objective standards
which such a judgment would require. But we have pursued the goal
of substantial equality of treatment in the face of clear
disparities in the nature of the appellate process afforded rich
versus poor. See, e.g., Draper v. Washington, 372 U.
S. 487 , 372 U. S.
495 -496 (1963); cf. Coppedge v. United States, 369 U. S. 438 , 369 U. S. 447 (1962).
[ Footnote 4/77 ]
Even if I put aside the Court's misreading of Griffin and Douglas, the Court fails to offer any reasoned
constitutional basis for restricting cases involving wealth
discrimination to instances in which there is an absolute
deprivation of the interest affected. As I have already discussed, see supra at 411 U. S. 88 -89,
the Equal Protection Clause guarantees equality of treatment of
those persons who are similarly situated; it does not merely bar
some form of excessive discrimination between such persons. Outside
the context of wealth discrimination, the Court's reapportionment
decisions clearly indicate that relative discrimination is within
the purview of the Equal Protection Clause. Thus, in Reynolds
v. Sims, 377 U. S. 533 , 377 U. S.
562 -563 (1964), the Court recognized:
"It would appear extraordinary to suggest that a State could be
constitutionally permitted to enact a law providing that certain of
the State's voters could vote two, five, or 10 times for their
legislative representatives, while voters living elsewhere could
vote only once. . . . Of course, the effect of state legislative
districting schemes which give the same number of representatives
to unequal numbers of constituents is identical. Overweighting and
over-valuation of the votes of those living here has the certain
effect of dilution and undervaluation of the votes of those living
there. . . . Their right to vote is simply not the same right to
vote as that of those living in a favored part of the State. . . .
One must be ever aware that the Constitution forbids 'sophisticated
as well as simple-minded modes of discrimination.'" See also Gray v. Sanders, 372 U.
S. 368 , 372 U. S.
380 -381 (1963). The Court gives no explanation why a
case involving wealth discrimination should be treated any
differently.
[ Footnote 4/78 ] But cf. Bullock v. Carter, 405 U.
S. 134 , 405 U. S. 144 (1972), where prospective candidates' threatened exclusion from a
primary ballot because of their inability to pay a filing fee was
seen as discrimination against both the impecunious candidates and
the "less affluent segment of the community" that supported such
candidates but was also too poor as a group to contribute enough
for the filing fees.
[ Footnote 4/79 ] But cf. M. Harrington, The Other America 13-17 (Penguin
ed.1963).
[ Footnote 4/80 ] See E. Banfield, The Unheavenly City 63, 75-76 (1970); cf. R. Lynd & H. Lynd, Middletown in Transition 450
(1937).
[ Footnote 4/81 ] Cf. New York v.
Miln , 11 Pet. 102, 36 U. S. 142 (1837).
[ Footnote 4/82 ]
Theoretically, at least, it may provide a mechanism for
implementing Texas' asserted interest in local educational control, see infra at 411 U. S.
126 .
[ Footnote 4/83 ]
True, a family may move to escape a property-poor school
district, assuming it has the means to do so. But such a view would
itself raise a serious constitutional question concerning an
impermissible burdening of the right to travel, or, more precisely,
the concomitant right to remain where one is. Cf. Shapiro v.
Thompson, 394 U. S. 618 , 394 U. S.
629 -631 (1969).
[ Footnote 4/84 ]
Indeed, the political difficulties that seriously disadvantaged
districts face in securing legislative redress are augmented by the
fact that little support is likely to be secured from only mildly
disadvantaged districts. Cf. Gray v. Sanders, 372 U.
S. 368 (1963). See also 411 U.S.
1 fn4/2|>n. 2, supra. [ Footnote 4/85 ] See Tex.Cities, Towns and Villages Code, Civ.Stat.Ann.
§§ 1011a-1011j (1963 and Supp. 1972-1973). See also, e.g.,
Skinner v. Reed, 265 S.W.2d 850 (Tex.Ct.Civ.App. 1954); Corpus Christi v. Jones, 144 S.W.2d 388 (Tex.Ct. Civ.App.
1940).
[ Footnote 4/86 ] Serrano v. Priest, 5 Cal. 3d at 603, 487 P.2d at 1254. See also Van Dusartz v. Hatfield, 334 F. Supp. at
875-876.
[ Footnote 4/87 ] Cf., e.g., Two Guys from Harrison-Allentown v.
McGinley, 366 U. S. 582 (1961); McGowan v. Maryland, 366 U.
S. 420 (1961); Goesaert v. Cleary, 335 U.
S. 464 (1948).
[ Footnote 4/88 ]
Tex.Educ.Code Ann. §§ 21.101-21.117. Criminal penalties are
provided for failure to teach certain required courses. Id. §§ 4.15-4.16.
[ Footnote 4/89 ] Id., §§ 12.11-12.35.
[ Footnote 4/90 ] Id., § 12.62.
[ Footnote 4/91 ] Id., §§ 13 031-13.046
[ Footnote 4/92 ] Id., § 21.004.
[ Footnote 4/93 ] See 411 U.S.
1 app1|>Appendix II, infra. [ Footnote 4/94 ] See Affidavit of Dr. Joe Cardenas, Superintendent of
School, Edgewood Independent School District, App. 234-238.
[ Footnote 4/95 ] See 411 U.S.
1 app4|>Appendix IV, infra. [ Footnote 4/96 ]
My Brother WHITE, in concluding that the Texas financing scheme
runs afoul of the Equal Protection Clause, likewise finds on
analysis that the means chosen by Texas -- local property taxation
dependent upon local taxable wealth -- is completely unsuited in
its present form to the achievement of the asserted goal of
providing local fiscal control. Although my Brother WHITE purports
to reach this result by application of that lenient standard of
mere rationality traditionally applied in the context of commercial
interests, it seems to me that the care with which he scrutinizes
the practical effectiveness of the present local property tax as a
device for affording local fiscal control reflects the application
of a more stringent standard of review, a standard which at the
least is influenced by the constitutional significance of the
process of public education.
[ Footnote 4/97 ] See 411 U.S.
1 fn4/98|>n. 98, infra. [ Footnote 4/98 ]
Centralized educational financing is, to be sure, one
alternative. On analysis, though, it is clear that even centralized
financing would not deprive local school districts of what has been
considered to be the essence of local educational control. See
Wright v. Council of the City of Emporia, 407 U.
S. 451 , 407 U. S.
477 -478 (BURGER, C.J., dissenting). Central financing
would leave in local hands the entire gamut of local educational
policymaking -- teachers, curriculum, school sites, the whole
process of allocating resources among alternative educational
objectives.
A second possibility is the much-discussed theory of district
power equalization put forth by Professors Coons, Clune, and
Sugarman in their seminal work, Private Wealth and Public Education
201-242 (1970). Such a scheme would truly reflect a dedication to
local fiscal control. Under their system, each school district
would receive a fixed amount of revenue per pupil for any
particular level of tax effort regardless of the level of local
property tax base. Appellants criticize this scheme on the rather
extraordinary ground that it would encourage poorer districts to
overtax themselves in order to obtain substantial revenues for
education. But, under the present discriminatory scheme, it is the
poor districts that are already taxing themselves at the highest
rates, yet are receiving the lowest returns.
District wealth reapportionment is yet another alternative which
would accomplish directly essentially what district power
equalization would seek to do artificially. Appellants claim that
the calculations concerning state property required by such a
scheme would be impossible, as a practical matter. Yet Texas is
already making far more complex annual calculations -- involving
not only local property values, but also local income and other
economic factors -- in conjunction with the Local Fund Assignment
portion of the Minimum Foundation School Program. See 5
Governor's Committee Report 43-44.
A fourth possibility would be to remove commercial, industrial,
and mineral property from local tax rolls, to tax this property on
a state-wide basis, and to return the resulting revenues to the
local districts in a fashion that would compensate for remaining
variations in the local tax bases.
None of these particular alternatives is necessarily
constitutionally compelled; rather, they indicate the breadth of
choice which would remain to the State if the present
inter-district disparities were eliminated.
[ Footnote 4/99 ] See 411 U. S. 98, supra. [ Footnote 4/100 ]
Of course, nothing in the Court's decision today should inhibit
further review of state educational funding schemes under state
constitutional provisions. See Milliken v. Green, 389
Mich. 1, 203 N.W.2d
457 (1972), rehearing granted, Jan.1973; Robinson
v. Cahill, 118 N.J.Super. 223, 287 A.2d 187 , 119 N.J.Super. 40, 289 A.2d 569 (1972); cf. Serrano v.
Priest, 5 Cal. 3d 584 ,
487 P.2d 1241 (1971). | Here is a summary of the U.S. Supreme Court case San Antonio Independent School District v. Rodriguez (1973):
Issue:
The case examined whether the Texas system of financing public schools, which relied on local property taxation, violated the Equal Protection Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment due to disparities in per-pupil expenditures among school districts.
Holding:
The Supreme Court held that the Texas school financing system did not violate equal protection requirements. The Court found that the system did not disadvantage any suspect class or interfere with the exercise of a fundamental right. While education is important, it is not a fundamental right explicitly or implicitly protected by the Constitution. The Court also noted that the state has a broad choice of options to address inter-district disparities in school funding.
Key Points:
- The Texas system of school financing was a combination of state and local funding, with local funding derived from property taxes.
- Appellees argued that this system favored affluent districts and disadvantaged poor families in districts with a low property tax base.
- The Court rejected the argument that wealth is a suspect classification and that education is a fundamental right.
- The Court emphasized that local control over educational policymaking, including resource allocation, curriculum, and teachers, would remain intact even with centralized financing.
- Several alternatives to the current system were suggested, including district power equalization, district wealth reapportionment, and state-wide taxation of commercial and industrial property.
- The Court encouraged further review of state educational funding schemes under state constitutional provisions. |
Equal Protection | U.S. Dept. of Agriculture v. Moreno | https://supreme.justia.com/cases/federal/us/413/528/ | U.S. Supreme Court United States Dept. of Agriculture v.
Moreno, 413
U.S. 528 (1973) United States Department of
Agriculture v. Moreno No. 72-534 Argued April 23, 1973 Decided June 25, 1973 413
U.S. 528 APPEAL FROM THE UNITED STATES
DISTRICT COURT FOR THE DISTRICT OF
COLUMBIA Syllabus Section 3(e) of the Food Stamp Act of 1964, as amended in 1971,
generally excludes from participation in the food stamp program any
household containing an individual who is unrelated to any other
household member. The Secretary of Agriculture issued regulations
thereunder rendering ineligible for participation in the program
any "household" whose members are not "all related to each other."
Congress stated that the purposes of the Act were
"to safeguard the health and wellbeing of the Nation's
population and raise levels of nutrition among low income
households . . . [and] that increased utilization of food in
establishing and maintaining adequate national levels of nutrition
will promote the distribution . . . of our agricultural abundance
and will strengthen cur agricultural economy. . . ."
The District Court held that the "unrelated person" provision of
§ 3(e) creates an irrational classification in violation of the
equal protection component of the Due Process Clause of the Fifth
Amendment. Held: The legislative classification here involved
cannot be sustained, the classification being clearly irrelevant to
the stated purposes of the Act and not rationally furthering any
other legitimate governmental interest. In practical operation, the
Act excludes not those who are "likely to abuse the program," but,
rather, only those who so desperately need aid that they cannot
even afford to alter their living arrangements so as to retain
their eligibility. Pp. 533-538. 345 F.
Supp. 310 , affirmed.
BRENNAN, J., delivered the opinion of the Court, in which
DOUGLAS, STEWART, WHITE, MARSHALL, BLACKMUN, and POWELL, JJ.,
joined. DOUGLAS J., filed a concurring opinion, post, p. 413 U. S. 538 .
REHNQUIST, J., filed a dissenting opinion, in which BURGER, C.J.,
joined, post, p. 413 U. S.
545 . Page 413 U. S. 529 MR. JUSTICE BRENNAN delivered the opinion of the Court.
This case requires us to consider the constitutionality of §
3(e) of the Food Stamp Act of 1964, 7 U.S.C. § 2012(e), as amended
in 1971, 84 Stat. 2048, which, with certain exceptions, excludes
from participation in the food stamp program any household
containing an individual who is unrelated to any other member of
the household. In practical effect, § 3(e) creates two classes of
persons for food stamp purposes: one class is composed of those
individuals who live in households all of whose members are related
to one another, and the other class consists of those individuals
who live in households containing one or more members who are
unrelated to the rest. The latter class of persons is denied
federal food assistance. A three-judge District Court for the
District of Columbia held this classification invalid as violative
of the Due Process Clause of the Fifth Amendment. 345 F.
Supp. 310 (1972). We noted probable jurisdiction. 409 U.S. 1036
(1972). We affirm. I The federal food stamp program was established in 1964 in an
effort to alleviate hunger and malnutrition among the more needy
segments of our society. 7 U.S.C. § 2011. Eligibility for
participation in the program is determined on a household, rather
than an individual basis. 7 CFR § 271.3(a). An eligible household
purchases sufficient food stamps to provide that household with a
nutritionally adequate diet. The household pays for the stamps at a
reduced rate based Page 413 U. S. 530 upon its size and cumulative income. The food stamps are then
used to purchase food at retail stores, and the Government redeems
the stamps at face value, thereby paying the difference between the
actual cost of the food and the amount paid by the household for
the stamps. See 7 U.S.C. §§ 2013(a), 2016, 2025(a).
As initially enacted, § 3(e) defined a "household" as
"a group of related or non-related individuals, who are
not residents of an institution or boarding house, but are living
as one economic unit sharing common cooking facilities and for whom
food is customarily purchased in common. [ Footnote 1 ]"
In January, 1971, however, Congress redefined the term
"household" so as to include only groups of related individuals. [ Footnote 2 ]
Pursuant to this amendment, the Secretary of Agriculture
promulgated regulations rendering ineligible for participation in
the program any "household" whose members are not "all related to
each other." [ Footnote 3 ] Page 413 U. S. 531 Appellees in this case consist of several groups of individuals
who allege that, although they satisfy the income eligibility
requirements for federal food assistance, they have nevertheless
been excluded from the program solely because the persons in each
group are not "all related to each other." Appellee Jacinta Moreno,
for example, is a 56-year-old diabetic who lives with Ermina
Sanchez and the latter's three children. They share common living
expenses, and Mrs. Sanchez helps to care for appellee. Appellee's
monthly income, derived from public assistance, is $75; Mrs.
Sanchez receives $133 per month from public assistance. The
household pays $135 per month for rent, gas, and electricity, of
which appellee pays $50. Appellee spends $10 per month for
transportation to a hospital for regular visits, and $5 per month
for laundry. That leaves her $10 per month for food and other
necessities. Despite her poverty, appellee has been denied federal
food assistance solely because she is unrelated to the other
members of her household. Moreover, although Mrs. Sanchez and her
three children were permitted to purchase $108 worth of food stamps
per month for $18, their participation in the program will be Page 413 U. S. 532 terminated if appellee Moreno continues to live with them.
Appellee Sheilah Hejny is married and has three children.
Although the Hejnys are indigent, they took in a 20-year-old girl,
who is unrelated to them, because "we felt she had emotional
problems." The Hejnys receive $144 worth of food stamps each month
for $14. If they allow the 20-year-old girl to continue to live
with them, they will be denied food stamps by reason of § 3(e).
Appellee Victoria Keppler has a daughter with an acute hearing
deficiency. The daughter requires special instruction in a school
for the deaf. The school is located in an area in which appellee
could not ordinarily afford to live. Thus, in order to make the
most of her limited resources, appellee agreed to share an
apartment near the school with a woman who, like appellee, is on
public assistance. Since appellee is not related to the woman,
appellee's food stamps have been, and will continue to be, cut off
if they continue to live together.
These and two other groups of appellees instituted a class
action against the Department of Agriculture, its Secretary, and
two other departmental officials, seeking declaratory and
injunctive relief against the enforcement of the 1971 amendment of
§ 3(e) and its implementing regulations. In essence, appellees
contend, [ Footnote 4 ] and the
District Court held, that the "unrelated person" provision of §
3(e) creates an irrational classification in violation Page 413 U. S. 533 of the equal protection component of the Due Process Clause of
the Fifth Amendment. [ Footnote
5 ] We agree. II Under traditional equal protection analysis, a legislative
classification must be sustained if the classification itself is
rationally related to a legitimate governmental interest. See
Jefferson v. Hackney, 406 U. S. 535 , 406 U. S. 546 (1972); Richardson v. Belcher, 404 U. S.
78 , 404 U. S. 81 (1971); Dandridge v. Williams. 397 U.
S. 471 , 397 U. S. 485 (1970); McGowan v. Maryland, 366 U.
S. 420 , 366 U. S. 426 (1961). The purposes of the Food Stamp Act were expressly set forth
in the congressional "declaration of policy":
"It is hereby declared to be the policy of Congress . . . to
safeguard the health and wellbeing of the Nation's population and
raise levels of nutrition among low income households. The Congress
hereby finds that the limited food purchasing power of low income
households contributes to hunger and malnutrition among members of
such households. The Congress further finds that increased
utilization of food in establishing and maintaining adequate
national levels of nutrition will promote the distribution in a
beneficial manner of our agricultural abundances and will
strengthen our agricultural economy, as well as result in more
orderly marketing and distribution of food. To alleviate such
hunger and malnutrition, a food stamp program is herein authorized
which will permit low income households to Page 413 U. S. 534 purchase a nutritionally adequate diet through normal channels
of trade."
7 U.S.C. § 2011. The challenged statutory classification
(households of related persons versus households containing one or
more unrelated persons) is clearly irrelevant to the stated
purposes of the Act. As the District Court recognized,
"[t]he relationships among persons constituting one economic
unit and sharing cooking facilities have nothing to do with their
abilities to stimulate the agricultural economy by purchasing farm
surpluses, or with their personal nutritional requirements."
345 F. Supp. at 313.
Thus, if it is to be sustained, the challenged classification
must rationally further some legitimate governmental interest other
than those specifically stated in the congressional "declaration of
policy." Regrettably, there is little legislative history to
illuminate the purposes of the 1971 amendment of § 3(e). [ Footnote 6 ] The legislative history
that does exist, however, indicates that that amendment was
intended to prevent so-called "hippies" and "hippie communes" from
participating in the food stamp program. See H.R.Conf.Rep.
No. 91-1793, p. 8; 116 Cong.Rec. 44439 (1970) (Sen. Holland). The
challenged classification clearly cannot be sustained by reference
to this congressional purpose. For if the constitutional conception
of "equal protection of the laws" means anything, it must, at the
very least, mean that a bare congressional desire to harm a
politically unpopular group cannot constitute a legitimate governmental interest. As a result,
"[a] purpose to discriminate against hippies cannot, in and of
itself and without reference to [some independent] considerations
in the Page 413 U. S. 535 public interest, justify the 1971 amendment."
345 F. Supp. at 314 n. 11.
Although apparently conceding this point, the Government
maintains that the challenged classification should nevertheless be
upheld as rationally related to the clearly legitimate governmental
interest in minimizing fraud in the administration of the food
stamp program. [ Footnote 7 ] In
essence, the Government contends that, in adopting the 1971
amendment, Congress might rationally have thought (1) that
households with one or more unrelated members are more likely than
"fully related" households to contain individuals who abuse the
program by fraudulently failing to report sources of income or by
voluntarily remaining poor; and (2) that such households are
"relatively unstable," thereby increasing the difficulty of
detecting such abuses. But even if we were to accept as rational
the Government's wholly unsubstantiated assumptions concerning the
differences between "related" and "unrelated" households, we still
could not agree with the Government's conclusion that the denial of
essential Page 413 U. S. 536 federal food assistance to all otherwise eligible households
containing unrelated members constitutes a rational effort to deal
with these concerns.
At the outset, it is important to note that the Food Stamp Act
itself contains provisions, wholly independent of § 3(e), aimed
specifically at the problems of fraud and of the voluntarily poor.
For example, with certain exceptions, § 5(c) of the Act, 7 U.S.C. §
2014(c), renders ineligible for assistance any household containing
"an able-bodied adult person between the ages of eighteen and
sixty-five" who fails to register for, and accept, offered
employment. Similarly, §§ 14(b) and (c), 7 U.S.C. §§ 2023(b) and
(c), specifically impose strict criminal penalties upon any
individual who obtains or uses food stamps fraudulently. [ Footnote 8 ] The existence of these
provisions Page 413 U. S. 537 necessarily casts considerable doubt upon the proposition that
the 1971 amendment could rationally have been intended to prevent
those very same abuses. See Eisenstadt v. Baird, 405 U. S. 438 , 405 U. S. 452 (1972); cf. Dunn v. Blumstein, 405 U.
S. 330 , 405 U. S.
353 -354 (1972).
Moreover, in practical effect, the challenged classification
simply does not operate so as rationally to further the prevention
of fraud. As previously noted, § 3(e) defines an eligible
"household" as
"a group of related individuals . . . [1] living as one economic
unit [2] sharing common cooking facilities [and 3] for whom food is
customarily purchased in common."
Thus, two unrelated persons living together and meeting
all three of these conditions would constitute a single household
ineligible for assistance. If financially feasible, however, these
same two individuals can legally avoid the "unrelated person"
exclusion simply by altering their living arrangements so as to
eliminate any one of the three conditions. By so doing, they
effectively create two separate "households," both of which are
eligible for assistance. See Knowles v.
Butz, 358 F.
Supp. 228 (ND Cal.1973). Indeed, as the California Director of
Social Welfare has explained:
"The 'related household' limitations will eliminate many
households from eligibility in the Food Stamp Program. It is my
understanding that the Congressional intent of the new regulations
are specifically aimed at the 'hippies' and 'hippie communes.' Most
people in this category can and will alter their living
arrangements in order to remain eligible for food stamps. However,
the AFDC mothers who try to raise their standard of living by
sharing housing will be affected. They will not be able to Page 413 U. S. 538 utilize the altered living patterns in order to continue o be
eligible without giving up their advantage of shared housing
costs."
Thus, in practical operation, the 1971 amendment excludes from
participation in the food stamp program, not those persons
who are "likely to abuse the program" but, rather, only those persons who are so desperately in need of aid that they
cannot even afford to alter their living arrangements so as to
retain their eligibility. Traditional equal protection analysis
does not require that every classification be drawn with precise
" mathematical nicety.'" Dandridge v. Williams, 397
U.S. at 397 U. S. 485 .
But the classification here in issue is not only "imprecise," it is
wholly without any rational basis. The judgment of the District
Court holding the "unrelated person" provision invalid under the
Due Process Clause of the Fifth Amendment is therefore Affirmed. [ Footnote 1 ]
78 Stat. 703 (emphasis added). The act provided further that
"[t]he term 'household' shall also mean a single individual
living alone who has cooking facilities and who purchases and
prepares food for home consumption." Ibid. [ Footnote 2 ]
84 Stat. 2048. The 1971 amendment did not affect certain groups
of nonrelated individuals over 60 years of age. As amended, § 3(e)
now provides:
"The term 'household' shall mean a group of related individuals
(including legally adopted children and legally assigned foster
children) or non-related individuals over age 60 who are not
residents of an institution or boarding house, but are living as
one economic unit sharing common cooking facilities and for whom
food is customarily purchased in common. The term 'household' shall
also mean (1) a single individual living alone who has cooking
facilities and who purchases and prepares food for home
consumption, or (2) an elderly person who meets the requirements of
section 2019(h) of this title."
7 U.S.C. § 2012(e).
[ Footnote 3 ]
Title 7 CFR § 270.2(jj) provides:
"(jj) 'Household' means a group of persons, excluding roomers,
boarders, and unrelated live-in attendants necessary for medical,
housekeeping, or child care reasons, who are not residents of an
institution or boarding house, and who are living as one economic
unit sharing common cooking facilities and for whom food is
customarily purchased in common: Provided, That: "
"(1) When all persons in the group are under 60 years of age,
they are all related to each other; and"
"(2) When more than one of the persons in the group is under 60
years of age, and one or more other persons in the group is 60
years of age or older, each of the persons under 60 years of age is
related to each other or to at least one of the persons who is 60
years of age or older."
"It shall also mean (i) a single individual living alone who
purchases and prepares food for home consumption, or (ii) an
elderly person as defined in this section, and his spouse."
[ Footnote 4 ]
Appellees also argued that the regulations themselves were
invalid because beyond the scope of the authority conferred upon
the secretary by the statute. The District Court rejected that
contention, and appellees have not pressed that argument on appeal.
Moreover, appellees did not challenge the constitutionality of the
statutes reliance on "households" rather than "individuals" as the
basic unit of the food stamp program. We therefore intimate no view
on that question.
[ Footnote 5 ]
"[W]hile the Fifth Amendment contains no equal protection
clause, it does forbid discrimination that is 'so unjustifiable as
to be violative of due process.'" Schneider v. Rusk, 377 U. S. 163 , 377 U. S. 168 (1964); see Frontiero v. Richardson, 411 U.
S. 677 , 411 U. S. 680 n. 5 (1973); Shapiro v. Thompson, 394 U.
S. 618 , 394 U. S.
641 -642 (1969); Bolling v. Sharpe, 347 U.
S. 497 (1954).
[ Footnote 6 ]
Indeed, the amendment first materialized, bare of committee
consideration, during a conference committee's consideration of
differing House and Senate bills.
[ Footnote 7 ]
The Government initially argued to the District Court that the
challenged classification might be justified as a means to foster
"morality." In rejecting that contention, the District Court noted
that "interpreting the amendment as an attempt to regulate morality
would raise serious constitutional questions." 345 F.
Supp. 310 , 314. Indeed, citing this Court's decisions in Griswold v. Connecticut, 381 U. S. 479 (1965), Stanley v. Georgia, 394 U.
S. 557 (1969), and Eisenstadt v. Baird, 405 U. S. 438 (1972), the District Court observed that it was doubtful, at best,
whether Congress, "in the name of morality," could "infringe the
rights to privacy and freedom of association in the home. "
345 F. Supp. at 314. (Emphasis in original.) Moreover, the court
also pointed out that the classification established in § 3(e) was
not rationally related
"to prevailing notions of morality, since it in terms
disqualifies all households of unrelated individuals, without
reference to whether a particular group contains both sexes." Id. at 315. The Government itself has now abandoned the
"morality" argument. See Brief for Appellants 9.
[ Footnote 8 ]
Title 7 U.S.C. §§ 2023(b) and (c) provide:
"(b) Whoever knowingly uses, transfers, acquires, alters, or
possesses coupons or authorization to purchase cards in any manner
not authorized by this [Act] or the regulations issued pursuant to
this [Act] shall, if such coupons or authorization to purchase
cards are of the value of $100 or more, be guilty of a felony and
shall, upon conviction thereof, be fined not more than $10,000 or
imprisoned for not more than five years or both, or, if such
coupons or authorization to purchase cards are of a value of less
than $100, shall be guilty of a misdemeanor and shall, upon
conviction thereof, be fined not more than $5,000 or imprisoned for
not more than one year, or both."
"(c) Whoever presents, or causes to be presented, coupons for
payment or redemption of the value of $100 or more, knowing the
same to have been received, transferred, or used in any manner in
violation of the provisions of this [Act] or the regulations issued
pursuant to this [Act] shall be guilty of a felony and shall, upon
conviction thereof, be fined not more than $10,000 or imprisoned
for not more than five years, or both, or, if such coupons are of a
value of less than $100, shall be guilty of a misdemeanor and
shall, upon conviction thereof, be fined not more than $5,000 or
imprisoned for not more than one year, or both."
MR. JUSTICE DOUGLAS, concurring.
Appellee Jacinta Moreno is a 56-year-old diabetic who lives with
Ermina Sanchez and the latter's three children. The two share
common living expenses, Mrs. Sanchez helping to care for this
appellee. Appellee's monthly income is $75, derived from public
assistance, and Mrs. Sanchez' is $133, also derived from public
assistance. This household pays $95 a month for rent, of which
appellee pays $40, and $40 a month for gas and electricity, of
which appellee pays $10. Appellee spends $10 a month for
transportation to a hospital for regular visits and $5 a month for
laundry. That leaves her $10 a month for food and other
necessities. Mrs. Sanchez and the three children received $108
worth of food stamps per month for $18. But under the "unrelated"
person Page 413 U. S. 539 provision of the Act, [ Footnote
2/1 ] she will be cut off if appellee Moreno continues to live
with her.
Appellee Sheilah Hejny is married and has three children, ages
two to five. She and her husband took in a 20-year-old girl who is
unrelated to them. She shares in the housekeeping. The Hejnys pay
$14 a month and receive $144 worth of food stamps. The Hejnys
comprise an indigent household. But if they allow the 20-year-old
girl to live with them, they too will be cut off from food stamps
by reason of the "unrelated" person provision. Page 413 U. S. 540 Appellee Keppler has a daughter with an acute hearing deficiency
who requires instruction in a school for the deaf. The school is in
an area where the mother cannot afford to live. So she and her two
minor children moved into a nearby apartment with a woman who, like
appellee Keppler, is on public assistance but who is not related to
her. As a result, appellee Keppler's food stamps have been cut off
because of the "unrelated" person provision.
These appellees instituted a class action to enjoin the
enforcement of the "unrelated" person provision of the Act.
The "unrelated" person provision of the Act creates two classes
of persons for food stamp purposes: one class is composed of people
who are all related to each other and all in dire need, and the
other class is composed of households that have one or more persons
unrelated to the others but have the same degree of need as those
in the first class. The first type of household qualifies for
relief, the second cannot qualify, no matter the need. It is that
application of the Act which is said to violate the conception of
equal protection that is implicit in the Due Process Clause of the
Fifth Amendment. Bolling v. Sharpe, 347 U.
S. 497 , 347 U. S.
499 .
The test of equal protection is whether the legislative line
that is drawn bears "some rational relationship to a legitimate"
governmental purpose. [ Footnote
2/2 ] Weber v.
Aetna Page 413 U. S. 541 Casualty & Surety Co., 406 U.
S. 164 , 406 U. S. 172 .
The requirement of equal protection denies government
"the power to legislate that different treatment be accorded to
persons placed by a statute into different classes on the basis of
criteria wholly unrelated to the objective"
of the enactment. Reed v. Reed, 404 U. S.
71 , 404 U. S.
75 -76.
This case involves desperately poor people with acute problems
who, though unrelated, come together for mutual help and
assistance. The choice of one's associates for social, political,
race, or religious purposes is basic in our constitutional scheme. NAACP v. Alabama, 357 U. S. 449 , 357 U. S. 460 ; De Jonge v. Oregon, 299 U. S. 353 , 299 U. S. 363 ; NAACP v. Button, 371 U. S. 415 , 371 U. S.
429 -431; Gibson v. Florida Legislative
Committee, 372 U. S. 539 ; NAACP v. Alabama, 377 U. S. 288 . It
extends to "the associational rights of the members" of a trade
union. Brotherhood of Railroad Trainmen v. Virginia Bar, 377 U. S. 1 , 377 U. S. 8 .
I suppose no one would doubt that an association of people
working in the poverty field would be entitled to the same
constitutional protection as those working in the racial, banking,
or agricultural field. I suppose poor people holding a meeting or
convention would be under the same constitutional umbrella as
others. The dimensions of the "unrelated" person problem under the
Food Stamp Act are in that category. As the facts of this case
show, the poor are congregating in households where they can better
meet the adversities of poverty. This banding together is an
expression of the right of freedom of association that is very deep
in our traditions. Page 413 U. S. 542 Other like rights have been recognized that are only peripheral
First Amendment rights -- the right to send one's child to a
religious school, the right to study the German language in a
private school, the protection of the entire spectrum of learning,
teaching, and communicating ideas, the marital right of privacy. Griswold v. Connecticut, 381 U. S. 479 , 381 U. S.
482 -483.
As the examples indicate, these peripheral constitutional rights
are exercised not necessarily in assemblies that congregate in
halls or auditoriums but in discrete individual actions such as
parents placing a child in the school of their choice. Taking a
person into one's home because he is poor or needs help or brings
happiness to the household is of the same dignity.
Congress might choose to deal only with members of a family of
one or two or three generations, treating it all as a unit.
Congress, however, has not done that here. Concededly an individual
living alone is not disqualified from the receipt of food stamp
aid, even though there are other members of the family with whom he
might theoretically live. Nor are common law couples disqualified:
they, like individuals living alone, may qualify under the Act if
they are poor -- whether they have abandoned their wives and
children and however anti-family their attitudes may be. In other
words, the "unrelated" person provision was not aimed at the
maintenance of normal family ties. It penalizes persons or families
who have brought under their roof an "unrelated" needy person. It
penalizes the poorest of the poor for doubling up against the
adversities of poverty.
But for the constitutional aspects of the problem, the
"unrelated" person provision of the Act might well be sustained as
a means to prevent fraud. Fraud is a concern of the Act. 7 U.S.C.
§§ 2023(b) and (c). Able-bodied persons must register and accept
work or lose their food. stamp rights. 7 U.S.C. § 2014(c). I Page 413 U. S. 543 could not say that this "unrelated" person provision has no
"rational" relation to control of fraud. We deal here, however,
with the right of association, protected by the First Amendment.
People who are desperately poor but unrelated come together and
join hands with the aim better to combat the crises of poverty. The
need of those living together better to meet those crises is
denied, while the need of households made up of relatives that is
no more acute is serviced. Problems of the fisc, as we stated in Shapiro v. Thompson, 394 U. S. 618 , 394 U. S. 633 ,
are legitimate concerns of government. But government "may not
accomplish such a purpose by invidious distinctions between classes
of its citizens." Ibid. The legislative history of the Act indicates that the
"unrelated" person provision of the Act was to prevent "essentially
unrelated individuals who voluntarily chose to cohabit and live off
food stamps" [ Footnote 2/3 ] --
so-called "hippies" or "hippy communes" -- from participating in
the food stamp program. As stated in the Conference Report,
[ Footnote 2/4 ] the definition of
household was "designed to prohibit food stamp assistance to
communal families' of unrelated individuals." The right of association, the right to invite the stranger into
one's home is too basic in our constitutional regime to deal with
roughshod. If there are abuses inherent in that pattern of living
against which the food stamp program should be protected, the Act
must be "narrowly drawn," Cantwell v. Connecticut, 310 U. S. 296 , 310 U. S. 307 ,
to meet the precise end. The method adopted and applied to these
cases makes § 3(e) of the Act unconstitutional by reason of the
invidious discrimination between the two classes of needy
persons. Page 413 U. S. 544 Dandridge v. Williams, 397 U.
S. 471 , is not opposed. It sustained a Maryland grant of
welfare, against the claim of violation of equal protection, which
placed an upper limit on the monthly amount any single family could
receive. The claimants had large families, so that their standard
of need exceeded the actual grants. Their claim was that the grants
of aid, considered in light of the size of their families, created
an invidious discrimination against them and in favor of small
needy families. The claim was rejected on the basis that state
economic or social legislation had long been judged by a less
strict standard than comes into play when constitutionally
protected rights are involved. Id. at 397 U. S.
484 -48. Laws touching social and economic matters can
pass muster under the Equal Protection Clause though they are
imperfect, the test being whether the classification has some
"reasonable basis." Ibid. Dandridge held that
"the Fourteenth Amendment gives the federal courts no power to
impose upon the States their views of what constitutes wise
economic or social policy." Id. at 397 U. S. 486 .
But for the First Amendment aspect of the case, Dandridge would control here. Dandridge, however, did not reach classifications
touching on associational rights that lie in the penumbra of the
First Amendment. Since the "unrelated" person provision is not
directed to the maintenance of the family as a unit but treats
impoverished households composed of relatives more favorably than
impoverished households having a single unrelated person, it draws
a line that can be sustained only on a showing of a "compelling"
governmental interest.
The "unrelated" person provision of the present Act has an
impact on the rights of people to associate for lawful purposes
with whom they choose. When state action "may have the effect of
curtailing the freedom to Page 413 U. S. 545 associate" it "is subject to the closest scrutiny." NAACP v.
Alabama, 357 U.S. at 357 U. S.
460 -461. The "right of the people peaceably to assemble"
guaranteed by the First Amendment covers a wide spectrum of human
interests -- including, as stated in id. at 357 U. S. 460 ,
"political, economic, religious, or cultural matters." Banding
together to combat the common foe of hunger is in that category.
The case therefore falls within the zone represented by Shapiro
v. Thompson, supra, which held that a waiting period on
welfare imposed by a State on the "in-migration of indigents"
penalizing the constitutional right to travel could not be
sustained absent a "compelling governmental interest." Id. at 394 U. S. 631 , 394 U. S.
634 .
[ Footnote 2/1 ]
Section 3(e) of the Food Stamp Act provides in relevant
part:
"The term 'household' shall mean a group of related individuals
(including legally adopted children and legally assigned foster
children) or non-related individuals over age 60 who are not
residents of an institution or boarding house, but are living as
one economic unit sharing common cooking facilities and for whom
food is customarily purchased in common."
7 U.S.C. § 2012(e).
The Regulations provide:
"'Household' means a group of persons, excluding roomers,
boarders, and unrelated live-in attendants necessary for medical,
housekeeping, or child care reasons, who are not residents of an
institution or boarding house, and who are living as one economic
unit sharing common cooking facilities and for whom food is
customarily purchased in common: Provided, That: "
"(1) When all persons in the group are under 60 years of age,
they are all related to each other; and"
"(2) When more than one of the persons in the group is under 60
years of age, and one or more other persons in the group is 60
years of age or older, each of the persons under 60 years of age is
related to each other or to at least one of the persons who is 60
years of age or older."
7 CFR § 270.2(jj).
"Eligibility for and participation in the program shall be on a
household basis. All persons, excluding roomers, boarders, and
unrelated live-in attendants necessary for medical, housekeeping,
or child care reasons, residing in common living quarters shall be
consolidated into a group prior to determining if such a group is a
household as determined in § 270.2(jj) of this subchapter."
7 CFR § 271.3(a).
[ Footnote 2/2 ]
The purpose of the present Act was stated by Congress:
"[T]o safeguard the health and wellbeing of the Nation's population and raise levels of nutrition among low income households. The Congress hereby finds that the
limited food purchasing power of low income households contributes
to hunger and malnutrition among members of such
households. The Congress further finds that increased utilization
of food in establishing and maintaining adequate national
levels of nutrition will promote the distribution in a
beneficial manner of our agricultural abundances and will
strengthen our agricultural economy, as well as result in more
orderly marketing and distribution of food. To alleviate such
hunger and malnutrition, a food stamp program is herein authorized
which will permit low income households to purchase a nutritionally adequate diet through normal channels of
trade."
7 U.S.C. § 2011. (Italics added.)
[ Footnote 2/3 ] See 116 Cong.Rec. 42003.
[ Footnote 2/4 ]
H.R.Conf.Rep. No. 91-1793, p. 8.
MR. JUSTICE REHNQUIST, with whom THE CHIEF JUSTICE concurs,
dissenting.
For much the same reasons as those stated in my dissenting
opinion in United States Department of Agriculture v. Murry,
ante p. 413 U. S. 522 ,
I am unable to agree with the Court's disposition of this case.
Here, appellees challenged a provision in the Federal Food Stamp
Act, 7 U.S.C. § 2011 et seq., which limited food stamps to
related people living in one "household." The result of this
provision is that unrelated persons who live under the same roof
and pool their resources may not obtain food stamps even though
otherwise eligible.
The Court's opinion would make a very persuasive congressional
committee report arguing against the adoption of the limitation in
question. Undoubtedly, Congress attacked the problem with a rather
blunt instrument, and, just as undoubtedly, persuasive arguments
may be made that what we conceive to be its purpose will not be
significantly advanced by the enactment of the limitation. But
questions such as this are for Congress, rather than for this
Court; our role is limited to the Page 413 U. S. 546 determination of whether there is any rational basis on which
Congress could decide that public funds made available under the
food stamp program should not go to a household containing an
individual who is unrelated to any other member of the
household.
I do not believe that asserted congressional concern with the
fraudulent use of food stamps is, when interpreted in the light
most favorable to sustaining the limitation, quite as irrational as
the Court seems to believe. A basic unit which Congress has chosen
for determination of availability for food stamps is the
"household," a determination which is not criticized by the Court.
By the limitation here challenged, it has singled out households
which contain unrelated persons and made such households
ineligible. I do not think it is unreasonable for Congress to
conclude that the basic unit which it was willing to support with
federal funding through food stamps is some variation on the family
as we know it -- a household consisting of related individuals.
This unit provides a guarantee which is not provided by households
containing unrelated individuals that the household exists for some
purpose other than to collect federal food stamps.
Admittedly, as the Court points out, the limitation will make
ineligible many households which have not been formed for the
purpose of collecting federal food stamps, and will, at the same
time, not wholly deny food stamps to those households which may
have been formed in large part to take advantage of the program.
But, as the Court concedes, "[t]raditional equal protection
analysis does not require that every classification be drawn with
precise mathematical nicety,'" ante at 413 U. S. 538 .
And earlier this Term, the constitutionality of a similarly
"imprecise" rule promulgated pursuant to the Truth in Lending Act
was challenged Page 413 U. S. 547 on grounds such as those urged by appellees here. In Mourning v. Family Publications Service, Inc., 411 U. S. 356 (1973), the imposition of the rule on all members of a defined
class was sustained because it served to discourage evasion by a
substantial portion of that class of disclosure mechanisms chosen
by Congress for consumer protection.
The limitation which Congress enacted could, in the judgment of
reasonable men, conceivably deny food stamps to members of
households which have been formed solely for the purpose of taking
advantage of the food stamp program. Since the food stamp program
is not intended to be a subsidy for every individual who desires
low-cost food, this was a permissible congressional decision quite
consistent with the underlying policy of the Act. The fact that the
limitation will have unfortunate and perhaps unintended
consequences beyond this does not make it unconstitutional. | The Supreme Court ruled that a provision in the Food Stamp Act of 1964 that excluded households with unrelated members from the food stamp program was unconstitutional. The Court found that the classification was irrelevant to the stated purposes of the Act and did not rationally further any legitimate governmental interest. The Court also noted that the provision excluded those who desperately needed aid, while not necessarily preventing those likely to abuse the program from receiving benefits.
Justice Brennan delivered the opinion of the Court, with Justices Douglas, Stewart, White, Marshall, Blackmun, and Powell joining. Justice Douglas wrote a separate concurring opinion, while Justice Rehnquist dissented, joined by Chief Justice Burger. |
Equal Protection | Mathews v. Lucas | https://supreme.justia.com/cases/federal/us/427/495/ | U.S. Supreme Court Mathews v. Lucas, 427
U.S. 495 (1976) Mathews v. Lucas No. 75-88 Argued January 13,
1976 Decided June 29, 1976 427
U.S. 495 APPEAL FROM THE UNITED STATES
DISTRICT COURT FOR THE DISTRICT OF RHODE
ISLAND Syllabus The Social Security Act provides that a child of an individual
who died fully insured under the Act, is entitled to surviving
child's benefits if the child is under 18, or a student under 22,
and was dependent at the time of the parent's death. A child is
considered dependent if the insured parent was living with him or
contributed to the child's support at the time of death. Certain
children, however, need not submit such individualized proof of
dependency. Unless adopted by some other person, a child who is
legitimate or would be entitled to inherit from the insured parent
under state law is considered dependent at the time of the parent's
death, or even lacking this relationship under state intestacy law
is entitled to a presumption of dependency if the decedent before
death had gone through a marriage ceremony with the other parent,
resulting in a purported marriage which, but for a nonobvious
defect, would have been valid, or had acknowledged in writing that
the child was his, or had been decreed by a court to be the child's
father, or had been ordered by a court to support the child because
the child was his. After their father died, appellee illegitimate
children were administratively denied surviving children's benefits
on the ground that they failed to show dependency by proof that
their father lived with them or was contributing to their support
at the time of his death, or by any of the statutory presumptions
of dependency. After this ruling was upheld on administrative
appeal, appellees filed an action for review against appellant
Secretary of Health, Education, and Welfare, alleging that the
denial of benefits violated the equal protection component of the
Due Process Clause of the Fifth Amendment because other children,
including all legitimate children, are statutorily entitled, as
appellee children are not, to survivors' benefits regardless of
actual dependency. The District Court held that the statutory
classifications were constitutionally impermissible, reversing the
administrative decision and ordering that benefits be paid to the
children. Held: 1. The judicial scrutiny traditionally devoted to cases
involving Page 427 U. S. 496 discrimination along lines of race or national origin is not
required because legislation treats legitimate and illegitimate
offspring differently. Pp. 427 U. S. 503 -506.
2. The challenged statutory classifications are permissible
because they are reasonably related to the likelihood of dependency
at death, and in failing to extend any presumption of dependency to
appellee children and others like them, the Act does not
impermissibly discriminate against them as compared with legitimate
children or those illegitimate children who are statutorily deemed
dependent. Pp. 427 U. S.
507 -516.
(a) While Congress was unwilling to assume that every child of a
deceased insured was dependent at the time of death, by presuming
dependency on the basis of relatively readily documented facts,
such as legitimate birth, or a support order or paternity decree,
which could be relied upon to indicate the likelihood of continued
actual dependency, Congress was able to avoid the burden and
expense of specific case-by-case determination in the large number
of cases where dependency is objectively probable. Such
presumptions in aid of administrative functions, though they may
approximate, rather than precisely mirror, the results that
case-by-case adjudication would show, are permissible under the
Fifth Amendment, so long as that lack of precise equivalence does
not exceed the bounds of substantiality tolerated by the applicable
level of scrutiny. Pp. 427 U. S.
509 -510.
(b) The challenged classifications are justified as reasonable
empirical judgments that are consistent with a design to qualify
entitlement to benefits upon a child's dependency at the time of
the parent's death. Gomez v. Perez, 409 U.
S. 535 ; New Jersey Welfare Rights Org. v.
Cahill, 411 U. S. 619 ; Weber v. Aetna Casualty & Surety Co., 406 U.
S. 164 ; Levy v. Louisiana, 391 U. S.
68 ; Jimenez v. Weinberger, 417 U.
S. 628 ; Frontiero v. Richardson, 411 U.
S. 677 , distinguished. Pp. 427 U. S.
510 -516. 390 F.
Supp. 1310 , reversed.
BLACKMUN, J., delivered the opinion of the Court, in which
BURGER, C.J., and STEWART, WHITE, POWELL, and REHNQUIST, JJ.,
joined. STEVENS, J., filed a dissenting opinion, in which BRENNAN
and MARSHALL, JJ., joined, post, p. 427 U. S.
516 . Page 427 U. S. 497 MR. JUSTICE BLACKMUN delivered the opinion of the Court.
This case presents the issue of the constitutionality, under the
Due Process Clause of the Fifth Amendment, of those provisions of
the Social Security Act that condition the eligibility of certain
illegitimate children for a surviving child's insurance benefits
upon a showing that the deceased wage earner was the claimant
child's parent and, at the time of his death was living with the
child or was contributing to his support. I Robert Cuffee, now deceased, lived with Belmira Lucas during the
years 1948 through 1966, but they were never married. Two children
were born to them during these years: Ruby M. Lucas, in 1953, and
Darin E. Lucas, in 1960. In 1966, Cuffee and Lucas separated.
Cuffee died in Providence, R.I., his home, in 1968. He died without
ever having acknowledged in writing his paternity of either Ruby or
Darin, and it was never determined in any judicial proceeding
during his lifetime that he was the father of either child. After
Cuffee's death, Mrs. Lucas filed an application on behalf of Ruby
and Darin for surviving children's benefits under § 202(d)(1) of
the Social Security Act, 70 Stat. 807, as amended, 42 U.S.C. §
402(d)(1) (1970 ed. and Supp. IV), based upon Cuffee's earnings
record. II In operative terms, the Act provides that an unmarried son or
daughter of an individual, who died fully or currently insured
under the Act, may apply for and be Page 427 U. S. 498 entitled to a survivor's benefit, if the applicant is under 18
years of age at the time of application (or is a full-time student
and under 22 years of age) and was dependent, within the meaning of
the statute, at the time of the parent's death. [ Footnote 1 ] A child is considered dependent
for this purpose if the insured father was living with or
contributing to the child's support at the time of death. Certain
children, however, are relieved of the burden of such
individualized proof of dependency. Unless the child has been
adopted by some other individual, a child Page 427 U. S. 499 who is legitimate, or a child who would be entitled to inherit
personal property from the insured parent's estate under the
applicable state intestacy law is considered to have been dependent
at the time of the parent's death. [ Footnote 2 ] Even lacking this relationship under state
law, a child, unless adopted by some other individual, is entitled
to a presumption of dependency if the decedent, before death, (a)
had gone through a marriage ceremony with the other parent,
resulting in a purported marriage between them which, but for a
nonobvious legal defect, would have been valid, or (b) in writing
had acknowledged the child to be his, or (c) had been decreed by a
court to be the child's father, or (d) had been ordered by a court
to support the child because the child was his. [ Footnote 3 ] Page 427 U. S. 500 Examiner of the Social Security Administration, after hearings,
determined that, while Cuffee's paternity was established, the
children had failed to demonstrate their dependency by proof that
Cuffee either lived with them or was contributing to their support
at the time Page 427 U. S. 501 of his death, or by any of the statutory presumptions of
dependency, and thus that they were not entitled to survivorship
benefits under the Act. The Appeals Council of the Social Security
Administration affirmed these rulings, and they became the final
decision of the Secretary of Health, Education, and Welfare. Lucas
then timely filed this action, pursuant to § 205(g) of the Act, 42
U.S.C. § 405(g), in the United States District Court for the
District of Rhode Island on behalf of the two children (hereinafter
sometimes called the appellees) for review of the Secretary's
decision.
The District Court ultimately affirmed each of the factual
findings of the administrative agency: that Robert Cuffee was the
children's father; that he never acknowledged his paternity in
writing; that his paternity or support obligations had not been the
subject of a judicial proceeding during his lifetime; that no
common law marriage had ever been contracted between Cuffee and
Lucas, so that the children could not inherit Cuffee's personal
property under the intestacy law of Rhode Island; and that, at the
time of his death, he was neither living with the children nor
contributing to their support. 390 F.
Supp. 1310 , 1312-1314 (1975). None of these factual matters is
at issue here. [ Footnote 4 ] Page 427 U. S. 502 A motion for summary judgment, filed by the appellees, relied on Jimenez v. Weinberger, 417 U. S. 628 (1974). It was urged that denial of benefits in this case, where
paternity was clear, violated the Fifth Amendment's Due Process
Clause, as that provision comprehends the principle of equal
protection of the laws, [ Footnote
5 ] because other children, including all legitimate children,
are statutorily entitled, as the Lucas children are not, to
survivorship benefits regardless of actual dependency. Addressing
this issue, the District Court ruled that the statutory
classifications were constitutionally impermissible. [ Footnote 6 ] 390 F. Supp. at 1314-1321.
Recognizing that the web of statutory provisions regarding
presumptive dependency was overinclusive because it entitled some
children, who were not actually dependent, to survivorship benefits
under the Act -- although not underinclusive, since no otherwise
eligible child who could establish actual dependency at the time of
death was denied such benefits -- the court concluded that the Act
was not intended merely to replace actual support that a
child lost through the death of the insured parent. Id. at
1319-1320. Rather, the court characterized the statute as one
designed to replace obligations of support or potential Page 427 U. S. 503 support lost through death, where the obligation was perceived
by Congress, on the basis of the responsibility of the relation
between the child's parents, to be a valid one. Thus, the court
concluded:
"[The Act] conditions eligibility on the basis of Congress'
views as to who is entitled to support and reflects society's view
that legitimate and 'legitimated' children are more entitled to
support by or through a parent than are illegitimate children. But
this is not a legitimate governmental interest, and thus
cannot support the challenged classification. Gomez v.
Perez , [ 409 U.S.
535 (1973)]." Id. at 1320. (Emphasis in original.) With this
conclusion, the District Court reversed the administrative decision
and ordered the Secretary to pay benefits for both children.
Jurisdictional Statement 28a.
The Secretary appealed directly to this Court. 28 U.S.C. § 1252.
We noted probable jurisdiction and set the case for argument with Norton v. Mathews, post, p. 427 U. S. 524 . 423 U. S. 19 (1975). III The Secretary does not disagree that the Lucas children and
others similarly circumstanced are treated differently, as a class,
from those children -- legitimate and illegitimate -- who are
relieved by statutory presumption of any requirement of proving
actual dependency at the time of death through cohabitation or
contribution: for children in the advantaged classes may be
statutorily entitled to benefits even if they have never been
dependent upon the father through whom they claim. [ Footnote 7 ] Statutory Page 427 U. S. 504 classifications, of course, are not per se unconstitutional; the matter depends upon the character of the
discrimination and its relation to legitimate legislative aims.
"The essential inquiry . . . is . . . inevitably a dual one:
what legitimate [governmental] interest does the classification
promote? What fundamental personal rights might the classification
endanger?" Weber v. Aetna Casualty & Surety Co., 406 U.
S. 164 , 406 U. S. 173 (1972).
Although the District Court concluded that close judicial
scrutiny of the statute's classifications was not necessary to its
conclusion invalidating those classifications, it also concluded
that legislation treating legitimate and illegitimate offspring
differently is constitutionally suspect, [ Footnote 8 ] 390 F. Supp. at 1318-1319, and requires the
judicial scrutiny traditionally devoted to cases involving
discrimination along lines of race [ Footnote 9 ] or national origin. [ Footnote 10 ] Appellees echo this approach. We
disagree. [ Footnote 11 ] Page 427 U. S. 505 It is true, of course, that the legal status of illegitimacy,
however defined, is, like race or national origin, a characteristic
determined by causes not within the control of the illegitimate
individual, and it bears no relation to the individual's ability to
participate in and contribute to society. The Court recognized in Weber that visiting condemnation upon the child in order
to express society's disapproval of the parents' liaisons
"is illogical and unjust. Moreover, imposing disabilities on the
illegitimate child is contrary to the basic concept of our system
that legal burdens should bear some relationship to individual
responsibility or wrongdoing. Obviously, no child is responsible
for his birth and penalizing the illegitimate child is an
ineffectual -- as well as an unjust -- way of deterring the
parent."
406 U.S. at 406 U. S. 175 .
(Footnote omitted.) But where the law is arbitrary in such a way,
we have had no difficulty in finding the discrimination
impermissible on less demanding standards than those advocated
here. New Jersey Welfare Rights Org. v. Cahill, 411 U. S. 619 (1973); Richardson v. Davis, 409 U.S. 1069 (1972); Richardson v. Griffin; 409 U.S. 1069 (1972); Weber,
supra; Levy v. Louisiana, 391 U. S. 68 (1968). And such irrationality in some classifications does not in
itself demonstrate that other, possibly rational, distinctions made
in part on the basis of legitimacy are inherently untenable.
Moreover, while the law has long Page 427 U. S. 506 placed the illegitimate child in an inferior position relative
to the legitimate in certain circumstances, particularly in regard
to obligations of support or other aspects of family law, see
generally, e.g., H. Krause, Illegitimacy: Law and Social
Policy 212 (1971); Gray & Rudovsky, The Court Acknowledges the
Illegitimate: Levy v. Louisiana and Glona v. American
Guarantee & Liability Insurance Co., 118 U.Pa.L.Rev. 1,
19-38 (1969), perhaps in part because the roots of the
discrimination rest in the conduct of the parents rather than the
child, [ Footnote 12 ] and
perhaps in part because illegitimacy does not carry an obvious
badge, as race or sex do, this discrimination against illegitimates
has never approached the severity or pervasiveness of the historic
legal and political discrimination against women and Negroes. See Frontiero v. Richardson, 411 U.
S. 677 , 411 U. S.
684 -686 (1973) (plurality opinion).
We therefore adhere to our earlier view, see Labine v.
Vincent, 401 U. S. 532 (1971), that the Act's discrimination between individuals on the
basis of their legitimacy does not "command extraordinary
protection from the majoritarian political process," San
Antonio School Dist. v. Rodriguez, 411 U.S. ___, 28 (1973),
which our most exacting scrutiny would entail. [ Footnote 13 ] See Jimenez, 417 U.S.
at 417 U. S.
631 -634, 417 U. S. 636 ; Weber, 406 U.S. at 406 U. S. 173 , 406 U. S.
175 -176. Page 427 U. S. 507 IV Relying on Weber, the Court, in Gomez v.
Perez, 409 U. S. 535 , 409 U. S. 538 (1973), held that
"once a State posits a judicially enforceable right on behalf of
children to needed support from their natural fathers there is no
constitutionally sufficient justification for denying such an
essential right to a child simply because its natural father has
not married its mother."
The same principle, which we adhere to now, applies when the
judicially enforceable right to needed support lies against the
Government, rather than a natural father. See New Jersey
Welfare Rights Org. v. Cahill, supra. Consistent with our decisions, the Secretary explains the design
of the statutory scheme assailed here as a program to provide for
all children of deceased insureds who can demonstrate their "need"
in terms of dependency at the times of the insureds' deaths. Cf. Jimenez, 417 U.S. at 417 U. S. 634 .
He authenticates this description by reference to the explicit
language of the Act specifying that the applicant child's
classification as legitimate, or acknowledged, etc., is ultimately
relevant only to the determination of dependency, and by reference
to legislative history indicating that the statute was not a
general welfare provision for legitimate or otherwise "approved"
children of deceased insureds, but was intended just "to replace
the support lost by a child when his father . . . dies. . . ."
S.Rep. No. 404, 89th Cong., 1st Sess., 110 (1965).
Taking this explanation at face value, we think it clear that
conditioning entitlement upon dependency at the time of death is
not impermissibly discriminatory in providing only for those
children for whom the loss of the parent is an immediate source of
the need. Cf. Geduldig v. Aiello, 417 U.
S. 484 , 417 U. S.
492 -497 (1974); Jefferson v. Hackney, 406 U. S. 535 (1972); Richardson v.
Belcher , Page 427 U. S. 508 404 U. S. 78 (1971). See also Weber, 406 U.S. at 406 U. S.
174 -175.
But appellees contend that the actual design of the statute
belies the Secretary's description, and that the statute was
intended to provide support for insured decedents' children
generally, if they had a "legitimate" claim to support, without
regard to actual dependency at death; in any case, they assert, the
statute's matrix of classifications bears no adequate relationship
to actual dependency at death. Since such dependency does not
justify the statute's discriminations, appellees argue, those
classifications must fall under Gomez v. Perez, supra. These assertions are, in effect, one and the same. [ Footnote 14 ] The basis for appellees'
argument is the obvious fact that Page 427 U. S. 509 each of the presumptions of dependency renders the class of
benefit recipients incrementally overinclusive, in the sense that
some children within each class of presumptive dependents are
automatically entitled to benefits under the statute although they
could not in fact prove their economic dependence upon insured wage
earners at the time of death. We conclude that the statutory
classifications are permissible, however, because they are
reasonably related to the likelihood of dependency at death. A Congress' purpose in adopting the statutory presumptions of
dependency was obviously to serve administrative convenience. While
Congress was unwilling to assume that every child of a deceased
insured was dependent at the time of death, by presuming dependency
on the basis of relatively readily documented facts, such as
legitimate birth, or existence of a support order or paternity
decree, which could be relied upon to indicate the likelihood of
continued actual dependency, Congress was able to avoid the burden
and expense of specific case-by-case determination in the large
number of cases where dependency is objectively probable. Such
presumptions in aid of administrative functions, though they may
approximate, rather than precisely mirror, the results that
case-by-case adjudication would show, are permissible under the
Fifth Amendment so long as that lack of precise equivalence does
not exceed the bounds of substantiality tolerated by the applicable
level of scrutiny. See Weinberger v. Salfi, 422 U.
S. 749 , 422 U. S. 772 (1975). [ Footnote 15 ]
In cases of strictest scrutiny, such approximations must be
supported at least by a showing that the Government's Page 427 U. S. 510 dollar "lost" to overincluded benefit recipients is returned by
a dollar "saved" in administrative expense avoided. Frontiero
v. Richardson, 411 U.S. at 411 U. S. 689 (plurality opinion). Under the standard of review appropriate here,
however, the materiality of the relation between the statutory
classifications and the likelihood of dependency they assertedly
reflect need not be " scientifically substantiated.'" James
v. Strange, 407 U. S. 128 , 407 U. S. 133 (1972), quoting Roth v. United States, 354 U.
S. 476 , 354 U. S. 501 (1957) (opinion of Harlan, J.). Nor, in any case, do we believe
that Congress is required in this realm of less than strictest
scrutiny to weigh the burdens of administrative inquiry solely in
terms of dollars ultimately "spent," ignoring the relative amounts
devoted to administrative rather than welfare uses. Cf.
Weinberger v. Salfi, 422 U.S. at 422 U. S. 784 .
Finally, while the scrutiny by which their showing is to be judged
is not a toothless one, e.g., Jimenez v. Weinberger, 417 U. S. 628 (1974); Frontiero v. Richardson, 411 U.S. at 411 U. S. 691 (STEWART, J., concurring in judgment, POWELL, J., concurring in
judgment); Reed v. Reed, 404 U. S. 71 (1971), the burden remains upon the appellees to demonstrate the
insubstantiality of that relation. See Lindsley v. Natural
Carbonic Gas Co., 220 U. S. 61 , 220 U. S. 78 -79
(1911); cf. United States v. Gainey, 380 U. S.
63 , 380 U. S. 67 (1965). B Applying these principles, we think that the statutory
classifications challenged here are justified as reasonable
empirical judgments that are consistent with a design to qualify
entitlement to benefits upon a child's dependency at the time of
the parent's death. To begin with, we note that the statutory
scheme is significantly different from the provisions confronted in
cases in which the Page 427 U. S. 511 Court has invalidated legislative discriminations among children
on the basis of legitimacy. See Gomez v. Perez, 409 U. S. 535 (1973); New Jersey Welfare Rights Org. v. Cahill, 411 U. S. 619 (1973); Weber v. Aetna Casualty & Surety Co., 406 U. S. 164 (1972); Levy v. Louisiana, 391 U. S.
68 (1968). These differences render those cases of
little assistance to appellees. It could not have been fairly
argued, with respect to any of the statutes struck down in those
cases, that the legitimacy of the child was simply taken as an
indication of dependency, or of some other valid ground of
qualification. Under all but one of the statutes, not only was the
legitimate child automatically entitled to benefits, but an
illegitimate child was denied benefits solely and finally on the
basis of illegitimacy, and regardless of any demonstration of
dependency or other legitimate factor. See also Griffin v.
Richardson, 346 F.
Supp. 1226 (Md.), summarily aff'd, 409 U.S. 1069
(1972); Davis v. Richardson, 342 F.
Supp. 588 (Conn.), summarily aff'd, 409 U.S. 1069
(1972). In Weber v. Aetna Casualty & Surety Co.,
supra, the sole partial exception, the statutory scheme
provided for a child's equal recovery under a workmen's
compensation plan in the event of the death of the father, not only
if the child was dependent, but also only if the dependent child
was legitimate. 406 U.S. at 406 U. S.
173 -174, and n. 12. Jimenez v. Weinberger,
supra, invalidating discrimination among afterborn
illegitimate children as to entitlement to a child's disability
benefits under the Social Security Act, is similarly
distinguishable. Under the somewhat related statutory matrix
considered there, legitimate children and those capable of
inheriting personal property under state intestacy law, and those
illegitimate solely on account of a nonobvious defect in their
parents' marriage, were eligible for benefits, even if they were
born after the onset of the father's disability. Page 427 U. S. 512 Other (illegitimate) afterborn children were conclusively denied
any benefits, regardless of any showing of dependency. The Court
held the discrimination among illegitimate afterborn children
impermissible, rejecting the Secretary's claim that the
classification was based upon considerations regarding trustworthy
proof of dependency, because it could not accept the assertion:
"[T]he blanket and conclusive exclusion of appellants' subclass
of illegitimates is reasonably related to the prevention of
spurious claims [of dependency]. Assuming that the appellants are
in fact dependent on the claimant [father], it would not serve the
purposes of the Act to conclusively deny them an opportunity to
establish their dependency and their right to insurance
benefits."
417 U.S. at 417 U. S. 636 .
Hence, it was held that
"to conclusively deny one subclass benefits presumptively
available to the other denies the former the equal protection of
the laws guaranteed by the due process provision of the Fifth
Amendment." Id. at 417 U. S. 637 . See also Weinberger v. Wiesenfeld, 420 U.
S. 636 , 420 U. S. 645 (1975); cf. Labine v. Vincent, 401 U.S. at 401 U. S. 539 .
But this conclusiveness in denying benefits to some classes of
afterborn illegitimate children, which belied the asserted
legislative reliance on dependency in Jimenez, is absent
here, for, as we have noted, any otherwise eligible child may
qualify for survivorship benefits by showing contribution to
support, or cohabitation, at the time of death. Cf. Vlandis v.
Kline, 412 U. S. 441 , 412 U. S.
452 -453, n. 9 (1973), distinguishing Starns v.
Malkerson, 326 F.
Supp. 234 (Minn.1970), summarily aff'd, 401 U.S. 985
(1971).
It is, of course, not enough simply that any child of a deceased
insured is eligible for benefits upon some showing Page 427 U. S. 513 of dependency. In Frontiero v. Richardson, supra, we
found it impermissible to qualify the entitlement to dependent's
benefits of a married woman in the uniformed services upon an
individualized showing of her husband's actual dependence upon her
for more than half his income, when no such showing of actual
dependency was required of a married man in the uniformed services
to obtain dependent's benefits on account of his wife. The
invalidity of that gender-based discrimination rested upon the
"overbroad" assumption, Schlesinger v. Ballard, 419 U. S. 498 , 419 U. S. 508 (1975), underlying the discrimination
"that male workers' earnings are vital to the support of their
families, while the earnings of female wage earners do not
significantly contribute to their families' support." Weinberger v. Wiesenfeld, 420 U.S. at 420 U. S. 643 ; see Frontiero, 411 U.S. at 411 U. S. 689 n. 23. Here, by contrast, the statute does not broadly discriminate
between legitimates and illegitimates without more, but is
carefully tuned to alternative considerations. The presumption of
dependency is withheld only in the absence of any significant
indication of the likelihood of actual dependency. Moreover, we
cannot say that the factors that give rise to a presumption of
dependency lack any substantial relation to the likelihood of
actual dependency. Rather, we agree with the assessment of the
three-judge court as it originally ruled in Norton v.
Weinberger, 364 F.
Supp. 1117 , 1128 (Md. 1973): [ Footnote 16 ]
"[I]t is clearly rational to presume the overwhelming number of
legitimate children are actually dependent upon their parents for
support. Likewise . . . the children of an invalid marriage . .
. Page 427 U. S. 514 would typically live in the wage earner's home or be supported
by him. . . . When an order of support is entered by a court it is
reasonable to assume compliance occurred. A paternity decree, while
not necessarily ordering support, would almost as strongly suggest
support was subsequently obtained. Conceding that a written
acknowledgment lacks the imprimatur of a judicial proceeding, it
too establishes the basis for a rational presumption. Men do not
customarily affirm in writing their responsibility for an
illegitimate child unless the child is theirs and a man who has
acknowledged a child is more likely to provide it support than one
who does not."
Similarly, we think, where state intestacy law provides that a
child may take personal property from a father's estate, it may
reasonably be thought that the child will more likely be dependent
during the parent's life and at his death. [ Footnote 17 ] For in its embodiment of the
popular Page 427 U. S. 515 view within the jurisdiction of how a parent would have his
property devolve among his children in the event of death, without
specific directions, such legislation also reflects to some degree
the popular conception within the jurisdiction of the felt parental
obligation to such an "illegitimate" child in other circumstances,
and thus something of the likelihood of actual parental support
during, as well as after, life. [ Footnote 18 ] Accord, Watts v. Veneman, 155
U.S.App.D.C. 84, 88, 476 F.2d 529, 533 (1973).
To be sure, none of these statutory criteria compels the
extension of a presumption of dependency. But the constitutional
question is not whether such a presumption is required, but whether
it is permitted. Nor, in ratifying these statutory classifications,
is our role to hypothesize independently on the desirability or
feasibility of any possible alternative basis for presumption.
These matters of practical judgment and empirical calculation are
for Congress. Drawing upon its own practical experience, Page 427 U. S. 516 Congress has tailored statutory classifications in accord with
its calculations of the likelihood of actual support suggested by a
narrow set of objective and apparently reasonable indicators. Our
role is simply to determine whether Congress' assumptions are so
inconsistent or insubstantial as not to be reasonably supportive of
its conclusions that individualized factual inquiry in order to
isolate each nondependent child in a given class of cases is
unwarranted as an administrative exercise. In the end, the precise
accuracy of Congress' calculations is not a matter of specialized
judicial competence, and we have no basis to question their detail
beyond the evident consistency and substantiality. Cf. United
States v. Gainey, 380 U.S. at 380 U. S. 67 . We
cannot say that these expectations are unfounded, or so
indiscriminate as to render the statute's classifications baseless.
We conclude, in short, that, in failing to extend any presumption
of dependency to appellees and others like them, the Act does not
impermissibly discriminate against them as compared with legitimate
children or those illegitimate children who are statutorily deemed
dependent. Reversed. [ Footnote 1 ]
Section 202(d)(1) of the Act, as set forth in 42 U.S.C. §
402(d)(1), provides in pertinent part:
"Every child (as defined in section 416(e) of this title) . . .
of an individual who dies a fully or currently insured individual,
if such child -- "
"(A) has filed application for child's insurance benefits,"
"(B) at the time such application was filed was unmarried and
(i) either had not attained the age of 18 or was a full-time
student and had not attained the age of 22 . . . and"
"(C) was dependent upon such individual --"
" * * * *" "(ii) if such individual has died, at the time of such death, .
. ."
" * * * *" "shall be entitled to a child's insurance benefit for each
month, beginning with the first month after August, 1950, in which
such child becomes so entitled to such insurance benefits. . .
."
Section 216(e), 42 U.S.C. § 416(e), includes, under the
definition of child, inter alia, "the child . . . of an
individual," certain legally adopted children, certain
stepchildren, and certain grandchildren and stepgrandchildren.
Additionally, § 216(h)(2)(A) of the Act, 42 U.S.C. § 416(h)(2)(A),
provides:
"In determining whether an applicant is the child . . . of a
fully or currently insured individual for purposes of this
subchapter, the Secretary shall apply such law as would be applied
in determining the devolution of intestate personal property . . .
by the courts of the State in which [such insured individual] was
domiciled at the time of his death. . . . Applicants who according
to such law would have the same status relative to taking intestate
personal property as a child . . . shall be deemed such."
[ Footnote 2 ]
Section 202(d)(3) of the Act, 42 U.S.C. § 402(d)(3), provides in
pertinent part:
"A child shall be deemed dependent upon his father or adopting
father or his mother or adopting mother at the time specified in
paragraph (1)(C) of this subsection unless, at such time, such
individual was not living with or contributing to the support of
such child and -- "
"(A) such child is neither the legitimate nor adopted child of
such individual, or"
"(B) such child has been adopted by some other individual."
Additionally, any child who qualifies under § 216(h)(2)(A), see n 1, supra, is considered legitimate for § 202(d)(3) purposes,
and thus dependent.
[ Footnote 3 ]
Section 202(d)(3), as set forth in 42 U.S.C. § 402(d)(3),
provides in pertinent part that
"a child deemed to be a child of a fully or currently insured
individual pursuant to section 416(h)(2)(B) or section 416(h)(3) .
. . shall be deemed to be the legitimate child of such
individual,"
and therefore presumptively dependent. Section 216(h)(2)(B), as
set forth in 42 U.S.C. § 416(h)(2)(b), provides:
"If an applicant is a son or daughter of a fully or currently
insured individual but is not (and is not deemed to be) the child
of such insured individual under subparagraph (A), such applicant
shall nevertheless be deemed to be the child of such insured
individual if such insured individual and the mother or father, as
the case may be, of such applicant went through a marriage ceremony
resulting in a purported marriage between them which, but for a
legal impediment described in the last sentence of paragraph
(1)(b), would have been a valid marriage."
The specified last sentence of § 216(h)(1)(B), 42 U.S.C. §
416(h)(1)(b), in turn, refers only to
"an impediment (i) resulting from the lack of dissolution of a
previous marriage or otherwise arising out of such previous
marriage or its dissolution, or (ii) resulting from a defect in the
procedure followed in connection with such purported marriage."
Section 216(h)(3), as set forth in 42 U.S.C. § 416(h)(3),
provides:
"An applicant who is the son or daughter of a fully or currently
insured individual, but who is not (and is not deemed to be) the
child of such insured individual under paragraph (2) of this
subsection, shall nevertheless be deemed to be the chi!d of such
insured individual if:"
" * * * *" "(C) In the case of a deceased individual --"
"(i) such insured individual -- "
"(I) had acknowledged in writing that the applicant is his son
or daughter,"
"(II) had been decreed by a court to be the father of the
applicant, or"
"(III) had been ordered by a court to contribute to the support
of the applicant because the applicant was his son or
daughter,"
"and such acknowledgment, court decree, or court order was made
before the death of such individual, or"
"(ii) such insured individual is shown by evidence satisfactory
to the Secretary to have been the father of the applicant, and such
insured individual was living with or contributing to the support
of the applicant at the time such insured individual died."
[ Footnote 4 ]
Upon the original petition for review under § 205(g), the
District Court affirmed the administrative findings that had then
been made, but remanded the case to the Secretary for him to
determine the common law status of the relationship between the
children's parents, a question left unconsidered in the first
administrative proceeding. After an adverse determination on this
point and an unsuccessful administrative appeal, Lucas, on behalf
of the children, again timely sought review in the District Court,
presenting the common law marriage question and asserting a
constitutional challenge to the Act. The District Court affirmed
the administrative conclusion of no common law marriage, and then
turned to the constitutional questions that are the subject of this
appeal.
[ Footnote 5 ] See, e.g., Jimenez v. Weinberger, 417 U.S. at 417 U. S. 637 ; United States Dept. of Agriculture v. Moreno, 413 U.
S. 528 , 413 U. S. 533 n. 5 (1973); Frontiero v. Richardson, 411 U.
S. 677 , 411 U. S. 680 n. 5 (1973) (plurality opinion).
[ Footnote 6 ]
The District Court affirmed the Secretary's factual findings in
a "Memorandum and Order" entered August 30, 1974, Viewing the
constitutional claim as one requiring the convention of a
three-judge district court under 28 U.S.C. §§ 2282 and 2284, the
single District Judge did not reach that issue. A three-judge
District Court was convened, but disbanded when appellees' renewed
motion for summary judgment omitted their earlier request for
injunctive relief. The constitutional claim thus was correctly
determined by a single District Judge.
[ Footnote 7 ]
It adds nothing to say that the illegitimate child is also
saddled with the procedural burden of proving entitlement on the
basis of facts the legitimate child need not prove. The legitimate
child is required, like the illegitimate, to prove the facts upon
which his statutory entitlement rests.
[ Footnote 8 ]
Appellees do not suggest, nor could they successfully, that
strict judicial scrutiny of the statutory classifications is
required here because, in regulating entitlement to survivorship
benefits, the statute discriminatorily interferes with interests of
constitutional fundamentality. Weinberger v. Salfi, 422 U. S. 749 , 422 U. S.
768 -770 (1975); Dandridge v. Williams, 397 U. S. 471 (1970).
The Court, of course, has found the privacy of familial
relationships to be entitled to procedural due process protections
from disruption by the State, whether or not those relationships
were legitimized by marriage under state law. Stanley v.
Illinois, 405 U. S. 645 (1972). But the concerns relevant to that context are only
tangential to the analysis here, since the statutory scheme does
not interfere in any way with familial relations.
[ Footnote 9 ] See Loving v. Virginia, 388 U. S.
1 , 388 U. S. 11 (1967); Bolling v. Sharpe, 347 U.
S. 497 (1954).
[ Footnote 10 ] See Oyama v. California, 332 U.
S. 633 , 332 U. S.
644 -646 (1948); Korematsu v. United States, 323 U. S. 214 , 323 U. S. 216 (1944); Hirabayashi v. United States, 320 U. S.
81 , 320 U. S. 100 (1943).
[ Footnote 11 ]
That the statutory classifications challenged here discriminate
among illegitimate children does not mean, of course, that they are
not also properly described as discriminating between legitimate
and illegitimate children. See Frontiero v. Richardson, supra;
cf. Weber v. Aetna Casualty & Surety Co., 406 U.
S. 164 , 406 U. S. 169 ,
172 (1972). In view of our conclusion regarding the applicable
standard of judicial scrutiny, we need not consider how the classes
of legitimate and illegitimate children would be constitutionally
defined under appellees' approach.
[ Footnote 12 ]
The significance of this consideration would seem to be
suggested by provisions enabling the parents to legitimatize
children born illegitimate. Compare Weber, 406 U.S. at 406 U. S.
170 -171, with Labine v. Vincent, 401 U.
S. 532 , 401 U. S. 539 (1971). Of course, the status of "dependency" as recognized by the
statute here is wholly within the control of the parent.
[ Footnote 13 ]
In Rodriguez, the Court identified a "suspect class"
entitled to the protections of strict judicial scrutiny as one
"saddled with such disabilities, or subjected to such a history
of purposeful unequal treatment, or relegated to such a position of
political powerlessness as to command extraordinary protection from
the majoritarian political process."
411 U.S. at 411 U. S. 28 .
[ Footnote 14 ]
We are not bound to agree with the Secretary's description of
the legislative design if the legislative history and the structure
of the provisions themselves belie it. Weinberger v.
Wiesenfeld, 420 U. S. 636 , 420 U. S. 648 n. 16 (1975); Jimenez v. Weinberger, 417 U.S. at 417 U. S. 634 .
Appellees are unable, however, to summon any meaningful legislative
history to support their position regarding the congressional
design. They rely largely upon a section of the House-Senate
Conference Committee Report on the 1965 Amendments to the Social
Security Act, reproduced at 111 Cong.Rec. 18383 (1965), partially
explaining, id. at 18387, the addition of § 216(h)(3), set
forth in n 3, supra, to the Act:
"A child would be paid benefits based on his father's earnings
without regard to whether he has the status of a child under State
inheritance laws if the father was supporting the child or had a
legal obligation to do so."
But the clause's reference to legal obligations to support
hardly establishes that the statute was designed to replace any
potential source of lifetime support; in our view the passage
appears only to be a partial description of the actual effect of §§
416(h)(3)(C)(i)(II) and (III), set forth in n 3, supra, not an enunciation of the general
purpose of the Act.
Thus, appellees, in order to make their case, must ultimately
rely upon the asserted failure of the legislative product
adequately to fit the purported legitimate aim.
[ Footnote 15 ]
That these provisions may thus reflect a "secondary" purpose of
Congress is, of course, of no moment. McGinnis v. Royster, 410 U. S. 263 , 410 U. S.
274 -277 (1973).
[ Footnote 16 ]
Vacated and remanded for further proceedings in light of Jimenez, 418 U.S. 902 (1972); adhered to on remand, 390 F.
Supp. 1084 (1975); aff'd sub nom. Norton v. Mathews,
post, p. 427 U. S. 524 .
[ Footnote 17 ]
The Secretary, pointing out that § 202(d)(3), as set forth in 42
U.S.C. § 402(d)(3), in specific terms provides only that
"a child deemed to be a child of a fully or currently insured
individual pursuant to section 416(h)(2)(B) or section 416(h)(3). .
. shall be deemed to be the legitimate child of such
individual,"
urges that we misconstrued the statute in Jimenez, 417 U.S. at 417 U. S. 631 n. 2, in concluding that an applicant qualifying as a child under §
216(h)(2)(A) is to be considered as a legitimate child,
and therefore dependent under § 202(d)(3). We have no question,
however, as to the correctness of that conclusion. First, it is
only through operation of § 216(h)(2)(A) that the recognition of
"legitimacy" by state law under § 202(d)(3)(A) as giving rise to a
presumption of dependency takes on a consistent operational
meaning. Second, §§ 216(h)(2)(B) and (3) specifically exclude any
child qualified under § 216(h)(2)(A); if a § 216(h)(2)(A) child
were not considered legitimate under § 202(d)(3), this would have
the anomalous effect that an illegitimate child who had been
acknowledged in a written statement by the insured father, for
example, would be deprived of otherwise established eligibility for
benefits, see § 216(h)(3)(C)(i)(I), if under applicable
state law such an acknowledgment worked to make the child an
intestate heir. Moreover, the legislative history is clear that the
Social Security Amendments of 1960, Pub.L. 86-778, 74 Stat. 924, §§
208(b) and (d), 42 U.S.C. § 408(b) and (d), adding § 216(h)(2)(b)
to the Act and inserting the provision in § 202(d)(3) specifying
that a § 216(h)(2)(B) child shall be deemed to be a legitimate, and
therefore dependent, child for death benefit purposes, were
intended to have the effect of deeming any § 216(h)(2)
child "legitimate," and thus "dependent." See S.Rep. No.
1856, 86th Cong., 2d Sess., 78-79, 133 (1960) (discussing §§ 207(b)
and (d)); H.R.Rep. No. 1799, 86th Cong., 2d Sess., 91-92, 152
(1960).
[ Footnote 18 ]
Appellees do not suggest, and we are unwilling to assume, that
discrimination against children in appellees' class in state
intestacy laws is constitutionally prohibited, see Labine v.
Vincent, 401 U. S. 532 (1971), in which case appellees would be made eligible for benefits
under § 216(h)(2)(A).
MR. JUSTICE STEVENS, with whom MR. JUSTICE BRENNAN and MR.
JUSTICE MARSHALL join, dissenting.
The reason why the United States Government should not add to
the burdens that illegitimate children inevitably acquire at birth
is radiantly clear: we are committed to the proposition that all
persons are created equal. The Court's reason for approving
discrimination against this class -- "administrative convenience"
-- is opaque and insufficient: opaque because the difference
between this justification and the argument rejected in Jimenez
v. Weinberger, 417 U. S. 628 , is
so difficult to Page 427 U. S. 517 discern; insufficient because it unfairly evaluates the
competing interests at stake. I Jimenez involved a requirement that the wage earner
must have contributed to the support of his illegitimate child
prior to the onset of his disability; this case involves the
requirement that the deceased wage earner was contributing to the
support of his illegitimate child at the time of his death. The
critical objections to the classification held invalid in Jimenez apply with equal force in this case.
The classification in Jimenez was "overinclusive"
because it conclusively presumed that all legitimates and some
illegitimates were dependent on the disabled wage earner when many
such persons were not in fact dependent. Since legitimate as well
as illegitimate children are sometimes abandoned by their father
before his death, precisely the same objection applies to this
statutory classification. Moreover, the Jimenez classification was "underinclusive" because it conclusively
excluded some illegitimates who were in fact dependent on the wage
earner. [ Footnote 2/1 ] In this
case, the two appellee children Page 427 U. S. 518 were conclusively excluded from the class of eligibles even
though they had been supported by their father for 15 years and
eight years, respectively. If the underinclusiveness of the Jimenez classification was arbitrary, this classification
is even more objectionable, because it attaches greater weight to
support at a particular moment in time than to support of several
years' duration.
In Jimenez, the Secretary told the Court that the
classification was "designed only to prevent spurious claims." Id. at 417 U. S. 633 .
The Court held that objective insufficient to justify "the blanket
and conclusive exclusion" of a subclass of illegitimates. Id. at 417 U. S. 636 .
The statute has not changed, but now we are told that the
justification for a similar blanket and conclusive exclusion is
"administrative convenience." I suggest that this is merely a
different name for the same federal interest. For the statutory
classification will not affect the processing of claims in any way
except by substituting a mechanical test of dependency for the kind
of inquiry that would otherwise be required to differentiate
between the spurious and the genuine.
I am unable to identify a relevant difference between Jimenez and this case. II The Court recognizes
"that the legal status of illegitimacy, however defined, is,
like race or national origin, a characteristic determined by causes
not within the control of the illegitimate individual, and it bears
no relation to the individual's ability to participate in and
contribute to society." Ante at 427 U. S. 505 .
For that reason, as the Court also recognizes,
"'imposing disabilities on the illegitimate child is contrary to
the basic concept of our system that legal burdens should bear some
relationship Page 427 U. S. 519 to individual responsibility or wrongdoing.'" Ibid. Thus, the Court starts its analysis from the
premise that the statutory classification is both " illogical
and unjust.'" Ibid. It seems rather plain to me that this
premise demands a conclusion that the classification is invalid
unless it is justified by a weightier governmental interest than
merely "administrative convenience." The Court has characterized the purpose of the statute as
providing benefits not for those individuals who had a legitimate
claim to support from the deceased wage earner, but rather for
those who were actually dependent on the wage earner at the time of
his death. In this analysis, the provisions of the statute which
allow certain classes -- such as legitimate children -- to receive
benefits without showing actual dependency are no more than
statutory presumptions in aid of administrative convenience. This
is an appropriate reading of the statute. [ Footnote 2/2 ]
The Court goes on, however, to hold that such presumptions in
aid of "administrative convenience" are permissible so long as the
lack of precise equivalence between the fact giving rise to the
presumption and the fact presumed "does not exceed the bounds of
substantiality tolerated by the applicable level of scrutiny," ante at 427 U. S. 509 .
The opinion tells us very little, however, about the "applicable
level of scrutiny." It is not "our most exacting scrutiny," ante at 427 U. S. 506 ;
on the other hand, if the classification derives "possibly
rational" support from another source, it is not "inherently
untenable" simply because it rests in part on illegitimacy. Ante at 427 U. S. 505 .
I believe an admittedly illogical and unjust result Page 427 U. S. 520 should not be accepted without both a better explanation and
also something more than a "possibly rational" basis.
The Court has repeatedly held that distinctions which disfavor
illegitimates simply because they are illegitimate are invalid. Gomez v. Perez, 409 U. S. 535 ; Weber v. Aetna Casualty & Surety Co., 406 U.
S. 164 . However irrational it may be to burden innocent
children because their parents did not marry, illegitimates are
nonetheless a traditionally disfavored class in our society.
Because of that tradition of disfavor, the Court should be
especially vigilant in examining any classification which involves
illegitimacy. For a traditional classification is more likely to be
used without pausing to consider its justification than is a newly
created classification. Habit, rather than analysis, makes it seem
acceptable and natural to distinguish between male and female,
alien and citizen, legitimate and illegitimate; for too much of our
history, there was the same inertia in distinguishing between black
and white. But that sort of stereotyped reaction may have no
rational relationship -- other than pure prejudicial discrimination
[ Footnote 2/3 ] -- to the Page 427 U. S. 521 stated purpose for which the classification is being made.
In this case, the "true" classification, according to the Court,
is one between children dependent on their fathers and children who
are not so dependent. All of the subsidiary classifications (which
have the actual effect of allowing certain children to be eligible
for benefits regardless of actual dependency) are supposedly
justified by the increased convenience for the agency in not being
required in every case to determine dependency. But do these
classifications actually bear any substantial relationship to the
fact of dependency?
In this statute, one or another of the criteria giving rise to a
"presumption of dependency" exists to make almost all children of
deceased wage earners eligible. If a child is legitimate, he
qualifies. If the child is illegitimate only because of a
nonobvious defect in his parents' marriage, he qualifies. If a
court has declared his father to be in fact his father, or has
issued an order of support against his father, or if the father has
acknowledged the child in writing, he qualifies. Apart from any of
these qualifications, if the child is lucky enough to live in a
State which allows him to inherit from his intestate father on a
par with other children, he also qualifies. And in none of these
situations need he allege, much less prove, actual dependency.
Indeed, if the contrary fact is undisputed, he is nevertheless
qualified.
The Court today attempts, at some length, to explain that each
of these factors is rationally and substantially related to the
actual fact of dependency, adopting even the somewhat tenuous
rationalization of the District Court that
"'[m]en do not customarily affirm in writing their
responsibility for an illegitimate child unless the Page 427 U. S. 522 child is theirs and a man who has acknowledged a child is more
likely to provide it support than one who does not,'" ante at 427 U. S. 514 ,
without also noting that a man who lives with a woman for 18 years,
during which two children are born, who has always orally
acknowledged that the children are his, and who has lived with the
children and supported them, may never perceive a need to make a
formal written acknowledgment of paternity. Even more tenuous is
the asserted relationship between the status of the illegitimate
under state intestacy law and actual dependency. The Court asserts
that,
"in its embodiment of the popular view within the jurisdiction
of how a parent would have his property devolve among his children
in the event of death, without specific directions, such
legislation also reflects to some degree the popular conception
within the jurisdiction of the felt parental obligation to such an
'illegitimate' child in other circumstances, and thus something of
the likelihood of actual parental support during, as well as after,
life." Ante at 427 U. S.
514 -515. That nebulous inference upon inference is
treated as more acceptable evidence of actual dependency than proof
of actual support for many years. [ Footnote 2/4 ]
Whether the classification is expressed in terms of eligible
classes or in terms of presumptions of dependency, the fact remains
that legitimacy, written acknowledgments, or state law make
eligible many children who are no more likely to be "dependent"
than are the children in appellees' situation. Yet, in the name of
"administrative convenience," the Court allows these survivors'
benefits to be allocated on grounds which have Page 427 U. S. 523 only the most tenuous connection to the supposedly controlling
factor -- the child's dependency on his father.
I am persuaded that the classification which is sustained today
in the name of "administrative convenience" is more probably the
product of a tradition of thinking of illegitimates as less
deserving persons than legitimates. The sovereign should firmly
reject that tradition. The fact that illegitimacy is not as
apparent to the observer as sex or race does not make this
governmental classification any less odious. It cannot be denied
that it is a source of social opprobrium, even if wholly unmerited,
or that it is a circumstance for which the individual has no
responsibility whatsoever
A fair evaluation of the competing interests at stake in this
litigation requires affirmance of the judgment of the District
Court.
I respectfully dissent.
[ Footnote 2/1 ]
"Even if children might rationally be classified on the basis of
whether they are dependent upon their disabled parent, the Act's
definition of these two subclasses of illegitimates is
'overinclusive' in that it benefits some children who are
legitimated, or entitled to inherit, or illegitimate solely because
of a defect in the marriage of their parents, but who are not
dependent on their disabled parent. Conversely, the Act is
'underinclusive' in that it conclusively excludes some
illegitimates in appellants' subclass who are, in fact, dependent
upon their disabled parent. Thus, for all that is shown in this
record, the two subclasses of illegitimates stand on equal footing,
and the potential for spurious claims is the same as to both;
hence, to conclusively deny one subclass benefits presumptively
available to the other denies the former the equal protection of
the laws guaranteed by the due process provision of the Fifth
Amendment."
417 U.S. at 417 U. S.
637 .
[ Footnote 2/2 ]
There are other survivors who receive benefits only if they show
dependency, e.g., parents, 42 U.S.C. § 402(h), and
widowers, 42 U.S.C.§ 402(f).
[ Footnote 2/3 ]
Such pure discrimination is most certainly not a "legitimate
purpose" for our Federal Government, which should be especially
sensitive to discrimination on grounds of birth.
"Distinctions between citizens solely because of their ancestry
are, by their very nature, odious to a free people whose
institutions are founded upon the doctrine of equality." Hirabayashi v. United States, 320 U. S.
81 , 320 U. S. 100 .
From its inception, the Federal Government has been directed to
treat all its citizens as having been "created equal" in the eyes
of the law. The Declaration of Independence states:
"We hold these truths to be self-evident, that all men are
created equal, that they are endowed by their Creator with certain
unalienable Rights, that among these are Life, Liberty and the
pursuit of Happiness."
And the rationale behind the prohibition against the grant of
any title of nobility by the United States, see U.S.Const., Art. I, § 9, cl. 8, equally would prohibit the United
States from attaching any badge of ignobility to a citizen at
birth.
[ Footnote 2/4 ]
If the relationship between an entitling presumption and the
actual fact of dependency is so nebulous that the conclusion can be
supported only by resort to a supposed popular conception within a
jurisdiction, the classification must either be irrational or serve
a purpose other than the one by which it is assertedly
justified. | Here is a summary of the case:
In Mathews v. Lucas, the United States Supreme Court considered whether the denial of surviving child benefits to illegitimate children under the Social Security Act violated the equal protection component of the Due Process Clause of the Fifth Amendment. The Court held that the different treatment of legitimate and illegitimate children under the Act was not subject to the same level of judicial scrutiny as discrimination based on race or national origin.
The Court upheld the Act's dependency requirements for surviving child benefits, finding that they were reasonably related to the likelihood of dependency at the time of the parent's death. The Court also found that the Act did not impermissibly discriminate against illegitimate children by failing to extend a presumption of dependency to them, as it did for legitimate children and some illegitimate children in specific circumstances.
The Court's decision affirmed the District Court's ruling, which had reversed the administrative denial of benefits to the appellee illegitimate children and ordered that benefits be paid to them. |
Equal Protection | Village of Arlington Heights v. Metropolitan Housing Dev. Corp. | https://supreme.justia.com/cases/federal/us/429/252/ | U.S. Supreme Court Arlington Heights v. Metropolitan
Housing Dev. Corp., 429
U.S. 252 (1977) Village of Arlington Heights v.
Metropolitan Housing Development
Corp. No. 75-616 Argued October 13,
1976 Decided January 11,
1977 429
U.S. 252 CERTIORARI TO THE UNITED STATES
COURT OF APPEALS FOR THE SEVENTH
CIRCUIT Syllabus Respondent Metropolitan Housing Development Corp. (MHDC), a
nonprofit developer, contracted to purchase a tract within the
boundaries of petitioner Village in order to build racially
integrated low- and moderate-income housing. The contract was
contingent upon securing rezoning as well as federal housing
assistance. MHDC applied to the Village for the necessary rezoning
from a single-family to a multiple-family (R-5) classification. At
a series of Village Plan Commission public meetings, both
supporters and opponents touched upon the fact that the project
would probably be racially integrated. Opponents also stressed
zoning factors that pointed toward denial of MHDC's application:
the location had always been zoned single-family, and the Village's
apartment policy called for limited use of R-5 zoning, primarily as
a buffer between single-family development and commercial or
manufacturing districts, none of which adjoined the project's
proposed location. After the Village denied rezoning, MHDC and
individual minority respondents filed this suit for injunctive and
declaratory relief, alleging that the denial was racially
discriminatory and violated, inter alia, the Equal
Protection Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment and the Fair Housing
Act. The District Court held that the Village's rezoning denial was
motivated not by racial discrimination but by a desire to protect
property values and maintain the Village's zoning plan. Though
approving those conclusions, the Court of Appeals reversed, finding
that the "ultimate effect" of the rezoning denial was racially
discriminatory and observing that the denial would
disproportionately affect blacks, particularly in view of the fact
that the general suburban area, though economically expanding,
continued to be marked by residential segregation. Held: 1. MHDC and at least one individual respondent have standing to
bring this action. Pp. 429 U. S.
260 -264.
(a) MHDC has met the constitutional standing requirements by
showing injury fairly traceable to petitioners' acts. The
challenged action of the Village stands as an absolute barrier to
constructing the housing for which MHDC had contracted, a barrier
which could be Page 429 U. S. 253 removed if injunctive relief were granted. MHDC, despite the
contingency provisions in its contract, has suffered economic
injury based upon the expenditures it made in support of its
rezoning petition, as well as noneconomic injury from the defeat of
its objective, embodied in its specific project, of making suitable
low-cost housing available where such housing is scarce. Pp. 429 U. S.
261 -263.
(b) Whether MHDC has standing to assert the constitutional
rights of its prospective minority tenants need not be decided, for
at least one of the individual respondents, a Negro working in the
Village and desirous of securing low-cost housing there but who now
lives 20 miles away, has standing. Focusing on the specific MHDC
project, he has adequately alleged an "actionable causal
relationship" between the Village's zoning practices and his
asserted injury. Warth v. Seldin, 422 U.
S. 490 , 422 U. S. 507 .
Pp. 429 U. S.
263 -264.
2. Proof of a racially discriminatory intent or purpose is
required to show a violation of the Equal Protection Clause of the
Fourteenth Amendment, and respondents failed to carry their burden
of proving that such an intent or purpose was a motivating factor
in the Village's rezoning decision. Pp. 429 U.S. 264 -271.
(a) Official action will not be held unconstitutional solely
because it results in a racially disproportionate impact. "[Such]
impact is not irrelevant, but it is not the sole touchstone of an
invidious racial discrimination." Washington v. Davis, 426 U. S. 229 , 426 U. S. 242 .
A racially discriminatory intent, as evidenced by such factors as
disproportionate impact, the historical background of the
challenged decision, the specific antecedent events, departures
from normal procedures, and contemporary statements of the
decisionmakers, must be shown. Pp. 429 U.S. 264 -268.
(b) The evidence does not warrant overturning the concurrent
findings of both courts below that there was no proof warranting
the conclusion that the Village's rezoning decision was racially
motivated. Pp. 429 U. S.
268 -271.
3. The statutory question whether the rezoning decision violated
the Fair Housing Act of 1968 was not decided by the Court of
Appeals, and should be considered on remand. P. 429 U. S.
271 .
517 F.2d 409, reversed and remanded.
POWELL, J., delivered the opinion of the Court, in which BURGER,
C.J., and STEWART, BLACKMUN, and REHNQUIST, JJ., joined. MARSHALL,
J., filed an opinion concurring in part and dissenting in part, in
which BRENNAN, J., joined, post, p. 429 U. S. 271 .
WHITE, J., filed a dissenting opinion, post, p. 429 U. S. 272 .
STEVENS, J., took no part in the consideration or decision of the
case. Page 429 U. S. 254 MR. JUSTICE POWELL delivered the opinion of the Court.
In 1971, respondent Metropolitan Housing Development Corporation
(MHDC) applied to petitioner, the Village of Arlington Heights,
Ill., for the rezoning of a 15-acre parcel from single-family to
multiple family classification. Using federal financial assistance,
MHDC planned to build 190 clustered townhouse units for low- and
moderate-income tenants. The Village denied the rezoning request.
MHDC, joined by other plaintiffs who are also respondents here,
brought suit in the United States District Court for the Northern
District of Illinois. [ Footnote
1 ] They alleged that the denial was racially discriminatory and
that it violated, inter alia, the Fourteenth Amendment and
the Fair Housing Act of 1968, 82 Stat. 81, 42 U.S.C. 3601 et
seq. Following a bench trial, the District Court entered
judgment for the Village, 373 F.
Supp. 208 (1974), and respondents appealed. The Court of
Appeals for the Seventh Circuit reversed, finding that the
"ultimate effect" of the denial was racially discriminatory, and
that the refusal to rezone therefore violated the Fourteenth
Amendment. 517 F.2d 409 (1975). We granted Page 429 U. S. 255 the Village's petition for certiorari, 423 U.S. 1030 (1975), and
now reverse. I Arlington Heights is a suburb of Chicago, located about 26 miles
northwest of the downtown Loop area. Most of the land in Arlington
Heights is zoned for detached single-family homes, and this is in
fact the prevailing land use. The Village experienced substantial
growth during the 1960's, but, like other communities in northwest
Cook County, its population of racial minority groups remained
quite low. According to the 1970 census, only 27 of the Village's
64,000 residents were black.
The Clerics of St. Viator, a religious order (Order), own an
80-acre parcel just east of the center of Arlington Heights. Part
of the site is occupied by the Viatorian high school, and part by
the Order's three-story novitiate building, which houses
dormitories and a Montessori school. Much of the site, however,
remains vacant. Since 1959, when the Village first adopted a zoning
ordinance, all the land surrounding the Viatorian property has been
zoned R-3, a single-family specification with relatively small
minimum lot-size requirements. On three sides of the Viatorian land
there are single-family homes just across a street; to the east,
the Viatorian property directly adjoins the backyards of other
single-family homes.
The Order decided in 1970 to devote some of its land to low- and
moderate-income housing. Investigation revealed that the most
expeditious way to build such housing was to work through a
nonprofit developer experienced in the use of federal housing
subsidies under § 236 of the National Housing Act, 48 Stat. 1246,
as added and amended, 12 U.S.C. § 17I5z-1. [ Footnote 2 ] Page 429 U. S. 256 MHDC is such a developer. It was organized in 1968 by several
prominent Chicago citizens for the purpose of building low- and
moderate-income housing throughout the Chicago area. In 1970, MHDC
was in the process of building one § 236 development near Arlington
Heights, and already had provided some federally assisted housing
on a smaller scale in other parts of the Chicago area.
After some negotiation, MHDC and the Order entered into a
99-year lease and an accompanying agreement of sale covering a
15-acre site in the southeast corner of the Viatorian property.
MHDC became the lessee immediately, but the sale agreement was
contingent upon MHDC's securing zoning clearances from the Village
and § 236 housing assistance from the Federal Government. If MHDC
proved unsuccessful in securing either, both the lease and the
contract of sale would lapse. The agreement established a bargain
purchase price of $300,000, low enough to comply with federal
limitations governing land-acquisition costs for § 236 housing.
MHDC engaged an architect and proceeded with the project, Page 429 U. S. 257 to be known as Lincoln Green. The plans called for 20 two-story
buildings with a total of 190 units, each unit having its own
private entrance from the outside. One hundred of the units would
have a single bedroom, thought likely to attract elderly citizens.
The remainder would have two, three, or four bedrooms. A large
portion of the site would remain open, with shrubs and trees to
screen the homes abutting the property to the east.
The planned development did not conform to the Village's zoning
ordinance, and could not be built unless Arlington Heights rezoned
the parcel to R-5, its multiple family housing classification.
Accordingly, MHDC filed with the Village Plan Commission a petition
for rezoning, accompanied by supporting materials describing the
development and specifying that it would be subsidized under § 236.
The materials made clear that one requirement under § 236 is an
affirmative marketing plan designed to assure that a subsidized
development is racially integrated. MHDC also submitted studies
demonstrating the need for housing of this type and analyzing the
probable impact of the development. To prepare for the hearings
before the Plan Commission and to assure compliance with the
Village building code, fire regulations, and related requirements,
MHDC consulted with the Village staff for preliminary review of the
development. The parties have stipulated that every change
recommended during such consultations was incorporated into the
plans.
During the spring of 1971, the Plan Commission considered the
proposal at a series of three public meetings, which drew large
crowds. Although many of those attending were quite vocal and
demonstrative in opposition to Lincoln Green, a number of
individuals and representatives of community groups spoke in
support of rezoning. Some of the comments, both from opponents and
supporters, addressed what was referred to as the "social issue" --
the desirability or undesirability of introducing at this location
in Arlington Heights Page 429 U. S. 258 low- and moderate income housing, housing that would probably be
racially integrated.
Many of the opponents, however, focused on the zoning aspects of
the petition, stressing two arguments. First, the area always had
been zoned single-family, and the neighboring citizens had built or
purchased there in reliance on that classification. Rezoning
threatened to cause a measurable drop in property value for
neighboring sites. Second, the Village's apartment policy, adopted
by the Village Board in 1962 and amended in 1970, called for R-5
zoning primarily to serve as a buffer between single-family
development and land uses thought incompatible, such as commercial
or manufacturing districts. Lincoln Green did not meet this
requirement, as it adjoined no commercial or manufacturing
district.
At the close of the third meeting, the Plan Commission adopted a
motion to recommend to the Village's Board of Trustees that it deny
the request. The motion stated:
"While the need for low and moderate income housing may exist in
Arlington Heights or its environs, the Plan Commission would be
derelict in recommending it at the proposed location."
Two members voted against the motion and submitted a minority
report, stressing that, in their view, the change to accommodate
Lincoln Green represented "good zoning." The Village Board met on
September 28, 1971, to consider MHDC's request and the
recommendation of the Plan Commission. After a public hearing, the
Board denied the rezoning by a 6-1 vote.
The following June, MHDC and three Negro individuals filed this
lawsuit against the Village, seeking declaratory and injunctive
relief. [ Footnote 3 ] A second
nonprofit corporation and an individual of Mexican-American descent
intervened as plaintiffs. Page 429 U. S. 259 The trial resulted in a judgment for petitioners. Assuming that
MHDC had standing to bring the suit, [ Footnote 4 ] the District Court held that the petitioners
were not motivated by racial discrimination or intent to
discriminate against low income groups when they denied rezoning,
but rather by a desire "to protect property values and the
integrity of the Village's zoning plan." 373 F. Supp. at 211. The
District Court concluded also that the denial would not have a
racially discriminatory effect.
A divided Court of Appeals reversed. It first approved the
District Court's finding that the defendants were motivated by a
concern for the integrity of the zoning plan, rather than by racial
discrimination. Deciding whether their refusal to rezone would have
discriminatory effects was more complex. The court observed that
the refusal would have a disproportionate impact on blacks. Based
upon family income, blacks constituted 40% of those Chicago area
residents who were eligible to become tenants of Lincoln Green,
although they composed a far lower percentage of total area
population. The court reasoned, however, that, under our decision
in James v. Valtierra, 402 U. S. 137 (1971), such a disparity in racial impact alone does not call for
strict scrutiny of a municipality's decision that prevents the
construction of the low-cost housing. [ Footnote 5 ]
There was another level to the court's analysis of allegedly
discriminatory results. Invoking language from Kennedy Park
Homes Assn. v. City of Lackawanna, 436 F.2d 108, Page 429 U. S. 260 112 (CA2 1970), cert. denied, 401 U.S. 1010 (1971), the
Court of Appeals ruled that the denial of rezoning must be examined
in light of its "historical context and ultimate effect." [ Footnote 6 ] 517 F.2d at 413. Northwest
Cook County was enjoying rapid growth in employment opportunities
and population, but it continued to exhibit a high degree of
residential segregation. The court held that Arlington Heights
could not simply ignore this problem. Indeed, it found that the
Village had been "exploiting" the situation by allowing itself to
become a nearly all-white community. Id. at 414. The
Village had no other current plans for building low- and
moderate-income housing, and no other R-5 parcels in the Village
were available to MHDC at an economically feasible price.
Against this background, the Court of Appeals ruled that the
denial of the Lincoln Green proposal had racially discriminatory
effects and could be tolerated only if it served compelling
interests. Neither the buffer policy nor the desire to protect
property values met this exacting standard. The court therefore
concluded that the denial violated the Equal Protection Clause of
the Fourteenth Amendment. II At the outset, petitioners challenge the respondents' standing
to bring the suit. It is not clear that this challenge was pressed
in the Court of Appeals, but since our jurisdiction to decide the
case is implicated, Jenkins v. McKeithen, 395 U.
S. 411 , 395 U. S. 421 (1969) (plurality opinion), we shall consider it.
In Warth v. Seldin, 422 U. S. 490 (1975), a case similar in some respects to this one, we reviewed
the constitutional limitations and prudential considerations that
guide a court in determining a party's standing, and we need not
repeat that discussion here. The essence of the standing
question, Page 429 U. S. 261 in its constitutional dimension, is
"whether the plaintiff has 'alleged such a personal stake in the
outcome of the controversy' as to warrant his invocation of federal
court jurisdiction and to justify exercise of the court's remedial
powers on his behalf." Id. at 422 U. S.
498 -499, quoting Baker v. Carr, 369 U.
S. 186 , 369 U. S. 204 (1962). The plaintiff must show that he himself is injured by the
challenged action of the defendant. The injury may be indirect, see United States v. SCRAP, 412 U.
S. 669 , 412 U. S. 688 (1973), but the complaint must indicate that the injury is indeed
fairly traceable to the defendant's acts or omissions. Simon v.
Eastern Ky. Welfare Rights Org., 426 U. S.
26 , 426 U. S. 41 -42
(1976); O'Shea v. Littleton, 414 U.
S. 488 , 414 U. S. 498 (1974); Linda R. S. v. Richard D., 410 U.
S. 614 , 410 U. S. 617 (1973). A Here there can be little doubt that MHDC meets the
constitutional standing requirements. The challenged action of the
petitioners stands as an absolute barrier to constructing the
housing MHDC had contracted to place on the Viatorian site. If MHDC
secures the injunctive relief it seeks, that barrier will be
removed. An injunction would not, of course, guarantee that Lincoln
Green will be built. MHDC would still have to secure financing,
qualify for federal subsidies, [ Footnote 7 ] and carry through with construction. But all
housing developments are subject to some extent to similar
uncertainties. When a project is as detailed and specific as
Lincoln Green, a court is not required to engage in undue
speculation Page 429 U. S. 262 as a predicate for finding that the plaintiff has the requisite
personal stake in the controversy. MHDC has shown an injury to
itself that is "likely to be redressed by a favorable decision." Simon v. Eastern Ky. Welfare Rights Org., supra at 426 U. S.
38 .
Petitioners nonetheless appear to argue that MHDC lacks standing
because it has suffered no economic injury. MHDC, they point out,
is not the owner of the property in question. Its contract of
purchase is contingent upon securing rezoning. [ Footnote 8 ] MHDC owes the owners nothing if
rezoning is denied.
We cannot accept petitioners' argument. In the first place, it
is inaccurate to say that MHDC suffers no economic injury from a
refusal to rezone, despite the contingency provisions in its
contract. MHDC has expended thousands of dollars on the plans for
Lincoln Green and on the studies submitted to the Village in
support of the petition for rezoning. Unless rezoning is granted,
many of these plans and studies will be worthless even if MHD finds
another site at an equally attractive price.
Petitioners' argument also misconceives our standing
requirements. It has long been clear that economic injury is not
the only kind of injury that can support a plaintiff's Page 429 U. S. 263 standing. United States v. SCRAP, supra at 412 U. S.
686 -687; Sierra Club v. Morton, 405 U.
S. 727 , 405 U. S. 734 (1972); Data Processing Service v. Camp, 397 U.
S. 150 , 397 U. S. 154 (1970). MHDC is a nonprofit corporation. Its interest in building
Lincoln Green stems not from a desire for economic gain, but rather
from an interest in making suitable low-cost housing available in
areas where such housing is scarce. This is not mere abstract
concern about a problem of general interest. See Sierra Club v.
Morton, supra at 405 U. S. 739 .
The specific project MHDC intends to build, whether or not it will
generate profits, provides that "essential dimension of
specificity" that informs judicial decisionmaking. Schlesinger
v. Reservists to Stop the War, 418 U.
S. 208 , 418 U. S. 221 (1974). B Clearly MHDC has met the constitutional requirements, and it
therefore has standing to assert its own rights. Foremost among
them is MHDC's right to be free of arbitrary or irrational zoning
actions. See Euclid v. Ambler Realty Co., 272 U.
S. 365 (1926); Nectow v. City of Cambridge, 277 U. S. 183 (1928); Village of Belle Terre v. Boraas, 416 U. S.
1 (1974). But the heart of this litigation has never
been the claim that the Village's decision fails the generous Euclid test, recently reaffirmed in Belle Terre. Instead, it has been the claim that the Village's refusal to rezone
discriminates against racial minorities in violation of the
Fourteenth Amendment. As a corporation, MHDC has no racial identity
and cannot be the direct target of the petitioners' alleged
discrimination. In the ordinary case, a party is denied standing to
assert the rights of third persons. Warth v. Seldin, 422
U.S. at 422 U. S. 499 .
But we need not decide whether the circumstances of this case would
justify departure from that prudential limitation and permit MHDC
to assert the constitutional rights of its prospective minority
tenants. See Barrows v. Jackson, 346 U.
S. 249 (1953); cf. 396 U. S. Page 429 U. S. 264 Little Hunting Park, 396 U. S. 229 , 396 U. S. 237 (1969); Buchanan v. Warley, 245 U. S.
60 , 245 U. S. 72 -73
(1917). For we have at least one individual plaintiff who has
demonstrated standing to assert these rights as his own. [ Footnote 9 ]
Respondent Ransom, a Negro, works at the Honeywell factory in
Arlington Heights and lives approximately 20 miles away in Evanston
in a 5-room house with his mother and his son. The complaint
alleged that he seeks and would qualify for the housing MHDC wants
to build in Arlington Heights. Ransom testified at trial that, if
Lincoln Green were built he would probably move there, since it is
closer to his job.
The injury Ransom asserts is that his quest for housing nearer
his employment has been thwarted by official action that is
racially discriminatory. If a court grants the relief he seeks,
there is at least a "substantial probability," Warth v. Seldin,
supra at 422 U. S. 504 ,
that the Lincoln Green project will materialize, affording Ransom
the housing opportunity he desires in Arlington Heights. His is not
a generalized grievance. Instead, as we suggested in Warth,
supra at 422 U. S. 507 , 422 U. S. 508 n. 18, it focuses on a particular project and is not dependent on
speculation about the possible actions of third parties not before
the court. See id. at 422 U. S. 505 ; Simon v. Eastern Ky. Welfare Rights Org., 426 U.S. at 426 U. S. 41 -42.
Unlike the individual plaintiffs in Warth, Ransom has
adequately averred an "actionable causal relationship" between
Arlington Heights' zoning practices and his asserted injury. Warth v. Seldin, supra at 422 U. S. 507 .
We therefore proceed to the merits. III Our decision last Term, in Washington v. Davis, 426 U. S. 229 (1976), made it clear that official action will not be held Page 429 U. S. 265 unconstitutional solely because it results in a racially
disproportionate impact. "Disproportionate impact is not
irrelevant, but it is not the sole touchstone of an invidious
racial discrimination." Id. at 426 U. S. 242 .
Proof of racially discriminatory intent or purpose is required to
show a violation of the Equal Protection Clause. Although some
contrary indications may be drawn from some of our cases, [ Footnote 10 ] the holding in Davis reaffirmed a principle well established in a variety
of contexts. E.g., Keyes v. School Dist. No. 1, Denver,
Colo., 413 U. S. 189 , 413 U. S. 208 (1973) (schools); Wright v. Rockefeller, 376 U. S.
52 , 376 U. S. 56 -57
(1964) (election districting); Akins v. Texas, 325 U. S. 398 , 325 U. S.
403 -404 (1945) (jury selection). Davis does not require a plaintiff to prove that the
challenged action rested solely on racially discriminatory
purposes. Rarely can it be said that a legislature or
administrative body operating under a broad mandate made a decision
motivated solely by a single concern, or even that a particular
purpose was the "dominant" or "primary" one. [ Footnote 11 ] In fact, it is because legislators
and administrators are properly concerned with balancing numerous
competing considerations that courts refrain from reviewing the
merits of their decisions, absent a showing of arbitrariness or
irrationality. But racial discrimination is not just another
competing consideration. When there is a proof that a
discriminatory purpose Page 429 U. S. 266 has been a motivating factor in the decision, this judicial
deference is no longer justified. [ Footnote 12 ]
Determining whether invidious discriminatory purpose was a
motivating factor demands a sensitive inquiry into such
circumstantial and direct evidence of intent as may be available.
The impact of the official action -- whether it "bears more heavily
on one race than another," Washington v. Davis, supra at 426 U. S. 242 -- may provide an important starting point. Sometimes a clear
pattern, unexplainable on grounds other than race, emerges from the
effect of the state action even when the governing legislation
appears neutral on its face. Yick Wo v. Hopkins, 118 U. S. 356 (1886); Guinn v. United States, 238 U.
S. 347 (1915); Lane v. Wilson, 307 U.
S. 268 (1939); Gomillion v. Lightfoot, 364 U. S. 339 (1960). The evidentiary inquiry is then relatively easy. [ Footnote 13 ] But such cases are
rare. Absent a pattern as stark as that in Gomillion or Yick Wo, impact alone is not determinative, [ Footnote 14 ] and the Court must look
to other evidence. [ Footnote
15 ] Page 429 U. S. 267 The historical background of the decision is one evidentiary
source, particularly if it reveals a series of official actions
taken for invidious purposes. See Lane v. Wilson, supra;
Griffin v. School Board, 377 U. S. 218 (1964); Davis v. Schnell, 81 F.
Supp. 872 (SD Ala.), aff'd per curiam, 336 U.S. 933
(1949); cf. Keyes v. School Dist. No. 1, Denver Colo.
supra at 413 U. S. 207 .
The specific sequence of events leading up to the challenged
decision also may shed some light on the decisionmaker's purposes. Reitman v. Mulkey, 387 U. S. 369 , 387 U. S.
373 -376 (1967); Grosjean v. American Press Co., 297 U. S. 233 , 297 U. S. 250 (1936). For example, if the property involved here always had been
zoned R-5 but suddenly was changed to R-3 when the town learned of
MHDC's plan to erect integrated housing, [ Footnote 16 ] we would have a far different case.
Departures from the normal procedural sequence also might afford
evidence that improper purposes are playing a role. Substantive
departures too may be relevant, particularly if the factors usually
considered important by the decisionmaker strongly favor a decision
contrary to the one reached. [ Footnote 17 ] Page 429 U. S. 268 The legislative or administrative history may be highly
relevant, especially where there are contemporary statements by
members of the decisionmaking body, minutes of its meetings, or
reports. In some extraordinary instances, the members might be
called to the stand at trial to testify concerning the purpose of
the official action, although even then such testimony frequently
will be barred by privilege. See Tenney v. Brandhove, 341 U. S. 367 (1951); United States v. Nixon, 418 U.
S. 683 , 418 U. S. 705 (1974); 8 J. Wigmore, Evidence § 2371 (McNaughton rev. ed.1961).
[ Footnote 18 ]
The foregoing summary identifies, without purporting to be
exhaustive, subjects of proper inquiry in determining whether
racially discriminatory intent existed. With these in mind, we now
address the case before us. IV This case was tried in the District Court and reviewed in the
Court of Appeals before our decision in Washington v. Davis,
supra. The respondents proceeded on the erroneous theory that
the Village's refusal to rezone carried a racially discriminatory
effect and was, without more, unconstitutional. But both courts
below understood that at least part of their function was to
examine the purpose underlying the decision. Page 429 U. S. 269 In making its findings on this issue, the District Court noted
that some of the opponents of Lincoln Green who spoke at the
various hearings might have been motivated by opposition to
minority groups. The court held, however, that the evidence "does
not warrant the conclusion that this motivated the defendants." 373
F. Supp. at 211.
On appeal, the Court of Appeals focused primarily on
respondents' claim that the Village's buffer policy had not been
consistently applied and was being invoked with a strictness here
that could only demonstrate some other underlying motive. The court
concluded that the buffer policy, though not always applied with
perfect consistency, had on several occasions formed the basis for
the Board's decision to deny other rezoning proposals. "The
evidence does not necessitate a finding that Arlington Heights
administered this policy in a discriminatory manner." 517 F.2d at
412. The Court of Appeals therefore approved the District Court's
findings concerning the Village's purposes in denying rezoning to
MHDC.
We also have reviewed the evidence. The impact of the Village's
decision does arguably bear more heavily on racial minorities.
Minorities constitute 18% of the Chicago area population, and 40%
of the income groups said to be eligible for Lincoln Green. But
there is little about the sequence of events leading up to the
decision that would spark suspicion. The area around the Viatorian
property has been zoned R-3 since 1959, the year when Arlington
Heights first adopted a zoning map. Single-family homes surround
the 80-acre site, and the Village is undeniably committed to
single-family homes as its dominant residential land use. The
rezoning request progressed according to the usual procedures.
[ Footnote 19 ] The Plan
Commission even scheduled two additional Page 429 U. S. 270 hearings, at least in part to accommodate MHDC and permit it to
supplement its presentation with answers to questions generated at
the first hearing.
The statements by the Plan Commission and Village Board members,
as reflected in the official minutes, focused almost exclusively on
the zoning aspects of the MHDC petition, and the zoning factors on
which they relied are not novel criteria in the Village's rezoning
decisions. There is no reason to doubt that there has been reliance
by some neighboring property owners on the maintenance of
single-family zoning in the vicinity. The Village originally
adopted its buffer policy long before MHDC entered the picture, and
has applied the policy too consistently for us to infer
discriminatory purpose from its application in this case. Finally,
MHDC called one member of the Village Board to the stand at trial.
Nothing in her testimony supports an inference of invidious
purpose. [ Footnote 20 ]
In sum, the evidence does not warrant overturning the concurrent
findings of both courts below. Respondents simply failed to carry
their burden of proving that discriminatory purpose was a
motivating factor in the Village's decision. [ Footnote 21 ] Page 429 U. S. 271 This conclusion ends the constitutional inquiry. The Court of
Appeals' further finding that the Village's decision carried a
discriminatory "ultimate effect" is without independent
constitutional significance. V Respondents' complaint also alleged that the refusal to rezone
violated the Fair Housing Act of 1968, 42 U.S.C. § 3601 et
seq. They continue to urge here that a zoning decision made by
a public body may, and that petitioners' action did, violate § 3604
or § 3617. The Court of Appeals, however, proceeding in a somewhat
unorthodox fashion, did not decide the statutory question. We
remand the case for further consideration of respondents' statutory
claims. Reversed and remanded. MR. JUSTICE STEVENS took no part in the consideration or
decision of this case.
[ Footnote 1 ]
Respondents named as defendants both the Village and a number of
its officials, sued in their official capacity. The latter were the
Mayor, the Village Manager, the Director of Building and Zoning,
and the entire Village Board of Trustees. For convenience, we will
occasionally refer to all the petitioners collectively as "the
Village."
[ Footnote 2 ]
Section 236 provides for "interest reduction payments" to owners
of rental housing projects which meet the Act's requirements, if
the savings are passed on to the tenants in accordance with a
rather complex formula. Qualifying owners effectively pay 1%
interest on money borrowed to construct, rehabilitate, or purchase
their properties. (Section 236 has been amended frequently in minor
respects since this litigation began. See 12 U.S.C. §
1715z-1 (1970 ed., Supp. V), and the Housing Authorization Act of
1976, § 4, 90 Stat. 1070.)
New commitments under § 236 were suspended in 1973 by executive
decision, and they have not been revived. Projects which formerly
could claim § 236 assistance, however, will now generally be
eligible for aid under § 8 of the United States Housing Act of
1937, as amended by § 201(a) of the Housing and Community
Development Act of 1974, 42 U.S.C. § 1437f (1970 ed., Supp. V), and
by the Housing Authorization Act of 1976, § 2, 90 Stat. 1068. Under
the § 8 program, the Department of Housing and Urban Development
contracts to pay the owner of the housing units a sum which will
make up the difference between a fair market rent for the area and
the amount contributed by the low-income tenant. The eligible
tenant family pays between 15% and 25% of its gross income for
rent. Respondents indicated at oral argument that, despite the
demise of the § 236 program, construction of the MHDC project could
proceed under § 8 if zoning clearance is now granted.
[ Footnote 3 ]
The individual plaintiffs sought certification of the action as
a class action pursuant to Fed.Rule Civ.Proc. 23 but the District
Court declined to certify. 373 F.
Supp. 208 , 209 (1974).
[ Footnote 4 ]
A different District Judge had heard early motions in the case.
He had sustained the complaint against a motion to dismiss for lack
of standing, and the judge who finally decided the case said he
found "no need to reexamine [the predecessor judge's] conclusions"
in this respect. Ibid. [ Footnote 5 ]
Nor is there reason to subject the Village's action to more
stringent review simply because it involves respondents' interest
in securing housing. Lindsey v. Normet, 405 U. S.
56 , 405 U. S. 73 -74
(1972). See generally San Antonio School Dist. v.
Rodriguez, 411 U. S. 1 , 411 U. S. 18 -39
(1973).
[ Footnote 6 ]
This language apparently derived from our decision in Reitman v. Mulkey, 387 U. S. 369 , 387 U. S. 373 (1967) (quoting from the opinion of the California Supreme Court in
the case then under review).
[ Footnote 7 ]
Petitioners suggest that the suspension of the § 236 housing
assistance program makes it impossible for MHDC to carry out its
proposed project, and therefore deprives MHDC of standing. The
District Court also expressed doubts about MHDC's position in the
case in light of the suspension. 373 F. Supp. at 211. Whether
termination of all available assistance programs would preclude
standing is not a matter we need to decide, in view of the current
likelihood that subsidies may be secured under § 8 of the United
States Housing Act of 1937, as amended by the Housing and Community
Development Act of 1974. See n 2, supra. [ Footnote 8 ]
Petitioners contend that MHDC lacks standing to pursue its claim
here because a contract purchaser whose contract is contingent upon
rezoning cannot contest a zoning decision in the Illinois courts.
Under the law of Illinois, only the owner of the property has
standing to pursue such an action. Clark Oil & Refining
Corp. v. City of Evanston, 23 Ill. 2d
48 , 177 N.E.2d
191 (1961); but see Solomon v. City of Evanston, 29
Ill.App.3d 782, 331 N.E.2d 380 (1975).
State law of standing, however, does not govern such
determinations in the federal courts. The constitutional and
prudential considerations canvassed at length in Warth v.
Seldin, 422 U. S. 490 (1975), respond to concerns that are peculiarly federal in nature.
Illinois may choose to close its courts to applicants for rezoning
unless they have an interest more direct than MHDC's, but this
choice does not necessarily disqualify MHDC from seeking relief in
federal courts for an asserted injury to its federal rights.
[ Footnote 9 ]
Because of the presence of this plaintiff, we need not consider
whether the other individual and corporate plaintiffs have standing
to maintain the suit.
[ Footnote 10 ] Palmer v. Thompson, 403 U. S. 217 , 403 U. S. 225 (1971); Wright v. Council of City of Emporia, 407 U.
S. 451 , 407 U. S.
461 -462 (1972); cf. United States v. O'Brien, 391 U. S. 367 , 391 U. S.
381 -386 (1968). See discussion in Washington v. Davis, 426 U.S. at 426 U. S.
242 -244.
[ Footnote 11 ]
In McGinnis v. Royster, 410 U.
S. 263 , 410 U. S.
276 -277 (1973), in a somewhat different context, we
observed:
"The search for legislative purpose is often elusive enough, Palmer v. Thompson, 403 U. S. 217 (1971), without a
requirement that primacy be ascertained. Legislation is frequently
multi-purposed: the removal of even a 'subordinate' purpose may
shift altogether the consensus of legislative judgment supporting
the statute."
[ Footnote 12 ]
For a scholarly discussion of legislative motivation, see Brest, Palmer v. Thompson: An Approach to the Problem
of Unconstitutional Legislative Motive, 1971 Sup.Ct.Rev. 95,
116-118.
[ Footnote 13 ]
Several of our jury-selection cases fall into this category.
Because of the nature of the jury selection task, however, we have
permitted a finding of constitutional violation even when the
statistical pattern does not approach the extremes of Yick
Wo or Gomillion. See, e.g., Turner v.
Fouche, 396 U. S. 346 , 396 U. S. 359 (1970); Sims v. Georgia, 389 U. S. 404 , 389 U. S. 407 (1967)
[ Footnote 14 ]
This is not to say that a consistent pattern of official racial
discrimination is a necessary predicate to a violation of the Equal
Protection Clause. A single invidiously discriminatory governmental
act -- in the exercise of the zoning power as elsewhere -- would
not necessarily be immunized by the absence of such discrimination
in the making of other comparable decisions. See City of
Richmond v. United States, 422 U. S. 358 , 422 U. S. 378 (1975).
[ Footnote 15 ]
In many instances, to recognize the limited probative value of
disproportionate impact is merely to acknowledge the
"heterogeneity" of the Nation's population. Jefferson v.
Hackney, 406 U. S. 535 , 406 U. S. 548 (1972); see also Washington v. Davis, supra at 426 U. S.
248 .
[ Footnote 16 ] See, e.g., Progress Development Corp. v. Mitchell, 286
F.2d 222 (CA7 1961) (park board allegedly condemned plaintiffs'
land for a park upon learning that the homes plaintiffs were
erecting there would be sold under a marketing plan designed to
assure integration); Kennedy Park Homes Assn. v. City of
Lackawanna, 436 F.2d 108 (CA2 1970), cert. denied, 401 U.S. 1010 (1971) (town declared moratorium on new subdivisions
and rezoned area for parkland shortly after learning of plaintiffs'
plans to build low-income housing). To the extent that the decision
in Kennedy Park Homes rested solely on a finding of
discriminatory impact, we have indicated our disagreement. Washington v. Davis, supra at 426 U. S.
244 -245.
[ Footnote 17 ] See Dailey v. City of Lawton, 425 F.2d 1037 (CA10
1970). The plaintiffs in Dailey planned to build
low-income housing on the site of a former school that they had
purchased. The city refused to rezone the land from PF, its public
facilities classification, to R-4, high-density residential. All
the surrounding area was zoned R-4, and both the present and the
former planning director for the city testified that there was no
reason "from a zoning standpoint" why the land should not be
classified R-4. Based on this and other evidence, the Court of
Appeals ruled that "the record sustains the [District Court's]
holding of racial motivation and of arbitrary and unreasonable
action." Id. at 1040.
[ Footnote 18 ]
This Court has recognized, ever since Fletcher v.
Peck , 6 Cranch 87, 10 U. S. 130 -131
(1810), that judicial inquiries into legislative or executive
motivation represent a substantial intrusion into the workings of
other branches of government. Placing a decisionmaker on the stand
is therefore "usually to be avoided." Citizens to Preserve
Overton Park v. Volpe, 401 U. S. 402 , 401 U. S. 420 (1971). The problems involved have prompted a good deal of
scholarly commentary. See Tussman & tenBroek, The
Equal Protection of the Laws, 37 Calif.L.Rev. 341, 356-361 (1949);
A. Bickel, The Least Dangerous Branch 208-221 (1962); Ely,
Legislative and Administrative Motivation in Constitutional Law, 79
Yale L.J. 1205 (1970); Brest, supra, n 12.
[ Footnote 19 ]
Respondents have made much of one apparent procedural departure.
The parties stipulated that the Village Planner, the staff member
whose primary responsibility covered zoning and planning matters,
was never asked for his written or oral opinion of the rezoning
request. The omission does seem curious, but respondents failed to
prove at trial what role the Planner customarily played in rezoning
decisions, or whether his opinion would be relevant to respondents'
claims.
[ Footnote 20 ]
Respondents complain that the District Court unduly limited
their efforts to prove that the Village Board acted for
discriminatory purposes, since it forbade questioning Board members
about their motivation at the time they cast their votes. We
perceive no abuse of discretion in the circumstances of this case,
even if such an inquiry into motivation would otherwise have been
proper. See n 18, supra. Respondents were allowed, both during the discovery
phase and at trial, to question Board members fully about materials
and information available to them at the time of decision. In light
of respondents' repeated insistence that it was effect, and not
motivation, which would make out a constitutional violation, the
District Court's action was not improper.
[ Footnote 21 ]
Proof that the decision by the Village was motivated in part by
a racially discriminatory purpose would not necessarily have
required invalidation of the challenged decision. Such proof would,
however, have shifted to the Village the burden of establishing
that the same decision would have resulted even had the
impermissible purpose not been considered. If this were
established, the complaining party in a case of this kind no longer
fairly could attribute the injury complained of to improper
consideration of a discriminatory purpose. In such circumstances,
there would be no justification for judicial interference with the
challenged decision. But, in this case, respondents failed to make
the required threshold showing. See Mt. Healthy City Board of
Ed. v. Doyle, post, p. 429 U. S. 274 .
MR. JUSTICE MARSHALL, with whom MR. JUSTICE BRENNAN joins,
concurring in part and dissenting in part.
I concur in Parts I-III of the Court's opinion. However, I
believe the proper result would be to remand this entire case to
the Court of Appeals for further proceedings consistent with Washington v. Davis, 426 U. S. 229 (1976), and today's opinion. The Court of Appeals is better
situated Page 429 U. S. 272 than this Court both to reassess the significance of the
evidence developed below in light of the standards we have set
forth and to determine whether the interests of justice require
further District Court proceedings directed toward those
standards.
MR. JUSTICE WHITE, dissenting.
The Court reverses the judgment of the Court of Appeals because
it finds, after reexamination of the evidence supporting the
concurrent findings below, that
"[r]espondents . . . failed to carry their burden of proving
that discriminatory purpose was a motivating factor in the
Village's decision." Ante at 429 U. S. 270 .
The Court reaches this result by interpreting our decision in Washington v. Davis, 426 U. S. 229 (1976), and applying it to this case, notwithstanding that the
Court of Appeals rendered its decision in this case before Washington v. Davis was handed down, and thus did not have
the benefit of our decision when it found a Fourteenth Amendment
violation.
The Court gives no reason for its failure to follow our usual
practice in this situation of vacating the judgment below and
remanding in order to permit the lower court to reconsider its
ruling in light of our intervening decision. The Court's
articulation of a legal standard nowhere mentioned in Davis indicates that it feels that the application of Davis to these facts calls for substantial analysis. If
this is true, we would do better to allow the Court of Appeals to
attempt that analysis in the first instance. Given that the Court
deems it necessary to reexamine the evidence in the case in light
of the legal standard it adopts, a remand is especially
appropriate. As the cases relied upon by the Court indicate, the
primary function of this Court is not to review the evidence
supporting findings of the lower courts. See, e.g., Wright v.
Rockefeller, 376 U. S. 52 , 376 U. S. 56 -57
(1964); Akins v. Texas, 325 U. S. 398 , 325 U. S. 402 (1945). Page 429 U. S. 273 A further justification for remanding on the constitutional
issue is that a remand is required in any event on respondents'
Fair Housing Act claim, 42 U.S.C. 3601 et seq., not yet
addressed by the Court of Appeals. While conceding that a remand is
necessary because of the Court of Appeals' "unorthodox" approach of
deciding the constitutional issue without reaching the statutory
claim, ante at 429 U. S. 271 ,
the Court refuses to allow the Court of Appeals to reconsider its
constitutional holding in light of Davis should it become
necessary to reach that issue.
Even if I were convinced that it was proper for the Court to
reverse the judgment below on the basis of an intervening decision
of this Court and after a reexamination of concurrent findings of
fact below, I believe it is wholly unnecessary for the Court to
embark on a lengthy discussion of the standard for proving the
racially discriminatory purpose required by Davis for a
Fourteenth Amendment violation. The District Court found that the
Village was motivated "by a legitimate desire to protect property
values and the integrity of the Village's zoning plan." The Court
of Appeals accepted this finding as not clearly erroneous, and the
Court quite properly refuses to overturn it on review here. There
is thus no need for this Court to list various "evidentiary
sources" or "subjects of proper inquiry" in determining whether a
racially discriminatory purpose existed.
I would vacate the judgment of the Court of Appeals and remand
the case for consideration of the statutory issue and, if
necessary, for consideration of the constitutional issue in light
of Washington v. Davis. | The Supreme Court ruled that the Metropolitan Housing Development Corp. (MHDC) had standing to bring a lawsuit against the Village of Arlington Heights for denying their rezoning request to build racially integrated housing, with the Court citing potential economic and non-economic injuries as a result of the Village's decision. The Court also found that at least one individual respondent had standing to join the lawsuit. The case was then sent back to the lower courts for further review, with instructions to consider both the constitutional issue and a statutory claim under the Fair Housing Act. |
Equal Protection | Craig v. Boren | https://supreme.justia.com/cases/federal/us/429/190/ | U.S. Supreme Court Craig v. Boren, 429
U.S. 190 (1976) Craig v. Boren No. 75-628 Argued October 5,
1976 Decided December 20,
1976 429
U.S. 190 APPEAL FROM THE UNITED STATES
DISTRICT COURT FOR THE WESTERN DISTRICT OF
OKLAHOMA Syllabus Appellant Craig, a male then between 18 and 21 years old, and
appellant Whitener, a licensed vendor of 3.2% beer, brought this
action for declaratory and injunctive relief, claiming that an
Oklahoma statutory scheme prohibiting the sale of "nonintoxicating"
3.2% beer to males under the age of 21 and to females under the age
of 18 constituted a gender-based discrimination that denied to
males 18-20 years of age the equal protection of the laws.
Recognizing that Reed v. Reed, 404 U. S.
71 , and later cases establish that classification by
gender must substantially further important governmental
objectives, a three-judge District Court held that appellees'
statistical evidence regarding young males' drunk-driving arrests
and traffic injuries demonstrated that the gender-based
discrimination was substantially related to the achievement of
traffic safety on Oklahoma roads. Held: 1. Since only declaratory and injunctive relief against
enforcement of the gender-based differential was sought, the
controversy has been mooted as to Craig, who became 21 after this
Court had noted probable jurisdiction. See, e.g., DeFunis v.
Odegaard, 416 U. S. 312 . P. 429 U. S.
192 .
2. Whitener has standing to make the equal protection challenge.
Pp. 429 U. S.
192 -197.
(a) No prudential objective thought to be served by limitations
of jus tertii standing can be furthered here, where the
lower court already has entertained the constitutional challenge
and the parties have sought resolution of the constitutional issue.
Pp. 429 U. S.
193 -194.
(b) Whitener in any event independently has established
third-party standing. She suffers "injury in fact," since the
challenged statutory provisions are addressed to vendors like her,
who either must obey the statutory provisions and incur economic
injury or disobey the statute and suffer sanctions. In such
circumstances, vendors may resist efforts to restrict their
operations by advocating the rights of third parties seeking access
to their market. See, e.g., Eisenstadt v. Baird, 405 U. S. 438 . Pp. 429 U. S.
194 -197.
3. Oklahoma's gender-based differential constitutes an invidious
discrimination against males 18-20 years of age in violation of the
Equal Protection Clause. Appellees' statistics (the most relevant
of which Page 429 U. S. 191 show only that .18% of females and 2% of males in the
18-20-year-old age group were arrested for driving while under the
influence of liquor) do not warrant the conclusion that sex
represents an accurate proxy for the regulation of drinking and
driving. Pp. 429 U. S.
199 -204.
4. The operation of the Twenty-first Amendment does not alter
the application of equal protection standards that otherwise govern
this case. The Court has never recognized that application of that
Amendment can defeat an otherwise established claim under the Equal
Protection Clause, the principles of which cannot be rendered
inapplicable here by reliance upon statistically measured but
loose-fitting generalities concerning the drinking tendencies of
aggregate groups. Pp. 429 U. S.
204 -210. 399
F. Supp. 1304 , reversed.
BRENNAN, J., delivered the opinion of the Court, in which WHITE,
MARSHALL, POWELL, and STEVENS, JJ., joined, and in all but Part
II-D of which BLACKMUN, J., joined. POWELL, J., post, p. 429 U. S. 210 ,
and STEVENS, J., post, p. 429 U. S. 211 ,
filed concurring opinions. BLACKMUN, J., filed a statement
concurring in part, post, p. 429 U. S. 214 .
STEWART, J., filed an opinion concurring in the judgment, post, p. 429 U. S. 214 .
BURGER, C.J., post, p. 429 U. S. 215 ,
and REHNQUIST, J., post, p. 429 U. S. 217 ,
filed dissenting opinions.
MR. JUSTICE BRENNAN delivered the opinion of the Court.
The interaction of two sections of an Oklahoma statute,
Okla.Stat., Tit. 37, § 241 and 245 (1958 and Supp. 1976), [ Footnote 1 ] Page 429 U. S. 192 prohibits the sale of "nonintoxicating" 3.2% beer to males under
the age of 21 and to females under the age of 18. The question to
be decided is whether such a gender-based differential constitutes
a denial to males 18-20 years of age of the equal protection of the
laws in violation of the Fourteenth Amendment.
This action was brought in the District Court for the Western
District of Oklahoma on December 20, 1972, by appellant Craig, a
male then between 18 and 21 years of age, and by appellant
Whitener, a licensed vendor of 3.2% beer. The complaint sought
declaratory and injunctive relief against enforcement of the
gender-based differential on the ground that it constituted
invidious discrimination against males 18-20 years of age. A
three-judge court convened under 28 U.S.C. § 2281 sustained the
constitutionality of the statutory differential and dismissed the
action. 399 F.
Supp. 1304 (1975). We noted probable jurisdiction of
appellants' appeal, 423 U.S. 1047 (1976). We reverse. I We first address a preliminary question of standing. Appellant
Craig attained the age of 21 after we noted probable jurisdiction.
Therefore, since only declaratory and injunctive relief against
enforcement of the gender-based differential is sought, the
controversy has been rendered moot as to Craig. See, e.g.,
DeFunis v. Odegaard, 416 U. S. 312 (1974). [ Footnote 2 ] The
question thus arises whether appellant Whitener, the licensed
vendor of 3.2% beer, who has a live controversy against enforcement
of the statute, may rely upon the equal protection objections of
males 18-20 years of age to establish her claim of Page 429 U. S. 193 unconstitutionality of the age-sex differential. We conclude
that she may.
Initially, it should be noted that, despite having had the
opportunity to do so, [ Footnote
3 ] appellees never raised before the District Court any
objection to Whitener's reliance upon the claimed unequal treatment
of 18-20-year-old males as the premise of her equal protection
challenge to Oklahoma's 3.2 beer law. See 399 F. Supp. at
1306 n. 1. Indeed, at oral argument, Oklahoma acknowledged that
appellees always "presumed" that the vendor, subject to sanctions
and loss of license for violation of the statute, was a proper
party in interest to object to the enforcement of the sex-based
regulatory provision. Tr. of Oral Arg. 41. While such a concession
certainly would not be controlling upon the reach of this Court's
constitutional authority to exercise jurisdiction under Art. III, see, e.g., Sierra Club v. Morton, 405 U.
S. 727 , 405 U. S. 732 n. 3 (1972); cf. Data Processing Service v. Camp, 397 U. S. 150 , 397 U. S. 151 (1970), our decisions have settled that limitations on a litigant's
assertion of jus tertii are not constitutionally mandated,
but rather stem from a salutary "rule of slf-restraint" designed to
minimize unwarranted intervention into controversies where the
applicable constitutional questions are ill-defined and
speculative. See, e.g., Barrows v. Jackson, 346 U.
S. 249 , 346 U. S. 255 ,
257 (1953); see also Singleton v. Wulff, 428 U.
S. 106 , 428 U. S.
123 -124 (1976) (POWELL, J., dissenting). These
prudential objectives, thought to be enhanced by restrictions on
third-party standing, cannot be furthered here, where the lower
court already has entertained the relevant constitutional challenge
and the parties have sought -- or at least have never resisted --
an authoritative constitutional determination. In such
circumstances, a decision by us to forgo Page 429 U. S. 194 consideration of the constitutional merits in order to await the
initiation of a new challenge to the statute by injured third
parties would be impermissibly to foster repetitive and
time-consuming litigation under the guise of caution and prudence.
Moreover, insofar as the applicable constitutional questions have
been and continue to be presented vigorously and "cogently," Holden v. Hardy, 169 U. S. 366 , 169 U. S. 397 (1898), the denial of jus tertii standing in deference to
a direct class suit can serve no functional purpose. Our Brother
BLACKMUN's comment is pertinent:
"[I]t may be that a class could be assembled, whose fluid
membership always included some [males] with live claims. But if
the assertion of the right is to be 'representative' to such an
extent anyway, there seems little loss in terms of effective
advocacy from allowing its assertion by"
the present jus tertii champion. Singleton v.
Wulff, supra at 428 U. S.
117 -118.
In any event, we conclude that appellant Whitener has
established independently her claim to assert jus tertii standing. The operation of §§ 241 and 245 plainly has inflicted
"injury in fact" upon appellant sufficient to guarantee her
"concrete adverseness," Baker v. Carr, 369 U.
S. 186 , 369 U. S. 204 (1962), and to satisfy the constitutionally based standing
requirements imposed by Art. III. The legal duties created by the
statutory sections under challenge are addressed directly to
vendors such as appellant. She is obliged either to heed the
statutory discrimination, thereby incurring a direct economic
injury through the constriction of her buyers' market, or to
disobey the statutory command and suffer, in the words of
Oklahoma's Assistant Attorney General, "sanctions and perhaps loss
of license." Tr. of Oral Arg. 41. This Court repeatedly has
recognized that such injuries establish the threshold requirements
of a "case or controversy" mandated by Art. III. See, e.g.,
Singleton v. Wulff, supra at 428 U. S. 113 (doctors who receive payments for their abortion services are
"classically adverse" to government as payer); Sullivan
v. Little Hunting Page 429 U. S. 195 Park, 396 U. S. 229 , 396 U. S. 237 (1969); Barrows v. Jackson, supra at 346 U. S.
255 -256.
As a vendor with standing to challenge the lawfulness of §§ 241
and 245, appellant Whitener is entitled to assert those concomitant
rights of third parties that would be "diluted or adversely
affected" should her constitutional challenge fail and the statutes
remain in force. Griswold v. Connecticut, 381 U.
S. 479 , 381 U. S. 481 (1965); see Note, Standing to Assert Constitutional Jus Tertii, 88 Harv.L.Rev. 423, 432 (1974). Otherwise, the
threatened imposition of governmental sanctions might deter
appellant Whitener and other similarly situated vendor from selling
3.2% beer to young males, thereby ensuring that "enforcement of the
challenged restriction against the [vendor] would result indirectly
in the violation of third parties' rights." Warth v.
Seldin, 422 U. S. 490 , 422 U. S. 510 (1975). Accordingly, vendors and those in like positions have been
uniformly permitted to resist efforts at restricting their
operations by acting as advocates of the rights of third parties
who seek access to their market or function. See, e.g.,
Eisenstadt v. Baird, 405 U. S. 438 (1972); Sullivan v. Little Hunting Park, supra; Barrows v.
Jackson, supra. [ Footnote
4 ] Page 429 U. S. 196 Indeed, the jus tertii question raised here is answered
by our disposition of a like argument in Eisenstadt v. Baird,
supra. There, as here, a state statute imposed legal duties
and disabilities upon the claimant, who was convicted of
distributing a package of contraceptive foam to a third party.
[ Footnote 5 ] Since the statute
was directed at Baird and penalized his conduct, the Court did not
hesitate -- again as here -- to conclude that the "case or
controversy" requirement of Art. III was satisfied. 405 U.S. at 405 U. S. 443 .
In considering Baird's constitutional objections, the Court fully
recognized his standing to defend the privacy interests of third
parties. Deemed crucial to the decision to permit jus
tertii standing was the recognition of "the impact of the
litigation on the third-party interests." Id. at 405 U. S. 445 .
Just as the defeat of Baird's suit and the "[e]nforcement of the
Massachusetts statute will materially impair the ability of single
persons to obtain contraceptives," id. at 405 U. S. 446 ,
so too the failure of Whitener to prevail in this suit and the
continued enforcement of §§ 241 and 245 will "materially impair the
ability of" males 18-20 years of age to purchase 3.2% beer despite
their classification by an overt gender-based criterion. Similarly,
just as the Massachusetts law in Eisenstadt "prohibit[ed], Page 429 U. S. 197 not use, but distribution," 405 U.S. at 405 U. S. 446 ,
and consequently the least awkward challenger was one in Baird's
position who was subject to that proscription, the law challenged
here explicitly regulates the sale, rather than use, of 3.2 beer,
thus leaving a vendor as the obvious claimant.
We therefore hold that Whitener has standing to raise relevant
equal protection challenges to Oklahoma's gender-based law. We now
consider those arguments. II A Before 1972, Oklahoma defined the commencement of civil majority
at age 18 for females and age 21 for males. Okla.Stat., Tit. 15, §
13 (1972 and Supp. 1976). In contrast, females were held criminally
responsible as adults at age 18, and males at age 16. Okla.Stat.,
Tit. 10, § 1101(a) (Supp. 1976). After the Court of Appeals for the
Tenth Circuit held, in 1972, on the authority of Reed v.
Reed, 404 U. S. 71 (1971), that the age distinction was unconstitutional for purposes
of establishing criminal responsibility as adults, Lamb v.
Brown, 456 F.2d 18, the Oklahoma Legislature fixed age 18 as
applicable to both males and females. Okla.Stat., Tit. 10, §
1101(a) (Supp. 1976). In 1972, 18 also was established as the age
of majority for males and females in civil matters, Okla.Stat.,
Tit. 15, § 13 (1972 and Supp. 1976), except that §§ 241 and 245 of
the 3.2% beer statute were simultaneously codified to create an
exception to the gender-free rule.
Analysis may appropriately begin with the reminder that Reed emphasized that statutory classifications that
distinguish between males and females are "subject to scrutiny
under the Equal Protection Clause." 404 U.S. at 404 U. S. 75 . To
withstand constitutional challenge, previous cases establish that
classifications by gender must serve important governmental
objectives and must be substantially related to achievement of
those objectives. Thus, in Reed, the objectives Page 429 U. S. 198 of "reducing the workload on probate courts," id. at 404 U. S. 76 ,
and "avoiding intra-family controversy," id. at 404 U. S. 77 ,
were deemed of insufficient importance to sustain use of an overt
gender criterion in the appointment of administrators of intestate
decedents' estates. Decisions following Reed similarly
have rejected administrative ease and convenience as sufficiently
important objectives to justify gender-based classifications. See, e.g., Stanley v. Illinois, 405 U.
S. 645 , 405 U. S. 656 (1972); Frontiero v. Richardson, 411 U.
S. 677 , 411 U. S. 690 (1973); cf. Schlesinger v. Ballard, 419 U.
S. 498 , 419 U. S.
506 -507 (1975). And only two Terms ago, Stanton v.
Stanton, 421 U. S. 7 (1975),
expressly stating that Reed v. Reed was "controlling," 421
U.S. at 421 U. S. 13 ,
held that Reed required invalidation of a Utah
differential age-of-majority statute, notwithstanding the statute's
coincidence with and furtherance of the State's purpose of
fostering "old notions" of role typing and preparing boys for their
expected performance in the economic and political worlds. 421 U.S.
at 421 U. S. 14 -15.
[ Footnote 6 ] Reed v. Reed has also provided the underpinning for
decisions that have invalidated statutes employing gender as an
inaccurate proxy for other, more germane bases of classification.
Hence, "archaic and overbroad" generalizations, Schlesinger v.
Ballard, supra at 419 U. S. 508 ,
concerning the financial position of servicewomen, Frontiero v.
Richardson, supra at 411 U. S. 689 n. 23, and working women, Weinberger v. Wiesenfeld, 420 U. S. 636 , 420 U. S. 643 (1975), could not justify use of a gender line in determining
eligibility for certain governmental entitlements. Similarly,
increasingly outdated Page 429 U. S. 199 misconceptions concerning the role of females in the home,
rather than in the "marketplace and world of ideas," were rejected
as loose-fitting characterizations incapable of supporting state
statutory schemes that were premised upon their accuracy. Stanton v. Stanton, supra; Taylor v. Louisiana, 419 U. S. 522 , 419 U. S. 535 n. 17 (1975). In light of the weak congruence between gender and
the characteristic or trait that gender purported to represent, it
was necessary that the legislatures choose either to realign their
substantive laws in a gender-neutral fashion or to adopt procedures
for identifying those instances where the sex-centered
generalization actually comported with fact. See, e.g., Stanley
v. Illinois, supra at 405 U. S. 658 ; cf. Cleveland Board of Education v.
LaFleur, 414 U. S. 632 , 414 U. S. 650 (1974).
In this case, too, " Reed, we feel, is controlling . . .
," Stanton v. Stanton, supra at 421 U. S. 13 . We
turn then to the question whether, under Reed, the
difference between males and females with respect to the purchase
of 3.2% beer warrants the differential in age drawn by the Oklahoma
statute. We conclude that it does not. B The District Court recognized that Reed v. Reed was
controlling. In applying the teachings of that case, the court
found the requisite important governmental objective in the traffic
safety goal proffered by the Oklahoma Attorney General. It then
concluded that the statistics introduced by the appellees
established that the gender-based distinction was substantially
related to achievement of that goal. C We accept for purposes of discussion the District Court's
identification of the objective underlying §§ 241 and 245 as the
enhancement of traffic safety. [ Footnote 7 ] Clearly, the protection Page 429 U. S. 200 of public health and safety represents an important function of
state and local governments. However, appellees' statistics, in our
view, cannot support the conclusion that the gender-based
distinction closely serves to achieve that objective, and therefore
the distinction cannot, under Reed, withstand equal
protection challenge.
The appellees introduced a variety of statistical surveys.
First, an analysis of arrest statistics for 1973 demonstrated that
18-20-year-old male arrests for "driving under the influence" and
"drunkenness" substantially exceeded female arrests for that same
age period. [ Footnote 8 ]
Similarly, youths aged 17-21 were found to be overrepresented among
those killed Page 429 U. S. 201 or injured in traffic accidents, with males again numerically
exceeding females in this regard. [ Footnote 9 ] Third, a random roadside survey in Oklahoma
City revealed that young male were more inclined to drive and drink
beer than were their female counterparts. [ Footnote 10 ] Fourth, Federal Bureau of
Investigation nationwide statistics exhibited a notable increase in
arrests for "driving under the influence." [ Footnote 11 ] Finally, statistical evidence
gathered in other jurisdictions, particularly Minnesota and
Michigan, was offered to corroborate Oklahoma's experience by
indicating the pervasiveness of youthful participation in motor
vehicle accidents following the imbibing of alcohol. Conceding that
"the case is not free from doubt," 399 F. Supp. at 1314, the
District Court nonetheless concluded that this statistical showing
substantiated "a rational basis for the legislative judgment
underlying the challenged classification." Id. at
1307.
Even were this statistical evidence accepted as accurate, it
nevertheless offers only a weak answer to the equal protection
question presented here. The most focused and relevant of the
statistical surveys, arrests of 18-20-year-olds for alcohol-related
driving offenses, exemplifies the ultimate unpersuasiveness of this
evidentiary record. Viewed in terms of the correlation between sex
and the actual activity that Oklahoma seeks to regulate -- driving
while under the influence of alcohol -- the statistics broadly
establish that .18% of females and 2% of males in that age group
were arrested for that offense. While such a disparity is not
trivial in a statistical sense, it hardly can form the basis for
employment of a gender line as a classifying device. Certainly if
maleness Page 429 U. S. 202 is to serves a proxy for drinking and driving, a correlation of
2% must be considered an unduly tenuous "fit." [ Footnote 12 ] Indeed, prior cases have
consistently rejected the use of sex as a decisionmaking factor
even though the statutes in question certainly rested on far more
predictive empirical relationships than this. [ Footnote 13 ]
Moreover, the statistics exhibit a variety of other shortcomings
that seriously impugn their value to equal protection analysis.
Setting aside the obvious methodological problems, [ Footnote 14 ] the surveys do not adequately
justify the salient Page 429 U. S. 203 features of Oklahoma's gender-based traffic safety law. None
purports to measure the use and dangerousness of 3.2% beer, as
opposed to alcohol generally, a detail that is of particular
importance since, in light of its low alcohol level, Oklahoma
apparently considers the 3.2% beverage to be "nonintoxicating."
Okla.Stat., Tit. 37, § 163.1 (1958); see State ex rel. Springer
v. Bliss, 199 Okla. 198 , 185 P.2d 220 (1947). Moreover, many of the studies, while graphically
documenting the unfortunate increase in driving while under the
influence of alcohol, make no effort to relate their findings to
age-sex differentials as involved here. [ Footnote 15 ] Indeed, the only survey that explicitly
centered its attention upon young drivers and their use of beer --
albeit apparently not of the diluted 3.2% variety -- reached
results that hardly can be viewed as impressive in justifying
either a gender or age classification. [ Footnote 16 ] Page 429 U. S. 204 There is no reason to belabor this line of analysis. It is
unrealistic to expect either members of the judiciary or state
officials to be well versed in the rigors of experimental or
statistical technique. But this merely illustrates that proving
broad sociological propositions by statistics is a dubious
business, and one that inevitably is in tension with the normative
philosophy that underlies the Equal Protection Clause. [ Footnote 17 ] Suffice to say that the
showing offered by the appellees does not satisfy us that sex
represents a legitimate, accurate proxy for the regulation of
drinking and driving. In fact, when it is further recognized that
Oklahoma's statute prohibits only the selling of 3.2% beer to young
males, and not their drinking the beverage once acquired (even
after purchase by their 18-20-year-old female companions), the
relationship between gender and traffic safety becomes far too
tenuous to satisfy Reed's requirement that the gender-based
difference be substantially related to achievement of the statutory
objective.
We hold, therefore, that under Reed, Oklahoma's 3.2% beer
statute invidiously discriminates against males 18-20 years of
age. D Appellees argue, however, that §§ 241 and 245 enforce state
policies concerning the sale and distribution of alcohol and by
force of the Twenty-first Amendment should therefore be held to
withstand the equal protection challenge. The District Court's
response to this contention is unclear. The court assumed that the
Twenty-first Amendment "strengthened" the State's police powers
with respect to alcohol regulation, 399 F. Supp. at 1307, but then
said that "the standards of review that [the Equal Protection
Clause] mandates are not relaxed." Id. at 1308. Our view
is, and we hold, that the Twenty-first Amendment does not save
the Page 429 U. S. 205 invidious gender-based discrimination from invalidation as a
denial of equal protection of the laws in violation of the
Fourteenth Amendment.
The history of state regulation of alcoholic beverages dates
from long before adoption of the Eighteenth Amendment. In the License Cases , 5 How. 504, 46 U. S. 579 (1847), the Court recognized a broad authority in state governments
to regulate the trade of alcoholic beverages within their borders
free from implied restrictions under the Commerce Clause. Later in
the century, however, Leisy v. Hardin, 135 U.
S. 100 (1890), undercut the theoretical underpinnings of
the License Cases. This led Congress, acting pursuant to
its powers under the Commerce Clause, to reinvigorate the State's
regulatory role through the passage of the Wilson [ Footnote 18 ] and Webb-Kenyon Acts.
[ Footnote 19 ] See, e.g.,
Clark Distilling Co. v. Western Maryland R. Co., 242 U.
S. 311 (1917) (upholding Webb-Kenyon Act); In re
Rahrer, 140 U. S. 545 (1891) (upholding Wilson Act). With passage of the Eighteenth
Amendment, the uneasy tension between the Commerce Clause and state
police power temporarily subsided.
The Twenty-first Amendment repealed the Eighteenth Amendment in
1933. The wording of § 2 of the Twenty-first Amendment [ Footnote 20 ] closely follows the
Webb-Kenyon and Wilson Page 429 U. S. 206 Acts, ex.pressing the framers' clear intention of
constitutionalizing the Commerce Clause framework established under
those statutes. This Court's decisions since have confirmed that
the Amendment primarily created an exception to the normal
operation of the Commerce Clause. See, e.g., Hostetter v.
Idlewild Bon Voyage Liquor Corp., 377 U.
S. 324 , 377 U. S. 330 (1964); Carter v. Virginia, 321 U.
S. 131 , 321 U. S.
139 -140 (1944) (Frankfurter, J., concurring); Finch
& Co. v. McKittrick, 305 U. S. 395 , 305 U. S. 398 (1939). Even here, however, the Twenty-first Amendment does not pro tanto repeal the Commerce Clause, but merely requires
that each provision "be considered in the light of the other, and
in the context of the issues and interests at stake in any concrete
case." Hostetter v. Idlewild Bon Voyage Liquor Corp.,
supra at 377 U. S. 332 ; cf. Department of Revenue v. James Beam Distilling Co., 377 U. S. 341 (1964); Collins v. Yosemite Park & Curry Co., 304 U. S. 518 (1938).
Once passing beyond consideration of the Commerce Clause, the
relevance of the Twenty-first Amendment to other constitutional
provisions becomes increasingly doubtful. As one commentator has
remarked:
"Neither the text nor the history of the Twenty-first Amendment
suggests that it qualifies individual rights protected by the Bill
of Rights and the Fourteenth Amendment where the sale or use of
liquor is concerned."
P. Brest Processes of Constitutional Decisionmaking, Cases and
Materials, 258 (1975). Any departures from this historical view
have been limited and sporadic. Two States successfully relied upon
the Twenty-first Amendment to respond to challenges of major liquor
importers to state authority to regulate the importation and
manufacture of alcoholic beverages on Commerce Clause and
Fourteenth Amendment grounds. See Mahoney v. Joseph Triner
Corp., 304 U. S. 401 (1938); State Board v. Young's Market
Co. , Page 429 U. S. 207 299 U. S. 59 , 299 U. S. 64 (196). In fact, however, the arguments in both cases centered upon
importation of intoxicants, a regulatory area where the State's
authority under the Twenty-first Amendment is transparently clear, Hostetter v. Idlewild Bon Voyage Liquor Corp., supra at 377 U. S. 330 ,
and n. 9, and touched upon purely economic matters that
traditionally merit only the mildest review under the Fourteenth
Amendment, see, e.g., Joseph E. Seagram & Sons v.
Hostetter, 384 U. S. 35 , 384 U. S. 47 -48, 384 U. S. 50 -51
(1966) (rejecting Fourteenth Amendment objections to state liquor
laws on the strength of Ferguson v. Skrupa, 372 U.
S. 726 , 372 U. S.
729 -730 (1963) and Williamson v. Lee Optical
Co., 348 U. S. 483 (1955)), [ Footnote 21 ] Cases
involving individual rights protected by the Due Process Clause
have been treated in sharp contrast. For example, when an
individual objected to the mandatory "posting" of her name in
retail liquor establishments and her characterization as an
"excessive drink[er]," the Twenty-first Amendment was held not to
qualify the scope of her due process rights. Wisconsin v.
Constantineau, 400 U. S. 433 , 400 U. S. 436 (1971).
It is true that California v. LaRue, 409 U.
S. 109 , 409 U. S. 115 (1972), relied upon the Twenty-first Amendment to "strengthen" the
State's authority to regulate live entertainment at establishments
licensed to dispense liquor, at least when the performances
"partake more of gross sexuality than of communication," id. at 409 U. S. 118 .
Nevertheless, the Court has never recognized sufficient "strength"
in the Amendment to defeat an otherwise established claim of
invidious discrimination in violation of the Equal Protection
Clause. Page 429 U. S. 208 Rather, Moose Lodge No. 107 v. Irvis, 407 U.
S. 163 , 407 U. S.
178 -179 (1972), establishes that state liquor regulatory
schemes cannot work invidious discriminations that violate the
Equal Protection Clause.
Following this approach, both federal and state courts uniformly
have declared the unconstitutionality of gender lines that restrain
the activities of customers of state-regulated liquor
establishments irrespective of the operation of the Twenty-first
Amendment. See, e.g., White v. Fleming, 522 F.2d 730 (CA7
1975); Women's Liberation Union of R.I. v. Israel, 512
F.2d 106 (CA1 1975); Daugherty v. Daley, 370 F.
Supp. 338 (ND Ill.1974) (three-judge court); Seidenberg v.
McSorleys' Old Ale House, Inc., 317 F.
Supp. 593 (SDNY 1970); Commonwealth Alcoholic Beverage
Control Bd. v. Burke, 481
S.W.2d 52 (Ky.1972); cf. Sail'er Inn, Inc. v.
Kirby, 5 Cal. 3d 1 , 485
P.2d 529 (1971); Paterson Tavern & G. O. A. v.
Hawthorne, 57 N.J. 180, 270 A.2d
628 (1970). Even when state officials have posited sociological
or empirical justifications for these gender-based
differentiations, the courts have struck down discriminations aimed
at an entire class under the guise of alcohol regulation. In fact,
social science studies that have uncovered quantifiable differences
in drinking tendencies dividing along both racial and ethnic lines
strongly suggest the need for application of the Equal Protection
Clause in preventing discriminatory treatment that almost certainly
would be perceived as invidious. [ Footnote 22 ] In sum, the principles embodied in the
Equal Page 429 U. S. 209 Protection. Clause are not to be rendered inapplicable by
statistically measured but loose-fitting generalities concerning
the drinking tendencies of aggregate groups. We thus hold that the
operation of the Twenty-first Amendment does not alter the
application of equal protection standards that otherwise govern
this case. Page 429 U. S. 210 We conclude that the gender-based differential contained in
Okla.Stat., Tit. 37, § 45 (1976 Supp.) constitutes a denial of the
equal protection of the laws to males aged 18-20, [ Footnote 23 ] and reverse the judgment of
the District Court. [ Footnote
24 ] It is so ordered. [ Footnote 1 ]
Sections 241 and 245 provide in pertinent part:
§ 241.
"It shall be unlawful for any person who holds a license to sell
and dispense beer . . . to sell, barter or give to any minor any
beverage containing more than one-half of one per cent of alcohol
measured by volume and not more than three and two-tenths (3.2) per
cent of alcohol measured by weight."
§ 245.
"A 'minor,' for the purposes of Section . . . 241 . . . is
defined as a female under the age of eighteen (18) years, and a
male under the age of twenty-one (21) years."
[ Footnote 2 ]
Appellants did not seek class certification of Craig as
representative of other similarly situated males 18-20 years of
age. See, e.g., Sosna v. Iowa, 419 U.
S. 393 , 419 U. S. 401 (1975).
[ Footnote 3 ]
The District Court' opinion confirms that Whitener from the
outset has based her constitutional challenge on
gender-discrimination ground, 399 F. Supp. at 1306, and "[n]o
challenge is made to [her] standing and requisite interest in the
controversy. . . ." Id. at 1306 n. 1.
[ Footnote 4 ]
The standing question presented here is not answered by the
principle stated in United States v. Raines, 362 U. S.
17 , 362 U. S. 21 (1960), that
"one to whom application of a statute is constitutional will not
be heard to attack the statute on the ground that impliedly it
might also be taken as applying to other persons or other
situations in which its application might be unconstitutional."
In Raines, the Court refused to permit certain public
officials of Georgia to defend against application of the Civil
Rights Act to their official conduct on the ground that the statute
also might be construed to encompass the "purely private actions"
of others. The Raines rule remains germane in such a
setting, where the interests of the litigant and the rights of the
proposed third parties are in no way mutually interdependent. Thus,
a successful suit against Raines did not threaten to impair or
diminish the independent private rights of others, and
consequently, consideration of those third-party rights properly
was deferred until another day.
Of course, the Raines principle has also been relaxed
where legal action against the claimant threatens to "chill" the
First Amendment rights of third parties. See, e.g., Lewis v.
New Orleans, 415 U. S. 130 (1974).
[ Footnote 5 ]
The fact that Baird chose to disobey the legal duty imposed upon
him by the Massachusetts anti-contraception statute, resulting in
his criminal conviction, 405 U.S. at 405 U. S. 440 ,
does not distinguish the standing inquiry from that pertaining to
the anticipatory attack in this case. In both Eisenstadt and here, the challenged statutes compel jus tertii claimants either to cease their proscribed activities or to suffer
appropriate sanctions. The existence of Art. III "injury in fact"
and the structure of the claimant's relationship to the third
parties are not altered by the litigative posture of the suit. And
certainly no suggestion will be heard that Whitener's anticipatory
challenge offends the normal requirements governing such actions. See generally Steffel v. Thompson, 415 U.
S. 452 (1974); Samuels v. Mackell, 401 U. S.
66 (1971); Younger v. Harris, 401 U. S.
37 (1971).
[ Footnote 6 ] Kahn v. Shevin, 416 U. S. 351 (1974) and Schlesinger v. Ballard, 419 U.
S. 498 (1975), upholding the use of gender-based
classifications, rested upon the Court's perception of the
laudatory purposes of those laws as remedying disadvantageous
conditions suffered by women in economic and military life. See 416 U.S. at 416 U. S.
353 -354; 419 U.S. at 419 U. S. 508 .
Needless to say, in this case, Oklahoma does not suggest that the
age-sex differential was enacted to ensure the availability of 3.2%
beer for women as compensation for previous deprivations.
[ Footnote 7 ]
That this was the true purpose is not at all self-evident. The
purpose is not apparent from the face of the statute, and the
Oklahoma Legislature does not preserve statutory history materials
capable of clarifying the objectives served by its legislative
enactments. The District Court acknowledged the nonexistence of
materials necessary "to reveal what the actual purpose of the
legislature was," but concluded that "we feel it apparent that a
major purpose of the legislature was to promote the safety of the
young persons affected and the public generally." 399 F. Supp. at
1311 n. 6. Similarly, the attorney for Oklahoma, while proposing
traffic safety as a legitimate rationale for the 3.2% beer law,
candidly acknowledged at oral argument that he is unable to assert
that traffic safety is "indeed the reason" for the gender line
contained in § 245. Tr. of Oral Arg. 27. For this appeal we find
adequate the appellee's representation of legislative purpose,
leaving for another day consideration of whether the statement of
the State's Assistant Attorney General should suffice to inform
this Court of the legislature's objectives, or whether the Court
must determine if the litigant simply is selecting a convenient,
but false, post hoc rationalization.
[ Footnote 8 ]
The disparities in 18-20-year-old male-female arrests were
substantial for both categories of offenses: 427 versus 24 for
driving under the influence of alcohol, and 966 versus 102 for
drunkenness. Even if we assume that a legislature may rely on such
arrest data in some situations, these figures do not offer support
for a differential age line, for the disproportionate arrests of
males persisted at older ages; indeed, in the case of arrests for
drunkenness, the figures for all ages indicated "even more male
involvement in such arrests at later ages." 399 F. Supp. at 1309. See also n 14, infra. [ Footnote 9 ]
This survey drew no correlation between the accident figures for
any age group and levels of intoxication found in those killed or
injured.
[ Footnote 10 ]
For an analysis of the results of this exhibit, see n 16, infra. [ Footnote 11 ]
The FBI made no attempt to relate these arrest figures either to
beer drinking or to an 18-21 age differential, but rather found
that male arrests for all ages exceeded 90% of the total.
[ Footnote 12 ]
Obviously, arrest statistics do not embrace all individuals who
drink and drive. But for purposes of analysis, this
"underinclusiveness" must be discounted somewhat by the
shortcomings inherent in this statistical sample, see n 14, infra. In any
event, we decide this case in light of the evidence offered by
Oklahoma, and know of no way of extrapolating these arrest
statistics to take into account the driving and drinking population
at large, including those who avoided arrest.
[ Footnote 13 ]
For example, we can conjecture that, in Reed, Idaho's
apparent premise that women lacked experience in formal business
matters (particularly compared to men) would have proved to be
accurate in substantially more than 2% of all cases. And in both Frontiero and Wiesenfeld, we expressly found
appellees' empirical defense of mandatory dependency tests for men
but not women to be unsatisfactory, even though we recognized that
husbands are still far less likely to be dependent on their wives
than vice versa. See, e.g., 411 U.S. at 411 U. S.
688 -690.
[ Footnote 14 ]
The very social stereotypes that find reflection in age
differential laws, see Stanton v. Stanton, 421 U. S.
7 , 421 U. S. 14 -15
(1975), are likely substantially to distort the accuracy of these
comparative statistics. Hence "reckless" young men who drink and
drive are transformed into arrest statistics, whereas their female
counterparts are chivalrously escorted home. See, e.g., W.
Reckless & B. Kay, The Female Offender 4, 7, 13, 16-17 (Report
to Presidential Commission on Law Enforcement and Administration of
Justice, 1967). Moreover, the Oklahoma surveys, gathered under a
regime where the age differential law in question has been in
effect, are lacking in controls necessary for appraisal of the
actual effectiveness of the male 3.2% beer prohibition. In this
regard, the disproportionately high arrest statistics for young
males -- and, indeed, the growing alcohol-related arrest figures
for all ages and sexes -- simply may be taken to document the
relative futility of controlling driving behavior by the 3.2% beer
statute and like legislation, although we obviously have no means
of estimating how many individuals, if any, actually were prevented
from drinking by these laws.
[ Footnote 15 ] See, e.g., nn. 9
and | 9 and S.
190fn11|>11, supra. See also 9 and S. 190fn16|>n. 16, infra. [ Footnote 16 ]
The random roadside survey of drivers conducted in Oklahoma City
during August 1972 found that 78% of drivers under 20 were male.
Turning to an evaluation of their drinking habits and factoring out
nondrinkers, 84% of the males, versus 77% of the females, expressed
a preference for beer. Further 16.5% of the men and 11.4% of the
women had consumed some alcoholic beverage within two hours of the
interview. Finally, a blood alcohol concentration greater than .01%
was discovered in 14.6% of the males compared to 11.5% of the
females. "The 1973 figures, although they contain some variations,
reflect essentially the same pattern." 399 F. Supp. at 1309.
Plainly these statistical disparities between the sexes are not
substantial. Moreover, when the 18-20 age boundaries are lifted and
all drivers analyzed, the 1972 roadside survey indicates that male
drinking rose slightly, whereas female exposure to alcohol remained
relatively constant. Again, in 1973, the survey established that,
"compared to all drivers interviewed, . . . the umder-20 age group
generally showed a lower involvement with alcohol in terms of
having drunk within the past two hours or having a significant BAC
(blood alcohol content)." Ibid. In sum, this survey
provides little support for a gender line among teenagers, and
actually runs counter to the imposition of drinking restrictions
based upon age.
[ Footnote 17 ] See, e.g., n 22, infra. [ Footnote 18 ]
The Wilson Act, enacted in 1890, reads in pertinent part:
"All . . . intoxicating liquors or liquids transported into any
State or Territory . . . shall upon arrival in such State or
Territory be subject to the operation and effect of the laws of
such State or Territory enacted in the exercise of its police
powers, to the same extent and in the same manner as though such
liquids or liquors had been produced in such State or Territory. .
. ."
27 U.S.C. § 121.
[ Footnote 19 ]
The Webb-Kenyon Act of 1913 prohibits
"[t]he shipment or transportation . . . of any . . .
intoxicating liquor of any kind, from one State, Territory, or
District . . . into any other State, Territory, or District . . .
[for the purpose of being] received, possessed, sold, or in any
manner used . . . in violation of any law of such State, Territory,
or District. . . ."
27 U.S.C. § 122.
[ Footnote 20 ]
"The transportation or importation into any State, Territory, or
possession of the United States for delivery or use therein of
intoxicating liquors, in violation of the laws thereof, is hereby
prohibited."
[ Footnote 21 ]
The dictum contained in State Board v. Young's Market
Co., 299 U. S. 59 , 299 U. S. 64 (1936), that "[a] classification recognized by the Twenty-first
Amendment cannot be deemed forbidden by the Fourteenth," is
inapplicable to this case. The Twenty-first Amendment does not
recognize, even indirectly, classifications based upon gender. And,
as the accompanying text demonstrates, that statement has not been
relied upon in recent cases that have considered Fourteenth
Amendment challenges to state liquor regulation.
[ Footnote 22 ]
Thus, if statistics were to govern the permissibility of state
alcohol regulation without regard to the Equal Protection Clause as
a limiting principle, it might follow that States could freely
favor Jews and Italian Catholics at the expense of all other
Americans, since available studies regularly demonstrate that the
former two groups exhibit the lowest rates of problem drinking. See, e.g., Haberman & Sheinberg, Implicative Drinking
Reported in a Household Survey: A Corroborative Note on Subgroup
Differences, 28 Q.J.Studies on Alcohol 538 (1967); Wechsler, Thum,
Demone, & Dwinnell, Social Characteristics and Blood Alcohol
Level, 33 Q.J.Studies on Alcohol 132, 141-142 (1972); Wechsler,
Demone, Thum, & Kasey, Religious-Ethnic Differences In Alcohol
Consumption, 11 J.Health & Soc.Behavior 21, 28 (1970); Schmidt
& Popham, Impressions of Jewish Alcoholics, 37 J.Studies on
Alcohol 931 (1976). Similarly, if a State were allowed simply to
depend upon demographic characteristics of adolescents in
identifying problem drinkers, statistics might support the
conclusion that only black teenagers should be permitted to drink,
followed by Asian-Americans and Spanish-Americans.
"Whites and American Indians have the lowest proportions of
abstainers and the highest proportions of moderate/heavy and heavy
drinkers."
Summary of Final Report of a National Study of Adolescent
Drinking Behavior, Attitudes and Correlates 147-148 (Center for the
Study of Social Behavior, Research Triangle Inst., Apr.1975)
(percentage of moderate/heavy and heavy adolescent drinkers by
race: black 15.2%; Asian-American 18.3%; Spanish-American 22.7%;
white 25.3%; American Indian 28.1%).
In the past, some States have acted upon their notions of the
drinking propensities of entire groups in fashioning their alcohol
policies. The most typical recipient of this treatment has been the
American Indian; indeed, several States established criminal
sanctions for the sale of alcohol to an Indian or "half- or
quarter-breed Indian." See, e.g., Fla.Stat.Ann. § 569.07
(1962 and 1976 Supp.) (repealed in 1972); Iowa Code Ann. § 732.5
(1950 and 1976 Supp.) (repealed in 1967); Minn.Stat.Ann. § 340.82
(1957) (repealed in 1969); Neb.Rev.Stat. 53-181 (1944) (repealed in
1955); Utah Code Ann. § 76-34-1 (1953 and 1975 Supp.) (repealed in
1955). Other statutes and constitutional provisions proscribed the
introduction of alcoholic beverages onto Indian reservations. See, e.g., Act of June 10, 1910, § 2, 36 Stat. 558;
Ariz.Const., Art. XX, § 3; N.M.Const., Art. XXI, § 8; Okla.Const.,
Art. 1, § 7. While Indian-oriented provisions were the most common,
state alcohol beverage prohibitions also have been directed at
other groups, notably German, Italian, and Catholic immigrants. See, e.g., J. Higham, Strangers in the Land 25, 267-268,
295 (1975). The repeal of most of these laws signals society's
perception of the unfairness and questionable constitutionality of
singling out groups to bear the brunt of alcohol regulation.
[ Footnote 23 ]
Insofar as Goesaert v. Cleary, 335 U.
S. 464 (1948), may be inconsistent, that decision is
disapproved. Undoubtedly reflecting the view that Goesaert's equal protection analysis no longer obtains,
the District Court made no reference to that decision in upholding
Oklahoma's statute. Similarly, the opinions of the federal and
state courts cited earlier in the text invalidating gender lines
with respect to alcohol regulation uniformly disparaged the
contemporary vitality of Goesaert. [ Footnote 24 ]
As noted in Stanton v. Stanton, 421 U.S. at 421 U. S. 17 -18,
the Oklahoma Legislature is free to redefine any cutoff age for the
purchase and sale of 3.2% beer that it may choose, provided that
the redefinition operates in a gender-neutral fashion.
MR. JUSTICE POWELL, concurring.
I join the opinion of the Court as I am in general agreement
with it. I do have reservations as to some of the discussion
concerning the appropriate standard for equal protection analysis
and the relevance of the statistical evidence. Accordingly, I add
this concurring statement.
With respect to the equal protection standard, I agree that Reed v. Reed, 404 U. S. 71 (1971), is the most relevant precedent. But I find it unnecessary,
in deciding this case, to read that decision as broadly as some of
the Court's language may imply. Reed and subsequent cases
involving gender-based classifications make clear that the Court
subjects such classifications to a more critical examination than
is normally applied when "fundamental" constitutional rights and
"suspect classes" are not present. * Page 429 U. S. 211 I view this as relatively easy case. No one questions the
legitimacy or importance of the asserted governmental objective:
the promotion of highway safety. The decision of the case turns on
whether the state legislature, by the classification it has chosen,
has adopted a means that bears a " fair and substantial
relation'" to this objective. Id. at 404 U. S. 76 ,
quoting Royster Guano Co. v. Virginia, 253 U.
S. 412 , 253 U. S. 415 (1920). It seems to me that the statistics offered by appellees and
relied upon by the District Court do tend generally to support the
view that young men drive more, possibly are inclined to drink
more, and -- for various reasons -- are involved in more accidents
than young women. Even so, I am not persuaded that these facts and
the inferences fairly drawn from them justify this classification
based on a three-year age differential between the sexes, and
especially one that is so easily circumvented as to be virtually
meaningless. Putting it differently, this gender-based
classification does not bear a fair and substantial relation to the
object of the legislation.
* As is evident from our opinions, the Court has had difficulty
in agreeing upon a standard of equal protection analysis that can
be applied consistently to the wide variety of legislative
classifications. There are valid reasons for dissatisfaction with
the "two-tier" approach that has been prominent in the Court's
decisions in the past decade. Although viewed by many as a
result-oriented substitute for more critical analysis, that
approach -- with its narrowly limited "upper-tier" -- now has
substantial precedential support. As has been true of Reed and its progeny, our decision today will be viewed by some as a
"middle-tier" approach. While I would not endorse that
characterization, and would not welcome a further subdividing of
equal protection analysis, candor compels the recognition that the
relatively deferential "rational basis" standard of review normally
applied takes on a sharper focus when we address a gender-based
classification. So much is clear from our recent cases. For
thoughtful discussions of equal protection analysis, see,
e.g., Gunther, The Supreme Court, 1971 Term -- Foreword: In
Search of Evolving Doctrine on a Changing Court: A Model for A
Newer Equal Protection, 86 Harv.L.Rev. 1 (1972); Wilkinson, The
Supreme Court, the Equal Protection Clause, and the Three Faces of
Constitutional Equality, 61 Va.L.Rev. 945 (1975).
MR. JUSTICE STEVENS, concurring.
There is only one Equal Protection Clause. It requires every
State to govern impartially. It does not direct the Page 429 U. S. 212 courts to apply one standard of review in some cases and a
different standard in other cases. Whatever criticism may be
leveled at a judicial opinion implying that there are at least
three such standards applies with the same force to a double
standard.
I am inclined to believe that what has become known as the
two-tiered analysis of equal protection claims does not describe a
completely logical method of deciding cases, but rather is a method
the Court has employed to explain decisions that actually apply a
single standard in a reasonably consistent fashion. I also suspect
that a careful explanation of the reasons motivating particular
decisions may contribute more to an identification of that standard
than an attempt to articulate it in all-encompassing terms. It may
therefore be appropriate for me to state the principal reasons
which persuaded me to join the Court's opinion.
In this case, the classification is not as obnoxious as some the
Court has condemned, [ Footnote 2/1 ]
nor as inoffensive as some the Court has accepted. It is
objectionable because it is based on an accident of birth,
[ Footnote 2/2 ] because it is a mere
remnant of the now almost universally rejected tradition of
discriminating against males in this age bracket, [ Footnote 2/3 ] and because, to the extent it
reflects any physical difference between male and Page 429 U. S. 213 females, it is actually perverse. [ Footnote 2/4 ] The question then is whether the traffic
safety justification put forward by the State is sufficient to make
an otherwise offensive classification acceptable.
The classification is not totally irrational. For the evidence
does indicate that there are more males than females in this age
bracket who drive, and also more who drink. Nevertheless, there are
several reasons why I regard the justification as unacceptable. It
is difficult to believe that the statute was actually intended to
cope with the problem of traffic safety, [ Footnote 2/5 ] since it has only a minimal effect on
access to a not very intoxicating beverage, and does not prohibit
its consumption. [ Footnote 2/6 ]
Moreover, the empirical data submitted by Page 429 U. S. 214 the State accentuate the unfairness of treating all
18-20-year-old males as inferior to their female counterparts. The
legislation imposes a restraint on 100% of the males in the class
allegedly because about 2% of them have probably violated one or
more laws relating to the consumption of alcoholic beverages.
[ Footnote 2/7 ] It is unlikely that
this law will have a significant deterrent effect either on that 2%
or on the law-abiding 98%. But even assuming some such slight
benefit, it does not seem to me that an insult to all of the young
men of the State can be justified by visiting the sins of the 2% on
the 98%.
[ Footnote 2/1 ]
Men as a general class have not been the victims of the kind of
historic, pervasive discrimination that has disadvantaged other
groups.
[ Footnote 2/2 ]
"[S]ince sex, like race and national origin, is an immutable
characteristic determined solely by the accident of birth, the
imposition of special disabilities upon the members of a particular
sex because of their sex would seem to violate 'the basic concept
of our system that legal burdens should bear some relationship to
individual responsibility . . . ,' Weber v. Aetna Casualty
& Surety Co., 406 U. S. 164 , 406 U. S.
175 ." Frontiero v. Richardson, 411 U.
S. 677 , 411 U. S.
686 .
[ Footnote 2/3 ]
Apparently Oklahoma is the only State to permit this narrow
discrimination to survive the elimination of the disparity between
the age of majority for males and females.
[ Footnote 2/4 ]
Because males are generally heavier than females, they have a
greater capacity to consume alcohol without impairing their driving
ability than do females.
[ Footnote 2/5 ]
There is no legislative history to indicate that this was the
purpose, and several features of the statutory scheme indicate the
contrary. The statute exempts license holders who dispense 3.2%
beer to their own children, and a related statute makes it unlawful
for 18-year-old men (but not women) to work in establishments in
which 3.2% beer accounts for over 25% of gross sales. Okla.Stat.,
Tit. 37, §§ 241, 243, 245 (1953 and Supp. 1976).
There is, of course, no way of knowing what actually motivated
this discrimination, but I would not be surprised if it represented
nothing more than the perpetuation of a stereotyped attitude about
the relative maturity of the members of the two sexes in this age
bracket. If so, the following comment is relevant:
"[A] traditional classification is more likely to be used
without pausing to consider its justification than is a newly
created classification. Habit, rather than analysis, makes it seem
acceptable and natural to distinguish between male and female,
alien and citizen, legitimate and illegitimate; for too much of our
history, there was the same inertia in distinguishing between black
and white. But that sort of stereotyped reaction may have no
rational relationship other than pure prejudicial discrimination --
to the stated purpose for which the classification is being
made." Mathews v. Lucas, 427 U. S. 495 , 427 U. S.
520 -521 (STEVENS, J., dissenting).
[ Footnote 2/6 ]
It forbids the sale of 3.2% beer to 18-20-year-old men without
forbidding possession, or preventing them from obtaining it from
other sources, such as friends who are either older or female.
Thus, the statute only slightly impedes access to 3.2% beer.
[ Footnote 2/7 ]
The only direct evidence submitted by the State concerning use
of beer by young drivers indicates that there is no substantial
difference between the sexes. In a random roadside survey of
drivers, 16.5% of the male drivers under 20 had consumed alcohol
within two hours of the interview, as opposed to 11.4% of the
women. Over three-fourths of the nonabstainers in both groups
expressed a preference for beer. And 14.6% of the men, as opposed
to 11.5% of the women, had blood alcohol concentrations over .01%. See ante at 429 U. S. 203 n. 16.
MR. JUSTICE BLACKMUN, concurring in part.
I join the Court's opinion except 429 U.
S. I agree, however, that the Twenty-first Amendment
does not save the challenged Oklahoma statute.
MR. JUSTICE STEWART, concurring in the judgment.
I agree that the appellant Whitener has standing to assert the
equal protection claims of males between 18 and 21 years old. Eisenstadt v. Baird, 405 U. S. 438 , 405 U. S.
443 -446; Griswold v. Connecticut, 381 U.
S. 479 , 381 U. S. 481 ; Barrows v. Jackson, 346 U. S. 249 , 346 U. S.
255 -260; Buchanan v. Warley, 245 U. S.
60 , 245 U. S. 72 -73; see Note, Standing To Assert Constitutional Jus
Tertii, 88 Harv.L.Rev. 423, 431-436 (1974). I also concur in
the Court's judgment on the merits of the constitutional issue
before us. Page 429 U. S. 215 Every State has load power under the Twenty-first Amendment to
control the dispensation of alcoholic beverages within its borders. E.g., California v. LaRue, 409 U.
S. 109 ; Joseph E. Seagram & Sons v.
Hostetter, 384 U. S. 35 ; Hostetter v. Idlewild Bon Voyage Liquor Corp., 377 U. S. 324 , 377 U. S. 330 ; Mahoney v. Joseph Triner Corp., 304 U.
S. 401 ; State Board v. Young's Market Co., 299 U. S. 59 .
But
"[t]his is not to say that the Twenty-first Amendment empowers a
State to act with total irrationality or invidious discrimination
in controlling the distribution and dispensation of liquor. . .
." California v. LaRue, supra at 409 U. S. 120 n. (concurring opinion).
The disparity created by these Oklahoma statutes amounts to
total irrationality. For the statistics upon which the State now
relies, whatever their other shortcomings, wholly fail to prove or
even suggest that 3.2% beer is somehow more deleterious when it
comes into the hands of a male aged 18-20 than of a female of like
age. The disparate statutory treatment of the sexes here, without
even a colorably valid justification or explanation, thus amounts
to invidious discrimination. See Reed v. Reed, 404 U. S. 71 .
MR. CHIEF JUSTICE BURGER, dissenting.
I am in general agreement with MR. JUSTICE REHNQUIST's dissent,
but even at the risk of compounding the obvious confusion created
by those voting to reverse the District Court, I will add a few
words.
At the outset, I cannot agree that appellant Whitener has
standing arising from her status as a saloonkeeper to assert the
constitutional rights of her customers. In this Court, "a litigant
may only assert his own constitutional rights or immunities." United States v. Raines, 362 U. S. 17 , 362 U. S. 22 (1960). There are a few, but strictly limited exceptions to that
rule; despite the most creative efforts, this case fits within none
of them. Page 429 U. S. 216 This is not Sullivan v. Little Hunting Park, 396 U. S. 229 (1969), or Barrows v. Jackson, 346 U.
S. 249 (1953), for there is here no barrier whatever to
Oklahoma males 18-20 years of age asserting, in an appropriate
forum, any constitutional rights they may claim to purchase 3.2%
beer. Craig's successful litigation of this very issue was
prevented only by the advent of his 21st birthday. There is thus no
danger of interminable dilution of those rights if appellant
Whitener is not permitted to litigate them here. Cf. Eisenstadt
v. Baird, 405 U. S. 438 , 405 U. S.
445 -446 (1972).
Nor is this controlled by Griswold v. Connecticut, 381 U. S. 479 (1965). It borders on the ludicrous to draw a parallel between a
vendor of beer and the intimate professional physician-patient
relationship which undergirded relaxation of standing rules in that
case.
Even in Eisenstadt, the Court carefully limited its
recognition of third-party standing to cases in which the
relationship between the claimant and the relevant third party
"was not simply the fortuitous connection between a vendor and
potential vendees, but the relationship between one who acted to
protect the rights of a minority and the minority itself."
405 U.S. at 405 U. S. 445 .
This is plainly not the case here. See also McGowan v.
Maryland, 366 U. S. 420 , 366 U. S.
429 -430 (1961); Brown v. United States, 411 U. S. 223 , 411 U. S. 230 (1973).
In sum, permitting a vendor to assert the constitutional rights
of vendees whenever those rights are arguably infringed introduces
a new concept of constitutional standing to which I cannot
subscribe.
On the merits, we have only recently recognized that our duty is
not "to create substantive constitutional rights in the name of
guaranteeing equal protection of the laws." San Antonio School
Dist. v. Rodriguez, 411 U. S. 1 , 411 U. S. 33 (1973). Thus, even interests of such importance in our society as
public education and housing do not qualify as "fundamental rights"
for equal protection purposes, because they have no Page 429 U. S. 217 textually independent constitutional status. See id. at 411 U. S. 29 -39
(education); Lindsey v. Normet, 405 U. S.
56 (1972) (housing). Though today's decision does not go
so far as to make gender-based classifications "suspect," it makes
gender a disfavored classification. Without an independent
constitutional basis supporting the right asserted or disfavoring
the classification adopted, I can justify no substantive
constitutional protection other than the normal McGowan v.
Maryland, supra at 366 U. S.
425 -426, protection afforded by the Equal Protection
Clause.
The means employed by the Oklahoma Legislature to achieve the
objectives sought may not be agreeable to some judges, but since
eight Members of the Court think the means not irrational, I see no
basis for striking down the statute as violative of the
Constitution simply because we find it unwise, unneeded, or
possibly even a bit foolish.
With MR. JUSTICE REHNQUIST, I would affirm the judgment of the
District Court.
MR. JUSTICE REHNQUIST, dissenting.
The Court's disposition of this case is objectionable on two
grounds. First is its conclusion that men challenging a
gender-based statute which treats them less favorably than women
may invoke a more stringent standard of judicial review than
pertains to most other types of classifications. Second is the
Court's enunciation of this standard, without citation to any
source, as being that
"classifications by gender must serve important governmental objectives, and must be substantially related
to achievement of those objectives." Ante at 429 U. S. 197 (emphasis added). The only redeeming feature of the Court's
opinion, to my mind, is that it apparently signals a retreat by
those who joined the plurality opinion in Frontiero v.
Richardson, 411 U. S. 677 (1973), from their view that sex is a "suspect" classification for
purposes of equal protection analysis. I think the Oklahoma statute
challenged here need pass only the "rational basis" equal Page 429 U. S. 218 protection analysis expounded in cases such as McGowan v.
Maryland, 366 U. S. 420 (1961), and Williamson v. Lee Optical Co., 348 U.
S. 483 (1955), and I believe that it is constitutional
under that analysis. I In Frontiero v. Richardson, supra, the opinion for the
plurality sets forth the reasons of four Justices for concluding
that sex should be regarded as a suspect classification for
purposes of equal protection analysis. These reasons center on our
Nation's "long and unfortunate history of sex discrimination," 411
U.S. at 411 U. S. 684 ,
which has been reflected in a whole range of restrictions on the
legal rights of women, not the least of which have concerned the
ownership of property and participation in the electoral process.
Noting that the pervasive and persistent nature of the
discrimination experienced by women is in part the result of their
ready identifiability, the plurality rested its invocation of
strict scrutiny largely upon the fact that
"statutory distinctions between the sexes often have the effect
of invidiously relegating the entire class of females to inferior
legal status without regard to the actual capabilities of its
individual members." Id. at 411 U. S.
686 -687. See Stanton v. Stanton, 421 U. S.
7 , 421 U. S. 14 -15
(1975).
Subsequent to Frontiero, the Court has declined to hold
that sex is a suspect class, Stanton v. Stanton, supra at 421 U. S. 13 , and
no such holding is imported by the Court's resolution of this case.
However, the Court's application here of an elevated or
"intermediate" level scrutiny, like that invoked in cases dealing
with discrimination against females, raises the question of why the
statute here should be treated any differently from counties
legislative classifications unrelated to sex which have been upheld
under a minimum rationality standard. Jefferson v.
Hackney, 406 U. S. 535 , 406 U. S.
546 -547 (1972); Richardson v. Belcher, 404 U. S. 78 , 404 U. S. 81 -84
(1971); Dandridge v. Williams, 397 U.
S. 471 , 397 U. S.
484 -485 (1970); Page 429 U. S. 219 McGowan v. Maryland, supra at 366 U. S.
425 -426; Flemming v. Nestor, 363 U.
S. 603 , 363 U. S. 611 (1960); Wlliamson v. Lee Optical Co., supra at 348 U. S.
488 -489.
Most obviously unavailable to support any kind of special
scrutiny in this case is a history or pattern of past
discrimination, such as was relied on by the plurality in Frontiero to support its invocation of strict scrutiny.
There is no suggestion in the Court's opinion that males in this
age group are in any way peculiarly disadvantaged, subject to
systematic discriminatory treatment, or otherwise in need of
special solicitude from the courts.
The Court does not discuss the nature of the right involved, and
there is no reason to believe that it sees the purchase of 3.2%
beer as implicating any important interest, let alone one that is
"fundamental" in the constitutional sense of invoking strict
scrutiny. Indeed, the Court's accurate observation that the statute
affects the selling, but not the drinking, of 3.2% beer, ante at 429 U. S. 204 ,
further emphasizes the limited effect that it has on even those
persons in the age group involved. There is, in sum, nothing about
the statutory classification involved here to suggest that it
affects an interest, or works against a group, which can claim
under the Equal Protection Clause that it is entitled to special
judicial protection.
It is true that a number of our opinions contain broadly phrased
dicta implying that the same test should be applied to all
classifications based on sex, whether affecting females or males. E.g., Frontiero v. Richardson, supra at 411 U. S. 688 ; Reed v. Reed, 404 U. S. 71 , 404 U. S. 76 (1971). However, before today, no decision of this Court has
applied an elevated level of scrutiny to invalidate a statutory
discrimination harmful to males, except where the statute impaired
an important personal interest protected by the Constitution.
[ Footnote 3/1 ] There being no such
interest Page 429 U. S. 220 here, and there being no plausible argument that this is a
discrimination against females, [ Footnote 3/2 ] the Court's reliance on our previous sex
discrimination cases is ill-founded. It treats gender
classification as a talisman which -- without regard to the rights
involved or the persons affected -- calls into effect a heavier
burden of judicial review.
The Court's conclusion that a law which treats males less
favorably than females "must serve important governmental
objectives and must be substantially related to achievement of
those objectives" apparently comes out of thin air. The Equal
Protection Clause contains no such language, and none of our
previous cases adopt that standard. I would think we have had
enough difficulty with the two standards of review which our cases
have recognized -- the Page 429 U. S. 221 norm of "rational basis," and the "compelling state interest"
required where a "suspect classification" is involved -- so as to
counsel weightily against the insertion of still another "standard"
between those two. How is this Court to divine what objectives are
important? How is it to determine whether a particular law is
"substantially" related to the achievement of such objective,
rather than related in some other way to its achievement? Both of
the phrases used are so diaphanous and elastic as to invite
subjective judicial preferences or prejudices relating to
particular types of legislation, masquerading as judgments whether
such legislation is directed at "important" objectives or, whether
the relationship to those objectives is "substantial" enough.
I would have thought that, if this Court were to leave anything
to decision by the popularly elected branches of the Government,
where no constitutional claim other than that of equal protection
is invoked, it would be the decision as to what governmental
objectives to be achieved by law are "important," and which are
not. As for the second part of the Court's new test, the Judicial
Branch is probably in no worse position than the Legislative or
Executive Branches to determine if there is any rational
relationship between a classification and the purpose which it
might be thought to serve. But the introduction of the adverb
"substantially" requires courts to make subjective judgments as to
operational effects, for which neither their expertise nor their
access to data fits them. And even if we manage to avoid both
confusion and the mirroring of our own preferences in the
development of this new doctrine, the thousands of judges in other
courts who must interpret the Equal Protection Clause may not be so
fortunate. II The applicable rational basis test is one which
"permits the States a wide scope of discretion in enacting laws
which affect some groups of citizens differently than Page 429 U. S. 222 others. The constitutional safeguard is offended only if the
classification rests on grounds wholly irrelevant to the
achievement of the State's objective. State legislatures are
presumed to have acted within their constitutional power despite
the fact that, in practice, their laws result in some inequality. A
statutory discrimination will not be set aside if any state of
facts reasonably may be conceived to justify it." McGowan v. Maryland, 366 U.S. at 366 U. S.
425 -426 (citations omitted).
Our decisions indicate that application of the Equal Protection
Clause in a context not justifying an elevated level of scrutiny
does not demand "mathematical nicety" or the elimination of all
inequality. Those cases recognize that the practical problems of
government may require rough accommodations of interests, and hold
that such accommodations should be respected unless no reasonable
basis can be found to support them. Dandridge v. Williams, 397 U.S. at 397 U. S. 485 .
Whether the same ends might have been better or more precisely
served by a different approach is no part of the judicial inquiry
under the traditional minimum rationality approach. Richardson
v. Belcher, 404 U.S. at 404 U. S.
84 .
The Court "accept[s] for purposes of discussion" the District
Court's finding that the purpose of the provisions in question was
traffic safety, and proceeds to examine the statistical evidence in
the record in order to decide if "the gender-based distinction
closed serves to achieve that objective." Ante at 429 U. S. 199 , 429 U. S. 200 (emphasis added). (Whether there is a difference between laws which
"closely serv[e]" objectives and those which are only
"substantially related" to their achievement, ante at 429 U. S. 197 ,
we are not told.) I believe that a more traditional type of
scrutiny is appropriate in this case, and I think that the Court
would have done well here to heed its own warning that "[i]t is
unrealistic to expect . . . members of the judiciary . . . to be
well versed in the rigors of experimental or statistical
technique." Ante at 429 U. S. 204 .
One Page 429 U. S. 223 need not immerse oneself in the fine points of statistical
analysis, however, in order to see the weaknesses in the Court's
attempted denigration of the evidence at hand.
One survey of arrest statistics assembled in 1973 indicated that
males in the 18-20 age group were arrested for "driving under the
influence" almost 18 times as often as their female counterparts,
and for "drunkenness" in a ratio of almost 10 to 1. [ Footnote 3/3 ] Accepting, as the Court does,
appellants' comparison of the total figures with 1973 Oklahoma
census data, this survey indicates a 2% arrest rate among males in
the age group, as compared to a .18% rate among females.
Other surveys indicated (1) that, over the five-year period from
1967 to 1972, nationwide arrests among those under 18 for drunken
driving increased 138%, and that 93% of all persons arrested for
drunken driving were male; [ Footnote
3/4 ] (2) that youths in the 17-21 age group were
overrepresented among those killed or injured in Oklahoma traffic
accidents, that male casualties substantially exceeded female, and
that deaths in this age group continued to rise, while overall
traffic deaths declined; [ Footnote
3/5 ] (3) that over three-fourths of the drivers under 20 in the
Oklahoma City area are males, and that each of them, on average,
drives half again as many miles per year as their female
counterparts; [ Footnote 3/6 ] (4)
that four-fifths of male drivers Page 429 U. S. 224 under 20 in the Oklahoma City area state a drink preference for
beer, while about three-fifths of female drivers of that age state
the same preference; [ Footnote 3/7 ]
and (5) that the percentage of male drivers under 20 admitting to
drinking within two hours of driving was half again larger than the
percentage for females, and that the percentage of male drivers of
that age group with a blood alcohol content greater than .01% was
almost half again larger than for female drivers. [ Footnote 3/8 ]
The Court's criticism of the statistics relied on by the
District Court conveys the impression that a legislature, in
enacting a new law, is to be subjected to the judicial equivalent
of a doctoral examination in statistics. Legislatures are not held
to any rules of evidence such as those which may govern courts or
other administrative bodies, and are entitled to draw factual
conclusions on the basis of the determination of probable cause
which an arrest by a police officer normally represents. In this
situation, they could reasonably infer that the incidence of drunk
driving is a good deal higher than the incidence of arrest.
And while, as the Court observes, relying on a report to a
Presidential Commission which it cites in a footnote, such
statistics may be distorted as a result of stereotyping, the
legislature is not required to prove before a court that its
statistics are perfect. In any event, if stereotypes are as
pervasive as the Court suggests, they may, in turn, influence the
conduct of the men and women in question, and cause the young men
to conform to the wild and reckless image which is their
stereotype.
The Court also complains of insufficient integration of the
various surveys on several counts -- that the injury and death
figures are in no way directly correlated with intoxication, ante at 429 U. S. 201 n. 9; that the national figures for drunk driving contain no
breakdown for the 18-21-year-old group, Page 429 U. S. 225 ante at 429 U. S. 201 n. 11; and that the arrest records for intoxication are not tied to
the consumption of 3.2% beer, ante at 429 U. S.
201 -202, nn. 11 and 12. But the State of Oklahoma -- and
certainly this Court for purposes of equal protection review -- can
surely take notice of the fact that drunkenness is a significant
cause of traffic casualties, and that youthful offenders have
participated in the increase of the drunk-driving problem. On this
latter point, the survey data indicating increased driving
casualties among 18-21-year-olds, while overall casualties dropped,
are not irrelevant.
Nor is it unreasonable to conclude from the expressed preference
for beer by four-fifths of the age-group males that that beverage
was a predominant source of their intoxication-related arrests.
Taking that as the predicate, the State could reasonably bar those
males from any purchases of alcoholic beer, including that of the
3.2% variety. This Court lacks the expertise or the data to
evaluate the intoxicating properties of that beverage, and, in that
posture, our only appropriate course is to defer to the reasonable
inference supporting the statute -- that taken in sufficient
quantity this beer has the same effect as any alcoholic
beverage.
Quite apart from these alleged methodological deficiencies in
the statistical evidence, the Court appears to hold that that
evidence, on its face, fails to support the distinction drawn in
the statute. The Court notes that only 2% of males (as against .18%
of females) in the age group were arrested for drunk driving, and
that this very low figure establishes "an unduly tenuous fit'"
between maleness and drunk driving in the 18-20-year-old group. On
this point, the Court misconceives the nature of the equal
protection inquiry. The rationality of a statutory classification for equal
protection purposes does not depend upon the statistical "fit"
between the class and the trait sought to be singled out. It turns
on whether there may be a sufficiently higher incidence Page 429 U. S. 226 of the trait within the included class than in the excluded
class to justify different treatment. Therefore the present equal
protection challenge to this gender-based discrimination poses only
the question whether the incidence of drunk driving among young men
is sufficiently greater than among young women to justify
differential treatment. Notwithstanding the Court's critique of the
statistical evidence, that evidence suggests clear differences
between the drinking and driving habits of young men and women.
Those differences are grounds enough for the State reasonably to
conclude that young males pose by far the greater drunk-driving
hazard, both in terms of sheer numbers and in terms of hazard on a
per-driver basis. The gender-based difference in treatment in this
case is therefore not irrational.
The Court's argument that a 2% correlation between maleness and
drunk driving is constitutionally insufficient therefore does not
pose an equal protection issue concerning discrimination between
males and females. The clearest demonstration of this is the fact
that the precise argument made by the Court would be equally
applicable to a flat bar on such purchases by anyone, male or
female, in the 18-20 age group; in fact it would apply a
fortiori in that case, given the even more "tenuous fit'"
between drunk driving arrests and femaleness. The statistics
indicate that about 1% of the age group population as a whole is
arrested. What the Court's argument is relevant to is not equal
protection, but due process -- whether there are enough persons in
the category who drive while drunk to justify a bar against
purchases by all members of the group. Cast in those terms, the argument carries little weight, in
light of our decisions indicating that such questions call for a
balance of the State's interest against the harm resulting from any
overinclusiveness or underinclusiveness. Vlandis v. Kline, 412 U. S. 441 , 412 U. S.
448 -452 (1973). The personal interest harmed Page 429 U. S. 227 here is very minor -- the present legislation implicates only
the right to purchase 3.2% beer, certainly a far cry from the
important personal interests which have on occasion supported this
Court's invalidation of statutes on similar reasoning. Cleveland Board of Education v. LaFleur, 414 U.
S. 632 , 414 U. S. 640 (1974); Stanley v. Illinois, 405 U.
S. 645 , 405 U. S. 651 (1972). And the state interest involved is significant -- the
prevention of injury and death on the highways.
This is not a case where the classification can only be
justified on grounds of administrative convenience. Vlandis v.
Kline, supra, at 412 U. S. 451 ; Stanley v. Illinois, supra at 405 U. S. 656 .
There being no apparent way to single out persons likely to drink
and drive, it seems plain that the legislature was faced here with
the not atypical legislative problem of legislating in terms of
broad categories with regard to the purchase and consumption of
alcohol. I trust, especially in light of the Twenty-first
Amendment, that there would be no due process violation if no one
in this age group were allowed to purchase 3.2% beer. Since males
drink and drive at a higher rate than the age group as a whole, I
fail to see how a statutory bar with regard only to them can create
any due process problem.
The Oklahoma Legislature could have believed that 18-20-year-old
males drive substantially more, and tend more often to be
intoxicated than their female counterparts; that they prefer beer
and admit to drinking and driving at a higher rate than females;
and that they suffer traffic injuries out of proportion to the part
they make up of the population. Under the appropriate rational
basis test for equal protection, it is neither irrational nor
arbitrary to bar them from making purchases of 3.2% beer, which
purchases might in many cases be made by a young man who
immediately returns to his vehicle with the beverage in his
possession. The record does not give any good indication of the
true proportion of males in the age group who drink and drive
(except Page 429 U. S. 228 that it is no doubt greater than the 2% who are arrested), but,
whatever it may be, I cannot see that the mere purchase right
involved could conceivably raise a due process question. There
being no violation of either equal protection or due process, the
statute should accordingly be upheld.
[ Footnote 3/1 ]
In Stanley v. Illinois, 405 U.
S. 645 (1972), the Court struck down a statute allowing
separation of illegitimate children from a surviving father, but
not a surviving mother, without any showing of parental unfitness.
The Court stated that
"the interest of a parent in the companionship, care, custody,
and management of his or her children 'come[s] to this Court with a
momentum for respect lacking when appeal is made to liberties which
derive merely from shifting economic arrangements.'"
In Kahn v. Shevin, 416 U. S. 351 (1974), the Court upheld Florida's $500 property tax exemption for
widows only. The opinion of the Court appears to apply a rational
basis test, id. at 416 U. S. 355 ,
and is so understood by the dissenters. Id. at 416 U. S. 357 (BRENNAN, J., joined by MARSHALL, J., dissenting).
In Weinberger v. Wiesenfeld, 420 U.
S. 636 (1975), the Court invalidated § 202(g) of the
Social Security Act, which allowed benefits to mothers, but not
fathers, of minor children who survive the wage earner. This
statute was treated, in the opinion of the Court, as a
discrimination against female wage earners, on the ground that it
minimizes the financial security which their work efforts provide
for their families. 420 U.S. at 420 U. S.
645 .
[ Footnote 3/2 ]
I am not unaware of the argument, from time to time advanced,
that all discriminations between the sexes ultimately redound to
the detriment of female because they tend to reinforce "old
notions" restricting the roles and opportunities of women. As a
general proposition applying equally to all sex categorizations, I
believe that this argument was implicitly found to carry little
weight in our decisions upholding gender-based differences. See
Schlesinger v. Ballard, 419 U. S. 498 (1975); Kahn v. Shevin, supra. Seeing no assertion that it
has special applicability to the situation at hand, I believe it
can be dismissed as an insubstantial consideration.
[ Footnote 3/3 ]
Extract from: Oklahoma Bureau of Investigation, Arrest
Statistics for September, October, November, and December, 1973.
Defendants' Exhibit 1, Jurisdictional Statement A22. Extract from:
Oklahoma City Police Department, Arrest Statistics for 1973.
Defendants' Exhibit 2, Jurisdictional Statement A23. See
ante at 429 U. S. 200 n. 8.
[ Footnote 3/4 ]
Extract from: Federal Bureau of Investigation, Crime in the
United States, 1972. Defendants' Exhibit 6, App. 182-184.
[ Footnote 3/5 ]
Extract from: Oklahoma Department. of Public Safety, Summary of
Statewide Collisions for 1972, 1973. Defendants' Exhibits 4 and 5,
Jurisdictional Statement A30-A31.
[ Footnote 3/6 ]
Extract from: Oklahoma Management and Engineering Consulting,
Inc., Report to Alcohol Safety Action Program (1973). Defendants'
Exhibit 3, Table 1, Jurisdictional Statement A25.
[ Footnote 3/7 ] Id. at A27 (Table 3), A29 (Table 5).
[ Footnote 3/8 ] Id. at A25 (Table (1)). See ante at 429 U. S. 203 n. 16. | Here is a summary of the Supreme Court case Craig v. Boren (1976):
Issue: Whether an Oklahoma law prohibiting the sale of 3.2% beer to males under 21 and females under 18 violated the Equal Protection Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment.
Holding: Yes, the Court held that the gender-based differential in the Oklahoma law constituted invidious discrimination against males aged 18-20 in violation of the Equal Protection Clause.
Reasoning: The Court recognized that gender-based classifications must substantially further important governmental objectives. However, the Court found that the statistical evidence presented by Oklahoma regarding drunk-driving arrests and traffic injuries among young males did not warrant the conclusion that gender was an accurate proxy for regulating drinking and driving.
Conclusion: The Court ruled that the Oklahoma law's gender-based differential violated the Equal Protection Clause, and that vendors had standing to challenge the law on equal protection grounds. |
Equal Protection | Regents of Univ. of California v. Bakke | https://supreme.justia.com/cases/federal/us/438/265/ | U.S. Supreme Court Regents of Univ. of California v.
Bakke, 438
U.S. 265 (1978) Regents of the University of
California v. Bakke No. 7811 Argued October 12,
1977 Decided June 28, 1978 438
U.S. 265 CERTIORARI TO THE SUPREME COURT OF
CALIFORNIA Syllabus The Medical School of the University of California at Davis
(hereinafter Davis) had two admissions programs for the entering
class of 100 students -- the regular admissions program and the
special admissions program. Under the regular procedure, candidates
whose overall undergraduate grade point averages fell below 2.5 on
a scale of 4.0 were summarily rejected. About one out of six
applicants was then given an interview, following which he was
rated on a scale of 1 to 100 by each of the committee members (five
in 1973 and six in 1974), his rating being based on the
interviewers' summaries, his overall grade point average, his
science courses grade point average, his Medical College Admissions
Test (MCAT) scores, letters of recommendation, extracurricular
activities, and other biographical data, all of which resulted in a
total "benchmark score." The full admissions committee then made
offers of admission on the basis of their review of the applicant's
file and his score, considering and acting upon applications as
they were received. The committee chairman was responsible for
placing names on the waiting list and had discretion to include
persons with "special skills." A separate committee, a majority of
whom were members of minority groups, operated the special
admissions program. The 1973 and 1974 application forms,
respectively, asked candidates whether they wished to be considered
as "economically and/or educationally disadvantaged" applicants and
members of a "minority group" (blacks, Chicanos, Asians, American
Indians). If an applicant of a minority group was found to be
"disadvantaged," he would be rated in a manner similar to the one
employed by the general admissions committee. Special candidates,
however, did not have to meet the 2.5 grade point cutoff and were
not ranked against candidates in the general admissions process.
About one-fifth of the special applicants were invited for
interviews in 1973 and 1974, following which they were given
benchmark scores, and the top choices were then given to the
general admissions committee, which could reject special candidates
for failure to meet course requirements or other specific
deficiencies. The special committee continued to recommend
candidates until 16 special admission selections had been made.
During a four-year period, 63 minority Page 438 U. S. 266 students were admitted to Davis under the special program and 44
under the general program. No disadvantaged whites were admitted
under the special program, though many applied. Respondent, a white
male, applied to Davis in 1973 and 1974, in both years being
considered only under the general admissions program. Though he had
a 468 out of 500 score in 1973, he was rejected, since no general
applicants with scores less than 470 were being accepted after
respondent's application, which was filed late in the year, had
been processed and completed. At that time, four special admission
slots were still unfilled. In 1974 respondent applied early, and
though he had a total score of 549 out of 600, he was again
rejected. In neither year was his name placed on the discretionary
waiting list. In both years, special applicants were admitted with
significantly lower scores than respondent's. After his second
rejection, respondent filed this action in state court for
mandatory, injunctive, and declaratory relief to compel his
admission to Davis, alleging that the special admissions program
operated to exclude him on the basis of his race in violation of
the Equal Protection Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment, a
provision of the California Constitution, and § 601 of Title VI of
the Civil Rights Act of 1964, which provides, inter alia, that no person shall on the ground of race or color be excluded
from participating in any program receiving federal financial
assistance. Petitioner cross-claimed for a declaration that its
special admissions program was lawful. The trial court found that
the special program operated as a racial quota, because minority
applicants in that program were rated only against one another, and
16 places in the class of 100 were reserved for them. Declaring
that petitioner could not take race into account in making
admissions decisions, the program was held to violate the Federal
and State Constitutions and Title VI. Respondent's admission was
not ordered, however, for lack of proof that he would have been
admitted but for the special program. The California Supreme Court,
applying a strict scrutiny standard, concluded that the special
admissions program was not the least intrusive means of achieving
the goals of the admittedly compelling state interests of
integrating the medical profession and increasing the number of
doctors willing to serve minority patients. Without passing on the
state constitutional or federal statutory grounds, the court held
that petitioner's special admissions program violated the Equal
Protection Clause. Since petitioner could not satisfy its burden of
demonstrating that respondent, absent the special program, would
not have been admitted, the court ordered his admission to
Davis. Held: The judgment below is affirmed insofar as it
orders respondent's admission to Davis and invalidates petitioner's
special admissions program, Page 438 U. S. 267 but is reversed insofar as it prohibits petitioner from taking
race into account as a factor in its future admissions
decisions. 18 Cal. 3d 34 ,
553 P.2d 1152, affirmed in part and reversed in part.
MR. JUSTICE POWELL concluded:
1. Title VI proscribes only those racial classifications that
would violate the Equal Protection Clause if employed by a State or
its agencies. Pp. 438 U. S.
281 -287.
2. Racial and ethnic classifications of any sort are inherently
suspect and call for the most exacting judicial scrutiny. While the
goal of achieving a diverse student body is sufficiently compelling
to justify consideration of race in admissions decisions under some
circumstances, petitioner's special admissions program, which
forecloses consideration to persons like respondent, is unnecessary
to the achievement of this compelling goal, and therefore invalid
under the Equal Protection Clause. Pp. 438 U. S.
287 -320.
3. Since petitioner could not satisfy its burden of proving that
respondent would not have been admitted even if there had been no
special admissions program, he must be admitted. P. 438 U. S.
320 .
MR. JUSTICE BRENNAN, MR. JUSTICE WHITE, MR. JUSTICE MARSHALL,
and MR. JUSTICE BLACKMUN concluded:
1. Title VI proscribes only those racial classifications that
would violate the Equal Protection Clause if employed by a State or
its agencies. Pp. 438 U. S.
328 -355.
2. Racial classifications call for strict judicial scrutiny.
Nonetheless, the purpose of overcoming substantial, chronic
minority underrepresentation in the medical profession is
sufficiently important to justify petitioner's remedial use of
race. Thus, the judgment below must be reversed in that it
prohibits race from being used as a factor in university
admissions. Pp. 438 U. S.
355 -379.
MR. JUSTICE STEVENS, joined by THE CHIEF JUSTICE, MR. JUSTICE
STEWART, and MR. JUSTICE REHNQUIST, being of the view that whether
race can ever be a factor in an admissions policy is not an issue
here; that Title VI applies; and that respondent was excluded from
Davis in violation of Title VI, concurs in the Court's judgment
insofar as it affirms the judgment of the court below ordering
respondent admitted to Davis. Pp. 438 U. S.
408 -421.
POWELL, J., announced the Court's judgment and filed an opinion
expressing his views of the case, in Parts I, III-A, and V-C of
which WHITE, J., joined; and in Parts I and V-C of which BRENNAN,
MARSHALL, and BLACKMUN, JJ., joined. BRENNAN, WHITE, MARSHALL, and
BLACKMUN, Page 438 U. S. 268 JJ., filed an opinion concurring in the judgment in part and
dissenting in part, post, p. 438 U. S. 324 .
WHITE, J., post, p. 438 U. S. 379 ,
MARSHALL, J., post, p. 438 U. S. 387 ,
and BLACKMUN, J., post, p. 438 U. S. 402 ,
filed separate opinions. STEVENS, J., filed an opinion concurring
in the judgment in part and dissenting in part, in which BURGER,
C.J., and STEWART and REHNQUIST, JJ., joined, post, p. 438 U. S.
408 . Page 438 U. S. 269 MR. JUSTICE POWELL announced the judgment of the Court.
This case presents a challenge to the special admissions program
of the petitioner, the Medical School of the University of
California at Davis, which is designed to assure the admission Page 438 U. S. 270 of a specified number of students from certain minority groups.
The Superior Court of California sustained respondent's challenge,
holding that petitioner's program violated the California
Constitution, Title VI of the Civil Rights Act of 1964, 42 U.S.C. §
2000d et seq., and the Equal Protection Clause of the
Fourteenth Amendment. The court enjoined petitioner from
considering respondent's race or the race of any other applicant in
making admissions decisions. It refused, however, to order
respondent's admission to the Medical School, holding that he had
not carried his burden of proving that he would have been admitted
but for the constitutional and statutory violations. The Supreme
Court of California affirmed those portions of the trial court's
judgment declaring the special admissions program unlawful and
enjoining petitioner from considering the race of any applicant. * Page 438 U. S. 271 It modified that portion of the judgment denying respondent's
requested injunction and directed the trial court to order his
admission.
For the reasons stated in the following opinion, I believe that
so much of the judgment of the California court as holds
petitioner's special admissions program unlawful and directs that
respondent be admitted to the Medical School must be affirmed. For
the reasons expressed in a separate opinion, my Brothers THE CHIEF
JUSTICE, MR. JUSTICE STEWART, MR. JUSTICE REHNQUIST, and MR.
JUSTICE STEVENS concur in this judgment. Page 438 U. S. 272 I also conclude, for the reasons stated in the following
opinion, that the portion of the court's judgment enjoining
petitioner from according any consideration to race in its
admissions process must be reversed. For reasons expressed in
separate opinions, my Brothers MR. JUSTICE BRENNAN, MR. JUSTICE
WHITE, MR. JUSTICE MARSHALL, and MR. JUSTICE BLACKMUN concur in
this judgment. Affirmed in part and reversed in part. I **
The Medical School of the University of California at Davis
opened in 1968 with an entering class of 50 students. In 1971, the
size of the entering class was increased to 100 students, a level
at which it remains. No admissions program for disadvantaged or
minority students existed when the school opened, and the first
class contained three Asians but no blacks, no Mexican-Americans,
and no American Indians. Over the next two years, the faculty
devised a special admissions program to increase the representation
of "disadvantaged" students in each Medical School class. [ Footnote 1 ] The special program
consisted of Page 438 U. S. 273 a separate admissions system operating in coordination with the
regular admissions process.
Under the regular admissions procedure, a candidate could submit
his application to the Medical School beginning in July of the year
preceding the academic year for which admission was sought. Record
149. Because of the large number of applications, [ Footnote 2 ] the admissions committee screened
each one to select candidates for further consideration. Candidates
whose overall undergraduate grade point averages fell below 2.5 on
a scale of 4.0 were summarily rejected. Id. at 63.
About Page 438 U. S. 274 one out of six applicants was invited for a personal interview. Ibid. Following the interviews, each candidate was rated
on a scale of 1 to 100 by his interviewers and four other members
of the admissions committee. The rating embraced the interviewers'
summaries, the candidate's overall grade point average, grade point
average in science courses, scores on the Medical College
Admissions Test (MCAT), letters of recommendation, extracurricular
activities, and other biographical data. Id. at 62. The
ratings were added together to arrive at each candidate's
"benchmark" score. Since five committee members rated each
candidate in 1973, a perfect score was 500; in 1974, six members
rated each candidate, so that a perfect score was 600. The full
committee then reviewed the file and scores of each applicant and
made offers of admission on a "rolling" basis. [ Footnote 3 ] The chairman was responsible for
placing names on the waiting list. They were not placed in strict
numerical order; instead, the chairman had discretion to include
persons with "special skills." Id. at 63-64.
The special admissions program operated with a separate
committee, a majority of whom were members of minority groups. Id. at 163. On the 1973 application form, candidates were
asked to indicate whether they wished to be considered as
"economically and/or educationally disadvantaged" applicants; on
the 1974 form the question was whether they wished to be considered
as members of a "minority group," which the Medical School
apparently viewed as "Blacks," "Chicanos," "Asians," and "American
Indians." Id. at 65-66, 146, 197, 203-205, 216-218. If
these questions were answered affirmatively, the application was
forwarded to the special admissions committee. No formal definition
of "disadvantaged" Page 438 U. S. 275 was ever produced, id. at 163-164, but the chairman of
the special committee screened each application to see whether it
reflected economic or educational deprivation. [ Footnote 4 ] Having passed this initial hurdle, the
applications then were rated by the special committee in a fashion
similar to that used by the general admissions committee, except
that special candidates did not have to meet the 2.5 grade point
average cutoff applied to regular applicants. About one-fifth of
the total number of special applicants were invited for interviews
in 1973 and 1974. [ Footnote 5 ]
Following each interview, the special committee assigned each
special applicant a benchmark score. The special committee then
presented its top choices to the general admissions committee. The
latter did not rate or compare the special candidates against the
general applicants, id. at 388, but could reject
recommended special candidates for failure to meet course
requirements or other specific deficiencies. Id. at
171-172. The special committee continued to recommend special
applicants until a number prescribed by faculty vote were admitted.
While the overall class size was still 50, the prescribed number
was 8; in 1973 and 1974, when the class size had doubled to 100,
the prescribed number of special admissions also doubled, to 16. Id. at 164, 166.
From the year of the increase in class size -- 1971 -- through
1974, the special program resulted in the admission of 21 black
students, 30 Mexican-Americans, and 12 Asians, for a total of 63
minority students. Over the same period, the regular admissions
program produced 1 black, 6 Mexican-Americans, Page 438 U. S. 276 and 37 Asians, for a total of 44 minority students. [ Footnote 6 ] Although disadvantaged
whites applied to the special program in large numbers, see n 5, supra, none received an offer of admission through that
process. Indeed, in 1974, at least, the special committee
explicitly considered only "disadvantaged" special applicants who
were members of one of the designated minority groups. Record
171.
Allan Bakke is a white male who applied to the Davis Medical
School in both 1973 and 1974. In both years, Bakke's application
was considered under the general admissions program, and he
received an interview. His 1973 interview was with Dr. Theodore C.
West, who considered Bakke "a very desirable applicant to [the]
medical school." Id. at 225. Despite a strong benchmark
score of 468 out of 500, Bakke was rejected. His application had
come late in the year, and no applicants in the general admissions
process with scores below 470 were accepted after Bakke's
application was completed. Id. at 69. There were four
special admissions slots unfilled at that time, however, for which
Bakke was not considered. Id. at 70. After his 1973
rejection, Bakke wrote to Dr. George H. Lowrey, Associate Dean and
Chairman of the Admissions Committee, protesting that the special
admissions program operated as a racial and ethnic quota. Id. at 259. Page 438 U. S. 277 Bakke's 1974 application was completed early in the year. Id. at 70. His student interviewer gave him an overall
rating of 94, finding him "friendly, well tempered, conscientious
and delightful to speak with." Id. at 229. His faculty
interviewer was, by coincidence, the same Dr. Lowrey to whom he had
written in protest of the special admissions program. Dr. Lowrey
found Bakke "rather limited in his approach" to the problems of the
medical profession, and found disturbing Bakke's "very definite
opinions which were based more on his personal viewpoints than upon
a study of the total problem." Id. at 226. Dr. Lowrey gave
Bakke the lowest of his six ratings, an 86; his total was 549 out
of 600. Id. at 230. Again, Bakke's application was
rejected. In neither year did the chairman of the admissions
committee, Dr. Lowrey, exercise his discretion to place Bakke on
the waiting list. Id. at 64. In both years, applicants
were admitted under the special program with grade point averages,
MCT scores, and benchmark scores significantly lower than Bakke's.
[ Footnote 7 ]
After the second rejection, Bakke filed the instant suit in the
Superior Court of California. [ Footnote 8 ] He sought mandatory, injunctive, and
declaratory relief compelling his admission to the Medical School.
He alleged that the Medical School's special admissions program
operated to exclude him from the Page 438 U. S. 278 school on the basis of his race, in violation of his rights
under the Equal Protection Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment,
[ Footnote 9 ] Art. I, § 21, of
the California Constitution, [ Footnote 10 ] and § 601 of Title VI of the Civil Rights
Act of 1964, 78 Stat. 252, 42 U.S.C. § 2000d. [ Footnote 11 ] The University cross-complained for
a declaration that its special admissions program was lawful. The
trial Page 438 U. S. 279 court found that the special program operated as a racial quota
because minority applicants in the special program were rated only
against one another, Record 388, and 16 places in the class of 100
were reserved for them. Id. at 295-296. Declaring that the
University could not take race into account in making admissions
decisions, the trial court held the challenged program violative of
the Federal Constitution, the State Constitution, and Title VI. The
court refused to order Bakke's admission, however, holding that he
had failed to carry his burden of proving that he would have been
admitted but for the existence of the special program.
Bakke appealed from the portion of the trial court judgment
denying him admission, and the University appealed from the
decision that its special admissions program was unlawful and the
order enjoining it from considering race in the processing of
applications. The Supreme Court of California transferred the case
directly from the trial court, "because of the importance of the
issues involved." 18 Cal. 3d 34 ,
39, 553 P.2d 1152, 1156 (1976). The California court accepted the
findings of the trial court with respect to the University's
program. [ Footnote 12 ]
Because the special admissions program involved a racial
classification, the Supreme Court held itself bound to apply strict
scrutiny. Id. at 49, 553 P.2d at 1162-1163. It then turned
to the goals of the University presented as justifying the special
program. Although the court agreed that the goals of integrating
the medical profession and increasing the number of physicians
willing to serve members of minority groups were compelling state
interests, id. at 53, 553 P.2d at 1165, it concluded that
the special admissions program was not the least intrusive means of
achieving those goals. Without passing on the state constitutional
or federal statutory grounds cited in the trial court's judgment,
the California court held Page 438 U. S. 280 that the Equal Protection Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment
required that
"no applicant may be rejected because of his race, in favor of
another who is less qualified, as measured by standards applied
without regard to race." Id. at 55, 553 P.2d at 1166.
Turning to Bakke's appeal, the court ruled that, since Bakke had
established that the University had discriminated against him on
the basis of his race, the burden of proof shifted to the
University to demonstrate that he would not have been admitted even
in the absence of the special admissions program. [ Footnote 13 ] Id. at 63-64, 553
P.2d at 1172. The court analogized Bakke's situation to that of a
plaintiff under Title VII of the Civil Rights Act of 1964, 42
U.S.C. §§ 2000e-17 (1970 ed., Supp. V), see, e.g., Franks v.
Bowman Transportation Co., 424 U. S. 747 , 424 U. S. 772 (176). 18 Cal. 3d at 64, 553 P.2d at 1172. On this basis, the court
initially ordered a remand for the purpose of determining whether,
under the newly allocated burden of proof, Bakke would have been
admitted to either the 1973 or the 1974 entering class in the
absence of the special admissions program. App. A to Application
for Stay 4. In its petition for rehearing below, however, the
University conceded its inability to carry that burden. App. B to
Application for Stay A19-A20. [ Footnote 14 ] The Page 438 U. S. 281 California court thereupon amended its opinion to direct that
the trial court enter judgment ordering Bakke's admission to the
Medical School. 18 Cal. 3d at 64, 553. P.2d at 1172. That order was
stayed pending review in this Court. 429 U.S. 953 (1976). We
granted certiorari to consider the important constitutional issue.
429 U.S. 1090 (1977). II In this Court, the parties neither briefed nor argued the
applicability of Title VI of the Civil Rights Act of 1964. Rather,
as had the California court, they focused exclusively upon the
validity of the special admissions program under the Equal
Protection Clause. Because it was possible, however, that a
decision on Title VI might obviate resort to constitutional
interpretation, see Ashwander v. TVA, 297 U.
S. 288 , 297 U. S.
346 -348 (1936) (concurring opinion), we requested
supplementary briefing on the statutory issue. 434 U.S. 900
(1977). A At the outset, we face the question whether a right of action
for private parties exists under Title VI. Respondent argues that
there is a private right of action, invoking the test set forth in Cort v. Ash, 422 U. S. 66 , 422 U. S. 78 (1975). He contends Page 438 U. S. 282 that the statute creates a federal right in his favor, that
legislative history reveals an intent to permit private actions,
[ Footnote 15 ] that such
actions would further the remedial purposes of the statute, and
that enforcement of federal rights under the Civil Rights Act
generally is not relegated to the States. In addition, he cites
several lower court decisions which have recognized or assumed the
existence of a private right of action. [ Footnote 16 ] Petitioner denies the existence of a
private right of action, arguing that the sole function of § 601, see n 11, supra, was to establish a predicate for administrative
action under § 602, 78 Stat. 252, 42 U.S.C. § 2000d-1. [ Footnote 17 ] In its view,
administrative curtailment of federal funds under that section was
the only sanction to be imposed upon recipients that Page 438 U. S. 283 violated § 601. Petitioner also points out that Title VI
contains no explicit grant of a private right of action, in
contrast to Titles II, III, IV, and VII, of the same statute, 42
U.S.C. §§ 2000a-3(a), 2000b-2, 2000c-8, and 2000e-5 =(f) (1970 ed.
and Supp. V). [ Footnote
18 ]
We find it unnecessary to resolve this question in the instant
case. The question of respondent's right to bring an action under
Title VI was neither argued nor decided in either of the courts
below, and this Court has been hesitant to review questions not
addressed below. McGoldrick v. Companie Generale
Transatlantique, 309 U. S. 430 , 309 U. S.
434 -435 (1940). See also Massachusetts v.
Westcott, 431 U. S. 322 (1977); Cardinale v. Louisiana, 394 U.
S. 437 , 394 U. S. 439 (1969). Cf. Singleton v. Wulff, 428 U.
S. 106 , 428 U. S. 121 (1976). We therefore do not address this difficult issue.
Similarly, we need not pass Page 438 U. S. 284 upon petitioner's claim that private plaintiffs under Title VI
must exhaust administrative remedies. We assume, only for the
purposes of this case, that respondent has a right of action under
Title VI. See Lau v. Nichols, 414 U.
S. 563 , 414 U. S. 571 n. 2 (1974) (STEWART, J., concurring in result). B The language of § 601, 78 Stat. 252, like that of the Equal
Protection Clause, is majestic in its sweep:
"No person in the United States shall, on the ground of race,
color, or national origin, be excluded from participation in, be
denied the benefits of, or be subjected to discrimination under any
program or activity receiving Federal financial assistance."
The concept of "discrimination," like the phrase "equal
protection of the laws," is susceptible of varying interpretations,
for, as Mr. Justice Holmes declared,
"[a] word is not a crystal, transparent and unchanged, it is the
skin of a living thought, and may vary greatly in color and content
according to the circumstances and the time in which it is
used." Towne v. Eisner, 245 U. S. 418 , 245 U. S. 425 (1918). We must, therefore, seek whatever aid is available in
determining the precise meaning of the statute before us. Train
v. Colorado Public Interest Research Group, 426 U. S.
1 , 426 U. S. 10 (1976), quoting United States v. American Trucking Assns., 310 U. S. 534 , 310 U. S.
543 -544 (1940). Examination of the voluminous
legislative history of Title VI reveals a congressional intent to
halt federal funding of entities that violate a prohibition of
racial discrimination similar to that of the Constitution. Although
isolated statements of various legislators, taken out of context,
can be marshaled in support of the proposition that § 601 enacted a
purely color-blind scheme, [ Footnote 19 ] without regard to the reach of the Equal
Protection Page 438 U. S. 285 Clause, these comments must be read against the background of
both the problem that Congress was addressing and the broader view
of the statute that emerges from a full examination of the
legislative debates.
The problem confronting Congress was discrimination against
Negro citizens at the hands of recipients of federal moneys.
Indeed, the color blindness pronouncements cited in the margin at n 19 generally occur in the
midst of extended remarks dealing with the evils of segregation in
federally funded programs. Over and over again, proponents of the
bill detailed the plight of Negroes seeking equal treatment in such
programs. [ Footnote 20 ]
There simply was no reason for Congress to consider the validity of
hypothetical preferences that might be accorded minority citizens;
the legislators were dealing with the real and pressing problem of
how to guarantee those citizens equal treatment.
In addressing that problem, supporters of Title VI repeatedly
declared that the bill enacted constitutional principles. For
example, Representative Celler, the Chairman of the House Judiciary
Committee and floor manager of the legislation in the House,
emphasized this in introducing the bill:
"The bill would offer assurance that hospitals financed by
Federal money would not deny adequate care to Negroes. It would
prevent abuse of food distribution programs whereby Negroes have
been known to be denied food Page 438 U. S. 286 surplus supplies when white persons were given such food. It
would assure Negroes the benefits now accorded only white students
in programs of high[er] education financed by Federal funds. It
would, in short, assure the existing right to equal
treatment in the enjoyment of Federal funds. It would not
destroy any rights of private property or freedom of
association."
110 Cong.Rec. 1519 (1964) (emphasis added). Other sponsors
shared Representative Celler's view that Title VI embodied
constitutional principles. [ Footnote 21 ]
In the Senate, Senator Humphrey declared that the purpose of
Title VI was "to insure that Federal funds are spent in accordance
with the Constitution and the moral sense of the Nation." Id. at 6544. Senator Ribicoff agreed that Title VI
embraced the constitutional standard:
"Basically, there is a constitutional restriction against
discrimination in the use of federal funds; and title VI simply
spells out the procedure to be used in enforcing that
restriction." Id. at 13333. Other Senators expressed similar views.
[ Footnote 22 ]
Further evidence of the incorporation of a constitutional
standard into Title VI appears in the repeated refusals of the
legislation's supporters precisely to define the term
"discrimination." Opponents sharply criticized this failure,
[ Footnote 23 ] but proponents
of the bill merely replied that the meaning of Page 438 U. S. 287 "discrimination" would be made clear by reference to the
Constitution or other existing law. For example, Senator Humphrey
noted the relevance of the Constitution:
"As I have said, the bill has a simple purpose. That purpose is
to give fellow citizens -- Negroes -- the same rights and
opportunities that white people take for granted. This is no more
than what was preached by the prophets, and by Christ Himself. It
is no more than what our Constitution guarantees." Id. at 6553. [ Footnote 24 ]
In view of the clear legislative intent, Title VI must be held
to proscribe only those racial classifications that would violate
the Equal Protection Clause or the Fifth Amendment. III A Petitioner does not deny that decisions based on race or ethnic
origin by faculties and administrations of state universities are
reviewable under the Fourteenth Amendment. See, e.g., Missouri
ex rel. Gaines v. Canada, 305 U. S. 337 (1938); Sipuel v. Board of Regents, 332 U.
S. 631 (1948); Sweatt v. Painter, 339 U.
S. 629 (1950); McLaurin v. Oklahoma State
Regents, 339 U. S. 637 (1950). For his part, respondent does not argue that all racial or
ethnic classifications are per se invalid. See, e.g.,
Hirabayashi v. United States, 320 U. S.
81 (1943); Korematsu v. United States, 323 U. S. 214 (1944); Lee v. Washington, 390 U.
S. 333 , 390 U. S. 334 (1968) (Black, Harlan, and STEWART, JJ., concurring); United
Jewish Organizations v. Carey, 430 U.
S. 144 (1977). The parties do disagree as to the level
of judicial scrutiny to be applied to the special admissions
program. Petitioner argues that the court below erred in applying
strict scrutiny, as this inexact term has been Page 438 U. S. 288 applied in our cases. That level of review, petitioner asserts,
should be reserved for classifications that disadvantage "discrete
and insular minorities." See United States v. Carolene Products
Co., 304 U. S. 144 , 304 U. S. 152 n. 4 (1938). Respondent, on the other hand, contends that the
California court correctly rejected the notion that the degree of
Judicial scrutiny accorded a particular racial or ethnic
classification hinges upon membership in a discrete and insular
minority and duly recognized that the "lights established [by the
Fourteenth Amendment] are personal rights." Shelley v.
Kraemer, 334 U. S. 1 , 334 U. S. 22 (1948).
En route to this crucial battle over the scope of judicial
review, [ Footnote 25 ] the
parties fight a sharp preliminary action over the proper
characterization of the special admissions program. Petitioner
prefers to view it as establishing a "goal" of minority
representation in the Medical School. Respondent, echoing the
courts below, labels it a racial quota. [ Footnote 26 ] Page 438 U. S. 289 This semantic distinction is beside the point: the special
admissions program is undeniably a classification based on race and
ethnic background. To the extent that there existed a pool of at
least minimally qualified minority applicants to fill the 16
special admissions seats, white applicants could compete only for
84 seats in the entering class, rather than the 100 open to
minority applicants. Whether this limitation is described as a
quota or a goal, it is a line drawn on the basis of race and ethnic
status. [ Footnote 27 ]
The guarantees of the Fourteenth Amendment extend to all
persons. Its language is explicit: "No State shall . . . deny to
any person within its jurisdiction the equal protection of the
laws." It is settled beyond question that the
"rights created by the first section of the Fourteenth Amendment
are, by its terms, guaranteed to the individual. The rights
established are personal rights," Shelley v. Kraemer, supra at 334 U. S. 22 . Accord, Missouri ex rel. Gaines v. Canada, supra at 305 U. S. 351 ; McCabe v. Atchison, T. & S.F. R. Co., 235 U.
S. 151 , 235 U. S.
161 -162 (1914). The guarantee of equal protection cannot
mean one thing when applied to one individual and something else
when Page 438 U. S. 290 applied to a person of another color. If both are not accorded
the same protection, then it is not equal.
Nevertheless, petitioner argues that the court below erred in
applying strict scrutiny to the special admissions program because
white males, such as respondent, are not a "discrete and insular
minority" requiring extraordinary protection from the majoritarian
political process. Carolene Products Co., supra at 304 U. S.
152 -153, n. 4. This rationale, however, has never been
invoked in our decisions as a prerequisite to subjecting racial or
ethnic distinctions to strict scrutiny. Nor has this Court held
that discreteness and insularity constitute necessary preconditions
to a holding that a particular classification is invidious.
[ Footnote 28 ] See, e.g.,
Skinner v. Oklahoma ex rel. Williamson, 316 U.
S. 535 , 316 U. S. 541 (1942); Carrington v. Rash, 380 U. S.
89 , 380 U. S. 96 -97
(1965). These characteristics may be relevant in deciding whether
or not to add new types of classifications to the list of "suspect"
categories or whether a particular classification survives close
examination. See, e.g., Massachusetts Board of Retirement v.
Murgia, 427 U. S. 307 , 427 U. S. 313 (1976) (age); San Antonio Independent School Dist. v.
Rodriguez, 411 U. S. 1 , 411 U. S. 28 (1973) (wealth); Graham v. Richardson, 403 U.
S. 365 , 403 U. S. 372 (1971) (aliens). Racial and ethnic classifications, however, are
subject to stringent examination without regard to these additional
characteristics. We declared as much in the first cases explicitly
to recognize racial distinctions as suspect:
"Distinctions between citizens solely because of their ancestry
are, by their very nature, odious to a free people Page 438 U. S. 291 whose institutions are founded upon the doctrine of
equality." Hirabayashi, 320 U.S. at 320 U. S.
100 .
"[A]ll legal restrictions which curtail the civil rights of a
single racial group are immediately suspect. That is not to say
that all such restrictions are unconstitutional. It is to say that
courts must subject them to the most rigid scrutiny." Korematsu, 323 U.S. at 323 U. S. 216 .
The Court has never questioned the validity of those
pronouncements. Racial and ethnic distinctions of any sort are
inherently suspect, and thus call for the most exacting judicial
examination. B This perception of racial and ethnic distinctions is rooted in
our Nation's constitutional and demographic history. The Court's
initial view of the Fourteenth Amendment was that its "one
pervading purpose" was
"the freedom of the slave race, the security and firm
establishment of that freedom, and the protection of the newly-made
freeman and citizen from the oppressions of those who had formerly
exercised dominion over him." Slaughter-House
Cases , 16 Wall. 36, 83 U. S. 71 (1873). The Equal Protection Clause, however, was "[v]irtually
strangled in infancy by post-civil-war judicial reactionism."
[ Footnote 29 ] It was
relegated to decades of relative desuetude while the Due Process
Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment, after a short germinal period,
flourished as a cornerstone in the Court's defense of property and
liberty of contract. See, e.g., Mugler v. Kansas, 123 U. S. 623 , 123 U. S. 661 (1887); Allgeyer v. Louisiana, 165 U.
S. 578 (1897); Lochner v. New York, 198 U. S. 45 (1905). In that cause, the Fourteenth Amendment's "one pervading
purpose" was displaced. See, e.g., Plessy v. Ferguson, 163 U. S. 537 (1896). It was only as the era of substantive due process came to a
close, see, e.g., 291 U. S. New Page 438 U. S. 292 York, 291 U. S. 502 (1934); West Coast Hotel Co. v. Parrish, 300 U.
S. 379 (1937), that the Equal Protection Clause began to
attain a genuine measure of vitality, see, e.g., United States
v. Carolene Products, 304 U. S. 144 (1938); Skinner v. Oklahoma ex rel. Williamson, supra. By that time ,it was no longer possible to peg the guarantees of
the Fourteenth Amendment to the struggle for equality of one racial
minority. During the dormancy of the Equal Protection Clause, the
United States had become a Nation of minorities. [ Footnote 30 ] Each had to struggle [ Footnote 31 ] -- and, to some extent,
struggles still [ Footnote
32 ] -- to overcome the prejudices not of a monolithic majority,
but of a "majority" composed of various minority groups of whom it
was said -- perhaps unfairly, in many cases -- that a shared
characteristic was a willingness to disadvantage other groups.
[ Footnote 33 ] As the Nation
filled with the stock of many lands, the reach of the Clause was
gradually extended to all ethnic groups seeking protection from
official discrimination. See Strauder v. West Virginia, 100 U. S. 303 , 100 U. S. 308 (1880) (Celtic Irishmen) (dictum); Yick Wo v. Hopkins, 118 U. S. 356 (1886) (Chinese); Truax v. Raich, 239 U. S.
33 , 239 U. S. 41 (1915) (Austrian resident aliens); Korematsu, supra, (Japanese); Hernandez v. Texas, 347 U.
S. 475 (1954) (Mexican-Americans). The guarantees of
equal protection, said the Court in Page 438 U. S. 293 Yick Wo, "are universal in their application, to all persons within the
territorial jurisdiction, without regard to any differences of
race, of color, or of nationality; and the equal protection of the
laws is a pledge of the protection of equal laws."
118 U.S. at 118 U. S.
369 .
Although many of the Framers of the Fourteenth Amendment
conceived of its primary function as bridging the vast distance
between members of the Negro race and the white "majority," Slaughter-House Cases, supra, the Amendment itself was
framed in universal terms, without reference to color, ethnic
origin, or condition of prior servitude. As this Court recently
remarked in interpreting the 1866 Civil Rights Act to extend to
claims of racial discrimination against white persons,
"the 39th Congress was intent upon establishing in the federal
law a broader principle than would have been necessary simply to
meet the particular and immediate plight of the newly freed Negro
slaves." McDonald v. Santa Fe Trail Transportation Co., 427 U. S. 273 , 427 U. S. 296 (1976). And that legislation was specifically broadened in 1870 to
ensure that "all persons," not merely "citizens," would enjoy equal
rights under the law. See Runyon v. McCrary, 427 U.
S. 160 , 427 U. S.
192 -202 (1976) (WHITE, J., dissenting). Indeed, it is
not unlikely that, among the Framers, were many who would have
applauded a reading of the Equal Protection Clause that states a
principle of universal application and is responsive to the racial,
ethnic, and cultural diversity of the Nation. See, e.g., Cong.Globe, 39th Cong., 1st Sess., 1056 (1866) (remarks of Rep.
Niblack); id. at 2891-2892 (remarks of Sen. Conness); id. 40th Cong., 2d Sess., 883 (1868) (remarks of Sen.
Howe) (Fourteenth Amendment "protect[s] classes from class
legislation"). See also Bickel, The Original Understanding
and the Segregation Decision, 69 Harv.L.Rev. 1, 60-63 (1955).
Over the past 30 years, this Court has embarked upon the crucial
mission of interpreting the Equal Protection Clause with the view
of assuring to all persons "the protection of Page 438 U. S. 294 equal laws," Yick Wo, supra at 118 U. S. 369 ,
in a Nation confronting a legacy of slavery and racial
discrimination. See, e.g., Shelley v. Kraemer, 334 U. S. 1 (1948); Brown v. Bard of Education, 347 U.
S. 483 (1954); Hills v. Gautreaux, 425 U.
S. 284 (1976). Because the landmark decisions in this
area arose in response to the continued exclusion of Negroes from
the mainstream of American society, they could be characterized as
involving discrimination by the "majority" white race against the
Negro minority. But they need not be read as depending upon that
characterization for their results. It suffices to say that,
"[o]ver the years, this Court has consistently repudiated
'[d]istinctions between citizens solely because of their ancestry'
as being 'odious to a free people whose institutions are founded
upon the doctrine of equality.'" Loving v. Virginia, 388 U. S. 1 , 388 U. S. 11 (1967), quoting Hirabayashi, 320 U.S. at 320 U. S.
100 .
Petitioner urges us to adopt for the first time a more
restrictive view of the Equal Protection Clause, and hold that
discrimination against members of the white "majority" cannot be
suspect if its purpose can be characterized as "benign." [ Footnote 34 ] Page 438 U. S. 295 The clock of our liberties, however, cannot be turned back to
1868. Brown v. Board of Education, supra at 347 U. S. 492 ; accord, Loving v. Virginia supra at 388 U. S. 9 . It is
far too late to argue that the guarantee of equal protection to all
persons permits the recognition of special wards entitled to a
degree of protection greater than that accorded others. [ Footnote 35 ]
"The Fourteenth Amendment is not directed solely against
discrimination due to a 'two-class theory' -- that is, bad upon
differences between 'white' and Negro." Hernandez, 347 U.S. at 347 U. S.
478 .
Once the artificial line of a "two-class theory" of the
Fourteenth Amendment is put aside, the difficulties entailed in
varying the level of judicial review according to a perceived
"preferred" status of a particular racial or ethnic minority are
intractable. The concepts of "majority" and "minority" necessarily
reflect temporary arrangements and political judgments. As observed
above, the white "majority" itself is composed of various minority
groups, most of which can lay claim to a history of prior
discrimination at the hands of the State and private individuals.
Not all of these groups can receive preferential treatment and
corresponding judicial tolerance Page 438 U. S. 296 of distinctions drawn in terms of race and nationality, for then
the only "majority" left would be a new minority of white
Anglo-Saxon Protestants. There is no principled basis for deciding
which groups would merit "heightened judicial solicitude" and which
would not. [ Footnote 36 ]
Courts would be asked to evaluate the extent of the prejudice and
consequent Page 438 U. S. 297 harm suffered by various minority groups. Those whose societal
injury is thought to exceed some arbitrary level of tolerability
then would be entitled to preferential classifications at the
expense of individuals belonging to other groups. Those
classifications would be free from exacting judicial scrutiny. As
these preferences began to have their desired effect, and the
consequences of past discrimination were undone, new judicial
rankings would be necessary. The kind of variable sociological and
political analysis necessary to produce such rankings simply does
not lie within the judicial competence -- even if they otherwise
were politically feasible and socially desirable. [ Footnote 37 ] Page 438 U. S. 298 Moreover, there are serious problems of justice connected with
the idea of preference itself. First, it may not always be clear
that a so-called preference is, in fact, benign. Courts may be
asked to validate burdens imposed upon individual members of a
particular group in order to advance the group's general interest. See United Jewish Organizations v. Carey, 430 U.S. at 430 U. S.
172 -173 (BRENNAN, J., concurring in part). Nothing in
the Constitution supports the notion that individuals may be asked
to suffer otherwise impermissible burdens in order to enhance the
societal standing of their ethnic groups. Second, preferential
programs may only reinforce common stereotypes holding that certain
groups are unable to achieve success without special protection
based on a factor having no relationship to individual worth. See DeFunis v. Odegaard, 416 U. S. 312 , 416 U. S. 343 (1974) (Douglas, J., dissenting). Third, there is a measure of
inequity in forcing innocent persons in respondent's position to
bear the burdens of redressing grievances not of their making.
By hitching the meaning of the Equal Protection Clause to these
transitory considerations, we would be holding, as a constitutional
principle, that judicial scrutiny of classifications touching on
racial and ethnic background may vary with the ebb and flow of
political forces. Disparate constitutional tolerance of such
classifications well may serve to exacerbate Page 438 U. S. 299 racial and ethnic antagonisms, rather than alleviate them. United Jewish Organizations, supra at 430 U. S.
173 -174 (BRENNAN, J., concurring in part). Also, the
mutability of a constitutional principle, based upon shifting
political and social judgments, undermines the chances for
consistent application of the Constitution from one generation to
the next, a critical feature of its coherent interpretation. Pollock v. Farmers' Loan & Trust Co., 157 U.
S. 429 , 157 U. S.
650 -651 (1895) (White, J., dissenting). In expounding
the Constitution, the Court's role is to discern
"principles sufficiently absolute to give them roots throughout
the community and continuity over significant periods of time, and
to lift them above the level of the pragmatic political judgments
of a particular time and place."
A. Cox, The Role of the Supreme Court in American Government 114
(1976).
If it is the individual who is entitled to judicial protection
against classifications based upon his racial or ethnic background
because such distinctions impinge upon personal rights, rather than
the individual only because of his membership in a particular
group, then constitutional standards may be applied consistently.
Political judgments regarding the necessity for the particular
classification may be weighed in the constitutional balance, Korematsu v. United States, 323 U.
S. 214 (1944), but the standard of justification will
remain constant. This is as it should be, since those political
judgments are the product of rough compromise struck by contending
groups within the democratic process. [ Footnote 38 ] When they touch upon an individual's race
or ethnic background, he is entitled to a judicial determination
that the burden he is asked to bear on that basis is precisely
tailored to serve a compelling governmental interest. The
Constitution guarantees that right to every person regardless of
his background. Shelley v. Kraemer, 334 U.S. at 334 U. S. 22 ; Missouri ex rel. Gaines v. Canada, 305 U.S. at 305 U. S.
351 . Page 438 U. S. 300 C Petitioner contends that, on several occasions, this Court has
approved preferential classifications without applying the most
exacting scrutiny. Most of the cases upon which petitioner relies
are drawn from three areas: school desegregation, employment
discrimination, and sex discrimination. Each of the cases cited
presented a situation materially different from the facts of this
case.
The school desegregation cases are inapposite. Each involved
remedies for clearly determined constitutional violations. E.g., Swann v. Charlotte-Mecklenburg Board of Education, 402 U. S. 1 (1971); McDaniel v. Barresi, 402 U. S. 39 (1971); Green v. County School Board, 391 U.
S. 430 (1968). Racial classifications thus were designed
as remedies for the vindication of constitutional entitlement.
[ Footnote 39 ] Moreover, the
scope of the remedies was not permitted to exceed the extent of
the Page 438 U. S. 301 violations. E.g., Dayton Board of Education v.
Brinkman, 433 U. S. 406 (1977); Milliken v. Bradley, 418 U.
S. 717 (1974); see Pasadena City Board of Education
v. Spangler, 427 U. S. 424 (1976). See also Austin Independent School Dist. v. United
States, 429 U.S. 990, 991-995 (1976) (POWELL, J., concurring).
Here, there was no judicial determination of constitutional
violation as a predicate for the formulation of a remedial
classification.
The employment discrimination cases also do not advance
petitioner's cause. For example, in Franks v. Bowman
Transportation Co., 424 U. S. 747 (1976), we approved a retroactive award of seniority to a class of
Negro truckdrivers who had been the victims of discrimination --
not just by society at large, but by the respondent in that case.
While this relief imposed some burdens on other employees, it was
held necessary " to make [the victims] whole for injuries
suffered on account of unlawful employment discrimination.'" Id. at 424 U. S. 763 ,
quoting Albemarle Paper Co. v. Moody, 422 U.
S. 405 , 422 U. S. 418 (1975). The Courts of Appeals have fashioned various types of
racial preferences as remedies for constitutional or statutory
violations resulting in identified, race-based injuries to
individuals held entitled to the preference. E.g., Bridgeport
Guardians, Inc. v. Bridgeport Civil Service Commission, 482
F.2d 1333 (CA2 1973); Carter v. Gallagher, 452 F.2d 315
(CA8 1972), modified on rehearing en banc, id. at 327.
Such preferences also have been upheld where a legislative or
administrative body charged with the responsibility made
determinations of past discrimination by the industries affected,
and fashioned remedies deemed appropriate to rectify the
discrimination. E.g., Contractors Association of Eastern
Pennsylvania v. Secretary of Labor, 442 F.2d 159 (CA3), cert. denied, 404 U.S. 854 (1971); [ Footnote 40 ] Associated
General Page 438 U. S. 302 Contractors of Massachusetts, Inc. v. Altshuler, 490
F.2d 9 (CA1 1973), cert. denied, 416 U.S. 957 (1974); cf. Katzenbach v. Morgan, 384 U.
S. 641 (1966). But we have never approved preferential
classifications in the absence of proved constitutional or
statutory violations. [ Footnote
41 ]
Nor is petitioner's view as to the applicable standard supported
by the fact that gender-based classifications are not subjected to
this level of scrutiny. E g., Califano v. Webster, 430 U. S. 313 , 430 U. S.
316 -317 (1977); Craig v. Boren, 429 U.
S. 190 , 429 U. S. 211 n. (1976) (POWELL, J., concurring). Gender-based distinctions are
less likely to create the analytical and practical Page 438 U. S. 303 problems present in preferential programs premised on racial or
ethnic criteria. With respect to gender, there are only two
possible classifications. The incidence of the burdens imposed by
preferential classifications is clear. There are no rival groups
which can claim that they, too, are entitled to preferential
treatment. Classwide questions as to the group suffering previous
injury and groups which fairly can be burdened are relatively
manageable for reviewing courts. See, e.g., Califano v.
Goldfarb, 430 U. S. 199 , 430 U. S.
212 -217 (1977); Weinberger v. Wiesenfeld, 420 U. S. 636 , 420 U. S. 645 (1975). The resolution of these same questions in the context of
racial and ethnic preferences presents far more complex and
intractable problems than gender-based classifications. More
importantly, the perception of racial classifications as inherently
odious stems from a lengthy and tragic history that gender-based
classifications do not share. In sum, the Court has never viewed
such classification as inherently suspect or as comparable to
racial or ethnic classifications for the purpose of equal
protection analysis.
Petitioner also cites Lau v. Nichols, 414 U.
S. 563 (1974), in support of the proposition that
discrimination favoring racial or ethnic minorities has received
judicial approval without the exacting inquiry ordinarily accorded
"suspect" classifications. In Lau, we held that the
failure of the San Francisco school system to provide remedial
English instruction for some 1,800 students of oriental ancestry
who spoke no English amounted to a violation of Title VI of the
Civil Rights Act of 1964, 42 U.S.C. § 2000d, and the regulations
promulgated thereunder. Those regulations required remedial
instruction where inability to understand English excluded children
of foreign ancestry from participation in educational programs. 414
U.S. at 414 U. S. 568 .
Because we found that the students in Lau were denied "a
meaningful opportunity to participate in the educational program," ibid., we remanded for the fashioning of a remedial
order. Page 438 U. S. 304 Lau provides little support for petitioner's argument.
The decision rested solely on the statute, which had been construed
by the responsible administrative agency to each educational
practices "which have the effect of subjecting individuals to
discrimination," ibid. We stated:
"Under these state-imposed standards, there is no equality of
treatment merely by providing students with the same facilities,
textbooks, teachers, and curriculum, for students who do not
understand English are effectively foreclosed from any meaningful
education." Id. at 414 U. S. 566 .
Moreover, the "preference" approved did not result in the denial of
the relevant benefit -- "meaningful opportunity to participate in
the educational program" -- to anyone else. No other student was
deprived by that preference of the ability to participate in San
Francisco's school system, and the applicable regulations required
similar assistance for all students who suffered similar linguistic
deficiencies. Id. at 414 U. S.
570 -571 (STEWART, J., concurring in result).
In a similar vein, [ Footnote
42 ] petitioner contends that our recent decision in United
Jewish Organization v. Carey, 430 U.
S. 144 (1977), indicates a willingness to approve racial
classifications designed to benefit certain minorities, without
denominating the classifications as "suspect." The State of New
York had redrawn its reapportionment plan to meet objections of the
Department of Justice under § 5 of the Voting Rights Act of 1965,
42 U.S.C. § 1973c (1970 ed., Supp. V). Specifically, voting
districts were redrawn to enhance the electoral power Page 438 U. S. 305 of certain "nonwhite" voters found to have been the victims of
unlawful "dilution" under the original reapportionment plan. United Jewish Organizations, like Lau, properly
is viewed as a case in which the remedy for an administrative
finding of discrimination encompassed measures to improve the
previously disadvantaged group's ability to participate, without
excluding individuals belonging to any other group from enjoyment
of the relevant opportunity -- meaningful participation in the
electoral process.
In this case, unlike Lau and United Jewish
Organizations, there has been no determination by the
legislature or a responsible administrative agency that the
University engaged in a discriminatory practice requiring remedial
efforts. Moreover, the operation of petitioner's special admissions
program is quite different from the remedial measures approved in
those cases. It prefers the designated minority groups at the
expense of other individuals who are totally foreclosed from
competition for the 16 special admissions seats in every Medical
School class. Because of that foreclosure, some individuals are
excluded from enjoyment of a state-provided benefit -- admission to
the Medical School -- they otherwise would receive. When a
classification denies an individual opportunities or benefits
enjoyed by others solely because of his race or ethnic background,
it must be regarded as suspect. E.g., McLaurin v. Oklahoma
State Regents, 339 U.S. at 339 U. S.
641 -642. IV We have held that, in
"order to justify the use of a suspect classification, a State
must show that its purpose or interest is both constitutionally
permissible and substantial, and that its use of the classification
is 'necessary . . . to the accomplishment' of its purpose or the
safeguarding of its interest." In re Griffiths, 413 U. S. 717 , 413 U. S.
721 -722 (1973) (footnotes omitted); Loving v.
Virginia, 388 U.S. at 388 U. S. 11 ; McLaughlin v. Florida, 379 U. S. 184 , 379 U. S. 196 (1964). The special admissions Page 438 U. S. 306 program purports to serve the purposes of: (i) "reducing the
historic deficit of traditionally disfavored minorities in medical
schools and in the medical profession," Brief for Petitioner 32;
(ii) countering the effects of societal discrimination; [ Footnote 43 ] (iii) increasing the
number of physicians who will practice in communities currently
underserved; and (iv) obtaining the educational benefits that flow
from an ethnically diverse student body. It is necessary to decide
which, if any, of these purposes is substantial enough to support
the use of a suspect classification. Page 438 U. S. 307 A If petitioner's purpose is to assure within its student body
some specified percentage of a particular group merely because of
its race or ethnic origin, such a preferential purpose must be
rejected not as insubstantial, but as facially invalid. Preferring
members of any one group for no reason other than race or ethnic
origin is discrimination for its own sake. This the Constitution
forbids. E.g., Loving v. Virginia, supra at 388 U. S. 11 ; McLaughlin v. Florida, supra at 379 U. S. 198 ; Brown v. Board of Education, 347 U.
S. 483 (1954). B The State certainly has a legitimate and substantial interest in
ameliorating, or eliminating where feasible, the disabling effects
of identified discrimination. The line of school desegregation
cases, commencing with Brown, attests to the importance of
this state goal and the commitment of the judiciary to affirm all
lawful means toward its attainment. In the school cases, the States
were required by court order to redress the wrongs worked by
specific instances of racial discrimination. That goal was far more
focused than the remedying of the effects of "societal
discrimination," an amorphous concept of injury that may be ageless
in its reach into the past.
We have never approved a classification that aids persons
perceived as members of relatively victimized groups at the expense
of other innocent individuals in the absence of judicial,
legislative, or administrative findings of constitutional or
statutory violations. See, e.g., Teamsters v. United
States, 431 U. S. 324 , 431 U. S.
367 -376 (1977); United Jewish Organizations, 430 U.S. at 430 U. S.
155 -156; South Carolina v. Katzenbach, 383 U. S. 301 , 383 U. S. 308 (1966). After such findings have been made, the governmental
interest in preferring members of the injured groups at the expense
of others is substantial, since the legal rights of the victims
must be vindicated. In such a case, the Page 438 U. S. 308 extent of the injury and the consequent remedy will have been
judicially, legislatively, or administratively defined. Also, the
remedial action usually remains subject to continuing oversight to
assure that it will work the least harm possible to other innocent
persons competing for the benefit. Without such findings of
constitutional or statutory violations, [ Footnote 44 ] it cannot be Page 438 U. S. 309 said that the government has any greater interest in helping one
individual than in refraining from harming another. Thus, the
government has no compelling justification for inflicting such
harm.
Petitioner does not purport to have made, and is in no position
to make, such findings. Its broad mission is education, not the
formulation of any legislative policy or the adjudication of
particular claims of illegality. For reasons similar to those
stated in 438 U. S. isolated segments of our vast governmental structures are not
competent to make those decisions, at least in the absence of
legislative mandates and legislatively determined criteria.
[ Footnote 45 ] Cf.
Hampton v. Mow Sun Wong, 426 U. S. 88 (1976); n. 41, supra. Before relying upon these sorts of
findings in establishing a racial classification, a governmental
body must have the authority and capability to establish, in the
record, that the classification is responsive to identified
discrimination. See, e.g., Califano v. Webster, 430 U.S.
at 430 U. S.
316 -321; Califano Page 438 U. S. 310 v. Goldfarb, 430 U.S. at 430 U. S.
212 -217. Lacking this capability, petitioner has not
carried its burden of justification on this issue.
Hence, the purpose of helping certain groups whom the faculty of
the Davis Medical School perceived as victims of "societal
discrimination" does not justify a classification that imposes
disadvantages upon persons like respondent, who bear no
responsibility for whatever harm the beneficiaries of the special
admissions program are thought to have suffered. To hold otherwise
would be to convert a remedy heretofore reserved for violations of
legal rights into a privilege that all institutions throughout the
Nation could grant at their pleasure to whatever groups are
perceived as victims of societal discrimination. That is a step we
have never approved. Cf. Pasadena Cty Board of Education v.
Spangler, 427 U. S. 424 (1976). C Petitioner identifies, as another purpose of its program,
improving the delivery of health care services to communities
currently underserved. It may be assumed that, in some situations,
a State's interest in facilitating the health care of its citizens
is sufficiently compelling to support the use of a suspect
classification. But there is virtually no evidence in the record
indicating that petitioner's special admissions program is either
needed or geared to promote that goal. [ Footnote 46 ] The court below addressed this failure of
proof:
"The University concedes it cannot assure that minority doctors
who entered under the program, all of whom expressed an 'interest'
in practicing in a disadvantaged community, will actually do so. It
may be correct to assume that some of them will carry out this
intention, and that it is more likely they will practice in
minority Page 438 U. S. 311 communities than the average white doctor. ( See Sandalow, Racial Preferences in Higher Education: Political
Responsibility and the Judicial Role (1975) 42 U.Chi.L.Rev. 653,
688.) Nevertheless, there are more precise and reliable ways to
identify applicants who are genuinely interested in the medical
problems of minorities than by race. An applicant of whatever race
who has demonstrated his concern for disadvantaged minorities in
the past and who declares that practice in such a community is his
primary professional goal would be more likely to contribute to
alleviation of the medical shortage than one who is chosen entirely
on the basis of race and disadvantage. In short, there is no
empirical data to demonstrate that any one race is more selflessly
socially oriented or by contrast that another is more selfishly
acquisitive."
18 Cal. 3d at 56, 553 P.2d at 1167.
Petitioner simply has not carried its burden of demonstrating
that it must prefer members of particular ethnic groups over all
other individuals in order to promote better health care delivery
to deprived citizens. Indeed, petitioner has not shown that its
preferential classification is likely to have any significant
effect on the problem. [ Footnote
47 ] D The fourth goal asserted by petitioner is the attainment of a
diverse student body. This clearly is a constitutionally
permissible Page 438 U. S. 312 goal for an institution of higher education. Academic freedom,
though not a specifically enumerated constitutional right, long has
been viewed as a special concern of the First Amendment. The
freedom of a university to make its own judgments as to education
includes the selection of its student body. Mr. Justice Frankfurter
summarized the "four essential freedoms" that constitute academic
freedom:
"'It is the business of a university to provide that atmosphere
which is most conducive to speculation, experiment and creation. It
is an atmosphere in which there prevail 'the four essential
freedoms' of a university -- to determine for itself on academic
grounds who may teach, what may be taught, how it shall be taught,
and who may be admitted to study.'" Sweezy v. New Hampshire, 354 U.
S. 234 , 354 U. S. 263 (1957) (concurring in result).
Our national commitment to the safeguarding of these freedoms
within university communities was emphasized in Keyishian v.
Board of Regents, 385 U. S. 589 , 385 U. S. 603 (1967):
"Our Nation is deeply committed to safeguarding academic
freedom, which is of transcendent value to all of us, and not
merely to the teachers concerned. That freedom is therefore a
special concern of the First Amendment. . . . The Nation's future
depends upon leaders trained through wide exposure to that robust
exchange of ideas which discovers truth 'out of a multitude of
tongues, [rather] than through any kind of authoritative
selection.' United States v. Associated
Press, 52 F. Supp.
362 , 372."
The atmosphere of "speculation, experiment and creation" -- so
essential to the quality of higher education -- is widely believed
to be promoted by a diverse student body. [ Footnote 48 ] As the Court Page 438 U. S. 313 noted in Keyishian, it is not too much to say that the
"nation's future depends upon leaders trained through wide
exposure" to the ideas and mores of students as diverse as this
Nation of many peoples.
Thus, in arguing that its universities must be accorded the
right to select those students who will contribute the most to the
"robust exchange of ideas," petitioner invokes a countervailing
constitutional interest, that of the First Amendment. In this
light, petitioner must be viewed as seeking to achieve a goal that
is of paramount importance in the fulfillment of its mission.
It may be argued that there is greater force to these views at
the undergraduate level than in a medical school, where the
training is centered primarily on professional competency. But even
at the graduate level, our tradition and experience lend support to
the view that the contribution of diversity is substantial. In Sweatt v. Painter, 339 U.S. at 339 U. S. 634 ,
the Page 438 U. S. 314 Court made a similar point with specific reference to legal
education:
"The law school, the proving ground for legal learning and
practice, cannot be effective in isolation from the individuals and
institutions with which the law interacts. Few students, and no one
who has practiced law, would choose to study in an academic vacuum,
removed from the interplay of ideas and the exchange of views with
which the law is concerned."
Physicians serve a heterogeneous population. An otherwise
qualified medical student with a particular background -- whether
it be ethnic, geographic, culturally advantaged or disadvantaged --
may bring to a professional school of medicine experiences,
outlooks, and ideas that enrich the training of its student body
and better equip its graduates to render with understanding their
vital service to humanity. [ Footnote 49 ]
Ethnic diversity, however, is only one element in a range of
factors a university properly may consider in attaining the goal of
a heterogeneous student body. Although a university must have wide
discretion in making the sensitive judgments as to who should be
admitted, constitutional limitations protecting individual rights
may not be disregarded. Respondent urges -- and the courts below
have held -- that petitioner's dual admissions program is a racial
classification that impermissibly infringes his rights under the
Fourteenth Amendment. As the interest of diversity is compelling in
the context of a university's admissions program, the question
remains whether the Page 438 U. S. 315 program's racial classification is necessary to promote this
interest. In re Griffiths, 413 U.S. at 413 U. S.
721 -722. V A It may be assumed that the reservation of a specified number of
seats in each class for individuals from the preferred ethnic
groups would contribute to the attainment of considerable ethnic
diversity in the student body. But petitioner's argument that this
is the only effective means of serving the interest of diversity is
seriously flawed. In a most fundamental sense, the argument
misconceives the nature of the state interest that would justify
consideration of race or ethnic background. It is not an interest
in simple ethnic diversity, in which a specified percentage of the
student body is in effect guaranteed to be members of selected
ethnic groups, with the remaining percentage an undifferentiated
aggregation of students. The diversity that furthers a compelling
state interest encompasses a far broader array of qualifications
and characteristics, of which racial or ethnic origin is but a
single, though important, element. Petitioner's special admissions
program, focused solely on ethnic diversity, would hinder, rather
than further, attainment of genuine diversity. [ Footnote 50 ]
Nor would the state interest in genuine diversity be served by
expanding petitioner's two-track system into a multi-track program
with a prescribed number of seats set aside for each identifiable
category of applicants. Indeed, it is inconceivable that a
university would thus pursue the logic of petitioner's two-track
program to the illogical end of insulating each category of
applicants with certain desired qualifications from competition
with all other applicants. Page 438 U. S. 316 The experience of other university admissions programs, which
take race into account in achieving the educational diversity
valued by the First Amendment, demonstrates that the assignment of
a fixed number of places to a minority group is not a necessary
means toward that end. An illuminating example is found in the
Harvard College program:
"In recent years, Harvard College has expanded the concept of
diversity to include students from disadvantaged economic, racial
and ethnic groups. Harvard College now recruits not only
Californians or Louisianans but also blacks and Chicanos and other
minority students. . . ."
"In practice, this new definition of diversity has meant that
race has been a factor in some admission decisions. When the
Committee on Admissions reviews the large middle group of
applicants who are 'admissible' and deemed capable of doing good
work in their courses, the race of an applicant may tip the balance
in his favor just as geographic origin or a life spent on a farm
may tip the balance in other candidates' cases. A farm boy from
Idaho can bring something to Harvard College that a Bostonian
cannot offer. Similarly, a black student can usually bring
something that a white person cannot offer. . . . [ See 438
U.S. 265 app|>Appendix hereto.]"
"In Harvard College admissions, the Committee has not set target
quotas for the number of blacks, or of musicians, football players,
physicists or Californians to be admitted in a given year. . . .
But that awareness [of the necessity of including more than a token
number of black students] does not mean that the Committee sets a
minimum number of blacks or of people from west of the Mississippi
who are to be admitted. It means only that, in choosing among
thousands of applicants who are not only 'admissible' academically
but have other strong qualities, the Committee, with a number of
criteria in mind, pays some attention to distribution among
many Page 438 U. S. 317 types and categories of students."
App. to Brief for Columbia University, Harvard University,
Stanford University, and the University of Pennsylvania, as Amici Curiae 2-3.
In such an admissions program, [ Footnote 51 ] race or ethnic background may be deemed a
"plus" in a particular applicant's file, yet it does not insulate
the individual from comparison with all other candidates for the
available seats. The file of a particular black applicant may be
examined for his potential contribution to diversity without the
factor of race being decisive when compared, for example, with that
of an applicant identified as an Italian-American if the latter is
thought to exhibit qualities more likely to promote beneficial
educational pluralism. Such qualities could include exceptional
personal talents, unique work or service experience, leadership
potential, maturity, demonstrated compassion, a history of
overcoming disadvantage, ability to communicate with the poor, or
other qualifications deemed important. In short, an admissions
program operated in this way is flexible enough to consider all
pertinent elements of diversity in light of the particular
qualifications of each applicant, and to place them on the same
footing for consideration, although not necessarily according them
the same weight. Indeed, the weight attributed to a Page 438 U. S. 318 particular quality may vary from year to year depending upon the
"mix" both of the student body and the applicants for the incoming
class.
This kind of program treats each applicant as an individual in
the admissions process. The applicant who loses out on the last
available seat to another candidate receiving a "plus" on the basis
of ethnic background will not have been foreclosed from all
consideration for that seat simply because he was not the right
color or had the wrong surname. It would mean only that his
combined qualifications, which may have included similar
nonobjective factors, did not outweigh those of the other
applicant. His qualifications would have been weighed fairly and
competitively, and he would have no basis to complain of unequal
treatment under the Fourteenth Amendment. [ Footnote 52 ]
It has been suggested that an admissions program which considers
race only as one factor is simply a subtle and more sophisticated
-- but no less effective -- means of according racial preference
than the Davis program. A facial intent to discriminate, however,
is evident in petitioner's preference program, and not denied in
this case. No such facial infirmity exists in an admissions program
where race or ethnic background is simply one element -- to be
weighed fairly against other elements -- in the selection process.
"A boundary line," as Mr. Justice Frankfurter remarked in another
connection, "is none the worse for being narrow." McLeod v.
Dilworth, 322 U. S. 327 , 322 U. S. 329 (1944). And a court would not assume that a university, professing
to employ a facially nondiscriminatory admissions policy, would
operate it as a cover for the functional equivalent of a quota
system. In short, good faith Page 438 U. S. 319 would be presumed in the absence of a showing to the contrary in
the manner permitted by our cases. See, e.g., Arlington Heights
v. Metropolitan Housing Dev. Corp., 429 U.
S. 252 (1977); Washington v. Davis, 426 U. S. 229 (1976); Swain v. Alabama, 380 U.
S. 202 (165). [ Footnote 53 ] B In summary, it is evident that the Davis special admissions
program involves the use of an explicit racial classification never
before countenanced by this Court. It tells applicants who are not
Negro, Asian, or Chicano that they are totally excluded from a
specific percentage of the seats in an entering class. No matter
how strong their qualifications, quantitative and extracurricular,
including their own potential for contribution to educational
diversity, they are never afforded the chance to compete with
applicants from the preferred groups for the special admissions
seats. At the same time, the preferred Page 438 U. S. 320 applicants have the opportunity to compete for every seat in the
class.
The fatal flaw in petitioner's preferential program is its
disregard of individual rights as guaranteed by the Fourteenth
Amendment. Shelley v. Kraemer, 334 U.S. at 334 U. S. 22 .
Such rights are not absolute. But when a State's distribution of
benefits or imposition of burdens hinges on ancestry or the color
of a person's skin, that individual is entitled to a demonstration
that the challenged classification is necessary to promote a
substantial state interest. Petitioner has failed to carry this
burden. For this reason, that portion of the California court's
judgment holding petitioner's special admissions program invalid
under the Fourteenth Amendment must be affirmed. C In enjoining petitioner from ever considering the race of any
applicant, however, the courts below failed to recognize that the
State has a substantial interest that legitimately may be served by
a properly devised admissions program involving the competitive
consideration of race and ethnic origin. For this reason, so much
of the California court's judgment as enjoins petitioner from any
consideration of the race of any applicant must be reversed. VI With respect to respondent's entitlement to an injunction
directing his admission to the Medical School, petitioner has
conceded that it could not carry its burden of proving that, but
for the existence of its unlawful special admissions program,
respondent still would not have been admitted. Hence, respondent is
entitled to the injunction, and that portion of the judgment must
be affirmed. [ Footnote
54 ] Page 438 U. S. 321 | 438
U.S. 265 app| APPENDIX TO OPINION OF POWELL, J. Harvard College Admissions Program [ Footnote 55 ] For the past 30 years, Harvard College has received each year
applications for admission that greatly exceed the number of places
in the freshman class. The number of applicants who are deemed to
be not "qualified" is comparatively small. The vast majority of
applicants demonstrate through test scores, high school records and
teachers' recommendations that they have the academic ability to do
adequate work at Harvard, and perhaps to do it with distinction.
Faced with the dilemma of choosing among a large number of
"qualified" candidates, the Committee on Admissions could use the
single criterion of scholarly excellence and attempt to determine
who among the candidates were likely to perform best academically.
But for the past 30 years, the Committee on Admissions has never
adopted this approach. The belief has been that, if scholarly
excellence were the sole or even predominant criterion, Harvard
College would lose a great deal of its vitality and intellectual
excellence, and that the quality of the educational Page 438 U. S. 322 experience offered to all students would suffer. Final Report of
W. J. Bender, Chairman of the Admission and Scholarship Committee
and Dean of Admissions and Financial Aid, pp. 20 et seq. (Cambridge, 1960). Consequently, after selecting those students
whose intellectual potential will seem extraordinary to the faculty
-- perhaps 150 or so out of an entering class of over 1,100 -- the
Committee seeks --
"variety in making its choices. This has seemed important . . .
in part because it adds a critical ingredient to the effectiveness
of the educational experience [in Harvard College]. . . . The
effectiveness of our students' educational experience has seemed to
the Committee to be affected as importantly by a wide variety of
interests, talents, backgrounds and career goals as it is by a fine
faculty and our libraries, laboratories and housing
arrangements. "
Dean of Admissions Fred L. Glimp, Final Report to the Faculty of
Arts and Sciences, 65 Official Register of Harvard University No.
25, 93, 10105 (1968) (emphasis supplied).
The belief that diversity adds an essential ingredient to the
educational process has long been a tenet of Harvard College
admissions. Fifteen or twenty years ago, however, diversity meant
students from California, New York, and Massachusetts; city
dwellers and farm boys; violinists, painters and football players;
biologists, historians and classicists; potential stockbrokers,
academics and politicians. The result was that very few ethnic or
racial minorities attended Harvard College. In recent years,
Harvard College has expanded the concept of diversity to include
students from disadvantaged economic, racial and ethnic groups.
Harvard College now recruits not only Californians or Louisianans,
but also blacks and Chicanos and other minority students.
Contemporary conditions in the United States mean that, if Harvard
College is to continue to offer a first-rate education to its
students, Page 438 U. S. 323 minority representation in the undergraduate body cannot be
ignored by the Committee on Admissions.
In practice, this new definition of diversity has meant that
race has been a factor in some admission decisions. When the
Committee on Admissions reviews the large middle group of
applicants who are "admissible" and deemed capable of doing good
work in their courses, the race of an applicant may tip the balance
in his favor just as geographic origin or a life spent on a farm
may tip the balance in other candidates' cases. A farm boy from
Idaho can bring something to Harvard College that a Bostonian
cannot offer. Similarly, a black student can usually bring
something that a white person cannot offer. The quality of the
educational experience of all the students in Harvard College
depends in part on these differences in the background and outlook
that students bring with them.
In Harvard College admissions, the Committee has not set target
quotas for the number of blacks, or of musicians, football players,
physicists or Californians to be admitted in a given year. At the
same time the Committee is aware that, if Harvard College is to
provide a truly heterogen[e]ous environment that reflects the rich
diversity of the United States, it cannot be provided without some
attention to numbers. It would not make sense, for example, to have
10 or 20 students out of 1, 100 whose homes are west of the
Mississippi. Comparably, 10 or 20 black students could not begin to
bring to their classmates and to each other the variety of points
of view, backgrounds and experiences of blacks in the United
States. Their small numbers might also create a sense of isolation
among the black students themselves, and thus make it more
difficult for them to develop and achieve their potential.
Consequently, when making its decisions, the Committee on
Admissions is aware that there is some relationship between numbers
and achieving the benefits to be derived from a diverse student
body, and between numbers and providing a reasonable environment
for those students admitted. But Page 438 U. S. 324 that awareness does not mean that the Committee sets a minimum
number of blacks or of people from west of the Mississippi who are
to be admitted. It means only that, in choosing among thousands of
applicants who are not only "admissible" academically but have
other strong qualities, the Committee, with a number of criteria in
mind, pays some attention to distribution among many types and
categories of students.
The further refinements sometimes required help to illustrate
the kind of significance attached to race. The Admissions
Committee, with only a few places left to fill, might find itself
forced to choose between A, the child of a successful black
physician in an academic community with promise of superior
academic performance, and B, a black who grew up in an inner-city
ghetto of semi-literate parents whose academic achievement was
lower, but who had demonstrated energy and leadership, as well as
an apparently abiding interest in black power. If a good number of
black students much like A, but few like B, had already been
admitted, the Committee might prefer B, and vice versa. If C, a
white student with extraordinary artistic talent, were also seeking
one of the remaining places, his unique quality might give him an
edge over both A and B. Thus, the critical criteria are often
individual qualities or experience not dependent upon race but
sometimes associated with it.
* MR. JUSTICE STEVENS views the judgment of the California court
as limited to prohibiting the consideration of race only in passing
upon Bakke's application. Post at 438 U. S.
408 -411. It must be remembered, however, that petitioner
here cross-complained in the trial court for a declaratory judgment
that its special program was constitutional, and it lost. The trial
court's judgment that the special program was unlawful was affirmed
by the California Supreme Court in an opinion which left no doubt
that the reason for its holding was petitioner's use of race in
consideration of ay candidate's application. Moreover, in
explaining the scope of its holding, the court quite clearly stated
that petitioner was prohibited from taking race into account in any
way in making admissions decisions:
"In addition, the University may properly as it in fact does,
consider other factors in evaluating an applicant, such as the
personal interview, recommendations, character, and matters
relating to the needs of the profession and society, such as an
applicant's professional goals. In short, the standards for
admission employed by the University are not constitutionally
infirm except to the extent that they are utilized in a racially
discriminatory manner. Disadvantaged applicants of all races must
be eligible for sympathetic consideration, and no applicant may be
rejected because of his race in favor of another who is less
qualified, as measured by standards applied without regard to race.
We reiterate, in view of the dissent's misinterpretation, that we
do not compel the University to utilize only 'the highest objective
academic credentials' as the criterion for admission." 18 Cal. 3d 34 ,
54-55, 553 P.2d 1152, 1166 (1976) (footnote omitted). This explicit
statement makes it unreasonable to assume that the reach of the
California court's judgment can be limited in the manner suggested
by MR. JUSTICE STEVENS.
** MR. JUSTICE BRENNAN, MR. JUSTICE WHITE, MR. JUSTICE MARSHALL,
and MR. JUSTICE BLACKMUN join Parts I and V-C of this opinion. MR.
JUSTICE WHITE also joins Part III-A of this opinion.
[ Footnote 1 ]
Material distributed to applicants for the class entering in
1973 described the special admissions program as follows:
"A special subcommittee of the Admissions Committee, made up of
faculty and medical students from minority groups, evaluates
applications from economically and/or educationally disadvantaged
backgrounds. The applicant may designate on the application form
that he or she requests such an evaluation. Ethnic minorities are
not categorically considered under the Task Force Program unless
they are from disadvantaged backgrounds. Our goals are: 1) A
short-range goal in the identification and recruitment of potential
candidates for admission to medical school in the near future, and
2) Our long-range goal is to stimulate career interest in health
professions among junior high and high school students."
"After receiving all pertinent information selected applicants
will receive a letter inviting them to our School of Medicine in
Davis for an interview. The interviews are conducted by at least
one faculty member and one student member of the Task Force
Committee. Recommendations are then made to the Admissions
Committee of the medical school. Some of the Task Force Faculty are
also members of the Admissions Committee."
"Long-range goals will be approached by meeting with counselors
and students of schools with large minority populations, as well as
with local youth and adult community groups."
"Applications for financial aid are available only after the
applicant has been accepted, and can only be awarded after
registration. Financial aid is available to students in the form of
scholarships and loans. In addition to the Regents' Scholarships
and President's Scholarship programs, the medical school
participates in the Health Professions Scholarship Program, which
makes funds available to students who otherwise might not be able
to pursue a medical education. Other scholarships and awards are
available to students who meet special eligibility qualifications.
Medical students are also eligible to participate in the Federally
Insured Student Loan Program and the American Medical Association
Education and Research Foundation Loan Program."
Applications for Admission are available from:
Admissions Office
School of Medicine
University of California
Davis, California 95616
Record 195. The letter distributed the following year was
virtually identical, except that the third paragraph was
omitted.
[ Footnote 2 ]
For the 1973 entering class of 100 seats, the Davis Medical
School received 2,464 applications. Id. at 117. For the
1974 entering class, 3,737 applications were submitted. Id. at 289.
[ Footnote 3 ]
That is, applications were considered and acted upon as they
were received, so that the process of filling the class took place
over a period of months, with later applications being considered
against those still on file from earlier in the year. Id. at 64.
[ Footnote 4 ]
The chairman normally checked to see if, among other things, the
applicant had been granted a waiver of the school's application
fee, which required a means test; whether the applicant had worked
during college or interrupted his education to support himself or
his family; and whether the applicant was a member of a minority
group. Id. at 666.
[ Footnote 5 ]
For the class entering in 1973, the total number of special
applicants was 297, of whom 73 were white. In 1974, 628 persons
applied to the special committee, of whom 172 were white. Id. at 133-134.
[ Footnote 6 ]
The following table provides a year-by-year comparison of
minority admissions at the Davis Medical School:
bwm:
Special Admissions Program General Admissions Total
---------------------------- ---------------------- -----
Blacks Chicanos Asians Total Blacks Chicanos Asians Total
1970. . . . 5 3 0 8 0 0 4 4 12
1971. . . . 4 9 2 15 1 0 8 9 24
1972. . . . 5 6 5 16 0 0 11 11 27
1973. . . . 6 8 2 16 0 2 13 15 31
1974. . . . 6 7 3 16 0 4 5 9 25
ewm: Id. at 216-218. Sixteen persons were admitted under the
special program in 1974, ibid., but one Asian withdrew
before the start of classes, and the vacancy was filled by a
candidate from the general admissions waiting list. Brief for
Petitioner 4 n. 5.
[ Footnote 7 ]
The following table compares Bakke's science grade point
average, overall grade point average, and MCAT scores with the
average scores of regular admittees and of special admittees in
both 1973 and 1974. Record 210, 223, 231, 234:
bwm:
Class Entering in 1973
MCAT (Percentiles)
Quanti- Gen.
SGPA OGPA Verbal tative Science Infor.
Bakke . . . . . . . 3.44 3.46 96 94 97 72
Average of regular
admittees. . . . . 3.51 3.49 81 76 83 69
Average of special
admittees. . . . . 2.62 2.88 46 24 35 33
Class Entering in 1974
MCAT (Percentiles)
Quanti- Gen.
SGPA OGPA Verbal tative Science Infor.
Bakke. . . . . . . . 3.44 3.46 96 94 97 72
Average of regular
admittees. . . . . 3.36 3.29 69 67 82 72
Average of special
admittees. . . . . 2.42 2.62 34 30 37 18
ewm:
Applicants admitted under the special program also had benchmark
scores significantly lower than many students, including Bakke,
rejected under the general admissions program, even though the
special rating system apparently gave credit for overcoming
"disadvantage." Id. at 181, 388.
[ Footnote 8 ]
Prior to the actual filing of the suit, Bakke discussed his
intentions with Peter C. Storandt, Assistant to the Dean of
Admissions at the Davis Medical School. Id. at 259-269.
Storandt expressed sympathy for Bakke's position and offered advice
on litigation strategy. Several amici imply that these
discussions render Bakke's suit "collusive." There is no
indication, however, that Storandt's views were those of the
Medical School, or that anyone else at the school even was aware of
Storandt's correspondence and conversations with Bakke. Storandt is
no longer with the University.
[ Footnote 9 ]
"[N]or shall any State . . . deny to any person within its
jurisdiction the equal protection of the laws."
[ Footnote 10 ]
"No special privileges or immunities shall ever be granted which
may not be altered, revoked, or repealed by the Legislature; nor
shall any citizen, or class of citizens, be granted privileges or
immunities which, upon the same terms, shall not be granted to all
citizens."
This section was recently repealed, and its provisions added to
Art. I, § 7, of the State Constitution.
[ Footnote 11 ]
Section 601 of Title VI, 78 Stat. 252, provides as follows:
"No person in the United States shall, on the ground of race,
color, or national origin, be excluded from participation in, be
denied the benefits of, or be subjected to discrimination under any
program or activity receiving Federal financial assistance."
[ Footnote 12 ]
Indeed, the University did not challenge the finding that
applicants who were not members of a minority group were excluded
from consideration in the special admissions process. 18 Cal. 3d at
44, 553 P.2d at 1159.
[ Footnote 13 ]
Petitioner has not challenged this aspect of the decision. The
issue of the proper placement of the burden of proof, then, is not
before us.
[ Footnote 14 ]
Several amici suggest that Bakke lacks standing,
arguing that he never showed that his injury -- exclusion from the
Medical School -- will be redressed by a favorable decision, and
that the petitioner "fabricated" jurisdiction by conceding its
inability to meet its burden of proof. Petitioner does not object
to Bakke's standing, but inasmuch as this charge concerns our
jurisdiction under Art. III, it must be considered and rejected.
First, there appears to be no reason to question the petitioner's
concession. It was not an attempt to stipulate to a conclusion of
law or to disguise actual facts of record. Cf. Swift &
Co. v. Hocking Valley R. Co., 243 U. S. 281 (1917).
Second, even if Bakke had been unable to prove that he would
have been admitted in the absence of the special program, it would
not follow that he lacked standing. The constitutional element of
standing is plaintiff's demonstration of any injury to himself that
is likely to be redressed by favorable decision of his claim. Warth v. Seldin, 422 U. S. 490 , 422 U. S. 498 (1975). The trial court found such an injury, apart from failure to
be admitted, in the University's decision not to permit Bakke to
compete for all 100 places in the class, simply because of his
race. Record 323. Hence, the constitutional requirements of Art.
III were met. The question of Bakke's admission vel non is
merely one of relief.
Nor is it fatal to Bakke's standing that he was not a
"disadvantaged" applicant. Despite the program's purported emphasis
on disadvantage, it was a minority enrollment program with a
secondary disadvantage element. White disadvantaged students were
never considered under the special program, and the University
acknowledges that its goal in devising the program was to increase
minority enrollment.
[ Footnote 15 ] See, e.g., 110 Cong.Rec. 5255 (1964) (remarks of Sen.
Case).
[ Footnote 16 ] E.g., Bossier Parish School Board v. Lemon, 370 F.2d
847, 851-852 (CA5), cert. denied, 388 U.S. 911 (1967); Natonbah v. Board of Education, 355 F.
Supp. 716 , 724 (NM 1973); cf. Lloyd v. Regional
Transportation Authority, 548 F.2d 1277, 1284-1287 (CA7 1977)
(Title V of Rehabilitation Act of 1973, 29 U.S.C. § 790 et
seq. (1976 ed.)); Piascik v. Cleveland Museum of
Art, 426 F.
Supp. 779 , 780 n. 1 (ND Ohio 1976) (Title IX of Education
Amendments of 1972, 20 U.S.C. § 1681 et seq. (1976
ed.)).
[ Footnote 17 ]
Section 602, as set forth in 42 U.S.C. § 2000d-1, reads as
follows:
"Each Federal department and agency which is empowered to extend
Federal financial assistance to any program or activity, by way of
grant, loan, or contract other than a contract of insurance or
guaranty, is authorized and directed to effectuate the provisions
of section 2000d of this title with respect to such program or
activity by issuing rules, regulations, or orders of general
applicability which shall be consistent with achievement of the
objectives of the statute authorizing the financial assistance in
connection with which the action is taken. No such rule,
regulation, or order shall become effective unless and until
approved by the President. Compliance with any requirement adopted
pursuant to this section may be effected (1) by the termination of
or refusal to grant or to continue assistance under such program or
activity to any recipient as to whom there has been an express
finding on the record, after opportunity for hearing, of a failure
to comply with such requirement, but such termination or refusal
shall be limited to the particular political entity, or part
thereof, or other recipient as to whom such a finding has been made
and, shall be �limited in its effect to the particular program, or
part thereof, in which such noncompliance has been so found, or(2)
by any other means authorized by law: Provided, however, That no
such action shall be taken until the department or agency concerned
has advised the appropriate person or persons of the failure to
comply with the requirement and has determined that compliance
cannot be secured by voluntary means. In the case of any action
terminating, or refusing to grant or continue, assistance because
of failure to comply with a requirement imposed pursuant to this
section, the head of the Federal department or agency shall file
with the committees of the House and Senate having legislative
jurisdiction over the program or activity involved a full written
report of the circumstances and the grounds for such action. No
such action shall become effective until thirty days have elapsed
after the filing of such report."
[ Footnote 18 ]
Several comments in the debates cast doubt on the existence of
any intent to create a private right of action. For example,
Representative Gill stated that no private right of action was
contemplated:
"Nowhere in this section do you find a comparable right of legal
action for a person who feels he has been denied his rights to
participate in the benefits of Federal funds. Nowhere. Only those
who have been cut off can go to court and present their claim."
110 Cong.Rec. 2467 (1964). Accord, id. at 7065 (remarks
of Sen. Keating); 6562 (remarks of Sen. Kuchel).
[ Footnote 19 ]
For example, Senator Humphrey stated as follows:
"Racial discrimination or segregation in the administration of
disaster relief is particularly shocking; and offensive to our
sense of justice and fair play. Human suffering draws no color
lines, and the administration of help to the sufferers should
not." Id. at 6547. See also id. at 12675 (remarks of
Sen. Allott); 6561 (remarks of Sen. Kuchel); 2494, 6047 (remarks of
Sen. Pastore). But see id. at 15893 (remarks of Rep.
MacGregor); 13821 (remarks of Sen. Saltonstall); 10920 (remarks of
Sen. Javits); 5266, 5807 (remarks of Sen. Keating).
[ Footnote 20 ] See, e.g., id. at 7064-7065 (remarks of Sen. Ribicoff);
7054-7055 (remarks of Sen. Pastore); 6543-6544 (remarks of Sen.
Humphrey); 2595 (remarks of Rep. Donohue); 2467-2468 (remarks of
Rep. Celler); 1643, 2481-2482 (remarks of Rep. Ryan); H.R.Rep. No.
914, 88th Cong., 1st Sess., pt. 2, pp. 24-25 (1963).
[ Footnote 21 ] See, e.g., 110 Cong.Rec. 2467 (1964) (remarks of Rep.
Lindsay). See also id. at 2766 (remarks of Rep.
Matsunaga); 2731-2732 (remarks of Rep. Dawson); 2595 (remarks of
Rep. Donohue); 1527-1528 (remarks of Rep. Celler).
[ Footnote 22 ] See, e.g., id. at 12675, 12677 (remarks of Sen.
Allott); 7064 (remarks of Sen. Pell); 7057, 7062-7064 (remarks of
Sen. Pastore); 5243 (remarks of Sen. Clark).
[ Footnote 23 ] See, e.g., id. at 6052 (remarks of Sen. Johnston); 5863
(remarks of Sen. Eastland); 5612 (remarks of Sen. Ervin); 5251
(remarks of Sen. Talmadge); 1632 (remarks of Rep. Dowdy); 1619
(remarks of Rep. Abernethy).
[ Footnote 24 ] See also id. at 7057, 13333 (remarks of Sen. Ribicoff);
7057 (remarks of Sen. Pastore); 5606-5607 (remarks of Sen. Javits);
5253, 5863-5864, 13442 (remarks of Sen. Humphrey).
[ Footnote 25 ]
That issue has generated a considerable amount of scholarly
controversy. See, e.g., Ely, The Constitutionality of
Reverse Racial Discrimination, 41 U.Chi.L.Rev. 723 (1974);
Greenawalt, Judicial Scrutiny of "Benign" Racial Preference in Law
School Admissions, 75 Colum.L.Rev. 559 (1975); Kaplan, Equal
Justice in an Unequal World: Equality for the Negro, 61 Nw.U.L.Rev.
363 (1966); Karst & Horowitz, Affirmative Action and Equal
Protection, 60 Va.L.Rev. 955 (1974); O'Neil, Racial Preference and
Higher Education: The Larger Context, 60 Va.L.Rev. 925 (1974);
Posner, The DeFunis Case and the Constitutionality of
Preferential Treatment of Racial Minorities, 1974 Sup.Ct.Rev. 1;
Redish, Preferential Law School Admissions and the Equal Protection
Clause: An Analysis of the Competing Arguments, 22 UCLA L.Rev. 343
(1974); Sandalow, Racial Preferences in Higher Education: Political
Responsibility and the Judicial Role, 42 U.Chi.L.Rev. 653 (1975);
Sedler, Racial Preference, Reality and the Constitution: Bakke
v. Regents of the University of California, 17 Santa Clara
L.Rev. 329 (1977); Seeburger, A Heuristic Argument Against
Preferential Admissions, 39 U.Pitt.L.Rev. 285 (1977).
[ Footnote 26 ]
Petitioner defines "quota" as a requirement which must be met,
but can never be exceeded, regardless of the quality of the
minority applicants. Petitioner declares that there is no "floor"
under the total number of minority students admitted; completely
unqualified students will not be admitted simply to meet a "quota."
Neither is there a "ceiling," since an unlimited number could be
admitted through the general admissions process. On this basis, the
special admissions program does not meet petitioner's definition of
a quota.
The court below found -- and petitioner does not deny -- that
white applicants could not compete for the 16 places reserved
solely for the special admissions program. 18 Cal. 3d at 44, 553
P.2d at 1159. Both courts below characterized this as a "quota"
system.
[ Footnote 27 ]
Moreover, the University's special admissions program involves a
purposeful, acknowledged use of racial criteria. This is not a
situation in which the classification on its face is racially
neutral, but has a disproportionate racial impact. In that
situation, plaintiff must establish an intent to discriminate. Arlington Heights v. Metropolitan Housing Dev. Corp., 429 U. S. 252 , 429 U. S.
264 -265 (1977); Washington v. Davis, 426 U. S. 229 , 426 U. S. 242 (1976); see Yick Wo v. Hopkins, 118 U.
S. 356 (1886).
[ Footnote 28 ]
After Carolene Products, the first specific reference
in our decisions to the elements of "discreteness and insularity"
appears in Minersville School District v. Gobitis, 310 U. S. 586 , 310 U. S. 606 (1940) (Stone, J., dissenting). The next does not appear until
1970. Oregon v. Mitchell, 400 U.
S. 112 , 400 U. S. 295 n. 14 (STEWART, J., concurring in part and dissenting in part).
These elements have been relied upon in recognizing a suspect class
in only one group of cases, those involving aliens. E.g.,
Graham v. Richardson, 403 U. S. 365 , 403 U. S. 372 (1971).
[ Footnote 29 ]
Tussman & tenBroek, The Equal Protection of the Law, 37
Calif.L.Rev. 341, 381 (1949).
[ Footnote 30 ]
M. Jones, American Immigration 177-246 (1960).
[ Footnote 31 ]
J. Higham, Strangers in the Land (1955); G. Abbott, The
Immigrant and the Community (1917); P. Roberts, The New Immigration
66-73, 86-91, 248-261 (1912). See also E. Fenton,
Immigrants and Unions: A Case Study 561-562 (1975).
[ Footnote 32 ]
"Members of various religious and ethnic groups, primarily but
not exclusively of Eastern, Middle, and Southern European ancestry,
such as Jews, Catholics, Italians, Greeks, and Slavic groups,
continue to be excluded from executive, middle-management, and
other job levels because of discrimination based upon their
religion and/or national origin."
41 CFR § 60-50.1(b) (1977).
[ Footnote 33 ] E.g., P. Roberts, supra, n 31, at 75; G. Abbott, supra, n 31, at 270-271. See
generally n 31, supra. [ Footnote 34 ]
In the view of MR. JUSTICE BRENNAN, MR. JUSTICE WHITE, MR.
JUSTICE MARSHALL, and MR. JUSTICE BLACKMUN, the pliable notion of
"stigma" is the crucial element in analyzing racial
classifications, see, e.g., post at 438 U. S. 361 , 438 U. S. 362 .
The Equal Protection Clause is not framed in terms of "stigma."
Certainly the word has no clearly defined constitutional meaning.
It reflects a subjective judgment that is standardless. All
state-imposed classifications that rearrange burdens and benefits
on the basis of race are likely to be viewed with deep resentment
by the individuals burdened. The denial to innocent persons of
equal rights and opportunities may outrage those so deprived, and
therefore may be perceived as invidious. These individuals are
likely to find little comfort in the notion that the deprivation
they are asked to endure is merely the price of membership in the
dominant majority, and that its imposition is inspired by the
supposedly benign purpose of aiding others. One should not lightly
dismiss the inherent unfairness of, and the perception of
mistreatment that accompanies, a system of allocating benefits and
privileges on the basis of skin color and ethnic origin. Moreover,
MR. JUSTICE BRENNAN, MR. JUSTICE WHITE, MR. JUSTICE MARSHALL, and
MR. JUSTICE BLACKMUN offer no principle for deciding whether
preferential classifications reflect a benign remedial purpose or a
malevolent stigmatic classification, since they are willing in this
case to accept mere post hoc declarations by an isolated
state entity -- a medical school faculty -- unadorned by
particularized findings of past discrimination, to establish such a
remedial purpose.
[ Footnote 35 ]
Professor Bickel noted the self-contradiction of that view:
"The lesson of the great decisions of the Supreme Court and the
lesson of contemporary history have been the same for at least a
generation -- discrimination on the basis of race is illegal,
immoral, unconstitutional, inherently wrong, and destructive of
democratic society. Now this is to be unlearned, and we are told
that this is not a matter of fundamental principle, but only a
matter of whose ox is gored. Those for whom racial equality was
demanded are to be more equal than others. Having found support in
the Constitution for equality, they now claim support for
inequality under the same Constitution."
A. Bickel, The Morality of Consent 133 (1975).
[ Footnote 36 ]
As I am in agreement with the view that race may be taken into
account as a factor in an admissions program, I agree with my
Brothers BRENNAN, WHITE, MARSHALL, and BLACKMUN that the portion of
the judgment that would proscribe all consideration of race must be
reversed. See 438 U. S. infra. But I disagree with much that is said in their
opinion.
They would require, as a justification for a program such as
petitioner's, only two findings: (i) that there has been some form
of discrimination against the preferred minority groups by "society
at large," post at 438 U. S. 369 (it being conceded that petitioner had no history of
discrimination), and (ii) that "there is reason to believe" that
the disparate impact sought to be rectified by the program is the
"product" of such discrimination:
"If it was reasonable to conclude -- as we hold that it was --
that the failure of minorities to qualify for admission at Davis
under regular procedures was due principally to the effects of past
discrimination, then there is a reasonable likelihood that, but for
pervasive racial discrimination, respondent would have failed to
qualify for admission even in the absence of Davis' special
admissions program." Post at 438 U. S.
365 -366.
The breadth of this hypothesis is unprecedented in our
constitutional system. The first step is easily taken. No one
denies the regrettable fact that there has been societal
discrimination in this country against various racial and ethnic
groups. The second step, however, involves a speculative leap: but
for this discrimination by society at large, Bakke "would have
failed to qualify for admission" because Negro applicants --
nothing is said about Asians, cf., e.g., post at 438 U. S. 374 n. 57 -- would have made better scores. Not one word in the record
supports this conclusion, and the authors of the opinion offer no
standard for courts to use in applying such a presumption of
causation to other racial or ethnic classifications. This failure
is a grave one, since, if it may be concluded on this record that
each of the minority groups preferred by the petitioner's special
program is entitled to the benefit of the presumption, it would
seem difficult to determine that any of the dozens of minority
groups that have suffered "societal discrimination" cannot also
claim it in any area of social intercourse. See 438 U. S. infra. [ Footnote 37 ]
Mr. Justice Douglas has noted the problems associated with such
inquiries:
"The reservation of a proportion of the law school class for
members of selected minority groups is fraught with . . . dangers,
for one must immediately determine which groups are to receive such
favored treatment and which are to be excluded, the proportions of
the class that are to be allocated to each, and even the criteria
by which to determine whether an individual is a member of a
favored group. [ Cf. Plessy v. Ferguson, 163 U. S.
537 , 163 U. S. 549 , 163 U. S.
552 (1896).] There is no assurance that a common
agreement can be reached, and first the schools, and then the
courts, will be buffeted with the competing claims. The University
of Washington included Filipinos, but excluded Chinese and
Japanese; another school may limit its program to blacks, or to
blacks and Chicanos. Once the Court sanctioned racial preferences
such as these, it could not then wash its hands of the matter,
leaving it entirely in the discretion of the school, for then we
would have effectively overruled Sweatt v. Painter, 339 U. S.
629 , and allowed imposition of a 'zero' allocation. But
what standard is the Court to apply when a rejected applicant of
Japanese ancestry brings suit to require the University of
Washington to extend the same privileges to his group? The
Committee might conclude that the population of Washington is now
2% Japanese, and that Japanese also constitute 2% of the Bar, but
that, had they not been handicapped by a history of discrimination,
Japanese would now constitute 5% of the Bar, or 20%. Or,
alternatively, the Court could attempt to assess how grievously
each group has suffered from discrimination, and allocate
proportions accordingly; if that were the standard, the current
University of Washington policy would almost surely fall, for there
is no Western State which can claim that it has always treated
Japanese and Chinese in a fair and evenhanded manner. See,
e.g., Yick Wo v. Hopkins, 118 U. S. 356 ; Terrace v.
Thompson, 263 U. S. 197 ; Oyama v.
California, 332 U. S. 633 . This Court has
not sustained a racial classification since the wartime cases of Korematsu v. United States, 323 U. S.
214 , and Hirabayashi v. United States, 320 U. S.
81 , involving curfews and relocations imposed upon
Japanese-Americans."
"Nor, obviously, will the problem be solved if, next year, the
Law School included only Japanese and Chinese, for then Norwegians
and Swedes, Poles and Italians, Puerto Ricans and Hungarians, and
all other groups which form this diverse Nation would have just
complaints." DeFunis v. Odegaard, 416 U. S. 312 , 416 U. S.
337 -340 (1974) (dissenting opinion) (footnotes omitted)
.
[ Footnote 38 ]
R. Dahl, A Preface to Democratic Theory (1956); Posner, supra, n 25, at
27.
[ Footnote 39 ]
Petitioner cites three lower court decisions allegedly deviating
from this general rule in school desegregation cases: Offermann
v. Nitkowski, 378 F.2d 22 (CA2 1967); Wanner v. County
School Board, 357 F.2d 452 (CA4 1966); Springfield School
Committee v. Barksdale, 348 F.2d 261 (CA1 1965). Of these, Wanner involved a school system held to have been de
jure segregated and enjoined from maintaining segregation;
racial districting was deemed necessary. 357 F.2d at 454. Cf.
United Jewish Organizations v. Carey, 430 U.
S. 144 (1977). In Barksdale and Offermann, courts did approve voluntary districting
designed to eliminate discriminatory attendance patterns. In
neither, however, was there any showing that the school board
planned extensive pupil transportation that might threaten liberty
or privacy interests. See Keyes v. School District No. 1, 413 U. S. 189 , 413 U.S. 240 -250 (1973)
(POWELL, J., concurring in part and dissenting in part). Nor were
white students deprived of an equal opportunity for education.
Respondent's position is wholly dissimilar to that of a pupil
bused from his neighborhood school to a comparable school in
another neighborhood in compliance with a desegregation decree.
Petitioner did not arrange for respondent to attend a different
medical school in order to desegregate Davis Medical School;
instead, it denied him admission, and may have deprived him
altogether of a medical education.
[ Footnote 40 ]
Every decision upholding the requirement of preferential hiring
under the authority of Exec.Order No. 11246, 3 CFR 339 (1964-1965
Comp.), has emphasized the existence of previous discrimination as
a predicate for the imposition of a preferential remedy. Contractors Association of Eastern Pennsylvania; Southern
Illinois Builders Assn. v. Ogilvie, 471 F.2d 680 (CA7 1972); Joyce v. McCrane, 320 F.
Supp. 1284 (NJ 1970); Weiner v. Cuyahoga Community College
District, 19 Ohio St.2d 35, 249 N.E.2d 907, cert.
denied, 396 U.S. 1004 (1970). See also Rosetti Contracting
Co. v. Brennan, 508 F.2d 1039, 1041 (CA7 1975); Associated
General Contractors of Massachusetts, Inc. v. Altshuler, 490
F.2d 9 (CA1 1973), cert. denied, 416 U.S. 957 (1974); Northeast Constr. Co. v. Romney, 157 U.S.App.D.C. 381,
383, 390, 485 F.2d 752, 754, 761 (1973).
[ Footnote 41 ]
This case does not call into question congressionally authorized
administrative actions, such as consent decrees under Title VII or
approval of reapportionment plans under § 5 of the Voting Rights
Act of 1965, 42 U.S.C. § 1973c (1970 ed., Supp. V). In such cases,
there has been detailed legislative consideration of the various
indicia of previous constitutional or statutory violations, e.g., South Carolina v. Katzenbach, 383 U.
S. 301 , 383 U. S.
308 -310 (1966) (§ 5), and particular administrative
bodies have been charged with monitoring various activities in
order to detect such violations and formulate appropriate remedies. See Hampton v. Mow Sun Wong, 426 U. S.
88 , 426 U. S. 103 (1976).
Furthermore, we are not here presented with an occasion to
review legislation by Congress pursuant to its powers under § 2 of
the Thirteenth Amendment and § 5 of the Fourteenth Amendment to
remedy the effects of prior discrimination. Katzenbach v.
Morgan, 384 U. S. 641 (1966); Jones v. Alfred H. Mayer Co., 392 U.
S. 409 (1968). We have previously recognized the special
competence of Congress to make findings with respect to the effects
of identified past discrimination and its discretionary authority
to take appropriate remedial measures.
[ Footnote 42 ]
Petitioner also cites our decision in Morton v.
Mancari, 417 U. S. 535 (1974), for the proposition that the State may prefer members of
traditionally disadvantaged groups. In Mancari, we
approved a hiring preference for qualified Indians in the Bureau of
Indian Affairs of the Department of the Interior (BIA). We observed
in that case, however, that the legal status of the BIA is sui
generis. Id. at 417 U. S. 554 .
Indeed, we found that the preference was not racial at all, but
"an employment criterion reasonably designed to further the
cause of Indian self-government and to make the BIA more responsive
to . . . groups . . . whose lives and activities are governed by
the BIA in a unique fashion." Ibid. [ Footnote 43 ]
A number of distinct subgoals have been advanced as falling
under the rubric of "compensation for past discrimination." For
example, it is said t.hat preferences for Negro applicants may
compensate for harm done them personally, or serve to place them at
economic levels they might have attained but for discrimination
against their forebears. Greenawalt, supra, n 25, at 581-586. Another view of the
"compensation" goal is that it serves as a form of reparation by
the "majority" to a victimized group as a whole. B. Bittker, The
Case for Black Reparations (1973). That justification for racial or
ethnic preference has been subjected to much criticism. E.
Greenawalt, supra, n 25, at 581; Posner, supra, n 25, at 16-17, and n. 33. Finally, it has
been argued that ethnic preferences "compensate" the group by
providing examples of success whom other members of the group will
emulate, thereby advancing the group's interest and society's
interest in encouraging new generations to overcome the barriers
and frustrations of the past. Redish, supra, n 25, at 391. For purposes of
analysis these subgoals need not be considered separately.
Racial classifications in admissions conceivably could serve a
fifth purpose, one which petitioner does not articulate: fair
appraisal of each individual's academic promise in the light of
some cultural bias in grading or testing procedures. To the extent
that race and ethnic background were considered only to the extent
of curing established inaccuracies in predicting academic
performance, it might be argued that there is no "preference" at
all. Nothing in this record, however, suggests either that any of
the quantitative factors considered by the Medical School were
culturally biased, or that petitioner's special admissions program
was formulated to correct for any such biases. Furthermore, if race
or ethnic background were used solely to arrive at an unbiased
prediction of academic success, the reservation of fixed numbers of
seats would be inexplicable.
[ Footnote 44 ]
MR. JUSTICE BRENNAN, MR. JUSTICE WHITE, MR. JUSTICE MARSHALL,
and MR. JUSTICE BLACKMUN misconceive the scope of this Court's
holdings under Title VII when they suggest that "disparate impact"
alone is sufficient to establish a violation of that statute and,
by analogy, other civil rights measures. See post at 438 U. S.
363 -366, and n. 42. That this was not the meaning of
Title VII was made quite clear in the seminal decision in this
area, Griggs v. Duke Power Co., 401 U.
S. 424 (1971):
" Discriminatory preference for any group, minority or
majority, is precisely and only what Congress has proscribed. What
is required by Congress is the removal of artificial,
arbitrary, and unnecessary barriers to employment when the
barriers operate invidiously to discriminate on the basis of racial
or other impermissible classification." Id. at 401 U. S. 431 (emphasis added). Thus, disparate impact is a basis for relief
under Title VII only if the practice in question is not founded on
"business necessity," ibid., or lacks "a manifest
relationship to the employment in question," id. at 401 U. S. 432 . See also McDonnell Douglas Corp. v. Green, 411 U.
S. 792 , 411 U. S.
802 -803, 411 U. S.
805 -806 (1973). Nothing in this record -- as opposed to
some of the general literature cited by MR. JUSTICE BRENNAN, MR
JUSTICE WHITE, MR. JUSTICE MARSHALL, and MR. JUSTICE BLACKMUN --
even remotely suggests that the disparate impact of the general
admissions program at Davis Medical School, resulting primarily
from the sort of disparate test scores and grades set forth in n 7, supra, is without
educational justification.
Moreover, the presumption in Griggs -- that disparate
impact without any showing of business justification established
the existence of discrimination in violation of the statute -- was
based on legislative determinations, wholly absent here, that past
discrimination had handicapped various minority groups to such an
extent that disparate impact could be traced to identifiable
instances of past discrimination:
"[Congress sought] to achieve equality of employment
opportunities and remove barriers that have operated in the past to
favor an identifiable group of white employees over other
employees. Under the Act, practices, procedures, or tests neutral
on their face, and even neutral in terms of intent, cannot be
maintained if they operate to 'freeze' the status quo of
prior discriminatory employment practices." Griggs, supra at 401 U. S.
429 -430. See, e.g., H.R.Rep. No. 914, 88th
Cong., 1st Sess., pt. 2, p. 26 (1963) ("Testimony supporting the
fact of discrimination in employment is overwhelming"). See
generally Vaas, Title VII: The Legislative History, 7 B. C.
Ind. & Com.L.Rev. 431 (1966). The Court emphasized that
"the Act does not command that any person be hired simply
because he was formerly the subject of discrimination, or because
he is a member of a minority group."
401 U.S. at 401 U. S.
430 -431. Indeed, § 703(j) of the Act makes it clear that
preferential treatment for an individual or minority group to
correct an existing "imbalance" may not be required under Title
VII. 42 U.S.C. § 2000e-2(j). Thus, Title VII principles support the
proposition that findings of identified discrimination must precede
the fashioning of remedial measures embodying racial
classifications.
[ Footnote 45 ]
For example, the University is unable to explain its selection
of only the four favored groups -- Negroes, Mexican-Americans,
American Indians, and Asians -- for preferential treatment. The
inclusion of the last group is especially curious in light of the
substantial numbers of Asians admitted through the regular
admissions process. See also n 37, supra. [ Footnote 46 ]
The only evidence in the record with respect to such
underservice is a newspaper article. Record 473.
[ Footnote 47 ]
It is not clear that petitioner's two-track system, even if
adopted throughout the country, would substantially increase
representation of blacks in the medical profession. That is the
finding of a recent study by Sleeth & Mishell, Black
Under-Representation in United States Medical Schools, 297 New
England J. of Med. 1146 (1977). Those authors maintain that the
cause of black underrepresentation lies in the small size of the
national pool of qualified black applicants. In their view, this
problem is traceable to the poor premedical experiences of black
undergraduates, and can be remedied effectively only by developing
remedial programs for black students before they enter college.
[ Footnote 48 ]
The president of Princeton University has described some of the
benefits derived from a diverse student body:
"[A] great deal of learning occurs informally. It occurs through
interactions among students of both sexes; of different races,
religions, and backgrounds; who come from cities and rural areas,
from various states and countries; who have a wide variety of
interests, talents, and perspectives; and who are able, directly or
indirectly, to learn from their differences and to stimulate one
another to reexamine even their most deeply held assumptions about
themselves and their world. As a wise graduate of ours observed in
commenting on this aspect of the educational process, 'People do
not learn very much when they are surrounded only by the likes of
themselves.'"
" * * * *" "In the nature of things, it is hard to know how, and when, and
even if, this informal 'learning through diversity' actually
occurs. It does not occur for everyone. For many, however, the
unplanned, casual encounters with roommates, fellow sufferers in an
organic chemistry class, student workers in the library, teammates
on a basketball squad, or other participants in class affairs or
student government can be subtle and yet powerful sources of
improved understanding and personal growth."
Bowen, Admissions and the Relevance of Race, Princeton Alumni
Weekly 7, 9 (Sept. 26, 1977).
[ Footnote 49 ]
Graduate admissions decisions, like those at the undergraduate
level, are concerned with
"assessing the potential contributions to the society of each
individual candidate following his or her graduation --
contributions defined in the broadest way to include the doctor and
the poet, the most active participant in business or government
affairs and the keenest critic of all things organized, the
solitary scholar and the concerned parent." Id. at 10.
[ Footnote 50 ] See Manning, The Pursuit of Fairness in Admissions to
Higher Education, in Carnegie Council on Policy Studies in Higher
Education, Selective Admission in Higher Education 19, 57-59
(1977).
[ Footnote 51 ]
The admissions program at Princeton has been described in
similar terms:
"While race is not, in and of itself, a consideration in
determining basic qualifications, and while there are obviously
significant differences in background and experience among
applicants of every race, in some situations, race can be helpful
information in enabling the admission officer to understand more
fully what a particular candidate has accomplished -- and against
what odds. Similarly, such factors as family circumstances and
previous educational opportunities may be relevant, either in
conjunction with race or ethnic background (with which they may be
associated) or on their own."
Bowen, supra, n 48, at 8-9.
For an illuminating discussion of such flexible admissions
systems, see Manning, supra, n 50, at 57-59.
[ Footnote 52 ]
The denial to respondent of this right to individualized
consideration without regard to his race is the principal evil of
petitioner' special admissions program. Nowhere in the opinion of
MR. JUSTICE BRENNAN, MR JUSTICE WHITE, MR. JUSTICE MARSHALL, and MR
JUSTICE BLACKMUN is this denial even addressed.
[ Footnote 53 ]
Universities, like the prosecutor in Swain, may make
individualized decisions, in which ethnic background plays a part,
under a presumption of legality and legitimate educational purpose.
So long as the university proceeds on an individualized,
case-by-case basis, there is no warrant for judicial interference
in the academic process. If an applicant can establish that the
institution does not adhere to a policy of individual comparisons,
or can show that a systematic exclusion of certain groups results,
the presumption of legality might be overcome, creating the
necessity of proving legitimate educational purpose.
There also are strong policy reasons that correspond to the
constitutional distinction between petitioner's preference program
and one that assures a measure of competition among all applicants.
Petitioner's program will be viewed as inherently unfair by the
public generally, as well as by applicants for admission to state
universities. Fairness in individual competition for opportunities,
especially those provided by the State, is a widely cherished
American ethic. Indeed, in a broader sense, an underlying
assumption of the rule of law is the worthiness of a system of
justice based on fairness to the individual. As Mr. Justice
Frankfurter declared in another connection, "[j]ustice must satisfy
the appearance of justice." Offutt v. United States, 348 U. S. 11 , 348 U. S. 14 (1954).
[ Footnote 54 ]
There is no occasion for remanding the case to permit petitioner
to reconstruct what might have happened if it had been operating
the type of program described as legitimate in 438 U.
S. supra. Cf. Mt. Healthy City Board of Ed.
v. Doyle, 429 U. S. 274 , 429 U. S.
284 -287 (1977). In Mt. Healthy, there was
considerable doubt whether protected First Amendment activity had
been the "but for" cause of Doyle's protested discharge. Here, in
contrast, there is no question as to the sole reason for
respondent's rejection -- purposeful racial discrimination in the
form of the special admissions program. Having injured respondent
solely on the basis of an unlawful classification, petitioner
cannot now hypothesize that it might have employed lawful means of
achieving the same result. See Arlington Heights v.
Metropolitan Housing Dev. Corp., 429 U.S. at 429 U. S.
265 -266. No one can say how -- or even if -- petitioner
would have operated its admissions process if it had known that
legitimate alternatives were available. Nor is there a record
revealing that legitimate alternative grounds for the decision
existed, as there was in Mt. Healthy. In sum, a remand
would result in fictitious recasting of past conduct.
[ Footnote 55 ]
This statement appears in the Appendix to the Brief for Columbia
University, Harvard University, Stanford University, and the
University of Pennsylvania, as Amici Curiae. Opinion of MR. JUSTICE BRENNAN, MR. JUSTICE WHITE, MR. JUSTICE
MARSHALL, and MR, JUSTICE BLACKMUN, concurring in the judgment in
part and dissenting in part.
The Court today, in reversing in part the judgment of the
Supreme Court of California, affirms the constitutional power of
Federal and State Governments to act affirmatively to achieve equal
opportunity for all. The difficulty of the issue presented --
whether government may use race-conscious programs to redress the
continuing effects of past discrimination -- Page 438 U. S. 325 and the mature consideration which each of our Brethren has
brought to it have resulted in many opinions, no single one
speaking for the Court. But this should not and must not mask the
central meaning of today's opinions: Government may take race into
account when it acts not to demean or insult any racial group, but
to remedy disadvantages cast on minorities by past racial
prejudice, at least when appropriate findings have been made by
judicial, legislative, or administrative bodies with competence to
act in this area.
THE CHIEF JUSTICE and our Brothers STEWART, REHNQUIST, and
STEVENS, have concluded that Title VI of the Civil Rights Act of
1964, 78 Stat. 252, as amended, 42 U.S.C. § 2000d et seq., prohibits programs such as that at the Davis Medical School. On
this statutory theory alone, they would hold that respondent Allan
Bakke's rights have been violated, and that he must, therefore, be
admitted to the Medical School. Our Brother POWELL, reaching the
Constitution, concludes that, although race may be taken into
account in university admissions, the particular special admissions
program used by petitioner, which resulted in the exclusion of
respondent Bakke, was not shown to be necessary to achieve
petitioner's stated goals. Accordingly, these Members of the Court
form a majority of five affirming the judgment of the Supreme Court
of California insofar as it holds that respondent Bakke "is
entitled to an order that he be admitted to the University." 18 Cal. 3d 34 ,
64, 553 P.2d 1152, 1172 (1976).
We agree with MR. JUSTICE POWELL that, as applied to the case
before us, Title VI goes no further in prohibiting the use of race
than the Equal Protection Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment
itself. We also agree that the effect of the California Supreme
Court's affirmance of the judgment of the Superior Court of
California would be to prohibit the University from establishing in
the future affirmative action programs that take race into account. See ante at 438 U. S. 271 n. Since we conclude that the affirmative admissions program at the
Davis Page 438 U. S. 326 Medical School is constitutional, we would reverse the judgment
below in all respects. MR. JUSTICE POWELL agrees that some uses of
race in university admissions are permissible and, therefore, he
joins with us to make five votes reversing the judgment below
insofar as it prohibits the University from establishing
race-conscious programs in the future. [ Footnote 2/1 ] I Our Nation was founded on the principle that "all Men are
created equal." Yet candor requires acknowledgment that the Framers
of our Constitution, to forge the 13 Colonies into one Nation,
openly compromised this principle of equality with its antithesis:
slavery. The consequences of this compromise are well known, and
have aptly been called our "American Dilemma." Still, it is well to
recount how recent the time has ben, if it has yet come, when the
promise of our principles has flowered into the actuality of equal
opportunity for all regardless of race or color.
The Fourteenth Amendment, the embodiment in the Constitution of
our abiding belief in human equality, has been the law of our land
for only slightly more than half its 200 years. And for half of
that half, the Equal Protection Clause of the Amendment was largely
moribund, so that, as late as 1927, Mr. Justice Holmes could sum up
the importance of that Clause by remarking that it was the "last
resort of constitutional arguments." Buck v. Bell, 274 U. S. 200 , 274 U. S. 208 (1927). Worse than desuetude, the Clause was early turned against
those whom it was intended to set free, condemning them to a
"separate but equal" [ Footnote 2/2 ]
status before the law, a status Page 438 U. S. 327 always separate but seldom equal. Not until 1954 -- only 24
years ago -- was this odious doctrine interred by our decision in Brown v. Board of Education, 347 U.
S. 483 ( Brown I ), and its progeny, [ Footnote 2/3 ] which proclaimed that
separate schools and public facilities of all sorts were inherently
unequal and forbidden under our Constitution. Even then, inequality
was not eliminated with "all deliberate speed." Brown v. Board
of Education, 349 U. S. 294 , 349 U. S. 301 (1955). In 1968 [ Footnote 2/4 ] and
again in 1971, [ Footnote 2/5 ] for
example, we were forced to remind school boards of their obligation
to eliminate racial discrimination root and branch. And a glance at
our docket [ Footnote 2/6 ] and at
dockets of lower courts will show that, even today, officially
sanctioned discrimination is not a thing of the past.
Against this background, claims that law must be "colorblind" or
that the datum of race is no longer relevant to public policy must
be seen as aspiration, rather than as description of reality. This
is not to denigrate aspiration; for reality rebukes us that race
has too often been used by those who would stigmatize and oppress
minorities. Yet we cannot -- and, as we shall demonstrate, need not
under our Constitution or Title VI, which merely extends the
constraints of the Fourteenth Amendment to private parties who
receive federal funds -- let color blindness become myopia which
masks the reality that many "created equal" have been treated
within our lifetimes as inferior both by the law and by their
fellow citizens. Page 438 U. S. 328 II The threshold question we must decide is whether Title VI of the
Civil Rights Act of 1964 bars recipients of federal funds from
giving preferential consideration to disadvantaged members of
racial minorities as part of a program designed to enable such
individuals to surmount the obstacles imposed by racial
discrimination. [ Footnote 2/7 ] We
join Parts I and V-C of our Brother POWELL's opinion, and three of
us agree with his conclusion in Part II that this case does not
require us to resolve the question whether there is a private right
of action under Title VI. [ Footnote
2/8 ]
In our view, Title VI prohibits only those uses of racial
criteria that would violate the Fourteenth Amendment if employed by
a State or its agencies; it does not bar the preferential treatment
of racial minorities as a means of remedying past societal
discrimination to the extent that such action is consistent with
the Fourteenth Amendment. The legislative history of Title VI,
administrative regulations interpreting the statute, subsequent
congressional and executive action, and the prior decisions of this
Court compel this conclusion. None of these sources lends support
to the proposition that Congress intended to bar all race-conscious
efforts to extend the benefits of federally financed programs to
minorities who have been historically excluded from the full
benefits of American life. A The history of Title VI -- from President Kennedy's request that
Congress grant executive departments and agencies authority Page 438 U. S. 329 to cut off federal funds to programs that discriminate against
Negroes through final enactment of legislation incorporating his
proposals -- reveals one fixed purpose: to give the Executive
Branch of Government clear authority to terminate federal funding
of private programs that use race as a means of disadvantaging
minorities in a manner that would be prohibited by the Constitution
if engaged in by government.
This purpose was first expressed in President Kennedy's June 19,
1963, message to Congress proposing the legislation that
subsequently became the Civil Rights Act of 1964. [ Footnote 2/9 ] Page 438 U. S. 330 Representative Celler, the Chairman of the House Judiciary
Committee, and the floor manager of the legislation in the House,
introduced Title VI in words unequivocally expressing the intent to
provide the Federal Government with the means of assuring that its
funds were not used to subsidize racial discrimination inconsistent
with the standards imposed by the Fourteenth and Fifth Amendments
upon state and federal action.
"The bill would offer assurance that hospitals financed by
Federal money would not deny adequate care to Negroes. It would
prevent abuse of food distribution programs whereby Negroes have
been known to be denied food surplus supplies when white persons
were given such food. It would assure Negroes the benefits now
accorded only white students in programs of high[er] education
financed by Federal funds. It would, in short, assure the existing
right to equal treatment in the enjoyment of Federal funds. It
would not destroy any rights of private property or freedom of
association."
110 Cong.Rec. 1519 (1964). It was clear to Representative Celler
that Title VI, apart from the fact that it reached all federally
funded activities even in the absence of sufficient state or
federal control to invoke the Fourteenth or Fifth Amendments, was
not placing new substantive limitations upon the use of racial
criteria, but rather was designed to extend to such activities "the
existing right to equal treatment" enjoyed by Negroes under those
Amendments, and he later specifically defined the purpose of Title
VI in this way:
"In general, it seems rather anomalous that the Federal
Government should aid and abet discrimination on the basis of race,
color, or national origin by granting money Page 438 U. S. 331 and other kinds of financial aid. It seems rather shocking,
moreover, that, while we have on the one hand the 14th Amendment,
which is supposed to do away with discrimination, since it provides
for equal protection of the laws, on the other hand, we have the
Federal Government aiding and abetting those who persist in
practicing racial discrimination."
"It is for these reasons that we bring forth title VI. The
enactment of title VI will serve to override specific provisions of
law which contemplate Federal assistance to racially segregated
institutions." Id. at 2467. Representative Celler also filed a
memorandum setting forth the legal basis for the enactment of Title
VI which reiterated the theme of his oral remarks:
"In exercising its authority to fix the terms on which Federal
funds will be disbursed . . . . Congress clearly has power to
legislate so as to insure that the Federal Government does not
become involved in a violation of the Constitution." Id. at 1528.
Other sponsors of the legislation agreed with Representative
Celler that the function of Title VI was to end the Federal
Government's complicity in conduct, particularly the segregation or
exclusion of Negroes, inconsistent with the standards to be found
in the antidiscrimination provisions of the Constitution.
Representative Lindsay, also a member of the Judiciary Committee,
candidly acknowledged, in the course of explaining why Title VI was
necessary, that it did not create any new standard of equal
treatment beyond that contained in the Constitution:
"Both the Federal Government and the States are under
constitutional mandates not to discriminate. Many have raised the
question as to whether legislation is required at all. Does not the
Executive already have the power in the distribution of Federal
funds to apply those conditions which will enable the Federal
Government itself to live up to the mandate of the Constitution and
to require Page 438 U. S. 332 States and local government entities to live up to the
Constitution, most especially the 5th and 14th amendments?" Id. at 2467. He then explained that legislation was
needed to authorize the termination of funding by the Executive
Branch because existing legislation seemed to contemplate the
expenditure of funds to support racially segregated institutions. Ibid. The views of Representatives Celler and Lindsay
concerning the purpose and function of Title VI were shared by
other sponsors and proponents of the legislation in the House.
[ Footnote 2/10 ] Nowhere is there
any suggestion that Title VI was intended to terminate federal
funding for any reason other than consideration of race or national
origin by the recipient institution in a manner inconsistent with
the standards incorporated in the Constitution.
The Senate's consideration of Title VI reveals an identical
understanding concerning the purpose and scope of the legislation.
Senator Humphrey, the Senate floor manager, opened the Senate
debate with a section-by-section analysis of the Civil Rights Act
in which he succinctly stated the purpose of Title VI:
"The purpose of title VI is to make sure that funds of the
United States are not used to support racial discrimination. In
many instances, the practices of segregation or discrimination,
which title VI seeks to end, are unconstitutional. This is clearly
so wherever Federal funds go to a State agency which engages in
racial discrimination. It may also be so where Federal funds go to
support private, segregated institutions, under the decision in Simkins v. Moses H. Cone Memorial Hospital, 323 F.2d 959
(C.A. 4, 1963), [ cert. denied, 376 U.S. 938 (1964)]. In
all cases, such discrimination is contrary to national policy, and
to the moral sense of the Nation. Thus, title VI is simply Page 438 U. S. 333 designed to insure that Federal funds are spent in accordance
with the Constitution and the moral sense of the Nation." Id. at 6544. Senator Humphrey, in words echoing
statements in the House, explained that legislation was needed to
accomplish this objective because it was necessary to eliminate
uncertainty concerning the power of federal agencies to terminate
financial assistance to programs engaging in racial discrimination
in the face of various federal statutes which appeared to authorize
grants to racially segregated institutions. Ibid. Although
Senator Humphrey realized that Title VI reached conduct which,
because of insufficient governmental action, might be beyond the
reach of the Constitution, it was clear to him that the substantive
standard imposed by the statute was that of the Fifth and
Fourteenth Amendments. Senate supporters of Title VI repeatedly
expressed agreement with Senator Humphrey's description of the
legislation as providing the explicit authority and obligation to
apply the standards of the Constitution to all recipients of
federal funds. Senator Ribicoff described the limited function of
Title VI:
"Basically, there is a constitutional restriction against
discrimination in the use of Federal funds; and title VI simply
spells out the procedure to be used in enforcing that
restriction." Id. at 13333. Other strong proponents of the
legislation in the Senate repeatedly expressed their intent to
assure that federal funds would only be spent in accordance with
constitutional standards. See remarks of Senator Pastore, id. at 7057, 7062; Senator Clark, id. at 5243;
Senator Allott, id. at 12675, 12677. [ Footnote 2/11 ] Page 438 U. S. 334 Respondent's contention that Congress intended Title VI to bar
affirmative action programs designed to enable minorities
disadvantaged by the effects of discrimination to participate in
federally financed programs is also refuted by an examination of
the type of conduct which Congress thought it was prohibiting by
means of Title VI. The debates reveal that the legislation was
motivated primarily by a desire to eradicate a very specific evil:
federal financial support of programs which disadvantaged Negroes
by excluding them from participation or providing them with
separate facilities. Again and again supporters of Title VI
emphasized that the purpose of the statute was to end segregation
in federally funded activities and to end other discriminatory uses
of race disadvantaging Negroes. Senator Humphrey set the theme in
his speech presenting Title VI to the Senate:
"Large sums of money are contributed by the United States each
year for the construction, operation, and maintenance of segregated
schools."
" * * * *" "Similarly, under the Hill-Burton Act, Federal grants are made
to hospitals which admit whites only or Negroes only. . . ."
"In higher education also, a substantial part of the Federal
grants to colleges, medical schools and so forth, in the South is
still going to segregated institutions. " Page 438 U. S. 335 "Nor is this all. In several States, agricultural extension
services, supported by Federal funds, maintain racially segregated
offices for Negroes and whites. . . ."
". . . Vocational training courses, supported with Federal
funds, are given in segregated schools and institutions and often
limit Negroes to training in less skilled occupations. In
particular localities it is reported that Negroes have been cut off
from relief rolls, or denied surplus agricultural commodities, or
otherwise deprived of the benefit of federally assisted programs,
in retaliation for their participation in voter registration
drives, sit-in demonstrations and the like." Id. at 6543-6544. See also the remarks of
Senator Pastore ( id. at 7054-7055); Senator Ribicoff
( id. at 7064-7065); Senator Clark ( id. at 5243,
9086); Senator Javits ( id. at 6050, 7102). [ Footnote 2/12 ]
The conclusion to be drawn from the foregoing is clear. Congress
recognized that Negroes, in some cases with congressional
acquiescence, were being discriminated against in the
administration of programs and denied the full benefits of
activities receiving federal financial support. It was aware that
there were many federally funded programs and institutions which
discriminated against minorities in a manner inconsistent with the
standards of the Fifth and Fourteenth Amendments, but whose
activities might not involve sufficient state or federal action so
as to be in violation of these Amendments. Moreover, Congress
believed that it was questionable whether the Executive Branch
possessed legal authority to terminate the funding of activities on
the ground that they discriminated racially against Negroes in a
manner violative of the standards contained in the Fourteenth and
Fifth Page 438 U. S. 336 Amendments. Congress' solution was to end the Government's
complicity in constitutionally forbidden racial discrimination by
providing the Executive Branch with the authority and the
obligation to terminate its financial support of any activity which
employed racial criteria in a manner condemned by the
Constitution.
Of course, it might be argued that the Congress which enacted
Title VI understood the Constitution to require strict racial
neutrality or color blindness, and then enshrined that concept as a
rule of statutory law. Later interpretation and clarification of
the Constitution to permit remedial use of race would then not
dislodge Title VI's prohibition of race-conscious action. But there
are three compelling reasons to reject such a hypothesis.
First, no decision of this Court has ever adopted the
proposition that the Constitution must be colorblind. See
infra at 438 U. S.
355 -356.
Second, even if it could be argued in 1964 that the Constitution
might conceivably require color blindness, Congress surely would
not have chosen to codify such a view unless the Constitution
clearly required it. The legislative history of Title VI, as well
as the statute itself, reveals a desire to induce voluntary
compliance with the requirement of nondiscriminatory treatment.
[ Footnote 2/13 ] See §
602 of the Act, 42 U.S.C. § 2000d-1 (no funds shall be terminated
unless and until it has been "determined that compliance cannot be
secured by voluntary means"); H.R.Rep. No. 914, 88th Cong., 1st
Sess., pt. 1, p. 25 (1963); 110 Cong Rec. 13700 (1964) (Sen.
Pastore); id. at 6546 (Sen. Humphrey). It is inconceivable
that Congress intended to encourage voluntary efforts to eliminate
the evil of racial discrimination while at the same time forbidding
the voluntary use of race-conscious remedies to cure acknowledged
or obvious statutory violations. Yet a reading of Title VI as
prohibiting all action predicated upon race which adversely Page 438 U. S. 337 affects any individual would require recipients guilty of
discrimination to await the imposition of such remedies by the
Executive Branch. Indeed, such an interpretation of Title VI would
prevent recipients of federal funds from taking race into account
even when necessary to bring their programs into compliance with
federal constitutional requirements. This would be a remarkable
reading of a statute designed to eliminate constitutional
violations, especially in light of judicial decisions holding that,
under certain circumstances, the remedial use of racial criteria is
not only permissible, but is constitutionally required to eradicate
constitutional violations. For example, in Board of Education
v. Swann, 402 U. S. 43 (1971), the Court held that a statute forbidding the assignment of
students on the basis of race was unconstitutional because it would
hinder the implementation of remedies necessary to accomplish the
desegregation of a school system:
"Just as the race of students must be considered in determining
whether a constitutional violation has occurred, so also must race
be considered in formulating a remedy." Id. at 402 U. S. 46 .
Surely Congress did not intend to prohibit the use of racial
criteria when constitutionally required or to terminate the funding
of any entity which implemented such a remedy. It clearly desired
to encourage all remedies, including the use of race, necessary to
eliminate racial discrimination in violation of the Constitution,
rather than requiring the recipient to await a judicial
adjudication of unconstitutionality and the judicial imposition of
a racially oriented remedy.
Third, the legislative history shows that Congress specifically
eschewed any static definition of discrimination in favor of broad
language that could be shaped by experience, administrative
necessity, and evolving judicial doctrine. Although it is clear
from the debates that the supporters of Title VI intended to ban
uses of race prohibited by the Constitution and, more specifically,
the maintenance of segregated Page 438 U. S. 338 facilities, they never precisely defined the term
"discrimination," or what constituted an exclusion from
participation or a denial of benefits on the ground of race. This
failure was not lost upon its opponents. Senator Ervin
complained:
"The word 'discrimination,' as used in this reference, has no
contextual explanation whatever, other than the provision that the
discrimination 'is to be against' individuals participating in or
benefiting from federally assisted programs and activities on the
ground specified. With this context, the discrimination condemned
by this reference occurs only when an individual is treated
unequally or unfairly because of his race, color, religion, or
national origin. What constitutes unequal or unfair treatment?
Section 601 and section 602 of title VI do not say. They leave the
determination of that question to the executive department or
agencies administering each program, without any guideline whatever
to point out what is the congressional intent."
110 Cong.Rec. 5612 (1964). See also remarks of
Representative Abernethy ( id. at 1619); Representative
Dowdy ( id. at 1632); Senator Talmadge ( id. at
5251); Senator Sparkman ( id. at 6052). Despite these
criticisms, the legislation's supporters refused to include in the
statute or even provide in debate a more explicit definition of
what Title VI prohibited.
The explanation for this failure is clear. Specific definitions
were undesirable, in the views of the legislation's principal
backers, because Title VI's standard was that of the Constitution,
and one that could and should be administratively and judicially
applied. See remarks of Senator Humphrey ( id. at
5253, 6553); Senator Ribicoff ( id. at 7057, 13333);
Senator Pastore ( id. at 7057); Senator Javits
( id. at 5606-5607, 6050). [ Footnote 2/14 ] Indeed, there was a strong emphasis
throughout Page 438 U. S. 339 Congress' consideration of Title VI on providing the Executive
Branch with considerable flexibility in interpreting and applying
the prohibition against racial discrimination. Attorney General
Robert Kennedy testified that regulations had not been written into
the legislation itself because the rules and regulations defining
discrimination might differ from one program to another, so that
the term would assume different meanings in different contexts.
[ Footnote 2/15 ] This
determination to preserve flexibility in the administration of
Title VI was shared by the legislation's supporters. When Senator
Johnston offered an amendment that would have expressly authorized
federal grantees to take race into account in placing children in
adoptive and foster homes, Senator Pastore opposed the amendment,
which was ultimately defeated by a 56-29 vote, on the ground that
federal administrators could be trusted to act reasonably, and that
there was no danger that they would prohibit the use of racial
criteria under such circumstances. Id. at 13695.
Congress' resolve not to incorporate a static definition of
discrimination into Title VI is not surprising. In 1963 and 1964,
when Title VI was drafted and debated, the courts had only recently
applied the Equal Protection Clause to strike down public racial
discrimination in America, and the scope of that Clause's
nondiscrimination principle was in a state of flux and rapid
evolution. Many questions, such as whether the Fourteenth Amendment
barred only de jure discrimination or, in at least some
circumstances, reached de facto discrimination, had not
yet received an authoritative judicial resolution. The
congressional debate reflects an awareness of the evolutionary Page 438 U. S. 340 change that constitutional law in the area of racial
discrimination was undergoing in 1964. [ Footnote 2/16 ]
In sum, Congress' equating of Title VI's prohibition with the
commands of the Fifth and Fourteenth Amendments, its refusal
precisely to define that racial discrimination which it intended to
prohibit, and its expectation that the statute would be
administered in a flexible manner, compel the conclusion that
Congress intended the meaning of the statute's prohibition to
evolve with the interpretation of the commands of the Constitution.
Thus, any claim that the use of racial criteria is barred by the
plain language of the statute must fail in light of the remedial
purpose of Title VI and its legislative history. The cryptic nature
of the language employed in Title VI merely reflects Congress'
concern with the then-prevalent use of racial standards as a means
of excluding or disadvantaging Negroes and its determination to
prohibit absolutely such discrimination. We have recently held
that,
""[w]hen aid to construction of the meaning of words, as used in
the statute, is available, there certainly can be no rule of
law' which forbids its use, however clear the words may appear on
`superficial examination.'"" Train v. Colorado Public Interest Research Group, 426 U. S. 1 , 426 U. S. 10 (1976), quoting United States v. American Trucking Assns., 310 U. S. 534 , 310 U. S.
544 -544 (1940). This is especially so when, as is the
case here, the literal application of what is believed to be the
plain language of the statute, assuming that it is so plain, would
lead to results in direct conflict with Congress' unequivocally
expressed legislative purpose. [ Footnote 2/17 ] Page 438 U. S. 341 B Section 602 of Title VI, 42 U.S.C. § 2000d-1, instructs federal
agencies to promulgate regulations interpreting Title Page 438 U. S. 342 VI. These regulations, which, under the terms of the statute,
require Presidential approval, are entitled to considerable
deference in construing Title VI. See, e.g., 414 U.
S. Nichols, Page 438 U. S. 343 414 U. S. 563 (1974); Mourning v. Family Publications Service, Inc., 411 U. S. 356 , 411 U. S. 369 (1973); Red Lion Broadcasting Co. v. FCC, 395 U.
S. 367 , 395 U. S. 381 (1969). Consequently, it is most significant that the Department of
Health, Education, and Welfare (HEW), which provides much of the
federal assistance to institutions of higher education, has adopted
regulations requiring affirmative measures designed to enable
racial minorities which have been previously discriminated against
by a federally funded institution or program to overcome the
effects of such actions and authorizing the voluntary undertaking
of affirmative action programs by federally funded institutions
that have not been guilty of prior discrimination in order to
overcome the effects of conditions which have adversely affected
the degree of participation by persons of a particular race.
Title 45 FR § 80.3(b)(6)(i) (1977) provides:
"In administering a program regarding which the recipient has
previously discriminated against persons on the ground of race,
color, or national origin, the recipient must take affirmative
action to overcome the effects of prior discrimination."
Title 45 CFR § 80.5(i) (1977) elaborates upon this
requirement:
"In some situations, even though past discriminatory practices
attributable to a recipient or applicant have been abandoned, the
consequences of such practices continue to impede the full
availability of a benefit. If the efforts required of the applicant
or recipient under § 80.6(d), to provide information as to the
availability of the program or activity and the rights of
beneficiaries under this regulation, have failed to overcome these
consequences, it will become necessary under the requirement stated
in (i) of § 80.3(b)(6) for such applicant or recipient to take
additional steps to make the benefits Page 438 U. S. 344 fully available to racial and nationality groups previously
subject to discrimination. This action might take the form, for
example, of special arrangements for obtaining referrals or making
selections which will insure that groups previously subjected to
discrimination are adequately served."
These regulations clearly establish that, where there is a need
to overcome the effects of past racially discriminatory or
exclusionary practices engaged in by a federally funded
institution, race-conscious action is not only permitted, but
required, to accomplish the remedial objectives of Title VI.
[ Footnote 2/18 ] Of course, there
is no evidence that the Medical School has been guilty of past
discrimination, and consequently these regulations would not compel
it to employ a program of preferential admissions in behalf of
racial minorities. It would be difficult to explain from the
language of Title I, however, much less from its legislative
history, why the statute compels race-conscious remedies
where a recipient institution has engaged in past discrimination,
but prohibits such remedial action where racial
minorities, as a result of the effects of past discrimination
imposed by entities other than the recipient, are excluded from the
benefits of federally funded programs. HEW was fully aware of the
incongruous nature of such an interpretation of Title VI.
Title 45 CFR § 80.3(b)(6)(ii) (1977) provides:
"Even in the absence of such prior discrimination, a recipient,
in administering a program, may take affirmative action to overcome
the effects of conditions which resulted Page 438 U. S. 345 in limiting participation by persons of a particular race,
color, or national origin."
An explanatory regulation explicitly states that the affirmative
action which § 80.3(b)(6)(ii) contemplates includes the use of
racial preferences:
"Even though an applicant or recipient has never used
discriminatory policies, the services and benefits of the program
or activity it administers may not, in fact, be equally available
to some racial or nationality groups. I n such circumstances, an
applicant or recipient may properly give special consideration to
race, color, or national origin to make the benefits of its program
more widely available to such groups, not then being adequately
served. For example, where a university is not adequately serving
members of a particular racial or nationality group, it may
establish special recruitment policies to make its program better
known and more readily available to such group, and take other
steps to provide that group with more adequate service."
45 CFR § 80.5(j) (1977) This interpretation of Title VI is fully
consistent with the statute's emphasis upon voluntary remedial
action and reflects the views of an agency [ Footnote 2/19 ] responsible for achieving its
objectives. [ Footnote 2/20 ] Page 438 U. S. 346 The Court has recognized that the construction of a statute by
those charged with its execution is particularly deserving of
respect where Congress has directed its attention to the
administrative construction and left it unaltered. Cf. Red Lion
Broadcasting Co. v. FCC, 395 U.S. at 395 U. S. 381 ; Zemel v. Rusk, 381 U. S. 1 , 381 U. S. 11 -12
(1965). Congress recently took just this kind of action when it
considered an amendment to the Departments of Labor and Health,
Education, and Welfare appropriation bill for 1978, which would
have restricted significantly the remedial use of race in programs
funded by the appropriation. The amendment, as originally submitted
by Representative Ashbrook, provided that
"[n]one of the funds appropriated in this Act may be used to
initiate, carry out or enforce any program of affirmative action or
any other system of quotas or goals in regard to admission policies
or employment practices which encourage or require any
discrimination on the basis of race, creed, religion, sex or
age."
123 Cong.Rec. Page 438 U. S. 347 19715 (1977). In support of the measure, Representative Ashbrook
argued that the 1964 Civil Rights Act never authorized the
imposition of affirmative action, and that this was a creation of
the bureaucracy. Id. at 19722. He explicitly stated,
however, that he favored permitting universities to adopt
affirmative action programs giving consideration to racial
identity, but opposed the imposition of such programs by the
Government. Id. at 19715. His amendment was itself amended
to reflect this position by only barring the imposition of
race-conscious remedies by HEW:
"None of the funds appropriated in this Act may be obligated or
expended in connection with the issuance, implementation, or
enforcement of any rule, regulation, standard, guideline,
recommendation, or order issued by the Secretary of Health,
Education, and Welfare which for purposes of compliance with any
ratio, quota, or other numerical requirement related to race,
creed, color, national origin, or sex requires any individual or
entity to take any action with respect to (1) the hiring or
promotion policies or practices of such individual or entity, or
(2) the admissions policies or practices of such individual or
entity." Id. at 19722. This amendment was adopted by the House. Ibid. The Senate bill, however, contained no such
restriction upon HEW's authority to impose race-conscious remedies,
and the Conference Committee, upon the urging of the Secretary of
HEW, deleted the House provision from the bill. [ Footnote 2/21 ] More significant for present
purposes, however, is the fact that even the proponents of imposing
limitations upon HEW's implementation of Title VI did not challenge
the right of federally funded educational institutions voluntarily
to extend preferences to racial minorities. Page 438 U. S. 348 Finally, congressional action subsequent to the passage of Title
VI eliminates any possible doubt about Congress' views concerning
the permissibility of racial preferences for the purpose of
assisting disadvantaged racial minorities. It confirms that
Congress did not intend to prohibit, and does not now believe that
Title VI prohibits, the consideration of race as part of a remedy
for societal discrimination even where there is no showing that the
institution extending the preference has been guilty of past
discrimination nor any judicial finding that the particular
beneficiaries of the racial preference have been adversely affected
by societal discrimination.
Just last year, Congress enacted legislation [ Footnote 2/22 ] explicitly requiring that no grants
shall be made
"for any local public works project unless the applicant gives
satisfactory assurance to the Secretary [of Commerce] that at least
10 per centum of the amount of each grant shall be expended for
minority business enterprises."
The statute defines the term "minority business enterprise"
as
"a business, at least 50 per centum of which is owned by
minority group members or, in case of a publicly owned business, at
least 51 per centum of the stock of which is owned by minority
group members."
The term "minority group members" is defined in explicitly
racial terms: "citizens of the United States who are Negroes,
Spanish-speaking, Orientals, Indians, Eskimos, and Aleuts."
Although the statute contains an exemption from this requirement
"to the extent that the Secretary determines otherwise," this
escape clause was provided only to deal with the possibility that
certain areas of the country might not contain sufficient qualified
"minority business enterprises" to permit compliance with the quota
provisions of the legislation. [ Footnote 2/23 ]
The legislative history of this race-conscious legislation
reveals that it represents a deliberate attempt to deal with Page 438 U. S. 349 the excessive rate of unemployment among minority citizens and
to encourage the development of viable minority controlled
enterprises. [ Footnote 2/24 ] It
was believed that such a "set-aside" was required in order to
enable minorities, still "new on the scene" and "relatively small,"
to compete with larger and more established companies which would
always be successful in underbidding minority enterprises. 123
Cong.Rec. 5327 (1977) (Rep. Mitchell). What is most significant
about the congressional consideration of the measure is that,
although the use of a racial quota or "set-aside" by a recipient of
federal funds would constitute a direct violation of Title VI if
that statute were read to prohibit race-conscious action, no
mention was made during the debates in either the House or the
Senate of even the possibility that the quota provisions for
minority contractors might in any way conflict with or modify Title
VI. It is inconceivable that such a purported conflict would have
escaped congressional attention through an inadvertent failure to
recognize the relevance of Title VI. Indeed, the Act of which this
affirmative action provision is a part also contains a provision
barring discrimination on the basis of sex which states that this
prohibition
"will be enforced through agency provisions and rules similar to
those already established, with respect to racial and other
discrimination under Title VI of the Civil Rights Act of 1964."
42 U.S.C. § 6709 (1976 ed.). Thus Congress, was fully aware of
the applicability of Title VI to the funding of public works
projects. Under these circumstances, the enactment of the 10%
"set-aside" for minority enterprises reflects a congressional
judgment that the remedial use of race is permissible under Title
VI. We have repeatedly recognized that subsequent legislation
reflecting an interpretation of an earlier Act is entitled to great
weight in determining the meaning of the earlier statute. Red
Lion Broadcasting Co. v. FCC, 395 U.S. at 395 U. S.
380 -381; Page 438 U. S. 350 Erlenbaugh v. United States, 409 U.
S. 239 , 409 U. S.
243 -244 (1972). See also United States v.
Stewart, 311 U. S. 60 , 311 U. S. 64 -65
(1940). [ Footnote 2/25 ] C Prior decisions of this Court also strongly suggest that Title
VI does not prohibit the remedial use of race where such action is
constitutionally permissible. In Lau v. Nichols, 414 U. S. 563 (1974), the Court held that the failure of the San Page 438 U. S. 351 Francisco school system to provide English language instruction
to students of Chinese ancestry who do not speak English, or to
provide them with instruction in Chinese, constituted a violation
of Title VI. The Court relied upon an HEW regulation which
stipulates that a recipient of federal funds "may not . . . utilize
criteria or methods of administration which have the effect of
subjecting individuals to discrimination" or have
"the effect of defeating or substantially impairing
accomplishment of the objectives of the program as respect
individuals of a particular race, color, or national origin."
45 CFR § 80.3(b)(2) (1977). It interpreted this regulation as
requiring San Francisco to extend the same educational benefits to
Chinese-speaking students as to English-speaking students, even
though there was no finding or allegation that the city's failure
to do so was a result of a purposeful design to discriminate on the
basis of race. Lau is significant in two related respects. First, it
indicates that, in at least some circumstances, agencies
responsible for the administration of Title VI may require
recipients who have not been guilty of any constitutional
violations to depart from a policy of color blindness and to be
cognizant of the impact of their actions upon racial minorities.
Secondly, Lau clearly requires that institutions receiving
federal funds be accorded considerable latitude in voluntarily
undertaking race-conscious action designed to remedy the exclusion
of significant numbers of Page 438 U. S. 352 minorities from the benefits of federally funded programs.
Although this Court has not yet considered the question,
presumably, by analogy to our decisions construing Title VII, a
medical school would not be in violation of Title VI under Lau because of the serious underrepresentation of racial
minorities in its student body as long as it could demonstrate that
its entrance requirements correlated sufficiently with the
performance of minority students in medical school and the medical
profession. [ Footnote 2/26 ] It
would be inconsistent with Lau and the emphasis of Title
VI and the HEW regulations on voluntary action, however, to require
that an institution wait to be adjudicated to be in violation of
the law before being permitted to voluntarily undertake corrective
action based upon a good faith and reasonable belief that the
failure of certain racial minorities to satisfy entrance
requirements is not a measure of their ultimate performance as
doctors, but a result of the lingering effects of past societal
discrimination.
We recognize that Lau, especially when read in light of
our subsequent decision in Washington v. Davis, 46 U. S. 229 (1976), which rejected the general proposition that governmental
action is unconstitutional solely because it has a racially
disproportionate impact, may be read as being predicated upon the
view that, at least under some circumstances, Title VI proscribes
conduct which might not be prohibited by the Constitution. Since we
are now of the opinion, for the reasons set forth above, that Title
VI's standard, applicable alike to public and private recipients of
federal funds, is no broader than the Constitution's, we have
serious doubts concerning the correctness of what appears to be the
premise of that decision. However, even accepting Lau's implication that impact alone is, in some contexts, sufficient to
establish a prima facie violation of Title VI, contrary to
our view that Title VI's definition of racial discrimination is
absolutely coextensive with the Constitution's, this would not
assist the respondent Page 438 U. S. 353 in the least. First, for the reasons discussed supra at 438 U. S.
336 -350, regardless of whether Title VI's prohibitions
extend beyond the Constitution's, the evidence fails to establish,
and, indeed, compels the rejection of, the proposition that
Congress intended to prohibit recipients of federal funds from
voluntarily employing race-conscious measures to eliminate the
effects of past societal discrimination against racial minorities
such as Negroes. Secondly, Lau itself, for the reasons set
forth in the immediately preceding paragraph, strongly supports the
view that voluntary race-conscious remedial action is permissible
under Title VI. If discriminatory racial impact alone is enough to
demonstrate at least a prima facie Title VI violation, it
is difficult to believe that the Title would forbid the Medical
School from attempting to correct the racially exclusionary effects
of its initial admissions policy during the first two years of the
School's operation.
The Court has also declined to adopt a "colorblind"
interpretation of other statutes containing nondiscrimination
provisions similar to that contained in Title VI. We have held
under Title VII that, where employment requirements have a
disproportionate impact upon racial minorities, they constitute a
statutory violation, even in the absence of discriminatory intent,
unless the employer is able to demonstrate that the requirements
are sufficiently related to the needs of the job. [ Footnote 2/27 ] More significantly, the Court has
required that preferences be given by employers to members of
racial minorities as a remedy for past violations of Title VII,
even where there has been no finding that the employer has acted
with a discriminatory intent. [ Footnote 2/28 ] Finally, we have construed the
Voting Page 438 U. S. 354 Rights Act.of 1965, 42 U.S.C. § 1973 et seq. (1970 ed.
and Supp. V), which contains a provision barring any voting
procedure or qualification that denies or abridges "the right
of Page 438 U. S. 355 any citizen of the United States to vote on account of race or
color," as permitting States to voluntarily take race into account
in a way that fairly represents the voting strengths of different
racial groups in order to comply with the commands of the statute,
even where the result is a gain for one racial group at the expense
of others. [ Footnote 2/29 ]
These prior decisions are indicative of the Court's
unwillingness to construe remedial statutes designed to eliminate
discrimination against racial minorities in a manner which would
impede efforts to attain this objective. There is no justification
for departing from this course in the case of Title VI and
frustrating the clear judgment of Congress that race-conscious
remedial action is permissible.
We turn, therefore, to our analysis of the Equal Protection
Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment. III A The assertion of human equality is closely associated with the
proposition that differences in color or creed, birth or status,
are neither significant nor relevant to the way in which persons
should be treated. Nonetheless, the position that such factors must
be "constitutionally an irrelevance," Edwards v.
California, 314 U. S. 160 , 314 U. S. 185 (1941) (Jackson, J., concurring), summed up by the shorthand phrase
" [o]ur Constitution is color-blind," Plessy v. Ferguson, 163 U. S. 537 , 163 U. S. 559 (1896) (Harlan, J., dissenting), has never been adopted by this
Court as the proper meaning of the Equal Protection Clause.
Indeed, Page 438 U. S. 356 we have expressly rejected this proposition on a number of
occasions.
Our cases have always implied that an "overriding statutory
purpose," McLaughlin v. Florida, 379 U.
S. 184 , 379 U. S. 192 (1984), could be found that would justify racial classifications. See, e.g., ibid.; Loving v. Virginia, 388 U. S.
1 , 388 U. S. 11 (1967); Korematsu v. United States, 323 U.
S. 214 , 323 U. S. 216 (1944); Hirabayashi v. United States, 320 U. S.
81 , 320 U. S.
100 -101 (1943). More recently, in McDaniel v.
Barresi, 402 U. S. 39 (1971)
this Court unanimously reversed the Georgia Supreme Court which had
held that a desegregation plan voluntarily adopted by a local
school board, which assigned students on the basis of race, was per se invalid because it was not colorblind. And in North Carolina Board of Education v. Swann, we held, again
unanimously, that a statute mandating colorblind school assignment
plans could not stand "against the background of segregation,"
since such a limit on remedies would "render illusory the promise
of Brown [I]. " 402 U.S. at 402 U. S.
45 -46.
We conclude, therefore, that racial classifications are not per se invalid under the Fourteenth Amendment.
Accordingly, we turn to the problem of articulating what our role
should be in reviewing state action that expressly classifies by
race. B Respondent argues that racial classifications are always
suspect, and, consequently, that this Court should weigh the
importance of the objectives served by Davis' special admissions
program to see if they are compelling. In addition, he asserts that
this Court must inquire whether, in its judgment, there are
alternatives to racial classifications which would suit Davis'
purposes. Petitioner, on the other hand, states that our proper
role is simply to accept petitioner's determination that the racial
classifications used by its program are reasonably related to what
it tells us are its benign Page 438 U. S. 357 purposes. We reject petitioner's view, but, because our prior
cases are in many respects inapposite to that before us now, we
find it necessary to define with precision the meaning of that
inexact term, "strict scrutiny."
Unquestionably we have held that a government practice or
statute which restricts "fundamental rights" or which contains
"suspect classifications" is to be subjected to "strict scrutiny,"
and can be justified only if it furthers a compelling government
purpose and, even then, only if no less restrictive alternative is
available. [ Footnote 2/30 ] See, e.g., San Antonio Independent School District v.
Rodriguez, 411 U. S. 1 , 411 U. S. 16 -17
(1973); Dunn v. Blumstein, 405 U.
S. 330 (1972). But no fundamental right is involved
here. See San Antonio, supra at 422 U. S. 29 -36.
Nor do whites, as a class, have any of the
"traditional indicia of suspectness: the class is not saddled
with such disabilities, or subjected to such a history of
purposeful unequal treatment, or relegated to such a position of
political powerlessness as to command extraordinary protection from
the majoritarian political process." Id. at 422 U. S. 28 ; see United States v. Carolene Products Co., 304 U.
S. 144 , 304 U. S. 152 n. 4 (1938). [ Footnote 2/31 ]
Moreover, if the University's representations are credited, this
is not a case where racial classifications are "irrelevant, and
therefore prohibited." Hirabayashi, supra at 320 U. S. 100 .
Nor has anyone suggested that the University's purposes contravene
the cardinal principle that racial classifications that stigmatize
-- because they are drawn on the presumption that one race is
inferior to another or because they put the weight of
government Page 438 U. S. 358 behind racial hatred and separatism -- are invalid without more. See Yick Wo v. Hopkins, 118 U. S. 356 , 118 U. S. 374 (1886); [ Footnote 2/32 ] accord, Strauder v. West Virginia, 100 U.
S. 303 , 100 U. S. 308 (1880); Korematsu v. United States, supra at 323 U. S. 223 ; Oyama v. California, 332 U. S. 633 , 332 U. S. 663 (1948) (Murphy, J., concurring); Brown I, 347 U.
S. 483 (1954); McLaughlin v. Florida, supra, at 379 U. S.
191 -192; Loving v. Virginia, supra, at 388 U. S. 11 -12; Reitman v. Mulkey, 387 U. S. 369 , 387 U. S.
375 -376 (1967); United Jewish Organizations v.
Carey, 430 U. S. 144 , 430 U. S. 165 (1977) ( UJO ) (opinion of WHITE, J., joined by REHNQUIST
and STEVENS, JJ.); id. at 430 U. S. 169 (opinion concurring in part). [ Footnote 2/33 ]
On the other hand, the fact that this case does not fit neatly
into our prior analytic framework for race cases does not mean that
it should be analyzed by applying the very loose rational basis
standard of review that is the very least that is always applied in
equal protection cases. [ Footnote
2/34 ]
"'[T]he mere recitation of a benign, compensatory purpose is not
an automatic shield Page 438 U. S. 359 which protects.against any inquiry into the actual purpose
underlying a statutory scheme.'" Califano v. Webster, 430 U. S. 313 , 430 U. S. 317 (1977), quoting Weinberger v. Wiesenfeld, 420 U.
S. 636 , 420 U. S. 648 (1975). Instead, a number of considerations -- developed in gender
discrimination cases but which carry even more force when applied
to racial classifications -- lead us to conclude that racial
classifications designed to further remedial purposes " must
serve important governmental objectives, and must be substantially
related to achievement of those objectives.'" Califano v.
Webster, supra at 430 U. S. 317 ,
quoting Craig v. Boren, 429 U. S. 190 , 429 U. S. 197 (1976). [ Footnote 2/35 ] Page 438 U. S. 360 First, race, like, "gender-based classifications, too often
[has] been inexcusably utilized to stereotype and stigmatize
politically powerless segments of society." Kahn v.
Shevin, 416 U. S. 351 , 416 U. S. 357 (1974) (dissenting opinion). While a carefully tailored statute
designed to remedy past discrimination could avoid these vices, see Califano v. Webster, supra; Schlesinger v. Ballard, 419 U. S. 498 (1975); Kahn v. Shevin, supra, we nonetheless have
recognized that the line between honest and thoughtful appraisal of
the effects of past discrimination and paternalistic stereotyping
is not so clear, and that a statute based on the latter is patently
capable of stigmatizing all women with a badge of inferiority. Cf. Schlesinger v. Ballard, supra at 419 U. S. 508 ; UJO, supra at 430 U. S. 174 ,
and n. 3 (opinion concurring in part); Califano v.
Goldfarb, 430 U. S. 199 , 430 U. S. 223 (1977) (STEVENS, J., concurring in judgment). See also Stanton
v. Stanton, 421 U. S. 7 , 421 U. S. 14 -15
(1975). State programs designed ostensibly to ameliorate the
effects of past racial discrimination obviously create the same
hazard of stigma, since they may promote racial separatism and
reinforce the views of those who believe that members of racial
minorities are inherently incapable of succeeding on their own. See UJO, supra at 430 U. S. 172 (opinion concurring in part); ante at 438 U. S. 298 (opinion of POWELL, J.).
Second, race, like gender and illegitimacy, see Weber v.
Aetna Casualty & Surety Co., 406 U.
S. 164 (1972), is an immutable characteristic which its
possessors are powerless to escape or set aside. While a
classification is not per se invalid because it divides
classes on the basis of an immutable characteristic, see
supra at 438 U. S.
355 -356, it is nevertheless true that such divisions are
contrary to our deep belief that "legal burdens should bear some
relationship to individual responsibility or Page 438 U. S. 361 wrongdoing," Weber, supra at 406 U. S. 175 ; Frontiero v. Richardson, 411 U. S. 677 , 411 U. S. 686 (1973) (opinion of BRENNAN, WHITE, and MARSHALL, JJ.), and that
advancement sanctioned, sponsored, or approved by the State should
ideally be based on individual merit or achievement, or at the
least on factors within the control of an individual. See
UJO, 430 U.S. at 430 U. S. 173 (opinion concurring in part); Kotch v. Board of River Port
Pilot Comm'rs, 330 U. S. 552 , 330 U. S. 566 (1947) (Rutledge, J., dissenting).
Because this principle is so deeply rooted, it might be supposed
that it would be considered in the legislative process and weighed
against the benefits of programs preferring individuals because of
their race. But this is not necessarily so: the
"natural consequence of our governing processes [may well be]
that the most 'discrete and insular' of whites . . . will be called
upon to bear the immediate, direct costs of benign
discrimination." UJO, supra at 430 U. S. 174 (opinion concurring in part). Moreover, it is clear from our cases
that there are limits beyond which majorities may not go when they
classify on the basis of immutable characteristics. See, e.g.,
Weber, supra. Thus, even if the concern for individualism is
weighed by the political process, that weighing cannot waive the
personal rights of individuals under the Fourteenth Amendment. See Lucas v. Colorado General Assembly, 377 U.
S. 713 , 377 U. S. 736 (1964).
In sum, because of the significant risk that racial
classifications established for ostensibly benign purposes can be
misused, causing effects not unlike those created by invidious
classifications, it is inappropriate to inquire only whether there
is any conceivable basis that might sustain such a classification.
Instead, to justify such a classification, an important and
articulated purpose for its use must be shown. In addition, any
statute must be stricken that stigmatizes any group or that singles
out those least well represented in the political process to bear
the brunt of a benign program. Thus, our review under the
Fourteenth Amendment should be Page 438 U. S. 362 strict -- not " strict' in theory and fatal in fact,"
[ Footnote 2/36 ] because it is
stigma that causes fatality -- but strict and searching
nonetheless. IV Davis' articulated purpose of remedying the effects of past
societal discrimination is, under our cases, sufficiently important
to justify the use of race-conscious admissions programs where
there is a sound basis for concluding that minority
underrepresentation is substantial and chronic, and that the
handicap of past discrimination is impeding access of minorities to
the Medical School. A At least since Green v. County School Board, 391 U. S. 430 (1968), it has been clear that a public body which has itself been
adjudged to have engaged in racial discrimination cannot bring
itself into compliance with the Equal Protection Clause simply by
ending its unlawful acts and adopting a neutral stance. Three years
later, Swann v. Charlotte-Mecklenburg Board of Education, 402 U. S. 1 (1971),
and its companion cases, Davis v. School Comm'rs of Mobile
County, 402 U. S. 33 (1971); McDaniel v. Barresi, 402 U. S.
39 (1971); and North Carolina Board of Education v.
Swann, 402 U. S. 43 (1971), reiterated that racially neutral remedies for past
discrimination were inadequate where consequences of past
discriminatory acts influence or control present decisions. See, e.g., Charlotte-Mecklenburg, supra at 402 U. S. 28 . And
the Court further held both that courts could enter desegregation
orders which assigned students and faculty by reference to race, Charlotte-Mecklenburg, supra; Davis, supra; United States v.
Montgomery County Board of Ed., 395 U.
S. 225 (1969), and that local school boards could
voluntarily adopt desegregation Page 438 U. S. 363 plans which made express reference to race if this was necessary
to remedy the effects of past discrimination. McDaniel v.
Barresi, supra. Moreover, we stated that school boards, even
in the absence of a judicial finding of past discrimination, could
voluntarily adopt plans which assigned students with the end of
creating racial pluralism by establishing fixed ratios of black and
white students in each school. Charlotte-Mecklenburg,
supra at 402 U. S. 16 . In
each instance, the creation of unitary school systems, in which the
effects of past discrimination had been "eliminated root and
branch," Green, supra at 391 U. S. 438 ,
was recognized as a compelling social goal justifying the overt use
of race.
Finally, the conclusion that state educational institutions may
constitutionally adopt admissions programs designed to avoid
exclusion of historically disadvantaged minorities, even when such
programs explicitly take race into account, finds direct support in
our cases construing congressional legislation designed to overcome
the present effects of past discrimination. Congress can and has
outlawed actions which have a disproportionately adverse and
unjustified impact upon members of racial minorities and has
required or authorized race-conscious action to put individuals
disadvantaged by such impact in the position they otherwise might
have enjoyed. See Franks v. Bowman Transportation Co., 424 U. S. 747 (1976); Teamsters v. United States, 431 U.
S. 324 (1977). Such relief does not require as a
predicate proof that recipients of preferential advancement have
been individually discriminated against; it is enough that each
recipient is within a general class of persons likely to have been
the victims of discrimination. See id. at 431 U. S.
357 -362. Nor is it an objection to such relief that
preference for minorities will upset the settled expectations of
nonminorities. See Franks, supra. In addition, we have
held that Congress, to remove barriers to equal opportunity, can
and has required employers to use test criteria that fairly reflect
the qualifications of minority applicants Page 438 U. S. 364 vis-a-vis nonminority applicants, even if this means
interpreting the qualifications of an applicant in light of his
race. See Albemarle Paper Co. v. Moody, 422 U.
S. 405 , 422 U. S. 435 (1975). [ Footnote 2/37 ]
These cases cannot be distinguished simply by the presence of
judicial findings of discrimination, for race-conscious remedies
have been approved where such findings have not been made. McDaniel v. Barresi, supra; UJO; see Califano v. Webster, 430 U. S. 313 (1977); Schlesinger v. Ballard, 419 U.
S. 498 (1975); Kahn v. Shevin, 416 U.
S. 351 (1974). See also Katzenbach v. Morgan, 384 U. S. 641 (1966). Indeed, the requirement of a judicial determination of a
constitutional or statutory violation as a predicate for
race-conscious remedial actions would be self-defeating. Such a
requirement would severely undermine efforts to achieve voluntary
compliance with the requirements of law. And our society and
jurisprudence have always stressed the value of voluntary efforts
to further the objectives of the law. Judicial intervention is a
last resort to achieve cessation of illegal conduct or the
remedying of its effects, rather than a prerequisite to action.
[ Footnote 2/38 ] Page 438 U. S. 365 Nor can our cases be distinguished on the ground that the entity
using explicit racial classifications itself had violated § 1 of
the Fourteenth Amendment or an antidiscrimination regulation, for
again race-conscious remedies have been approved where this is not
the case. See UJO, 430 U.S. at 430 U. S. 157 (opinion of WHITE, J., joined by BRENNAN, BLACKMUN, and STEVENS,
JJ.); [ Footnote 2/39 ] id. at 430 U. S. 167 (opinion of WHITE, J., joined by REHNQUIST and STEVENS, JJ.);
[ Footnote 2/40 ] cf. Califano
v. Webster, supra, at 430 U. S. 317 ; Kahn v. Shevin, supra. Moreover,
the presence or absence of past discrimination by universities or
employers is largely irrelevant to resolving respondent's
constitutional claims. The claims of those burdened by the
race-conscious actions of a university or employer who has never
been adjudged in violation of an antidiscrimination law are not any
more or less entitled to deference than the claims of the burdened
nonminority workers in Franks v. Bowman Transportation Co.,
supra, in which the employer had violated Title VII, for, in
each case, the employees are innocent of past discrimination. And,
although it might be argued that, where an employer has violated an
antidiscrimination law, the expectations of nonminority workers are
themselves products of discrimination and hence "tainted," see
Franks, supra at 424 U. S. 776 ,
and therefore more easily upset, the same argument can be made with
respect to respondent. If it was reasonable to conclude -- as we
hold that it was -- that the failure of minorities to qualify for
admission at Davis under regular procedures was due principally to
the effects of past discrimination, than there is a reasonable
likelihood that, but for pervasive racial discrimination, Page 438 U. S. 366 respondent would have failed to qualify for admission even in
the absence of Davis' special admissions program. [ Footnote 2/41 ]
Thus, our cases under Title VII of the Civil Rights Act have
held that, in order to achieve minority participation in previously
segregated areas of public life, Congress may require or authorize
preferential treatment for those likely disadvantaged by societal
racial discrimination. Such legislation has been sustained even
without a requirement of findings of intentional racial
discrimination by those required or authorized to accord
preferential treatment, or a case-by-case determination that those
to be benefited suffered from racial discrimination. These
decisions compel the conclusion that States also may adopt
race-conscious programs designed to overcome substantial, chronic
minority underrepresentation where there is reason to believe that
the evil addressed is a product of past racial discrimination.
[ Footnote 2/42 ] Page 438 U. S. 367 Title VII was enacted pursuant to Congress' power under the
Commerce Clause and § 5 of the Fourteenth Amendment. To he extent
that Congress acted under the Commerce Clause power, it was
restricted in the use of race in governmental decisionmaking by the
equal protection component of the Due Process Clause of the Fifth
Amendment precisely to the same extent as are the States by § 1 of
the Fourteenth Amendment. [ Footnote
2/43 ] Therefore, to the extent that Title VII rests on the
Commerce Clause power, our decisions such a Franks and Page 438 U. S. 368 Teamsters v. United States, 431 U.
S. 324 (1977), implicitly recognize that the affirmative
use of race is consistent with the equal protection component of
the Fifth Amendment, and therefore with the Fourteenth Amendment.
To the extent that Congress acted pursuant to § 5 of the Fourteenth
Amendment, those cases impliedly recognize that Congress was
empowered under that provision to accord preferential treatment to
victims of past discrimination in order to overcome the effects of
segregation, and we see no reason to conclude that the States
cannot voluntarily accomplish under § 1 of the Fourteenth Amendment
what Congress under § 5 of the Fourteenth Amendment validly may
authorize or compel either the States or private persons to do. A
contrary position would conflict with the traditional understanding
recognizing the competence of the States to initiate measures
consistent with federal policy in the absence of congressional
preemption of the subject matter. Nothing whatever in the
legislative history of either the Fourteenth Amendment or the Civil
Rights Acts even remotely suggests that the States are foreclosed
from furthering the fundamental purpose of equal opportunity to
which the Amendment and these Acts are addressed. Indeed, voluntary
initiatives by the States to achieve the national goal of equal
opportunity have been recognized to be essential to its attainment.
"To use the Fourteenth Amendment as a sword against such State
power would stultify that Amendment." Railway Mail Assn. v.
Corsi, 326 U. S. 88 , 326 U. S. 98 (1945) (Frankfurter, J., concurring). [ Footnote 2/44 ] We therefore Page 438 U. S. 369 conclude that Davis' goal of admitting minority students
disadvantaged by the effects of past discrimination is sufficiently
important to justify use of race-conscious admissions criteria. B Properly construed, therefore, our prior cases unequivocally
show that a state government may adopt race-conscious programs if
the purpose of such programs is to remove the disparate racial
impact its actions might otherwise have, and if there is reason to
believe that the disparate impact is itself the product of past
discrimination, whether its own or that of society at large. There
is no question that Davis' program is valid under this test.
Certainly, on the basis of the undisputed factual submissions
before this Court, Davis had a sound basis for believing that the
problem of underrepresentation of minorities was substantial and
chronic, and that the problem was attributable to handicaps imposed
on minority applicants by past and present racial discrimination.
Until at least 1973, the practice of medicine in this country was,
in fact, if not in law, largely the prerogative of whites.
[ Footnote 2/45 ] In 1950, for
example, while Negroes Page 438 U. S. 370 constituted 10% of the total population, Negro physicians
constituted only 2.2% of the total number of physicians. [ Footnote 2/46 ] The overwhelming majority
of these, moreover, were educated in two predominantly Negro
medical schools, Howard and Meharry. [ Footnote 2/47 ] By 1970, the gap between the proportion
of Negroes in medicine and their proportion in the population had
widened: the number of Negroes employed in medicine remained frozen
at 2.2% [ Footnote 2/48 ] while the
Negro population had increased to 11.1%. [ Footnote 2/49 ] The number of Negro admittees to
predominantly white medical schools, moreover, had declined in
absolute numbers during the years 1955 to 1964. Odegaard 19.
Moreover, Davis had very good reason to believe that the
national pattern of underrepresentation of minorities in medicine
would be perpetuated if it retained a single admissions standard.
For example, the entering classes in 1968 and 1969, the years in
which such a standard was used, included only 1 Chicano and 2
Negroes out of the 50 admittees for each year. Nor is there any
relief from this pattern of underrepresentation in the statistics
for the regular admissions program in later years. [ Footnote 2/50 ]
Davis clearly could conclude that the serious and persistent
underrepresentation of minorities in medicine depicted by these
statistics is the result of handicaps under which minority
applicants labor as a consequence of a background of deliberate,
purposeful discrimination against minorities in education Page 438 U. S. 371 and in society generally, as well as in the medical profession.
From the inception of our national life, Negroes have been
subjected to unique legal disabilities impairing access to equal
educational opportunity. Under slavery, penal sanctions were
imposed upon anyone attempting to educate Negroes. [ Footnote 2/51 ] After enactment of the
Fourteenth Amendment the States continued to deny Negroes equal
educational opportunity, enforcing a strict policy of segregation
that itself stamped Negroes as inferior, Brown I, 347 U. S. 483 (1954), that relegated minorities to inferior educational
institutions, [ Footnote 2/52 ] and
that denied them intercourse in the mainstream of professional life
necessary to advancement. See Sweatt v. Painter, 339 U. S. 629 (1950). Segregation was not limited to public facilities, moreover,
but was enforced by criminal penalties against private action as
well. Thus, as late as 1908, this Court enforced a state criminal
conviction against a private college for teaching Negroes together
with whites. Berea College v. Kentucky, 211 U. S.
45 . See also Plessy v. Ferguson, 163 U.
S. 537 (1896). Green v. County School Board, 391 U.
S. 430 (1968), gave explicit recognition to the fact
that the habit of discrimination and the cultural tradition of race
prejudice cultivated by centuries of legal slavery and segregation
were not immediately dissipated when Brown I, supra, announced the constitutional principle that equal educational
opportunity and participation in all aspects of American life could
not be denied on the basis of race. Rather, massive official and
private resistance prevented, and to a lesser extent still
prevents, attainment of equal opportunity in education at all
levels and in the professions. The generation of minority students
applying to Davis Medical School since it opened in 1968 -- most of
whom Page 438 U. S. 372 were born before or about the time Brown I was decided
-- clearly have been victims of this discrimination. Judicial
decrees recognizing discrimination in public education in
California testify to the fact of widespread discrimination
suffered by California-born minority applicants; [ Footnote 2/53 ] many minority group members living
in California, moreover, were born and reared in school districts
in Southern States segregated by law. [ Footnote 2/54 ] Since separation of schoolchildren by
race
"generates a feeling of inferiority as to their status in the
community that may affect their hearts and minds in a way unlikely
ever to be undone," Brown I, supra at 347 U. S. 494 ,
the conclusion is inescapable that applicants to medical school
must be few indeed who endured the effects of de jure segregation, the resistance to Brown I, or the equally
debilitating pervasive private discrimination fostered by our long
history of official discrimination, cf. Reitman v. Mulkey, 387 U. S. 369 (1967), and yet come to the starting line with an education equal
to whites. [ Footnote 2/55 ]
Moreover, we need not rest solely on our own conclusion that
Davis had sound reason to believe that the effects of past
discrimination were handicapping minority applicants to the Medical
School, because the Department of Health, Education, and Welfare,
the expert agency charged by Congress with promulgating regulations
enforcing Title VI of the Civil Rights Act of 1964, see
supra at 438 U. S.
341 -343, has also reached the conclusion that race may
be taken into account in situations Page 438 U. S. 373 where a failure to do so would limit participation by minorities
in federally funded programs, and regulations promulgated by the
Department expressly contemplate that appropriate race-conscious
programs may be adopted by universities to remedy unequal access to
university programs caused by their own or by past societal
discrimination. See supra at 438 U. S.
344 -345, discussing 45 CFR §§ 80.3(b)(6)(ii) and 80.5(j)
(1977). It cannot be questioned that, in the absence of the special
admissions program, access of minority students to the Medical
School would be severely limited and, accordingly, race-conscious
admissions would be deemed an appropriate response under these
federal regulations. Moreover, the Department's regulatory policy
is not one that has gone unnoticed by Congress. See supra at 438 U. S.
346 -347. Indeed, although an amendment to an
appropriations bill was introduced just last year that would have
prevented the Secretary of Health, Education, and Welfare from
mandating race-conscious programs in university admissions,
proponents of this measure, significantly, did not question the
validity of voluntary implementation of race-conscious admissions
criteria. See ibid. In these circumstances, the conclusion
implicit in the regulations -- that the lingering effects of past
discrimination continue to make race-conscious remedial programs
appropriate means for ensuring equal educational opportunity in
universities -- deserves considerable judicial deference. See,
e.g., Katzenbach v. Morgan, 384 U. S. 641 (1966); UJO, 430 U.S. at 430 U. S.
175 -178 (opinion concurring in part). [ Footnote 2/56 ] C The second prong of our test -- whether the Davis program
stigmatizes any discrete group or individual and whether race Page 438 U. S. 374 is reasonably used in light of the program's objectives -- is
clearly satisfied by the Davis program.
It is not even claimed that Davis' program in any way operates
to stigmatize or single out any discrete and insular, or even any
identifiable, nonminority group. Nor will harm comparable to that
imposed upon racial minorities by exclusion or separation on
grounds of race be the likely result of the program. It does not,
for example, establish an exclusive preserve for minority students
apart from and exclusive of whites. Rather, its purpose is to
overcome the effects of segregation by bringing the races together.
True, whites are excluded from participation in the special
admissions program, but this fact only operates to reduce the
number of whites to be admitted in the regular admissions program
in order to permit admission of a reasonable percentage -- less
than their proportion of the California population [ Footnote 2/57 ] -- of otherwise
underrepresented qualified minority applicants. [ Footnote 2/58 ] Page 438 U. S. 375 Nor was Bakke in any sense stamped as inferior by the Medical
School's rejection of him. Indeed, it is conceded by all that he
satisfied those criteria regarded by the school as generally
relevant to academic performance better than most of the minority
members who were admitted. Moreover, there is absolutely no basis
for concluding that Bakke's rejection as a result of Davis' use of
racial preference will affect him throughout his life in the same
way as the segregation of the Negro schoolchildren in Brown
I would have affected them. Unlike discrimination against
racial minorities, the use of racial preferences for remedial
purposes does not inflict a pervasive injury upon individual whites
in the sense that, wherever they go or whatever they do, there is a
significant likelihood that they will be treated as second-class
citizens because of their color. This distinction does not mean
that the exclusion of a white resulting from the preferential use
of race is not sufficiently serious to require justification; but
it does mean that the injury inflicted by such a policy is not
distinguishable from disadvantages caused by a wide range of
government actions, none of which has ever been thought
impermissible for that reason alone.
In addition, there is simply no evidence that the Davis program
discriminates intentionally or unintentionally against any minority
group which it purports to benefit. The program does not establish
a quota in the invidious sense of a ceiling on the number of
minority applicants to be admitted. Nor can the program reasonably
be regarded as stigmatizing the program's beneficiaries or their
race as inferior. The Davis program does not simply advance less
qualified applicants; rather, it compensates applicants, who it is
uncontested are fully qualified to study medicine, for educational
disadvantages which it was reasonable to conclude were a product
of Page 438 U. S. 376 state-fostered discrimination. Once admitted, these students
must satisfy the same degree requirements as regularly admitted
students; they are taught by the same faculty in the same classes;
and their performance is evaluated by the same standards by which
regularly admitted students are judged. Under these circumstances,
their performance and degrees must be regarded equally with the
regularly admitted students with whom they compete for standing.
Since minority graduates cannot justifiably be regarded as less
well qualified than nonminority graduates by virtue of the special
admissions program, there is no reasonable basis to conclude that
minority graduates at schools using such programs would be
stigmatized as inferior by the existence of such programs. D We disagree with the lower courts' conclusion that the Davis
program's use of race was unreasonable in light of its objectives.
First, as petitioner argues, there are no practical means by which
it could achieve its ends in the foreseeable future without the use
of race-conscious measures. With respect to any factor (such as
poverty or family educational background) that may be used as a
substitute for race as an indicator of past discrimination, whites
greatly outnumber racial minorities simply because whites make up a
far larger percentage of the total population, and therefore far
outnumber minorities in absolute terms at every socioeconomic
level. [ Footnote 2/59 ] For
example, of a class of recent medical school applicants from
families with less than $10,000 income, at least 71% were white.
[ Footnote 2/60 ] Of all 1970
families headed by a Page 438 U. S. 377 person not a highschool graduate which included related children
under 18, 80% were white and 20% were racial minorities. [ Footnote 2/61 ] Moreover, while race is
positively correlated with differences in GPA and MCAT scores,
economic disadvantage is not. Thus, it appears that economically
disadvantaged whites do not score less well than economically
advantaged whites, while economically advantaged blacks score less
well than do disadvantaged whites. [ Footnote 2/62 ] These statistics graphically illustrate
that the University's purpose to integrate its classes by
compensating for past discrimination could not be achieved by a
general preference for the economically disadvantaged or the
children of parents of limited education unless such groups were to
make up the entire class.
Second, the Davis admissions program does not simply equate
minority status with disadvantage. Rather, Davis considers on an
individual basis each applicant's personal history to determine
whether he or she has likely been disadvantaged by racial
discrimination. The record makes clear that only minority
applicants likely to have been isolated from the mainstream of
American life are considered in the special program; other minority
applicants are eligible only through the regular admissions
program. True, the procedure by which disadvantage is detected is
informal, but we have never insisted that educators conduct their
affairs through adjudicatory proceedings, and such insistence here
is misplaced. A case-by-case inquiry into the extent to which each
individual applicant has been affected, either directly or
indirectly, by racial discrimination, would seem to be, as a
practical matter, virtually impossible, despite the fact that there
are excellent reasons for concluding that such effects generally
exist. When individual measurement is impossible or extremely
impractical, there is nothing to prevent a State Page 438 U. S. 378 from using categorical means to achieve its ends, at least where
the category is closely related to the goal. Cf. Gaston County
v. United States, 395 U. S. 285 , 395 U. S. 25 -296
(1969); Katzenbach v. Morgan, 384 U.
S. 641 (1966). And it is clear from our cases that
specific proof that a person has been victimized by discrimination
is not a necessary predicate to offering him relief where the
probability of victimization is great. See Teamsters v. United
States, 431 U. S. 324 (1977). E Finally, Davis' special admissions program cannot be said to
violate the Constitution simply because it has set aside a
predetermined number of places for qualified minority applicants,
rather than using minority status as a positive factor to be
considered in evaluating the applications of disadvantaged minority
applicants. For purposes of constitutional adjudication, there is
no difference between the two approaches. In any admissions program
which accords special consideration to disadvantaged racial
minorities, a determination of the degree of preference to be given
is unavoidable, and any given preference that results in the
exclusion of a white candidate is no more or less constitutionally
acceptable than a program such as that at Davis. Furthermore, the
extent of the preference inevitably depends on how many minority
applicants the particular school is seeking to admit in any
particular year, so long as the number of qualified minority
applicants exceeds that number. There is no sensible, and certainly
no constitutional, distinction between, for example, adding a set
number of points to the admissions rating of disadvantaged minority
applicants as an expression of the preference with the expectation
that this will result in the admission of an approximately
determined number of qualified minority applicants and setting a
fixed number of places for such applicants, as was done here.
[ Footnote 2/63 ] Page 438 U. S. 379 The "Harvard" program, see ante at 438 U. S.
316 -318, as those employing it readily concede, openly
and successfully employs a racial criterion for the purpose of
ensuring that some of the scarce places in institutions of higher
education are allocated to disadvantaged minority students. That
the Harvard approach does not also make public the extent of the
preference and the precise workings of the system, while the Davis
program employs a specific, openly stated number, does not condemn
the latter plan for purposes of Fourteenth Amendment adjudication.
It may be that the Harvard plan is more acceptable to the public
than is the Davis "quota." If it is, any State, including
California, is free to adopt it in preference to a less acceptable
alternative, just as it is generally free, as far as the
Constitution is concerned, to abjure granting any racial
preferences in its admissions program. But there is no basis for
preferring a particular preference program simply because, in
achieving the same goals that the Davis Medical School is pursuing,
it proceeds in a manner that is not immediately apparent to the
public. V Accordingly, we would reverse the judgment of the Supreme Court
of California holding the Medical School's special admissions
program unconstitutional and directing respondent's admission, as
well as that portion of the judgment enjoining the Medical School
from according any consideration to race in the admissions
process.
[ Footnote 2/1 ]
We also agree with MR. JUSTICE POWELL that a plan like the
"Harvard" plan, see ante at 438 U. S.
316 -318, is constitutional under our approach, at least
so long as the use of race to achieve an integrated student body is
necessitated by the lingering effects of past discrimination.
[ Footnote 2/2 ] See Plessy v. Ferguson, 163 U.
S. 537 (1896).
[ Footnote 2/3 ] New Orleans City Park Improvement Assn. v. Detiege, 358 U. S. 54 (1958); Muir v. Louisville Park Theatrical Assn., 347 U.S.
971 (1954); Mayor of Baltimore v. Dawson, 350 U.S. 877
(1955); Holmes v. Atlanta, 350 U.S. 879 (1955); Gayle
v. Browder, 352 U.S. 903 (1956).
[ Footnote 2/4 ] See Green v. County School Board, 391 U.
S. 430 (1968).
[ Footnote 2/5 ] See Swann v. Charlotte-Mecklenburg Board of Education, 402 U. S. 1 (1971); Davis v. School Comm'rs of Mobile County, 402 U. S.
33 (1971); North Carolina Board of Education v.
Swann, 402 U. S. 43 (1971).
[ Footnote 2/6 ] See, e.g., cases collected in Monell v. New York
City Dept. of Social Services, 436 U.
S. 658 , 436 U. S. 663 n. 5 (1978).
[ Footnote 2/7 ]
Section 601 of Title VI provides:
"No person in the United States shall, on the ground of race,
color, or national origin, be excluded from participation in, be
denied the benefits of, or be subjected to discrimination under any
program or activity receiving Federal financial assistance."
42 U.S.C. § 2000d.
[ Footnote 2/8 ]
MR. JUSTICE WHITE believes we should address the "private right
of action" issue. Accordingly, he has filed a separate opinion
stating his view that there is no private right of action under
Title VI. See post, p. 438 U. S.
379 .
[ Footnote 2/9 ]
"Simple justice requires that public funds, to which all
taxpayers of all races contribute, not be spent in any fashion
which encourages, entrenches, subsidizes or results in racial
discrimination. Direct discrimination by Federal, State or local
governments is prohibited by the Constitution. But indirect
discrimination, through the use of Federal funds, is just as
invidious; and it should not be necessary to resort to the courts
to prevent each individual violation. Congress and the Executive
have their responsibilities to uphold the Constitution also. . . .
"
"Many statutes providing Federal financial assistance, however,
define with such precision both the Administrator's role and the
conditions upon which specified amounts shall be given to
designated recipients that the amount of administrative discretion
remaining -- which might be used to withhold funds if
discrimination were not ended -- is, at best, questionable. No
administrator has the unlimited authority to invoke the
Constitution in opposition to the mandate of the Congress. Nor
would it always be helpful to require unconditionally -- as is
often proposed -- the withdrawal of all Federal funds from programs
urgently needed by Negroes as well as whites, for this may only
penalize those who least deserve it without ending
discrimination."
"Instead of permitting this issue to become a political device
often exploited by those opposed to social or economic progress, it
would be better at this time to pass a single comprehensive
provision making it clear that the Federal Government is not
required, under any statute, to furnish any kind of financial
assistance -- by way of grant, loan, contract, guaranty, insurance,
or otherwise -- to any program or activity in which racial
discrimination occurs. This would not permit the Federal Government
to cut off all Federal aid of all kinds as a means of punishing an
area for the discrimination occurring therein -- but it would
clarify the authority of any administrator with respect to Federal
funds or financial assistance and discriminatory practices."
109 Cong.Rec. 11161 (1963).
[ Footnote 2/10 ] See, e.g., 110 Cong.Rec. 2732 (1964) (Rep. Dawson); id. at 2481-2482 (Rep. Ryan); id. at 2766 (Rep.
Matzunaga); id. at 2595 (Rep. Donahue) .
[ Footnote 2/11 ]
There is also language in 42 U.S.C. § 2000d-5, enacted in 1966,
which supports the conclusion that Title VI's standard is that of
the Constitution. Section 2000d-5 provides that,
"for the purpose of determining whether a local educational
agency is in compliance with [Title VI], compliance by such agency
with a final order or judgment of a Federal court for the
desegregation of the school or school system operated by such
agency shall be deemed to be compliance with [Title VI], insofar as
the matters covered in the order or judgment are concerned."
This provision was clearly intended to avoid subjecting local
educational agencies simultaneously to the jurisdiction of the
federal courts and the federal administrative agencies in
connection with the imposition of remedial measures designed to end
school segregation. Its inclusion reflects the congressional
judgment that the requirements imposed by Title VI are identical to
those imposed by the Constitution as interpreted by the federal
courts.
[ Footnote 2/12 ]
As has already been seen, the proponents of Title VI in the
House were motivated by the identical concern. See remarks
of Representative Celler (110 Cong.Rec. 2467 (1964));
Representative Ryan ( id. at 1643, 2481-2482); H.R.Rep. No.
914, 88th Cong., 1st Sess., pt. 2, Additional Views of Seven
Representatives 2425 (1963).
[ Footnote 2/13 ] See separate opinion of MR. JUSTICE WHITE, post at 438 U. S.
382 -383, n. 2.
[ Footnote 2/14 ]
These remarks also reflect the expectations of Title VI's
proponents that the application of the Constitution to the conduct
at the core of their concern -- the segregation of Negroes in
federally funded programs and their exclusion from the full
benefits of such programs -- was clear. See supra at 438 U. S.
333 -336; infra at 438 U. S.
340 -342, n. 17.
[ Footnote 2/15 ]
Testimony of Attorney General Kennedy in Hearings before the
Senate Committee on the Judiciary on S. 1731 and S. 1750, 88th
Cong., 1st Sess., 398-399 (1963).
[ Footnote 2/16 ] See, e.g., 110 Cong.Rec. 6544, 13820 (1964) (Sen.
Humphrey); id. at 6050 (Sen. Javits); id. at
12677 (Sen. Allott).
[ Footnote 2/17 ]
Our Brother STEVENS finds support for a colorblind theory of
Title VI in its legislative history, but his interpretation gives
undue weight to a few isolated passages from among the thousands of
pages of the legislative history of Title VI. See id. at
6547 (Sen. Humphrey); id. at 6047, 7055 (Sen. Pastore); id. at 12675 (Sen. Allott); id. at 6561 (Sen.
Kuchel). These fragmentary comments fall far short of supporting a
congressional intent to prohibit a racially conscious admissions
program designed to assist those who are likely to have suffered
injuries from the effects of past discrimination. In the first
place, these statements must be read in the context in which they
were made. The concern of the speakers was far removed from the
incidental injuries which may be inflicted upon nonminorities by
the use of racial preferences. It was rather with the evil of the
segregation of Negroes in federally financed programs and, in some
cases, their arbitrary exclusion on account of race from the
benefits of such programs. Indeed, in this context, there can be no
doubt that the Fourteenth Amendment does command color blindness,
and forbids the use of racial criteria. No consideration was given
by these legislators, however, to the permissibility of racial
preference designed to redress the effects of injuries suffered as
a result of one's color. Significantly, one of the legislators,
Senator Pastore, and perhaps also Senator Kuchel, who described
Title VI as proscribing decisionmaking based upon skin color, also
made it clear that Title VI does not outlaw the use of racial
criteria in all circumstances. See supra at 438 U. S.
339 -340; 110 Cong.Rec. 6562 (1964). See also
id. at 2494 (Rep. Celler). Moreover, there are many statements
in the legislative history explicitly indicating that Congress
intended neither to require nor to prohibit the remedial use of
racial preferences where not otherwise required or prohibited by
the Constitution. Representative MacGregor addressed directly the
problem of preferential treatment:
"Your mail and mine, your contacts and mine with our
constituents, indicates a great degree of misunderstanding about
this bill. People complain about racial 'balancing' in the public
schools, about open occupancy in housing, about preferential
treatment or quotas in employment. There is a mistaken belief that
Congress is legislating in these areas in this bill. When we
drafted this bill, we excluded these issues largely because the
problems raised by these controversial questions are more properly
handled at a governmental level close to the American people and by
communities and individuals themselves. The Senate has spelled out
our intentions more specifically." Id. at 15893. Other legislators explained that the
achievement of racial balance in elementary and secondary schools
where there had been no segregation by law was not compelled by
Title VI, but was rather left to the judgment of state and local
communities. See, e.g., id. at 10920 (Sen. Javits); id. at 5807, 5266 (Sen. Keating); id. at 13821
(Sens. Humphrey and Saltonstall). See also id. at 6562
(Sen. Kuchel); id. at 13695 (Sen. Pastore).
Much the same can be said of the scattered remarks to be found
in the legislative history of Title VII of the Civil Rights Act of
1964, 42 U.S.C. § 2000e et seq. (1970 ed. and Supp. V),
which prohibits employment discrimination on the basis of race in
terms somewhat similar to those contained in Title VI, see 42 U.S.C. § 2000e-2(a)(1) (unlawful "to fail or refuse to hire" any
applicant "because of such individual's race, color, religion, sex,
or national origin. . . . "), to the effect that any deliberate
attempt by an employer to maintain a racial balance is not required
by the statute, and might in fact violate it. See, e.g., 110 Cong.Rec. 7214 (1964) (Sens. Clark and Case); id. at
6549 (Sen. Humphrey); id. at 2560 (Rep. Goodell). Once
again, there is no indication that Congress intended to bar the
voluntary use of racial preferences to assist minorities to
surmount the obstacles imposed by the remnants of past
discrimination. Even assuming that Title VII prohibits employers
from deliberately maintaining a particular racial composition in
their workforce as an end in itself, this does not imply, in the
absence of any consideration of the question, that Congress
intended to bar the use of racial preferences as a tool for
achieving the objective of remedying past discrimination or other
compelling ends. The former may well be contrary to the
requirements of the Fourteenth Amendment (where state action is
involved), while the latter presents very different constitutional
considerations. Indeed, as discussed infra at 438 U. S. 353 ,
this Court has construed Title VII as requiring the use of racial
preferences for the purpose of hiring and advancing those who have
been adversely affected by past discriminatory employment
practices, even at the expense of other employees innocent of
discrimination. Franks v. Bowman Transportation Co., 424 U. S. 747 , 424 U. S.
767 -768 (1976). Although Title VII clearly does not
require employers to take action to remedy the disadvantages
imposed upon racial minorities by hands other than their own, such
an objective is perfectly consistent with the remedial goals of the
statute. See id. at 424 U. S.
762 -770; Albemarle Paper Co. v. Moody, 422 U. S. 405 , 422 U. S. 418 (1975). There is no more indication in the legislative history of
Title VII than in that of Title VI that Congress desired to
prohibit such affirmative action to the extent that it is permitted
by the Constitution, yet judicial decisions as well as subsequent
executive and congressional action clearly establish that Title VII
does not forbid race-conscious remedial action. See infra at 438 U. S.
353 -355, and n. 28.
[ Footnote 2/18 ]
HEW has stated that the purpose of these regulations is
"to specify that affirmative steps to make services more
equitably available are not prohibited and that such steps are
required when necessary to overcome the consequences of prior
discrimination."
36 Fed.Reg. 23494 (1971). Other federal agencies which provide
financial assistance pursuant to Title VI have adopted similar
regulations. See Supplemental Brief for United States as Amicus Curiae 16 n. 14.
[ Footnote 2/19 ]
Moreover, the President has delegated to the Attorney General
responsibility for coordinating the enforcement of Title VI by
federal departments and agencies, and has directed him to "assist
the departments and agencies in accomplishing effective
implementation." Exec.Order No. 11764, 3 CFR 849 (1971-1975 Comp.).
Accordingly, the views of the Solicitor General, as well as those
of HEW, that the use of racial preferences for remedial purposes is
consistent with Title VI are entitled to considerable respect.
[ Footnote 2/20 ]
HEW administers at least two explicitly race-conscious programs.
Details concerning them may be found in the Office of Management
and Budget, 1977 Catalogue of Federal Domestic Assistance 205-206,
401-402. The first program, No. 13.375, "Minority Biomedical
Support," has as its objectives:
"To increase the number of ethnic minority faculty, students,
and investigators engaged in biomedical research. To broaden the
opportunities for participation in biomedical research of ethnic
minority faculty, students, and investigators by providing support
for biomedical research programs at eligible institutions."
Eligibility for grants under this program is limited to (1)
four-year colleges, universities, and health professional schools
with over 50% minority enrollments; (2) four-year institutions with
significant but not necessarily over 50% minority enrollment
provided they have a history of encouragement and assistance to
minorities; (3) two-year colleges with 50% minority enrollment; and
(4) American Indian Tribal Councils. Grants made pursuant to this
program are estimated to total $9,711,000 for 1977.
The second program, No. 13.880, entitled "Minority Access To
Research Careers," has as its objective to "assist minority
institutions to train greater numbers of scientists and teachers in
health related fields." Grants under this program are made directly
to individuals and to institutions for the purpose of enabling them
to make grants to individuals.
[ Footnote 2/21 ]
H.R.Conf.Rep. No. 9538, p. 22 (1977); 123 Cong.Rec. 26188
(1977). See H.J.Res. 662, 95th Cong., 1st Sess. (1977);
Pub.L. 95-205, 91 Stat. 1460.
[ Footnote 2/22 ]
91 Stat. 117, 42 U.S.C. § 6705(f)(2) (1976 ed.).
[ Footnote 2/23 ]
123 Cong.Rec.7156 (1977); id. at 5327-5330.
[ Footnote 2/24 ] See id. at 7156 (Sen. Brooke).
[ Footnote 2/25 ]
In addition to the enactment of the 10% quota provision
discussed supra, Congress has also passed other Acts
mandating race-conscious measures to overcome disadvantages
experienced by racial minorities. Although these statutes have less
direct bearing upon the meaning of Title VI, they do demonstrate
that Congress believes race-conscious remedial measures to be both
permissible and desirable under at least some circumstances. This,
in turn, undercuts the likelihood that Congress intended to limit
voluntary efforts to implement similar measures. For example, §
7(a) of the National Science Foundation Authorization Act, 1977,
provides:
"The Director of the National Science Foundation shall initiate
an intensive search for qualified women, members of minority
groups, and handicapped individuals to fill executive level
positions in the National Science Foundation. In carrying out the
requirement of this subsection, the Director shall work closely
with organizations which have been active in seeking greater
recognition and utilization of the scientific and technical
capabilities of minorities, women, and handicapped individuals. The
Director shall improve the representation of minorities, women, and
handicapped individuals on advisory committees,, review panels, and
all other mechanisms by which the scientific community provides
assistance to the Foundation."
90 Stat. 2056, note following 42 U.S.C. 1873 (1976 ed.). Perhaps
more importantly, the Act also authorizes the funding of Minority
Centers for Graduate Education. Section 7(C)(2) of the Act, 90
Stat. 2056, requires that these Centers:
"(A) have substantial minority student enrollment;"
"(B) are geographically located near minority population
centers;"
"(C) demonstrate a commitment to encouraging and assisting
minority students, researchers, and faculty;"
" * * * *" "(F) will serve as a regional resource in science and
engineering for the minority community which the Center is designed
to serve; and"
"(G) will develop joint educational programs with nearby
undergraduate institutions of higher education which have a
substantial minority student enrollment."
Once again, there is no indication in the legislative history of
this Act or elsewhere that Congress saw any inconsistency between
the race-conscious nature of such legislation and the meaning of
Title VI. And, once again, it is unlikely in the extreme that a
Congress which believed that it had commanded recipients of federal
funds to be absolutely colorblind would itself expend federal funds
in such a race-conscious manner. See also the Railroad
Revitalization and Regulatory Reform Act of 1976, 45 U.S.C. § 801 et seq. (1976 ed.), 49 U.S.C. § 1657a et seq. (1976 ed.); the Emergency School Aid Act, 20 U.S.C. § 1601 et
seq. (1976 ed.).
[ Footnote 2/26 ] Cf. Griggs v. Duke Power Co., 401 U.
S. 424 (1971).
[ Footnote 2/27 ] Ibid.; Albemarle Paper Co. v. Moody, 422 U.
S. 405 (1975).
[ Footnote 2/28 ] Franks v. Bowman Transportation Co., 424 U.
S. 747 (1976); Teamsters v. United States, 431 U. S. 324 (1977). Executive, judicial, and congressional action subsequent to
the passage of Title VII conclusively established that the Title
did not bar the remedial use of race. Prior to the 1972 amendments
to Title VII (Equal Employment Opportunity Act of 1972, 86 Stat.
103), a number of Courts of Appeals approved race-conscious action
to remedy the effects of employment discrimination. See, e.g.,
Heat & Frost Insulators & Asbestos Workers v. Voler, 407 F.2d 1047 (CA5 1969); United States v. Electrical
Workers, 428 F.2d 144, 149-150 (CA6), cert. denied, 400 U.S. 943 (1970); United States v. Sheetmetal Workers, 416 F.2d 123 (CA8 1969). In 1965, the President issued Exec.Order
No. 11246, 3 CFR 339 (1964-1965 Comp.), which, as amended by
Exec.Order No. 11375, 3 CFR 684 (1966-1970 Comp.), required federal
contractors to take affirmative action to remedy the
disproportionately low employment of racial minorities in the
construction industry. The Attorney General issued an opinion
concluding that the race consciousness required by Exec Order No
11246 did not conflict with Title VII:
"It is not correct to say that Title VII prohibits employers
from making race or national origin a factor for consideration at
any stage in the process of obtaining employees. The legal
definition of discrimination is an evolving one, but it is now well
recognized in judicial opinions that the obligation of
nondiscrimination, whether imposed by statute or by the
Constitution, does not require and, in some circumstances, may not
permit, obliviousness or indifference to the racial consequences of
alternative courses of action which involve the application of
outwardly neutral criteria."
42 Op.Atty.Gen. 405, 411 (1969). The federal courts agreed. See, e.g., Contractors Assn. of Eastern Pa. v. Secretary of
Labor, 442 F.2d 159 (CA3), cert. denied, 404 U.S. 854
(1971) (which also held, 442 F.2d at 173, that race-conscious
affirmative action was permissible under Title VI); Southern
Illinois Builders Assn. v. Ogilvie, 471 F.2d 680 (CA7 1972).
Moreover, Congress, in enacting the 1972 amendments to Title VII,
explicitly considered and rejected proposals to alter Exec.Order
No. 11246 and the prevailing judicial interpretations of Title VII
as permitting, and in some circumstances requiring, race-conscious
action. See Comment, The Philadelphia Plan: A Study in the
Dynamics of Executive Power, 39 U.Chi.L.Rev. 723, 747-757 (1972).
The section-by-section analysis of the 1972 amendments to Title VII
undertaken by the Conference Committee Report on H.R. 1746 reveals
a resolve to accept the then (as now) prevailing judicial
interpretations of the scope of Title VII:
"In any area where the new law does not address itself, or in
any areas where a specific contrary intent is not indicated, it was
assumed that the present case law as developed by the courts would
continue to govern the applicability and construction of Title
VII."
Legislative History of the Equal Employment Opportunity Act of
1972, p. 1844 (Comm.Print 1972).
[ Footnote 2/29 ] United Jewish Organizations v. Carey, 430 U.
S. 144 (1977). See also id. at 430 U. S.
167 -168 (opinion of WHITE, J.).
[ Footnote 2/30 ]
We do not pause to debate whether our cases establish a
"two-tier" analysis, a "sliding scale" analysis, or something else
altogether. It is enough for present purposes that strict scrutiny
is applied at least in some cases.
[ Footnote 2/31 ]
Of course, the fact that whites constitute a political majority
in our Nation does not necessarily mean that active judicial
scrutiny of racial classifications that disadvantage whites is
inappropriate. Cf. Castaneda v. Partida, 430 U.
S. 482 , 430 U. S.
499 -500 (1977); id. at 430 U. S. 501 (MARSHALL, J., concurring) .
[ Footnote 2/32 ]
"[T]he conclusion cannot be resisted, that no reason for [the
refusal to issue permits to Chinese] exists except hostility to the
race and nationality to which the petitioners belong. . . . The
discrimination is, therefore, illegal. . . ."
[ Footnote 2/33 ]
Indeed, even in Plessy v. Ferguson, the Court
recognized that a classification by race that presumed one race to
be inferior to another would have to be condemned. See 163
U.S. at 163 U. S.
544 -551.
[ Footnote 2/34 ]
Paradoxically, petitioner's argument is supported by the cases
generally thought to establish the "strict scrutiny" standard in
race cases, Hirabayashi v. United States, 320 U. S.
81 (1943), and Korematsu v. United States, 323 U. S. 214 (1944). In Hirabayashi, for example, the Court, responding
to a claim that a racial classification was rational, sustained a
racial classification solely on the basis of a conclusion in the
double negative that it could not say that facts which might have
been available "could afford no ground for differentiating citizens
of Japanese ancestry from other groups in the United States." 320
U.S. at 320 U. S. 101 .
A similar mode of analysis was followed in Korematsu, see 323 U.S. at 323 U. S. 224 ,
even though the Court stated there that racial classifications were
"immediately suspect," and should be subject to "the most rigid
scrutiny." Id. at 323 U. S. 216 .
[ Footnote 2/35 ]
We disagree with our Brother POWELL's suggestion, ante at 438 U. S. 303 ,
that the presence of "rival groups which can claim that they, too,
are entitled to preferential treatment" distinguishes the gender
cases or is relevant to the question of scope of judicial review of
race classifications. We are not asked to determine whether groups
other than those favored by the Davis program should similarly be
favored. All we are asked to do is to pronounce the
constitutionality of what Davis has done.
But, were we asked to decide whether any given rival group --
German-Americans for example -- must constitutionally be accorded
preferential treatment, we do have a "principled basis," ante at 438 U. S. 296 ,
for deciding this question, one that is well established in our
cases: the Davis program expressly sets out four classes which
receive preferred status. Ante at 438 U. S. 274 .
The program clearly distinguishes whites, but one cannot reason
from this a conclusion that German-Americans, as a national group,
are singled out for invidious treatment. And even if the Davis
program had a differential impact on German-Americans, they would
have no constitutional claim unless they could prove that Davis
intended invidiously to discriminate against German-Americans. See Arlington Heights v. Metropolitan Housing Dev. Corp., 429 U. S. 252 , 429 U. S.
264 -265 (1977); Washington v. Davis, 426 U. S. 229 , 426 U. S.
238 -241 (1976). If this could not be shown, then "the
principle that calls for the closest scrutiny of distinctions in
laws denying fundamental rights . . . is inapplicable," Katzenbach v. Morgan, 384 U. S. 641 , 384 U. S. 657 (1966), and the only question is whether it was rational for Davis
to conclude that the groups it preferred had a greater claim to
compensation than the groups it excluded. See ibid.; San
Antonio Independent School District v. Rodriguez, 411 U. S.
1 , 411 U. S. 38 -39
(1973) (applying Katzenbach test to state action intended to remove
discrimination in educational opportunity). Thus, claims of rival
groups, although they may create thorny political problems, create
relatively simple problems for the courts.
[ Footnote 2/36 ]
Gunther, The Supreme Court, 1971 Term -- Foreword: In Search of
Evolving Doctrine on a Changing Court: A Model for a Newer Equal
Protection, 86 Harv.L.Rev. 1, 8 (1972).
[ Footnote 2/37 ]
In Albemarle, we approved "differential validation" of
employment tests. See 422 U.S. at 422 U. S. 435 .
That procedure requires that an employer must ensure that a test
score of, for example, 50 for a minority job applicant means the
same thing as a score of 50 for a nonminority applicant. By
implication, were it determined that a test score of 50 for a
minority corresponded in "potential for employment" to a 60 for
whites, the test could not be used consistently with Title VII
unless the employer hired minorities with scores of 50 even though
he might not hire nonminority applicants with scores above 50 but
below 60. Thus, it is clear that employers, to ensure equal
opportunity, may have to adopt race-conscious hiring practices.
[ Footnote 2/38 ]
Indeed, Titles VI and VII of the Civil Rights Act of 1964 put
great emphasis on voluntarism in remedial action. See
supra at 438 U. S.
336 -338. And, significantly, the Equal Employment
Opportunity Commission has recently proposed guidelines authorizing
employers to adopt racial preferences as a remedial measure where
they have a reasonable basis for believing that they might
otherwise be held in violation of Title VII. See 42
Fed.Reg. 64826 (1977).
[ Footnote 2/39 ]
"[T]he [Voting Rights] Act's prohibition . . . is not dependent
upon proving past unconstitutional apportionments. . . ."
[ Footnote 2/40 ]
"[T]he State is [not] powerless to minimize the consequences of
racial discrimination by voters when it is regularly practiced at
the polls."
[ Footnote 2/41 ]
Our cases cannot be distinguished by suggesting, as our Brother
POWELL does, that in none of them was anyone deprived of "the
relevant benefit." Ante at 438 U. S. 304 .
Our school cases have deprived whites of the neighborhood school of
their choice; our Title VII cases have deprived nondiscriminating
employees of their settled seniority expectations; and UJO deprived the Hassidim of bloc-voting strength. Each of these
injuries was constitutionally cognizable as is respondent's
here.
[ Footnote 2/42 ]
We do not understand MR. JUSTICE POWELL to disagree that
providing a remedy for past racial prejudice can constitute a
compelling purpose sufficient to meet strict scrutiny. See
ante at 438 U. S. 305 .
Yet, because petitioner is a corporation administering a
university, he would not allow it to exercise such power in the
absence of "judicial, legislative, or administrative findings of
constitutional or statutory violations." Ante at 438 U. S. 307 .
While we agree that reversal in this case would follow a
fortiori had Davis been guilty of invidious racial
discrimination or if a federal statute mandated that universities
refrain from applying any admissions policy that had a disparate
and unjustified racial impact, see, e.g., McDaniel v.
Barresi, 402 U. S. 39 (1971); Franks v. Bowman Transportation Co., 424 U.
S. 747 (1976), we do not think it of constitutional
significance that Davis has not been so adjudged.
Generally, the manner in which a State chooses to delegate
governmental functions is for it to decide. Cf. Sweezy v. New
Hampshire, 354 U. S. 234 , 354 U. S. 256 (1957) (Frankfurter, J., concurring in result). California, by
constitutional provision, has chosen to place authority over the
operation of the University of California in the Board of Regents. See Cal.Const., Art. 9, § 9(a). Control over the
University is to be found not in the legislature, but rather in the
Regents who have been vested with full legislative (including
policymaking), administrative, and adjudicative powers by the
citizens of California. See ibid.; Ishimatsu v.
Regents, 266 Cal. App.
2d 854 , 863-864, 72 Cal. Rptr. 756, 762-763 (1968); Goldberg v. Regents, 248 Cal. App.
2d 867 , 874, 57 Cal. Rptr. 463, 468 (1967); 30 Op.Cal.Atty.
Gen. 162, 166 (1957) ("The Regents, not the legislature, have the
general rulemaking or policymaking power in regard to the
University"). This is certainly a permissible choice, see
Sweezy, supra, and we, unlike our Brother POWELL, find nothing
in the Equal Protection Clause that requires us to depart from
established principle by limiting the scope of power the Regents
may exercise more narrowly than the powers that may
constitutionally be wielded by the Assembly.
Because the Regents can exercise plenary legislative and
administrative power, it elevates form over substance to insist
that Davis could not use race-conscious remedial programs until it
had been adjudged in violation of the Constitution or an
antidiscrimination statute. For, if the Equal Protection Clause
required such a violation as a predicate, the Regents could simply
have promulgated a regulation prohibiting disparate treatment not
justified by the need to admit only qualified students, and could
have declared Davis to have been in violation of such a regulation
on the basis of the exclusionary effect of the admissions policy
applied during the first two years of its operation. See
infra at 438 U. S.
370 .
[ Footnote 2/43 ]
"Equal protection analysis in the Fifth Amendment area is the
same as that under the Fourteenth Amendment." Buckley v.
Valeo, 424 U. S. 1 , 424 U. S. 93 (1976) (per curiam), citing Weinberger v. Wiesenfeld, 420 U. S. 636 , 420 U. S. 638 n. 2 (1975).
[ Footnote 2/44 ] Railway Mail Assn. held that a state statute forbidding
racial discrimination by certain labor organizations did not
abridge the Association's due process rights secured by the
Fourteenth Amendment, because that result
"would be a distortion of the policy manifested in that
amendment, which was adopted to prevent state legislation designed
to perpetuate discrimination on the basis of race or color."
326 U.S. at 326 U. S. 94 .
That case thus established the principle that a State voluntarily
could go beyond what the Fourteenth Amendment required in
eliminating private racial discrimination.
[ Footnote 2/45 ]
According to 89 schools responding to a questionnaire sent to
112 medical schools (all of the then-accredited medical schools in
the United States except Howard and Meharry), substantial efforts
to admit minority students did not begin until 1968. That year was
the earliest year of involvement for 34% of the schools; an
additional 66% became involved during the years 1969 to 1973. See C. Odegaard, Minorities in Medicine: From Receptive
Passivity to Positive Action, 1966-1976, p. 19 (1977) (hereinafter
Odegaard). These efforts were reflected in a significant increase
in the percentage of minority M.D. graduates. The number of
American Negro graduates increased from 2.2% in 1970 to 3.3% in
1973 and 5.0% in 1975. Significant percentage increases in the
number of Mexican-American, American Indian, and mainland Puerto
Rican graduates were also recorded during those years. Id. at 40.
The statistical information cited in this and the following
notes was compiled by Government officials or medical educators,
and has been brought to our attention in many of the briefs.
Neither the parties nor the amici challenge the validity
of the statistics alluded to in our discussion.
[ Footnote 2/46 ]
D. Reitzes, Negroes and Medicine, pp. xxvii, 3 (1958).
[ Footnote 2/47 ]
Between 1955 and 1964, for example, the percentage of Negro
physicians graduated in the United States who were trained at these
schools ranged from 69.0% to 75.8%. See Odegaard 19.
[ Footnote 2/48 ]
U.S. Dept. of Health, Education, and Welfare, Minorities and
Women in the Health Fields 7 (Pub. No. (HRA) 75-22, May, 1974).
[ Footnote 2/49 ]
U.S. Dept. of Commerce, Bureau of the Census, 1970 Census, vol.
1, pt. 1, Table 60 (1973).
[ Footnote 2/50 ] See ante at 438 U. S. 276 n. 6 (opinion of POWELL, J.).
[ Footnote 2/51 ] See, e.g., R. Wade, Slavery in the Cities: The South
1820-1860, pp. 991 (1964).
[ Footnote 2/52 ]
For an example of unequal facilities in California schools, see Sona v. Oxnard School Dist. Board, 386 F.
Supp. 539 , 542 (CD Cal.1974). See also R. Kluger,
Simple Justice (1976).
[ Footnote 2/53 ] See, e.g., Crawford v. Board of
Education, 17 Cal. 3d
280 , 551 P.2d 28 (1976); Soria v. Oxnard School Dist.
Board, supra; Spangler v. Pasadena City Board of
Education, 311 F.
Supp. 501 (CD Cal.1970); C. Wollenberg, All Deliberate Speed:
Segregation and Exclusion in California Schools, 1855-1975, pp.
136-177 (1976).
[ Footnote 2/54 ]
For example, over 40% of American-born Negro males aged 20 to 24
residing in California in 1970 were born in the South, and the
statistic for females was over 48%. These statistics were computed
from data contained in Census, supra, 438
U.S. 265 fn2/49|>n. 49, pt. 6, California, Tables 139,
140.
[ Footnote 2/55 ] See, e.g., O'Neil, Preferential Admissions: Equalizing
the Access of Minority Groups to Higher Education, 80 Yale L.J.
699, 729-731 (1971).
[ Footnote 2/56 ]
Congress and the Executive have also adopted a series of
race-conscious programs, each predicated on an understanding that
equal opportunity cannot be achieved by neutrality, because of the
effects of past and present discrimination. See supra at 438 U. S.
348 -349.
[ Footnote 2/57 ]
Negroes and Chicanos alone constitute approximately 22% of
California's population. This percentage was computed from data
contained in Census, supra, 438
U.S. 265 fn2/49|>n. 49, pt. 6, California, sec. 1,6-4, and
Table 139.
[ Footnote 2/58 ]
The constitutionality of the special admissions program is
buttressed by its restriction to only 16% of the positions in the
Medical School, a percentage less than that of the minority
population in California, see ibid., and to those minority
applicants deemed qualified for admission and deemed likely to
contribute to the Medical School and the medical profession. Record
67. This is consistent with the goal of putting minority applicants
in the position they would have ben in if not for the evil of
racial discrimination. Accordingly, this case does not raise the
question whether even a remedial use of race would be
unconstitutional if it admitted unqualified minority applicants in
preference to qualified applicants or admitted, as a result of
preferential consideration, racial minorities in numbers
significantly in excess of their proportional representation in the
relevant population. Such programs might well be inadequately
justified by the legitimate remedial objectives. Our allusion to
the proportional percentage of minorities in the population of the
State administering the program is not intended to establish either
that figure or that population universe as a constitutional
benchmark. In this case, even respondent, as we understand him,
does not argue that, if the special admissions program is otherwise
constitutional, the allotment of 16 places in each entering class
for special admittees is unconstitutionally high.
[ Footnote 2/59 ] See Census, supra, 438
U.S. 265 fn2/49|>n. 49, Sources and Structure of Family
Income, pp. 1-12.
[ Footnote 2/60 ]
This percentage was computed from data presented in B. Waldman,
Economic and Racial Disadvantage as Reflected in Traditional
Medical School Selection Factors: A Study of 1976 Applicants to
U.S. Medical Schools 34 (Table A-15), 42 (Table A-23) (Association
of American Medical Colleges 1977).
[ Footnote 2/61 ]
This figure was computed from data contained in Census, supra, 438
U.S. 265 fn2/49|>n. 49, pt. 1, United States Summary, Table
209.
[ Footnote 2/62 ] See Waldman, supra, 438
U.S. 265 fn2/60|>n. 60, at 10-14 (Figures 1-5).
[ Footnote 2/63 ]
The excluded white applicant, despite MR. JUSTICE POWELL's
contention to the contrary, ante at 438 U. S. 318 n. 52, receives no more or less "individualized consideration"
under our approach than under his.
MR. JUSTICE WHITE.
I write separately concerning the question of whether Title VI
of the Civil Rights Act of 1964, 42 U.S.C. § 2000d et
seq., provides for a private cause of action. Four Justices
are apparently of the view that such a private cause of action Page 438 U. S. 380 exists, and four Justices assume it for purposes of this case. I
am unwilling merely to assume an affirmative answer. If, in fact,
no private cause of action exists, this Court and the lower courts
as well are without jurisdiction to consider respondent's Title VI
claim. As I see it, if we are not obliged to do so, it is at least
advisable to address this threshold jurisdictional issue. See
United States v. Griffin, 303 U. S. 226 , 303 U. S. 229 (1938). [ Footnote 3/1 ] Furthermore,
just as it is inappropriate to address constitutional issues
without determining whether statutory grounds urged before us are
dispositive, it is at least questionable practice to adjudicate a
novel and difficult statutory issue without first considering
whether we have jurisdiction to decide it. Consequently, I address
the question of whether respondent may bring suit under Title
VI.
A private cause of action under Title VI, in terms both of Page 438 U. S. 381 the Civil Rights Act as a whole and that Title, would not be
"consistent with the underlying purposes of the legislative
scheme," and would be contrary to the legislative intent. Cort
v. Ash, 422 U. S. 66 , 422 U. S. 78 (1975). Title II, 42 U.S.C. § 2000a et seq., dealing with
public accommodations, and Title VII, 42 U.S.C. § 2000e et
seq. (1970 ed. and Supp. V), dealing with employment,
proscribe private discriminatory conduct that, as of 1964, neither
the Constitution nor other federal statutes had been construed to
forbid. Both Titles carefully provided for private actions as well
as for official participation in enforcement. Title III, 42 U.S.C.
§ 2000b et seq., and Title IV, 42 U.S.C. § 2000c et
seq. (1970 ed and Supp. V), dealing with public facilities and
public education, respectively, authorize suits by the Attorney
General to eliminate racial discrimination in these areas. Because
suits to end discrimination in public facilities and public
education were already available under 42 U.S.C. § 1983, it was, of
course, unnecessary to provide for private actions under Titles III
and IV. But each Title carefully provided that its provisions for
public actions would not adversely affect preexisting private
remedies. § § 2000b-2 and 2000c-8.
The role of Title VI was to terminate federal financial support
for public and private institutions or programs that discriminated
on the basis of race. Section 601, 42 U.S.C. § 2000d, imposed the
proscription that no person, on the grounds of race, color, or
national origin, was to be excluded from or discriminated against
under any program or activity receiving federal financial
assistance. But there is no express provision for private actions
to enforce Title VI, and it would be quite incredible if Congress,
after so carefully attending to the matter of private actions in
other Titles of the Act, intended silently to create a private
cause of action to enforce Title VI.
It is also evident from the face of § 602, 42 U.S.C. § 2000d-1,
that Congress intended the departments and agencies Page 438 U. S. 382 to define and to refine, by rule or regulation, the general
proscription of § 601, subject only to judicial review of agency
action in accordance with established procedures. Section 602
provides for enforcement: every federal department or agency
furnishing financial support is to implement the proscription by
appropriate rule or regulation, each of which requires approval by
the President. Termination of funding as a sanction for
noncompliance is authorized, but only after a hearing and after the
failure of voluntary means to secure compliance. Moreover,
termination may not take place until the department or agency
involved files with the appropriate committees of the House and
Senate a full written report of the circumstances and the grounds
for such action and 30 days have elapsed thereafter. Judicial
review was provided, at least for actions terminating financial
assistance.
Termination of funding was regarded by Congress as a serious
enforcement step, and the legislative history is replete with
assurances that it would not occur until every possibility for
conciliation had been exhausted. [ Footnote 3/2 ] To allow a private Page 438 U. S. 383 individual to sue to cut off funds under Title VI would
compromise these assurances and short-circuit the procedural
preconditions provided in Title VI. If the Federal Government may
not cut off funds except pursuant to an agency rule, approved by
the President, and presented to the appropriate committee of
Congress for a layover period, and after voluntary means to achieve
compliance have failed, it is inconceivable that Congress intended
to permit individuals to circumvent these administrative
prerequisites themselves.
Furthermore, although Congress intended Title VI to end federal
financial support for racially discriminatory policies of not only
public but also private institutions and programs, it is extremely
unlikely that Congress, without a word indicating that it intended
to do so, contemplated creating an independent, private statutory
cause of action against all private, as well as public, agencies
that might be in violation of the section. There is no doubt that
Congress regarded private litigation as an important tool to attack
discriminatory practices. It does not at all follow, however, that
Congress anticipated new private actions under Title VI itself.
Wherever a discriminatory program was a public undertaking, such as
a public school, private remedies were already available under
other statutes, and a private remedy under Title VI was Page 438 U. S. 384 unnecessary. Congress was well aware of this fact.
Significantly, there was frequent reference to Simkins v. Moses
H. Cone Memorial Hospital, 323 F.2d 059 (CA4 1963), cert.
denied, 376 U.S. 938 (1964), throughout the congressional
deliberations. See, e.g., 110 Cong.Rec. 654 (1964) (Sen.
Humphrey). Simkins held that, under appropriate
circumstances, the operation of a private hospital with "massive
use of public funds and extensive state-federal sharing in the
common plan" constituted "state action" for the purposes of the
Fourteenth Amendment. 323 F.2d at 967. It was unnecessary, of
course, to create a Title VI private action against private
discriminators where they were already within the reach of existing
private remedies. But when they were not -- and Simkins carefully disclaimed holding that "every subvention by the federal
or state government automatically involves the beneficiary in state action,'" ibid. [ Footnote 3/3 ] -- it is difficult Page 438 U. S. 385 to believe that Congress silently created a private remedy to
terminate conduct that previously had been entirely beyond the
reach of federal law.
For those who believe, contrary to my views, that Title VI was
intended to create a stricter standard of colorblindness than the
Constitution itself requires, the result of no private cause of
action follows even more readily. In that case, Congress must be
seen to have banned degrees of discrimination, as well as types of
discriminators, not previously reached by law. A Congress careful
enough to provide that existing private causes of action would be
preserved (in Titles III and IV) would not leave for inference a
vast new extension of private enforcement power. And a Congress so
exceptionally concerned with the satisfaction of procedural
preliminaries before confronting fund recipients with the choice of
a cutoff or of stopping discriminating would not permit private
parties to pose precisely that same dilemma in a greatly widened
category of cases with no procedural requirements whatsoever.
Significantly, in at least three instances, legislators who
played a major role in the passage of Title VI explicitly stated
that a private right of action under Title VI does not exist.
[ Footnote 3/4 ] Page 438 U. S. 386 As an "indication of legislative intent, explicit or implicit,
either to create such a remedy or to deny one," Cort v.
Ash, 422 U.S. at 422 U. S. 78 ,
clearer statements cannot be imagined, and under Cort, "an
explicit purpose to deny such cause of action [is] controlling." Id. at 422 U. S. 82 .
Senator Keating, for example, proposed a private "right to sue" for
the "person suffering from discrimination"; but the Department of
Justice refused to include it, and the Senator acquiesced.
[ Footnote 3/5 ] These are not
neutral, ambiguous statements. They indicate the absence of a
legislative intent to create a private remedy. Nor do any of these
statements make nice distinctions between a private cause of action
to enjoin discrimination and one to cut off funds, as MR. JUSTICE
STEVENS and the three Justices who join his opinion apparently
would. See post at 438 U. S.
419 -420, n. 26. Indeed, it would be odd if they did,
since the practical effect of either type of private cause of
action would be identical. If private suits to enjoin conduct
allegedly violative of § 601 were permitted, recipients of federal
funds would be presented with the choice of either ending what the
court, rather than the agency, determined to be a discriminatory
practice within the meaning of Title VI or refusing federal funds,
and thereby escaping from the statute's jurisdictional predicate.
[ Footnote 3/6 ] This is precisely
the same choice as would confront recipients if suit were brought
to cut off funds. Both types of actions would equally jeopardize
the administrative processes so carefully structured into the
law. Page 438 U. S. 387 This Court has always required
"that the inference of such a private cause of action not
otherwise authorized by the statute must be consistent with the
evident legislative intent and, of course, with the effectuation of
the purposes intended to be served by the Act." National Railroad Passenger Corp. v. National Association of
Railroad Passengers, 414 U. S. 453 , 414 U. S. 458 (1974). See also Securities Investor Protection Corp. v.
Barbour, 421 U. S. 412 , 421 U. S. 418 420 (1975). A private cause of action under Title VI is unable to
satisfy either prong of this test.
Because each of my colleagues either has a different view or
assumes a private cause of action, however, the merits of the Title
VI issue must be addressed. My views in that regard, as well as my
views with respect to the equal protection issue, are included in
the joint opinion that my Brothers BRENNAN, MARSHALL, and BLACKMUN
and I have filed. [ Footnote
3/7 ]
[ Footnote 3/1 ]
It is also clear from Griffin that "lack of
jurisdiction . . . touching the subject matter of the litigation
cannot be waived by the parties. . . ." 303 U.S. at 303 U. S. 229 . See also Mount Healthy City Bd. of Ed. v. Doyle, 429 U. S. 274 , 429 U. S. 278 (1977); Louisville & Nashville R. Co. v. Mottley, 211 U. S. 149 , 211 U. S. 152 (1908); Mansfield, C. & L. M. R. Co. v. Swan, 111 U. S. 379 , 111 U. S. 382 (1884).
In Lau v. Nichols, 414 U. S. 563 (1974), we did adjudicate a Title VI claim brought by a class of
individuals. But the existence of a private cause of action was not
at issue. In addition, the understanding of MR. JUSTICE STEWART's
concurring opinion, which observed that standing was not being
contested, was that the standing alleged by petitioners was as
third-party beneficiaries of the funding contract between the
Department of Health, Education, and Welfare and the San Francisco
United School District, a theory not alleged by the present
respondent. Id. at 414 U. S. 571 n. 2. Furthermore, the plaintiffs in Lau alleged
jurisdiction under 42 U.S.C. § 1983, rather than directly under the
provisions of Title VI, as does the plaintiff in this case.
Although the Court undoubtedly had an obligation to consider the
jurisdictional question, this is surely not the first instance in
which the Court has bypassed a jurisdictional problem not presented
by the parties. Certainly the Court's silence on the jurisdictional
question, when considered in the context of the indifference of the
litigants to it and the fact that jurisdiction was alleged under §
1983, does not foreclose a reasoned conclusion that Title VI
affords no private cause of action.
[ Footnote 3/2 ]
"Yet, before that principle [that 'Federal funds are not to be
used to support racial discrimination'] is implemented to the
detriment of any person, agency, or State, regulations giving
notice of what conduct is required must be drawn up by the agency
administering the program. . . . Before such regulations become
effective, they must be submitted to and approved by the
President."
"Once having become effective, there is still a long road to
travel before any sanction whatsoever is imposed. Formal action to
compel compliance can only take place after the following has
occurred: first, there must be an unsuccessful attempt to obtain
voluntary compliance; second, there must be an administrative
hearing; third, a written report of the circumstances and the
grounds for such action must be filed with the appropriate
committees of the House and Senate; and fourth, 30 days must have
elapsed between such filing and the action denying benefits under a
Federal program. Finally, even that action is by no means final,
because it is subject to judicial review, and can be further
postponed by judicial action granting temporary relief pending
review in order to avoid irreparable injury. It would be difficult
indeed to concoct any additional safeguards to incorporate in such
a procedure."
110 Cong.Rec. 6749 (1964) (Sen. Moss).
"[T]he authority to cut off funds is hedged about with a number
of procedural restrictions. . . . [There follow details of the
preliminary steps.]"
"In short, title VI is a reasonable, moderate, cautious,
carefully worked out solution to a situation that clearly calls for
legislative action." Id. at 6544 (Sen. Humphrey).
"Actually, no action whatsoever can be taken against
anyone until the Federal agency involved has advised the
appropriate person of his failure to comply with nondiscrimination
requirements and until voluntary efforts to secure compliance have
failed." Id. at 1519 (Rep. Celler) (emphasis added). See
also remarks of Sen. Ribicoff ( id. at 7066-7067);
Sen. Proxmire ( id. at 8345); en. Kuchel ( id. at
6562). These safeguards were incorporated into 42 U.S.C. §
2000d-1.
[ Footnote 3/3 ]
This Court has never held that the mere receipt of federal or
state funds is sufficient to make the recipient a federal or state
actor. In Norwood v. Harrison, 413 U.
S. 455 (1973), private schools that received state aid
were held subject to the Fourteenth Amendment's ban on
discrimination, but the Court's test required "tangible financial
aid" with a "significant tendency to facilitate, reinforce, and
support private discrimination." Id. at 413 U. S. 466 .
The mandate of Burton v. Wilmington Parking Authority, 365 U. S. 715 , 365 U. S. 722 (1961), to sift facts and weigh circumstances of governmental
support in each case to determine whether private or state action
was involved, has not been abandoned for an automatic rule based on
receipt of funds.
Contemporaneous with the congressional debates on the Civil
Rights Act was this Court's decision in Griffin v. School
Board, 377 U. S. 218 (1964). Tuition grants and tax concessions were provided for
parents of students in private schools which discriminated
racially. The Court found sufficient state action, but carefully
limited its holding to the circumstances presented:
"[C]losing the Prince Edward schools and meanwhile contributing
to the support of the private segregated white schools that took
their place denied petitioners the equal protection of the
laws." Id. at 377 U. S.
232 .
Hence, neither at the time of the enactment of Title VI nor at
the present time, to the extent this Court has spoken, has mere
receipt of state funds created state action. Moreover, Simkins has not met with universal approval among the
United States Courts of Appeals. See cases cited in Greco v. Orange Memorial Hospital Corp., 423 U.
S. 1000 , 1004 (1975) (WHITE, J., dissenting from denial
of certiorari).
[ Footnote 3/4 ]
"Nowhere in this section do you find a comparable right of legal
action for a person who feels he has been denied his rights to
participate in the benefits of Federal funds. Nowhere. Only those
who have been cut off can go to court and present their claim."
110 Cong.Rec. 2467 (1964) (Rep. Gill).
"[A] good case could be made that a remedy is provided for the
State or local official who is practicing discrimination, but none
is provided for the victim of the discrimination." Id. at 6562 (Sen. Kuchel).
"Parenthetically, while we favored the inclusion of the right to
sue on the part of the agency, the State, or the facility which was
deprived of Federal funds, we also favored the inclusion of a
provision granting the right to sue to the person suffering from
discrimination. This was not included in the bill. However, both
the Senator from Connecticut and I are grateful that our other
suggestions were adopted by the Justice Department." Id. at 7065 (Sen. Keating).
[ Footnote 3/5 ] Ibid. [ Footnote 3/6 ]
As Senator Ribicoff stated:
"Sometimes those eligible for Federal assistance may elect to
reject such aid, unwilling to agree to a nondiscrimination
requirement. If they choose that course, the responsibility is
theirs." Id. at 7067.
[ Footnote 3/7 ]
I also join Parts I, III-A, and V-C of MR. JUSTICE POWELL's
opinion.
MR. JUSTICE MARSHALL.
I agree with the judgment of the Court only insofar as it
permits a university to consider the race of an applicant in making
admissions decisions. I do not agree that petitioner's admissions
program violates the Constitution. For it must be remembered that,
during most of the past 200 years, the Constitution, as interpreted
by this Court, did not prohibit the most ingenious and pervasive
forms of discrimination against the Negro. Now, when a State acts
to remedy the effects of that legacy of discrimination, I cannot
believe that this same Constitution stands as a barrier. I A Three hundred and fifty years ago, the Negro was dragged to this
country in chains to be sold into slavery. Uprooted from his
homeland and thrust into bondage for forced labor, Page 438 U. S. 388 the slave was deprived of all legal rights. It was unlawful to
teach him to read; he could be sold away from his family and
friends at the whim of his master; and killing or maiming him was
not a crime. The system of slavery brutalized and dehumanized both
master and slave. [ Footnote
4/1 ]
The denial of human rights was etched into the American
Colonies' first attempts at establishing self-government. When the
colonists determined to seek their independence from England, they
drafted a unique document cataloguing their grievances against the
King and proclaiming as "self-evident" that "all men are created
equal" and are endowed "with certain unalienable Rights," including
those to "Life, Liberty and the pursuit of Happiness." The
self-evident truths and the unalienable rights were intended,
however, to apply only to white men. An earlier draft of the
Declaration of Independence, submitted by Thomas Jefferson to the
Continental Congress, had included among the charges against the
King that
"[h]e has waged cruel war against human nature itself, violating
its most sacred rights of life and liberty in the persons of a
distant people who never offended him, captivating and carrying
them into slavery in another hemisphere, or to incur miserable
death in their transportation thither."
Franklin 88. The Southern delegation insisted that the charge be
deleted; the colonists themselves were implicated in the slave
trade, and inclusion of this claim might have made it more
difficult to justify the continuation of slavery once the ties to
England were severed. Thus, even as the colonists embarked on a Page 438 U. S. 389 course to secure their own freedom and equality, they ensured
perpetuation of the system that deprived a whole race of those
rights.
The implicit protection of slavery embodied in the Declaration
of Independence was made explicit in the Constitution, which
treated a slave as being equivalent to three-fifths of a person for
purposes of apportioning representatives and taxes among the
States. Art. I, § 2. The Constitution also contained a clause
ensuring that the "Migration or Importation" of slaves into the
existing States would be legal until at least 1808, Art. I, § 9,
and a fugitive slave clause requiring that, when a slave escaped to
another State, he must be returned on the claim of the master, Art.
IV, § 2. In their declaration of the principles that were to
provide the cornerstone of the new Nation, therefore, the Framers
made it plain that "we the people," for whose protection the
Constitution was designed, did not include those whose skins were
the wrong color. As Professor John Hope Franklin has observed,
Americans
"proudly accepted the challenge and responsibility of their new
political freedom by establishing the machinery and safeguards that
insured the continued enslavement of blacks."
Franklin 100.
The individual States likewise established the machinery to
protect the system of slavery through the promulgation of the Slave
Codes, which were designed primarily to defend the property
interest of the owner in his slave. The position of the Negro slave
as mere property was confirmed by this Court in Dred Scott
v. Sandford , 19 How. 393 (1857), holding that the
Missouri Compromise -- which prohibited slavery in the portion of
the Louisiana Purchase Territory north of Missouri -- was
unconstitutional because it deprived slave owners of their property
without due process. The Court declared that, under the
Constitution, a slave was property, and "[t]he right to traffic in
it, like an ordinary article of merchandise and property, was
guarantied to the citizens of the United Page 438 U. S. 390 States. . . ." Id. at 60 U. S. 451 .
The Court further concluded that Negroes were not intended to be
included as citizens under the Constitution, but were
"regarded as beings of an inferior order . . . altogether unfit
to associate with the white race, either in social or political
relations; and so far inferior that they had no rights which the
white man was bound to respect . . . ." Id. at 60 U. S.
407 . B The status of the Negro as property was officially erased by his
emancipation at the end of the Civil War. But the long-awaited
emancipation, while freeing the Negro from slavery, did not bring
him citizenship or equality in any meaningful way. Slavery was
replaced by a system of
"laws which imposed upon the colored race onerous disabilities
and burdens, and curtailed their rights in the pursuit of life,
liberty, and property to such an extent that their freedom was of
little value." Slaughter-House
Cases , 16 Wall. 36, 83 U. S. 70 (1873). Despite the passage of the Thirteenth, Fourteenth, and
Fifteenth Amendments, the Negro was systematically denied the
rights those Amendments were supposed to secure. The combined
actions and inactions of the State and Federal Governments
maintained Negroes in a position of legal inferiority for another
century after the Civil War.
The Southern States took the first steps to reenslave the
Negroes. Immediately following the end of the Civil War, many of
the provisional legislatures passed Black Codes, similar to the
Slave Codes, which, among other things, limited the rights of
Negroes to own or rent property and permitted imprisonment for
breach of employment contracts. Over the next several decades, the
South managed to disenfranchise the Negroes in spite of the
Fifteenth Amendment by various techniques, including poll taxes,
deliberately complicated balloting processes, property and literacy
qualifications, and, finally, the white primary.
Congress responded to the legal disabilities being imposed Page 438 U. S. 391 in the Southern States by passing the Reconstruction Acts and
the Civil Rights Acts. Congress also responded to the needs of the
Negroes at the end of the Civil War by establishing the Bureau of
Refugees, Freedmen, and Abandoned Lands, better known as the
Freedmen's Bureau, to supply food, hospitals, land, and education
to the newly freed slaves. Thus, for a time, it seemed as if the
Negro might be protected from the continued denial of his civil
rights, and might be relieved of the disabilities that prevented
him from taking his place as a free and equal citizen.
That time, however, was short-lived. Reconstruction came to a
close, and, with the assistance of this Court, the Negro was
rapidly stripped of his new civil rights. In the words of C. Vann
Woodward:
"By narrow and ingenious interpretation [the Supreme Court's]
decisions over a period of years had whittled away a great part of
the authority presumably given the government for protection of
civil rights."
Woodward 139.
The Court began by interpreting the Civil War Amendments in a
manner that sharply curtailed their substantive protections. See, e.g., Slaughter-House Cases, supra; United States v.
Reese, 92 U. S. 214 (1876); United States v. Cruikshank, 92 U. S.
542 (1876). Then, in the notorious Civil Rights
Cases, 109 U. S. 3 (1883),
the Court strangled Congress' efforts to use its power to promote
racial equality. In those cases, the Court invalidated sections of
the Civil Rights Act of 1875 that made it a crime to deny equal
access to "inns, public conveyances, theatres and other places of
public amusement." Id. at 109 U. S. 10 .
According to the Court, the Fourteenth Amendment gave Congress the
power to proscribe only discriminatory action by the State. The
Court ruled that the Negroes who were excluded from public places
suffered only an invasion of their social rights at the hands of
private individuals, and Congress had no power to remedy that. Id. at 109 U. S.
24 -25.
"When a man has emerged from slavery, and, by the aid of
beneficent legislation, has shaken off the inseparable concomitants
of that Page 438 U. S. 392 state,"
the Court concluded,
"there must be some stage in the progress of his elevation when
he takes the rank of a mere citizen, and ceases to be the special
favorite of the laws. . . ." Id. at 109 U. S. 25 . As
Mr. Justice Harlan noted in dissent, however, the Civil War
Amendments and Civil Rights Acts did not make the Negroes the
"special favorite" of the laws, but instead
"sought to accomplish in reference to that race . . . -- what
had already been done in every State of the Union for the white
race -- to secure and protect rights belonging to them as freemen
and citizens; nothing more." Id. at 109 U. S. 61 .
The Court's ultimate blow to the Civil War Amendments and to the
equality of Negroes came in Plessy v. Ferguson, 163 U. S. 537 (1896). In upholding a Louisiana law that required railway
companies to provide "equal but separate" accommodations for whites
and Negroes, the Court held that the Fourteenth Amendment was not
intended
"to abolish distinctions based upon color, or to enforce social,
as distinguished from political, equality, or a commingling of the
two races upon terms unsatisfactory to either." Id. at 163 U. S. 544 .
Ignoring totally the realities of the positions of the two races,
the Court remarked:
"We consider the underlying fallacy of the plaintiff's argument
to consist in the assumption that the enforced separation of the
two races stamps the colored race with a badge of inferiority. If
this be so, it is not by reason of anything found in the act, but
solely because the colored race chooses to put that construction
upon it." Id. at 163 U. S.
551 .
Mr. Justice Harlan's dissenting opinion recognized the
bankruptcy of the Court's reasoning. He noted that the "real
meaning" of the legislation was "that colored citizens are so
inferior and degraded that they cannot be allowed to sit in public
coaches occupied by white citizens." Id. at 163 U. S. 560 .
He expressed his fear that, if like laws were enacted in other Page 438 U. S. 393 States, "the effect would be in the highest degree mischievous." Id. at 163 U. S. 563 .
Although slavery would have disappeared, the States would retain
the power
"to interfere with the full enjoyment of the blessings of
freedom; to regulate civil rights, common to all citizens, upon the
basis of race; and to place in a condition of legal inferiority a
large body of American citizens. . . ." Ibid. The fears of Mr. Justice Harlan were soon to be realized. In the
wake of Plessy, many States expanded their Jim Crow laws,
which had, up until that time, been limited primarily to passenger
trains and schools. The segregation of the races was extended to
residential areas, parks, hospitals, theaters, waiting rooms, and
bathrooms. There were even statutes and ordinances which authorized
separate phone booths for Negroes and whites, which required that
textbooks used by children of one race be kept separate from those
used by the other, and which required that Negro and white
prostitutes be kept in separate districts. In 1898, after Plessy, the Charlestown News and Courier printed a parody
of Jim Crow laws:
"'If there must be Jim Crow cars on the railroads, there should
be Jim Crow cars on the street railways. Also on all passenger
boats. . . . If there are to be Jim Crow cars, moreover, there
should be Jim Crow waiting saloons at all stations, and Jim Crow
eating houses. . . . There should be Jim Crow sections of the jury
box, and a separate Jim Crow dock and witness stand in every court
-- and a Jim Crow Bible for colored witnesses to kiss.'"
Woodward 68. The irony is that, before many years had passed,
with the exception of the Jim Crow witness stand,
"all the improbable applications of the principle suggested by
the editor in derision had been put into practice -- down to and
including the Jim Crow Bible." Id. at 69.
Nor were the laws restricting the rights of Negroes limited Page 438 U. S. 394 solely to the Southern States. In many of the Northern States,
the Negro was denied the right to vote, prevented from serving on
juries, and excluded from theaters, restaurants, hotels, and inns.
Under President Wilson, the Federal Government began to require
segregation in Government buildings; desks of Negro employees were
curtained off; separate bathrooms and separate tables in the
cafeterias were provided; and even the galleries of the Congress
were segregated. When his segregationist policies were attacked,
President Wilson responded that segregation was " not
humiliating, but a benefit,'" and that he was "`rendering [the
Negroes] more safe in their possession of office, and less likely
to be discriminated against.'" Kluger 91. The enforced segregation of the races continued into the middle
of the 20th century. In both World Wars, Negroes were, for the most
part, confined to separate military units; it was not until 1948
that an end to segregation in the military was ordered by President
Truman. And the history of the exclusion of Negro children from
white public schools is too well known and recent to require
repeating here. That Negroes were deliberately excluded from public
graduate and professional schools -- and thereby denied the
opportunity to become doctors, lawyers, engineers, and the like is
also well established. It is, of course, true that some of the Jim
Crow laws (which the decisions of this Court had helped to foster)
were struck down by this Court in a series of decisions leading up
to Brown v. Board of Education, 347 U.
S. 483 (1954). See, e.g., Morgan v. Virginia, 328 U. S. 373 (1946); Sweatt v. Painter, 339 U.
S. 629 (1950); McLaurin v. Oklahoma State
Regents, 339 U. S. 637 (1950). Those decisions, however, did not automatically end
segregation, nor did they move Negroes from a position of legal
inferiority to one of equality. The legacy of years of slavery and
of years of second-class citizenship in the wake of emancipation
could not be so easily eliminated. Page 438 U. S. 395 II The position of the Negro today in America is the tragic but
inevitable consequence of centuries of unequal treatment. Measured
by any benchmark of comfort or achievement, meaningful equality
remains a distant dream for the Negro.
A Negro child today has a life expectancy which is shorter by
more than five years than that of a white child. [ Footnote 4/2 ] The Negro child's mother is over
three times more likely to die of complications in childbirth,
[ Footnote 4/3 ] and the infant
mortality rate for Negroes is nearly twice that for whites.
[ Footnote 4/4 ] The median income of
the Negro family is only 60% that of the median of a white family,
[ Footnote 4/5 ] and the percentage
of Negroes who live in families with incomes below the poverty line
is nearly four times greater than that of whites. [ Footnote 4/6 ]
When the Negro child reaches working age, he finds that America
offers him significantly less than it offers his white counterpart.
For Negro adults, the unemployment rate is twice that of whites,
[ Footnote 4/7 ] and the unemployment
rate for Negro teenagers is nearly three times that of white
teenagers. [ Footnote 4/8 ] A Negro
male who completes four years of college can expect a median annual
income of merely $110 more than a white male who has only a high
school diploma. [ Footnote 4/9 ]
Although Negroes Page 438 U. S. 396 represent 11.5% of the population, [ Footnote 4/10 ] they are only 1.2% of the lawyers and
judges, 2% of the physicians, 2.3% of the dentists, 1.1% of the
engineers and 2.6% of the college and university professors.
[ Footnote 4/11 ]
The relationship between those figures and the history of
unequal treatment afforded to the Negro cannot be denied. At every
point from birth to death, the impact of the past is reflected in
the still disfavored position of the Negro.
In light of the sorry history of discrimination and its
devastating impact on the lives of Negroes, bringing the Negro into
the mainstream of American life should be a state interest of the
highest order. To fail to do so is to ensure that America will
forever remain a divided society. III I do not believe that the Fourteenth Amendment requires us to
accept that fate. Neither its history nor our past cases lend any
support to the conclusion that a university may not remedy the
cumulative effects of society's discrimination by giving
consideration to race in an effort to increase the number and
percentage of Negro doctors. A This Court long ago remarked that
"in any fair and just construction of any section or phrase of
these [Civil War] amendments, it is necessary to look to the
purpose which we have said was the pervading spirit of them all,
the evil which they were designed to remedy. . . ." Slaughter-House Cases, 16 Wall. at 83 U. S. 72 . It
is plain that the Fourteenth Amendment was not intended to prohibit
measures designed to remedy the effects of the Page 438 U. S. 397 Nation's past treatment of Negroes. The Congress that passed the
Fourteenth Amendment is the same Congress that passed the 1866
Freedmen's Bureau Act, an Act that provided many of its benefits
only to Negroes. Act of July 16, 1866, ch. 200, 14 Stat. 173; see supra at 438 U. S. 391 .
Although the Freedmen's Bureau legislation provided aid for
refugees, thereby including white persons within some of the relief
measures, 14 Stat. 174; see also Act of Mar. 3, 1865, ch.
90, 13 Stat. 507, the bill was regarded, to the dismay of many
Congressmen, as "solely and entirely for the freedmen, and to the
exclusion of all other persons. . . ." Cong.Globe, 39th Cong., 1st
Sess., 544 (1866) (remarks of Rep. Taylor). See also id. at 634-635 (remarks of Rep. Ritter); id. at App. 78, 80-81
(remarks of Rep. Chandler). Indeed, the bill was bitterly opposed
on the ground that it "undertakes to make the negro in some
respects . . . superior . . . , and gives them favors that the poor
white boy in the North cannot get." Id. at 401 (remarks of
Sen. McDougall). See also id. at 319 (remarks of Sen.
Hendricks); id. at 362 (remarks of Sen. Saulsbury); id. at 397 (remarks of Sen. Willey); id. at 544
(remarks of Rep. Taylor). The bill's supporters defended it not by
rebutting the claim of special treatment, but by pointing to the
need for such treatment:
"The very discrimination it makes between 'destitute and
suffering' negroes and destitute and suffering white paupers
proceeds upon the distinction that, in the omitted case, civil
rights and immunities are already sufficiently protected by the
possession of political power, the absence of which in the case
provided for necessitates governmental protection." Id. at App. 75 (remarks of Rep. Phelps) .
Despite the objection to the special treatment the bill would
provide for Negroes, it was passed by Congress. Id. at
421, 688. President Johnson vetoed this bill, and also a subsequent
bill that contained some modifications; one of his principal Page 438 U. S. 398 objections to both bills was that they gave special benefits to
Negroes. 8 Messages and Papers of the Presidents 3596, 3599, 3620,
3623 (1897). Rejecting the concerns of the President and the bill's
opponents, Congress overrode the President's second veto.
Cong.Globe, 39th Cong., 1st Sess., 3842, 3850 (1866).
Since the Congress that considered and rejected the objections
to the 1866 Freedmen's Bureau Act concerning special relief to
Negroes also proposed the Fourteenth Amendment, it is inconceivable
that the Fourteenth Amendment was intended to prohibit all
race-conscious relief measures. It
"would be a distortion of the policy manifested in that
amendment, which was adopted to prevent state legislation designed
to perpetuate discrimination on the basis of race or color," Railway Mail Assn. v. Corsi, 326 U. S.
88 , 326 U. S. 94 (1945), to hold that it barred state action to remedy the effects
of that discrimination. Such a result would pervert the intent of
the Framers by substituting abstract equality for the genuine
equality the Amendment was intended to achieve. B As has been demonstrated in our joint opinion, this Court's past
cases establish the constitutionality of race-conscious remedial
measures. Beginning with the school desegregation cases, we
recognized that, even absent a judicial or legislative finding of
constitutional violation, a school board constitutionally could
consider the race of students in making school assignment
decisions. See Swann v. Charlotte-Mecklenburg Board of
Education, 402 U. S. 1 , 402 U. S. 16 (1971); McDaniel v. Barresi, 402 U. S.
39 , 402 U. S. 41 (1971). We noted, moreover, that a
"flat prohibition against assignment of students for the purpose
of creating a racial balance must inevitably conflict with the duty
of school authorities to disestablish dual school systems. As we
have held in Swann, the Constitution does not compel any
particular degree of Page 438 U. S. 399 racial balance or mixing, but when past and continuing
constitutional violations are found, some ratios are likely to be
useful as starting points in shaping a remedy. An absolute
prohibition against use of such a device -- even as a starting
point -- contravenes the implicit command of Green v. County
School Board, 391 U. S. 430 (1968), that all
reasonable methods be available to formulate an effective
remedy." Board of Education v. Swann, 402 U. S.
43 , 402 U. S. 46 (1971). As we have observed, "[a]ny other approach would freeze the status quo that is the very target of all desegregation
processes." McDaniel v. Barresi, supra at 402 U. S.
41 .
Only last Term, in United Jewish Organizations v.
Carey, 430 U. S. 144 (1977), we upheld a New York reapportionment plan that was
deliberately drawn on the basis of race to enhance the electoral
power of Negroes and Puerto Ricans; the plan had the effect of
diluting the electoral strength of the Hasidic Jewish community. We
were willing in UJO to sanction the remedial use of a
racial classification even though it disadvantaged otherwise
"innocent" individuals. In another case last Term, Califano v.
Webster, 430 U. S. 313 (1977), the Court upheld a provision in the Social Security laws
that discriminated against men because its purpose was " the
permissible one of redressing our society's longstanding disparate
treatment of women.'" Id. at 430 U. S. 317 ,
quoting Califano v. Goldfarb, 430 U.
S. 199 , 430 U. S. 209 n. 8 (1977) (plurality opinion). We thus recognized the
permissibility of remedying past societal discrimination through
the use of otherwise disfavored classifications. Nothing in those cases suggests that a university cannot
similarly act to remedy past discrimination. [ Footnote 4/12 ] It is true that, Page 438 U. S. 400 in both UJO and Webster, the use of the
disfavored classification was predicated on legislative or
administrative action, but in neither case had those bodies made
findings that there had been constitutional violations or that the
specific individuals to be benefited had actually been the victims
of discrimination. Rather, the classification in each of those
cases was based on a determination that the group was in need of
the remedy because of some type of past discrimination. There is
thus ample support for the conclusion that a university can employ
race-conscious measures to remedy past societal discrimination
without the need for a finding that those benefited were actually
victims of that discrimination. IV While I applaud the judgment of the Court that a university may
consider race in its admissions process, it is more than a little
ironic that, after several hundred years of class-based
discrimination against Negroes, the Court is unwilling to hold that
a class-based remedy for that discrimination is permissible. In
declining to so hold, today's judgment ignores the fact that. for
several hundred years, Negroes have been discriminated against not
as individuals, but rather solely because of the color of their
skins. It is unnecessary in 20th-century America to have individual
Negroes demonstrate that they have been victims of racial
discrimination; the racism of our society has been so pervasive
that none, regardless of wealth or position, has managed to escape
its impact. The experience of Negroes in America has been different
in kind, not just in degree, from that of other ethnic groups. It
is not merely the history of slavery alone, but also that a whole
people were marked as inferior by the law. And that mark has
endured. The dream of America as the great melting pot has Page 438 U. S. 401 not been realized for the Negro; because of his skin color, he
never even made it into the pot.
These differences in the experience of the Negro make it
difficult for me to accept that Negroes cannot be afforded greater
protection under the Fourteenth Amendment where it is necessary to
remedy the effects of past discrimination. In the Civil Rights
Cases, supra, the Court wrote that the Negro emerging from
slavery must cease "to be the special favorite of the laws." 109
U.S. at 109 U. S. 25 ; see supra at 438 U. S. 392 .
We cannot, in light of the history of the last century, yield to
that view. Had the Court, in that decision and others, been willing
to
"do for human liberty and the fundamental rights of American
citizenship what it did . . . for the protection of slavery and the
rights of the masters of fugitive slaves,"
109 U.S. at 109 U. S. 53 (Harlan, J., dissenting), we would not need now to permit the
recognition of any "special wards."
Most importantly, had the Court been willing in 1896, in Plessy v. Ferguson, to hold that the Equal Protection
Clause forbids differences in treatment based on race, we would not
be faced with this dilemma in 1978. We must remember, however, that
the principle that the "Constitution is colorblind" appeared only
in the opinion of the lone dissenter. 163 U.S. at 163 U. S. 559 .
The majority of the Court rejected the principle of color
blindness, and for the next 60 years, from Plessy to Brown v. Board of Education, ours was a Nation where, by
law, an individual could be given "special" treatment based on the
color of his skin.
It is because of a legacy of unequal treatment that we now must
permit the institutions of this society to give consideration to
race in making decisions about who will hold the positions of
influence, affluence, and prestige in America. For far too long,
the doors to those positions have been shut to Negroes. If we are
ever to become a fully integrated society, one in which the color
of a person's skin will not determine the opportunities available
to him or her, we must be willing Page 438 U. S. 402 to take steps to open those doors. I do not believe that anyone
can truly look into America's past and still find that a remedy for
the effects of that past is impermissible.
It has been said that this case involves only the individual,
Bakke, and this University. I doubt, however, that there is a
computer capable of determining the number of persons and
institutions that may be affected by the decision in this case. For
example, we are told by the Attorney General of the United States
that at least 27 federal agencies have adopted regulations
requiring recipients of federal funds to take
"' affirmative action to overcome the effects of
conditions which resulted in limiting participation . . . by
persons of a particular race, color, or national origin.'"
Supplemental Brief for United States as Amicus Curiae 16 (emphasis added). I cannot even guess the number of state and
local governments that have set up affirmative action programs,
which may be affected by today's decision.
I fear that we have come full circle. After the Civil War, our
Government started several "affirmative action" programs. This
Court, in the Civil Rights Cases and Plessy v.
Ferguson, destroyed the movement toward complete equality. For
almost a century, no action was taken, and this nonaction was with
the tacit approval of the courts. Then we had Brown v. Board of
Education and the Civil Rights Acts of Congress, followed by
numerous affirmative action programs. Now, we have this Court again
stepping in, this time to stop affirmative action programs of the
type used by the University of California.
[ Footnote 4/1 ]
The history recounted here is perhaps too well known to require
documentation. But I must acknowledge the authorities on which I
rely in retelling it. J. Franklin, From Slavery to Freedom (4th
ed.1974) (hereinafter Franklin); R. Kluger, Simple Justice (1975)
(hereinafter Kluger); C. Woodward, The Strange Career of Jim Crow
(3d ed.1974) (hereinafter Woodward).
[ Footnote 4/2 ]
U.S. Dept. of Commerce, Bureau of the Census, Statistical
Abstract of the United States 65 (1977) (Table 94).
[ Footnote 4/3 ] Id. at 70 (Table 102) .
[ Footnote 4/4 ] Ibid. [ Footnote 4/5 ]
U.S. Dept. of Commerce, Bureau of the Census, Current Population
Reports, Series P-60, No. 107, p. 7 (1977) (Table 1).
[ Footnote 4/6 ] Id. at 20 (Table 14).
[ Footnote 4/7 ]
U.S. Dept. of Labor, Bureau of Labor Statistics, Employment and
Earnings, January, 1978, p. 170 (Table 44).
[ Footnote 4/8 ] Ibid. [ Footnote 4/9 ]
U.S. Dept. of Commerce, Bureau of the Census, Current Population
Reports, Series P-60, No. 105, p. 198 (1977) (Table 47).
[ Footnote 4/10 ]
U.S. Dept. of Commerce, Bureau of the Census, Statistical
Abstract, supra, at 25 (Table 24).
[ Footnote 4/11 ] Id. at 407-408 (Table 662) (based on 1970 census).
[ Footnote 4/12 ]
Indeed, the action of the University finds support in the
regulations promulgated under Title VI by the Department of Health,
Education, and Welfare and approved by the President, which
authorize a federally funded institution to take affirmative steps
to overcome past discrimination against groups even where the
institution was not guilty of prior discrimination. 45 CFR §
80.3(b)(6)(ii) (1977).
MR. JUSTICE BLACKMUN.
I participate fully, of course, in the opinion, ante p. 438 U. S. 324 ,
that bears the names of my Brothers BRENNAN, WHITE, MARSHALL, and
myself. I add only some general observations that hold particular
significance for me, and then a few comments on equal
protection. Page 438 U. S. 403 I At least until the early 1970's, apparently only a very small
number, less than 2%, of the physicians, attorneys, and medical and
law students in the United States were members of what we now refer
to as minority groups. In addition, approximately three-fourths of
our Negro physicians were trained at only two medical schools. If
ways are not found to remedy that situation, the country can never
achieve its professed goal of a society that is not
race-conscious.
I yield to no one in my earnest hope that the time will come
when an "affirmative action" program is unnecessary and is, in
truth, only a relic of the past. I would hope that we could reach
this stage within a decade, at the most. But the story of Brown
v. Board of Education, 347 U. S. 483 (1954), decided almost a quarter of a century ago, suggests that
that hope is a slim one. At some time, however, beyond any period
of what some would claim is only transitional inequality, the
United States must and will reach a stage of maturity where action
along this line is no longer necessary. Then persons will be
regarded as persons, and discrimination of the type we address
today will be an ugly feature of history that is instructive, but
that is behind us.
The number of qualified, indeed highly qualified, applicants for
admission to existing medical schools in the United States far
exceeds the number of places available. Wholly apart from racial
and ethnic considerations, therefore, the selection process
inevitably results in the denial of admission to many qualified
persons, indeed, to far more than the number of those who are
granted admission. Obviously, it is a denial to the deserving. This
inescapable fact is brought into sharp focus here because Allan
Bakke is not himself charged with discrimination, and yet is the
one who is disadvantaged, and because the Medical School of the
University of California at Davis itself is not charged with
historical discrimination.
One theoretical solution to the need for more minority Page 438 U. S. 404 members in higher education would be to enlarge our graduate
schools. Then all who desired and were qualified could enter, and
talk of discrimination would vanish. Unfortunately, this is neither
feasible nor realistic. The vast resources that apparently would be
required simply are not available. And the need for more
professional graduates, in the strict numerical sense, perhaps has
not been demonstrated at all.
There is no particular or real significance in the 84-16
division at Davis. The same theoretical, philosophical, social,
legal, and constitutional considerations would necessarily apply to
the case if Davis' special admissions program had focused on any
lesser number, that is, on 12 or 8 or 4 places or, indeed, on only
1.
It is somewhat ironic to have us so deeply disturbed over a
program where race is an element of consciousness, and yet to be
aware of the fact, as we are, that institutions of higher learning,
albeit more on the undergraduate than the graduate level, have
given conceded preferences up to a point to those possessed of
athletic skills, to the children of alumni, to the affluent who may
bestow their largess on the institutions, and to those having
connections with celebrities, the famous, and the powerful.
Programs of admission to institutions of higher learning are
basically a responsibility for academicians and for administrators
and the specialists they employ. The judiciary, in contrast, is
ill-equipped and poorly trained for this. The administration and
management of educational institutions are beyond the competence of
judges and are within the special competence of educators, provided
always that the educators perform within legal and constitutional
bounds. For me, therefore, interference by the judiciary must be
the rare exception, and not the rule. II I, of course, accept the propositions that (a) Fourteenth
Amendment rights are personal; (b) racial and ethnic
distinctions, Page 438 U. S. 405 where they are stereotypes, are inherently suspect and call for
exacting judicial scrutiny; (c) academic freedom is a special
concern of the First Amendment; and (d) the Fourteenth Amendment
has expanded beyond its original 1868 concept, and now is
recognized to have reached a point where, as MR. JUSTICE POWELL
states, ante at 438 U. S. 293 ,
quoting from the Court's opinion in McDonald v. Santa Fe Trail
Transp. Co., 427 U. S. 273 , 427 U. S. 296 (1976), it embraces a "broader principle."
This enlargement does not mean for me, however, that the
Fourteenth Amendment has broken away from its moorings and its
original intended purposes. Those original aims persist. And that,
in a distinct sense, is what "affirmative action," in the face of
proper facts, is all about. If this conflicts with idealistic
equality, that tension is original Fourteenth Amendment tension,
constitutionally conceived and constitutionally imposed, and it is
part of the Amendment's very nature until complete equality is
achieved in the area. In this sense, constitutional equal
protection is a shield.
I emphasize in particular that the decided cases are not easily
to be brushed aside. Many, of course, are not precisely on point,
but neither are they off point. Racial factors have been given
consideration in the school desegregation cases, in the employment
cases, in Lau v. Nichols, 414 U.
S. 563 (1974), and in United Jewish Organizations v.
Carey, 430 U. S. 144 (1977). To be sure, some of these may be "distinguished" on the
ground that victimization was directly present. But who is to say
that victimization is not present for some members of today's
minority groups, although it is of a lesser and perhaps different
degree. The petitioners in United Jewish Organizations certainly complained bitterly of their reapportionment treatment,
and I rather doubt that they regard the "remedy" there imposed as
one that was "to improve" the group's ability to participate, as
MR. JUSTICE POWELL describes it, ante at 438 U. S. 305 .
And surely. in Lau v. Nichols, we looked to ethnicity. Page 438 U. S. 406 I am not convinced, as MR. JUSTICE POWELL seems to be, that the
difference between the Davis program and the one employed by
Harvard is very profound, or constitutionally significant. The line
between the two is a thin and indistinct one. In each, subjective
application is at work. Because of my conviction that admission
programs are primarily for the educators, I am willing to accept
the representation that the Harvard program is one where good faith
in its administration is practiced, as well as professed. I agree
that such a program, where race or ethnic background is only one of
many factors, is a program better formulated than Davis' two-track
system. The cynical, of course, may say that, under a program such
as Harvard's, one may accomplish covertly what Davis concedes it
does openly. I need not go that far, for, despite its two-track
aspect, the Davis program, for me, is within constitutional bounds,
though perhaps barely so. It is surely free of stigma, and, as in United Jewish Organizations, I am not willing to infer a
constitutional violation.
It is worth noting, perhaps, that governmental preference has
not been a stranger to our legal life. We see it in veterans'
preferences. We see it in the aid-to-the-handicapped programs. We
see it in the progressive income tax. We see it in the Indian
programs. We may excuse some of these on the ground that they have
specific constitutional protection or, as with Indians, that those
benefited are wards of the Government. Nevertheless, these
preferences exist, and may not be ignored. And in the admissions
field, as I have indicated, educational institutions have always
used geography, athletic ability, anticipated financial largess,
alumni pressure, and other factors of that kind.
I add these only as additional components on the edges of the
central question as to which I join my Brothers BRENNAN, WHITE, and
MARSHALL in our more general approach. It is gratifying to know
that the Court at least finds it constitutional for an academic
institution to take race and ethnic background into consideration
as one factor, among many, in Page 438 U. S. 407 the administration of its admissions program. I presume that
that factor always has been there, though perhaps not conceded or
even admitted. It is a fact of life, however, and a part of the
real world of which we are all a part. The sooner we get down the
road toward accepting and being a part of the real world, and not
shutting it out and away from us, the sooner will these
difficulties vanish from the scene.
I suspect that it would be impossible to arrange an affirmative
action program in a racially neutral way and have it successful. To
ask that this be so is to demand the impossible. In order to get
beyond racism, we must first take account of race. There is no
other way. And in order to treat some persons equally, we must
treat them differently. We cannot -- we dare not -- let the Equal
Protection Clause perpetuate racial supremacy.
So the ultimate question, as it was at the beginning of this
litigation, is: among the qualified, how does one choose?
A long time ago, as time is measured for this Nation, a Chief
Justice, both wise and far-sighted, said:
"In considering this question, then, we must never forget, that
it is a constitution we are expounding." McCulloch v.
Maryland , 4 Wheat. 316, 17 U. S. 407 (1819) (emphasis in original). In the same opinion, the Great Chief
Justice further observed:
"Let the end be legitimate, let it be within the scope of the
constitution, and all means which are appropriate, which are
plainly adapted to that end, which are not prohibited, but consist
with the letter and spirit of the constitution, are
constitutional." Id. at 17 U. S. 421 .
More recently, one destined to become a Justice of this Court
observed:
"The great generalities of the constitution have a content and a
significance that vary from age to age."
B. Cardozo, The Nature of the Judicial Process 17 (1921). Page 438 U. S. 408 And an educator who became a President of the United States
said:
"But the Constitution of the United States is not a mere
lawyers' document: it is a vehicle of life, and its spirit is
always the spirit of the age."
W. Wilson, Constitutional Government in the United States 69
(1911).
These precepts of breadth and flexibility and ever-present
modernity are basic to our constitutional law. Today, again, we are
expounding a Constitution. The same principles that governed
McCulloch's case in 1819 govern Bakke's case in 1978. There can be
no other answer.
MR. JUSTICE STEVENS, with whom THE CHIEF JUSTICE, MR. JUSTICE
STEWART, and MR. JUSTICE REHNQUIST join, concurring in the judgment
in part and dissenting in part.
It is always important at the outset to focus precisely on the
controversy before the Court. [ Footnote
5/1 ] It is particularly important to do so in this case,
because correct identification of the issues will determine whether
it is necessary or appropriate to express any opinion about the
legal status of any admissions program other than petitioner's. I This is not a class action. The controversy is between two
specific litigants. Allan Bakke challenged petitioner's special
admissions program, claiming that it denied him a place in medical
school because of his race in violation of the Federal and
California Constitutions and of Title VI of the Civil Rights Act of
1964, 42 U.S.C. § 2000d et seq. The California Supreme
Court upheld his challenge and ordered him admitted. If the Page 438 U. S. 409 state court was correct in its view that the University's
special program was illegal, and that Bakke was therefore
unlawfully excluded from the Medical School because of his race, we
should affirm its judgment, regardless of our views about the
legality of admissions programs that are not now before the
Court.
The judgment as originally entered by the trial court contained
four separate paragraphs, two of which are of critical importance.
[ Footnote 5/2 ] Paragraph 3 declared
that the University's special admissions program violated the
Fourteenth Amendment, the State Constitution, and Title VI. The
trial court did not order the University to admit Bakke, because it
concluded that Bakke had not shown that he would have been admitted
if there had been no special program. Instead, in paragraph 2 of
its judgment, it ordered the University to consider Bakke's
application for admission without regard to his race or the race of
any other applicant. The order did not include any broad Page 438 U. S. 410 prohibition against any use of race in the admissions process;
its terms were clearly limited to the University's consideration of
Bakke's application. [ Footnote 5/3 ]
Because the University has since been ordered to admit Bakke,
paragraph 2 of the trial court's order no longer has any
significance.
The California Supreme Court, in a holding that is not
challenged, ruled that the trial court incorrectly placed the
burden on Bakke of showing that he would have been admitted in the
absence of discrimination. The University then conceded "that it
[could] not meet the burden of proving that the special admissions
program did not result in Mr. Bakke's failure to be admitted."
[ Footnote 5/4 ] Accordingly, the
California Supreme Court directed the trial court to enter judgment
ordering Bakke's admission. [ Footnote
5/5 ] Since that order superseded paragraph Page 438 U. S. 411 2 of the trial court's judgment, there is no outstanding
injunction forbidding any consideration of racial criteria in
processing applications.
It is therefore perfectly clear that the question whether race
can ever be used as a factor in an admissions decision is not an
issue in this case, and that discussion of that issue is
inappropriate. [ Footnote 5/6 ] II Both petitioner and respondent have asked us to determine the
legality of the University's special admissions program by
reference to the Constitution. Our settled practice, however, is to
avoid the decision of a constitutional issue if a case can be
fairly decided on a statutory ground.
"If there is one doctrine more deeply rooted than any other in
the process of constitutional adjudication, it is that we ought not
to pass on questions of constitutionality . . . unless such
adjudication is unavoidable." Spector Motor Co. v. McLaughlin, 323 U.
S. 101 , 323 U. S. 105 .
[ Footnote 5/7 ] The more important
the issue, the more force Page 438 U. S. 412 there is to this doctrine. [ Footnote
5/8 ] In this case, we are presented with a constitutional
question of undoubted and unusual importance. Since, however, a
dispositive statutory claim was raised at the very inception of
this case, and squarely decided in the portion of the trial court
judgment affirmed by the California Supreme Court, it is our plain
duty to confront it. Only if petitioner should prevail on the
statutory issue would it be necessary to decide whether the
University's admissions program violated the Equal Protection
Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment. III Section 601 of the Civil Rights Act of 1964, 78 Stat. 252, 42
U.S.C. § 2000d, provides:
"No person in the United States shall, on the ground of race,
color, or national origin, be excluded from participation in, be
denied the benefits of, or be subjected to discrimination under any
program or activity receiving Federal financial assistance."
The University, through its special admissions policy, excluded
Bakke from participation in its program of medical education
because of his race. The University also acknowledges that it was,
and still is, receiving federal financial assistance. [ Footnote 5/9 ] The plain language of the
statute therefore requires affirmance of the judgment below. A
different result Page 438 U. S. 413 cannot be justified unless that language misstates the actual
intent of the Congress that enacted the statute or the statute is
not enforceable in a private action. Neither conclusion is
warranted.
Title VI is an integral part of the far-reaching Civil Rights
Act of 1964. No doubt, when this legislation was being debated,
Congress was not directly concerned with the legality of "reverse
discrimination" or "affirmative action" programs. Its attention was
focused on the problem at hand, the "glaring . . . discrimination
against Negroes which exists throughout our Nation," [ Footnote 5/10 ] and, with respect to Title
VI, the federal funding of segregated facilities. [ Footnote 5/11 ] The genesis of the legislation,
however, did not limit the breadth of the solution adopted. Just as
Congress responded to the problem of employment discrimination by
enacting a provision that protects all races, see McDonald v.
Santa Fe Trail Transp. Co., 427 U. S. 273 , 427 U. S. 279 ,
[ Footnote 5/12 ] so, too, its
answer to the problem of federal funding of segregated facilities
stands as a broad prohibition against the exclusion of any individual from a federally funded program "on the ground of race."
In the words of the House Report, Title VI stands for
"the general principle that no person . . . be excluded
from participation . . . on the ground of race, color, or national
origin under any program or activity receiving Federal financial
assistance."
H.R.Rep. No. 914, 88th Page 438 U. S. 414 Cong., 1st Sess, pt. l, p. 25 (1963) (emphasis added). This same
broad view of Title VI and § 601 was echoed throughout the
congressional debate and was stressed by every one of the major
spokesmen for the Act. [ Footnote
5/13 ]
Petitioner contends, however, that exclusion of applicants on
the basis of race does not violate Title VI if the exclusion
carries with it no racial stigma. No such qualification or
limitation of § 601's categorical prohibition of "exclusion" is
justified by the statute or its history. The language of the entire
section is perfectly clear; the words that follow "excluded from"
do not modify or qualify the explicit outlawing of any exclusion on
the stated grounds.
The legislative history reinforces this reading. The only
suggestion that § 601 would allow exclusion of nonminority
applicants came from opponents of the legislation, and then only by
way of a discussion of the meaning of the word "discrimination."
[ Footnote 5/14 ] The opponents
feared that the term "discrimination" Page 438 U. S. 415 would be read as mandating racial quotas and "racially balanced"
colleges and universities, and they pressed for a specific
definition of the term in order to avoid this possibility.
[ Footnote 5/15 ] In response, the
proponents of the legislation gave repeated assurances that the Act
would be "colorblind" in its application. [ Footnote 5/16 ] Senator Humphrey, the Senate floor
manager for the Act, expressed this position as follows:
"[T]he word 'discrimination' has been used in many a court case.
What it really means in the bill is a distinction in treatment . .
. given to different individuals because of their different race,
religion or national origin. . . ."
"The answer to this question [what was meant by
'discrimination'] is that if race is not a factor, we do not have
to worry about discrimination because of race. . . . The Internal
Revenue Code does not provide that colored people do not have to
pay taxes, or that they can pay their taxes 6 months later than
everyone else."
110 Cong.Rec. 5864 (1964).
"[I]f we started to treat Americans as Americans, not as fat
ones, thin ones, short ones, tall ones, brown ones, green ones,
yellow ones, or white ones, but as Americans. If we did that, we
would not need to worry about discrimination." Id. at 5866. Page 438 U. S. 416 In giving answers such as these, it seems clear that the
proponents of Title VI assumed that the Constitution itself
required a colorblind standard on the part of government, [ Footnote 5/17 ] but that does not mean
that the legislation only codifies an existing constitutional
prohibition. The statutory prohibition against discrimination in
federally funded projects contained in § 601 is more than a simple
paraphrasing of what the Fifth or Fourteenth Amendment would
require. The Act's proponents plainly considered Title VI
consistent with their view of the Constitution, and they sought to
provide an effective weapon to implement that view. [ Footnote 5/18 ] As a distillation of what
the supporters of the Act believed the Constitution demanded of
State and Federal Governments, § 601 has independent force, with
language and emphasis in addition to that found in the
Constitution. [ Footnote 5/19 ] Page 438 U. S. 417 As with other provisions of the Civil Rights Act, Congress'
expression of it policy to end racial discrimination may
independently proscribe conduct that the Constitution does not.
[ Footnote 5/20 ] However, we need
not decide the congruence -- or lack of congruence -- of the
controlling statute and the Constitution Page 438 U. S. 418 since the meaning of the Title VI ban on exclusion is crystal
clear: race cannot be the basis of excluding anyone from
participation in a federally funded program.
In short, nothing in the legislative history justifies the
conclusion that the broad language of § 601 should not be given its
natural meaning. We are dealing with a distinct statutory
prohibition, enacted at a particular time with particular concerns
in mind; neither its language nor any prior interpretation suggests
that its place in the Civil Rights Act, won after long debate, is
simply that of a constitutional appendage. [ Footnote 5/21 ] In unmistakable terms, the Act prohibits
the exclusion of individuals from federally funded programs because
of their race. [ Footnote 5/22 ] As
succinctly phrased during the Senate debate, under Title VI, it is
not "permissible to say yes' to one person, but to say `no' to
another person, only because of the color of his skin." [ Footnote 5/23 ] Belatedly, however, petitioner argues that Title VI cannot be
enforced by a private litigant. The claim is unpersuasive in the
context of this case. Bakke requested injunctive and declaratory
relief under Title VI; petitioner itself then joined Page 438 U. S. 419 issue on the question of the legality of its program under Title
VI by asking for a declaratory judgment that it was in compliance
with the statute. [ Footnote 5/24 ]
Its view during state court litigation was that a private cause of
action does exist under Title VI. Because petitioner questions the
availability of a private cause of action for the first time in
this Court, the question is not properly before us. See
McGoldrick v. Companie Generale Transatlantique, 309 U.
S. 430 , 309 U. S. 434 .
Even if it were, petitioner's original assumption is in accord with
the federal courts' consistent interpretation of the Act. To date,
the courts, including this Court, have unanimously concluded or
assumed that a private action may be maintained under Title VI.
[ Footnote 5/25 ] The United States
has taken the same position; in its amicus curiae brief
directed to this specific issue, it concluded that such a remedy is
clearly available, [ Footnote
5/26 ] Page 438 U. S. 420 and Congress has repeatedly enacted legislation predicated on
the assumption that Title VI may be enforced in a private action.
[ Footnote 5/27 ] The conclusion
that an individual may maintain a private cause of action is amply
supported in the legislative history of Title VI itself. [ Footnote 5/28 ] In short, a fair
consideration of Page 438 U. S. 421 petitioner's tardy attack on the propriety of Bakke's suit under
Title VI requires that it be rejected.
The University's special admissions program violated Title VI of
the Civil Rights Act of 1964 by excluding Bakke from the Medical
School because of his race. It is therefore our duty to affirm the
judgment ordering Bakke admitted to the University.
Accordingly, I concur in the Court's judgment insofar as it
affirms the judgment of the Supreme Court of California. To the
extent that it purports to do anything else, I respectfully
dissent.
[ Footnote 5/1 ]
Four Members of the Court have undertaken to announce the legal
and constitutional effect of this Court's judgment. See opinion of JUSTICES BRENNAN, WHITE, MARSHALL, and BLACKMUN, ante at 438 U. S.
324 -325. It is hardly necessary to state that only a
majority can speak for the Court or determine what is the "central
meaning" of any judgment of the Court.
[ Footnote 5/2 ]
The judgment first entered by the trial court read, in its
entirety, as follows:
"IT IS HEREBY ORDERED, ADJUDGED AND DECREED:"
"1. Defendant, the Regents of the University of California, have
judgment against plaintiff, Allan Bakke, denying the mandatory
injunction requested by plaintiff ordering his admission to the
University of California at Davis Medical School;"
"2. That plaintiff is entitled to have his application for
admission to the medical school considered without regard to his
race or the race of any other applicant, and defendants are hereby
restrained and enjoined from considering plaintiff's race or the
race of any other applicant in passing upon his application for
admission;"
"3. Cross-defendant Allan Bakke have judgment against
cross-complaint, the Regents of the University of California,
declaring that the special admissions program at the University of
California at Davis Medical School violates the Fourteenth
Amendment to the United States Constitution, Article 1, Section 21
of the California Constitution, and the Federal Civil Rights Act
[42 U.S.C. § 2000d];"
"4. That plaintiff have and recover his court costs incurred
herein in the sum of $217.35."
App. to Pet. for Cert. 120a.
[ Footnote 5/3 ]
In paragraph 2, the trial court ordered that
"plaintiff [Bakke] is entitled to have his application for
admission to the medical school considered without regard to his
race or the race of any other applicant, and defendants are hereby
restrained and enjoined from considering plaintiff's race or the
race of any other applicant in passing upon his application for admission." See 438
U.S. 265 fn5/2|>n. 2, supra, (emphasis added). The
only way in which this order can be broadly read as prohibiting any
use of race in the admissions process, apart from Bakke's
application, is if the final "his" refers to "any other applicant."
But the consistent use of the pronoun throughout the paragraph to
refer to Bakke makes such a reading entirely unpersuasive, as does
the failure of the trial court to suggest that it was issuing
relief to applicants who were not parties to the suit.
[ Footnote 5/4 ]
Appendix B to Application for Stay A19-A20.
[ Footnote 5/5 ] 18 Cal. 3d 34 ,
64, 553 P.2d 1152, 1172 (1976). The judgment of the Supreme Court
of the State of California affirms only paragraph 3 of the trial
court's judgment. The Supreme Court's judgment reads as
follows:
"IT IS ORDERED, ADJUDGED, AND DECREED by the Court that the
judgment of the Superior Court[,] County of Yolo[,] in the
above-entitled cause, is hereby affirmed insofar as it determines
that the special admission program is invalid; the judgment is
reversed insofar as it denies Bakke an injunction ordering that he
be admitted to the University, and the trial court is directed to
enter judgment ordering Bakke to be admitted. 'Bakke shall recover
his costs on these appeals.'"
[ Footnote 5/6 ]
"This Court . . . reviews judgments, not statements in
opinions." Black v. Cutter Laboratories, 351 U.
S. 292 , 351 U. S.
297 .
[ Footnote 5/7 ]
"From Hayburn's Case , 2 Dall. 409,
to Alma
Motor Co. v. Timken-Detroit Axle Co. [, 329 U. S.
129 ,] and the Hatch Act case \[United Public Workers v.
Mitchell , 330 U. S. 75 ,] decided this term,
this Court has followed a policy of strict necessity in disposing
of constitutional issues. The earliest exemplifications, too well
known for repeating the history here, arose in the Court's refusal
to render advisory opinions and in applications of the related
jurisdictional policy drawn from the case and controversy
limitation. U.S.Const., Art. III. . . ."
"The policy, however, has not been limited to jurisdictional
determinations. For, in addition,"
"the Court [has] developed, for its own governance in the cases
confessedly within its jurisdiction, a series of rules under which
it has avoided passing upon a large part of all the constitutional
questions pressed upon it for decision."
"Thus, as those rules were listed in support of the statement
quoted, constitutional issues affecting legislation will not be
determined in friendly, nonadversary proceedings; in advance of the
necessity of deciding them; in broader terms than are required by
the precise facts to which the ruling is to be applied; if the
record presents some other ground upon which the case may be
disposed of; at the instance of one who fails to show that he is
injured by the statute's operation, or who has availed himself of
its benefits; or if a construction of the statute is fairly
possible by which the question may be avoided." Rescue Army v. Municipal Court, 331 U.
S. 549 , 331 U. S.
568 -569 (footnotes omitted). See also Ashwander v.
TVA, 297 U. S. 288 , 297 U. S.
346 -348 (Brandeis, J., concurring).
[ Footnote 5/8 ]
The doctrine reflects both our respect for the Constitution as
an enduring set of principles and the deference we owe to the
Legislative and Executive Branches of Government in developing
solutions to complex social problems. See A. Bickel, The
Least Dangerous Branch 131 (1962).
[ Footnote 5/9 ]
Record 29.
[ Footnote 5/10 ]
H.R.Rep. No. 914, 88th Cong., 1st Sess., pt. 1, p. 18
(1963).
[ Footnote 5/11 ]
It is apparent from the legislative history that the immediate
object of Title VI was to prevent federal funding of segregated
facilities. See, e.g., 110 Cong.Rec. 1521 (1964) (remarks
of Rep. Celler); id. at 6544 (remarks of Sen.
Humphrey).
[ Footnote 5/12 ]
In McDonald v. Santa Fe Trail Transp. Co., the Court
held that "Title VII prohibits racial discrimination against . . .
white petitioners . . . upon the same standards as would be
applicable were they Negroes. . . ." 427 U.S. at 427 U. S. 280 .
Quoting from our earlier decision in Griggs v Duke Power
Co., 401 U. S. 424 , 401 U. S. 431 ,
the Court reaffirmed the principle that the statute "prohibit[s] [d]iscriminatory preference for any [racial] group, minority or majority. '" 427 U.S. at 427 U. S. 279 (emphasis in original). [ Footnote 5/13 ] See, e.g., 110 Cong.Rec. 1520 (1964) (remarks of Rep.
Celler); id. at 5864 (remarks of Sen. Humphrey); id. at 6561 (remarks of Sen. Kuchel); id. at 7055
(remarks of Sen. Pastore). (Representative Celler and Senators
Humphrey and Kuchel were the House and Senate floor managers for
the entire Civil Rights Act, and Senator Pastore was the majority
Senate floor manager for Title VI.)
[ Footnote 5/14 ]
Representative Abernethy's comments were typical:
"Title VI has been aptly described as the most harsh and
unprecedented proposal contained in the bill. . . . "
"It is aimed toward eliminating discrimination in federally
assisted programs. It contains no guideposts and no yardsticks as
to what might constitute discrimination in carrying out federally
aided programs and projects. . . ."
" * * * *" "Presumably, the college would have to have a 'racially
balanced' staff from the dean's office to the cafeteria. . . ."
"The effect of this title, if enacted into law, will interject
race as a factor in every decision involving the selection of an
individual. . . . The concept of 'racial imbalance' would hover
like a black cloud over every transaction. . . ." Id. at 1619. See also, e.g., id. at 5611-5613
(remarks of Sen. Ervin); id. at 9083 (remarks of Sen.
Gore).
[ Footnote 5/15 ] E.g., id. at 5863, 5874 (remarks of Sen. Eastland).
[ Footnote 5/16 ] See, e.g., id. at 8364 (remarks off Sen. Proxmire)
("Taxes are collected from whites and Negroes, and they should be
expended without discrimination"); id. at 7055 (remarks of
Sen. Pastore) ("[Title VI] will guarantee that the money collected
by colorblind tax collectors will be distributed Federal and State
administrators who are equally colorblind"); and id. at
6543 (remarks of Sen. Humphrey) (" Simple justice requires that
public funds, to which all taxpayers of all races contribute, not
be spent in any fashion which encourages, entrenches, subsidizes,
or results in racial discrimination'") (quoting from President
Kennedy's Message to Congress, June 19, 1963). [ Footnote 5/17 ] See, e.g., 110 Cong.Rec. 5253 (1964) (remarks of Sen.
Humphrey); and id. at 7102 (remarks of Sen. Javits). The
parallel between the prohibitions of Title VI and those of the
Constitution was clearest with respect to the immediate goal of the
Act -- an end to federal funding of "separate but equal"
facilities.
[ Footnote 5/18 ]
"As in Monroe \[v. Pape , 365 U. S.
167 ], we have no occasion here to"
"reach the constitutional question whether Congress has the
power to make municipalities liable for acts of its officers that
violate the civil rights of individuals."
"365 U.S. at 365 U. S. 191 . For in
interpreting the statute, it is not our task to consider whether
Congress was mistaken in 1871 in its view of the limit of its power
over municipalities; rather, we must construe the statute in light
of the impressions under which Congress did, in fact, act, see
Ries v. Lynskey, 452 F.2d at 175." Moor v. County of Alameda, 411 U.
S. 693 , 411 U. S.
709 .
[ Footnote 5/19 ]
Both Title VI and Title VII express Congress' belief that, in
the long struggle to eliminate social prejudice and the effects of
prejudice, the principle of individual equality, without regard to
race or religion, was one on which there could be a "meeting of the
minds" among all races and a common national purpose. See Los
Angeles Dept. of Water & Power v. Manhart, 435 U.
S. 702 , 435 U. S. 709 ("[T]he basic policy of the statute [Title VII] requires that we
focus on fairness to individuals, rather than fairness to
classes"). This same principle of individual fairness is embodied
in Title VI.
"The basic fairness of title VI is so clear that I find it
difficult to understand why it should create any opposition. . .
."
" * * * *" "Private prejudices, to be sure, cannot be eliminated overnight.
However, there is one area where no room at all exists for private
prejudices. That is the area of governmental conduct. As the first
Mr. Justice Harlan said in his prophetic dissenting opinion in Plessy v. Ferguson, 163 U. S. 537 , 163 U. S.
559 :"
"Our Constitution is color-blind."
"So -- I say to Senators -- must be our Government. . . ."
"Title VI closes the gap between our purposes as a democracy and
our prejudices as individuals. The cuts of prejudice need healing.
The costs of prejudice need understanding. We cannot have hostility
between two great parts of our people without tragic loss in our
human values. . . . "
"Title VI offers a place for the meeting of our minds as to
Federal money."
110 Cong.Rec. 7063-7064 (1964) (remarks of Sen. Pastore). Of
course, one of the reasons marshaled in support of the conclusion
that Title VI was "noncontroversial" was that its prohibition was
already reflected in the law. See ibid. (remarks of Sen.
Pell and Sen. Pastore).
[ Footnote 5/20 ]
For example, private employers now under duties imposed by Title
VII were wholly free from the restraints imposed by the Fifth and
Fourteenth Amendments which are directed only to governmental
action.
In Lau v. Nichols, 414 U. S. 563 , the
Government's brief stressed that
"the applicability of Title VI . . . does not depend upon the
outcome of the equal protection analysis. . . . [T]he statute
independently proscribes the conduct challenged by petitioners, and
provides a discrete basis for injunctive relief."
Brief for United States as Amicus Curiae, O.T. 1973,
No. 72-6520, p. 15. The Court, in turn, rested its decision on
Title VI. MR. JUSTICE POWELL takes pains to distinguish Lau from the case at hand because the Lau decision "rested solely on the statute." Ante at 438 U. S. 304 . See also Washington v. Davis, 426 U.
S. 229 , 426 U. S.
238 -239; Allen v. State Board of Elections, 393 U. S. 544 , 393 U. S. 588 (Harlan, J., concurring and dissenting).
[ Footnote 5/21 ]
As explained by Senator Humphrey, § 601 expresses a principle
imbedded in the constitutional and moral understanding of
the times.
"The purpose of title VI is to make sure that funds of the
United States are not used to support racial discrimination. In many instances, the practices of segregation or
discrimination, which title VI seeks to end, are unconstitutional.
. . . In all cases, such discrimination is contrary to
national policy, and to the moral sense of the Nation. Thus, title
VI is simply designed to insure that Federal funds are spent in
accordance with the Constitution and the moral sense of the
Nation."
110 Cong.Rec. 6544 (1964) (emphasis added).
[ Footnote 5/22 ]
Petitioner's attempt to rely on regulations issued by HEW for a
contrary reading of the statute is unpersuasive. Where no
discriminatory policy was in effect., HEW's example of permissible
"affirmative action" refers to "special recruitment policies." 45
CFR § 80.5(j) (1977). This regulation, which was adopted in 1973,
sheds no light on the legality of the admissions program that
excluded Bakke in this case.
[ Footnote 5/23 ]
110 Cong.Rec. 6047 (1964) (remarks of Sen. Pastore).
[ Footnote 5/24 ]
Record 30-31.
[ Footnote 5/25 ] See, e.g., Lau v. Nichols, supra; Bossier Parish School
Board v. Lemon, 370 F.2d 847 (CA5 1967), cert.
denied, 388 U.S. 911; Uzzell v. Friday, 547 F.2d 801
(CA4 1977), opinion on rehearing en banc, 558 F.2d 727, cert. pending, No. 77-635; Serna v. Portales, 499
F.2d 1147 (CA10 1974); cf. Chambers v. Omaha Public School
District, 536 F.2d 222, 225 n. 2 (CA8 1976) (indicating doubt
over whether a money judgment can be obtained under Title
VI). Indeed, the Government's brief in Lau v. Nichols,
supra, succinctly expressed this common assumption: "It is
settled that petitioners . . . have standing to enforce Section
601. . . ." Brief for United States as Amicus Curiae in Lau v. Nichols, O.T. 1973, No. 72-6520, p. 13 n. 5.
[ Footnote 5/26 ]
Supplemental Brief for United States as Amicus Curiae 24-34. The Government's supplemental brief also suggests that there
may be a difference between a private cause of action brought to
end a particular discriminatory practice and such an action brought
to cut off federal funds. Id. at 28-30. Section 601 is
specifically addressed to personal rights, while § 602 -- the fund
cutoff provision -- establishes "an elaborate mechanism for governmental enforcement by federal agencies."
Supplemental Brief, supra at 28 (emphasis added).
Arguably, private enforcement of this "elaborate mechanism" would
not fit within the congressional scheme, see separate
opinion of MR. JUSTICE WHITE, ante at 438 U. S.
380 -383. But Bakke did not seek to cut off the
University's federal funding; he sought admission to medical
school. The difference between these two courses of action is clear
and significant. As the Government itself states:
"[T]he grant of an injunction or a declaratory judgment in a
private action would not be inconsistent with the administrative
program established by Section 602. . . . A declaratory judgment or
injunction against future discrimination would not raise the
possibility that funds would be terminated, and it would not
involve bringing the forces of the Executive Branch to bear on
state programs; it therefore would not implicate the concern that
led to the limitations contained in Section 602."
Supplemental Brief, supra at 30 n. 25.
The notion that a private action seeking injunctive or
declaratory judgment relief is inconsistent with a federal statute
that authorizes termination of funds has clearly been rejected by
this Court in prior cases. See Rosado v. Wyman, 397 U. S. 397 , 397 U. S.
420 .
[ Footnote 5/27 ] See 29 U.S.C. § 794 (1976 ed.) (the Rehabilitation Act
of 1973) (in particular, the legislative history discussed in Lloyd v. Regional Transportation Authority, 548 F.2d 1277,
1285-1286 (CA7 1977)); 20 U.S.C. § 1617 (1976 ed.) (attorney fees
under the Emergency School Aid Act); and 31 U.S.C. § 1244 (1976
ed.) (private action under the Financial Assistance Act). Of
course, none of these subsequent legislative enactments is
necessarily reliable evidence of Congress' intent in 1964 in
enacting Title VI, and the legislation was not intended to change
the existing status of Title VI.
[ Footnote 5/28 ]
Framing the analysis in terms of the four-part Cort v.
Ash test, see 422 U. S. 66 , 422 U. S. 78 , it
is clear that all four parts of the test are satisfied. (1) Bakke's
status as a potential beneficiary of a federally funded program
definitely brings him within the " class for whose especial benefit the statute was enacted,'" ibid. (emphasis in original). (2) A cause of action based on race
discrimination has not been "traditionally relegated to state law." Ibid. (3) While a few excerpts from the voluminous
legislative history suggest that Congress did not intend to create
a private cause of action, see opinion of MR. JUSTICE
POWELL, ante at 438 U. S. 283 n. 18, an examination of the entire legislative history makes it
clear that Congress had no intention to foreclose a private right
of action. (4) There is ample evidence that Congress considered
private causes of action to be consistent with, if not essential
to, the legislative scheme. See, e.g., remarks of Senator
Ribicoff: "We come then to the crux of the dispute -- how this right [to
participate in federally funded programs without discrimination]
should be protected. And even this issue becomes clear upon the
most elementary analysis. If Federal funds are to be dispensed on a
nondiscriminatory basis, the only possible remedies must fall into
one of two categories: first, action to end discrimination; or
second, action to end the payment of funds. Obviously action to end
discrimination is preferable, since that reaches the objective of
extending the funds on a nondiscriminatory basis. But if the
discrimination persists and cannot be effectively terminated, how
else can the principle of nondiscrimination be vindicated except by
nonpayment of funds?"
110 Cong.Rec. 7065 (1964). See also id. at 5090, 6543,
6544 (remarks of Sen. Humphrey); id. at 7103, 12719
(remarks of Sen. Javits); id. at 7062, 7063 (remarks of
Sen. Pastore).
The congressional debates thus show a clear understanding that
the principle embodied in § 601 involves personal federal rights
that administrative procedures would not, for the most part, be
able to protect. The analogy to the Voting Rights Act of 1965, 42
U.S.C. § 1973 et seq. (1970 ed. and Supp. V), is clear.
Both that Act and Title VI are broadly phrased in terms of personal
rights ("no person shall be denied . . ."); both Acts were drafted
with broad remedial purposes in mind; and the effectiveness of both
Acts would be "severely hampered" without the existence of a
private remedy to supplement administrative procedures. See
Allen v. State Bd. of Elections, 393 U.
S. 544 , 393 U. S. 556 .
In Allen, of course, this Court found a private right of
action under the Voting Rights Act. | The University of California, Davis, Medical School had two admissions programs, a regular admissions program and a special admissions program for minority applicants. White applicant Allan Bakke was twice denied admission, and he sued, alleging that the special admissions program violated the Equal Protection Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment and Title VI of the Civil Rights Act of 1964.
The Supreme Court of California concluded that the special admissions program was unconstitutional and ordered Bakke admitted. The U.S. Supreme Court affirmed in part and reversed in part.
The Court held that the Constitution prohibited state and federal governments from discriminating on the basis of race, but universities could use race as one of many factors in admissions decisions. The Court found that the Medical School's use of fixed quotas in its special admissions program was impermissible racial discrimination and violated Title VI and the Equal Protection Clause.
However, the Court also held that universities had a compelling interest in achieving a diverse student body, and race could be considered as part of a holistic review of applicants. The Court emphasized that universities must ensure that each applicant is evaluated as an individual, and race-conscious admissions policies must be limited in time.
In this case, the Court struck down the Medical School's rigid racial quota but allowed race to be considered as a factor in admissions, provided it was part of a flexible, holistic review process and was limited in duration. This decision shaped affirmative action policies in higher education for decades. |
Equal Protection | Ambach v. Norwick | https://supreme.justia.com/cases/federal/us/441/68/ | U.S. Supreme Court Ambach v. Norwick, 441 U.S.
68 (1979) Ambach v. Norwick No. 76-808 Argued January 10,
1979 Decided April 17,
1979 441 U.S.
68 APPEAL FROM THE UNITED STATES
DISTRICT COURT FOR THE SOUTHERN DISTRICT OF NEW
YORK Syllabus Held: A New York statute forbidding permanent
certification as a public school teacher of any person who is not a
United States citizen unless that person has manifested an
intention to apply for citizenship does not violate the Equal
Protection Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment. Pp. 441 U. S.
72 -81.
(a) As a general principle, some state functions are so bound up
with the operation of the State as a governmental entity as to
permit exclusion from those functions of all persons who have not
become part of the process of self-government. Accordingly, a State
is required to justify its exclusion of aliens from such
governmental positions only "by a showing of some rational
relationship between the interest sought to be protected and the
limiting classification." Foley v. Connelie, 435 U.
S. 291 , 435 U. S. 296 .
Pp 441 U. S.
73 -74.
(b) This rule for governmental functions, which is an exception
to the stricter general standard applicable to classifications
based on alienage, rests on important principles inherent in the
Constitution. The distinction between citizens and aliens, though
ordinarily irrelevant to private activity, is fundamental to the
definition and government of a State, and the references to such
distinction in the Constitution itself indicate that the status of
citizenship was meant to have significance in the structure of our
government. It is because of this special significance of
citizenship that governmental entities, when exercising the
functions of government, have wider latitude in limiting the
participation of noncitizens. P. 441 U. S.
75 .
(c) Taking into consideration the role of public education and
the degree of responsibility and discretion teachers possess in
fulfilling that role, it is clear that public school teachers come
well within the "governmental function" principle recognized in Sugarman v. Dougall, 413 U. S. 634 , and Foley v. Connelie, supra, and, accordingly, the
Constitution requires only that a citizenship requirement
applicable to teaching in the public school bear a rational
relationship to a legitimate state interest. Pp. 441 U. S.
75 -80. Page 441 U. S. 69 (d) Here, the statute in question does bear a rational
relationship to the State's interest in furthering its educational
goals, especially with respect to regarding all teachers as having
an obligation to promote civic virtues and understanding in their
classes, regardless of the subject taught. Pp. 441 U. S.
80 -81. 417 F.
Supp. 913 , reversed.
POWELL, J., delivered the opinion of the Court, in which BURGER,
C.J., and STEWART, WHITE, and REHNQUIST, JJ., joined. BLACKMUN, J.,
filed a dissenting opinion, in which BRENNAN, MARSHALL, and
STEVENS, JJ., joined, post, p. 441 U. S.
81 .
MR. JUSTICE POWELL delivered the opinion of the Court.
This case presents the question whether a State, consistently
with the Equal Protection Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment, may
refuse to employ as elementary and secondary school teachers aliens
who are eligible for United States citizenship but who refuse to
seek naturalization. I New York Education Law § 3001(3) (McKinney 1970) forbids
certification as a public school teacher of any person who is not a
citizen of the United States, unless that person has Page 441 U. S. 70 manifested an intention to apply for citizenship. [ Footnote 1 ] The Commissioner of Education is
authorized to create exemptions from this prohibition, and has done
so with respect to aliens who are not yet eligible for citizenship.
[ Footnote 2 ] Unless a teacher
obtains certification, he may not work in a public elementary or
secondary school in New York. [ Footnote 3 ] Page 441 U. S. 71 Appellee Norwick was born in Scotland, and is a subject of Great
Britain. She has resided in this country since 1965, and is married
to a United States citizen. Appellee Dachinger is a Finnish subject
who came to this country in 1966, and also is married to a United
States citizen. Both Norwick and Dachinger currently meet all of
the educational requirements New York has set for certification as
a public school teacher, but they consistently have refused to seek
citizenship in spite of their eligibility to do so. Norwick applied
in 1973 for a teaching certificate covering nursery school through
sixth grade, and Dachinger sought a certificate covering the same
grades in 1975. [ Footnote 4 ]
Both applications were denied because of appellees' failure to meet
the requirements of § 3001(3). Norwick then filed this suit seeking
to enjoin the enforcement of § 3001(3), and Dachinger obtained
leave to intervene as a plaintiff.
A three-judge District Court was convened pursuant to 28 U.S.C.
§ 2281 (1970 ed.). Applying the "close judicial scrutiny" standard
of Graham v. Richardson, 403 U. S. 365 , 403 U. S. 372 (1971), the court held that § 3001(3) discriminated against aliens
in violation of the Equal Protection Clause. Norwick v.
Nyquist, 417 F.
Supp. 913 (SDNY 1976). The court believed that the statute was
overbroad, because it excluded all resident aliens from all
teaching jobs regardless of the subject sought to be taught, the
alien's nationality, the nature of the Page 441 U. S. 72 alien's relationship to this country, and the alien's
willingness to substitute some other sign of loyalty to this
Nation's political values, such as an oath of allegiance. Id. at 921. We noted probable jurisdiction over the state
school officials' appeal, 436 U.S. 902 (1978), and now reverse. II A The decisions of this Court regarding the permissibility of
statutory classifications involving aliens have not formed an
unwavering line over the years. State regulation of the employment
of aliens long has been subject to constitutional constraints. In Yick Wo v. Hopkins, 118 U. S. 356 (1886), the Court struck down an ordinance which was applied to
prevent aliens from running laundries, and in Truax v.
Raich, 239 U. S. 33 (1915), a law requiring at least 80% of the employees of certain
businesses to be citizens was held to be an unconstitutional
infringement of an alien's "right to work for a living in the
common occupations of the community. . . ." Id. at 239 U. S. 41 . At
the same time, however, the Court also has recognized a greater
degree of latitude for the States when aliens were sought to be
excluded from public employment. At the time Truax was
decided, the governing doctrine permitted States to exclude aliens
from various activities when the restriction pertained to "the
regulation or distribution of the public domain, or of the common
property or resources of the people of the State. . . ." Id. at 239 U. S. 39 .
Hence, as part of a larger authority to forbid aliens from owning
land, Frick v. Webb, 263 U. S. 326 (1923); Webb v. O'Brien, 263 U. S. 313 (1923); Terrace v. Thompson, 263 U.
S. 197 (1923); Blythe v. Hinckley, 180 U.
S. 333 (1901); Hauenstein v. Lynham, 100 U. S. 483 (1880); harvesting wildlife, Patsone v. Pennsylvania, 232 U. S. 138 (1914); McCready v. Virginia, 94 U. S.
391 (1877); Page 441 U. S. 73 or maintaining an inherently dangerous enterprise, Ohio ex
rel. Clarke v. Deckebach, 274 U. S. 392 (1927), States permissibly could exclude aliens from working on
public construction projects, Crane v. New York, 239 U. S. 195 (1915), and, it appears, from engaging in any form of public
employment at all, see Truax, supra at 239 U. S.
40 .
Over time, the Court's decisions gradually have restricted the
activities from which States are free to exclude aliens. The first
sign that the Court would question the constitutionality of
discrimination against aliens even in areas affected with a "public
interest" appeared in Oyama v. California, 332 U.
S. 633 (1948). The Court there held that statutory
presumptions designed to discourage evasion of California's ban on
alien landholding discriminated against the citizen children of
aliens. The same Term, the Court held that the "ownership" a State
exercises over fish found in its territorial waters
"is inadequate to justify California in excluding any or all
aliens who are lawful residents of the State from making a living
by fishing in the ocean off its shores while permitting all others
to do so." Takahashi v. Fish & Game Comm'n, 334 U.
S. 410 , 334 U. S. 421 (1948). This process of withdrawal from the former doctrine
culminated in Graham v. Richardson, supra, which, for the
first time, treated classifications based on alienage as
"inherently suspect and subject to close judicial scrutiny." 403
U.S. at 403 U. S. 372 .
Applying Graham, this Court has held invalid statutes that
prevented aliens from entering a State's classified civil service, Sugarman v. Dougall, 413 U. S. 634 (1973), practicing law, In re Griffiths, 413 U.
S. 717 (1973), working as an engineer, Examining
Board v. Flores de Otero, 426 U. S. 572 (1976), and receiving state educational benefits, Nyquist v.
Mauclet, 432 U. S. 1 (1977).
Although our more recent decisions have departed substantially
from the public interest doctrine of Truax's day, they
have not abandoned the general principle that some state functions
are so bound up with the operation of the State as Page 441 U. S. 74 a governmental entity as to permit the exclusion from those
functions of all persons who have not become part of the process of
self-government. In Sugarman, we recognized that a State
could, "in an appropriately defined class of positions, require
citizenship as a qualification for office." We went on to
observe:
"Such power inheres in the State by virtue of its obligation,
already noted above, 'to preserve the basic conception of a
political community.' . . . And this power and responsibility of
the State applies not only to the qualifications of voters, but
also to persons holding state elective or important nonelective
executive, legislative, and judicial positions, for officers who
participate directly in the formulation, execution, or review of
broad public policy perform functions that go to the heart of
representative government."
413 U.S. at 413 U. S. 647 (citation omitted). The exclusion of aliens from such governmental
positions would not invite as demanding scrutiny from this Court. Id. at 413 U. S. 648 . See also Nyquist v. Mauclet, supra at 432 U. S. 11 ; Perkins v. Smith, 370 F.
Supp. 134 (Md.1974), summarily aff'd, 426 U.
S. 913 (1976).
Applying the rational basis standard, we held last Term that New
York could exclude aliens from the ranks of its police force. Foley v. Connelie, 435 U. S. 291 (1978). Because the police function fulfilled "a most fundamental
obligation of government to its constituency," and, by necessity,
cloaked policemen with substantial discretionary powers, we viewed
the police force as being one of those appropriately defined
classes of positions for which a citizenship requirement could be
imposed. Id. at 435 U. S. 297 .
Accordingly, the State was required to justify its classification
only "by a showing of some rational relationship between the
interest sought to be protected and the limiting classification." Id. at 435 U. S.
296 . Page 441 U. S. 75 The rule for governmental functions, which is an exception to
the general standard applicable to classifications based on
alienage, rests on important principles inherent in the
Constitution. The distinction between citizens and aliens, though
ordinarily irrelevant to private activity, is fundamental to the
definition and government of a State. The Constitution itself
refers to the distinction no less than 11 times, see Sugarman
v. Dougall, supra at 413 U. S.
651 -652 (REHNQUIST, J., dissenting), indicating that the
status of citizenship was meant to have significance in the
structure of our government. The assumption of that status, whether
by birth or naturalization, denotes an association with the polity
which, in a democratic republic, exercises the powers of
governance. See Foley v. Connelie, supra at 435 U. S. 295 .
The form of this association is important: an oath of allegiance or
similar ceremony cannot substitute for the unequivocal legal bond
citizenship represents. It is because of this special significance
of citizenship that governmental entities, when exercising the
functions of government, have wider latitude in limiting the
participation of noncitizens. [ Footnote 5 ] B In determining whether, for purposes of equal protection
analysis, teaching in public schools constitutes a governmental
function, we look to the role of public education and to the degree
of responsibility and discretion teachers possess in fulfilling
that role. See Foley v. Connelie, supra, at 435 U. S. 297 .
Each of these considerations supports the conclusion that public
school teachers may be regarded as performing a task "that Page 441 U. S. 76 go[es] to the heart of representative government." Sugarman
v. Dougall, supra at 413 U. S. 647 .
[ Footnote 6 ]
Public education, like the police function, "fulfills a most
fundamental obligation of government to its constituency." Foley, supra, at 435 U. S. 297 .
The importance of public schools in the preparation of individuals
for participation as citizens, and in the preservation of the
values on which our society rests, long has been recognized by our
decisions:
"Today, education is perhaps the most important function of
state and local governments. Compulsory school attendance laws and
the great expenditures for education Page 441 U. S. 77 both demonstrate our recognition of the importance of education
to our democratic society. It is required in the performance of our
most basic public responsibilities, even service in the armed
forces. It is the very foundation of good citizenship. Today it is
a principal instrument in awakening the child to cultural values,
in preparing him for later professional training, and in helping
him to adjust normally to his environment." Brown v. Board of Education, 347 U.
S. 483 , 347 U. S. 493 (1954). See also Keyes v. School Dist. No. 1, Denver,
Colo., 413 U. S. 189 , 413 U. S. 246 (1973) (POWELL, J., concurring in part and dissenting in part); San Antonio Independent School Dist. v. Rodriguez, 411 U. S. 1 , 411 U. S. 29 -30
(1973); Wisconsin v. Yoder, 406 U.
S. 205 , 406 U. S. 213 (1972); id. at 406 U. S.
238 -239 (WHITE, J., concurring); Abington School
Dist. v. Schempp, 374 U. S. 203 , 374 U. S. 230 (1963) (BRENNAN, J., concurring); Adler v. Board of
Education, 342 U. S. 485 , 342 U. S. 493 (1952); McCollum v. Board of Education, 333 U.
S. 203 , 333 U. S. 212 (1948) (opinion of Frankfurter, J.); Pierce v. Society of
Sisters, 268 U. S. 510 (1925); Meyer v. Nebraska, 262 U.
S. 390 (1923); Interstate Consolidated Street R. Co.
v. Massachusetts, 207 U. S. 79 (1907). [ Footnote 7 ] Other
authorities have perceived public schools as an "assimilative
force" by which diverse and conflicting elements in our society are
brought together on a broad but common ground. See, e.g., J. Dewey, Democracy and Education 26 (1929); N. Edwards & H.
Richey, The School in the American Social Order 623-624 (2d
ed.1963). These perceptions of the public schools as inculcating
fundamental values necessary to the maintenance of a democratic
political system have been confirmed by the observations of social
scientists. See R. Dawson Page 441 U. S. 78 & K. Prewitt, Political Socialization 146-167 (1969); R.
Hess & J. Torney, The Development of Political Attitudes in
Children 114, 158-171, 217-220 (1967); V. Key, Public Opinion and
American Democracy 323-343 (1961). [ Footnote 8 ]
Within the public school system, teachers play a critical part
in developing students' attitude toward government and
understanding of the role of citizens in our society. Alone among
employees of the system, teachers are in direct, day-to-day contact
with students both in the classrooms and in the other varied
activities of a modern school. In shaping the students' experience
to achieve educational goals, teachers, by necessity, have wide
discretion over the way the course material is communicated to
students. They are responsible for presenting and explaining the
subject matter in a way that is both comprehensible and inspiring.
No amount of standardization of teaching materials or lesson plans
can eliminate the personal qualities a teacher brings to bear in
achieving these goals. Further, a teacher serves as a role model
for his students, exerting a subtle but important influence over
their Page 441 U. S. 79 perceptions and values. Thus, through both the presentation of
course materials and the example he sets, a teacher has an
opportunity to influence the attitudes of students toward
government, the political process, and a citizen's social
responsibilities. [ Footnote 9 ]
This influence is crucial to the continued good health of a
democracy. [ Footnote 10 ]
Furthermore, it is clear that all public school teachers, and
not just those responsible for teaching the courses most directly
related to government, history, and civic duties, should Page 441 U. S. 80 help fulfill the broader function of the public school system.
[ Footnote 11 ] Teachers,
regardless of their specialty, may be called upon to teach other
subjects, including those expressly dedicated to political and
social subjects. [ Footnote
12 ] More importantly, a State properly may regard all teachers
as having an obligation to promote civic virtues and understanding
in their classes, regardless of the subject taught. Certainly a
State also may take account of a teacher's function as an example
for students, which exists independently of particular classroom
subjects. In light of the foregoing considerations, we think it
clear that public school teachers come well within the
"governmental function" principle recognized in Sugarman and Foley. Accordingly, the Constitution requires only
that a citizenship requirement applicable to teaching in the public
schools bear a rational relationship to a legitimate state
interest. See Massachusetts Board of Retirement v. Murgia, 427 U. S. 307 , 427 U. S. 314 (1976). III As the legitimacy of the State's interest in furthering the
educational goals outlined above is undoubted, it remains only to
consider whether § 3001(3) bears a rational relationship to this
interest. The restriction is carefully framed to serve its purpose,
as it bars from teaching only those aliens who have demonstrated
their unwillingness to obtain United States citizenship. [ Footnote 13 ] Appellees, and aliens
similarly situated, in effect have chosen to classify themselves.
They prefer to retain citizenship in a foreign country, with the
obligations it entails Page 441 U. S. 81 of primary duty and loyalty. [ Footnote 14 ] They have rejected the open invitation
extended to qualify for eligibility to teach by applying for
citizenship in this country. The people of New York, acting through
their elected representatives, have made a judgment that
citizenship should be a qualification for teaching the young of the
State in the public schools, and § 3001(3) furthers that judgment.
[ Footnote 15 ] Reversed. [ Footnote 1 ]
The statute provides:
"No person shall be employed or authorized to teach in the
public schools of the state who is:"
" * * * *" "3. Not a citizen. The provisions of this subdivision shall not
apply, however, to an alien teacher now or hereafter employed,
provided such teacher shall make due application to become a
citizen and thereafter within the time prescribed by law shall
become a citizen. The provisions of this subdivision shall not
apply after July first, nineteen hundred sixty-seven, to an alien
teacher employed pursuant to regulations adopted by the
commissioner of education permitting such employment."
N.Y.Educ.Law § 3001(3) (McKinney 1970).
The statute contains an exception for persons who are ineligible
for United States citizenship solely because of an oversubscribed
quota. § 3001-a (McKinney 1970). Because this statutory provision
is in all respects narrower than the exception provided by
regulation, see n 2, infra as a practical matter it has no effect.
The State does not certify the qualifications of teachers in the
private schools, although it does require that such teachers be
"competent." N.Y.Educ.Law § 3204(2) (McKinney Supp. 1978-1979).
Accordingly, we are not presented with the question of, and express
no view as to, the permissibility of a citizenship requirement
pertaining to teachers in private schools.
[ Footnote 2 ]
The following regulation governs here:
" Citizenship. A teacher who is not a citizen of the
United States or who has not declared intention of becoming a
citizen may be issued a provisional certificate providing such
teacher has the appropriate educational qualifications as defined
in the regulations and (1) possesses skills or competencies not
readily available among teachers holding citizenship, or (2) is
unable to declare intention of becoming a citizen for valid
statutory reasons."
8 N.Y.C.R.R. § 80.2(i) (1978).
[ Footnote 3 ]
Certification by the Commissioner of Education is not required
of teachers at state institutions of higher education, and the
citizenship restriction accordingly does not apply to them. Brief
for Appellants 13 n. *.
[ Footnote 4 ]
At the time of her application, Norwick had not yet met the
postgraduate educational requirements for a permanent certificate,
and accordingly applied only for a temporary certificate, which
also is governed by § 3001(3). She since has obtained the necessary
graduate degree for full certification. Dachinger previously had
obtained a temporary certificate, which had lapsed at the time of
her 1975 application. The record does not indicate whether
Dachinger previously had declared an intent to obtain citizenship
or had obtained the temporary certificate because of some
applicable exception to the citizenship requirement.
[ Footnote 5 ]
That the significance of citizenship has constitutional
dimensions also has been recognized by several of our decisions. In Trop v. Dulles, 356 U. S. 86 (1958), a plurality of the Court held that the expatriation of an
American citizen constituted cruel and unusual punishment for the
crime of desertion in time of war. In Afroyim v. Rusk, 387 U. S. 253 (1967), the Court held that the Constitution forbade Congress from
depriving a person of his citizenship against his will for any
reason.
[ Footnote 6 ]
The dissenting opinion of MR. JUSTICE BLACKMUN, in reaching an
opposite conclusion, appears to apply a different analysis from
that employed in our prior decisions. Rather than considering
whether public school teachers perform a significant government
function, the inquiry mandated by Foley v. Connelie, 435 U. S. 291 (1978), and Sugarman v. Dougall, the dissent focuses
instead on the general societal importance of primary and secondary
school teachers, both public and private. Thus, the dissent, on the
one hand, depreciates the importance of New York's citizenship
requirement because it is not applied to private school teachers,
and, on the other hand, argues that the role teachers perform in
our society is no more significant than that filled by attorneys.
This misses the point of Foley and Sugarman. New
York's citizenship requirement is limited to a governmental
function because it applies only to teachers employed by and acting
as agents of the State. The Connecticut statute held
unconstitutional in In re Griffiths, 413 U.
S. 717 (1973), by contrast, applied to all attorneys,
most of whom do not work for the government. The exclusion of
aliens from access to the bar implicated the right to pursue a
chosen occupation, not access to public employment. Cf. Nyquist
v. Mauclet, 432 U. S. 1 , 432 U. S. 116 ,
n. (1977) (POWELL, J., dissenting). The distinction between a
private occupation and a government function was noted expressly in Griffiths: "Lawyers do indeed occupy professional positions of
responsibility and influence that impose on them duties correlative
with their vital right of access to the courts. Moreover, by virtue
of their professional aptitudes and natural interests, lawyers have
been leaders in government throughout the history of our country.
Yet they are not officials of government by virtue of being
lawyers."
413 U.S. at 413 U. S.
729 .
[ Footnote 7 ]
As San Antonio Independent School Dist. v. Rodriguez recognized, there is no inconsistency between our recognition of
the vital significance of public education and our holding that
access to education is not guaranteed by the Constitution. 411 U.S.
at 411 U. S.
335 .
[ Footnote 8 ]
The curricular requirements of New York's public school system
reflect some of the ways a public school system promotes the
development of the understanding that is prerequisite to
intelligent participation in the democratic process. The schools
are required to provide instruction
"to promote a spirit of patriotic and civic service and
obligation and to foster in the children of the state moral and
intellectual qualities which are essential in preparing to meet the
obligations of citizenship in peace or in war. . . ."
N.Y.Educ.Law § 801(1) (McKinney 1969). Flag and other patriotic
exercises also are prescribed, as loyalty is a characteristic of
citizenship essential to the preservation of a country. § 802
(McKinney 1969 and Supp. 1978-1979). In addition, required courses
include classes in civics, United States and New York history, and
principles of American government. §§ 3204(3)(a)(1), (2) (McKinney
1970).
Although private schools also are bound by most of these
requirements, the State has a stronger interest in ensuring that
the schools it most directly controls, and for which it bears the
cost, are as effective as possible in teaching these courses.
[ Footnote 9 ]
Although the findings of scholars who have written on the
subject are not conclusive, they generally reinforce the common
sense judgment, and the experience of most of us, that a teacher
exerts considerable influence over the development of fundamental
social attitudes in students, including those attitudes which in
the broadest sense of the term may be viewed as political. See,
e.g., R. Dawson & K. Prewitt, Political Socialization
158-167 (1969); R. Hess & J. Torney, The Development of
Political Attitudes in Children 162-163, 217-218 (1967). Cf. Note, Aliens' Right to Teach: Political Socialization
and the Public Schools, 85 Yale L.J. 90, 99-104 (1975).
[ Footnote 10 ]
Appellees contend that restriction of an alien's freedom to
teach in public schools is contrary to principles of diversity of
thought and academic freedom embodied in the First Amendment. See also id. at 106-109. We think that the attempt to draw
an analogy between choice of citizenship and political expression
or freedom of association is wide of the mark, as the argument
would bar any effort by the State to promote particular values and
attitudes toward government. Section 3001(3) does not inhibit
appellees from expressing freely their political or social views or
from associating with whomever they please. Cf. Givhan v.
Western Line Consol. School Dist., 439 U.
S. 410 , 439 U. S.
415 -416 (1979); Mt. Healthy City Board of Education
v. Doyle, 429 U. S. 274 (1977); Pickering v. Board of Education, 391 U.
S. 563 (1968). Nor are appellees discouraged from
joining with others to advance particular political ends. Cf.
Shelton v. Tucker, 364 U. S. 479 (1960). The only asserted liberty of appellees withheld by the New
York statute is the opportunity to teach in the State's schools so
long as they elect not to become citizens of this country. This is
not a liberty that is accorded constitutional protection.
[ Footnote 11 ]
At the primary school level, for which both appellees sought
certification, teachers are responsible for all of the basic
curriculum.
[ Footnote 12 ]
In New York, for example, all certified teachers, including
those in the secondary schools, are required to be available for up
to five hours of teaching a week in subjects outside their
specialty. 8 N.Y.C.R.R. § 80.2(c) (1978) .
[ Footnote 13 ] See n 2, supra. [ Footnote 14 ]
As our cases have emphasized, resident aliens pay taxes, serve
in the Armed Forces, and have made significant contributions to our
country in private and public endeavors. See In re
Griffiths, 413 U.S. at 413 U. S. 722 ; Sugarman v. Dougall, 413 U.S. at 413 U. S. 645 ; Graham v. Richardson, 403 U. S. 365 , 403 U. S. 376 (1971). No doubt many of them, and we do not exclude appellees,
would make excellent public school teachers. But the legislature,
having in mind the importance of education to state and local
governments, see Brown v. Board of Education, 347 U.
S. 483 , 347 U. S. 493 (1954), may determine eligibility for the key position in
discharging that function on the assumption that generally persons
who are citizens, or who have not declined the opportunity to seek
United States citizenship, are better qualified than are those who
have elected to remain aliens. We note in this connection that
regulations promulgated pursuant to § 3001(3) do provide for
situations where a particular alien's special qualifications as a
teacher outweigh the policy primarily served by the statute. See 8 N.Y.C.R.R. § 80.2 (i)(1) (1978). The appellants
inform us, however, that the authority conferred by this regulation
has not been exercised. Brief for Appellants 7 n. *.
[ Footnote 15 ]
Appellees argue that the State cannot rationally exclude aliens
from teaching positions and yet permit them to vote for and sit on
certain local school boards. We note, first, that the State's
legislature has not expressly endorsed this policy. Rather,
appellants, as an administrative matter, have interpreted the
statute governing New York City's unique community school boards,
N.Y.Educ.Law § 2590-C(4) (McKinney Supp. 1978-1979), to permit
aliens who are the parents of public school students to participate
in these boards. See App. 27, 29. We also may assume,
without having to decide, that there is rational basis for a
distinction between teachers and board members based on their
respective responsibilities. Although possessing substantial
responsibility for the administration of the schools, board members
teach no classes, and rarely, if ever, are known or identified by
the students.
MR. JUSTICE BLACKMUN, with whom MR. JUSTICE BRENNAN, MR. JUSTICE
MARSHALL, and MR. JUSTICE STEVENS join, dissenting.
Once again the Court is asked to rule upon the constitutionality
of one of New York's many statutes that impose a Page 441 U. S. 82 requirement of citizenship upon a person before that person may
earn his living in a specified occupation. [ Footnote 2/1 ] These New York statutes, for the most
part, have their origin in the frantic and over-reactive days of
the First World War when attitudes of parochialism and fear of the
foreigner were the order of the day. This time we are concerned
with the right to teach in the public schools of the State, at the
elementary and secondary levels, and with the citizenship
requirement that N.Y.Educ.Law § 3001(3) (McKinney 1970), quoted by
the Court ante at 441 U. S. 70 n. 1 imposes. [ Footnote 2/2 ]
As the Court acknowledges, ante at 441 U. S. 72 ,
its decisions regarding the permissibility of statutory
classifications concerning aliens "have not formed an unwavering
line over the years." [ Footnote
2/3 ] Thus, just last Term, in Foley v. Connelie, 435 U. S. 291 (1978), the Court upheld against equal protection challenge the New
York statute limiting appointment of members of the state police
force to citizens of the United States. The touchstone, the Court
indicated, was that citizenship may be Page 441 U. S. 83 a relevant qualification for fulfilling
"'important nonelective executive, legislative, and judicial
positions' held by 'officers who participate directly in the
formulation, execution, or review of broad public policy.'" Id. at 435 U. S. 296 ,
quoting Sugarman v. Dougall, 413 U.
S. 634 , 413 U. S. 647 (1973). For such positions, a State need show only some rational
relationship between the interest sought to be protected and the
limiting classification. Police, it then was felt, were clothed
with authority to exercise an almost infinite variety of
discretionary powers that could seriously affect members of the
public. 435 U.S. at 435 U. S. 297 .
They thus fell within the category of important officers who
participate directly in the execution of "broad public policy." The
Court was persuaded that citizenship bore a rational relationship
to the special demands of police positions, and that a State
therefore could constitutionally confine that public responsibility
to citizens of the United States. Id. at 435 U. S. 300 .
The propriety of making citizenship a qualification for a narrowly
defined class of positions was also recognized, in passing, in Sugarman v. Dougall, 413 U.S. at 413 U. S. 647 ,
and in Nyquist v. Mauclet, 432 U. S.
1 , 432 U. S. 11 (1977).
On the other hand, the Court frequently has invalidated a state
provision that denies a resident alien the right to engage in
specified occupational activity: Yick Wo v. Hopkins, 118 U. S. 356 (1886) (ordinance applied so as to prevent Chinese subjects from
engaging in the laundry business); Truax v. Raich, 239 U. S. 33 (1915)
(statute requiring an employer's workforce to be composed of not
less than 80% "qualified electors or native-born citizens"); Takahashi v. Fish & Game Comm'n, 334 U.
S. 410 (1948) (limitation of commercial fishing licenses
to persons not "ineligible to citizenship"); Sugarman v.
Dougall, supra, (New York statute relating to permanent
positions in the "competitive class" of the state civil service); In re Griffiths, 413 U. S. 717 (1973) (the practice of law); Nelson v. Miranda, 413 U.S.
902 (1973), summarily aff'g 351 F.
Supp. 735 (Ariz.1972) (social service worker Page 441 U. S. 84 and teacher); Examining Board v. Flores de Otero, 426 U. S. 572 (1976) (the practice of civil engineering). See also Nyquist v.
Mauclet, supra, (New York statute barring certain resident
aliens from state financial assistance for higher education).
Indeed, the Court has held more than once that state
classifications based on alienage are "inherently suspect and
subject to close judicial scrutiny." Graham v. Richardson, 403 U. S. 365 , 403 U. S. 372 (1971). See Examining Board v. Flores de Otero, 426 U.S.
at 426 U. S.
601 -602; In re Griffiths, 413 U.S. at 413 U. S. 721 ; Sugarman v. Dougall, 413 U.S. at 413 U. S. 642 ; Nyquist v. Mauclet, 432 U.S. at 432 U. S. 7 . And
"[a]lienage classifications by a State that do not withstand this
stringent examination cannot stand." Ibid. There is thus a line, most recently recognized in Foley v.
Connelie, between those employments that a State, in its
wisdom, constitutionally may restrict to United States citizens, on
the one hand, and those employments, on the other, that the State
may not deny to resident aliens. For me, the present case falls on
the Sugarman-Griffiths-Flores de Otero-Mauclet side of
that line, rather than on the narrowly isolated Foley side.
We are concerned here with elementary and secondary education in
the public schools of New York State. We are not concerned with
teaching at the college or graduate levels. It seems
constitutionally absurd, to say the least, that, in these lower
levels of public education, a Frenchman may not teach French or,
indeed, an Englishwoman may not teach the grammar of the English
language. The appellees, to be sure, are resident "aliens" in the
technical sense, but there is not a word in the record that either
appellee does not have roots in this country or is unqualified in
any way, other than the imposed requirement of citizenship, to
teach. Both appellee Norwick and appellee Dachinger have been in
this country for Page 441 U. S. 85 over 12 years. Each is married to a United States citizen. Each
currently meets all the requirements, other than citizenship, that
New York has specified for certification as a public school
teacher. Tr. of Oral Arg. 4. [ Footnote
2/4 ] Each is willing, if required, to subscribe to an oath to
support the Constitutions of the United States and of New York.
[ Footnote 2/5 ] Each lives in an
American community, must obey its laws, and must pay all of the
taxes citizens are obligated to pay. Appellees, however, have
hesitated to give up their respective British and Finnish
citizenships, just as lawyer Fre Le Poole Griffiths, the subject of In re Griffiths, supra, hesitated to renounce her
Netherlands citizenship, although married to a citizen of the
United States and a resident of Connecticut.
But the Court, to the disadvantage of appellees, crosses the
line from Griffiths to Foley by saying, ante at 441 U. S. 75 ,
that the
"distinction between citizens and aliens, though ordinarily
irrelevant to private activity, is fundamental to the definition
and government of a State."
It then concludes that public school teaching "constitutes a
governmental function," ibid., and that public school
teachers may be regarded as performing a task that goes "to the
heart of representative government." Ante at 441 U. S. 76 .
The Court speaks of the importance of public schools in the
preparation of individuals for participation as citizens, and in
the preservation of the values on which Page 441 U. S. 86 our society rests. [ Footnote
2/6 ] After then observing that teachers play a critical part in
all this, the Court holds that New York's citizenship requirement
is constitutional because it bears a rational relationship to the
State's interest in furthering these educational goals.
I perceive a number of difficulties along the easy road the
Court takes to this conclusion:
First, the New York statutory structure itself refutes the
argument. Section 3001(3), the very statute at issue here, provides
for exceptions with respect to alien teachers "employed pursuant to
regulations adopted by the commissioner of education permitting
such employment." Section 3001-a (McKinney 1970) provides another
exception for persons ineligible for United States citizenship
because of oversubscribed quotas. Also, New York is unconcerned
with any citizenship qualification for teachers in the private
schools of the State, even though the record indicates that about
18% of the pupils at the elementary and secondary levels attend
private schools. The education of those pupils seems not to be
inculcated with something less than what is desirable for
citizenship and what the Court calls an influence "crucial to the
continued good health of a democracy." Ante at 441 U. S. 73 .
The State, apparently under § 3001(3), would not hesitate to employ
an alien teacher while he waits to attain citizenship, even though
he may fail ever to attain it. And the stark fact that the State
permits some aliens to sit on certain local school boards,
N.Y.Educ.Law 2590-c(4) (McKinney Supp. 1978-1979), reveals how
shallow and indistinct is New York's line of demarcation between
citizenship and noncitizenship. The Court's attempted Page 441 U. S. 87 rationalization of this fact, ante at 441 U. S. 81 -82,
n. 15, hardly extinguishes the influence school board members,
including these otherwise "disqualified" resident aliens, possess
in school administration, in the selection of faculty, and in the
approval of textbooks and instructional materials.
Second, the New York statute is all-inclusive in its
disqualifying provisions: "No person shall be employed or
authorized to teach in the public schools of the state who is . . .
[n]ot a citizen." It sweeps indiscriminately. It is "neither
narrowly confined nor precise in its application," nor limited to
the accomplishment of substantial state interests. Sugarman v.
Dougall, 413 U.S. at 413 U. S. 643 . See Note, Aliens' Right to Teach: Political Socialization
and the Public Schools, 85 Yale L.J. 90, 109-111 (1975).
Third, the New York classification is irrational. Is it better
to employ a poor citizen teacher than an excellent resident alien
teacher? Is it preferable to have a citizen who has never seen
Spain or a Latin American country teach Spanish to eighth graders
and to deny that opportunity to a resident alien who may have lived
for 20 years in the culture of Spain or Latin America? The State
will know how to select its teachers responsibly, wholly apart from
citizenship, and can do so selectively and intelligently. [ Footnote 2/7 ] That is the way to Page 441 U. S. 88 accomplish the desired result. An artificial citizenship bar is
not a rational way. It is, instead, a stultifying provision. The
route to "diverse and conflicting elements" and their being
"brought together on a broad but common ground," which the Court so
emphasizes, ante at 441 U. S. 77 , is
hardly to be achieved by disregarding some of the diverse elements
that are available, competent, and contributory to the richness of
our society and of the education it could provide.
Fourth, it is logically impossible to differentiate between this
case, concerning teachers, and In re Griffiths, concerning
attorneys. If a resident alien may not constitutionally be barred
from taking a state bar examination, and thereby becoming qualified
to practice law in the courts of a State, how is one to comprehend
why a resident alien may constitutionally be barred from teaching
in the elementary and secondary levels of a State's public schools?
One may speak proudly of the role model of the teacher, of his
ability to mold young minds, of his inculcating force as to
national ideals, and of his profound influence in the impartation
of our society's values. Are the attributes of an attorney.any the
less? He represents us in our critical courtroom controversies even
when citizenship and loyalty may be questioned. He stands as an
officer of every court in which he practices. He is responsible for
strict adherence to the announced and implied standards of
professional conduct, and to the requirements of evolving ethical
codes, and for honesty and integrity in his professional Page 441 U. S. 89 and personal life. Despite the almost continuous criticism
leveled at the legal profession, he, too, is an influence in
legislation, in the community, and in the role-model figure that
the professional person enjoys. [ Footnote 2/8 ] The Court specifically recognized this in In re Griffiths: "Lawyers do indeed occupy professional positions of
responsibility and influence that impose on them duties correlative
with their vital right of access to the courts. Moreover, by virtue
of their professional aptitudes and natural interests, lawyers have
been leaders in government throughout the history of our
country."
413 U.S. at 413 U. S. 729 .
[ Footnote 2/9 ]
If an attorney has a constitutional right to take a bar
examination and practice law, despite his being a resident alien,
it is impossible for me to see why a resident alien otherwise
completely competent and qualified, as these appellees concededly
are, is constitutionally disqualified from teaching in the public
schools of the great State of New York. The Page 441 U. S. 90 District Court expressed it well and forcefully when it observed
that New York's exclusion "seems repugnant to the very heritage the
State is seeking to inculcate." Norwick v.
Nyquist, 417 F.
Supp. 913 , 922 (SDNY 1976). I respectfully dissent.
[ Footnote 2/1 ]
One of the appellees in Nyquist v. Mauclet, 432 U. S. 1 (1977),
submitted a list of the New York statutes that required
citizenship, or a declaration of intent to become a citizen, for no
fewer than 37 occupations. Brief for Appellee Mauclet, O.T. 1976,
No. 76-208, pp. 19-22, nn. 8-44, inclusive. Some of those statutes
have been legislatively repealed or modified, or judicially
invalidated. Others are still in effect. Among the latter are those
relating to the occupations of inspector, certified shorthand
reporter, funeral director, masseur, physical therapist, and animal
technician.
[ Footnote 2/2 ]
This particular citizenship requirement had its origin in 1918
N.Y.Laws, ch. 158, effective Apr. 4, 1918.
[ Footnote 2/3 ]
"To be sure, the course of decisions protecting the employment
rights of resident aliens has not been an unswerving one." In
re Griffiths, 413 U. S. 717 , 413 U. S. 720 (1973).
[ Footnote 2/4 ]
Appellee Norwick is a summa cum laude graduate of a
Massachusetts college, and received an A average in full-time
graduate work in the State University of New York at Albany. She
has taught both in this country and in Great Britain.
Appellee Dachinger is a cum laude graduate, with a
major in German, of Lehman College, a unit of the City University
of New York, and possesses a master's degree in Early Childhood
Education from that institution. She has taught at a day-care
center in the Bronx.
Each appellee, thus, has received and excelled in educational
training the State of New York itself offers.
[ Footnote 2/5 ] See In re Griffiths, 413 U.S. at 413 U. S. 726 n. 18.
[ Footnote 2/6 ]
One, of course, can agree with this observation. One may
concede, also, that public schools are an " assimilative force'
by which diverse and conflicting elements in our society are
brought together on a broad but common ground," ante at 441 U. S. 77 ,
and that the inculcation of fundamental values by our public
schools is necessary to the maintenance of a democratic political
system. [ Footnote 2/7 ]
In In re Griffiths, the Court significantly has
observed:
"Connecticut has wide freedom to gauge on a case-by-case basis
the fitness of an applicant to practice law. Connecticut can, and
does, require appropriate training and familiarity with Connecticut
law. Apart from such tests of competence, it requires a new lawyer
to take both an 'attorney's oath' to perform his functions
faithfully and honestly and a 'commissioner's oath' to 'support the
constitution of the United States, and the constitution of the
state of Connecticut.' Appellant has indicated her willingness and
ability to subscribe to the substance of both oaths, and
Connecticut may quite properly conduct a character investigation to
insure, in any given case,"
"that an applicant is not one who 'swears to an oath pro
forma while declaring or manifesting his disagreement with or
indifference to the oath.' Bond v. Floyd, 385 U. S.
116 , 385 U. S. 132 ."
" Law Students Research Council v. Wadmond, 401 U.S. at 401 U. S. 164 . Moreover,
once admitted to the bar, lawyers are subject to continuing
scrutiny by the organized bar and the courts. In addition to
discipline for unprofessional conduct, the range of post-admission
sanctions extends from judgments for contempt to criminal
prosecutions and disbarment. In sum, the Committee simply has not
established that it must exclude all aliens from the practice of
law in order to vindicate its undoubted interest in high
professional standards."
413 U.S. at 413 U. S.
725 -727 (footnotes omitted).
[ Footnote 2/8 ] See also Stockton v.
Ford , 11 How. 232, 52 U. S. 247 (1851); Hickman v. Taylor, 329 U.
S. 495 , 329 U. S.
514 -515 (1947) (concurring opinion); Schware v.
Board of Bar Examiners, 353 U. S. 232 , 353 U. S. 247 (1957) (concurring opinion); In re Sawyer, 360 U.
S. 622 , 360 U. S. 668 (1959) (dissenting opinion); J. Story, Miscellaneous Writings,
Value and Importance of Legal Studies 503-549 (W. Story ed.1972);
Stone, The Public Influence of the Bar, 48 Harv.L.Rev. 1 (1934); W.
Brennan, The Responsibilities of the Legal Profession, Address
before the Law School of Harvard University (1967); A. de
Tocqueville, Democracy in America 321-331 (Schocken ed.1961); J.
Rogers, The Lawyer in American Public Life, in Morrison Foundation
Lectures 41, 61 (1940).
[ Footnote 2/9 ]
In order to keep attorneys on the nongovernmental side of the
classification line, the Court continued:
"Yet they are not officials of government by virtue of being
lawyers. Nor does the status of holding a license to practice law
place one so close to the core of the political process as to make
him a formulator of govern ment policy."
413 U.S. at 413 U. S.
729 . | In Ambach v. Norwick, the Supreme Court upheld a New York statute that prevented non-citizens from becoming permanent public school teachers unless they intended to apply for citizenship. The Court applied a rational basis test, finding that the statute was rationally related to the state's interest in furthering its educational goals and promoting civic virtues and understanding in the classroom. This decision highlights the Court's view of public education and the role of teachers as a "governmental function," allowing for broader state discretion in employment decisions. |
Equal Protection | City of Cleburne v. Cleburne Living Center, Inc. | https://supreme.justia.com/cases/federal/us/473/432/ | U.S. Supreme Court Cleburne v. Cleburne Living Ctr., 473
U.S. 432 (1985) City of Cleburne, Texas v. Cleburne
Living Center, Inc. No. 84-468 Argued March 18, 1985 Reargued April 23,
1985 Decided July 1, 1985 473
U.S. 432 CERTIORARI TO THE UNITED STATES
COURT OF APPEALS FOR THE FIFTH CIRCUIT Syllabus Respondent Cleburne Living Center, Inc. (CLC), which anticipated
leasing a certain building for the operation of a group home for
the mentally retarded, was informed by petitioner city that a
special use permit would be required, the city having concluded
that the proposed group home should be classified as a "hospital
for the feebleminded" under the zoning ordinance covering the area
in which the proposed home would be located. Accordingly, CLC
applied for a special use permit, but the City Council, after a
public hearing, denied the permit. CLC and others (also respondents
here) then filed suit against the city and a number of its
officials, alleging that the zoning ordinance, on its face and as
applied, violated the equal protection rights of CLC and its
potential residents. The District Court held the ordinance and its
application constitutional. The Court of Appeals reversed, holding
that mental retardation is a "quasi-suspect" classification; that,
under the applicable "heightened scrutiny" equal protection test,
the ordinance was facially invalid because it did not substantially
further an important governmental purpose; and that the ordinance
was also invalid as applied. Held: 1. The Court of Appeals erred in holding mental retardation a
quasi-suspect classification calling for a more exacting standard
of judicial review than is normally accorded economic and social
legislation. Pp. 473 U. S.
439 -447.
(a) Where individuals in a group affected by a statute have
distinguishing characteristics relevant to interests a State has
the authority to implement, the Equal Protection Clause requires
only that the classification drawn by the statute be rationally
related to a legitimate state interest. When social or economic
legislation is at issue, the Equal Protection Clause allows the
States wide latitude. Pp. 473 U. S.
439 -442.
(b) Mentally retarded persons, who have a reduced ability to
cope with and function in the everyday world, are thus different
from other persons, and the States' interest in dealing with and
providing for them Page 473 U. S. 433 is plainly a legitimate one. The distinctive legislative
response, both national and state, to the plight of those who are
mentally retarded demonstrates not only that they have unique
problems, but also that the lawmakers have been addressing their
difficulties in a manner that belies a continuing antipathy or
prejudice and a corresponding need for more intrusive oversight by
the judiciary than is afforded under the normal equal protection
standard. Moreover, the legislative response, which could hardly
have occurred and survived without public support, negates any
claim that the mentally retarded are politically powerless in the
sense that they have no ability to attract the attention of the
lawmakers. The equal protection standard requiring that legislation
be rationally related to a legitimate governmental purpose affords
government the latitude necessary both to pursue policies designed
to assist the retarded in realizing their full potential, and to
freely and efficiently engage in activities that burden the
retarded in what is essentially an incidental manner. Pp. 473 U. S.
442 -447.
2. Requiring a special use permit for the proposed group home
here deprives respondents of the equal protection of the laws, and
thus it is unnecessary to decide whether the ordinance's permit
requirement is facially invalid where the mentally retarded are
involved. Although the mentally retarded, as a group, are different
from those who occupy other facilities -- such as boarding houses
and hospitals -- that are permitted in the zoning area in question
without a special permit, such difference is irrelevant unless the
proposed group home would threaten the city's legitimate interests
in a way that the permitted uses would not. The record does not
reveal any rational basis for believing that the proposed group
home would pose any special threat to the city's legitimate
interests. Requiring the permit in this case appears to rest on an
irrational prejudice against the mentally retarded, including those
who would occupy the proposed group home and who would live under
the closely supervised and highly regulated conditions expressly
provided for by state and federal law. Pp. 473 U. S.
447 -450.
726 F.2d 191, affirmed in part, vacated in part, and
remanded.
WHITE, J., delivered the opinion of the Court, in which BURGER,
C.J., and POWELL, REHNQUIST, STEVENS, and O'CONNOR, JJ., joined.
STEVENS, J., filed a concurring opinion, in which BURGER, C.J.,
joined, post, p. 473 U. S. 451 .
MARSHALL, J., filed an opinion concurring in the judgment in part
and dissenting in part, in which BRENNAN and BLACKMUN, JJ., joined, post, p. 473 U. S.
455 . Page 473 U. S. 435 JUSTICE WHITE delivered the opinion of the Court.
A Texas city denied a special use permit for the operation of a
group home for the mentally retarded, acting pursuant to a
municipal zoning ordinance requiring permits for such homes. The
Court of Appeals for the Fifth Circuit held that mental retardation
is a "quasi-suspect" classification, and that the ordinance
violated the Equal Protection Clause because it did not
substantially further an important governmental purpose. We hold
that a lesser standard of scrutiny is appropriate, but conclude
that, under that standard, the ordinance is invalid as applied in
this case. I In July, 1980, respondent Jan Hannah purchased a building at 201
Featherston Street in the city of Cleburne, Texas, with the
intention of leasing it to Cleburne Living Center, Inc. (CLC),
[ Footnote 1 ] for the operation
of a group home for the mentally retarded. It was anticipated that
the home would house 13 retarded men and women, who would be under
the constant supervision of CLC staff members. The house had four
bedrooms and two baths, with a half bath to be added. CLC planned
to comply with all applicable state and federal regulations.
[ Footnote 2 ] Page 473 U. S. 436 The city informed CLC that a special use permit would be
required for the operation of a group home at the site, and CLC
accordingly submitted a permit application. In response to a
subsequent inquiry from CLC, the city explained that, under the
zoning regulations applicable to the site, a special use permit,
renewable annually, was required for the construction of
"[h]ospitals for the insane or feeble-minded, or alcoholic
[ sic ] or drug addicts, or penal or correctional
institutions." [ Footnote 3 ] The
city had determined that the proposed Page 473 U. S. 437 group home should be classified as a "hospital for the
feebleminded." After holding a public hearing on CLC's application,
the City Council voted 3 to 1 to deny a special use permit.
[ Footnote 4 ]
CLC then filed suit in Federal District Court against the city
and a number of its officials, alleging, inter alia, that
the zoning ordinance was invalid on its face and as applied because
it discriminated against the mentally retarded in violation of the
equal protection rights of CLC and its potential residents. The
District Court found that,
"[i]f the potential residents of the Featherston Street home
were not mentally retarded, but the home was the same in all other
respects, its use would be permitted under the city's zoning
ordinance,"
and that the City Council's decision "was motivated primarily by
the fact that the residents of the home would be persons who are
mentally retarded." App. 93, 94. Even so, the District Court held
the ordinance and its application constitutional. Concluding that
no fundamental right was implicated, and that mental retardation
was neither a suspect nor a quasi-suspect classification, the court
employed the minimum level of judicial scrutiny applicable to equal
protection claims. The court deemed the ordinance, as written and
applied, to be rationally related to the city's legitimate
interests in "the legal responsibility of CLC and its residents, .
. . the safety and fears of residents in the adjoining
neighborhood," and the number of people to be housed in the home.
[ Footnote 5 ] Id. at
103.
The Court of Appeals for the Fifth Circuit reversed, determining
that mental retardation was a quasi-suspect classification and that
it should assess the validity of the ordinance Page 473 U. S. 438 under intermediate-level scrutiny. 726 F.2d 191 (1984). Because
mental retardation was in fact relevant to many legislative
actions, strict scrutiny was not appropriate. But in light of the
history of "unfair and often grotesque mistreatment" of the
retarded, discrimination against them was "likely to reflect
deep-seated prejudice." Id. at 197. In addition, the
mentally retarded lacked political power, and their condition was
immutable. The court considered heightened scrutiny to be
particularly appropriate in this case, because the city's ordinance
withheld a benefit which, although not fundamental, was very
important to the mentally retarded. Without group homes, the court
stated, the retarded could never hope to integrate themselves into
the community. [ Footnote 6 ]
Applying the test that it considered appropriate, the court held
that the ordinance was invalid on its face because it did not
substantially further any important governmental interests. The
Court of Appeals went on to hold that the ordinance was also
invalid as applied. [ Footnote
7 ] Rehearing en banc was Page 473 U. S. 439 denied with six judges dissenting in an opinion urging en banc
consideration of the panel's adoption of a heightened standard of
review. We granted certiorari, 469 U.S. 1016 (1984). [ Footnote 8 ] II The Equal Protection Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment commands
that no State shall "deny to any person within its jurisdiction the
equal protection of the laws," which is essentially a direction
that all persons similarly situated should be treated alike. Plyler v. Doe, 457 U. S. 202 , 457 U. S. 216 (1982). Section 5 of the Amendment empowers Congress to enforce
this mandate, but absent controlling congressional direction, the
courts have themselves devised standards for Page 473 U. S. 440 determining the validity of state legislation or other official
action that is challenged as denying equal protection. The general
rule is that legislation is presumed to be valid, and will be
sustained if the classification drawn by the statute is rationally
related to a legitimate state interest. Schweiker v.
Wilson, 450 U. S. 221 , 450 U. S. 230 (1981); United States Railroad Retirement Board v. Fritz, 449 U. S. 166 , 449 U. S.
174 -175 (1980); Vance v. Bradley, 440 U. S.
93 , 440 U. S. 97 (1979); New Orleans v. Dukes, 427 U.
S. 297 , 427 U. S. 303 (1976). When social or economic legislation is at issue, the Equal
Protection Clause allows the States wide latitude, United
States Railroad Retirement Board v. Fritz, supra, at 449 U. S. 174 ; New Orleans v. Dukes, supra, at 427 U. S. 303 ,
and the Constitution presumes that even improvident decisions will
eventually be rectified by the democratic processes.
The general rule gives way, however, when a statute classifies
by race, alienage, or national origin. These factors are so seldom
relevant to the achievement of any legitimate state interest that
laws grounded in such considerations are deemed to reflect
prejudice and antipathy -- a view that those in the burdened class
are not as worthy or deserving as others. For these reasons, and
because such discrimination is unlikely to be soon rectified by
legislative means, these laws are subjected to strict scrutiny, and
will be sustained only if they are suitably tailored to serve a
compelling state interest. McLaughlin v. Florida, 379 U. S. 184 , 379 U. S. 192 (1964); Graham v. Richardson, 403 U.
S. 365 (1971). Similar oversight by the courts is due
when state laws impinge on personal rights protected by the
Constitution. Kramer v. Union Free School District No. 15, 395 U. S. 621 (1969); Shapiro v. Thompson, 394 U.
S. 618 (1969); Skinner v. Oklahoma ex rel.
Williamson, 316 U. S. 535 (1942).
Legislative classifications based on gender also call for a
heightened standard of review. That factor generally provides no
sensible ground for differential treatment.
"[W]hat differentiates sex from such nonsuspect statuses as
intelligence or physical disability . . . is that the sex
characteristic Page 473 U. S. 441 frequently bears no relation to ability to perform or contribute
to society." Frontiero v. Richardson, 411 U.
S. 677 , 411 U. S. 686 (1973) (plurality opinion). Rather than resting on meaningful
considerations, statutes distributing benefits and burdens between
the sexes in different ways very likely reflect outmoded notions of
the relative capabilities of men and women. A gender classification
fails unless it is substantially related to a sufficiently
important governmental interest. Mississippi University for
Women v. Hogan, 458 U. S. 718 (1982); Craig v. Boren, 429 U. S. 190 (1976). Because illegitimacy is beyond the individual's control and
bears "no relation to the individual's ability to participate in
and contribute to society," Mathews v. Lucas, 427 U.
S. 495 , 427 U. S. 505 (1976), official discriminations resting on that characteristic are
also subject to somewhat heightened review. Those restrictions
"will survive equal protection scrutiny to the extent they are
substantially related to a legitimate state interest." Mills v.
Habluetzel, 456 U. S. 91 , 456 U. S. 99 (1982).
We have declined, however, to extend heightened review to
differential treatment based on age:
"While the treatment of the aged in this Nation has not been
wholly free of discrimination, such persons, unlike, say, those who
have been discriminated against on the basis of race or national
origin, have not experienced a 'history of purposeful unequal
treatment' or been subjected to unique disabilities on the basis of
stereotyped characteristics not truly indicative of their
abilities." Massachusetts Board of Retirement v. Murgia, 427 U. S. 307 , 427 U. S. 313 (1976).
The lesson of Murgia is that, where individuals in the
group affected by a law have distinguishing characteristics
relevant to interests the State has the authority to implement, the
courts have been very reluctant, as they should be in our federal
system and with our respect for the separation of powers, to
closely scrutinize legislative choices as to whether, how, and to
what extent those interests should be Page 473 U. S. 442 pursued. In such cases, the Equal Protection Clause requires
only a rational means to serve a legitimate end. III Against this background, we conclude for several reasons that
the Court of Appeals erred in holding mental retardation a
quasi-suspect classification calling for a more exacting standard
of judicial review than is normally accorded economic and social
legislation. First, it is undeniable, and it is not argued
otherwise here, that those who are mentally retarded have a reduced
ability to cope with and function in the everyday world. Nor are
they all cut from the same pattern: as the testimony in this record
indicates, they range from those whose disability is not
immediately evident to those who must be constantly cared for.
[ Footnote 9 ] They are thus
different, immutably so, in relevant respects, and the States'
interest in dealing with and providing for them is plainly a
legitimate one. [ Footnote
10 ] How this large and diversified group is to be treated Page 473 U. S. 443 under the law is a difficult and often a technical matter, very
much a task for legislators guided by qualified professionals, and
not by the perhaps ill-informed opinions of the judiciary.
Heightened scrutiny inevitably involves substantive judgments about
legislative decisions, and we doubt that the predicate for such
judicial oversight is present where the classification deals with
mental retardation.
Second, the distinctive legislative response, both national and
state, to the plight of those who are mentally retarded
demonstrates not only that they have unique problems, but also that
the lawmakers have been addressing their difficulties in a manner
that belies a continuing antipathy or prejudice and a corresponding
need for more intrusive oversight by the judiciary. Thus, the
Federal Government has not only outlawed discrimination against the
mentally retarded in federally funded programs, see § 504
of the Rehabilitation Act of 1973, 29 U.S.C. § 794, but it has also
provided the retarded with the right to receive "appropriate
treatment, services, and habilitation" in a setting that is "least
restrictive of [their] personal liberty." Developmental
Disabilities Assistance and Bill of Rights Act, 42 U.S.C. §§
6010(1), (2). In addition, the Government has conditioned federal
education funds on a State's assurance that retarded children will
enjoy an education that, "to the maximum extent appropriate," is
integrated with that of nonmentally retarded children. Education of
the Handicapped Act, 20 U.S.C. § 1412(5)(B). The Government has
also facilitated the hiring of the mentally retarded into the
federal civil service by exempting them from the requirement of
competitive examination. Page 473 U. S. 444 See 5 CFR § 213.3102(t) (1984). The State of Texas has
similarly enacted legislation that acknowledges the special status
of the mentally retarded by conferring certain rights upon them,
such as "the right to live in the least restrictive setting
appropriate to [their] individual needs and abilities," including
"the right to live . . . in a group home." Mentally Retarded
Persons Act of 1977, Tex.Rev.Civ.Stat.Ann., Art. 5547-300, § 7
(Vernon Supp.1985). [ Footnote
11 ]
Such legislation thus singling out the retarded for special
treatment reflects the real and undeniable differences between the
retarded and others. That a civilized and decent society expects
and approves such legislation indicates that governmental
consideration of those differences in the vast majority of
situations is not only legitimate but also desirable. It may be, as
CLC contends, that legislation designed to benefit, rather than
disadvantage, the retarded would generally withstand examination
under a test of heightened scrutiny. See Brief for
Respondents 38-41. The relevant inquiry, however, is whether
heightened scrutiny is constitutionally mandated in the first
instance. Even assuming that many of these laws could be shown to
be substantially related to an important governmental purpose,
merely requiring the legislature to justify its efforts in these
terms may lead it to refrain from acting at all. Much recent
legislation intended to benefit the retarded also assumes the need
for measures that might be perceived to disadvantage them. The
Education of the Handicapped Act, for example, requires an
"appropriate" education, not one that is equal in all respects Page 473 U. S. 445 to the education of nonretarded children; clearly, admission to
a class that exceeded the abilities of a retarded child would not
be appropriate. [ Footnote
12 ] Similarly, the Developmental Disabilities Assistance Act
and the Texas Act give the retarded the right to live only in the
"least restrictive setting" appropriate to their abilities,
implicitly assuming the need for at least some restrictions that
would not be imposed on others. [ Footnote 13 ] Especially given the wide variation in the
abilities and needs of the retarded themselves, governmental bodies
must have a certain amount of flexibility and freedom from judicial
oversight in shaping and limiting their remedial efforts.
Third, the legislative response, which could hardly have
occurred and survived without public support, negates any claim
that the mentally retarded are politically powerless in the sense
that they have no ability to attract the attention of the
lawmakers. Any minority can be said to be powerless to assert
direct control over the legislature, but if that were a criterion
for higher level scrutiny by the courts, much economic and social
legislation would now be suspect.
Fourth, if the large and amorphous class of the mentally
retarded were deemed quasi-suspect for the reasons given by the
Court of Appeals, it would be difficult to find a principled way to
distinguish a variety of other groups who have perhaps immutable
disabilities setting them off from others, who cannot themselves
mandate the desired legislative responses, and who can claim some
degree of prejudice from at least part of the public at large. One
need mention in this respect only Page 473 U. S. 446 the aging, the disabled, the mentally ill, and the infirm. We
are reluctant to set out on that course, and we decline to do
so.
Doubtless, there have been and there will continue to be
instances of discrimination against the retarded that are, in fact,
invidious, and that are properly subject to judicial correction
under constitutional norms. But the appropriate method of reaching
such instances is not to create a new quasi-suspect classification
and subject all governmental action based on that classification to
more searching evaluation. Rather, we should look to the likelihood
that governmental action premised on a particular classification is
valid as a general matter, not merely to the specifics of the case
before us. Because mental retardation is a characteristic that the
government may legitimately take into account in a wide range of
decisions, and because both State and Federal Governments have
recently committed themselves to assisting the retarded, we will
not presume that any given legislative action, even one that
disadvantages retarded individuals, is rooted in considerations
that the Constitution will not tolerate.
Our refusal to recognize the retarded as a quasi-suspect class
does not leave them entirely unprotected from invidious
discrimination. To withstand equal protection review, legislation
that distinguishes between the mentally retarded and others must be
rationally related to a legitimate governmental purpose. This
standard, we believe, affords government the latitude necessary
both to pursue policies designed to assist the retarded in
realizing their full potential, and to freely and efficiently
engage in activities that burden the retarded in what is
essentially an incidental manner. The State may not rely on a
classification whose relationship to an asserted goal is so
attenuated as to render the distinction arbitrary or irrational. See Zobel v. Williams, 457 U. S. 55 , 457 U. S. 61 -63
(1982); United States Dept. of Agriculture v. Moreno, 413 U. S. 528 , 413 U. S. 535 (1973). Furthermore, some objectives -- Page 473 U. S. 447 such as "a bare . . . desire to harm a politically unpopular
group," id. at 413 U. S. 534 -- are not legitimate state interests. See also Zobel,
supra, at 457 U. S. 63 .
Beyond that, the mentally retarded, like others, have and retain
their substantive constitutional rights in addition to the right to
be treated equally by the law. IV We turn to the issue of the validity of the zoning ordinance
insofar as it requires a special use permit for homes for the
mentally retarded. [ Footnote
14 ] We inquire first whether requiring a special use permit for
the Featherston home in the circumstances here deprives respondents
of the equal protection of the laws. If it does, there will be no
occasion to decide whether the special use permit provision is
facially invalid where the mentally retarded are involved, or to
put it another way, whether the city may never insist on a special
use permit for a home for the mentally retarded in an R-3 zone.
This is the preferred course of adjudication, since it enables
courts to avoid making unnecessarily broad constitutional
judgments. Brockett v. Spokane Arcades, Inc., 472 U.
S. 491 , 472 U. S.
501 -502 (1985); United States v. Grace, 461 U. S. 171 (1983); NAACP v. Button, 371 U. S. 415 (1963).
The constitutional issue is clearly posed. The city does not
require a special use permit in an R-3 zone for apartment houses,
multiple dwellings, boarding and lodging houses, fraternity or
sorority houses, dormitories, apartment hotels, hospitals,
sanitariums, nursing homes for convalescents or the aged (other
than for the insane or feeble-minded or alcoholics or drug
addicts), private clubs or fraternal orders, and other specified
uses. It does, however, insist on a special permit for the
Featherston home, and it does so, as the District Court found,
because it would be a facility for the mentally Page 473 U. S. 448 retarded. May the city require the permit for this facility when
other care and multiple-dwelling facilities are freely
permitted?
It is true, as already pointed out, that the mentally retarded,
as a group, are indeed different from others not sharing their
misfortune, and in this respect they may be different from those
who would occupy other facilities that would be permitted in an R-3
zone without a special permit. But this difference is largely
irrelevant unless the Featherston home and those who would occupy
it would threaten legitimate interests of the city in a way that
other permitted uses such as boarding houses and hospitals would
not. Because, in our view, the record does not reveal any rational
basis for believing that the Featherston home would pose any
special threat to the city's legitimate interests, we affirm the
judgment below insofar as it holds the ordinance invalid as applied
in this case.
The District Court found that the City Council's insistence on
the permit rested on several factors. First, the Council was
concerned with the negative attitude of the majority of property
owners located within 200 feet of the Featherston facility, as well
as with the fears of elderly residents of the neighborhood. But
mere negative attitudes, or fear, unsubstantiated by factors which
are properly cognizable in a zoning proceeding, are not permissible
bases for treating a home for the mentally retarded differently
from apartment houses, multiple dwellings, and the like. It is
plain that the electorate as a whole, whether by referendum or
otherwise, could not order city action violative of the Equal
Protection Clause, Lucas v. Forty-Fourth General Assembly of
Colorado, 377 U. S. 713 , 377 U. S.
736 -737 (1964), and the city may not avoid the
strictures of that Clause by deferring to the wishes or objections
of some fraction of the body politic. "Private biases may be
outside the reach of the law, but the law cannot, directly or
indirectly, give them effect." Palmore v. Sidoti, 466 U. S. 429 , 466 U. S. 433 (1984). Page 473 U. S. 449 Second, the Council had two objections to the location of the
facility. It was concerned that the facility was across the street
from a junior high school, and it feared that the students might
harass the occupants of the Featherston home. But the school itself
is attended by about 30 mentally retarded students, and denying a
permit based on such vague, undifferentiated fears is again
permitting some portion of the community to validate what would
otherwise be an equal protection violation. The other objection to
the home's location was that it was located on "a five-hundred-year
flood plain." This concern with the possibility of a flood,
however, can hardly be based on a distinction between the
Featherston home and, for example, nursing homes, homes for
convalescents or the aged, or sanitariums or hospitals, any of
which could be located on the Featherston site without obtaining a
special use permit. The same may be said of another concern of the
Council -- doubts about the legal responsibility for actions which
the mentally retarded might take. If there is no concern about
legal responsibility with respect to other uses that would be
permitted in the area, such as boarding and fraternity houses, it
is difficult to believe that the groups of mildly or moderately
mentally retarded individuals who would live at 201 Featherston
would present any different or special hazard.
Fourth, the Council was concerned with the size of the home and
the number of people that would occupy it. The District Court
found, and the Court of Appeals repeated, that,
"[i]f the potential residents of the Featherston Street home
were not mentally retarded, but the home was the same in all other
respects, its use would be permitted under the city's zoning
ordinance."
App. 93; 726 F.2d at 200. Given this finding, there would be no
restrictions on the number of people who could occupy this home as
a boarding house, nursing home, family dwelling, fraternity house,
or dormitory. The question is whether it is rational to treat the
mentally retarded differently. It is true that they suffer
disability Page 473 U. S. 450 not shared by others, but why this difference warrants a density
regulation that others need not observe is not at all apparent. At
least this record does not clarify how, in this connection, the
characteristics of the intended occupants of the Featherston home
rationally justify denying to those occupants what would be
permitted to groups occupying the same site for different purposes.
Those who would live in the Featherston home are the type of
individuals who, with supporting staff, satisfy federal and state
standards for group housing in the community; and there is no
dispute that the home would meet the federal
square-footage-per-resident requirement for facilities of this
type. See 42 CFR § 442.447 (1984). In the words of the
Court of Appeals,
"[t]he City never justifies its apparent view that other people
can live under such 'crowded' conditions when mentally retarded
persons cannot."
726 F.2d at 202.
In the courts below, the city also urged that the ordinance is
aimed at avoiding concentration of population and at lessening
congestion of the streets. These concerns obviously fail to explain
why apartment houses, fraternity and sorority houses, hospitals and
the like, may freely locate in the area without a permit. So, too,
the expressed worry about fire hazards, the serenity of the
neighborhood, and the avoidance of danger to other residents fail
rationally to justify singling out a home such as 201 Featherston
for the special use permit, yet imposing no such restrictions on
the many other uses freely permitted in the neighborhood.
The short of it is that requiring the permit in this case
appears to us to rest on an irrational prejudice against the
mentally retarded, including those who would occupy the Featherston
facility and who would live under the closely supervised and highly
regulated conditions expressly provided for by state and federal
law.
The judgment of the Court of Appeals is affirmed insofar as it
invalidates the zoning ordinance as applied to the Featherston
home. The judgment is otherwise vacated, and the case is
remanded. It is so ordered. Page 473 U. S. 451 [ Footnote 1 ]
Cleburne Living Center, Inc., is now known as Community Living
Concepts, Inc. Hannah is the vice-president and part owner of CLC.
For convenience, both Hannah and CLC will be referred to as "CLC."
A third respondent is Advocacy, Inc., a nonprofit corporation that
provides legal services to developmentally disabled persons.
[ Footnote 2 ]
It was anticipated that the home would be operated as a private
Level I Intermediate Care Facility for the Mentally Retarded, or
ICF-MR, under a program providing for joint federal-state
reimbursement for residential services for mentally retarded
clients. See 42 U.S.C. § 1396d(a)(15); Tex. Human
Resources Code Ann. § 32.001 et seq. (1980 and Supp.1985).
ICF-MR's are covered by extensive regulations and guidelines
established by the United States Department of Health and Human
Services and the Texas Departments of Human Resources, Mental
Health and Mental Retardation, and Health. See App. 92. See also 42 CFR § 442.1 et seq. (1984); 40
Tex.Adm.Code § 27.101 et seq. (1981).
[ Footnote 3 ]
The site of the home is in an area zoned "R-3," an "Apartment
House District." App. 51. Section 8 of the Cleburne zoning
ordinance, in pertinent part, allows the following uses in an R-3
district:
"1. Any use permitted in District R-2."
"2. Apartment houses, or multiple dwellings."
"3. Boarding and lodging houses."
"4. Fraternity or sorority houses and dormitories."
"5. Apartment hotels."
"6. Hospitals, sanitariums, nursing homes or homes for
convalescents or aged, other than for the insane or feeble-minded or alcoholics or drug addicts."
"7. Private clubs or fraternal orders, except those whose chief
activity is carried on as a business."
"8. Philanthropic or eleemosynary institutions, other than penal
institutions."
"9. Accessory uses customarily incident to any of the above
uses. . . ." Id. at 60-61 (emphasis added).
Section 16 of the ordinance specifies the uses for which a
special use permit is required. These include "[h]ospitals for the
insane or feeble-minded, or alcoholic [ sic ] or drug
addicts, or penal or correctional institutions." Id. at
63. Section 16 provides that a permit for such a use may be issued
by "the Governing Body, after public hearing, and after
recommendation of the Planning Commission." All special use permits
are limited to one year, and each applicant is required "to obtain
the signatures of the property owners within two hundred (200) feet
of the property to be used." Ibid. [ Footnote 4 ]
The city's Planning and Zoning Commission had earlier held a
hearing and voted to deny the permit. Id. at 91.
[ Footnote 5 ]
The District Court also rejected CLC's other claims, including
the argument that the city had violated due process by improperly
delegating its zoning powers to the owners of adjoining property.
App. 105. Cf. Washington ex rel. Seattle Title Trust Co. v.
Roberge, 278 U. S. 116 (1928). The Court of Appeals did not address this argument, and it
has not been raised by the parties in this Court.
[ Footnote 6 ]
The District Court had found:
"Group homes currently are the principal community living
alternatives for persons who are mentally retarded. The
availability of such a home in communities is an essential
ingredient of normal living patterns for persons who are mentally
retarded, and each factor that makes such group homes harder to
establish operates to exclude persons who are mentally retarded
from the community."
App. 94.
[ Footnote 7 ]
The city relied on a recently passed state regulation limiting
group homes to 6 residents in support of its argument that the CLC
home would be overcrowded with 13. But, the Court of Appeals
observed, the city had failed to justify its apparent view that any
other group of 13 people could live under these allegedly "crowded"
conditions, nor had it explained why 6 would be acceptable, but 13
not.
CLC concedes that it could not qualify for certification under
the new Texas regulation. Tr. of Oral Rearg. 31. The Court of
Appeals stated that the new regulation applied only to applications
made after May 1, 1982, and therefore did not apply to the CLC
home. 726 F.2d at 202. The regulation itself contains no
grandfather clause, see App. 78-81, and the District Court
made no specific finding on this point. See id. at 96.
However, the State has asserted in an amici brief filed in
this Court that " the six-bed rule' would not pose an obstacle
to the proposed Featherston Street group home at issue in this
case." Brief for State of Texas et al. as Amici
Curiae 15, n. 7. If the six-bed requirement were to apply to
the home, there is a serious possibility that CLC would no longer
be interested in injunctive relief. David Southern, an officer of
CLC, testified that "to break even on a facility of this type, you
have to have at least ten or eleven residents." App. 32. However,
because CLC requested damages as well as an injunction, see
id. at 15, the case would not be moot. After oral argument, the city brought to our attention the
recent enactment of a Texas statute, effective September 1, 1985,
providing that "family homes" are permitted uses in "all
residential zones or districts in this state." The statute defines
a "family home" as a community-based residence housing no more than
six disabled persons, including the mentally retarded, along with
two supervisory personnel. The statute does not appear to affect
the city's actions with regard to group homes that plan to house
more than six residents. The enactment of this legislation
therefore does not affect our disposition of this case.
[ Footnote 8 ] Macon Assn. for Retarded Citizens v. Macon-Bibb County
Planning and Zoning Comm'n, 252 Ga. 484, 314 S.E.2d 218 (1984), dism'd for want of a substantial federal question, 469 U.S. 802 (1984), has no controlling effect on this case. Macon Assn. for Retarded Citizens involved an ordinance
that had the effect of excluding a group home for the retarded only
because it restricted dwelling units to those occupied by a single
family, defined as no more than four unrelated persons. In Village of Belle Terre v. Boraas, 416 U. S.
1 (1974), we upheld the constitutionality of a similar
ordinance, and the Georgia Supreme Court, in Macon Assn., specifically held that the ordinance did not discriminate against
the retarded. 252 Ga., at 487, 314 S.E.2d at 221.
[ Footnote 9 ]
Mentally retarded individuals fall into four distinct
categories. The vast majority -- approximately 89% -- are
classified as "mildly" retarded, meaning that their IQ is between
50 and 70. Approximately 6% are "moderately" retarded, with IQs
between 35 and 50. The remaining two categories are "severe" (IQs
of 20 to 35) and "profound" (IQs below 20). These last two
categories together account for about 5% of the mentally retarded
population. App. 39 (testimony of Dr. Philip Roos).
Mental retardation is not defined by reference to intelligence
or IQ alone, however. The American Association on Mental Deficiency
(AAMD) has defined mental retardation as
"'significantly subaverage general intellectual functioning
existing concurrently with deficits in adaptive behavior and
manifested during the developmental period.'"
Brief for AAMD et al. as Amici Curiae 3
(quoting AAMD, Classification in Mental Retardation 1 (H. Grossman
ed.1983)). "Deficits in adaptive behavior" are limitations on
general ability to meet the standards of maturation, learning,
personal independence, and social responsibility expected for an
individual's age level and cultural group. Brief for AAMD et
al. as Amici Curiae 4, n. 1. Mental retardation is
caused by a variety of factors, some genetic, some environmental,
and some unknown. Id. at 4.
[ Footnote 10 ]
As Dean Ely has observed:
"Surely one has to feel sorry for a person disabled by something
he or she can't do anything about, but I'm not aware of any reason
to suppose that elected officials are unusually unlikely to share
that feeling. Moreover, classifications based on physical
disability and intelligence are typically accepted as legitimate,
even by judges and commentators who assert that immutability is
relevant. The explanation, when one is given, is that those
characteristics (unlike the one the commentator is trying to render
suspect) are often relevant to legitimate purposes. At that point,
there's not much left of the immutability theory, is there?"
J. Ely, Democracy and Distrust 150 (1980) (footnote omitted). See also id. at 154-155.
[ Footnote 11 ]
CLC originally sought relief under the Act, but voluntarily
dismissed this pendent state claim when the District Court
indicated that its presence might make abstention appropriate. The
Act had never been construed by the Texas courts. App. 12, 14,
84-87.
A number of States have passed legislation prohibiting zoning
that excludes the retarded. See, e.g., Cal.Health &
Safety Code Ann. § 1566 et seq. (West 1979 and Supp.1985);
Conn.Gen.Stat. § 8-3e (Supp.1985); N.D.Cent.Code § 25-16-14(2)
(Supp.1983); R.I.Gen.Laws. § 45-24-22 (1980). See also Md.
Health Code Ann. § 7-102 (Supp.1984).
[ Footnote 12 ]
The Act, which specifically included the mentally retarded in
its definition of handicapped, see 20 U.S.C. § 1401(1),
also recognizes the great variations within the classification of
retarded children. The Act requires that school authorities devise
an "individualized educational program," § 1401 (19), that is
"tailored to the unique needs of the handicapped child." Hendrick Hudson District Board of Education v. Rowley, 458 U. S. 176 , 458 U. S. 181 (1982).
[ Footnote 13 ]
The Developmental Disabilities Assistance Act also withholds
public funds from any program that does not prohibit the use of
physical restraint "unless absolutely necessary." 42 U.S.C. §
6010(3).
[ Footnote 14 ]
It goes without saying that there is nothing before us with
respect to the validity of requiring a special use permit for the
other uses listed in the ordinance. See n 3, supra. JUSTICE STEVENS, with whom THE CHIEF JUSTICE joins,
concurring.
The Court of Appeals disposed of this case as if a critical
question to be decided were which of three clearly defined
standards of equal protection review should be applied to a
legislative classification discriminating against.the mentally
retarded. [ Footnote 2/1 ] In fact,
our cases have not delineated three -- or even one or two -- such
well-defined standards. [ Footnote
2/2 ] Rather, our cases reflect a continuum of judgmental
responses to differing classifications which have been explained in
opinions by terms ranging from "strict scrutiny" at one extreme to
"rational basis" at the other. I have never been persuaded that
these so-called "standards" adequately explain the decisional
process. [ Footnote 2/3 ] Cases
involving classifications based on alienage, Page 473 U. S. 452 illegal residency, illegitimacy, gender, age, or -- as in this
case -- mental retardation, do not fit well into sharply defined
classifications.
"I am inclined to believe that what has become known as the
[tiered] analysis of equal protection claims does not describe a
completely logical method of deciding cases, but rather is a method
the Court has employed to explain decisions that actually apply a
single standard in a reasonably consistent fashion." Craig v. Boren, 429 U. S. 190 , 429 U. S. 212 (1976) (STEVENS, J., concurring). In my own approach to these
cases, I have always asked myself whether I could find a "rational
basis" for the classification at issue. The term "rational," of
course, includes a requirement that an impartial lawmaker could
logically believe that the classification would serve a legitimate
public purpose that transcends the harm to the members of the
disadvantaged class. [ Footnote 2/4 ]
Thus, the word "rational" -- for me at least -- includes elements
of legitimacy and neutrality that must always characterize the
performance of the sovereign's duty to govern impartially.
[ Footnote 2/5 ]
The rational basis test, properly understood, adequately
explains why a law that deprives a person of the right to vote
because his skin has a different pigmentation than that of other
voters violates the Equal Protection Clause. It would be utterly
irrational to limit the franchise on the basis of height or weight;
it is equally invalid to limit it on the basis of skin color. None
of these attributes has any bearing at all Page 473 U. S. 453 on the citizen's willingness or ability to exercise that civil
right. We do not need to apply a special standard, or to apply
"strict scrutiny," or even "heightened scrutiny," to decide such
cases.
In every equal protection case, we have to ask certain basic
questions. What class is harmed by the legislation, and has it been
subjected to a "tradition of disfavor" by our laws? [ Footnote 2/6 ] What is the public purpose
that is being served by the law? What is the characteristic of the
disadvantaged class that justifies the disparate treatment?
[ Footnote 2/7 ] In most cases, the
answer to these questions will tell us whether the statute has a
"rational basis." The answers will result in the virtually
automatic invalidation of racial classifications and in the
validation of most economic classifications, but they will provide
differing results in cases involving classifications based on
alienage, [ Footnote 2/8 ] gender,
[ Footnote 2/9 ] or illegitimacy.
[ Footnote 2/10 ] But that is not
because we Page 473 U. S. 454 apply an "intermediate standard of review" in these cases;
rather, it is because the characteristics of these groups are
sometimes relevant and sometimes irrelevant to a valid public
purpose, or, more specifically, to the purpose that the challenged
laws purportedly intended to serve. [ Footnote 2/11 ]
Every law that places the mentally retarded in a special class
is not presumptively irrational. The differences between mentally
retarded persons and those with greater mental capacity are
obviously relevant to certain legislative decisions. An impartial
lawmaker -- indeed, even a member of a class of persons defined as
mentally retarded -- could rationally vote in favor of a law
providing funds for special education and special treatment for the
mentally retarded. A mentally retarded person could also recognize
that he is a member of a class that might need special supervision
in some situations, both to protect himself and to protect others.
Restrictions on his right to drive cars or to operate hazardous
equipment might well seem rational even though they deprived him of
employment opportunities and the kind of freedom of travel enjoyed
by other citizens.
"That a civilized and decent society expects and approves such
legislation indicates that governmental consideration of those
differences in the vast majority of situations is not only
legitimate, but also desirable." Ante at 473 U. S.
444 .
Even so, the Court of Appeals correctly observed that, through
ignorance and prejudice, the mentally retarded "have been subjected
to a history of unfai and often grotesque mistreatment." 726 F.2d
191, 197 (CA5 1984). The dis-
crimination against the mentally retarded that is at issue in
this case is the city's decision to require an annual special use
permit before property in an apartment house district may be used
as a group home for persons who are mildly retarded. The record
convinces me that this permit was required because of the
irrational fears of neighboring property owners, rather than for
the protection of the mentally retarded persons who would reside in
respondent's home. [ Footnote
2/12 ]
Although the city argued in the Court of Appeals that legitimate
interests of the neighbors justified the restriction, the court
unambiguously rejected that argument. Id. at 201. In this
Court, the city has argued that the discrimination was really
motivated by a desire to protect the mentally retarded from the
hazards presented by the neighborhood. Zoning ordinances are not
usually justified on any such basis, and in this case, for the
reasons explained by the Court, ante at 473 U. S.
447 -450, I find that justification wholly unconvincing.
I cannot believe that a rational member of this disadvantaged class
could ever approve of the discriminatory application of the city's
ordinance in this case.
Accordingly, I join the opinion of the Court. Page 473 U. S. 455 [ Footnote 2/1 ]
The three standards -- "rationally related to a legitimate state
interest," "somewhat heightened review," and "strict scrutiny" are
briefly described ante at 473 U. S. 440 ,
441.
[ Footnote 2/2 ]
In United States Railroad Retirement Board v. Fritz, 449 U. S. 166 , 449 U. S.
176 -177, n. 10 (1980), after citing 11 cases applying
the rational basis standard, the Court stated:
"The most arrogant legal scholar would not claim that all of
these cases applied a uniform or consistent test under equal
protection principles."
Commenting on the intermediate standard of review in his dissent
in Craig v. Boren, 429 U. S. 190 , 429 U. S.
220 -221 (1976), JUSTICE REHNQUIST wrote:
"I would think we have had enough difficulty with the two
standards of review which our cases have recognized -- the norm of
'rational basis,' and the 'compelling state interest' required
where a 'suspect classification' is involved -- so as to counsel
weightily against the insertion of still another 'standard' between
those two. How is this Court to divine what objectives are
important? How is it to determine whether a particular law is
'substantially' related to the achievement of such objective,
rather than related in some other way to its achievement? Both of
the phrases used are so diaphanous and elastic as to invite
subjective judicial preferences or prejudices relating to
particular types of legislation, masquerading as judgments whether
such legislation is directed at 'important' objectives or, whether
the relationship to those objectives is 'substantial' enough."
[ Footnote 2/3 ] Cf. San Antonio Independent School District v.
Rodriguez, 411 U. S. 1 , 411 U. S. 98 (1973) (MARSHALL, J., dissenting, joined by Douglas, J.)
(criticizing "the Court's rigidified approach to equal protection
analysis").
[ Footnote 2/4 ]
"I therefore believe that we must discover a correlation between
the classification and either the actual purpose of the statute or
a legitimate purpose that we may reasonably presume to have
motivated an impartial legislature. If the adverse impact on the
disfavored class is an apparent aim of the legislature, its
impartiality would be suspect. If, however, the adverse impact may
reasonably be viewed as an acceptable cost of achieving a larger
goal, an impartial lawmaker could rationally decide that that cost
should be incurred." United States Railroad Retirement Board v. Fritz, 449
U.S. at 449 U. S.
180 -181 (STEVENS, J., concurring in judgment).
[ Footnote 2/5 ] See Lehr v. Robertson, 463 U.
S. 248 , 463 U. S. 265 (1983); Hampton v. Mow Sun Wong, 426 U. S.
88 , 426 U. S. 100 (1976).
[ Footnote 2/6 ]
The Court must be especially vigilant in evaluating the
rationality of any classification involving a group that has been
subjected to a
"tradition of disfavor, [for] a traditional classification is
more likely to be used without pausing to consider its
justification than is a newly created classification. Habit, rather
than analysis, makes it seem acceptable and natural to distinguish
between male and female, alien and citizen, legitimate and
illegitimate; for too much of our history, there was the same
inertia in distinguishing between black and white. But that sort of
stereotyped reaction may have no rational relationship -- other
than pure prejudicial discrimination -- to the stated purpose for
which the classification is being made." Mathews v. Lucas, 427 U. S. 495 , 427 U. S.
520 -521 (1976) (STEVENS, J., dissenting). See also
New York Transit Authority v. Beazer, 440 U.
S. 568 , 440 U. S. 593 (1979).
[ Footnote 2/7 ] See Foley v. Connelie, 435 U.
S. 291 , 435 U. S. 308 (1978) (STEVENS, J., dissenting).
[ Footnote 2/8 ] See Mathews v. Diaz, 426 U. S. 67 , 426 U. S. 78 -80
(1976); compare Sugarman v. Dougall, 413 U.
S. 634 (1973), and In re Griffiths, 413 U. S. 717 (1973), with Ambach v. Norwick, 441 U. S.
68 (1979), and Foley v. Connelie, 435 U.
S. 291 (1978).
[ Footnote 2/9 ] Compare Reed v. Reed, 404 U. S. 71 (1971), and Califano v. Goldfarb, 430 U.
S. 199 (1977), with Personnel Administrator of Mass.
v. Feeney, 442 U. S. 256 (1979), and Heckler v. Mathews, 465 U.
S. 728 (1984).
[ Footnote 2/10 ] Compare Lalli v. Lalli, 439 U.
S. 259 (1978), with Trimble v. Gordon, 430 U. S. 762 (1977).
[ Footnote 2/11 ] See Michael M. v. Superior Court of Sonoma County, 450 U. S. 464 , 450 U. S.
497 -498, and n. 4 (1981) (STEVENS, J., dissenting). See also Caban v. Mohammed, 441 U.
S. 380 , 441 U. S.
406 -407 (1979) (STEVENS, J., dissenting) ("But as a
matter of equal protection analysis, it is perfectly obvious that
at the time and immediately after a child is born our of wedlock,
differences between men and women justify some differential
treatment of the mother and father in the adoption process.").
[ Footnote 2/12 ]
In fact, the ordinance provides that each applicant for a
special use permit "shall be required to obtain the signatures of
the property owners within two hundred (200) feet of the property
to be used." App. 63.
JUSTICE MARSHALL, with whom JUSTICE BRENNAN and JUSTICE BLACKMUN
join, concurring in the judgment in part and dissenting in
part.
The Court holds that all retarded individuals cannot be grouped
together as the "feeble-minded" and deemed presumptively unfit to
live in a community. Underlying this holding is the principle that
mental retardation, per se, cannot be a proxy for
depriving retarded people of their rights and interests without
regard to variations in individual ability. Page 473 U. S. 456 With this holding and principle I agree. The Equal Protection
Clause requires attention to the capacities and needs of retarded
people as individuals.
I cannot agree, however, with the way in which the Court reaches
its result or with the narrow, as-applied remedy it provides for
the city of Cleburne's equal protection violation. The Court holds
the ordinance invalid on rational basis grounds, and disclaims that
anything special, in the form of heightened scrutiny, is taking
place. Yet Cleburne's ordinance surely would be valid under the
traditional rational basis test applicable to economic and
commercial regulation. In my view, it is important to articulate,
as the Court does not, the facts and principles that justify
subjecting this zoning ordinance to the searching review -- the
heightened scrutiny -- that actually leads to its invalidation.
Moreover, in invalidating Cleburne's exclusion of the
"feeble-minded" only as applied to respondents, rather than on its
face, the Court radically departs from our equal protection
precedents. Because I dissent from this novel and truncated remedy,
and because I cannot accept the Court's disclaimer that no "more
exacting standard" than ordinary rational basis review is being
applied, ante at 473 U. S. 442 ,
I write separately. I At the outset, two curious and paradoxical aspects of the
Court's opinion must be noted. First, because the Court invalidates
Cleburne's zoning ordinance on rational basis grounds, the Court's
wide-ranging discussion of heightened scrutiny is wholly
superfluous to the decision of this case. This "two for the price
of one" approach to constitutional decisionmaking -- rendering two
constitutional rulings where one is enough to decide the case --
stands on their head traditional and deeply embedded principles
governing exercise of the Court's Article III power. Just a few
weeks ago, the Court
"call[ed] to mind two of the cardinal rules governing Page 473 U. S. 457 the federal courts: 'One, never to anticipate a question of
constitutional law in advance of the necessity of deciding it; the
other never to formulate a rule of constitutional law broader than
is required by the precise facts to which it is to be
applied.'" Brockett v. Spokane Arcades, Inc., 472 U.
S. 491 , 472 U. S. 501 (1985) (WHITE, J.) (quoting Liverpool, New York &
Philadelphia S.S. Co. v. Commissioners of Emigration, 113 U. S. 33 , 113 U. S. 39 (1885)). [ Footnote 3/1 ] When a
lower court correctly decides a case, albeit on what this Court
concludes are unnecessary constitutional grounds, [ Footnote 3/2 ] "our usual custom" is not to compound
the problem by following suit, but rather to affirm on the
narrower, dispositive ground available. Alexander v.
Louisiana, 405 U. S. 625 , 405 U. S. 633 (1972). [ Footnote 3/3 ] The Court
offers no principled justification for departing from these
principles, nor, given our equal protection precedents, could it. See Mississippi University for Women v. Hogan, 458 U. S. 718 , 458 U. S. 724 ,
n. 9 (1982) (declining to address strict scrutiny when heightened
scrutiny sufficient to invalidate action challenged); Stanton
v. Stanton, 421 U. S. 7 , 421 U. S. 13 (1975) Page 473 U. S. 458 (same); Hooper v. Bernalillo County Assessor, 472 U. S. 612 , 472 U. S. 618 (1985) (declining to reach heightened scrutiny in review of
residency-based classifications that fail rational basis test); Zobel v. Williams, 457 U. S. 55 , 457 U. S. 60 -61
(1982) (same); cf. Mitchell v. Forsyth, 472 U.
S. 511 , 472 U. S.
537 -538 (1985) (O'CONNOR, J., concurring in part).
Second, the Court's heightened scrutiny discussion is even more
puzzling given that Cleburne's ordinance is invalidated only after
being subjected to precisely the sort of probing inquiry associated
with heightened scrutiny. To be sure, the Court does not label its
handiwork heightened scrutiny, and perhaps the method employed must
hereafter be called "second order" rational basis review, rather
than "heightened scrutiny." But however labeled, the rational basis
test invoked today is most assuredly not the rational basis test of Williamson v. Lee Optical of Oklahoma, Inc., 348 U.
S. 483 (1955); Allied Stores of Ohio, Inc. v.
Bowers, 358 U. S. 522 (1959), and their progeny.
The Court, for example, concludes that legitimate concerns for
fire hazards or the serenity of the neighborhood do not justify
singling out respondents to bear the burdens of these concerns, for
analogous permitted uses appear to pose similar threats. Yet under
the traditional and most minimal version of the rational basis
test, "reform may take one step at a time, addressing itself to the
phase of the problem which seems most acute to the legislative
mind." Williamson v. Lee Optical of Oklahoma, Inc., supra, at 348 U. S. 489 ; see American Federation of Labor v. American Sash Co., 335 U. S. 538 (1949); Semler v. Dental Examiners, 294 U.
S. 608 (1935). The "record" is said not to support the
ordinance's classifications, ante at 473 U. S. 448 , 473 U. S. 450 ,
but under the traditional standard, we do not sift through the
record to determine whether policy decisions are squarely supported
by a firm factual foundation. Exxon Corp. v. Eagerton, 462 U. S. 176 , 462 U. S. 196 (1983); Minnesota v. Clover Leaf Creamery Co., 449 U. S. 456 , 449 U. S.
461 -462, Page 473 U. S. 459 449 U. S. 464 (1981); Firemen v. Chicago, R. I. & P. R. Co., 393 U. S. 129 , 393 U. S.
138 -139 (1968). Finally, the Court further finds it
"difficult to believe" that the retarded present different or
special hazards inapplicable to other groups. In normal
circumstances, the burden is not on the legislature to convince the
Court that the lines it has drawn are sensible; legislation is
presumptively constitutional, and a State "is not required to
resort to close distinctions or to maintain a precise, scientific
uniformity with reference" to its goals. Allied Stores of Ohio,
Inc. v. Bowers, supra, at 358 U. S. 527 ; Metropolis Theatre Co. v. City of Chicago, 228 U. S.
61 , 228 U. S. 68 -70
(1913).
I share the Court's criticisms of the overly broad lines that
Cleburne's zoning ordinance has drawn. But if the ordinance is to
be invalidated for its imprecise classifications, it must be
pursuant to more powerful scrutiny than the minimal rational basis
test used to review classifications affecting only economic and
commercial matters. The same imprecision in a similar ordinance
that required opticians but not optometrists to be licensed to
practice, see Williamson v. Lee Optical of Oklahoma, Inc.,
supra, or that excluded new but not old businesses from parts
of a community, see New Orleans v. Dukes, supra, would
hardly be fatal to the statutory scheme.
The refusal to acknowledge that something more than minimum
rationality review is at work here is, in my view, unfortunate in
at least two respects. [ Footnote
3/4 ] The suggestion that Page 473 U. S. 460 the traditional rational basis test allows this sort of
searching inquiry creates precedent for this Court and lower courts
to subject economic and commercial classifications to similar and
searching "ordinary" rational basis review -- a small and
regrettable step back toward the days of Lochner v. New
York, 198 U. S. 45 (1905). Moreover, by failing to articulate the factors that justify
today's "second order" rational basis review, the Court provides no
principled foundation for determining when more searching inquiry
is to be invoked. Lower courts are thus left in the dark on this
important question, and this Court remains unaccountable for its
decisions employing, or refusing to employ, particularly searching
scrutiny. Candor requires me to acknowledge the particular factors
that justify invalidating Cleburne's zoning ordinance under the
careful scrutiny it today receives. II I have long believed the level of scrutiny employed in an equal
protection case should vary with
"the constitutional and societal importance of the interest
adversely affected and the recognized invidiousness of the basis
upon which the particular classification is drawn." San Antonio Independent School District v. Rodriguez, 411 U. S. 1 , 411 U. S. 99 (1973) (MARSHALL, J., dissenting). See also Plyler v. Doe, 457 U. S. 202 , 457 U. S.
230 -231 (1982) (MARSHALL, J., concurring); Dandridge
v. Williams, 397 U. S. 471 , 397 U. S. 508 (1970) (MARSHALL, J., dissenting). When a zoning ordinance works to
exclude the retarded from all residential districts in a community,
these two considerations require that the ordinance be convincingly
justified as substantially furthering legitimate and important
purposes. Plyler, supra; Mississippi University for Women v.
Hogan, 458 U. S. 718 (1982); Frontiero v. Richardson, 411 U.
S. 677 (1973); Mills v. Habluetzel, 456 U. S. 91 (1982); see also Buchanan v. Warley, 245 U. S.
60 (1917). Page 473 U. S. 461 First, the interest of the retarded in establishing group homes
is substantial. The right to "establish a home" has long been
cherished as one of the fundamental liberties embraced by the Due
Process Clause. See Meyer v. Nebraska, 262 U.
S. 390 , 262 U. S. 399 (1923). For retarded adults, this right means living together in
group homes, for as deinstitutionalization has progressed, group
homes have become the primary means by which retarded adults can
enter life in the community. The District Court found as a matter
of fact that
"[t]he availability of such a home in communities is an
essential ingredient of normal living patterns for persons who are
mentally retarded, and each factor that makes such group homes
harder to establish operates to exclude persons who are mentally
retarded from the community."
App. to Pet. for Cert. A-8. Excluding group homes deprives the
retarded of much of what makes for human freedom and fulfillment --
the ability to form bonds and take part in the life of a community.
[ Footnote 3/5 ]
Second, the mentally retarded have been subject to a "lengthy
and tragic history," University of California Regents v.
Bakke, 438 U. S. 265 , 438 U. S. 303 (1978) (opinion of POWELL, J.), of segregation and discrimination
that can only be called grotesque. During much of the 19th century,
mental retardation was viewed as neither curable nor dangerous, and
the retarded were largely left to their own devices. [ Footnote 3/6 ] By the latter part of the
century and during the first decades of the new one, however,
social views of the retarded underwent a radical transformation.
Fueled by the rising tide of Social Darwinism, the "science" of
eugenics, and the extreme Page 473 U. S. 462 xenophobia of those years, [ Footnote
3/7 ] leading medical authorities and others began to portray
the "feeble-minded" as a "menace to society and civilization . . .
responsible in a large degree for many, if not all, of our social
problems." [ Footnote 3/8 ] A regime
of state-mandated segregation and degradation soon emerged that, in
its virulence and bigotry, rivaled, and indeed paralleled, the
worst excesses of Jim Crow. Massive custodial institutions were
built to warehouse the retarded for life; the aim was to halt
reproduction of the retarded and "nearly extinguish their race."
[ Footnote 3/9 ] Retarded children
were categorically excluded from Page 473 U. S. 463 public schools, based on the false stereotype that all were
ineducable and on the purported need to protect nonretarded
children from them. [ Footnote
3/10 ] State laws deemed the retarded "unfit for citizenship."
[ Footnote 3/11 ]
Segregation was accompanied by eugenic marriage and
sterilization laws that extinguished for the retarded one of the
"basic civil rights of man" -- the right to marry and procreate. Skinner v. Oklahoma ex rel. Williamson, 316 U.
S. 535 , 316 U. S. 541 (1942). Marriages of the retarded were made, and in some States
continue to be, not only voidable but also often a criminal
offense. [ Footnote 3/12 ] The
purpose of such limitations, which frequently applied only to women
of child-bearing age, was unabashedly eugenic: to prevent the
retarded from propagating. [ Footnote
3/13 ] To assure this end, 29 States enacted compulsory eugenic
sterilization laws between 1907 and 1931. J. Landman, Human
Sterilization 302-303 (1932). See Buck v. Bell, 274 U. S. 200 , 274 U. S. 207 (1927) (Holmes, J.); cf. 163 U. S. Ferguson, Page 473 U. S. 464 163 U. S. 537 (1896); Bradwell v.
Illinois , 16 Wall. 130, 83 U. S. 141 (1873) (Bradley, J., concurring in judgment).
Prejudice, once let loose, is not easily cabined. See
University of California Regents v. Bakke, 438 U.S. at 435 U. S. 395 (opinion of MARSHALL, J.). As of 1979, most States still
categorically disqualified "idiots" from voting, without regard to
individual capacity and with discretion to exclude left in the
hands of low-level election officials. [ Footnote 3/14 ] Not until Congress enacted the Education
of the Handicapped Act, 84 Stat. 175, as amended, 20 U.S.C. § 1400 et seq., were "the door[s] of public education" opened
wide to handicapped children. Hendrick Hudson District Board of
Education v. Rowley, 458 U. S. 176 , 458 U. S. 192 (1982). [ Footnote 3/15 ] But most
important, lengthy and continuing isolation of the retarded has
perpetuated the ignorance, irrational fears, and stereotyping that
long have plagued them. [ Footnote
3/16 ]
In light of the importance of the interest at stake and the
history of discrimination the retarded have suffered, the Equal
Protection Clause requires us to do more than review the
distinctions drawn by Cleburne's zoning ordinance as if they
appeared in a taxing statute or in economic or commercial
legislation. [ Footnote 3/17 ] The
searching scrutiny I would give to restrictions Page 473 U. S. 465 on the ability of the retarded to establish community group
homes leads me to conclude that Cleburne's vague generalizations
for classifying the "feeble-minded" with drug addicts, alcoholics,
and the insane, and excluding them where the elderly, the ill, the
boarder, and the transient are allowed, are not substantial or
important enough to overcome the suspicion that the ordinance rests
on impermissible assumptions or outmoded and perhaps invidious
stereotypes. See Plyler v. Doe, 457 U.
S. 202 (1982); Roberts v. United States
Jaycees, 468 U. S. 609 (1984); Mississippi University for Women v. Hogan, 458 U. S. 718 (1982); Mills v. Habluetzel, 456 U. S.
91 (1982). III In its effort to show that Cleburne's ordinance can be struck
down under no "more exacting standard . . . than is normally
accorded economic and social legislation," ante at 473 U. S. 442 ,
the Court offers several justifications as to why the retarded do
not warrant heightened judicial solicitude. These justifications,
however, find no support in our heightened scrutiny precedents, and
cannot withstand logical analysis.
The Court downplays the lengthy "history of purposeful unequal
treatment" of the retarded, see San Antonio Independent School
District v. Rodriguez, 411 U.S. at 411 U. S. 28 , by
pointing to recent legislative action that is said to "beli[e] a
continuing antipathy or prejudice." Ante at 473 U. S. 443 .
Building on this point, the Court similarly concludes that the
retarded Page 473 U. S. 466 are not "politically powerless," and deserve no greater judicial
protection than "[a]ny minority" that wins some political battles
and loses others. Ante at 473 U. S. 445 .
The import of these conclusions, it seems, is that the only
discrimination courts may remedy is the discrimination they alone
are perspicacious enough to see. Once society begins to recognize
certain practices as discriminatory, in part because previously
stigmatized groups have mobilized politically to lift this stigma,
the Court would refrain from approaching such practices with the
added skepticism of heightened scrutiny.
Courts, however, do not sit or act in a social vacuum. Moral
philosophers may debate whether certain inequalities are absolute
wrongs, but history makes clear that constitutional principles of
equality, like constitutional principles of liberty, property, and
due process, evolve over time; what once was a "natural" and
"self-evident" ordering later comes to be seen as an artificial and
invidious constraint on human potential and freedom. Compare
Plessy v. Ferguson, 163 U. S. 537 (1896), and Bradwell v. Illinois, supra, at 83 U. S. 141 (Bradley, J., concurring in judgment), with Brown v. Board of
Education, 347 U. S. 483 (1954), and Reed v. Reed, 404 U. S.
71 (1971). Shifting cultural, political, and social
patterns at times come to make past practices appear inconsistent
with fundamental principles upon which American society rests, an
inconsistency legally cognizable under the Equal Protection Clause.
It is natural that evolving standards of equality come to be
embodied in legislation. When that occurs, courts should look to
the fact of such change as a source of guidance on evolving
principles of equality. In an analysis the Court today ignores, the
Court reached this very conclusion when it extended heightened
scrutiny to gender classifications and drew on parallel legislative
developments to support that extension:
"[O]ver the past decade, Congress has itself manifested an
increasing sensitivity to sex-based classifications Page 473 U. S. 467 [citing examples]. Thus, Congress itself has concluded that
classifications based upon sex are inherently invidious, and this
conclusion of a coequal branch of Government is not without
significance to the question presently under consideration." Frontiero v. Richardson, 411 U.S. at 411 U. S. 687 .
[ Footnote 3/18 ]
Moreover, even when judicial action has catalyzed legislative
change, that change certainly does not eviscerate the underlying
constitutional principle. The Court, for example, has never
suggested that race-based classifications became any less suspect
once extensive legislation had been enacted on the subject. See
Palmore v. Sidoti, 466 U. S. 429 (1984).
For the retarded, just as for Negroes and women, much has
changed in recent years, but much remains the same; outdated
statutes are still on the books, and irrational fears or ignorance,
traceable to the prolonged social and cultural isolation of the
retarded, continue to stymie recognition of the dignity and
individuality of retarded people. Heightened judicial scrutiny of
action appearing to impose unnecessary barriers to the retarded is
required in light of increasing recognition that such barriers are
inconsistent with evolving principles of equality embedded in the
Fourteenth Amendment.
The Court also offers a more general view of heightened
scrutiny, a view focused primarily on when heightened scrutiny does not apply, as opposed to when it does apply. [ Footnote 3/19 ] Two Page 473 U. S. 468 principles appear central to the Court's theory. First,
heightened scrutiny is said to be inapplicable where individuals in a group have distinguishing characteristics
that legislatures properly may take into account in some
circumstances. Ante at 473 U. S.
441 -442. Heightened scrutiny is also purportedly
inappropriate when many legislative classifications affecting the group are likely to be valid. We must, so the Court
says,
"look to the likelihood that governmental action premised on a
particular classification is valid as a general matter, not merely
to the specifics of the case before us,"
in deciding whether to apply heightened scrutiny. Ante at 473 U. S.
446 .
If the Court's first principle were sound, heightened scrutiny
would have to await a day when people could be cut from a cookie
mold. Women are hardly alike in all their characteristics, but
heightened scrutiny applies to them because legislatures can rarely
use gender itself as a proxy for these other characteristics.
Permissible distinctions between persons must bear a reasonable
relationship to their relevant characteristics, Zobel v.
Williams, 457 U.S. at 457 U. S. 70 (BRENNAN, J., concurring), and gender per se is almost never relevant. Similarly, that some
retarded people have reduced capacities in some areas does not
justify using retardation as a proxy for reduced capacity in areas
where relevant individual variations in capacity do exist.
The Court's second assertion -- that the standard of review must
be fixed with reference to the number of classifications to which a
characteristic would validly be relevant -- is similarly flawed.
Certainly the assertion is not a logical one; that a characteristic
may be relevant under some or even many circumstances does not
suggest any reason to presume it relevant under other circumstances
where there is reason to suspect it is not. A sign that says "men
only" looks very Page 473 U. S. 469 different on a bathroom door than a courthouse door. But see 83 U. S. Illinois, 16 Wall. 130 (1873).
Our heightened-scrutiny precedents belie the claim that a
characteristic must virtually always be irrelevant to warrant
heightened scrutiny. Plyler, for example, held that the
status of being an undocumented alien is not a "constitutional
irrelevancy," and therefore declined to review with strict scrutiny
classifications affecting undocumented aliens. 457 U.S. at 457 U. S. 219 ,
n.19. While Frontiero stated that gender "frequently" and
"often" bears no relation to legitimate legislative aims, it did
not deem gender an impermissible basis of state action in all
circumstances. 411 U.S. at 411 U. S. 686 -687. Indeed, the Court has upheld some
gender-based classifications. Rostker v. Goldberg, 453 U. S. 57 (1981); Michael M. v. Superior Court of Sonoma County, 450 U. S. 464 (1981). Heightened but not strict, scrutiny is considered
appropriate in areas such as gender, illegitimacy, or alienage
[ Footnote 3/20 ] because the Court
views the trait as relevant under some circumstances, but not
others. [ Footnote 3/21 ] That view
-- indeed the very concept of heightened, as opposed to strict,
scrutiny -- is flatly inconsistent with the notion that heightened
scrutiny should not apply to the retarded because "mental
retardation is a characteristic that the government may
legitimately take into account in a wide range of decisions." Ante at 473 U. S. 446 .
Because the government also may not take this characteristic into
account in many circumstances, such as those presented here,
careful review is required to separate the permissible from the
invalid in classifications relying on retardation. Page 473 U. S. 470 The fact that retardation may be deemed a constitutional
irrelevancy in some circumstances is enough, given the
history of discrimination the retarded have suffered, to require
careful judicial review of classifications singling out the
retarded for special burdens. Although the Court acknowledges that
many instances of invidious discrimination against the retarded
still exist, the Court boldly asserts that, "in the vast majority
of situations," special treatment of the retarded is "not only
legitimate, but also desirable." Ante at 473 U. S. 444 .
That assertion suggests the Court would somehow have us calculate
the percentage of "situations" in which a characteristic is validly
and invalidly invoked before determining whether heightened
scrutiny is appropriate. But heightened scrutiny has not been
"triggered" in our past cases only after some undefined numerical
threshold of invalid "situations" has been crossed. An inquiry into
constitutional principle, not mathematics, determines whether
heightened scrutiny is appropriate. Whenever evolving principles of
equality, rooted in the Equal Protection Clause, require that
certain classifications be viewed as potentially discriminatory, and when history reveals systemic unequal
treatment, more searching judicial inquiry than minimum rationality
becomes relevant.
Potentially discriminatory classifications exist only where some
constitutional basis can be found for presuming that equal rights
are required. Discrimination, in the Fourteenth Amendment sense,
connotes a substantive constitutional judgment that two individuals
or groups are entitled to be treated equally with respect to
something. With regard to economic and commercial matters, no basis
for such a conclusion exists, for as Justice Holmes urged the Lochner Court, the Fourteenth Amendment was not "intended
to embody a particular economic theory. . . ." Lochner v. New
York, 198 U.S. at 198 U. S. 75 (dissenting). As a matter of substantive policy, therefore,
government is free to move in any Page 473 U. S. 471 direction, or to change directions, [ Footnote 3/22 ] in the economic and commercial sphere.
[ Footnote 3/23 ] The structure of
economic and commercial life is a matter of political compromise,
not constitutional principle, and no norm of equality requires that
there be as many opticians as optometrists, see Williamson v.
Lee Optical of Oklahoma, Inc., 348 U.
S. 483 (1955), or new businesses as old, see New
Orleans v. Dukes, 427 U. S. 297 (1976).
But the Fourteenth Amendment does prohibit other results under
virtually all circumstances, such as castes created by law along
racial or ethnic lines, see Palmore v. Sidoti, 466 U.S. at 466 U. S.
432 -433; Loving v. Virginia, 388 U. S.
1 (1967); McLaughlin v. Florida, 379 U.
S. 184 (1964); Shelley v. Kraemer, 334 U. S.
1 , 334 U. S. 23 (1948); Hernandez v. Texas, 347 U.
S. 475 (1954), and significantly constrains the range of
permissible government choices where gender or illegitimacy, for
example, are concerned. Where such constraints, derived from the
Fourteenth Amendment, are present, and where history teaches that
they have systemically been ignored, a "more searching judicial
inquiry" is required. United States v. Carolene Products
Co., 304 U. S. 144 , 304 U. S. 153 ,
n. 4 (1938).
That more searching inquiry, be it called heightened scrutiny or
"second order" rational basis review, is a method of Page 473 U. S. 472 approaching certain classifications skeptically, with judgment
suspended until the facts are in and the evidence considered. The
government must establish that the classification is substantially
related to important and legitimate objectives, see, e.g.,
Craig v. Boren, 429 U. S. 190 (1976), so that valid and sufficiently weighty policies actually
justify the departure from equality. Heightened scrutiny does not
allow courts to second-guess reasoned legislative or professional
judgments tailored to the unique needs of a group like the
retarded, but it does seek to assure that the hostility or
thoughtlessness with which there is reason to be concerned has not
carried the day. By invoking heightened scrutiny, the Court
recognizes, and compels lower courts to recognize, that a group may
well be the target of the sort of prejudiced, thoughtless, or
stereotyped action that offends principles of equality found in the
Fourteenth Amendment. Where classifications based on a particular
characteristic have done so in the past, and the threat that they
may do so remains, heightened scrutiny is appropriate. [ Footnote 3/24 ] Page 473 U. S. 473 As the history of discrimination against the retarded and its
continuing legacy amply attest, the mentally retarded have been,
and in some areas may still be, the targets of action the Equal
Protection Clause condemns. With respect to a liberty so valued as
the right to establish a home in the community, and so likely to be
denied on the basis of irrational fears and outright hostility,
heightened scrutiny is surely appropriate. IV In light of the scrutiny that should be applied here, Cleburne's
ordinance sweeps too broadly to dispel the suspicion that it rests
on a bare desire to treat the retarded as outsiders, pariahs who do
not belong in the community. The Court, while disclaiming that
special scrutiny is necessary or warranted, reaches the same
conclusion. Rather than striking the ordinance down, however, the
Court invalidates it merely as applied to respondents. I must
dissent from the novel proposition that "the preferred course of
adjudication" Page 473 U. S. 474 is to leave standing a legislative Act resting on "irrational
prejudice," ante at 473 U. S. 450 ,
thereby forcing individuals in the group discriminated against to
continue to run the Act's gauntlet.
The Court appears to act out of a belief that the ordinance
might be "rational" as applied to some subgroup of the retarded
under some circumstances, such as those utterly without the
capacity to live in a community, and that the ordinance should not
be invalidated in toto if it is capable of ever being
validly applied. But the issue is not "whether the city may never
insist on a special use permit for the mentally retarded in an R-3
zone." Ante at 473 U. S. 447 .
The issue is whether the city may require a permit pursuant to a
blunderbuss ordinance drafted many years ago to exclude all the
"feeble-minded," or whether the city must enact a new ordinance
carefully tailored to the exclusion of some well-defined subgroup
of retarded people in circumstances in which exclusion might
reasonably further legitimate city purposes.
By leaving the sweeping exclusion of the "feebleminded" to be
applied to other groups of the retarded, the Court has created
peculiar problems for the future. The Court does not define the
relevant characteristics of respondents or their proposed home that
make it unlawful to require them to seek a special permit. Nor does
the Court delineate any principle that defines to which, if any,
set of retarded people the ordinance might validly be applied.
Cleburne's City Council and retarded applicants are left without
guidance as to the potentially valid, and invalid, applications of
the ordinance. As a consequence, the Court's as-applied remedy
relegates future retarded applicants to the standardless discretion
of low-level officials who have already shown an all too willing
readiness to be captured by the "vague, undifferentiated fears," ante at 473 U. S. 449 ,
of ignorant or frightened residents.
Invalidating on its face the ordinance's special treatment of
the "feeble-minded," in contrast, would place the responsibility
for tailoring and updating Cleburne's unconstitutional Page 473 U. S. 475 ordinance where it belongs: with the legislative arm of the city
of Cleburne. If Cleburne perceives a legitimate need for requiring
a certain well-defined subgroup of the retarded to obtain special
permits before establishing group homes, Cleburne will, after
studying the problem and making the appropriate policy decisions,
enact a new, more narrowly tailored ordinance. That ordinance might
well look very different from the current one; it might separate
group homes (presently treated nowhere in the ordinance) from
hospitals, and it might define a narrow subclass of the retarded
for whom even group homes could legitimately be excluded. Special
treatment of the retarded might be ended altogether. But whatever
the contours such an ordinance might take, the city should not be
allowed to keep its ordinance on the books intact, and thereby
shift to the courts the responsibility to confront the complex
empirical and policy questions involved in updating statutes
affecting the mentally retarded. A legislative solution would yield
standards and provide the sort of certainty to retarded applicants
and administrative officials that case-by-case judicial rulings
cannot provide. Retarded applicants should not have to continue to
attempt to surmount Cleburne's vastly overbroad ordinance.
The Court's as-applied approach might be more defensible under
circumstances very different from those presented here. Were the
ordinance capable of being cleanly severed, in one judicial cut,
into its permissible and impermissible applications, the problems I
have pointed out would be greatly reduced. Cf. United States v.
Grace, 461 U. S. 171 (1983) (statute restricting speech and conduct in Supreme Court
building and on its grounds invalid as applied to sidewalks); but cf. id. at 461 U. S.
184 -188 (opinion concurring in part and dissenting in
part). But no readily apparent construction appears, nor has the
Court offered one, to define which group of retarded people the
city might validly require a permit of, and which it might not, in
the R-3 zone. The Court's as-applied holding is particularly
inappropriate here, Page 473 U. S. 476 for nine-tenths of the group covered by the statute appears
similarly situated to respondents, see ante at 473 U. S. 442 ,
n. 9 -- a figure that makes the statutory presumption enormously
overbroad. Cf. Stanley v. Illinois, 405 U.
S. 645 (1972) (invalidating statutory presumption
despite State's insistence that it validly applied to "most" of
those covered).
To my knowledge, the Court has never before treated an equal
protection challenge to a statute on an as-applied basis. When
statutes rest on impermissibly overbroad generalizations, our cases
have invalidated the presumption on its face. [ Footnote 3/25 ] We do not instead leave to the
courts the task of redrafting the statute through an ongoing and
cumbersome process of "as applied" constitutional rulings. In Cleveland Board of Education v. LaFleur, 414 U.
S. 632 (1974), for Page 473 U. S. 477 example, we invalidated, inter alia, a maternity leave
policy that required pregnant schoolteachers to take unpaid leave
beginning five months before their expected due date. The school
board argued that some teachers became physically incapable of
performing adequately in the latter stages of their pregnancy, and
we accepted this justification for purposes of our decision.
Assuming the policy might validly be applied to some teachers,
particularly in the last few weeks of their pregnancy, id. at 414 U. S. 647 ,
n. 13, we nonetheless invalidated it in toto, rather than
simply as applied to the particular plaintiff. The Court required
school boards to employ "alternative administrative means" to
achieve their legitimate health and safety goal, id. at 414 U. S. 647 ,
or the legislature to enact a more carefully tailored statute, id. at 414 U. S. 647 ,
n. 13.
Similarly, Caban v. Mohammed, 441 U.
S. 380 (1979), invalidated a law that required parental
consent to adoption from unwed mothers, but not from unwed fathers.
This distinction was defended on the ground, inter alia, that unwed fathers were often more difficult to locate,
particularly during a child's infancy. We suggested the legislature
might make proof of abandonment easier or proof of paternity
harder, but we required the legislature to draft a new statute
tailored more precisely to the problem of locating unwed fathers.
The statute was not left on the books by invalidating it only as
applied to unwed fathers who actually proved they could be located.
When a presumption is unconstitutionally overbroad, the preferred
course of adjudication is to strike it down. See also United
States Dept. of Agriculture v. Moreno, 413 U.
S. 528 (1973); Stanley v. Illinois, supra; Vlandis
v. Kline, 412 U. S. 441 , 412 U. S.
453 -454 (1973); Carrington v. Rash, 380 U. S. 89 (1965); Sugarman v. Dougall, 413 U.
S. 634 , 413 U. S.
646 -649 (1973); Weber v. Aetna Casualty & Surety
Co., 406 U. S. 164 (1972); Levy v. Louisiana, 391 U. S.
68 (1968).
In my view, the Court's remedial approach is both unprecedented
in the equal protection area and unwise. This doctrinal Page 473 U. S. 478 change, of course, was not sought by the parties, suggested by
the various amici, or discussed at oral argument.
Moreover, the Court does not persuasively reason its way to its
novel remedial holding nor reconsider our prior cases directly on
point. Instead, the Court simply asserts that "this is the
preferred course of adjudication." Given that this assertion
emerges only from today's decision, one can only hope it will not
become entrenched in the law without fuller consideration. V The Court's opinion approaches the task of principled equal
protection adjudication in what I view as precisely the wrong way.
The formal label under which an equal protection claim is reviewed
is less important than careful identification of the interest at
stake and the extent to which society recognizes the classification
as an invidious one. Yet in focusing obsessively on the appropriate
label to give its standard of review, the Court fails to identify
the interests at stake or to articulate the principle that
classifications based on mental retardation must be carefully
examined to assure they do not rest on impermissible assumptions or
false stereotypes regarding individual ability and need. No
guidance is thereby given as to when the Court's free-wheeling, and
potentially dangerous, "rational basis standard" is to be employed,
nor is attention directed to the invidiousness of grouping all
retarded individuals together. Moreover, the Court's narrow,
as-applied remedy fails to deal adequately with the overbroad
presumption that lies at the heart of this case. Rather than
leaving future retarded individuals to run the gauntlet of this
overbroad presumption, I would affirm the judgment of the Court of
Appeals in its entirety, and would strike down on its face the
provision at issue. I therefore concur in the judgment in part and
dissent in part.
[ Footnote 3/1 ] See also Spector Motor Service, Inc. v. McLaughlin, 323 U. S. 101 , 323 U. S. 105 (1944) ("If there is one doctrine more deeply rooted than any other
in the process of constitutional adjudication, it is that we ought
not to pass on questions of constitutionality . . . unless such
adjudication is unavoidable"); Burton v. United States, 196 U. S. 283 , 196 U. S. 295 (1905) ("It is not the habit of the court to decide questions of a
constitutional nature unless absolutely necessary to a decision of
the case"); see generally Ashwander v. TVA, 297 U.
S. 288 , 297 U. S.
346 -348 (1936) (Brandeis, J., concurring).
Even today, the Court again "calls to mind" these principles, ante at 473 U. S. 447 ,
but given the Court's lengthy dicta on heightened scrutiny, this
call to principle must be read with some irony.
[ Footnote 3/2 ]
I do not suggest the lower court erred in relying on heightened
scrutiny, for I believe more searching inquiry than the traditional
rational basis test is required to invalidate Cleburne's ordinance. See infra at 473 U. S.
458 -460.
[ Footnote 3/3 ] See also Three Affiliated Tribes v. Wold Engineering, 467 U. S. 138 , 467 U. S.
157 -158 (1984); Leroy v. Great Western United
Corp., 443 U. S. 173 , 443 U. S. 181 (1979).
[ Footnote 3/4 ]
The two cases the Court cites in its rational basis discussion, Zobel v. Williams, 457 U. S. 55 (1982), and United States Dept. of Agriculture v. Moreno, 413 U. S. 528 (1973), expose the special nature of the rational basis test
employed today. As two of only a handful of modern equal protection
cases striking down legislation under what purports to be a
rational basis standard, these cases must be, and generally have
been, viewed as intermediate review decisions masquerading in
rational basis language. See, e.g., L. Tribe, American
Constitutional Law § 16-31, p. 1090, n. 10 (1978) (discussing Moreno ); see also Moreno, supra, at 413 U. S. 538 (Douglas, J., concurring); Zobel, supra, at 457 U. S. 65 (BRENNAN, J., concurring).
[ Footnote 3/5 ]
Indeed, the group home in this case was specifically located
near a park, a school, and a shopping center so that its residents
would have full access to the community at large.
[ Footnote 3/6 ]
S. Herr, Rights and Advocacy for Retarded People 18 (1983).
[ Footnote 3/7 ]
On the role of these ideologies in this era, see K.
Stampp, Era of Reconstruction, 1865-1877, pp. 18-22 (1965).
[ Footnote 3/8 ]
H. Goddard, The Possibilities of Research as Applied to the
Prevention of Feeblemindedness, Proceedings of the National
Conference of Charities and Correction 307 (1915), cited in A.
Deutsch, The Mentally Ill in America 360 (2d ed.1949). See
also Fernald, The Burden of Feeblemindedness, 17 J.
Psycho-Asthenics 87, 90 (1913) (the retarded "cause unutterable
sorrow at home and are a menace and danger to the community");
Terman, Feeble-Minded Children in the Public Schools of California,
5 Schools & Society 161 (1917) ("[O]nly recently have we begun
to recognize how serious a menace [feeblemindedness] is to the
social, economic and moral welfare of the state. . . . [I]t is
responsible . . . for the majority of cases of chronic and
semi-chronic pauperism, and for much of our alcoholism,
prostitution, and venereal diseases"). Books with titles such as
"The Menace of the Feeble Minded in Connecticut" (1915), issued by
the Connecticut School for Imbeciles, became commonplace. See C. Frazier, (Chairman, Executive Committee of Public
Charities Assn. of Pennsylvania), The Menace of the Feeble-Minded
In Pennsylvania (1913); W. Fernald, The Burden of Feeble-Mindedness
(1912) (Mass.); Juvenile Protection Association of Cincinnati, The
Feeble-Minded, Or the Hub to Our Wheel of Vice (1915) (Ohio). The
resemblance to such works as R. Shufeldt, The Negro: A Menace to
American Civilization (1907), is striking, and not
coincidental.
[ Footnote 3/9 ]
A. Moore, The Feeble-Minded in New York 3 (1911). This book was
sponsored by the State Charities Aid Association. See also P. Tyor & L. Bell, Caring for the Retarded in America 71-104
(1984). The segregationist purpose of these laws was clear. See, e.g., Act of Mar. 22, 1915, ch. 90, 1915 Tex.Gen.Laws
143 (repealed 1955) (Act designed to relieve society of "the heavy
economic and moral losses arising from the existence at large of
these unfortunate persons").
[ Footnote 3/10 ] See Pennsylvania Assn. for Retarded Children v.
Pennsylvania, 343 F.
Supp. 279 , 294-295 (ED Pa.1972); see generally S.
Sarason & J. Doris, Educational Handicap, Public Policy, and
Social History 271-272 (1979).
[ Footnote 3/11 ]
Act of Apr. 3, 1920, ch. 210, § 17, 1920 Miss. Laws 288,
294.
[ Footnote 3/12 ] See, e.g., Act of Mar.19, 1928, ch. 156, 1928 Ky.Acts
534, remains in effect, Ky.Rev.Stat. § 402.990(2) (1984); Act of
May 25, 1905, No. 136, § 1, 1905 Mich.Pub.Acts 185, 186, remains in
effect; Mich.Comp.Laws § 551.6 (1979); Act of Apr. 3, 1920, ch.
210, § 29, 1920 Miss. Gen. Laws 288, 300, remains in effect with
minor changes, Miss.Code Ann. § 41-21-45 (1972).
[ Footnote 3/13 ] See Chamberlain, Current Legislation -- Eugenics and
Limitations of Marriage, 9 A.B.A.J. 429 (1923); Lau v.
Lau, 81 N. H. 44, 122 A. 345, 346 (1923); State v.
Wyman , 118 Conn. 501, 173 A. 155, 156 (1934). See
generally Linn & Bowers, The Historical Fallacies Behind
Legal Prohibitions of Marriages Involving Mentally Retarded Persons
-- The Eternal Child Grows Up, 13 Gonz.L.Rev. 625 (1978); Shaman,
Persons Who Are Mentally Retarded: Their Right to Marry and Have
Children, 12 Family L. Q. 61 (1978); Note, The Right of the
Mentally Disabled to Marry: A Statutory Evaluation, 15 J. Family L.
463 (1977).
[ Footnote 3/14 ] See Note, Mental Disability and the Right to Vote, 88
Yale L.J. 1644 (1979).
[ Footnote 3/15 ]
Congress expressly found that most handicapped children,
including the retarded, were simply shut out from the public school
system. See 20 U.S.C. § 1400(b).
[ Footnote 3/16 ] See generally G. Allport, The Nature of Prejudice
(1958) (separateness among groups exaggerates differences).
[ Footnote 3/17 ]
This history of discrimination may well be directly relevant to
the issue before the Court. Cleburne's current exclusion of the
"feeble-minded" in its 1965 zoning ordinance appeared as a similar
exclusion of the "feebleminded" in the city's 1947 ordinance, see Act of Sept. 26, 1947, § 5; the latter tracked word
for word a similar exclusion in the 1929 comprehensive zoning
ordinance for the nearby city of Dallas. See Dallas
Ordinance, No. 2052, § 4, passed Sept. 11, 1929.
Although we have been presented with no legislative history for
Cleburne's zoning ordinances, this genealogy strongly suggests that
Cleburne's current exclusion of the "feeble-minded" was written in
the darkest days of segregation and stigmatization of the retarded,
and simply carried over to the current ordinance. Recently we held
that extant laws originally motivated by a discriminatory purpose
continue to violate the Equal Protection Clause, even if they would
be permissible were they reenacted without a discriminatory motive. See Hunter v. Underwood, 471 U. S. 222 , 471 U. S. 233 (1985). But in any event, the roots of a law that, by its terms,
excludes from a community the "feebleminded" are clear. As the
examples above attest, see 473
U.S. 432 fn3/7|>n. 7, supra, "feebleminded" was the
defining term for all retarded people in the era of overt and
pervasive discrimination.
[ Footnote 3/18 ]
Although Frontiero was a plurality opinion, it is now
well established that gender classifications receive heightened
scrutiny. See, e.g., Mississippi University for Women v.
Hogan, 458 U. S. 718 (1982).
[ Footnote 3/19 ]
For its general theories about heightened scrutiny, the Court
relies heavily, indeed virtually exclusively, on the "lesson" of Massachusetts Board of Retirement v. Murgia, 427 U.
S. 307 (1976). The brief per curiam in Murgia, however, was handed down in the days before the Court explicitly
acknowledged the existence of heightened scrutiny. See Craig v.
Boren, 429 U. S. 190 (1976); id. at 429 U. S. 210 (POWELL, J., concurring). Murgia explains why age-based
distinctions do not trigger strict scrutiny, but says nothing about
whether such distinctions warrant heightened scrutiny. Nor have
subsequent cases addressed this issue. See Vance v.
Bradley, 440 U. S. 93 , 440 U. S. 97 (1979).
[ Footnote 3/20 ]
Alienage classifications present a related variant, for strict
scrutiny is applied to such classifications in the economic and
social area, but only heightened scrutiny is applied when the
classification relates to "political functions." Cabell v.
Chavez-Salido, 454 U. S. 432 , 454 U. S. 439 (1982); see also Bernal v. Fainter, 467 U.
S. 216 , 467 U. S.
220 -222 (1984). Thus, characterization of the area to
which an alienage classification applies is necessary to determine
how strongly it must be justified.
[ Footnote 3/21 ]
I express no view here as to whether strict scrutiny ought to be
extended to these classifications.
[ Footnote 3/22 ]
Constitutional provisions other than the Equal Protection
Clause, such as the Contracts Clause, the Just Compensation Clause,
or the Due Process Clause, may constrain the extent to which
government can upset settled expectations when changing course and
the process by which it must implement such changes.
[ Footnote 3/23 ]
Only when it can be said that "Congress misapprehended what it
was doing," United States Railroad Retirement Bd. v.
Fritz, 449 U. S. 166 , 449 U. S. 193 (1980) (BRENNAN, J., dissenting), will a classification fail the
minimal rational basis standard. Even then, the classification
fails not because of limits on the directions which substantive
policy can take in the economic and commercial area, but because
the classification reflects no underlying substantive
policy -- it is simply arbitrary.
[ Footnote 3/24 ]
No single talisman can define those groups likely to be the
target of classifications offensive to the Fourteenth Amendment and
therefore warranting heightened or strict scrutiny; experience, not
abstract logic, must be the primary guide. The "political
powerlessness" of a group may be relevant, San Antonio
Independent School District v. Rodriguez, 411 U. S.
1 , 411 U. S. 28 (1973), but that factor is neither necessary, as the gender cases
demonstrate, nor sufficient, as the example of minors illustrates.
Minors cannot vote and thus might be considered politically
powerless to an extreme degree. Nonetheless, we see few statutes
reflecting prejudice or indifference to minors, and I am not aware
of any suggestion that legislation affecting them be viewed with
the suspicion of heightened scrutiny. Similarly, immutability of
the trait at issue may be relevant, but many immutable
characteristics, such as height or blindness, are valid bases of
governmental action and classifications under a variety of
circumstances. See ante at 473 U. S.
442 -443, n. 10.
The political powerlessness of a group and the immutability of
its defining trait are relevant insofar as they point to a social
and cultural isolation that gives the majority little reason to
respect or be concerned with that group's interests and needs.
Statutes discriminating against the young have not been common nor
need be feared because those who do vote and legislate were once
themselves young, typically have children of their own, and
certainly interact regularly with minors. Their social integration
means that minors, unlike discrete and insular minorities, tend to
be treated in legislative arenas with full concern and respect,
despite their formal and complete exclusion from the electoral
process.
The discreteness and insularity warranting a "more searching
judicial inquiry," United States v. Carolene Products Co., 304 U. S. 144 , 304 U. S. 153 ,
n. 4 (1938), must therefore be viewed from a social and cultural
perspective, as well as a political one. To this task judges are
well suited, for the lessons of history and experience are surely
the best guide as to when, and with respect to what interests,
society is likely to stigmatize individuals as members of an
inferior caste, or view them as not belonging to the community.
Because prejudice spawns prejudice, and stereotypes produce
limitations that confirm the stereotype on which they are based, a
history of unequal treatment requires sensitivity to the prospect
that its vestiges endure. In separating those groups that are
discrete and insular from those that are not, as in many important
legal distinctions, "a page of history is worth a volume of logic." New York Trust Co. v. Eisner, 256 U.
S. 345 , 256 U. S. 349 (1921) (Holmes, J.).
[ Footnote 3/25 ]
The Court strongly suggests that the loose fit of the ordinance
to its purported objectives signifies that the ordinance rests on
"an irrational prejudice," ante at 473 U. S. 450 ,
an unconstitutional legislative purpose. See Mississippi
University for Women v. Hogan, 458 U.S. at 458 U. S. 725 .
In that event, recent precedent should make clear that the
ordinance must, in its entirety, be invalidated. See Hunter v.
Underwood, 471 U. S. 222 (1985). Hunter involved a 1902 constitutional provision
disenfranchising various felons. Because that provision had been
motivated, at least in part, by a desire to disenfranchise Negroes,
we invalidated it on its face. In doing so, we did not suggest that
felons could not be deprived of the vote through a statute
motivated by some purpose other than racial discrimination. See
Richardson v. Ramirez, 418 U. S. 24 (1974). Yet that possibility, or the possibility that the provision
might have been only partly motivated by the desire to
disenfranchise Negroes, did not suggest the provision should be
invalidated only "as applied" to the particular plaintiffs in Hunter, or even as applied to Negroes more generally.
Instead we concluded:
"Without deciding whether § 182 would be valid if enacted today
without any impermissible motivation, we simply observe that its
original enactment was motivated by a desire to discriminate
against blacks on account of race, and the section continues to
this day to have that effect. As such, it violates equal protection
under Arlington Heights [v. Metropolitan Housing Development
Corp., 429 U. S. 252 (1977)]."
471 U.S. at 471 U. S. 233 .
If a discriminatory purpose infects a legislative Act, the Act
itself is inconsistent with the Equal Protection Clause, and cannot
validly be applied to anyone. | The Supreme Court ruled that a Texas city's decision to require a special use permit for a group home for the mentally disabled was not a violation of the Equal Protection Clause. The Court held that mental retardation is not a "quasi-suspect" classification and that the city's action was rationally related to a legitimate state interest. The Court found that the city's interest in dealing with and providing for the mentally disabled was legitimate and that the legislative response to their needs did not indicate continuing antipathy or prejudice. The Court also noted the importance of considering social and cultural perspectives when evaluating equal protection claims. |
Equal Protection | Minnesota v. Clover Leaf Creamery Co. | https://supreme.justia.com/cases/federal/us/449/456/ | U.S. Supreme Court Minnesota v. Clover Leaf Creamery Co., 449
U.S. 456 (1981) Minnesota v. Clover Leaf Creamery
Co. No. 79-1171 Argued November 3,
1980 Decided January 21,
1981 449
U.S. 456 CERTIORARI TO THE SUPREME COURT OF
MINNESOTA Syllabus For the stated purposes of promoting resource conservation,
easing solid waste disposal problems, and conserving energy, the
Minnesota Legislature enacted a statute banning the retail sale of
milk in plastic nonreturnable, nonrefillable containers, but
permitting such sale in other nonreturnable, nonrefillable
containers, such as paperboard cartons. Respondents filed suit in
Minnesota District Court, seeking to enjoin enforcement of the
statute on constitutional grounds. The District Court held that the
statute violated, inter alia, the Equal Protection Clause
of the Fourteenth Amendment and the Commerce Clause. Finding that
"the evidence conclusively demonstrate[d] that the discrimination
against plastic nonrefillables [was] not rationally related to the
Act's objectives," the Minnesota Supreme Court affirmed on the
equal protection ground without reaching the Commerce Clause
issue. Held: 1. The ban on plastic nonreturnable milk containers bears a
rational relation to the State's objectives, and must be sustained
under the Equal Protection Clause. Pp. 449 U. S.
461 -470.
(a) The Equal Protection Clause does not deny Minnesota the
authority to ban one type of milk container conceded to cause
environmental problems merely because another already established
type is permitted to continue in use. Whether in fact the statute
will promote more environmentally desirable milk packaging is not
the question. The Equal Protection Clause is satisfied if the
Minnesota Legislature could rationally have decided that its ban on
plastic milk jugs might foster greater use of environmentally
desirable alternatives. Pp. 449 U. S.
465 -466.
(b) The fact that the state legislature, having concluded that
nonreturnable, nonrefillable milk containers pose environmental
hazards, decided to ban the most recent entry in the field, and
thus, in effect, "grandfathered" paperboard containers, at least
temporarily, does not make the ban on plastic containers arbitrary
or irrational. Cf. New Orleans v. Dukes, 427 U.
S. 297 . Pp. 449 U. S.
466 -468.
(c) Where the evidence as to whether the statute would help to
conserve energy was "at least debatable," the Minnesota Supreme
Court erred in substituting its judgment for that of the
legislature by finding, contrary to the legislature, that the
production of plastic nonrefillable Page 449 U. S. 457 containers required less energy than production of paper
containers. Pp. 449 U. S.
468 -69.
(d) Similarly, the Minnesota Supreme Court erred in finding,
contrary to the legislature's finding based on a reputable study,
that plastic milk jugs take up less space in landfills and present
fewer solid waste disposal problems than do paperboard containers.
Pp. 449 U. S.
469 -470.
2. The statute does not violate the Commerce Clause as
constituting an unreasonable burden on interstate commerce. Pp. 449 U. S.
470 -474.
(a) The statute does not discriminate between interstate and
intrastate commerce, but regulates evenhandedly by prohibiting all
milk retailers from selling their products in plastic containers,
without regard to whether the milk, the containers, or the sellers
are from outside the State. Pp. 449 U. S.
471 -472.
(b) The incidental burden imposed on interstate commerce by the
statute is not excessive in relation to the putative local
benefits. Milk products may continue to move freely across the
Minnesota border, and since most dairies package their products in
more than one type of container, the inconvenience of having to
conform to different packaging requirements in Minnesota and the
surrounding States should be slight. Even granting that the
out-of-state plastics industry is burdened relatively more heavily
than the Minnesota pulpwood industry, this burden is not "clearly
excessive" in light of the substantial state interest in promoting
conservation of energy and other natural resources and easing solid
waste disposal problems. These local benefits amply support
Minnesota's decision under the Commerce Clause. Pp. 449 U. S.
472 -474. 289 N.W.2d
79 , reversed.
BRENNAN, J., delivered the opinion of the Court, in which
BURGER, C.J., and STEWART, WHITE, MARSHALL, and BLACKMUN, JJ.,
joined. POWELL, J., filed an opinion concurring in part and
dissenting in part, post, p. 449 U. S. 474 .
STEVENS, J., filed a dissenting opinion, post, p. 449 U. S. 477 .
REHNQUIST, J., took no part in the consideration or decision of the
case. Page 449 U. S. 458 JUSTICE BRENNAN delivered the opinion of the Court:
In 1977, the Minnesota Legislature enacted a statute banning the
retail sale of milk in plastic nonreturnable, nonrefillable
containers, but permitting such sale in other nonreturnable,
nonrefillable containers, such as paperboard milk cartons. 1977
Minn. Laws, ch. 268, Minn.Stat. § 116 F. 21 (1978). Respondents
[ Footnote 1 ] contend that the
statute violates the Equal Protection and Commerce Clauses of the
Constitution. I The purpose of the Minnesota statute is set out as § 1:
"The legislature finds that the use of nonreturnable,
nonrefillable containers for the packaging of milk and other milk
products presents a solid waste management problem for the state,
promotes energy waste, and depletes natural resources. The
legislature therefore, in Page 449 U. S. 459 furtherance of the policies stated in Minnesota Statutes,
Section 116 F. 01, [ Footnote 2 ]
determines that the use of nonreturnable, nonrefillable containers
for packaging milk and other milk products should be discouraged,
and that the use of returnable and reusable packaging for these
products is preferred, and should be encouraged."
1977 Minn.Laws, ch. 268, § 1, codified as Minn.Stat. § 116 F. 21
(1978). Section 2 of the Act forbids the retail sale of milk and
fluid milk products, other than sour cream, cottage cheese, and
yogurt, in nonreturnable, nonrefillable rigid or semirigid
containers composed at least 50% of plastic. [ Footnote 3 ]
The Act was introduced with the support of the state Pollution
Control Agency, Department of Natural Resources, Department of
Agriculture, Consumer Services Division, and Energy Agency,
[ Footnote 4 ] and debated
vigorously in both houses of the state legislature. Proponents of
the legislation argued that it would promote resource conservation,
ease solid waste disposal problems, and conserve energy. Relying on
the results of studies and other information, [ Footnote 5 ] they stressed the need to Page 449 U. S. 460 stop introduction of the plastic nonreturnable container before
it became entrenched in the market. Opponents of the Act, also
presenting empirical evidence, argued that the Act would not
promote the goals asserted by the proponents, but would merely
increase costs of retail milk products and prolong the use of
ecologically undesirable paperboard milk cartons.
After the Act was passed, respondents filed suit in Minnesota
District Court, seeking to enjoin its enforcement. The court
conducted extensive evidentiary hearings into the Act's probable
consequences, and found the evidence "in sharp conflict." App.
A-25. Nevertheless, finding itself "as factfinder . . . obliged to
weigh and evaluate this evidence," ibid., the court
resolved the evidentiary conflicts in favor of respondents, and
concluded that the Act "will not succeed in effecting the
Legislature's published policy goals. . . ." Id. at A-21.
The court further found that, contrary to the statement of purpose
in § 1, the "actual basis" for the Act
"was to promote the economic interests of certain segments of
the local dairy and pulpwood industries at the expense of the
economic interests of other segments of the dairy industry and the
plastics industry." Id. at A-19. The court therefore declared the Act
"null, void, and unenforceable" and enjoined its enforcement,
basing the judgment on substantive due process under the Fourteenth
Amendment to the United States Constitution and Art. 1 § 7, of the
Minnesota Constitution; equal protection under the Fourteenth
Amendment; and prohibition of unreasonable burdens on interstate
commerce under Art. I, § 8, of the United States Constitution. App.
A-23.
The State appealed to the Supreme Court of Minnesota, which
affirmed the District Court on the federal equal protection and due
process grounds, without reaching the Commerce Clause or state law
issues. 289 N.W.2d
79 (1979). Unlike the District Court, the State Supreme Court
found that the purpose of the Act was
"to promote the state interests Page 449 U. S. 461 of encouraging the reuse and recycling of materials and reducing
the amount and type of material entering the solid waste
stream,"
and acknowledged the legitimacy of this purpose. Id. at
82. Nevertheless, relying on the District Court's findings of fact,
the full record, and an independent review of documentary sources,
the State Supreme Court held that "the evidence conclusively
demonstrates that the discrimination against plastic nonrefillables
is not rationally related to the Act's objectives." Ibid. We granted certiorari, 445 U.S. 949, and now reverse. II The parties agree that the standard of review applicable to this
case under the Equal Protection Clause is the familiar "rational
basis" test. See Vance v. Bradley, 440 U. S.
93 , 440 U. S. 97 (1979); New Orleans v. Dukes, 427 U.
S. 297 , 427 U. S. 303 (1976). [ Footnote 6 ] Moreover,
they agree that the purposes of the Act Page 449 U. S. 462 cited by the legislature -- promoting resource conservation,
easing solid waste disposal problems, and conserving energy -- are
legitimate state purposes. Thus, the controversy in this Page 449 U. S. 463 case centers on the narrow issue whether the legislative
classification between plastic and nonplastic nonreturnable milk
containers is rationally related to achievement of the statutory
purposes. [ Footnote 7 ] A Respondents apparently have not challenged the theoretical
connection between a ban on plastic nonreturnables and the purposes
articulated by the legislature; instead, they have argued that
there is no empirical connection between the two. They
produced impressive supporting evidence at trial to prove that the
probable consequences of the ban on plastic nonreturnable milk
containers will be to deplete natural resources, exacerbate solid
waste disposal problems, and waste energy, because consumers unable
to purchase milk in plastic Page 449 U. S. 464 containers will turn to paperboard milk cartons, allegedly a
more environmentally harmful product.
But States are not required to convince the courts of the
correctness of their legislative judgments. Rather,
"those challenging the legislative judgment must convince the
court that the legislative facts on which the classification is
apparently based could not reasonably be conceived to be true by
the governmental decisionmaker."
" Vance v. Bradley, 440 U.S. at 111. See also
Day-Brite Lighting, Inc. v. Missouri, 342 U. S.
421 , 342 U. S. 425 (1952); Henderson Co. v. Thompson, 300 U. S.
258 , 300 U. S. 264 -265
(1937)."
Although parties challenging legislation under the Equal
Protection Clause may introduce evidence supporting their claim
that it is irrational, United States v. Carolene Products
Co., 304 U. S. 144 , 304 U. S.
153 -154 (1938), [ Footnote 8 ] they cannot prevail so long as
"it is evident from all the considerations presented to [the
legislature], and those of which we may take judicial notice, that
the question is at least debatable." Id. at 304 U. S. 154 .
Where there was evidence before the legislature reasonably
supporting the classification, litigants may not procure
invalidation of the legislation merely by tendering evidence in
court that the legislature was mistaken.
The District Court candidly admitted that the evidence was "in
sharp conflict," App. A-25, but resolved the conflict in favor of
respondents and struck down the statute. The Supreme Court of
Minnesota, however, did not reverse on the basis of this patent
violation of the principles governing rationality analysis under
the Equal Protection Clause. Rather, the court analyzed the statute
afresh under the Equal Protection Clause, and reached the
conclusion that the statute is Page 449 U. S. 465 constitutionally invalid. The State contends that, in this
analysis, the court impermissibly substituted its judgment for that
of the legislature. We turn now to that argument. B The State identifies four reasons why the classification between
plastic and nonplastic nonreturnables is rationally related to the
articulated statutory purposes. If any one of the four
substantiates the State's claim, we must reverse the Minnesota
Supreme Court and sustain the Act.
First, the State argues that elimination of the popular plastic
milk jug will encourage the use of environmentally superior
containers. There is no serious doubt that the plastic containers
consume energy resources and require solid waste disposal, nor that
refillable bottles and plastic pouches are environmentally
superior. Citing evidence that the plastic jug is the most popular,
and the gallon paperboard carton the most cumbersome and least well
regarded package in the industry, the State argues that the ban on
plastic nonreturnables will buy time during which environmentally
preferable alternatives may be further developed and promoted.
As Senator Spear argued during the Senate debate:
"[T]his bill is designed to prevent the beginning of another
system of non-returnables that is going to be very, very difficult
[to stop] once it begins. It is true that our alternative now is
not a returnable system in terms of milk bottles. Hopefully we are
eventually going to be able to move to that kind of a system, but
we are never going to move to a returnable system so long as we
allow another nonreturnable system with all the investment and all
of the vested interest that that is going to involve to begin."
Transcript of the Full Senate Floor Discussion of H.F. 45, p. 6
(May 20, 1977), reprinted as Plaintiffs' Exhibit J. Accord,
id. at 1-2 (statement of Sen. Luther). Page 449 U. S. 466 The Minnesota Supreme Court dismissed this asserted state
interest as "speculative and illusory." 289 N.W.2d at 86. The court
expressed doubt that the Minnesota Legislature or Pollution Control
Agency would take any further steps to promote environmentally
sound milk packaging, and stated that there is no evidence that
paperboard cartons will cease to be used in Minnesota. Ibid. We find the State's approach fully supportable under our
precedents. This Court has made clear that a legislature need not
"strike at all evils at the same time or in the same way," Semler v. Oregon State Board of Dental Examiners, 294 U. S. 608 , 294 U. S. 610 (1935), and that a legislature
"may implement [its] program step by step, . . . adopting
regulations that only partially ameliorate a perceived evil and
deferring complete elimination of the evil to future
regulations."
" New Orleans v. Dukes, 427 U.S. at 427 U. S.
303 . See also Katzenbach v. Morgan, 384 U. S.
641 , 384 U. S. 657 (1966); Williamson v. Lee Optical Co., 348 U. S.
483 , 348 U. S. 489 (1955); Railway Express Agency, Inc. v. New York, 336 U. S.
106 , 336 U. S. 110 (1949). The
Equal Protection Clause does not deny the State of Minnesota the
authority to ban one type of milk container conceded to cause
environmental problems, merely because another type, already
established in the market, is permitted to continue in use. Whether
in fact the Act will promote more environmentally desirable milk
packaging is not the question: the Equal Protection Clause is
satisfied by our conclusion that the Minnesota Legislature could rationally have decided that its ban on plastic
nonreturnable milk jugs might foster greater use of environmentally
desirable alternatives."
Second, the State argues that its ban on plastic nonreturnable
milk containers will reduce the economic dislocation foreseen from
the movement toward greater use of environmentally superior
containers. The State notes that plastic nonreturnables have only
recently been introduced on a wide scale in Minnesota, and that, at
the time the legislature was Page 449 U. S. 467 considering the Act, many Minnesota dairies were preparing to
invest large amounts of capital in plastic container production. As
Representative Munger, chief sponsor of the bill in the House of
Representatives, explained:
"Minnesota's dairy market is on the verge of making a major
change over from essentially a paperboard container system to a
system of primarily single use, throwaway plastic bottles. The
major dairies in our state have ordered the blow-mold equipment to
manufacture in plant the nonreturnable plastic milk bottle. Members
of the House, I feel now is an ideal time for this legislation when
only one dairy in our state is firmly established in manufacturing
and marketing the throwaway plastic milk bottle."
Transcript of the Debate of the Minnesota House of
Representatives on H.F. 45, p. 2 (Mar. 10, 1977), reprinted as
Plaintiffs' Exhibit J. See also Transcript of the Full
Senate Floor Discussion on H.F. 45, p. 6 (May 20, 1977), reprinted
as Plaintiffs' Exhibit J (statement of Sen. Milton); id. at 9 (statement of Sen. Schaaf); id. at 10-11 (statement
of Sen. Perpich).
Moreover, the State explains, to ban both the plastic and the
paperboard nonreturnable milk container at once would cause an
enormous disruption in the milk industry, because few dairies are
now able to package their products in refillable bottles or plastic
pouches. Thus, by banning the plastic container while continuing to
permit the paperboard container, the State was able to prevent the
industry from becoming reliant on the new container, while avoiding
severe economic dislocation.
The Minnesota Supreme Court did not directly address this
justification, but we find it supported by our precedents as well.
In New Orleans v. Dukes, supra, we upheld a city
regulation banning pushcart food vendors, but exempting from the
ban two vendors who had operated in the city for over eight years.
Noting that the "city could reasonably decide Page 449 U. S. 468 that newer businesses were less likely to have built up
substantial reliance interests in continued operation," we held
that the city "could rationally choose initially to eliminate
vendors of more recent vintage." Id. at 427 U. S. 305 . Accord, United States v. Maryland Savings-Share Ins.
Corp., 400 U. S. 4 , 400 U. S. 6 (1970). This case is not significantly different. The state
legislature concluded that nonreturnable, nonrefillable milk
containers pose environmental hazards, and decided to ban the most
recent entry into the field. The fact that the legislature in
effect "grandfathered" paperboard containers, at least temporarily,
does not make the Act's ban on plastic nonreturnables arbitrary or
irrational.
Third, the State argues that the Act will help to conserve
energy. It points out that plastic milk jugs are made from plastic
resin, an oil and natural gas derivative, whereas paperboard milk
cartons are primarily composed of pulpwood, which is a renewable
resource. This point was stressed by the Act's proponents in the
legislature. Senator Luther commented:
"We have been through an energy crisis in Minnesota. We know
what it is like to go without and what we are looking at here is a
total blatant waste of petroleum and natural gas. . . ."
Transcript of the Full Senate Floor Discussion on H. F. 45, p.
12 (May 20, 1977), reprinted as Plaintiffs' Exhibit J.
Representative Munger said in a similar vein:
"A sweep to the plastic throwaway bottle in the gallon size
container alone would use enough additional natural gas and
petroleum to heat 3,100 homes each year in Minnesota when compared
to a refillable system and 1,400 compared to the present paperboard
system. Plastic containers are made from a non-renewable resource,
while the paperboard is made from Minnesota's forest products."
Transcript of the Debate of the Minnesota House of
Representatives on H.F. 45, p. 2 (Mar. 10, 1977), reprinted as
Plaintiffs' Exhibit J. Page 449 U. S. 469 The Minnesota Supreme Court held, in effect, that the
legislature misunderstood the facts. The court admitted that the
results of a reliable study [ Footnote 9 ] support the legislature's conclusion that less
energy is consumed in the production of paperboard containers than
in the production of plastic nonreturnables, but, after crediting
the contrary testimony of respondents' expert witness and altering
certain factual assumptions, [ Footnote 10 ] the court concluded that "production of
plastic nonrefillables requires less energy than production of
paper containers." 289 N.W.2d at 85.
The Minnesota Supreme Court may be correct that the Act is not a
sensible means of conserving energy. But we reiterate that "it is
up to legislatures, not courts, to decide on the wisdom and utility
of legislation." Ferguson v. Skrupa, 372 U.
S. 726 , 372 U. S. 729 (1963). Since, in view of the evidence before the legislature, the
question clearly is "at least debatable," United States v.
Carolene Products Co., 304 U.S. at 304 U. S. 154 ,
the Minnesota Supreme Court erred in substituting its judgment for
that of the legislature.
Fourth, the State argues that the Act will ease the State's
solid waste disposal problem. Most solid consumer wastes in
Minnesota are disposed of in landfills. A reputable study before
the Minnesota Legislature indicated that plastic milk jugs occupy a
greater volume in landfills than other nonreturnable milk
containers. [ Footnote 11 ]
This was one of the legislature's major concerns. For example, in
introducing the bill to the House of Representatives,
Representative Munger asked rhetorically: Page 449 U. S. 470 "Why do we need this legislation?" Part of his answer to the
query as that "the plastic non-refillable containers will increase
the problems of solid waste in our state." Transcript of the Debate
of the Minnesota House of Representatives on H.F. 45, p. 1 (Mar.
10, 1977), reprinted as Plaintiffs' Exhibit J.
The Minnesota Supreme Court found that plastic milk jugs in fact
take up less space in landfills and present fewer solid waste
disposal problems than do paperboard containers. 289 N.W.2d at
82-85. But its ruling on this point must be rejected for the same
reason we rejected its ruling concerning energy conservation: it is
not the function of the courts to substitute their evaluation of
legislative facts for that of the legislature.
We therefore conclude that the ban on plastic nonreturnable milk
containers bears a rational relation to the State's objectives, and
must be sustained under the Equal Protection Clause. [ Footnote 12 ] III The District Court also held that the Minnesota statute is
unconstitutional under the Commerce Clause [ Footnote 13 ] because it imposes an unreasonable
burden on interstate commerce. [ Footnote 14 ] We cannot agree. Page 449 U. S. 471 When legislating in areas of legitimate local concern, such as
environmental protection and resource conservation, States are
nonetheless limited by the Commerce Clause. See Lewis v. BT
Investment Managers, Inc., 447 U. S. 27 , 447 U. S. 36 (1980); Hunt v. Washington Apple Advertising Comm'n, 432 U. S. 333 , 432 U. S. 350 (1977); Southern Pacific Co. v. Arizona ex rel. Sullivan, 325 U. S. 761 , 325 U. S. 767 (1945). If a state law purporting to promote environmental purposes
is in reality "simple economic protectionism," we have applied a
"virtually per se rule of invalidity." Philadelphia v.
New Jersey, 437 U. S. 617 , 437 U. S. 624 (1978). [ Footnote 15 ] Even
if a statute regulates "evenhandedly," and imposes only
"incidental" burdens on interstate commerce, the courts must
nevertheless strike it down if "the burden imposed on such commerce
is clearly excessive in relation to the putative local benefits." Pike v. Bruce Church, Inc., 397 U.
S. 137 , 397 U. S. 142 (1970). Moreover,
"the extent of the burden that will be tolerated will of course
depend on the nature of the local interest involved, and on whether
it could be promoted as well with a lesser impact on interstate
activities." Ibid. Minnesota's statute does not effect "simple protectionism," but
"regulates evenhandedly" by prohibiting all milk retailers from
selling their products in plastic, nonreturnable milk containers,
without regard to whether the milk, the containers, Page 449 U. S. 472 or the sellers are from outside the State. This statute is
therefore unlike statutes discriminating against interstate
commerce, which we have consistently struck down. E.g., Lewis
v. BT Investment Managers, Inc., supra, (Florida statutory
scheme prohibiting investment advisory services by bank holding
companies with principal offices out of the State); Hughes v.
Oklahoma, 441 U. S. 322 (1979) (Oklahoma statute prohibiting the export of natural minnows
from the State); Philadelphia v. New Jersey, supra, (New
Jersey statute prohibiting importation of solid and liquid wastes
into the State); Hunt v. Washington Apple Advertising Comm'n,
supra (North Carolina statute imposing additional costs on
Washington, but not on North Carolina, apple shippers) .
Since the statute does not discriminate between interstate and
intrastate commerce, the controlling question is whether the
incidental burden imposed on interstate commerce by the Minnesota
Act is "clearly excessive in relation to the putative local
benefits." Pike v. Bruce Church, Inc., supra at 397 U. S. 142 .
We conclude that it is not.
The burden imposed on interstate commerce by the statute is
relatively minor. Milk products may continue to move freely across
the Minnesota border, and since most dairies package their products
in more than one type of containers, [ Footnote 16 ] the inconvenience of having to conform to
different packaging requirements in Minnesota and the surrounding
States should be slight. See Pacific States Box & Basket
Co. v. White, 296 U. S. 176 , 296 U. S. 184 (1935). Within Minnesota, business will presumably shift from
manufacturers of plastic nonreturnable containers to producers of
paperboard cartons, refillable bottles, Page 449 U. S. 473 and plastic pouches, but there is no reason to suspect that the
gainers will be Minnesota firms, or the losers out-of-state firms.
Indeed, two of the three dairies, the sole milk retailer, and the
sole milk container producer challenging the statute in this
litigation are Minnesota firms. [ Footnote 17 ]
Pulpwood producers are the only Minnesota industry likely to
benefit significantly from the Act at the expense of out-of-state
firms. Respondents point out that plastic resin, the raw material
used for making plastic nonreturnable milk jugs, is produced
entirely by non-Minnesota firms, while pulpwood, used for making
paperboard, is a major Minnesota product. Nevertheless, it is clear
that respondents exaggerate the degree of burden on out-of-state
interests, both because plastics will continue to be used in the
production of plastic pouches, plastic returnable bottles, and
paperboard itself, and because out-of-state pulpwood producers will
presumably absorb some of the business generated by the Act.
Even granting that the out-of-state plastics industry is
burdened relatively more heavily than the Minnesota pulpwood
industry, we find that this burden is not "clearly excessive" in
light of the substantial state interest in promoting conservation
of energy and other natural resources and easing solid waste
disposal problems, which we have already reviewed in the context of
equal protection analysis. See supra at 449 U. S.
465 -470. We find these local benefits ample to support
Minnesota's decision under the Commerce Clause. Moreover, we find
that no approach with "a lesser impact on interstate activities," Pike v. Bruce Church, Inc., supra at 397 U. S. 142 ,
is available. Respondents have suggested several alternative
statutory schemes, but these alternatives are either more
burdensome on commerce than the Act (as, for example, banning all
nonreturnables) or less likely to be effective (as, for
example, Page 449 U. S. 474 providing incentives for recycling). See Brief for
Respondents 32-33.
In Exxon Corp. v. Governor of Maryland, 437 U.
S. 117 (1978), we upheld a Maryland statute barring
producers and refiners of petroleum products -- all of which were
out-of-state businesses -- from retailing gasoline in the State. We
stressed that the Commerce Clause "protects the interstate market,
not particular interstate firms, from prohibitive or burdensome
regulations." Id. at 437 U. S.
127 -128. A nondiscriminatory regulation serving
substantial state purposes is not invalid simply because it causes
some business to shift from a predominantly out-of-state industry
to a predominantly in-state industry. Only if the burden on
interstate commerce clearly outweighs the State's legitimate
purposes does such a regulation violate the Commerce Clause.
The judgment of the Minnesota Supreme Court is Reversed. JUSTICE REHNQUIST took no part in the consideration or decision
of this case.
[ Footnote 1 ]
Respondents, plaintiffs below, are a Minnesota dairy that owns
equipment for producing plastic nonreturnable milk jugs, a
Minnesota dairy that leases such equipment, a non-Minnesota company
that manufactures such equipment, a Minnesota company that produces
plastic nonreturnable milk jugs, a non-Minnesota dairy that sells
milk products in Minnesota in plastic nonreturnable milk jugs, a
Minnesota milk retailer, a non-Minnesota manufacturer of
polyethylene resin that sells such resin in many States, including
Minnesota, and a plastics industry trade association.
[ Footnote 2 ]
Minnesota Stat. § 116 F. 01 (1978) provides in relevant
part:
" Statement of policy. The legislature seeks to
encourage both the reduction of the amount and type of material
entering the solid waste stream and the reuse and recycling of
materials. Solid waste represents discarded materials and energy
resources, and it also represents an economic burden to the people
of the state. The recycling of solid waste materials is one
alternative for the conservation of material and energy resources,
but it is also in the public interest to reduce the amount of
materials requiring recycling or disposal."
[ Footnote 3 ]
Minnesota is apparently the first State so to regulate milk
containers. 289 N.W.2d
79 , 81, n. 6 (1979).
[ Footnote 4 ]
Transcript of the Debate of the Minnesota House of
Representatives on H.F. 45, p. 1 (Mar. 10, 1977), reprinted as
Plaintiffs' Exhibit J.
[ Footnote 5 ]
The principal empirical study cited in legislative debate, see, e.g., Transcript of the Full Senate Floor Discussion
on H.F. 45, p. 12 (May 20, 1977), reprinted as Plaintiffs' Exhibit
J (statement of Sen. Luther), is Midwest Research Institute,
Resource and Environmental Profile Analysis of Five Milk Container
Systems, admitted into evidence as Plaintiffs' Exhibit I.
[ Footnote 6 ]
JUSTICE STEVENS' dissenting opinion argues that the Minnesota
Supreme Court, when reviewing a challenge to a Minnesota statute on
equal protection grounds, is not bound by the limits applicable to
federal courts, but may independently reach conclusions contrary to
those of the legislature concerning legislative facts bearing on
the wisdom or utility of the legislation. This argument, though
novel, is without merit. A state court may, of course, apply a more
stringent standard of review as a matter of state law under the
State's equivalent to the Equal Protection or Due Process Clauses. E.g., Baker v. City of Fairbanks, 471 P.2d 386 ,
401-402 (Alaska 1970); Serrano v. Priest, 18 Cal. 3d
728 , 764-765, 557 P.2d 929, 950-951 (1976), cert.
denied, 432 U.S. 907 (1977); State v. Kaluna, 55 Haw.
361, 368-369, 520 P.2d 51 ,
58-59 (1974); see Brennan, State Constitutions and the
Protection of Individual Rights, 90 Harv.L.Rev. 489 (1977). And as
the dissent correctly notes, post at 449 U. S.
479 -481, the States are free to allocate the lawmaking
function to whatever branch of state government they may choose. Uphaus v. Wyman, 360 U. S. 72 , 360 U. S. 77 (1959); Sweezy v. New Hampshire, 354 U.
S. 234 , 354 U. S.
256 -257 (1957) (Frankfurter, J., concurring in result); Dreyer v. Illinois, 187 U. S. 71 , 187 U. S. 83 -84
(1902). But when a state court reviews state legislation challenged
as violative of the Fourteenth Amendment, it is not free to impose
greater restrictions as a matter of federal constitutional law than
this Court has imposed. Oregon v. Hass, 420 U.
S. 714 , 420 U. S. 719 (1975).
The standard of review under equal protection rationality
analysis -- without regard to which branch of the state government
has made the legislative judgment -- is governed by federal
constitutional law, and a state court's application of that
standard is fully reviewable in this Court on writ of certiorari.
28 U.S.C. § 1257(3). JUSTICE STEVENS concedes the flaw in his
argument when he admits that "a state court's decision invalidating
state legislation on federal constitutional grounds may be reversed
by this Court if the state court misinterpreted the relevant
federal constitutional standard." Post at 449 U. S. 489 .
And contrary to his argument that today's judgment finds "no
precedent in this Court's decisions," post at 449 U. S. 482 ,
we have frequently reversed State Supreme Court decisions
invalidating state statutes or local ordinances on the basis of
equal protection analysis more stringent than that sanctioned by
this Court. E.g., Idaho Dept. of Employment v. Smith, 434 U. S. 100 (1977); Arlington County Board v. Richards, 434 U. S.
5 (1977); Richardson v. Ramirez, 418 U. S.
24 (1974); Lehnhausen v. Lake Shore Auto Parts
Co., 410 U. S. 356 (1973). See also North Dakota Pharmacy Board v. Snyder's Drug
Stores, Inc., 414 U. S. 156 (1973); Dean v. Gadsen Times Publishing Corp., 412 U. S. 543 (1973); McDaniel v. Barresi, 402 U. S.
39 (1971). Never have we suggested that our review of
the judgments in such cases differs in any relevant respect because
they were reached by state courts, rather than federal courts.
Indeed, JUSTICE STEVENS has changed his own view. Previously, he
has stated that state court decisions under the Fourteenth
Amendment granting litigants "more protection than the Federal
Constitution requires," are in error. Idaho Dept. of Employment
v. Smith, supra at 434 U. S. 104 (STEVENS, J., dissenting in part). This is in agreement with the
conclusion of one commentator:
"In reviewing state court resolutions of federal constitutional
issues, the Supreme Court has not differentiated between those
decisions which sustain and those which reject claims of federal
constitutional right. In both instances, once having granted
review, the Court has simply determined whether the state court's
federal constitutional decision is 'correct,' meaning, in this
context, whether it is the decision that the Supreme Court would
independently reach."
Sager, Fair Measure: The Legal Status of Underenforced
Constitutional Norms, 91 Harv.L.Rev. 1212, 1243 (1978) (footnote
omitted). Thus, JUSTICE STEVENS' argument in the dissenting opinion
that today's treatment of the instant case is extraordinary and
unprecedented, see post at 449 U. S. 482 ,
and n. 7, is simply wrong.
[ Footnote 7 ]
Respondents, citing the District Court's Finding of Fact No. 12,
App. A-19, also assert that the actual purpose for the Act was
illegitimate: to "isolate from interstate competition the interests
of certain segments of the local dairy and pulpwood industries."
Brief for Respondents 23. We accept the contrary holding of the
Minnesota Supreme Court that the articulated purpose of the Act is
its actual purpose. See 289 N.W.2d at 82. In equal
protection analysis, this Court will assume that the objectives
articulated by the legislature are actual purposes of the statute
unless an examination of the circumstances forces us to conclude
that they "could not have been a goal of the legislation." See
Weinberger v. Wiesenfeld, 420 U. S. 636 , 420 U. S. 648 ,
n. 16 (1975). Here, a review of the legislative history supports
the Minnesota Supreme Court's conclusion that the principal
purposes of the Act were to promote conservation and ease solid
waste disposal problems. The contrary evidence cited by
respondents, see Brief for Respondents 29-31, is easily
understood, in context, as economic defense of an Act genuinely
proposed for environmental reasons. We will not invalidate a state
statute under the Equal Protection Clause merely because some
legislators sought to obtain votes for the measure on the basis of
its beneficial side effects on state industry.
[ Footnote 8 ]
We express no view whether the District Court could have
dismissed this case on the pleadings or granted summary judgment
for the State on the basis of the legislative history, without
hearing respondents' evidence. See Vance v. Bradley, 440 U. S. 93 , 440 U. S.
109 -112 (1979); Bayside Fish Flour Co. v.
Gentry, 297 U. S. 422 (1936).
[ Footnote 9 ] See n 5, supra. [ Footnote 10 ]
The court adopted the higher of two possible measurements of
energy consumption from paperboard production, apparently because
the lower figure contemplated the use of waste products, such as
sawdust, for energy production. In addition, the court substituted
a lower measurement of the energy consumption from plastic
nonreturnable production for that used in the study. 289 N.W.2d at
885.
[ Footnote 11 ]
This was the conclusion of the Midwest Research Institute study, see n. 5, supra. Brief for Petitioner 21.
[ Footnote 12 ]
The District Court also held that the Act violated substantive
due process, and was apparently affirmed by the State Supreme Court
on this ground. Conclusion of Law No. 1, App. A-23; 289 N.W.2d at
87, n. 20. From our conclusion under equal protection, however, it
follows a fortiori that the Act does not violate the
Fourteenth Amendment's Due Process Clause. See Exxon Corp. v.
Governor of Maryland, 437 U. S. 117 , 372 U. S.
124 -125 (1978); Ferguson v. Skrupa, 372 U. S. 726 (1963).
[ Footnote 13 ]
"The Congress shall have Power . . . To regulate Commerce . . .
among the several States. . . . " U.S.Const., Art. I, § 8, cl.
3.
[ Footnote 14 ]
The Minnesota Supreme Court did not reach the Commerce Clause
issue. 289 N.W.2d at 87, n. 20. The parties and amici have
fully briefed and argued the question, and because of the obvious
factual connection between the rationality analysis under the Equal
Protection Clause and the balancing of interests under the Commerce
Clause, we will reach and decide the question. See New York
City Transit Authority v. Beazer, 440 U.
S. 568 , 440 U. S. 583 ,
n. 24 (1979).
[ Footnote 15 ]
A court may find that a state law constitutes "economic
protectionism" on proof either of discriminatory effect, see
Philadelphia v. New Jersey, or of discriminatory purpose, see Hunt v. Washington Apple Advertising Comm'n, 432 U.S.
at 432 U. S.
352 -353. Respondents advance a "discriminatory purpose"
argument, relying on a finding by the District Court that the
Act's
"actual basis was to promote the economic interests of certain
segments of the local dairy and pulpwood industries at the expense
of the economic interests of other segments of the dairy industry
and the plastics industry."
App. A-19. We have already considered and rejected this argument
in the equal protection context, see n 7, supra, and do so in this context as
well.
[ Footnote 16 ]
Respondent Wells Dairy, an Iowa firm, sells 60% of its milk in
plastic nonreturnable containers, and the remainder in other types
of packages, including paperboard cartons. Tr. 419, 426, 439. The
Chairman of the Board of respondent Marigold Foods, Inc., a
Minnesota dairy, admitted at trial that his firm would continue to
sell milk in plastic nonreturnable containers in other States,
despite the passage of the Act. Id. at 474.
[ Footnote 17 ] See n. 1, supra. The existence of major
in-state interests adversely affected by the Act is a powerful
safeguard against legislative abuse. South Carolina State
Highway Dept. v. Barnwell Bros., Inc., 303 U.
S. 177 , 303 U. S. 187 (1938).
JUSTICE POWELL, concurring in part and dissenting in part.
The Minnesota statute at issue bans the retail sale of milk in
plastic nonreturnable, nonrefillable containers, but permits such
sale in paperboard milk cartons. Respondents challenged the
validity of the statute under both the Equal Protection and
Commerce Clauses. The Minnesota District Court agreed with
respondents on both grounds. The Supreme Court of Minnesota also
agreed that the statute violated the Equal Protection Clause, but
found it unnecessary to reach the Commerce Clause issue.
This Court today reverses the Supreme Court of Minnesota,
finding no merit in either of the alleged grounds of invalidity. I
concur in the view that the statute survives equal protection
challenge, and therefore join the Judgment of reversal on this Page 449 U. S. 475 ground. I also agree with most of Parts I and II of the Court's
opinion.
I would not, however, reach the Commerce Clause issue, but would
remand it for consideration by the Supreme Court of Minnesota. The
District Court expressly found:
"12. Despite the purported policy statement published by the
legislature as its basis for enacting Chapter 268, the actual basis
was to promote the economic interests of certain segments of the
local dairy and pulpwood industries at the expense of the economic
interests of other segments of the dairy industry and the plastics
industry."
App. to Pet. for Cert. A-24. At a subsequent point in its
opinion, and in even more explicit language, the District Court
reiterated its finding that the purpose of the statute related to
interstate commerce. [ Footnote 2/1 ]
These findings were highly relevant to the question whether the
statute discriminated against interstate commerce. See
Philadelphia v. New Jersey, 437 U. S. 617 , 437 U. S. 624 (1978) ("The crucial inquiry . . . must be directed to determining
whether [the statute] is basically a protectionist measure, or
whether it can fairly be viewed as a law directed to legitimate
local concerns, with effects upon interstate commerce that are only
incidental"). Indeed, the trial court's findings normally would
require us to conclude that the Minnesota Legislature was engaging
in such discrimination, as they were not rejected by the Minnesota
Supreme Court. That court simply invalidated the statute on equal
protection grounds, and had no reason to consider the claim of
discrimination against interstate commerce. Page 449 U. S. 476 The Minnesota Supreme Court did accept the avowed legislative purpose of the statute. It stated:
"The Act is intended to promote the policies stated in Minn.St.
116 F. 01; therefore, it is intended to promote the state interest
of encouraging the reuse and recycling of materials and reducing
the amount and type of material entering the solid waste
stream." 289 N.W.2d
79 , 82 (1979). The Court today reads this statement as an
implied rejection of the trial court's specific finding that
the
"actual [purpose] was to promote the economic interests of
certain segments of the local dairy and pulpwood industries at the
expense of the economic interests"
of the nonresident dairy and plastics industry. In my view,
however, the Minnesota Supreme Court was merely assuming that the
statute was intended to promote its stated purposes. It was
entirely appropriate for that court to accept, for purposes of
equal protection analysis, the purpose expressed in the statute. See ante at 449 U. S. 463 ,
n. 7. When the court did so, however, there is no reason to
conclude that it intended to express or imply any view on any issue
it did not consider. In drawing its conclusions, the court included
no discussion whatever of the Commerce Clause issue and, certainly,
no rejection of the trial court's express and repeated findings
concerning the legislature's actual purpose. [ Footnote 2/2 ]
I conclude therefore that this Court has no basis for inferring a rejection of the quite specific factfindings
by the trial court. The Court's decision today, holding that
Chapter 268 does not violate the Commerce Clause, is flatly
contrary Page 449 U. S. 477 to the only relevant specific findings of fact. Although we are
not barred from reaching the Commerce Clause issue, in doing so, we
also act without the benefit of a decision by the highest court of
Minnesota on the question. In these circumstances, it is both
unnecessary and, in my opinion, inappropriate for this Court to
decide the Commerce Clause issue. See, e.g., FTC v.
Anheuser-Busch, Inc., 363 U. S. 536 , 363 U. S. 542 (1960); United States v. Ballard, 322 U. S.
78 , 322 U. S. 88 (1944). Because no reason has been offered for a departure from our
customary restraint, I would remand the case with instructions to
consider specifically whether the statute discriminated
impermissibly against interstate commerce.
[ Footnote 2/1 ]
Finding 23 of the District Court was as follows:
"23. Despite the purported policy reasons published by the
Legislature as bases for enacting Chapter 268, actual bases
were to isolate from interstate competition the interests of
certain segments of the local dairy and pulpwood industries. The
economic welfare of such local interests can be promoted without
the remedies prescribed in Chapter 268."
App. to Pet. for Cert. A-27 (emphasis added).
[ Footnote 2/2 ]
Commerce Clause analysis differs from analysis under the
"rational basis" test. Under the Commerce Clause, a court is
empowered to disregard a legislature's statement of purpose if it
considers it a pretext. See Dean Milk Co. v. Madison, 340 U. S. 349 , 340 U. S. 354 (1951) ("A different view, that the ordinance is valid simply
because it professes to be a health measure, would mean that the
Commerce Clause, of itself, imposes no limitations on state action
other than those laid down by the Due Process Clause, save for the
rare instance where a state artlessly discloses an avowed purpose
to discriminate against interstate goods").
JUSTICE STEVENS, dissenting.
While the Court in this case seems to do nothing more than apply
well established equal protection and Commerce Clause principles to
a particular state statute, in reality, its reversal of the
Minnesota Supreme Court is based upon a newly discovered principle
of federal constitutional law. According to this principle, which
is applied but not explained by the majority, the Federal
Constitution defines not only the relationship between Congress and
the federal courts, but also the relationship between state
legislatures and state courts. Because I can find no support for
this novel constitutional doctrine in either the language of the
Federal Constitution or the prior decisions of this Court, I
respectfully dissent. I The keystone of the Court's equal protection analysis is its
pronouncement that "it is not the function of the courts to
substitute their evaluation of legislative facts for that of the
legislature." Ante at 449 U. S. 470 .
[ Footnote 3/1 ] If the pronouncement
concerned Page 449 U. S. 478 the function of federal courts, it would be amply
supported by reason and precedent. For federal tribunals are courts
of limited jurisdiction, whose powers are confined by the Federal
Constitution, by statute, and by the decisions of this Court. It is
not surprising, therefore, that the Court's pronouncement is
supported by citation only to precedents dealing with the function
that a federal court may properly perform when it is
reviewing the constitutionality of a law enacted by Congress or by
a state legislature. [ Footnote
3/2 ] Page 449 U. S. 479 But what.is the source -- if indeed there be one -- of this
Court's power to make the majestic announcement that it is not the
function of a state court to substitute its evaluation of
legislative facts for that of a state legislature? I should have
thought the allocation of functions within the structure of a state
government would be a matter for the State to determine. I know of
nothing in the Federal Constitution that prohibits a State from
giving lawmaking power to its courts. [ Footnote 3/3 ] Page 449 U. S. 480 Nor is there anything in the Federal Constitution that prevents
a state court from reviewing factual determinations made by a state
legislature or any other state agency. [ Footnote 3/4 ] If a state statute expressly authorized a
state tribunal to sit as a Council of Revision with full power to
modify or to amend Page 449 U. S. 481 the work product of its legislature, that statute would not
violate any federal rule of which I am aware. The functions that a
state court shall perform within the structure of state government
are unquestionably matters of state law.
One of the few propositions that this Court has respected with
unqualified consistency -- until today -- is the rule that a
federal court is bound to respect the interpretation of state law
announced by the highest judicial tribunal in a State. [ Footnote 3/5 ] In this case, the Minnesota
Supreme Court has held that the state trial court acted properly
when it reviewed the factual basis for the state legislation, and
implicitly the Minnesota Supreme Court also has held that its own
review of the legislative record was proper. Moreover, it also has
determined as a matter of state law how it properly should resolve
conflicts in the evidence presented to the state legislature, as
supplemented by the additional evidence presented to the trial
court in this case. [ Footnote 3/6 ]
In my opinion, the factual conclusions Page 449 U. S. 482 drawn by the Minnesota courts concerning the deliberations of
the Minnesota Legislature are entitled to just as much deference as
if they had been drafted by the state legislature itself and
incorporated in a preamble to the state statute. The State of
Minnesota has told us in unambiguous language that this statute is
not rationally related to any environmental objective; it seems to
me to be a matter of indifference, for purposes of applying the
federal Equal Protection Clause, whether that message to us from
the State of Minnesota is conveyed by the State Supreme Court, or
by the state legislature itself.
I find it extraordinary that this federal tribunal feels free to
conduct its own de novo review of a state legislative
record in search of a rational basis that the highest court of the
State has expressly rejected. There is no precedent in this Court's
decisions for such federal oversight of a State's lawmaking
process. [ Footnote 3/7 ] Of course,
if a federal trial court had reviewed the Page 449 U. S. 483 factual basis for a state law, conflicts in the evidence would
have to be resolved in favor of the State. [ Footnote 3/8 ] But when a state court has conducted the
review, it is not our business to disagree Page 449 U. S. 484 with the state tribunal's evaluation of the State's own
lawmaking process. Even if the state court should tell us that a
state statute has a meaning that we believe the state Page 449 U. S. 485 legislature plainly did not intend, we are not free to take our
own view of the matter. [ Footnote
3/9 ]
Once it is recognized that this Court may not review the
question of state law presented by the Minnesota courts' decision
to reevaluate the evidence presented to the legislature, the result
we must reach in this case is apparent. Because the factual
conclusions drawn by the Minnesota courts are clearly supported by
the record, [ Footnote 3/10 ] the
only federal issue that this case presents is whether a
discriminatory statute that is Page 449 U. S. 486 admittedly irrational violates the Equal Protection Clause of
the Fourteenth Amendment. The Court implicitly acknowledges that
the Minnesota Supreme Court applied the proper rule of federal law
when it answered that question. [ Footnote 3/11 ] Whatever we may think about the
environmental consequences of this discriminatory law, it follows
inexorably that it is our duty as federal judges to affirm the
judgment of the Minnesota Supreme Court. II In light of my conclusion that the Minnesota Supreme Court's
equal protection decision must be affirmed, I need not address the
Commerce Clause question resolved by the majority. Ante at 449 U. S.
470 -474. Nonetheless, I believe that the majority's
treatment of that question compels two observations.
First, in my opinion, the Court errs in undertaking to decide
the Commerce Clause question at all. The state trial court
addressed the question and found that the statute was designed by
the Minnesota Legislature to promote the economic interests of the
local dairy and pulpwood industries at the expense of competing
economic groups. [ Footnote 3/12 ]
On appeal, the Page 449 U. S. 487 Minnesota Supreme Court expressly declined to consider this
aspect of the trial court's decision, and accordingly made no
comment at all upon the merits of the Commerce Clause question. 289 N.W.2d
79 , 87, n. 20 (1979). Generally, when reviewing state court
decisions, this Court will not decide questions which the highest
court of a State has properly declined to address. The majority
offers no persuasive explanation for its unusual action in this
case. [ Footnote 3/13 ] In the
absence Page 449 U. S. 488 of some substantial justification for this action, I would not
deprive the Minnesota Supreme Court of the first opportunity to
review this aspect of the decision of the Minnesota trial
court.
Second, the Court's Commerce Clause analysis suffers from the
same flaw as its equal protection analysis. The Court rejects the
findings of the Minnesota trial court not because they are clearly
erroneous, but because the Court is of the view that the Minnesota
courts are not authorized to exercise such a broad power of review
over the Minnesota Legislature. See ante at 449 U. S. 471 ,
n. 15. After rejecting the trial court's findings, the Court goes
on to find that any burden the Minnesota statute may impose upon
interstate commerce is not excessive in light of the substantial
state interests furthered by the statute. Ante at 449 U. S. 473 .
However, the Minnesota Supreme Court expressly found that the
statute is not rationally related to the substantial state
interests identified by the majority. [ Footnote 3/14 ] Because I believe, as explained in 449 U. S. supra, that the Court's intrusion upon the lawmaking
process of the State of Minnesota is without constitutional
sanction or precedential support, it is clear to me that the
findings of the Minnesota Supreme Court must be respected by this
Court. Accordingly, the essential predicate for the majority's
conclusion that the "local benefits [are] ample to support
Minnesota's decision under the Commerce Clause," ante at 449 U. S. 473 ,
is absent. III The majority properly observes that a state court, when applying
the provisions of the Federal Constitution, may not Page 449 U. S. 489 apply a constitutional standard more stringent than that
announced in the relevant decisions of this Court. See
ante at 449 U. S.
461 -463, n. 6. It follows from this observation that a
state court's decision invalidating state legislation on federal
constitutional grounds may be reversed by this Court if the state
court misinterpreted the relevant federal constitutional standard.
In this case, however, the Minnesota Supreme Court applied the
correct federal equal protection standard and properly declined to
consider the Commerce Clause. The majority reverses this decision
because it disagrees with the Minnesota courts' perception of their
role in the State's lawmaking process, not because of any error in
the application of federal law. In my opinion, this action is
beyond the Court's authority. I therefore respectfully dissent.
[ Footnote 3/1 ] See also ante at 449 U. S. 464 ,
where the Court states that
"States are not required to convince the courts of the
correctness of their legislative judgments'; and ibid., where the Court states that 'litigants may not procure invalidation
of the legislation merely by tendering evidence in court that the
legislature was mistaken."
[ Footnote 3/2 ]
The majority cites Vance v. Bradley, 440 U. S.
93 (1979); Ferguson v. Skrupa, 372 U.
S. 726 (1963); Day-Brite Lighting, Inc. v.
Missouri, 342 U. S. 421 (1952); United States v. Carolene Products Co., 304 U. S. 144 (1938); and Henderson Co. v. Thompson, 300 U.
S. 258 (1937), in support of its conclusion that it is
not the function of the Minnesota courts to reevaluate facts
considered by the Minnesota Legislature. See ante at 449 U. S. 464 , 449 U. S. 469 .
However, even a cursory examination of these cases reveals that
they provide no support for the Court's decision in this case.
In four of the cited cases, the Court reviewed the actions of
lower federal, not state, courts. These cases thus shed no light
upon the role a state court properly may play in reviewing actions
of the state legislature. In Vance v. Bradley and United States v. Carolene Products, Federal District
Courts had invalidated federal statutes on federal constitutional
grounds. In both cases, this Court reversed because the District
Courts had exceeded the scope of their powers by reevaluating the
factual bases for the congressional enactments. See Vance,
supra, at 440 U. S.
111 -112; Carolene Products, supra, at 440 U. S. 152 , 440 U. S. 154 .
In Ferguson v. Skrupa, a Federal District Court had
invalidated a Kansas statute on federal constitutional grounds.
This Court reversed, finding that the District Court had exceeded
constitutional limitations by substituting its judgment for that of
the Kansas Legislature. See 372 U.S. at 372 U. S.
729 -731. The Court also indicated in Ferguson that its own power to supervise the actions of state legislatures
is narrowly circumscribed. Id. at 372 U. S.
730 -731. Finally, in Henderson Co. v. Thompson, a Federal District Court had sustained a Texas statute in the face
of a constitutional challenge. In affirming that decision, the
Court simply observed that "[t]he needs of conservation are to be
determined by the Legislature." 300 U.S. at 300 U. S.
264 .
In only one of the cases cited by the majority did the Court
review a state court judgment. In Day-Brite Lighting, Inc. v.
Missouri, a Missouri statute was challenged on due process,
equal protection, and Contract Clause theories. The Missouri
Supreme Court had upheld the statute, and this Court affirmed. In
the course of its opinion, the Court stated that it was
not free to reevaluate the legislative judgment or act as "a
superlegislature." 342 U.S. at 342 U. S. 423 , 342 U. S. 425 .
The Court did not comment at all upon the extent of the Missouri
Supreme Court's authority to supervise the activities of the
Missouri Legislature. Nothing in the Day-Brite Lighting opinion can be construed as the source of the Court's newly found
power to determine for the States which lawmaking powers may be
allocated to their courts and which to their legislatures.
[ Footnote 3/3 ]
Responding to an argument that the lawmaking power of the
Virginia Legislature had been improperly assigned to another arm of
the State's government, Justice Cardozo, writing for the Court in Highland Farms Dairy, Inc. v. Agnew, 300 U.
S. 608 , 300 U. S.
612 -613 (1937), stated:
"The Constitution of the United States, in the circumstances
here exhibited, has no voice upon the subject. The statute
challenged as invalid is one adopted by a state. This removes
objections that might be worthy of consideration if we were dealing
with an act of Congress. How power shall be distributed by a state
among its governmental organs is commonly, if not always, a
question for the state itself. Nothing in the distribution here
attempted supplies the basis for an exception. The statute is not a
denial of a republican form of government. Constitution, Art. IV, §
4. Even if it were, the enforcement of that guarantee, according to
the settled doctrine, is for Congress, not the courts. Pacific
States Telephone Co. v. Oregon, 223 U. S.
118 ; Davis v. Hildebrant, 241 U. S.
565 ; Ohio ex rel. Bryant v. Akron Park
District, 281 U. S. 74 , 281 U. S.
79 , 241 U. S. 80 . Cases such as Panama Refining Co. v. Ryan, 293 U. S.
388 , and Schechter Poultry Corp. v. United
States, 295 U. S. 495 , cited by
appellants, are quite beside the point. What was in controversy
there was the distribution of power between President and Congress,
or between Congress and administrative officers or commissions, a
controversy affecting the structure of the national government as
established by the provisions of the national constitution."
"So far as the objection to delegation is founded on the
Constitution of Virginia, it is answered by a decision of the
highest court of the state. In Reynolds v. Milk
Commission, 163 Va. 957; 179 S.E. 507, the Supreme Court of
Appeals passed upon the validity of the statute now in question. .
. . A judgment by the highest court of a state as to the meaning
and effect of its own constitution is decisive and controlling
everywhere." See also Dreyer v. Illinois, 187 U. S.
71 , 187 U. S. 83 -84
(1902); Sweezy v. New Hampshire, 354 U.
S. 234 , 354 U. S.
256 -257 (1957) (Frankfurter, J., concurring in
result).
[ Footnote 3/4 ]
In Ferguson v. Skrupa, supra, the Court indicated that
the Federal Constitution does prevent the federal courts from
reviewing factual determinations made by a state legislature. In
rejecting the substantive due process cases of an earlier era, the
Court stated:
"Under the system of government created by our Constitution, it
is up to legislatures, not courts, to decide on the wisdom and
utility of legislation."
372 U.S. at 372 U. S. 729 .
The Court went on to explain this constitutional limitation:
"We have returned to the original constitutional proposition
that courts do not substitute their social and economic beliefs for
the judgment of legislative bodies, who are elected to pass laws. .
. . Legislative bodies have broad scope to experiment with economic
problems, and this Court does not sit to"
"subject the State to an intolerable supervision hostile to the
basic principles of our Government and wholly beyond the protection
which the general clause of the Fourteenth Amendment was intended
to secure." Id. at 372 U. S. 730 (footnote omitted).
The Court's conclusion in Ferguson that the Constitution imposes
limitations upon the power of the federal courts to review
legislative judgments was clearly correct, and was consistent with
the structure of the Federal Constitution and "the system of
government created" therein. The Constitution defines the
relationship among the coordinate branches of the Federal
Government and prescribes for each branch certain limited powers.
The Federal Constitution, however, is silent with respect to the
powers of the coordinate branches of state governments and the
relationship among those branches.
[ Footnote 3/5 ]
Although this proposition is so well established as to require
no citation of authority, abundant authority is readily available. See, e.g., North Carolina v. Butler, 441 U.
S. 369 , 441 U. S. 376 ,
n. 7 (1979); Ward v. Illinois, 431 U.
S. 767 , 431 U. S. 772 (1977); Eastlake v. Forest City Enterprises, Inc., 426 U. S. 668 , 426 U. S. 674 ,
n. 9 (1976); Hortonville Joint School District No. 1 v.
Hortonville Education Assn., 426 U. S. 482 , 426 U. S. 488 (1976); Mullaney v. Wilbur, 421 U.
S. 684 , 421 U. S. 691 (1975); Memorial Hospital v. Maricopa County, 415 U.
S. 250 , 415 U. S. 256 (1974); Wardius v. Oregon, 412 U.
S. 470 , 412 U. S. 477 (1973); Groppi v. Wisconsin, 400 U.
S. 505 , 400 U. S. 507 (1971).
[ Footnote 3/6 ]
In its memorandum in this case, the state trial court initially
observed that it was not free to "substitute its judgment for that
of the legislature as to the wisdom or desirability of the act."
App. A-24. With respect to the facts considered by the legislature,
however, the trial court found that, "as factfinder, [it was]
obliged to weigh and evaluate this evidence, much of which was in
sharp conflict." Id. at A-25.
In its opinion affirming the trial court's decision, the
Minnesota Supreme Court took a similar view of the function to be
performed by the Minnesota courts when reviewing Minnesota
legislation:
"We are aware of the deference that is accorded to the
legislature when the present type of statute is analyzed on equal
protection grounds. Nevertheless, our inquiry into the
constitutional propriety of the present classification separating
paper containers from plastic nonrefillables is dependent upon
facts. Based upon the relevant findings of fact by the trial court,
supported by the record, and upon our own independent review of
documentary sources, we believe the evidence conclusively
demonstrates that the discrimination against plastic nonrefillables
is not rationally related to the Act's objectives." 289 N.W.2d
79 , 82 (1979).
[ Footnote 3/7 ]
In its footnote 6, ante at 449 U. S.
461 -463, the Court takes issue with my suggestion t.hat
its action in this case is unprecedented by citing four cases in
which the Court reversed State Supreme Court decision invalidating
provisions of state law on federal equal protection grounds. See Idaho Dept. of Employment v. Smith, 434 U.
S. 100 (1977) (per curiam); Arlington County Board
v. Richards, 434 U. S. 5 (1977)
(per curiam); Richardson v. Ramirez, 418 U. S.
24 (1974); Lehnhausen v. Lake Shore Auto Parts, 410 U. S. 356 (1973). In each of those cases, however, this Court concluded that
the state court had applied an incorrect legal standard; in none
did this Court reassess the factual predicate for the state court
decision.
In Idaho Dept. of Employment, the Idaho Supreme Court had
invalidated a statutory classification not because it generally
failed to further legitimate state goals, but rather because the
court had found that the classification was imperfect, since some
members of the class denied unemployment benefits were in fact as
available for full-time employment as members of the class entitled
to benefits under the Idaho statute. See Smith v. Department of
Employment, 98 Idaho 43, 43-44, 557 P.2d 637, 637-638 (1976),
citing Kerr v. Department of Employment, 97 Idaho 385, 545
P.2d 473 (1976). This Court did not disagree with the Idaho court's
finding that the classification was imperfect, but merely held that
this imperfection was legally insufficient to invalidate the
statute under the Equal Protection Clause. 434 U.S. at 434 U. S.
101 -102. In Arlington County Board v. Richards, the Virginia Supreme Court had recognized the rational basis test
as the appropriate equal protection standard, but then had
proceeded to apply a more stringent standard to the municipal
ordinance at issue. The court had expressly noted that the
municipal ordinance "may relieve the [parking] problems to which it
was directed." However, the court concluded that the means employed
by the county to deal with these problems -- a classification based
upon residency -- created an unconstitutional "invidious
discrimination." See Arlington County Board v. Richards, 217 Va. 645, 651, 231 S.E.2d 231, 235 (1977). This Court reversed,
rejecting the conclusion that the ordinance's residency
classification resulted in an invidious discrimination. 434 U.S. at 434 U. S. 7 . In Richardson v. Ramirez, a voting rights case, the
California Supreme Court was reversed not because it had reexamined
the factual determinations of the California Legislature, but
because this Court found that the statutory discrimination at issue
was expressly authorized by § 2 of the Fourteenth Amendment. 418
U.S. at 418 U. S. 41 -56.
Finally, in Lake Shore Auto Parts v. Lehnhausen, the
Illinois Supreme Court had held, in essence, that a classification
used in determining liability for a property tax must, as a
constitutional matter, be based upon the nature of the property at
issue, and not upon the corporate or noncorporate character of the
property's owner. See Lake Shore Auto Parts v.
Korzen, 49 Ill. 2d
137 , 149-151, 273 N.E.2d
592 , 598-599 (1971). This Court rejected this principle,
finding it inconsistent with prior decisions clearly establishing
that distinctions between individuals and corporations in tax
legislation violated no constitutional rights. 410 U.S. at 410 U. S.
359 -365.
As the majority observes, the Court in each of these cases
reversed the state court decisions because the state courts had
applied an equal protection standard more stringent than that
sanctioned by this Court. Quite frankly, in my opinion, it would
have been sound judicial policy in all four of those cases to allow
the state courts to accord even greater protection within their
respective jurisdictions than the Federal Constitution commands. See my dissent in Idaho Dept. of Employment,
supra at 434 U. S. 104 .
But what is especially relevant here is the fact that in none of
those cases had the state courts found, after a full evidentiary
hearing, that the factual predicate for the state law at issue was
simply not true. The Minnesota courts in this case made such a
finding after the development of an extensive record. The Minnesota
courts then applied the correct federal legal standard to the facts
revealed by this record, and concluded that the statutory
classification was not rationally related to a legitimate state
purpose. As I read the cases cited by the majority, they are simply
inapposite in this case. My own research has uncovered no instance
in which the Court has reversed the decision of the highest court
of a State, as it does in this case, because the state court
exceeded some federal constitutional limitation upon its power to
review the factual determinations of the state legislature. The
Court has never before, to my knowledge, undertaken to define, as a
matter of federal law, the appropriate relationship between a state
court and a state legislature.
[ Footnote 3/8 ]
In most of the cases in which the Court has indicated that
courts may not substitute their judgment for that of the
legislature, the Court was reviewing decisions of the lower federal
courts. See, e.g., New Orleans v. Dukes, 427 U.
S. 297 , 427 U. S. 303 (1976) (per curiam); Hughes v. Alexandria Scrap Corp., 426 U. S. 794 , 426 U. S. 812 (1976); United States v. Maryland Savings-Share Ins.
Corp., 400 U. S. 4 , 400 U. S. 6 (1970)
(per curiam); Firemen v. Chicago, R.I. & P. R. Co., 393 U. S. 129 , 393 U. S. 136 ,
138-139 (1968); Williamson v. Lee Optical Co., 348 U. S. 483 , 348 U. S.
487 -488 (1955); Secretary of Agriculture v. Central
Roig Refining Co., 338 U. S. 604 , 338 U. S.
618 -619 (1950); Daniel v. Family Insurance Co., 336 U. S. 220 , 336 U. S. 224 (1949); Clark v. Paul Gray, Inc., 306 U.
S. 583 , 306 U. S. 594 (1939); South Carolina State Highway Dept. v. Barnwell Bros.,
Inc., 303 U. S. 177 , 303 U. S.
190 -191 (1938); Bayside Fish Flour Co. v.
Gentry, 297 U. S. 422 , 297 U. S.
427 -428, 297 U. S. 430 (1936); Borden's Farm Products Co. v. Ten Eyck, 297 U. S. 251 , 297 U. S. 263 (1936); Sproles v. Binford, 286 U.
S. 374 , 286 U. S.
388 -389 (1932); Standard Oil Co. v. Marysville, 279 U. S. 582 , 279 U. S. 584 ,
586 (1929); Hebe Co. v. Shaw, 248 U.
S. 297 , 248 U. S. 303 (1919). In those instances in which the Court was reviewing state
court decisions, its statements with respect to the limited role of
the judiciary in reviewing state legislation clearly concerned its
own authority to act as a "superlegislature," not the authority of
a state court to do so where permitted by state law. See, e.g.,
Exxon Corp. v. Governor of Maryland, 437 U.
S. 117 , 437 U. S. 124 (1978); Railway Express Agency, Inc. v. New York, 336 U. S. 106 , 336 U. S. 109 (1949); Olsen v. Nebraska, 313 U.
S. 236 , 313 U. S. 246 (1941); Zahn v. Board of Public Works, 274 U.
S. 325 , 274 U. S. 328 (1927); Cusack Co. v. Chicago, 242 U.
S. 526 , 242 U. S. 531 (1917); Hadacheck v. Los Angeles, 239 U.
S. 394 , 239 U. S.
413 -414 (1915); Price v. Illinois, 238 U.
S. 446 , 238 U. S.
452 -453 (1915); Laurel Hill Cemetery v. San
Francisco, 216 U. S. 358 , 216 U. S. 365 (1910).
[ Footnote 3/9 ]
This Court will defer to the interpretation of state law
announced by the highest court of a State even where a more
reasonable interpretation is apparent, see, e.g., O'Brien v.
Skinner, 414 U. S. 524 , 414 U. S. 531 (1974), a contrary construction might save a state statute from
constitutional invalidity, see, e.g., Landmark Communications,
Inc. v. Virginia, 435 U. S. 829 , 435 U. S. 837 ,
n. 9 (1978), or it appears that the state court has attributed an
unusually inflexible command to its legislature, see, e.g.,
Kingsley Pictures Corp. v Regents, 360 U.
S. 684 , 360 U. S.
688 -689 (1959).
[ Footnote 3/10 ]
As the majority notes, the evidence considered by the Minnesota
courts was conflicting, ante at 449 U. S. 460 , 449 U. S. 464 , 449 U. S. 469 ,
and the respondents "produced impressive supporting evidence at
trial" indicating that the decision of the Minnesota Legislature
was factually unsound. Ante at 449 U. S. 463 .
In light of this record, this Court clearly cannot reverse the
concurrent factual findings of two state courts.
Moreover, since there is no significant difference between
plastic containers and paper containers in terms of environmental
impact, and since no one contends that the Minnesota statute will
reduce the consumption of dairy products, it is not difficult to
understand the state judges' skeptical scrutiny of a legislative
ban on the use of one kind of container without imposing any
present or future restriction whatsoever on the use of the
other.
[ Footnote 3/11 ]
It is true that the Court carefully avoids an express
acknowledgment that the Minnesota Supreme Court applied the correct
legal standard. Not one word in the Court's opinion, however,
suggests that the Court has any disagreement with the state court's
understanding of the proper federal rule.
[ Footnote 3/12 ]
The trial court made the following findings of fact.
"12. Despite the purported policy statement published by the
Legislature as its basis for enacting Chapter 268, the actual basis
was to promote the economic interests of certain segments of the
local dairy and pulpwood industries at the expense of the economic
interests of other segments of the dairy industry and the plastics
industry."
" * * * *" "23. Despite the purported policy reasons published by the
Legislature as bases for enacting Chapter 268, actual bases were to
isolate from interstate competition the interests of certain
segments of the local dairy and pulpwood industries. The economic
welfare of such local interests can be promoted without the
remedies prescribed in Chapter 268."
App. A-19, A-22. These findings were repeated in the memorandum
filed by the trial court in this case:
"The relevant legislative history of Chapter 268 support
[ sic ] a conclusion that the real basis for it was to serve
certain economic interests (paper, pulpwood, and some dairies) at
the expense of other competing economic groups (plastic and certain
dairies) by prohibiting the plastic milk bottle." Id. at A-24.
[ Footnote 3/13 ]
According to the majority, its decision to address the Commerce
Clause question is justified
"because of the obvious factual connection between the
rationality analysis under the Equal Protection Clause and the
balancing of interests under the Commerce Clause." Ante at 449 U. S. 470 ,
n. 14. The majority cites New York City Transit Authority v.
Beazer, 440 U. S. 568 (1979), in support of this rationale. This justification is
inadequate, in my opinion, for two reasons.
First, in light of the trial court's factual finding that the
Minnesota Legislature enacted the statute for protectionist, rather
than environmental, reasons, see 449
U.S. 456 fn3/12|>n. 12, supra, the Equal Protection
Clause and Commerce Clause inquiries are not necessarily as similar
as the Court suggests. As the majority acknowledges, if a state law
which purports to promote environmental goals is actually
protectionist in design, a virtually automatic rule of invalidity,
not a balancing of interests test, is applied. See ante at 449 U. S. 471 . See also New Orleans v. Dukes, 427 U.S. at 427 U. S. 304 ,
n. 5.
Second, in Beazer, the Court reviewed the decision of a
lower federal court, not a state supreme court. While this Court,
in its discretion, may elect to deprive lower federal courts of the
opportunity to decide particular statutory questions, it seems to
me that respect for the Minnesota Supreme Court as the highest
court of a sovereign State dictates that we not casually divest it
of authority to decide a constitutional question on which it
properly declined to comment when this case was first before it.
Such deference is especially appropriate here because the Court's
analysis of the Commerce Clause issue requires rejection of the
state trial court's findings of fact.
[ Footnote 3/14 ]
As noted in 449 U. S. supra, the Court rejects the Minnesota Supreme Court's
findings not because they are without support in the record -- they
clearly are adequately supported, see 449
U.S. 456 fn3/10|>n. 10, supra -- but because it
feels that the Minnesota Supreme Court was without authority to do
anything other than endorse the factual conclusions of the
Minnesota Legislature. | Minnesota banned the sale of milk in plastic containers to promote resource conservation, ease waste disposal, and conserve energy. The ban was challenged in court, arguing it violated the Equal Protection Clause and Commerce Clause. The Minnesota Supreme Court ruled against the ban, but the US Supreme Court overturned this, ruling that the ban was rationally related to the state's objectives and did not violate the Equal Protection Clause. The Court accepted the state's environmental goals and respected the legislature's authority to address them, even if the facts were debatable. The Court did not address the Commerce Clause issue. |
Equal Protection | Village of Willowbrook v. Olech | https://supreme.justia.com/cases/federal/us/528/562/ | OCTOBER TERM, 1999
Syllabus
VILLAGE OF WILLOWBROOK ET AL. v. OLECH
CERTIORARI TO THE UNITED STATES COURT OF APPEALS FOR THE SEVENTH
CIRCUIT
No. 98-1288. Argued January 10, 2000-Decided February 23,
2000
When respondent Olech and her late husband first asked
petitioner Village of Willowbrook (Village) to connect their
property to the municipal water supply, the Village conditioned the
connection on the Olechs granting it a 33-foot easement. Although
it subsequently reduced the easement to the 15 feet required of
other property owners, Olech sued, claiming that the Village's
demand for an additional 18-foot easement violated the Fourteenth
Amendment's Equal Protection Clause, and asserting that the
easement was irrational and arbitrary, that the Village was
motivated by ill will resulting from the Olechs' success in an
unrelated lawsuit against the Village, and that the Village acted
either with the intent to deprive Olech of her rights or in
reckless disregard of her rights. The District Court dismissed the
suit for failure to state a claim, but the Seventh Circuit
reversed, holding that Olech's spiteful ill will allegation stated
a claim. Held: The Equal Protection Clause gives rise to a cause
of action on behalf of a "class of one" where the plaintiff does
not allege membership in a class or group, but alleges that she has
been intentionally treated differently from others similarly
situated and that there is no rational basis for such treatment.
See, e. g., Sioux City Bridge Co. v. Dakota County, 260 U. S. 441 .
The Clause secures every person within a State's jurisdiction
against intentional and arbitrary discrimination, whether
occasioned by a statute's express terms or by its improper
execution. Id., at 445. Here, Olech's allegations that the
Village intentionally demanded a 33-foot easement from her when it
required only 15 feet from similarly situated property owners, that
the demand was irrational and arbitrary, and that the Village
ultimately connected her property in return for a 15-foot
easement-quite apart from the Village's subjective motive-state a
claim for relief under traditional equal protection analysis. Thus,
the Court does not reach the alternative "subjective ill will"
theory on which the Seventh Circuit relied. 160 F.3d
386 , affirmed. James L. DeAno argued the cause and filed briefs for
petitioners. 563 Irving L. Gornstein argued the cause for the United States as
amicus curiae. With him on the brief were Solicitor General Waxman,
Acting Assistant Attorney General Ogden, Deputy Solicitor General
Underwood, and Mark B. Stern. John R. Wimmer argued the cause and filed a brief for
respondent. *
PER CURIAM.
Respondent Grace Olech and her late husband Thaddeus asked
petitioner Village of Willowbrook (Village) to connect their
property to the municipal water supply. The Village at first
conditioned the connection on the Olechs granting the Village a
33-foot easement. The Olechs objected, claiming that the Village
only required a 15-foot easement from other property owners seeking
access to the water supply. After a 3-month delay, the Village
relented and agreed to provide water service with only a 15-foot
easement.
Olech sued the Village, claiming that the Village's demand of an
additional 18-foot easement violated the Equal Protection Clause of
the Fourteenth Amendment. Olech asserted that the 33-foot easement
demand was "irrational and wholly arbitrary"; that the Village's
demand was actually motivated by ill will resulting from the
Olechs' previous filing of an unrelated, successful lawsuit against
the Village; and that the Village acted either with the intent to
deprive Olech of her rights or in reckless disregard of her rights.
App. 10, 12.
The District Court dismissed the lawsuit pursuant to Federal
Rule of Civil Procedure 12(b)(6) for failure to state a cognizable
claim under the Equal Protection Clause. Relying on Circuit
precedent, the Court of Appeals for the Sev- * Richard Ruda, James I. Crowley, and Donald B.
Ayer filed a brief for the International City/County Management
Association et al. as amici curiae urging reversal.
Harvey Grossman, Steven R. Shapiro, and Richard J. O'Brien filed a brief for the ACLU as amicus curiae urging
affirmance. 564 enth Circuit reversed, holding that a plaintiff can allege an
equal protection violation by asserting that state action was
motivated solely by a "'spiteful effort to "get" him for reasons
wholly unrelated to any legitimate state objective.'" 160 F.3d
386 , 387 (1998) (quoting Esmail v. Macrane, 53 F.
3d 176, 180 (CA7 1995)). It determined that Olech's
complaint sufficiently alleged such a claim. 160 F. 3d, at 388. We
granted certiorari to determine whether the Equal Protection Clause
gives rise to a cause of action on behalf of a "class of one" where
the plaintiff did not allege membership in a class or group. * 527
U. S. 1067 (1999).
Our cases have recognized successful equal protection claims
brought by a "class of one," where the plaintiff alleges that she
has been intentionally treated differently from others similarly
situated and that there is no rational basis for the difference in
treatment. See Sioux City Bridge Co. v. Dakota
County, 260 U. S.
441 (1923); Allegheny Pittsburgh Coal Co. v. Commission of Webster Cty., 488 U. S. 336 (1989). In
so doing, we have explained that" '[t]he purpose of the equal
protection clause of the Fourteenth Amendment is to secure every
person within the State's jurisdiction against intentional and
arbitrary discrimination, whether occasioned by express terms of a
statute or by its improper execution through duly constituted
agents.'" Sioux City Bridge Co., supra, at 445 (quoting Sunday Lake Iron Co. v. Township of Wakefield, 247 U. S. 350 ,
352 (1918)).
*We note that the complaint in this case could be read to allege
a class of five. In addition to Grace and Thaddeus Olech, their
neighbors Rodney and Phyllis Zimmer and Howard Brinkman requested
to be connected to the municipal water supply, and the Village
initially demanded the 33-foot easement from all of them. The
Zimmers and Mr. Brinkman were also involved in the previous,
successful lawsuit against the Village, which allegedly created the
ill will motivating the excessive easement demand. Whether the
complaint alleges a class of one or of five is of no consequence
because we conclude that the number of individuals in a class is
immaterial for equal protection analysis. 565 That reasoning is applicable to this case. Olech's complaint can
fairly be construed as alleging that the Village intentionally
demanded a 33-foot easement as a condition of connecting her
property to the municipal water supply where the Village required
only a 15-foot easement from other similarly situated property
owners. See Conley v. Gibson, 355 U. S. 41 , 45-46
(1957). The complaint also alleged that the Village's demand was
"irrational and wholly arbitrary" and that the Village ultimately
connected her property after receiving a clearly adequate 15-foot
easement. These allegations, quite apart from the Village's
subjective motivation, are sufficient to state a claim for relief
under traditional equal protection analysis. We therefore affirm
the judgment of the Court of Appeals, but do not reach the
alternative theory of "subjective ill will" relied on by that
court.
It is so ordered.
JUSTICE BREYER, concurring in the result.
The Solicitor General and the village of Willowbrook have
expressed concern lest we interpret the Equal Protection Clause in
this case in a way that would transform many ordinary violations of
city or state law into violations of the Constitution. It might be
thought that a rule that looks only to an intentional difference in
treatment and a lack of a rational basis for that different
treatment would work such a transformation. Zoning decisions, for
example, will often, perhaps almost always, treat one landowner
differently from another, and one might claim that, when a city's
zoning authority takes an action that fails to conform to a city
zoning regulation, it lacks a "rational basis" for its action (at
least if the regulation in question is reasonably clear).
This case, however, does not directly raise the question whether
the simple and common instance of a faulty zoning decision would
violate the Equal Protection Clause. That is because the Court of
Appeals found that in this case respond- 566 ent had alleged an extra factor as well-a factor that the Court
of Appeals called "vindictive action," "illegitimate animus," or
"ill will." 160 F.3d
386 , 388 (CA7 1998). And, in that respect, the court
said this case resembled Esmail v. Macrane, 53 F.3d
176 (CA71995), because the Esmail plaintiff had
alleged that the municipality's differential treatment "was the
result not of prosecutorial discretion honestly (even if
ineptly-even if arbitrarily) exercised but of an illegitimate
desire to 'get' him." 160 F. 3d, at 388.
In my view, the presence of that added factor in this case is
sufficient to minimize any concern about transforming
run-of-the-mill zoning cases into cases of constitutional right.
For this reason, along with the others mentioned by the Court, I
concur in the result. 567 The next page is purposely numbered 801. The numbers between 566
and 801 were intentionally omitted, in order to make it possible to
publish the orders with permanent page numbers, thus making
the official citations available upon publication of the
preliminary prints of the United States Reports. 568 OCTOBER 4, 1999 Certiorari Granted-Vacated and Remanded
No. 98-9308. CROSS V. CALIFORNIA. Ct. App. Cal., 1st
App.
Dist.; and
No. 98-9504. COOPER V. CALIFORNIA. Ct. App. Cal., 1st
App.
Dist. Motions of petitioners for leave to proceed in forma
pauperis granted. Certiorari granted, judgment vacated, and
cases remanded for further consideration in light of Lilly v. Virginia, 527 U. S. 116 (1999).
Miscellaneous Orders
No. D-1961. IN RE DISBARMENT OF WEISSER. Disbarment entered.
[For earlier order herein, see 524 U. S. 913.]
No. D-2073. IN RE DISBARMENT OF NUNES. Disbarment entered. [For
earlier order herein, see 526 U. S. 1128.]
No. D-2076. IN RE DISBARMENT OF PATT. Disbarment entered. [For
earlier order herein, see 526 U. S. 1143.]
No. D-2088. IN RE DISBARMENT OF ROBINS. Disbarment entered. [For
earlier order herein, see 527 U. S. 1020.]
No. D-2101. IN RE DISBARMENT OF JACOBS. Patricia Dianne Jacobs,
of Washington, D. C., is suspended from the practice of law
in this Court, and a rule will issue, returnable within 40 days,
requiring her to show cause why she should not be disbarred from
the practice of law in this Court.
No. D-2102. IN RE DISBARMENT OF EAGLE. Saul L. Eagle, of New
York, N. Y., is suspended from the practice of law in this Court,
and a rule will issue, returnable within 40 days, requiring him to
show cause why he should not be disbarred from the practice of law
in this Court.
No. D-2103. IN RE DISBARMENT OF MANEY. William Kenneth Maney, of
Johnson City, N. Y., is suspended from the practice 801 | The Supreme Court ruled that the Equal Protection Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment allows a "class of one" claim, where a person is intentionally treated differently from others similarly situated, and there is no rational basis for such treatment. The Court affirmed the lower court's ruling that the Village of Willowbrook's demand for a larger easement from the Olechs, compared to other property owners, was irrational and arbitrary and thus violated the Equal Protection Clause. |
Equal Protection | Michael M. v. Superior Court | https://supreme.justia.com/cases/federal/us/450/464/ | U.S. Supreme Court Michael M. v. Superior Ct., 450
U.S. 464 (1981) Michael M. v. Superior
Court No. 79-1344 Argued November 4,
1980 Decided March 23,
1981 450
U.S. 464 CERTIORARI TO THE SUPREME COURT OF
CALIFORNIA Syllabus Petitioner, then a 17 1/2-year-old male, was charged with
violating California's "statutory rape" law, which defines unlawful
sexual intercourse as "an act of sexual intercourse accomplished
with a female not the wife of the perpetrator, where the female is
under the age of 18 years." Prior to trial, petitioner sought to
set aside the information on both state and federal constitutional
grounds, asserting that the statute unlawfully discriminated on the
basis of gender since men alone were criminally liable thereunder.
The trial court and the California Court of Appeal denied relief,
and on review the California Supreme Court upheld the statute. Held: The judgment is affirmed. Pp. 450 U. S.
468 -476; 450 U. S.
481 -487. 25 Cal. 3d
608 , 601 P.2d 572, affirmed.
JUSTICE REHNQUIST, joined by CHIEF JUSTICE BURGER, JUSTICE
STEWART, and JUSTICE POWELL, concluded that the statute does not
violate the Equal Protection Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment.
Pp. 450 U. S.
468 -476.
(a) Gender-based classifications are not "inherently suspect" so
as to be subject to so-called "strict scrutiny," but will be upheld
if they bear a "fair and substantial relationship" to legitimate
state ends. Reed v. Reed, 404 U. S.
71 . Because the Equal Protection Clause does not "demand
that a statute necessarily apply equally to all persons" or require
"things which are different in fact . . . to be treated in law as
though they were the same," Rinaldi v. Yeager, 384 U. S. 305 , 384 U. S. 309 ,
a statute will be upheld where the gender classification is not
invidious, but rather realistically reflects the fact that the
sexes are not similarly situated in certain circumstances. Pp. 450 U. S.
468 -469.
(b) One of the purposes of the California statute in which the
State has a strong interest is the prevention of illegitimate
teenage pregnancies. The statute protects women from sexual
intercourse and pregnancy at an age when the physical, emotional,
and psychological consequences are particularly severe. Because
virtually all of the significant harmful and identifiable
consequences of teenage pregnancy fall on the female, a legislature
acts well within its authority when it Page 450 U. S. 465 elects to punish only the participant who, by nature, suffers
few of the consequences of his conduct. Pp. 450 U. S.
470 -473.
(c) There is no merit in petitioner's contention that the
statute is impermissibly underinclusive, and must, in order to pass
judicial scrutiny, be broadened so as to hold the female as
criminally liable as the male. The relevant inquiry is not whether
the statute is drawn as precisely as it might have been, but
whether the line chosen by the California Legislature is within
constitutional limitations. In any event, a gender-neutral statute
would frustrate the State's interest in effective enforcement,
since a female would be less likely to report violations of the
statute if she herself would be subject to prosecution. The Equal
Protection Clause does not require a legislature to enact a statute
so broad that it may well be incapable of enforcement. Pp. 450 U. S.
473 -474.
(d) Nor is the statute impermissibly overbroad because it makes
unlawful sexual intercourse with prepubescent females, incapable of
becoming pregnant. Aside from the fact that the statute could be
justified on the grounds that very young females are particularly
susceptible to physical injury from sexual intercourse, the
Constitution does not require the California Legislature to limit
the scope of the statute to older teenagers and exclude young
girls. P. 450 U. S.
475 .
(e) And the statute is not unconstitutional as applied to
petitioner who, like the girl involved, was under 18 at the time of
sexual intercourse, on the asserted ground that the statute
presumes in such circumstances that the male is the culpable
aggressor. The statute does not rest on such an assumption, but
instead is an attempt to prevent illegitimate teenage pregnancy by
providing an additional deterrent for men. The age of the man is
irrelevant, since young men are as capable as older men of
inflicting the harm sought to be prevented. P. 450 U. S.
475 .
BLACKMUN, J., concluded that the California statutory rape law
is a sufficiently reasoned and constitutional effort to control at
its inception the problem of teenage pregnancies, and that the
California Supreme Court's judgment should be affirmed on the basis
of the applicable test for gender-based classifications as set
forth in Reed v. Reed, 404 U. S. 71 , 404 U. S. 76 ,
and Craig v. Boren, 429 U. S. 190 , 429 U. S. 197 .
Pp. 450 U. S.
481 -487.
REHNQUIST, J., announced the judgment of the Court and delivered
an opinion, in which BURGER, C.J. and STEWART and POWELL, JJ.,
joined. STEWART, J., filed a concurring opinion, post, p. 450 U. S. 476 .
BLACKMUN, J., filed an opinion concurring in the judgment, post, p. 450 U. S. 481 .
BRENNAN, J., filed a dissenting opinion, in which WHITE and
MARSALL, JJ., joined, post, p. 450 U. S. 488 .
STEVENS, J., filed a dissenting opinion, post, p. 450 U. S.
496 . Page 450 U. S. 466 JUSTICE REHNQUIST announced the judgment of the Court and
delivered an opinion, in which THE CHIEF JUSTICE, JUSTICE STEWART,
and JUSTICE POWELL joined.
The question presented in this case is whether California's
"statutory rape" law, § 261.5 of the Cal.Penal Code Ann. (West
Supp. 1981), violates the Equal Protection Clause of the Fourteenth
Amendment. Section 261.5 defines unlawful sexual intercourse as "an
act of sexual intercourse accomplished with a female not the wife
of the perpetrator, where the female is under the age of 18 years."
The statute thus makes men alone criminally liable for the act of
sexual intercourse.
In July, 1978, a complaint was filed in the Municipal Court of
Sonoma County, Cal., alleging that petitioner, then a 17
1/2-year-old male, had had unlawful sexual intercourse with a
female under the age of 18, in violation of § 261.5. The evidence
adduced at a preliminary hearing showed that, at approximately
midnight on June 3, 1978, petitioner and two friends approached
Sharon, a 16 1/2-year-old female, and her sister as they waited at
a bus stop. Petitioner and Sharon, Page 450 U. S. 467 who had already been drinking, moved away from the others and
began to kiss. After being struck in the face for rebuffing
petitioner's initial advances, Sharon submitted to sexual
intercourse with petitioner. Prior to trial, petitioner sought to
set aside the information on both state and federal constitutional
grounds, asserting that § 261.5 unlawfully discriminated on the
basis of gender. The trial court and the California Court of Appeal
denied petitioner's request for relief, and petitioner sought
review in the Supreme Court of California.
The Supreme Court held that "section 261.5 discriminates on the
basis of sex, because only females may be victims and only males
may violate the section." 25 Cal. 3d
608 , 611, 601 P.2d 572, 574. The court then subjected the
classification to "strict scrutiny," stating that it must be
justified by a compelling state interest. It found that the
classification was "supported not by mere social convention, but by
the immutable physiological fact that it is the female exclusively
who can become pregnant." Ibid. Canvassing "the tragic
human costs of illegitimate teenage pregnancies," including the
large number of teenage abortions, the increased medical risk
associated with teenage pregnancies, and the social consequences of
teenage childbearing, the court concluded that the State has a
compelling interest in preventing such pregnancies. Because males
alone can "physiologically cause the result which the law properly
seeks to avoid," the court further held that the gender
classification was readily justified as a means of identifying
offender and victim. For the reasons stated below, we affirm the
judgment of the California Supreme Court. [ Footnote 1 ] Page 450 U. S. 468 As is evident from our opinions, the Court has had some
difficulty in agreeing upon the proper approach and analysis in
cases involving challenges to gender-based classifications. The
issues posed by such challenges range from issues of standing, see Orr v. Orr, 440 U. S. 268 (1979), to the appropriate standard of judicial review for the
substantive classification. Unlike the California Supreme Court, we
have not held that gender-based classifications are "inherently
suspect," and thus we do not apply so-called "strict scrutiny" to
those classifications. See Stanton v. Stanton, 421 U. S. 7 (1975).
Our cases have held, however, that the traditional minimum
rationality test takes on a somewhat "sharper focus" when
gender-based classifications are challenged. See Craig v.
Boren, 429 U. S. 190 , 429 U. S. 210 n.* (1976) (POWELL, J., concurring). In Reed v. Reed, 404 U. S. 71 (1971), for example, the Court stated that a gender-based
classification will be upheld if it Page 450 U. S. 469 bears a "fair and substantial relationship" to legitimate state
ends, while in Craig v. Boren, supra at 429 U. S. 197 ,
the Court restated the test to require the classification to bear a
"substantial relationship" to "important governmental
objectives."
Underlying these decisions is the principle that a legislature
may not
"make overbroad generalizations based on sex which are entirely
unrelated to any differences between men and women or which demean
the ability or social status of the affected class." Parham v. Hughes, 441 U. S. 347 , 441 U. S. 354 (1979) (plurality opinion of STEWART, J.). But because the Equal
Protection Clause does not "demand that a statute necessarily apply
equally to all persons" or require " things which are different
in fact . . . to be treated in law as though they were the same,'" Rinaldi v. Yeager, 384 U. S. 305 , 384 U. S. 309 (1966), quoting Tigner v. Texas, 310 U.
S. 141 , 310 U. S. 147 (1940), this Court has consistently upheld statutes where the
gender classification is not invidious, but rather realistically
reflects the fact that the sexes are not similarly situated in
certain circumstances. Parham v. Hughes, supra; Califano v.
Webster, 430 U. S. 313 (1977); Schlesinger v. Ballard, 419 U.
S. 498 (1975); Kahn v. Shevin, 416 U.
S. 351 (1974). As the Court has stated, a legislature
may "provide for the special problems of women." Weinberger v.
Wiesenfeld, 420 U. S. 636 , 420 U. S. 653 (1975). Applying those principles to this case, the fact that the
California Legislature criminalized the act of illicit sexual
intercourse with a minor female is a sure indication of its intent
or purpose to discourage that conduct. [ Footnote 2 ] Precisely why the legislature desired that
result is, of course, somewhat less clear. This Court has long
recognized that "[i]nquiries into congressional motives or purposes
are a hazardous matter," United States v. O'Brien, 391 U. S. 367 , 391 U. S.
383 -384 (1968); Palmer v. Thompson, 403 U. S. 217 , 403 U. S. 224 (1971), and the Page 450 U. S. 470 search for the "actual" or "primary" purpose of a statute is
likely to be elusive. Arlington Heights v. Metropolitan Housing
Dev. Corp., 429 U. S. 252 , 429 U. S. 265 (1977); McGinnis v. Royster, 410 U.
S. 263 , 410 U. S.
276 -277 (1973). Here, for example, the individual
legislators may have voted for the statute for a variety of
reasons. Some legislators may have been concerned about preventing
teenage pregnancies, others about protecting young females from
physical injury or from the loss of "chastity," and still others
about promoting various religious and moral attitudes towards
premarital sex.
The justification for the statute offered by the State and
accepted by the Supreme Court of California, is that the
legislature sought to prevent illegitimate teenage pregnancies.
That finding, of course, is entitled to great deference. Reitman v. Mulkey, 387 U. S. 369 , 387 U. S.
373 -374 (1967). And although our cases establish that
the State's asserted reason for the enactment of a statute may be
rejected, if it "could not have been a goal of the legislation," Weinberger v. Wiesenfeld, supra at 420 U. S. 648 ,
n. 16, this is not such a case.
We are satisfied not only that the prevention of illegitimate
pregnancy is at least one of the "purposes" of the statute, but
also that the State has a strong interest in preventing such
pregancy. At the risk of stating the obvious, teenage pregnancies,
which have increased dramatically over the last two decades,
[ Footnote 3 ] have significant
social, medical, and economic consequences for both the mother and
her child, and the State. [ Footnote
4 ] Page 450 U. S. 471 Of particular concern to the State is that approximately half of
all teenage pregnancies end in abortion. [ Footnote 5 ] And of those children who are born, their
illegitimacy makes them likely candidates to become wards of the
State. [ Footnote 6 ]
We need not be medical doctors to discern that young men and
young women are not similarly situated with respect to the problems
and the risks of sexual intercourse. Only women may become
pregnant, and they suffer disproportionately the profound physical,
emotional, and psychological consequences of sexual activity. The
statute at issue here Page 450 U. S. 472 protects women from sexual intercourse at an age when those
consequences are particularly severe. [ Footnote 7 ]
The question thus boils down to whether a State may attack the
problem of sexual intercourse and teenage pregnancy directly by
prohibiting a male from having sexual intercourse with a minor
female. [ Footnote 8 ] We hold
that such a statute is Page 450 U. S. 473 sufficiently related to the State's objectives to pass
constitutional muster.
Because virtually all of the significant harmful and inescapably
identifiable consequences of teenage pregnancy fall on the young
female, a legislature acts well within its authority when it elects
to punish only the participant who, by nature, suffers few of the
consequences of his conduct. It is hardly unreasonable for a
legislature acting to protect minor females to exclude them from
punishment. Moreover, the risk of pregnancy itself constitutes a
substantial deterrence to young females. No similar natural
sanctions deter males. A criminal sanction imposed solely on males
thus serves to roughly "equalize" the deterrents on the sexes.
We are unable to accept petitioner's contention that the statute
is impermissibly underinclusive and must, in order to pass judicial
scrutiny, be broadened so as to hold the female as
criminally liable as the male. It is argued that this statute is
not necessary to deter teenage pregnancy because a
gender-neutral statute, where both male and female would be subject
to prosecution, would serve that goal equally well. The relevant
inquiry, however, is not whether the statute is drawn as precisely
as it might have been, but whether the line chosen by the
California Legislature is within constitutional limitations. Kahn v. Shevin, 416 U.S. at 3 416 U. S. 56 , n.
10.
In any event, we cannot say that a gender-neutral statute would
be as effective as the statute California has chosen to enact. The
State persuasively contends that a gender-neutral statute would
frustrate its interest in effective enforcement. Its view is that a
female is surely less likely to report Page 450 U. S. 474 violations of the statute if she herself would be subject to
criminal prosecution. [ Footnote
9 ] In an area already fraught with prosecutorial dificulties,
we decline to hold that the Equal Protection Clause requires a
legislature to enact a statute so broad that it may well be
incapable of enforcement. [ Footnote 10 ] Page 450 U. S. 475 We similarly reject petitioner's argument that § 261.5 is
impermissibly overbroad because it makes unlawful sexual
intercourse with prepubescent females, who are, by definition,
incapable of becoming pregnant. Quite apart from the fact that the
statute could well be justified on the grounds that very young
females are particularly susceptible to physical injury from sexual
intercourse, see Rundlett v. Oliver, 607 F.2d 495 (CA1
1979), it is ludicrous to suggest that the Constitution requires
the California Legislature to limit the scope of its rape statute
to older teenagers and exclude young girls.
There remains only petitioner's contention that the statute is
unconstitutional as it is applied to him because he, like Sharon,
was under 18 at the time of sexual intercourse. Petitioner argues
that the statute is flawed because it presumes that, as between two
persons under 18, the male is the culpable aggressor. We find
petitioner's contentions unpersuasive. Contrary to his assertions,
the statute does not rest on the assumption that males are
generally the aggressors. It is, instead, an attempt by a
legislature to prevent illegitimate teenage pregnancy by providing
an additional deterrent for men. The age of the man is irrelevant,
since young men are as capable as older men of inflicting the harm
sought to be prevented.
In upholding the California statute, we also recognize that this
is not a case where a statute is being challenged on the grounds
that it "invidiously discriminates" against females. Page 450 U. S. 476 To the contrary, the statute places a burden on males which is
not shared by females. But we find nothing to suggest that men,
because of past discrimination or peculiar disadvantages, are in
need of the special solicitude of the courts. Nor is this a case
where the gender classification is made "solely for . . .
administrative convenience," as in Frontiero v.
Richardson, 411 U. S. 677 , 411 U. S. 690 (1973) (emphasis omitted), or rests on "the baggage of sexual
stereotypes" as in Orr v. Orr, 440 U.S. at 440 U. S. 283 .
As we have held, the statute instead reasonably reflects the fact
that the consequences of sexual intercourse and pregnancy fall more
heavily on the female than on the male.
Accordingly the judgment of the California Supreme Court is Affirmed. [ Footnote 1 ]
The lower federal courts and state courts have almost uniformly
concluded that statutory rape law are constitutional. See,
e.g., Rundlett v. Oliver, 607 F.2d 495 (CA1 1979); Hall v.
McKenzie, 537 F.2d 1232 (CA4 1976); Hall v.
State, 365
So. 2d 1249 , 1252-1253 (Ala.App. 1978), cert.
denied, 365 So.
2d 1253 (Ala.1979); State v. Gray, 122 Ariz. 445,
446-477, 595 P.2d 990 ,
991-992 (1979); People v. Mackey, 46 Cal. App. 3d
755 , 760-761, 120 Cal. Rptr. 157, 160, cert. denied, 423 U.S. 951 (1975); People v. Salinas, 191 Colo. 171, 551 P.2d 703 (1976); State v. Brothers, 384
A.2d 402 (Del.Super.1978); In re
W.E.P., 318
A.2d 286 , 289-290 (DC 1974); Barnes v. State, 244 Ga.
302, 303-304, 260 S.E.2d 40 ,
41-42 (1979); State v. Drake, 219 N.W.2d
492 , 495-496 (Iowa 1974); State v.
Bell, 377 So.
2d 303 (La.1979); State v. Rundlett, 391 A.2d
815 (Me.1978); Green v. State, 270 So. 2d
695 (Miss.1972); In re J.D.G., 498 S.W.2d
786 , 792-793 (Mo.1973); State v. Meloon, 116 N.H. 669,
366 A.2d 1176 (1976); State v. Thompson, 162 N.J.Super.
302, 392 A.2d 678 (1978); People v. Whidden, 51 N.Y.2d 457,
415 N.E.2d 927 (1980); State v. Wilson, 296 N.C. 298,
311-313, 250 S.E.2d
621 , 629-630 (1979); Olson v. State, 588 P.2d 1018 (Nev.1979); State v. Elmore, 24 Ore.App. 651, 546 P.2d
1117 (1976); State v. Ware, ___ R.I. ___ , 418 A.2d
1 (1980); Roe v. State, 584 S.W.2d 257, 259
(Tenn.Crim.App. 1979); Ex parte Groves, 571
S.W.2d 888 , 892-893 (Tex.Crim.App. 1978); Moore v.
McKenzie, 236 S.E.2d
342 , 342 -343
(W.Va.1977); Flores v. State, 69 Wis.2d 509, 510-511, 230 N.W.2d
637 , 638 (1975). Contra, Navedo v. Preisser, 630 F.2d
636 (CA8 1980); United States v. Hicks, 625 F.2d 216 (CA9
1980); Meloon v. Helgemoe, 564 F.2d 602 (CA1 1977)
(limited in Rundlett v. Oliver, supra ), cert.
denied, 436 U.S. 950 (1978).
[ Footnote 2 ]
The statute was enacted as part of California's first penal code
in 1850, 1850 Cal.Stats., ch. 99, § 47, p. 234, and recodified and
amended in 1970.
[ Footnote 3 ]
In 1976, approximately one million 15-to-19-year-olds became
pregnant, one-tenth of all women in that age group. Two-thirds of
the pregnancies were illegitimate. Illegitimacy rates for teenagers
(births per 1,000 unmarried females ages 14 to 19) increased 75%
for 14-to-17-year-olds between 1961 and 1974 and 33% for
18-to-19-year-olds. Alan Guttmacher Institute, 11 Million Teenagers
10, 13 (1976); C. Chilman, Adolescent Sexuality In a Changing
American Society 195 (NIH Pub. No. 80-1426, 1980).
[ Footnote 4 ]
The risk of maternal death is 60% higher for a teenager under
the age of 15 than for a women in her early twenties. The risk is
13% higher for 15-to-19-year-olds. The statistics further show that
most teenage mothers drop out of school and face a bleak economic
future. See, e.g., 11 Million Teenagers, supra at
23, 25; Bennett & Bardon, The Effects of a School Program On
Teenager Mothers and Their Chil&ren, 47 Am.J.Orthopsychiatry
671 (1977); Phipps-Yonas, Teenage Pregnancy and Motherhood, 50
Am.J.Orthopsychiatry 403, 414 (1980).
[ Footnote 5 ]
This is because teenagers are disproportionately likely to seek
abortions. Center for Disease Control, Abortion Surveillance 1976,
pp. 22-24 (1978). In 1978, for example, teenagers in California had
approximately 54,000 abortions and 53,800 live births. California
Center for Health Statistics, Reproductive Health Status of
California Teenage Women 1, 23 (Mar.1980).
[ Footnote 6 ]
The policy and intent of the California Legislature evinced in
other legislation buttresses our view that the prevention of
teenage pregnancy is a purpose of the statute. The preamble to the
Pregnancy Freedom of Choice Act, for example, states:
"The legislature finds that pregnancy among unmarried persons
under 21 years of age constitutes an increasing social problem in
the State of California."
Cal.Welf. & Inst.Code Ann. § 16145 (West 1980).
Subsequent to the decision below, the California Legislature
considered and rejected proposals to render § 261.5 gender neutral,
thereby ratifying the judgment of the Galifornia Supreme Court.
That is enough to answer petitioner's contention that the statute
was the " accidental byproduct of a traditional way of thinking
about females.'" Califano v. Webster, 430 U.
S. 313 , 430 U. S. 320 (1977) (quoting Califano v. Goldfarb, 430 U.
S. 199 , 430 U. S. 223 (1977) (STEVENS, J., concurring in judgment)). Certainly this
decision of the California Legislature is as good a source as is
this Court in deciding what is "current" and what is "outmoded" in
the perception of women. [ Footnote 7 ]
Although petitioner concedes that the State has a "compelling"
interest in preventing teenage pregnancy, he contends that the
"true" purpose of § 261.5 is to protect the virtue and chastity of
young women. As such, the statute is unjustifiable because it rests
on archaic stereotypes. What we have said above is enough to
dispose of that contention. The question for us -- and the only
question under the Federal Constitution -- is whether the
legislation violates the Equal Protection Clause of the Fourteenth
.mendment, not whether its supporters may have endorsed it for
reasons no longer generally accepted. Even if the preservation of
female chastity were one of the motives of the statute, and even if
that motive be impermissible, petitioner's argument must fail
because
"[i]t is a familiar practice of constitutional law that this
court will not strike down an otherwise constitutional statute on
the basis of an alleged illicit legislative motive." United States v. O'Brien, 391 U.
S. 367 , 391 U. S. 383 (1968). In Orr v. Orr, 440 U. S. 268 (1979), for example, the Court rejected one asserted purpose as
impermissible, but then considered other purposes to determine if
they could justify the statute. Similarly, in Washington v.
Davis, 426 U. S. 229 , 426 U. S. 243 (1976), the Court distinguished Palmer v. Thompson, 403 U. S. 217 (1971), on the grounds that the purposes of the ordinance there
were not open to impeachment by evidence that the legislature was
actually motivated by an impermissible purpose. See also Arlington Heights v. Metropolitan Housing Dev. Corp., 429 U. S. 252 , 429 U. S. 270 ,
n. 21 (1977); Mobile v. Bolden, 446 U. S.
55 , 446 U. S. 91 (1980) (STEVENS, J., concurring in judgment).
[ Footnote 8 ]
We do not understand petitioner to question a State's authority
to make sexual intercourse among teenagers a criminal act, at least
on a gender-neutral basis. In Carey v. Population Services
International, 431 U. S. 678 , 431 U. S. 694 ,
n. 17 (1977) (plurality opinion of BRENNAN, J.), four Members of
the Court assumed for the purposes of that case that a State may
regulate the sexual behavior of minors, while four other Members of
the Court more emphatically stated that such regulation would be
permissible. Id. at 431 U. S. 702 , 431 U. S. 703 (WHITE, J., concurring in part and concurring in result); id. at 431 U. S.
705 -707, 431 U. S. 709 (POWELL, J., concurring in part and concurring in judgment); id. at 431 U. S. 713 (STEVENS, J., concurring in part and concurring in judgment); id. at 431 U. S. 718 (REHNQUIST, J., dissenting). The Court has long recognized that
State has even broader authority to protect the physical, mental,
and moral wellbeing of its youth than of its adults. See, e.g.,
Planned Parenthood of Central Mo. v. Danforth, 428 U. S.
52 , 428 U. S. 72 -74
(1976); Ginsberg v. New York, 390 U.
S. 629 , 390 U. S.
639 -640 (1968); Prince v. Massachusetts, 321 U. S. 158 , 321 U. S. 170 (1944).
[ Footnote 9 ]
Petitioner contends that a gender-neutral statute would not
hinder prosecutions because the prosecutor could take into account
the relative burdens on females and males and generally only
prosecute males. But to concede this is to concede all. If the
prosecutor, in exercising discretion, will virtually always
prosecute just the man and not the woman, we do not see why it is
impermissible for the legislature to enact a statute to the same
effect.
[ Footnote 10 ]
The question whether a statute is substantially related to its
asserted goals is, at best, an opaque one. It can be plausibly
argued that a gender-neutral statute would produce fewer
prosecutions than the statute at issue here. See STEWART,
J., concurring, post at 450 U. S. 481 ,
n. 13. JUSTICE BRENNAN's dissent argues, on the other hand,
that
"even assuming that a gender-neutral statute would be more
difficult to enforce, . . . [c]ommon sense . . . suggests that a
gender-neutral statutory rape law is potentially a greater
deterrent of sexual activity than a gender-based law, for the
simple reason that a gender-neutral law subjects both men and women
to criminal sanctions, and thus arguably has a deterrent effect on
twice as many potential violators." Post at 450 U. S.
493 -494 (emphasis deleted). Where such differing
speculations as to the effect of a statute are plausible, we think
it appropriate to defer to the decision of the California Supreme
Court,
"armed as it was with the knowledge of the facts and
circumstances concerning the passage and potential impact of [the
statute], and familiar with the milieu in which that provision
would operate." Reitman v. Mulkey, 387 U. S. 369 , 387 U. S.
378 -379 (1967).
It should be noted that two of the three cases relied upon by
JUSTICE BRENNAN's dissent are readily distinguishable from the
instant one. See post at 450 U. S. 490 ,
n. 3. In both Navedo v. Preisser, 630 F.2d 636 (CA8 1980),
and Meloon v. Helgemoe, 564 F.2d 602 (CA1 1977), cert.
denied, 436 U.S. 950 (1978), the respective governments
asserted that the purpose of the statute vas to protect young women
from physical injury. Both courts rejected the justification on the
grounds that there had been no showing that young females are more
likely than males to suffer physical injury from sexual
intercourse. They further held, contrary to our decision, that
pregnancy prevention was not a "plausible" purpose of the
legislation. Thus, neither court reached the issue presented here,
whether the statute is substantially related to the prevention of
teenage pregnancy. Significantly, Meloon has been severely
limlted by Rundlett v. Oliver, 607 F.2d 495 (CA1 1979),
where the court upheld a statutory rape law on the ground that the
State had shown that sexual intercourse physically injures young
women more than males. Here, of course, even JUSTICE BRENNAN's
dissent does not dispute that young women suffer disproportionately
the deleterious consequences of illegitimate pregnancy.
JUSTICE STEWART, concurring.
Section 261.5, on its face, classifies on the basis of sex. A
male who engages in sexual intercourse with an underage female who
is not his wife violates the statute; a female who engages in
sexual intercourse with an underage male who is not her husband
does not. [ Footnote 2/1 ] The
petitioner contends that this state law, which punishes only males
for the conduct in question, violates his Fourteenth Amendment
right to the equal protection of the law. The Court today correctly
rejects that contention. A At the outset, it should be noted that the statutory
discrimination, when viewed as part of the wider scheme of
California law, is not as clearcut as might at first appear.
Females are not freed from criminal liability in California for
engaging in sexual activity that may be harmful. It is unlawful,
for example, for any person, of either sex, to molest, annoy, or
contribute to the delinquency of anyone under 18 years of Page 450 U. S. 477 age. [ Footnote 2/2 ] All persons
are prohibited from committing "any lewd or lascivious act,"
including consensual intercourse, with a child under 14. [ Footnote 2/3 ] And members of both sexes may
be convicted for engaging in deviant sexual acts with anyone under
18. [ Footnote 2/4 ] Finally, females
may be brought within the proscription of § 261.5 itself, since a
female may be charged with aiding and abetting its violation.
[ Footnote 2/5 ]
Section 261.5 is thus but one part of a broad statutory scheme
that protects all minors from the problems and risks attendant upon
adolescent sexual activity. To be sure, § 261.5 creates an
additional measure of punishment for males who engage in sexual
intercourse with females between the ages of 14 and 17. [ Footnote 2/6 ] The question then is whether
the Constitution prohibits a state legislature from imposing this additional sanction on a gender-specific basis. B The Constitution is violated when government, state or federal,
invidiously classifies similarly situated people on the basis of
the immutable characteristics with which they were Page 450 U. S. 478 born. Thus, detrimental racial classifications by government
always violate the Constitution, for the simple reason that, so far
as the Constitution is concerned, people of different races are
always similarly situated. See Fullilove v. Klutznick, 448 U. S. 448 , 448 U. S. 522 (dissenting opinion); McLaughlin v. Florida, 379 U.
S. 184 , 379 U. S. 198 (concurring opinion); Brown v. Board of Ed., 347 U.
S. 483 ; Plessy v. Ferguson, 163 U.
S. 537 , 163 U. S. 552 (dissenting opinion). By contrast, while detrimental gender
classifications by government often violate the Constitution, they
do not always do so, for the reason that there are differences
between males and females that the Constitution necessarily
recognizes. In this case, we deal with the most basic of these
differences: females can become pregnant as the result of sexual
intercourse; males cannot.
As was recognized in Parham v. Hughes, 441 U.
S. 347 , 441 U. S.
354 ,
"a State is not free to make overbroad generalizations based on
sex which are entirely unrelated to any differences between men and
women or which demean the ability or social status of the affected
class."
Gender-based classifications may not be based upon
administrative convenience, or upon archaic assumptions about the
proper roles of the sexes. Craig v. Boren, 429 U.
S. 190 ; Frontiero v. Richardson, 411 U.
S. 677 ; Reed v. Reed, 404 U. S.
71 . But we have recognized that, in certain narrow
circumstances, men and women are not similarly situated; in these
circumstances, a gender classification based on clear differences
between the sexes is not invidious, and a legislative
classification realistically based upon those differences is not
unconstitutional. See Parham v. Hughes, supra; Califano v.
Webster, 430 U. S. 313 , 430 U. S.
316 -317; Schlesinger v. Ballard, 419 U.
S. 498 ; cf. San Antonio Independent School Dist v.
Rodriguez, 411 U. S. 1 , 411 U. S. 59 (concurring opinion).
"[G]ender-based classifications are not invariably invalid. When
men and women are not, in fact, similarly situated in the area
covered by the legislation in question, the Equal Protection Clause
is not violated." Caban v. Mohammed, 441 U. S. 380 , 441 U. S. 398 (dissenting opinion). Page 450 U. S. 479 Applying these principles to the classification enacted by the
California Legislature, it is readily apparent that § 261.5 does
not violate the Equal Protection Clause. Young women and men are
not similarly situated with respect to the problems and risks
associated with intercourse and pregnancy, and the statute is
realistically related to the legitimate state purpose of reducing
those problems and risks. C As the California Supreme Court's catalog shows, the pregnant
unmarried female confronts problems more numerous and more severe
than any faced by her male partner. [ Footnote 2/7 ] She alone endures the medical risks of
pregnancy or abortion. [ Footnote
2/8 ] She suffers disproportionately the social, educational,
and emotional consequences of pregnancy. [ Footnote 2/9 ] Recognizing this disproportion, Page 450 U. S. 480 California has attempted to protect teenage females by
prohibiting males from participating in the act necessary for
conception. [ Footnote 2/10 ]
The fact that males and females are not similarly situated with
respect to the risks of sexual intercourse applies with the same
force to males under 18 as it does to older males. The risk of
pregnancy is a significant deterrent for unwed young females that
is not shared by unmarried males, regardless of their age.
Experienced observation confirms the common sense notion that
adolescent males disregard the possibility of pregnancy far more
than do adolescent females. [ Footnote
2/11 ] And to the extent that § 261.5 may punish males for
intercourse with prepubescent females, that punishment is
justifiable because of the substantial physical risks for
prepubescent females that are not shared by their male
counterparts. [ Footnote 2/12 ] Page 450 U. S. 481 D The petitioner argues that the California Legislature could have
drafted the statute differently, so that its purpose would be
accomplished more precisely.
"But the issue, of course, is not whether the statute could have
been drafted more wisely, but whether the lines chosen by the . . .
[l]egislature are within constitutional limitations." Kahn v. Shevin, 416 U. S. 351 , 416 U. S. 356 ,
n. 10. That other States may have decided to attack the same
problems more broadly, with gender-neutral statutes, does not mean
that every State is constitutionally compelled to do so. [ Footnote 2/13 ] E In short, the Equal Protection Clause does not mean that the
physiological differences between men and women must be
disregarded. While those differences must never be permitted to
become a pretext for invidious discrimination, no such
discrimination is presented by this case. The Constitution surely
does not require a State to pretend that demonstrable differences
between men and women do not really exist.
[ Footnote 2/1 ] But see 450
U.S. 464 fn2/5|>n. 5 and accompanying text, infra. [ Footnote 2/2 ] See Cal.Penal Code Ann. §§ 272, 647a (West Supp.
1981).
[ Footnote 2/3 ]
Cal.Penal Code Ann. § 288 (West Supp. 1981). See People v.
Dontanville, 10 Cal. App. 3d
783 , 796, 89 Cal. Rptr.
172 , 180 (2d Dist.).
[ Footnote 2/4 ] See Cal.Penal Code Ann. §§ 286(b)(1), 288a(b)(1) (West
Supp. 1981) .
[ Footnote 2/5 ] See Cal.Penal Code Ann. § 31 (West 1970); People v.
Haywood, 131 Cal. App.
2d 259 , 280 P.2d 180 (2d Dist.); People v.
Lewis, 113 Cal. App.
2d 468 , 248 P.2d 461 (1st Dist.). According to statistics
maintained by the California Department of Justice Bureau of
Criminal Statistics, approximately 14% of the juveniles arrested
for participation in acts made unlawful by § 261.5 between 1975 and
1979 were females. Moreover, an underage female who is as culpable
as her male partner, or more culpable, may be prosecuted as a
juvenile delinquent. Cal.Welf. & Inst.Code Ann. § 602 (West
Supp. 1981); In re Gladys R., 1 Cal. 3d
855 , 867-869, 464 P.2d 127, 136-138.
[ Footnote 2/6 ]
Males and females are equally prohibited by § 288 from sexual
intercourse with minors under 14. Compare Cal.Penal Code
Ann. § 288 (West Supp. 1981) with Cal.Penal Code Ann. §§
18, 264 (West Supp. 1981).
[ Footnote 2/7 ]
The court noted that, from 1971 through 1976, 83.6% of the 4,860
children born to girls uder 15 in California were illegitimate, as
were 51% of those born to girls 15 to 17. The court also observed
that, while accounting for only 21% of California pregnancies in
1976, teenagers accounted for 34.7% of legal abortions. See
ante at 450 U. S. 470 ,
n. 3.
[ Footnote 2/8 ]
There is also empirical evidence that sexual abuse of young
females is a more serious problem than sexual abuse of young males.
For example, a review of five studies found that 88% of sexually
abused minors were female. Jaffe, Dynneson, & ten Bensel,
Sexual Abuse of Children, 129 Am.J. of Diseases of Children 689,
690 (1975). Another study, involving admissions to a hospital
emergency room over a 3-year period, reported that 86 of 100
children examined for sexual abuse were girls. Orr & Prietto,
Emergency Management of Sexually Abused Children, 133 Am.J. of
Diseased Children 630 (1979). See also State v. Craig, 169
Mont. 150, 156-157, 545 P.2d 649, 653; Sarafino, An Estimate of
Nationwide Incidence of Sexual Offenses Against Children, 58 Child
Welfare 127, 131 (1979).
[ Footnote 2/9 ]
Most teenage mothers do not finish high school, and are
disadvantaged economically thereafter. See Moore, Teenage
Childbirth and Welfare Dependency, 10 Family Planning Perspectives
233-235 (1978). The suicide rate for teenage mothers is seven times
greater than that for teenage girls without children. F. Nye,
School-Age Parenthood (Wash.State U.Ext.Bull. No. 667) 8 (1976).
And 60% of adolescent mothers aged 15 to 17 are on welfare within
two to five years of the birth of their children. Teenage
Pregnancy, Everybody's Problem 3-4 (DHEW Publication (HSA) No.
77-5619).
[ Footnote 2/10 ]
Despite the increased availability of contraceptives and sex
education, the pregnancy rates for young women are increasing. See Alan Guttmacher Institute, 11 Million Teenagers 12
(1976). See generally C. Chilman, Adolescent Sexuality in
a Changing American Society (NIH Pub. No. 80-1426, 1980).
The petitioner contends that the statute is overinclusive
because it does not allow a defense that contraceptives were used,
or that procreation was for some other reason impossible. The
petitioner does not allege, however, that he used a contraceptive,
or that pregnancy could not have resulted from the conduct with
which he was charged. But even assuming the petitioner's standing
to raise the claim of overbreadth, it is clear that a statute
recognizing the defenses he suggests would encounter difficult, if
not impossible, problems of proof.
[ Footnote 2/11 ] See, e.g., Phipps-Yonas, Tecnage Pregnancy and
Motherhood, 50 Am.J.Orthopsychiatry 403, 412 (1980). See also
State v. Rundlett, 391 A.2d
815 , 819, n. 13, 822 (Me.); Rundlett v. Oliver, 607
F.2d 495, 502 (CA1).
[ Footnote 2/12 ] See Barnes v. State, 244 Ga. 302, 260 S.E.2d 40 ; see generally Orr & Prietto, supra; Jaffee,
Dynneson, & ten Bensel, supra; Chilman, supra. [ Footnote 2/13 ]
The fact is that a gender-neutral statute would not necessarily
lead to a closer fit with the aim of reducing the problems
associated with teenage pregnancy. If both parties were equally
liable to prosecution, a female would be far less likely to
complain; the very complaint would be self-incriminating.
Accordingly, it is possible that a gender-neutral statute would
result in fewer prosecutions than the one before us.
In any event, a state legislature is free to address itself to
what it believes to be the most serious aspect of a broader
problem.
"[T]he Equal Protection Clause does not require that a State
must choose between attacking every aspect of a problem or not
attacking the problem at all." Dandridge v. Williams, 397 U.
S. 471 , 397 U. S.
486 -487; see also Williamson v. Lee Optical
Co., 348 U. S. 483 .
JUSTICE BLACKMUN, concurring in the judgment.
It is gratifying that the plurality recognizes that, "[a]t the
risk of stating the obvious, teenage pregnancies . . . have
increased dramatically over the last two decades," and "have
significant social, medical, and economic consequences for both Page 450 U. S. 482 the mother and.her child, and the State." Ante at 450 U. S. 470 (footnotes omitted). There have been times when I have wondered
whether the Court was capable of this perception, particularly when
it has struggled with the different but not unrelated problems that
attend abortion issues. See, for example, the opinions
(and the dissenting opinions) in Beal v. Doe, 432 U.
S. 438 (1977); Maher v. Roe, 432 U.
S. 464 (1977); Poelker v. Doe, 432 U.
S. 519 (1977); Harris v. McRae, 448 U.
S. 297 (1980); Williams v. Zbaraz, 448 U.
S. 358 (1980); and today's opinion in H.L. v.
Matheson, ante p. 450 U. S.
389 .
Some might conclude that the two uses of the criminal sanction
-- here flatly to forbid intercourse in order to forestall teenage
pregnancies, and, in Matheson, to prohibit a physician's
abortion procedure except upon notice to the parents of the
pregnant minor -- are vastly different proscriptions. But the basic
social and privacy problems are much the same. Both Utah's statute
in Matheson and California's statute in this case are
legislatively created tools intended to achieve similar ends and
addressed to the same societal concerns: the control and direction
of young people's sexual activities. The plurality opinion
impliedly concedes as much when it notes that "approximately half
of all teenage pregnancies end in abortion," and that "those
children who are born" are "likely candidates to become wards of
the State," Ante at 450 U. S. 471 ,
and n. 6.
I, however, cannot vote to strike down the California statutory
rape law, for I think it is a sufficiently reasoned and
constitutional effort to control the problem at its inception. For
me, there is an important difference between this state action and
a State's adamant and rigid refusal to face, or even to recognize,
the "significant . . consequences" -- to the woman -- of a forced
or unwanted conception. I have found it difficult to rule
constitutional, for example, state efforts to block, at that later
point, a woman's attempt to deal with the enormity of the problem
confronting her, just as I have rejected state efforts to prevent
women from rationally taking Page 450 U. S. 483 steps to prevent that problem from arising. See, e.g., Carey
v. Population Services International, 431 U.
S. 678 (1977). See also Griswold v.
Connecticut, 381 U. S. 479 (1965). In contrast, I am persuaded that, although a minor has
substantial privacy rights in intimate affairs connected with
procreation, California's efforts to prevent teenage pregnancy are
to be viewed differently from Utah's efforts to inhibit a woman
from dealing with pregnancy once it has become an
inevitability. Craig v. Boren, 429 U. S. 190 (1976), was an opinion which, in large part, I joined, id. at 429 U. S. 214 .
The plurality opinion in the present case points out, ante at 450 U. S.
468 -469, the Court's respective phrasings of the
applicable test in Reed v. Reed, 404 U. S.
71 , 404 U. S. 76 (1971), and in Craig v. Boren, 429 U.S. at 429 U. S. 197 .
I vote to affirm the judgment of the Supreme Court of California
and to uphold the State's gender-based classification on that test
and as exemplified by those two cases and by Schlesinger v.
Ballard, 419 U. S. 498 (1975); Weinberger v. Wiesenfeld, 420 U.
S. 636 (1975); and Kahn v. Shevin, 416 U.
S. 351 (1974).
I note also that § 261.5 of the California Penal Code is just
one of several California statutes intended to protect the
juvenile. JUSTICE STEWART, in his concurring opinion, appropriately
observes that § 261.5 is
"but one part of a broad statutory scheme that protects all
minors from the problems and risks attendant upon adolescent sexual
activity." Ante at 450 U. S.
477 .
I think too that it is only fair, with respect to this
particular petitioner, to point out that his partner, Sharon,
appears not to have been an unwilling participant in at least the
initial stages of the intimacies that took place the night of June
3, 1978. * Petitioner's and
Sharon's nonacquaintance Page 450 U. S. 484 with each other before the incident: their drinking; their
withdrawal from the others of the group; their foreplay, in which
she willingly participated and seems to have encouraged; Page 450 U. S. 485 and the closeness of their ages (a difference of only one year
and 18 days) are factors that should make this case an unattractive
one to prosecute at all, and especially to prosecute Page 450 U. S. 486 as a felony, rather than as a misdemeanor chargeable under §
261.5. But the State has chosen to prosecute in that Page 450 U. S. 487 manner, and the facts, I reluctantly conclude, may fit the
crime. Page 450 U. S. 488 * Sharon at the preliminary hearing testified as follows:
"Q [By the Deputy District Attorney]. On June the 4th, at
approximately midnight -- midnight of June the 3rd, were you in
Rohnert Park?"
"A [by Sharon]. Yes."
"Q. Is that in Sonoma County?"
"A. Yes."
"Q. Did anything unusual happen to you that night in Rohnert
Park?"
"A. Yes."
"Q. Would you briefly describe what happened that night? Did you
see the defendant that night in Rohnert Park?"
"A. Yes."
"Q. Where did you first meet him?"
"A. At a bus stop."
"Q. Was anyone with you?"
"A. My sister."
"Q. Was anyone with the defendant?"
"A. Yes."
"Q. How many people were with the defendant?"
"A. Two."
"Q. Now, after you met the defendant, what happened?"
"A. We walked down to the railroad tracks."
"Q. What happened at the railroad tracks?"
"A. We were drinking at the railroad tracks and we walked over
to this bush and he started kissing me and stuff, and I was kissing
him back, too, at first. Then, I was telling him to stop -- "
"Q. Yes."
"A. -- and I was telling him to slow down and stop. He said,
'Okay, okay.' But then he just kept doing it. He just kept doing
it, and then my sister and two other guys came over to where we
were and my sister said -- told me to get up and come home. And
then I didn't -- "
"Q. Yes."
"A. -- and then my sister and -- "
"Q. All right."
"A. -- David, one of the boys that were there, started walking
home, and we stayed there, and then later -- "
"Q. All right."
"A. -- Bruce left Michael, you know."
"The Court: Michael being the defendant?"
"The Witness: Yeah. We was laying there and we were kissing each
other, and then he asked me if I wanted to walk him over to the
park; so we walked over to the park and we sat down on a bench and
then he started kissing me again, and we were laying on the bench.
And he told me to take my pants off."
"I said, 'No,' and I was trying to get up and he hit me back
down on the bench, and then I just said to myself, 'Forget it,' and
I let him do what he wanted to do, and he took my pants off and he
was telling me to put my legs around him and stuff -- "
"Q. Did you have sexual intercourse with the defendant?"
"A. Yeah."
"Q. He did put his penis into your vagina?"
"A. Yes."
"Q. You said that he hit you?"
"A. Yeah."
"Q. How did he hit you?"
"A. He slugged me in the face."
"Q. With what did he slug you?"
"A. His fist."
"Q. Where abouts in the face?"
"A. On my chin."
"Q. As a result of that, did you have any bruises or any kind of
an injury?"
"A. Yeah."
"Q. What happened?"
"A. I had bruises."
"The Court: Did he hit you one time or did he hit you more than
once?"
"The Witness: He hit me about two or three times." * * * * "Q. Now, during the course of that evening, did the defendant
ask you your age?"
"A. Yeah."
"Q. And what did you tell him?"
"A. Sixteen."
"Q. Did you tell him you were sixteen?"
"A. Yes."
"Q. Now, you said you had been drinking, is that correct?"
"A. Yes."
"Q. Would you describe your condition as a result of the
drinking?"
"A. I was a little drunk."
App. 20-23.
CROSS-EXAMINATION
"Q. Did you go off with Mr. M. away from the others?"
"A. Yeah."
"Q. Why did you do that?"
"A. I don't know. I guess I wanted to."
"Q. Did you have any need to go to the bathroom when you were
there."
"A. Yes."
"Q. And what did you do?"
"A. Me and my sister walked down the railroad tracks to some
bushes and went to the bathroom."
"Q. Now, you and Mr. M., as I understand it, went off into the
bushes, is that correct?"
"A. Yes."
"Q. Okay. And what did you do when you and Mr. M. were there in
the bushes?"
"A. We were kissing and hugging."
"Q. Were you sitting up?"
"A. We were laying down."
"Q. You were lying down. This was in the bushes?"
"A. Yes."
"Q. How far away from the rest of them were you?"
"A. They were just bushes right next to the railroad tracks. We
just walked off into the bushes; not very far." * * * * "Q. So your sister and the other two boys came over to where you
were, you and Michael were, is that right?"
"A. Yeah."
"Q. What did they say to you, if you remember?"
"A. My sister didn't say anything. She said, 'Come on, Sharon,
let's go home.'"
"Q. She asked you to go home with her?"
"A. (Affirmative nod.)"
"Q. Did you go home with her?"
"A. No."
"Q. You wanted to stay with Mr. M.?"
"A. I don't know."
"Q. Was this before or after he hit you?"
"A. Before." * * * * "Q. What happened in the five minutes that Bruce stayed there
with you and Michael?"
"A. I don't remember."
"Q. You don't remember at all?"
"A. (Negative head shake.)"
"Q. Did you have occasion at that time to kiss Bruce?"
"A. Yeah."
"Q, You did? You were kissing Bruce at that time?"
"A. (Affirmative nod.)"
"Q. Was Bruce kissing you?"
"A. Yes."
"Q. And were you standing up at this time?"
"A. No, we were sitting down."
"Q. Okay, so at this point in time, you had left Mr, M. and you
were hugging and kissing with Bruce, is that right?"
"A. Yeah."
"Q. And you were sitting up."
"A. Yes,"
"Q. Was your sister still there then?"
"A. No. Yeah, she was at first"
"Q. What was she doing?"
"A. She was standing up with Michael and David,"
"Q. Yes. Was she doing anything with Michael and David?"
"A. No, I don't think so."
"Q. Whose idea was it for you and Bruce to kiss? Did you
initiate that?"
"A. Yes."
"Q. What happened after Bruce left?"
"A. Michael asked me if I wanted to go walk to the park."
"Q. And what did you say?"
"A. I said 'Yes.'"
"Q. And then what happened?"
"A. We walked to the park," * * * * "Q. How long did it take you to get to the park?"
"A. About ten or fifteen minutes."
"Q. And did you walk there?"
"A. Yes."
"Q. Did Mr. M. ever mention his name?"
"A. Yes." Id. at 27-32.
JUSTICE BRENNAN, with whom JUSTICES WHITE and MARSHALL join,
dissenting.
It is disturbing to find the Court so splintered on a case that
presents such a straightforward issue: whether the admittedly
gender-based classification in Cal.Penal Code Ann. 261.5 (West
Supp. 1981) bears a sufficient relationship to the State's asserted
goal of preventing teenage pregnancies to survive the "mid-level"
constitutional scrutiny mandated by Craig v. Boren, 429 U. S. 190 (1976). [ Footnote 3/1 ] Applying the
analytical framework provided by our precedents, I am convinced
that there is only one proper resolution of this issue: the
classification must be declared unconstitutional. I fear that the
plurality opinion and JUSTICES STEWART and BLACKMUN reach the
opposite result by placing too much emphasis on the desirability of
achieving the State's asserted statutory goal -- prevention of
teenage pregnancy -- and not enough emphasis on the fundamental
question of whether the sex-based discrimination Page 450 U. S. 489 in the California statute is substantially related to the
achievement of that goal. [ Footnote
3/2 ] II After some uncertainty as to the proper framework for analyzing
equal protection challenges to statutes containing gender-based
classifications, see ante at 450 U. S. 468 ,
this Court settled upon the proposition that a statute containin a
gender-based classification cannot withstand constitutional
challenge unless Page 450 U. S. 490 the classification is substantially related to the achievement
of an important governmental objective. Kirchberg v. Feenstra,
ante at 450 U. S. 459 ; Wengler v. Druggists Mutual Ins. Co., 446 U.
S. 142 , 446 U. S. 150 (1980); Califano v. Westcott, 443 U. S.
76 , 443 U. S. 85 (1979); Caban v. Mohammed, 441 U.
S. 380 , 441 U. S. 388 (1979); Orr v. Orr, 440 U. S. 268 , 440 U. S. 279 (1979); Califano v. Goldfarb, 430 U.
S. 199 , 430 U. S.
210 -211 (1977); Califano v. Webster, 430 U. S. 313 , 430 U. S.
316 -317 (1977); Craig v. Boren, supra at 429 U. S. 197 .
This analysis applies whether the classification discriminates
against males or against females. Caban v. Mohammed, supra at 441 U. S. 394 ; Orr v. Orr, supra at 440 U. S.
278 -279; Craig v. Boren, supra, at 429 U. S. 204 .
The burden is on the government to prove both the importance of its
asserted objective and the substantial relationship between the
classification and that objective. See Kirchberg v. Feenstra,
ante at 450 U. S. 461 ; Wengler v. Druggists Mutual Ins. Co., supra at 446 U. S.
151 -152; Caban v. Mohammed, supra at 441 U. S. 393 ; Craig v. Boren, supra at 429 U. S. 204 .
And the State cannot meet that burden without showing that a
gender-neutral statute would be a less effective means of achieving
that goal. Wengler v. Druggists Mutual Ins. Co., supra at 446 U. S.
151 -152; Orr v. Orr, supra, at 440 U. S. 281 ,
283. [ Footnote 3/3 ]
The State of California vigorously asserts that the "important
governmental objective" to be served by § 261.5 is the prevention
of teenage pregnancy. It claims that its statute furthers this goal
by deterring sexual activity by males -- the class of persons it
considers more responsible for causing those pregnancies. [ Footnote 3/4 ] But even assuming that
prevention of teenage Page 450 U. S. 491 pregnancy is an important governmental objective and that it is,
in fact, an objective of § 261.5, see infra, at 450 U. S.
491 -196, California still has the burden of proving that
there are fewer teenage pregnancies under its gender-based
statutory rape law than there would be if the law were
gender-neutral. To meet this burden, the State must show that,
because its statutory rape law punishes only males, and not
females, it more effectively deters minor females from having
sexual intercourse. [ Footnote
3/5 ]
The plurality assumes that a gender-neutral statute would be
less effective than § 261.5 in deterring sexual activity because a
gender-neutral statute would create significant enforcement
problems. The plurality thus accepts the State's assertion that
"a female is surely less likely to report violations of the
statute if she herself would be subject to crimina prosecution. Page 450 U. S. 492 In an area already fraught with prosecutorial difficulties, we
decline to hold that the Equal Protection Clause requires a
legislature to enact a statute so broad that it may well be
incapable of enforcement." Ante at 450 U. S.
473 -474 (footnotes omitted). However, a State's bare
assertion that its gender-based statutory classification
substantially furthers an important governmental interest is not
enough to meet its burden of proof under Craig v. Boren. Rather, the State must produce evidence that will persuade the
court that its assertion is true. See Craig v. Boren, 429
U.S. at 429 U. S.
200 -204.
The State has not produced such evidence in this case. Moreover,
there are at least two serious flaws in the State's assertion that
law enforcement problems created by a gender-neutral statutory rape
law would make such a statute less effective than a gender-based
statute in deterring sexual activity.
First, the experience of other jurisdictions, and California
itself, belies the plurality's conclusion that a gender-neutral
statutory rape law "may well be incapable of enforcement." There
are now at least 37 States that have enacted gender-neutral
statutory rape laws. Although most of these laws protect young
persons (of either sex) from the sexual exploitation of older
individuals, the laws of Arizona, Florida, and Illinois permit
prosecution of both minor females and minor males for engaging in
mutual sexual conduct. [ Footnote
3/6 ] California has introduced no evidence that those States
have been handicapped Page 450 U. S. 493 by the enforcement problems the plurality finds so persuasive.
[ Footnote 3/7 ] Surely, if those
States could provide such evidence, we might expect that California
would have introduced it.
In addition, the California Legislature in recent years has
revised other sections of the Penal Code to make them
gender-neutral. For example, Cal.Penal Code Ann. §§ 286(b)(1) and
288a(b)(1) (West Supp. 1981), prohibiting sodomy and oral
copulation with a "person who is under 18 years of age," could
cause two minor homosexuals to be subjected to criminal sanctions
for engaging in mutually consensual conduct. Again, the State has
introduced no evidence to explain why a gender-neutral statutory
rape law would be any more difficult to enforce than those
statutes.
The second flaw in the State's assertion is that, even assuming
that a gender-neutral statute would be more difficult to enforce,
the State has still not shown that those enforcement problems would
make such a statute less effective than a gender-based statute in
deterring minor females from engaging in sexual intercourse.
[ Footnote 3/8 ] Common sense,
however, suggests Page 450 U. S. 494 that a gende-neutral statutory rape law is potentially a rgeater
deterrent of sexual activity than a gender-based law, for the
simple reason that a gender-neutral law subjects both men and women
to criminal sanctions, and thus arguably has a deterrent effect on
twice as many potential violators. Even if fewer persons were
prosecuted under the gender-neutral law, as the State suggests, it
would still be true that twice as many persons would be subject to
arrest. The State's failure to prove that a gender-neutral law
would be a less effective deterrent than a gender-based law, like
the State's failure to prove that a gender-neutral law would be
difficult to enforce, should have led this Court to invalidate §
261.5. III Until very recently, no California court or commentator had
suggested that the purpose of California's statutory rape law was
to protect young women from the risk of pregnancy. Indeed, the
historical development of § 261.5 demonstrates that the law was
initially enacted on the premise that young women, in contrast to
young men, were to be deemed legally incapable of consenting to an
act of sexual intercourse. [ Footnote
3/9 ] Because Page 450 U. S. 495 their chastity was considered particularly precious, those young
women were felt to be uniquely in need of the State's protection.
[ Footnote 3/10 ] In contrast,
young men were assumed to Page 450 U. S. 496 be capable of making such decisions for themselves; the law
therefore did not offer them any special protection.
It is perhaps because the gender classifiation in California's
statutory rape law was initially designed to further these outmoded
sexual stereotypes, rather than to reduce the incidence of teenage
pregnancies, that the State has been unable to demonstrate a
substantial relationship beween the classification and its newly
asserted goal. Cf. Califano v. Goldfarb, 430 U.S. at 430 U. S. 223 (STEVENS, J., concurring in judgment). But whatever the reason, the
State has not shown that Cal.Penal Cod § 261.5 is any more
effective than a gender-neutral law would be in deterring minor
females from engaging in sexual intercourse. It has therefore not
met its burden of proving that the statutory classification is
substantially related to the achievement of its asserted goal.
I would hold that § 261.5 violates the Equal Protection Clause
of the Fourteenth Amendment, and I would reverse the judgment of
the California Supreme Court.
[ Footnote 3/1 ]
The California Supreme Court acknowledged, and indeed the
parties do not dispute, that Cal.Penal Code Ann. § 261.5 (West
Supp. 1981) discriminates on the basis of sex. Ante at 450 U. S. 467 .
Because petitioner is male, he faces criminal felony charges and a
possible prison term, while his female partner remains immune from
prosecution. The gender of the participants, not their relative
responsibility, determines which of them is subject to criminal
sanctions under § 2615
As the California Supreme Court stated in People v.
Hernandez, 61 Cal. 2d
529 , 531, 393 P.2d 673, 674 (1964) (footnote omitted):
"[E]ven in circumstances where a girl's actual comprehension
contradicts the law's presumption [that a minor female is too
innocent and naive to understand the implications and nature of her
act], the male is deemed criminally responsible for the act,
although himself young and naive and responding to advances which
may have been made to him."
[ Footnote 3/2 ]
None of the three opinions upholding the California statute
fairly applies the equal protection analysis this Court has so
carefully developed since Craig v. Boren, 429 U.
S. 190 (1976). The plurality opinion, for example,
focusing on the obvious and uncontested fact that only females can
become pregnant, suggests that the statutory gender discrimination,
rather than being invidious, actually ensures equality of
treatment. Since only females are subject. to a risk of pregnancy,
the plurality opinion concludes that "[a] criminal sanction imposed
solely on males . . . serves to roughly equalize' the
deterrents on the sexes." Ante at 450 U. S. 473 .
JUSTICE STEWART adopts a similar approach. Recognizing that
"females can become pregnant as the result of sexual intercourse;
males cannot," JUSTICE STEWART concludes that "[y]oung women and
men are not similarly situated with respect to the problems and
risks associated with intercourse and pregnancy," and therefore §
261.5 "is realistically related to the legitimate state
purpose of reducing those problems and risks" (emphasis added). Ante at 450 U. S. 478 , 450 U. S. 479 .
JUSTICE BLACKMUN, conceding that some limits must. be placed on a
State's power to regulate "the control and direction of young
people's sexual activities," also finds the statute constitutional. Ante at 450 U. S. 482 .
He distinguishes the State's power in the abortion context, where
the pregnancy has already occurred, from its power in the present
context, where the "problem [is] at its inception." He then
concludes, without explanation, that "the California statutory rape
law . . . is a sufficiently reasoned and constitutional effort to
control the problem at its inception." Ibid. All three of these approaches have a common failing. They
overlook the fact that the State has not met its hurden of proving
that the gender discrimination in § 261.5 is substantially related to the achievement of the State's asserted statutory goal.
My Brethren seem not to recognize that California has the burden of
proving that a gender-neutral statutory rape law would be less
effective than § 261.5 in deterring sexual activity leading to
teenage pregnancy. Because they fail to analyze the issue in these
terms, I believe they reach an unsupportable result.
[ Footnote 3/3 ]
Gender-based statutory rape laws were struck down in Navedo
v. Preisser, 630 F.2d 636 (CA8 1980), United State v.
Hicks, 625 F.2d 216 (CA9 1980), and Meloon v.
Helgemoe, 564 F.2d 602 (CA1 1977), cert. denied, 436
U.S. 950 (1978), precisely because the government failed to meet
this burden of proof.
[ Footnote 3/4 ]
In a remarkable display of sexual stereotyping, the California
Supreme Court stated:
"The Legislature is well within its power in imposing criminal
sanctions against males alone, because they are the only persons who may physiologically cause the result which the law
properly seeks to avoid." 25 Cal. 3d
608 , 612, 601 P.2d 572, 575 (1979) (emphasis in original).
[ Footnote 3/5 ]
Petitioner has not questioned the State's constitutional power
to achieve its asserted objective by criminalizing consensual
sexual activity. However, I note that our cases would not foreclose
such a privacy challenge.
The State is attempting to reduce the incidence of teenage
pregnancy by imposing criminal sanctions on those who engage in
consensual sexual activity with minor females. We have stressed,
however, that,
"[i]f the right of privacy means anything, it is the right of
the individual, married or single, to be free from unwarranted
governmental intrusion into matters so fundamentally affecting a
person as the decision whether to bear or beget a child." Eisenstadt v. Baird, 405 U. S. 438 , 405 U. S. 453 (1972) (footnote omitted). Minors, too, enjoy a right of privacy in
connection with decisions affecting procreation. Carey v.
Population Services International, 431 U.
S. 678 , 431 U. S. 693 (1977). Thus, despite the suggestion of the plurality to the
contrary, ante at 450 U. S. 472 -473, n. 8, it is not settled that a State
may rely on a pregnancy prevention justification to make consensual
sexual intercourse among minors a criminal act.
[ Footnote 3/6 ] See Ariz.Rev.Stat.Ann. § 13-1405 (1978); Fla.Stat. §
794.05 (1979); Ill.Rev.Stat., ch. 38, � 11-5 (1979). In addition,
eight other States permit both parties to be prosecuted when one of
the participants to a consensual act of sexual intercourse is under
the age of 16. See Kan.Stat.Ann. § 21-3503 (1974);
Mass.Gen.Laws Ann., ch. 265, § 23 (West Supp. 1981); Mich.Comp.Laws
§ 750.13 (1970); Mont.Code Ann. §§ 45-5-501 to 45-5-503 (1979);
N.H.Rev.Stat. § 632-A:3 (Supp. 1979); Tenn.Code Ann. § 39-3705 (4)
(Supp. 1979); Utah Code Ann. § 76-5-401 (Supp. 1979); Vt.Stat.Ann.,
Tit. 13, § 3252(3) (Supp. 1980).
[ Footnote 3/7 ]
There is a logical reason for this. In contrast to laws
governing forcible rape, statutory rape laws apply to consensual
sexual activity. Force is not an element of the crime. Since a
woman who consents to an act of sexual intercourse is unlikely to
report her partner to the police -- whether or not she is subject
to criminal sanctions -- enforcement would not be undermined if the
statute were to be made gender-neutral. See 450
U.S. 464 fn3/8|>n. 8, infra. [ Footnote 3/8 ]
As it is, § 261.5 seems to be an ineffective deterrent of sexual
activity. Cf. Carey v. Population Services International,
supra at 431 U. S. 695 (substantial reason to doubt that limiting access to contraceptives
will substantially discourage early sexual behavior). According to
statistics provided by the State, an average of only 61 juvenile
males and 352 adult males were arrested for statutory rape each
year between 1975 and 1978. Brief for Respondent 19. During each of
those years, there were approximately one million Californian girls
between the ages of 13-17. Cal. Dept. of Finance, Population
Projections for California Counties, 1975-2020, with Age/Sex Detail
to 2000, Series 150 (1977). Although the record in this case does
not indicate the incidence of sexual intercourse involving those
girls during that period, the California State Department of Health
estimates that there were almost 50,000 pregnancies among
13-to-17-year-old girls during 1976. Cal.Dept. of Health, Birth and
Abortion Records, and Physician Survey of Office Abortions (1976).
I think it is fair to speculate from this evidence that a
comparison of the number of arrests for statutory rape in
California with the number of acts of sexual intercourse involving
minor females in that State would likely demonstrate to a male
contemplating sexual activity with a minor female that his chances
of being arrested are reassuringly low. I seriously question,
therefore, whether § 261.5, as enforced, has a substantial
deterrent effect . See Craig v. Boren, 429 U.S. at 429 U. S. 214 (STEVENS, J., concurring).
[ Footnote 3/9 ]
California's statutory rape law had its origins in the Statutes
of Westminster enacted during the reign of Edward I at the close of
the 13th century (3 Edw. 1, ch. 13 (1275); 13 Edw. 1, ch. 34
(1285)). The age of consent at that time was 12 years, reduced to
10 years in 1576 (18 Eliz. 1, ch. 7, § 4). This statute was part of
the common law brought to the United States. Thus, when the first
California penal statute was enacted, it contained a provision
(1850 Cal.Stats., ch. 99, § 47, p. 234) that proscribed sexual
intercourse with females under the age of 10. In 1889, the
California statute was amended to make the age of consent 14 (1889
Cal.Stats., ch.191, § 1, p. 223). In 1897, the age was advanced to
16 (1897 Cal.Stats., ch. 139, § 1, p. 201). In 1913, it was fixed
at 18, where it now remains (1913 Cal.Stats., ch. 122, § 1, p.
212).
Because females generally have not reached puberty by the age of
10, it is inconceivable that a statute designed to prevent
pregnancy would be directed at acts of sexual intercourse with
females under that age.
The only legislative history available, the draftsmen's notes to
the Penal Code of 1872, supports the view that the purpose of
California's statutory rape law was to protect those who were too
young to give consent. The draftsmen explained that the
"[statutory rape] provision embodies the well settled rule of
the existing law; that a girl under ten years of age is incapable
of giving any consent to an act of intercourse which can reduce it
below the grade of rape."
Code Commissioners' note, subd. 1, following Cal.Penal Code §
261, p. 111 (1st ed. 1872). There was no mention whatever of
pregnancy prevention. See also Note, Forcible and
Statutory Rape: An Exploration of the Operation and Objectives of
the Consent Standard, 62 Yale L.J. 55, 74-76 (1952).
[ Footnote 3/10 ]
Past decisions of the California courts confirm that the law was
designed to protect the State's young females from their own
uninformed decisionmaking. In People v. Verdereen, 106
Cal. 211, 214-215, 39 P. 607, 608-609 (1895), for example, the
California Supreme Court stated:
"The obvious purpose of [the statutory rape law] is the
protection of society by protecting from violation the virtue of
young and unsophisticated girls. . . . It is the insidious approach
and vile tampering with their persons that primarily undermines the
virtue of young girls, and eventually destroys it; and the
prevention of this, as much as the principal act, must undoubtedly
have been the intent of the legislature."
As recently as 1964, the California Supreme Court decided People v. Hernandez, 61 Cal. 2d at 531, 393 P.2d at 674,
in which it stated that the under-age female
"is presumed too innocent and naive to understand the
implications and nature of her act. . . . The law's concern with
her capacity or lack thereof to so understand is explained in part
by a popular conception of the social, moral and personal values
which are preserved by the abstinence from sexual indulgence on the
part of a young woman. An unwise disposition of her sexual favor is
deemed to do harm both to herself and the social mores by which the
community's conduct patterns are established. Hence, the law of
statutory rape intervenes in an effort to avoid such a
disposition."
It was only in deciding Michael M. that the California
Supreme Court decided, for the first time in the 130-year history
of the statute, that pregnancy prevention had become one of the
purposes of the statute.
JUSTICE STEVENS, dissenting.
Local custom and belief -- rather than statutory laws of
venerable but doubtful ancestry -- will determine the volume of
sexual activity among unmarried teenagers. [ Footnote 4/1 ] The empirical Page 450 U. S. 497 evidence clted by the plurality demonstrates the futility of the
notion that a statutory prohibition will significantly affect the
volume of that activity or provide a meaningful solution to the
problems created by it. [ Footnote
4/2 ] Nevertheless, as a matter of constitutional power, unlike
my Brother BRENNAN, see ante at 450 U. S. 491 ,
n. 5, I would have no doubt about the validity of a state law
prohibiting all unmarried teenagers from engaging in sexual
intercourse. The societal interests in reducing the incidence of
venereal disease and teenage pregnancy are sufficient, in my
judgment, to justify a prohibition of conduct that increases the
risk of those harms. [ Footnote
4/3 ]
My conclusion that a nondiscriminatory prohibition would be
constitutional does not help me answer the question whether a
prohibition applicable to only half of the joint participants in
the risk-creating conduct is also valid. It cannot be true that the
validity of a total ban is an adequate justification for a
selective prohibition; otherwise, the constitutional objection to
discriminatory rules would be meaningless. The question in this
case is whether the difference between males and females justifies
this statutory discrimination based entirely on sex. [ Footnote 4/4 ] Page 450 U. S. 498 The fact that the Court did not immediately acknowledge that the
capacity to become pregnant is what primarily differentiates the
female from the male [ Footnote 4/5 ]
does not impeach the validity of the plurality's newly found
wisdom. I think the plurality is quite correct in making the
assumption that the joint act that this law seeks to prohibit
creates a greater risk of harm for the female than for the male.
But the plurality surely cannot believe that the risk of pregnancy
confronted by the female -- any more than the risk of venereal
disease confronted by males as well a females -- has provided an
effective deterrent to voluntary female participation in the
risk-creating conduct. Yet the plurality' decision seems to rest on
the assumption that the California Legislature acted on the basis
of that rather fanciful notion. Page 450 U. S. 499 In my judgment, the fact that a class of persons is especially
vulnerable to a risk that a statute is designed to avoid is a
reason for making the statute applicable to that class. The
argument that a special need for protection provides a rational
explanation for an exemption is one I simply do not comprehend.
[ Footnote 4/6 ]
In this case, the fact that a female confronts a greater risk of
harm than a male is a reason for applying the prohibition to her --
not a reason for granting her a license to use her own judgment on
whether or not to assume the risk. Surely, if we examine the
problem from the point of view of society's interest in preventing
the risk-creating conduct from occurring at all, it is irrational
to exempt 50% of the potential violators. See dissent of
JUSICE BRENNAN, ante at 450 U. S.
493 -494. And, if we view the government's interest as
that of a parens patriae seeking to protect its subjects
from harming themselves, the discrimination is actually perverse.
Would a rational parent making rules for the conduct of twin
children of opposite sex simultaneously forbid the son and
authorize the daughter to engage in conduct that is especially
harmful to the daughter? That is the effect of this statutory
classification.
If pregnancy or some other special harm is suffered by one of
the two participants in the prohibited act, that special harm no
doubt would constitute a legitimate mitigating factor in deciding
what, if any, punishment might be appropriate in a given case. But
from the standpoint of fashioning a general preventive rule -- or,
indeed, in determining appropriate punishment when neither party in
fact has suffered any special Page 450 U. S. 500 harm -- I regard a total exemption for the members of the more
endangered class as utterly irrational.
In my opinion, the only acceptable justification for a general
rule requiring disparate treatment of the two participants in a
joint act must be a legislative judgment that one is more guilty
than the other. The risk-creating conduct that this statute is
designed to prevent requires the participation of two persons --
one male and one female. [ Footnote
4/7 ] In many situations, it is probably true that one is the
aggressor and the other is either an unwilling, or at least a less
willing, participant in the joint act. If a statute authorized
punishment of only one participant and required the prosecutor to
prove that that participant had been the aggressor, I assume that
the discrimination would be valid. Although the question is less
clear, I also assume, for the purpose of deciding this case, that
it would be permissible to punish only the male participant if one
element of the offense were proof that he had been the aggressor,
or at least in some respects the more responsible participant, in
the joint act. The statute at issue in this case, however, requires
no such proof. The question raised by this statute is whether the
State, consistently with the Federal Constitution, may always
punish the male and never the female when they are equally
responsible or when the female is the more responsible of the
two.
It would seem to me that an impartial lawmaker could give only
one answer to that question. The fact that the California
Legislature has decided to apply its prohibition only to Page 450 U. S. 501 the male may reflect a legislative judgment that, in the typical
case the male is actually the more guilty party. Any such judgment
must, in turn, assume that the decision to engage in the
risk-creating conduct is always -- or at least typically -- a male
decision. If that assumption is valid, the statutory classification
should also be valid. But what is the support for the assumption?
It is not contained in the record of this case or in any
legislative history or scholarly study that has been called to our
attention. I think it is supported to some extent by traditional
attitudes toward male-female relationships. But the possibility
that such a habitual attitude may reflect nothing more than an
irrational prejudice makes it an insufficient justification for
discriminatory treatment that is otherwise blatantly unfair. For,
as I read this statute, it requires that one, and only one, of two
equally guilty wrongdoers be stigmatized by a criminal
conviction.
I cannot accept the State's argument that the constitutionality
of the discriminatory rule can be saved by an assumption that
prosecutors will commonly invoke this statute only in cases that
actually involve a forcible rape, but one that cannot be
established by proof beyond a reasonable doubt. [ Footnote 4/8 ] That assumption implies that a State
has a legitimate interest in convicting a defendant on evidence
that is constitutionally insufficient. Of course, the State may
create a lesser-included offense that would authorize punishment of
the more guilty party, but surely the interest in obtaining
convictions on inadequate Page 450 U. S. 502 proof cannot justify a statute that punishes one who is equally
or less guilty than his partner. [ Footnote 4/9 ]
Nor do I find at all persuasive the suggestion that this
discrimination is adequately justified by the desire to encourage
females to inform against their male partners. Even if the concept
of a wholesale informant's exemption were an acceptable enforcement
device, what is the justification for defining the exempt class
entirely by reference to sex, rather than by reference to a more
neutral criterion such as relative innocence? Indeed, if the exempt
class is to be composed entirely of members of one sex, what is
there to support the view that the statutory purpose will be better
served by granting the informing license to females, rather than to
males? If a discarded male partner informs on a promiscuous female,
a timely threat of prosecution might well prevent the precise harm
the statute is intended to minimize.
Finally, even if my logic is faulty and there actually is some
speculative basis for treating equally guilty males and females
differently, I still believe that any such speculative
justification would be outweighed by the paramount interest in
evenhanded enforcement of the law. A rule that authorizes
punishment of only one of two equally guilty wrongdoers violates
the essence of the constitutional requirement that the sovereign
must govern impartially.
I respectfully dissent.
[ Footnote 4/1 ]
"Common sense indicates that many young people will engage in
sexual activity regardless of what the New York Legislature does,
and further, that the incidence of venereal disease and premarital
pregnancy is affected by the availability or unavailability of
contraceptives. Although young persons theoretically may avoid
those harms by practicing total abstention, inevitably many will
not." Carey v. Population Services International, 431 U. S. 678 , 431 U. S. 714 (STEVENSI J., concurring in part and in judgment).
[ Footnote 4/2 ]
If a million teenagers became pregnant in 1976, see
ante at 450 U. S. 470 ,
n. 3, there must be countless violations of the California statute.
The statistics cited by JUSTICE BRENNAN also indicate, as he
correctly observes, that the statute "seems to be an ineffective
deterrent of sexual activity." See ante at 450 U. S.
493 -494, n. 8.
[ Footnote 4/3 ] See Carey v. Population Services International, supra, at 431 U. S. 713 (STEVENS, J., concurring in part and in judgment).
[ Footnote 4/4 ]
Equal protection analysis is often said to involve different
"levels of scrutiny." It may be more accurate to say that the
burden of sustaining an equal protection challenge is much heavier
in some cases than in others. Racial classifications, which are
subjected to "strict scrutiny," are presumptively invalid because
there is seldom, if ever, any legitimate reason for treating
citizens differently because of their race. On the other hand, most
economic classifications are presumptively valid because they are a
necessary component of most regulatory programs. In cases involving
discrimination between men and women, the natural differences
between the sexes are sometimes relevant and sometimes wholly
irrelevant. If those differences are obviously irrelevant, the
discrimination should be t.reated as presumptively unlawful in the
same way that racial clasifications are presumptively unlawful. Cf. Califano v. Goldfarb, 430 U.
S. 199 , 430 U. S. 223 (STEVENS, J., concurring in judgment). But if, as in this case,
there is an apparent connection between the discrimination and the
fact that only women can become pregnant, it may be appropriate to
presume that the classification is lawful. This presumption,
however, may be overcome by a demonstration that the apparent
justification for the discrimination is illusory or wholly
inadequate. Thus, instead of applying a "mid-level" form of
scrutiny in all sex discrimination cases, perhaps the burden is
heavier in some than in others. Nevertheless, as I have previously
suggested, the ultimate standard in these, as in all other equal
protection cases, is essentially the same. See Craig v.
Boren, 429 U. S. 190 , 429 U. S.
211 -212 (STEVENS, J., concurring). Professor Cox
recently noted that, however the level of scrutiny is described, in
the final analysis,
"the Court is always deciding whether, in its judgment, the harm
done to the disadvantaged class by the legislative classification
is disproportionate to the public purposes the measure is likely to
achieve."
Cox, Book Review, 94 Harv.L.Rev. 700, 706 (1981).
[ Footnote 4/5 ] See General Electric Co. v. Gilbert, 429 U.
S. 125 , 429 U. S. 162 (STEVENS, J., dissenting).
[ Footnote 4/6 ]
A hypothetical racial classification will illustrate my point.
Assume that skin pigmentation provides some measure of protection
against cancer caused by exposure to certain chemicals in the
atmosphere and, therefore, that white employees confront a greater
risk than black employees in certain industrial settings. Would it
be rational to require black employees to wear protective clothing
but to exempt whites from that requirement? It seems to me that the
greater risk of harm to white workers would be a reason for
including them in the requirement -- not for granting them an
exemption.
[ Footnote 4/7 ]
In light of this indisputable biological fact, I find somewhat
puzzling the California Supreme Court's conclusion, quoted by the
plurality, ante at 450 U. S. 467 ,
that males "are the only persons who may physiologically
cause the result which the law properly seeks to avoid." 25 Cal. 3d
608 , 612, 601 P.2d 572, 575 (1979) (emphasis in original).
Presumably, the California Supreme Court was referring to the
equally indisputable biological fact that only females may become
pregnant. However, if pregnancy results from sexual intercourse
between two willing participants -- and the California statute is
directed at such conduct -- I would find it difficult to conclude
that the pregnancy was "caused" solely by the male participant.
[ Footnote 4/8 ]
According to the State of California:
"The statute is commonly employed in situations involving force,
prostitution, pornography, or coercion due to status relationships,
and the state's interest in these situations is apparent."
Brief for Respondent 3. See also id. at 23-25. The
State's interest in these situations is indeed apparent, and
certainly sufficient to justify statutory prohibition of forcible
rape, prostitution, pornography, and nonforcible, but nonetheless
coerced, sexual intercourse. However, it is not at all apparent to
me how this state interest can justify a statute not specifically
directed to any of these offenses.
[ Footnote 4/9 ]
Both JUSTICE REHNQUIST and JUSTICE BLACKMUN apparently attach
significance to the testimony at the preliminary hearing indicating
that the petitioner struck his partner. See opinion of
REHNQUIST, J., ante at 450 U. S. 467 ;
opinion of BLACKMUN, J., ante at 450 U. S.
483 -488, n. In light of the fact that the petitioner
would be equally guilty of the crime charged in the complaint
whether or not that testimony is true, it obviously has no bearing
on the legal question presented by this case. The question is not
whether "the facts . . . fit the crime," opinion of BLACKMUN, J., ante at 450 U. S. 487 -- that is a question to be answered at trial -- but rather,
whether the statute defining the crime fits the constitutional
requirement that justice be administered in an evenhanded
fashion. | The Supreme Court upheld a California statute that criminalizes sexual intercourse between a male and a female under the age of 18, known as "statutory rape." The Court ruled that the law does not violate the Equal Protection Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment, as gender-based classifications are not "inherently suspect." The Court found that the statute serves the legitimate state interest of preventing teenage pregnancies and protecting young women from the physical, emotional, and psychological consequences of pregnancy. The Court also rejected the argument that the statute is discriminatory or underinclusive and emphasized that the Equal Protection Clause does not require identical treatment for all persons. |
Equal Protection | Grutter v. Bollinger | https://supreme.justia.com/cases/federal/us/539/306/ | OCTOBER TERM, 2002
Syllabus
GRUTTER v. BOLLINGER ET AL.
CERTIORARI TO THE UNITED STATES COURT OF APPEALS FOR THE SIXTH
CIRCUIT
No.02-241. Argued April 1, 2003-Decided June 23, 2003
The University of Michigan Law School (Law School), one of the
Nation's top law schools, follows an official admissions policy
that seeks to achieve student body diversity through compliance
with Regents of Univ. of Cal. v. Bakke , 438 U. S. 265 . Focusing
on students' academic ability coupled with a flexible assessment of
their talents, experiences, and potential, the policy requires
admissions officials to evaluate each applicant based on all the
information available in the file, including a personal statement,
letters of recommendation, an essay describing how the applicant
will contribute to Law School life and diversity, and the
applicant's undergraduate grade point average (GPA) and Law School
Admission Test (LSAT) score. Additionally, officials must look
beyond grades and scores to so-called "soft variables," such as
recommenders' enthusiasm, the quality of the undergraduate
institution and the applicant's essay, and the areas and difficulty
of undergraduate course selection. The policy does not define
diversity solely in terms of racial and ethnic status and does not
restrict the types of diversity contributions eligible for
"substantial weight," but it does reaffirm the Law School's
commitment to diversity with special reference to the inclusion of
African-American, Hispanic, and Native-American students, who
otherwise might not be represented in the student body in
meaningful numbers. By enrolling a "critical mass" of
underrepresented minority students, the policy seeks to ensure
their ability to contribute to the Law School's character and to
the legal profession.
When the Law School denied admission to petitioner Grutter, a
white Michigan resident with a 3.8 GPA and 161 LSAT score, she
filed this suit, alleging that respondents had discriminated
against her on the basis of race in violation of the Fourteenth
Amendment, Title VI of the Civil Rights Act of 1964, and 42 U. S.
C. § 1981; that she was rejected because the Law School uses race
as a "predominant" factor, giving applicants belonging to certain
minority groups a significantly greater chance of admission than
students with similar credentials from disfavored racial groups;
and that respondents had no compelling interest to justify that use
of race. The District Court found the Law School's use of race as
an admissions factor unlawful. The Sixth Circuit reversed, holding
that Justice Powell's opinion in Bakke was binding
precedent establishing [307] diversity as a compelling state interest, and that the Law
School's use of race was narrowly tailored because race was merely
a "potential 'plus' factor" and because the Law School's program
was virtually identical to the Harvard admissions program described
approvingly by Justice Powell and appended to his Bakke opinion. Held: The Law School's narrowly tailored use of race in
admissions decisions to further a compelling interest in obtaining
the educational benefits that flow from a diverse student body is
not prohibited by the Equal Protection Clause, Title VI, or § 1981.
Pp. 322-344.
(a) In the landmark Bakke case, this Court reviewed a
medical school's racial set-aside program that reserved 16 out of
100 seats for members of certain minority groups. The decision
produced six separate opinions, none of which commanded a majority.
Four Justices would have upheld the program on the ground that the
government can use race to remedy disadvantages cast on minorities
by past racial prejudice. 438 U. S., at 325. Four other Justices
would have struck the program down on statutory grounds. Id. , at 408. Justice Powell, announcing the Court's
judgment, provided a fifth vote not only for invalidating the
program, but also for reversing the state court's injunction
against any use of race whatsoever. In a part of his opinion that
was joined by no other Justice, Justice Powell expressed his view
that attaining a diverse student body was the only interest
asserted by the university that survived scrutiny. Id. , at
311. Grounding his analysis in the academic freedom that "long has
been viewed as a special concern of the First Amendment," id. , at 312, 314, Justice Powell emphasized that the
"'nation's future depends upon leaders trained through wide
exposure' to the ideas and mores of students as diverse as this
Nation." Id. , at 313. However, he also emphasized that
"[i]t is not an interest in simple ethnic diversity, in which a
specified percentage of the student body is in effect guaranteed to
be members of selected ethnic groups," that can justify using race. Id. , at 315. Rather, "[t]he diversity that furthers a
compelling state interest encompasses a far broader array of
qualifications and characteristics of which racial or ethnic origin
is but a single though important element." Ibid. Since Bakke , Justice Powell's opinion has been the touchstone
for constitutional analysis of race-conscious admissions policies.
Public and private universities across the Nation have modeled
their own admissions programs on Justice Powell's views. Courts,
however, have struggled to discern whether Justice Powell's
diversity rationale is binding precedent. The Court finds it
unnecessary to decide this issue because the Court endorses Justice
Powell's view that student body diversity is a compelling state
interest in the context of university admissions. Pp. 322-325. [308] (b) All government racial classifications must be analyzed by a
reviewing court under strict scrutiny. Adarand Constructors,
Inc. v. Peña , 515 U. S. 200 , 227. But
not all such uses are invalidated by strict scrutiny. Race-based
action necessary to further a compelling governmental interest does
not violate the Equal Protection Clause so long as it is narrowly
tailored to further that interest. E. g., Shaw v. Hunt , 517 U. S. 899 ,
908. Context matters when reviewing such action. See Gomillion
v. Lightfoot , 364 U. S. 339 , 343-344.
Not every decision influenced by race is equally objectionable, and
strict scrutiny is designed to provide a framework for carefully
examining the importance and the sincerity of the government's
reasons for using race in a particular context. Pp. 326-327.
(c) The Court endorses Justice Powell's view that student body
diversity is a compelling state interest that can justify using
race in university admissions. The Court defers to the Law School's
educational judgment that diversity is essential to its educational
mission. The Court's scrutiny of that interest is no less strict
for taking into account complex educational judgments in an area
that lies primarily within the university's expertise. See, e.
g., Bakke , 438 U. S., at 319, n. 53 (opinion of Powell, J.).
Attaining a diverse student body is at the heart of the Law
School's proper institutional mission, and its "good faith" is
"presumed" absent "a showing to the contrary." Id. , at
318-319. Enrolling a "critical mass" of minority students simply to
assure some specified percentage of a particular group merely
because of its race or ethnic origin would be patently
unconstitutional. E.g., id. , at 307. But the Law School
defines its critical mass concept by reference to the substantial,
important, and laudable educational benefits that diversity is
designed to produce, including cross-racial understanding and the
breaking down of racial stereotypes. The Law School's claim is
further bolstered by numerous expert studies and reports showing
that such diversity promotes learning outcomes and better prepares
students for an increasingly diverse work force, for society, and
for the legal profession. Major American businesses have made clear
that the skills needed in today's increasingly global marketplace
can only be developed through exposure to widely diverse people,
cultures, ideas, and viewpoints. High-ranking retired officers and
civilian military leaders assert that a highly qualified, racially
diverse officer corps is essential to national security. Moreover,
because universities, and in particular, law schools, represent the
training ground for a large number of the Nation's leaders, Sweatt v. Painter , 339 U. S. 629 , 634, the
path to leadership must be visibly open to talented and qualified
individuals of every race and ethnicity. Thus, the Law School has a
compelling interest in attaining a diverse student body. Pp.
327-333. [309] (d) The Law School's admissions program bears the hallmarks of a
narrowly tailored plan. To be narrowly tailored, a race-conscious
admissions program cannot "insulat[e] each category of applicants
with certain desired qualifications from competition with all other
applicants." Bakke , 438 U. S., at 315 (opinion of Powell,
J.). Instead, it may consider race or ethnicity only as a "'plus'
in a particular applicant's file"; i. e. , it must be
"flexible enough to consider all pertinent elements of diversity in
light of the particular qualifications of each applicant, and to
place them on the same footing for consideration, although not
necessarily according them the same weight," id. , at 317.
It follows that universities cannot establish quotas for members of
certain racial or ethnic groups or put them on separate admissions
tracks. See id. , at 315-316. The Law School's admissions
program, like the Harvard plan approved by Justice Powell,
satisfies these requirements. Moreover, the program is flexible
enough to ensure that each applicant is evaluated as an individual
and not in a way that makes race or ethnicity the defining feature
of the application. See id. , at 317. The Law School
engages in a highly individualized, holistic review of each
applicant's file, giving serious consideration to all the ways an
applicant might contribute to a diverse educational environment.
There is no policy, either de jure or de facto ,
of automatic acceptance or rejection based on any single "soft"
variable. Gratz v. Bollinger, ante , p. 244, distinguished.
Also, the program adequately ensures that all factors that may
contribute to diversity are meaningfully considered alongside race.
Moreover, the Law School frequently accepts nonminority applicants
with grades and test scores lower than underrepresented minority
applicants (and other nonminority applicants) who are rejected. The
Court rejects the argument that the Law School should have used
other race-neutral means to obtain the educational benefits of
student body diversity, e.g. , a lottery system or
decreasing the emphasis on GPA and LSAT scores. N arrow tailoring
does not require exhaustion of every conceivable race-neutral
alternative or mandate that a university choose between maintaining
a reputation for excellence or fulfilling a commitment to provide
educational opportunities to members of all racial groups. See, e. g., Wygant v. Jackson Bd. of Ed. , 476 U. S. 267 , 280, n. 6.
The Court is satisfied that the Law School adequately considered
the available alternatives. The Court is also satisfied that, in
the context of individualized consideration of the possible
diversity contributions of each applicant, the Law School's
race-conscious admissions program does not unduly harm nonminority
applicants. Finally, race-conscious admissions policies must be
limited in time. The Court takes the Law School at its word that it
would like nothing better than to find a race-neutral admissions
formula and will terminate its use of racial [310] preferences as soon as practicable. The Court expects that 25
years from now, the use of racial preferences will no longer be
necessary to further the interest approved today. Pp. 333-343.
(e) Because the Law School's use of race in admissions decisions
is not prohibited by the Equal Protection Clause, petitioner's
statutory claims based on Title VI and § 1981 also fail. See Bakke, supra , at 287 (opinion of Powell, J.); General
Building Contractors Assn., Inc. v. Pennsylvania , 458 U. S. 375 , 389-391.
Pp. 343-344.
288 F.3d 732, affirmed.
O'CONNOR, J., delivered the opinion of the Court, in which
STEVENS, SOUTER, GINSBURG, and BREYER, JJ., joined, and in which
SCALIA and THOMAS, JJ., joined in part insofar as it is consistent
with the views expressed in Part VII of the opinion of THOMAS, J.
GINSBURG, J., filed a concurring opinion, in which BREYER, J.,
joined, post , p. 344. SCALIA, J., filed an opinion
concurring in part and dissenting in part, in which THOMAS, J.,
joined, post , p. 346. THOMAS, J., filed an opinion
concurring in part and dissenting in part, in which SCALIA, J.,
joined as to Parts I-VII, post , p. 349. REHNQUIST, C. J.,
filed a dissenting opinion, in which SCALIA, KENNEDY, and THOMAS,
JJ., joined, post , p. 378. KENNEDY, J., filed a dissenting
opinion, post , p. 387.
Kirk O. Kolbo argued the cause for petitioner. With him on the
briefs were David F. Herr, R. Lawrence Purdy, Michael C. McCarthy,
Michael E. Rosman, Hans Bader, and Kerry L. Morgan.
Solicitor General Olson argued the cause for the United States
as amicus curiae urging reversal. With him on the brief were
Assistant Attorney General Boyd and Deputy Solicitor General
Clement.
Maureen E. Mahoney argued the cause for respondent Bollinger et
al. With her on the brief were John H. Pickering, John Payton,
Brigida Benitez, Craig Goldblatt, Terry A. Maroney, Marvin Krislov,
Jonathan Alger, Evan Caminker, Philip J. Kessler, and Leonard M.
Niehoff Miranda K. S. Massie and George B. Washington filed a brief for respondent James et al.[ Footnote * ] [311] JUSTICE O'CONNOR delivered the opinion of the Court. This case
requires us to decide whether the use of race as a factor in
student admissions by the University of Michigan Law School (Law
School) is unlawful. [312] I A
The Law School ranks among the Nation's top law schools.
It receives more than 3,500 applications each year for a
class [313] of around 350 students. Seeking to "admit a group of students
who individually and collectively are among the most capable," the
Law School looks for individuals with "sub- [314] stantial promise for success in law school" and "a strong
likelihood of succeeding in the practice of law and contributing in
diverse ways to the well-being of others." App. 110. More broadly,
the Law School seeks "a mix of students with varying backgrounds
and experiences who will respect and learn from each other." Ibid. In 1992, the dean of the Law School charged a
faculty committee with crafting a written admissions policy to
implement these goals. In particular, the Law School sought to
ensure that its efforts to achieve student body diversity complied
with this Court's most recent ruling on the use of race in
university admissions. See Regents of Univ. of Cal. v.
Bakke , 438 U. S.
265 (1978). [315] Upon the unanimous adoption of the committee's report by the Law
School faculty, it became the Law School's official admissions
policy.
The hallmark of that policy is its focus on academic ability
coupled with a flexible assessment of applicants' talents,
experiences, and potential "to contribute to the learning of those
around them." App.111. The policy requires admissions officials to
evaluate each applicant based on all the information available in
the file, including a personal statement, letters of
recommendation, and an essay describing the ways in which the
applicant will contribute to the life and diversity of the Law
School. Id. , at 83-84, 114-121. In reviewing an
applicant's file, admissions officials must consider the
applicant's undergraduate grade point average (GPA) and Law School
Admission Test (LSAT) score because they are important (if
imperfect) predictors of academic success in law school. Id. , at 112. The policy stresses that "no applicant should
be admitted unless we expect that applicant to do well enough to
graduate with no serious academic problems." Id. , at
111.
The policy makes clear, however, that even the highest possible
score does not guarantee admission to the Law School. Id. ,
at 113. Nor does a low score automatically disqualify an applicant. Ibid. Rather, the policy requires admissions officials to
look beyond grades and test scores to other criteria that are
important to the Law School's educational objectives. Id. ,
at 114. So-called" 'soft' variables" such as "the enthusiasm of
recommenders, the quality of the undergraduate institution, the
quality of the applicant's essay, and the areas and difficulty of
undergraduate course selection" are all brought to bear in
assessing an "applicant's likely contributions to the intellectual
and social life of the institution." Ibid. The policy aspires to "achieve that diversity which has the
potential to enrich everyone's education and thus make a law school
class stronger than the sum of its parts." Id. , at
118. [316] The policy does not restrict the types of diversity
contributions eligible for "substantial weight" in the admissions
process, but instead recognizes "many possible bases for diversity
admissions." Id. , at 118, 120. The policy does, however,
reaffirm the Law School's longstanding commitment to "one
particular type of diversity," that is, "racial and ethnic
diversity with special reference to the inclusion of students from
groups which have been historically discriminated against, like
African-Americans, Hispanics and Native Americans, who without this
commitment might not be represented in our student body in
meaningful numbers." Id. , at 120. By enrolling a "
'critical mass' of [underrepresented] minority students," the Law
School seeks to "ensur[e] their ability to make unique
contributions to the character of the Law School." Id. , at
120-121.
The policy does not define diversity "solely in terms of racial
and ethnic status." Id. , at 121. Nor is the policy
"insensitive to the competition among all students for admission to
the [L]aw [S]chool." Ibid. Rather, the policy seeks to
guide admissions officers in "producing classes both diverse and
academically outstanding, classes made up of students who promise
to continue the tradition of outstanding contribution by Michigan
Graduates to the legal profession." Ibid. B
Petitioner Barbara Grutter is a white Michigan resident who
applied to the Law School in 1996 with a 3.8 GPA and 161 LSAT
score. The Law School initially placed petitioner on a waiting
list, but subsequently rejected her application. In December 1997,
petitioner filed suit in the United States District Court for the
Eastern District of Michigan against the Law School, the Regents of
the University of Michigan, Lee Bollinger (Dean of the Law School
from 1987 to 1994, and President of the University of Michigan from
1996 to 2002), Jeffrey Lehman (Dean of the Law School), and Dennis
Shields (Director of Admissions at the Law School from 1991 [317] until 1998). Petitioner alleged that respondents discriminated
against her on the basis of race in violation of the Fourteenth
Amendment; Title VI of the Civil Rights Act of 1964, 78 Stat. 252,
42 U. S. C. § 2000d; and Rev. Stat. § 1977, as amended, 42 U. S. C.
§ 1981.
Petitioner further alleged that her application was rejected
because the Law School uses race as a "predominant" factor, giving
applicants who belong to certain minority groups "a significantly
greater chance of admission than students with similar credentials
from disfavored racial groups." App.33-34. Petitioner also alleged
that respondents "had no compelling interest to justify their use
of race in the admissions process." Id. , at 34. Petitioner
requested compensatory and punitive damages, an order requiring the
Law School to offer her admission, and an injunction prohibiting
the Law School from continuing to discriminate on the basis of
race. Id. , at 36. Petitioner clearly has standing to bring
this lawsuit. Northeastern Fla. Chapter, Associated Gen.
Contractors of America v. Jacksonville , 508 U. S. 656 , 666
(1993).
The District Court granted petitioner's motion for class
certification and for bifurcation of the trial into liability and
damages phases. The class was defined as " 'all persons who (A)
applied for and were not granted admission to the University of
Michigan Law School for the academic years since (and including)
1995 until the time that judgment is entered herein; and (B) were
members of those racial or ethnic groups, including Caucasian, that
Defendants treated less favorably in considering their applications
for admission to the Law School.'" App. to Pet. for Cert.
191a-192a.
The District Court heard oral argument on the parties'
cross-motions for summary judgment on December 22, 2000. Taking the
motions under advisement, the District Court indicated that it
would decide as a matter of law whether the Law School's asserted
interest in obtaining the educational benefits that flow from a
diverse student body was compel- [318] ling. The District Court also indicated that it would conduct a
bench trial on the extent to which race was a factor in the Law
School's admissions decisions, and whether the Law School's
consideration of race in admissions decisions constituted a
race-based double standard.
During the 15-day bench trial, the parties introduced extensive
evidence concerning the Law School's use of race in the admissions
process. Dennis Shields, Director of Admissions when petitioner
applied to the Law School, testified that he did not direct his
staff to admit a particular percentage or number of minority
students, but rather to consider an applicant's race along with all
other factors. Id. , at 206a. Shields testified that at the
height of the admissions season, he would frequently consult the
so-called "daily reports" that kept track of the racial and ethnic
composition of the class (along with other information such as
residency status and gender). Id. , at 207a. This was done,
Shields testified, to ensure that a critical mass of
underrepresented minority students would be reached so as to
realize the educational benefits of a diverse student body. Ibid. Shields stressed, however, that he did not seek to
admit any particular number or percentage of underrepresented
minority students. Ibid. Erica Munzel, who succeeded Shields as Director of Admissions,
testified that" 'critical mass'" means" 'meaningful numbers'" or
"'meaningful representation,'" which she understood to mean a
number that encourages underrepresented minority students to
participate in the classroom and not feel isolated. Id. ,
at 208a-209a. Munzel stated there is no number, percentage, or
range of numbers or percentages that constitute critical mass. Id. , at 209a. Munzel also asserted that she must consider
the race of applicants because a critical mass of underrepresented
minority students could not be enrolled if admissions decisions
were based primarily on undergraduate GPAs and LSAT scores. Ibid. The current Dean of the Law School, Jeffrey Lehman, also
testified. Like the other Law School witnesses, Lehman did [319] not quantify critical mass in terms of numbers or percentages. Id. , at 211a. He indicated that critical mass means
numbers such that underrepresented minority students do not feel
isolated or like spokespersons for their race. Ibid. When
asked about the extent to which race is considered in admissions,
Lehman testified that it varies from one applicant to another. Ibid. In some cases, according to Lehman's testimony, an
applicant's race may play no role, while in others it may be a
"'determinative'" factor. Ibid. The District Court heard extensive testimony from Professor
Richard Lempert, who chaired the faculty committee that drafted the
1992 policy. Lempert emphasized that the Law School seeks students
with diverse interests and backgrounds to enhance classroom
discussion and the educational experience both inside and outside
the classroom. Id. , at 213a. When asked about the
policy's" 'commitment to racial and ethnic diversity with special
reference to the inclusion of students from groups which have been
historically discriminated against,'" Lempert explained that this
language did not purport to remedy past discrimination, but rather
to include students who may bring to the Law School a perspective
different from that of members of groups which have not been the
victims of such discrimination. Ibid. Lempert acknowledged
that other groups, such as Asians and Jews, have experienced
discrimination, but explained they were not mentioned in the policy
because individuals who are members of those groups were already
being admitted to the Law School in significant numbers. Ibid. Kent Syverud was the final witness to testify about the Law
School's use of race in admissions decisions. Syverud was a
professor at the Law School when the 1992 admissions policy was
adopted and is now Dean of Vanderbilt Law School. In addition to
his testimony at trial, Syverud submitted several expert reports on
the educational benefits of diversity. Syverud's testimony
indicated that when a critical mass of underrepresented minority
students is pres- [320] ent, racial stereotypes lose their force because nonminority
students learn there is no "'minority viewpoint'" but rather a
variety of viewpoints among minority students. Id. , at
215a.
In an attempt to quantify the extent to which the Law School
actually considers race in making admissions decisions, the parties
introduced voluminous evidence at trial. Relying on data obtained
from the Law School, petitioner's expert, Dr. Kinley Larntz,
generated and analyzed "admissions grids" for the years in question
(1995-2000). These grids show the number of applicants and the
number of admittees for all combinations of GPAs and LSAT scores.
Dr. Larntz made" 'cell-by-cell'" comparisons between applicants of
different races to determine whether a statistically significant
relationship existed between race and admission rates. He concluded
that membership in certain minority groups "'is an extremely strong
factor in the decision for acceptance,'" and that applicants from
these minority groups "'are given an extremely large allowance for
admission'" as compared to applicants who are members of nonfavored
groups. Id. , at 218a-220a. Dr. Larntz conceded, however,
that race is not the predominant factor in the Law School's
admissions calculus. 12 Tr. 11-13 (Feb. 10, 2001).
Dr. Stephen Raudenbush, the Law School's expert, focused on the
predicted effect of eliminating race as a factor in the Law
School's admission process. In Dr. Raudenbush's view, a race-blind
admissions system would have a "'very dramatic,'" negative effect
on underrepresented minority admissions. App. to Pet. for Cert.
223a. He testified that in 2000, 35 percent of underrepresented
minority applicants were admitted. Ibid. Dr. Raudenbush
predicted that if race were not considered, only 10 percent of
those applicants would have been admitted. Ibid. Under
this scenario, underrepresented minority students would have
constituted 4 percent of the entering class in 2000 instead of the
actual figure of 14.5 percent. Ibid. [321] In the end, the District Court concluded that the Law School's
use of race as a factor in admissions decisions was unlawful.
Applying strict scrutiny, the District Court determined that the
Law School's asserted interest in assembling a diverse student body
was not compelling because "the attainment of a racially diverse
class . . . was not recognized as such by Bakke and it is not a remedy for past discrimination." Id. , at
246a. The District Court went on to hold that even if diversity
were compelling, the Law School had not narrowly tailored its use
of race to further that interest. The District Court granted
petitioner's request for declaratory relief and enjoined the Law
School from using race as a factor in its admissions decisions. The
Court of Appeals entered a stay of the injunction pending
appeal.
Sitting en banc, the Court of Appeals reversed the District
Court's judgment and vacated the injunction. The Court of Appeals
first held that Justice Powell's opinion in Bakke was
binding precedent establishing diversity as a compelling state
interest. According to the Court of Appeals, Justice Powell's
opinion with respect to diversity constituted the controlling
rationale for the judgment of this Court under the analysis set
forth in Marks v. United States , 430 U. S. 188 (1977). The
Court of Appeals also held that the Law School's use of race was
narrowly tailored because race was merely a "potential 'plus'
factor" and because the Law School's program was "virtually
identical" to the Harvard admissions program described approvingly
by Justice Powell and appended to his Bakke opinion. 288 F.3d 732 , 746, 749 (CA62002).
Four dissenting judges would have held the Law School's use of
race unconstitutional. Three of the dissenters, rejecting the
majority's Marks analysis, examined the Law School's
interest in student body diversity on the merits and concluded it
was not compelling. The fourth dissenter, writing separately, found
it unnecessary to decide whether diversity was a compelling
interest because, like the other dissent- [322] ers, he believed that the Law School's use of race was not
narrowly tailored to further that interest.
We granted certiorari, 537 U. S. 1043 (2002), to resolve the
disagreement among the Courts of Appeals on a question of national
importance: Whether diversity is a compelling interest that can
justify the narrowly tailored use of race in selecting applicants
for admission to public universities. Compare Hopwood v.
Texas , 78 F.3d 932 (CA5 1996) (Hopwood I) (holding
that diversity is not a compelling state interest), with Smith
v. University of Wash. Law School , 233 F.3d 1188 (CA9 2000)
(holding that it is).
II A
We last addressed the use of race in public higher education
over 25 years ago. In the landmark Bakke case, we reviewed
a racial set-aside program that reserved 16 out of 100 seats in a
medical school class for members of certain minority groups. 438 U. S. 265 (1978). The decision produced six separate opinions, none of which
commanded a majority of the Court. Four Justices would have upheld
the program against all attack on the ground that the government
can use race to "remedy disadvantages cast on minorities by past
racial prejudice." Id. , at 325 (joint opinion of Brennan,
White, Marshall, and Blackmun, JJ., concurring in judgment in part
and dissenting in part). Four other Justices avoided the
constitutional question altogether and struck down the program on
statutory grounds. Id. , at 408 (opinion of STEVENS, J.,
joined by Burger, C. J., and Stewart and REHNQUIST, JJ., concurring
in judgment in part and dissenting in part). Justice Powell
provided a fifth vote not only for invalidating the set-aside
program, but also for reversing the state court's injunction
against any use of race whatsoever. The only holding for the Court
in Bakke was that a "State has a substantial interest that
legitimately may be served by a properly devised admissions program
involv- [323] ing the competitive consideration of race and ethnic origin." Id. , at 320. Thus, we reversed that part of the lower
court's judgment that enjoined the university "from any
consideration of the race of any applicant." Ibid. Since this Court's splintered decision in Bakke ,
Justice Powell's opinion announcing the judgment of the Court has
served as the touchstone for constitutional analysis of
race-conscious admissions policies. Public and private universities
across the Nation have modeled their own admissions programs on
Justice Powell's views on permissible race-conscious policies. See, e.g. , Brief for Judith Areen et al. as Amici
Curiae 12-13 (law school admissions programs employ "methods
designed from and based on Justice Powell's opinion in Bakke"); Brief for Amherst College et al. as Amici
Curiae 27 ("After Bakke , each of the amici (and undoubtedly other selective colleges and universities as well)
reviewed their admissions procedures in light of Justice Powell's
opinion . . . and set sail accordingly"). We therefore
discuss Justice Powell's opinion in some detail.
Justice Powell began by stating that "[t]he guarantee of equal
protection cannot mean one thing when applied to one individual and
something else when applied to a person of another color. If both
are not accorded the same protection, then it is not equaL" Bakke , 438 U. S., at 289-290. In Justice Powell's view,
when governmental decisions "touch upon an individual's race or
ethnic background, he is entitled to a judicial determination that
the burden he is asked to bear on that basis is precisely tailored
to serve a compelling governmental interest." Id. , at 299.
Under this exacting standard, only one of the interests asserted by
the university survived Justice Powell's scrutiny.
First, Justice Powell rejected an interest in "'reducing the
historic deficit of traditionally disfavored minorities in medical
schools and in the medical profession'" as an unlawful interest in
racial balancing. Id. , at 306-307. Second, Justice Powell
rejected an interest in remedying societal dis- [324] crimination because such measures would risk placing unnecessary
burdens on innocent third parties "who bear no responsibility for
whatever harm the beneficiaries of the special admissions program
are thought to have suffered." Id. , at 310. Third, Justice
Powell rejected an interest in "increasing the number of physicians
who will practice in communities currently underserved," concluding
that even if such an interest could be compelling in some
circumstances the program under review was not "geared to promote
that goal." Id. , at 306, 310.
Justice Powell approved the university's use of race to further
only one interest: "the attainment of a diverse student body." Id. , at 311. With the important proviso that
"constitutional limitations protecting individual rights may not be
disregarded," Justice Powell grounded his analysis in the academic
freedom that "long has been viewed as a special concern of the
First Amendment." Id. , at 312, 314. Justice Powell
emphasized that nothing less than the "'nation's future depends
upon leaders trained through wide exposure' to the ideas and mores
of students as diverse as this Nation of many peoples." Id. , at 313 (quoting Keyishian v. Board of Regents of
Univ. of State of N. Y. , 385 U. S. 589 , 603
(1967)). In seeking the "right to select those students who will
contribute the most to the 'robust exchange of ideas,'" a
university seeks "to achieve a goal that is of paramount importance
in the fulfillment of its mission." 438 U. S., at 313. Both
"tradition and experience lend support to the view that the
contribution of diversity is substantial." Ibid. Justice Powell was, however, careful to emphasize that in his
view race "is only one element in a range of factors a university
properly may consider in attaining the goal of a heterogeneous
student body." Id. , at 314. For Justice Powell, "[i]t is
not an interest in simple ethnic diversity, in which a specified
percentage of the student body is in effect guaranteed to be
members of selected ethnic groups," that [325] can justify the use of race. Id. , at 315. Rather,
"[t]he diversity that furthers a compelling state interest
encompasses a far broader array of qualifications and
characteristics of which racial or ethnic origin is but a single
though important element." Ibid. In the wake of our fractured decision in Bakke , courts
have struggled to discern whether Justice Powell's diversity
rationale, set forth in part of the opinion joined by no other
Justice, is nonetheless binding precedent under Marks. In
that case, we explained that "[w]hen a fragmented Court decides a
case and no single rationale explaining the result enjoys the
assent of five Justices, the holding of the Court may be viewed as
that position taken by those Members who concurred in the judgments
on the narrowest grounds." 430 U. S., at 193 (internal quotation
marks and citation omitted). As the divergent opinions of the lower
courts demonstrate, however, "[t]his test is more easily stated
than applied to the various opinions supporting the result in [Bakke]." Nichols v. United States , 511 U. S. 738 , 745-746
(1994). Compare, e. g., Johnson v. Board of Regents of Univ. of
Ga., 263 F. 3d 1234 (CAll 2001) (Justice Powell's diversity
rationale was not the holding of the Court); Hopwood v. Texas,
236 F. 3d 256, 274-275 (CA5 2000) (Hopwood II) (same); Hopwood I , 78 F.3d 932 (CA5 1996)
(same), with Smith v. University of Wash. Law School , 233
F. 3d, at 1199 (Justice Powell's opinion, including the diversity
rationale, is controlling under Marks). We do not find it necessary to decide whether Justice Powell's
opinion is binding under Marks. It does not seem "useful
to pursue the Marks inquiry to the utmost logical
possibility when it has so obviously baffled and divided the lower
courts that have considered it." Nichols v. United States,
supra , at 745-746. More important, for the reasons set out
below, today we endorse Justice Powell's view that student body
diversity is a compelling state interest that can justify the use
of race in university admissions. [326] B
The Equal Protection Clause provides that no State shall "deny
to any person within its jurisdiction the equal protection of the
laws." U. S. Const., Amdt. 14, § 2. Because the Fourteenth
Amendment "protect[s] persons , not groups," all
"governmental action based on race-a group classification
long recognized as in most circumstances irrelevant and therefore
prohibited-should be subjected to detailed judicial inquiry to
ensure that the personal right to equal protection of the
laws has not been infringed." Adarand Constructors, Inc. v.
Peña , 515 U. S.
200 , 227 (1995) (emphasis in original; internal quotation marks
and citation omitted). We are a "free people whose institutions are
founded upon the doctrine of equality." Loving v.
Virginia , 388 U.
S. 1 , 11 (1967) (internal quotation marks and citation
omitted). It follows from that principle that "government may treat
people differently because of their race only for the most
compelling reasons." Adarand Constructors, Inc. v. Peña,
515 U. S., at 227.
We have held that all racial classifications imposed by
government "must be analyzed by a reviewing court under strict
scrutiny." Ibid. This means that such classifications are
constitutional only if they are narrowly tailored to further
compelling governmental interests. "Absent searching judicial
inquiry into the justification for such race-based measures," we
have no way to determine what "classifications are 'benign' or
'remedial' and what classifications are in fact motivated by
illegitimate notions of racial inferiority or simple racial
politics." Richmond v. J. A. Croson Co. , 488 U. S. 469 , 493 (1989)
(plurality opinion). We apply strict scrutiny to all racial
classifications to "'smoke out' illegitimate uses of race by
assuring that [government] is pursuing a goal important enough to
warrant use of a highly suspect tool." Ibid. Strict scrutiny is not "strict in theory, but fatal in
fact." Adarand Constructors, Inc. v. Peña, supra , at 237
(internal quotation marks and citation omitted). Although all
gov- [327] ernmental uses of race are subject to strict scrutiny, not all
are invalidated by it. As we have explained, "whenever the
government treats any person unequally because of his or her race,
that person has suffered an injury that falls squarely within the
language and spirit of the Constitution's guarantee of equal
protection." 515 U. S., at 229-230. But that observation "says
nothing about the ultimate validity of any particular law; that
determination is the job of the court applying strict scrutiny." Id. , at 230. When race-based action is necessary to
further a compelling governmental interest, such action does not
violate the constitutional guarantee of equal protection so long as
the narrow-tailoring requirement is also satisfied.
Context matters when reviewing race-based governmental action
under the Equal Protection Clause. See Gomillion v.
Lightfoot , 364
U. S. 339 , 343-344 (1960) (admonishing that, "in dealing with
claims under broad provisions of the Constitution, which derive
content by an interpretive process of inclusion and exclusion, it
is imperative that generalizations, based on and qualified by the
concrete situations that gave rise to them, must not be applied out
of context in disregard of variant controlling facts"). In Adarand Constructors , Inc. v. Peña , we made clear
that strict scrutiny must take " 'relevant differences' into
account." 515 U. S., at 228. Indeed, as we explained, that is its
"fundamental purpose." Ibid. Not every decision influenced
by race is equally objectionable, and strict scrutiny is designed
to provide a framework for carefully examining the importance and
the sincerity of the reasons advanced by the governmental
decisionmaker for the use of race in that particular context.
III
A
With these principles in mind, we turn to the question whether
the Law School's use of race is justified by a compelling state
interest. Before this Court, as they have [328] throughout this litigation, respondents assert only one
justification for their use of race in the admissions process:
obtaining "the educational benefits that flow from a diverse
student body." Brief for Respondent Bollinger et al. i. In other
words, the Law School asks us to recognize, in the context of
higher education, a compelling state interest in student body
diversity.
We first wish to dispel the notion that the Law School's
argument has been foreclosed, either expressly or implicitly, by
our affirmative-action cases decided since Bakke. It is
true that some language in those opinions might be read to suggest
that remedying past discrimination is the only permissible
justification for race-based governmental action. See, e. g.,
Richmond v. J. A. Croson Co., supra , at 493
(plurality opinion) (stating that unless classifications based on
race are "strictly reserved for remedial settings, they may in fact
promote notions of racial inferiority and lead to a politics of
racial hostility"). But we have never held that the only
governmental use of race that can survive strict scrutiny is
remedying past discrimination. Nor, since Bakke , have we
directly addressed the use of race in the context of public higher
education. Today, we hold that the Law School has a compelling
interest in attaining a diverse student body.
The Law School's educational judgment that such diversity is
essential to its educational mission is one to which we defer. The
Law School's assessment that diversity will, in fact, yield
educational benefits is substantiated by respondents and their amici. Our scrutiny of the interest asserted by the Law
School is no less strict for taking into account complex
educational judgments in an area that lies primarily within the
expertise of the university. Our holding today is in keeping with
our tradition of giving a degree of deference to a university's
academic decisions, within constitutionally prescribed limits. See Regents of Univ. of Mich. v. Ewing , 474 U. S. 214 , 225
(1985); Board of Curators of Univ. of Mo. [329] v. Horowitz , 435 U. S. 78 , 96, n. 6
(1978); Bakke , 438 U. S., at 319, n. 53 (opinion of
Powell, J.).
We have long recognized that, given the important purpose of
public education and the expansive freedoms of speech and thought
associated with the university environment, universities occupy a
special niche in our constitutional tradition. See, e. g.,
Wieman v. Updegraff , 344 U. S. 183 , 195 (1952)
(Frankfurter, J., concurring); Sweezy v. New Hampshire , 354 U. S. 234 ,
250 (1957); Shelton v. Tucker , 364 U. S. 479 , 487
(1960); Keyishian v. Board of Regents of Univ. of State of N. Y. , 385 U. S., at 603. In announcing the principle of
student body diversity as a compelling state interest, Justice
Powell invoked our cases recognizing a constitutional dimension,
grounded in the First Amendment, of educational autonomy: "The
freedom of a university to make its own judgments as to education
includes the selection of its student body." Bakke, supra ,
at 312. From this premise, Justice Powell reasoned that by claiming
"the right to select those students who will contribute the most to
the 'robust exchange of ideas,'" a university "seek[s] to achieve a
goal that is of paramount importance in the fulfillment of its
mission." 438 U. S., at 313 (quoting Keyishian v. Board of
Regents of Univ. of State of N. Y., supra , at 603).
Our conclusion that the Law School has a compelling interest in a
diverse student body is informed by our view that attaining a
diverse student body is at the heart of the Law School's proper
institutional mission, and that "good faith" on the part of a
university is "presumed" absent "a showing to the contrary." 438 U.
S., at 318-319.
As part of its goal of "assembling a class that is both
exceptionally academically qualified and broadly diverse," the Law
School seeks to "enroll a 'critical mass' of minority students."
Brief for Respondent Bollinger et al. 13. The Law School's interest
is not simply "to assure within its student body some specified
percentage of a particular group merely because of its race or
ethnic origin." Bakke , 438 U. S., at [330] 307 (opinion of Powell, J.). That would amount to outright
racial balancing, which is patently unconstitutional. Ibid.;
Freeman v. Pitts , 503 U. S. 467 , 494 (1992)
("Racial balance is not to be achieved for its own sake"); Richmond v. J. A. Croson Co. , 488 U. S., at 507.
Rather, the Law School's concept of critical mass is defined by
reference to the educational benefits that diversity is designed to
produce.
These benefits are substantial. As the District Court
emphasized, the Law School's admissions policy promotes
"cross-racial understanding," helps to break down racial
stereotypes, and "enables [students] to better understand persons
of different races." App. to Pet. for Cert. 246a. These benefits
are "important and laudable," because "classroom discussion is
livelier, more spirited, and simply more enlightening and
interesting" when the students have "the greatest possible variety
of backgrounds." Id. , at 246a, 244a.
The Law School's claim of a compelling interest is further
bolstered by its amici , who point to the educational
benefits that flow from student body diversity. In addition to the
expert studies and reports entered into evidence at trial, numerous
studies show that student body diversity promotes learning
outcomes, and "better prepares students for an increasingly diverse
workforce and society, and better prepares them as professionals."
Brief for American Educational Research Association et al. as Amici Curiae 3; see, e.g. , W. Bowen & D. Bok,
The Shape of the River (1998); Diversity Challenged: Evidence on
the Impact of Affirmative Action (G. Orfield & M. Kurlaender
eds. 2001); Compelling Interest: Examining the Evidence on Racial
Dynamics in Colleges and Universities (M. Chang, D. Witt, J. Jones,
& K. Hakuta eds. 2003).
These benefits are not theoretical but real, as major American
businesses have made clear that the skills needed in to day's
increasingly global marketplace can only be developed through
exposure to widely diverse people, cultures, ideas, and viewpoints.
Brief for 3M et al. as Amici Curiae [331] 5; Brief for General Motors Corp. as Amicus Curiae 3-4. What is more, high-ranking retired officers and civilian leaders of
the United States military assert that, "[b]ased on [their] decades
of experience," a "highly qualified, racially diverse officer corps
. . . is essential to the military's ability to fulfill
its principle mission to provide national security." Brief for
Julius W. Becton, Jr., et al. as Amici Curiae 5. The
primary sources for the Nation's officer corps are the service
academies and the Reserve Officers Training Corps (ROTC), the
latter comprising students already admitted to participating
colleges and universities. Ibid. At present, "the military
cannot achieve an officer corps that is both highly
qualified and racially diverse unless the service
academies and the ROTC used limited race-conscious recruiting and
admissions policies." Ibid. (emphasis in original). To
fulfill its mission, the military "must be selective in admissions
for training and education for the officer corps, and it
must train and educate a highly qualified, racially diverse officer
corps in a racially diverse educational setting." Id. , at
29 (emphasis in original). We agree that "[i]t requires only a
small step from this analysis to conclude that our country's other
most selective institutions must remain both diverse and
selective." Ibid. We have repeatedly acknowledged the overriding importance of
preparing students for work and citizenship, describing education
as pivotal to "sustaining our political and cultural heritage" with
a fundamental role in maintaining the fabric of society. Plyler
v. Doe , 457 U.
S. 202 , 221 (1982). This Court has long recognized that
"education . . . is the very foundation of good
citizenship." Brown v. Board of Education , 347 U. S. 483 , 493
(1954). For this reason, the diffusion of knowledge and opportunity
through public institutions of higher education must be accessible
to all individuals regardless of race or ethnicity. The United
States, as amicus curiae , affirms that "[e]nsuring that
public institutions are open and available to all segments of
American [332] society, including people of all races and ethnicities,
represents a paramount government objective." Brief for United
States as Amicus Curiae 13. And, "[n]owhere is the
importance of such openness more acute than in the context of
higher education." Ibid. Effective participation by
members of all racial and ethnic groups in the civic life of our
Nation is essential if the dream of one Nation, indivisible, is to
be realized.
Moreover, universities, and in particular, law schools,
represent the training ground for a large number of our N ation's
leaders. Sweatt v. Painter , 339 U. S. 629 , 634 (1950)
(describing law school as a "proving ground for legal learning and
practice"). Individuals with law degrees occupy roughly half the
state governorships, more than half the seats in the United States
Senate, and more than a third of the seats in the United States
House of Representatives. See Brief for Association of American Law
Schools as Amicus Curiae 5-6. The pattern is even more
striking when it comes to highly selective law schools. A handful
of these schools accounts for 25 of the 100 United States Senators,
74 United States Courts of Appeals judges, and nearly 200 of the
more than 600 United States District Court judges. Id. , at
6.
In order to cultivate a set of leaders with legitimacy in the
eyes of the citizenry, it is necessary that the path to leadership
be visibly open to talented and qualified individuals of every race
and ethnicity. All members of our heterogeneous society must have
confidence in the openness and integrity of the educational
institutions that provide this training. As we have recognized, law
schools "cannot be effective in isolation from the individuals and
institutions with which the law interacts." See Sweatt v.
Painter, supra , at 634. Access to legal education (and thus
the legal profession) must be inclusive of talented and qualified
individuals of every race and ethnicity, so that all members of our
heterogeneous society [333] may participate in the educational institutions that provide the
training and education necessary to succeed in America.
The Law School does not premise its need for critical mass on
"any belief that minority students always (or even consistently)
express some characteristic minority viewpoint on any issue." Brief
for Respondent Bollinger et al. 30. To the contrary, diminishing
the force of such stereotypes is both a crucial part of the Law
School's mission, and one that it cannot accomplish with only token
numbers of minority students. Just as growing up in a particular
region or having particular professional experiences is likely to
affect an individual's views, so too is one's own, unique
experience of being a racial minority in a society, like our own,
in which race unfortunately still matters. The Law School has
determined, based on its experience and expertise, that a "critical
mass" of underrepresented minorities is necessary to further its
compelling interest in securing the educational benefits of a
diverse student body.
B
Even in the limited circumstance when drawing racial
distinctions is permissible to further a compelling state interest,
government is still "constrained in how it may pursue that end:
[T]he means chosen to accomplish the [government's] asserted
purpose must be specifically and narrowly framed to accomplish that
purpose." Shaw v. Hunt , 517 U. S. 899 , 908 (1996)
(internal quotation marks and citation omitted). The purpose of the
narrow tailoring requirement is to ensure that "the means chosen
'fit' thee] compelling goal so closely that there is little or no
possibility that the motive for the classification was illegitimate
racial prejudice or stereotype." Richmond v. J. A.
Croson Co. , 488 U. S., at 493 (plurality opinion).
Since Bakke , we have had no occasion to define the
contours of the narrow-tailoring inquiry with respect to
race-conscious university admissions programs. That inquiry [334] must be calibrated to fit the distinct issues raised by the use
of race to achieve student body diversity in public higher
education. Contrary to JUSTICE KENNEDY'S assertions, we do not
"abando[n] strict scrutiny," see post , at 394 (dissenting
opinion). Rather, as we have already explained, supra , at
327, we adhere to Adarand's teaching that the very purpose
of strict scrutiny is to take such "relevant differences into
account." 515 U. S., at 228 (internal quotation marks omitted).
To be narrowly tailored, a race-conscious admissions program
cannot use a quota system-it cannot "insulat[e] each category of
applicants with certain desired qualifications from competition
with all other applicants." Bakke, 438 U. S., at 315
(opinion of Powell, J.). Instead, a university may consider race or
ethnicity only as a " 'plus' in a particular applicant's file,"
without "insulat[ing] the individual from comparison with all other
candidates for the available seats." Id. , at 317. In other
words, an admissions program must be "flexible enough to consider
all pertinent elements of diversity in light of the particular
qualifications of each applicant, and to place them on the same
footing for consideration, although not necessarily according them
the same weight." Ibid. We find that the Law School's admissions program bears the
hallmarks of a narrowly tailored plan. As Justice Powell made clear
in Bakke , truly individualized consideration demands that
race be used in a flexible, nonmechanical way. It follows from this
mandate that universities cannot establish quotas for members of
certain racial groups or put members of those groups on separate
admissions tracks. See id. , at 315-316. Nor can
universities insulate applicants who belong to certain racial or
ethnic groups from the competition for admission. Ibid. Universities can, however, consider race or ethnicity more flexibly
as a "plus" factor in the context of individualized consideration
of each and every applicant. Ibid. [335] We are satisfied that the Law School's admissions program, like
the Harvard plan described by Justice Powell, does not operate as a
quota. Properly understood, a "quota" is a program in which a
certain fixed number or proportion of opportunities are "reserved
exclusively for certain minority groups." Richmond v. J. A. Croson Co., supra , at 496 (plurality opinion). Quotas"
'impose a fixed number or percentage which must be attained, or
which cannot be exceeded,'" Sheet Metal Workers v. EEOC , 478 U. S. 421 ,
495 (1986) (O'CONNOR, J., concurring in part and dissenting in
part), and "insulate the individual from comparison with all other
candidates for the available seats," Bakke, supra , at 317
(opinion of Powell, J.). In contrast, "a permissible goal
. . . require[s] only a good-faith effort . . .
to come within a range demarcated by the goal itself," Sheet
Metal Workers v. EEOC, supra , at 495, and permits
consideration of race as a "plus" factor in any given case while
still ensuring that each candidate "compete[s] with all other
qualified applicants," Johnson v. Transportation Agency, Santa
Clara Cty., 480 U. S. 616, 638 (1987).
Justice Powell's distinction between the medical school's rigid
16-seat quota and Harvard's flexible use of race as a "plus" factor
is instructive. Harvard certainly had minimum goals for
minority enrollment, even if it had no specific number firmly in
mind. See Bakke, supra , at 323 (opinion of Powell, J.)
("10 or 20 black students could not begin to bring to their
classmates and to each other the variety of points of view,
backgrounds and experiences of blacks in the United States"). What
is more, Justice Powell flatly rejected the argument that Harvard's
program was "the functional equivalent of a quota" merely because
it had some " 'plus'" for race, or gave greater "weight" to race
than to some other factors, in order to achieve student body
diversity. 438 U. S., at 317-318.
The Law School's goal of attaining a critical mass of
underrepresented minority students does not transform its pro- [336] gram into a quota. As the Harvard plan described by Justice
Powell recognized, there is of course "some relationship between
numbers and achieving the benefits to be derived from a diverse
student body, and between numbers and providing a reasonable
environment for those students admitted." Id. , at 323.
"[S]ome attention to numbers," without more, does not transform a
flexible admissions system into a rigid quota. Ibid. Nor,
as JUSTICE KENNEDY posits, does the Law School's consultation of
the "daily reports," which keep track of the racial and ethnic
composition of the class (as well as of residency and gender),
"sugges[t] there was no further attempt at individual review save
for race itself" during the final stages of the admissions process.
See post , at 392 (dissenting opinion). To the contrary,
the Law School's admissions officers testified without
contradiction that they never gave race any more or less weight
based on the information contained in these reports. Brief for
Respondent Bollinger et al. 43, n. 70 (citing App. in Nos. 01-1447
and 01-1516 (CA6), p. 7336). Moreover, as JUSTICE KENNEDY concedes,
see post , at 390, between 1993 and 1998, the number of
African-American, Latino, and Native-American students in each
class at the Law School varied from 13.5 to 20.1 percent, a range
inconsistent with a quota.
THE CHIEF JUSTICE believes that the Law School's policy conceals
an attempt to achieve racial balancing, and cites admissions data
to contend that the Law School discriminates among different groups
within the critical mass. Post , at 380-386 (dissenting
opinion). But, as THE CHIEF JUSTICE concedes, the number of
underrepresented minority students who ultimately enroll in the Law
School differs substantially from their representation in the
applicant pool and varies considerably for each group from year to
year. See post , at 385 (dissenting opinion).
That a race-conscious admissions program does not operate as a
quota does not, by itself, satisfy the requirement of
individualized consideration. When using race as a "plus" [337] factor in university admissions, a university's admissions
program must remain flexible enough to ensure that each applicant
is evaluated as an individual and not in a way that makes an
applicant's race or ethnicity the defining feature of his or her
application. The importance of this individualized consideration in
the context of a race-conscious admissions program is paramount.
See Bakke , 438 U. S., at 318, n. 52 (opinion of Powell,
J.) (identifying the "denial . . . of th[e] right to
individualized consideration" as the "principal evil" of the
medical school's admissions program).
Here, the Law School engages in a highly individualized,
holistic review of each applicant's file, giving serious
consideration to all the ways an applicant might contribute to a
diverse educational environment. The Law School affords this
individualized consideration to applicants of all races. There is
no policy, either de jure or de facto , of
automatic acceptance or rejection based on any single "soft"
variable. Unlike the program at issue in Gratz v. Bollinger,
ante , p. 244, the Law School awards no mechanical,
predetermined diversity "bonuses" based on race or ethnicity. See ante , at 271-272 (distinguishing a race-conscious
admissions program that automatically awards 20 points based on
race from the Harvard plan, which considered race but "did not
contemplate that any single characteristic automatically ensured a
specific and identifiable contribution to a university's
diversity"). Like the Harvard plan, the Law School's admissions
policy "is flexible enough to consider all pertinent elements of
diversity in light of the particular qualifications of each
applicant, and to place them on the same footing for consideration,
although not necessarily according them the same weight." Bakke, supra , at 317 (opinion of Powell, J.).
We also find that, like the Harvard plan Justice Powell
referenced in Bakke , the Law School's race-conscious
admissions program adequately ensures that all factors that may
contribute to student body diversity are meaningfully considered
alongside race in admissions decisions. With re- [338] spect to the use of race itself, all underrepresented minority
students admitted by the Law School have been deemed qualified. By
virtue of our Nation's struggle with racial inequality, such
students are both likely to have experiences of particular
importance to the Law School's mission, and less likely to be
admitted in meaningful numbers on criteria that ignore those
experiences. See App. 120.
The Law School does not, however, limit in any way the broad
range of qualities and experiences that may be considered valuable
contributions to student body diversity. To the contrary, the 1992
policy makes clear "[t]here are many possible bases for diversity
admissions," and provides examples of admittees who have lived or
traveled widely abroad, are fluent in several languages, have
overcome personal adversity and family hardship, have exceptional
records of extensive community service, and have had successful
careers in other fields. Id. , at 118-119. The Law School
seriously considers each "applicant's promise of making a notable
contribution to the class by way of a particular strength,
attainment, or characteristic-e. g., an unusual intellectual
achievement, employment experience, nonacademic performance, or
personal background." Id. , at 83-84. All applicants have
the opportunity to highlight their own potential diversity
contributions through the submission of a personal statement,
letters of recommendation, and an essay describing the ways in
which the applicant will contribute to the life and diversity of
the Law School.
What is more, the Law School actually gives substantial weight
to diversity factors besides race. The Law School frequently
accepts nonminority applicants with grades and test scores lower
than underrepresented minority applicants (and other nonminority
applicants) who are rejected. See Brief for Respondent Bollinger et
al. 10; App. 121-122. This shows that the Law School seriously
weighs many other diversity factors besides race that can make a
real and dispositive difference for nonminority applicants as well.
By this [339] flexible approach, the Law School sufficiently takes into
account, in practice as well as in theory, a wide variety of
characteristics besides race and ethnicity that contribute to a
diverse student body. JUSTICE KENNEDY speculates that "race is
likely outcome determinative for many members of minority groups"
who do not fall within the upper range of LSAT scores and grades. Post , at 389 (dissenting opinion). But the same could be
said of the Harvard plan discussed approvingly by Justice Powell in Bakke , and indeed of any plan that uses race as one of
many factors. See 438 U. S., at 316 (" 'When the Committee on
Admissions reviews the large middle group of applicants who are
"admissible" and deemed capable of doing good work in their
courses, the race of an applicant may tip the balance in his favor'
").
Petitioner and the United States argue that the Law School's
plan is not narrowly tailored because race-neutral means exist to
obtain the educational benefits of student body diversity that the
Law School seeks. We disagree. N arrow tailoring does not require
exhaustion of every conceivable race-neutral alternative. Nor does
it require a university to choose between maintaining a reputation
for excellence or fulfilling a commitment to provide educational
opportunities to members of all racial groups. See Wygant v.
Jackson Bd. of Ed. , 476 U. S. 267 , 280, n. 6
(1986) (alternatives must serve the interest" 'about as well' "); Richmond v. J. A. Croson Co. , 488 U. S., at
509-510 (plurality opinion) (city had a "whole array of
race-neutral" alternatives because changing requirements "would
have [had] little detrimental effect on the city's interests").
Narrow tailoring does, however, require serious, good faith
consideration of workable race-neutral alternatives that will
achieve the diversity the university seeks. See id. , at
507 (set-aside plan not narrowly tailored where "there does not
appear to have been any consideration of the use of race-neutral
means"); Wygant v. Jackson Bd. of Ed., supra , at 280, n. 6
(narrow tailoring [340] "require[s] consideration" of "lawful alternative and less
restrictive means").
We agree with the Court of Appeals that the Law School
sufficiently considered workable race-neutral alternatives. The
District Court took the Law School to task for failing to consider
race-neutral alternatives such as "using a lottery system" or
"decreasing the emphasis for all applicants on undergraduate GPA
and LSAT scores." App. to Pet. for Cert. 251a. But these
alternatives would require a dramatic sacrifice of diversity, the
academic quality of all admitted students, or both.
The Law School's current admissions program considers race as
one factor among many, in an effort to assemble a student body that
is diverse in ways broader than race. Because a lottery would make
that kind of nuanced judgment impossible, it would effectively
sacrifice all other educational values, not to mention every other
kind of diversity. So too with the suggestion that the Law School
simply lower admissions standards for all students, a drastic
remedy that would require the Law School to become a much different
institution and sacrifice a vital component of its educational
mission. The United States advocates "percentage plans," recently
adopted by public undergraduate institutions in Texas, Florida, and
California, to guarantee admission to all students above a certain
class-rank threshold in every high school in the State. Brief for
United States as Amicus Cu riae 14-18. The United States
does not, however, explain how such plans could work for graduate
and professional schools. Moreover, even assuming such plans are
raceneutral, they may preclude the university from conducting the
individualized assessments necessary to assemble a student body
that is not just racially diverse, but diverse along all the
qualities valued by the university. We are satisfied that the Law
School adequately considered race-neutral alternatives currently
capable of producing a critical mass without forcing the Law School
to abandon the academic selectivity that is the cornerstone of its
educational mission. [341] We acknowledge that "there are serious problems of justice
connected with the idea of preference itself." Bakke , 438
U. S., at 298 (opinion of Powell, J.). Narrow tailoring, therefore,
requires that a race-conscious admissions program not unduly harm
members of any racial group. Even remedial race-based governmental
action generally "remains subject to continuing oversight to assure
that it will work the least harm possible to other innocent persons
competing for the benefit." Id. , at 308. To be narrowly
tailored, a race-conscious admissions program must not "unduly
burden individuals who are not members of the favored racial and
ethnic groups." Metro Broadcasting, Inc. v. FCC , 497 U. S. 547 , 630 (1990)
(O'CONNOR, J., dissenting).
We are satisfied that the Law School's admissions program does
not. Because the Law School considers "all pertinent elements of
diversity," it can (and does) select nonminority applicants who
have greater potential to enhance student body diversity over
underrepresented minority applicants. See Bakke, supra , at
317 (opinion of Powell, J.). As Justice Powell recognized in Bakke , so long as a race-conscious admissions program uses
race as a "plus" factor in the context of individualized
consideration, a rejected applicant "will not have been foreclosed from all consideration for that
seat simply because he was not the right color or had the wrong
surname . . . . His qualifications would have been
weighed fairly and competitively, and he would have no basis to
complain of unequal treatment under the Fourteenth Amendment." 438
U. S., at 318. We agree that, in the context of its individualized inquiry into
the possible diversity contributions of all applicants, the Law
School's race-conscious admissions program does not unduly harm
nonminority applicants.
We are mindful, however, that "[a] core purpose of the
Fourteenth Amendment was to do away with all governmentally imposed
discrimination based on race." Palmore v. Si- [342] doti , 466
U. S. 429 , 432 (1984). Accordingly, race-conscious admissions
policies must be limited in time. This requirement reflects that
racial classifications, however compelling their goals, are
potentially so dangerous that they may be employed no more broadly
than the interest demands. Enshrining a permanent justification for
racial preferences would offend this fundamental equal protection
principle. We see no reason to exempt race-conscious admissions
programs from the requirement that all governmental use of race
must have a logical end point. The Law School, too, concedes that
all "race-conscious programs must have reasonable
durationallimits." Brief for Respondent Bollinger et al. 32.
In the context of higher education, the durational requirement
can be met by sunset provisions in race-conscious admissions
policies and periodic reviews to determine whether racial
preferences are still necessary to achieve student body diversity.
Universities in California, Florida, and Washington State, where
racial preferences in admissions are prohibited by state law, are
currently engaged in experimenting with a wide variety of
alternative approaches. Universities in other States can and should
draw on the most promising aspects of these race-neutral
alternatives as they develop. Cf. United States v. Lopez , 514 U. S. 549 ,
581 (1995) (KENNEDY, J., concurring) ("[T]he States may perform
their role as laboratories for experimentation to devise various
solutions where the best solution is far from clear").
The requirement that all race-conscious admissions programs have
a termination point "assure[s] all citizens that the deviation from
the norm of equal treatment of all racial and ethnic groups is a
temporary matter, a measure taken in the service of the goal of
equality itself." Richmond v. J. A. Croson Co. ,
488 U. S., at 510 (plurality opinion); see also Nathanson &
Bartnik, The Constitutionality of Preferential Treatment for
Minority Applicants to Professional Schools, [343] 58 Chicago Bar Rec. 282, 293 (May-June 1977) ("It would be a sad
day indeed, were America to become a quota-ridden society, with
each identifiable minority assigned proportional representation in
every desirable walk of life. But that is not the rationale for
programs of preferential treatment; the acid test of their
justification will be their efficacy in eliminating the need for
any racial or ethnic preferences at all").
We take the Law School at its word that it would "like nothing
better than to find a race-neutral admissions formula" and will
terminate its race-conscious admissions program as soon as
practicable. See Brief for Respondent Bollinger et al. 34; Bakke, supra , at 317-318 (opinion of Powell, J.)
(presuming good faith of university officials in the absence of a
showing to the contrary). It has been 25 years since Justice Powell
first approved the use of race to further an interest in student
body diversity in the context of public higher education. Since
that time, the number of minority applicants with high grades and
test scores has indeed increased. See Tr. of Oral Arg. 43. We
expect that 25 years from now, the use of racial preferences will
no longer be necessary to further the interest approved today.
IV
In summary, the Equal Protection Clause does not prohibit the
Law School's narrowly tailored use of race in admissions decisions
to further a compelling interest in obtaining the educational
benefits that flow from a diverse student body. Consequently,
petitioner's statutory claims based on Title VI and 42 U. S. C. §
1981 also fail. See Bakke, supra , at 287 (opinion of
Powell, J.) ("Title VI . . . proscribe[s] only those
racial classifications that would violate the Equal Protection
Clause or the Fifth Amendment"); General Building Contractors
Assn., Inc. v. Pennsylvania , 458 U. S. 375 , 389-391
(1982) (the prohibition against discrimination in § 1981 is
coextensive with the Equal Protection Clause). The judgment [344] of the Court of Appeals for the Sixth Circuit, accordingly, is
affirmed.
It is so ordered.
JUSTICE GINSBURG, with whom JUSTICE BREYER joins,
concurring.
The Court's observation that race-conscious programs "must have
a logical end point," ante , at 342, accords with the
international understanding of the office of affirmative action.
The International Convention on the Elimination of All Forms of
Racial Discrimination, ratified by the United States in 1994, see
State Dept., Treaties in Force 422-423 (June 1996), endorses
"special and concrete measures to ensure the adequate development
and protection of certain racial groups or individuals belonging to
them, for the purpose of guaranteeing them the full and equal
enjoyment of human rights and fundamental freedoms." Annex to G. A.
Res. 2106, 20 U. N. GAOR, 20th Sess., Res. Supp. (No. 14), p. 47,
U. N. Doc. A/6014, Art. 2(2) (1965). But such measures, the
Convention instructs, "shall in no case entail as a consequence the
maintenance of unequal or separate rights for different racial
groups after the objectives for which they were taken have been
achieved." Ibid.; see also Art. 1(4) (similarly providing
for temporally limited affirmative action); Convention on the
Elimination of All Forms of Discrimination against Women, Annex to
G. A. Res. 34/180, 34 U. N. GAOR, 34th Sess., Res. Supp. (No. 46),
p. 194, U. N. Doc. A/34/46, Art. 4(1) (1979) (authorizing
"temporary special measures aimed at accelerating de facto equality" that "shall be discontinued when the objectives of
equality of opportunity and treatment have been achieved").
The Court further observes that "[i]t has been 25 years since
Justice Powell [in Regents of Univ. of Cal. v. Bakke , 438 U. S. 265 (1978)] first approved the use of race to further an interest in
student body diversity in the context of public higher education." Ante , at 343. For at least part of that [345] time, however, the law could not fairly be described as
"settled," and in some regions of the Nation, overtly
race-conscious admissions policies have been proscribed. See Hopwood v. Texas , 78 F.3d 932 (CA5 1996); cf. Wessmann v. Gittens , 160 F.3d 790 (CA1 1998); Tuttle v. Arlington Cty. School Bd. , 195 F.3d 698 (CA4 1999); Johnson v. Board of Regents of Univ. of
Ga. , 263 F.3d 1234 (CAll 2001). Moreover, it was only 25 years
before Bakke that this Court declared public school
segregation unconstitutional, a declaration that, after prolonged
resistance, yielded an end to a law-enforced racial caste system,
itself the legacy of centuries of slavery. See Brown v. Board
of Education , 347 U. S. 483 (1954); cf. Cooper v. Aaron , 358 U. S. 1 (1958).
It is well documented that conscious and unconscious race bias,
even rank discrimination based on race, remain alive in our land,
impeding realization of our highest values and ideals. See, e.
g., Gratz v. Bollinger, ante , at 298-301 (GINSBURG, J.,
dissenting); Adarand Constructors, Inc. v. Peña , 515 U. S. 200 , 272-274
(1995) (GINSBURG, J., dissenting); Krieger, Civil Rights
Perestroika: Intergroup Relations after Affirmative Action, 86
Calif. L. Rev. 1251, 1276-1291, 1303 (1998). As to public
education, data for the years 20002001 show that 71.6% of
African-American children and 76.3% of Hispanic children attended a
school in which minorities made up a majority of the student body.
See E. Frankenberg, C. Lee, & G. Orfield, A Multiracial Society
with Segregated Schools: Are We Losing the Dream? p. 4 (Jan. 2003),
http://www.civilrightsproject.harvard.edu/research/reseg03/AreWeLosingtheDream.pdf
(as visited June 16, 2003, and available in Clerk of Court's case
file). And schools in predominantly minority communities lag far
behind others measured by the educational resources available to
them. See id. , at 11; Brief for National Urban League et
al. as Amici Curiae 11-12 (citing General Accounting
Office, PerPupil Spending Differences Between Selected Inner City
and Suburban Schools Varied by Metropolitan Area 17 (2002)). [346] However strong the public's desire for improved education
systems may be, see P. Hart & R. Teeter, A National Priority:
Americans Speak on Teacher Quality 2, 11 (2002) (public opinion
research conducted for Educational Testing Service); No Child Left
Behind Act of 2001, Pub. L. 107-110, 115 Stat. 1806, 20 U. S. C. §
7231 (2000 ed., Supp. I), it remains the current reality that many
minority students encounter markedly inadequate and unequal
educational opportunities. Despite these inequalities, some
minority students are able to meet the high threshold requirements
set for admission to the country's finest undergraduate and
graduate educational institutions. As lower school education in
minority communities improves, an increase in the number of such
students may be anticipated. From to day's vantage point, one may
hope, but not firmly forecast, that over the next generation's
span, progress toward nondiscrimination and genuinely equal
opportunity will make it safe to sunset affirmative
action.[ Footnote * ]
JUSTICE SCALIA, with whom JUSTICE THOMAS joins, concurring in
part and dissenting in part.
I join the opinion of THE CHIEF JUSTICE. As he demonstrates, the
University of Michigan Law School's mystical [347] "critical mass" justification for its discrimination by race
challenges even the most gullible mind. The admissions statistics
show it to be a sham to cover a scheme of racially proportionate
admissions.
I also join Parts I through VII of JUSTICE THOMAS'S
opinion.[ Footnote * ] I find particularly
unanswerable his central point: that the allegedly "compelling
state interest" at issue here is not the incremental "educational
benefit" that emanates from the fabled "critical mass" of minority
students, but rather Michigan's interest in maintaining a
"prestige" law school whose normal admissions standards
disproportionately exclude blacks and other minorities. If that is
a compelling state interest, everything is.
I add the following: The "educational benefit" that the
University of Michigan seeks to achieve by racial discrimination
consists, according to the Court, of" 'cross-racial
understanding,'" ante , at 330, and" 'better prepar[ation
of] students for an increasingly diverse workforce and society,'"
ibid., all of which is necessary not only for work, but also for
good "citizenship," ante , at 331. This is not, of course,
an "educational benefit" on which students will be graded on their
law school transcript (Works and Plays Well with Others: B+) or
tested by the bar examiners (Q: Describe in 500 words or less your
cross-racial understanding). For it is a lesson of life rather than
law-essentially the same lesson taught to (or rather learned by,
for it cannot be "taught" in the usual sense) people three feet
shorter and 20 years younger than the fullgrown adults at the
University of Michigan Law School, in institutions ranging from Boy
Scout troops to public-school kindergartens. If properly considered
an "educational benefit" at all, it is surely not one that is
either uniquely relevant to law school or uniquely "teachable" in a
formal educational setting. And therefore: If it is
appropriate for the Univer- [348] sity of Michigan Law School to use racial discrimination for the
purpose of putting together a "critical mass" that will convey
generic lessons in socialization and good citizenship, surely it is
no less appropriate-indeed, particularly appropriate-for
the civil service system of the State of Michigan to do so. There,
also, those exposed to "critical masses" of certain races will
presumably become better Americans, better Michiganders, better
civil servants. And surely private employers cannot be
criticized--indeed, should be praised--if they also "teach" good
citizenship to their adult employees through a patriotic,
all-American system of racial discrimination in hiring. The
nonminority individuals who are deprived of a legal education, a
civil service job, or any job at all by reason of their skin color
will surely understand.
Unlike a clear constitutional holding that racial preferences in
state educational institutions are impermissible, or even a clear
anticonstitutional holding that racial preferences in state
educational institutions are OK, today's Grutter-Gratz split double header seems perversely designed to prolong the
controversy and the litigation. Some future lawsuits will
presumably focus on whether the discriminatory scheme in question
contains enough evaluation of the applicant "as an individual," ante , at 337, and sufficiently avoids "separate admissions
tracks," ante , at 334, to fall under Grutter rather than Gratz. Some will focus on whether a university
has gone beyond the bounds of a "'good-faith effort'" and has so
zealously pursued its "critical mass" as to make it an
unconstitutional de facto quota system, rather than merely
"'a permissible goal.' " Ante , at 335 (quoting Sheet
Metal Workers v. EEOC , 478 U. S. 421 , 495 (1986)
(O'CONNOR, J., concurring in part and dissenting in part)). Other
lawsuits may focus on whether, in the particular setting at issue,
any educational benefits flow from racial diversity. (That issue
was not contested in Grutter; and while the opinion
accords "a degree of deference to a university's academic
decisions," ante , at 328, "deference does not imply [349] abandonment or abdication of judicial review," Miller-El v.
Cockrell , 537 U.
S. 322 , 340 (2003).) Still other suits may challenge the bona
fides of the institution's expressed commitment to the educational
benefits of diversity that immunize the discriminatory scheme in Grutter. (Tempting targets, one would suppose, will be
those universities that talk the talk of multiculturalism and
racial diversity in the courts but walk the walk of tribalism and
racial segregation on their campuses-through minority-only student
organizations, separate minority housing opportunities, separate
minority student centers, even separate minority-only graduation
ceremonies.) And still other suits may claim that the institution's
racial preferences have gone below or above the mystical
Grutter-approved "critical mass." Finally, litigation can be
expected on behalf of minority groups intentionally short changed
in the institution's composition of its generic minority "critical
mass." I do not look forward to any of these cases. The
Constitution proscribes government discrimination on the basis of
race, and state-provided education is no exception.
JUSTICE THOMAS, with whom JUSTICE SCALIA joins as to Parts
I-VII, concurring in part and dissenting in part.
Frederick Douglass, speaking to a group of abolitionists almost
140 years ago, delivered a message lost on to day's majority: "[I]n regard to the colored people, there is always more that is
benevolent, I perceive, than just, manifested towards us. What I
ask for the negro is not benevolence, not pity, not sympathy, but
simply justice. The American people have always been
anxious to know what they shall do with us . . . . I
have had but one answer from the beginning. Do nothing with us!
Your doing with us has already played the mischief with us. Do
nothing with us! If the apples will not remain on the tree of [350] their own strength, if they are worm-eaten at the core, if they
are early ripe and disposed to fall, let them fall! . . .
And if the negro cannot stand on his own legs, let him fall also.
All I ask is, give him a chance to stand on his own legs! Let him
alone! . . . [Y]our interference is doing him positive
injury." What the Black Man Wants: An Address Delivered in Boston,
Massachusetts, on 26 January 1865, reprinted in 4 The Frederick
Douglass Papers 59, 68 (J. Blassingame & J. McKivigan eds.
1991) (emphasis in original). Like Douglass, I believe blacks can achieve in every avenue of
American life without the meddling of university administrators.
Because I wish to see all students succeed whatever their color, I
share, in some respect, the sympathies of those who sponsor the
type of discrimination advanced by the University of Michigan Law
School (Law School). The Constitution does not, however, tolerate
institutional devotion to the status quo in admissions policies
when such devotion ripens into racial discrimination. Nor does the
Constitution countenance the unprecedented deference the Court
gives to the Law School, an approach inconsistent with the very
concept of "strict scrutiny."
No one would argue that a university could set up a lower
general admissions standard and then impose heightened requirements
only on black applicants. Similarly, a university may not maintain
a high admissions standard and grant exemptions to favored races.
The Law School, of its own choosing, and for its own purposes,
maintains an exclusionary admissions system that it knows produces
racially disproportionate results. Racial discrimination is not a
permissible solution to the self-inflicted wounds of this elitist
admissions policy.
The majority upholds the Law School's racial discrimination not
by interpreting the people's Constitution, but by responding to a
faddish slogan of the cognoscenti. Nevertheless, I concur in part
in the Court's opinion. First, I agree with the Court insofar as
its decision, which approves of only [351] one racial classification, confirms that further use of race in
admissions remains unlawful. Second, I agree with the Court's
holding that racial discrimination in higher education admissions
will be illegal in 25 years. See ante , at 343 (stating
that racial discrimination will no longer be narrowly tailored, or
"necessary to further" a compelling state interest, in 25 years). I
respectfully dissent from the remainder of the Court's opinion and
the judgment, however, because I believe that the Law School's
current use of race violates the Equal Protection Clause and that
the Constitution means the same thing today as it will in 300
months.
I
The majority agrees that the Law School's racial discrimination
should be subjected to strict scrutiny. Ante , at 326.
Before applying that standard to this case, I will briefly revisit
the Court's treatment of racial classifications.
The strict scrutiny standard that the Court purports to apply in
this case was first enunciated in Korematsu v. United
States , 323 U.
S. 214 (1944). There the Court held that "[p]ressing public
necessity may sometimes justify the existence of [racial
discrimination]; racial antagonism never can." Id. , at
216. This standard of "pressing public necessity" has more
frequently been termed "compelling governmental interest,"[ Footnote 1 ] see, e. g., Regents of Univ. of Cal. v.
Bakke , 438 U. S.
265 , 299 (1978) (opinion of Powell, J.). A majority of the
Court has validated only two circumstances where "pressing public
necessity" or a "compelling state interest" can possibly justify
racial discrimination by state actors. First, the lesson of Korematsu is that national security constitutes a
"pressing public necessity," though the government's use of race to
advance that objective must be narrowly tailored. Second, the Court
has recognized as a compelling state interest a government's effort
to remedy [352] past discrimination for which it is responsible. Richmond The contours of "pressing public necessity" can be further
discerned from those interests the Court has rejected as bases for
racial discrimination. For example, Wygant v. Jackson Bd. of
Ed. , 476 U. S.
267 (1986), found unconstitutional a collective-bargaining
agreement between a school board and a teachers' union that favored
certain minority races. The school board defended the policy on the
grounds that minority teachers provided "role models" for minority
students and that a racially "diverse" faculty would improve the
education of all students. See Brief for Respondents, O. T. 1984,
No. 84-1340, pp. 27-28; 476 U. S., at 315 (STEVENS, J., dissenting)
("[A]n integrated faculty will be able to provide benefits to the
student body that could not be provided by an all-white, or nearly
all-white, faculty"). Nevertheless, the Court found that the use of
race violated the Equal Protection Clause, deeming both asserted
state interests insufficiently compelling. Id. , at 275-276
(plurality opinion); id. , at 295 (White, J., concurring in
judgment) ("None of the interests asserted by the [school board]
. . . justify this racially discriminatory layoff
policy").[ Footnote 2 ]
An even greater governmental interest involves the sensitive
role of courts in child custody determinations. In Palmore v.
Sidoti , 466 U.
S. 429 (1984), the Court held that even the best interests of a
child did not constitute a compelling state interest that would
allow a state court to award custody to the father because the
mother was in a mixed-race marriage. Id. , at 433 (finding
the interest "substantial" but [353] holding the custody decision could not be based on the race of
the mother's new husband).
Finally, the Court has rejected an interest in remedying general
societal discrimination as a justification for race discrimination.
See Wygant, supra , at 276 (plurality opinion); Croson , 488 U. S., at 496-498 (plurality opinion); id. , at 520-521 (SCALIA, J., concurring in judgment).
"Societal discrimination, without more, is too amorphous a basis
for imposing a racially classified remedy" because a "court could
uphold remedies that are ageless in their reach into the past, and
timeless in their ability to affect the future." Wygant,
supra , at 276 (plurality opinion). But see Gratz v.
Bollinger, ante , p. 298 (GINSBURG, J., dissenting).
Where the Court has accepted only national security, and
rejected even the best interests of a child, as a justification for
racial discrimination, I conclude that only those measures the
State must take to provide a bulwark against anarchy, or to prevent
violence, will constitute a "pressing public necessity." Cf. Lee v. Washington , 390 U. S. 333 , 334 (1968) (per curiam) (Black, J., concurring) (indicating that
protecting prisoners from violence might justify narrowly tailored
racial discrimination); Croson, supra , at 521 (SCALIA, J.,
concurring in judgment) ("At least where state or local action is
at issue, only a social emergency rising to the level of imminent
danger to life and limb . . . can justify [racial
discrimination]").
The Constitution abhors classifications based on race, not only
because those classifications can harm favored races or are based
on illegitimate motives, but also because every time the government
places citizens on racial registers and makes race relevant to the
provision of burdens or benefits, it demeans us all. "Purchased at
the price of immeasurable human suffering, the equal protection
principle reflects our Nation's understanding that such
classifications ultimately have a destructive impact on the
individual and our society." [354] Adarand Constructors, Inc. v. Peña , 515 U. S. 200 , 240 (1995)
(THOMAS, J., concurring in part and concurring in judgment).
II
Unlike the majority, I seek to define with precision the
interest being asserted by the Law School before determining
whether that interest is so compelling as to justify racial
discrimination. The Law School maintains that it wishes to obtain
"educational benefits that flow from student body diversity," Brief
for Respondent Bollinger et al. 14. This statement must be
evaluated carefully, because it implies that both "diversity" and
"educational benefits" are components of the Law School's
compelling state interest. Additionally, the Law School's refusal
to entertain certain changes in its admissions process and status
indicates that the compelling state interest it seeks to validate
is actually broader than might appear at first glance.
Undoubtedly there are other ways to "better" the education of
law students aside from ensuring that the student body contains a
"critical mass" of underrepresented minority students. Attaining
"diversity," whatever it means,[ Footnote 3 ] is
the [355] mechanism by which the Law School obtains educational benefits,
not an end of itself. The Law School, however, apparently believes
that only a racially mixed student body can lead to the educational
benefits it seeks. How, then, is the Law School's interest in these
allegedly unique educational "benefits" not simply the
forbidden interest in "racial balancing," ante , at 330,
that the majority expressly rejects?
A distinction between these two ideas (unique educational
benefits based on racial aesthetics and race for its own sake) is
purely sophistic-so much so that the majority uses them
interchangeably. Compare ante , at 328 ("[T]he Law School
has a compelling interest in attaining a diverse student body"),
with ante , at 333 (referring to the "compelling interest
in securing the educational benefits of a diverse student
body" (emphasis added)). The Law School's argument, as facile as it
is, can only be understood in one way: Classroom aesthetics yields
educational benefits, racially discriminatory admissions policies
are required to achieve the right racial mix, and therefore the
policies are required to achieve the educational benefits. It is
the educational benefits that are the end, or allegedly
compelling state interest, not "diversity." But see ante ,
at 332 (citing the need for "openness and integrity of the
educational institutions that provide [legal] training" without
reference to any consequential educational benefits).
One must also consider the Law School's refusal to entertain
changes to its current admissions system that might produce the
same educational benefits. The Law School adamantly disclaims any
race-neutral alternative that would reduce "academic selectivity,"
which would in turn "require the Law School to become a very
different institution, and to sacrifice a core part of its
educational mission." Brief for Respondent Bollinger et al. 33-36.
In other words, the Law School seeks to improve marginally the
education it offers [356] without sacrificing too much of its exclusivity and elite
status.[ Footnote 4 ]
The proffered interest that the majority vindicates today, then,
is not simply "diversity." Instead the Court upholds the use of
racial discrimination as a tool to advance the Law School's
interest in offering a marginally superior education while
maintaining an elite institution. Unless each constituent part of
this state interest is of pressing public necessity, the Law
School's use of race is unconstitutional. I find each of them to
fall far short of this standard.
III
A
A close reading of the Court's opinion reveals that all of its
legal work is done through one conclusory statement: The Law School
has a "compelling interest in securing the educational benefits of
a diverse student body." Ante , at 333. No serious effort
is made to explain how these benefits fit with the state interests
the Court has recognized (or rejected) as compelling, see Part I, supra , or to place any theoretical constraints on an
enterprising court's desire to discover still more justifications
for racial discrimination. In the absence of any explanation, one
might expect the Court to fall back on the judicial policy of stare decisis. But the Court eschews even this weak
defense of its holding, shunning an analysis of the extent to which
Justice Powell's opinion in Regents of Univ. of Cal. v.
Bakke , 438 U. S.
265 (1978), [357] is binding, ante , at 325, in favor of an unfounded
wholesale adoption of it.
Justice Powell's opinion in Bakke and the Court's
decision today rest on the fundamentally flawed proposition that
racial discrimination can be contextualized so that a goal, such as
classroom aesthetics, can be compelling in one context but not in
another. This "we know it when we see it" approach to evaluating
state interests is not capable of judicial application. Today, the
Court insists on radically expanding the range of permissible uses
of race to something as trivial (by comparison) as the assembling
of a law school class. I can only presume that the majority's
failure to justify its decision by reference to any principle
arises from the absence of any such principle. See Part VI, infra. B
Under the proper standard, there is no pressing public necessity
in maintaining a public law school at all and, it follows,
certainly not an elite law school. Likewise, marginal improvements
in legal education do not qualify as a compelling state
interest.
1
While legal education at a public university may be good policy
or otherwise laudable, it is obviously not a pressing public
necessity when the correct legal standard is applied. Additionally,
circumstantial evidence as to whether a state activity is of
pressing public necessity can be obtained by asking whether all
States feel compelled to engage in that activity. Evidence that
States, in general, engage in a certain activity by no means
demonstrates that the activity constitutes a pressing public
necessity, given the expansive role of government in to day's
society. The fact that some fraction of the States reject a
particular enterprise, however, creates a presumption that the
enterprise itself is not a compelling state interest. In this
sense, the absence of a public, American Bar Association (ABA)
accredited, law school in [358] Alaska, Delaware, Massachusetts, New Hampshire, and Rhode
Island, see ABA-LSAC Official Guide to ABAApproved Law Schools (w.
Margolis, B. Gordon, J. Puskarz, & D. Rosenlieb eds. 2004)
(hereinafter ABA-LSAC Guide), provides further evidence that
Michigan's maintenance of the Law School does not constitute a
compelling state interest.
2
As the foregoing makes clear, Michigan has no compelling
interest in having a law school at all, much less an elite one. Still, even assuming that a State may, under appropriate
circumstances, demonstrate a cognizable interest in having an elite
law school, Michigan has failed to do so here.
This Court has limited the scope of equal protection review to
interests and activities that occur within that State's
jurisdiction. The Court held in Missouri ex rel. Gaines v.
Canada , 305 U.
S. 337 (1938), that Missouri could not satisfy the demands of
"separate but equal" by paying for legal training of blacks at
neighboring state law schools, while maintaining a segregated law
school within the State. The equal protection "obligation is imposed by the Constitution upon the States
severally as governmental entities,-each responsible for its own
laws establishing the rights and duties of persons within its
borders. It is an obligation the burden of which cannot be cast by
one State upon another, and no State can be excused from
performance by what another State may do or fail to do. That separate responsibility of each State within its own sphere is
of the essence of statehood maintained under our dual system." Id. , at 350 (emphasis added). The Equal Protection Clause, as interpreted by the Court in Gaines , does not permit States to justify racial
discrimination on the basis of what the rest of the Nation "may do
or fail to do." The only interests that can satisfy the Equal [359] Protection Clause's demands are those found within a State's
jurisdiction.
The only cognizable state interests vindicated by operating a
public law school are, therefore, the education of that State's
citizens and the training of that State's lawyers. James Campbell's
address at the opening of the Law Department at the University of
Michigan on October 3, 1859, makes this clear: "It not only concerns the State that every one should
have all reasonable facilities for preparing himself for any honest
position in life to which he may aspire, but it also concerns the community that the Law should be taught and understood
. . . . There is not an office in the State in which serious legal inquiries may not frequently arise
. . . . In all these matters, public and private
rights are constantly involved and discussed, and ignorance of the
Law has frequently led to results deplorable and alarming
. . . . [I]n the history of this State , in
more than one instance, that ignorance has led to unlawful
violence, and the shedding of innocent blood." E. Brown, Legal
Education at Michigan 1859-1959, pp. 404-406 (1959) (emphasis
added). The Law School today, however, does precious little training of
those attorneys who will serve the citizens of Michigan. In 2002,
graduates of the Law School made up less than 6% of applicants to
the Michigan bar, Michigan Lawyers Weekly, available at
http://www.michiganlawyersweekly.com/barpassers0202.cfm,barpassers0702.cfm
(all Internet materials as visited June 13, 2003, and available in
Clerk of Court's case file), even though the Law School's graduates
constitute nearly 30% of all law students graduating in Michigan. Ibid. Less than 16% of the Law School's graduating class
elects to stay in Michigan after law school. ABA-LSAC Guide 427.
Thus, while a mere 27% of the Law School's 2002 entering class is
from Michigan, see University of [360] Michigan Law School Website, available at
http://www.law.umich.edu/prospectivestudents/Admissions/index.htm,
only half of these, it appears, will stay in Michigan.
In sum, the Law School trains few Michigan residents and
overwhelmingly serves students, who, as lawyers, leave the State of
Michigan. By contrast, Michigan's other public law school, Wayne
State University Law School, sends 88% of its graduates on to serve
the people of Michigan. ABA-LSAC Guide 775. It does not take a
social scientist to conclude that it is precisely the Law School's
status as an elite institution that causes it to be a waystation
for the rest of the country's lawyers, rather than a training
ground for those who will remain in Michigan. The Law School's
decision to be an elite institution does little to advance the
welfare of the people of Michigan or any cognizable interest of the
State of Michigan.
Again, the fact that few States choose to maintain elite law
schools raises a strong inference that there is nothing compelling
about elite status. Arguably, only the public law schools of the
University of Texas, the University of California, Berkeley (Boalt
Hall), and the University of Virginia maintain the same reputation
for excellence as the Law School.[ Footnote 5 ] Two
of these States, Texas and California, are so large that they could
reasonably be expected to provide elite legal training at a
separate law school to students who will, in fact, stay in the
State and provide legal services to its citizens. And these two
schools far outshine the Law School in producing in-state lawyers.
The University of Texas, for example, sends over three-fourths of
its graduates on to work in the State of Texas, vindicating the
State's interest (compelling or not) in training Texas' lawyers. Id. , at 691. [361] 3
Finally, even if the Law School's racial tinkering produces
tangible educational benefits, a marginal improvement in legal
education cannot justify racial discrimination where the Law School
has no compelling interest either in its existence or in its
current educational and admissions policies.
IV
The interest in remaining elite and exclusive that the majority
thinks so obviously critical requires the use of admissions
"standards" that, in turn, create the Law School's "need" to
discriminate on the basis of race. The Court validates these
admissions standards by concluding that alternatives that would
require "a dramatic sacrifice of . . . the academic
quality of all admitted students," ante , at 340, need not
be considered before racial discrimination can be
employed.[ Footnote 6 ] In the majority's view,
such methods are not required by the "narrow tailoring" prong of
strict scrutiny because that inquiry demands, in this context, that
any race-neutral alternative work "'about as well.'" Ante ,
at 339 (quoting Wygant , 476 U. S., at 280, n. 6). The
majority errs, however, because race-neutral alternatives must only
be "workable," ante , at 339, and do "about as well" in
vindicating the compelling state interest. The Court never
explicitly holds that the Law School's desire to retain the status
quo in "academic selectivity" is itself a compelling state
interest, and, as I have demonstrated, it is not. See Part III-B, supra. Therefore, the Law School should be forced to
choose between its classroom aesthetic and its exclusionary
admissions system-it cannot have it both ways.
With the adoption of different admissions methods, such as
accepting all students who meet minimum qualifications, [362] see Brief for United States as Amicus Curiae 13-14, the
Law School could achieve its vision of the racially aesthetic
student body without the use of racial discrimination. The Law
School concedes this, but the Court holds, implicitly and under the
guise of narrow tailoring, that the Law School has a compelling
state interest in doing what it wants to do. I cannot agree. First,
under strict scrutiny, the Law School's assessment of the benefits
of racial discrimination and devotion to the admissions status quo
are not entitled to any sort of deference, grounded in the First
Amendment or anywhere else. Second, even if its "academic
selectivity" must be maintained at all costs along with racial
discrimination, the Court ignores the fact that other top law
schools have succeeded in meeting their aesthetic demands without
racial discrimination.
A
The Court bases its unprecedented deference to the Law School-a
deference antithetical to strict scrutiny-on an idea of
"educational autonomy" grounded in the First Amendment. Ante , at 329. In my view, there is no basis for a right of
public universities to do what would otherwise violate the Equal
Protection Clause.
The constitutionalization of "academic freedom" began with the
concurring opinion of Justice Frankfurter in Sweezy v. New
Hampshire , 354
U. S. 234 (1957). Sweezy, a Marxist economist, was investigated
by the Attorney General of New Hampshire on suspicion of being a
subversive. The prosecution sought, inter alia , the
contents of a lecture Sweezy had given at the University of New
Hampshire. The Court held that the investigation violated due
process. Id. , at 254.
Justice Frankfurter went further, however, reasoning that the
First Amendment created a right of academic freedom that prohibited
the investigation. Id. , at 256-267 (opinion concurring in
result). Much of the rhetoric in Justice Frankfurter's opinion was
devoted to the personal right of Sweezy to free speech. See, e.g., id. , at 265 ("For a citizen to be [363] made to forego even a part of so basic a liberty as his
political autonomy, the subordinating interest of the State must be
compelling"). Still, claiming that the United States Reports "need
not be burdened with proof," Justice Frankfurter also asserted that
a "free society" depends on "free universities" and "[t]his means
the exclusion of governmental intervention in the intellectual life
of a university." Id. , at 262. According to Justice
Frankfurter: "It is the business of a university to provide that
atmosphere which is most conducive to speculation, experiment and
creation. It is an atmosphere in which there prevail 'the four
essential freedoms' of a university-to determine for itself on
academic grounds who may teach, what may be taught, how it shall be
taught, and who may be admitted to study." Id. , at 263
(citation omitted).
In my view, "[i]t is the business" of this Court to explain
itself when it cites provisions of the Constitution to invent new
doctrines-including the idea that the First Amendment authorizes a
public university to do what would otherwise violate the Equal
Protection Clause. The majority fails in its summary effort to
prove this point. The only source for the Court's conclusion that
public universities are entitled to deference even within the
confines of strict scrutiny is Justice Powell's opinion in Bakke. Justice Powell, for his part, relied only on
Justice Frankfurter's opinion in Sweezy and the Court's
decision in Keyishian v. Board of Regents of Univ. of State
of N. Y. , 385 U. S. 589 (1967), to
support his view that the First Amendment somehow protected a
public university's use of race in admissions. Bakke , 438
U. S., at 312. Keyishian provides no answer to the
question whether the Fourteenth Amendment's restrictions are
relaxed when applied to public universities. In that case, the
Court held that state statutes and regulations designed to prevent
the "appointment or retention of 'subversive' persons in state
employment," 385 U. S., at 592, violated the First Amendment for
vagueness. The statutes covered all public employees and were not
invalidated only as applied to uni- [364] versity faculty members, although the Court appeared sympathetic
to the notion of academic freedom, calling it a "special concern of
the First Amendment." Id. , at 603. Again, however, the
Court did not relax any independent constitutional restrictions on
public universities.
I doubt that when Justice Frankfurter spoke of governmental
intrusions into the independence of universities, he was thinking
of the Constitution's ban on racial discrimination. The majority's
broad deference to both the Law School's judgment that racial
aesthetics leads to educational benefits and its stubborn refusal
to alter the status quo in admissions methods finds no basis in the
Constitution or decisions of this Court.
B 1
The Court's deference to the Law School's conclusion that its
racial experimentation leads to educational benefits will, if
adhered to, have serious collateral consequences. The Court relies
heavily on social science evidence to justify its deference. See ante , at 330-332; but see also Rothman, Lipset, &
Nevitte, Racial Diversity Reconsidered, 151 Public Interest 25
(2003) (finding that the racial mix of a student body produced by
racial discrimination of the type practiced by the Law School in
fact hinders students' perception of academic quality). The Court
never acknowledges, however, the growing evidence that racial (and
other sorts) of heterogeneity actually impairs learning among black
students. See, e.g. , Flowers & Pascarella, Cognitive
Effects of College Racial Composition on African American Students
After 3 Years of College, 40 J. of College Student Development 669,
674 (1999) (concluding that black students experience superior
cognitive development at Historically Black Colleges (HBCs) and
that, even among blacks, "a substantial diversity moderates the
cognitive effects of attending an HBC"); Allen, The Color of
Success: African-American College Stu- [365] dent Outcomes at Predominantly White and Historically Black
Public Colleges and Universities, 62 Harv. Educ. Rev. 26, 35 (1992)
(finding that black students attending HBCs report higher academic
achievement than those attending predominantly white colleges).
At oral argument in Gratz v. Bollinger, ante , p. 244,
counsel for respondents stated that "most every single one of [the
HBCs] do have diverse student bodies." Tr. of Oral Arg. in No.
02-516, p. 52. What precisely counsel meant by "diverse" is
indeterminate, but it is reported that in 2000 at Morehouse
College, one of the most distinguished HBCs in the Nation, only
0.1% of the student body was white, and only 0.2% was Hispanic.
College Admissions Data Handbook 2002-2003, p. 613 (43d ed. 2002)
(hereinafter College Admissions Data Handbook). And at Mississippi
Valley State University, a public HBC, only 1.1% of the freshman
class in 2001 was white. Id. , at 603. If there is a
"critical mass" of whites at these institutions, then "critical
mass" is indeed a very small proportion.
The majority grants deference to the Law School's "assessment
that diversity will, in fact, yield educational benefits," ante , at 328. It follows, therefore, that an HBC's
assessment that racial homogeneity will yield educational benefits
would similarly be given deference.[ Footnote 7 ]
An HBC's rejection of white applicants in order to maintain racial
homogeneity seems permissible, therefore, under the majority's view
of the Equal Protection Clause. But see United States v.
Fordice , 505 U.
S. 717 , 748 (1992) (THOMAS, J., concurring) ("Obviously, a
State cannot maintain . . . traditions by closing
particular institutions, historically white or historically black,
to particular racial groups"). Contained within today's majority
opinion is the seed of a new constitutional [366] justification for a concept I thought long and rightly
rejected-racial segregation.
2
Moreover one would think, in light of the Court's decision in United States v. Virginia , 518 U. S. 515 (1996),
that before being given license to use racial discrimination, the
Law School would be required to radically reshape its admissions
process, even to the point of sacrificing some elements of its
character. In Virginia , a majority of the Court, without a
word about academic freedom, accepted the all-male Virginia
Military Institute's (VMI) representation that some changes in its
"adversative" method of education would be required with the
admission of women, id. , at 540, but did not defer to
VMI's judgment that these changes would be too great. Instead, the
Court concluded that they were "manageable." Id. , at 551,
n. 19. That case involved sex discrimination, which is subjected to
intermediate, not strict, scrutiny. Id. , at 533; Craig
v. Boren , 429 U.
S. 190 , 197 (1976). So in Virginia , where the standard
of review dictated that greater flexibility be granted to VMI's
educational policies than the Law School deserves here, this Court
gave no deference. Apparently where the status quo being defended
is that of the elite establishment-here the Law School-rather than
a less fashionable Southern military institution, the Court will
defer without serious inquiry and without regard to the applicable
legal standard.
C Virginia is also notable for the fact that the Court
relied on the "experience" of formerly single-sex institutions,
such as the service academies, to conclude that admission of women
to VMI would be "manageable." 518 U. S., at 544545. Today, however,
the majority ignores the "experience" of those institutions that
have been forced to abandon explicit racial discrimination in
admissions. [367] The sky has not fallen at Boalt Hall at the University of
California, Berkeley, for example. Prior to Proposition 209's
adoption of Cal. Const., Art. 1, § 31(a), which bars the State from
"grant[ing] preferential treatment . . . on the basis of
race . . . in the operation of . . . public
education,"[ Footnote 8 ] Boalt Hall enrolled 20
blacks and 28 Hispanics in its first-year class for 1996. In 2002,
without deploying express racial discrimination in admissions,
Boalt's entering class enrolled 14 blacks and 36
Hispanics.[ Footnote 9 ] University of California
Law and Medical School Enrollments, available at
http://www.ucop.edu/acadadv/datamgmt/lawmed/law-enrolls-eth2.html.
Total underrepresented minority student enrollment at Boalt Hall
now exceeds 1996 levels. Apparently the Law School cannot be
counted on to be as resourceful. The Court is willfully blind to
the very real experience in California and elsewhere, which raises
the inference that institutions with "reputation[s] for
excellence," ante , at 339, rivaling the Law School's have
satisfied their sense of mission without resorting to prohibited
racial discrimination.
V
Putting aside the absence of any legal support for the
majority's reflexive deference, there is much to be said for the
view that the use of tests and other measures to "predict" academic
performance is a poor substitute for a system that gives every
applicant a chance to prove he can succeed in the study of law. The
rallying cry that in the absence of racial discrimination in
admissions there would be a true [368] meritocracy ignores the fact that the entire process is poisoned
by numerous exceptions to "merit." For example, in the national
debate on racial discrimination in higher education admissions,
much has been made of the fact that elite institutions utilize a
so-called "legacy" preference to give the children of alumni an
advantage in admissions. This, and other, exceptions to a "true"
meritocracy give the lie to protestations that merit admissions are
in fact the order of the day at the Nation's universities. The
Equal Protection Clause does not, however, prohibit the use of
unseemly legacy preferences or many other kinds of arbitrary
admissions procedures. What the Equal Protection Clause does
prohibit are classifications made on the basis of race. So while
legacy preferences can stand under the Constitution, racial
discrimination cannot.[ Footnote 10 ] I will not
twist the Constitution to invalidate legacy preferences or
otherwise impose my vision of higher education admissions on the
Nation. The majority should similarly stay its impulse to validate
faddish racial discrimination the Constitution clearly forbids.
In any event, there is nothing ancient, honorable, or
constitutionally protected about "selective" admissions. The
University of Michigan should be well aware that alternative
methods have historically been used for the admission of students,
for it brought to this country the German certificate system in the
late-19th century. See H. Wechsler, The Qualified Student 16-39
(1977) (hereinafter Qualified Student). Under this system, a
secondary school was certified by a university so that any graduate
who completed the course offered by the school was offered
admission to the university. The certification regime supplemented,
and later virtually replaced (at least in the Midwest), the prior
regime of rigor- [369] ous subject-matter entrance examinations. Id. , at
57-58. The facially race-neutral "percent plans" now used in Texas,
California, and Florida, see ante , at 340, are in many
ways the descendents of the certificate system.
Certification was replaced by selective admissions in the
beginning of the 20th century, as universities sought to exercise
more control over the composition of their student bodies. Since
its inception, selective admissions has been the vehicle for
racial, ethnic, and religious tinkering and experimentation by
university administrators. The initial driving force for the
relocation of the selective function from the high school to the
universities was the same desire to select racial winners and
losers that the Law School exhibits today. Columbia, Harvard, and
others infamously determined that they had "too many" Jews, just as
today the Law School argues it would have "too many" whites if it
could not discriminate in its admissions process. See Qualified
Student 155-168 (Columbia); H. Broun & G. Britt, Christians
Only: A Study in Prejudice 53-54 (1931) (Harvard).
Columbia employed intelligence tests precisely because Jewish
applicants, who were predominantly immigrants, scored worse on such
tests. Thus, Columbia could claim (falsely) that" '[w]e have not
eliminated boys because they were Jews and do not propose to do so.
We have honestly attempted to eliminate the lowest grade of
applicant [through the use of intelligence testing] and it turns
out that a good many of the low grade men are New York City
Jews.''' Letter from Herbert E. Hawkes, dean of Columbia College,
to E. B. Wilson, June 16, 1922 (reprinted in Qualified Student
160-161). In other words, the tests were adopted with full
knowledge of their disparate impact. Cf. DeFunis v.
Odegaard , 416 U.
S. 312 , 335 (1974) (per curiam) (Douglas, J.,
dissenting).
Similarly no modern law school can claim ignorance of the poor
performance of blacks, relatively speaking, on the Law School
Admission Test (LSAT). Nevertheless, law schools [370] continue to use the test and then attempt to "correct" for black
underperformance by using racial discrimination in admissions so as
to obtain their aesthetic student body. The Law School's continued
adherence to measures it knows produce racially skewed results is
not entitled to deference by this Court. See Part IV; supra. The Law School itself admits that the test is
imperfect, as it must, given that it regularly admits students who
score at or below 150 (the national median) on the test. See App.
156-203 (showing that, between 1995 and 2000, the Law School
admitted 37 students-27 of whom were black; 31 of whom were
"underrepresented minorities"-with LSAT scores of 150 or lower).
And the Law School's amici cannot seem to agree on the
fundamental question whether the test itself is useful. Compare
Brief for Law School Admission Council as Amicus Curiae 12
("LSAT scores . . . are an effective predictor of
students' performance in law school") with Brief for Harvard Black
Law Students Association et al. as Amici Curiae 27
("Whether [the LSAT] measure[s] objective merit . . . is
certainly questionable").
Having decided to use the LSAT, the Law School must accept the
constitutional burdens that come with this decision. The Law School
may freely continue to employ the LSAT and other allegedly
merit-based standards in whatever fashion it likes. What the Equal
Protection Clause forbids, but the Court today allows, is the use
of these standards hand-in-hand with racial discrimination. An
infinite variety of admissions methods are available to the Law
School. Considering all of the radical thinking that has
historically occurred at this country's universities, the Law
School's intractable approach toward admissions is striking.
The Court will not even deign to make the Law School try other
methods, however, preferring instead to grant a 25-year license to
violate the Constitution. And the same Court that had the courage
to order the desegregation of all public schools in the South now
fears, on the basis of plati- [371] tudes rather than principle, to force the Law School to abandon
a decidedly imperfect admissions regime that provides the basis for
racial discrimination.
VI
The absence of any articulated legal principle supporting the
majority's principal holding suggests another rationale. I believe
what lies beneath the Court's decision today are the benighted
notions that one can tell when racial discrimination benefits
(rather than hurts) minority groups, see Adarand , 515 U.
S., at 239 (SCALIA, J., concurring in part and concurring in
judgment), and that racial discrimination is necessary to remedy
general societal ills. This Court's precedents supposedly settled
both issues, but clearly the majority still cannot commit to the
principle that racial classifications are per se harmful
and that almost no amount of benefit in the eye of the beholder can
justify such classifications.
Putting aside what I take to be the Court's implicit rejection
of Adarand's holding that beneficial and burdensome racial
classifications are equally invalid, I must contest the notion that
the Law School's discrimination benefits those admitted as a result
of it. The Court spends considerable time discussing the impressive
display of amicus support for the Law School in this case
from all corners of society. Ante , at 330-331. But nowhere
in any of the filings in this Court is any evidence that the
purported "beneficiaries" of this racial discrimination prove
themselves by performing at (or even near) the same level as those
students who receive no preferences. Cf. Thernstrom &
Thernstrom, Reflections on the Shape of the River, 46 UCLA L. Rev.
1583, 1605-1608 (1999) (discussing the failure of defenders of
racial discrimination in admissions to consider the fact that its
"beneficiaries" are underperforming in the classroom).
The silence in this case is deafening to those of us who view
higher education's purpose as imparting knowledge and skills to
students, rather than a communal, rubber-stamp, [372] credentialing process. The Law School is not looking for those
students who, despite a lower LSAT score or undergraduate grade
point average, will succeed in the study of law. The Law School
seeks only a facade-it is sufficient that the class looks right,
even if it does not perform right.
The Law School tantalizes unprepared students with the promise
of a University of Michigan degree and all of the opportunities
that it offers. These overmatched students take the bait, only to
find that they cannot succeed in the cauldron of competition. And
this mismatch crisis is not restricted to elite institutions. See
T. Sowell, Race and Culture 176-177 (1994) ("Even if most minority
students are able to meet the normal standards at the 'average'
range of colleges and universities, the systematic mismatching of
minority students begun at the top can mean that such students are
generally overmatched throughout all levels of higher education").
Indeed, to cover the tracks of the aestheticists, this cruel farce
of racial discrimination must continuein selection for the Michigan
Law Review, see University of Michigan Law School Student Handbook
2002-2003, pp. 39-40 (noting the presence of a "diversity plan" for
admission to the review), and in hiring at law firms and for
judicial clerks hips-until the "beneficiaries" are no longer
tolerated. While these students may graduate with law degrees,
there is no evidence that they have received a qualitatively better
legal education (or become better lawyers) than if they had gone to
a less "elite" law school for which they were better prepared. And
the aestheticists will never address the real problems facing
"underrepresented minorities,"[ Footnote 11 ]
instead continuing their social experiments on other people's
children. [373] Beyond the harm the Law School's racial discrimination visits
upon its test subjects, no social science has disproved the notion
that this discrimination "engender[s] attitudes of superiority or,
alternatively, provoke[s] resentment among those who believe that
they have been wronged by the government's use of race." Adarand , 515 U. S., at 241 (THOMAS, J., concurring in part
and concurring in judgment). "These programs stamp minorities with
a badge of inferiority and may cause them to develop dependencies
or to adopt an attitude that they are 'entitled' to preferences." Ibid. It is uncontested that each year, the Law School admits a
handful of blacks who would be admitted in the absence of racial
discrimination. See Brief for Respondent Bollinger et al. 6. Who
can differentiate between those who belong and those who do not?
The majority of blacks are admitted to the Law School because of
discrimination, and because of this policy all are tarred as
undeserving. This problem of stigma does not depend on determinacy
as to whether those stigmatized are actually the "beneficiaries" of
racial discrimination. When blacks take positions in the highest
places of government, industry, or academia, it is an open question
today whether their skin color played a part in their advancement.
The question itself is the stigma-because either racial
discrimination did playa role, in which case the person may be
deemed "otherwise unqualified," or it did not, in which case asking
the question itself unfairly marks those blacks who would succeed
without discrimination. Is this what the Court means by "visibly
open"? Ante , at 332.
Finally, the Court's disturbing reference to the importance of
the country's law schools as training grounds meant to cultivate "a
set of leaders with legitimacy in the eyes of the citizenry," ibid. , through the use of racial discrimination deserves
discussion. As noted earlier, the Court has soundly [374] rejected the remedying of societal discrimination as a
justification for governmental use of race. Wygant , 476 U.
S., at 276 (plurality opinion); Croson , 488 U. S., at 497
(plurality opinion); id. , at 520-521 (SCALIA, J.,
concurring in judgment). For those who believe that every racial
disproportionality in our society is caused by some kind of racial
discrimination, there can be no distinction between remedying
societal discrimination and erasing racial disproportionalities in
the country's leadership caste. And if the lack of proportional
racial representation among our leaders is not caused by societal
discrimination, then "fixing" it is even less of a pressing public
necessity.
The Court's civics lesson presents yet another example of
judicial selection of a theory of political representation based on
skin color-an endeavor I have previously rejected. See Holder
v. Hall , 512 U.
S. 874 , 899 (1994) (THOMAS, J., concurring in judgment). The
majority appears to believe that broader utopian goals justify the
Law School's use of race, but "[t]he Equal Protection Clause
commands the elimination of racial barriers, not their creation in
order to satisfy our theory as to how society ought to be
organized." DeFunis , 416 U. S., at 342 (Douglas, J.,
dissenting).
VII
As the foregoing makes clear, I believe the Court's opinion to
be, in most respects, erroneous. I do, however, find two points on
which I agree.
A
First, I note that the issue of unconstitutional racial
discrimination among the groups the Law School prefers is not
presented in this case, because petitioner has never argued that
the Law School engages in such a practice, and the Law School
maintains that it does not. See Brief for Respondent Bollinger et
al. 32, n. 50, and 6-7, n. 7. I join the Court's opinion insofar as
it confirms that this type of racial discrimination remains
unlawful. Ante , at 326-327. Under to day's [375] decision, it is still the case that racial discrimination that
does not help a university to enroll an unspecified number, or
"critical mass," of underrepresented minority students is
unconstitutional. Thus, the Law School may not discriminate in
admissions between similarly situated blacks and Hispanics, or
between whites and Asians. This is so because preferring black to
Hispanic applicants, for instance, does nothing to further the
interest recognized by the majority today.[ Footnote
12 ] Indeed, the majority describes such racial balancing as
"patently unconstitutional." Ante , at 330. Like the Court, ante , at 336, I express no opinion as to whether the Law
School's current admissions program runs afoul of this
prohibition.
B
The Court also holds that racial discrimination in admissions
should be given another 25 years before it is deemed no longer
narrowly tailored to the Law School's fabricated compelling state
interest. Ante , at 343. While I agree that in 25 years the
practices of the Law School will be illegal, they are, for the
reasons I have given, illegal now. The majority does not and cannot
rest its time limitation on any evidence that the gap in
credentials between black and white [376] students is shrinking or will be gone in that
timeframe.[ Footnote 13 ] In recent years there
has been virtually no change, for example, in the proportion of law
school applicants with LSAT scores of 165 and higher who are
black.[ Footnote 14 ] In 1993 blacks constituted
1.1% of law school applicants in that score range, though they
represented 11.1% of all applicants. Law School Admission Council,
National Statistical Report (1994) (hereinafter LSAC Statistical
Report). In 2000 the comparable numbers were 1.0% and 11.3%. LSAC
Statistical Report (2001). No one can seriously contend, and the
Court does not, that the racial gap in academic credentials will
disappear in 25 years. Nor is the Court's holding that racial
discrimination will be unconstitutional in 25 years made contingent
on the gap closing in that time.[ Footnote
15 ] [377] Indeed, the very existence of racial discrimination of the type
practiced by the Law School may impede the narrowing of the LSAT
testing gap. An applicant's LSAT score can improve dramatically
with preparation, but such preparation is a cost, and there must be
sufficient benefits attached to an improved score to justify
additional study. Whites scoring between 163 and 167 on the LSAT
are routinely rejected by the Law School, and thus whites aspiring
to admission at the Law School have every incentive to improve
their score to levels above that range. See App. 199 (showing that
in 2000, 209 out of 422 white applicants were rejected in this
scoring range). Blacks, on the other hand, are nearly guaranteed
admission if they score above 155. Id. , at 198 (showing
that 63 out of 77 black applicants are accepted with LSAT scores
above 155). As admission prospects approach certainty, there is no
incentive for the black applicant to continue to prepare for the
LSAT once he is reasonably assured of achieving the requisite
score. It is far from certain that the LSAT test-taker's behavior
is responsive to the Law School's admissions policies.[ Footnote 16 ] Nevertheless, the possibility remains that
this racial discrimination will help fulfill the bigot's prophecy
about black underperformance-just as it confirms the conspiracy
theorist's belief that "institutional racism" is at fault for every
racial disparity in our society.
I therefore can understand the imposition of a 25-year time
limit only as a holding that the deference the Court pays to the
Law School's educational judgments and refusal to change its
admissions policies will itself expire. At that point these
policies will clearly have failed to "'eliminat[e] [378] the [perceived] need for any racial or ethnic'" discrimination
because the academic credentials gap will still be there. Ante , at 343 (quoting Nathanson & Bartnik, The
Constitutionality of Preferential Treatment for Minority Applicants
to Professional Schools, 58 Chicago Bar Rec. 282, 293 (MayJune
1977)). The Court defines this time limit in terms of narrow
tailoring, see ante , at 343, but I believe this arises
from its refusal to define rigorously the broad state interest
vindicated today. Cf. Part II, supra. With these
observations, I join the last sentence of Part III of the opinion
of the Court.
***
For the immediate future, however, the majority has placed its imprimatur on a practice that can only weaken the
principle of equality embodied in the Declaration of Independence
and the Equal Protection Clause. "Our Constitution is color-blind,
and neither knows nor tolerates classes among citizens." Plessy
v. Ferguson , 163
U. S. 537 , 559 (1896) (Harlan, J., dissenting). It has been
nearly 140 years since Frederick Douglass asked the intellectual
ancestors of the Law School to "[d]o nothing with us!" and the
Nation adopted the Fourteenth Amendment. Now we must wait another
25 years to see this principle of equality vindicated. I therefore
respectfully dissent from the remainder of the Court's opinion and
the judgment.
CHIEF JUSTICE REHNQUIST, with whom JUSTICE SCALIA, JUSTICE
KENNEDY, and JUSTICE THOMAS join, dissenting.
I agree with the Court that, "in the limited circumstance when
drawing racial distinctions is permissible," the government must
ensure that its means are narrowly tailored to achieve a compelling
state interest. Ante , at 333; see also Fullilove v.
Klutznick , 448
U. S. 448 , 498 (1980) (Powell, J., concurring) ("[E]ven if the
government proffers a compelling interest to support reliance upon
a suspect classification, the means selected must be narrowly drawn
to fulfill the govern- [379] mental purpose"). I do not believe, however, that the University
of Michigan Law School's (Law School) means are narrowly tailored
to the interest it asserts. The Law School claims it must take the
steps it does to achieve a "'critical mass'" of underrepresented
minority students. Brief for Respondent Bollinger et al. 13. But
its actual program bears no relation to this asserted goal.
Stripped of its "critical mass" veil, the Law School's program is
revealed as a naked effort to achieve racial balancing.
As we have explained many times, '" "[a]ny preference based on
racial or ethnic criteria must necessarily receive a most searching
examination."'" Adarand Constructors, Inc. v. Peña , 515 U. S. 200 ,
223 (1995) (quoting Wygant v. Jackson Bd. of Ed. , 476 U. S. 267 , 273 (1986)
(plurality opinion of Powell, J.)). Our cases establish that, in
order to withstand this demanding inquiry, respondents must
demonstrate that their methods of using race "'fit'" a compelling
state interest "with greater precision than any alternative means." Id. , at 280, n. 6; Regents of Univ. of Cal. v.
Bakke , 438 U. S.
265 , 299 (1978) (opinion of Powell, J.) ("When [political
judgments] touch upon an individual's race or ethnic background, he
is entitled to a judicial determination that the burden he is asked
to bear on that basis is precisely tailored to serve a compelling
governmental interest").
Before the Court's decision today, we consistently applied the
same strict scrutiny analysis regardless of the government's
purported reason for using race and regardless of the setting in
which race was being used. We rejected calls to use more lenient
review in the face of claims that race was being used in "good
faith" because" '[m]ore than good motives should be required when
government seeks to allocate its resources by way of an explicit
racial classification systern.'" Adarand, supra , at 226; Fullilove, supra , at 537 (STEVENS, J., dissenting)
("Racial classifications are simply too pernicious to permit any
but the most exact connection between justification and
classification"). We likewise re- [380] jected calls to apply more lenient review based on the
particular setting in which race is being used. Indeed, even in the
specific context of higher education, we emphasized that
"constitutional limitations protecting individual rights may not be
disregarded." Bakke, supra , at 314.
Although the Court recites the language of our strict scrutiny
analysis, its application of that review is unprecedented in its
deference.
Respondents' asserted justification for the Law School's use of
race in the admissions process is "obtaining 'the educational
benefits that flow from a diverse student body.'" Ante , at
328 (quoting Brief for Respondent Bollinger et al. i). They contend
that a "critical mass" of underrepresented minorities is necessary
to further that interest. Ante , at 330. Respondents and
school administrators explain generally that "critical mass" means
a sufficient number of underrepresented minority students to
achieve several objectives:
To ensure that these minority students do not feel isolated or
like spokespersons for their race; to provide adequate
opportunities for the type of interaction upon which the
educational benefits of diversity depend; and to challenge all
students to think critically and reexamine stereotypes. See App. to
Pet. for Cert. 211a; Brief for Respondent Bollinger et al. 26.
These objectives indicate that "critical mass" relates to the size
of the student body. Id. , at 5 (claiming that the Law
School has enrolled "critical mass," or "enough minority students
to provide meaningful integration of its classrooms and residence
halls"). Respondents further claim that the Law School is achieving
"critical mass." Id. , at 4 (noting that the Law School's
goals have been "greatly furthered by the presence of
. . . a 'critical mass' of" minority students in the
student body).
In practice, the Law School's program bears little or no
relation to its asserted goal of achieving "critical mass."
Respondents explain that the Law School seeks to accumulate a
"critical mass" of each underrepresented minority [381] group. See, e.g. , id. , at 49, n. 79 ("The Law
School's . . . current policy . . . provide[s]
a special commitment to enrolling a 'critical mass' of 'Hispanics'
"). But the record demonstrates that the Law School's admissions
practices with respect to these groups differ dramatically and
cannot be defended under any consistent use of the term "critical
mass."
From 1995 through 2000, the Law School admitted between 1,130
and 1,310 students. Of those, between 13 and 19 were Native
American, between 91 and 108 were African-American, and between 47
and 56 were Hispanic. If the Law School is admitting between 91 and
108 AfricanAmericans in order to achieve "critical mass," thereby
preventing African-American students from feeling "isolated or like
spokespersons for their race," one would think that a number of the
same order of magnitude would be necessary to accomplish the same
purpose for Hispanics and Native Americans. Similarly, even if all
of the Native American applicants admitted in a given year
matriculate, which the record demonstrates is not at all the
case,[ Footnote * ] how can this possibly
constitute a "critical mass" of Native Americans in a class of over
350 students? In order for this pattern of admission to be
consistent with the Law School's explanation of "critical mass,"
one would have to believe that the objectives of "critical mass"
offered by respondents are achieved with only half the number of
Hispanics and one-sixth the number of Native Americans as compared
to AfricanAmericans. But respondents offer no race-specific reasons
for such disparities. Instead, they simply emphasize the importance
of achieving "critical mass," without any explanation of why that
concept is applied differently among the three underrepresented
minority groups. [382] These different numbers, moreover, come only as a result of
substantially different treatment among the three underrepresented
minority groups, as is apparent in an example offered by the Law
School and highlighted by the Court:
The school asserts that it "frequently accepts nonminority
applicants with grades and test scores lower than underrepresented
minority applicants (and other nonminority applicants) who are
rejected." Ante , at 338 (citing Brief for Respondent
Bollinger et al. 10). Specifically, the Law School states that
"[s]ixty-nine minority applicants were rejected between 1995 and
2000 with at least a 3.5 [Grade Point Average (GPA)] and a [score
of] 159 or higher on the [Law School Admission Test (LSAT)]" while
a number of Caucasian and Asian-American applicants with similar or
lower scores were admitted. Ibid. Review of the record reveals only 67 such individuals. Of these
67 individuals, 56 were Hispanic, while only 6 were
African-American, and only 5 were Native American. This discrepancy
reflects a consistent practice. For example, in 2000, 12 Hispanics
who scored between a 159-160 on the LSAT and earned a GPA of 3.00
or higher applied for admission and only 2 were admitted. App.
200-201. Meanwhile, 12 African-Americans in the same range of
qualifications applied for admission and all 12 were admitted. Id. , at 198. Likewise, that same year, 16 Hispanics who
scored between a 151-153 on the LSAT and earned a 3.00 or higher
applied for admission and only 1 of those applicants was admitted. Id. , at 200-201. Twenty-three similarly qualified
AfricanAmericans applied for admission and 14 were admitted. Id. , at 198.
These statistics have a significant bearing on petitioner's
case. Respondents have never offered any race-specific
arguments explaining why significantly more individuals from one
underrepresented minority group are needed in order to achieve
"critical mass" or further student body diversity. They certainly
have not explained why Hispanics, who they [383] have said are among "the groups most isolated by racial barriers
in our country," should have their admission capped out in this
manner. Brief for Respondent Bollinger et al. 50. True, petitioner
is neither Hispanic nor Native American. But the Law School's
disparate admissions practices with respect to these minority
groups demonstrate that its alleged goal of "critical mass" is
simply a sham. Petitioner may use these statistics to expose this
sham, which is the basis for the Law School's admission of less
qualified underrepresented minorities in preference to her. Surely
strict scrutiny cannot permit these sorts of disparities without at
least some explanation.
Only when the "critical mass" label is discarded does a likely
explanation for these numbers emerge. The Court states that the Law
School's goal of attaining a "critical mass" of underrepresented
minority students is not an interest in merely" 'assur[ing] within
its student body some specified percentage of a particular group
merely because of its race or ethnic origin.'" Ante , at
329 (quoting Bakke, 438 U. S., at 307 (opinion of Powell,
J.)). The Court recognizes that such an interest "would amount to
outright racial balancing, which is patently unconstitutional." Ante , at 330. The Court concludes, however, that the Law
School's use of race in admissions, consistent with Justice
Powell's opinion in Bakke , only pays" '[s]ome attention to
numbers.'" Ante , at 336 (quoting Bakke, supra , at
323).
But the correlation between the percentage of the Law School's
pool of applicants who are members of the three minority groups and
the percentage of the admitted applicants who are members of these
same groups is far too precise to be dismissed as merely the result
of the school paying "some attention to [the] numbers." As the
tables below show, from 1995 through 2000 the percentage of
admitted applicants who were members of these minority groups
closely tracked the percentage of individuals in the school's
applicant pool who were from the same groups. [384] Table 1 Year Number of law school applicants Number of African-American applicants % of applicants who were African-American Number of applicants admitted by the law
school Number of African-American applicants
admitted % of admitted applicants who were
African-American 1995 4147 404 9.7% 1130 106 9.4% 1996 3677 342 9.3% 1170 108 9.2% 1997 3429 320 9.3% 1218 101 8.3% 1998 3537 304 8.6% 1310 103 7.9% 1999 3400 247 7.3% 1280 91 7.1% 2000 3432 259 7.5% 1249 91 7.3% Table 2 Year Number of law school applicants Number of Hispanic applicants % of applicants who were Hispanic Number of applicants admitted by the law
school Number of Hispanic applicants admitted % of admitted applicants who were Hispanic 1995 4147 213 5.1% 1130 56 5.0% 1996 3677 186 5.1% 1170 54 4.6% 1997 3429 163 4.8% 1218 47 3.9% 1998 3537 150 4.2% 1310 55 4.2% 1999 3400 152 4.5% 1280 48 3.8% 2000 3432 168 4.9% 1249 53 4.2% Table 3 Year Number of law school applicants Number of Native American applicants % of applicants who were Native American Number of applicants admitted by the law
school Number of Native American applicants
admitted % of admitted applicants who were Native
American 1995 4147 45 1.1% 1130 14 1.2% 1996 3677 31 0.8% 1170 13 1.1% 1997 3429 37 1.1% 1218 19 1.6% 1998 3537 40 1.1% 1310 18 1.4% 1999 3400 25 0.7% 1280 13 1.0% 2000 3432 35 1.0% 1249 14 1.1% [385] For example, in 1995, when 9.7% of the applicant pool was
African-American, 9.4% of the admitted class was African-American.
By 2000, only 7.5% of the applicant pool was African-American, and
7.3% of the admitted class was African-American. This correlation
is striking. Respondents themselves emphasize that the number of
underrepresented minority students admitted to the Law School would
be significantly smaller if the race of each applicant were not
considered. See App. to Pet. for Cert. 223a; Brief for Respondent
Bollinger et al. 6 (quoting App. to Pet. for Cert. 299a). But, as
the examples above illustrate, the measure of the decrease would
differ dramatically among the groups. The tight correlation between
the percentage of applicants and admittees of a given race,
therefore, must result from careful race based planning by the Law
School. It suggests a formula for admission based on the
aspirational assumption that all applicants are equally qualified
academically, and therefore that the proportion of each group
admitted should be the same as the proportion of that group in the
applicant pool. See Brief for Respondent Bollinger et al. 43, n. 70
(discussing admissions officers' use of "periodic reports" to track
"the racial composition of the developing class").
Not only do respondents fail to explain this phenomenon, they
attempt to obscure it. See id. , at 32, n. 50 ("The Law
School's minority enrollment percentages . . . diverged
from the percentages in the applicant pool by as much as 17.7% from
1995-2000"). But the divergence between the percentages of
underrepresented minorities in the applicant pool and in the enrolled classes is not the only relevant comparison. In
fact, it may not be the most relevant comparison. The Law School
cannot precisely control which of its admitted applicants decide to
attend the university. But it can and, as the numbers demonstrate,
clearly does employ racial preferences in extending offers of
admission. Indeed, the ostensibly flexible nature of the Law
School's admissions program [386] that the Court finds appealing, see ante , at 337-338,
appears to be, in practice, a carefully managed program designed to
ensure proportionate representation of applicants from selected
minority groups.
I do not believe that the Constitution gives the Law School such
free rein in the use of race. The Law School has offered no
explanation for its actual admissions practices and, unexplained,
we are bound to conclude that the Law School has managed its
admissions program, not to achieve a "critical mass," but to extend
offers of admission to members of selected minority groups in
proportion to their statistical representation in the applicant
pool. But this is precisely the type of racial balancing that the
Court itself calls "patently unconstitutional." Ante , at
330.
Finally, I believe that the Law School's program fails strict
scrutiny because it is devoid of any reasonably precise time limit
on the Law School's use of race in admissions. We have emphasized
that we will consider "the planned duration of the remedy" in
determining whether a race-conscious program is constitutional. Fullilove , 448 U. S., at 510 (Powell, J., concurring); see
also United States v. Paradise , 480 U. S. 149 ,171 (1987)
("In determining whether race-conscious remedies are appropriate,
we look to several factors, including the . . . duration
of the relief"). Our previous cases have required some limit on the
duration of programs such as this because discrimination on the
basis of race is invidious.
The Court suggests a possible 25-year limitation on the Law
School's current program. See ante , at 343. Respondents,
on the other hand, remain more ambiguous, explaining that "[t]he
Law School of course recognizes that race-conscious programs must
have reasonable durational limits, and the Sixth Circuit properly
found such a limit in the Law School's resolve to cease considering
race when genuine race-neutral alternatives become available."
Brief for Respondent Bollinger et al. 32. These discussions of a
time [387] limit are the vaguest of assurances. In truth, they permit the
Law School's use of racial preferences on a seemingly permanent
basis. Thus, an important component of strict scrutiny-that a
program be limited in time-is casually subverted.
The Court, in an unprecedented display of deference under our
strict scrutiny analysis, upholds the Law School's program despite
its obvious flaws. We have said that when it comes to the use of
race, the connection between the ends and the means used to attain
them must be precise. But here the flaw is deeper than that; it is
not merely a question of "fit" between ends and means. Here the
means actually used are forbidden by the Equal Protection Clause of
the Constitution.
JUSTICE KENNEDY, dissenting.
The separate opinion by Justice Powell in Regents of Univ.
of Cal. v. Bakke , 438 U. S. 265 , 289-291,
315-318 (1978), is based on the principle that a university
admissions program may take account of race as one, nonpredominant
factor in a system designed to consider each applicant as an
individual, provided the program can meet the test of strict
scrutiny by the judiciary. This is a unitary formulation. If strict
scrutiny is abandoned or manipulated to distort its real and
accepted meaning, the Court lacks authority to approve the use of
race even in this modest, limited way. The opinion by Justice
Powell, in my view, states the correct rule for resolving this
case. The Court, however, does not apply strict scrutiny. By trying
to say otherwise, it undermines both the test and its own
controlling precedents.
Justice Powell's approval of the use of race in university
admissions reflected a tradition, grounded in the First Amendment,
of acknowledging a university's conception of its educational
mission. Id. , at 312-314; ante , at 329. Our
precedents provide a basis for the Court's acceptance of a
university's considered judgment that racial diversity among [388] students can further its educational task, when supported by
empirical evidence. Ante , at 329-331.
It is unfortunate, however, that the Court takes the first part
of Justice Powell's rule but abandons the second. Having approved
the use of race as a factor in the admissions process, the majority
proceeds to nullify the essential safeguard Justice Powell insisted
upon as the precondition of the approval. The safeguard was
rigorous judicial review, with strict scrutiny as the controlling
standard. Bakke, supra , at 291 ("Racial and ethnic
distinctions of any sort are inherently suspect and thus call for
the most exacting judicial examination"). This Court has
reaffirmed, subsequent to Bakke , the absolute necessity of
strict scrutiny when the State uses race as an operative category. Adarand Constructors, Inc. v. Peña , 515 U. S. 200 , 224 (1995)
("[A]ny person, of whatever race, has the right to demand that any
governmental actor subject to the Constitution justify any racial
classification subjecting that person to unequal treatment under
the strictest judicial scrutiny"); Richmond v. J. A.
Croson Co. , 488
U. S. 469 , 493-494 (1989); see id. , at 519 (KENNEDY,
J., concurring in part and concurring in judgment) ("[A]ny racial
preference must face the most rigorous scrutiny by the courts").
The Court confuses deference to a university's definition of its
educational objective with deference to the implementation of this
goal. In the context of university admissions the objective of
racial diversity can be accepted based on empirical data known to
us, but deference is not to be given with respect to the methods by
which it is pursued. Preferment by race, when resorted to by the
State, can be the most divisive of all policies, containing within
it the potential to destroy confidence in the Constitution and in
the idea of equality. The majority today refuses to be faithful to
the settled principle of strict review designed to reflect these
concerns.
The Court, in a review that is nothing short of perfunctory,
accepts the University of Michigan Law School's (Law [389] School) assurances that its admissions process meets with
constitutional requirements. The majority fails to confront the
reality of how the Law School's admissions policy is implemented.
The dissenting opinion by THE CHIEF JUSTICE, which I join in full,
demonstrates beyond question why the concept of critical mass is a
delusion used by the Law School to mask its attempt to make race an
automatic factor in most instances and to achieve numerical goals
indistinguishable from quotas. An effort to achieve racial balance
among the minorities the school seeks to attract is, by the Court's
own admission, "patently unconstitutional." Ante , at 330;
see also Bakke, supra , at 307 (opinion of Powell, J.). It
remains to point out how critical mass becomes inconsistent with
individual consideration in some more specific aspects of the
admissions process.
About 80% to 85% of the places in the entering class are given
to applicants in the upper range of Law School Admissions Test
scores and grades. An applicant with these credentials likely will
be admitted without consideration of race or ethnicity. With
respect to the remaining 15% to 20% of the seats, race is likely
outcome determinative for many members of minority groups. That is
where the competition becomes tight and where any given applicant's
chance of admission is far smaller if he or she lacks minority
status. At this point the numerical concept of critical mass has
the real potential to compromise individual review.
The Law School has not demonstrated how individual consideration
is, or can be, preserved at this stage of the application process
given the instruction to attain what it calls critical mass. In
fact the evidence shows otherwise. There was little deviation among
admitted minority students during the years from 1995 to 1998. The
percentage of enrolled minorities fluctuated only by 0.3%, from
13.5% to 13.8%. The number of minority students to whom offers were
extended varied by just a slightly greater magnitude of 2.2%, from
the high of 15.6% in 1995 to the low of 13.4% in 1998. [390] The District Court relied on this uncontested fact to draw an
inference that the Law School's pursuit of critical mass mutated
into the equivalent of a quota. 137 F. Supp. 2d 821, 851 (ED Mich.
2001). Admittedly, there were greater fluctuations among enrolled
minorities in the preceding years, 1987-1994, by as much as 5% or
6%. The percentage of minority offers, however, at no point fell
below 12%, historically defined by the Law School as the bottom of
its critical mass range. The greater variance during the earlier
years, in any event, does not dispel suspicion that the school
engaged in racial balancing. The data would be consistent with an
inference that the Law School modified its target only twice, in
1991 (from 13% to 19%), and then again in 1995 (back from 20% to
13%). The intervening year, 1993, when the percentage dropped to
14.5%, could be an aberration, caused by the school's
miscalculation as to how many applicants with offers would accept
or by its redefinition, made in April 1992, of which minority
groups were entitled to race-based preference. See Brief for
Respondent Bollinger et al. 49, n. 79. Year Percentage of enrolled minority students 1987 12.3% 1988 13.6% 1989 14.4% 1990 13.4% 1991 19.1% 1992 19.8% 1993 14.5% 1994 20.1% 1995 13.5% 1996 13.8% 1997 13.6% 1998 13.8% The narrow fluctuation band raises an inference that the Law
School subverted individual determination, and strict [391] scrutiny requires the Law School to overcome the inference.
Whether the objective of critical mass "is described as a quota or
a goal, it is a line drawn on the basis of race and ethnic status,"
and so risks compromising individual assessment. Bakke ,
438 U. S., at 289 (opinion of Powell, J.). In this respect the Law
School program compares unfavorably with the experience of Little
Ivy League colleges. Amicus Amherst College, for example,
informs us that the offers it extended to students of
African-American background during the period from 1993 to 2002
ranged between 81 and 125 out of 950 offers total, resulting in a
fluctuation from 24 to 49 matriculated students in a class of about
425. See Brief for Amherst College et al. as Amici Curiae 10-11. The Law School insisted upon a much smaller fluctuation,
both in the offers extended and in the students who eventually
enrolled, despite having a comparable class size.
The Law School has the burden of proving, in conformance with
the standard of strict scrutiny, that it did not utilize race in an
unconstitutional way. Adarand Constructors, 515 U. S., at
224. At the very least, the constancy of admitted minority students
and the close correlation between the racial breakdown of admitted
minorities and the composition of the applicant pool, discussed by
THE CHIEF JUSTICE, ante , at 380-386, require the Law
School either to produce a convincing explanation or to show it has
taken adequate steps to ensure individual assessment. The Law
School does neither.
The obvious tension between the pursuit of critical mass and the
requirement of individual review increased by the end of the
admissions season. Most of the decisions where race may decide the
outcome are made during this period. See supra , at 389.
The admissions officers consulted the daily reports which indicated
the composition of the incoming class along racial lines. As Dennis
Shields, Director of Admissions from 1991 to 1996, stated, "the
further [he] went into the [admissions] season the more frequently
[he] would [392] want to look at these [reports] and see the change from
dayto-day." These reports would "track exactly where [the Law
School] st[ood] at any given time in assembling the class," and so
would tell the admissions personnel whether they were short of
assembling a critical mass of minority students. Shields generated
these reports because the Law School's admissions policy told him
the racial makeup of the entering class was "something [he]
need[ed] to be concerned about," and so he had "to find a way of
tracking what's going on." Deposition of Dennis Shields in Civ.
Action No. 9775928, pp. 129-130, 141 (ED Mich., Dec. 7, 1998).
The consultation of daily reports during the last stages in the
admissions process suggests there was no further attempt at
individual review save for race itself. The admissions officers
could use the reports to recalibrate the plus factor given to race
depending on how close they were to achieving the Law School's goal
of critical mass. The bonus factor of race would then become
divorced from individual review; it would be premised instead on
the numerical objective set by the Law School.
The Law School made no effort to guard against this danger. It
provided no guidelines to its admissions personnel on how to
reconcile individual assessment with the directive to admit a
critical mass of minority students. The admissions program could
have been structured to eliminate at least some of the risk that
the promise of individual evaluation was not being kept. The daily
consideration of racial breakdown of admitted students is not a
feature of affirmative-action programs used by other institutions
of higher learning. The Little Ivy League colleges, for instance,
do not keep ongoing tallies of racial or ethnic composition of
their entering students. See Brief for Amherst College et al. as Amici Curiae 10. To be constitutional, a university's compelling interest in a
diverse student body must be achieved by a system where individual
assessment is safeguarded through the entire process. There is no
constitutional objection to the goal of [393] considering race as one modest factor among many others to
achieve diversity, but an educational institution must ensure,
through sufficient procedures, that each applicant receives
individual consideration and that race does not become a
predominant factor in the admissions decisionmaking. The Law School
failed to comply with this requirement, and by no means has it
carried its burden to show otherwise by the test of strict
scrutiny.
The Court's refusal to apply meaningful strict scrutiny will
lead to serious consequences. By deferring to the law schools'
choice of minority admissions programs, the courts will lose the
talents and resources of the faculties and administrators in
devising new and fairer ways to ensure individual consideration.
Constant and rigorous judicial review forces the law school
faculties to undertake their responsibilities as state employees in
this most sensitive of areas with utmost fidelity to the mandate of
the Constitution. Dean Allan Stillwagon, who directed the Law
School's Office of Admissions from 1979 to 1990, explained the
difficulties he encountered in defining racial groups entitled to
benefit under the Law School's affirmative action policy. He
testified that faculty members were "breathtakingly cynical" in
deciding who would qualify as a member of underrepresented
minorities. An example he offered was faculty debate as to whether
Cubans should be counted as Hispanics: One professor objected on
the grounds that Cubans were Republicans. Many academics at other
law schools who are "affirmative action's more forthright defenders
readily concede that diversity is merely the current rationale of
convenience for a policy that they prefer to justify on other
grounds." Schuck, Affirmative Action: Past, Present, and Future, 20
Yale L. & Pol'y Rev. 1, 34 (2002) (citing Levinson, Diversity,
2 U. Pa. J. Const. L. 573, 577-578 (2000); Rubenfeld, Affirmative
Action, 107 Yale L. J. 427, 471 (1997)). This is not to suggest the
faculty at Michigan or other law schools do not pursue aspirations
they consider laudable and consistent with our constitutional [394] traditions. It is but further evidence of the necessity for
scrutiny that is real, not feigned, where the corrosive category of
race is a factor in decisionmaking. Prospective students, the
courts, and the public can demand that the State and its law
schools prove their process is fair and constitutional in every
phase of implementation.
It is difficult to assess the Court's pronouncement that
race-conscious admissions programs will be unnecessary 25 years
from now. Ante , at 341-343. If it is intended to mitigate
the damage the Court does to the concept of strict scrutiny,
neither petitioner nor other rejected law school applicants will
find solace in knowing the basic protection put in place by Justice
Powell will be suspended for a full quarter of a century. Deference
is antithetical to strict scrutiny, not consistent with it.
As to the interpretation that the opinion contains its own
self-destruct mechanism, the majority's abandonment of strict
scrutiny undermines this objective. Were the courts to apply a
searching standard to race-based admissions schemes, that would
force educational institutions to seriously explore race-neutral
alternatives. The Court, by contrast, is willing to be satisfied by
the Law School's profession of its own good faith. The majority
admits as much: "We take the Law School at its word that it would
'like nothing better than to find a race-neutral admissions
formula' and will terminate its race-conscious admissions program
as soon as practicable." Ante , at 343 (quoting Brief for
Respondent Bollinger et al. 34).
If universities are given the latitude to administer programs
that are tantamount to quotas, they will have few incentives to
make the existing minority admissions schemes transparent and
protective of individual review. The unhappy consequence will be to
perpetuate the hostilities that proper consideration of race is
designed to avoid. The perpetuation, of course, would be the worst
of all outcomes. Other programs do exist which will be more
effective in [395] bringing about the harmony and mutual respect among all citizens
that our constitutional tradition has always sought. They, and not
the program under review here, should be the model, even if the
Court defaults by not demanding it.
It is regrettable the Court's important holding allowing racial
minorities to have their special circumstances considered in order
to improve their educational opportunities is accompanied by a
suspension of the strict scrutiny which was the predicate of
allowing race to be considered in the first place. If the Court
abdicates its constitutional duty to give strict scrutiny to the
use of race in university admissions, it negates my authority to
approve the use of race in pursuit of student diversity. The
Constitution cannot confer the right to classify on the basis of
race even in this special context absent searching judicial review.
For these reasons, though I reiterate my approval of giving
appropriate consideration to race in this one context, I must
dissent in the present case.
[ Footnote * ]
Briefs of amici curiae urging reversal were filed for
the State of Florida et al. by Charlie Crist , Attorney
General of Florida, Christopher M. Kise , Solicitor
General, Louis F. Hubener , Deputy Solicitor
General, and Daniel Woodring; for the Cato Institute by Robert A. Levy, Timothy Lynch, James L. Swanson , and Samuel Estreicher; for the Center for Equal Opportunity et
al. by Roger Clegg and C. Mark Pickrell; for the
Center for Individual Freedom by Renee L. Giachino; for
the Center for New Black Leadership by Clint Bolick, William H.
Mellor , and Richard D. Komer; for the Center for the
Advancement of Capitalism by David Reed Burton; for the
Claremont Institute Center for Constitutional Jurisprudence by Edwin Meese III; for the Michigan Association of Scholars
by William F. Mohrman; for the National
Association of Scholars by William H. Allen, Oscar M.
Garibaldi , and Keith A. Noreika; for the Pacific
Legal Foundation by John H. Findley; for Law Professor
Larry Alexander et al. by Erik S. Jaffe; and for
the Reason Foundation by Martin S. Kaufman. Briefs of amici curiae urging affirmance were filed for
the State of Maryland et al. by J. Joseph Curran, Jr. ,
Attorney General of Maryland, Andrew H. Baida , Solicitor
General, Mark J. Davis and William F. Brockman , Assistant Attorneys General, Eliot
Spitzer , Attorney General of New York, Caitlin J. Halligan , Solicitor General, Michelle Aronowitz ,
Deputy Solicitor General, and Julie Mathy Sheridan and Sachin S. Pandya , Assistant Solicitors General,
and by the Attorneys General for their respective jurisdictions as
follows: Terry Goddard of Arizona, Bill Lockyer of California, Ken Salazar of Colorado, Richard
Blumenthal of Connecticut, Lisa Madigan of Illinois, Thomas J. Miller of Iowa, G. Steven Rowe of Maine, Thomas F. Reilly of Massachusetts, Mike Hatch of Minnesota, Mike McGrath of Montana, Patricia A. Madrid of New Mexico, Roy Cooper of
North Carolina, W A. Drew Edmondson of Oklahoma, Hardy
Myers of Oregon, Patrick Lynch of Rhode Island, William H. Sorrell of Vermont, Iver A. Stridiron of the Virgin Islands, Christine Q Gregoire of Washington, Darrell V. McGraw, Jr. , of West Virginia, and Peggy A.
Lautenschlager of Wisconsin; for the State of New Jersey by David Samson , Attorney General, Jeffrey Burstein ,
Assistant Attorney General, and Donna Arons and Anne
Marie Kelly , Deputy Attorneys General; for New York City
Council Speaker A. Gifford Miller et al. by Jack Greenberg and Saul B. Shapiro; for the City of Philadelphia,
Pennsylvania, et al. by Victor A. Bolden and Nelson A.
Diaz; for the American Bar Association by Paul M.
Dodyk and Rowan D. Wilson; for the American
Educational Research Association et al. by Angelo N.
Ancheta; for the American Jewish Committee et al. by Stewart D. Aaron, Thomas M. Jancik, Jeffrey P. Sinensky, Kara
H. Stein , and Richard T. Foltin; for the American Law
Deans Association by Samuel Issacharoff; for the American
Psychological Association by Paul R. Friedman, William F. Sheehan , and Nathalie F. P. Gilfoyle; for the American Sociological Association et al. by Bill Lann
Lee and Deborah J. Merritt; for Amherst
College et al. by Charles S. Sims; for the
Arizona State University College of Law by Ralph S. Spritzer and Paul Bender; for the Association of
American Law Schools by Pamela S. Karlan; for the
Association of American Medical Colleges et al. by Robert A.
Burgoyne and Joseph A. Keyes, Jr.; for the Bay Mills
Indian Community et al. by Vanya S. Hogen; for
the Clinical Legal Education Association by Timothy A. Nelsen,
Frances P. Kao , and Eric J. Gorman; for
Columbia University et al. by Floyd Abrams and Susan
Buckley; for the Graduate Management Admission Council et al.
by Stephen M. McNabb; for the Harvard Black Law Students
Association et al. by George W Jones, Jr., William J. Jefferson, Theodore V. Wells, Jr. , and David W
Brown; for Harvard University et al. by Laurence H. Tribe,
Jonathan S. Massey, Beverly Ledbetter, Robert B.
Donin , and Wendy S. White; for the Hispanic
National Bar Association et al. by Gilbert Paul Carrasco; for Howard University by Janell M. Byrd; for Indiana
University by James Fitzpatrick, Lauren K. Robel , and Jeffrey Evans Stake; for the King County Bar Association
by John Warner Widell, John H. Chun , and Melissa
O'Loughlin White; for the Law School Admission Council by Walter Dellinger, Pamela Harris , and Jonathan D.
Hacker; for the Lawyers' Committee for Civil Rights Under Law
et al. by John S. Skilton, David E. Jones, Barbara R.
Arnwine, Thomas J. Henderson, Dennis C. Hayes,
Marcia D. Greenberger , and Judith L. Lichtman; for
the Leadership Conference on Civil Rights et al. by Robert N.
Weiner and William L. Taylor; for the Mexican
American Legal Defense and Educational Fund et al. by Antonia
Hernandez; for the Michigan Black Law Alumni Society by Christopher J. Wright, Timothy J. Simeone , and Kathleen McCree Lewis; for the NAACP
Legal Defense and Educational Fund, Inc., et al. by Theodore M.
Shaw, Norman J. Chachkin, Robert H. Stroup, Elise C. Boddie , and Christopher A. Hansen; for the
National Center for Fair & Open Testing by John T.
Affeldt and Mark Savage; for the National Coalition
of Blacks for Reparations in America et al. by Kevin
Outterson; for the National Education
Association et al. by Robert H. Chanin, John M. West, Elliot
Mincberg, Larry P. Weinberg , and John C. Dempsey; for the National Urban League et al. by William A. Norris and Michael C. Small; for the New America Alliance by Thomas R. Julin and D.
Patricia Wallace; for the New Mexico Hispanic Bar Association
et al. by Edward Benavidez; for the NOW Legal Defense and
Educational Fund et al. by Wendy R. Weiser and Martha F. Davis; for the School of Law of the
University of North Carolina by John Charles Boger, Julius L.
Chambers , and Charles E. Daye; for the Society of
American Law Teachers by Michael Selmi and Gabriel J. Chin; for the UCLA School of Law
Students of Color by Sonia Mercado; for the United Negro
College Fund et al. by Drew S. Days III and Beth S. Brinkmann; for the University of Michigan
Asian Pacific American Law Students Association et al. by Jerome S. Hirsch; for the University of
Pittsburgh et al. by David C. Frederick and Sean A. Lev; for Judith Areen et al. by Neal
Katyal and Kumiki Gibson; for Lieutenant General
Julius W. Becton, Jr., et al. by Virginia A. Seitz, Joseph R.
Reeder, Robert P. Charrow , and Kevin E. Stern; for
Hillary Browne et al. by Gregory Alan Berry; for Senator
Thomas A. Daschle et al. by David T. Goldberg and Penny Shane; for the Hayden Family by Roy C. Howell; for Glenn C. Loury by Jeffrey F. Liss and James J. Halpert; and for
13,922 Current Law Students at Accredited American Law Schools by Julie R. O'Sullivan and Peter J. Rubin. Briefs of amici curiae were filed for Michigan Governor
Jennifer M. Granholm by John D. Pirich and Mark A.
Goldsmith; for Members and Former Members of the Pennsylvania
General Assembly et al. by Mark B. Cohen and Eric S. Fillman; for the American Council on Education et al.
by Martin Michaelson, Alexander E. Dreier , and Sheldon
E. Steinbach; for the American Federation of Labor and
Congress of Industrial Organizations by Harold Craig Becker,
David J. Strom, Jonathan P. Hiatt , and Daniel W
Sherrick; for the Anti-Defamation League by Martin E.
Karlinsky and Steven M. Freeman; for the Asian
American Legal Foundation by Daniel C. Girard and Gordon M. Fauth, Jr.; for Banks Broadcasting, Inc., by Elizabeth G. Taylor; for the Black Women Lawyers
Association of Greater Chicago, Inc., by Sharon E. Jones; for the Boston Bar Association et al. by Thomas E. Dwyer,
Jr. , and Joseph L. Kociubes; for the Carnegie Mellon
University et al. by W Thomas McGough, Jr., Kathy M. Banke,
Gary L. Kaplan , and Edward N. Stoner II; for the
Coalition for Economic Equity et al. by Eva J. Paterson and Eric K. Yamamoto; for the Committee
of Concerned Black Graduates of ABA Accredited Law Schools et al.
by Mary Mack Adu ; for the Criminal Justice Legal
Foundation by Kent S. Scheidegger ; for the Equal
Employment Advisory Council by Jeffrey A. Norris and Ann Elizabeth Reesman ; for Exxon Mobil Corp. by Richard R. Brann ; for General Motors Corp. by Kenneth
S. Geller , Eileen Penner , and Thomas A.
Gottschalk ; for Human Rights Advocates et al. by Constance
de la Vega ; for the Massachusetts Institute of Technology et
al. by Donald B. Ayer , Elizabeth Rees , Debra
L. Zumwalt , and Stacey J. Mobley ; for the
Massachusetts School of Law by Lawrence R. Velvel ; for the
National Asian Pacific American Legal Consortium et al. by Mark
A. Packman , Karen K. Narasaki , Vincent A.
Eng , and Trang Q. Tran ; for the National School
Boards Association et al. by Julie Underwood and Naomi
Gittins ; for the New York State Black and Puerto Rican
Legislative Caucus by Victor Goode ; for Veterans of the
Southern Civil Rights Movement et al. by Mitchell
Zimmerman ; for 3M et al. by David W DeBruin , Deanne E. Maynard , Daniel Mach , Russell W
Porter, Jr. , Charles R. Wall , Martin J.
Barrington , Deval L. Patrick , William J.
O'Brien , Gary P. Van Graafeiland , Kathryn A.
Oberly , Randall E. Mehrberg , Donald M. Remy , Ben W Heineman, Jr. , Brackett B. Denniston III , Elpidio Villarreal , Wayne A. Budd , J. Richard
Smith , Stewart S. Hudnut , John A. Shutkin , Theodore L. Banks , Kenneth C. Frazier , David
R. Andrews , Jeffrey B. Kinder , Teresa M.
Holland , Charles W Gerdts III , John L.
Sander , Mark P. Klein , and Stephen P.
Sawyer ; for Ward Connerly by Manuel S. Klausner and Patrick J. Manshardt ; for Representative John Conyers,
Jr., et al. by Paul J. Lawrence and Anthony R.
Miles ; and for Representative Richard A. Gephardt et al. by Andrew L. Sandler and Mary L. Smith .
[ Footnote * ]
As the Court explains, the admissions policy challenged here
survives review under the standards stated in Adarand
Constructors, Inc. v. Peña , 515 U. S. 200 (1995), Richmond v. J. A. Croson Co. , 488 U. S. 469 (1989), and
Justice Powell's opinion in Regents of Univ. of Cal. v. Bakke,
438 U. S. 265 (1978). This case therefore does not require the
Court to revisit whether all governmental classifications by race,
whether designed to benefit or to burden a historically
disadvantaged group, should be subject to the same standard of
judicial review. Cf. Gratz, ante , at 301-302 (GINSBURG,
J., dissenting); Adarand , 515 U. S., at 274, n. 8
(GINSBURG, J., dissenting). Nor does this case necessitate
reconsideration whether interests other than "student body
diversity," ante , at 325, rank as sufficiently important
to justify a race-conscious government program. Cf. Gratz,
ante , at 301-302 (GINSBURG, J., dissenting); Adarand ,
515 U. S., at 273-274 (GINSBURG, J., dissenting).
[ Footnote * ]
Part VII of JUSTICE THOMAS'S opinion describes those portions of
the Court's opinion in which I concur. See post , at
374-378 (opinion concurring in part and dissenting in part).
[ Footnote 1 ]
Throughout I will use the two phrases interchangeably.
[ Footnote 2 ]
The Court's refusal to address Wygant's rejection of a
state interest virtually indistinguishable from that presented by
the Law School is perplexing. If the Court defers to the Law
School's judgment that a racially mixed student body confers
educational benefits to all, then why would the Wygant Court not defer to the school board's judgment with respect to the
benefits a racially mixed faculty confers?
[ Footnote 3 ]
"[D]iversity," for all of its devotees, is more a fashionable
catchphrase than it is a useful term, especially when something as
serious as racial discrimination is at issue. Because the Equal
Protection Clause renders the color of one's skin constitutionally
irrelevant to the Law School's mission, I refer to the Law School's
interest as an "aesthetic." That is, the Law School wants to have a
certain appearance, from the shape of the desks and tables in its
classrooms to the color of the students sitting at them.
I also use the term "aesthetic" because I believe it underlines
the ineffectiveness of racially discriminatory admissions in
actually helping those who are truly underprivileged. Cf. Orr
v. Orr , 440 U.
S. 268 , 283 (1979) (noting that suspect classifications are
especially impermissible when "the choice made by the State appears
to redound . . . to the benefit of those without need for
special solicitude"). It must be remembered that the Law School's
racial discrimination does nothing for those too poor or uneducated
to participate in elite higher education and therefore presents
only an illusory solution to the challenges facing our Nation.
[ Footnote 4 ]
The Law School believes both that the educational benefits of a
racially engineered student body are large and that adjusting its
overall admissions standards to achieve the same racial mix would
require it to sacrifice its elite status. If the Law School is
correct that the educational benefits of "diversity" are so great,
then achieving them by altering admissions standards should not
compromise its elite status. The Law School's reluctance to do this
suggests that the educational benefits it alleges are not
significant or do not exist at all.
[ Footnote 5 ]
Cf. U. S. News & World Report, America's Best Graduate
Schools 28 (2004 ed.) (placing these schools in the uppermost 15 in
the Nation).
[ Footnote 6 ]
The Court refers to this component of the Law School's
compelling state interest variously as "academic quality," avoiding
"sacrifice [of] a vital component of its educational mission," and
"academic selectivity." Ante , at 340.
[ Footnote 7 ]
For example, North Carolina A&T State University, which is
currently 5.4% white, College Admissions Data Handbook 643, could
seek to reduce the representation of whites in order to gain
additional educational benefits.
[ Footnote 8 ]
Cal. Const., Art. 1, § 31(a), states in full:
"The state shall not discriminate against, or grant preferential
treatment to, any individual or group on the basis of race, sex,
color, ethnicity, or national origin in the operation of public
employment, public education, or public contracting." See Coalition for Economic Equity v. Wilson , 122 F.3d 692 (CA9
1997).
[ Footnote 9 ]
Given the incredible deference the Law School receives from the
Court, I think it appropriate to indulge in the presumption that
Boalt Hall operates without violating California law.
[ Footnote 10 ]
Were this Court to have the courage to forbid the use of racial
discrimination in admissions, legacy preferences (and similar
practices) might quickly become less popular-a possibility not
lost, I am certain, on the elites (both individual and
institutional) supporting the Law School in this case.
[ Footnote 11 ]
For example, there is no recognition by the Law School in this
case that even with their racial discrimination in place, black men are "underrepresented" at the Law School. See ABA-LSAC
Guide 426 (reporting that the Law School has 46 black women and 28
black men). Why does the Law School not also discriminate in favor
of black men over black women, given this underrepresentation? The
answer is, again, that all the Law School cares about is its own
image among know-it-all elites, not solving real problems like the
crisis of black male underperformance.
[ Footnote 12 ]
That interest depends on enrolling a "critical mass" of
underrepresented minority students, as the majority repeatedly
states. Ante , at 316, 318, 319, 330, 333, 335, 340; cf. ante , at 333 (referring to the unique experience of being
a "racial minority," as opposed to being black, or Native
American); ante , at 335-336 (rejecting argument that the
Law School maintains a disguised quota by referring to the total
number of enrolled underrepresented minority students, not specific
races). As it relates to the Law School's racial discrimination,
the Court clearly approves of only one use of race-the distinction
between underrepresented minority applicants and those of all other
races. A relative preference awarded to a black applicant over, for
example, a similarly situated Native American applicant, does not
lead to the enrollment of even one more underrepresented minority
student, but only balances the races within the "critical
mass."
[ Footnote 13 ]
I agree with JUSTICE GINSBURG that the Court's holding that
racial discrimination in admissions will be illegal in 25 years is
not based upon a "forecast," post , at 346 (concurring
opinion). I do not agree with JUSTICE GINSBURG'S characterization
of the Court's holding as an expression of "hope." Ibid. [ Footnote 14 ]
14 I use a score of 165 as the benchmark here because the Law
School feels it is the relevant score range for applicant
consideration (absent race discrimination). See Brief for
Respondent Bollinger et al. 5; App. to Pet. for Cert. 309a (showing
that the median LSAT score for all accepted applicants from
1995-1998 was 168); id. , at 310a-311a (showing the median
LSAT score for accepted applicants was 167 for the years 1999 and
2000); University of Michigan Law School Website, available at
http://www.law.umich.edu/prospectivestudents/Admissions/index.htm
(showing that the median LSAT score for accepted applicants in 2002
was 166).
[ Footnote 15 ]
15 The majority's non sequitur observation that since 1978 the
number of blacks that have scored in these upper ranges on the LSAT
has grown, ante , at 343, says nothing about current
trends. First, black participation in the LSAT until the early
1990's lagged behind black representation in the general
population. For instance, in 1984 only 7.3% of law school
applicants were black, whereas in 2000 11.3% oflaw school
applicants were black. See LSAC Statistical Reports (1984 and
2000). Today, however, unless blacks were to begin applying to law
school in proportions greater than their representation in the
general population, the growth in absolute numbers of high scoring
blacks should be expected to plateau, and it has.
In 1992, 63 black applicants to law school had LSAT scores above
165. In 2000, that number was 65. See LSAC Statistical Reports
(1992 and 2000).
[ Footnote 16 ]
16 I use the LSAT as an example, but the same incentive
structure is in place for any admissions criteria, including
undergraduate grades, on which minorities are consistently admitted
at thresholds significantly lower than whites.
[ Footnote * ]
Indeed, during this 5-year time period, enrollment of Native
American students dropped to as low as three such
students. Any assertion that such a small group constituted a
"critical mass" of Native Americans is simply absurd. | The University of Michigan Law School's admissions policy, which considers race as a factor, was challenged by a white applicant who claimed racial discrimination. The court ruled that the Law School's use of race was unlawful, but the Sixth Circuit reversed, citing diversity as a compelling state interest and the policy as narrowly tailored. The Supreme Court affirmed, finding that the Law School's use of race was necessary to further a compelling interest in obtaining the educational benefits of a diverse student body and was narrowly tailored to achieve that goal. The court emphasized that the Law School's policy was flexible and individualized, treating each applicant as a unique person, and did not operate as a quota. However, Justice Thomas dissented, arguing that the Law School's use of race was not narrowly tailored and that the court's decision perpetuated racial discrimination. |
Equal Protection | U.S. v. Virginia | https://supreme.justia.com/cases/federal/us/518/515/ | OCTOBER TERM, 1995
Syllabus
UNITED STATES v. VIRGINIA ET AL.
CERTIORARI TO THE UNITED STATES COURT OF APPEALS FOR THE FOURTH
CIRCUIT
No.94-1941. Argued January 17, 1996-Decided June 26,1996*
Virginia Military Institute (VMI) is the sole single-sex school
among Virginia's public institutions of higher learning. VMI's
distinctive mission is to produce "citizen-soldiers," men prepared
for leadership in civilian life and in military service. Using an
"adversative method" of training not available elsewhere in
Virginia, VMI endeavors to instill physical and mental discipline
in its cadets and impart to them a strong moral code. Reflecting
the high value alumni place on their VMI training, VMI has the
largest per-student endowment of all public undergraduate
institutions in the Nation. The United States sued Virginia and
VMI, alleging that VMI's exclusively male admission policy violated
the Fourteenth Amendment's Equal Protection Clause. The District
Court ruled in VMI's favor. The Fourth Circuit reversed and ordered
Virginia to remedy the constitutional violation. In response,
Virginia proposed a parallel program for women: Virginia Women's
Institute for Leadership (VWIL), located at Mary Baldwin College, a
private liberal arts school for women. The District Court found
that Virginia's proposal satisfied the Constitution's equal
protection requirement, and the Fourth Circuit affirmed. The
appeals court deferentially reviewed Virginia's plan and determined
that provision of single-gender educational options was a
legitimate objective. Maintenance of single-sex programs, the court
concluded, was essential to that objective. The court recognized,
however, that its analysis risked bypassing equal protection
scrutiny, so it fashioned an additional test, asking whether VMI
and VWIL students would receive "substantively comparable"
benefits. Although the Court of Appeals acknowledged that the VWIL
degree lacked the historical benefit and prestige of a VMI degree,
the court nevertheless found the educational opportunities at the
two schools sufficiently comparable.
Held:
1. Parties who seek to defend gender-based government action
must demonstrate an "exceedingly persuasive justification" for that
action. E. g., Mississippi Univ. for Women v. Hogan, 458 U. S.
718 ,724. Nei-
*Together with No. 94-2107, Virginia et al. v. United
States, also on certiorari to the same court. 516 Syllabus
ther federal nor state government acts compatibly with equal
protection when a law or official policy denies to women, simply
because they are women, full citizenship stature-equal opportunity
to aspire, achieve, participate in and contribute to society based
on their individual talents and capacities. To meet the burden of
justification, a State must show "at least that the [challenged]
classification serves 'important governmental objectives and that
the discriminatory means employed' are 'substantially related to
the achievement of those objectives.''' Ibid., quoting Wengler v. Druggists Mut. Ins. Co., 446 U. S. 142 , 150. The
justification must be genuine, not hypothesized or invented post
hoc in response to litigation. And it must not rely on
overbroad generalizations about the different talents, capacities,
or preferences of males and females. See, e. g., Weinberger v. Wiesenfeld, 420 U. S. 636 , 643, 648.
The heightened review standard applicable to sex-based
classifications does not make sex a proscribed classification, but
it does mean that categorization by sex may not be used to create
or perpetuate the legal, social, and economic inferiority of women.
pp. 531-534.
2. Virginia's categorical exclusion of women from the
educational opportunities VMI provides denies equal protection to
women. Pp. 534-546.
(a) Virginia contends that single-sex education yields important
educational benefits and that provision of an option for such
education fosters diversity in educational approaches. Benign
justifications proffered in defense of categorical exclusions,
however, must describe actual state purposes, not rationalizations
for actions in fact differently grounded. Virginia has not shown
that VMI was established, or has been maintained, with a view to
diversifying, by its categorical exclusion of women, educational
opportunities within the Commonwealth. A purpose genuinely to
advance an array of educational options is not served by VMI's
historic and constant plan to afford a unique educational benefit
only to males. However well this plan serves Virginia's sons, it
makes no provision whatever for her daughters. Pp. 535-540.
(b) Virginia also argues that VMI's adversative method of
training provides educational benefits that cannot be made
available, unmodified, to women, and that alterations to
accommodate women would necessarily be so drastic as to destroy
VMI's program. It is uncontested that women's admission to VMI
would require accommodations, primarily in arranging housing
assignments and physical training programs for female cadets. It is
also undisputed, however, that neither the goal of producing
citizen-soldiers, VMI's raison d'etre, nor VMI's
implementing methodology is inherently unsuitable to women. The
District Court made "findings" on "gender-based developmental
differences" that restate the opinions of Virginia's expert
witnesses about typically male or typically female "tendencies."
Courts, however, must take "a hard 517 look" at generalizations or tendencies of the kind Virginia
pressed, for state actors controlling gates to opportunity have no
warrant to exclude qualified individuals based on "fixed notions
concerning the roles and abilities of males and females." Mississippi Univ. for Women, 458 U. S., at 725. The notion
that admission of women would downgrade VMI's stature, destroy the
adversative system and, with it, even the school, is a judgment
hardly proved, a prediction hardly different from other
"self-fulfilling prophec[ies], see id., at 730, once
routinely used to deny rights or opportunities. Women's successful
entry into the federal military academies, and their participation
in the Nation's military forces, indicate that Virginia's fears for
VMI's future may not be solidly grounded. The Commonwealth's
justification for excluding all women from "citizen-soldier"
training for which some are qualified, in any event, does not rank
as "exceedingly persuasive." Pp. 540-546.
3. The remedy proffered by Virginia-maintain VMI as a male-only
college and create VWIL as a separate program for women-does not
cure the constitutional violation. Pp. 546-558.
(a) A remedial decree must closely fit the constitutional
violation; it must be shaped to place persons unconstitutionally
denied an opportunity or advantage in the position they would have
occupied in the absence of discrimination. See Milliken v. Bradley, 433
U. S. 267 , 280. The constitutional violation in this case is
the categorical exclusion of women, in disregard of their
individual merit, from an extraordinary educational opportunity
afforded men. Virginia chose to leave untouched VMI's exclusionary
policy, and proposed for women only a separate program, different
in kind from VMI and unequal in tangible and intangible facilities.
VWIL affords women no opportunity to experience the rigorous
military training for which VMI is famed. Kept away from the
pressures, hazards, and psychological bonding characteristic of
VMI's adversative training, VWIL students will not know the feeling
of tremendous accomplishment commonly experienced by VMI's
successful cadets. Virginia maintains that methodological
differences are justified by the important differences between men
and women in learning and developmental needs, but generalizations
about "the way women are," estimates of what is appropriate for most women, no longer justify denying opportunity to women
whose talent and capacity place them outside the average
description. In myriad respects other than military training, VWIL
does not qualify as VMI's equal. The VWIL program is a pale shadow
of VMI in terms of the range of curricular choices and faculty
stature, funding, prestige, alumni support and influence. Virginia
has not shown substantial equality in the separate educational
opportunities the Commonwealth supports at VWIL and VMI. Cf. Sweatt v. Painter, 339 U. S. 629 . Pp.
547-554. 518 Syllabus
(b) The Fourth Circuit failed to inquire whether the proposed
remedy placed women denied the VMI advantage in the position they
would have occupied in the absence of discrimination, Milliken, 433 U. S., at 280, and considered instead whether
the Commonwealth could provide, with fidelity to equal protection,
separate and unequal educational programs for men and women. In
declaring the substantially different and significantly unequal
VWIL program satisfactory, the appeals court displaced the exacting
standard developed by this Court with a deferential standard, and
added an inquiry of its own invention, the "substantive
comparability" test. The Fourth Circuit plainly erred in exposing
Virginia's VWIL plan to such a deferential analysis, for "all
genderbased classifications today" warrant "heightened scrutiny."
See J. E. B. v. Alabama ex rel. T. B., 511 U. S. 127 ,
136. Women seeking and fit for a VMI-quality education cannot be
offered anything less, under the Commonwealth's obligation to
afford them genuinely equal protection. Pp. 554-558.
No. 94-2107, 976 F.2d
890 , affirmed; No. 94-1941, 44 F.3d
1229 , reversed and remanded.
GINSBURG, J., delivered the opinion of the Court, in which
STEVENS, O'CONNOR, KENNEDY, SOUTER, and BREYER, JJ., joined.
REHNQUIST, C. J., filed an opinion concurring in the judgment, post, p. 558. SCALIA, J., filed a dissenting opinion, post, p. 566. THOMAS, J., took no part in the consideration
or decision of the case.
Paul Bender argued the cause for the United States in both
cases. With him on the briefs were Solicitor General Days,
Assistant Attorney General Patrick, Cornelia T. L. Pillard, Jessica
Dunsay Silver, and Thomas E. Chandler.
Theodore B. Olson argued the cause and filed briefs for
respondents in No. 94-1941 and petitioners in No. 94-2107. With him
on the briefs were James S. Gilmore III, Attorney General of
Virginia, William H. Hurd, Deputy Attorney General, Thomas G.
Hungar, D. Jarrett Arp, Robert H. Patterson, Jr., Anne Marie
Whittemore, William G. Broaddus, J. William Boland, Griffin
B. Bell, and William A. Clineburg, Jr.t
tBriefs of amici curiae urging reversal in No. 94-1941
were filed for the State of Maryland et al. by J. Joseph
Curran, Jr., Attorney General of Maryland, and Andrew H.
Baida, Assistant Attorney General, and by the Attorneys General
for their respective jurisdictions as follows: Margery 519 JUSTICE GINSBURG delivered the opinion of the Court. Virginia's
public institutions of higher learning include an incomparable
military college, Virginia Military Institute (VMI). The United
States maintains that the Constitution's equal protection guarantee
precludes Virginia from reserving exclusively to men the unique
educational opportunities VMI affords. We agree.
S. Bronster of Hawaii, Scott Harshbarger of Massachusetts,
Frankie Sue Del Papa of Nevada, C. Sebastian Aloot of the Northern
Mariana Islands, and Theodore R. Kulongoski of Oregon; for the
Employment Law Center et al. by Patricia A. Shiu and Judith Kurtz;
and for the National Women's Law Center et al. by Robert N. Weiner,
Marcia D. Greenberger, Sara L. Mandelbaum, Janet Gallagher, Mary
Wyckoff, Steven R. Shapiro, and Susan Deller Ross.
Briefs of amici curiae urging affirmance in No. 94-1941
were filed for the State of South Carolina et al. by Charles
Molony Condon, Attorney General, Treva Ashworth, Deputy
Attorney General, Kenneth P. Woodington, Senior Assistant
Attorney General, Reginald I. Lloyd, Assistant Attorney
General, and M. Dawes Cooke, Jr.; and for Kenneth E. Clark
et al. by James C. Roberts and George A.
Somerville. Briefs of amici curiae were filed in both cases for the
State of Wyoming et al. by William U. Hill, Attorney General
of Wyoming, Thomas W Corbett, Jr., Attorney General of
Pennsylvania, and Bradley B. Cavedo; for Bennett College et
al. by Wendy S. White; for the Center for Military
Readiness et al. by Mellissa Wells-Petry and Jordan W
Lorence; for the Employment Law Center et al. by Patricia A.
Shiu and Judith Kurtz; for the Independent Women's Forum
et al. by Anita K. Blair and C. Douglas Welty; for
Mary Baldwin College by Craig T. Merritt and Richard K.
Willard; for the South Carolina Institute of Leadership for
Women by Julianne Farnsworth; for Wells College et al. by David M. Lascell; for Women's Schools Together, Inc., et al.
by John C. Danforth and Thomas C. Walsh; and for Nancy Mellette by Valorie K. Vojdik, Henry
Weisburg, Suzanne E. Coe, and Robert R. Black. Briefs of amici curiae were filed in No. 94-1941 for the
American Association of University Professors et al. by Joan E.
Bertin and Ann H. Franke; and for Rhonda Cornum et al.
by Allan L. Gropper. Daniel F. Kolb, Herbert J. Hansell, Paul C. Saunders,
Norman Redlich, Barbara R. Arnwine, Thomas J. Henderson, and
Richard T. Seymour filed a brief for the Lawyers' Committee for
Civil Rights Under Law as amicus curiae in No. 94-2107. 520 I
Founded in 1839, VMI is today the sole single-sex school among
Virginia's 15 public institutions of higher learning. VMI's
distinctive mission is to produce "citizen-soldiers," men prepared
for leadership in civilian life and in military service. VMI
pursues this mission through pervasive training of a kind not
available anywhere else in Virginia. Assigning prime place to
character development, VMI uses an "adversative method" modeled on
English public schools and once characteristic of military
instruction. VMI constantly endeavors to instill physical and
mental discipline in its cadets and impart to them a strong moral
code. The school's graduates leave VMI with heightened
comprehension of their capacity to deal with duress and stress, and
a large sense of accomplishment for completing the hazardous
course.
VMI has notably succeeded in its mission to produce leaders;
among its alumni are military generals, Members of Congress, and
business executives. The school's alumni overwhelmingly perceive
that their VMI training helped them to realize their personal
goals. VMI's endowment reflects the loyalty of its graduates; VMI
has the largest per-student endowment of all public undergraduate
institutions in the Nation.
N either the goal of producing citizen-soldiers nor VMI's
implementing methodology is inherently unsuitable to women. And the
school's impressive record in producing leaders has made admission
desirable to some women. Nevertheless, Virginia has elected to
preserve exclusively for men the advantages and opportunities a VMI
education affords.
II A
From its establishment in 1839 as one of the Nation's first
state military colleges, see 1839 Va. Acts, ch. 20, VMI has
remained financially supported by Virginia and "subject to 521 the control of the [Virginia] General Assembly," Va. Code Ann. §
23-92 (1993). First southern college to teach engineering and
industrial chemistry, see H. Wise, Drawing Out the Man: The VMI
Story 13 (1978) (The VMI Story), VMI once provided teachers for the
Commonwealth's schools, see 1842 Va. Acts, ch. 24, § 2 (requiring
every cadet to teach in one of the Commonwealth's schools for a
2-year period).l Civil War strife threatened the school's vitality,
but a resourceful superintendent regained legislative support by
highlighting "VMI's great potential[,] through its technical
know-how," to advance Virginia's postwar recovery. The VMI Story
47.
VMI today enrolls about 1,300 men as cadets.2 Its academic
offerings in the liberal arts, sciences, and engineering are also
available at other public colleges and universities in Virginia.
But VMI's mission is special. It is the mission of the school "'to produce educated and honorable men, prepared for the varied
work of civil life, imbued with love of learning, confident in the
functions and attitudes of leadership, possessing a high sense of
public service, advocates of the American democracy and free
enterprise system, and ready as citizen-soldiers to defend their
country in 1 During the Civil War, school teaching became a field dominated
by women. See A. Scott, The Southern Lady: From Pedestal to
Politics, 1830-1930, p. 82 (1970).
2 Historically, most of Virginia's public colleges and
universities were single sex; by the mid-1970's, however, all
except VMI had become coeducational. 766 F. Supp. 1407, 1418-1419
(WD Va. 1991). For example, Virginia's legislature incorporated
Farmville Female Seminary Association in 1839, the year VMI opened.
1839 Va. Acts, ch. 167. Originally providing instruction in
"English, Latin, Greek, French, and piano" in a "home atmosphere,"
R. Sprague, Longwood College: A History 7-8, 15 (1989) (Longwood
College), Farmville Female Seminary became a public institution in
1884 with a mission to train "white female teachers for public
schools," 1884 Va. Acts, ch. 311. The school became Longwood
College in 1949, Longwood College 136, and introduced coeducation
in 1976, id., at 133. 522 time of national periL'" 766 F. Supp. 1407, 1425 (WD Va. 1991)
(quoting Mission Study Committee of the VMI Board of Visitors,
Report, May 16, 1986). In contrast to the federal service academies, institutions
maintained "to prepare cadets for career service in the armed
forces," VMI's program "is directed at preparation for both
military and civilian life"; "[o]nly about 15% of VMI cadets enter
career military service." 766 F. Supp., at 1432.
VMI produces its "citizen-soldiers" through "an adversative, or
doubting, model of education" which features "[p]hysical rigor,
mental stress, absolute equality of treatment, absence of privacy,
minute regulation of behavior, and indoctrination in desirable
values." Id., at 1421. As one Commandant of Cadets described
it, the adversative method "'dissects the young student,'" and
makes him aware of his "'limits and capabilities,'" so that he
knows "'how far he can go with his anger, ... how much he can take
under stress, ... exactly what he can do when he is physically
exhausted.'" Id., at 1421-1422 (quoting Col. N.
Bissell).
VMI cadets live in spartan barracks where surveillance is
constant and privacy nonexistent; they wear uniforms, eat together
in the mess hall, and regularly participate in drills. Id., at 1424, 1432. Entering students are incessantly exposed to the rat
line, "an extreme form of the adversative model," comparable in
intensity to Marine Corps boot camp. Id., at 1422.
Tormenting and punishing, the rat line bonds new cadets to their
fellow sufferers and, when they have completed the 7 -month
experience, to their former tormentors. Ibid. VMI's "adversative model" is further characterized by a
hierarchical "class system" of privileges and responsibilities, a
"dyke system" for assigning a senior class mentor to each entering
class "rat," and a stringently enforced "honor code," which
prescribes that a cadet" 'does not lie, cheat, steal nor tolerate
those who do.'" Id., at 1422-1423. 523 VMI attracts some applicants because of its reputation as an
extraordinarily challenging military school, and "because its
alumni are exceptionally close to the school." Id., at 1421.
"[W]omen have no opportunity anywhere to gain the benefits of [the
system of education at VMI]." Ibid. B
In 1990, prompted by a complaint filed with the Attorney General
by a female high-school student seeking admission to VMI, the
United States sued the Commonwealth of Virginia and VMI, alleging
that VMI's exclusively male admission policy violated the Equal
Protection Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment. Id., at
1408.3 Trial of the action consumed six days and involved an array
of expert witnesses on each side. Ibid. In the two years preceding the lawsuit, the District Court
noted, VMI had received inquiries from 347 women, but had responded
to none of them. Id., at 1436. "[S]ome women, at least," the
court said, "would want to attend the school if they had the
opportunity." Id., at 1414. The court further recognized
that, with recruitment, VMI could "achieve at least 10% female
enrollment"-"a sufficient 'critical mass' to provide the female
cadets with a positive educational experience." Id., at
1437-1438. And it was also established that "some women are capable
of all of the individual activities required of VMI cadets." Id., at 1412. In addition, experts agreed that if VMI
admitted women, "the VMI ROTC experience would become a better
training program from the perspective of the armed forces, because
it would provide training in dealing with a mixed-gender army." Id., at 1441.
The District Court ruled in favor of VMI, however, and rejected
the equal protection challenge pressed by the United States. That
court correctly recognized that Mississippi Univ. for Women v. Hogan, 458
U. S. 718 (1982), was
3 The District Court allowed the VMI Foundation and the VMI
Alumni Association to intervene as defendants. 766 F. Supp., at
1408. 524 the closest guide. 766 F. Supp., at 1410. There, this Court
underscored that a party seeking to uphold government action based
on sex must establish an "exceedingly persuasive justification" for
the classification. Mississippi Univ. for Women, 458 U. S.,
at 724 (internal quotation marks omitted). To succeed, the defender
of the challenged action must show "at least that the
classification serves important governmental objectives and that
the discriminatory means employed are substantially related to the
achievement of those objectives." Ibid. (internal quotation
marks omitted).
The District Court reasoned that education in "a singlegender
environment, be it male or female," yields substantial benefits.
766 F. Supp., at 1415. VMI's school for men brought diversity to an
otherwise coeducational Virginia system, and that diversity was
"enhanced by VMI's unique method of instruction." Ibid. If
single-gender education for males ranks as an important
governmental objective, it becomes obvious, the District Court
concluded, that the only means of achieving the objective
"is to exclude women from the all-male institution- VMI." Ibid. "Women are [indeed] denied a unique educational opportunity that
is available only at VMI," the District Court acknowledged. Id., at 1432. But "[VMI's] single-sex status would be lost,
and some aspects of the [school's] distinctive method would be
altered," if women were admitted, id., at 1413: "Allowance
for personal privacy would have to be made," id., at 1412;
"[p]hysical education requirements would have to be altered, at
least for the women," id., at 1413; the adversative
environment could not survive unmodified, id., at 1412-1413.
Thus, "sufficient constitutional justification" had been shown, the
District Court held, "for continuing [VMI's] single-sex policy." Id., at 1413.
The Court of Appeals for the Fourth Circuit disagreed and
vacated the District Court's judgment. The appellate court held:
"The Commonwealth of Virginia has not ... advanced any state policy
by which it can justify its determination, 525 under an announced policy of diversity, to afford VMI's unique
type of program to men and not to women." 976
The appeals court greeted with skepticism Virginia's assertion
that it offers single-sex education at VMI as a facet of the
Commonwealth's overarching and undisputed policy to advance
"autonomy and diversity." The court underscored Virginia's
nondiscrimination commitment: "'[I]t is extremely important that
[colleges and universities] deal with faculty, staff, and students without regard to sex, race, or ethnic origin.'" Id., at 899
(quoting 1990 Report of the Virginia Commission on the University
of the 21st Century). "That statement," the Court of Appeals said,
"is the only explicit one that we have found in the record in which
the Commonwealth has expressed itself with respect to gender
distinctions." 976 F. 2d, at 899. Furthermore, the appeals court
observed, in urging "diversity" to justify an all-male VMI, the
Commonwealth had supplied "no explanation for the movement away
from [single-sex education] in Virginia by public colleges and
universities." Ibid. In short, the court concluded, "[a]
policy of diversity which aims to provide an array of educational
opportunities, including single-gender institutions, must do more
than favor one gender." Ibid. The parties agreed that "some women can meet the physical
standards now imposed on men," id., at 896, and the court
was satisfied that "neither the goal of producing citizen soldiers
nor VMI's implementing methodology is inherently unsuitable to
women," id., at 899. The Court of Appeals, however, accepted
the District Court's finding that "at least these three aspects of
VMI's program-physical training, the absence of privacy, and the
adversative approach-would be materially affected by coeducation." Id., at 896-897. Remanding the case, the appeals court
assigned to Virginia, in the first instance, responsibility for
selecting a remedial course. The court suggested these options for
the Commonwealth: Admit women to VMI; establish parallel
institutions 526 or programs; or abandon state support, leaving VMI free to
pursue its policies as a private institution. Id., at 900.
In May 1993, this Court denied certiorari. See 508 U. S. 946; see
also ibid. (opinion of SCALIA, J., noting the interlocutory
posture of the litigation).
C
In response to the Fourth Circuit's ruling, Virginia proposed a
parallel program for women: Virginia Women's Institute for
Leadership (VWIL). The 4-year, state-sponsored undergraduate
program would be located at Mary Baldwin College, a private liberal
arts school for women, and would be open, initially, to about 25 to
30 students. Although VWIL would share VMI's mission-to produce
"citizensoldiers" -the VWIL program would differ, as does Mary
Baldwin College, from VMI in academic offerings, methods of
education, and financial resources. See 852 F. Supp. 471, 476-477
(WD Va. 1994).
The average combined SAT score of entrants at Mary Baldwin is
about 100 points lower than the score for VMI freshmen. See id., at 501. Mary Baldwin's faculty holds "significantly
fewer Ph. D.'s than the faculty at VMI," id., at 502, and
receives significantly lower salaries, see Tr. 158 (testimony of
James Lott, Dean of Mary Baldwin College), reprinted in 2 App. in
Nos. 94-1667 and 94-1717 (CA4) (hereinafter Tr.). While VMI offers
degrees in liberal arts, the sciences, and engineering, Mary
Baldwin, at the time of trial, offered only bachelor of arts
degrees. See 852 F. Supp., at 503. A VWIL student seeking to earn
an engineering degree could gain one, without public support, by
attending Washington University in St. Louis, Missouri, for two
years, paying the required private tuition. See ibid. Experts in educating women at the college level composed the
Task Force charged with designing the VWIL program; Task Force
members were drawn from Mary Baldwin's own faculty and staff. Id., at 476. Training its attention on methods of
instruction appropriate for "most women," the 527 Task Force determined that a military model would be "wholly
inappropriate" for VWIL. Ibid.; see 44
F.3d 1229 , 1233 (CA4 1995).
VWIL students would participate in ROTC programs and a newly
established, "largely ceremonial" Virginia Corps of Cadets, id., at 1234, but the VWIL House would not have a military
format, 852 F. Supp., at 477, and VWIL would not require its
students to eat meals together or to wear uniforms during the
schoolday, id., at 495. In lieu of VMI's adversative method,
the VWIL Task Force favored "a cooperative method which reinforces
self-esteem." Id., at 476. In addition to the standard
bachelor of arts program offered at Mary Baldwin, VWIL students
would take courses in leadership, complete an off-campus leadership
externship, participate in community service projects, and assist
in arranging a speaker series. See 44 F. 3d, at 1234.
Virginia represented that it will provide equal financial
support for in-state VWIL students and VMI cadets, 852 F. Supp., at
483, and the VMI Foundation agreed to supply a $5.4625 million
endowment for the VWIL program, id., at 499. Mary Baldwin's
own endowment is about $19 million; VMI's is $131 million. Id., at 503. Mary Baldwin will add $35 million to its
endowment based on future commitments; VMI will add $220 million. Ibid. The VMI Alumni Association has developed a network of
employers interested in hiring VMI graduates. The Association has
agreed to open its network to VWIL graduates, id., at 499,
but those graduates will not have the advantage afforded by a VMI
degree.
D
Virginia returned to the District Court seeking approval of its
proposed remedial plan, and the court decided the plan met the
requirements of the Equal Protection Clause. Id., at 473.
The District Court again acknowledged evidentiary support for these
determinations: "[T]he VMI methodology could be used to educate
women and, in fact, some 528 women ... may prefer the VMI methodology to the VWIL
methodology." Id., at 481. But the "controlling legal
principles," the District Court decided, "do not require the
Commonwealth to provide a mirror image VMI for women." Ibid. The court anticipated that the two schools would "achieve
substantially similar outcomes." Ibid. It concluded: "If VMI
marches to the beat of a drum, then Mary Baldwin marches to the
melody of a fife and when the march is over, both will have arrived
at the same destination." Id., at 484.
A divided Court of Appeals affirmed the District Court's
judgment. 44 F.3d
1229 (CA4 1995). This time, the appellate court determined to
give "greater scrutiny to the selection of means than to the
[Commonwealth's] proffered objective." Id., at 1236. The
official objective or purpose, the court said, should be reviewed
deferentially. Ibid. Respect for the "legislative will," the
court reasoned, meant that the judiciary should take a "cautious
approach," inquiring into the "legitima[cy]" of the governmental
objective and refusing approval for any purpose revealed to be
"pernicious." Ibid. "[P]roviding the option of a single-gender college education may
be considered a legitimate and important aspect of a public system
of higher education," the appeals court observed, id., at
1238; that objective, the court added, is "not pernicious," id., at 1239. Moreover, the court continued, the adversative
method vital to a VMI education "has never been tolerated in a
sexually heterogeneous environment." Ibid. The method itself
"was not designed to exclude women," the court noted, but women
could not be accommodated in the VMI program, the court believed,
for female participation in VMI's adversative training "would
destroy ... any sense of decency that still permeates the
relationship between the sexes." Ibid. Having determined, deferentially, the legitimacy of Virginia's
purpose, the court considered the question of means. 529 Exclusion of "men at Mary Baldwin College and women at VMI," the
court said, was essential to Virginia's purpose, for without such
exclusion, the Commonwealth could not "accomplish [its] objective
of providing single-gender education." Ibid. The court recognized that, as it analyzed the case, means merged
into end, and the merger risked "bypass[ing] any equal protection
scrutiny." Id., at 1237. The court therefore added another
inquiry, a decisive test it called "substantive comparability." Ibid. The key question, the court said, was whether men at
VMI and women at VWIL would obtain "substantively comparable
benefits at their institution or through other means offered by the
[S]tate." Ibid. Although the appeals court recognized that
the VWIL degree "lacks the historical benefit and prestige" of a
VMI degree, it nevertheless found the educational opportunities at
the two schools "sufficiently comparable." Id., at 1241.
Senior Circuit Judge Phillips dissented. The court, in his
judgment, had not held Virginia to the burden of showing an
"'exceedingly persuasive [justification]''' for the Commonwealth's
action. Id., at 1247 (quoting Mississippi Univ. for
Women, 458 U. S., at 724). In Judge Phillips' view, the court had
accepted "rationalizations compelled by the exigencies of this
litigation," and had not confronted the Commonwealth's "actual
overriding purpose." 44 F. 3d, at 1247. That purpose, Judge
Phillips said, was clear from the historical record; it was "not to
create a new type of educational opportunity for women, ... nor to
further diversify the Commonwealth's higher education system[,] ...
but [was] simply ... to allow VMI to continue to exclude women in
order to preserve its historic character and mission." Ibid. Judge Phillips suggested that the Commonwealth would satisfy the
Constitution's equal protection requirement if it "simultaneously
opened single-gender undergraduate institutions having
substantially comparable curricular and extra-curricular programs,
funding, physical plant, adminis- 530 tration and support services, and faculty and library
resources." Id., at 1250. But he thought it evident that the
proposed VWIL program, in comparison to VMI, fell "far short ...
from providing substantially equal tangible and intangible
educational benefits to men and women." Ibid. The Fourth Circuit denied rehearing en bane. 52 F.3d
90 (1995). Circuit Judge Motz, joined by Circuit Judges Hall,
Murnaghan, and Michael, filed a dissenting opinion.4 Judge Motz
agreed with Judge Phillips that Virginia had not shown an
"'exceedingly persuasive justification'" for the disparate
opportunities the Commonwealth supported. Id., at 92
(quoting Mississippi Univ. for Women, 458 U. S., at 724).
She asked: "[H]ow can a degree from a yet to be implemented
supplemental program at Mary Baldwin be held 'substantively
comparable' to a degree from a venerable Virginia military
institution that was established more than 150 years ago?" 52 F.
3d, at 93. "Women need not be guaranteed equal 'results,'" Judge
Motz said, "but the Equal Protection Clause does require equal
opportunity ... [and] that opportunity is being denied here." Ibid. III
The cross-petitions in this suit present two ultimate issues.
First, does Virginia's exclusion of women from the educational
opportunities provided by VMI -extraordinary opportunities for
military training and civilian leadership development-deny to women
"capable of all of the individual activities required of VMI
cadets," 766 F. Supp., at 1412, the equal protection of the laws
guaranteed by the Fourteenth Amendment? Second, if VMI's "unique"
situation, id., at 1413-as Virginia's sole single-sex public
institution of
4 Six judges voted to rehear the case en banc, four voted
against rehearing, and three were recused. The Fourth Circuit's
local Rule permits rehearing en banc only on the vote of a majority
of the Circuit's judges in regular active service (currently 13)
without regard to recusals. See 52 F. 3d, at 91, and n. 1. 531 higher education-offends the Constitution's equal protection
principle, what is the remedial requirement?
IV
We note, once again, the core instruction of this Court's
pathmarking decisions in J. E. B. v. Alabama ex
rel. T. B., 511
U. S. 127 , 136-137, and n. 6 (1994), and Mississippi Univ.
for Women, 458 U. S., at 724 (internal quotation marks
omitted): Parties who seek to defend gender-based government action
must demonstrate an "exceedingly persuasive justification" for that
action.
Today's skeptical scrutiny of official action denying rights or
opportunities based on sex responds to volumes of history. As a
plurality of this Court acknowledged a generation ago, "our Nation
has had a long and unfortunate history of sex discrimination." Frontiero v. Richardson, 411 U. S. 677 , 684
(1973). Through a century plus three decades and more of that
history, women did not count among voters composing "We the
People"; 5 not until 1920 did women gain a constitutional right to
the franchise. Id., at 685. And for a half century
thereafter, it remained the prevailing doctrine that government,
both federal and state, could withhold from women opportunities
accorded men so long as any "basis in reason" could be conceived
for the discrimination. See, e. g., Goesaert v. Cleary, 335
U. S. 464 , 467 (1948) (rejecting challenge of female tavern
owner and her daughter to Michigan law denying bartender licenses
to females-except for wives and daughters of male tavern owners;
Court would not "give ear" to the contention that "an unchivalrous
desire of male
5 As Thomas Jefferson stated the view prevailing when the
Constitution was new:
"Were our State a pure democracy ... there would yet be excluded
from their deliberations ... [w]omen, who, to prevent depravation
of morals and ambiguity of issue, could not mix promiscuously in
the public meetings of men." Letter from Thomas Jefferson to Samuel
Kercheval (Sept. 5, 1816), in 10 Writings of Thomas Jefferson
45-46, n. 1 (P. Ford ed. 1899). 532 bartenders to ... monopolize the calling" prompted the
legislation).
In 1971, for the first time in our Nation's history, this Court
ruled in favor of a woman who complained that her State had denied
her the equal protection of its laws. Reed v. Reed, 404 U. S. 71 , 73
(holding unconstitutional Idaho Code prescription that, among
"'several persons claiming and equally entitled to administer [a
decedent's estate], males must be preferred to females' "). Since Reed, the Court has repeatedly recognized that neither
federal nor state government acts compatibly with the equal
protection principle when a law or official policy denies to women,
simply because they are women, full citizenship stature-equal
opportunity to aspire, achieve, participate in and contribute to
society based on their individual talents and capacities. See, e. g., Kirchberg v. Feenstra, 450 U. S. 455 , 462-463
(1981) (affirming invalidity of Louisiana law that made husband
"head and master" of property jointly owned with his wife, giving
him unilateral right to dispose of such property without his wife's
consent); Stanton v. Stanton, 421 U. S. 7 (1975)
(invalidating Utah requirement that parents support boys until age
21, girls only until age 18).
Without equating gender classifications, for all purposes, to
classifications based on race or national origin,6 the Court, in post-Reed decisions, has carefully inspected official action
that closes a door or denies opportunity to women (or to men). See J. E. B., 511 U. S., at 152 (KENNEDY, J., concurring in
judgment) (case law evolving since 1971 "reveal[s] a strong
presumption that gender classifications are invalid"). To summarize
the Court's current directions for cases of official classification
based on gender: Focusing on the differen-
6 The Court has thus far reserved most stringent judicial
scrutiny for classifications based on race or national origin, but
last Term observed that strict scrutiny of such classifications is
not inevitably "fatal in fact." Adarand Constructors, Inc. v. Pena, 515
U. S. 200 , 237 (1995) (internal quotation marks omitted). 533 tial treatment or denial of opportunity for which relief is
sought, the reviewing court must determine whether the proffered
justification is "exceedingly persuasive." The burden of
justification is demanding and it rests entirely on the State. See Mississippi Univ. for Women, 458 U. S., at 724. The State
must show "at least that the [challenged] classification serves
'important governmental objectives and that the discriminatory
means employed' are 'substantially related to the achievement of
those objectives.'" Ibid. (quoting Wengler v. Druggists Mut. Ins. Co., 446 U. S. 142 , 150
(1980)). The justification must be genuine, not hypothesized or
invented post hoc in response to litigation. And it must not
rely on overbroad generalizations about the different talents,
capacities, or preferences of males and females. See Weinberger v. Wiesenfeld, 420 U. S. 636 , 643, 648
(1975); Califano v. Goldfarb, 430 U. S. 199 , 223-224
(1977) (STEVENS, J., concurring in judgment).
The heightened review standard our precedent establishes does
not make sex a proscribed classification. Supposed "inherent
differences" are no longer accepted as a ground for race or
national origin classifications. See Loving v. Virginia, 388 U.
S. 1 (1967). Physical differences between men and women,
however, are enduring: "[T]he two sexes are not fungible; a
community made up exclusively of one [sex] is different from a
community composed of both." Ballard v. United
States, 329 U. S.
187 , 193 (1946).
"Inherent differences" between men and women, we have come to
appreciate, remain cause for celebration, but not for denigration
of the members of either sex or for artificial constraints on an
individual's opportunity. Sex classifications may be used to
compensate women "for particular economic disabilities [they have]
suffered," Califano v. Webster, 430 U. S. 313, 320
(1977) (per curiam), to "promot[e] equal employment
opportunity," see California Fed. Sav. & Loan
Assn. v. Guerra, 479 U. S. 272 , 289
(1987), to advance full development of the talent and capacities of
our Nation's peo- 534 ple.7 But such classifications may not be used, as they once
were, see Goesaert, 335 U. S., at 467, to create or
perpetuate the legal, social, and economic inferiority of
women.
Measuring the record in this case against the review standard
just described, we conclude that Virginia has shown no "exceedingly
persuasive justification" for excluding all women from the
citizen-soldier training afforded by VMI. We therefore affirm the
Fourth Circuit's initial judgment, which held that Virginia had
violated the Fourteenth Amendment's Equal Protection Clause.
Because the remedy proffered by Virginia-the Mary Baldwin VWIL
program-does not cure the constitutional violation, i. e., it does not provide equal opportunity, we reverse the Fourth
Circuit's final judgment in this case.
V
The Fourth Circuit initially held that Virginia had advanced no
state policy by which it could justify, under equal protection
principles, its determination "to afford VMI's unique type of
program to men and not to women." 976 F. 2d, at 892. Virginia
challenges that "liability" ruling and asserts two justifications
in defense of VMI's exclusion of
7 Several amici have urged that diversity in educational
opportunities is an altogether appropriate governmental pursuit and
that single-sex schools can contribute importantly to such
diversity. Indeed, it is the mission of some single-sex schools "to
dissipate, rather than perpetuate, traditional gender
classifications." See Brief for Twenty-six Private Women's Colleges
as Amici Curiae 5. We do not question the Commonwealth's
prerogative evenhandedly to support diverse educational
opportunities. We address specifically and only an educational
opportunity recognized by the District Court and the Court of
Appeals as "unique," see 766 F. Supp., at 1413, 1432; 976 F. 2d, at
892, an opportunity available only at Virginia's premier military
institute, the Commonwealth's sole single-sex public university or
college. Cf. Mississippi Univ. for Women v. Hogan, 458 U. S. 718 ,
720, n. 1 (1982) ("Mississippi maintains no other single-sex public
university or college. Thus, we are not faced with the question of
whether States can provide 'separate but equal' undergraduate
institutions for males and females."). 535 women. First, the Commonwealth contends, "single-sex education
provides important educational benefits," Brief for
Cross-Petitioners 20, and the option of single-sex education
contributes to "diversity in educational approaches," id., at 25. Second, the Commonwealth argues, "the unique VMI method of
character development and leadership training," the school's
adversative approach, would have to be modified were VMI to admit
women. Id., at 33-36 (internal quotation marks omitted). We
consider these two justifications in turn.
A
Single-sex education affords pedagogical benefits to at least
some students, Virginia emphasizes, and that reality is uncontested
in this litigation.8 Similarly, it is not disputed that diversity
among public educational institutions can serve the public good.
But Virginia has not shown that VMI was established, or has been
maintained, with a view to diversifying, by its categorical
exclusion of women, educational opportunities within the
Commonwealth. In cases of this genre, our precedent instructs that
"benign" justifications proffered in defense of categorical
exclusions will not be accepted automatically; a tenable
justification must describe actual state purposes, not
rationalizations for ac-
8 On this point, the dissent sees fire where there is no flame.
See post, at 596-598, 598-600. "Both men and women can
benefit from a single-sex education," the District Court
recognized, although "the beneficial effects" of such education,
the court added, apparently "are stronger among women than among
men." 766 F. Supp., at 1414. The United States does not challenge
that recognition. Cf. C. Jencks & D. Riesman, The Academic
Revolution 297-298 (1968):
"The pluralistic argument for preserving all-male colleges is
uncomfortably similar to the pluralistic argument for preserving
all-white colleges .... The all-male college would be relatively
easy to defend if it emerged from a world in which women were
established as fully equal to men. But it does not. It is therefore
likely to be a witting or unwitting device for preserving tacit
assumptions of male superiority-assumptions for which women must
eventually pay." 536 tions in fact differently grounded. See Wiesenfeld, 420 U. S., at 648, and n. 16 ("mere recitation of a benign [or]
compensatory purpose" does not block "inquiry into the actual
purposes" of government-maintained gender-based classifications); Goldfarb, 430 U. S., at 212-213 (rejecting
government-proffered purposes after "inquiry into the actual
purposes" (internal quotation marks omitted)).
Mississippi Univ. for Women is immediately in point.
There the State asserted, in justification of its exclusion of
men from a nursing school, that it was engaging in "educational
affirmative action" by "compensat[ing] for discrimination against
women." 458 U. S., at 727. Undertaking a "searching analysis," id., at 728, the Court found no close resemblance between
"the alleged objective" and "the actual purpose underlying the
discriminatory classification," id., at 730. Pursuing a
similar inquiry here, we reach the same conclusion.
Neither recent nor distant history bears out Virginia's alleged
pursuit of diversity through single-sex educational options. In
1839, when the Commonwealth established VMI, a range of educational
opportunities for men and women was scarcely contemplated. Higher
education at the time was considered dangerous for women; 9
reflecting
9 Dr. Edward H. Clarke of Harvard Medical School, whose
influential book, Sex in Education, went through 17 editions, was
perhaps the most well-known speaker from the medical community
opposing higher education for women. He maintained that the
physiological effects of hard study and academic competition with
boys would interfere with the development of girls' reproductive
organs. See E. Clarke, Sex in Education 38-39, 62-63 (1873); id., at 127 ("identical education of the two sexes is a
crime before God and humanity, that physiology protests against,
and that experience weeps over"); see also H. Maudsley, Sex in Mind
and in Education 17 (1874) ("It is not that girls have not
ambition, nor that they fail generally to run the intellectual race
[in coeducational settings], but it is asserted that they do it at
a cost to their strength and health which entails life-long
suffering, and even incapacitates them for the adequate performance
of the natural functions of their sex."); C. Meigs, Females and
Their Diseases 350 (1848) (after five or six weeks of "mental and
educational discipline," a healthy woman would "lose ... the habit
of menstruation" 537 widely held views about women's proper place, the Nation's first
universities and colleges-for example, Harvard in Massachusetts,
William and Mary in Virginia-admitted only men. See E. Farello, A
History of the Education of Women in the United States 163 (1970).
VMI was not at all novel in this respect: In admitting no women,
VMI followed the lead of the Commonwealth's flagship school, the
University of Virginia, founded in 1819.
"[N]o struggle for the admission of women to a state
university," a historian has recounted, "was longer drawn out, or
developed more bitterness, than that at the University of
Virginia." 2 T. Woody, A History of Women's Education in the United
States 254 (1929) (History of Women's Education). In 1879, the
State Senate resolved to look into the possibility of higher
education for women, recognizing that Virginia "'has never, at any
period of her history,'" provided for the higher education of her
daughters, though she" 'has liberally provided for the higher
education of her sons.'" Ibid. (quoting 10 Educ. J. Va. 212
(1879)). Despite this recognition, no new opportunities were
instantly open to women.10
Virginia eventually provided for several women's seminaries and
colleges. Farmville Female Seminary became a public institution in
1884. See supra, at 521, n. 2. Two women's schools, Mary
Washington College and James Madison University, were founded in
1908; another, Radford University, was founded in 1910. 766 F.
Supp., at 1418-1419. By the mid-1970's, all four schools had become
coeducational. Ibid. Debate concerning women's admission as undergraduates at the
main university continued well past the century's midpoint.
Familiar arguments were rehearsed. If women
and suffer numerous ills as a result of depriving her body for
the sake of her mind).
10 Virginia's Superintendent of Public Instruction dismissed the
coeducational idea as '''repugnant to the prejudices of the
people'" and proposed a female college similar in quality to
Girton, Smith, or Vassar. 2 History of Women's Education 254
(quoting Dept. of Interior, 1 Report of Commissioner of Education,
H. R. Doc. No.5, 58th Cong., 2d Sess., 438 (1904)). 538 were admitted, it was feared, they "would encroach on the rights
of men; there would be new problems of government, perhaps
scandals; the old honor system would have to be changed; standards
would be lowered to those of other coeducational schools; and the
glorious reputation of the university, as a school for men, would
be trailed in the dust." 2 History of Women's Education 255.
Ultimately, in 1970, "the most prestigious institution of higher
education in Virginia," the University of Virginia, introduced
coeducation and, in 1972, began to admit women on an equal basis
with men. See Kirstein v. Rector and Visitors of Univ. of
Virginia, 309 F. Supp. 184, 186 (ED Va. 1970). A three-judge
Federal District Court confirmed:
"Virginia may not now deny to women, on the basis of sex,
educational opportunities at the Charlottesville campus that are
not afforded in other institutions operated by the [S]tate." Id., at 187.
Virginia describes the current absence of public single-sex
higher education for women as "an historical anomaly." Brief for
Cross-Petitioners 30. But the historical record indicates action
more deliberate than anomalous: First, protection of women against
higher education; next, schools for women far from equal in
resources and stature to schools for men; finally, conversion of
the separate schools to coeducation. The state legislature, prior
to the advent of this controversy, had repealed "[a]ll Virginia
statutes requiring individual institutions to admit only men or
women." 766 F. Supp., at 1419. And in 1990, an official commission,
"legislatively established to chart the future goals of higher
education in Virginia," reaffirmed the policy" 'of affording broad
access" while maintaining "autonomy and diversity.'" 976 F. 2d, at
898-899 (quoting Report of the Virginia Commission on the
University of the 21st Century). Significantly, the commission
reported: "'Because colleges and universities provide opportunities for
students to develop values and learn from role 539 models, it is extremely important that they deal with faculty,
staff, and students without regard to sex, race, or ethnic
origin.'" Id., at 899 (emphasis supplied by Court of Appeals
deleted). This statement, the Court of Appeals observed, "is the only
explicit one that we have found in the record in which the
Commonwealth has expressed itself with respect to gender
distinctions." Ibid. Our 1982 decision in Mississippi Univ. for Women prompted
VMI to reexamine its male-only admission policy. See 766 F. Supp.,
at 1427-1428. Virginia relies on that reexamination as a legitimate
basis for maintaining VMI's single-sex character. See Reply Brief
for Cross-Petitioners 6. A Mission Study Committee, appointed by
the VMI Board of Visitors, studied the problem from October 1983
until May 1986, and in that month counseled against "change of VMI
status as a single-sex college." See 766 F. Supp., at 1429
(internal quotation marks omitted). Whatever internal purpose the
Mission Study Committee served-and however well meaning the framers
of the report-we can hardly extract from that effort any
commonwealth policy evenhandedly to advance diverse educational
options. As the District Court observed, the Committee's analysis
"primarily focuse[d] on anticipated difficulties in attracting
females to VMI," and the report, overall, supplied "very little
indication of how thee] conclusion was reached." Ibid. In sum, we find no persuasive evidence in this record that VMI's
male-only admission policy "is in furtherance of a state policy of
'diversity.'" See 976 F. 2d, at 899. No such policy, the Fourth
Circuit observed, can be discerned from the movement of all other
public colleges and universities in Virginia away from single-sex
education. See ibid. That court also questioned "how one
institution with autonomy, but with no authority over any other
state institution, can give effect to a state policy of diversity
among institutions." Ibid. A purpose genuinely to advance an
array of educa- 540 tional options, as the Court of Appeals recognized, is not
served by VMI's historic and constant plan-a plan to "affor[d] a
unique educational benefit only to males." Ibid. However
"liberally" this plan serves the Commonwealth's sons, it makes no
provision whatever for her daughters. That is not equal protection.
B
Virginia next argues that VMI's adversative method of training
provides educational benefits that cannot be made available,
unmodified, to women. Alterations to accommodate women would
necessarily be "radical," so "drastic," Virginia asserts, as to
transform, indeed "destroy," VMI's program. See Brief for
Cross-Petitioners 34-36. Neither sex would be favored by the
transformation, Virginia maintains:
Men would be deprived of the unique opportunity currently
available to them; women would not gain that opportunity because
their participation would "eliminat[e] the very aspects of [the]
program that distinguish [VMI] from ... other institutions of
higher education in Virginia." Id., at 34.
The District Court forecast from expert witness testimony, and
the Court of Appeals accepted, that coeducation would materially
affect "at least these three aspects of VMI's program-physical
training, the absence of privacy, and the adversative approach."
976 F. 2d, at 896-897. And it is uncontested that women's admission
would require accommodations, primarily in arranging housing
assignments and physical training programs for female cadets. See
Brief for Cross-Respondent 11, 29-30. It is also undisputed,
however, that "the VMI methodology could be used to educate women."
852 F. Supp., at 481. The District Court even allowed that some
women may prefer it to the methodology a women's college might
pursue. See ibid. "[S]ome women, at least, would want to
attend [VMI] if they had the opportunity," the District Court
recognized, 766 F. Supp., at 1414, and "some women," the expert
testimony established, "are 541 capable of all of the individual activities required of VMI
cadets," id., at 1412. The parties, furthermore, agree that "some women can meet the physical standards [VMI] now
impose[s] on men." 976 F. 2d, at 896. In sum, as the Court of
Appeals stated, "neither the goal of producing citizen soldiers,"
VMI's raison detre, "nor VMI's implementing methodology is
inherently unsuitable to women." Id., at 899.
In support of its initial judgment for Virginia, a judgment
rejecting all equal protection objections presented by the United
States, the District Court made "findings" on "gender-based
developmental differences." 766 F. Supp., at 1434-1435. These
"findings" restate the opinions of Virginia's expert witnesses,
opinions about typically male or typically female "tendencies." Id., at 1434. For example, "[m]ales tend to need an
atmosphere of adversativeness," while "[f]emales tend to thrive in
a cooperative atmosphere." Ibid. "I'm not saying that some
women don't do well under [the] adversative model," VMI's expert on
educational institutions testified, "undoubtedly there are some
[women] who do"; but educational experiences must be designed
"around the rule," this expert maintained, and not "around the
exception." Ibid. (internal quotation marks omitted).
The United States does not challenge any expert witness
estimation on average capacities or preferences of men and women.
Instead, the United States emphasizes that time and again since
this Court's turning point decision in Reed v. Reed, 404 U. S. 71 (1971), we have cautioned reviewing courts to take a "hard look" at
generalizations or "tendencies" of the kind pressed by Virginia,
and relied upon by the District Court. See O'Connor, Portia's
Progress, 66 N. Y. U. L. Rev. 1546, 1551 (1991). State actors
controlling gates to opportunity, we have instructed, may not
exclude qualified individuals based on "fixed notions concerning
the roles and abilities of males and females." Mississippi Univ.
for Women, 458 U. S., at 725; see J. E. B., 511 U. S.,
at 139, n. 11 (equal protection principles, as applied to gender
classifications, mean 542 state actors may not rely on "overbroad" generalizations to make
"judgments about people that are likely to ... perpetuate
historical patterns of discrimination").
It may be assumed, for purposes of this decision, that most
women would not choose VMI's adversative method. As Fourth Circuit
Judge Motz observed, however, in her dissent from the Court of
Appeals' denial of rehearing en bane, it is also probable that
"many men would not want to be educated in such an environment." 52
F. 3d, at 93. (On that point, even our dissenting colleague might
agree.) Education, to be sure, is not a "one size fits all"
business. The issue, however, is not whether "women-or men-should
be forced to attend VMI"; rather, the question is whether the
Commonwealth can constitutionally deny to women who have the will
and capacity, the training and attendant opportunities that VMI
uniquely affords. Ibid. The notion that admission of women would downgrade VMI's
stature, destroy the adversative system and, with it, even the
school,l1 is a judgment hardly proved,12 a prediction
11 See post, at 566, 598-599, 603. Forecasts of the same
kind were made regarding admission of women to the federal military
academies. See, e. g., Hearings on H. R. 9832 et al.
before Subcommittee No.2 of the House Committee on Armed Services,
93d Cong., 2d Sess., 137 (1975) (statement of Lt. Gen. A. P. Clark,
Superintendent of U. S. Air Force Academy) ("It is my considered
judgment that the introduction of female cadets will inevitably
erode this vital atmosphere."); id., at 165 (statement of
Hon. H. H. Callaway, Secretary of the Army) ("Admitting women to
West Point would irrevocably change the Academy .... The Spartan
atmospherewhich is so important to producing the final
product-would surely be diluted, and would in all probability
disappear.").
12 See 766 F. Supp., at 1413 (describing testimony of expert
witness David Riesman: "[I]f VMI were to admit women, it would
eventually find it necessary to drop the adversative system
altogether, and adopt a system that provides more nurturing and
support for the students."). Such judgments have attended, and
impeded, women's progress toward full citizenship stature
throughout our Nation's history. Speaking in 1879 in support of
higher education for females, for example, Virginia State Senator
C. T. Smith of Nelson recounted that legislation proposed to
pro- 543 hardly different from other "self-fulfilling prophec[ies]," see Mississippi Univ. for Women, 458 U. S., at 730, once
routinely used to deny rights or opportunities. When women first
sought admission to the bar and access to legal education, concerns
of the same order were expressed. For example, in 1876, the Court
of Common Pleas of Hennepin County, Minnesota, explained why women
were thought ineligible for the practice of law. Women train and
educate the young, the court said, which "forbids that they shall bestow that time (early and late) and
labor, so essential in attaining to the eminence to which the true
lawyer should ever aspire. It cannot therefore be said that the
opposition of courts to the admission of females to practice ... is
to any extent the outgrowth of ... 'old fogyism[.J' ... [I]t arises
rather from a comprehension of the magnitude of the
responsibilities connected with the successful practice of law, and
a desire to grade up the profession." In re Application of
Martha Angle Dorsett to Be Admitted to Practice as Attorney and
Counselor at Law (Minn. C. P. Hennepin Cty., 1876), in The Syllabi,
Oct. 21, 1876, pp. 5, 6 (emphasis added). A like fear, according to a 1925 report, accounted for Columbia
Law School's resistance to women's admission, although "[t]he faculty ... never maintained that women could not master
legal learning .... No, its argument has been ... more practical.
If women were admitted to tect the property rights of women had encountered resistance. 10
Educ. J. Va. 213 (1879). A Senator opposing the measures objected
that "there [was] no formal call for the [legislation]," and
"depicted in burning eloquence the terrible consequences such laws
would produce." Ibid. The legislation passed, and a year or
so later, its sponsor, C. T. Smith, reported that "not one of [the
forecast "terrible consequences"] has or ever will happen, even
unto the sounding of Gabriel's trumpet." Ibid. See also supra, at 537-538. 544 the Columbia Law School, [the faculty] said, then the choicer,
more manly and red-blooded graduates of our great universities
would go to the Harvard Law Schoo!!" The Nation, Feb. 18, 1925, p.
173. Medical faculties similarly resisted men and women as partners
in the study of medicine. See R. Morantz-Sanchez, Sympathy and
Science: Women Physicians in American Medicine 51-54, 250 (1985);
see also M. Walsh, "Doctors Wanted:
No Women Need Apply" 121-122 (1977) (quoting E. Clarke, Medical
Education of Women, 4 Boston Med. & Surg. J. 345, 346 (1869) ("
'God forbid that I should ever see men and women aiding each other
to display with the scalpel the secrets of the reproductive system
.... ' ")); cf. supra, at 536537, n. 9. More recently, women
seeking careers in policing encountered resistance based on fears
that their presence would "undermine male solidarity," see F.
Heidensohn, Women in Control? 201 (1992); deprive male partners of
adequate assistance, see id., at 184-185; and lead to sexual
misconduct, see C. Milton et al., Women in Policing 32-33 (1974).
Field studies did not confirm these fears. See Heidensohn, supra, at 92-93; P. Bloch & D. Anderson, Policewomen on
Patrol: Final Report (1974).
Women's successful entry into the federal military academies,13
and their participation in the Nation's military forces,14 indicate
that Virginia's fears for the future of VMI
13 Women cadets have graduated at the top of their class at
every federal military academy. See Brief for Lieutenant Colonel
Rhonda Cornum et al. as Amici Curiae 11, n. 25; cf. Defense
Advisory Committee on Women in the Services, Report on the
Integration and Performance of Women at West Point 64 (1992).
14 Brief for Lieutenant Colonel Rhonda Cornum, supra, at
5-9 (reporting the vital contributions and courageous performance
of women in the military); see Mintz, President Nominates 1st Woman
to Rank of Three-Star General, Washington Post, Mar. 27, 1996, p.
A19, col. 1 (announcing President's nomination of Marine Corps
Major General Carol Mutter to rank of Lieutenant General; Mutter
will head corps manpower and planning); Tousignant, A New Era for
the Old Guard, Washington Post, Mar. 23, 545 may not be solidly grounded.15 The Commonwealth's justification
for excluding all women from "citizen-soldier" training for which
some are qualified, in any event, cannot rank as "exceedingly
persuasive," as we have explained and applied that standard.
Virginia and VMI trained their argument on "means" rather than
"end," and thus misperceived our precedent. Single-sex education at
VMI serves an "important governmental objective," they maintained,
and exclusion of women is not only "substantially related," it is
essential to that objective. By this notably circular argument, the
"straightforward" test Mississippi Univ. for Women described, see 458 U. S., at 724-725, was bent and bowed.
The Commonwealth's misunderstanding and, in turn, the District
Court's, is apparent from VMI's mission: to produce
"citizen-soldiers," individuals "'imbued with love of learning, confident in the functions and
attitudes of leadership, possessing a high sense of public service,
advocates of the American democracy and free enterprise system, and
ready ... to defend their country in time of national periL'" 766
F. Supp., at 1425 (quoting Mission Study Committee of the VMI Board
of Visitors, Report, May 16, 1986). Surely that goal is great enough to accommodate women, who today
count as citizens in our American democracy equal in stature to
men. Just as surely, the Commonwealth's
1996, p. C1, col. 2 (reporting admission of Sergeant
Heather Johnsen to elite Infantry unit that keeps round-the-clock
vigil at Tomb of the Unknowns in Arlington National Cemetery).
15 Inclusion of women in settings where, traditionally, they
were not wanted inevitably entails a period of adjustment. As one
West Point cadet squad leader recounted: "[T]he classes of '78 and
'79 see the women as women, but the classes of '80 and '81 see them
as classmates." U. S. Military Academy, A. Vitters, Report of
Admission of Women (Project Athena II) 84 (1978) (internal
quotation marks omitted). 546 great goal is not substantially advanced by women's categorical
exclusion, in total disregard of their individual merit, from the
Commonwealth's premier "citizen-soldier" corps.16 Virginia, in sum,
"has fallen far short of establishing the 'exceedingly persuasive
justification,'" Mississippi Univ. for Women, 458 U. S., at
731, that must be the solid base for any gender-defined
classification.
VI
In the second phase of the litigation, Virginia presented its
remedial plan-maintain VMI as a male-only college and create VWIL
as a separate program for women. The plan met District Court
approval. The Fourth Circuit, in turn, deferentially reviewed the
Commonwealth's proposal and decided that the two single-sex
programs directly served Virginia's reasserted purposes:
single-gender education, and "achieving the results of an
adversative method in a military environment." See 44 F. 3d, at
1236, 1239. Inspecting the VMI and VWIL educational programs to
determine whether they "afford[ed] to both genders benefits
comparable in substance, [if] not in form and detail," id., at 1240, the Court of Appeals concluded that Virginia had arranged
for men and women opportunities "sufficiently comparable" to
survive equal protection evaluation, id., at 1240-1241. The
United States challenges this "remedial" ruling as pervasively
misguided.
16 VMI has successfully managed another notable change. The
school admitted its first African-American cadets in 1968. See The
VMI Story 347-349 (students no longer sing "Dixie," salute the
Confederate flag or the tomb of General Robert E. Lee at ceremonies
and sports events). As the District Court noted, VMI established a
program on "retention of black cadets" designed to offer academic
and social-cultural support to "minority members of a dominantly
white and tradition-oriented student body." 766 F. Supp., at
1436-1437. The school maintains a "special recruitment program for
blacks" which, the District Court found, "has had little, if any,
effect on VMI's method of accomplishing its mission." Id., at 1437. 547 A
A remedial decree, this Court has said, must closely fit the
constitutional violation; it must be shaped to place persons
unconstitutionally denied an opportunity or advantage in "the
position they would have occupied in the absence of
[discrimination]." See Milliken v. Bradley, 433 U. S. 267 , 280 (1977)
(internal quotation marks omitted). The constitutional violation in
this suit is the categorical exclusion of women from an
extraordinary educational opportunity afforded men. A proper remedy
for an unconstitutional exclusion, we have explained, aims to
"eliminate [so far as possible] the discriminatory effects of the
past" and to "bar like discrimination in the future." Louisiana v. United States, 380 U. S. 145 , 154
(1965).
Virginia chose not to eliminate, but to leave untouched, VMI's
exclusionary policy. For women only, however, Virginia proposed a
separate program, different in kind from VMI and unequal in
tangible and intangible facilities.17 Having violated the
Constitution's equal protection requirement, Virginia was obliged
to show that its remedial proposal "directly address[ed] and
relate[d] to" the violation, see Milliken, 433 U. S., at
282, i. e., the equal protection denied to women ready,
willing, and able to benefit from educational
17 As earlier observed, see supra, at 529, Judge
Phillips, in dissent, measured Virginia's plan against a paradigm
arrangement, one that "could survive equal protection scrutiny":
single-sex schools with "substantially comparable curricular and
extra-curricular programs, funding, physical plant, administration
and support services, ... faculty[,] and library resources." 44 F.3d
1229 , 1250 (CA4 1995). Cf. Bray v. Lee, 337 F. Supp. 934 (Mass. 1972) (holding inconsistent with the Equal
Protection Clause admission of males to Boston's Boys Latin School
with a test score of 120 or higher (up to a top score of 200) while
requiring a score, on the same test, of at least 133 for admission
of females to Girls Latin School, but not ordering coeducation).
Measuring VMIIVWIL against the paradigm, Judge Phillips said,
"reveals how far short the [Virginia] plan falls from providing
substantially equal tangible and intangible educational benefits to
men and women." 44 F. 3d, at 1250. 548 opportunities of the kind VMI offers. Virginia described VWIL as
a "parallel program," and asserted that VWIL shares VMI's mission
of producing "citizen-soldiers" and VMI's goals of providing
"education, military training, mental and physical discipline,
character ... and leadership development." Brief for Respondents 24
(internal quotation marks omitted). If the VWIL program could not
"eliminate the discriminatory effects of the past," could it at
least "bar like discrimination in the future"? See Louisiana,
380 U. S., at 154. A comparison of the programs said to be
"parallel" informs our answer. In exposing the character of, and
differences in, the VMI and VWIL programs, we recapitulate facts
earlier presented. See supra, at 520-523, 526-527.
VWIL affords women no opportunity to experience the rigorous
military training for which VMI is famed. See 766 F. Supp., at
1413-1414 ("No other school in Virginia or in the United States,
public or private, offers the same kind of rigorous military
training as is available at VMI."); id., at 1421 (VMI "is
known to be the most challenging military school in the United
States"). Instead, the VWIL program "deemphasize[s]" military
education, 44 F. 3d, at 1234, and uses a "cooperative method" of
education "which reinforces self-esteem," 852 F. Supp., at 476.
VWIL students participate in ROTC and a "largely ceremonial"
Virginia Corps of Cadets, see 44 F. 3d, at 1234, but Virginia
deliberately did not make VWIL a military institute. The VWIL House
is not a military-style residence and VWIL students need not live
together throughout the 4-year program, eat meals together, or wear
uniforms during the schoolday. See 852 F. Supp., at 477, 495. VWIL
students thus do not experience the "barracks" life "crucial to the
VMI experience," the spartan living arrangements designed to foster
an "egalitarian ethic." See 766 F. Supp., at 14231424. "[T]he most
important aspects of the VMI educational experience occur in the
barracks," the District Court 549 found, id., at 1423, yet Virginia deemed that core
experience nonessential, indeed inappropriate, for training its
female citizen-soldiers.
VWIL students receive their "leadership training" in seminars,
externships, and speaker series, see 852 F. Supp., at 477, episodes
and encounters lacking the "[p]hysical rigor, mental stress, ...
minute regulation of behavior, and indoctrination in desirable
values" made hallmarks of VMI's citizen-soldier training, see 766
F. Supp., at 1421.18 Kept away from the pressures, hazards, and
psychological bonding characteristic of VMI's adversative training,
see id., at 1422, VWIL students will not know the "feeling
of tremendous accomplishment" commonly experienced by VMI's
successful cadets, id., at 1426.
Virginia maintains that these methodological differences are
"justified pedagogically," based on "important differences between
men and women in learning and developmental needs," "psychological
and sociological differences" Virginia describes as "real" and "not
stereotypes." Brief for Respondents 28 (internal quotation marks
omitted). The Task Force charged with developing the leadership
program for women, drawn from the staff and faculty at Mary Baldwin
College, "determined that a military model and, especially VMI's
adversative method, would be wholly inappropriate for educating and
training most women." 852 F. Supp., at 476 (emphasis added).
See also 44 F. 3d, at 1233-1234 (noting Task Force conclusion that,
while "some women would be suited to and interested in [a VMI
-style experience]," VMI's adversative method "would not be
effective for women as a group" (emphasis added)). The
Com-
18 Both programs include an honor system. Students at VMI are
expelled forthwith for honor code violations, see 766 F. Supp., at
1423; the system for VWIL students, see 852 F. Supp., at 496-497,
is less severe, see Tr. 414-415 (testimony of Mary Baldwin College
President Cynthia Tyson). 550 monwealth embraced the Task Force view, as did expert witnesses
who testified for Virginia. See 852 F. Supp., at 480-481.
As earlier stated, see supra, at 541-542, generalizations
about "the way women are," estimates of what is appropriate for most women, no longer justify denying opportunity to women
whose talent and capacity place them outside the average
description. Notably, Virginia never asserted that VMI's method of
education suits most men. It is also revealing that Virginia
accounted for its failure to make the VWIL experience "the entirely
militaristic experience of VMI" on the ground that VWIL "is planned
for women who do not necessarily expect to pursue military
careers." 852 F. Supp., at 478. By that reasoning, VMI's "entirely
militaristic" program would be inappropriate for men in general or as a group, for "[o]nly about 15% of VMI cadets enter career
military service." See 766 F. Supp., at 1432.
In contrast to the generalizations about women on which Virginia
rests, we note again these dispositive realities:
VMI's "implementing methodology" is not "inherently unsuitable
to women," 976 F. 2d, at 899; "some women ... do well under [the]
adversative model," 766 F. Supp., at 1434 (internal quotation marks
omitted); "some women, at least, would want to attend [VMI] if they
had the opportunity," id., at 1414; "some women are capable
of all of the individual activities required of VMI cadets," id., at 1412, and "can meet the physical standards [VMI] now
impose[s] on men," 976 F. 2d, at 896. It is on behalf of these
women that the United States has instituted this suit, and it is
for them that a remedy must be crafted,19 a remedy that will end
their
19 Admitting women to VMI would undoubtedly require alterations
necessary to afford members of each sex privacy from the other sex
in living arrangements, and to adjust aspects of the physical
training programs. See Brief for Petitioner 27-29; cf. note
following 10 U. S. C. § 4342 (academic and other standards for
women admitted to the Military, Naval, 551 exclusion from a state-supplied educational opportunity for
which they are fit, a decree that will "bar like discrimination in
the future." Louisiana, 380 U. S., at 154.
B
In myriad respects other than military training, VWIL does not
qualify as VMI's equal. VWIL's student body, faculty, course
offerings, and facilities hardly match VMI's. Nor can the VWIL
graduate anticipate the benefits associated with VMI's 157-year
history, the school's prestige, and its influential alumni
network.
Mary Baldwin College, whose degree VWIL students will gain,
enrolls first-year women with an average combined SAT score about
100 points lower than the average score for VMI freshmen. 852 F.
Supp., at 501. The Mary Baldwin faculty holds "significantly fewer
Ph. D.'s," id., at 502, and receives substantially lower
salaries, see Tr. 158 (testimony of James Lott, Dean of Mary
Baldwin College), than the faculty at VMI.
Mary Baldwin does not offer a VWIL student the range of
curricular choices available to a VMI cadet. VMI awards
baccalaureate degrees in liberal arts, biology, chemistry, civil
engineering, electrical and computer engineering, and mechanical
engineering. See 852 F. Supp., at 503; Virginia Military Institute:
More than an Education 11 (Govt. exh. 75,
and Air Force Academies "shall be the same as those required for
male individuals, except for those minimum essential adjustments in
such standards required because of physiological differences
between male and female individuals"). Experience shows such
adjustments are manageable. See U. S. Military Academy, A. Vitters,
N. Kinzer, & J. Adams, Report of Admission of Women (Project
Athena I-IV) (1977-1980) (4-year longitudinal study of the
admission of women to West Point); Defense Advisory Committee on
Women in the Services, Report on the Integration and Performance of
Women at West Point 17-18 (1992). 552 lodged with Clerk of this Court). VWIL students attend a school
that "does not have a math and science focus," 852 F. Supp., at
503; they cannot take at Mary Baldwin any courses in engineering or
the advanced math and physics courses VMI offers, see id., at 477.
For physical training, Mary Baldwin has "two multipurpose
fields" and "[o]ne gymnasium." Id., at 503. VMI has "an NCAA
competition level indoor track and field facility; a number of
multi-purpose fields; baseball, soccer and lacrosse fields; an
obstacle course; large boxing, wrestling and martial arts
facilities; an ll-laps-to-the-mile indoor running course; an indoor
pool; indoor and outdoor rifle ranges; and a football stadium that
also contains a practice field and outdoor track." Ibid. Although Virginia has represented that it will provide equal
financial support for in-state VWIL students and VMI cadets, id., at 483, and the VMI Foundation has agreed to endow VWIL
with $5.4625 million, id., at 499, the difference between
the two schools' financial reserves is pronounced. Mary Baldwin's
endowment, currently about $19 million, will gain an additional $35
million based on future commitments; VMI's current endowment, $131
million-the largest public college per-student endowment in the
Nation-will gain $220 million. Id., at 503.
The VWIL student does not graduate with the advantage of a VMI
degree. Her diploma does not unite her with the legions of VMI
"graduates [who] have distinguished themselves" in military and
civilian life. See 976 F. 2d, at 892893. "[VMI] alumni are
exceptionally close to the school," and that closeness accounts, in
part, for VMI's success in attracting applicants. See 766 F. Supp.,
at 1421. A VWIL graduate cannot assume that the "network of
business owners, corporations, VMI graduates and non-graduate
employers ... interested in hiring VMI graduates," 852 F. Supp., at
499, will be equally responsive to her search for employment, 553 see 44 F. 3d, at 1250 (Phillips, J., dissenting) ("the powerful
political and economic ties of the VMI alumni network cannot be
expected to open" for graduates of the fledgling VWIL program).
Virginia, in sum, while maintaining VMI for men only, has failed
to provide any "comparable single-gender women's institution." Id., at 1241. Instead, the Commonwealth has created a VWIL
program fairly appraised as a "pale shadow" of VMI in terms of the
range of curricular choices and faculty stature, funding, prestige,
alumni support and influence. See id., at 1250 (Phillips,
J., dissenting).
Virginia's VWIL solution is reminiscent of the remedy Texas
proposed 50 years ago, in response to a state trial court's 1946
ruling that, given the equal protection guarantee,
African-Americans could not be denied a legal education at a state
facility. See Sweatt v. Painter, 339 U. S. 629 (1950).
Reluctant to admit African-Americans to its flagship University of
Texas Law School, the State set up a separate school for Heman
Sweatt and other black law students. Id., at 632. As
originally opened, the new school had no independent faculty or
library, and it lacked accreditation. Id., at 633.
Nevertheless, the state trial and appellate courts were satisfied
that the new school offered Sweatt opportunities for the study of
law "substantially equivalent to those offered by the State to
white students at the University of Texas." Id., at 632
(internal quotation marks omitted).
Before this Court considered the case, the new school had gained
"a faculty of five full-time professors; a student body of 23; a
library of some 16,500 volumes serviced by a full-time staff; a
practice court and legal aid association; and one alumnus who ha[d]
become a member of the Texas Bar." Id., at 633. This Court
contrasted resources at the new school with those at the school
from which Sweatt had been excluded. The University of Texas Law
School had a full-time faculty of 16, a student body of 850, a
library containing over 554 65,000 volumes, scholarship funds, a law review, and moot court
facilities. Id., at 632-633.
More important than the tangible features, the Court emphasized,
are "those qualities which are incapable of objective measurement
but which make for greatness" in a school, including "reputation of
the faculty, experience of the administration, position and
influence of the alumni, standing in the community, traditions and
prestige." Id., at 634. Facing the marked differences
reported in the Sweatt opinion, the Court unanimously ruled
that Texas had not shown "substantial equality in the [separate]
educational opportunities" the State offered. Id., at 633.
Accordingly, the Court held, the Equal Protection Clause required
Texas to admit AfricanAmericans to the University of Texas Law
School. Id., at 636. In line with Sweatt, we rule
here that Virginia has not shown substantial equality in the
separate educational opportunities the Commonwealth supports at
VWIL and VMI.
C
When Virginia tendered its VWIL plan, the Fourth Circuit did not
inquire whether the proposed remedy, approved by the District
Court, placed women denied the VMI advantage in "the position they
would have occupied in the absence of [discrimination]." Milliken, 433 U. S., at 280 (internal quotation marks
omitted). Instead, the Court of Appeals considered whether the
Commonwealth could provide, with fidelity to the equal protection
principle, separate and unequal educational programs for men and
women.
The Fourth Circuit acknowledged that "the VWIL degree from Mary
Baldwin College lacks the historical benefit and prestige of a
degree from VMI." 44 F. 3d, at 1241. The Court of Appeals further
observed that VMI is "an ongoing and successful institution with a
long history," and there remains no "comparable single-gender
women's institution." Ibid. Nevertheless, the appeals court
declared the substantially different and significantly unequal VWIL
program sat- 555 isfactory. The court reached that result by revising the
applicable standard of review. The Fourth Circuit displaced the
standard developed in our precedent, see supra, at 532534,
and substituted a standard of its own invention.
We have earlier described the deferential review in which the
Court of Appeals engaged, see supra, at 528-529, a brand of
review inconsistent with the more exacting standard our precedent
requires, see supra, at 532-534. Quoting in part from Mississippi Univ. for Women, the Court of Appeals candidly
described its own analysis as one capable of checking a legislative
purpose ranked as "pernicious," but generally according "deference
to [the] legislative will." 44 F. 3d, at 1235, 1236. Recognizing
that it had extracted from our decisions a test yielding "little or
no scrutiny of the effect of a classification directed at
[single-gender education]," the Court of Appeals devised another
test, a "substantive comparability" inquiry, id., at 1237,
and proceeded to find that new test satisfied, id., at
1241.
The Fourth Circuit plainly erred in exposing Virginia's VWIL
plan to a deferential analysis, for "all gender-based
classifications today" warrant "heightened scrutiny." See J. E. B., 511 U. S., at 136. Valuable as VWIL may prove for students
who seek the program offered, Virginia's remedy affords no cure at
all for the opportunities and advantages withheld from women who
want a VMI education and can make the grade. See supra, at
549-554.20 In sum, Virginia's
20 Virginia's prime concern, it appears, is that "plac[ing] men
and women into the adversative relationship inherent in the VMI
program ... would destroy, at least for that period of the
adversative training, any sense of decency that still permeates the
relationship between the sexes." 44 F. 3d, at 1239; see supra, at 540-546. It is an ancient and familiar fear.
Compare In re Lavinia Goodell, 39 Wis. 232, 246 (1875)
(denying female applicant's motion for admission to the bar of its
court, Wisconsin Supreme Court explained: "Discussions are
habitually necessary in courts of justice, which are unfit for
female ears. The habitual presence of women at these would tend to
relax the public sense of decency and propriety."), with Levine,
Closing Comments, 6 Law & Inequality 41 (1988) (presentation
at 556 remedy does not match the constitutional violation; the
Commonwealth has shown no "exceedingly persuasive justification"
for withholding from women qualified for the experience premier
training of the kind VMI affords.
VII
A generation ago, "the authorities controlling Virginia higher
education," despite long established tradition, agreed "to innovate
and favorably entertain[ed] the [then] relatively new idea that
there must be no discrimination by sex in offering educational
opportunity." Kirstein, 309 F. Supp., at 186. Commencing in
1970, Virginia opened to women "educational opportunities at the
Charlottesville campus that [were] not afforded in other
[state-operated] institutions." Id., at 187; see supra, at 538. A federal court approved the Commonwealth's
innovation, emphasizing that the University of Virginia "offer[ed]
courses of instruction ... not available elsewhere." 309 F. Supp.,
at 187. The court further noted: "[T]here exists at Charlottesville
a 'prestige' factor
Eighth Circuit Judicial Conference, Colorado Springs, Colo.,
July 17, 1987) (footnotes omitted);
"Plato questioned whether women should be afforded equal
opportunity to become guardians, those elite Rulers of Platonic
society. Ironically, in that most undemocratic system of
government, the Republic, women's native ability to serve as
guardians was not seriously questioned. The concern was over the
wrestling and exercise class in which all candidates for
guardianship had to participate, for rigorous physical and mental
training were prerequisites to attain the exalted status of
guardian. And in accord with Greek custom, those exercise classes
were conducted in the nude. Plato concluded that their virtue would
clothe the women's nakedness and that Platonic society would not
thereby be deprived of the talent of qualified citizens for reasons
of mere gender."
For Plato's full text on the equality of women, see 2 The
Dialogues of Plato 302-312 (B. Jowett transl., 4th ed. 1953).
Virginia, not bound to ancient Greek custom in its "rigorous
physical and mental training" programs, could more readily make the
accommodations necessary to draw on "the talent of [all] qualified
citizens." Cf. supra, at 550-551, n. 19. 557 [not paralleled in] other Virginia educational institutions." Ibid. VMI, too, offers an educational opportunity no other Virginia
institution provides, and the school's "prestige"-associated with
its success in developing "citizen-soldiers"-is unequaled. Virginia
has closed this facility to its daughters and, instead, has devised
for them a "parallel program," with a faculty less impressively
credentialed and less well paid, more limited course offerings,
fewer opportunities for military training and for scientific
specialization. Cf. Sweatt, 339 U. S., at 633. VMI, beyond
question, "possesses to a far greater degree" than the VWIL program
"those qualities which are incapable of objective measurement but
which make for greatness in a ... school," including "position and
influence of the alumni, standing in the community, traditions and
prestige." Id., at 634. Women seeking and fit for a VMI
-quality education cannot be offered anything less, under the
Commonwealth's obligation to afford them genuinely equal
protection.
A prime part of the history of our Constitution, historian
Richard Morris recounted, is the story of the extension of
constitutional rights and protections to people once ignored or
excluded.21 VMI's story continued as our comprehension of "We the
People" expanded. See supra, at 532, n. 6.
21 R. Morris, The Forging of the Union, 1781-1789, p. 193
(1987); see id., at 191, setting out letter to a friend from
Massachusetts patriot (later second President) John Adams, on the
subject of qualifications for voting in his home State:
"[I]t is dangerous to open so fruitful a source of controversy
and altercation as would be opened by attempting to alter the
qualifications of voters; there will be no end of it. New claims
will arise; women will demand a vote; lads from twelve to
twenty-one will think their rights not enough attended to; and
every man who has not a farthing, will demand an equal voice with
any other, in all acts of state. It tends to confound and destroy
all distinctions, and prostrate all ranks to one common level."
Letter from John Adams to James Sullivan (May 26, 1776), in 9 Works
of John Adams 378 (C. Adams ed. 1854). 558 REHNQUIST, C. J., concurring in judgment
There is no reason to believe that the admission of women
capable of all the activities required of VMI cadets would destroy
the Institute rather than enhance its capacity to serve the "more
perfect Union."
***
For the reasons stated, the initial judgment of the Court of
Appeals, 976 F.2d
890 (CA4 1992), is affirmed, the final judgment of the Court of
Appeals, 44 F.3d
1229 (CA4 1995), is reversed, and the case is remanded for
further proceedings consistent with this opinion.
It is so ordered.
JUSTICE THOMAS took no part in the consideration or decision of
these cases.
CHIEF JUSTICE REHNQUIST, concurring in the judgment. The Court
holds first that Virginia violates the Equal Protection Clause by
maintaining the Virginia Military Institute's (VMI's) all-male
admissions policy, and second that establishing the Virginia
Women's Institute for Leadership (VWIL) program does not remedy
that violation. While I agree with these conclusions, I disagree
with the Court's analysis and so I write separately.
I
Two decades ago in Craig v. Boren, 429 U. S. 190 , 197
(1976), we announced that "[t]o withstand constitutional challenge,
... classifications by gender must serve important governmental
objectives and must be substantially related to achievement of
those objectives." We have adhered to that standard of scrutiny
ever since. See Califano v. Goldfarb, 430 U. S. 199 , 210-211
(1977); Califano v. Webster, 430 U. S. 313, 316-317
(1977); Orr v. Orr, 440 U. S. 268 , 279
(1979); Caban v. Mohammed, 441 U. S. 380 , 388
(1979); Davis v. Passman, 442 U. S. 228 , 234-235,
235, n. 9 (1979); Personnel Administrator of Mass. v. Feeney, 442 U.
S. 256 , 273 (1979); 559 Califano v. Westcott, 443 U. S. 76 ,85 (1979); Wengler v. Druggists Mut. Ins. Co., 446 U. S. 142 , 150
(1980); Kirchberg v. Feenstra, 450 U. S. 455 , 459-460
(1981); Michael M. v. Superior Court, Sonoma Cty., 450 U. S. 464 ,
469 (1981); Mississippi Univ. for Women v. Hogan, 458 U. S. 718 ,
724 (1982); Heckler v. Mathews, 465 U. S. 728 , 744
(1984); J. E. B. v. Alabama ex rel. T. B., 511 U. S. 127 ,
137, n. 6 (1994). While the majority adheres to this test today, ante, at 524, 533, it also says that the Commonwealth must
demonstrate an "'exceedingly persuasive justification'" to support
a gender-based classification. See ante, at 524, 529, 530,
531, 533, 534, 545, 546, 556. It is unfortunate that the Court
thereby introduces an element of uncertainty respecting the
appropriate test.
While terms like "important governmental objective" and
"substantially related" are hardly models of precision, they have
more content and specificity than does the phrase "exceedingly
persuasive justification." That phrase is best confined, as it was
first used, as an observation on the difficulty of meeting the
applicable test, not as a formulation of the test itself. See, e. g., Feeney, supra, at 273 ("[T]hese precedents dictate
that any state law overtly or covertly designed to prefer males
over females in public employment require an exceedingly persuasive
justification"). To avoid introducing potential confusion, I would
have adhered more closely to our traditional, "firmly established," Hogan, supra, at 723; Heckler, supra, at 744,
standard that a gender-based classification "must bear a close and
substantial relationship to important governmental objectives." Feeney, supra, at 273.
Our cases dealing with gender discrimination also require that
the proffered purpose for the challenged law be the actual purpose.
See ante, at 533, 535-536. It is on this ground that the
Court rejects the first of two justifications Virginia offers for
VMI's single-sex admissions policy, namely, the goal of diversity
among its public educational institutions. While I ultimately agree
that the Common- 560 REHNQUIST, C. J., concurring in judgment
wealth has not carried the day with this justification, I
disagree with the Court's method of analyzing the issue.
VMI was founded in 1839, and, as the Court notes, ante, at 536-537, admission was limited to men because under the
then-prevailing view men, not women, were destined for higher
education. However misguided this point of view may be by
present-day standards, it surely was not unconstitutional in 1839.
The adoption of the Fourteenth Amendment, with its Equal Protection
Clause, was nearly 30 years in the future. The interpretation of
the Equal Protection Clause to require heightened scrutiny for
gender discrimination was yet another century away.
Long after the adoption of the Fourteenth Amendment, and well
into this century, legal distinctions between men and women were
thought to raise no question under the Equal Protection Clause. The
Court refers to our decision in Goesaert v. Cleary, 335 U. S. 464 (1948). Likewise representing that now abandoned view was Hoyt v. Florida, 368 U. S. 57 (1961), where the Court
upheld a Florida system of jury selection in which men were
automatically placed on jury lists, but women were placed there
only if they expressed an affirmative desire to serve. The Court
noted that despite advances in women's opportunities, the "woman is
still regarded as the center of home and family life." Id., at 62.
Then, in 1971, we decided Reed v. Reed, 404 U. S. 71 , which the
Court correctly refers to as a seminal case. But its facts have
nothing to do with admissions to any sort of educational
institution. An Idaho statute governing the administration of
estates and probate preferred men to women if the other statutory
qualifications were equal. The statute's purpose, according to the
Idaho Supreme Court, was to avoid hearings to determine who was
better qualified as between a man and a woman both applying for
letters of administration. This Court held that such a rule
violated the Fourteenth Amendment because "a mandatory preference
to members of either 561 sex over members of the other, merely to accomplish the
elimination of hearings," was an "arbitrary legislative choice
forbidden by the Equal Protection Clause." Id., at 76. The
brief opinion in Reed made no mention of either Goesaert or Hoyt. Even at the time of our decision in Reed v. Reed, therefore, Virginia and VMI were scarcely on notice that its
holding would be extended across the constitutional board. They
were entitled to believe that "one swallow doesn't make a summer"
and await further developments. Those developments were 11 years in
coming. In Mississippi Univ. for Women v. Hogan,
supra, a case actually involving a singlesex admissions policy
in higher education, the Court held that the exclusion of men from
a nursing program violated the Equal Protection Clause. This
holding did place Virginia on notice that VMI's men-only admissions
policy was open to serious question.
The VMI Board of Visitors, in response, appointed a Mission
Study Committee to examine "the legality and wisdom of VMI's
single-sex policy in light of" Hogan. 766 F. Supp. 1407,
1427 (WD Va. 1991). But the committee ended up cryptically
recommending against changing VMI's status as a single-sex college.
After three years of study, the committee found "'no information'"
that would warrant a change in VMI's status. Id., at 1429.
Even the District Court, ultimately sympathetic to VMI's position,
found that "[t]he Report provided very little indication of how
[its] conclusion was reached" and that "[t]he one and one-half
pages in the committee's final report devoted to analyzing the
information it obtained primarily focuses on anticipated
difficulties in attracting females to VMI." Ibid. The
reasons given in the report for not changing the policy were the
changes that admission of women to VMI would require, and the
likely effect of those changes on the institution. That VMI would
have to change is simply not helpful in addressing the
constitutionality of the status after Hogan. 562 REHNQUIST, C. J., concurring in judgment
Before this Court, Virginia has sought to justify VMI's
single-sex admissions policy primarily on the basis that diversity
in education is desirable, and that while most of the public
institutions of higher learning in the Commonwealth are
coeducational, there should also be room for single-sex
institutions. I agree with the Court that there is scant evidence
in the record that this was the real reason that Virginia decided
to maintain VMI as men only. * But, unlike the majority, I would
consider only evidence that postdates our decision in Hogan, and would draw no negative inferences from the Commonwealth's
actions before that time. I think that after Hogan, the
Commonwealth was entitled to reconsider its policy with respect to
VMI, and not to have earlier justifications, or lack thereof, held
against it.
Even if diversity in educational opportunity were the
Commonwealth's actual objective, the Commonwealth's position would
still be problematic. The difficulty with its position is that the
diversity benefited only one sex; there was single-sex public
education available for men at VMI, but no corresponding single-sex
public education available for women. When Hogan placed
Virginia on notice that
*The dissent equates our conclusion that VMI's "asserted
interest in promoting diversity" is not" 'genuine,'" with a
"charge" that the diversity rationale is "a pretext for
discriminating against women." Post, at 579580. Of course,
those are not the same thing. I do not read the Court as saying
that the diversity rationale is a pretext for discrimination, and I
would not endorse such a proposition. We may find that diversity
was not the Commonwealth's real reason without suggesting, or
having to show, that the real reason was "antifeminism," post, at 580. Our cases simply require that the proffered
purpose for the challenged gender classification be the actual
purpose, although not necessarily recorded. See ante, at
533, 535-536. The dissent also says that the interest in diversity
is so transparent that having to articulate it is "absurd on its
face." Post, at 592. Apparently, that rationale was not
obvious to the Mission Study Committee which failed to list it
among its reasons for maintaining VMI's all-men admissions
policy. 563 VMI's admissions policy possibly was unconstitutional, VMI could
have dealt with the problem by admitting women; but its governing
body felt strongly that the admission of women would have seriously
harmed the institution's educational approach. Was there something
else the Commonwealth could have done to avoid an equal protection
violation? Since the Commonwealth did nothing, we do not have to
definitively answer that question.
I do not think, however, that the Commonwealth's options were as
limited as the majority may imply. The Court cites, without
expressly approving it, a statement from the opinion of the
dissenting judge in the Court of Appeals, to the effect that the
Commonwealth could have "simultaneously opened single-gender
undergraduate institutions having substantially comparable
curricular and extra-curricular programs, funding, physical plant,
administration and support services, and faculty and library
resources." Ante, at 529-530 (internal quotation marks
omitted). If this statement is thought to exclude other
possibilities, it is too stringent a requirement. VMI had been in
operation for over a century and a half, and had an established,
successful, and devoted group of alumni. No legislative wand could
instantly call into existence a similar institution for women; and
it would be a tremendous loss to scrap VMI's history and tradition.
In the words of Grover Cleveland's second inaugural address, the
Commonwealth faced a condition, not a theory. And it was a
condition that had been brought about, not through defiance of
decisions construing gender bias under the Equal Protection Clause,
but, until the decision in Hogan, a condition that had not
appeared to offend the Constitution. Had Virginia made a genuine
effort to devote comparable public resources to a facility for
women, and followed through on such a plan, it might well have
avoided an equal protection violation. I do not believe the
Commonwealth was faced with the stark choice of either admitting
women to VMI, on the 564 REHNQUIST, C. J., concurring in judgment
one hand, or abandoning VMI and starting from scratch for both
men and women, on the other.
But, as I have noted, neither the governing board of VMI nor the
Commonwealth took any action after 1982. If diversity in the form
of single-sex, as well as coeducational, institutions of higher
learning were to be available to Virginians, that diversity had to
be available to women as well as to men.
The dissent criticizes me for "disregarding the four allwomen's
private colleges in Virginia (generously assisted by public
funds)." Post, at 595. The private women's colleges are
treated by the Commonwealth exactly as all other private
schools are treated, which includes the provision of
tuition-assistance grants to Virginia residents. Virginia gives no
special support to the women's single-sex education. But obviously,
the same is not true for men's education. Had the Commonwealth
provided the kind of support for the private women's schools that
it provides for VMI, this may have been a very different case. For
in so doing, the Commonwealth would have demonstrated that its
interest in providing a single-sex education for men was to some
measure matched by an interest in providing the same opportunity
for women.
Virginia offers a second justification for the single-sex
admissions policy: maintenance of the adversative method. I agree
with the Court that this justification does not serve an important
governmental objective. A State does not have substantial interest
in the adversative methodology unless it is pedagogically
beneficial. While considerable evidence shows that a single-sex
education is pedagogically beneficial for some students, see 766 F.
Supp., at 1414, and hence a State may have a valid interest in
promoting that methodology, there is no similar evidence in the
record that an adversative method is pedagogically beneficial or is
any more likely to produce character traits than other
methodologies. 565 II
The Court defines the constitutional violation in these cases as
"the categorical exclusion of women from an extraordinary
educational opportunity afforded to men." Ante, at 547. By
defining the violation in this way, and by emphasizing that a
remedy for a constitutional violation must place the victims of
discrimination in "'the position they would have occupied in the
absence of [discrimination],'" ibid., the Court necessarily
implies that the only adequate remedy would be the admission of
women to the allmale institution. As the foregoing discussion
suggests, I would not define the violation in this way; it is not
the "exclusion of women" that violates the Equal Protection Clause,
but the maintenance of an all-men school without providing any-much
less a comparable-institution for women.
Accordingly, the remedy should not necessarily require either
the admission of women to VMI or the creation of a VMI clone for
women. An adequate remedy in my opinion might be a demonstration by
Virginia that its interest in educating men in a single-sex
environment is matched by its interest in educating women in a
single-sex institution. To demonstrate such, the Commonwealth does
not need to create two institutions with the same number of faculty
Ph. Do's, similar SAT scores, or comparable athletic fields. See ante, at 551-552. Nor would it necessarily require that the
women's institution offer the same curriculum as the men's; one
could be strong in computer science, the other could be strong in
liberal arts. It would be a sufficient remedy, I think, if the two
institutions offered the same quality of education and were of the
same overall caliber.
If a State decides to create single-sex programs, the State
would, I expect, consider the public's interest and demand in
designing curricula. And rightfully so. But the State should avoid
assuming demand based on stereotypes; it must not assume a
priori, without evidence, that there would be 566 no interest in a women's school of civil engineering, or in a
men's school of nursing.
In the end, the women's institution Virginia proposes, VWIL,
fails as a remedy, because it is distinctly inferior to the
existing men's institution and will continue to be for the
foreseeable future. VWIL simply is not, in any sense, the
institution that VMI is. In particular, VWIL is a program appended
to a private college, not a self-standing institution; and VWIL is
substantially underfunded as compared to VMI. I therefore
ultimately agree with the Court that Virginia has not provided an
adequate remedy.
JUSTICE SCALIA, dissenting.
Today the Court shuts down an institution that has served the
people of the Commonwealth of Virginia with pride and distinction
for over a century and a half. To achieve that desired result, it
rejects (contrary to our established practice) the factual findings
of two courts below, sweeps aside the precedents of this Court, and
ignores the history of our people. As to facts: It explicitly
rejects the finding that there exist "gender-based developmental
differences" supporting Virginia's restriction of the "adversative"
method to only a men's institution, and the finding that the
all-male composition of the Virginia Military Institute (VMI) is
essential to that institution's character. As to precedent: It
drastically revises our established standards for reviewing
sex-based classifications. And as to history: It counts for nothing
the long tradition, enduring down to the present, of men's military
colleges supported by both States and the Federal Government.
Much of the Court's opinion is devoted to deprecating the
closed-mindedness of our forebears with regard to women's
education, and even with regard to the treatment of women in areas
that have nothing to do with education. Closedminded they were-as
every age is, including our own, with regard to matters it cannot
guess, because it simply does not 567 consider them debatable. The virtue of a democratic system with
a First Amendment is that it readily enables the people, over time,
to be persuaded that what they took for granted is not so, and to
change their laws accordingly. That system is destroyed if the smug
assurances of each age are removed from the democratic process and
written into the Constitution. So to counterbalance the Court's
criticism of our ancestors, let me say a word in their praise: They
left us free to change. The same cannot be said of this most
illiberal Court, which has embarked on a course of inscribing one
after another of the current preferences of the society (and in
some cases only the countermajoritarian preferences of the
society's law-trained elite) into our Basic Law. Today it enshrines
the notion that no substantial educational value is to be served by
an all-men's military academy-so that the decision by the people of
Virginia to maintain such an institution denies equal protection to
women who cannot attend that institution but can attend others.
Since it is entirely clear that the Constitution of the United
States-the old one-takes no sides in this educational debate, I
dissent.
I
I shall devote most of my analysis to evaluating the Court's
opinion on the basis of our current equal protection jurisprudence,
which regards this Court as free to evaluate everything under the
sun by applying one of three tests: "rational basis" scrutiny,
intermediate scrutiny, or strict scrutiny. These tests are no more
scientific than their names suggest, and a further element of
randomness is added by the fact that it is largely up to us which
test will be applied in each case. Strict scrutiny, we have said,
is reserved for state "classifications based on race or national
origin and classifications affecting fundamental rights," Clark v. Jeter, 486 U. S. 456 , 461 (1988)
(citation omitted). It is my position that the term "fundamental
rights" should be limited to "interest[s] traditionally protected
by our society," Michael H. 568 v. Gerald D., 491 U. S. 110 , 122 (1989)
(plurality opinion of SCALIA, J.); but the Court has not accepted
that view, so that strict scrutiny will be applied to the
deprivation of whatever sort of right we consider "fundamental." We
have no established criterion for "intermediate scrutiny" either,
but essentially apply it when it seems like a good idea to load the
dice. So far it has been applied to content-neutral restrictions
that place an incidental burden on speech, to disabilities
attendant to illegitimacy, and to discrimination on the basis of
sex. See, e. g., Turner Broadcasting System, Inc. v. FCC, 512 U. S.
622 , 662 (1994); Mills v. Habluetzel, 456 U. S. 91 , 98-99 (1982); Craig v. Boren, 429 U. S. 190 , 197
(1976).
I have no problem with a system of abstract tests such as
rational basis, intermediate, and strict scrutiny (though I think
we can do better than applying strict scrutiny and intermediate
scrutiny whenever we feel like it). Such formulas are essential to
evaluating whether the new restrictions that a changing society
constantly imposes upon private conduct comport with that "equal
protection" our society has always accorded in the past. But in my
view the function of this Court is to preserve our society's
values regarding (among other things) equal protection, not to revise them; to prevent backsliding from the degree of
restriction the Constitution imposed upon democratic government,
not to prescribe, on our own authority, progressively higher
degrees. For that reason it is my view that, whatever abstract
tests we may choose to devise, they cannot supersede-and indeed
ought to be crafted so as to reflect-those constant and
unbroken national traditions that embody the people's understanding
of ambiguous constitutional texts. More specifically, it is my view
that "when a practice not expressly prohibited by the text of the
Bill of Rights bears the endorsement of a long tradition of open,
widespread, and unchallenged use that dates back to the beginning
of the Republic, we have no proper basis for striking it down." Rutan v. Republican Party of Ill., 497 U. S. 62 , 95 (1990)
(SCALIA, J., 569 dissenting). The same applies, mutatis mutandis, to a
practice asserted to be in violation of the post-Civil War
Fourteenth Amendment. See, e. g., Burnham v. Superior
Court of Cal., County of Marin, 495 U. S. 604 (1990)
(plurality opinion of SCALIA, J.) (Due Process Clause); J. E. B. v. Alabama ex rel. T. B., 511 U. S. 127 , 156-163
(1994) (SCALIA, J., dissenting) (Equal Protection Clause); Planned Parenthood of Southeastern Pa. v. Casey, 505 U. S. 833 ,
979-984, 1000-1001 (1992) (SCALIA, J., dissenting) (various alleged
"penumbras").
The all-male constitution of VMI comes squarely within such a
governing tradition. Founded by the Commonwealth of Virginia in
1839 and continuously maintained by it since, VMI has always
admitted only men. And in that regard it has not been unusual. For
almost all of VMI's more than a century and a half of existence,
its single-sex status reflected the uniform practice for
government-supported military colleges. Another famous Southern
institution, The Citadel, has existed as a state-funded school of
South Carolina since 1842. And all the federal military
colleges-West Point, the Naval Academy at Annapolis, and even the
Air Force Academy, which was not established until 1954-admitted
only males for most of their history. Their admission of women in
1976 (upon which the Court today relies, see ante, at
544-545, nn. 13, 15) came not by court decree, but because the
people, through their elected representatives, decreed a change.
See, e. g., § 803(a), 89 Stat. 537, note following 10
U. S. C. § 4342. In other words, the tradition of having
government-funded military schools for men is as well rooted in the
traditions of this country as the tradition of sending only men
into military combat. The people may decide to change the one
tradition, like the other, through democratic processes; but the
assertion that either tradition has been unconstitutional through
the centuries is not law, but politics-smuggled-into-Iaw.
And the same applies, more broadly, to single-sex education in
general, which, as I shall discuss, is threatened by 570 today's decision with the cutoff of all state and federal
support. Government-run nonmilitary educational institutions for
the two sexes have until very recently also been part of our
national tradition. "[It is] [c]oeducation, historically, [that] is
a novel educational theory. From grade school through high school,
college, and graduate and professional training, much of the
Nation's population during much of our history has been educated in
sexually segregated classrooms." Mississippi Univ. for Women v. Hogan, 458
U. S. 718 , 736 (1982) (Powell, J., dissenting); see id., at 736-739. These traditions may of course be changed by the
democratic decisions of the people, as they largely have been.
Today, however, change is forced upon Virginia, and reversion to
single-sex education is prohibited nationwide, not by democratic
processes but by order of this Court. Even while bemoaning the
sorry, bygone days of "fixed notions" concerning women's education,
see ante, at 536-537, and n. 10, 537539, 542-544, the Court
favors current notions so fixedly that it is willing to write them
into the Constitution of the United States by application of
custom-built "tests." This is not the interpretation of a
Constitution, but the creation of one.
II
To reject the Court's disposition today, however, it is not
necessary to accept my view that the Court's made-up tests cannot
displace longstanding national traditions as the primary
determinant of what the Constitution means. It is only necessary to
apply honestly the test the Court has been applying to sex-based
classifications for the past two decades. It is well settled, as
JUSTICE O'CONNOR stated some time ago for a unanimous Court, that
we evaluate a statutory classification based on sex under a
standard that lies "[b]etween thee] extremes of rational basis
review and strict scrutiny." Clark v. Jeter, 486 U.
S., at 461. We have denominated this standard "intermediate
scrutiny" and under it have inquired whether the statutory
classification is "sub- 571 stantially related to an important governmental objective."
Ibid. See, e. g., Heckler v. Mathews, 465 U. S. 728 , 744
(1984); Wengler v. Druggists Mut. Ins. Co., 446 U. S. 142 , 150
(1980); Craig v. Boren, 429 U. S., at 197.
Before I proceed to apply this standard to VMI, I must comment
upon the manner in which the Court avoids doing so.
Notwithstanding our above-described precedents and their" 'firmly
established principles,'" Heckler, supra, at 744 (quoting Hogan, supra, at 723), the United States urged us to hold in
this litigation "that strict scrutiny is the correct constitutional
standard for evaluating classifications that deny opportunities to
individuals based on their sex." Brief for United States in No.
94-2107, p. 16. (This was in fiat contradiction of the Government's
position below, which was, in its own words, to "stat[e] unequivocally that the appropriate standard in this case is
'intermediate scrutiny.'" 2 Record, Doc. No. 88, p. 3 (emphasis
added).) The Court, while making no reference to the Government's
argument, effectively accepts it.
Although the Court in two places recites the test as stated in Hogan, see ante, at 524, 532-533, which asks whether
the State has demonstrated "that the classification serves
important governmental objectives and that the discriminatory means
employed are substantially related to the achievement of those
objectives," 458 U. S., at 724 (internal quotation marks omitted),
the Court never answers the question presented in anything
resembling that form. When it engages in analysis, the Court
instead prefers the phrase "exceedingly persuasive justification"
from Hogan. The Court's nine invocations of that phrase, see ante, at 524, 529, 530, 531, 533, 534, 545, 546, 556, and
even its fanciful description of that imponderable as "the core
instruction" of the Court's decisions in J. E. B. v. Alabama ex rel. T. B., supra, and Hogan, supra, see ante, at 531, would be unobjectionable if the Court
acknowledged that whether a "justification" is "exceedingly
persuasive" must be assessed by asking 572 "[whether] the classification serves important governmental
objectives and [whether] the discriminatory means employed are
substantially related to the achievement of those objectives."
Instead, however, the Court proceeds to interpret "exceedingly
persuasive justification" in a fashion that contradicts the
reasoning of Hogan and our other precedents.
That is essential to the Court's result, which can only be
achieved by establishing that intermediate scrutiny is not survived
if there are some women interested in attending VMI, capable
of undertaking its activities, and able to meet its physical
demands. Thus, the Court summarizes its holding as follows: "In contrast to the generalizations about women on which
Virginia rests, we note again these dispositive realities:
VMI's implementing methodology is not inherently unsuitable
to women; some women do well under the adversative model; some women, at least, would want to attend VMI if they had
the opportunity; some women are capable of all of the
individual activities required of VMI cadets and can meet the
physical standards VMI now imposes on men." Ante, at 550
(internal quotation marks, citations, and punctuation omitted;
emphasis added). Similarly, the Court states that "[t]he Commonwealth's
justification for excluding all women from 'citizen-soldier'
training for which some are qualified ... cannot rank as
'exceedingly persuasive' .... " Ante, at 545.1
1 Accord, ante, at 541 ("In sum ... , neither the goal of
producing citizensoldiers, VMI's raison d'etre, nor VMI's
implementing methodology is inherently unsuitable to women"
(internal quotation marks omitted; emphasis added)); ante, at 542 ("[T]he question is whether the Commonwealth can
constitutionally deny to women who have the will and capacity, the
training and attendant opportunities that VMI uniquely affords"); ante, at 547-548 (the "violation" is that "equal protection
[has been] denied to women ready, willing, and able to benefit from
educational opportunities of the kind VMI offers"); ante, at
550 ("As earlier stated, see supra, at 541-542, gen- 573 Only the amorphous "exceedingly persuasive justification"
phrase, and not the standard elaboration of intermediate scrutiny,
can be made to yield this conclusion that VMI's single-sex
composition is unconstitutional because there exist several women
(or, one would have to conclude under the Court's reasoning, a
single woman) willing and able to undertake VMI's program.
Intermediate scrutiny has never required a least-restrictive-means
analysis, but only a "substantial relation" between the
classification and the state interests that it serves. Thus, in Califano v. Webster, 430 U. S. 313 (1977) (per
curiam), we upheld a congressional statute that provided higher
Social Security benefits for women than for men. We reasoned that
"women ... as such have been unfairly hindered from earning as much
as men," but we did not require proof that each woman so benefited
had suffered discrimination or that each disadvantaged man had not;
it was sufficient that even under the former congressional scheme
"women on the average received lower retirement benefits
than men." Id., at 318, and n. 5 (emphasis added). The
reasoning in our other intermediate-scrutiny cases has similarly
required only a substantial relation between end and means, not a
perfect fit. In Rostker v. Goldberg, 453 U. S. 57 (1981), we
held that selective-service registration could constitutionally
exclude women, because even "assuming that a small number of women
could be drafted for noncombat roles, Congress simply did not
consider it worth the added burdens of including women in draft and
registration plans." Id., at 81. In Metro Broadcasting,
Inc. v. FCC, 497 U. S. 547 , 579,
582-583 (1990), overruled on other grounds, Adarand
Constructors, Inc. v. Pena, 515 U. S. 200 , 227
(1995), we held that a classification need not be accurate "in
every case" to survive intermediate scrutiny so long as, "in the
aggregate," it advances the underlying
eralizations about 'the way women are,' estimates of what is
appropriate for most women, no longer justify denying
opportunity to women whose talent and capacity place them outside
the average description"). 574 objective. There is simply no support in our cases for the
notion that a sex-based classification is invalid unless it relates
to characteristics that hold true in every instance.
Not content to execute a de facto abandonment of the
intermediate scrutiny that has been our standard for sex-based
classifications for some two decades, the Court purports to reserve
the question whether, even in principle, a higher standard (i. e., strict scrutiny) should apply. "The Court has," it says, "thus far reserved most stringent judicial scrutiny for
classifications based on race or national origin ... ," ante, at 532, n. 6 (emphasis added); and it describes our
earlier cases as having done no more than decline to "equat[e]
gender classifications, for all purposes, to classifications
based on race or national origin," ante, at 532 (emphasis
added). The wonderful thing about these statements is that they are
not actually false-just as it would not be actually false to say
that "our cases have thus far reserved the 'beyond a reasonable
doubt' standard of proof for criminal cases," or that "we have not
equated tort actions, for all purposes, to criminal prosecutions."
But the statements are misleading, insofar as they suggest that we
have not already categorically held strict scrutiny to be
inapplicable to sexbased classifications. See, e. g.,
Heckler v. Mathews, 465 U. S. 728 (1984) (upholding state action after applying only intermediate scrutiny); Michael M. v. Superior Court,
Somoma Cty., 450
U. S. 464 (1981) (plurality and both concurring opinions)
(same); Califano v. Webster, supra (per curiam) (same). And the statements are irresponsible, insofar as they are
calculated to destabilize current law. Our task is to clarify the
law-not to muddy the waters, and not to exact overcompliance by
intimidation. The States and the Federal Government are entitled to
know before they act the standard to which they will be
held, rather than be compelled to guess about the outcome of
Supreme Court peek-a-boo.
The Court's intimations are particularly out of place because it
is perfectly clear that, if the question of the applica- 575 ble standard of review for sex-based classifications were to be
regarded as an appropriate subject for reconsideration, the
stronger argument would be not for elevating the standard to strict
scrutiny, but for reducing it to rational-basis review. The latter
certainly has a firmer foundation in our past jurisprudence:
Whereas no majority of the Court has ever applied strict scrutiny
in a case involving sex-based classifications, we routinely applied
rational-basis review until the 1970's, see, e. g., Hoyt v. Florida, 368 U. S. 57 (1961); Goesaert v. Cleary, 335 U. S. 464 (1948). And
of course normal, rational-basis review of sex-based
classifications would be much more in accord with the genesis of
heightened standards of judicial review, the famous footnote in United States v. Carolene Products Co., 304 U. S. 144 (1938),
which said (intimatingly) that we did not have to inquire in the
case at hand "whether prejudice against discrete and insular minorities may
be a special condition, which tends seriously to curtail the
operation of those political processes ordinarily to be relied upon
to protect minorities, and which may call for a correspondingly
more searching judicial inquiry." Id., at 152-153, n. 4. It is hard to consider women a "discrete and insular minorit[y]"
unable to employ the "political processes ordinarily to be relied
upon," when they constitute a majority of the electorate. And the
suggestion that they are incapable of exerting that political power
smacks of the same paternalism that the Court so roundly condemns.
See, e. g., ante, at 536-537, 542-546 (and
accompanying notes). Moreover, a long list of legislation proves
the proposition false. See, e. g., Equal Pay Act of
1963, 29 U. S. C. § 206(d); Title VII of the Civil Rights Act of
1964, 42 U. S. C. § 2000e-2; Title IX of the Education Amendments
of 1972, 20 U. S. C. § 1681; Women's Business Ownership Act of
1988, Pub. L. 100-533, 102 Stat. 2689; 576 Violence Against Women Act of 1994, Pub. L. 103-322, Title IV;
108 Stat. 1902.
III
With this explanation of how the Court has succeeded in making
its analysis seem orthodox-and indeed, if intimations are to be
believed, even overly generous to VMI-I now proceed to describe how
the analysis should have been conducted. The question to be
answered, I repeat, is whether the exclusion of women from VMI is
"substantially related to an important governmental objective."
A
It is beyond question that Virginia has an important state
interest in providing effective college education for its citizens.
That single-sex instruction is an approach substantially related to
that interest should be evident enough from the long and continuing
history in this country of men's and women's colleges. But beyond
that, as the Court of Appeals here stated: "That single-gender
education at the college level is beneficial to both sexes is a fact established in this case." 44 F.3d
1229 , 1238 (CA4 1995) (emphasis added).
The evidence establishing that fact was overwhelmingindeed,
"virtually uncontradicted" in the words of the court that received
the evidence, 766 F. Supp. 1407, 1415 (WD Va. 1991). As an initial
matter, Virginia demonstrated at trial that "[a] substantial body
of contemporary scholarship and research supports the proposition
that, although males and females have significant areas of
developmental overlap, they also have differing developmental needs
that are deepseated." Id., at 1434. While no one questioned
that for many students a coeducational environment was nonetheless
not inappropriate, that could not obscure the demonstrated benefits
of single-sex colleges. For example, the District Court stated as
follows: "One empirical study in evidence, not questioned by any expert,
demonstrates that single-sex colleges pro- 577 vide better educational experiences than coeducational
institutions. Students of both sexes become more academically
involved, interact with faculty frequently, show larger increases
in intellectual self-esteem and are more satisfied with practically
all aspects of college experience (the sole exception is social
life) compared with their counterparts in coeducational
institutions. Attendance at an all-male college substantially
increases the likelihood that a student will carry out career plans
in law, business and college teaching, and also has a substantial
positive effect on starting salaries in business. Women's colleges
increase the chances that those who attend will obtain positions of
leadership, complete the baccalaureate degree, and aspire to higher
degrees." Id., at 1412. See also id., at 1434-1435 (factual findings). "[I]n the
light of this very substantial authority favoring single-sex
education," the District Court concluded that "the VMI Board's
decision to maintain an all-male institution is fully justified
even without taking into consideration the other unique features of
VMI's teaching and training." Id., at 1412. This finding
alone, which even this Court cannot dispute, see ante, at
535, should be sufficient to demonstrate the constitutionality of
VMI's all-male composition.
But besides its single-sex constitution, VMI is different from
other colleges in another way. It employs a "distinctive
educational method," sometimes referred to as the "adversative, or
doubting, model of education." 766 F. Supp., at 1413, 1421.
"Physical rigor, mental stress, absolute equality of treatment,
absence of privacy, minute regulation of behavior, and
indoctrination in desirable values are the salient attributes of
the VMI educational experience." Id., at 1421. No one
contends that this method is appropriate for all individuals;
education is not a "one size fits all" business. Just as a State
may wish to support junior colleges, vocational institutes, or a
law school that emphasizes case 578 practice instead of classroom study, so too a State's decision
to maintain within its system one school that provides the
adversative method is "substantially related" to its goal of good
education. Moreover, it was uncontested that "if the state were to
establish a women's VMI-type [i. e., adversative] program,
the program would attract an insufficient number of participants to
make the program work," 44 F. 3d, at 1241; and it was found by the
District Court that if Virginia were to include women in VMI, the
school "would eventually find it necessary to drop the adversative
system altogether," 766 F. Supp., at 1413. Thus, Virginia's options
were an adversative method that excludes women or no adversative
method at all.
There can be no serious dispute that, as the District Court
found, single-sex education and a distinctive educational method
"represent legitimate contributions to diversity in the Virginia
higher education system." Ibid. As a theoretical matter,
Virginia's educational interest would have been best served
(insofar as the two factors we have mentioned are concerned) by six
different types of public colleges-an all-men's, an all-women's,
and a coeducational college run in the "adversative method," and an
all-men's, an all-women's, and a coeducational college run in the
"traditional method." But as a practical matter, of course,
Virginia's financial resources, like any State's, are not
limitless, and the Commonwealth must select among the available
options. Virginia thus has decided to fund, in addition to some 14
coeducational4-year colleges, one college that is run as an
all-male school on the adversative model: the Virginia Military
Institute.
Virginia did not make this determination regarding the make-up
of its public college system on the unrealistic assumption that no
other colleges exist. Substantial evidence in the District Court
demonstrated that the Commonwealth has long proceeded on the
principle that" '[h]igher education resources should be viewed as a
whole-public and pri- 579 vate' "-because such an approach enhances diversity and because
"'it is academic and economic waste to permit unwarranted
duplication.'" Id., at 1420-1421 (quoting 1974 Report of the
General Assembly Commission on Higher Education to the General
Assembly of Virginia). It is thus significant that, whereas there
are "four all-female private [colleges] in Virginia," there is only
"one private all-male college," which "indicates that the private
sector is providing for thee] [former] form of education to a much
greater extent that it provides for all-male education." 766 F.
Supp., at 1420-1421. In these circumstances, Virginia's election to
fund one public all-male institution and one on the adversative
model-and to concentrate its resources in a single entity that
serves both these interests in diversity-is substantially related
to the Commonwealth's important educational interests.
B
The Court today has no adequate response to this clear
demonstration of the conclusion produced by application of
intermediate scrutiny. Rather, it relies on a series of contentions
that are irrelevant or erroneous as a matter of law, foreclosed by
the record in this litigation, or both.
1. I have already pointed out the Court's most fundamental
error, which is its reasoning that VMI's all-male composition is
unconstitutional because "some women are capable of all of the
individual activities required of VMI cadets," 766 F. Supp., at
1412, and would prefer military training on the adversative model.
See supra, at 571-574. This unacknowledged adoption of what
amounts to (at least) strict scrutiny is without antecedent in our
sex-discrimination cases and by itself discredits the Court's
decision.
2. The Court suggests that Virginia's claimed purpose in
maintaining VMI as an all-male institution-its asserted interest in
promoting diversity of educational options-is not "genuin[e]," but
is a pretext for discriminating against women. Ante, at 539;
see ante, at 535-540. To support this 580 charge, the Court would have to impute that base motive to VMI's
Mission Study Committee, which conducted a 3-year study from 1983
to 1986 and recommended to VMI's Board of Visitors that the school
remain all male. The committee, a majority of whose members
consisted of non- VMI graduates, "read materials on education and
on women in the military," "made site visits to single-sex and
newly coeducational institutions" including West Point and the
Naval Academy, and "considered the reasons that other institutions
had changed from single-sex to coeducational status"; its work was
praised as "thorough" in the accreditation review of VMI conducted
by the Southern Association of Colleges and Schools. See 766 F.
Supp., at 1413, 1428; see also id., at 1427-1430 (detailed
findings of fact concerning the Mission Study Committee). The Court
states that "[w]hatever internal purpose the Mission Study
Committee servedand however well meaning the framers of the
report-we can hardly extract from that effort any commonwealth
policy evenhandedly to advance diverse educational options." Ante, at 539. But whether it is part of the evidence to
prove that diversity was the Commonwealth's objective (its
short report said nothing on that particular subject) is quite
separate from whether it is part of the evidence to prove that
antifeminism was not. The relevance of the Mission Study
Committee is that its very creation, its sober 3-year study, and
the analysis it produced utterly refute the claim that VMI has
elected to maintain its all-male student-body composition for some
misogynistic reason.
The Court also supports its analysis of Virginia's "actual state
purposes" in maintaining VMI's student body as all male by stating
that there is no explicit statement in the record "'in which the
Commonwealth has expressed itself'" concerning those purposes. Ante, at 535, 539 (quoting 976 F.2d
890 , 899 (CA4 1992)); see also ante, at 525. That is
wrong on numerous grounds. First and foremost, in its implication
that such an explicit statement of "actual purposes" 581 is needed. The Court adopts, in effect, the argument of the
United States that since the exclusion of women from VMI in 1839
was based on the "assumptions" of the time "that men alone were fit
for military and leadership roles," and since "[b]efore this
litigation was initiated, Virginia never sought to supply a valid,
contemporary rationale for VMI's exclusionary policy," "[t]hat
failure itself renders the VMI policy invalid." Brief for United
States in No. 94-2107, at 10. This is an unheard-of doctrine. Each
state decision to adopt or maintain a governmental policy need not
be accompanied-in anticipation of litigation and on pain of being
found to lack a relevant state interest-by a lawyer's
contemporaneous recitation of the State's purposes. The
Constitution is not some giant Administrative Procedure Act, which
imposes upon the States the obligation to set forth a "statement of
basis and purpose" for their sovereign Acts, see 5 U. S. C. §
553(c). The situation would be different if what the Court assumes
to have been the 1839 policy had been enshrined and
remained enshrined in legislation-a VMI charter, perhaps,
pronouncing that the institution's purpose is to keep women in
their place. But since the 1839 policy was no more explicitly
recorded than the Court contends the present one is, the mere fact
that today's Commonwealth continues to fund VMI "is enough
to answer [the United States'] contention that the [classification]
was the 'accidental by-product of a traditional way of thinking
about females.'" Michael M., 450 U. S., at 471, n. 6
(pluralityopinion) (quoting Califano v. Webster, 430
U. S., at 320) (internal quotation marks omitted).
It is, moreover, not true that Virginia's contemporary reasons
for maintaining VMI are not explicitly recorded. It is hard to
imagine a more authoritative source on this subject than the 1990
Report of the Virginia Commission on the University of the 21st
Century (1990 Report). As the parties stipulated, that report
"notes that the hallmarks of Virginia's educational policy are
'diversity and autonomy.'" Stipula- 582 tions of Fact 37, reprinted in Lodged Materials from the Record
64 (Lodged Materials). It said: "The formal system of higher
education in Virginia includes a great array of institutions:
state-supported and independent, two-year and senior, research and
highly specialized, traditionally black and single-sex." 1990 Report, quoted in relevant part at Lodged Materials 64-65
(emphasis added).2 The Court's only response to this is repeated
reliance on the Court of Appeals' assertion that "'the only
explicit [statement] that we have found in the record in which the
Commonwealth has expressed itself with respect to gender
distinctions'" (namely, the statement in the 1990 Report that the
Commonwealth's institutions must "deal with faculty, staff, and
students without regard to sex") had nothing to do with the purpose
of diversity. Ante, at 525, 539 (quoting 976 F. 2d, at 899).
This proves, I suppose, that the Court of Appeals did not find a
statement dealing with sex and diversity in the record; but the
pertinent question (accepting the need for such a statement) is whether it was there. And the plain fact, which the Court
does not deny, is that it was. 2 This statement is supported by other evidence in the record
demonstrating, by reference to both public and private
institutions, that Virginia actively seeks to foster its "'rich
heritage of pluralism and diversity in higher education,'" 1969
Report of the Virginia Commission on Constitutional Revision,
quoted in relevant part at Lodged Materials 53; that Virginia
views" '[o]ne special characteristic of the Virginia system [as
being] its diversity,'" 1989 Virginia Plan for Higher Education,
quoted in relevant part at Lodged Materials 64; and that in the
Commonwealth's view "[h]igher education resources should be viewed
as a whole-public and private"-because '''Virginia needs the
diversity inherent in a dual system of higher education,'" 1974
Report of the General Assembly Commission on Higher Education to
the General Assembly of Virginia, quoted in 766 F. Supp. 1407, 1420
(WD Va. 1991). See also Budget Initiatives for 19901992 of State
Council of Higher Education for Virginia 10 (June 21, 1989) (Budget
Initiatives), quoted at n. 3, infra. It should be noted (for
this point will be crucial to my later discussion) that these
official reports quoted here, in text and footnote, regard the
Commonwealth's educational system-public and private-as a
unitary one. 583 The Court contends that "[a] purpose genuinely to advance an
array of educational options ... is not served" by VMI. Ante, at 539-540. It relies on the fact that all of
Virginia's other public colleges have become coeducational. Ibid.; see also ante, at 521, n. 2. The apparent
theory of this argument is that unless Virginia pursues a great
deal of diversity, its pursuit of some diversity must be a sham.
This fails to take account of the fact that Virginia's resources
cannot support all possible permutations of schools, see supra, at 578, and of the fact that Virginia coordinates its
public educational offerings with the offerings of in-state private
educational institutions that the Commonwealth provides money for
its residents to attend and otherwise assists-which include four
women's colleges.3
Finally, the Court unreasonably suggests that there is some
pretext in Virginia's reliance upon decentralized deci-
3 The Commonwealth provides tuition assistance, scholarship
grants, guaranteed loans, and work-study funds for residents of
Virginia who attend private colleges in the Commonwealth. See, e. g., Va. Code Ann. §§ 23-38.11 to 23-38.19 (1993
and Supp. 1995) (Tuition Assistance Grant Act); §§ 23-38.30 to
23-38.44:3 (Virginia Student Assistance Authorities); Va. Code Ann.
§§ 23-38.45 to 23-38.53 (1993) (College Scholarship Assistance
Act); §§ 23-38.53:1 to 23-38.53:3 (Virginia Scholars Program); §§
2338.70,23-38.71 (Virginia Work-Study Program). These programs
involve substantial expenditures: for example, Virginia
appropriated $4,413,750 (not counting federal funds it also
earmarked) for the College Scholarship Assistance Program for both
1996 and 1997, and for the Tuition Assistance Grant Program
appropriated $21,568,000 for 1996 and $25,842,000 for 1997. See
1996 Va. Appropriations Act, ch. 912, pt. 1, § 160.
In addition, as the parties stipulated in the District Court,
the Commonwealth provides other financial support and assistance to
private institutions-including single-sex colleges-through low-cost
building loans, state-funded services contracts, and other
programs. See, e. g., Va. Code Ann. §§ 23-30.39 to
23.30.58 (1993) (Educational Facilities Authority Act). The State
Council of Higher Education for Virginia, in a 1989 document not
created for purposes of this litigation but introduced into
evidence, has described these various programs as a "means by which
the Commonwealth can provide funding to its independent
institutions, thereby helping to maintain a diverse system of
higher education." Budget Initiatives 10. 584 sionmaking to achieve diversity-its granting of substantial
autonomy to each institution with regard to student-body
composition and other matters, see 766 F. Supp., at 1419. The Court
adopts the suggestion of the Court of Appeals that it is not
possible for "one institution with autonomy, but with no authority
over any other state institution, [to] give effect to a state
policy of diversity among institutions." Ante, at 539
(internal quotation marks omitted). If it were impossible for
individual human beings (or groups of human beings) to act
autonomously in effective pursuit of a common goal, the game of
soccer would not exist. And where the goal is diversity in a free
market for services, that tends to be achieved even by autonomous
actors who act out of entirely selfish interests and make no effort
to cooperate. Each Virginia institution, that is to say, has a
natural incentive to make itself distinctive in order to attract a
particular segment of student applicants. And of course none of the
institutions is entirely autonomous; if and when the
legislature decides that a particular school is not well serving
the interest of diversity-if it decides, for example, that a men's
school is not much needed-funding will cease.4
4 The Court, unfamiliar with the Commonwealth's policy of
diverse and independent institutions, and in any event careless of
state and local traditions, must be forgiven by Virginians for
quoting a reference to "'the Charlottesville campus'" of the
University of Virginia. See ante, at 538. The University of
Virginia, an institution even older than VMI, though not as old as
another of the Commonwealth's universities, the College of William
and Mary, occupies the portion of Charlottesville known, not as the
"campus," but as "the grounds." More importantly, even if it were a
"campus," there would be no need to specify "the Charlottesville
campus," as one might refer to the Bloomington or Indianapolis
campus of Indiana University. Unlike university systems with which
the Court is perhaps more familiar, such as those in New York (e. g., the State University of New York at Binghamton or
Buffalo), Illinois (University of Illinois at Urbana-Champaign or
at Chicago), and California (University of California, Los Angeles,
or University of California, Berkeley), there is only one University of Virginia. It happens (because Thomas Jefferson lived
near there) to be located at Charlottesville. To many Virginians it
is known, 585 3. In addition to disparaging Virginia's claim that VMI's
single-sex status serves a state interest in diversity, the Court
finds fault with Virginia's failure to offer education based on the
adversative training method to women. It dismisses the District
Court's "'findings' on 'gender-based developmental differences'" on
the ground that "[t]hese 'findings' restate the opinions of
Virginia's expert witnesses, opinions about typically male or
typically female 'tendencies.'" Ante, at 541 (quoting 766 F.
Supp., at 1434-1435). How remarkable to criticize the District
Court on the ground that its findings rest on the evidence (i. e., the testimony of Virginia's witnesses)! That is what
findings are supposed to do. It is indefensible to tell the
Commonwealth that "[t]he burden of justification is demanding and
it rests entirely on [you]," ante, at 533, and then to
ignore the District Court's findings because they rest on
the evidence put forward by the Commonwealth-particularly when, as
the District Court said, "[t]he evidence in the case ... is virtually uncontradicted," 766 F. Supp., at 1415 (emphasis
added).
Ultimately, in fact, the Court does not deny the evidence
supporting these findings. See ante, at 541-546. It instead
makes evident that the parties to this litigation could have saved
themselves a great deal of time, trouble, and expense by omitting a
trial. The Court simply dispenses with the evidence submitted at
trial-it never says that a single finding of the District Court is
clearly erroneous-in favor of the Justices' own view of the world,
which the Court proceeds to support with (1) references to
observations of someone
simply, as "the University," which suffices to distinguish it
from the Commonwealth's other institutions offering 4-year college
instruction, which include Christopher Newport College, Clinch
Valley College, the College of William and Mary, George Mason
University, James Madison University, Longwood College, Mary
Washington University, Norfolk State University, Old Dominion
University, Radford University, Virginia Commonwealth University,
Virginia Polytechnic Institute and State University, Virginia State
University-and, of course, VMI. 586 who is not a witness, nor even an educational expert, nor even a
judge who reviewed the record or participated in the judgment
below, but rather a judge who merely dissented from the Court of
Appeals' decision not to rehear this litigation en bane, see ante, at 542, (2) citations of nonevidentiary materials such
as amicus curiae briefs filed in this Court, see ante, at 544-545, nn. 13, 14, and (3) various historical
anecdotes designed to demonstrate that Virginia's support for VMI
as currently constituted reminds the Justices of the "bad old
days," see ante, at 542-544.
It is not too much to say that this approach to the litigation
has rendered the trial a sham. But treating the evidence as
irrelevant is absolutely necessary for the Court to reach its
conclusion. Not a single witness contested, for example, Virginia's
"substantial body of 'exceedingly persuasive' evidence ... that
some students, both male and female, benefit from attending a
single-sex college" and "[that] [f]or those students, the
opportunity to attend a single-sex college is a valuable one,
likely to lead to better academic and professional achievement."
766 F. Supp., at 1411-1412. Even the United States' expert witness
"called himself a 'believer in single-sex education,'" although it
was his "personal, philosophical preference," not one "born of
educational-benefit considerations," "that single-sex education
should be provided only by the private sector." Id., at
1412.
4. The Court contends that Virginia, and the District Court,
erred, and "misperceived our precedent," by "train[ing] their
argument on 'means' rather than 'end,'" ante, at 545. The
Court focuses on "VMI's mission," which is to produce individuals
"imbued with love of learning, confident in the functions and
attitudes of leadership, possessing a high sense of public service,
advocates of the American democracy and free enterprise system, and
ready ... to defend their country in time of national peril." 766
F. Supp., at 1425 (quoting Mission Study Committee of the VMI Board
of 587 Visitors, Report, May 16, 1986). "Surely," the Court says, "that
goal is great enough to accommodate women." Ante, at
545.
This is lawmaking by indirection. What the Court describes as
"VMI's mission" is no less the mission of all Virginia
colleges. Which of them would the Old Dominion continue to fund if
they did not aim to create individuals "imbued with love of
learning, etc.," right down to being ready "to defend their country
in time of national peril"? It can be summed up as "learning,
leadership, and patriotism." To be sure, those general educational
values are described in a particularly martial fashion in VMI's
mission statement, in accordance with the military, adversative,
and all-male character of the institution. But imparting those
values in that fashion-i. e., in a military, adversative,
all-male environment-is the distinctive mission of VMI. And
as I have discussed (and both courts below found), that mission is not "great enough to accommodate women."
The Court's analysis at least has the benefit of producing
foreseeable results. Applied generally, it means that whenever a
State's ultimate objective is "great enough to accommodate women"
(as it always will be), then the State will be held to have
violated the Equal Protection Clause if it restricts to men even
one means by which it pursues that objective-no matter how few
women are interested in pursuing the objective by that means, no
matter how much the single-sex program will have to be changed if
both sexes are admitted, and no matter how beneficial that program
has theretofore been to its participants.
5. The Court argues that VMI would not have to change very much
if it were to admit women. See, e. g., ante, at 540-542. The principal response to that argument is that it is
irrelevant: If VMI's single-sex status is substantially related to
the government's important educational objectives, as I have
demonstrated above and as the Court refuses to dis- 588 cuss, that concludes the inquiry. There should be no debate in
the federal judiciary over "how much" VMI would be required to
change if it admitted women and whether that would constitute "too
much" change.
But if such a debate were relevant, the Court would certainly be
on the losing side. The District Court found as follows: "[T]he
evidence establishes that key elements of the adversative VMI
educational system, with its focus on barracks life, would be
fundamentally altered, and the distinctive ends of the system would
be thwarted, if VMI were forced to admit females and to make
changes necessary to accommodate their needs and interests." 766 F.
Supp., at 1411. Changes that the District Court's detailed analysis
found would be required include new allowances for personal privacy
in the barracks, such as locked doors and coverings on windows,
which would detract from VMI's approach of regulating minute
details of student behavior, "contradict the principle that
everyone is constantly subject to scrutiny by everyone else," and
impair VMI's "total egalitarian approach" under which every student
must be "treated alike"; changes in the physical training program,
which would reduce "[t]he intensity and aggressiveness of the
current program"; and various modifications in other respects of
the adversative training program that permeates student life. See id., at 1412-1413, 1435-1443. As the Court of Appeals
summarized it, "the record supports the district court's findings
that at least these three aspects of VMI's programphysical
training, the absence of privacy, and the adversative
approach-would be materially affected by coeducation, leading to a
substantial change in the egalitarian ethos that is a critical
aspect of VMI's training." 976 F. 2d, at 896-897.
In the face of these findings by two courts below, amply
supported by the evidence, and resulting in the conclusion that VMI
would be fundamentally altered if it admitted women, this Court
simply pronounces that "[t]he notion that 589 admission of women would downgrade VMI's stature, destroy the
adversative system and, with it, even the school, is a judgment
hardly proved." Ante, at 542 (footnote omitted). The point
about "downgrad[ing] VMI's stature" is a straw man; no one has made
any such claim. The point about "destroy[ing] the adversative
system" is simply false; the District Court not only stated that
"[e]vidence supports this theory," but specifically concluded that
while "[w]ithout a doubt" VMI could assimilate women, "it is
equally without a doubt that VMI's present methods of training and
education would have to be changed" by a "move away from its
adversative new cadet system." 766 F. Supp., at 1413, and n. 8,
1440. And the point about "destroy[ing] the school," depending upon
what that ambiguous phrase is intended to mean, is either false or
else sets a standard much higher than VMI had to meet. It sufficed
to establish, as the District Court stated, that VMI would be
"significantly different" upon the admission of women, 766 F.
Supp., at 1412, and "would eventually find it necessary to drop the
adversative system altogether," id., at 1413.5
5 The Court's do-it-yourself approach to factfinding, which
throughout is contrary to our well-settled rule that we will not
"undertake to review concurrent findings of fact by two courts
below in the absence of a very obvious and exceptional showing of
error," Graver Tank & Mfg. Co. v. Linde Air
Products Co., 336
U. S. 271 , 275 (1949) (and cases cited), is exemplified by its
invocation of the experience of the federal military academies to
prove that not much change would occur. See ante, at 542, n.
11; 544545, and n. 15; 550-551, n. 19. In fact, the District Court
noted that "the West Point experience" supported the theory
that a coeducational VMI would have to "adopt a [different]
system," for West Point found it necessary upon becoming
coeducational to "move away" from its adversative system. 766 F.
Supp., at 1413, 1440. ''Without a doubt ... VMI's present methods
of training and education would have to be changed as West Point's
were." Id., at 1413, n. 8; accord, 976
F.2d 890 , 896-897 (CA4 1992) (upholding District Court's
findings that "the unique characteristics of VMI's program,"
including its "unique methodology," "would be destroyed by
coeducation"). 590 6. Finally, the absence of a precise "all-women's analogue" to
VMI is irrelevant. In Mississippi Univ. for Women v. Hogan, 458 U.
S. 718 (1982), we attached no constitutional significance to
the absence of an all-male nursing school. As Virginia notes, if a
program restricted to one sex is necessarily unconstitutional
unless there is a parallel program restricted to the other sex,
"the opinion in Hogan could have ended with its first
footnote, which observed that 'Mississippi maintains no other
single-sex public university or college.'" Brief for
Cross-Petitioners in No. 94-2107, p. 38 (quoting Mississippi
Univ. for Women v. Hogan, supra, at 720, n. 1).
Although there is no precise female-only analogue to VMI,
Virginia has created during this litigation the Virginia Women's
Institute for Leadership (VWIL), a state-funded all-women's program
run by Mary Baldwin College. I have thus far said nothing about
VWIL because it is, under our established test, irrelevant, so long
as VMFs all-male character is "substantially related" to an
important state goal. But VWIL now exists, and the Court's
treatment of it shows how far reaching today's decision is.
VWIL was carefully designed by professional educators who have
long experience in educating young women. The program rejects the proposition that there is a "difference in the
respective spheres and destinies of man and woman," Bradwell v. State, 16 Wall. 130, 141 (1873), and is designed to
"provide an all-female program that will achieve substantially
similar outcomes [to VMI's] in an all-female environment," 852 F.
Supp. 471, 481 (WD Va. 1994). After holding a trial where
voluminous evidence was submitted and making detailed findings of
fact, the District Court concluded that "there is a legitimate
pedagogical basis for the different means employed [by VMI and
VWIL] to achieve the sub- 591 stantially similar ends." Ibid. The Court of Appeals
undertook a detailed review of the record and affirmed. 44 F.3d
1229 (CA4 1995).6 But it is Mary Baldwin College, which runs
VWIL, that has made the point most succinctly: "It would have been possible to develop the VWIL program to more
closely resemble VMI, with adversative techniques associated with
the rat line and barracks-like living quarters. Simply replicating
an existing program would have required far less thought, research,
and educational expertise. But such a facile approach would have
produced a paper program with no real prospect of successful
implementation." Brief for Mary Baldwin College as Amicus Curiae
5. It is worth noting that none of the United States' own experts
in the remedial phase of this litigation was willing to testify
that VMI's adversative method was an appropriate methodology for
educating women. This Court, however, does not care. Even though
VWIL was carefully designed by professional educators who have
tremendous experience in the area, and survived the test of
adversarial litigation, the Court simply declares, with no basis in
the evidence, that
6 The Court is incorrect in suggesting that the Court of Appeals
applied a "deferential" "brand of review inconsistent with the more
exacting standard our precedent requires." Ante, at 555.
That court "inquir[ed] (1) whether the state's objective is
'legitimate and important,' and (2) whether 'the requisite direct,
substantial relationship between objective and means is present,'"
44 F. 3d, at 1235 (quoting Mississippi Univ. for Women v. Hogan, 458 U.
S. 718 , 725 (1982)). To be sure, such review is "deferential"
to a degree that the Court's new standard is not, for it is
intermediate scrntiny. (The Court cannot evade this point or
prove the Court of Appeals too deferential by stating that that
court "devised another test, a 'substantive comparability'
inquiry,' " ante, at 555 (quoting 44 F. 3d, at 1237), for as
that court explained, its "substantive comparability" inquiry was
an "additional step" that it engrafted on "th[e] traditional
test" of intermediate scrutiny, ibid. (emphasis added).) 592 these professionals acted on "'overbroad' generalizations," ante, at 542, 550.
C
A few words are appropriate in response to the concurrence,
which finds VMI unconstitutional on a basis that is more moderate
than the Court's but only at the expense of being even more
implausible. The concurrence offers three reasons: First, that
there is "scant evidence in the record," ante, at 562, that
diversity of educational offering was the real reason for
Virginia's maintaining VMI. "Scant" has the advantage of being an
imprecise term. I have cited the clearest statements of diversity
as a goal for higher education in the 1990 Report, the 1989
Virginia Plan for Higher Education, the Budget Initiatives prepared
in 1989 by the State Council of Higher Education for Virginia, the
1974 Report of the General Assembly Commission on Higher Education
to the General Assembly of Virginia, and the 1969 Report of the
Virginia Commission on Constitutional Revision. See supra, at 579, 581-582, and n. 2, 583, n. 3. There is no evidence
to the contrary, once one rejects (as the concurrence rightly does)
the relevance of VMI's founding in days when attitudes toward the
education of women were different. Is this conceivably not enough
to foreclose rejecting as clearly erroneous the District Court's
determination regarding "the Commonwealth's objective of
educational diversity"? 766 F. Supp., at 1413. Especially since it
is absurd on its face even to demand "evidence" to prove
that the Commonwealth's reason for maintaining a men's military
academy is that a men's military academy provides a distinctive
type of educational experience (i. e., fosters diversity).
What other purpose would the Commonwealth have? One may
argue, as the Court does, that this type of diversity is
designed only to indulge hostility toward women-but that is a
separate point, explicitly rejected by the concurrence, and amply
refuted by the evidence I have mentioned in dis- 593 cussing the Court's opinion.7 What is now under discussion-the
concurrence's making central to the disposition of this litigation
the supposedly "scant" evidence that Virginia maintained VMI in
order to offer a diverse educational experience-is rather like
making crucial to the lawfulness of the United States Army record
"evidence" that its purpose is to do battle. A legal culture that
has forgotten the concept of res ipsa loquitur deserves the
fate that it today decrees for VMI.
Second, the concurrence dismisses out of hand what it calls
Virginia's "second justification for the single-sex admissions
policy: maintenance of the adversative method." Ante, at
564. The concurrence reasons that "this justification does not
serve an important governmental objective" because, whatever the
record may show about the pedagogical benefits of single-sex education, "there is no similar evidence in the record that an
adversative method is pedagogically beneficial or is any more
likely to produce character traits than other methodologies." Ibid. That is simply wrong. See, e. g., 766 F.
Supp., at 1426 (factual findings concerning character traits
produced by VMI's adversative methodology); id., at 1434
(factual findings concerning benefits for many college-age men of
an adversative approach in general). In reality, the pedagogical
benefits of VMI's adversative approach were not only proved, but
were a given in this litigation. The reason the woman
applicant who prompted this suit wanted to enter VMI was assuredly
not that she wanted to go to an all-male school; it would cease
being all-male as
7 The concurrence states that it "read[s] the Court" not "as
saying that the diversity rationale is a pretext" for
discriminating against women, but as saying merely that the
diversity rationale is not genuine. Ante, at 562, n. The
Court itself makes no such disclaimer, which would be difficult to
credit inasmuch as the foundation for its conclusion that the
diversity rationale is not "genuin[e]," ante, at 539, is its
antecedent discussion of Virginia's "deliberate" actions over the
past century and a half, based on "[f]amiliar arguments," that
sought to enforce once "widely held views about women's proper
place," ante, at 537, 538. 594 soon as she entered. She wanted the distinctive adversative
education that VMI provided, and the battle was joined (in the
main) over whether VMI had a basis for excluding women from that
approach. The Court's opinion recognizes this, and devotes much of
its opinion to demonstrating that "'some women ... do well under
[the] adversative model''' and that "[i]t is on behalf of these
women that the United States has instituted this suit." Ante, at 550 (quoting 766 F. Supp., at 1434). Of course, in
the last analysis it does not matter whether there are any benefits
to the adversative method. The concurrence does not contest that
there are benefits to single-sex education, and that alone
suffices to make Virginia's case, since admission of a woman will
even more surely put an end to VMI's single-sex education than it
will to VMI's adversative methodology.
A third reason the concurrence offers in support of the judgment
is that the Commonwealth and VMI were not quick enough to react to
the "further developments" in this Court's evolving jurisprudence. Ante, at 561. Specifically, the concurrence believes it
should have been clear after Hogan that "[t]he difficulty
with [Virginia's] position is that the diversity benefited only one
sex; there was single-sex public education available for men at
VMI, but no corresponding single-sex public education available for
women." Ante, at 562. If only, the concurrence asserts,
Virginia had "made a genuine effort to devote comparable public
resources to a facility for women, and followed through on such a
plan, it might well have avoided an equal protection violation." Ante, at 563. That is to say, the concurrence believes that
after our decision in Hogan (which held a program of the
Mississippi University for Women to be unconstitutional-without any
reliance on the fact that there was no corresponding Mississippi
all-men's program), the Commonwealth should have known that what
this Court expected of it was ... yes!, the creation of a state
all-women's program. Any lawyer who gave that advice to the
Commonwealth 595 ought to have been either disbarred or committed. (The proof of
that pudding is today's 6-Justice majority opinion.) And any
Virginia politician who proposed such a step when there were
already four 4-year women's colleges in Virginia (assisted by state
support that may well exceed, in the aggregate, what VMI costs, see
n. 3, supra) ought to have been recalled.
In any event, "diversity in the form of single-sex, as well as
coeducational, institutions of higher learning" is "available to women as well as to men" in Virginia. Ante, at
564. The concurrence is able to assert the contrary only by
disregarding the four all-women's private colleges in Virginia
(generously assisted by public funds) and the Commonwealth's
longstanding policy of coordinating public with private educational
offerings, see supra, at 579, 581-582, and n. 2, 583-584,
and n. 3. According to the concurrence, the reason Virginia's assistance to its four all-women's private colleges does
not count is that "[t]he private women's colleges are treated by
the State exactly as all other private schools are treated." Ante, at 564. But if Virginia cannot get credit for
assisting women's education if it only treats women's private
schools as it does all other private schools, then why should it
get blame for assisting men's education if it only treats
VMI as it does all other public schools? This is a great
puzzlement.
IV
As is frequently true, the Court's decision today will have
consequences that extend far beyond the parties to the litigation.
What I take to be the Court's unease with these consequences, and
its resulting unwillingness to acknowledge them, cannot alter the
reality.
A
Under the constitutional principles announced and applied today,
single-sex public education is unconstitutional. By going through
the motions of applying a balancing test-ask- 596 ing whether the State has adduced an "exceedingly persuasive
justification" for its sex-based classification-the Court creates
the illusion that government officials in some future case will
have a clear shot at justifying some sort of singlesex public
education. Indeed, the Court seeks to create even a greater
illusion than that: It purports to have said nothing of relevance
to other public schools at all. "We address specifically and
only an educational opportunity recognized ... as 'unique.'" Ante, at 534, n. 7.
The Supreme Court of the United States does not sit to announce
"unique" dispositions. Its principal function is to establish precedent-that is, to set forth principles of law that every
court in America must follow. As we said only this Term, we expect
both ourselves and lower courts to adhere to the "rationale upon which the Court based the results of its earlier decisions." Seminole Tribe of Fla. v. Florida, 517 U. S. 44 , 66-67 (1996)
(emphasis added). That is the principal reason we publish our
opinions.
And the rationale of today's decision is sweeping: for sexbased
classifications, a redefinition of intermediate scrutiny that makes
it indistinguishable from strict scrutiny. See supra, at
571-574. Indeed, the Court indicates that if any program restricted
to one sex is "uniqu[e]," it must be opened to members of the
opposite sex "who have the will and capacity" to participate in it. Ante, at 542. I suggest that the single-sex program that
will not be capable of being characterized as "unique" is not only
unique but nonexistent.8
In any event, regardless of whether the Court's rationale leaves
some small amount of room for lawyers to argue, it ensures that
single-sex public education is functionally dead.
8 In this regard, I note that the Court-which I concede is under
no obligation to do so-provides no example of a program that would pass muster under its reasoning today: not even, for
example, a football or wrestling program. On the Court's theory,
any woman ready, willing, and physically able to participate in
such a program would, as a constitutional matter, be
entitled to do so. 597 The costs of litigating the constitutionality of a single-sex
education program, and the risks of ultimately losing that
litigation, are simply too high to be embraced by public officials.
Any person with standing to challenge any sex-based classification
can haul the State into federal court and compel it to establish by
evidence (presumably in the form of expert testimony) that there is
an "exceedingly persuasive justification" for the classification.
Should the courts happen to interpret that vacuous phrase as
establishing a standard that is not utterly impossible of
achievement, there is considerable risk that whether the standard
has been met will not be determined on the basis of the record
evidence-indeed, that will necessarily be the approach of any court
that seeks to walk the path the Court has trod today. No state
official in his right mind will buy such a high-cost, high-risk
lawsuit by commencing a single-sex program. The enemies of
singlesex education have won; by persuading only seven Justices
(five would have been enough) that their view of the world is
enshrined in the Constitution, they have effectively imposed that
view on all 50 States.
This is especially regrettable because, as the District Court
here determined, educational experts in recent years have
increasingly come to "suppor[t] [the] view that substantial
educational benefits flow from a single-gender environment, be it
male or female, that cannot be replicated in a coeducational
setting." 766 F. Supp., at 1415 (emphasis added). "The evidence
in th[is] case," for example, "is virtually uncontradicted" to that
effect. Ibid. Until quite recently, some public officials
have attempted to institute new single-sex programs, at least as
experiments. In 1991, for example, the Detroit Board of Education
announced a program to establish three boys-only schools for
inner-city youth; it was met with a lawsuit, a preliminary
injunction was swiftly entered by a District Court that purported
to rely on Hogan, see Garrett v. Board of Ed. of
School Dist. of Detroit, 775 F. Supp. 1004, 1006 (ED Mich.
1991), and the 598 Detroit Board of Education voted to abandon the litigation and
thus abandon the plan, see Detroit Plan to Aid Blacks with All-Boy
Schools Abandoned, Los Angeles Times, Nov. 8, 1991, p. A4, col. 1.
Today's opinion assures that no such experiment will be tried
again.
B
There are few extant single-sex public educational programs. The
potential of today's decision for widespread disruption of existing
institutions lies in its application to private single-sex
education. Government support is immensely important to private
educational institutions. Mary Baldwin College-which designed and
runs VWILnotes that private institutions of higher education in the
1990-1991 school year derived approximately 19 percent of their
budgets from federal, state, and local government funds, not
including financial aid to students. See Brief for Mary Baldwin
College as Amicus Curiae 22, n. 13 (citing U. S. Dept. of
Education, National Center for Education Statistics, Digest of
Education Statistics, p. 38 and Note (1993)). Charitable status
under the tax laws is also highly significant for private
educational institutions, and it is certainly not beyond the Court
that rendered today's decision to hold that a donation to a
single-sex college should be deemed contrary to public policy and
therefore not deductible if the college discriminates on the basis
of sex. See Note, The Independent Sector and the Tax Laws: Defining
Charity in an Ideal Democracy, 64 S. Cal. L. Rev. 461, 476 (1991).
See also Bob Jones Univ. v. United States, 461 U. S. 574 (1983).
The Court adverts to private single-sex education only briefly,
and only to make the assertion (mentioned above) that "[w]e address
specifically and only an educational opportunity recognized by the
District Court and the Court of Appeals as 'unique.'" Ante, at 534, n. 7. As I have already remarked, see supra, at 596,
that assurance assures nothing, unless it is to be taken as a
promise that in the future 599 the Court will disclaim the reasoning it has used today to
destroy VMI. The Government, in its briefs to this Court, at least
purports to address the consequences of its attack on VMI for
public support of private single-sex education. It contends that
private colleges that are the direct or indirect beneficiaries of
government funding are not thereby necessarily converted into state
actors to which the Equal Protection Clause is then applicable. See
Brief for United States in No. 94-2107, at 35-37 (discussing Rendell-Baker v. Kohn, 457 U. S. 830 (1982), and Blum v. Yaretsky, 457 U. S. 991 (1982)).
That is true. It is also virtually meaningless.
The issue will be not whether government assistance turns
private colleges into state actors, but whether the government itself would be violating the Constitution by providing
state support to single-sex colleges. For example, in Norwood v. Harrison, 413 U. S. 455 (1973), we
saw no room to distinguish between state operation of racially
segregated schools and state support of privately run segregated
schools. "Racial discrimination in state-operated schools is barred
by the Constitution and '[i]t is also axiomatic that a state may
not induce, encourage or promote private persons to accomplish what
it is constitutionally forbidden to accomplish.'" Id., at
465 (quoting Lee v. Macon County Bd. of Ed., 267 F.
Supp. 458, 475-476 (MD Ala. 1967)); see also Cooper v. Aaron, 358 U. S.
1 , 19 (1958) ("State support of segregated schools through any
arrangement, management, funds, or property cannot be squared with
the [Fourteenth] Amendment's command that no State shall deny to
any person within its jurisdiction the equal protection of the
laws"); Grove City College v. Bell, 465 U. S. 555 , 565 (1984)
(case arising under Title IX of the Education Amendments of 1972
and stating that "[t]he economic effect of direct and indirect
assistance often is indistinguishable"). When the Government was
pressed at oral argument concerning the implications of these cases
for private single-sex education if government-provided single-sex
education is unconstitu- 600 tional, it stated that the implications will not be so
disastrous, since States can provide funding to racially segregated private schools, "depend[ing] on the
circumstances," Tr. of Oral Arg. 56. I cannot imagine what those
"circumstances" might be, and it would be as foolish for
privateschool administrators to think that that assurance from the
Justice Department will outlive the day it was made, as it was for
VMI to think that the Justice Department's "unequivoca[l]" support
for an intermediate-scrutiny standard in this litigation would
survive the Government's loss in the courts below.
The only hope for state-assisted single-sex private schools is
that the Court will not apply in the future the principles of law
it has applied today. That is a substantial hope, I am happy and
ashamed to say. After all, did not the Court today abandon the
principles of law it has applied in our earlier sex-classification
cases? And does not the Court positively invite private colleges to
rely upon our ad-hocery by assuring them this litigation is
"unique"? I would not advise the foundation of any new single-sex
college (especially an all-male one) with the expectation of being
allowed to receive any government support; but it is too soon to
abandon in despair those single-sex colleges already in existence.
I t will certainly be possible for this Court to write a future
opinion that ignores the broad principles of law set forth today,
and that characterizes as utterly dispositive the opinion's
perceptions that VMI was a uniquely prestigious allmale
institution, conceived in chauvinism, etc., etc. I will not join
that opinion.
***
Justice Brandeis said it is "one of the happy incidents of the
federal system that a single courageous State may, if its citizens
choose, serve as a laboratory; and try novel social and economic
experiments without risk to the rest of the country." New State
Ice Co. v. Liebmann, 285 U. S. 262 , 311 601 (1932) (dissenting opinion). But it is one of the unhappy
incidents of the federal system that a self-righteous Supreme
Court, acting on its Members' personal view of what would make a "
'more perfect Union,'" ante, at 558 (a criterion only
slightly more restrictive than a "more perfect world"), can impose
its own favored social and economic dispositions nationwide. As
today's disposition, and others this single Term, show, this places
it beyond the power of a "single courageous State," not only to
introduce novel dispositions that the Court frowns upon, but to
reintroduce, or indeed even adhere to, disfavored dispositions that
are centuries old. See, e. g., BMW of North America, Inc. v. Gore, 517 U.
S. 559 (1996); Romer v. Evans, 517 U. S. 620 (1996). The
sphere of self-government reserved to the people of the Republic is
progressively narrowed.
In the course of this dissent, I have referred approvingly to
the opinion of my former colleague, Justice Powell, in Mississippi Univ. for Women v. Hogan, 458 U. S. 718 (1982).
Many of the points made in his dissent apply with equal force
here-in particular, the criticism of judicial opinions that purport
to be "narro[w]" but whose "logic" is "sweepin[g]." Id., at
745-746, n. 18. But there is one statement with which I cannot
agree. Justice Powell observed that the Court's decision in Hogan, which struck down a single-sex program offered by the
Mississippi University for Women, had thereby "[l]eft without honor
... an element of diversity that has characterized much of American
education and enriched much of American life." Id., at 735.
Today's decision does not leave VMI without honor; no court opinion
can do that.
In an odd sort of way, it is precisely VMI's attachment to such
old-fashioned concepts as manly "honor" that has made it, and the
system it represents, the target of those who today succeed in
abolishing public single-sex education. The record contains a
booklet that all first-year VMI stu- 602 dents (the so-called "rats") were required to keep in their
possession at all times. N ear the end there appears the following
period piece, entitled "The Code of a Gentleman": "Without a strict observance of the fundamental Code of Honor,
no man, no matter how 'polished,' can be considered a gentleman.
The honor of a gentleman demands the inviolability of his word, and
the incorruptibility of his principles. He is the descendant of the
knight, the crusader; he is the defender of the defenseless and the
champion of justice ... or he is not a Gentleman. "A Gentleman ... "Does not discuss his family affairs in public or with
acquaintances. "Does not speak more than casually about his girl friend. "Does not go to a lady's house if he is affected by alcohol. He
is temperate in the use of alcohol. "Does not lose his temper; nor exhibit anger, fear, hate,
embarrassment, ardor or hilarity in public. "Does not hail a lady from a club window. "A gentleman never discusses the merits or demerits of a
lady. "Does not mention names exactly as he avoids the mention of what
things cost. "Does not borrow money from a friend, except in dire need. Money
borrowed is a debt of honor, and must be repaid as promptly as
possible. Debts incurred by a deceased parent, brother, sister or
grown child are assumed by honorable men as a debt of honor. "Does not display his wealth, money or possessions. "Does not
put his manners on and off, whether in the club or in a ballroom.
He treats people with courtesy, no matter what their social
position may be. 603 "Does not slap strangers on the back nor so much as lay a finger
on a lady. "Does not 'lick the boots of those above' nor 'kick the face of
those below him on the social ladder.' "Does not take advantage of another's helplessness or ignorance
and assumes that no gentleman will take advantage of him. "A Gentleman respects the reserves of others, but demands that
others respect those which are his. "A Gentleman can become what he wills to be .... "
I do not know whether the men of VMI lived by this code; perhaps
not. But it is powerfully impressive that a public institution of
higher education still in existence sought to have them do so. I do
not think any of us, women included, will be better off for its
destruction. | The United States sued Virginia and the Virginia Military Institute (VMI), arguing that VMI's male-only admission policy violated the Fourteenth Amendment's Equal Protection Clause. The Fourth Circuit Court of Appeals ruled in favor of the United States and ordered Virginia to remedy the constitutional violation. Virginia proposed a separate program for women, which the courts found satisfied equal protection requirements. The Supreme Court upheld that single-gender educational options are legitimate, but maintained that equal protection scrutiny is necessary. The Court concluded that Virginia's proposal provided "substantively comparable" benefits to both men and women, satisfying equal protection requirements. |
Equal Protection | Parents Involved in Community Schools v. Seattle School District No. 1 | https://supreme.justia.com/cases/federal/us/551/701/ | OPINION OF THE COURT PARENTS INVOLVED IN COMMUNITY SCHOOLS V.SEATTLE SCHOOL DIST. NO.
1 551 U. S. ____ (2007) SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES NOS. 05-908 AND 05-915 PARENTS INVOLVED IN COMMUNITY SCHOOLS,
PETITIONER
05–908 v. SEATTLE SCHOOL DISTRICT NO. 1
et al. on writ of certiorari to the united states
court of appeals for the ninth circuit CRYSTAL D. MEREDITH, custodial parent and next
friend of JOSHUA RYAN McDONALD, PETITIONER
05–915 v. JEFFERSON COUNTY BOARD OF EDUCATION
et al. on writ of certiorari to the united states
court of appeals for the sixth circuit [June 28, 2007] Chief Justice Roberts announced the judgment of the Court, and delivered the opinion of
the Court with respect to Parts I, II, III–A, and III–C, and an
opinion with respect to Parts III–B and IV, in which Justices
Scalia, Thomas, and Alito join.
The school districts in these
cases voluntarily adopted student assignment plans that rely upon
race to determine which public schools certain children may attend.
The Seattle school district classifies children as white or
nonwhite; the Jefferson County school district as black or “other.”
In Seattle, this racial classification is used to allocate slots in
oversubscribed high schools. In Jefferson County, it is used to
make certain elementary school assignments and to rule on transfer
requests. In each case, the school district relies upon an
individual student’s race in assigning that student to a particular
school, so that the racial balance at the school falls within a
predetermined range based on the racial composition of the school
district as a whole. Parents of students denied assignment to
particular schools under these plans solely because of their race
brought suit, contending that allocating children to different
public schools on the basis of race violated the Fourteenth
Amendment guarantee of equal protection. The Courts of Appeals
below upheld the plans. We granted certiorari, and now reverse.
I
Both cases present the same
underlying legal question—whether a public school that had not
operated legally segregated schools or has been found to be unitary
may choose to classify students by race and rely upon that
classification in making school assignments. Although we examine
the plans under the same legal framework, the specifics of the two
plans, and the circumstances surrounding their adoption, are in
some respects quite different.
A
Seattle School District No. 1
operates 10 regular public high schools. In 1998, it adopted the
plan at issue in this case for assigning students to these schools.
App. in No. 05–908, pp. 90a–92a.[ Footnote 1 ] The plan allows incoming ninth graders to
choose from among any of the district’s high schools, ranking
however many schools they wish in order of preference.
Some schools are more popular
than others. If too many students list the same school as their
first choice, the district employs a series of “tiebreakers” to
determine who will fill the open slots at the oversubscribed
school. The first tiebreaker selects for admission students who
have a sibling currently enrolled in the chosen school. The next
tiebreaker depends upon the racial composition of the particular
school and the race of the individual student. In the district’s
public schools approximately 41 percent of enrolled students are
white; the remaining 59 percent, comprising all other racial
groups, are classified by Seattle for assignment purposes as
nonwhite. Id., at 38a, 103a.[ Footnote 2 ] If an oversubscribed school is not within 10
percentage points of the district’s overall white/nonwhite racial
balance, it is what the district calls “integration positive,” and
the district employs a tiebreaker that selects for assignment
students whose race “will serve to bring the school into balance.” Id., at 38a. See Parents Involved VII, 426
F. 3d 1162, 1169–1170 (CA9 2005) (en banc).[ Footnote 3 ] If it is still necessary to select
students for the school after using the racial tiebreaker, the next
tiebreaker is the geographic proximity of the school to the
student’s residence. App. in No. 05–908, at 38a.
Seattle has never operated segregated
schools—legally separate schools for students of different
races—nor has it ever been subject to court-ordered desegregation.
It nonetheless employs the racial tiebreaker in an attempt to
address the effects of racially identifiable housing patterns on
school assignments. Most white students live in the northern part
of Seattle, most students of other racial backgrounds in the
southern part. Parents Involved VII , supra , at
1166. Four of Seattle’s high schools are located in the
north—Ballard, Nathan Hale, Ingraham, and Roosevelt—and five in the
south—Rainier Beach, Cleveland, West Seattle, Chief Sealth, and
Franklin. One school—Garfield—is more or less in the center of
Seattle. App. in No. 05–908, at 38a–39a, 45a.
For the 2000–2001 school year, five of these
schools were oversubscribed—Ballard, Nathan Hale, Roosevelt,
Garfield, and Franklin—so much so that 82 percent of incoming ninth
graders ranked one of these schools as their first choice. Id., at 38a. Three of the oversubscribed schools were
“integration positive” because the school’s white enrollment the
previous school year was greater than 51 percent—Ballard, Nathan
Hale, and Roosevelt. Thus, more nonwhite students (107, 27, and 82,
respectively) who selected one of these three schools as a top
choice received placement at the school than would have been the
case had race not been considered, and proximity been the next
tiebreaker. Id., at 39a–40a. Franklin was “integration
positive” because its nonwhite enrollment the previous school year
was greater than 69 percent; 89 more white students were assigned
to Franklin by operation of the racial tiebreaker in the 2000–2001
school year than otherwise would have been. Ibid. Garfield
was the only oversubscribed school whose composition during the
1999–2000 school year was within the racial guidelines, although in
previous years Garfield’s enrollment had been predominantly
nonwhite, and the racial tiebreaker had been used to give
preference to white students. Id., at 39a.
Petitioner Parents Involved in Community
Schools (Parents Involved) is a nonprofit corporation comprising
the parents of children who have been or may be denied assignment
to their chosen high school in the district because of their race.
The concerns of Parents Involved are illustrated by Jill Kurfirst,
who sought to enroll her ninth-grade son, Andy Meeks, in Ballard
High School’s special Biotechnology Career Academy. Andy suffered
from attention deficit hyperactivity disorder and dyslexia, but had
made good progress with hands-on instruction, and his mother and
middle school teachers thought that the smaller biotechnology
program held the most promise for his continued success. Andy was
accepted into this selective program but, because of the racial
tiebreaker, was denied assignment to Ballard High School. Id., at 143a–146a, 152a–160a. Parents Involved commenced
this suit in the Western District of Washington, alleging that
Seattle’s use of race in assignments violated the Equal Protection
Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment,[ Footnote 4 ] Title VI of the Civil Rights Act of
1964,[ Footnote 5 ] and the
Washington Civil Rights Act.[ Footnote 6 ] Id., at 28a–35a.
The District Court granted summary judgment to
the school district, finding that state law did not bar the
district’s use of the racial tiebreaker and that the plan survived
strict scrutiny on the federal constitutional claim because it was
narrowly tailored to serve a compelling government interest. 137
F. Supp. 2d 1224, 1240 (WD Wash. 2001) ( Parents Involved
I ). The Ninth Circuit initially reversed based on its
interpretation of the Washington Civil Rights Act, 285 F. 3d
1236, 1253 (2002) ( Parents Involved II ), and enjoined the
district’s use of the integration tiebreaker, id., at
1257. Upon realizing that the litigation would not be resolved in
time for assignment decisions for the 2002–2003 school year, the
Ninth Circuit withdrew its opinion, 294 F. 3d 1084 (2002)
( Parents Involved III ), vacated the injunction, and,
pursuant to Wash. Rev. Code §2.60.020 (2006), certified the
state-law question to the Washington Supreme Court, 294 F. 3d
1085, 1087 (2002) ( Parents Involved IV ).
The Washington Supreme Court determined that
the State Civil Rights Act bars only preferential treatment
programs “where race or gender is used by government to select a
less qualified applicant over a more qualified applicant,” and not
“[p]rograms which are racially neutral, such as the [district’s]
open choice plan.” Parents Involved in Community Schools v. Seattle School Dist., No. 1, 149 Wash. 2d 660, 689–690,
663, 72 P. 3d 151, 166, 153 (2003) (en banc) ( Parents
Involved V ). The state court returned the case to the Ninth
Circuit for further proceedings. Id., at 690, 72
P. 3d, at 167.
A panel of the Ninth Circuit then again
reversed the District Court, this time ruling on the federal
constitutional question. Parents Involved VI, 377
F. 3d 949 (2004). The panel determined that while achieving
racial diversity and avoiding racial isolation are compelling
government interests, id., at 964, Seattle’s use of the
racial tiebreaker was not narrowly tailored to achieve these
interests, id., at 980. The Ninth Circuit granted
rehearing en banc, 395 F. 3d 1168 (2005), and overruled the
panel decision, affirming the District Court’s determination that
Seattle’s plan was narrowly tailored to serve a compelling
government interest, Parents Involved VII , 426 F. 3d,
at 1192–1193. We granted certiorari. 547 U. S. __ (2006).
B
Jefferson County Public Schools
operates the public school system in metropolitan Louisville,
Kentucky. In 1973 a federal court found that Jefferson County had
maintained a segregated school system, Newburg Area Council,
Inc. v. Board of Ed. of Jefferson Cty. , 489
F. 2d 925, 932 (CA6), vacated and remanded, 418 U. S. 918 ,
reinstated with modifications, 510 F. 2d 1358, 1359 (CA6
1974), and in 1975 the District Court entered a desegregation
decree. See Hampton v. Jefferson Cty. Bd. of Ed. ,
72 F. Supp. 2d 753, 762–764 (WD Ky. 1999). Jefferson County
operated under this decree until 2000, when the District Court
dissolved the decree after finding that the district had achieved
unitary status by eliminating “[t]o the greatest extent
practicable” the vestiges of its prior policy of segregation. Hampton v. Jefferson Cty. Bd. of Ed. , 102
F. Supp. 2d 358, 360 (2000). See Board of Ed. of Oklahoma
City Public Schools v. Dowell , 498 U. S. 237 , 249–250
(1991); Green v. School Bd. of New Kent Cty. , 391 U. S. 430 ,
435–436 (1968).
In 2001, after the decree had
been dissolved, Jefferson County adopted the voluntary student
assignment plan at issue in this case. App. in No. 05–915, p. 77.
Approximately 34 percent of the district’s 97,000 students are
black; most of the remaining 66 percent are white. McFarland v. Jefferson Cty. Public Schools , 330
F. Supp. 2d 834, 839–840, and n. 6 (WD Ky. 2004)
( McFarland I ). The plan requires all nonmagnet schools to
maintain a minimum black enrollment of 15 percent, and a maximum
black enrollment of 50 percent. App. in No. 05–915, at 81; McFarland I , supra , at 842.
At the elementary school level, based on his
or her address, each student is designated a “resides” school to
which students within a specific geographic area are assigned;
elementary resides schools are “grouped into clusters in order to
facilitate integration.” App. in No. 05–915, at 82. The district
assigns students to nonmagnet schools in one of two ways: Parents
of kindergartners, first-graders, and students new to the district
may submit an application indicating a first and second choice
among the schools within their cluster; students who do not submit
such an application are assigned within the cluster by the
district. “Decisions to assign students to schools within each
cluster are based on available space within the schools and the
racial guidelines in the District’s current student assignment
plan.” Id., at 38. If a school has reached the “extremes
of the racial guidelines,” a student whose race would contribute to
the school’s racial imbalance will not be assigned there. Id., at 38–39, 82. After assignment, students at all grade
levels are permitted to apply to transfer between nonmagnet schools
in the district. Transfers may be requested for any number of
reasons, and may be denied because of lack of available space or on
the basis of the racial guidelines. Id., at 43.[ Footnote 7 ]
When petitioner Crystal Meredith moved into
the school district in August 2002, she sought to enroll her son,
Joshua McDonald, in kindergarten for the 2002–2003 school year. His
resides school was only a mile from his new home, but it had no
available space—assignments had been made in May, and the class was
full. Jefferson County assigned Joshua to another elementary school
in his cluster, Young Elementary. This school was 10 miles from
home, and Meredith sought to transfer Joshua to a school in a
different cluster, Bloom Elementary, which—like his resides
school—was only a mile from home. See Tr. in McFarland I, pp. 1–49 through 1–54 (Dec. 8, 2003). Space was available at
Bloom, and intercluster transfers are allowed, but Joshua’s
transfer was nonetheless denied because, in the words of Jefferson
County, “[t]he transfer would have an adverse effect on
desegregation compliance” of Young. App. in No. 05–915, at
97.[ Footnote 8 ]
Meredith brought suit in the Western District
of Kentucky, alleging violations of the Equal Protection Clause of
the Fourteenth Amendment. The District Court found that Jefferson
County had asserted a compelling interest in maintaining racially
diverse schools, and that the assignment plan was (in all relevant
respects) narrowly tailored to serve that compelling interest. McFarland I , supra , at 837.[ Footnote 9 ] The Sixth Circuit affirmed in a per curiam opinion relying upon the reasoning of the
District Court, concluding that a written opinion “would serve no
useful purpose.” McFarland v. Jefferson Cty. Public
Schools , 416 F. 3d 513, 514 (2005) ( McFarland
II ). We granted certiorari. 547 U. S. __ (2006).
II
As a threshold matter, we must
assure ourselves of our jurisdiction. Seattle argues that Parents
Involved lacks standing because none of its current members can
claim an imminent injury. Even if the district maintains the
current plan and reinstitutes the racial tiebreaker, Seattle
argues, Parents Involved members will only be affected if their
children seek to enroll in a Seattle public high school and choose
an oversubscribed school that is integration positive—too
speculative a harm to maintain standing. Brief for Respondents in
No. 05–908, pp. 16–17.
This argument is unavailing. The
group’s members have children in the district’s elementary, middle,
and high schools, App. in No. 05–908, at 299a–301a; Affidavit of
Kathleen Brose Pursuant to this Court’s Rule 32.3 (Lodging of
Petitioner Parents Involved), and the complaint sought declaratory
and injunctive relief on behalf of Parents Involved members whose
elementary and middle school children may be “denied admission to
the high schools of their choice when they apply for those schools
in the future,” App. in No. 05–908, at 30a. The fact that it is
possible that children of group members will not be denied
admission to a school based on their race—because they choose an
undersubscribed school or an oversubscribed school in which their
race is an advantage—does not eliminate the injury claimed.
Moreover, Parents Involved also asserted an interest in not being
“forced to compete for seats at certain high schools in a system
that uses race as a deciding factor in many of its admissions
decisions.” Ibid. As we have held, one form of injury
under the Equal Protection Clause is being forced to compete in a
race-based system that may prejudice the plaintiff, Adarand
Constructors, Inc. v. Peńa , 515 U. S. 200 , 211 (1995); Northeastern Fla. Chapter, Associated Gen. Contractors of
America v. Jacksonville , 508 U. S. 656 , 666
(1993), an injury that the members of Parents Involved can validly
claim on behalf of their children.
In challenging standing, Seattle also notes
that it has ceased using the racial tiebreaker pending the outcome
of this litigation. Brief for Respondents in No. 05–908,
at 16–17. But the district vigorously defends the
constitutionality of its race-based program, and nowhere suggests
that if this litigation is resolved in its favor it will not resume
using race to assign students. Voluntary cessation does not moot a
case or controversy unless “subsequent events ma[ke] it absolutely
clear that the allegedly wrongful behavior could not reasonably be
expected to recur,” Friends of Earth, Inc. v. Laidlaw
Environmental Services (TOC), Inc. , 528 U. S. 167 , 189
(2000) (quoting United States v. Concentrated
Phosphate Export Assn., Inc. , 393 U. S. 199 , 203
(1968) (internal quotation marks omitted)), a heavy burden that
Seattle has clearly not met.
Jefferson County does not challenge our
jurisdiction, Tr. of Oral Arg. in No. 05–915, p. 48, but we are
nonetheless obliged to ensure that it exists, Arbaugh v. Y & H Corp. , 546 U. S. 500 , 514
(2006). Although apparently Joshua has now been granted a transfer
to Bloom, the school to which transfer was denied under the racial
guidelines, Tr. of Oral Arg. in No. 05–915, at 45, the racial
guidelines apply at all grade levels. Upon Joshua’s enrollment in
middle school, he may again be subject to assignment based on his
race. In addition, Meredith sought damages in her complaint, which
is sufficient to preserve our ability to consider the question. Los Angeles v. Lyons , 461 U. S. 95 , 109
(1983).
III
A
It is well established that when
the government distributes burdens or benefits on the basis of
individual racial classifications, that action is reviewed under
strict scrutiny. Johnson v. California , 543 U. S. 499 , 505–506
(2005); Grutter v. Bollinger , 539 U. S. 306 , 326
(2003); Adarand, supra , at 224. As the Court recently
reaffirmed, “ ‘racial classifications are simply too
pernicious to permit any but the most exact connection between
justification and classification.’ ” Gratz v. Bollinger , 539 U. S. 244 , 270
(2003) (quoting Fullilove v. Klutznick , 448 U. S. 448 , 537
(1980) (Stevens, J., dissenting); brackets omitted). In order to
satisfy this searching standard of review, the school districts
must demonstrate that the use of individual racial classifications
in the assignment plans here under review is “narrowly tailored” to
achieve a “compelling” government interest. Adarand , supra , at 227.
Without attempting in these cases to set forth
all the interests a school district might assert, it suffices to
note that our prior cases, in evaluating the use of racial
classifications in the school context, have recognized two
interests that qualify as compelling. The first is the compelling
interest of remedying the effects of past intentional
discrimination. See Freeman v. Pitts , 503 U. S. 467 , 494 (1992). Yet the
Seattle public schools have not shown that they were ever
segregated by law, and were not subject to court-ordered
desegregation decrees. The Jefferson County public schools were
previously segregated by law and were subject to a desegregation
decree entered in 1975. In 2000, the District Court that entered
that decree dissolved it, finding that Jefferson County had
“eliminated the vestiges associated with the former policy of
segregation and its pernicious effects,” and thus had achieved
“unitary” status. Hampton , 102 F. Supp. 2d, at 360.
Jefferson County accordingly does not rely upon an interest in
remedying the effects of past intentional discrimination in
defending its present use of race in assigning students. See Tr. of
Oral Arg. in No. 05–915, at 38.
Nor could it. We have emphasized
that the harm being remedied by mandatory desegregation plans is
the harm that is traceable to segregation, and that “the
Constitution is not violated by racial imbalance in the schools,
without more.” Milliken v. Bradley , 433 U. S. 267 , 280,
n. 14 (1977). See also Freeman , supra , at
495–496; Dowell , 498 U. S., at 248; Milliken v. Bradley , 418 U. S. 717 , 746
(1974). Once Jefferson County achieved unitary status, it had
remedied the constitutional wrong that allowed race-based
assignments. Any continued use of race must be justified on some
other basis.[ Footnote
10 ]
The second government interest we have
recognized as compelling for purposes of strict scrutiny is the
interest in diversity in higher education upheld in Grutter , 539 U. S., at 328. The specific interest found
compelling in Grutter was student body diversity “in the
context of higher education.” Ibid. The diversity interest
was not focused on race alone but encompassed “all factors that may
contribute to student body diversity.” Id., at 337. We
described the various types of diversity that the law school
sought:
“[The law school’s] policy makes clear there are
many possible bases for diversity admissions, and provides examples
of admittees who have lived or traveled widely abroad, are fluent
in several languages, have overcome personal adversity and family
hardship, have exceptional records of extensive community service,
and have had successful careers in other fields.” Id., at
338 (brackets and internal quotation marks omitted).
The Court quoted the articulation of diversity from
Justice Powell’s opinion in Regents of the University of
California v. Bakke , 438 U. S. 265 (1978),
noting that “it is not an interest in simple ethnic diversity, in
which a specified percentage of the student body is in effect
guaranteed to be members of selected ethnic groups, that can
justify the use of race.” Grutter , supra, at
324–325 (citing and quoting Bakke , supra , at
314–315 (opinion of Powell, J.); brackets and internal quotation
marks omitted). Instead, what was upheld in Grutter was
consideration of “a far broader array of qualifications and
characteristics of which racial or ethnic origin is but a single
though important element.” 539 U. S., at 325 (quoting Bakke , supra , at 315 (opinion of Powell, J.);
internal quotation marks omitted).
The entire gist of the analysis in Grutter was that the admissions program at issue there
focused on each applicant as an individual, and not simply as a
member of a particular racial group. The classification of
applicants by race upheld in Grutter was only as part of a
“highly individualized, holistic review,” 539 U. S., at 337. As the
Court explained, “[t]he importance of this individualized
consideration in the context of a race-conscious admissions program
is paramount.” Ibid. The point of the narrow tailoring
analysis in which the Grutter Court engaged was to ensure
that the use of racial classifications was indeed part of a broader
assessment of diversity, and not simply an effort to achieve racial
balance, which the Court explained would be “patently
unconstitutional.” Id. , at 330.
In the present cases, by contrast, race is not
considered as part of a broader effort to achieve “exposure to
widely diverse people, cultures, ideas, and viewpoints,” ibid. ; race, for some students, is determinative standing
alone. The districts argue that other factors, such as student
preferences, affect assignment decisions under their plans, but
under each plan when race comes into play, it is decisive by
itself. It is not simply one factor weighed with others in reaching
a decision, as in Grutter ; it is the factor. Like
the University of Michigan undergraduate plan struck down in Gratz , 539 U. S., at 275, the plans here “do not provide
for a meaningful individualized review of applicants” but instead
rely on racial classifications in a “nonindividualized, mechanical”
way. Id., at 276, 280 (O’Connor, J., concurring).
Even when it comes to race, the plans here
employ only a limited notion of diversity, viewing race exclusively
in white/nonwhite terms in Seattle and black/“other” terms in
Jefferson County.[ Footnote
11 ] But see Metro Broadcasting, Inc. v. FCC , 497 U. S. 547 ,
610 (1990) (“We are a Nation not of black and white alone, but one
teeming with divergent communities knitted together with various
traditions and carried forth, above all, by individuals”)
(O’Connor, J., dissenting). The Seattle “Board Statement
Reaffirming Diversity Rationale” speaks of the “inherent
educational value” in “[p]roviding students the opportunity to
attend schools with diverse student enrollment,” App. in No.
05–908, at 128a, 129a. But under the Seattle plan, a school with 50
percent Asian-American students and 50 percent white students but
no African-American, Native-American, or Latino students would
qualify as balanced, while a school with 30 percent Asian-American,
25 percent African-American, 25 percent Latino, and 20 percent
white students would not. It is hard to understand how a plan that
could allow these results can be viewed as being concerned with
achieving enrollment that is “ ‘broadly diverse,’ ” Grutter, supra , at 329.
Prior to Grutter , the courts of
appeals rejected as unconstitutional attempts to implement
race-based assignment plans—such as the plans at issue here—in
primary and secondary schools. See, e.g., Eisenberg v. Montgomery Cty. Public Schools , 197
F. 3d 123, 133 (CA4 1999); Tuttle v. Arlington
Cty. School Bd. , 195 F. 3d 698, 701 (CA4 1999); Wessman v. Gittens , 160 F. 3d 790, 809 (CA1
1998). See also Ho v. San Francisco Unified School
Dist. , 147 F. 3d 854, 865 (CA9 1998). After Grutter , however, the two Courts of Appeals in these
cases, and one other, found that race-based assignments were
permissible at the elementary and secondary level, largely in
reliance on that case. See Parents Involved VII , 426
F. 3d, at 1166; McFarland II , 416 F. 3d, at 514; Comfort v. Lynn School Comm. , 418 F. 3d 1,
13 (CA1 2005).
In upholding the admissions plan in Grutter , though, this Court relied upon considerations
unique to institutions of higher education, noting that in light of
“the expansive freedoms of speech and thought associated with the
university environment, universities occupy a special niche in our
constitutional tradition.” 539 U. S., at 329. See also Bakke , supra , at 312, 313 (opinion of Powell,
J.). The Court explained that “[c]ontext matters” in applying
strict scrutiny, and repeatedly noted that it was addressing the
use of race “in the context of higher education.” Grutter , supra , at 327, 328, 334. The Court in Grutter expressly articulated key limitations on its holding—defining a
specific type of broad-based diversity and noting the unique
context of higher education—but these limitations were largely
disregarded by the lower courts in extending Grutter to
uphold race-based assignments in elementary and secondary schools.
The present cases are not governed by Grutter .
B
Perhaps recognizing that reliance
on Grutter cannot sustain their plans, both school
districts assert additional interests, distinct from the interest
upheld in Grutter , to justify their race-based
assignments. In briefing and argument before this Court, Seattle
contends that its use of race helps to reduce racial concentration
in schools and to ensure that racially concentrated housing
patterns do not prevent nonwhite students from having access to the
most desirable schools. Brief for Respondents in No. 05–908,
at 19. Jefferson County has articulated a similar goal,
phrasing its interest in terms of educating its students “in a
racially integrated environment.” App. in No. 05–915, at
22.[ Footnote 12 ] Each school
district argues that educational and broader socialization benefits
flow from a racially diverse learning environment, and each
contends that because the diversity they seek is racial
diversity—not the broader diversity at issue in Grutter —it
makes sense to promote that interest directly by relying on race
alone.
The parties and their amici dispute whether racial diversity in schools in fact
has a marked impact on test scores and other objective yardsticks
or achieves intangible socialization benefits. The debate is not
one we need to resolve, however, because it is clear that the
racial classifications employed by the districts are not narrowly
tailored to the goal of achieving the educational and social
benefits asserted to flow from racial diversity. In design and
operation, the plans are directed only to racial balance, pure and
simple, an objective this Court has repeatedly condemned as
illegitimate.
The plans are tied to each district’s specific
racial demographics, rather than to any pedagogic concept of the
level of diversity needed to obtain the asserted educational
benefits. In Seattle, the district seeks white enrollment of
between 31 and 51 percent (within 10 percent of “the district white
average” of 41 percent), and nonwhite enrollment of between 49 and
69 percent (within 10 percent of “the district minority average” of
59 percent). App. in No. 05–908, at 103a. In Jefferson County, by
contrast, the district seeks black enrollment of no less than 15 or
more than 50 percent, a range designed to be “equally above and
below Black student enrollment systemwide,” McFarland I , 330 F. Supp. 2d, at 842, based on
the objective of achieving at “all schools … an African-American
enrollment equivalent to the average district-wide African-American
enrollment” of 34 percent. App. in No. 05–915, at 81. In Seattle,
then, the benefits of racial diversity require enrollment of at
least 31 percent white students; in Jefferson County, at least 50
percent. There must be at least 15 percent nonwhite students under
Jefferson County’s plan; in Seattle, more than three times that
figure. This comparison makes clear that the racial demographics in
each district—whatever they happen to be—drive the required
“diversity” numbers. The plans here are not tailored to achieving a
degree of diversity necessary to realize the asserted educational
benefits; instead the plans are tailored, in the words of Seattle’s
Manager of Enrollment Planning, Technical Support, and
Demographics, to “the goal established by the school board of
attain-ing a level of diversity within the schools that
approximates the district’s overall demographics.” App. in No.
05–908, at 42a.
The districts offer no evidence that the level
of racial diversity necessary to achieve the asserted educational
benefits happens to coincide with the racial demographics of the
respective school districts—or rather the white/nonwhite or
black/“other” balance of the districts, since that is the only
diversity addressed by the plans. Indeed, in its brief Seattle
simply assumes that the educational benefits track the racial
breakdown of the district. See Brief for Respondents in No. 05–908,
at 36 (“For Seattle, ‘racial balance’ is clearly not an end in
itself but rather a measure of the extent to which the educational
goals the plan was designed to foster are likely to be achieved”).
When asked for “a range of percentage that would be diverse,”
however, Seattle’s expert said it was important to have “sufficient
numbers so as to avoid students feeling any kind of specter of
exceptionality.” App. in No. 05–908, at 276a. The district did not
attempt to defend the proposition that anything outside its range
posed the “specter of exceptionality.” Nor did it demonstrate in
any way how the educational and social benefits of racial diversity
or avoidance of racial isolation are more likely to be achieved at
a school that is 50 percent white and 50 percent Asian-American,
which would qualify as diverse under Seattle’s plan, than at a
school that is 30 percent Asian-American, 25 percent
African-American, 25 percent Latino, and 20 percent white, which
under Seattle’s definition would be racially concentrated.
Similarly, Jefferson County’s expert referred
to the importance of having “at least 20 percent” minority group
representation for the group “to be visible enough to make a
difference,” and noted that “small isolated minority groups in a
school are not likely to have a strong effect on the overall
school.” App. in No. 05–915, at 159, 147. The Jefferson County
plan, however, is based on a goal of replicating at each school “an
African-American enrollment equivalent to the average district-wide
African-American enrollment.” Id., at 81. Joshua
McDonald’s requested transfer was denied because his race was
listed as “other” rather than black, and allowing the transfer
would have had an adverse effect on the racial guideline compliance
of Young Elementary, the school he sought to leave. Id., at 21. At the time, however, Young Elementary was 46.8 percent
black. Id. , at 73. The transfer might have had an adverse
effect on the effort to approach district-wide racial
proportionality at Young, but it had nothing to do with preventing
either the black or “other” group from becoming “small” or
“isolated” at Young.
In fact, in each case the extreme measure of
relying on race in assignments is unnecessary to achieve the stated
goals, even as defined by the districts. For example, at Franklin
High School in Seattle, the racial tiebreaker was applied because
nonwhite enrollment exceeded 69 percent, and resulted in an
incoming ninth-grade class in 2000–2001 that was 30.3 percent
Asian-American, 21.9 percent African-American, 6.8 percent Latino,
0.5 percent Native-American, and 40.5 percent Caucasian. Without
the racial tiebreaker, the class would have been 39.6 percent
Asian-American, 30.2 percent African-American, 8.3 percent Latino,
1.1 percent Native-American, and 20.8 percent Caucasian. See App.
in No. 05–908, at 308a. When the actual racial breakdown is
considered, enrolling students without regard to their race yields
a substantially diverse student body under any definition of
diversity.[ Footnote 13 ]
In Grutter , the number of minority
students the school sought to admit was an undefined “meaningful
number” necessary to achieve a genuinely diverse student body. 539
U. S., at 316, 335–336. Although the matter was the subject of
disagreement on the Court, see id., at 346–347 (Scalia,
J., concurring in part and dissenting in part); id., at
382–383 (Rehnquist, C. J., dissenting); id., at
388–392 (Kennedy, J., dissenting), the majority concluded that the
law school did not count back from its applicant pool to arrive at
the “meaningful number” it regarded as necessary to diversify its
student body. Id., at 335–336. Here the racial balance the
districts seek is a defined range set solely by reference to the
demographics of the respective school districts.
This working backward to achieve a particular
type of racial balance, rather than working forward from some
demonstration of the level of diversity that provides the purported
benefits, is a fatal flaw under our existing precedent. We have
many times over reaffirmed that “[r]acial balance is not to be
achieved for its own sake.” Freeman , 503 U. S., at 494.
See also Richmond v. J. A. Croson Co. , 488 U. S. 469 , 507
(1989); Bakke , 438 U. S., at 307 (opinion of Powell, J.)
(“If petitioner’s purpose is to assure within its student body some
specified percentage of a particular group merely because of its
race or ethnic origin, such a preferential purpose must be rejected
… as facially invalid”). Grutter itself reiterated that
“outright racial balancing” is “patently unconstitutional.” 539 U.
S., at 330.
Accepting racial balancing as a compelling
state interest would justify the imposition of racial
proportionality throughout American society, contrary to our
repeated recognition that “[a]t the heart of the Constitution’s
guarantee of equal protection lies the simple command that the
Government must treat citizens as individuals, not as simply
components of a racial, religious, sexual or national class.” Miller v. Johnson , 515 U. S. 900 , 911
(1995) (quoting Metro Broadcasting , 497 U. S., at 602
(O’Connor, J., dissenting); internal quotation marks
omitted).[ Footnote 14 ]
Allowing racial balancing as a compelling end in itself would
“effectively assur[e] that race will always be relevant in American
life, and that the ‘ultimate goal’ of ‘eliminating entirely from
governmental decisionmaking such irrelevant factors as a human
being’s race’ will never be achieved.” Croson, supra , at
495 (plurality opinion of O’Connor, J.) (quoting Wygant v. Jackson Bd. of Ed. , 476 U. S. 267 , 320
(1986) (Stevens, J., dissenting), in turn quoting Fullilove, 448 U. S., at 547 (Stevens, J., dissenting);
brackets and citation omitted). An interest “linked to nothing
other than proportional representation of various races … would
support indefinite use of racial classifications, employed first to
obtain the appropriate mixture of racial views and then to ensure
that the [program] continues to reflect that mixture.” Metro
Broadcasting , supra , at 614 (O’Connor, J.,
dissenting).
The validity of our concern that racial
balancing has “no logical stopping point,” Croson , supra , at 498 (quoting Wygant , supra , at
275 (plurality opinion); internal quotation marks omitted); see
also Grutter, supra , at 343, is demonstrated here by the
degree to which the districts tie their racial guidelines to their
demographics. As the districts’ demographics shift, so too will
their definition of racial diversity. See App. in No. 05–908, at
103a (describing application of racial tiebreaker based on
“ current white percentage” of 41 percent and
“ current minority percentage” of 59 percent (emphasis
added)).
The Ninth Circuit below stated that it
“share[d] in the hope” expressed in Grutter that in 25
years racial preferences would no longer be necessary to further
the interest identified in that case. Parents Involved
VII , 426 F. 3d, at 1192. But in Seattle the plans are
defended as necessary to address the consequences of racially
identifiable housing patterns. The sweep of the mandate claimed by
the district is contrary to our rulings that remedying past
societal discrimination does not justify race-conscious government
action. See, e.g., Shaw v. Hunt , 517 U. S. 899 ,
909–910 (1996) (“[A]n effort to alleviate the effects of societal
discrimination is not a compelling interest”); Croson , supra , at 498–499; Wygant , 476 U. S., at 276
(plurality opinion) (“Societal discrimination, without more, is too
amorphous a basis for imposing a racially classified remedy”); id., at 288 (O’Connor, J., concurring in part and
concurring in judgment) (“[A] governmental agency’s interest in
remedying ‘societal’ discrimination, that is, discrimination not
traceable to its own actions, cannot be deemed sufficiently
compelling to pass constitutional muster”).
The principle that racial balancing is not
permitted is one of substance, not semantics. Racial balancing is
not transformed from “patently unconstitutional” to a compelling
state interest simply by relabeling it “racial diversity.” While
the school districts use various verbal formulations to describe
the interest they seek to promote—racial diversity, avoidance of
racial isolation, racial integration—they offer no definition of
the interest that suggests it differs from racial balance. See, e.g., App. in No. 05–908, at 257a (“Q. What’s your
understanding of when a school suffers from racial isolation? A. I
don’t have a definition for that”); id., at 228a–229a (“I
don’t think we’ve ever sat down and said, ‘Define racially
concentrated school exactly on point in quantitative terms.’ I
don’t think we’ve ever had that conversation”); Tr. in McFarland I , at 1–90 (Dec. 8, 2003) (“Q. How does the
Jefferson County School Board define diversity … ?” “A.
Well, we want to have the schools that make up the percentage of
students of the population”).
Jefferson County phrases its interest as
“racial integration,” but integration certainly does not require
the sort of racial proportionality reflected in its plan. Even in
the context of mandatory desegregation, we have stressed that
racial proportionality is not required, see Milliken, 433
U. S., at 280, n. 14 (“[A desegregation] order contemplating the
substantive constitutional right [to a] particular degree of racial
balance or mixing is … infirm as a matter of law” (internal
quotation marks omitted)); Swann v. Charlotte-Mecklenburg Bd. of Ed. , 402 U. S. 1 , 24 (1971) (“The
constitutional command to desegregate schools does not mean that
every school in every community must always reflect the racial
composition of the school system as a whole”), and here Jefferson
County has already been found to have eliminated the vestiges of
its prior segregated school system.
The en banc Ninth Circuit declared that “when
a racially diverse school system is the goal (or racial
concentration or isolation is the problem), there is no more
effective means than a consideration of race to achieve the
solution.” Parents Involved VII , supra , at 1191.
For the foregoing reasons, this conclusory argument cannot sustain
the plans. However closely related race-based assignments may be to
achieving racial balance, that itself cannot be the goal, whether
labeled “racial diversity” or anything else. To the extent the
objective is sufficient diversity so that students see fellow
students as individuals rather than solely as members of a racial
group, using means that treat students solely as members of a
racial group is fundamentally at cross-purposes with that end.
C
The districts assert, as they
must, that the way in which they have employed individual racial
classifications is necessary to achieve their stated ends. The
minimal effect these classifications have on student assignments,
however, suggests that other means would be effective. Seattle’s
racial tiebreaker results, in the end, only in shifting a small
number of students between schools. Approximately 307 student
assignments were affected by the racial tiebreaker in 2000–2001;
the district was able to track the enrollment status of 293 of
these students. App. in No. 05–908, at 162a. Of these, 209 were
assigned to a school that was one of their choices, 87 of whom were
assigned to the same school to which they would have been assigned
without the racial tiebreaker. Eighty-four students were assigned
to schools that they did not list as a choice, but 29 of those
students would have been assigned to their respective school
without the racial tiebreaker, and 3 were able to attend one of the
oversubscribed schools due to waitlist and capacity adjustments. Id., at 162a–163a. In over one-third of the assignments
affected by the racial tiebreaker, then, the use of race in the end
made no difference, and the district could identify only 52
students who were ultimately affected adversely by the racial
tiebreaker in that it resulted in assignment to a school they had
not listed as a preference and to which they would not otherwise
have been assigned.
As the panel majority in Parents Involved VI concluded:
“[T]he tiebreaker’s annual effect is thus merely to
shuffle a few handfuls of different minority students between a few
schools—about a dozen additional Latinos into Ballard, a dozen
black students into Nathan Hale, perhaps two dozen Asians into
Roosevelt, and so on. The District has not met its burden of
proving these marginal changes … outweigh the cost of subjecting
hundreds of students to disparate treatment based solely upon the
color of their skin.” 377 F. 3d, at 984–985 (footnote
omitted).
Similarly, Jefferson County’s use
of racial classifications has only a minimal effect on the
assignment of students. Elementary school students are assigned to
their first- or second-choice school 95 percent of the time, and
transfers, which account for roughly 5 percent of assignments, are
only denied 35 percent of the time—and presumably an even smaller
percentage are denied on the basis of the racial guidelines, given
that other factors may lead to a denial. McFarland I , 330
F. Supp. 2d, at 844–845, nn. 16, 18. Jefferson County
estimates that the racial guidelines account for only 3 percent of
assignments. Brief in Opposition in No. 05–915, p. 7,
n. 4; Tr. of Oral Arg. in No. 05–915, at 46. As Jefferson
County explains, “the racial guidelines have minimal impact in this
process, because they ‘mostly influence student assignment in
subtle and indirect ways.’ ” Brief for Respondents in No.
05–915, pp. 8–9.
While we do not suggest that greater use of race would be preferable, the minimal impact of the
districts’ racial classifications on school enrollment casts doubt
on the necessity of using racial classifications. In Grutter , the consideration of race was viewed as
indispensable in more than tripling minority representation at the
law school—from 4 to 14.5 percent. See 539 U. S., at 320. Here the
most Jefferson County itself claims is that “because the guidelines
provide a firm definition of the Board’s goal of racially
integrated schools, they ‘provide administrators with the authority
to facilitate, negotiate and collaborate with principals and staff
to maintain schools within the 15–50% range.’ ” Brief in
Opposition in No. 05–915, at 7 (quoting McFarland I , supra , at 842). Classifying and assigning schoolchildren
according to a binary conception of race is an extreme approach in
light of our precedents and our Nation’s history of using race in
public schools, and requires more than such an amorphous end to
justify it.
The districts have also failed to show that
they considered methods other than explicit racial classifications
to achieve their stated goals. Narrow tailoring requires “serious,
good faith consideration of workable race-neutral alternatives,” Grutter, supra , at 339, and yet in Seattle several
alternative assignment plans—many of which would not have used
express racial classifications—were rejected with little or no
consideration. See, e.g. , App. in No. 05–908, at
224a–225a, 253a–259a, 307a. Jefferson County has failed to present
any evidence that it considered alternatives, even though the
district already claims that its goals are achieved primarily
through means other than the racial classifications. Brief for
Respondents in No. 05–915, at 8–9. Compare Croson ,
488 U. S., at 519 (Kennedy, J., concurring in part and concurring
in judgment) (racial classifications permitted only “as a last
resort”).
IV
Justice Breyer’s dissent takes a
different approach to these cases, one that fails to ground the
result it would reach in law. Instead, it selectively relies on
inapplicable precedent and even dicta while dismissing contrary
holdings, alters and misapplies our well-established legal
framework for assessing equal protection challenges to express
racial classifications, and greatly exaggerates the consequences of
today’s decision.
To begin with, Justice Breyer
seeks to justify the plans at issue under our precedents
recognizing the compelling interest in remedying past intentional
discrimination. See post , at 18–24. Not even the school
districts go this far, and for good reason. The distinction between
segregation by state action and racial imbalance caused by other
factors has been central to our jurisprudence in this area for
generations. See, e.g. , Milliken , 433 U. S., at
280, n. 14; Freeman , 503 U. S., at 495–496 (“Where
resegregation is a product not of state action but of private
choices, it does not have constitutional implications”). The
dissent elides this distinction between de jure and de
facto segregation, casually intimates that Seattle’s school
attendance patterns reflect illegal segregation, post , at
5, 18, 23,[ Footnote 15 ] and
fails to credit the judicial determination—under the most rigorous
standard—that Jefferson County had eliminated the vestiges of prior
segregation. The dissent thus alters in fundamental ways not only
the facts presented here but the established law.
Justice Breyer’s reliance on McDaniel v. Barresi , 402 U. S. 39 (1971), post , at 23–24, 29–30, highlights how far removed the
discussion in the dissent is from the question actually presented
in these cases. McDaniel concerned a Georgia school system
that had been segregated by law. There was no doubt that the county
had operated a “dual school system,” McDaniel , supra , at 41, and no one questions that the obligation to
disestablish a school system segregated by law can include
race-conscious remedies—whether or not a court had issued an order
to that effect. See supra , at 12. The present cases are
before us, however, because the Seattle school district was never
segregated by law, and the Jefferson County district has been found
to be unitary, having eliminated the vestiges of its prior dual
status. The justification for race-conscious remedies in McDaniel is therefore not applicable here. The dissent’s
persistent refusal to accept this distinction—its insistence on
viewing the racial classifications here as if they were just like
the ones in McDaniel , “devised to overcome a history of
segregated public schools,” post , at 47—explains its
inability to understand why the remedial justification for racial
classifications cannot decide these cases.
Justice Breyer’s dissent next relies heavily
on dicta from Swann v. Charlotte-Mecklenburg Bd. of
Ed. , 402 U. S., at 16—far more heavily than the school
districts themselves. Compare post , at 3, 22–28, with
Brief for Respondents in No. 05–908, at 19–20; Brief for
Respondents in No. 05–915, at 31. The dissent acknowledges that the
two-sentence discussion in Swann was pure dicta, post , at 22, but nonetheless asserts that it demonstrates
a “basic principle of constitutional law” that provides
“authoritative legal guidance.” Post , at 22, 30.
Initially, as the Court explained just last Term, “we are not bound
to follow our dicta in a prior case in which the point now at issue
was not fully debated.” Central Va. Community College v. Katz, 546
U. S. 356 , 363 (2006). That is particularly true given that,
when Swann was decided, this Court had not yet confirmed
that strict scrutiny applies to racial classifications like those
before us. See n. 16, infra . There is nothing
“technical” or “theoretical,” post , at 30, about our
approach to such dicta. See, e.g., Cohens v. Virginia , 6 Wheat. 264, 399–400 (1821) (Marshall,
C. J.) (explaining why dicta is not binding).
Justice Breyer would not only put such
extraordinary weight on admitted dicta, but relies on the statement
for something it does not remotely say. Swann addresses
only a possible state objective; it says nothing of the permissible means —race conscious or otherwise—that a school district
might employ to achieve that objective. The reason for this
omission is clear enough, since the case did not involve any
voluntary means adopted by a school district. The dissent’s
characterization of Swann as recognizing that “the Equal
Protection Clause permits local school boards to use race-conscious
criteria to achieve positive race-related goals” is—at best—a
dubious inference. Post , at 22. Even if the dicta from Swann were entitled to the weight the dissent would give
it, and no dicta is, it not only did not address the question
presented in Swann , it also does not address the question
presented in these cases—whether the school districts’ use of
racial classifications to achieve their stated goals is
permissible.
Further, for all the lower court cases Justice
Breyer cites as evidence of the “prevailing legal assumption”
embodied by Swann , very few are pertinent. Most are not.
For example, the dissent features Tometz v. Board of
Ed., Waukegan City School Dist. No. 61 , 39 Ill. 2d 593,
596–598, 237 N. E. 2d 498, 500–502 (1968), an Illinois
decision, as evidence that “state and federal courts had considered
the matter settled and uncontroversial.” Post , at 25. But Tometz addressed a challenge to a statute requiring
race-consciousness in drawing school attendance boundaries—an issue
well beyond the scope of the question presented in these cases.
Importantly, it considered that issue only under rational-basis
review, 39 Ill. 2d, at 600, 237 N. E. 2d, at 502 (“The test of
any legislative classification essentially is one of
reasonableness”), which even the dissent grudgingly recognizes is
an improper standard for evaluating express racial classifications.
Other cases cited are similarly inapplicable. See, e.g. , Citizens for Better Ed. v. Goose Creek Consol.
Independent School Dist. , 719 S. W. 2d 350, 352–353 (Tex.
App. 1986) (upholding rezoning plan under rational-basis
review).[ Footnote 16 ]
Justice Breyer’s dissent next looks for
authority to a footnote in Washington v. Seattle
School Dist. No. 1 , 458 U. S. 457 , 472, n. 15 (1982), post , at 56–57, but there this Court expressly noted that
it was not passing on the propriety of race-conscious
student assignments in the absence of a finding of de jure segregation. Similarly, the citation of Crawford v. Board of Ed. of Los Angeles , 458 U. S. 527 (1982), post , at 24, in which a state referendum prohibiting a
race-based assignment plan was challenged, is inapposite—in Crawford the Court again expressly reserved the question
presented by these cases. 458 U. S. , at 535, n. 11.
Such reservations and preliminary analyses of course did not decide
the merits of this question—as evidenced by the disagreement among
the lower courts on this issue. Compare Eisenberg , 197
F. 3d, at 133, with Comfort , 418 F. 3d, at
13.
Justice Breyer’s dissent also asserts that
these cases are controlled by Grutter, claiming that the
existence of a compelling interest in these cases “follows a
fortiori ” from Grutter, post, at 41, 64–66, and
accusing us of tacitly overruling that case, see post, at
64–66. The dissent overreads Grutter, however, in
suggesting that it renders pure racial balancing a constitutionally
compelling interest; Grutter itself recognized that using
race simply to achieve racial balance would be “patently
unconstitutional,” 539 U. S. , at 330. The Court was
exceedingly careful in describing the interest furthered in Grutter as “not an interest in simple ethnic diversity”
but rather a “far broader array of qualifications and
characteristics” in which race was but a single element. 539 U. S.,
at 324–325 (internal quotation marks omitted). We take the Grutter Court at its word. We simply do not understand how
Justice Breyer can maintain that classifying every schoolchild as
black or white, and using that classification as a determinative
factor in assigning children to achieve pure racial balance, can be
regarded as “less burdensome, and hence more narrowly tailored”
than the consideration of race in Grutter , post, at 47, when the Court in Grutter stated that “[t]he
importance of … individualized consideration” in the program was
“paramount,” and consideration of race was one factor in a “highly
individualized, holistic review.” 539 U. S., at 337. Certainly if
the constitutionality of the stark use of race in these cases were
as established as the dissent would have it, there would have been
no need for the extensive analysis undertaken in Grutter .
In light of the foregoing, Justice Breyer’s appeal to stare
decisis rings particularly hollow. See post, at
65–66.
At the same time it relies on inapplicable
desegregation cases, misstatements of admitted dicta, and other
noncontrolling pronouncements, Justice Breyer’s dissent candidly
dismisses the significance of this Court’s repeated holdings that all racial classifications must be reviewed
under strict scrutiny, see post , at 31–33, 35–36, arguing
that a different standard of review should be applied because the
districts use race for beneficent rather than malicious purposes,
see post , at 31–36.
This Court has recently reiterated, however,
that “ ‘ all racial classifications [imposed by
government] … must be analyzed by a reviewing court under strict
scrutiny.’ ” Johnson , 543 U. S., at 505 (quoting Adarand , 515 U. S., at 227; emphasis added by Johnson Court). See also Grutter , supra ,
at 326 (“[G]overnmental action based on race—a group classification
long recognized as in most circumstances irrelevant and therefore
prohibited—should be subjected to detailed judicial inquiry”
(internal quotation marks and emphasis omitted)). Justice Breyer
nonetheless relies on the good intentions and motives of the school
districts, stating that he has found “no case that … repudiated
this constitutional asymmetry between that which seeks to exclude and that which seeks to include members
of minority races.” Post , at 29 (emphasis in original). We
have found many. Our cases clearly reject the argument that motives
affect the strict scrutiny analysis. See Johnson , supra , at 505 (“We have insisted on strict scrutiny in
every context, even for so-called ‘benign’ racial
classifications”); Adarand , 515 U. S., at 227 (rejecting
idea that “ ‘benign’ ” racial classifications may be held
to “different standard”); Croson , 488 U. S., at 500
(“Racial classifications are suspect, and that means that simple
legislative assurances of good intention cannot suffice”).
This argument that different rules should
govern racial classifications designed to include rather than
exclude is not new; it has been repeatedly pressed in the past,
see, e.g. , Gratz , 539 U. S., at 282 (Breyer, J.,
concurring in judgment); id. , at 301 (Ginsburg, J.,
dissenting); Adarand , supra , at 243 (Stevens, J.,
dissenting); Wygant , 476 U. S., at 316–317 (Stevens, J.,
dissenting), and has been repeatedly rejected. See also Bakke , 438 U. S., at 289–291 (opinion of Powell, J.)
(rejecting argument that strict scrutiny should be applied only to
classifications that disadvantage minorities, stating “[r]acial and
ethnic distinctions of any sort are inherently suspect and thus
call for the most exacting judicial examination”).
The reasons for rejecting a motives test for
racial classifications are clear enough. “The Court’s emphasis on
‘benign racial classifications’ suggests confidence in its ability
to distinguish good from harmful governmental uses of racial
criteria. History should teach greater humility… . ‘[B]enign’
carries with it no independent meaning, but reflects only
acceptance of the current generation’s conclusion that a
politically acceptable burden, imposed on particular citizens on
the basis of race, is reasonable.” Metro Broadcasting , 497
U. S., at 609–610 (O’Connor, J., dissenting). See also Adarand , supra , at 226 (“ ‘[I]t may not
always be clear that a so-called preference is in fact
benign’ ” (quoting Bakke , supra , at 298
(opinion of Powell, J.))). Accepting Justice Breyer’s approach
would “do no more than move us from ‘separate but equal’ to
‘unequal but benign.’ ” Metro Broadcasting , supra , at 638 (Kennedy, J., dissenting).
Justice Breyer speaks of bringing “the races”
together (putting aside the purely black-and-white nature of the
plans), as the justification for excluding individuals on the basis
of their race. See post , at 28–29. Again, this approach to
racial classifications is fundamentally at odds with our precedent,
which makes clear that the Equal Protection Clause “protect[s] persons , not groups ,” Adarand , 515 U.
S., at 227 (emphasis in original). See ibid. (“[A]ll
governmental action based on race—a group classification
long recognized as ‘in most circumstances irrelevant and therefore
prohibited,’ Hirabayashi [v. United States , 320 U. S. 81 , 100
(1943)]—should be subjected to detailed judicial inquiry to ensure
that the personal right to equal protection of the laws
has not been infringed” (first emphasis in original); Metro
Broadcasting , supra , at 636 (“[O]ur Constitution
protects each citizen as an individual, not as a member of a group”
(Kennedy, J., dissenting)); Bakke , supra , at 289
(opinion of Powell, J.) (Fourteenth Amendment creates rights
“guaranteed to the individual. The rights established are personal
rights”). This fundamental principle goes back, in this context, to Brown itself. See Brown v. Board of
Education , 349
U. S. 294 , 300 (1955) ( Brown II ) (“At stake is the personal interest of the plaintiffs in admission to public
schools … on a nondiscriminatory basis” (emphasis added)). For the
dissent, in contrast, “ ‘individualized scrutiny’ is simply
beside the point.” Post , at 55.
Justice Breyer’s position comes down to a
familiar claim: The end justifies the means. He admits that “there
is a cost in applying ‘a state-mandated racial label,’ ” post , at 67, but he is confident that the cost is worth
paying. Our established strict scrutiny test for racial
classifications, however, insists on “detailed examination, both as
to ends and as to means.” Adarand , supra , at 236 (emphasis added). Simply because the school
districts may seek a worthy goal does not mean they are free to
discriminate on the basis of race to achieve it, or that their
racial classifications should be subject to less exacting
scrutiny.
Despite his argument that these cases should
be evaluated under a “standard of review that is not ‘strict’ in
the traditional sense of that word,” post , at 36, Justice
Breyer still purports to apply strict scrutiny to these cases. See post , at 37. It is evident, however, that Justice Breyer’s
brand of narrow tailoring is quite unlike anything found in our
precedents. Without any detailed discussion of the operation of the
plans, the students who are affected, or the districts’ failure to
consider race-neutral alternatives, the dissent concludes that the
districts have shown that these racial classifications are
necessary to achieve the districts’ stated goals. This conclusion
is divorced from any evaluation of the actual impact of the plans
at issue in these cases—other than to note that the plans “often
have no effect.” Post , at 46.[ Footnote 17 ] Instead, the dissent suggests that some
combination of the development of these plans over time, the
difficulty of the endeavor, and the good faith of the districts
suffices to demonstrate that these stark and controlling racial
classifications are constitutional. The Constitution and our
precedents require more.
In keeping with his view that strict scrutiny
should not apply, Justice Breyer repeatedly urges deference to
local school boards on these issues. See, e.g. , post , at 21, 48–49, 66. Such deference “is fundamentally
at odds with our equal protection jurisprudence. We put the burden
on state actors to demonstrate that their race-based policies are
justified.” Johnson , 543 U. S., at 506, n. 1. See Croson , 488 U. S., at 501 (“The history of racial
classifications in this country suggests that blind judicial
deference to legislative or executive pronouncements of necessity
has no place in equal protection analysis”); West Virginia Bd.
of Ed. v. Barnette , 319 U. S. 624 , 637
(1943) (“The Fourteenth Amendment … protects the citizen against
the State itself and all of its creatures—Boards of Education not
excepted”).
Justice Breyer’s dissent ends on an
unjustified note of alarm. It predicts that today’s decision
“threaten[s]” the validity of “[h]undreds of state and federal
statutes and regulations.” Post , at 61; see also post , at 27–28. But the examples the dissent mentions—for
example, a provision of the No Child Left Behind Act that requires
States to set measurable objectives to track the achievement of
students from major racial and ethnic groups, 20 U. S. C.
§6311(b)(2)(C)(v)—have nothing to do with the pertinent issues in
these cases.
Justice Breyer also suggests that other means
for achieving greater racial diversity in schools are necessarily
unconstitutional if the racial classifications at issue in these
cases cannot survive strict scrutiny. Post , at 58–62.
These other means— e.g. , where to construct new schools,
how to allocate resources among schools, and which academic
offerings to provide to attract students to certain
schools—implicate different considerations than the explicit racial
classifications at issue in these cases, and we express no opinion
on their validity—not even in dicta. Rather, we employ the familiar
and well-established analytic approach of strict scrutiny to
evaluate the plans at issue today, an approach that in no way
warrants the dissent’s cataclysmic concerns. Under that approach,
the school districts have not carried their burden of showing that
the ends they seek justify the particular extreme means they have
chosen—classifying individual students on the basis of their race
and discriminating among them on that basis.
* * *
If the need for the racial
classifications embraced by the school districts is unclear, even
on the districts’ own terms, the costs are undeniable.
“[D]istinctions between citizens solely because of their ancestry
are by their very nature odious to a free people whose institutions
are founded upon the doctrine of equality.” Adarand , 515
U. S., at 214 (internal quotation marks omitted). Government action
dividing us by race is inherently suspect because such
classifications promote “notions of racial inferiority and lead to
a politics of racial hostility,” Croson , supra ,
at 493, “reinforce the belief, held by too many for too much of our
history, that individuals should be judged by the color of their
skin,” Shaw v. Reno , 509 U. S. 630 , 657
(1993), and “endorse race-based reasoning and the conception of a
Nation divided into racial blocs, thus contributing to an
escalation of racial hostility and conflict.” Metro
Broadcasting , 497 U. S., at 603 (O’Connor, J., dissenting). As
the Court explained in Rice v. Cayetano , 528 U. S. 495 , 517
(2000), “[o]ne of the principal reasons race is treated as a
forbidden classification is that it demeans the dignity and worth
of a person to be judged by ancestry instead of by his or her own
merit and essential qualities.”
All this is true enough in the
contexts in which these statements were made—government
contracting, voting districts, allocation of broadcast licenses,
and electing state officers—but when it comes to using race to
assign children to schools, history will be heard. In Brown v. Board of Education , 347 U. S. 483 (1954)
( Brown I ), we held that segregation deprived black
children of equal educational opportunities regardless of whether
school facilities and other tangible factors were equal, because
government classification and separation on grounds of race
themselves denoted inferiority. Id., at 493–494. It was
not the inequality of the facilities but the fact of legally
separating children on the basis of race on which the Court relied
to find a constitutional violation in 1954. See id., at
494 (“ ‘The impact [of segregation] is greater when it has the
sanction of the law’ ”). The next Term, we accordingly stated
that “full compliance” with Brown I required school
districts “to achieve a system of determining admission to the
public schools on a nonracial basis .” Brown II, 349 U. S., at 300–301 (emphasis added).
The parties and their amici debate
which side is more faithful to the heritage of Brown , but
the position of the plaintiffs in Brown was spelled out in
their brief and could not have been clearer: “[T]he Fourteenth
Amendment prevents states from according differential treatment to
American children on the basis of their color or race.” Brief for
Appellants in Nos. 1, 2, and 4 and for Respondents in No. 10 on
Reargument in Brown I , O. T. 1953, p. 15
(Summary of Argument). What do the racial classifications at issue
here do, if not accord differential treatment on the basis of race?
As counsel who appeared before this Court for the plaintiffs in Brown put it: “We have one fundamental contention which we
will seek to develop in the course of this argument, and that
contention is that no State has any authority under the
equal-protection clause of the Fourteenth Amendment to use race as
a factor in affording educational opportunities among its
citizens.” Tr. of Oral Arg. in Brown I , p. 7 (Robert L.
Carter, Dec. 9, 1952). There is no ambiguity in that statement. And
it was that position that prevailed in this Court, which emphasized
in its remedial opinion that what was “[a]t stake is the personal
interest of the plaintiffs in admission to public schools as soon
as practicable on a nondiscriminatory basis ,” and what was
required was “determining admission to the public schools on a nonracial basis .” Brown II , supra , at 300–301 (emphasis added). What do the racial
classifications do in these cases, if not determine admission to a
public school on a racial basis? Before Brown , schoolchildren were told where they could and could
not go to school based on the color of their skin. The school
districts in these cases have not carried the heavy burden of
demonstrating that we should allow this once again—even for very
different reasons. For schools that never segregated on the basis
of race, such as Seattle, or that have removed the vestiges of past
segregation, such as Jefferson County, the way “to achieve a system
of determining admission to the public schools on a nonracial
basis,” Brown II , 349 U. S., at 300–301, is to stop
assigning students on a racial basis. The way to stop
discrimination on the basis of race is to stop discriminating on
the basis of race.
The judgments of the Courts of Appeals for the
Sixth and Ninth Circuits are reversed, and the cases are remanded
for further proceedings.
It is so ordered. Footnote 1 The plan was in effect from 1999–2002, for
three school years. This litigation was commenced in July 2000, and
the record in the District Court was closed before assignments for
the 2001–2002 school year were made. See Brief for Respondents in
No. 05–908, p. 9, n. 9. We rely, as did the lower courts,
largely on data from the 2000–2001 school year in evaluating the
plan. See 426 F. 3d 1162, 1169–1171 (CA9 2005) (en banc)
( Parents Involved VII ). Footnote 2 The racial breakdown of this nonwhite group
is approximately 23.8 percent Asian-American, 23.1 percent
African-American, 10.3 percent Latino, and 2.8 percent
Native-American. See 377 F. 3d 949, 1005–1006 (CA9 2004)
( Parents Involved VI ) (Graber, J., dissenting). Footnote 3 For the 2001–2002 school year, the deviation
permitted from the desired racial composition was increased from 10
to 15 percent. App. in No. 05–908, p. 38a. The bulk of the data in
the record was collected using the 10 percent band, see n. 1, supra . Footnote 4 “No State shall … deny to any person within
its jurisdiction the equal protection of the laws.” U. S. Const.,
Amdt. 14, §1. Footnote 5 “No person in the United States shall, on the
ground of race … be denied the benefits of, or be subjected to
discrimination under any program or activity receiving Federal
financial assistance.” 78 Stat. 252, 42 U. S. C. §2000d. Footnote 6 “The state shall not discriminate against, or
grant preferential treatment to, any individual or group on the
basis of race, sex, color, ethnicity, or national origin in the
operation of public employment, public education, or public
contracting.” Wash. Rev. Code §49.60.400(1) (2006). Footnote 7 Middle and high school students are
designated a single resides school and assigned to that school
unless it is at the extremes of the racial guidelines. Students may
also apply to a magnet school or program, or, at the high school
level, take advantage of an open enrollment plan that allows
ninth-grade students to apply for admission to any nonmagnet high
school. App. in No. 05–915, pp. 39–41, 82–83. Footnote 8 It is not clear why the racial guidelines
were even applied to Joshua’s transfer application—the guidelines
supposedly do not apply at the kindergarten level. Id., at
43. Neither party disputes, however, that Joshua’s transfer
application was denied under the racial guidelines, and Meredith’s
objection is not that the guidelines were misapplied but rather
that race was used at all. Footnote 9 Meredith joined a pending lawsuit filed by
several other plaintiffs. See id., at 7–11. The other
plaintiffs all challenged assignments to certain specialized
schools, and the District Court found these assignments, which are
no longer at issue in this case, unconstitutional. McFarland I , 330 F. Supp. 2d 834, 837, 864
(WD Ky. 2004). Footnote 10 The districts point to dicta in a prior
opinion in which the Court suggested that, while not
constitutionally mandated, it would be constitutionally permissible
for a school district to seek racially balanced schools as a matter
of “educational policy.” See Swann v. Charlotte-Mecklenburg Bd. of Ed. , 402 U. S. 1 , 16 (1971). The districts
also quote with approval an in-chambers opinion in which
then-Justice Rehnquist made a suggestion to the same effect. See Bustop, Inc. v. Los Angeles Bd. of Ed. , 439 U. S. 1380 , 1383
(1978). The citations do not carry the significance the districts
would ascribe to them. Swann , evaluating a school district
engaged in court-ordered desegregation, had no occasion to consider
whether a district’s voluntary adoption of race-based assignments
in the absence of a finding of prior de jure segregation
was constitutionally permissible, an issue that was again expressly
reserved in Washington v. Seattle School Dist. No.
1 , 458 U. S. 457 , 472, n. 15 (1982). Bustop , addressing in the context of an emergency
injunction application a busing plan imposed by the Superior Court
of Los Angeles County, is similarly unavailing. Then-Justice
Rehnquist, in denying emergency relief, stressed that “equitable
consideration[s]” counseled against preliminary relief. 439 U. S.,
at 1383. The propriety of preliminary relief and resolution of the
merits are of course “significantly different” issues. University of Texas v. Camenisch , 451 U. S. 390 , 393
(1981). Footnote 11 The way Seattle classifies its students bears
this out. Upon enrolling their child with the district, parents are
required to identify their child as a member of a particular racial
group. If a parent identifies more than one race on the form,
“[t]he application will not be accepted and, if necessary, the
enrollment service person taking the application will indicate one
box.” App. in No. 05–908, at 303a. Footnote 12 Jefferson County also argues that it
would be incongruous to hold that what was constitutionally
required of it one day—race-based assignments pursuant to the
desegregation decree—can be constitutionally prohibited the next.
But what was constitutionally required of the district prior to
2000 was the elimination of the vestiges of prior segregation—not
racial proportionality in its own right. See Freeman v. Pitts , 503 U. S. 467 , 494–496 (1992). Once
those vestiges were eliminated, Jefferson County was on the same
footing as any other school district, and its use of race must be
justified on other grounds. Footnote 13 Data for the Seattle schools in the several years
since this litigation was commenced further demonstrate the minimal
role that the racial tiebreaker in fact played. At Ballard, in
2005–2006—when no class at the school was subject to the racial
tiebreaker—the student body was 14.2 percent Asian-American, 9
percent African-American, 11.7 percent Latino, 62.3 percent
Caucasian, and 2.8 percent Native-American. Reply Brief for
Petitioner in No. 05–908, p. 7. In 2000–2001, when the racial
tiebreaker was last used, Ballard’s total enrollment was 17.5
percent Asian-American, 10.8 percent African-American, 10.7 percent
Latino, 56.4 percent Caucasian, and 4.6 percent Native-American.
App. in No. 05–908, at 283a. Franklin in 2005–2006 was 48.9 percent
Asian-American, 33.5 percent African-American, 6.6 percent Latino,
10.2 percent Caucasian, and 0.8 percent Native-American. Reply
Brief for Petitioner in No. 05–908, at 7. With the racial
tiebreaker in 2000–2001, total enrollment was 36.8 percent
Asian-American, 32.2 percent African-American, 5.2 percent Latino,
25.1 percent Caucasian, and 0.7 percent Native-American. App. in
No. 05–908, at 284a. Nathan Hale’s 2005–2006 enrollment was 17.3
percent Asian-American, 10.7 percent African-American, 8 percent
Latino, 61.5 percent Caucasian, and 2.5 percent Native-American.
Reply Brief for Petitioner in No. 05–908, at 7. In 2000–2001, with
the racial tiebreaker, it was 17.9 percent Asian-American, 13.3
percent African-American, 7 percent Latino, 58.4 percent Caucasian,
and 3.4 percent Native-American. App. in No. 05–908, at 286a. Footnote 14 In contrast, Seattle’s website formerly
described “emphasizing individualism as opposed to a more
collective ideology” as a form of “cultural racism,” and currently
states that the district has no intention “to hold onto
unsuccessful concepts such as [a] … colorblind mentality.” Harrell,
School Web Site Removed: Examples of Racism Sparked Controversy,
Seattle Post-Intelligencer, June 2, 2006, pp. B1, B5. Compare Plessy v. Ferguson , 163 U. S. 537 , 559
(1896) (Harlan, J., dissenting) (“Our Constitution is color-blind,
and neither knows nor tolerates classes among citizens. In respect
of civil rights, all citizens are equal before the law”). Footnote 15 Justice Breyer makes much of the fact that in
1978 Seattle “settled” an NAACP complaint alleging illegal
segregation with the federal Office for Civil Rights (OCR). See post , at 5, 8–9, 18, 23. The memorandum of agreement
between Seattle and OCR, of course, contains no admission by
Seattle that such segregation ever existed or was ongoing at the
time of the agreement, and simply reflects a “desire to avoid the
incovenience [ sic ] and expense of a formal OCR
investigation,” which OCR was obligated under law to initiate upon
the filing of such a complaint. Memorandum of Agreement between
Seattle School District No. 1 of King County, Washington, and the
Office for Civil Rights, United States Department of Health,
Education, and Welfare 2 (June 9, 1978); see also 45 CFR §80.7(c)
(2006). Footnote 16 In fact, all the cases Justice Breyer’s
dissent cites as evidence of the “prevailing legal assumption,” see post , at 25–27, were decided before this Court
definitively determined that “all racial classifications … must be
analyzed by a reviewing court under strict scrutiny.” Adarand
Constructors, Inc. v. Peńa , 515 U. S. 200 , 227 (1995). Many
proceeded under the now-rejected view that classifications seeking
to benefit a disadvantaged racial group should be held to a lesser
standard of review. See, e.g. , Springfield School
Comm. v. Barksdale , 348 F. 2d 261, 266 (CA1
1965). Even if this purported distinction, which Justice Stevens
would adopt, post , at 2, n. 3 (dissenting opinion),
had not been already rejected by this Court, the distinction has no
relevance to these cases, in which students of all races are
excluded from the schools they wish to attend based solely on the
racial classifications. See, e.g. , App. in No. 05–908, at
202a (noting that 89 nonwhite students were denied assignment to a
particular school by operation of Seattle’s racial tiebreaker).
Justice Stevens’s reliance on School Comm. of Boston v. Board of Ed., 352 Mass. 693, 227 N. E. 2d 729 (1967),
appeal dism’d, 389
U. S. 572 (1968) (per curiam) , post , at 3–5,
is inapposite for the same reason that many of the cases cited by
Justice Breyer are inapposite; the case involved a Massachusetts
law that required school districts to avoid racial imbalance in
schools but did not specify how to achieve this goal—and certainly
did not require express racial classifications as the means to do
so. The law was upheld under rational-basis review, with the state
court explicitly rejecting the suggestion—which is now plainly the
law—that “racial group classifications bear a far heavier burden of
justification.” 352 Mass., at 700, 227 N. E. 2d, at 734
(internal quotation marks and citation omitted). The passage
Justice Stevens quotes proves our point; all the quoted language
says is that the school committee “shall prepare a plan to
eliminate the imbalance.” Id., at 695, 227 N. E. 2d,
at 731; see post , at 4, n. 5. Nothing in the opinion
approves use of racial classifications as the means to address the
imbalance. The suggestion that our decision today is somehow
inconsistent with our disposition of that appeal is belied by the
fact that neither the lower courts, the respondent school
districts, nor any of their 51 amici saw fit even to cite
the case. We raise this fact not to argue that the dismissal should
be afforded any different stare decisis effect, but rather
simply to suggest that perhaps—for the reasons noted above—the
dismissal does not mean what Justice Stevens believes it does. Footnote 17 Justice Breyer also tries to downplay the
impact of the racial assignments by stating that in Seattle
“students can decide voluntarily to transfer to a preferred
district high school (without any consideration of race-conscious
criteria).” Post , at 46. This presumably refers to the
district’s decision to cease, for 2001–2002 school year
assignments, applying the racial tiebreaker to students seeking to
transfer to a different school after ninth grade. See App. in No.
05–908, at 137a–139a. There are obvious disincentives for students
to transfer to a different school after a full quarter of their
high school experience has passed, and the record sheds no light on
how transfers to the oversubscribed high schools are handled. OPINION OF KENNEDY, J. PARENTS INVOLVED IN COMMUNITY SCHOOLS V.SEATTLE SCHOOL DIST. NO.
1 551 U. S. ____ (2007) SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES NOS. 05-908 AND 05-915 PARENTS INVOLVED IN COMMUNITY SCHOOLS,
PETITIONER
05–908 v. SEATTLE SCHOOL DISTRICT NO. 1
et al. on writ of certiorari to the united states
court of appeals for the ninth circuit CRYSTAL D. MEREDITH, custodial parent and next
friend of JOSHUA RYAN McDONALD, PETITIONER
05–915 v. JEFFERSON COUNTY BOARD OF EDUCATION
et al. on writ of certiorari to the united states
court of appeals for the sixth circuit [June 28, 2007] Justice Kennedy ,
concurring in part and concurring in the judgment.
The Nation’s schools strive to
teach that our strength comes from people of different races,
creeds, and cultures uniting in commitment to the freedom of all.
In these cases two school districts in different parts of the
country seek to teach that principle by having classrooms that
reflect the racial makeup of the surrounding community. That the
school districts consider these plans to be necessary should remind
us our highest aspirations are yet unfulfilled. But the solutions
mandated by these school districts must themselves be lawful. To
make race matter now so that it might not matter later may entrench
the very prejudices we seek to overcome. In my view the
state-mandated racial classifications at issue, official labels
proclaiming the race of all persons in a broad class of
citizens—elementary school students in one case, high school
students in another—are unconstitutional as the cases now come to
us.
I agree with The Chief Justice that we have
jurisdiction to decide the cases before us and join Parts I and II
of the Court’s opinion. I also join Parts III–A and III–C for
reasons provided below. My views do not allow me to join the
balance of the opinion by The Chief Justice, which seems to me to
be inconsistent in both its approach and its implications with the
history, meaning, and reach of the Equal Protection Clause. Justice
Breyer’s dissenting opinion, on the other hand, rests on what in my
respectful submission is a misuse and mistaken interpretation of
our precedents. This leads it to advance propositions that, in my
view, are both erroneous and in fundamental conflict with basic
equal protection principles. As a consequence, this separate
opinion is necessary to set forth my conclusions in the two cases
before the Court.
I
The opinion of the Court and
Justice Breyer’s dissenting opinion (hereinafter dissent) describe
in detail the history of integration efforts in Louisville and
Seattle. These plans classify individuals by race and allocate
benefits and burdens on that basis; and as a result, they are to be
subjected to strict scrutiny. See Johnson v. California , 543 U. S. 499 , 505–506
(2005); ante , at 11. The dissent finds that the school
districts have identified a compelling interest in increasing
diversity, including for the purpose of avoiding racial isolation.
See post , at 37–45. The plurality, by contrast, does not
acknowledge that the school districts have identified a compelling
interest here. See ante , at 17–25. For this reason, among
others, I do not join Parts III–B and IV. Diversity, depending on
its meaning and definition, is a compelling educational goal a
school district may pursue.
It is well established that when
a governmental policy is subjected to strict scrutiny, “the
government has the burden of proving that racial classifications
‘are narrowly tailored measures that further compelling
governmental interests.’ ” Johnson , supra ,
at 505 (quoting Adarand Constructors, Inc. v. Peńa , 515 U. S. 200 , 227 (1995)). “Absent
searching judicial inquiry into the justification for such
race-based measures, there is simply no way of determining what
classifications are ‘benign’ or ‘remedial’ and what classifications
are in fact motivated by illegitimate notions of racial inferiority
or simple racial politics.” Richmond v. J. A. Croson
Co. , 488 U. S.
469 , 493 (1989) (plurality opinion). And the inquiry into less
restrictive alternatives demanded by the narrow tailoring analysis
requires in many cases a thorough understanding of how a plan
works. The government bears the burden of justifying its use of
individual racial classifications. As part of that burden it must
establish, in detail, how decisions based on an individual
student’s race are made in a challenged governmental program. The
Jefferson County Board of Education fails to meet this threshold
mandate.
Petitioner Crystal Meredith challenges the
district’s decision to deny her son Joshua McDonald a requested
transfer for his kindergarten enrollment. The district concedes it
denied his request “under the guidelines,” which is to say, on the
basis of Joshua’s race. Brief for Respondents in No. 05–915, p. 10;
see also App. in No. 05–915, p. 97. Yet the district also maintains
that the guidelines do not apply to “kindergartens,” Brief for
Respondents in No. 05–915, at 4, and it fails to explain the
discrepancy. Resort to the record, including the parties’
Stipulation of Facts, further confuses the matter. See App. in No.
05–915, at 43 (“Transfer applications can be denied because of lack
of available space or, for students in grades other than Primary 1
(kindergarten), the racial guidelines in the District’s current
student assignment plan”); id ., at 29 (“The student
assignment plan does not apply to . . . students in Primary 1”);
see also Stipulation of Facts in No. 3:02–CV–00620–JGH; Doc. 32,
Exh. 44, p. 6 (2003–04 Jefferson County Public Schools
Elementary Student Assignment Application, Section B) (“Assignment
is made to a school for Primary 1 (Kindergarten) through Grade Five
as long as racial guidelines are maintained. If the Primary 1
(Kindergarten) placement does not enhance racial balance, a new
application must be completed for Primary 2 (Grade One)”).
The discrepancy identified is not some simple
and straightforward error that touches only upon the peripheries of
the district’s use of individual racial classifications. To the
contrary, Jefferson County in its briefing has explained how and
when it employs these classifications only in terms so broad and
imprecise that they cannot withstand strict scrutiny. See, e.g ., Brief for Respondents in No. 05–915, at 4–10. While
it acknowledges that racial classifications are used to make
certain assignment decisions, it fails to make clear, for example,
who makes the decisions; what if any oversight is employed; the
precise circumstances in which an assignment decision will or will
not be made on the basis of race; or how it is determined which of
two similarly situated children will be subjected to a given
race-based decision. See ibid . ; see also App. in
No. 05–915, at 38, 42 (indicating that decisions are “based on …
the racial guidelines” without further explanation); id .,
at 81 (setting forth the blanket mandate that “[s]chools shall work
cooperatively with each other and with central office to ensure
that enrollment at all schools [in question] is within the racial
guidelines annually and to encourage that the enrollment at all
schools progresses toward the midpoint of the guidelines”); id ., at 43, 76–77, 81–83; McFarland v. Jefferson Cty. Public Schools , 330 F. Supp. 2d 834,
837–845, 855–862 (WD Ky. 2004). When litigation, as here, involves
a “complex, comprehensive plan that contains multiple strategies
for achieving racially integrated schools,” Brief for Respondents
in No. 05–915, at 4, these ambiguities become all the more
problematic in light of the contradictions and confusions that
result. Compare, e.g ., App. in No. 05–915, at 37 (“Each
[Jefferson County] school … has a designated geographic attendance
area, which is called the ‘resides area’ of the school[, and each]
such school is the ‘resides school’ for those students whose
parent’s or guardian’s residence address is within the school’s
geographic attendance area”); id ., at 82 (“All elementary
students … shall be assigned to the school which serves the area in
which they reside”); and Brief for Respondents in No. 05–915, at 5
(“There are no selection criteria for admission to [an elementary
school student’s] resides school, except attainment of the
appropriate age and completion of the previous grade”), with App.
in No. 05–915, at 38 (“Decisions to assign students to schools
within each cluster are based on available space within the
[elementary] schools and the racial guidelines in the District’s
current student assignment plan”); id ., at 82
(acknowledging that a student may not be assigned to his or her
resides school if it “has reached … the extremes of the racial
guidelines”). One can attempt to identify a
construction of Jefferson County’s student assignment plan that, at
least as a logical matter, complies with these competing
propositions; but this does not remedy the underlying problem.
Jefferson County fails to make clear to this Court—even in the
limited respects implicated by Joshua’s initial assignment and
transfer denial—whether in fact it relies on racial classifications
in a manner narrowly tailored to the interest in question, rather
than in the far-reaching, inconsistent, and ad hoc manner that a less forgiving reading of the record would suggest.
When a court subjects governmental action to strict scrutiny, it
cannot construe ambiguities in favor of the State. As for the Seattle case, the
school district has gone further in describing the methods and
criteria used to determine assignment decisions on the basis of
individual racial classifications. See, e.g ., Brief for
Respondents in No. 05–908, p. 5–11. The district, nevertheless, has
failed to make an adequate showing in at least one respect. It has
failed to explain why, in a district composed of a diversity of
races, with fewer than half of the students classified as “white,”
it has employed the crude racial categories of “white” and
“non-white” as the basis for its assignment decisions. See, e.g., id ., at 1–11. The district has identified its
purposes as follows: “(1) to promote the educational benefits of
diverse school enrollments; (2) to reduce the potentially harmful
effects of racial isolation by allowing students the opportunity to
opt out of racially isolated schools; and (3) to make sure that
racially segregated housing patterns did not prevent non-white
students from having equitable access to the most popular
over-subscribed schools.” Id ., at 19. Yet the school
district does not explain how, in the context of its diverse
student population, a blunt distinction between “white” and
“non-white” furthers these goals. As the Court explains, “a school
with 50 percent Asian-American students and 50 percent white
students but no African-American, Native-American, or Latino
students would qualify as balanced, while a school with 30 percent
Asian-American, 25 percent African-American, 25 percent Latino, and
20 percent white students would not.” Ante , at 15–16; see
also Brief for United States as Amicus Curiae in No.
05–908, pp. 13–14. Far from being narrowly tailored to its
purposes, this system threatens to defeat its own ends, and the
school district has provided no convincing explanation for its
design. Other problems are evident in Seattle’s system, but there
is no need to address them now. As the district fails to account
for the classification system it has chosen, despite what appears
to be its ill fit, Seattle has not shown its plan to be narrowly
tailored to achieve its own ends; and thus it fails to pass strict
scrutiny. II Our Nation from the
inception has sought to preserve and expand the promise of liberty
and equality on which it was founded. Today we enjoy a society that
is remarkable in its openness and opportunity. Yet our tradition is
to go beyond present achievements, however significant, and to
recognize and confront the flaws and injustices that remain. This
is especially true when we seek assurance that opportunity is not
denied on account of race. The enduring hope is that race should
not matter; the reality is that too often it does. This is by way of
preface to my respectful submission that parts of the opinion by
The Chief Justice imply an all-too-unyielding insistence that race
cannot be a factor in instances when, in my view, it may be taken
into account. The plurality opinion is too dismissive of the
legitimate interest government has in ensuring all people have
equal opportunity regardless of their race. The plurality’s
postulate that “[t]he way to stop discrimination on the basis of
race is to stop discriminating on the basis of race,” ante , at 40–41, is not sufficient to decide these cases.
Fifty years of experience since Brown v. Board of
Education, 347
U. S. 483 (1954), should teach us that the problem before us
defies so easy a solution. School districts can seek to reach Brown ’s objective of equal educational opportunity. The
plurality opinion is at least open to the interpretation that the
Constitution requires school districts to ignore the problem of de facto resegregation in schooling. I cannot endorse that
conclusion. To the extent the plurality opinion suggests the
Constitution mandates that state and local school authorities must
accept the status quo of racial isolation in schools, it is, in my
view, profoundly mistaken. The statement by Justice Harlan
that “[o]ur Constitution is color-blind” was most certainly
justified in the context of his dissent in Plessy v. Ferguson , 163 U. S. 537 , 559
(1896). The Court’s decision in that case was a grievous error it
took far too long to overrule. Plessy , of course,
concerned official classification by race applicable to all persons
who sought to use railway carriages. And, as an aspiration, Justice
Harlan’s axiom must command our assent. In the real world, it is
regrettable to say, it cannot be a universal constitutional
principle. In the administration of public
schools by the state and local authorities it is permissible to
consider the racial makeup of schools and to adopt general policies
to encourage a diverse student body, one aspect of which is its
racial composition. Cf. Grutter v. Bollinger , 539 U. S. 306 (2003); id. , at
387–388 (Kennedy, J., dissenting). If school authorities are
concerned that the student-body compositions of certain schools
interfere with the objective of offering an equal educational
opportunity to all of their students, they are free to devise
race-conscious measures to address the problem in a general way and
without treating each student in different fashion solely on the
basis of a systematic, individual typing by race. School boards may pursue the goal
of bringing together students of diverse backgrounds and races
through other means, including strategic site selection of new
schools; drawing attendance zones with general recognition of the
demographics of neighborhoods; allocating resources for special
programs; recruiting students and faculty in a targeted fashion;
and tracking enrollments, performance, and other statistics by
race. These mechanisms are race conscious but do not lead to
different treatment based on a classification that tells each
student he or she is to be defined by race, so it is unlikely any
of them would demand strict scrutiny to be found permissible. See Bush v. Vera , 517 U. S. 952 , 958
(1996) (plurality opinion) (“Strict scrutiny does not apply merely
because redistricting is performed with consciousness of
race… . Electoral district lines are ‘facially race neutral’
so a more searching inquiry is necessary before strict scrutiny can
be found applicable in redistricting cases than in cases of
‘classifications based explicitly on race’ ” (quoting Adarand , 515 U. S., at 213)). Executive and legislative
branches, which for generations now have considered these types of
policies and procedures, should be permitted to employ them with
candor and with confidence that a constitutional violation does not
occur whenever a decisionmaker considers the impact a given
approach might have on students of different races. Assigning to
each student a personal designation according to a crude system of
individual racial classifications is quite a different matter; and
the legal analysis changes accordingly. Each respondent has asserted that
its assignment of individual students by race is permissible
because there is no other way to avoid racial isolation in the
school districts. Yet, as explained, each has failed to provide the
support necessary for that proposition. Cf. Croson , 488 U.
S., at 501 (“The history of racial classifications in this country
suggests that blind judicial deference to legislative or executive
pronouncements of necessity has no place in equal protection
analysis”). And individual racial classifications employed in this
manner may be considered legitimate only if they are a last resort
to achieve a compelling interest. See id. , at 519
(Kennedy, J., concurring in part and concurring in
judgment). In the cases before us it is
noteworthy that the number of students whose assignment depends on
express racial classifications is limited. I join Part III–C of the
Court’s opinion because I agree that in the context of these plans,
the small number of assignments affected suggests that the schools
could have achieved their stated ends through different means.
These include the facially race-neutral means set forth above or,
if necessary, a more nuanced, individual evaluation of school needs
and student characteristics that might include race as a component.
The latter approach would be informed by Grutter , though
of course the criteria relevant to student placement would differ
based on the age of the students, the needs of the parents, and the
role of the schools. III The dissent rests on
the assumptions that these sweeping race-based classifications of
persons are permitted by existing precedents; that its confident
endorsement of race categories for each child in a large segment of
the community presents no danger to individual freedom in other,
prospective realms of governmental regulation; and that the racial
classifications used here cause no hurt or anger of the type the
Constitution prevents. Each of these premises is, in my respectful
view, incorrect. A The dissent’s
reliance on this Court’s precedents to justify the explicit,
sweeping, classwide racial classifications at issue here is a
misreading of our authorities that, it appears to me, tends to
undermine well-accepted principles needed to guard our freedom. And
in his critique of that analysis, I am in many respects in
agreement with The Chief Justice. The conclusions he has set forth
in Part III–A of the Court’s opinion are correct, in my view,
because the compelling interests implicated in the cases before us
are distinct from the interests the Court has recognized in
remedying the effects of past intentional discrimination and in
increasing diversity in higher education. See ante , at
12–13. As the Court notes, we recognized the compelling nature of
the interest in remedying past intentional discrimination in Freeman v. Pitts , 503 U. S. 467 , 494
(1992), and of the interest in diversity in higher education in Grutter . At the same time, these compelling interests, in
my view, do help inform the present inquiry. And to the extent the
plurality opinion can be interpreted to foreclose consideration of
these interests, I disagree with that reasoning. As to the dissent, the general
conclusions upon which it relies have no principled limit and would
result in the broad acceptance of governmental racial
classifications in areas far afield from schooling. The dissent’s
permissive strict scrutiny (which bears more than a passing
resemblance to rational-basis review) could invite widespread
governmental deployment of racial classifications. There is every
reason to think that, if the dissent’s rationale were accepted,
Congress, assuming an otherwise proper exercise of its spending
authority or commerce power, could mandate either the Seattle or
the Jefferson County plans nationwide. There seems to be no
principled rule, moreover, to limit the dissent’s rationale to the
context of public schools. The dissent emphasizes local control,
see post , at 48–49, the unique history of school
desegregation, see post , at 2, and the fact that these
plans make less use of race than prior plans, see post , at
57, but these factors seem more rhetorical than integral to the
analytical structure of the opinion. This brings us to the
dissent’s reliance on the Court’s opinions in Gratz v. Bollinger , 539 U. S. 244 (2003),
and Grutter , 539 U. S. 306 . If today’s
dissent said it was adhering to the views expressed in the separate
opinions in Gratz and Grutter , see Gratz , 539 U. S., at 281 (Breyer, J., concurring in
judgment); id., at 282 (Stevens, J., dissenting); id., at 291 (Souter, J., dissenting); id., at 298
(Ginsburg, J., dissenting); Grutter , supra , at
344 (Ginsburg, J., concurring), that would be understandable, and
likely within the tradition—to be invoked, in my view, in rare
instances—that permits us to maintain our own positions in the face
of stare decisis when fundamental points of doctrine are
at stake. See, e.g., Federal Maritime Comm’n v. South Carolina Ports Authority , 535 U. S. 743 , 770
(2002) (Stevens, J., dissenting). To say, however, that we must
ratify the racial classifications here at issue based on the
majority opinions in Gratz and Grutter is, with
all respect, simply baffling. Gratz involved a system
where race was not the entire classification. The procedures in Gratz placed much less reliance on race than do the plans
at issue here. The issue in Gratz arose, moreover, in the
context of college admissions where students had other choices and
precedent supported the proposition that First Amendment interests
give universities particular latitude in defining diversity. See Regents of Univ. of Cal. v. Bakke , 438 U. S. 265 , 312–314 (1978) (opinion
of Powell, J.). Even so the race factor was found to be invalid. Gratz , supra , at 251. If Gratz is to be
the measure, the racial classification systems here are a
fortiori invalid. If the dissent were to say that college
cases are simply not applicable to public school systems in
kindergarten through high school, this would seem to me wrong, but
at least an arguable distinction. Under no fair reading, though,
can the majority opinion in Gratz be cited as authority to
sustain the racial classifications under consideration
here. The same must be said for the
controlling opinion in Grutter . There the Court sustained
a system that, it found, was flexible enough to take into account
“all pertinent elements of diversity,” 539 U. S., at 341 (internal
quotation marks omitted), and considered race as only one factor
among many, id ., at 340. Seattle’s plan, by contrast,
relies upon a mechanical formula that has denied hundreds of
students their preferred schools on the basis of three rigid
criteria: placement of siblings, distance from schools, and race.
If those students were considered for a whole range of their
talents and school needs with race as just one consideration, Grutter would have some application. That, though, is not
the case. The only support today’s dissent can draw from Grutter must be found in its various separate opinions,
not in the opinion filed for the Court. B To uphold these
programs the Court is asked to brush aside two concepts of central
importance for determining the validity of laws and decrees
designed to alleviate the hurt and adverse consequences resulting
from race discrimination. The first is the difference between de jure and de facto segregation; the second, the
presumptive invalidity of a State’s use of racial classifications
to differentiate its treatment of individuals. In the immediate aftermath of Brown the Court addressed other instances where laws and
practices enforced de jure segregation. See, e.g., Loving v. Virginia , 388 U. S. 1 (1967)
(marriage); New Orleans City Park Improvement Assn. v. Detiege , 358
U. S. 54 (1958) (per curiam) (public parks); Gayle v. Browder , 352 U. S. 903 (1956) (per curiam) (buses); Holmes v. Atlanta , 350 U. S. 879 (1955) (per curiam) (golf courses); Mayor of
Baltimore v. Dawson , 350 U. S. 877 (1955) (per curiam) (beaches). But with reference to schools, the
effect of the legal wrong proved most difficult to correct. To
remedy the wrong, school districts that had been segregated by law
had no choice, whether under court supervision or pursuant to
voluntary desegregation efforts, but to resort to extraordinary
measures including individual student and teacher assignment to
schools based on race. See, e.g., Swann v. Charlotte-Mecklenburg Bd. of Ed. , 402 U. S. 1 , 8–10 (1971);
see also Croson , 488 U. S., at 519 (Kennedy, J.,
concurring in part and concurring in judgment) (noting that racial
classifications “may be the only adequate remedy after a judicial
determination that a State or its instrumentality has violated the
Equal Protection Clause”). So it was, as the dissent observes, see post , at 13–14, that Louisville classified children by
race in its school assignment and busing plan in the
1970’s. Our cases recognized
a fundamental difference between those school districts that had
engaged in de jure segregation and those whose segregation
was the result of other factors. School districts that had engaged
in de jure segregation had an affirmative constitutional
duty to desegregate; those that were de facto segregated
did not. Compare Green v. School Bd. of New Kent
Cty. , 391 U. S.
430 , 437–438 (1968), with Milliken v. Bradley , 418 U. S. 717 , 745
(1974). The distinctions between de jure and de
facto segregation extended to the remedies available to
governmental units in addition to the courts. For example, in Wygant v. Jackson Bd. of Ed. , 476 U. S. 267 , 274
(1986), the plurality noted: “This Court never has held that
societal discrimination alone is sufficient to justify a racial
classification. Rather, the Court has insisted upon some showing of
prior discrimination by the governmental unit involved before
allowing limited use of racial classifications in order to remedy
such discrimination.” The Court’s decision in Croson,
supra , reinforced the difference between the remedies
available to redress de facto and de jure discrimination: “To accept [a] claim that past societal
discrimination alone can serve as the basis for rigid racial
preferences would be to open the door to competing claims for
‘remedial relief’ for every disadvantaged group. The dream of a
Nation of equal citizens in a society where race is irrelevant to
personal opportunity and achievement would be lost in a mosaic of
shifting preferences based on inherently unmeasurable claims of
past wrongs.” Id. , at 505–506. From the standpoint
of the victim, it is true, an injury stemming from racial prejudice
can hurt as much when the demeaning treatment based on race
identity stems from bias masked deep within the social order as
when it is imposed by law. The distinction between government and
private action, furthermore, can be amorphous both as a historical
matter and as a matter of present-day finding of fact. Laws arise
from a culture and vice versa. Neither can assign to the other all
responsibility for persisting injustices. Yet, like so many other legal
categories that can overlap in some instances, the constitutional
distinction between de jure and de facto segregation has been thought to be an important one. It must be
conceded its primary function in school cases was to delimit the
powers of the Judiciary in the fashioning of remedies. See, e.g., Milliken, supra, at 746. The distinction
ought not to be altogether disregarded, however, when we come to
that most sensitive of all racial issues, an attempt by the
government to treat whole classes of persons differently based on
the government’s systematic classification of each individual by
race. There, too, the distinction serves as a limit on the exercise
of a power that reaches to the very verge of constitutional
authority. Reduction of an individual to an assigned racial
identity for differential treatment is among the most pernicious
actions our government can undertake. The allocation of
governmental burdens and benefits, contentious under any
circumstances, is even more divisive when allocations are made on
the basis of individual racial classifications. See, e.g., Regents of Univ. of Cal. v. Bakke , 438 U. S. 265 (1978); Adarand , 515 U. S. 200 . Notwithstanding these concerns,
allocation of benefits and burdens through individual racial
classifications was found sometimes permissible in the context of
remedies for de jure wrong. Where there has been de
jure segregation, there is a cognizable legal wrong, and the
courts and legislatures have broad power to remedy it. The remedy,
though, was limited in time and limited to the wrong. The Court has
allowed school districts to remedy their prior de jure segregation by classifying individual students based on their race.
See North Carolina Bd. of Ed. v. Swann , 402 U. S. 43 , 45–46
(1971). The limitation of this power to instances where there has
been de jure segregation serves to confine the nature,
extent, and duration of governmental reliance on individual racial
classifications. The cases here were argued upon
the assumption, and come to us on the premise, that the
discrimination in question did not result from de jure actions. And when de facto discrimination is at issue our
tradition has been that the remedial rules are different. The State
must seek alternatives to the classification and differential
treatment of individuals by race, at least absent some
extraordinary showing not present here. C The dissent refers to
an opinion filed by Judge Kozinski in one of the cases now before
us, and that opinion relied upon an opinion filed by Chief Judge
Boudin in a case presenting an issue similar to the one here. See post , at 35 (citing 426 F. 3d 1162, 1193–1196 (CA9
2005) (concurring opinion) (citing Comfort v. Lynn
School Comm. , 418 F. 3d 1, 27–29 (CA1 2005) (Boudin,
C. J., concurring))). Though this may oversimplify the matter
a bit, one of the main concerns underlying those opinions was this:
If it is legitimate for school authorities to work to avoid racial
isolation in their schools, must they do so only by indirection and
general policies? Does the Constitution mandate this inefficient
result? Why may the authorities not recognize the problem in candid
fashion and solve it altogether through resort to direct
assignments based on student racial classifications? So, the
argument proceeds, if race is the problem, then perhaps race is the
solution. The argument ignores
the dangers presented by individual classifications, dangers that
are not as pressing when the same ends are achieved by more
indirect means. When the government classifies an individual by
race, it must first define what it means to be of a race. Who
exactly is white and who is nonwhite? To be forced to live under a
state-mandated racial label is inconsistent with the dignity of
individuals in our society. And it is a label that an individual is
powerless to change. Governmental classifications that command
people to march in different directions based on racial typologies
can cause a new divisiveness. The practice can lead to corrosive
discourse, where race serves not as an element of our diverse
heritage but instead as a bargaining chip in the political process.
On the other hand race-conscious measures that do not rely on
differential treatment based on individual classifications present
these problems to a lesser degree. The idea that if race is the
problem, race is the instrument with which to solve it cannot be
accepted as an analytical leap forward. And if this is a
frustrating duality of the Equal Protection Clause it simply
reflects the duality of our history and our attempts to promote
freedom in a world that sometimes seems set against it. Under our
Constitution the individual, child or adult, can find his own
identity, can define her own persona, without state intervention
that classifies on the basis of his race or the color of her
skin. * * * This Nation has a
moral and ethical obligation to fulfill its historic commitment to
creating an integrated society that ensures equal opportunity for
all of its children. A compelling interest exists in avoiding
racial isolation, an interest that a school district, in its
discretion and expertise, may choose to pursue. Likewise, a
district may consider it a compelling interest to achieve a diverse
student population. Race may be one component of that diversity,
but other demographic factors, plus special talents and needs,
should also be considered. What the government is not permitted to
do, absent a showing of necessity not made here, is to classify
every student on the basis of race and to assign each of them to
schools based on that classification. Crude measures of this sort
threaten to reduce children to racial chits valued and traded
according to one school’s supply and another’s demand. That statement, to be sure,
invites this response: A sense of stigma may already become the
fate of those separated out by circumstances beyond their immediate
control. But to this the replication must be: Even so, measures
other than differential treatment based on racial typing of
individuals first must be exhausted. The decision today
should not prevent school districts from continuing the important
work of bringing together students of different racial, ethnic, and
economic backgrounds. Due to a variety of factors—some influenced
by government, some not—neighborhoods in our communities do not
reflect the diversity of our Nation as a whole. Those entrusted
with directing our public schools can bring to bear the creativity
of experts, parents, administrators, and other concerned citizens
to find a way to achieve the compelling interests they face without
resorting to widespread governmental allocation of benefits and
burdens on the basis of racial classifications. With this explanation I concur in
the judgment of the Court. THOMAS, J., CONCURRING PARENTS INVOLVED IN COMMUNITY SCHOOLS V.SEATTLE SCHOOL DIST. NO.
1 551 U. S. ____ (2007) SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES NOS. 05-908 AND 05-915 PARENTS INVOLVED IN COMMUNITY SCHOOLS,
PETITIONER
05–908 v. SEATTLE SCHOOL DISTRICT NO. 1
et al. on writ of certiorari to the united states
court of appeals for the ninth circuit CRYSTAL D. MEREDITH, custodial parent and next
friend of JOSHUA RYAN McDONALD, PETITIONER
05–915 v. JEFFERSON COUNTY BOARD OF EDUCATION
et al. on writ of certiorari to the united states
court of appeals for the sixth circuit [June 28, 2007] Justice Thomas ,
concurring.
Today, the Court holds that state
entities may not experiment with race-based means to achieve ends
they deem socially desirable. I wholly concur in The Chief
Justice’s opinion. I write separately to address several of the
contentions in Justice Breyer’s dissent (hereinafter the dissent).
Contrary to the dissent’s arguments, resegregation is not occurring
in Seattle or Louisville; these school boards have no present
interest in remedying past segregation; and these race-based
student-assignment programs do not serve any compelling state
interest. Accordingly, the plans are unconstitutional. Disfavoring
a color-blind interpretation of the Constitution, the dissent would
give school boards a free hand to make decisions on the basis of
race—an approach reminiscent of that advocated by the
segregationists in Brown v. Board of Education, 347 U. S.483 (1954). This approach is just as wrong today as it was
a half-century ago. The Constitution and our cases require us to be
much more demanding before permitting local school boards to make
decisions based on race.
I
The dissent repeatedly claims
that the school districts are threatened with resegregation and
that they will succumb to that threat if these plans are declared
unconstitutional. It also argues that these plans can be justified
as part of the school boards’ attempts to “eradicat[e] earlier
school segregation.” See, e.g. , post , at 4.
Contrary to the dissent’s rhetoric, neither of these school
districts is threatened with resegregation, and neither is
constitutionally compelled or permitted to undertake race-based
remediation. Racial imbalance is not segregation, and the mere
incantation of terms like resegregation and remediation cannot make
up the difference.
A
Because this Court has authorized
and required race-based remedial measures to address de
jure segregation, it is important to define segregation
clearly and to distinguish it from racial imbalance. In the context
of public schooling, segregation is the deliberate operation of a
school system to “carry out a governmental policy to separate
pupils in schools solely on the basis of race.” Swann v. Charlotte-Mecklenburg Bd. of Ed. , 402 U. S. 1 , 6 (1971); see
also Monroe v. Board of Comm’rs of Jackson , 391 U. S. 450 ,
452 (1968). In Brown, this Court declared that segregation
was unconstitutional under the Equal Protection Clause of the
Fourteenth Amendment. Swann , supra , at 6; see
also Green v. School Bd. of New Kent Cty. , 391 U. S. 430 ,
435 (1968) (“[T]he State, acting through the local school board and
school officials, organized and operated a dual system, part
‘white’ and part ‘Negro.’ It was such dual systems that 14 years
ago Brown I [, 347 U. S. 483 ,] held unconstitutional
and a year later Brown II [, 349 U. S. 294 (1955)]
held must be abolished”) .[ Footnote 1 ] Racial imbalance is the
failure of a school district’s individual schools to match or
approximate the demographic makeup of the student population at
large. Cf. Washington v. Seattle School Dist. No. 1 , 458 U. S. 457 ,
460 (1982). Racial imbalance is not segregation.[ Footnote 2 ] Although presently observed racial
imbalance might result from past de jure segregation,
racial imbalance can also result from any number of innocent
private decisions, including voluntary housing choices. See Swann , supra , at 25–26; Missouri v. Jenkins , 515 U. S. 70 , 116 (1995) (Thomas, J.,
concurring). Because racial imbalance is not inevitably linked to
unconstitutional segregation, it is not unconstitutional in and of
itself. Dayton Bd. of Ed. v. Brinkman , 433 U. S. 406 , 413
(1977); Dayton Bd. of Ed. v. Brinkman , 443 U. S. 526 , 531,
n. 5 (1979) (“Racial imbalance … is not per se a
constitutional violation”); Freeman v. Pitts , 503 U. S. 467 ,
494 (1992); see also Swann , supra , at 31–32; cf. Milliken v. Bradley , 418 U. S. 717 , 740–741,
and n. 19 (1974).
Although there is arguably a danger of racial
imbalance in schools in Seattle and Louisville, there is no danger
of resegregation. No one contends that Seattle has established or
that Louisville has reestablished a dual school system that
separates students on the basis of race. The statistics cited in
Appendix A to the dissent are not to the contrary. See post , at 69–72. At most, those statistics show a national
trend toward classroom racial imbalance. However, racial imbalance
without intentional state action to separate the races does not
amount to segregation. To raise the specter of resegregation to
defend these programs is to ignore the meaning of the word and the
nature of the cases before us.[ Footnote 3 ]
B
Just as the school districts lack
an interest in preventing resegregation, they also have no present
interest in remedying past segregation. The Constitution generally
prohibits government race-based decisionmaking, but this Court has
authorized the use of race-based measures for remedial purposes in
two narrowly defined circumstances. First, in schools that were
formerly segregated by law, race-based measures are sometimes
constitutionally compelled to remedy prior school segregation.
Second, in Croson , the Court appeared willing to authorize
a government unit to remedy past discrimination for which it was
responsible. Richmond v. J. A. Croson Co. , 488 U. S. 469 ,
504 (1989). Without explicitly resting on either of these strands
of doctrine, the dissent repeatedly invokes the school districts’
supposed interests in remedying past segregation. Properly
analyzed, though, these plans do not fall within either existing
category of permissible race-based remediation.
1
The Constitution does not permit
race-based government decisionmaking simply because a school
district claims a remedial purpose and proceeds in good faith with
arguably pure motives. Grutter v. Bollinger , 539 U. S. 306 , 371 (2003) (Thomas, J.,
concurring in part and dissenting in part) (citing Adarand
Constructors, Inc. v. Peńa , 515 U. S. 200 , 239 (1995) (Scalia, J.,
concurring in part and concurring in judgment)). Rather, race-based
government decisionmaking is categorically prohibited unless
narrowly tailored to serve a compelling interest. Grutter , supra , at 326; see also Part II–A, infra . This
exacting scrutiny “has proven automatically fatal” in most cases. Jenkins , supra , at 121 (Thomas, J., concurring);
cf. Hirabayashi v. United States , 320 U. S. 81 , 100 (1943)
(“[R]acial discriminations are in most circumstances irrelevant and
therefore prohibited”). And appropriately so. “The Constitution
abhors classifications based on race, not only because those
classifications can harm favored races or are based on illegitimate
motives, but also because every time the government places citizens
on racial registers and makes race relevant to the provision of
burdens or benefits, it demeans us all.” Grutter , supra , at 353 (opinion of Thomas, J.). Therefore, as a
general rule, all race-based government decisionmaking—regardless
of context—is unconstitutional.
2
This Court has carved out a
narrow exception to that general rule for cases in which a school
district has a “history of maintaining two sets of schools in a
single school system deliberately operated to carry out a
governmental policy to separate pupils in schools solely on the
basis of race.”[ Footnote 4 ] See Swann , 402 U. S., at 5–6. In such cases, race-based
remedial measures are sometimes required.[ Footnote 5 ] Green , 391 U. S., at 437–438; cf. United States v. Fordice , 505 U. S. 717 , 745 (1992) (Thomas, J.,
concurring).[ Footnote 6 ] But
without a history of state-enforced racial separation, a school
district has no affirmative legal obligation to take race-based
remedial measures to eliminate segregation and its vestiges.
Neither of the programs before us
today is compelled as a remedial measure, and no one makes such a
claim. Seattle has no history of de jure segregation;
therefore, the Constitution did not require Seattle’s
plan.[ Footnote 7 ] Although
Louisville once operated a segregated school system and was subject
to a Federal District Court’s desegregation decree, see ante , at 7; Hampton v. Jefferson Cty. Bd. of
Ed., 102 F. Supp. 2d 358, 376–377 (WD Ky. 2000), that
decree was dissolved in 2000, id. , at 360. Since then, no
race-based remedial measures have been required in Louisville.
Thus, the race-based student-assignment plan at issue here, which
was instituted the year after the dissolution of the desegregation
decree, was not even arguably required by the Constitution.
3
Aside from constitutionally
compelled remediation in schools, this Court has permitted
government units to remedy prior racial discrimination only in
narrow circumstances. See Wygant v. Jackson Bd. of
Ed. , 476 U. S.
267 , 277 (1986) (plurality opinion). Regardless of the
constitutional validity of such remediation, see Croson , supra , at 524–525 (Scalia, J., concurring in judgment), it
does not apply here. Again, neither school board asserts that its
race-based actions were taken to remedy prior discrimination.
Seattle provides three forward-looking—as opposed to
remedial—justifications for its race-based assignment plan. Brief
for Respondents in No. 05–908, pp. 24–34. Louisville asserts
several similar forward-looking interests, Brief for Respondents in
No. 05–915, pp. 24–29, and at oral argument, counsel for Louisville
disavowed any claim that Louisville’s argument “depend[ed] in any
way on the prior de jure segregation,” Tr. of Oral Arg. in No.
05–915, p. 38.
Furthermore, for a government
unit to remedy past discrimination for which it was responsible,
the Court has required it to demonstrate “a ‘strong basis in
evidence for its conclusion that remedial action was
necessary.’ ” Croson , 488 U. S., at 500 (quoting Wygant , supra , at 277 (plurality opinion)).
Establishing a “strong basis in evidence” requires proper findings
regarding the extent of the government unit’s past racial
discrimination. Croson , 488 U. S., at 504. The findings
should “define the scope of any injury [and] the necessary remedy,” id., at 505, and must be more than “inherently
unmeasurable claims of past wrongs,” id., at 506.
Assertions of general societal discrimination are plainly
insufficient. Id., at 499, 504; Wygant , supra , at 274 (plurality opinion); cf. Regents of
Univ. of Cal. v. Bakke , 438 U. S. 265 , 310
(1978) (opinion of Powell, J.). Neither school district has made
any such specific findings. For Seattle, the dissent attempts to
make up for this failing by adverting to allegations made in past
complaints filed against the Seattle school district. However,
allegations in complaints cannot substitute for specific findings
of prior discrimination—even when those allegations lead to
settlements with complaining parties. Cf. Croson , supra , at 505; Wygant , supra , at 279,
n. 5 (plurality opinion). As for Louisville, its slate was
cleared by the District Court’s 2000 dissolution decree, which
effectively declared that there were no longer any effects of de jure discrimination in need of remediation.[ Footnote 8 ]
Despite the dissent’s repeated intimation of a
remedial purpose, neither of the programs in question qualifies as
a permissible race-based remedial measure. Thus, the programs are
subject to the general rule that government race-based
decisionmaking is unconstitutional.
C
As the foregoing demonstrates,
racial balancing is sometimes a constitutionally permissible remedy
for the discrete legal wrong of de jure segregation, and
when directed to that end, racial balancing is an exception to the
general rule that government race-based decisionmaking is
unconstitutional. Perhaps for this reason, the dissent conflates
the concepts of segregation and racial imbalance: If racial
imbalance equates to segregation, then it must also be
constitutionally acceptable to use racial balancing to remedy
racial imbalance.
For at least two reasons,
however, it is wrong to place the remediation of segregation on the
same plane as the remediation of racial imbalance. First, as
demonstrated above, the two concepts are distinct. Although racial
imbalance can result from de jure segregation, it does not
necessarily, and the further we get from the era of state-sponsored
racial separation, the less likely it is that racial imbalance has
a traceable connection to any prior segregation. See Freeman , 503 U. S., at 496; Jenkins , 515 U. S.,
at 118 (Thomas, J., concurring).
Second, a school cannot “remedy” racial
imbalance in the same way that it can remedy segregation.
Remediation of past de jure segregation is a one-time
process involving the redress of a discrete legal injury inflicted
by an identified entity. At some point, the discrete injury will be
remedied, and the school district will be declared unitary. See Swann , 402 U. S., at 31. Unlike de jure segregation, there is no ultimate remedy for racial imbalance.
Individual schools will fall in and out of balance in the natural
course, and the appropriate balance itself will shift with a school
district’s changing demographics. Thus, racial balancing will have
to take place on an indefinite basis—a continuous process with no
identifiable culpable party and no discernable end point. In part
for those reasons, the Court has never permitted outright racial
balancing solely for the purpose of achieving a particular racial
balance.
II
Lacking a cognizable interest in
remediation, neither of these plans can survive strict scrutiny
because neither plan serves a genuinely compelling state interest.
The dissent avoids reaching that conclusion by unquestioningly
accepting the assertions of selected social scientists while
completely ignoring the fact that those assertions are the subject
of fervent debate. Ultimately, the dissent’s entire analysis is
corrupted by the considerations that lead it initially to question
whether strict scrutiny should apply at all. What emerges is a
version of “strict scrutiny” that combines hollow assurances of
harmlessness with reflexive acceptance of conventional wisdom. When
it comes to government race-based decisionmaking, the Constitution
demands more.
A
The dissent claims that “the law
requires application here of a standard of review that is not
‘strict’ in the traditional sense of that word.” Post , at
36. This view is informed by dissents in our previous cases and the
concurrences of two Court of Appeals judges. Post, at
34–36 (citing 426 F. 3d 1162, 1193–1194 (CA9 2005) (Kozinski,
J., concurring); Comfort v. Lynn School Comm., 418 F. 3d 1, 28–29 (CA1 2005) (Boudin, C. J.,
concurring)). Those lower court judges reasoned that programs like
these are not “aimed at oppressing blacks” and do not “seek to give
one racial group an edge over another.” Comfort , supra , at 27 (Boudin, C. J., concurring); 426
F. 3d, at 1193 (Kozinski, J., concurring). They were further
persuaded that these plans differed from other race-based programs
this Court has considered because they are “certainly more benign
than laws that favor or disfavor one race, segregate by race, or
create quotas for or against a racial group,” Comfort , 418
F. 3d, at 28 (Boudin, C. J., concurring), and they are
“far from the original evils at which the Fourteenth Amendment was
addressed,” id., at 29; 426 F. 3d, at 1195 (Kozinski,
J., concurring). Instead of strict scrutiny, Judge Kozinski would
have analyzed the plans under “robust and realistic rational basis
review.” Id., at 1194.
These arguments are inimical to
the Constitution and to this Court’s precedents.[ Footnote 9 ] We have made it unusually clear that
strict scrutiny applies to every racial classification. Adarand , 515 U. S., at 227; Grutter , 539 U. S.,
at 326; Johnson v. California , 543 U. S. 499 , 505 (2005) (“We have
insisted on strict scrutiny in every context, even for so-called
‘benign’ racial classifications”).[ Footnote 10 ] There are good reasons not to apply a lesser
standard to these cases. The constitutional problems with
government race-based decisionmaking are not diminished in the
slightest by the presence or absence of an intent to oppress any
race or by the real or asserted well-meaning motives for the
race-based decisionmaking. Adarand , 515 U. S., at 228–229.
Purportedly benign race-based decisionmaking suffers the same
constitutional infirmity as invidious race-based decisionmaking. Id., at 240 (Thomas, J., concurring in part and concurring
in judgment) (“As far as the Constitution is concerned, it is
irrelevant whether a government’s racial classifications are drawn
by those who wish to oppress a race or by those who have a sincere
desire to help those thought to be disadvantaged”).
Even supposing it mattered to the
constitutional analysis, the race-based student assignment programs
before us are not as benign as the dissent believes. See post , at 34–35. “[R]acial paternalism and its unintended
consequences can be as poisonous and pernicious as any other form
of discrimination.” Adarand , supra , at 241
(opinion of Thomas, J.). As these programs demonstrate, every time
the government uses racial criteria to “bring the races together,” post , at 29, someone gets excluded, and the person
excluded suffers an injury solely because of his or her race. The
petitioner in the Louisville case received a letter from the school
board informing her that her kindergartener would not be
allowed to attend the school of petitioner’s choosing because of
the child’s race. App. in No. 05–915, p. 97. Doubtless,
hundreds of letters like this went out from both school boards
every year these race-based assignment plans were in operation.
This type of exclusion, solely on the basis of race, is precisely
the sort of government action that pits the races against one
another, exacerbates racial tension, and “provoke[s] resentment
among those who believe that they have been wronged by the
government’s use of race.” Adarand , supra , at 241
(opinion of Thomas, J.). Accordingly, these plans are simply one
more variation on the government race-based decisionmaking we have
consistently held must be subjected to strict scrutiny. Grutter , supra , at 326.
B
Though the dissent admits to
discomfort in applying strict scrutiny to these plans, it claims to
have nonetheless applied that exacting standard. But in its search
for a compelling interest, the dissent casually accepts even the
most tenuous interests asserted on behalf of the plans, grouping
them all under the term “ ‘integration.’ ” See post , at 37. “ ‘[I]ntegration,’ ” we are told,
has “three essential elements.” Ibid. None of these
elements is compelling. And the combination of the three
unsubstantiated elements does not produce an interest any more
compelling than that represented by each element independently.
1
According to the dissent,
integration involves “an interest in setting right the consequences
of prior conditions of segregation.” Post , at 37. For the
reasons explained above, the records in these cases do not
demonstrate that either school board’s plan is supported by an
interest in remedying past discrimination. Part I–B, supra .
Moreover, the school boards have
no interest in remedying the sundry consequences of prior
segregation unrelated to schooling, such as “housing patterns,
employment practices, economic conditions, and social attitudes.” Post , at 38. General claims that past school segregation
affected such varied societal trends are “too amorphous a basis for
imposing a racially classified remedy,” Wygant , 476 U. S.,
at 276 (plurality opinion), because “[i]t is sheer speculation” how
decades-past segregation in the school system might have affected
these trends, see Croson , 488 U. S., at 499. Consequently,
school boards seeking to remedy those societal problems with
race-based measures in schools today would have no way to gauge the
proper scope of the remedy. Id., at 498. Indeed, remedial
measures geared toward such broad and unrelated societal ills have
“ ‘no logical stopping point,’ ” ibid. , and
threaten to become “ageless in their reach into the past, and
timeless in their ability to affect the future,” Wygant , supra , at 276 (plurality opinion). See Grutter ,
539 U. S., at 342 (stating the “requirement that all governmental
use of race must have a logical end point”).
Because the school boards lack any further
interest in remedying segregation, this element offers no support
for the purported interest in “integration.”
2
Next, the dissent argues that the
interest in integration has an educational element. The dissent
asserts that racially balanced schools improve educational outcomes
for black children. In support, the dissent unquestioningly cites
certain social science research to support propositions that are
hotly disputed among social scientists. In reality, it is far from
apparent that coerced racial mixing has any educational benefits,
much less that integration is necessary to black achievement.
Scholars have differing opinions
as to whether educational benefits arise from racial balancing.
Some have concluded that black students receive genuine educational
benefits. See, e.g. , Crain & Mahard, Desegregation and
Black Achievement: A Review of the Research, 42 L. & Contemp.
Probs. 17, 48 (1978). Others have been more circumspect. See, e.g. , Henderson, Greenberg, Schneider, Uribe, &
Verdugo, High Quality Schooling for African American Students, in
Beyond Desegregation 166 (M. Shujaa ed. 1996) (“Perhaps
desegregation does not have a single effect, positive or negative,
on the academic achievement of African American students, but
rather some strategies help, some hurt, and still others make no
difference whatsoever. It is clear to us that focusing simply on
demographic issues detracts from focusing on improving schools”).
And some have concluded that there are no demonstrable educational
benefits. See, e.g. , Armor & Rossell, Desegregation
and Resegregation in the Public Schools, in Beyond the Color Line:
New Perspectives on Race and Ethnicity in America 239, 251 (A.
Thernstrom & S. Thernstrom eds. 2002).
The amicus briefs in the cases before
us mirror this divergence of opinion. Supporting the school boards,
one amicus has assured us that “both early desegregation
research and recent statistical and econometric analyses … indicate
that there are positive effects on minority student achievement
scores arising from diverse school settings.” Brief for American
Educational Research Association as Amicus Curiae 10.
Another brief claims that “school desegregation has a modest
positive impact on the achievement of African-American students.”
App. to Brief for 553 Social Scientists as Amici Curiae 13–14 (footnote omitted). Yet neither of those briefs contains
specific details like the magnitude of the claimed positive effects
or the precise demographic mix at which those positive effects
begin to be realized. Indeed, the social scientists’ brief rather
cautiously claims the existence of any benefit at all, describing
the “positive impact” as “modest,” id., at 13,
acknowledging that “there appears to be little or no effect on math
scores,” id., at 14, and admitting that the “underlying
reasons for these gains in achievement are not entirely clear,” id., at 15.[ Footnote
11 ]
Other amici dispute these findings.
One amicus reports that “[i]n study after study, racial
composition of a student body, when isolated, proves to be an
insignificant determinant of student achievement.” Brief for Dr.
John Murphy et al. as Amici Curiae in No. 05–908,
p. 8; see also id. , at 9 (“[T]here is no evidence
that diversity in the K–12 classroom positively affects student
achievement”). Another amicus surveys several social
science studies and concludes that “a fair and comprehensive
analysis of the research shows that there is no clear and
consistent evidence of [educational] benefits.” Brief for David J.
Armor et al. as Amici Curiae 29.
Add to the inconclusive social science the
fact of black achievement in “racially isolated” environments. See
T. Sowell, Education: Assumptions Versus History 7–38 (1986).
Before Brown , the most prominent example of an exemplary
black school was Dunbar High School. Id., at 29 (“[I]n the
period 1918–1923, Dunbar graduates earned fifteen degrees from Ivy
League colleges, and ten degrees from Amherst, Williams, and
Wesleyan”). Dunbar is by no means an isolated example. See id., at 10–32 (discussing other successful black schools);
Walker, Can Institutions Care? Evidence from the Segregated
Schooling of African American Children, in Beyond Desegregation
209–226 (M. Shujaa ed. 1996); see also T. Sowell, Affirmative
Action Around the World: An Empirical Study 141–165 (2004). Even
after Brown , some schools with predominantly black
enrollments have achieved outstanding educational results. See, e.g. , S. Carter, No Excuses: Lessons from 21
High-Performing, High-Poverty Schools 49–50, 53–56, 71–73, 81–84,
87–88 (2001); A. Thernstrom & S. Thernstrom, No Excuses:
Closing the Racial Gap in Learning 43–64 (2003); see also L. Izumi,
They Have Overcome: High-Poverty, High-Performing Schools in
California (2002) (chronicling exemplary achievement in
predominantly Hispanic schools in California). There is also
evidence that black students attending historically black colleges
achieve better academic results than those attending predominantly
white colleges. Grutter , supra , at 364–365
(Thomas, J., concurring in part and concurring in judgment) (citing
sources); see also Fordice , 505 U. S., at 748–749 (Thomas,
J., concurring).
The Seattle school board itself must believe
that racial mixing is not necessary to black achievement. Seattle
operates a K–8 “African-American Academy,” which has a “nonwhite”
enrollment of 99%. See App. in No. 05–908, p. 227a; Reply
Brief in No. 05–908, p. 13, n. 13. That school was
founded in 1990 as part of the school board’s effort to “increase
academic achievement.”[ Footnote
12 ] See African American Academy History, online at http://www.
seattleschools.org/schools/aaa/history.htm (all Internet materials
as visited June 26, 2007, and available in Clerk of Court’s case
file). According to the school’s most recent annual report,
“[a]cademic excellence” is its “primary goal.” See African American
Academy 2006 Annual Report, p. 2, online at
http://www.seattleschools.org/area/
siso/reports/anrep/altern/938.pdf. This racially imbalanced
environment has reportedly produced test scores “higher across all
grade levels in reading, writing and math.” Ibid. Contrary
to what the dissent would have predicted, see post , at
38–39, the children in Seattle’s African American Academy have
shown gains when placed in a “highly segregated” environment.
Given this tenuous relationship between forced
racial mixing and improved educational results for black children,
the dissent cannot plausibly maintain that an educational element
supports the integration interest, let alone makes it
compelling.[ Footnote 13 ] See Jenkins , 515 U. S., at 121–122 (Thomas, J., concurring)
(“[T]here is no reason to think that black students cannot learn as
well when surrounded by members of their own race as when they are
in an integrated environment”).
Perhaps recognizing as much, the dissent
argues that the social science evidence is “strong enough to permit
a democratically elected school board reasonably to determine that
this interest is a compelling one.” Post , at 38. This
assertion is inexplicable. It is not up to the school boards—the
very government entities whose race-based practices we must
strictly scrutinize—to determine what interests qualify as
compelling under the Fourteenth Amendment to the United States
Constitution. Rather, this Court must assess independently the
nature of the interest asserted and the evidence to support it in
order to determine whether it qualifies as compelling under our
precedents. In making such a determination, we have deferred to
state authorities only once, see Grutter , 539 U. S., at
328–330, and that deference was prompted by factors uniquely
relevant to higher education. Id., at 328 (“Our holding
today is in keeping with our tradition of giving a degree of
deference to a university’s academic decisions”). The dissent’s
proposed test—whether sufficient social science evidence supports a
government unit’s conclusion that the interest it asserts is
compelling—calls to mind the rational-basis standard of review the
dissent purports not to apply, post , at 36-37. See Williamson v. Lee Optical of Okla., Inc. , 348 U. S. 483 ,
488 (1955) (“It is enough that there is an evil at hand for
correction, and that it might be thought that the particular
legislative measure was a rational way to correct it”).
Furthermore, it would leave our equal-protection jurisprudence at
the mercy of elected government officials evaluating the evanescent
views of a handful of social scientists. To adopt the dissent’s
deferential approach would be to abdicate our constitutional
responsibilities.[ Footnote
14 ]
3
Finally, the dissent asserts a
“democratic element” to the integration interest. It defines the
“democratic element” as “an interest in producing an educational
environment that reflects the ‘pluralistic society’ in which our
children will live.” Post , at 39.[ Footnote 15 ] Environmental reflection, though,
is just another way to say racial balancing. And “[p]referring
members of any one group for no reason other than race or ethnic
origin is discrimination for its own sake.” Bakke , 438 U.
S., at 307 (opinion of Powell, J.). “This the Constitution
forbids.” Ibid.; Grutter , supra, at
329–330; Freeman , 503 U. S., at 494.
Navigating around that
inconvenient authority, the dissent argues that the racial
balancing in these plans is not an end in itself but is instead
intended to “teac[h] children to engage in the kind of cooperation
among Americans of all races that is necessary to make a land of
three hundred million people one Nation.” Post , at 39–40.
These “generic lessons in socialization and good citizenship” are
too sweeping to qualify as compelling interests. Grutter ,
539 U. S., at 348 (Scalia, J., concurring in part and dissenting in
part). And they are not “uniquely relevant” to schools or “uniquely
‘teachable’ in a formal educational setting.” Id., at 347.
Therefore, if governments may constitutionally use racial balancing
to achieve these aspirational ends in schools, they may use racial
balancing to achieve similar goals at every level—from
state-sponsored 4–H clubs, see Bazemore v. Friday , 478
U. S. 385 , 388–390 (1986) (Brennan, J., concurring), to the
state civil service. See Grutter , 539 U. S. 347 –348
(opinion of Scalia, J.).
Moreover, the democratic interest has no
durational limit, contrary to Grutter ’s command. See id., at 342; see also Croson , 488 U. S., at 498; Wygant , 476 U. S., at 275 (plurality opinion). In other
words, it will always be important for students to learn
cooperation among the races. If this interest justifies
race-conscious measures today, then logically it will justify
race-conscious measures forever. Thus, the democratic interest,
limitless in scope and “timeless in [its] ability to affect the
future,” id., at 276 (plurality opinion), cannot justify
government race-based decisionmaking.[ Footnote 16 ]
In addition to these defects, the democratic
element of the integration interest fails on the dissent’s own
terms. The dissent again relies upon social science research to
support the proposition that state-compelled racial mixing teaches
children to accept cooperation and improves racial attitudes and
race relations. Here again, though, the dissent overstates the data
that supposedly support the interest.
The dissent points to data that indicate that
“black and white students in desegregated schools are less racially
prejudiced than those in segregated schools.” Post , at 40
(internal quotation marks omitted). By the dissent’s account,
improvements in racial attitudes depend upon the increased contact
between black and white students thought to occur in more racially
balanced schools. There is no guarantee, however, that students of
different races in the same school will actually spend time with
one another. Schools frequently group students by academic ability
as an aid to efficient instruction, but such groupings often result
in classrooms with high concentrations of one race or another. See, e.g. , Yonezawa, Wells, & Serna, Choosing Tracks:
“Freedom of Choice” in Detracting Schools, 39 Am. Ed. Research J.,
No. 1, p. 38 (Spring 2002); Mickelson, Subverting Swann:
First- and Second-Generation Segregation in the
Charlotte-Mecklenburg Schools, 38 Am. Ed. Research J., No. 2, pp.
233–234 (Summer 2001) (describing this effect in schools in
Charlotte, North Carolina). In addition to classroom separation,
students of different races within the same school may separate
themselves socially. See Hallinan & Williams, Interracial
Friendship Choices in Secondary Schools, 54 Am. Sociological Rev.,
No. 1, pp. 72–76 (Feb. 1989); see also Clotfelter, Interracial
Contact in High School Extracurricular Activities, 34 Urban Rev.,
No. 1, pp. 41–43 (Mar. 2002). Therefore, even supposing interracial
contact leads directly to improvements in racial attitudes and race
relations, a program that assigns students of different races to
the same schools might not capture those benefits. Simply putting
students together under the same roof does not necessarily mean
that the students will learn together or even interact.
Furthermore, it is unclear whether increased
interracial contact improves racial attitudes and
relations.[ Footnote 17 ] One
researcher has stated that “the reviews of desegregation and
intergroup relations were unable to come to any conclusion about
what the probable effects of desegregation were … [;] virtually all
of the reviewers determined that few, if any, firm conclusions
about the impact of desegregation on intergroup relations could be
drawn.” Schofield, School Desegregation and Intergroup Relations: A
Review of the Literature, in 17 Review of Research in Education 356
(G. Grant ed. 1991). Some studies have even found that a
deterioration in racial attitudes seems to result from racial
mixing in schools. See N. St. John, School Desegregation Outcomes
for Children 67–68 (1975) (“A glance at [the data] shows that for
either race positive findings are less common than negative
findings”); Stephan, The Effects of School Desegregation: An
Evaluation 30 Years After Brown, in Advances in Applied Social
Psychology 183–186 (M. Saks & L. Saxe eds. 1986). Therefore, it
is not nearly as apparent as the dissent suggests that increased
interracial exposure automatically leads to improved racial
attitudes or race relations.
Given our case law and the paucity of evidence
supporting the dissent’s belief that these plans improve race
relations, no democratic element can support the integration
interest.[ Footnote 18 ]
4
The dissent attempts to buttress
the integration interest by claiming that it follows a
fortiori from the interest this Court recognized as compelling
in Grutter . Post , at 41. Regardless of the merit
of Grutter , the compelling interest recognized in that
case cannot support these plans. Grutter recognized a
compelling interest in a law school’s attainment of a diverse
student body. 539 U. S., at 328. This interest was critically
dependent upon features unique to higher education: “the expansive
freedoms of speech and thought associated with the university
environment,” the “special niche in our constitutional tradition”
occupied by universities, and “[t]he freedom of a university to
make its own judgments as to education[,] includ[ing] the selection
of its student body.” Id., at 329 (internal quotation
marks omitted). None of these features is present in elementary and
secondary schools. Those schools do not select their own students,
and education in the elementary and secondary environment generally
does not involve the free interchange of ideas thought to be an
integral part of higher education. See 426 F. 3d, at 1208
(Bea, J., dissenting). Extending Grutter to this context
would require us to cut that holding loose from its theoretical
moorings. Thus, only by ignoring Grutter ’s reasoning can
the dissent claim that recognizing a compelling interest in these
cases is an a fortiori application of Grutter .
C
Stripped of the baseless and
novel interests the dissent asserts on their behalf, the school
boards cannot plausibly maintain that their plans further a
compelling interest. As I explained in Grutter , only
“those measures the State must take to provide a bulwark against
anarchy … or to prevent violence” and “a government’s effort to
remedy past discrimination for which it is responsible” constitute
compelling interests. 539 U. S., at 351–352, 353. Neither of the
parties has argued—nor could they—that race-based student
assignment is necessary to provide a bulwark against anarchy or to
prevent violence. And as I explained above, the school districts
have no remedial interest in pursuing these programs. See Part I–B, supra . Accordingly, the school boards cannot satisfy
strict scrutiny. These plans are unconstitutional.
III
Most of the dissent’s criticisms
of today’s result can be traced to its rejection of the color-blind
Constitution. See post , at 29. The dissent attempts to
marginalize the notion of a color-blind Constitution by consigning
it to me and Members of today’s plurality.[ Footnote 19 ] See ibid.; see also post, at 61. But I am quite comfortable in the company I
keep. My view of the Constitution is Justice Harlan’s view in Plessy: “Our Constitution is color-blind, and neither
knows nor tolerates classes among citizens.” Plessy v. Ferguson , 163 U. S. 537 , 559 (1896) (dissenting
opinion). And my view was the rallying cry for the lawyers who
litigated Brown . See, e.g. , Brief for Appellants
in Brown v. Board of Education , O. T. 1953,
Nos. 1, 2, and 4 p. 65 (“That the Constitution is color blind
is our dedicated belief”); Brief for Appellants in Brown v. Board of Education , O. T. 1952, No. 1, p. 5
(“The Fourteenth Amendment precludes a state from imposing
distinctions or classifications based upon race and color
alone”);[ Footnote 20 ] see
also In Memoriam: Honorable Thurgood Marshall, Proceedings of the
Bar and Officers of the Supreme Court of the United States, X
(1993) (remarks of Judge Motley) (“Marshall had a ‘Bible’ to which
he turned during his most depressed moments. The ‘Bible’ would be
known in the legal community as the first Mr. Justice Harlan’s
dissent in Plessy v. Ferguson , 163 U. S. 537 , 552 (1896). I do not
know of any opinion which buoyed Marshall more in his
pre- Brown days …”).
The dissent appears to pin its
interpretation of the Equal Protection Clause to current societal
practice and expectations, deference to local officials, likely
practical consequences, and reliance on previous statements from
this and other courts. Such a view was ascendant in this Court’s
jurisprudence for several decades. It first appeared in Plessy, where the Court asked whether a state law
providing for segregated railway cars was “a reasonable
regulation.” 163 U. S., at 550. The Court deferred to local
authorities in making its determination, noting that in inquiring
into reasonableness “there must necessarily be a large discretion
on the part of the legislature.” Ibid. The Court likewise
paid heed to societal practices, local expectations, and practical
consequences by looking to “the established usages, customs and
traditions of the people, and with a view to the promotion of their
comfort, and the preservation of the public peace and good order.” Ibid. Guided by these principles, the Court concluded:
“[W]e cannot say that a law which authorizes or even requires the
separation of the two races in public conveyances is unreasonable,
or more obnoxious to the Fourteenth Amendment than the acts of
Congress requiring separate schools for colored children in the
District of Columbia.” Id., at 550–551.
The segregationists in Brown embraced
the arguments the Court endorsed in Plessy . Though Brown decisively rejected those arguments, today’s dissent
replicates them to a distressing extent. Thus, the dissent argues
that “[e]ach plan embodies the results of local experience and
community consultation.” Post , at 47. Similarly, the
segregationists made repeated appeals to societal practice and
expectation. See, e.g. , Brief for Appellees on Reargument
in Briggs v. Elliott , O. T. 1953, No. 2, p.
76 (“[A] State has power to establish a school system which is
capable of efficient administration, taking into account local
problems and conditions”).[ Footnote 21 ] The dissent argues that “weight [must be
given] to a local school board’s knowledge, expertise, and
concerns,” post , at 48, and with equal vigor, the
segregationists argued for deference to local authorities. See, e.g. , Brief for Kansas on Reargument in Brown v. Board of Education , O. T. 1953, No. 1, p. 14
(“We advocate only a concept of constitutional law that permits
determinations of state and local policy to be made on state and
local levels. We defend only the validity of the statute that
enables the Topeka Board of Education to determine its own
course”).[ Footnote 22 ] The
dissent argues that today’s decision “threatens to substitute for
present calm a disruptive round of race-related litigation,” post , at 2, and claims that today’s decision “risks
serious harm to the law and for the Nation,” post, at 65.
The segregationists also relied upon the likely practical
consequences of ending the state-imposed system of racial
separation. See, e.g. , Brief for Appellees on Reargument
in Davis v. County School Board , O. T. 1953,
No. 3, p. 37 (“Yet a holding that school segregation by race
violates the Constitution will result in upheaval in all of those
places not now subject to Federal judicial scrutiny. This Court has
made many decisions of widespread effect; none would affect more
people more directly in more fundamental interests and, in fact,
cause more chaos in local government than a reversal of the
decision in this case”).[ Footnote 23 ] And foreshadowing today’s dissent, the
segregationists most heavily relied upon judicial precedent. See, e.g. , Brief for Appellees on Reargument in Briggs v. Elliott , O. T. 1953, No. 2, p. 59 (“[I]t would be
difficult indeed to find a case so favored by precedent as is the
case for South Carolina here”).[ Footnote 24 ]
The similarities between the dissent’s
arguments and the segregationists’ arguments do not stop there.
Like the dissent, the segregationists repeatedly cautioned the
Court to consider practicalities and not to embrace too theoretical
a view of the Fourteenth Amendment.[ Footnote 25 ] And just as the dissent argues that the need
for these programs will lessen over time, the segregationists
claimed that reliance on segregation was lessening and might
eventually end.[ Footnote
26 ]
What was wrong in 1954 cannot be right
today.[ Footnote 27 ] Whatever
else the Court’s rejection of the segregationists’ arguments in Brown might have established, it certainly made clear that
state and local governments cannot take from the Constitution a
right to make decisions on the basis of race by adverse possession.
The fact that state and local governments had been discriminating
on the basis of race for a long time was irrelevant to the Brown Court. The fact that racial discrimination was
preferable to the relevant communities was irrelevant to the Brown Court. And the fact that the state and local
governments had relied on statements in this Court’s opinions was
irrelevant to the Brown Court. The same principles guide
today’s decision. None of the considerations trumpeted by the
dissent is relevant to the constitutionality of the school boards’
race-based plans because no contextual detail—or collection of
contextual details, post , at 2–22—can “provide refuge from
the principle that under our Constitution, the government may not
make distinctions on the basis of race.” Adarand , 515 U.
S., at 240 (Thomas, J., concurring in part and concurring in
judgment).[ Footnote 28 ]
In place of the color-blind Constitution, the
dissent would permit measures to keep the races together and
proscribe measures to keep the races apart.[ Footnote 29 ] See post , at 28–34,
64–65. Although no such distinction is apparent in the Fourteenth
Amendment, the dissent would constitutionalize today’s faddish
social theories that embrace that distinction. The Constitution is
not that malleable. Even if current social theories favor classroom
racial engineering as necessary to “solve the problems at hand,” post , at 21, the Constitution enshrines principles
independent of social theories. See Plessy , 163 U. S., at
559 (Harlan, J., dissenting) (“The white race deems itself to be
the dominant race in this country. And so it is, in prestige, in
achievements, in education, in wealth and in power. So, I doubt
not, it will continue to be for all time … . But in view of
the Constitution, in the eye of the law, there is in this country
no superior, dominant, ruling class of citizens. … Our Constitution
is color-blind, and neither knows nor tolerates classes among
citizens”). Indeed, if our history has taught us anything, it has
taught us to beware of elites bearing racial theories.[ Footnote 30 ] See, e.g. , Dred Scott v. Sandford , 19 How. 393, 407 (1857)
(“[T]hey [members of the “negro African race”] had no rights which
the white man was bound to respect”). Can we really be sure that
the racial theories that motivated Dred Scott and Plessy are a relic of the past or that future theories
will be nothing but beneficent and progressive? That is a gamble I
am unwilling to take, and it is one the Constitution does not
allow.
* * *
The plans before us base school
assignment decisions on students’ race. Because “[o]ur Constitution
is color-blind, and neither knows nor tolerates classes among
citizens,” such race-based decisionmaking is unconstitutional. Plessy , supra, at 559 (Harlan, J., dissenting). I
concur in the Chief Justice’s opinion so holding. Footnote 1 In this Court’s paradigmatic segregation
cases, there was a local ordinance, state statute, or state
constitutional provision requiring racial separation. See, e.g. , Brief for Petitioners in Bolling v. Sharpe , O. T. 1952, No. 4, pp. 28–30 (cataloging
state laws requiring separa- tion of the races); id., at
App. A (listing “Statutory and Consti- tutional Provisions in the
States Where Segregation in Education is Institutionalized”). Footnote 2 The dissent refers repeatedly and reverently
to “ ‘integration.’ ” However, outside of the context of
remediation for past de jure segregation, “integration” is
simply racial balancing. See post , at 37. Therefore, the
school districts’ attempts to further “integrate” are properly
thought of as little more than attempts to achieve a particular
racial balance. Footnote 3 The dissent’s assertion that these plans are
necessary for the school districts to maintain their “hard-won
gains” reveals its conflation of segregation and racial imbalance. Post , at 38. For the dissent’s purposes, the relevant
hard-won gains are the present racial compositions in the
individual schools in Seattle and Louisville. However, the actual
hard-won gain in these cases is the elimination of the vestiges of
the system of state-enforced racial separation that once existed in
Louisville. To equate the achievement of a certain statistical mix
in several schools with the elimination of the system of systematic de jure segregation trivializes the latter accomplishment.
Nothing but an interest in classroom aesthetics and a
hypersensitivity to elite sensibilities justifies the school
districts’ racial balancing programs. See Part II–B, infra . But “the principle of inherent equality that
underlies and infuses our Constitution” required the
disestablishment of de jure segregation. See Adarand
Constructors, Inc. v. Peńa , 515 U. S. 200 , 240 (1995) (Thomas, J.,
concurring in part and concurring in judgment). Assessed in any
objective manner, there is no comparison between the two. Footnote 4 The dissent makes much of the supposed
difficulty of determining whether prior segregation was de
jure or de facto . See, e.g. , post ,
at 19–20. That determination typically will not be nearly as
difficult as the dissent makes it seem. In most cases, there either
will or will not have been a state constitutional amendment, state
statute, local ordinance, or local administrative policy explicitly
requiring separation of the races. See, e.g. , n. 1, supra . And even if the determination is difficult, it is
one the dissent acknowledges must be made to determine what
remedies school districts are required to adopt. Post , at
43. Footnote 5 This Court’s opinion in McDaniel v. Barresi , 402
U. S. 39 (1971), fits comfortably within this framework. There,
a Georgia school board voluntarily adopted a desegregation plan. At
the time of Brown , v. Board of Education, 347 U. S. 483 (1954), Georgia’s
Constitution required that “[s]eparate schools shall be provided
for the white and colored races.” Ga. Const., Art. VII, §1,
ch. 2–6401 (1948). Given that state law had previously required the
school board to maintain a dual school system, the county was
obligated to take measures to remedy its prior de jure segregation. This Court recognized as much in its opinion, which
stated that the school board had an “affirmative duty to
disestablish the dual school system.” McDaniel , supra , at 41. Footnote 6 As I have explained elsewhere, the remedies
this Court authorized lower courts to compel in early desegregation
cases like Green and Swann were exceptional. See Missouri v. Jenkins , 515 U. S. 70 , 124–125 (1995), (Thomas,
J., concurring). Sustained resistance to Brown prompted
the Court to authorize extraordinary race-conscious remedial
measures (like compelled racial mixing) to turn the Constitution’s
dictate to desegregate into reality. 515 U. S., at 125 (Thomas, J.,
concurring). Even if these measures were appropriate as remedies in
the face of widespread resistance to Brown ’s mandate, they
are not forever insulated from constitutional scrutiny. Rather,
“such powers should have been temporary and used only to overcome
the widespread resistance to the dictates of the Constitution.” 515
U. S., at 125 (Thomas, J., concurring). Footnote 7 Though the dissent cites every manner of
complaint, record material, and scholarly article relating to
Seattle’s race-based student assignment efforts, post , at
73–75, it cites no law or official policy that required separation
of the races in Seattle’s schools. Nevertheless, the dissent tries
to cast doubt on the historical fact that the Seattle schools were
never segregated by law by citing allegations that the National
Association for the Advancement of Colored People and other
organizations made in court filings to the effect that Seattle’s
schools were once segregated by law. See post , at 7–9, 23.
These allegations were never proved and were not even made in this
case. Indeed, the record before us suggests the contrary. See App.
in No. 05–908, pp. 214a, 225a, 257a. Past allegations in
another case provide no basis for resolving these cases. Footnote 8 Contrary to the dissent’s argument, post , at 44, the Louisville school district’s interest in
remedying its past de jure segregation did vanish the day
the District Court found that Louisville had eliminated the
vestiges of its historic de jure segregation. See Hampton v. Jefferson Cty. Bd. of Ed., 102
F. Supp. 2d 358, at 360 (WD Ky. 2000). If there were further
remediation to be done, the District Court could not logically have
reached the conclusion that Louisville “ha[d] eliminated the
vestiges associated with the former policy of segregation and its
pernicious effects.” Ibid. Because Louisville could use
race-based measures only as a remedy for past de jure segregation, it is not “incoherent,” post , at 56, to say
that race-based decisionmaking was allowed to Louisville one
day—while it was still remedying—and forbidden to it the next—when
remediation was finished. That seemingly odd turnaround is merely a
result of the fact that the remediation of de jure segregation is a jealously guarded exception to the Equal
Protection Clause’s general rule against government race-based
decisionmaking. Footnote 9 The dissent’s appeal to stare
decisis , post , at 65, is particularly ironic in light
of its apparent willingness to depart from these precedents, post , at 36–37. Footnote 10 The idea that government racial
classifications must be subjected to strict scrutiny did not
originate in Adarand . As early as Loving v. Virginia , 388
U. S. 1 (1967), this Court made clear that government action
that “rest[s] solely upon distinctions drawn according to race” had
to be “subjected to the ‘most rigid scrutiny.’ ” Id., at 11 (quoting Korematsu v. United States , 323 U. S. 214 ,
216 (1944)); see also McLaughlin v. Florida , 379 U. S. 184 ,
196 (1964) (requiring a statute drawing a racial classification to
be “necessary, and not merely rationally related, to accomplishment
of a permissible state policy”); id., at 197 (Harlan, J.,
concurring) (“The necessity test … should be equally applicable in
a case involving state racial discrimination”). Footnote 11 At least one of the academic articles the
dissent cites to support this proposition fails to establish a
causal connection between the supposed educational gains realized
by black students and racial mixing. See Hallinan, Diversity
Effects on Student Outcomes: Social Science Evidence, 59 Ohio St.
L. J. 733 (1998). In the pages following the ones the dissent
cites, the author of that article remarks that “the main reason
white and minority students perform better academically in majority
white schools is likely that these schools provide greater
opportunities to learn. In other words, it is not desegregation per
se that improves achievement, but rather the learning advantages
some desegregated schools provide.” Id., at 744. Evidence
that race is a good proxy for other factors that might be
correlated with educational benefits does not support a compelling
interest in the use of race to achieve academic results. Footnote 12 Of course, if the Seattle school board were
truly committed to the notion that diversity leads directly to
educational benefits, operating a school with such a high
“nonwhite” enrollment would be a shocking dereliction of its duty
to educate the students enrolled in that school. Footnote 13 In fact, the available data from the Seattle
school district appear to undercut the dissent’s view. A comparison
of the test results of the schools in the last year the racial
balancing program operated to the results in the 2004-to-2005
school year (in which student assignments were race-neutral) does
not indicate the decline in black achieve- ment one would expect to
find if black achievement were contin- gent upon a particular
racial mix. See Washington State Report Card, online at
http://reportcard.ospi.k12.wa.us/summary.aspx?schoolId=
1099&OrgType=4&reportLevel=School;
http://reportcard.ospi.k12.wa.us/
summary.aspx?schoolId=1104&reportLevel=School&orgLinkId=1104&yrs=;
http: // reportcard . ospi . k12 . wa . us / summary . aspx ? schoolId = 1061 & report
Level = School & orgLinkId = 1061 & yrs = ;
http: // reportcard . ospi.k12 . wa.us/
summary . aspx ? schoolId = 1043 & reportLevel = School & orgLinkId = 1043 &
yrs= (showing that reading scores went up, not down, when Seattle’s
race-based assignment program ended at Sealth High School, Ingraham
High School, and Franklin High School—some of the schools most
affected by the plan). Footnote 14 The dissent accuses me of “feel[ing]
confident that, to end invidious discrimination, one must end all governmental use of race-conscious criteria” and
chastises me for not deferring to democratically elected
majorities. See post , at 62. Regardless of what Justice
Breyer’s goals might be, this Court does not sit to “create a
society that includes all Americans” or to solve the problems of
“troubled inner city schooling.” Ibid. We are not social
engineers. The United States Constitution dictates that local
governments cannot make decisions on the basis of race.
Consequently, regardless of the perceived negative effects of
racial imbalance, I will not defer to legislative majorities where
the Constitution forbids it.
It should escape no one that behind Justice
Breyer’s veil of judicial modesty hides an inflated role for the
Federal Judiciary. The dissent’s approach confers on judges the
power to say what sorts of discrimination are benign and which are
invidious. Having made that determination (based on no objective
measure that I can detect), a judge following the dissent’s
approach will set the level of scrutiny to achieve the desired
result. Only then must the judge defer to a democratic majority. In
my view, to defer to one’s preferred result is not to defer at
all. Footnote 15 The notion that a “democratic” interest
qualifies as a compelling interest (or constitutes a part of a
compelling interest) is proposed for the first time in today’s
dissent and has little basis in the Constitution or our precedent,
which has narrowly restricted the interests that qualify as
compelling. See Grutter v. Bollinger, 539 U. S. 306 , 351–354 (2003) (Thomas,
J., concurring in part and dissenting in part). The Fourteenth
Amendment does not enact the dissent’s newly minted understanding
of liberty. See Lochner v. New York , 198 U. S. 45 , 75 (1905)
(Holmes, J., dissenting) (“The Fourteenth Amendment does not enact
Mr. Herbert Spencer’s Social Statics”). Footnote 16 The dissent does not explain how its
recognition of an interest in teaching racial understanding and
cooperation here is consistent with the Court’s rejection of a
similar interest in Wygant . In Wygant , a school
district justified its race-based teacher-layoff program in part on
the theory that “minority teachers provided ‘role models’ for
minority students and that a racially ‘diverse’ faculty would
improve the education of all students.” Grutter , supra , at 352 (opinion of Thomas, J.) (citing Brief for
Respondents, O. T. 1984, No. 84–1340, pp. 27–28; 476 U. S., at
315 (Stevens, J., dissenting)). The Court rejected the interests
asserted to justify the layoff program as insufficiently
compelling. Wygant, 476 U. S., at 275–276 (plurality
opinion); id., at 295 (White, J., concurring in judgment).
If a school district has an interest in teaching racial
understanding and cooperation, there is no logical reason why that
interest should not extend to the composition of the teaching staff
as well as the composition of the student body. The dissent’s
reliance on this interest is, therefore, inconsistent with Wygant . Footnote 17 Outside the school context, this Court’s
cases reflect the fact that racial mixing does not always lead to
harmony and understanding. In Johnson v. California , 543 U. S. 499 (2005), this Court
considered a California prison policy that separated inmates
racially. Id., at 525–528 (Thomas, J., dissenting). That
policy was necessary because of “numerous incidents of racial
violence.” Id., at 502; id ., at 532–534 (Thomas,
J., dissenting). As a result of this Court’s insistence on strict
scrutiny of that policy, but see id., at 538–547, inmates
in the California prisons were killed. See Beard v. Banks , 548 U. S. ___, ___ (2006) (Thomas, J., concurring
in judgment) (noting that two were killed and hundreds were injured
in race rioting subsequent to this Court’s decision in Johnson ). Footnote 18 After discussing the “democratic element,”
the dissent repeats its assertion that the social science evidence
supporting that interest is “sufficiently strong to permit a school
board to determine … that this interest is compelling.” Post , at 40. Again, though, the school boards have no say
in deciding whether an interest is compelling. Strict scrutiny of
race-based government decisionmaking is more searching than Chevron -style administrative review for reasonableness.
See Chevron U. S. A. Inc. v. Natural Resources
Defense Council, Inc. , 467 U. S. 837 , 845
(1984). Footnote 19 The dissent half-heartedly attacks the
historical underpinnings of the color-blind Constitution. Post , at 28–29. I have no quarrel with the proposition
that the Fourteenth Amendment sought to bring former slaves into
American society as full members. Post, at 28 (citing Slaughter-House Cases , 16 Wall. 36, 71–72 (1873)). What
the dissent fails to understand, however, is that the color-blind
Constitution does not bar the government from taking measures to
remedy past state-sponsored discrimination—indeed, it requires that
such measures be taken in certain circumstances. See, e.g. , Part I–B, supra. Race-based government
measures during the 1860’s and 1870’s to remedy state-enforced
slavery were therefore not inconsistent with the color-blind
Constitution. Footnote 20 See also Juris. Statement in Davis v. County School Board , O. T. 1952, No. 3, p. 8
(“[W]e take the unqualified position that the Fourteenth Amendment
has totally stripped the state of power to make race and color the
basis for governmental action”); Tr. of Oral Arg. in Brown v. Board of Education , O. T. 1952, No. 1, p. 7 (“We
have one fundamental contention which we will seek to develop in
the course of this argument, and that contention is that no State
has any authority under the equal-protection clause of the
Fourteenth Amendment to use race as a factor in affording
educational opportunities among its citizens”); Tr. of Oral Arg. in Briggs v. Elliott , O. T. 1953, No. 2, p. 50
(“[T]he state is deprived of any power to make any racial
classifications in any governmental field”). Footnote 21 See also Brief for Appellees in Davis v. County School Board , O. T. 1952,
No. 3, p. 1 (“[T]he Court is asked … to outlaw the fixed
policies of the several States which are based on local social
conditions well known to the respective legislatures”); id., at 9 (“For this purpose, Virginia history and present
Virginia conditions are important”); Tr. of Oral Arg. in Davis v. County School Board , O. T. 1952,
No. 3, p. 57 (“[T]he historical background that exists, certainly
in this Virginia situation, with all the strife and the history
that we have shown in this record, shows a basis, a real basis, for
the classification that has been made”); id., at 69
(describing the potential abolition of segregation as “contrary to
the customs, the traditions and the mores of what we might claim to
be a great people, established through generations, who themselves
are fiercely and irrevocably dedicated to the preservation of the
white and colored races”). Accord, post , at 68 (“Today,
almost 50 years later, attitudes toward race in this Nation have
changed dramatically. Many parents, white and black alike, want
their children to attend schools with children of different races.
Indeed, the very school districts that once spurned integration now
strive for it. The long history of their efforts reveals the
complexities and difficulties they have faced”); post, at
21 (emphasizing the importance of “local circumstances” and
encouraging different localities to “try different solutions to
common problems and gravitate toward those that prove most
successful or seem to them best to suit their individual needs”
(citations and internal quotation marks omitted)); post, at 48 (emphasizing the school districts’ “40-year history” during
which both school districts have tried numerous approaches “to
achieve more integrated schools”); post , at 63 (“[T]he
histories of Louisville and Seattle reveal complex circumstances
and a long tradition of conscientious efforts by local school
boards”). Footnote 22 See also Brief for Appellees in Brown v. Board of Education , O. T. 1952, No.
1, p. 29 (“ ‘It is universally held, therefore, that each
state shall determine for itself, subject to the observance of the
fundamental rights and liberties guaranteed by the federal
Constitution, how it shall exercise the police power … . And
in no field is this right of the several states more clearly
recognized than in that of public education’ ” (quoting Briggs v. Elliott, 98 F. Supp. 529, 532 (SC
1951))); Brief for Appellees in Briggs v. Elliott , O. T. 1952, No. 2, p. 7 (“Local
self-government in local affairs is essential to the peace and
happiness of each locality and to the strength and stability of our
whole federal system. Nowhere is this more profoundly true than in
the field of education”); Tr. of Oral Arg. in Briggs v. Elliott , O. T. 1952, No. 2, pp. 54–55 (“What is
the great national and federal policy on this matter? Is it not a
fact that the very strength and fiber of our federal system is
local self-government in those matters for which local action is
competent? Is it not of all the activities of government the one
which most nearly approaches the hearts and minds of people, the
question of the education of their young? Is it not the height of
wisdom that the manner in which that shall be conducted should be
left to those most immediately affected by it, and that the wishes
of the parents, both white and colored, should be ascertained
before their children are forced into what may be an unwelcome
contact?”). Accord, post , at 48 (“[L]ocal school boards
better understand their own communities and have a better knowledge
of what in practice will best meet the educational needs of their
pupils”); post , at 66 (“[W]hat of respect for democratic
local decisionmaking by States and school boards?”); ibid. (explaining “that the Constitution grants local school districts a
significant degree of leeway”). Footnote 23 See also Reply Brief for Appellees in Davis v. County School Board , O. T. 1953,
No. 3, p. 17 (“The Court is … dealing with thousands of local
school districts and schools. Is each to be the subject of
litigation in the District Courts?”); Brief for Kansas on
Reargument in Brown v. Board of Education ,
O. T. 1953, No. 1, p. 51 (“The delicate nature of the problem
of segregation and the paramount interest of the State of Kansas in
preserving the internal peace and tranquility of its people
indicates that this is a question which can best be solved on the
local level, at least until Congress declares otherwise”). Accord, post , at 61 (“At a minimum, the plurality’s views would
threaten a surge of race-based litigation. Hundreds of state and
federal statutes and regulations use racial classifications for
educational or other purposes… . In many such instances, the
contentious force of legal challenges to these classifications,
meritorious or not, would displace earlier calm”); post, at 65 (“Indeed, the consequences of the approach the Court takes
today are serious. Yesterday, the plans under review were lawful.
Today, they are not”); post, at 66 (predicting “further
litigation, aggravating race-related conflict”). Footnote 24 See also Statement of Appellees Opposing
Jurisdiction and Motion to Dismiss or Affirm in Davis v. County School Board , O. T. 1952, No. 3, p. 5
(“[I]t would be difficult to find from any field of law a legal
principle more repeatedly and conclusively decided than the one
sought to be raised by appellants”); Brief for Appellees in Davis v. County School Board , O. T. 1953,
No. 3, p. 46–47 (“If this case were to be decided solely on
the basis of precedent, this brief could have been much more
limited. There is ample precedent in the decisions of this Court to
uphold school segregation”); Brief for Petitioners in Gebhart v. Belton , O. T. 1952, No. 5,
p. 27 (“Respondents ask this Court to upset a long established
and well settled principle recognized by numerous state
Legislatures, and Courts, both state and federal, over a long
period of years”); Tr. of Oral Arg. in Briggs v. Elliott , O. T. 1953, No. 2, p. 79 (“But be that
doctrine what it may, somewhere, sometime to every principle comes
a moment of repose when it has been so often announced, so
confidently relied upon, so long continued, that it passes the
limits of judicial discretion and disturbance… . We relied on
the fact that this Court had not once but seven times, I think it
is, pronounced in favor of the separate but equal doctrine. We
relied on the fact that the courts of last appeal of some sixteen
or eighteen States have passed upon the validity of the separate
but equal doctrine vis-a-vis the Fourteenth Amendment. We relied on
the fact that Congress has continuously since 1862 segregated its
schools in the District of Columbia”); Brief for Appellees in Briggs v. Elliott , O. T. 1952, No. 2, App. D
(collecting citations of state and federal cases “[w]hich
[e]nunciate the [p]rinciple that [s]tate [l]aws [p]roviding for
[r]acial [s]egregation in the [p]ublic [s]chools do not [c]onflict
with the Fourteenth Amendment”). Accord, post , at 22
(“[T]he Court set forth in Swann a basic principle of
constitutional law—a principle of law that has found wide
acceptance in the legal culture” (citations and internal quotation
marks omitted)); post, at 25 (“Lower state and federal
courts had considered the matter settled and uncontroversial even
before this Court decided Swann ”); post , at 26
(“Numerous state and federal courts explicitly relied upon Swann ’s guidance for decades to follow”); post, at 27 (stating “how lower courts understood and followed Swann ’s enunciation of the relevant legal principle”); post , at 30 (“The constitutional principle enunciated in Swann, reiterated in subsequent cases, and relied upon
over many years, provides, and has widely been thought to provide,
authoritative legal guidance”); post , at 61 (“[T]oday’s
opinion will require setting aside the laws of several States and
many local communities”); post , at 66 (“And what has
happened to Swann? To McDaniel? To Crawford? To Harris? To School Committee of
Boston? To Seattle School Dist. No. 1? After decades
of vibrant life, they would all, under the plurality’s logic, be
written out of the law”). Footnote 25 Compare Brief for Appellees in Davis v. County School Board , O. T. 1952, No. 3,
p. 16–17 (“ ‘It is by such practical considerations based
on experience rather than by theoretical inconsistencies that the
question of equal protection is to be answered’ ” (quoting Railway Express Agency, Inc. v. New York, 336 U. S. 110 (1949))); Brief for Appellees on Reargument in Davis v. County School Board , O. T. 1953, No. 3, p. 76 (“The
question is a practical one for them to solve; it is not subject to
solution in the theoretical realm of abstract principles”); Tr. of
Oral Arg. in Davis v. County School Board ,
O. T. 1953, No. 4, p. 86 (“[Y]ou cannot talk about this
problem just in a vacuum in the manner of a law school
discussion”), with post , at 57 (“The Founders meant the
Constitution as a practical document”). Footnote 26 Compare Brief for Kansas on Reargument in Brown v. Board of Education , O. T. 1953, No.
1, p. 57 (“[T]he people of Kansas . . . are abandoning the
policy of segregation whenever local conditions and local attitudes
make it feasible”), Brief for Appellees on Reargument in Davis v. County School Board , O. T. 1953,
No. 3, p. 76 (“As time passes, it may well be that segregation will
end”), with post , at 19 (“[T]hey use race-conscious
criteria in limited and gradually diminishing ways”); post , at 48 (“[E]ach plan’s use of race-conscious elements
is diminished compared to the use of race in preceding
integration plans”); post, at 55 (describing the
“historically-diminishing use of race” in the school
districts). Footnote 27 It is no answer to say that these cases can
be distinguished from Brown because Brown involved invidious racial classifications whereas the racial
classifications here are benign. See post , at 62. How does
one tell when a racial classification is invidious? The
segregationists in Brown argued that their racial
classifications were benign, not invidious. See Tr. of Oral Arg. in Briggs v. Elliott , O. T. 1953, No. 2, p. 83
(“It [South Carolina] is confident of its good faith and intention
to produce equality for all of its children of whatever race or
color. It is convinced that the happiness, the progress and the
welfare of these children is best promoted in segregated schools”);
Brief for Appellees on Reargument in Davis v. County
School Board , O. T. 1953, No. 3, p. 82–83 (“Our many
hours of research and investigation have led only to confirmation
of our view that segregation by race in Virginia’s public schools
at this time not only does not offend the Constitution of the
United States but serves to provide a better education for living
for the children of both races”); Tr. of Oral Arg. in Davis v. County School Board , O. T. 1952,
No. 3, p. 71 (“[T]o make such a transition, would undo what we have
been doing, and which we propose to continue to do for the uplift
and advancement of the education of both races. It would stop this
march of progress, this onward sweep”). It is the height of
arrogance for Members of this Court to assert blindly that their
motives are better than others. Footnote 28 See also id., at 8–9 (“It has been
urged that [these state laws and policies] derive validity as a
consequence of a long duration supported and made possible by a
long line of judicial decisions, including expressions in some of
the decisions of this Court. At the same time, it is urged that
these laws are valid as a matter of constitutionally permissible
social experimentation by the States. On the matter of stare
decisis, I submit that the duration of the challenged practice,
while it is persuasive, is not controlling… . As a matter of
social experimentation, the laws in question must satisfy the
requirements of the Constitution. While this Court has permitted
the States to legislate or otherwise officially act experimentally
in the social and economic fields, it has always recognized and
held that this power is subject to the limitations of the
Constitution, and that the tests of the Constitution must be met”);
Reply Brief for Appellants in Briggs v. Elliott ,
O. T. 1953, No. 2, pp. 18–19 (“The truth of the matter is
that this is an attempt to place local mores and customs above the
high equalitarian principles of our Government as set forth in our
Constitution and particularly the Fourteenth Amendment. This entire
contention is tantamount to saying that the vindication and
enjoyment of constitutional rights recognized by this Court as
present and personal can be postponed whenever such postponement is
claimed to be socially desirable”). Footnote 29 The dissent does not face the complicated
questions attending its proposed standard. For example, where does
the dissent’s principle stop? Can the government force racial
mixing against the will of those being mixed? Can the government
force black families to relocate to white neighborhoods in the name
if bringing the races together? What about historically black
colleges, which have “established traditions and programs that
might disproportionately appeal to one race or another”? United
States v. Fordice , 505 U. S. 717 , 749 (1992) (Thomas, J.,
concurring). The dissent does not and cannot answer these questions
because the contours of the distinction it propounds rest entirely
in the eye of the beholder. Footnote 30 Justice Breyer’s good intentions, which I do
not doubt, have the shelf life of Justice Breyer’s tenure. Unlike
the dissenters, I am unwilling to delegate my constitutional
responsibilities to local school boards and allow them to
experiment with race-based decisionmaking on the assumption that
their intentions will forever remain as good as Justice Breyer’s.
See The Federalist No. 51, p. 349 (J. Cooke ed. 1961) (“If men were
angels, no government would be necessary”). Indeed, the racial
theories endorsed by the Seattle school board should cause the
dissenters to question whether local school boards should be
entrusted with the power to make decisions on the basis of race.
The Seattle school district’s Website formerly contained the
following definition of “cultural racism”: “Those aspects of
society that overtly and covertly attribute value and normality to
white people and whiteness, and devalue, stereotype, and label
people of color as ‘other,’ different, less than, or render them
invisible. Examples of these norms include defining white skin
tones as nude or flesh colored, having a future time orientation,
emphasizing individualism as opposed to a more collective ideology,
defining one form of English as standard . . . .” See Harrell,
School Web Site Removed: Examples of Racism Sparked Controversy,
Seattle Post-Intelligencer, June 2, 2006, p. B1. After the site was
removed, the district offered the comforting clarification that the
site was not intended “ ‘to hold onto unsuccessful concepts
such as melting pot or colorblind mentality.’ ” Ibid.; see also ante , at 22, n. 15
(plurality opinion).
More recently, the school district sent a
delegation of high school students to a “White Privilege
Conference.” See Equity and Race Relations White Privilege
Conference, https://www.seattleschools.
org/area/equityandrace/whiteprivilegeconference.xml. One conference
participant described “white privilege” as “an invisible package of
unearned assets which I can count on cashing in each day, but about
which I was meant to remain oblivious. White Privilege is like an
invisible weightless knapsack of special provisions, maps,
passports, codebooks, visas, clothes, tools, and blank checks.” See
White Privilege Conference, Questions and Answers,
http://www.uccs.edu/~wpc/ faqs.htm; see generally Westneat, School
District’s Obsessed with Race, Seattle Times, Apr. 1, 2007, p. B1
(describing racial issues in Seattle schools). STEVENS, J., DISSENTING PARENTS INVOLVED IN COMMUNITY SCHOOLS V.SEATTLE SCHOOL DIST. NO.
1 551 U. S. ____ (2007) SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES NOS. 05-908 AND 05-915 PARENTS INVOLVED IN COMMUNITY SCHOOLS,
PETITIONER
05–908 v. SEATTLE SCHOOL DISTRICT NO. 1
et al. on writ of certiorari to the united states
court of appeals for the ninth circuit CRYSTAL D. MEREDITH, custodial parent and next
friend of JOSHUA RYAN McDONALD, PETITIONER
05–915 v. JEFFERSON COUNTY BOARD OF EDUCATION
et al. on writ of certiorari to the united states
court of appeals for the sixth circuit [June 28, 2007] Justice Stevens ,
dissenting.
While I join Justice Breyer’s
eloquent and unanswerable dissent in its entirety, it is
appropriate to add these words.
There is a cruel irony in The Chief Justice’s
reliance on our decision in Brown v. Board of
Education, 349
U. S. 294 (1955). The first sentence in the concluding
paragraph of his opinion states: “Before Brown, schoolchildren were told where they could and could not go to
school based on the color of their skin.” Ante, at 40.
This sentence reminds me of Anatole France’s observation: “[T]he
majestic equality of the la[w], forbid[s] rich and poor alike to
sleep under bridges, to beg in the streets, and to steal their
bread.”[ Footnote 1 ] The Chief
Justice fails to note that it was only black schoolchildren who
were so ordered; indeed, the history books do not tell stories of
white children struggling to attend black schools.[ Footnote 2 ] In this and other ways, The
Chief Justice rewrites the history of one of this Court’s most
important decisions. Compare ante, at 39 (“history will be
heard”), with Brewer v. Quarterman, 550 U. S.
___, ___ (2007) (slip op., at 11) (Roberts, C. J., dissenting)
(“It is a familiar adage that history is written by the
victors”).
The Chief Justice rejects the conclusion that
the racial classifications at issue here should be viewed
differently than others, because they do not impose burdens on one
race alone and do not stigmatize or exclude.[ Footnote 3 ] The only justification for refusing
to acknowledge the obvious importance of that difference is the
citation of a few recent opinions—none of which even approached
unanimity—grandly proclaiming that all racial classifications must
be analyzed under “strict scrutiny.” See, e.g., Adarand
Constructors, Inc. v. Peńa, 515 U. S. 200 , 227 (1995). Even today,
two of our wisest federal judges have rejected such a wooden
reading of the Equal Protection Clause in the context of school
integration. See 426 F. 3d 1162, 1193–1196 (CA9 2005) (Kozinski,
J., concurring); Comfort v. Lynn School Comm., 418 F. 3d 1, 27–29 (CA1 2005) (Boudin, C. J.,
concurring). The Court’s misuse of the three-tiered approach to
Equal Protection analysis merely reconfirms my own view that there
is only one such Clause in the Constitution. See Craig v. Boren , 429
U. S. 190 , 211 (1976) (concurring opinion).[ Footnote 4 ]
If we look at cases decided during the interim
between Brown and Adarand, we can see how a rigid
adherence to tiers of scrutiny obscures Brown ’s clear
message. Perhaps the best example is provided by our approval of
the decision of the Supreme Judicial Court of Massachusetts in 1967
upholding a state statute mandating racial integration in that
State’s school system. See School Comm. of Boston v. Board of Education, 352 Mass. 693, 227 N. E. 2d
729.[ Footnote 5 ] Rejecting
arguments comparable to those that the plurality accepts
today,[ Footnote 6 ] that court
noted: “It would be the height of irony if the racial imbalance
act, enacted as it was with the laudable purpose of achieving equal
educational opportunities, should, by prescribing school pupil
allocations based on race, founder on unsuspected shoals in the
Fourteenth Amendment.” Id., at 698, 227 N. E. 2d, at
733 (footnote omitted).
Invoking our mandatory appellate
jurisdiction,[ Footnote 7 ] the
Boston plaintiffs prosecuted an appeal in this Court. Our ruling on
the merits simply stated that the appeal was “dismissed for want of
a substantial federal question.” School Comm. of Boston v. Board of Education , 389 U. S. 572 (1968) (per
curiam). That decision not only expressed our appraisal of the
merits of the appeal, but it constitutes a precedent that the Court
overrules today. The subsequent statements by the unanimous Court
in Swann v. Charlotte-Mecklenburg Bd. of Ed., 402 U. S. 1 , 16
(1971), by then-Justice Rehnquist in chambers in Bustop,
Inc. v. Los Angeles Bd. of Ed., 439 U. S. 1380 , 1383
(1978), and by the host of state court decisions cited by Justice
Breyer, see post , 25–27,[ Footnote 8 ] were fully consistent with that disposition.
Unlike today’s decision, they were also entirely loyal to Brown. The Court has changed significantly since it
decided School Comm. of Boston in 1968. It was then more
faithful to Brown and more respectful of our precedent
than it is today. It is my firm conviction that no Member of the
Court that I joined in 1975 would have agreed with today’s
decision. Footnote 1 Le Lys Rouge (The Red Lily) 95 (W. Stephens
transl. 6th ed. 1922). Footnote 2 See, e.g. , J. Wilkinson, From Brown to Bakke 11 (1979) (“Everyone understands
that Brown v. Board of Education helped deliver
the Negro from over three centuries of legal bondage”); Black, The
Lawfulness of the Segregation Decisions, 69 Yale L. J. 421,
424–425 (“History, too, tells us that segregation was imposed on
one race by the other race; consent was not invited or required.
Segregation in the South grew up and is kept going because and only
because the white race has wanted it that way—an incontrovertible
fact which itself hardly consorts with equality”). Footnote 3 I have long adhered to the view that a
decision to exclude a member of a minority because of his race is
fundamentally different from a decision to include a member of a
minority for that reason. See, e.g. , Adarand
Constructors, Inc. v. Peńa , 515 U. S. 200 , 243, 248, n. 6
(1995) (Stevens, J., dissenting); Wygant v. Jackson
Bd. of Ed. , 476 U. S. 267 , 316 (1986) (same). This
distinction is critically important in the context of education.
While the focus of our opinions is often on the benefits that
minority schoolchildren receive from an integrated education, see, e.g. , ante , at 15 (Thomas, J., concurring),
children of all races benefit from integrated classrooms
and playgrounds, see Wygant , 476 U. S., at 316 (“[T]he
fact that persons of different races do, indeed, have differently
colored skin, may give rise to a belief that there is some
significant difference between such persons. The inclusion of
minority teachers in the educational process inevitably tends to
dispel that illusion whereas their exclusion could only tend to
foster it”). Footnote 4 The Chief Justice twice cites my dissent in Fullilove v. Klutznick , 448 U. S. 448 (1980).
See ante , at 12, 23. In that case, I stressed the
importance of confining a remedy for past wrongdoing to
the members of the injured class. See 448 U. S., at 539. The
present cases, unlike Fullilove but like our decision in Wygant , 476 U. S. 267 , require us to “ask
whether the Board[s’] actions[s] advanc[e] the public interest in
educating children for the future ,” id ., at 313
(Stevens, J., dissenting) (emphasis added). See ibid . (“In
my opinion, it is not necessary to find that the Board of Education
has been guilty of racial discrimination in the past to support the
conclusion that it has a legitimate interest in employing more
black teachers in the future”). See also Adarand, 515 U.
S., at 261–262 (1995) (Stevens, J., dissenting) (“This program,
then, if in part a remedy for past discrimination, is most
importantly a forward-looking response to practical problems faced
by minority subcontractors”). Footnote 5 The Chief Justice states that the
Massachusetts racial imbalance Act did not require express
classifications. See ante , at 31-32, n. 16. This is
incorrect. The Massachusetts Supreme Judicial Court expressly
stated:
“The racial imbalance act requires the school committee of every
municipality annually to submit statistics showing the percentage
of nonwhite pupils in all public schools and in each school.
Whenever the board finds that racial imbalance exists in a public
school, it shall give written notice to the appropriate school
committee, which shall prepare a plan to eliminate imbalance and
file a copy with the board. ‘The term “racial imbalance” refers to
a ratio between nonwhite and other students in public schools which
is sharply out of balance with the racial composition of the
society in which nonwhite children study, serve and work. For the
purpose of this section, racial imbalance shall be deemed to exist
when the per cent of nonwhite students in any public school is in
excess of fifty per cent of the total number of students in such
school.’ ” 352 Mass., at 695, 227 N. E. 2d, at 731. Footnote 6 Compare ante , at 39 (“It was not the
inequality of the facilities but the fact of legally separating
children on the basis of race on which the Court relied to find a
constitutional violation in 1954”), with Juris. Statement in School Comm. of Boston v. Board of Education, O. T. 1967, No. 67–759, p. 11 (“It is implicit in Brown v. Board of Education of Topeka, 347 U. S. 483 ,
that color or race is a constitutionally impermissible standard for
the assignment of school children to public schools. We construe Brown as endorsing Mr. Justice Harlan’s classical
statement in Plessy v. Ferguson , 163 U. S. 537 , 539: ‘Our
constitution is color-blind, and neither knows nor tolerates
classes among citizens’ ”). Footnote 7 In 1968 our mandatory jurisdiction was
defined by the provision of the 1948 Judicial Code then codified at
28 U. S. C. §1257, see 62 Stat. 929; that provision was
repealed in 1988, see 102 Stat. 662. Footnote 8 For example, prior to our decision in School Comm. of Boston, the Illinois Supreme
Court had issued an unpublished opinion holding unconstitutional a
similar statute aimed at eliminating racial imbalance in public
schools. See Juris. Statement in School Comm. of Boston v. Board of Education, O. T. 1967, No. 67–759, at 9
(“Unlike the Massachusetts Court, the Illinois Supreme Court has
recently held its law to eliminate racial imbalance
unconstitutional on the ground that it violated the Equal
Protection Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment”); ibid., n. 1. However, shortly after we dismissed the Massachusetts
suit for want of a substantial federal question, the Illinois
Supreme Court reversed course and upheld its statute in the
published decision that Justice Breyer extensively quotes in his
dissent. See Tometz v. Board of Ed., Waukegan School
Dist. No. 6, 39 Ill. 2d 593, 237 N. E. 2d 498 (1968). In
so doing, the Illinois Supreme Court acted in explicit reliance on
our decision in School Comm. of Boston. See 39 Ill. 2d, at
599–600, 237 N. E. 2d, at 502 (“Too, the United States Supreme
Court on January 15, 1968, dismissed an appeal in School Committee
of Boston v. Board of Education, (Mass. 1967) 227 N. E. 2d
729, which challenged the statute providing for elimination of
racial imbalance in public schools ‘for want of a substantial
federal question.’ 389 U. S. 572 ”). BREYER, J., DISSENTING PARENTS INVOLVED IN COMMUNITY SCHOOLS V.SEATTLE SCHOOL DIST. NO.
1 551 U. S. ____ (2007) SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES NOS. 05-908 AND 05-915 PARENTS INVOLVED IN COMMUNITY SCHOOLS,
PETITIONER
05–908 v. SEATTLE SCHOOL DISTRICT NO. 1
et al. on writ of certiorari to the united states
court of appeals for the ninth circuit CRYSTAL D. MEREDITH, custodial parent and next
friend of JOSHUA RYAN McDONALD, PETITIONER
05–915 v. JEFFERSON COUNTY BOARD OF EDUCATION
et al. on writ of certiorari to the united states
court of appeals for the sixth circuit [June 28, 2007] Justice Breyer , with
whom Justice Stevens, Justice Souter, and Justice Ginsburg join,
dissenting.
These cases consider the
longstanding efforts of two local school boards to integrate their
public schools. The school board plans before us resemble many
others adopted in the last 50 years by primary and secondary
schools throughout the Nation. All of those plans represent local
efforts to bring about the kind of racially integrated education
that Brown v. Board of Education , 347
U. S. 483 (1954), long ago promised—efforts that this Court has
repeatedly required, permitted, and encouraged local authorities to
undertake. This Court has recognized that the public interests at
stake in such cases are “compelling.” We have approved of “narrowly
tailored” plans that are no less race-conscious than the plans
before us. And we have understood that the Constitution permits local communities to adopt desegregation plans
even where it does not require them to do so.
The plurality pays inadequate attention to
this law, to past opinions’ rationales, their language, and the
contexts in which they arise. As a result, it reverses course and
reaches the wrong conclusion. In doing so, it distorts precedent,
it misapplies the relevant constitutional principles, it announces
legal rules that will obstruct efforts by state and local
governments to deal effectively with the growing resegregation of
public schools, it threatens to substitute for present calm a
disruptive round of race-related litigation, and it undermines Brown ’s promise of integrated primary and secondary
education that local communities have sought to make a reality.
This cannot be justified in the name of the Equal Protection
Clause.
I Facts The historical and factual
context in which these cases arise is critical. In Brown , this
Court held that the government’s segregation of schoolchildren by
race violates the Constitution’s promise of equal protection. The
Court emphasized that “education is perhaps the most important
function of state and local governments.” 347 U. S., at 493. And it
thereby set the Nation on a path toward pub-lic school
integration.
In dozens of subsequent cases,
this Court told school districts previously segregated by law what
they must do at a minimum to comply with Brown ’s
constitutional holding. The measures required by those cases often
included race-conscious practices, such as mandatory busing and
race-based restrictions on voluntary transfers. See, e.g. , Columbus Bd. of Ed. v. Penick , 443 U. S. 449 , 455,
n. 3 (1979); Davis v. Board of School Comm’rs of
Mobile Cty. , 402
U. S. 33 , 37–38 (1971); Green v. School Bd. of New
Kent Cty. , 391
U. S. 430 , 441–442 (1968).
Beyond those minimum
requirements, the Court left much of the determination of how to
achieve integration to the judgment of local communities. Thus, in
respect to race-conscious desegregation measures that the
Constitution permitted, but did not require (measures similar to those at issue here), this Court unanimously
stated:
“School authorities are traditionally charged with
broad power to formulate and implement educational policy and might
well conclude, for example, that in order to prepare students to
live in a pluralistic society each school should have a prescribed
ratio of Negro to white students reflecting the proportion for the
district as a whole. To do this as an educational policy is
within the broad discretionary powers of school authorities .” Swann v. Charlotte-Mecklenburg Bd. of Ed. , 402 U. S. 1 , 16
(1971) (emphasis added).
As a result, different
districts—some acting under court decree, some acting in order to
avoid threatened lawsuits, some seeking to comply with federal
administrative orders, some acting purely voluntarily, some acting
after federal courts had dissolved earlier orders—adopted,
modified, and experimented with hosts of different kinds of plans,
including race-conscious plans, all with a similar objective:
greater racial integration of public schools. See F. Welch & A.
Light, New Evidence on School Desegregation v (1987) (hereinafter
Welch) (prepared for the Commission on Civil Rights) (reviewing a
sample of 125 school districts, constituting 20% of national public
school enrollment, that had experimented with nearly 300 different
plans over 18 years). The techniques that different districts have
employed range “from voluntary transfer programs to mandatory
reassignment.” Id. , at 21. And the design of particular
plans has been “dictated by both the law and the specific needs of
the district.” Ibid .
Overall these efforts brought
about considerable racial integration. More recently, however,
progress has stalled. Between 1968 and 1980, the number of black
children attending a school where minority children constituted
more than half of the school fell from 77% to 63% in the Nation
(from 81% to 57% in the South) but then reversed direction by the
year 2000, rising from 63% to 72% in the Nation (from 57% to 69% in
the South). Similarly, between 1968 and 1980, the number of black
children attending schools that were more than 90% minority fell
from 64% to 33% in the Nation (from 78% to 23% in the South), but
that too reversed direction, rising by the year 2000 from 33% to
37% in the Nation (from 23% to 31% in the South). As of 2002,
almost 2.4 million students, or over 5% of all public school
enrollment, attended schools with a white population of less than
1%. Of these, 2.3 million were black and Latino students, and only
72,000 were white. Today, more than one in six black children
attend a school that is 99–100% minority. See Appendix A, infra. In light of the evident risk of a return to school
systems that are in fact (though not in law) resegregated, many
school districts have felt a need to maintain or to extend their
integration efforts.
The upshot is that myriad school districts
operating in myriad circumstances have devised myriad plans, often
with race-conscious elements, all for the sake of eradicating
earlier school segregation, bringing about integration, or
preventing retrogression. Seattle and Louisville are two such
districts, and the histories of their present plans set forth
typical school integration stories.
I describe those histories at length in order
to highlight three important features of these cases. First, the
school districts’ plans serve “compelling interests” and are
“narrowly tailored” on any reasonable definition of those terms.
Second, the distinction between de jure segregation
(caused by school systems) and de facto segregation
(caused, e.g. , by housing patterns or generalized societal
discrimination) is meaningless in the present context, thereby
dooming the plurality’s endeavor to find support for its views in
that distinction. Third, real-world efforts to substitute racially
diverse for racially segregated schools (however caused) are
complex, to the point where the Constitution cannot plausibly be
interpreted to rule out categorically all local efforts to use
means that are “conscious” of the race of individuals.
In both Seattle and Louisville, the local
school districts began with schools that were highly segregated in
fact. In both cities plaintiffs filed lawsuits claiming
unconstitutional segregation. In Louisville, a federal district
court found that school segregation reflected pre- Brown state laws separating the races. In Seattle, the plaintiffs alleged
that school segregation unconstitutionally reflected not only
generalized societal discrimination and residential housing
patterns, but also school board policies and actions that
had helped to create, maintain, and aggravate racial segregation.
In Louisville, a federal court entered a remedial decree. In
Seattle, the parties settled after the school district pledged to
undertake a desegregation plan. In both cities, the school boards
adopted plans designed to achieve integration by bringing about
more racially diverse schools. In each city the school board
modified its plan several times in light of, for example, hostility
to busing, the threat of resegregation, and the desirability of
introducing greater student choice. And in each city, the school
boards’ plans have evolved over time in ways that progressively diminish the plans’ use of explicit race-conscious
criteria.
The histories that follow set forth these
basic facts. They are based upon numerous sources, which for ease
of exposition I have cataloged, along with their corresponding
citations, at Appendix B, infra. A Seattle 1. Segregation, 1945 to
1956. During and just after World War II, significant numbers
of black Americans began to make Seattle their home. Few black
residents lived outside the central section of the city. Most
worked at unskilled jobs. Although black students made up about 3%
of the total Seattle population in the mid-1950’s, nearly all black
children attended schools where a majority of the population was
minority. Elementary schools in central Seattle were between 60%
and 80% black; Garfield, the central district high school, was more
than 50% minority; schools outside the central and southeastern
sections of Seattle were virtually all white. 2. Preliminary Challenges,
1956 to 1969. In 1956, a memo for the Seattle School Board
reported that school segregation reflected not only segregated
housing patterns but also school board policies that permitted
white students to transfer out of black schools while restricting
the transfer of black students into white schools. In 1958, black
parents whose children attended Harrison Elementary School (with a
black student population of over 75%) wrote the Seattle board,
complaining that the “ ‘boundaries for the Harrison Elementary
School were not set in accordance with the long-established
standards of the School District … but were arbitrarily set with an
end to excluding colored children from McGilvra School, which is
adjacent to the Harrison school district.’ ”
In 1963, at the insistence of the
National Association for the Advancement of Colored People (NAACP)
and other community groups, the school board adopted a new
race-based transfer policy. The new policy added an explicitly
racial criterion: If a place exists in a school, then, irrespective
of other transfer criteria, a white student may transfer to a
predominantly black school, and a black student may transfer to a
predominantly white school.
At that time one high school, Garfield, was
about two-thirds minority; eight high schools were virtually all
white. In 1963, the transfer program’s first year, 239 black
students and 8 white students transferred. In 1969, about 2,200 (of
10,383 total) of the district’s black students and about 400 of the
district’s white students took advantage of the plan. For the next
decade, annual program transfers remained at approximately this
level. 3. The NAACP’s First Legal Challenge and
Seattle’s Response, 1969 to 1977. In 1969 the NAACP filed a
federal lawsuit against the school board, claiming that the board
had “unlawfully and unconstitutionally” “establish[ed]” and
“maintain[ed]” a system of “racially segregated public schools.”
The complaint said that 77% of black public elementary school
students in Seattle attended 9 of the city’s 86 elementary schools
and that 23 of the remaining schools had no black students at all.
Similarly, of the 1,461 black students enrolled in the 12 senior
high schools in Seattle, 1,151 (or 78.8%) attended 3 senior high
schools, and 900 (61.6%) attended a single school, Garfield.
The complaint charged that the school board
had brought about this segregated system in part by “mak[ing] and
enforc[ing]” certain “rules and regulations,” in part by “drawing .
. . boundary lines” and “executing school attendance policies” that
would create and maintain “predominantly Negro or non-white
schools,” and in part by building schools “in such a manner as to
restrict the Negro plaintiffs and the class they represent to
predominantly negro or non-white schools.” The complaint also
charged that the board discriminated in assigning teachers.
The board responded to the lawsuit by
introducing a plan that required race-based transfers and mandatory
busing. The plan created three new middle schools at three school
buildings in the predominantly white north end. It then created a
“mixed” student body by assigning to those schools students who
would otherwise attend predominantly white, or predominantly black,
schools elsewhere. It used explicitly racial criteria in making
these assignments ( i.e. , it deliberately assigned to the
new middle schools black students, not white students, from the
black schools and white students, not black students, from the
white schools). And it used busing to transport the students to
their new assignments. The plan provoked considerable local
opposition. Opponents brought a lawsuit. But eventually a state
court found that the mandatory busing was lawful.
In 1976–1977, the plan involved
the busing of about 500 middle school students (300 black students
and 200 white students). Another 1,200 black students and 400 white
students participated in the previously adopted voluntary transfer
program. Thus about 2,000 students out of a total district
population of about 60,000 students were involved in one or the
other transfer program. At that time, about 20% or 12,000 of the
district’s students were black. And the board continued to describe
26 of its 112 schools as “segregated.” 4. The NAACP’s
Second Legal Challenge, 1977. In 1977, the NAACP filed another
legal complaint, this time with the federal Department of Health,
Education, and Welfare’s Office for Civil Rights (OCR). The
complaint alleged that the Seattle School Board had created or
perpetuated unlawful racial segregation through, e.g. ,
certain school-transfer criteria, a construction program that
needlessly built new schools in white areas, district line-drawing
criteria, the maintenance of inferior facilities at black schools,
the use of explicit racial criteria in the assignment of teachers
and other staff, and a general pattern of delay in respect to the
implementation of promised desegregation efforts.
The OCR and the school board entered into a
formal settlement agreement. The agreement required the board to
implement what became known as the “Seattle Plan.” 5. The Seattle Plan: Mandatory Busing,
1978 to 1988. The board began to implement the Seattle Plan in
1978. This plan labeled “racially imbalanced” any school at which
the percentage of black students exceeded by more than 20% the
minority population of the school district as a whole. It applied
that label to 26 schools, including 4 high schools—Cleveland (72.8%
minority), Franklin (76.6% minority), Garfield (78.4% minority),
and Rainier Beach (58.9% minority). The plan paired (or “triaded”)
“imbalanced” black schools with “imbalanced” white schools. It then
placed some grades (say, third and fourth grades) at one school
building and other grades (say, fifth and sixth grades) at the
other school building. And it thereby required, for example, all
fourth grade students from the previously black and previously
white schools first to attend together what would now be a “mixed”
fourth grade at one of the school buildings and then the next year
to attend what would now be a “mixed” fifth grade at the other
school building.
At the same time, the plan provided that a
previous “black” school would remain about 50% black, while a
previous “white” school would remain about two-thirds white. It was
consequently necessary to decide with some care which students would attend the new “mixed” grade. For this purpose,
administrators cataloged the racial makeup of each neighborhood
housing block. The school district met its percentage goals by
assigning to the new “mixed” school an appropriate number of
“black” housing blocks and “white” housing blocks. At the same
time, transport from house to school involved extensive busing,
with about half of all students attending a school other than the
one closest to their home.
The Seattle Plan achieved the school
integration that it sought. Just prior to the plan’s
implementation, for example, 4 of Seattle’s 11 high schools were
“imbalanced,” i.e. , almost exclusively “black” or almost
exclusively “white.” By 1979, only two were out of “balance.” By
1980 only Cleveland remained out of “balance” (as the board defined
it) and that by a mere two students.
Nonetheless, the Seattle Plan, due to its
busing, provoked serious opposition within the State. See generally Washington v. Seattle School Dist. No. 1 , 458
U. S. 457 , 461–466 (1982). Thus, Washington state voters
enacted an initiative that amended state law to require students to
be assigned to the schools closest to their homes. Id. , at
462. The Seattle School Board challenged the constitutionality of
the initiative. Id. , at 464. This Court then held that the
initiative—which would have prevented the Seattle Plan from taking
effect—violated the Fourteenth Amendment. Id. , at 470. 6. Student Choice, 1988 to 1998. By
1988, many white families had left the school district, and many
Asian families had moved in. The public school population had
fallen from about 100,000 to less than 50,000. The racial makeup of
the school population amounted to 43% white, 24% black, and 23%
Asian or Pacific Islander, with Hispanics and Native Americans
making up the rest. The cost of busing, the harm that members of
all racial communities feared that the Seattle Plan caused, the
desire to attract white families back to the public schools, and
the interest in providing greater school choice led the board to
abandon busing and to substitute a new student assignment policy
that resembles the plan now before us.
The new plan permitted each student to choose
the school he or she wished to attend, subject to race-based
constraints. In respect to high schools, for example, a student was
given a list of a subset of schools, carefully selected by the
board to balance racial distribution in the district by including
neighborhood schools and schools in racially different
neighborhoods elsewhere in the city. The student could then choose
among those schools, indicating a first choice, and other choices
the student found acceptable. In making an assignment to a
particular high school, the district would give first preference to
a student with a sibling already at the school. It gave second
preference to a student whose race differed from a race that was
“over-represented” at the school ( i.e., a race that
accounted for a higher percentage of the school population than of
the total district population). It gave third preference to
students residing in the neighborhood. It gave fourth preference to
students who received child care in the neighborhood. In a typical
year, say, 1995, about 20,000 potential high school students
participated. About 68% received their first choice. Another 16%
received an “acceptable” choice. A further 16% were assigned to a
school they had not listed. 7. The Current Plan, 1999 to the
Present. In 1996, the school board adopted the present plan,
which began in 1999. In doing so, it sought to deemphasize the use
of racial criteria and to increase the likelihood that a student
would receive an assignment at his first or second choice high
school. The district retained a racial tiebreaker for
oversubscribed schools, which takes effect only if the school’s
minority or majority enrollment falls outside of a 30% range
centered on the minority/majority population ratio within the
district. At the same time, all students were free subsequently to
transfer from the school at which they were initially placed to a
different school of their choice without regard to race. Thus, at
worst, a student would have to spend one year at a high school he
did not pick as a first or second choice.
The new plan worked roughly as expected for
the two school years during which it was in effect (1999–2000 and
2000–2001). In the 2000–2001 school year, for example, with the
racial tiebreaker, the entering ninth grade class at Franklin High
School had a 60% minority population; without the racial tiebreaker
that same class at Franklin would have had an almost 80% minority
population. (We consider only the ninth grade since only students
entering that class were subject to the tiebreaker, and because the
plan was not in place long enough to change the composition of an
entire school.) In the year 2005–2006, by which time the racial
tiebreaker had not been used for several years, Franklin’s overall
minority enrollment had risen to 90%. During the period the
tiebreaker applied, it typically affected about 300 students per
year. Between 80% and 90% of all students received their first
choice assignment; between 89% and 97% received their first or
second choice assignment.
Petitioner Parents Involved in
Community Schools objected to Seattle’s most recent plan under the
State and Federal Constitutions. In due course, the Washington
Supreme Court, the Federal District Court, and the Court of Appeals
for the Ninth Circuit (sitting en banc) rejected the challenge and
found Seattle’s plan lawful.
B Louisville 1. Before the Lawsuit, 1954
to 1972. In 1956, two years after Brown made clear
that Kentucky could no longer require racial segregation by law,
the Louisville Board of Education created a geography-based student
assignment plan designed to help achieve school integration. At the
same time it adopted an open transfer policy under which
approximately 3,000 of Louisville’s 46,000 students applied for
transfer. By 1972, however, the Louisville School District remained
highly segregated. Approximately half the district’s public school
enrollment was black; about half was white. Fourteen of the
district’s nineteen non-vocational middle and high schools were
close to totally black or totally white. Nineteen of the district’s
forty-six elementary schools were between 80% and 100% black.
Twenty-one elementary schools were between roughly 90% and 100%
white. 2. Court-Imposed Guidelines
and Busing, 1972 to 1991. In 1972, civil rights groups and
parents, claiming unconstitutional segregation, sued the Louisville
Board of Education in federal court. The original litigation
eventually became a lawsuit against the Jefferson County School
System, which in April 1975 absorbed Louisville’s schools and
combined them with those of the surrounding suburbs. (For ease of
exposition, I shall still use “Louisville” to refer to what is now
the combined districts.) After preliminary rulings and an eventual
victory for the plaintiffs in the Court of Appeals for the Sixth
Circuit, the District Court in July 1975 entered an order requiring
desegregation.
The order’s requirements reflected a (newly
enlarged) school district student population of about 135,000,
approximately 20% of whom were black. The order required the school
board to create and to maintain schools with student populations
that ranged, for elementary schools, between 12% and 40% black, and
for secondary schools (with one exception), between 12.5% and 35%
black.
The District Court also adopted a
complex desegregation plan designed to achieve the order’s targets.
The plan required redrawing school attendance zones, closing 12
schools, and busing groups of students, selected by race and the
first letter of their last names, to schools outside their
immediate neighborhoods. The plan’s initial busing requirements
were extensive, involving the busing of 23,000 students and a
transportation fleet that had to “operate from early in the morning
until late in the evening.” For typical students, the plan meant
busing for several years (several more years for typical black
students than for typical white students). The following notice,
published in a Louisville newspaper in 1976, gives a sense of how
the district’s race-based busing plan operated in practice:
[Graphic omitted; see printed opinion]
Louisville Courier Journal, June 18, 1976
(reproduced in J. Wilkinson, From Brown to Bakke: The Supreme Court and School Integration 1954–1978, p. 176
(1979)).
The District Court monitored implementation of
the plan. In 1978, it found that the plan had brought all of
Louisville’s schools within its “ ‘guidelines’ for racial
composition” for “at least a substantial portion of the [previous]
three years.” It removed the case from its active docket while
stating that it expected the board “to continue to implement those
portions of the desegregation order which are by their nature of a
continuing effect.”
By 1984, after several schools had fallen out
of compliance with the order’s racial percentages due to shifting
demographics in the community, the school board revised its
desegregation plan. In doing so, the board created a new racial
“guideline,” namely a “floating range of 10% above and 10% below
the countywide average for the different grade levels.” The board
simultaneously redrew district boundaries so that middle school
students could attend the same school for three years and high
school students for four years. It added “magnet” programs at two
high schools. And it adjusted its alphabet-based system for
grouping and busing students. The board estimated that its new plan
would lead to annual reassignment (with busing) of about 8,500
black students and about 8,000 white students. 3. Student Choice and Project Renaissance,
1991 to 1996. By 1991, the board had concluded that assigning
elementary school students to two or more schools during their
elementary school years had proved educationally unsound and, if
continued, would undermine Kentucky’s newly adopted Education
Reform Act. It consequently conducted a nearly year-long review of
its plan. In doing so, it consulted widely with parents and other
members of the local community, using public presentations, public
meetings, and various other methods to obtain the public’s input.
At the conclusion of this review, the board adopted a new plan,
called “Project Renaissance,” that emphasized student choice.
Project Renaissance again revised the board’s
racial guidelines. It provided that each elementary school would
have a black student population of between 15% and 50%; each middle
and high school would have a black population and a white
population that fell within a range, the boundaries of which were
set at 15% above and 15% below the general student population
percentages in the county at that grade level. The plan then drew
new geographical school assignment zones designed to satisfy these
guidelines; the district could reassign students if particular
schools failed to meet the guidelines and was required to do so if
a school repeatedly missed these targets.
In respect to elementary schools, the plan
first drew a neighborhood line around each elementary school, and
it then drew a second line around groups of elementary schools
(called “clusters”). It initially assigned each student to his or
her neighborhood school, but it permitted each student freely to
transfer between elementary schools within each cluster provided that the transferring student (a) was black if
transferring from a predominantly black school to a predominantly
white school, or (b) was white if transferring from a predominantly
white school to a predominantly black school. Students could also
apply to attend magnet elementary schools or programs.
The plan required each middle school student
to be assigned to his or her neighborhood school unless the student
applied for, and was accepted by, a magnet middle school. The plan
provided for “open” high school enrollment. Every 9th or 10th
grader could apply to any high school in the system, and the high
school would accept applicants according to set criteria—one of
which consisted of the need to attain or remain in compliance with
the plan’s racial guidelines. Finally, the plan created two new
magnet schools, one each at the elementary and middle school
levels. 4. The Current Plan: Project Renaissance
Modified, 1996 to 2003. In 1995 and 1996, the Louisville
School Board, with the help of a special “Planning Team,” community
meetings, and other official and unofficial study groups, monitored
the effects of Project Renaissance and considered proposals for
improvement. Consequently, in 1996, the board modified Project
Renaissance, thereby creating the present plan.
At the time, the district’s public school
population was approximately 30% black. The plan consequently
redrew the racial “guidelines,” setting the boundaries at 15% to
50% black for all schools. It again redrew school
assignment boundaries. And it expanded the transfer opportunities
available to elementary and middle school pupils. The plan forbade
transfers, however, if the transfer would lead to a school
population outside the guideline range, i.e. , if it would
create a school where fewer than 15% or more than 50% of the
students were black.
The plan also established “Parent Assistance
Centers” to help parents and students navigate the school selection
and assignment process. It pledged the use of other resources in
order to “encourage all schools to achieve an African-American
enrollment equivalent to the average district-wide African-American
enrollment at the school’s respective elementary, middle or high
school level.” And the plan continued use of magnet schools.
In 1999, several parents brought a lawsuit in
federal court attacking the plan’s use of racial guidelines at one
of the district’s magnet schools. They asked the court to dissolve
the desegregation order and to hold the use of magnet school racial guidelines unconstitutional. The board opposed
dissolution, arguing that “the old dual system” had left a
“demographic imbalance” that “prevent[ed] dissolution.” In 2000,
after reviewing the present plan, the District Court dissolved the
1975 order. It wrote that there was “overwhelming evidence of the
Board’s good faith compliance with the desegregation Decree and its
underlying purposes.” It added that the Louisville School Board had
“treated the ideal of an integrated system as much more than a
legal obligation—they consider it a positive, desirable policy and
an essential element of any well-rounded public school
education.”
The Court also found that the magnet programs
available at the high school in question were “not available at
other high schools” in the school district. It consequently held
unconstitutional the use of race-based “targets” to govern
admission to magnet schools . And it ordered the board not
to control access to those scarce programs through the use of
racial targets. 5. The Current Lawsuit, 2003
to the Present. Subsequent to the District Court’s dissolution
of the desegregation order (in 2000) the board simply continued to
implement its 1996 plan as modified to reflect the court’s magnet
school determination. In 2003, the petitioner now before us,
Crystal Meredith, brought this lawsuit challenging the plan’s
unmodified portions, i.e. , those portions that dealt with ordinary , not magnet, schools. Both the District Court and
the Court of Appeals for the Sixth Circuit rejected Meredith’s
challenge and held the unmodified aspects of the plan
constitutional.
C
The histories I have set forth
describe the extensive and ongoing efforts of two school districts
to bring about greater racial integration of their public schools.
In both cases the efforts were in part remedial. Louisville began
its integration efforts in earnest when a federal court in 1975
entered a school desegregation order. Seattle undertook its
integration efforts in response to the filing of a federal lawsuit
and as a result of its settlement of a segregation complaint filed
with the federal OCR.
The plans in both Louisville and
Seattle grow out of these earlier remedial efforts. Both districts
faced problems that reflected initial periods of severe racial
segregation, followed by such remedial efforts as busing, followed
by evidence of resegregation, followed by a need to end busing and
encourage the return of, e.g. , suburban students through
increased student choice. When formulating the plans under review,
both districts drew upon their considerable experience with earlier
plans, having revised their policies periodically in light of that
experience. Both districts rethought their methods over time and
explored a wide range of other means, including non-race-conscious
policies. Both districts also considered elaborate studies and
consulted widely within their communities.
Both districts sought greater racial
integration for educational and democratic, as well as for
remedial, reasons. Both sought to achieve these objectives while
preserving their commitment to other educational goals, e.g. , districtwide commitment to high quality public
schools, increased pupil assignment to neighborhood schools,
diminished use of busing, greater student choice, reduced risk of
white flight, and so forth. Consequently, the present plans expand
student choice; they limit the burdens (including busing) that
earlier plans had imposed upon students and their families; and
they use race-conscious criteria in limited and gradually
diminishing ways. In particular, they use race-conscious criteria
only to mark the outer bounds of broad population-related
ranges.
The histories also make clear the futility of
looking simply to whether earlier school segregation was de
jure or de facto in order to draw firm lines
separating the constitutionally permissible from the
constitutionally forbidden use of “race-conscious” criteria.
Justice Thomas suggests that it will be easy to identify de
jure segregation because “[i]n most cases, there either will
or will not have been a state constitutional amendment, state
statute, local ordinance, or local administrative policy explicitly
requiring separation of the races.” Ante , at 6, n. 4
(concurring opinion). But our precedent has recognized that de
jure discrimination can be present even in the absence of
racially explicit laws. See Yick Wo v. Hopkins , 118 U. S. 356 , 373–374 (1886).
No one here disputes that Louisville’s
segregation was de jure . But what about Seattle’s? Was it de facto? De jure? A mixture? Opinions differed.
Or is it that a prior federal court had not adjudicated the matter?
Does that make a difference? Is Seattle free on remand to say that
its schools were de jure segregated, just as in 1956 a
memo for the School Board admitted? The plurality does not seem
confident as to the answer. Compare ante , at 12 (opinion
of the Court) (“[T]he Seattle public schools have never
shown that they were ever segregated by law” (emphasis
added)), with ante at 29–30 (plurality opinion) (assuming
“the Seattle school district was never segregated by law,” but
seeming to concede that a school district with de jure segregation need not be subject to a court order to be allowed to
engage in race-based remedial measures).
A court finding of de
jure segregation cannot be the crucial variable. After all, a
number of school districts in the South that the Government or
private plaintiffs challenged as segregated by law voluntarily desegregated their schools without a court
order —just as Seattle did. See, e.g. , Coleman,
Desegregation of the Public Schools in Kentucky—The Second Year
After the Supreme Court’s Decision, 25 J. Negro Educ. 254, 256, 261
(1956) (40 of Kentucky’s 180 school districts began desegre- gation
without court orders); Branton, Little Rock Revisited:
Desegregation to Resegregation, 52 J. Negro Educ. 250, 251 (1983)
(similar in Arkansas); Bullock & Rodgers, Coercion to
Compliance: Southern School Districts and School Desegregation
Guidelines, 38 J. Politics 987, 991 (1976) (similar in Georgia); McDaniel v. Barresi , 402 U. S. 39 , 40, n. 1
(1971) (Clarke County, Georgia). See also Letter from Robert F.
Kennedy, Attorney General, to John F. Kennedy, President (Jan. 24,
1963) (hereinafter Kennedy Report), available at
http://www.gilderlehrman.org/search/collection_pdfs/05/63/0/05630.pdf
(all Internet materials as visited June 26, 2007, and available in
Clerk of Court’s case file) (reporting successful efforts by the
Government to induce voluntary desegregation).
Moreover, Louisville’s history makes clear
that a community under a court order to desegregate might submit a
race-conscious remedial plan before the court dissolved
the order, but with every intention of following that plan even after dissolution. How could such a plan be lawful the day
before dissolution but then become unlawful the very next day? On
what legal ground can the majority rest its contrary view? But see ante , at 12–13, 17, n. 12.
Are courts really to treat as
merely de facto segregated those school districts that
avoided a federal order by voluntarily complying with Brown ’s requirements? See id. , at 12, 29–30. This
Court has previously done just the opposite, permitting a
race-conscious remedy without any kind of court decree. See McDaniel , supra , at 41. Because the Constitution
emphatically does not forbid the use of race-conscious measures by
districts in the South that voluntarily desegregated their schools,
on what basis does the plurality claim that the law forbids Seattle
to do the same? But see ante , at 29.
The histories also indicate the complexity of
the tasks and the practical difficulties that local school boards
face when they seek to achieve greater racial integration. The
boards work in communities where demographic patterns change, where
they must meet traditional learning goals, where they must attract
and retain effective teachers, where they should (and will) take
account of parents’ views and maintain their commitment to
public school education, where they must adapt to court
intervention, where they must encourage voluntary student and
parent action—where they will find that their own good faith, their
knowledge, and their understanding of local circumstances are
always necessary but often insufficient to solve the problems at
hand.
These facts and circumstances
help explain why in this context, as to means, the law often leaves
legislatures, city councils, school boards, and voters with a broad
range of choice, thereby giving “different communities” the
opportunity to “try different solutions to common problems and
gravitate toward those that prove most successful or seem to them
best to suit their individual needs.” Comfort v. Lynn
School Comm. , 418 F. 3d 1, 28 (CA1 2005) (Boudin,
C. J., concurring) (citing United States v. Lopez , 514
U. S. 549 , 581 (1995) (Kennedy, J., concurring)), cert. denied, 546 U. S. 1061 (2005).
With this factual background in mind, I turn
to the legal question: Does the United States Constitution prohibit
these school boards from using race-conscious criteria in the
limited ways at issue here?
II The Legal Standard A longstanding and unbroken
line of legal authority tells us that the Equal Protection Clause
permits local school boards to use race-conscious criteria to
achieve positive race-related goals, even when the Constitution
does not compel it. Because of its importance, I shall repeat what
this Court said about the matter in Swann . Chief Justice
Burger, on behalf of a unanimous Court in a case of exceptional
importance, wrote:
“School authorities are
traditionally charged with broad power to formulate and implement
educational policy and might well conclude, for example, that in
order to prepare students to live in a pluralistic society each
school should have a prescribed ratio of Negro to white students
reflecting the proportion for the district as a whole. To do this
as an educational policy is within the broad discretionary powers
of school authorities.” 402 U. S., at 16.
The statement was not a technical holding in the
case. But the Court set forth in Swann a basic principle
of constitutional law—a principle of law that has found “wide
acceptance in the legal culture.” Dickerson v. United
States , 530 U.
S. 428 , 443 (2000) (internal quotation marks omitted); Mitchell v. United States , 526 U. S. 314 , 330
(1999); id. , at 331, 332 (Scalia, J., dissenting) (citing
“ ‘wide acceptance in the legal culture’ ” as “adequate
reason not to overrule” prior cases).
Thus, in North Carolina Bd.
of Ed. v. Swann , 402 U. S. 43 , 45 (1971), this Court,
citing Swann, restated the point. “[S]chool authorities,”
the Court said, “have wide discretion in formulating school policy,
and . . . as a matter of educational policy school authorities may
well conclude that some kind of racial balance in the schools is
desirable quite apart from any constitutional requirements.”
Then-Justice Rehnquist echoed this view in Bustop, Inc. v. Los Angeles Bd. of Ed. , 439 U. S. 1380 , 1383
(1978) (opinion in chambers), making clear that he too believed
that Swann ’s statement reflected settled law: “While I
have the gravest doubts that [a state supreme court] was required by the United States Constitution to take the
[desegregation] action that it has taken in this case, I have very
little doubt that it was permitted by that Constitution to
take such action.” (Emphasis in original.)
These statements nowhere suggest that this
freedom is limited to school districts where court-ordered
desegregation measures are also in effect. Indeed, in McDaniel , a case decided the same day as Swann , a
group of parents challenged a race-conscious student assignment
plan that the Clarke County School Board had voluntarily adopted as a remedy without a court order (though under federal
agency pressure—pressure Seattle also encountered). The plan
required that each elementary school in the district maintain 20%
to 40% enrollment of African-American students, corresponding to
the racial composition of the district. See Barresi v. Browne , 226 Ga. 456, 456–459, 175 S. E. 2d 649,
650–651 (1970). This Court upheld the plan, see McDaniel ,
402 U. S., at 41, rejecting the parents’ argument that “a person
may not be included or excluded solely because he
is a Negro or because he is white.” Brief for Respondents in McDaniel , O. T. 1970, No. 420, p. 25.
Federal authorities had claimed—as the NAACP
and the OCR did in Seattle—that Clarke County schools were
segregated in law, not just in fact. The plurality’s claim that
Seattle was “never segregated by law” is simply not accurate.
Compare ante , at 29, with supra , at 6–9. The
plurality could validly claim that no court ever found
that Seattle schools were segregated in law. But that is also true
of the Clarke County schools in McDaniel . Unless we
believe that the Constitution enforces one legal standard for the
South and another for the North, this Court should grant Seattle
the permission it granted Clarke County, Georgia. See McDaniel , 402 U. S., at 41 (“[S]teps will almost
invariably require that students be assigned ‘differently because
of their race.’ . . . Any other approach would freeze the status
quo that is the very target of all desegregation processes.”).
This Court has also held that school districts
may be required by federal statute to undertake race-conscious
desegregation efforts even when there is no likelihood that de
jure segregation can be shown. In Board of Ed. of City
School Dist. of New York v. Harris , 444 U. S. 130 , 148–149
(1979), the Court concluded that a federal statute required school
districts receiving certain federal funds to remedy faculty
segregation, even though in this Court’s view the racial
disparities in the affected schools were purely de facto and would not have been actionable under the Equal Protection
Clause. Not even the dissenters thought the race-conscious remedial
program posed a constitutional problem. See id. ,
at 152 (opinion of Stewart, J.). See also, e.g. , Crawford v. Board of Ed. of Los Angeles , 458 U. S. 527 , 535–536
(1982) (“[S]tate courts of California continue to have an
obligation under state law to order segregated school districts to
use voluntary desegregation techniques, whether or not there
has been a finding of intentional segregation . . . . [S]chool
districts themselves retain a state-law obligation to take
reasonably feasible steps to desegregate, and they remain free
to adopt reassignment and busing plans to effectuate
desegregation ” (emphasis added)); School Comm. of
Boston v. Board of Education , 389 U. S. 572 (1968) (per curiam) (dismissing for want of a federal question a
challenge to a voluntary statewide integration plan using express
racial criteria).
Lower state and federal courts had considered
the matter settled and uncontroversial even before this Court
decided Swann . Indeed, in 1968, the Illinois Supreme Court
rejected an equal protection challenge to a race-conscious state
law seeking to undo de facto segregation:
“To support [their] claim, the
defendants heavily rely on three Federal cases, each of which held,
no State law being involved, that a local school board does not
have an affirmative constitutional duty to act to alleviate racial
imbalance in the schools that it did not cause. However, the
question as to whether the constitution requires a local school
board, or a State, to act to undo de facto school
segregation is simply not here concerned. The issue here is whether
the constitution permits, rather than prohibits, voluntary State
action aimed toward reducing and eventually eliminating de
facto school segregation.
“State laws or administrative policies,
directed toward the reduction and eventual elimination of de
facto segregation of children in the schools and racial
imbalance, have been approved by every high State court which has
considered the issue. Similarly, the Federal courts which have
considered the issue . . . have recognized that voluntary programs
of local school authorities designed to alleviate de facto segregation and racial imbalance in the schools are not
constitutionally forbidden.” Tometz v. Board of Ed.,
Waukegan School Dist. No. 6 , 39 Ill. 2d 593, 597–598, 237
N. E. 2d 498, 501 (1968) (citations omitted) (citing decisions
from the high courts of Pennsylvania, Massachusetts, New Jersey,
California, New York, and Connecticut, and from the Courts of
Appeals for the First, Second, Fourth, and Sixth Circuits).
See also, e.g. , Offerman v. Nitkowski , 378 F. 2d 22, 24 (CA2 1967); Deal v. Cincinnati Bd. of Ed. , 369 F. 2d 55, 61 (CA6
1966), cert. denied, 389 U. S. 847 (1967); Springfield School Comm. v. Barksdale , 348
F. 2d 261, 266 (CA1 1965); Pennsylvania Human Relations
Comm’n v. Chester School Dist. , 427 Pa. 157, 164, 233
A. 2d 290, 294 (1967); Booker v. Board of Ed. of
Plainfield, Union Cty. , 45 N. J. 161, 170, 212 A. 2d
1, 5 (1965); Jackson v. Pasadena City School
Dist. , 59 Cal. 2d 876, 881–882, 382 P. 2d 878, 881–882
(1963) (in bank).
I quote the Illinois Supreme
Court at length to illustrate the prevailing legal assumption at
the time Swann was decided. In this respect, Swann was not a sharp or unexpected departure from prior
rulings; it reflected a consensus that had already emerged among
state and lower federal courts.
If there were doubts before Swann was decided, they did not survive this Court’s
decision. Numerous state and federal courts explicitly relied upon Swann ’s guidance for decades to follow. For instance, a
Texas appeals court in 1986 rejected a Fourteenth Amendment
challenge to a voluntary integration plan by explaining:
“[T]he absence of a court order to desegregate does
not mean that a school board cannot exceed minimum requirements in
order to promote school integration. School authorities are
traditionally given broad discretionary powers to formulate and
implement educational policy and may properly decide to ensure to
their students the value of an integrated school experience.” Citizens for Better Ed. v. Goose Creek Consol.
Independent School Dist. , 719 S. W. 2d 350, 352-353 (Ct.
App. Tex. 1986) (citing Swann and North Carolina Bd.
of Ed. ), appeal dism’d for want of a substantial federal
question, 484 U. S.
804 (1987).
Similarly, in Zaslawsky v. Bd. of Ed.
of Los Angeles City Unified School Dist. , 610 F. 2d 661,
662–664 (1979), the Ninth Circuit rejected a federal constitutional
challenge to a school district’s use of mandatory faculty transfers
to ensure that each school’s faculty makeup would fall within 10%
of the districtwide racial composition. Like the Texas court, the
Ninth Circuit relied upon Swann and North Carolina Bd.
of Ed. to reject the argument that “a race-conscious plan is
permissible only when there has been a judicial finding of de
jure segregation.” 610 F. 2d, at 663–664. See also, e.g. , Darville v. Dade County School
Bd. , 497 F. 2d 1002, 1004–1006 (CA5 1974); State ex
rel. Citizens Against Mandatory Bussing v. Brooks , 80
Wash. 2d 121, 128–129, 492 P. 2d 536, 541–542 (1972) (en
banc), overruled on other grounds, Cole v. Webster , 103 Wash. 2d 280, 692 P. 2d 799 (1984) (en
banc); School Comm. of Springfield v. Board of
Ed. , 362 Mass. 417, 428–429 287 N. E. 2d 438, 447–448
(1972). These decisions illustrate well how lower courts understood
and followed Swann ’s enunciation of the relevant legal
principle.
Courts are not alone in accepting
as constitutionally valid the legal principle that Swann enunciated— i.e. , that the government may voluntarily adopt
race-conscious measures to improve conditions of race even when it
is not under a constitutional obligation to do so. That principle
has been accepted by every branch of government and is rooted in
the history of the Equal Protection Clause itself. Thus, Congress
has enacted numerous race-conscious statutes that illustrate that
principle or rely upon its validity. See, e.g. , 20 U. S.
C. §6311(b)(2)(C)(v) (No Child Left Behind Act); §1067 et
seq. (authorizing aid to minority institutions). In fact,
without being exhaustive, I have counted 51 federal statutes that
use racial classifications. I have counted well over 100 state
statutes that similarly employ racial classifications. Presidential
administrations for the past half-century have used and supported
various race-conscious measures. See, e.g. , Exec. Order
No. 10925, 26 Fed. Reg. 1977 (1961) (President Kennedy); Exec.
Order No. 11246, 30 Fed. Reg. 12319 (1965) (President Johnson);
Sugrue, Breaking Through: The Troubled Origins of Affirmative
Action in the Workplace, in Colorlines: Affirmative Action,
Immigration, and Civil Rights Options for America 31 (Skretny ed.
2001) (describing President Nixon’s lobbying for affirmative action
plans, e.g. , the Philadelphia Plan); White, Affirmative
Action’s Alamo: Gerald Ford Returns to Fight Once More for
Michigan, Time, Aug. 23, 1999, p. 48 (reporting on President Ford’s
support for affirmative action); Schuck, Affirmative Action: Past,
Present, and Future, 20 Yale L. & Pol’y Rev. 1, 50 (2002)
(describing President Carter’s support for affirmation action). And
during the same time, hundreds of local school districts have
adopted student assignment plans that use race-conscious criteria.
See Welch 83–91.
That Swann ’s legal statement should
find such broad acceptance is not surprising. For Swann is
predicated upon a well-established legal view of the Fourteenth
Amendment. That view understands the basic objective of those who
wrote the Equal Protection Clause as forbidding practices that lead
to racial exclusion. The Amendment sought to bring into American
society as full members those whom the Nation had previously held
in slavery. See Slaughter-House Cases , 16 Wall. 36, 71
(1872) (“[N]o one can fail to be impressed with the one pervading
purpose found in [all the Reconstruction amendments] . . . we mean
the freedom of the slave race”); Strauder v. West
Virginia , 100 U. S. 303 , 306 (1879) (“[The
Fourteenth Amendment] is one of a series of constitutional
provisions having a common purpose; namely, securing to a race
recently emancipated . . . all the civil rights that the superior
race enjoy”).
There is reason to believe that those who
drafted an Amendment with this basic purpose in mind would have
understood the legal and practical difference between the use of
race-conscious criteria in defiance of that purpose, namely to keep
the races apart, and the use of race-conscious criteria to further
that purpose, namely to bring the races together. See generally R.
Sears, A Utopian Experiment in Kentucky: Integration and Social
Equality at Berea, 1866–1904 (1996) (describing federal funding,
through the Freedman’s Bureau, of race-conscious school integration
programs). See also R. Fischer, The Segregation Struggle in
Louisiana 1862–77, p. 51 (1974) (describing the use of
race-conscious remedies); Harlan, Desegregation in New Orleans
Public Schools During Reconstruction, 67 Am. Hist. Rev. 663, 664
(1962) (same); W. Vaughn, Schools for All: The Blacks and Public
Education in the South, 1865–1877, pp. 111–116 (1974) (same).
Although the Constitution almost always forbids the former, it is
significantly more lenient in respect to the latter. See Gratz v. Bollinger , 539 U. S. 244 , 301 (2003) (Ginsburg,
J., dissenting); Adarand Constructors, Inc. v. Peńa , 515 U. S. 200 , 243 (1995) (Stevens,
J., dissenting).
Sometimes Members of this Court have disagreed
about the degree of leniency that the Clause affords to programs
designed to include. See Wygant v. Jackson Board of
Education , 476
U. S. 267 , 274 (1986); Fullilove v. Klutznick , 448 U. S. 448 , 507
(1980). But I can find no case in which this Court has followed
Justice Thomas’ “colorblind” approach. And I have found no case
that otherwise repudiated this constitutional asymmetry between
that which seeks to exclude and that which seeks to include members of minority races.
What does the plurality say in response?
First, it seeks to distinguish Swann and other similar
cases on the ground that those cases involved remedial plans in
response to judicial findings of de jure segregation. As McDaniel and Harris show, that is
historically untrue. See supra , at 22–24. Many school
districts in the South adopted segregation remedies (to which Swann clearly applies) without any such federal
order , see supra, at 19–20. See also Kennedy
Report. Seattle’s circumstances are not meaningfully different from
those in, say, McDaniel , where this Court approved
race-conscious remedies. Louisville’s plan was created and
initially adopted when a compulsory district court order was in
place. And, in any event, the histories of Seattle and Louisville
make clear that this distinction—between court-ordered and
voluntary desegregation—seeks a line that sensibly cannot be
drawn.
Second, the plurality downplays the importance
of Swann and related cases by frequently describing their
relevant statements as “dicta.” These criticisms,
however, miss the main point. Swann did not hide its
understanding of the law in a corner of an obscure opinion or in a
footnote, unread but by experts. It set forth its view prominently
in an important opinion joined by all nine Justices, knowing that
it would be read and followed throughout the Nation. The basic
problem with the plurality’s technical “dicta”-based response lies
in its overly theoretical approach to case law, an approach that
emphasizes rigid distinctions between holdings and dicta in a way
that serves to mask the radical nature of today’s decision. Law is
not an exercise in mathematical logic. And statements of a legal
rule set forth in a judicial opinion do not always divide neatly
into “holdings” and “dicta.” (Consider the legal “status” of
Justice Powell’s separate opinion in Regents of Univ. of
Cal. v. Bakke , 438 U. S. 265 (1978).) The
constitutional principle enunciated in Swann, reiterated
in subsequent cases, and relied upon over many years, provides, and
has widely been thought to provide, authoritative legal guidance.
And if the plurality now chooses to reject that principle, it
cannot adequately justify its retreat simply by affixing the label
“dicta” to reasoning with which it disagrees. Rather, it must
explain to the courts and to the Nation why it would
abandon guidance set forth many years before, guidance that
countless others have built upon over time, and which the law has
continuously embodied.
Third, a more important response is the
plurality’s claim that later cases—in particular Johnson , Adarand , and Grutter —supplanted Swann .
See ante , at 11–12, 31–32, n. 16, 34–35 (citing Adarand , supra, at 227; Johnson v. California , 543 U. S. 499 , 505 (2005); Grutter v. Bollinger , 539 U. S. 306 , 326
(2003)). The plurality says that cases such as Swann and
the others I have described all “were decided before this Court
definitively determined that ‘all racial classifications . . . must
be analyzed by a reviewing court under strict scrutiny.’ ” Ante , at 31, n. 16 (quoting Adarand , 515 U.
S., at 227). This Court in Adarand added that “such
classifications are constitutional only if they are narrowly
tailored measures that further compelling governmental interests.” Ibid . And the Court repeated this same statement in Grutter . See 539 U. S., at 326.
Several of these cases were significantly more
restrictive than Swann in respect to the degree of
leniency the Fourteenth Amendment grants to programs designed to include people of all races. See, e.g. , Adarand , supra; Gratz , supra; Grutter , supra . But that legal circumstance
cannot make a critical difference here for two separate
reasons.
First, no case—not Adarand , Gratz , Grutter , or any other—has ever held that
the test of “strict scrutiny” means that all racial
classifications—no matter whether they seek to include or
exclude—must in practice be treated the same. The Court did not say
in Adarand or in Johnson or in Grutter that it was overturning Swann or its central
constitutional principle.
Indeed, in its more recent opinions, the Court
recognized that the “fundamental purpose” of strict scrutiny review
is to “take relevant differences” between “fundamentally different
situations . . . into account.” Adarand , supra ,
at 228 (internal quotation marks omitted). The Court made clear
that “[s]trict scrutiny does not trea[t] dissimilar race-based
decisions as though they were equally objectionable.” Ibid. It added that the fact that a law “treats [a person]
unequally because of his or her race . . . says nothing about the
ultimate validity of any particular law.” Id. , at 229–230
(internal quotation marks omitted). And the Court, using the very
phrase that Justice Marshall had used to describe strict scrutiny’s
application to any exclusionary use of racial criteria,
sought to “ dispel the notion that strict scrutiny” is as
likely to condemn inclusive uses of “race-conscious”
criteria as it is to invalidate exclusionary uses. That
is, it is not in all circumstances “ ‘strict in
theory, but fatal in fact.’ ” Id. , at 237 (quoting Fullilove v. Klutznick , 448 U. S., at 519
(Marshall, J., concurring in judgment)).
The Court in Grutter elaborated:
“Strict scrutiny is not ‘strict
in theory, but fatal in fact.’ . . . Although all governmental uses
of race are subject to strict scrutiny, not all are invalidated by
it. . . .
“Context matters when reviewing race-based
governmental action under the Equal Protection Clause. See Gomillion v. Lightfoot , 364 U. S. 339 , 343–344 (1960)
(admonishing that, ‘in dealing with claims under broad provisions
of the Constitution, which derive content by an interpretive
process of inclusion and exclusion, it is imperative that
generalizations, based on and qualified by the concrete situations
that gave rise to them, must not be applied out of context in
disregard of variant controlling facts’). . . . Not every decision
influenced by race is equally objectionable, and strict scrutiny is
designed to provide a framework for carefully examining the
importance and the sincerity of the reasons advanced by the
governmental decisionmaker for the use of race in that particular
context.” 539 U. S., at 326–327.
The Court’s holding in Grutter demonstrates that the Court meant what it said, for the Court
upheld an elite law school’s race-conscious admissions program.
The upshot is that the cases to which the
plurality refers, though all applying strict scrutiny, do not treat
exclusive and inclusive uses the same. Rather, they apply the
strict scrutiny test in a manner that is “fatal in fact” only to
racial classifications that harmfully exclude; they apply
the test in a manner that is not fatal in fact to racial
classifications that seek to include .
The plurality cannot avoid this simple fact.
See ante , at 34–36. Today’s opinion reveals that the
plurality would rewrite this Court’s prior jurisprudence, at least
in practical application, transforming the “strict scrutiny” test
into a rule that is fatal in fact across the board. In doing so,
the plurality parts company from this Court’s prior cases, and it
takes from local government the longstanding legal right to use
race-conscious criteria for inclusive purposes in limited ways.
Second, as Grutter specified,
“[c]ontext matters when reviewing race-based governmental action
under the Equal Protection Clause.” 539 U. S., at 327 (citing Gomillion v. Lightfoot, 364 U. S. 339 , 343–344 (1960)). And
contexts differ dramatically one from the other. Governmental use
of race-based criteria can arise in the context of, for example,
census forms, research expenditures for diseases, assignments of
police officers patrolling predominantly minority-race
neighborhoods, efforts to desegregate racially segregated schools,
policies that favor minorities when distributing goods or services
in short supply, actions that create majority-minority electoral
districts, peremptory strikes that remove potential jurors on the
basis of race, and others. Given the significant differences among
these contexts, it would be surprising if the law required an
identically strict legal test for evaluating the constitutionality
of race-based criteria as to each of them.
Here, the context is one in which school
districts seek to advance or to maintain racial integration in
primary and secondary schools. It is a context, as Swann makes clear, where history has required special administrative
remedies. And it is a context in which the school boards’ plans
simply set race-conscious limits at the outer boundaries of a broad
range.
This context is not a context that
involves the use of race to decide who will receive goods or
services that are normally distributed on the basis of merit and
which are in short supply. It is not one in which race-conscious
limits stigmatize or exclude; the limits at issue do not pit the
races against each other or otherwise significantly exacerbate
racial tensions. They do not impose burdens unfairly upon members
of one race alone but instead seek benefits for members of all
races alike. The context here is one of racial limits that seek,
not to keep the races apart, but to bring them together.
The importance of these differences is clear
once one compares the present circumstances with other cases where
one or more of these negative features are present. See, e.g. , Strauder v. West Virginia , 100 U. S. 303 (1880); Yick Wo v. Hopkins , 118 U. S. 356 (1886); Brown , 347
U. S. 483 ; Loving v. Virginia , 388 U. S. 1 (1967); Regents of Univ. of Cal. v. Bakke , 438 U. S. 265 (1978); Batson v. Kentucky , 476 U. S. 79 (1986); Richmond v. J. A. Croson Co. , 488 U. S. 469 (1989); Shaw v. Reno , 509 U. S. 630 (1993); Adarand Constructors, Inc. v. Peńa , 515 U. S. 200 (1995); Grutter , supra; Gratz v. Bollinger , 539 U. S. 244 (2003); Johnson v. California , 543 U. S. 499 (2005).
If one examines the context more specifically,
one finds that the districts’ plans reflect efforts to overcome a
history of segregation, embody the results of broad experience and
community consultation, seek to expand student choice while
reducing the need for mandatory busing, and use race-conscious
criteria in highly limited ways that diminish the use of race
compared to preceding integration efforts. Compare Wessmann v. Gittens , 160 F. 3d 790, 809–810
(CA1 1998) (Boudin, J., concurring), with Comfort , 418 F.
3d, at 28–29 (Boudin, C. J., concurring). They do not seek to
award a scarce commodity on the basis of merit, for they are not
magnet schools; rather, by design and in practice, they offer
substantially equivalent academic programs and electives. Although
some parents or children prefer some schools over others, school
popularity has varied significantly over the years. In 2000, for
example, Roosevelt was the most popular first choice high school in
Seattle; in 2001, Ballard was the most popular; in 2000, West
Seattle was one of the least popular; by 2003, it was one of the
more popular. See Research, Evaluation and Assessment, Student
Information Serv- ices Office, District Summaries 1999–2005,
available at http:
//www.seattleschools.org /area /siso /disprof /2005 /DP05
all.pdf. In a word, the school plans under review do not involve
the kind of race-based harm that has led this Court, in other
contexts, to find the use of race-conscious criteria
unconstitutional.
These and related considerations convinced one
Ninth Circuit judge in the Seattle case to apply a standard of
constitutionality review that is less than “strict,” and to
conclude that this Court’s precedents do not require the contrary.
See 426 F. 3d 1162, 1193–1194 (2005) (Kozinski, J.,
concurring) (“That a student is denied the school of his choice may
be disappointing, but it carries no racial stigma and says nothing
at all about that individual’s aptitude or ability”). That judge is
not alone. Cf. Gratz , supra , at 301 (Ginsburg,
J., dissenting); Adarand , supra , at 243 (Stevens,
J., dissenting); Carter, When Victims Happen To Be Black, 97 Yale
L. J. 420, 433–434 (1988).
The view that a more lenient standard than
“strict scrutiny” should apply in the present context would not
imply abandonment of judicial efforts carefully to determine the
need for race-conscious criteria and the criteria’s tailoring in
light of the need. And the present context requires a court to
examine carefully the race-conscious program at issue. In doing so,
a reviewing judge must be fully aware of the potential dangers and
pitfalls that Justice Thomas and Justice Kennedy mention. See ante , at 11–12 (Thomas, J., concurring); ante , at
3, 17 (opinion of Kennedy, J.).
But unlike the plurality, such a judge would
also be aware that a legislature or school administrators,
ultimately accountable to the electorate, could nonetheless properly conclude that a racial classification
sometimes serves a purpose important enough to overcome the risks
they mention, for example, helping to end racial isolation or to
achieve a diverse student body in public schools. Cf. ante , at 17–18 (opinion of Kennedy, J.). Where that is so,
the judge would carefully examine the program’s details to
determine whether the use of race-conscious criteria is
proportionate to the important ends it serves.
In my view, this contextual approach to
scrutiny is altogether fitting. I believe that the law requires
application here of a standard of review that is not “strict” in
the traditional sense of that word, although it does require the
careful review I have just described. See Gratz , supra , at 301 (Ginsburg, J., joined by Souter, J.,
dissenting); Adarand , supra , at 242–249 (Stevens,
J., joined by Ginsburg, J., dissenting); 426 F. 3d, at
1193–1194 (Kozinski, J., concurring). Apparently Justice Kennedy
also agrees that strict scrutiny would not apply in respect to
certain “race-conscious” school board policies. See ante ,
at 9 (“Executive and legislative branches, which for generations
now have considered these types of policies and procedures, should
be permitted to employ them with candor and with confidence that a
constitutional violation does not occur whenever a decisionmaker
considers the impact a given approach might have on students of
different races”).
Nonetheless, in light of Grutter and
other precedents, see, e.g. , Bakke , 438 U. S., at
290 (opinion of Powell, J.), I shall adopt the first alternative. I
shall apply the version of strict scrutiny that those cases embody.
I shall consequently ask whether the school boards in Seattle and
Louisville adopted these plans to serve a “compelling governmental
interest” and, if so, whether the plans are “narrowly tailored” to
achieve that interest. If the plans survive this strict review,
they would survive less exacting review a fortiori . Hence,
I conclude that the plans before us pass both parts of the strict
scrutiny test. Consequently I must conclude that the plans here are
permitted under the Constitution.
III Applying the Legal Standard A Compelling Interest The principal interest
advanced in these cases to justify the use of race-based criteria
goes by various names. Sometimes a court refers to it as an
interest in achieving racial “diversity.” Other times a court, like
the plurality here, refers to it as an interest in racial
“balancing.” I have used more general terms to signify that
interest, describing it, for example, as an interest in promoting
or preserving greater racial “integration” of public schools. By
this term, I mean the school districts’ interest in eliminating
school-by-school racial isolation and increasing the degree to
which racial mixture characterizes each of the district’s schools
and each individual student’s public school experience. Regardless of its name,
however, the interest at stake possesses three essential elements.
First, there is a historical and remedial element: an interest in
setting right the consequences of prior conditions of segregation.
This refers back to a time when public schools were highly
segregated, often as a result of legal or administrative policies
that facilitated racial segregation in public schools. It is an
interest in continuing to combat the remnants of segregation caused
in whole or in part by these school-related policies, which have
often affected not only schools, but also housing patterns,
employment practices, economic conditions, and social attitudes. It
is an interest in maintaining hard-won gains. And it has its roots
in preventing what gradually may become the de facto resegregation of America’s public schools. See Part I, supra , at 4; Appendix A, infra. See also ante , at 17 (opinion of Kennedy, J.) (“This Nation has a
moral and ethical obligation to fulfill its historic commitment to
creating an integrated society that ensures equal opportunity for
all of its children”).
Second, there is an educational element: an
interest in overcoming the adverse educational effects produced by
and associated with highly segregated schools. Cf. Grutter , 539 U. S. , at 345 (Ginsburg, J.,
concurring). Studies suggest that children taken from those schools
and placed in integrated settings often show positive academic
gains. See, e.g. , Powell, Living and Learning: Linking
Housing and Education, in Pursuit of a Dream Deferred: Linking
Housing and Education Policy 15, 35 (J. Powell, G. Kearney, &
V. Kay eds. 2001) (hereinafter Powell); Hallinan, Diversity Effects
on Student Outcomes: Social Science Evidence, 59 Ohio St.
L. J. 733, 741–742 (1998) (hereinafter Hallinan).
Other studies reach different conclusions.
See, e.g. , D. Armor, Forced Justice (1995). See also ante , at 15–17 (Thomas, J., concurring). But the evidence
supporting an educational interest in racially integrated schools
is well established and strong enough to permit a democratically
elected school board reasonably to determine that this interest is
a compelling one.
Research suggests, for example, that black
children from segregated educational environments significantly
increase their achievement levels once they are placed in a more
integrated setting. Indeed in Louisville itself the achievement gap
between black and white elementary school students grew
substantially smaller (by seven percentage points) after the
integration plan was implemented in 1975. See Powell 35.
Conversely, to take another example, evidence from a district in
Norfolk, Virginia, shows that resegregated schools led to a decline
in the achievement test scores of children of all races. Ibid .
One commentator, reviewing dozens of studies
of the educational benefits of desegregated schooling, found that
the studies have provided “remarkably consistent” results, showing
that: (1) black students’ educational achievement is improved in
integrated schools as compared to racially isolated schools, (2)
black students’ educational achievement is improved in integrated
classes, and (3) the earlier that black students are removed from
racial isolation, the better their educational outcomes. See
Hallinan 741–742. Multiple studies also indicate that black alumni
of integrated schools are more likely to move into occupations
traditionally closed to African-Americans, and to earn more money
in those fields. See, e.g. , Schofield, Review of Research
on School Desegregation’s Impact on Elementary and Secondary School
Students, in Handbook of Research on Multicultural Education 597,
606–607 (J. Banks & C. Banks eds. 1995). Cf. W. Bowen & D.
Bok, The Shape of the River 118 (1998) (hereinafter Bowen &
Bok).
Third, there is a democratic element: an
interest in producing an educational environment that reflects the
“pluralistic society” in which our children will live. Swann , 402 U. S., at 16. It is an interest in helping our
children learn to work and play together with children of different
racial backgrounds. It is an interest in teaching children to
engage in the kind of cooperation among Americans of all races that
is necessary to make a land of three hundred million people one
Nation.
Again, data support this insight. See, e.g. , Hallinan 745; Quillian & Campbell, Beyond Black
and White: The Present and Future of Multiracial Friendship
Segregation, 68 Am. Sociological Rev. 540, 541 (2003) (hereinafter
Quillian & Campbell); Dawkins & Braddock, The Continuing
Significance of Desegregation: School Racial Composition and
African American Inclusion in American Society, 63 J. Negro Ed.
394, 401–403 (1994) (hereinafter Dawkins & Braddock); Wells
& Crain, Perpetuation Theory and the Long-Term Effects of
School Desegregation, 64 Rev. Educational Research 531, 550 (1994)
(hereinafter Wells & Crain).
There are again studies that offer contrary
conclusions. See, e.g. , Schofield, School Desegregation
and Intergroup Relations, in 17 Review of Research in Education 356
(G. Grant ed. 1991). See also ante , at 22–23 (Thomas, J.,
concurring). Again, however, the evidence supporting a democratic
interest in racially integrated schools is firmly established and
sufficiently strong to permit a school board to determine, as this
Court has itself often found, that this interest is compelling.
For example, one study documented that “black
and white students in desegregated schools are less racially
prejudiced than those in segregated schools,” and that “interracial
contact in desegregated schools leads to an increase in interracial
sociability and friendship.” Hallinan 745. See also Quillian &
Campbell 541. Cf. Bowen & Bok 155. Other studies have found
that both black and white students who attend integrated schools
are more likely to work in desegregated companies after graduation
than students who attended racially isolated schools. Dawkins &
Braddock 401–403; Wells & Crain 550. Further research has shown
that the desegregation of schools can help bring adult communities
together by reducing segregated housing. Cities that have
implemented successful school desegregation plans have witnessed
increased interracial contact and neighborhoods that tend to become
less racially segregated. Dawkins & Braddock 403. These effects
not only reinforce the prior gains of integrated primary and
secondary education; they also foresee a time when there is less
need to use race-conscious criteria.
Moreover, this Court from Swann to Grutter has treated these civic effects as an important
virtue of racially diverse education. See, e.g. , Swann , supra , at 16; Seattle School Dist. No.
1 , 458 U. S., at 472–473. In Grutter, in the context
of law school admissions, we found that these types of interests
were, constitutionally speaking, “compelling.” See 539 U. S., at
330 (recognizing that Michigan Law School’s race-conscious
admissions policy “promotes cross-racial understanding, helps to
break down racial stereotypes, and enables [students] to better
understand persons of different races,” and pointing out that “the
skills needed in today’s increasingly global marketplace can only
be developed through exposure to widely diverse people, cultures,
ideas, and viewpoints” (internal quotation marks omitted;
alteration in original)).
In light of this Court’s conclusions in Grutter, the “compelling” nature of these interests in the
context of primary and secondary public education follows here a fortiori . Primary and secondary schools are where the
education of this Nation’s children begins, where each of us begins
to absorb those values we carry with us to the end of our days. As
Justice Marshall said, “unless our children begin to learn
together, there is little hope that our people will ever learn to
live together.” Milliken v. Bradley , 418 U. S. 717 , 783
(1974) (dissenting opinion).
And it was Brown, after all, focusing
upon primary and secondary schools, not Sweatt v. Painter , 339 U. S. 629 (1950),
focusing on law schools, or McLaurin v. Oklahoma State
Regents for Higher Ed. , 339 U. S. 637 (1950),
focusing on graduate schools, that affected so deeply not only
Americans but the world. R. Kluger, Simple Justice: The History of Brown v. Board of Education and Black America’s
Struggle for Equality, p. x (1975) (arguing that perhaps no other
Supreme Court case has “affected more directly the minds, hearts,
and daily lives of so many Americans”); Patterson, Brown v. Board of Education xxvii (2001) (identifying Brown as “the most eagerly awaited and dramatic judicial
decision of modern times”). See also Parents Involved VII, 426 F. 3d, at 1194 (Kozinski, J., concurring); Strauss,
Discriminatory Intent and the Taming of Brown , 56 U. Chi.
L. Rev. 935, 937 (1989) (calling Brown “the Supreme
Court’s greatest anti-discrimination decision”); Brief for United
States as Amicus Curiae in Brown, 347
U. S. 483 ; Dudziak, Brown as a Cold War Case, 91 J.
Am. Hist. 32 (2004); A Great Decision, Hindustan Times (New Dehli,
May 20, 1954), p. 5; USA Takes Positive Step, West African
Pilot (Lagos, May 22, 1954), p. 2 (stating that Brown is
an acknowledgment that the “United States should set an example for
all other nations by taking the lead in removing from its national
life all signs and traces of racial intolerance, arrogance or
discrimination”). Hence, I am not surprised that Justice Kennedy
finds that, “a district may consider it a compelling interest to
achieve a diverse student population,” including a racially diverse population. Ante , at 17–18.
The compelling interest at issue here, then,
includes an effort to eradicate the remnants, not of general
“societal discrimination,” ante , at 23 (plurality
opinion), but of primary and secondary school segregation, see supra , at 7, 14; it includes an effort to create school
environments that provide better educational opportunities for all
children; it includes an effort to help create citizens better
prepared to know, to understand, and to work with people of all
races and backgrounds, thereby furthering the kind of democratic
government our Constitution foresees. If an educational interest
that combines these three elements is not “compelling,” what
is?
The majority acknowledges that in prior cases
this Court has recognized at least two interests as compelling: an
interest in “remedying the effects of past intentional
discrimination,” and an interest in “diversity in higher
education.” Ante , at 12, 13. But the plurality does not
convincingly explain why those interests do not constitute a
“compelling interest” here. How do the remedial interests here
differ in kind from those at issue in the voluntary desegregation
efforts that Attorney General Kennedy many years ago described in
his letter to the President? Supra , at 19–20. How do the
educational and civic interests differ in kind from those that
underlie and justify the racial “diversity” that the law school
sought in Grutter , where this Court found a compelling
interest?
The plurality tries to draw a distinction by
reference to the well-established conceptual difference between de jure segregation (“segregation by state action”) and de facto segregation (“racial imbalance caused by other
factors”). Ante , at 28. But that distinction concerns what
the Constitution requires school boards to do, not what it permits them to do. Compare, e.g. , Green, 391 U. S., at 437–438 (“School boards … operating
state-compelled dual systems” have an “affirmative duty to take
whatever steps might be necessary to convert to a unitary system in
which racial discrimination would be eliminated root and branch”),
with, e.g. , Milliken , 418 U. S., at 745 (the
Constitution does not impose a duty to desegregate upon districts
that have not been “shown to have committed any constitutional
violation”).
The opinions cited by the plurality to justify
its reliance upon the de jure/de facto distinction only
address what remedial measures a school district may be
constitutionally required to undertake. See, e.g. , Freeman v. Pitts , 503 U. S. 467 , 495
(1992). As to what is permitted , nothing in our equal
protection law suggests that a State may right only those wrongs
that it committed. No case of this Court has ever relied upon the de jure/de facto distinction in order to limit what a
school district is voluntarily allowed to do. That is what is at
issue here. And Swann , McDaniel, Crawford , North Carolina Bd. of Ed. , Harris , and Bustop made one thing clear: significant as the difference
between de jure and de facto segregation may be
to the question of what a school district must do, that
distinction is not germane to the question of what a school
district may do.
Nor does any precedent indicate, as the
plurality suggests with respect to Louisville, ante , at
29, that remedial interests vanish the day after a federal court
declares that a district is “unitary.” Of course, Louisville
adopted those portions of the plan at issue here before a
court declared Louisville “unitary.” Moreover, in Freeman ,
this Court pointed out that in “one sense of the term, vestiges of
past segregation by state decree do remain in our society and in
our schools. Past wrongs to the black race, wrongs committed by the
State and in its name, are a stubborn fact of history. And stubborn
facts of history linger and persist.” 503 U. S., at 495. See also ante , at 15 (opinion of Kennedy, J.). I do not understand
why this Court’s cases, which rest the significance of a “unitary”
finding in part upon the wisdom and desirability of returning
schools to local control, should deprive those local officials of
legal permission to use means they once found necessary to
combat persisting injustices.
For his part, Justice Thomas faults my
citation of various studies supporting the view that school
districts can find compelling educational and civic interests in
integrating their public schools. See ante , at 15–17, 23
(concurring opinion). He is entitled of course to his own opinion
as to which studies he finds convincing—although it bears mention
that even the author of some of Justice Thomas’ preferred studies
has found some evidence linking integrated learning
environments to increased academic achievement. Cf. ante ,
at 15–17 (opinion of Thomas, J.) (citing Armor & Rossell,
Desegregation and Resegregation in the Public Schools, in Beyond
the Color Line 239 (A. Thernstrom & S. Thernstrom eds. 2002);
Brief for Armor et al. as Amici Curiae , with
Rosen, Perhaps Not All Affirmative Action is Created Equal,
N. Y. Times, June 11, 2006 (quoting David Armor as commenting
“ ‘[w]e did find the [racial] achievement gap changing significantly ’ ” and acknowledging that he
“ ‘did find a modest association for math but not reading in
terms of racial composition and achievement, but there’s a big
state variation’ ” (emphasis added)). If we are to insist upon
unanimity in the social science literature before finding a
compelling interest, we might never find one. I believe only that
the Constitution allows democratically elected school boards to
make up their own minds as to how best to include people of all
races in one America.
B Narrow Tailoring I next ask whether the plans
before us are “narrowly tailored” to achieve these “compelling”
objectives. I shall not accept the school board’s assurances on
faith, cf. Miller v. Johnson , 515 U. S. 900 , 920
(1995), and I shall subject the “tailoring” of their plans to
“rigorous judicial review.” Grutter , 539 U. S., at 388
(Kennedy, J., dissenting). Several factors, taken together,
nonetheless lead me to conclude that the boards’ use of
race-conscious criteria in these plans passes even the strictest
“tailoring” test.
First, the race-conscious
criteria at issue only help set the outer bounds of broad ranges. Cf. id., at 390 (Kennedy, J., dissenting)
(expressing concern about “narrow fluctuation band[s]”). They
constitute but one part of plans that depend primarily upon other,
nonracial elements. To use race in this way is not to set a
forbidden “quota.” See id., at 335 (“Properly understood,
a ‘quota’ is a program in which a certain fixed number or
proportion of opportunities are ‘reserved exclusively for certain
minority groups’ ” (quoting Croson , 488 U. S., at
496)).
In fact, the defining feature of both plans is
greater emphasis upon student choice. In Seattle, for example, in
more than 80% of all cases, that choice alone determines which high
schools Seattle’s ninth graders will attend. After ninth grade,
students can decide voluntarily to transfer to a preferred district
high school (without any consideration of race-conscious criteria). Choice , therefore, is the “predominant factor” in these
plans. Race is not. See Grutter , supra ,
at 393 (Kennedy, J., dissenting) (allowing consideration of race
only if it does “not become a predominant factor”).
Indeed, the race-conscious ranges at issue in
these cases often have no effect, either because the particular
school is not oversubscribed in the year in question, or because
the racial makeup of the school falls within the broad range, or
because the student is a transfer applicant or has a sibling at the
school. In these respects, the broad ranges are less like a quota
and more like the kinds of “useful starting points” that this Court
has consistently found permissible, even when they set boundaries
upon voluntary transfers, and even when they are based upon a
community’s general population. See, e.g. , North
Carolina Bd. of Ed. v. Swann , 402 U. S. 43 , 46 (1971) (no “absolute
prohibition against [the] use” of mathematical ratios as a
“starting point”); Swann , 402 U. S., at 24–25 (approving
the use of a ratio reflecting “the racial composition of the whole
school system” as a “useful starting point,” but not as an
“inflexible requirement”). Cf. United States v. Montgomery County Bd. of Ed. , 395 U. S. 225 , 232
(1969) (approving a lower court desegregation order that “provided
that the [school] board must move toward a goal under which ‘in
each school the ratio of white to Negro faculty members is
substantially the same as it is throughout the system,’ ” and
“immediately” requiring “[t]he ratio of Negro to white teachers” in
each school to be equal to “the ratio of Negro to white teachers in
… the system as a whole”).
Second, broad-range limits on voluntary school
choice plans are less burdensome, and hence more narrowly tailored,
see Grutter, supra , at 341, than other race-conscious
restrictions this Court has previously approved. See, e.g. , Swann , supra , at 26–27; Montgomery Co. Bd. of Ed. , supra , at 232. Indeed,
the plans before us are more narrowly tailored than the
race-conscious admission plans that this Court approved in Grutter . Here, race becomes a factor only in a fraction of
students’ non-merit-based assignments—not in large numbers of
students’ merit-based applications. Moreover, the effect of
applying race-conscious criteria here affects potentially
disadvantaged students less severely, not more
severely, than the criteria at issue in Grutter .
Disappointed students are not rejected from a State’s flagship
graduate program; they simply attend a different one of the
district’s many public schools, which in aspiration and in fact are
substantially equal. Cf. Wygant , 476 U. S., at 283. And,
in Seattle, the disadvantaged student loses at most one year at the
high school of his choice. One will search Grutter in vain
for similarly persuasive evidence of narrow tailoring as the school
districts have presented here.
Third, the manner in which the school boards
developed these plans itself reflects “narrow tailoring.” Each plan
was devised to overcome a history of segregated public schools.
Each plan embodies the results of local experience and community
consultation. Each plan is the product of a process that has sought
to enhance student choice, while diminishing the need for mandatory
busing. And each plan’s use of race-conscious elements is diminished compared to the use of race in preceding
integration plans.
The school boards’ widespread consultation,
their experimentation with numerous other plans, indeed, the
40-year history that Part I sets forth, make clear that plans that
are less explicitly race-based are unlikely to achieve the board’s
“compelling” objectives. The history of each school system reveals
highly segregated schools, followed by remedial plans that involved
forced busing, followed by efforts to attract or retain students
through the use of plans that abandoned busing and replaced it with
greater student choice. Both cities once tried to achieve more
integrated schools by relying solely upon measures such as redrawn
district boundaries, new school building construction, and
unrestricted voluntary transfers. In neither city did these prior
attempts prove sufficient to achieve the city’s integration goals.
See Parts I–A and I–B, supra , at 6–18 . Moreover, giving some degree of weight to a
local school board’s knowledge, expertise, and concerns in these
particular matters is not inconsistent with rigorous judicial
scrutiny. It simply recognizes that judges are not well suited to
act as school administrators. Indeed, in the context of school
desegregation, this Court has repeatedly stressed the importance of
acknowledging that local school boards better understand their own
communities and have a better knowledge of what in practice will
best meet the educational needs of their pupils. See Milliken , 418 U. S., at 741–42 (“No single tradition in
public education is more deeply rooted than local control over the
operation of schools; local autonomy has long been thought
essential both to the maintenance of community concern and support
for public schools and to quality of the educational process”). See
also San Antonio Independent School Dist. v. Rodriguez , 411 U. S. 1 , 49–50 (1973)
(extolling local control for “the opportunity it offers for
participation in the decisionmaking process that determines how . .
. local tax dollars will be spent. Each locality is free to tailor
local programs to local needs. Pluralism also affords some
opportunity for experimentation, innovation, and a healthy
competition for educational excellence”); Epperson v. Arkansas , 393 U. S. 97 , 104 (1968)
(“Judicial interposition in the operation of the public school
system of the Nation raises problems requiring care and restraint.
. . . By and large, public education in our Nation is committed to
the control of state and local authorities”); Brown v. Board of Education , 349 U. S. 294 , 299
(1955) (Brown II) (“Full implementation of these
constitutional principles may require solution of varied local
school problems. School authorities have the primary responsibility
for elucidating, assessing, and solving these problems; courts will
have to consider whether the action of school authorities
constitutes good faith implementation of the governing
constitutional principles”).
Experience in Seattle and Louisville is
consistent with experience elsewhere. In 1987, the U. S. Commission
on Civil Rights studied 125 large school districts seeking
integration. It reported that most districts—92 of them, in
fact—adopted desegregation policies that combined two or more
highly race-conscious strategies, for example, rezoning or pairing.
See Welch 83–91.
Having looked at dozens of amicus briefs, public reports, news stories, and the records in many of
this Court’s prior cases, which together span 50 years of
desegregation history in school districts across the Nation, I have
discovered many examples of districts that sought integration
through explicitly race-conscious methods, including mandatory
busing. Yet, I have found no example or model that would
permit this Court to say to Seattle and to Louisville: “Here is an
instance of a desegregation plan that is likely to achieve your
objectives and also makes less use of race-conscious criteria than
your plans.” And, if the plurality cannot suggest such a model—and
it cannot—then it seeks to impose a “narrow tailoring” requirement
that in practice would never be met.
Indeed, if there is no such plan, or if such
plans are purely imagined, it is understandable why, as the
plurality notes, ante , at 27, Seattle school officials
concentrated on diminishing the racial component of their
districts’ plan, but did not pursue eliminating that element
entirely. For the plurality now to insist as it does, ante , at 27–28, that these school districts ought to have
said so officially is either to ask for the superfluous (if they
need only make explicit what is implicit) or to demand the
impossible (if they must somehow provide more proof that there is
no hypothetical other plan that could work as well as
theirs). I am not aware of any case in which this Court has read
the “narrow tailoring” test to impose such a requirement. Cf. People Who Care v. Rockford Bd. of Ed. School Dist.
No. 205 , 961 F. 2d 1335, 1338 (CA7 1992) (Easterbrook,
J.) (“Would it be necessary to adjudicate the obvious before
adopting (or permitting the parties to agree on) a remedy . . .
?”).
The plurality also points to the school
districts’ use of numerical goals based upon the racial breakdown
of the general school population, and it faults the districts for
failing to prove that no other set of numbers will work .
See ante , at 18–20. The plurality refers to no case in
support of its demand. Nor is it likely to find such a case. After
all, this Court has in many cases explicitly permitted districts to
use target ratios based upon the district’s underlying population.
See, e.g. , Swann , 402 U. S., at 24–25; North
Carolina Bd. of Ed. , 402 U. S., at 46; Montgomery County
Bd. of Ed. , 395 U. S., at 232. The reason is obvious: In
Seattle, where the overall student population is 41% white,
permitting 85% white enrollment at a single school would make it
much more likely that other schools would have very few white
students, whereas in Jefferson County, with a 60% white enrollment,
one school with 85% white students would be less likely to skew
enrollments elsewhere.
Moreover, there is research-based evidence
supporting, for example, that a ratio no greater than 50%
minority—which is Louisville’s starting point, and as close as
feasible to Seattle’s starting point—is helpful in limiting the
risk of “white flight.” See Orfield, Metropolitan School
Desegregation: Impacts on Metropolitan Society, in Pursuit of a
Dream Deferred: Linking Housing and Education Policy 121, 125.
Federal law also assumes that a similar target percentage will help
avoid detrimental “minority group isolation.” See No Child Left
Behind Act of 2001, Title V, Part C, 115 Stat. 1806, 20 U.
S. C. §7231 et seq. (2000 ed., Supp. IV); 34 CFR
§§280.2, 280.4 (2006) (implementing regulations). What other
numbers are the boards to use as a “starting point”? Are they to
spend days, weeks, or months seeking independently to validate the
use of ratios that this Court has repeatedly authorized in prior
cases? Are they to draw numbers out of thin air? These districts
have followed this Court’s holdings and advice in “tailoring” their
plans. That, too, strongly supports the lawfulness of their
methods.
Nor could the school districts have
accomplished their desired aims ( e.g. , avoiding forced
busing, countering white flight, maintaining racial diversity) by
other means. Nothing in the extensive history of desegregation
efforts over the past 50 years gives the districts, or this Court,
any reason to believe that another method is possible to accomplish
these goals. Nevertheless, Justice Kennedy suggests that school
boards:
“may pursue the goal of bringing together students
of diverse backgrounds and races through other means, including
strategic site selection of new schools; drawing attendance zones
with general recognition of the demographics of neighborhoods;
allocating resources for special programs; recruiting students and
faculty in a targeted fashion; and tracking enrollments,
performance, and other statistics by race.” Ante , at
8.
But, as to “strategic site selection,” Seattle has
built one new high school in the last 44 years (and that
specialized school serves only 300 students). In fact, six of the
Seattle high schools involved in this case were built by the
1920’s; the other four were open by the early 1960’s. See generally
N. Thompson & C. Marr, Building for Learning: Seattle Public
Schools Histories, 1862–2000 (2002). As to “drawing” neighborhood
“attendance zones” on a racial basis, Louisville tried it, and it
worked only when forced busing was also part of the plan. See supra , at 12–14. As to “allocating resources for special
programs,” Seattle and Louisville have both experimented with this;
indeed, these programs are often referred to as “magnet schools,”
but the limited desegregation effect of these efforts extends at
most to those few schools to which additional resources are
granted. In addition, there is no evidence from the experience of
these school districts that it will make any meaningful impact. See
Brief for Respondents in No. 05–908, p. 42. As to “recruiting
faculty” on the basis of race, both cities have tried, but only as
one part of a broader program. As to “tracking enrollments,
performance and other statistics by race,” tracking reveals the problem; it does not cure it.
Justice Kennedy sets forth two
additional concerns related to “narrow tailoring.” In respect to
Louisville, he says first that officials stated (1) that
kindergarten assignments are not subject to the race-conscious
guidelines, and (2) that the child at issue here was denied
permission to attend the kindergarten he wanted because of those
guidelines. Both, he explains, cannot be true. He adds that this
confusion illustrates that Louisville’s assignment plan (or its
explanation of it to this Court) is insufficiently precise in
respect to “who makes the decisions,” “oversight,” “the precise
circumstances in which an assignment decision” will be made; and
“which of two similarly situated children will be subjected to a
given race-based decision.” Ante , at 4.
The record suggests, however, that the child
in question was not assigned to the school he preferred because he
missed the kindergarten application deadline. See App. in 05–915,
p. 20. After he had enrolled and after the academic year had begun,
he then applied to transfer to his preferred school after the
kindergarten assignment deadline had passed, id. , at 21,
possibly causing school officials to treat his late request as an
application to transfer to the first grade, in respect to which the
guidelines apply. I am not certain just how the remainder of
Justice Kennedy’s concerns affect the lawfulness of the Louisville
program, for they seem to be failures of explanation, not of
administration. But Louisville should be able to answer the
relevant questions on remand.
Justice Kennedy’s second concern is directly
related to the merits of Seattle’s plan: Why does Seattle’s plan
group Asian-Americans, Hispanic-Americans, Native-Americans, and
African-Americans together, treating all as similar minorities? Ante , at 6–7. The majority suggests that Seattle’s
classification system could permit a school to be labeled “diverse”
with a 50% Asian-American and 50% white student body, and no
African-American students, Hispanic students, or students of other
ethnicity. Ante , at 6; ante , at 15–16 (opinion of
the Court).
The 50/50 hypothetical has no support in the
record here; it is conjured from the imagination. In fact, Seattle
apparently began to treat these different minority groups alike in
response to the federal Emergency School Aid Act’s requirement that
it do so. Siqueland 116–117. See also Hanawalt 31; Pub. L. 95–561,
Tit. VI (1978) (prescribing percentage enrollment requirements for
“minority” students); Siqueland 55 (discussing HEW definition of
“minority”). Moreover, maintaining this federally mandated system
of classification makes sense insofar as Seattle’s experience
indicates that the relevant circumstances in respect to each of
these different minority groups are roughly similar, e.g. ,
in terms of residential patterns, and call for roughly similar
responses. This is confirmed by the fact that Seattle has been able
to achieve a desirable degree of diversity without the greater emphasis on race that drawing fine lines among
minority groups would require. Does the plurality’s view of the
Equal Protection Clause mean that courts must give no weight to
such a board determination? Does it insist upon especially strong
evidence supporting inclusion of multiple minority groups in an
otherwise lawful government minority-assistance program? If so, its
interpretation threatens to produce divisiveness among minority
groups that is incompatible with the basic objectives of the
Fourteenth Amendment. Regardless, the plurality cannot object that
the constitutional defect is the individualized use of race and
simultaneously object that not enough account of individuals’ race
has been taken.
Finally, I recognize that the Court seeks to
distinguish Grutter from these cases by claiming that Grutter arose in “ ‘the context of higher
education.’ ” Ante , at 16. But that is not a
meaningful legal distinction. I have explained why I do not believe
the Constitution could possibly find “compelling” the provision of
a racially diverse education for a 23-year-old law student but not
for a 13-year-old high school pupil. See supra , at 46–48.
And I have explained how the plans before us are more narrowly
tailored than those in Grutter . See supra , at 45.
I add that one cannot find a relevant distinction in the fact that
these school districts did not examine the merits of applications
“individual[ly].” See ante , at 13–15. The context here
does not involve admission by merit; a child’s academic, artistic,
and athletic “merits” are not at all relevant to the child’s
placement. These are not affirmative action plans, and hence
“individualized scrutiny” is simply beside the point.
The upshot is that these plans’ specific
features—(1) their limited and historically-diminishing use of
race, (2) their strong reliance upon other non-race-conscious
elements, (3) their history and the manner in which the districts
developed and modified their approach, (4) the comparison with
prior plans, and (5) the lack of reasonably evident
alternatives—together show that the districts’ plans are “narrowly
tailored” to achieve their “compelling” goals. In sum, the
districts’ race-conscious plans satisfy “strict scrutiny” and are
therefore lawful.
IV Direct Precedent Two additional precedents
more directly related to the plans here at issue reinforce my
conclusion. The first consists of the District Court determination
in the Louisville case when it dissolved its desegregation order
that there was “overwhelming evidence of the Board’s good faith
compliance with the desegregation Decree and its underlying
purposes,” indeed that the Board had “treated the ideal of an
integrated system as much more than a legal obligation—they
consider it a positive, desirable policy and an essential element
of any well-rounded public school education.” Hampton II , 102
F. Supp. 2d, at 370. When the court made this determination in
2000, it did so in the context of the Louisville desegregation plan
that the board had adopted in 1996. That plan, which took effect
before 1996, is the very plan that in all relevant respects is in
effect now and is the subject of the present challenge.
No one claims that (the relevant
portion of) Louisville’s plan was unlawful in 1996 when Louisville
adopted it. To the contrary, there is every reason to believe that
it represented part of an effort to implement the 1978
desegregation order. But if the plan was lawful when it was first
adopted and if it was lawful the day before the District Court
dissolved its order, how can the plurality now suggest that it
became unlawful the following day? Is it conceivable that
the Constitution, implemented through a court desegregation order,
could permit (perhaps require ) the district to make use of
a race-conscious plan the day before the order was dissolved and
then forbid the district to use the identical plan the day
after? See id., at 380 (“The very analysis for dissolving
desegregation decrees supports continued maintenance of a
desegregated system as a compelling state interest”). The Equal
Protection Clause is not incoherent. And federal courts would
rightly hesitate to find unitary status if the consequences of the
ruling were so dramatically disruptive.
Second, Seattle School Dist. No. 1 , 458
U. S. 457 , is directly on point. That case involves the
original Seattle Plan, a more heavily race-conscious
predecessor of the very plan now before us. In Seattle
School Dist. No. 1 , this Court struck down a state referendum
that effectively barred implementation of Seattle’s desegregation
plan and “burden[ed] all future attempts to integrate Washington
schools in districts throughout the State.” Id. , at
462–463, 483. Because the referendum would have prohibited the
adoption of a school-integration plan that involved mandatory
busing, and because it would have imposed a special burden on
school integration plans (plans that sought to integrate previously
segregated schools), the Court found it unconstitutional. Id ., at 483–487.
In reaching this conclusion, the Court did not
directly address the constitutional merits of the underlying
Seattle plan. But it explicitly cited Swann ’s statement
that the Constitution permitted a local district to adopt such a
plan. 458 U. S., at 472, n. 15. It also cited to Justice
Powell’s opinion in Bakke , approving of the
limited use of race-conscious criteria in a university-admissions
“affirmative action” case. 458 U. S., at 472, n. 15 . In
addition, the Court stated that “[a]ttending an ethnically diverse
school,” id. , at 473, could help prepare “minority
children for citizenship in our pluralistic society,” hopefully
“teaching members of the racial majority to live in harmony and
mutual respect with children of minority heritage.” Ibid. (internal quotation marks and citation omitted).
It is difficult to believe that the Court that
held unconstitutional a referendum that would have interfered with
the implementation of this plan thought that the integration plan
it sought to preserve was itself an unconstitutional plan.
And if Seattle School Dist. No. 1 is premised upon the
constitutionality of the original Seattle Plan, it is equally
premised upon the constitutionality of the present plan, for the
present plan is the Seattle Plan, modified only insofar as
it places even less emphasis on race-conscious elements
than its predecessors.
It is even more difficult to accept the
plurality’s contrary view, namely that the underlying plan was
unconstitutional. If that is so, then all of Seattle’s
earlier (even more race-conscious) plans must also have been
unconstitutional. That necessary implication of the plurality’s
position strikes the 13th chime of the clock. How could the
plurality adopt a constitutional standard that would hold
unconstitutional large numbers of race-conscious integration plans
adopted by numerous school boards over the past 50 years while
remaining true to this Court’s desegregation precedent?
V Consequences The Founders meant the
Constitution as a practical document that would transmit its basic
values to future generations through principles that remained
workable over time. Hence it is important to consider the potential
consequences of the plurality’s approach, as measured against the
Constitution’s objectives. To do so provides
further reason to believe that the plurality’s approach is legally
unsound. For one thing, consider the
effect of the plurality’s views on the parties before us and on
similar school districts throughout the Nation. Will Louisville and
all similar school districts have to return to systems like
Louisville’s initial 1956 plan, which did not consider race at all?
See supra , at 12. That initial 1956 plan proved ineffective.
Sixteen years into the plan, 14 of 19 middle and high schools
remained almost totally white or almost totally black. Ibid. The districts’ past and current plans are not
unique. They resemble other plans, promulgated by hundreds of local
school boards, which have attempted a variety of desegregation
methods that have evolved over time in light of experience. A 1987
Civil Rights Commission Study of 125 school districts in the Nation
demonstrated the breadth and variety of desegregation plans:
“The [study] documents almost 300
desegregation plans that were implemented between 1961 and 1985.
The degree of heterogeneity within these districts is immediately
apparent. They are located in every region of the country and range
in size from Las Cruces, New Mexico, with barely over 15,000
students attending 23 schools in 1968, to New York City, with more
than one million students in 853 schools. The sample includes
districts in urban areas of all sizes, suburbs ( e.g. ,
Arlington County, Virginia) and rural areas ( e.g. ,
Jefferson Parish, Louisiana, and Raleigh County, West Virginia). It
contains 34 countywide districts with central cities (the 11
Florida districts fit this description, plus Clark County, Nevada
and others) and a small number of consolidated districts (New
Castle County, Delaware and Jefferson County, Kentucky).
“The districts also vary in their racial
compositions and levels of segregation. Initial plans were
implemented in Mobile, Alabama and Mecklenburg County, North
Carolina, and in a number of other southern districts in the face
of total racial segregation. At the other extreme, Santa Clara,
California had a relatively even racial distribution prior to its
1979 desegregation plan. When the 1965 plan was designed for
Harford County, Maryland, the district was 92 percent white.
Compton, California, on the other hand, became over 99 percent
black in the 1980s, while Buffalo, New York had a virtual 50–50
split between white and minority students prior to its 1977
plan.
“It is not surprising to find a large number
of different desegregation strategies in a sample with this much
variation.” Welch 23 (footnotes omitted).
A majority of these desegregation techniques
explicitly considered a student’s race. See id. , at 24–28.
Transfer plans, for example, allowed students to shift from a
school in which they were in the racial majority to a school in
which they would be in a racial minority. Some districts, such as
Richmond, California, and Buffalo, New York, permitted only
“one-way” transfers, in which only black students attending
predominantly black schools were permitted to transfer to
designated receiver schools. Id. , at 25. Fifty-three of
the 125 studied districts used transfers as a component of their
plans. Id., at 83–91.
At the state level, 46 States and
Puerto Rico have adopted policies that encourage or require local
school districts to enact interdistrict or intradistrict open
choice plans. Eight of those States condition approval of transfers
to another school or district on whether the transfer will produce
increased racial integration. Eleven other States require local
boards to deny transfers that are not in compliance with the local
school board’s desegre- gation plans. See Education Commission of
the States, Open Enrollment: 50-State Report (2007), online at
http://mb2.ecs.org/reports/Report.aspx?id=268.
Arkansas, for example, provides by statute
that “[n]o student may transfer to a nonresident district where the
percentage of enrollment for the student’s race exceeds that
percentage in the student’s resident district.” Ark. Code Ann.
§6–18–206(f)(1), as amended 2007 Ark. Gen. Acts 552 (2007). An Ohio
statute provides, in respect to student choice, that each school
district must establish “[p]rocedures to ensure that an appropriate
racial balance is maintained in the district schools.” Ohio Rev.
Code Ann. §3313.98(B)(2)(b)(iii) (Lexis Supp. 2006). Ohio adds that
a “district may object to the enrollment of a native student in an
adjacent or other district in order to maintain an appropriate
racial balance.” §3313.98 (F)(1)(a).
A Connecticut statute states that its student
choice program will seek to “preserve racial and ethnic balance.”
Conn. Gen. Stat. §10–266aa(b)(2) (2007). Connecticut law requires
each school district to submit racial group population figures to
the State Board of Education. §10–226a. Another Connecticut
regulation provides that “[a]ny school in which the Proportion for
the School falls outside of a range from 25 percentage points less
to 25 percentage points more than the Comparable Proportion for the
School District, shall be determined to be racially imbalanced.”
Conn. Agencies Regs. §10–226e–3(b) (1999). A “racial imbalance”
determination requires the district to submit a plan to correct the
racial imbalance, which plan may include “mandatory pupil
reassignment.” §§10–226e–5(a) and (c)(4).
Interpreting that State’s Constitution, the
Connecticut Supreme Court has held legally inadequate the reliance
by a local school district solely upon some of the techniques
Justice Kennedy today recommends ( e.g. , reallocating
resources, etc.). See Sheff v. O’Neill , 238 Conn.
1, 678 A. 2d 1267 (1996). The State Supreme Court wrote:
“Despite the initiatives undertaken by the defendants to alleviate
the severe racial and ethnic disparities among school districts,
and despite the fact that the defendants did not intend to create
or maintain these disparities, the disparities that continue to
burden the education of the plaintiffs infringe upon their
fundamental state constitutional right to a substantially equal
educational opportunity.” Id. , at 42, 678 A. 2d, at
1289.
At a minimum, the plurality’s views would
threaten a surge of race-based litigation. Hundreds of state and
federal statutes and regulations use racial classifications for
educational or other purposes. See supra , at 27. In many
such instances, the contentious force of legal challenges to these
classifications, meritorious or not, would displace earlier
calm.
The wide variety of different integration
plans that school districts use throughout the Nation suggests that
the problem of racial segregation in schools, including de
facto segregation, is difficult to solve. The fact that many
such plans have used explicitly racial criteria suggests that such
criteria have an important, sometimes necessary, role to play. The
fact that the controlling opinion would make a school district’s
use of such criteria often unlawful (and the plurality’s
“colorblind” view would make such use always unlawful) suggests
that today’s opinion will require setting aside the laws of several
States and many local communities.
As I have pointed out, supra , at 4, de facto resegregation is on the rise. See Appendix A, infra . It is reasonable to conclude that such
resegregation can create serious educational, social, and civic
problems. See supra, at 37–45. Given the conditions in
which school boards work to set policy, see supra, at
20–21, they may need all of the means presently at their disposal
to combat those problems. Yet the plurality would deprive them of
at least one tool that some districts now consider vital—the
limited use of broad race-conscious student population ranges.
I use the words “may need” here deliberately.
The plurality, or at least those who follow Justice Thomas’
“ ‘color-blind’ ” approach, see ante , at 26–27
(Thomas, J., concurring); Grutter , 539 U. S., at 353–354
(Thomas, J., concurring in part and dissenting in part), may feel
confident that, to end invidious discrimination, one must end all governmental use of race-conscious criteria including
those with inclusive objectives. See ante , at 40–41
(plurality opinion); see also ante , at 26 (Thomas, J.,
concurring). By way of contrast, I do not claim to know how best to
stop harmful discrimination; how best to create a society that
includes all Americans; how best to overcome our serious problems
of increasing de facto segregation, troubled inner city
schooling, and poverty correlated with race. But, as a judge, I do
know that the Constitution does not authorize judges to dictate
solutions to these problems. Rather, the Constitution creates a
democratic political system through which the people themselves
must together find answers. And it is for them to debate how best
to educate the Nation’s children and how best to administer
America’s schools to achieve that aim. The Court should leave them
to their work. And it is for them to decide, to quote the
plurality’s slogan, whether the best “way to stop discrimination on
the basis of race is to stop discriminating on the basis of race.” Ante , at 40–41. See also Parents Involved VII ,
426 F. 3d, at 1222 (Bea, J., dissenting) (“The way to end
racial discrimination is to stop discriminating by race”). That is
why the Equal Protection Clause outlaws invidious discrimination,
but does not similarly forbid all use of race-conscious
criteria.
Until today, this Court understood the
Constitution as affording the people, acting through their elected
representatives, freedom to select the use of “race-conscious”
criteria from among their available options. See Adarand
Constructors, Inc. , 515 U. S., at 237 (“[S]trict scrutiny” in
this context is “[not] ‘strict in theory, but fatal in fact’ ”
(quoting Fullilove , 448 U. S., at 519 (Marshall, J.,
concurring in judgment))). Today, however, the Court restricts (and
some Members would eliminate) that leeway. I fear the consequences
of doing so for the law, for the schools, for the democratic
process, and for America’s efforts to create, out of its diversity,
one Nation.
VI Conclusions To show that the school
assignment plans here meet the requirements of the Constitution, I
have written at exceptional length. But that length is necessary. I
cannot refer to the history of the plans in these cases to justify
the use of race-conscious criteria without describing that history
in full. I cannot rely upon Swann ’s statement that the use of
race-conscious limits is permissible without showing, rather than
simply asserting, that the statement represents a constitutional
principle firmly rooted in federal and state law. Nor can I explain
my disagreement with the Court’s holding and the plurality’s
opinion, without offering a detailed account of the arguments they
propound and the consequences they risk.
Thus, the opinion’s reasoning is
long. But its conclusion is short: The plans before us satisfy the
requirements of the Equal Protection Clause. And it is the
plurality’s opinion, not this dissent that “fails to ground the
result it would reach in law.” Ante , at 28.
Four basic considerations have led me to this
view. First , the histories of Louisville and Seattle
reveal complex circumstances and a long tradition of conscientious
efforts by local school boards to resist racial segregation in
public schools. Segregation at the time of Brown gave way
to expansive remedies that included busing, which in turn gave rise
to fears of white flight and resegregation. For decades now, these
school boards have considered and adopted and revised assignment
plans that sought to rely less upon race, to emphasize greater
student choice, and to improve the conditions of all schools for
all students, no matter the color of their skin, no matter where
they happen to reside. The plans under review—which are less
burdensome, more egalitarian, and more effective than prior
plans—continue in that tradition. And their history reveals school
district goals whose remedial, educational, and democratic elements
are inextricably intertwined each with the others. See Part I, supra , at 2–21. Second , since this Court’s decision in Brown , the law has consistently and unequivocally approved
of both voluntary and compulsory race-conscious measures to combat
segregated schools. The Equal Protection Clause, ratified following
the Civil War, has always distinguished in practice between state
action that excludes and thereby subordinates racial minorities and
state action that seeks to bring together people of all races. From Swann to Grutter , this Court’s decisions have
emphasized this distinction, recognizing that the fate of race
relations in this country depends upon unity among our children,
“for unless our children begin to learn together, there is little
hope that our people will ever learn to live together.” Milliken , 418 U. S., at 783 (Marshall, J., dissenting).
See also C. Sumner, Equality Before the Law: Unconstitutionality of
Separate Colored Schools in Massachusetts, in 2 The Works of
Charles Sumner 327, 371 (1849) (“The law contemplates not only that
all be taught, but that all shall be taught together”). See Part
II, supra , at 21–37. Third , the plans before
us, subjected to rigorous judicial review, are supported by
compelling state interests and are narrowly tailored to accomplish
those goals. Just as diversity in higher education was deemed
compelling in Grutter , diversity in public primary and
secondary schools—where there is even more to gain—must be, a
fortiori , a compelling state interest. Even apart from Grutter , five Members of this Court agree that “avoiding
racial isolation” and “achiev[ing] a diverse student population”
remain today compelling interests. Ante , at 17–18 (opinion
of Kennedy, J.). These interests combine remedial, educational, and
democratic objectives. For the reasons discussed above, however, I
disagree with Justice Kennedy that Seattle and Louisville have not
done enough to demonstrate that their present plans are necessary
to continue upon the path set by Brown . These plans are more “narrowly tailored” than the race-conscious law
school admissions criteria at issue in Grutter . Hence,
their lawfulness follows a fortiori from this Court’s
prior decisions. See Parts III–IV, supra , at 37–57. Fourth , the plurality’s approach
risks serious harm to the law and for the Nation. Its view of the
law rests either upon a denial of the distinction between
exclusionary and inclusive use of race-conscious criteria in the
context of the Equal Protection Clause, or upon such a rigid
application of its “test” that the distinction loses practical
significance. Consequently, the Court’s decision today slows down
and sets back the work of local school boards to bring about
racially diverse schools. See Part V, supra , at 57–63.
Indeed, the consequences of the approach the
Court takes today are serious. Yesterday, the plans under review
were lawful. Today, they are not. Yesterday, the citizens of this
Nation could look for guidance to this Court’s unanimous
pronouncements concerning desegregation. Today, they cannot.
Yesterday, school boards had available to them a full range of
means to combat segregated schools. Today, they do not.
The Court’s decision undermines other basic
institutional principles as well. What has happened to stare
decisis? The history of the plans before us, their educational
importance, their highly limited use of race—all these and
more—make clear that the compelling interest here is stronger than
in Grutter . The plans here are more narrowly tailored than
the law school admissions program there at issue. Hence, applying Grutter ’s strict test, their lawfulness follows a
fortiori . To hold to the contrary is to transform that test
from “strict” to “fatal in fact”—the very opposite of what Grutter said. And what has happened to Swann? To McDaniel? To Crawford? To Harris? To School Committee of Boston? To Seattle School Dist.
No. 1? After decades of vibrant life, they would all, under
the plurality’s logic, be written out of the law.
And what of respect for democratic local
decisionmaking by States and school boards? For several decades
this Court has rested its public school decisions upon Swann ’s basic view that the Constitution grants local
school districts a significant degree of leeway where the inclusive
use of race-conscious criteria is at issue. Now localities will
have to cope with the difficult problems they face (including
resegregation) deprived of one means they may find necessary.
And what of law’s concern to diminish and
peacefully settle conflict among the Nation’s people? Instead of
accommodating different good-faith visions of our country and our
Constitution, today’s holding upsets settled expectations, creates
legal uncertainty, and threatens to produce considerable further
litigation, aggravating race-related conflict.
And what of the long history and moral vision
that the Fourteenth Amendment itself embodies? The plurality cites
in support those who argued in Brown against segregation,
and Justice Thomas likens the approach that I have taken to that of
segregation’s defenders. See ante , at 39–41 (plurality
opinion) (comparing Jim Crow segregation to Seattle and
Louisville’s integration polices); ante , at 28–32 (Thomas,
J., concurring). But segregation policies did not simply tell
schoolchildren “where they could and could not go to school based
on the color of their skin,” ante , at 40 (plurality
opinion); they perpetuated a caste system rooted in the
institutions of slavery and 80 years of legalized subordination.
The lesson of history, see ante , at 39 (plurality
opinion), is not that efforts to continue racial segregation are
constitutionally indistinguishable from efforts to achieve racial
integration. Indeed, it is a cruel distortion of history to compare
Topeka, Kansas, in the 1950’s to Louisville and Seattle in the
modern day—to equate the plight of Linda Brown (who was ordered to
attend a Jim Crow school) to the circumstances of Joshua McDonald
(whose request to transfer to a school closer to home was initially
declined). This is not to deny that there is a cost in applying “a
state-mandated racial label.” Ante , at 17 (Kennedy, J.,
concurring in part and concurring in judgment). But that cost does
not approach, in degree or in kind, the terrible harms of slavery,
the resulting caste system, and 80 years of legal racial
segregation.
* * *
Finally, what of the hope and
promise of Brown? For much of this Nation’s history, the
races remained divided. It was not long ago that people of
different races drank from separate fountains, rode on separate
buses, and studied in separate schools. In this Court’s finest
hour, Brown v. Board of Education challenged this
history and helped to change it. For Brown held out a
promise. It was a promise embodied in three Amendments designed to
make citizens of slaves. It was the promise of true racial
equality—not as a matter of fine words on paper, but as a matter of
everyday life in the Nation’s cities and schools. It was about the
nature of a democracy that must work for all Americans. It sought
one law, one Nation, one people, not simply as a matter of legal
principle but in terms of how we actually live.
Not everyone welcomed this
Court’s decision in Brown . Three years after that decision
was handed down, the Governor of Arkansas ordered state militia to
block the doors of a white schoolhouse so that black children could
not enter. The President of the United States dispatched the 101st
Airborne Division to Little Rock, Arkansas, and federal troops were
needed to enforce a desegregation decree. See Cooper v. Aaron , 358 U.
S. 1 (1958). Today, almost 50 years later, attitudes toward
race in this Nation have changed dramatically. Many parents, white
and black alike, want their children to attend schools with
children of different races. Indeed, the very school districts that
once spurned integration now strive for it. The long history of
their efforts reveals the complexities and difficulties they have
faced. And in light of those challenges, they have asked us not to
take from their hands the instruments they have used to rid their
schools of racial segregation, instruments that they believe are
needed to overcome the problems of cities divided by race and
poverty. The plurality would decline their modest request.
The plurality is wrong to do so. The last
half-century has witnessed great strides toward racial equality,
but we have not yet realized the promise of Brown . To
invalidate the plans under review is to threaten the promise of Brown . The plurality’s position, I fear, would break that
promise. This is a decision that the Court and the Nation will come
to regret.
I must dissent.
APPENDIXES TO OPINION OF Breyer, J. A Resegregation
Trends Percentage of Black Students in
90–100 Percent Nonwhite and Majority Nonwhite Public Schools by
Region, 1950–1954 to 2000, Fall Enrollment Region 1950–1954 1960–1961 1968 1972 1976 1980 1989 1999 2000 Percentage in 90–100%
Nonwhite Schools Northeast — 40 42.7 46.9 51.4 48.7 49.8 50.2 51.2 Border 100 59 60.2 54.7 42.5 37.0 33.7 39.7 39.6 South 100 100 77.8 24.7 22.4 23.0 26.0 31.1 30.9 Midwest 53 56 58.0 57.4 51.1 43.6 40.1 45.0 46.3 West — 27 50.8 42.7 36.3 33.7 26.7 29.9 29.5 U.
S. 64.3 38.7 35.9 33.2 33.8 37.4 37.4 Percentage in
50–100% Nonwhite Schools Northeast — 62 66.8 69.9 72.5 79.9 75.4 77.5 78.3 Border 100 69 71.6 67.2 60.1 59.2 58.0 64.8 67.0 South 100 100 80.9 55.3 54.9 57.1 59.3 67.3 69.0 Midwest 78 80 77.3 75.3 70.3 69.5 69.4 67.9 73.3 West — 69 72.2 68.1 67.4 66.8 67.4 76.7 75.3 U. S. 76.6 63.6 62.4 62.9 64.9 70.1 71.6 Source: C. Clotfelter, After Brown: The
Rise and Retreat of School Desegregation 56 (2004) (Table
2.1). Changes in the Percentage of White Students in
Schools Attended by the Average Black Student by State, 1970–2003
(includes States with 5% or greater enrollment of black students in
1970 and 1980) %
White % White Students in School of Average
Black Student Change 2003 1970 1980 1991 2003 1970–1980 1980–1991 1991–2003 Alabama 60 33 38 35 30 5 -3 -5 Arkansas 70 43 47 44 36 4 -3 -8 California 33 26 28 27 22 2 -1 -5 Connecticut 68 44 40 35 32 -4 -5 -3 Delaware 57 47 69 65 49 22 -4 -16 Florida 51 43 51 43 34 8 -8 -9 Georgia 52 35 38 35 30 3 -3 -5 Illinois 57 15 19 20 19 4 1 -1 Indiana 82 32 39 47 41 7 8 -6 Kansas 76 52 59 58 51 7 -1 -7 Kentucky 87 49 74 42 65 25 -2 -7 Louisiana 48 31 33 32 27 2 -1 -5 Maryland 50 30 35 29 23 5 -6 -6 Massachusetts 75 48 50 45 38 2 -5 -7 Michigan 73 22 23 22 22 1 -1 0 Mississippi 47 30 29 30 26 -1 1 -4 Missouri 78 21 34 40 33 13 6 -7 Nebraska 80 33 66 62 49 33 -4 -13 New
Jersey 58 32 26 26 25 -6 0 -1 New
York 54 29 23 20 18 -6 -3 -2 Nevada 51 56 68 62 38 12 -6 -24 N.
Carolina 58 49 54 51 40 5 -3 -11 Ohio 79 28 43 41 32 15 -2 -9 Oklahoma 61 42 58 51 42 16 -7 -9 Pennsylvania 76 28 29 31 30 1 2 -1 S.
Carolina 54 41 43 42 39 2 -1 -3 Tennessee 73 29 38 36 32 9 -2 -4 Texas 39 31 35 35 27 4 0 -8 Virginia 61 42 47 46 41 5 -1 -5 Wisconsin 79 26 45 39 29 19 -6 -10 Source: G. Orfield & C.
Lee, Racial Transformation and the Changing Nature of Segregation
18 (Table 8) (Jan. 2006), (Civil Rights Project), online at
http://www.civilrightspro
ject.harvard.edu/research/deseg/Racial_Transformation.pdf. Percentage of
White Students in Schools Attended by the Average Black Student,
1968–2000 [Graphic omitted; see
printed
opinion] Source:
Modified from E. Frankenberg, C. Lee, & G. Orfield, A
Multiracial Society with Segregated Schools: Are We Losing the
Dream?, p. 30, fig. 5 (Jan. 2003), online at
http://www.civilrightsproject.harvard.edu/ research / reseg03 /Are WeLosingtheDream.pdf
(Frankenberg, Lee, & Orfield) (using U. S. Dept. of Education
and National Center for Education Statistics Common Core
data). Percentage of Students in Minority Schools by Race,
2000–2001 [Graphic
omitted; see printed opinion] Source: Id. , at 28, fig.
4. B Sources for Parts I–A and
I–B Part I–A:
Seattle Section 1.
Segregation ¶1
C. Schmid & W. McVey, Growth and Distribution of Minority Races
in Seattle, Washington, 3, 7–9 (1964); F. Hanawalt & R.
Williams, The History of Desegregation in Seattle Public Schools,
1954–1981, pp. 1–7 (1981) (hereinafter Hanawalt); Taylor, The
Civil Rights Movement in the American West: Black Protest in
Seattle, 1960–1970, 80 J. Negro Hist. 1, 2–3 (1995); A. Siqueland,
Without A Court Order: The Desegregation of Seattle’s Schools 10
(1981) (hereinafter Siqueland); D. Pieroth, Desegregating the
Public Schools, Seattle, Washington, 1954–1968, p. 6
(Dissertation Draft 1979) (hereinafter
Pieroth). Section 2. Preliminary Challenges, 1956 to
1969 ¶1
Pieroth 32, 41; Hanawalt
4. ¶2
Hanawalt
11–13. ¶3 Id ., at 5, 13,
27. Section 3. The NAACP’s First Legal Challenge and Seattle’s
Response, 1969 to
1977 ¶1
Complaint in Adams v. Forbes Bottomly , Civ. No.
6704 (WD Wash., 1969),
pp. 10–11. ¶2 Id. , at 10,
14–15. ¶3
Planning and Evaluation Dept., Seattle Public Schools, The Plan
Adopted by the Seattle School Board to Desegregate Fifth, Sixth,
Seventh, and Eighth Grade Pupils in the Garfield, Lincoln, and
Roosevelt High School Districts by September, 1971, pp. 6, 11
(on file with the University of Washington Library); see generally
Siqueland 12–15; Hanawalt
18–20. ¶4
Siqueland 5, 7,
21. Section 4. The NAACP’s Second Legal Challenge , 1977 ¶1
Administrative Complaint in Seattle Branch, NAACP v. Seattle School Dist. No. 1 , pp. 2–3 (OCR, Apr. 22,
1977) (OCR Complaint) (filed with Court as Exhibit in Seattle
School Dist. No. 1 , 458
U. S. 457 ); see generally Siqueland
23–24 . ¶2
Memorandum of Agreement between Seattle School District No. 1 of
King Cty., Washington, and the OCR (June 9, 1978) (filed with the
Court as Exh. A to Kiner Affidavit in Seattle School Dist. No.
1 , supra . Section 5. The Seattle Plan: Mandatory Busing, 1978 to
1988 ¶1
See generally Seattle School Dist. No. 1 , supra, at 461; Seattle Public Schools Desegregation Planning Office,
Proposed Alternative Desegregation Plans: Options for Eliminating
Racial Imbalance by the 1979-80 School Year (Sept. 1977) (filed
with the Court as Exh. B to Roe Affidavit in Seattle School
Dist. No. 1 , supra ); Hanawalt 36–38, 40; Siqueland 3,
184, Table
4. ¶2 Id., at 151–152; Hanawalt 37–38; Seattle School Dist.
No. 1 , supra, at 461; Complaint and Motion to Dismiss
or Affirm in Seattle School Dist. No. 1 , supra . ¶3 Seattle School Dist. No. 1, supra, at 461; Hanawalt
40. ¶4
See generally Seattle School Dist. No. 1,
supra. Section 6. Student Choice, 1988 to
1998 ¶1
L. Kohn, Priority Shift: The Fate of Mandatory Busing for School
Desegregation in Seattle and the Nation 27–30, 32 (Mar.
1996). ¶2 Id., at
32–34. Section 7. The Current Plan, 1999 to the
Present ¶1
App. in No. 05–908, p. 84a; Brief for Respondents in No.
05–908, pp. 5–7; 426 F. 3d 1162, 1169–1170 (CA9 2005) (en
banc) (Parents Involved
VII). ¶2
App. in No. 05–908, at 39–42; Research, Evaluation and Assessment,
Student Information Services Office, Seattle Public Schools Data
Profile: DistrictSummary December 2005, online at
http://www.seattleschools.org/ area/siso/disprof/2005/DP05all.pdf;
Brief for Respond- ents in No. 05–908, at 9–10, 47; App. in No.
05–908, at 309a; School Board Report, School Choices and
Assignments 2005–2006 School Year (Apr. 2005), online at
http:// www.seattleschools.org/ area/ facilties&nbhyph;plan/ Choice/ 05&nbhyph;
06AppsChoicesBoardApril2005final.pdf. ¶3 Parents Involved in Community Schools v. Seattle
School Dist., No. 1 , 149 Wash. 2d 660, 72 P. 3d 151
(2003); 137 F. Supp. 2d 1224 (2001); 426 F. 3d 1162 (CA9
2005) (en banc) (Parents Involved
VII) . Part I–B:
Louisville Section 1. Before the Lawsuit, 1954 to
1972 ¶1 Hampton v. Jefferson Cty., Bd. of Ed. , 72
F. Supp. 2d 753, 756, and nn. 2, 4, 5 (WD Ky. 1999) (Hampton
I) . Section 2. Court-Imposed Guidelines and Busing, 1972 to
1991 ¶1 Hampton I , supra , at 757–758, 762; Newburg
Area Council, Inc. v. Board of Ed. of Jefferson Cty. ,
489 F. 2d 925 (CA6 1973), vacated and remanded, 418 U. S. 918 (1974),
reinstated with modifications, 510 F. 2d 1358 (CA6 1974) (per curiam); Judgment and Findings of Fact and
Conclusions of Law in Newburg Area Council, Inc. v. Board of Ed., of Jefferson Cty. , Nos. 7045 and 7291 (WD
Ky., July 30, 1975) (1975 Judgment and
Findings). ¶2 Id., at 2, 3, and Attachment
1. ¶3 Id., at
4–16. ¶4
Memorandum Opinion and Order in Haycraft v. Board of
Ed. of Jefferson Cty. , Nos. 7045 and 7291, (WD Ky., June 16,
1978), pp. 1, 2, 4, 18 (1978 Memo &
Order). ¶5
Memorandum Opinion and Order, Haycraft v. Board of Ed.
of Jefferson Cty. , Nos. 7045 and 7291 (WD Ky., Sept. 24,
1985), p. 3; Memorandum from Donald W. Ingwerson,
Superintendent, to the Board of Education, Jefferson Cty. Public
School Dist., pp. 1, 3, 5 (Apr. 4, 1984) (1984 Memorandum);
Memorandum from Donald W. Ingwerson, Superintendent, to the Board
of Education, Jefferson County Public School District, pp. 4–5
(Dec. 19, 1991) (1991
Memorandum). Section 3. Student Choice and Project Renaissance, 1991 to
1996 ¶1
1991 Memorandum 1–4, 7–11 (Stipulated Exh. 72); Brief for
Respondents in No. 05–915, P. 12,
n. 13. ¶2
1991 Memorandum
14–16. ¶3 Id., at 11,
14–15. ¶4 Id., at 15–16; Memorandum from Stephen W. Daeschner,
Superintendent, to the Board of Education, Jefferson Cty. Public
School Dist., p. 2 (Aug. 6, 1996) (1996
Memorandum). Section 4. The Current Plan: Project Renaissance
Modified, 1996 to
2003 ¶1
1996 Memorandum 1–4; Brief for Respondents in No. 05–915, at 12,
and
n. 13. ¶2
1996 Memorandum 4–7, and Attachment 2; Hampton I , supra , at
768. ¶3
1996 Memorandum 5–8; Hampton I , supra , at 768,
n. 30. ¶4 Hampton v. Jefferson Cty. Bd. of Ed. , 102
F. Supp. 2d 358, 359, 363, 370, 377 (WD Ky. 2000) (Hampton
II) . ¶5 Id., at
380–381. Section 5. The Current Lawsuit, 2003 to the
Present ¶1 McFarland v. Jefferson Cty. Public Schools , 330
F. Supp. 2d 834 (WD Ky. 2004); McFarland v. Jefferson Cty. Public Schools , 416 F. 3d 513 (2005);
Memorandum from Stephen W. Daeschner, Superintendent, to the Board
of Education, Jefferson Cty. Public School Dist., 3–4 (Apr. 2,
2001). | The Supreme Court ruled that public schools may not classify students by race and use that classification to determine school assignments, even if the goal is to promote diversity. This decision applies to schools that have not been legally segregated or found to be racially imbalanced. The Court found that the use of racial classifications in school assignments, even as part of a voluntary plan, violates the Equal Protection Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment. |
Gun Rights | Garland v. Cargill | https://supreme.justia.com/cases/federal/us/602/22-976/ | NOTICE: This opinion is subject to
formal revision before publication in the United States Reports.
Readers are requested to notify the Reporter of Decisions, Supreme
Court of the United States, Washington, D. C. 20543,
[email protected], of any typographical or other formal
errors.
SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES
_________________
No. 22–976
_________________
MERRICK B. GARLAND, ATTORNEY GENERAL, et al.,
PETITIONERS v. MICHAEL CARGILL
on writ of certiorari to the united states
court of appeals for the fifth circuit
[June 14, 2024]
Justice Thomas delivered the opinion of the
Court.
Congress has long restricted access to
“ ‘machinegun[s],’ ” a category of firearms defined by
the ability to “shoot, automatically more than one shot
. . . by a single function of the trigger.” 26
U. S. C. §5845(b); see also 18 U. S. C.
§922( o ). Semiautomatic firearms, which require shooters to
reengage the trigger for every shot, are not machineguns. This case
asks whether a bump stock—an accessory for a semiautomatic rifle
that allows the shooter to rapidly reengage the trigger (and
therefore achieve a high rate of fire)—converts the rifle into a
“machinegun.” We hold that it does not and therefore affirm.
I
A
Under the National Firearms Act of 1934, a
“machinegun” is “any weapon which shoots, is designed to shoot, or
can be readily restored to shoot, automatically more than one shot,
without manual reloading, by a single function of the trigger.”
§5845(b). The statutory definition also includes “any part designed
and intended . . . for use in converting a weapon into a
machinegun.” Ibid. With a machinegun, a shooter can fire
multiple times, or even continuously, by engaging the trigger only
once. This capability distinguishes a machinegun from a
semiautomatic firearm. With a semiautomatic firearm, the shooter
can fire only one time by engaging the trigger. The shooter must
release and reengage the trigger to fire another shot. Machineguns
can ordinarily achieve higher rates of fire than semiautomatic
firearms because the shooter does not need to release and reengage
the trigger between shots.
Shooters have devised techniques for firing
semiautomatic firearms at rates approaching those of some
machineguns. One technique is called bump firing. A shooter who
bump fires a rifle uses the firearm’s recoil to help rapidly
manipulate the trigger. The shooter allows the recoil from one shot
to push the whole firearm backward. As the rifle slides back and
away from the shooter’s stationary trigger finger, the trigger is
released and reset for the next shot. Simultaneously, the shooter
uses his nontrigger hand to maintain forward pressure on the
rifle’s front grip. The forward pressure counteracts the recoil and
causes the firearm (and thus the trigger) to move forward and
“bump” into the shooter’s trigger finger. This bump reengages the
trigger and causes another shot to fire, and so on.
Bump firing is a balancing act. The shooter must
maintain enough forward pressure to ensure that he will bump the
trigger with sufficient force to engage it. But, if the shooter
applies too much forward pressure, the rifle will not slide back
far enough to allow the trigger to reset. The right balance
produces a reciprocating motion that permits the shooter to
repeatedly engage and release the trigger in rapid succession.
Although bump firing does not require any
additional equipment, there are accessories designed to make the
technique easier. A “bump stock” is one such accessory.[ 1 ] It replaces a semiautomatic rifle’s
stock (the back part of the rifle that rests against the shooter’s
shoulder) with a plastic casing that allows every other part of the
rifle to slide back and forth. This casing helps manage the
back-and-forth motion required for bump firing. A bump stock also
has a ledge to keep the shooter’s trigger finger stationary. A bump
stock does not alter the basic mechanics of bump firing. As with
any semiautomatic firearm, the trigger still must be released and
reengaged to fire each additional shot.
B
The question in this case is whether a bump
stock transforms a semiautomatic rifle into a “machinegun,” as
defined by §5845(b). For many years, the Bureau of Alcohol,
Tobacco, Firearms and Explosives (ATF) took the position that
semiautomatic rifles equipped with bump stocks were not machineguns
under the statute. On more than 10 separate occasions over several
administrations, ATF consistently concluded that rifles equipped
with bump stocks cannot “automatically” fire more than one shot “by
a single function of the trigger.” See App. 16–68. In April 2017,
for example, ATF explained that a rifle equipped with a bump stock
does not “operat[e] automatically” because “forward pressure must
be applied with the support hand to the forward handguard.” Id., at 66. And, because the shooter slides the rifle
forward in the stock “to fire each shot, each succeeding shot
fir[es] with a single trigger function.” Id., at 67.
ATF abruptly reversed course in response to a
mass shooting in Las Vegas, Nevada. In October 2017, a gunman fired
on a crowd attending an outdoor music festival in Las Vegas,
killing 58 people and wounding over 500 more. The gunman equipped
his weapons with bump stocks, which allowed him to fire hundreds of
rounds in a matter of minutes.
This tragedy created tremendous political
pressure to outlaw bump stocks nationwide. Within days, Members of
Congress proposed bills to ban bump stocks and other devices
“designed . . . to accelerate the rate of fire of a
semiautomatic rifle.” S. 1916, 115th Cong., 1st Sess., §2 (2017);
see also H. R. 3947, 115th Cong., 1st Sess. (2017); H. R.
3999, 115th Cong., 1st Sess. (2017). None of these bills became
law. Similar proposals in the intervening years have also stalled.
See, e . g ., H. R. 396, 118th Cong., 1st Sess.
(2023); S. 1909, 118th Cong., 1st Sess. (2023); H. R.
5427, 117th Cong., 1st Sess. (2021).
While the first wave of bills was pending, ATF
began considering whether to reinterpret §5845(b)’s definition of
“machinegun” to include bump stocks. It proposed a rule that would
amend its regulations to “clarify” that bump stocks are
machineguns. 83 Fed. Reg. 13442 (2018). ATF’s about-face drew
criticism from some observers, including those who agreed that bump
stocks should be banned. Senator Dianne Feinstein, for example,
warned that ATF lacked statutory authority to prohibit bump stocks,
explaining that the proposed regulation “ ‘hinge[d] on a
dubious analysis’ ” and that the “ ‘gun lobby and
manufacturers [would] have a field day with [ATF’s]
reasoning’ ” in court. Statement on Regulation To Ban Bump
Stocks (Mar. 23, 2018). She asserted that “ ‘legislation is
the only way to ban bump stocks.’ ” Ibid .
ATF issued its final Rule in 2018. 83 Fed. Reg.
66514. The agency’s earlier regulations simply restated §5845(b)’s
statutory definition. Ibid. The final Rule amended those
regulations by adding the following language:
“[T]he term ‘automatically’ as it modifies
‘shoots, is designed to shoot, or can be readily restored to
shoot,’ means functioning as the result of a self-acting or
self-regulating mechanism that allows the firing of multiple rounds
through a single function of the trigger; and ‘single function of
the trigger’ means a single pull of the trigger and analogous
motions. The term ‘machinegun’ includes a bump-stock-type device, i . e ., a device that allows a semi-automatic firearm
to shoot more than one shot with a single pull of the trigger by
harnessing the recoil energy of the semi-automatic firearm to which
it is affixed so that the trigger resets and continues firing
without additional physical manipulation of the trigger by the
shooter.” Id ., at 66553–66554.
The final Rule also repudiated ATF’s previous
guidance that bump stocks did not qualify as “machineguns” under
§5845(b). Id ., at 66530–66531. And, it ordered owners of
bump stocks to destroy them or surrender them to ATF within 90
days. Id ., at 66530. Bump-stock owners who failed to comply
would be subject to criminal prosecution. Id ., at 66525; see
also 18 U. S. C. §922( o )(1).
C
Michael Cargill surrendered two bump stocks to
ATF under protest. He then filed suit to challenge the final Rule,
asserting a claim under the Administrative Procedure Act. As
relevant, Cargill alleged that ATF lacked statutory authority to
promulgate the final Rule because bump stocks are not
“machinegun[s]” as defined in §5845(b). After a bench trial, the
District Court entered judgment for ATF. The court concluded that
“a bump stock fits the statutory definition of a
‘machinegun.’ ” Cargill v. Barr , 502
F. Supp. 3d 1163, 1194 (WD Tex. 2020).
The Court of Appeals initially affirmed, 20
F. 4th 1004 (CA5 2021), but later reversed after rehearing en
banc, 57 F. 4th 447 (CA5 2023). A majority agreed, at a
minimum, that §5845(b) is ambiguous as to whether a semiautomatic
rifle equipped with a bump stock fits the statutory definition of a
machinegun. And, the majority concluded that the rule of lenity
required resolving that ambiguity in Cargill’s favor. Id .,
at 469; see also id ., at 450, n. An eight-judge plurality
determined that the statutory definition of “machinegun”
unambiguously excludes such weapons. A semiautomatic rifle equipped
with a bump stock, the plurality reasoned, fires only one shot
“each time the trigger ‘acts,’ ” id. , at 459, and so
does not fire “more than one shot . . . by a single
function of the trigger,” §5845(b). The plurality also concluded
that a bump stock does not enable a semiautomatic rifle to fire
more than one shot “automatically” because the shooter must
“maintain manual, forward pressure on the barrel.” Id ., at
463.
We granted certiorari, 601 U. S. ___
(2023), to address a split among the Courts of Appeals regarding
whether bump stocks meet §5845(b)’s definition of
“machinegun.”[ 2 ] We now
affirm.
II
Section 5845(b) defines a “machinegun” as any
weapon capable of firing “automatically more than one shot
. . . by a single function of the trigger.” We hold that
a semiautomatic rifle equipped with a bump stock is not a
“machinegun” because it cannot fire more than one shot “by a single
function of the trigger.” And, even if it could, it would not do so
“automatically.” ATF therefore exceeded its statutory authority by
issuing a Rule that classifies bump stocks as machineguns.
A
A semiautomatic rifle equipped with a bump
stock does not fire more than one shot “by a single function of the
trigger.” With or without a bump stock, a shooter must release and
reset the trigger between every shot. And, any subsequent shot
fired after the trigger has been released and reset is the result
of a separate and distinct “function of the trigger.” All that a
bump stock does is accelerate the rate of fire by causing these
distinct “function[s]” of the trigger to occur in rapid
succession.
As always, we start with the statutory text,
which refers to “a single function of the trigger.” The “function”
of an object is “the mode of action by which it fulfils its
purpose.” 4 Oxford English Dictionary 602 (1933); see also American
Heritage Dictionary 533 (1969) (“The natural or proper action for
which a . . . mechanism . . . is fitted or
employed”). And, a “trigger” is an apparatus, such as a “movable
catch or lever,” that “sets some force or mechanism in action.” 11
Oxford English Dictionary, at 357; see also American Heritage
Dictionary, at 1371 (“The lever pressed by the finger to discharge
a firearm” or “[a]ny similar device used to release or activate a
mechanism”); Webster’s New International Dictionary 2711 (2d ed.
1934) (“A piece, as a lever, connected with a catch or detent as a
means of releasing it; specif., Firearms , the part of a lock
moved by the finger to release the cock in firing”). The phrase
“function of the trigger” thus refers to the mode of action by
which the trigger activates the firing mechanism. For most
firearms, including the ones at issue here, the trigger is a curved
metal lever. On weapons with these standard trigger mechanisms, the
phrase “function of the trigger” means the physical trigger
movement required to shoot the firearm.
No one disputes that a semiautomatic rifle
without a bump stock is not a machinegun because it fires only one
shot per “function of the trigger.” That is, engaging the trigger a
single time will cause the firing mechanism to discharge only one
shot. To understand why, it is helpful to consider the mechanics of
the firing cycle for a semiautomatic rifle. Because the statutory
definition is keyed to a “function of the trigger,” only the
trigger assembly is relevant for our purposes. Although trigger
assemblies for semiautomatic rifles vary, the basic mechanics are
generally the same. The following series of illustrations depicts
how the trigger assembly on an AR–15 style semiautomatic rifle
works.[ 3 ] In each illustration,
the front of the rifle ( i . e ., the barrel) would be
pointing to the left.
We begin with an overview of the relevant
components:
Figure 1.
The trigger is a simple lever that moves
backward and forward. P. Sweeney, Gunsmithing the AR–15,
p. 131 (2016). The square point at the top left edge of the
trigger locks into a notch at the bottom of the hammer. P. Sweeney,
Gunsmithing: Rifles 269 (1999). The hammer is a spring-loaded part
that swings forward toward the barrel and strikes the firing pin,
causing a shot to fire. Ibid. The disconnector is the
component responsible for resetting the hammer to its original
position after a shot is fired. Ibid. We turn next to how these components
operate:
Figure 2.
When the shooter engages the trigger by moving
it backward (as indicated by the arrow), the square point of the
trigger pivots downward and out of the notch securing the hammer. Ibid. This movement releases the spring-loaded hammer,
allowing it to swing forward. Ibid. Figure 3.
At the top of the hammer’s rotation, it strikes
the firing pin, causing the weapon to fire a single shot. See ibid. Figure 4.
The firearm then ejects the spent cartridge from
the chamber and loads a new one in its place. D. Long, The Complete
AR–15/M16 Sourcebook 206 (2001). The mechanism that performs this
task swings the hammer backward at the same time. Ibid. Figure 5.
As the hammer swings backward, it latches onto
the disconnector. Sweeney, Gunsmithing: Rifles, at 269. This
latching (circled above) prevents the hammer from swinging forward
again after a new cartridge is loaded into the chamber. Ibid. The disconnector will hold the hammer in that position
for as long as the shooter holds the trigger back, thus preventing
the firearm from firing another shot.[ 4 ] Ibid. Figure 6.
Finally, when the shooter takes pressure off the
trigger and allows it to move forward (as indicated by the arrow),
the hammer slips off the disconnector just as the square point of
the trigger rises into the notch on the hammer (circled above). Ibid. The trigger mechanism is thereby reset to the original
position shown in Figure 1. A semiautomatic rifle must complete
this cycle for each shot fired.[ 5 ]
ATF does not dispute that this complete process
is what constitutes a “single function of the trigger.” A shooter
may fire the weapon again after the trigger has reset, but only by
engaging the trigger a second time and thereby initiating a new
firing cycle. For each shot, the shooter must engage the trigger
and then release the trigger to allow it to reset. Any additional
shot fired after one cycle is the result of a separate and distinct
“function of the trigger.”
Nothing changes when a semiautomatic rifle is
equipped with a bump stock. The firing cycle remains the same.
Between every shot, the shooter must release pressure from the
trigger and allow it to reset before reengaging the trigger for
another shot. A bump stock merely reduces the amount of time that
elapses between separate “functions” of the trigger. The bump stock
makes it easier for the shooter to move the firearm back toward his
shoulder and thereby release pressure from the trigger and reset
it. And, it helps the shooter press the trigger against his finger
very quickly thereafter. A bump stock does not convert a
semiautomatic rifle into a machinegun any more than a shooter with
a lightning-fast trigger finger does. Even with a bump stock, a
semiautomatic rifle will fire only one shot for every “function of
the trigger.” So, a bump stock cannot qualify as a machinegun under
§5845(b)’s definition.
Although ATF agrees on a semiautomatic rifle’s
mechanics, it nevertheless insists that a bump stock allows a
semiautomatic rifle to fire multiple shots “by a single function of
the trigger.” ATF starts by interpreting the phrase “single
function of the trigger” to mean “a single pull of the trigger and
analogous motions.” 83 Fed. Reg. 66553. A shooter using a bump
stock, it asserts, must pull the trigger only one time to initiate
a bump-firing sequence of multiple shots. Id ., at 66554.
This initial trigger pull sets off a sequence—fire, recoil, bump,
fire—that allows the weapon to continue firing “without additional
physical manipulation of the trigger by the shooter.” Ibid. According to ATF, all the shooter must do is keep his trigger
finger stationary on the bump stock’s ledge and maintain constant
forward pressure on the front grip to continue firing. The dissent
offers similar reasoning. See post , at 7–9 (opinion of
Sotomayor, J.).
This argument rests on the mistaken premise that
there is a difference between a shooter flexing his finger to pull
the trigger and a shooter pushing the firearm forward to bump the
trigger against his stationary finger. ATF and the dissent seek to
call the shooter’s initial trigger pull a “function of the trigger”
while ignoring the subsequent “bumps” of the shooter’s finger
against the trigger before every additional shot. But, §5845(b)
does not define a machinegun based on what type of human input
engages the trigger—whether it be a pull, bump, or something else.
Nor does it define a machinegun based on whether the shooter has
assistance engaging the trigger. The statutory definition instead
hinges on how many shots discharge when the shooter engages the
trigger. And, as we have explained, a semiautomatic rifle will fire
only one shot each time the shooter engages the trigger—with or
without a bump stock.[ 6 ] Supra , at 7–12.
In any event, ATF’s argument cannot succeed on
its own terms. The final Rule defines “function of the trigger” to
include not only “a single pull of the trigger” but also any
“analogous motions.” 83 Fed. Reg. 66553. ATF concedes that one such
analogous motion that qualifies as a single function of the trigger
is “sliding the rifle forward” to bump the trigger. Brief for
Petitioners 22. But, if that is true, then every bump is a separate
“function of the trigger,” and semiautomatic rifles equipped with
bump stocks are therefore not machineguns. ATF resists the natural
implication of its reasoning, insisting that the bumping motion is
a “function of the trigger” only when it initiates, but not when it
continues, a firing sequence. But, Congress did not write a
statutory definition of “machinegun” keyed to when a firing
sequence begins and ends. Section 5845(b) asks only whether a
weapon fires more than one shot “by a single function of the
trigger.”
Finally, the position that ATF and the dissent
endorse is logically inconsistent. They reason that a semiautomatic
rifle equipped with a bump stock fires more than one shot by a
single function of the trigger because a shooter “need only pull
the trigger and maintain forward pressure” to “activate continuous
fire.” Post , at 10; see also Brief for Petitioners 23. If
that is correct, however, then the same should be true for a
semiautomatic rifle without a bump stock. After all, as the
dissent and ATF themselves acknowledge, a shooter manually bump
firing a semiautomatic rifle can achieve continuous fire by holding
his trigger finger stationary and maintaining forward pressure with
his nontrigger hand. See post , at 5; 83 Fed. Reg. 66533.
Yet, they agree that a semiautomatic rifle without a bump stock
“fires only one shot each time the shooter pulls the trigger.” Post , at 4; see also 83 Fed. Reg. 66534. Their argument is
thus at odds with itself.
We conclude that semiautomatic rifle equipped
with a bump stock is not a “machinegun” because it does not fire
more than one shot “by a single function of the trigger.”
B
A bump stock is not a “machinegun” for another
reason: Even if a semiautomatic rifle with a bump stock could fire
more than one shot “by a single function of the trigger,” it would
not do so “automatically.” Section 5845(b) asks whether a weapon
“shoots . . . automatically more than one shot
. . . by a single function of the trigger.” The statute
thus specifies the precise action that must “automatically” cause a
weapon to fire “more than one shot”—a “single function of the
trigger.” If something more than a “single function of the trigger”
is required to fire multiple shots, the weapon does not satisfy the
statutory definition. As Judge Henderson put it, the “statutory
definition of ‘machinegun’ does not include a firearm that shoots
more than one round ‘automatically’ by a single pull of the trigger AND THEN SOME .” Guedes v. Bureau of Alcohol,
Tobacco, Firearms and Explosives , 920 F.3d 1, 44 (CADC 2019)
(opinion concurring in part and dissenting in part).
Firing multiple shots using a semiautomatic
rifle with a bump stock requires more than a single function of the
trigger. A shooter must also actively maintain just the right
amount of forward pressure on the rifle’s front grip with his
nontrigger hand. See supra , at 2–3. Too much forward
pressure and the rifle will not slide back far enough to release
and reset the trigger, preventing the rifle from firing another
shot. Too little pressure and the trigger will not bump the
shooter’s trigger finger with sufficient force to fire another
shot. Without this ongoing manual input, a semiautomatic rifle with
a bump stock will not fire multiple shots. Thus, firing multiple
shots requires engaging the trigger one time—and then
some.[ 7 ]
ATF and the dissent counter that machineguns
also require continuous manual input from a shooter: He must both
engage the trigger and keep it pressed down to continue shooting.
In their view, there is no meaningful difference between holding
down the trigger of a traditional machinegun and maintaining
forward pressure on the front grip of a semiautomatic rifle with a
bump stock. This argument ignores that Congress defined a
machinegun by what happens “automatically” “by a single function of
the trigger.” Simply pressing and holding the trigger down on a
fully automatic rifle is not manual input in addition to a
trigger’s function—it is what causes the trigger to function in the
first place. By contrast, pushing forward on the front grip of a
semiautomatic rifle equipped with a bump stock is not part of
functioning the trigger. After all, pushing on the front grip will
not cause the weapon to fire unless the shooter also engages the
trigger with his other hand. Thus, while a fully automatic rifle
fires multiple rounds “automatically . . . by a single
function of the trigger,” a semiautomatic rifle equipped with a
bump stock can achieve the same result only by a single function of
the trigger and then some.
Moreover, a semiautomatic rifle with a bump
stock is indistinguishable from another weapon that ATF concedes
cannot fire multiple shots “automatically”: the Ithaca Model 37
shotgun. The Model 37 allows the user to “slam fire”—that is, fire
multiple shots by holding down the trigger while operating the
shotgun’s pump action. Each pump ejects the spent cartridge and
loads a new one into the chamber. If the shooter is holding down
the trigger, the new cartridge will fire as soon as it is loaded.
According to ATF, the Model 37 fires more than one shot by a single
function of the trigger, but it does not do so “automatically”
because the shooter must manually operate the pump action with his
nontrigger hand. See 83 Fed. Reg. 66534. That logic mandates the
same result here. Maintaining the proper amount of forward pressure
on the front grip of a bump-stock equipped rifle is no less
additional input than is operating the pump action on the Model
37.[ 8 ]
ATF responds that a shooter is less physically
involved with operating a bump-stock equipped rifle than operating
the Model 37’s pump action. Once the shooter pulls the rifle’s
trigger a single time, the bump stock “harnesses the firearm’s
recoil energy in a continuous back-and-forth cycle that allows the
shooter to attain continuous firing.” Id., at 66519. But,
even if one aspect of a weapon’s operation could be seen as
“automatic,” that would not mean the weapon “shoots . . .
automatically more than one shot . . . by a single
function of the trigger .” §5845(b) (emphasis added). After all,
many weapons have some “automatic” features. For example,
semiautomatic rifles eject the spent cartridge from the firearm’s
chamber and load a new one in its place without any input from the
shooter. See supra , at 10. A semiautomatic rifle is
therefore “automatic” in the general sense that it performs some
operations that would otherwise need to be completed by hand. But,
as all agree, a semiautomatic rifle cannot fire more than one shot
“automatically . . . by a single function of the trigger”
because the shooter must do more than simply engage the trigger one
time. The same is true of a semiautomatic rifle equipped with a
bump stock.
Thus, even if a semiautomatic rifle could fire
more than one shot by a single function of the trigger, it would
not do so “automatically.”
C
Abandoning the text, ATF and the dissent
attempt to shore up their position by relying on the presumption
against ineffectiveness. That presumption weighs against
interpretations of a statute that would “rende[r] the law in a
great measure nugatory, and enable offenders to elude its
provisions in the most easy manner.” The Emily , 9 Wheat.
381, 389 (1824). It is a modest corollary to the commonsense
proposition “that Congress presumably does not enact useless laws.” United States v. Castleman , 572
U.S. 157 , 178 (2014) (Scalia, J., concurring in part and
concurring in judgment).
In ATF’s view, Congress “restricted machineguns
because they eliminate the manual movements that a shooter would
otherwise need to make in order to fire continuously” at a high
rate of fire, as bump stocks do. Brief for Petitioners 40. So, ATF
reasons, concluding that bump stocks are lawful “simply because the
[trigger] moves back and forth . . . would exalt artifice
above reality and enable evasion of the federal machinegun ban.” Id ., at 41–42 (internal quotation marks omitted). The
dissent endorses a similar view. See post , at 14–17.
The presumption against ineffectiveness cannot
do the work that ATF and the dissent ask of it. A law is not
useless merely because it draws a line more narrowly than one of
its conceivable statutory purposes might suggest. Interpreting
§5845(b) to exclude semiautomatic rifles equipped with bump stocks
comes nowhere close to making it useless. Under our reading,
§5845(b) still regulates all traditional machineguns. The fact that
it does not capture other weapons capable of a high rate of fire
plainly does not render the law useless. Moreover, it is difficult
to understand how ATF can plausibly argue otherwise, given that its
consistent position for almost a decade in numerous separate
decisions was that §5845(b) does not capture semiautomatic rifles
equipped with bump stocks. See App. 16–68. Curiously, the dissent
relegates ATF’s about-face to a footnote, instead pointing to its
classification of other devices. See post , at 14–17, and
n. 6.
The dissent’s additional argument for applying
the presumption against ineffectiveness fails on its own terms. To
argue that our interpretation makes §5845(b) “far less effective,”
the dissent highlights that a shooter with a bump-stock-equipped
rifle can achieve a rate of fire that rivals traditional
machineguns. Post , at 16. But, the dissent elsewhere
acknowledges that a shooter can do the same with an unmodified semiautomatic rifle using the manual bump-firing
technique. See post , at 5. The dissent thus fails to prove
that our reading makes §5845(b) “far less effective,” much less
ineffective (as is required to invoke the presumption). In any
event, Congress could have linked the definition of “machinegun” to
a weapon’s rate of fire, as the dissent would prefer. But, it
instead enacted a statute that turns on whether a weapon can fire
more than one shot “automatically . . . by a single
function of the trigger.” §5845(b). And, “it is never our job to
rewrite . . . statutory text under the banner of
speculation about what Congress might have done.” Henson v. Santander Consumer USA Inc. , 582 U.S. 79, 89
(2017).[ 9 ]
III
For the foregoing reasons, we affirm the
judgment of the Court of Appeals.
It is so ordered. Notes 1 Some bump stocks (called
mechanical bump stocks) rely on an internal spring, rather than
forward pressure from the shooter’s nontrigger hand, to force the
rifle and trigger forward after recoil. These devices are not at
issue in this case. 2 See, e . g ., Hardin v. Bureau of Alcohol, Tobacco, Firearms and
Explosives , 65 F. 4th 895 (CA6 2023); Guedes v. Bureau of Alcohol, Tobacco, Firearms and Explosives , 45
F. 4th 306 (CADC 2022); Aposhian v. Barr , 958
F.3d 969 (CA10 2020). 3 These illustrations are
found in the Brief for FPC Action Foundation as Amicus
Curiae 14–15. 4 Machinegun variants of
the AR–15 style rifle include an additional component known as an
auto sear. The auto sear catches the hammer as it swings backwards,
but will release it again once a new cartridge is loaded if the
trigger is being held back. P. Sweeney, 1 The Gun Digest Book of
the AR–15, p. 38 (2005). An auto sear thus permits a shooter to
fire multiple shots while engaging the trigger only once. ATF has
accordingly recognized that modifying a semiautomatic rifle or
handgun with an auto sear converts it into a machinegun. See ATF
Ruling 81–4. 5 An animated graphic that
displays the relevant movements is available at
https://www.supremecourt.gov/media/images/AR-15.gif. 6 The dissent says that we
“resis[t]” the “ordinary understanding of the term ‘function of the
trigger’ with two technical arguments.” Post , at 10. But,
the arguments it refers to explain why, even assuming a
semiautomatic rifle equipped with a bump stock could fire more than
one shot by a single function of the trigger, it could not do so
“automatically.” See infra , at 14–17. Those arguments have
nothing to do with our explanation of what a “single function of
the trigger” means. Ibid. 7 The dissent seemingly
concedes this point, repeatedly recognizing that the shooter must
both pull the trigger and maintain forward pressure on the
front grip. See, e . g ., post , at 6 (“[A] single
pull of the trigger provides continuous fire as long as the shooter
maintains forward pressure on the gun”); ibid . (“A
bump-stock-equipped semiautomatic rifle is a machinegun because
. . . a shooter can . . . fire continuous shots
without any human input beyond maintaining forward pressure”); post , at 10 (“[A] shooter of a bump-stock-equipped AR–15
need only pull the trigger and maintain forward pressure”); post , at 13 (“After a shooter pulls the trigger, if he
maintains continuous forward pressure on the gun, the bump stock
harnesses the recoil to move the curved lever back and forth
against his finger”). 8 The dissent attempts to
undermine this analogy by pointing out that a Model 37 requires
manual reloading and therefore cannot qualify as a machinegun under
§5845(b). Post , at 12–13, n. 5. But, that is beside the
point. As ATF itself agrees, the Model 37 is not a machinegun for
another, independent reason: It cannot “automatically” fire more
than one shot by a single function of the trigger. See Brief for
Petitioners 38. And, as explained, the reasons why a Model 37
cannot do so apply with equal force to semiautomatic rifles
equipped with bump stocks. 9 The dissent concludes by
claiming that our interpretation of §5845(b) “renders Congress’s
clear intent readily evadable.” Post , at 17. And, it
highlights that “[e]very Member of the majority has previously
emphasized that the best way to respect congressional intent is to
adhere to the ordinary understanding of the terms Congress uses.” Ibid . But, “[w]hen Congress takes the trouble to define the
terms it uses, a court must respect its definitions as virtually
conclusive. . . . This Court will not deviate from an
express statutory definition merely because it varies from the
term’s ordinary meaning.” Department of Agriculture Rural
Development Rural Housing Service v. Kirtz , 601 U.S. 42,
59 (2024) (internal quotation marks and alteration omitted)
(unanimous opinion). SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES
_________________
No. 22–976
_________________
MERRICK B. GARLAND, ATTORNEY GENERAL, et al.,
PETITIONERS v. MICHAEL CARGILL
on writ of certiorari to the united states
court of appeals for the fifth circuit
[June 14, 2024]
Justice Alito, concurring.
I join the opinion of the Court because there is
simply no other way to read the statutory language. There can be
little doubt that the Congress that enacted 26 U. S. C.
§5845(b) would not have seen any material difference between a
machinegun and a semiautomatic rifle equipped with a bump stock.
But the statutory text is clear, and we must follow it.
The horrible shooting spree in Las Vegas in 2017
did not change the statutory text or its meaning. That event
demonstrated that a semiautomatic rifle with a bump stock can have
the same lethal effect as a machinegun, and it thus strengthened
the case for amending §5845(b). But an event that highlights the
need to amend a law does not itself change the law’s meaning.
There is a simple remedy for the disparate
treatment of bump stocks and machineguns. Congress can amend the
law—and perhaps would have done so already if ATF had stuck with
its earlier interpretation. Now that the situation is clear,
Congress can act. SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES
_________________
No. 22–976
_________________
MERRICK B. GARLAND, ATTORNEY GENERAL, et al.,
PETITIONERS v. MICHAEL CARGILL
on writ of certiorari to the united states
court of appeals for the fifth circuit
[June 14, 2024]
Justice Sotomayor, with whom Justice Kagan and
Justice Jackson join, dissenting.
On October 1, 2017, a shooter opened fire from a
hotel room overlooking an outdoor concert in Las Vegas, Nevada, in
what would become the deadliest mass shooting in U. S.
history. Within a matter of minutes, using several hundred rounds
of ammunition, the shooter killed 58 people and wounded over 500.
He did so by affixing bump stocks to commonly available,
semiautomatic rifles. These simple devices harness a rifle’s recoil
energy to slide the rifle back and forth and repeatedly “bump” the
shooter’s stationary trigger finger, creating rapid fire. All the
shooter had to do was pull the trigger and press the gun forward.
The bump stock did the rest.
Congress has sharply restricted civilian
ownership of machineguns since 1934. Federal law defines a
“machinegun” as a weapon that can shoot “automatically more than
one shot, without manual reloading, by a single function of the
trigger.” 26 U. S. C. §5845(b). Shortly after the Las
Vegas massacre, the Trump administration, with widespread
bipartisan support, banned bump stocks as machineguns under the
statute.
Today, the Court puts bump stocks back in
civilian hands. To do so, it casts aside Congress’s definition of
“machinegun” and seizes upon one that is inconsistent with the
ordinary meaning of the statutory text and unsupported by context
or purpose. When I see a bird that walks like a duck, swims like a
duck, and quacks like a duck, I call that bird a duck. A
bump-stock-equipped semiautomatic rifle fires “automatically more
than one shot, without manual reloading, by a single function of
the trigger.” §5845(b). Because I, like Congress, call that a
machinegun, I respectfully dissent.
I
A
Machineguns were originally developed in the
19th century as weapons of war. See J. Ellis, The Social History of
the Machine Gun 21–45 (1986) (Ellis). Smaller and lighter
submachine guns were not commercially available until the 1920s.
See Brief for Patrick J. Charles as Amicus Curiae 5 (Charles
Brief ). Although these weapons were originally marketed to
law enforcement, they inevitably made it into the hands of
gangsters. See id ., at 8–9; Ellis 149–165. Gangsters like Al
Capone used machineguns to rob banks, ambush the police, and murder
rivals. See Ellis 153–154, 157–158. Newspaper headlines across the
country flashed “ ‘Gangsters Use Machine Guns,’ ”
“ ‘Machine Gun Used in Bank Hold-Up,’ ” and
“ ‘Machine Gun Thugs Kill Postal Employee.’ ” Charles
Brief 9.
Congress responded in 1934 by sharply
restricting civilian ownership of machineguns. See National
Firearms Act of 1934, §§3–6, 48Stat. 1236, 1237–1238. The Senate
Report explaining the 1934 Act emphasized that the “gangster as a
law violator must be deprived of his most dangerous weapon, the
machine gun.” S. Rep. No. 1444, 73d Cong., 2d Sess., 1–2.
“[W]hile there is justification for permitting the citizen to keep
a pistol or revolver for his own
protection . . . , there is no reason why
anyone except a law officer should have a machine gun.” Id .,
at 2.
These early machineguns allowed a shooter to
fire in a variety of ways. Some would fire continuously with a
single pull of the trigger or push of a button. See Charles Brief
7, and n. 12 (noting that a Browning M1918 rifle fired eight
rounds “ ‘in a second with one pull of the trigger’ ”);
see also Brief for Petitioners 22 (noting that a Browning M2 fired
with a push of the thumb). Others, such as the famous Thompson
Submachine Gun Caliber .45, or “Tommy Gun,” would fire continuously
only so long as the shooter maintained backward pressure on the
trigger; a shooter could still fire single shots by pulling and
releasing the trigger each time. See Test of Thompson Submachine
Gun, 69 Army and Navy Register 355 (Apr. 9, 1921) (noting that the
shooter of a Tommy Gun “can fire the contents of the magazine with
a single prolonged pull or fire a single shot by merely releasing
the trigger”). The internal mechanisms of automatic-fire weapons
also varied enormously, with many (such as the Tommy Gun) relying
principally on the recoil energy produced by each bullet’s
discharge to effectuate automatic fire. See, e . g .,
War Dept., Basic Field Manual: Thompson Submachine Gun, Caliber
.45, M1928A1, p. 1 (1941) (“The Thompson submachine gun
. . . is an air-cooled, recoil-operated, magazine-fed
weapon”); W. Smith, Small Arms of the World: The Basic Manual of
Military Small Arms 165 (1955) (describing Tommy guns as “recoil
operated weapons on the elementary blowback principle”).
To account for these differences, Congress
adopted a definition of “machinegun” that captured “any weapon
which shoots, or is designed to shoot, automatically
. . . more than one shot, without manual reloading, by a
single function of the trigger.” National Firearms Act, 48Stat.
1236. That essential definition still governs today. See 26
U. S. C. §5845(b).[ 1 ]
B
The archetypal modern “machinegun” is the
military’s standard-issue M16 assault rifle. With an M16 in
automatic mode, the shooter pulls the trigger once to achieve a
fire rate of 700 to 950 rounds per minute. See Dept. of Defense,
Defense Logistics Agency, Small Arms, https://www.
dla.mil/Disposition-Services/Offers/ Law- Enforcement /
Weapons/. An internal mechanism automates the M16’s continuous
fire, so that all the shooter has to do is keep backward pressure
on the trigger. See Brief for Giffords Law Center to Prevent Gun
Violence et al. as Amici Curiae 9–11 (Giffords
Brief ) (discussing internal firing mechanism of M16). If the
shooter stops putting pressure on the trigger, the gun stops
firing.
Semiautomatic weapons are not “machineguns”
under the statute. Take, for instance, an AR–15-style semiautomatic
assault rifle. To rapidly fire an AR–15, a shooter must rapidly
pull the trigger himself. It is “semi” automatic because, although
the rifle automatically loads a new cartridge into the chamber
after it is fired, it fires only one shot each time the shooter
pulls the trigger. See 18 U. S. C. §921(a)(29) (2018 ed.,
Supp. IV).
To fire an M16 or AR–15 rifle, a person
typically holds the “grip” next to the trigger with his firing
hand. He stabilizes the weapon with his other hand on its barrel or
“front grip.” He then raises the weapon so that the butt, or
“stock,” of the gun rests against his shoulder, lines up the sights
to look down the gun, and squeezes the trigger. See Dept. of the
Army, Field Manual 23–9, Rifle Marksmanship M16A1, M16A2/3, M16A4,
and M4 Carbine, Ch. 4, Section III, p. 4-22 (Sept. 13, 2006)
(M16 Field Manual). A regular person with an AR–15 can achieve a
fire rate of around 60 rounds per minute, with one pull of the
trigger per second. Tr. of Oral Arg. 39. A professional sport
shooter can use the AR–15 to fire at a rate of up to 180 rounds per
minute, pulling the trigger three times per second. Giffords Brief
14.
A shooter can also manually “bump” an AR–15 to
increase the rate of fire by using a belt loop or rubber band to
hold his trigger finger in place and harness the recoil from the
first shot to fire the rifle continuously. See 83 Fed. Reg.
66532–66533 (2018). To use a belt loop, he must hold the rifle low
against his hip, put his finger in the trigger guard, and then loop
his finger through a belt loop on his pants to lock the finger in
place. See id ., at 66533. With his other hand, he then
pushes the rifle forward until his stationary finger engages the
trigger to fire the first shot. See ibid. The recoil from
that shot pushes the rifle violently backward. See ibid. If
the shooter keeps pressing the rifle forward against the finger in
his belt loop, the repeated backward jump of the recoil combined
with his forward pressure allows the rifle to fire continuously.
See ibid. A shooter using this method, however, cannot shoot
very precisely. He has neither the advantage of the sights to line
up his shot, nor his shoulder to stabilize the recoil. A shooter
can also use a rubber band or zip tie to tie a finger close to the
trigger. See id ., at 66532. If the shooter is strong and
skilled enough physically to control the distance and direction of
the rifle’s significant recoil, the rifle will fire
continuously.
A bump stock automates and stabilizes the bump
firing process. It replaces a rifle’s standard stock, which is the
part held against the shoulder. See id ., at 66516. A bump
stock, unlike a standard stock, allows the rifle’s upper assembly
to slide back and forth in the stock. See ibid. It also
typically includes a finger rest on which the shooter can place his
finger while shooting, and a “receiver module” that guides and
regulates the weapon’s recoil. Ibid. To fire a semiautomatic
rifle equipped with a bump stock, the shooter either pulls the
trigger, see ibid. , or slides the gun forward in the bump
stock, which presses the trigger into his trigger finger, Cargill v. Barr , 502 F. Supp. 3d 1163, 1175 (WD
Tex. 2020). As long as the shooter keeps his trigger finger on the
finger rest and maintains constant forward pressure on the rifle’s
barrel or front grip, the weapon will fire continuously. See 83
Fed. Reg. 66516. A rifle equipped with a bump stock can fire at a
rate between 400 and 800 rounds per minute. Tr. of Oral Arg.
40.
II
A machinegun does not fire itself. The
important question under the statute is how a person can fire it. A
weapon is a “machinegun” when a shooter can (1) “by a single
function of the trigger,” (2) shoot “automatically more than one
shot, without manually reloading.” 26 U. S. C. §5845(b).
The plain language of that definition refers most obviously to a
rifle like an M16, where a single pull of the trigger provides
continuous fire as long as the shooter maintains backward pressure
on the trigger. The definition of “machinegun” also includes “any
part designed and intended . . . for use in converting a
weapon into a machinegun.” Ibid. That language naturally
covers devices like bump stocks, which “conver[t]” semiautomatic
rifles so that a single pull of the trigger provides continuous
fire as long as the shooter maintains forward pressure on the
gun.
This is not a hard case. All of the textual
evidence points to the same interpretation. A bump-stock-equipped
semiautomatic rifle is a machinegun because (1) with a single pull
of the trigger, a shooter can (2) fire continuous shots without any
human input beyond maintaining forward pressure. The majority looks
to the internal mechanism that initiates fire, rather than the
human act of the shooter’s initial pull, to hold that a “single
function of the trigger” means a reset of the trigger mechanism.
Its interpretation requires six diagrams and an animation to
decipher the meaning of the statutory text. See ante, at
8–11, and n. 5. Then, shifting focus from the internal
mechanism of the gun to the perspective of the shooter, the
majority holds that continuous forward pressure is too much human
input for bump-stock-enabled continuous fire to be “automatic.” See ante, at 14–17.
The majority’s reading flies in the face of this
Court’s standard tools of statutory interpretation. By casting
aside the statute’s ordinary meaning both at the time of its
enactment and today, the majority eviscerates Congress’s regulation
of machineguns and enables gun users and manufacturers to
circumvent federal law.
A
Start with the phrase “single function of the
trigger.” All the tools of statutory interpretation, including
dictionary definitions, evidence of contemporaneous usage, and this
Court’s prior interpretation, point to that phrase meaning the
initiation of the firing sequence by an act of the shooter, whether
via a pull, push, or switch of the firing mechanism. The majority
nevertheless interprets “function of the trigger” as “the mode of
action by which the trigger activates the firing mechanism.” Ante, at 7. Because in a bump-stock-equipped semiautomatic
rifle, the trigger’s internal mechanism must reset each time a
weapon fires, the majority reads each reset as a new “function.”
That reading fixates on a firearm’s internal mechanics while
ignoring the human act on the trigger referenced by the
statute.
Consider the relevant dictionary definitions. In
1934, when Congress passed the National Firearms Act, “function”
meant “the mode of action by which [something] fulfils its
purpose.” 4 Oxford English Dictionary 602 (1933). A “trigger” meant
the “movable catch or lever” that “sets some force or mechanism in
action.” 11 id ., at 357. The majority agrees with those
definitions. Ante, at 7. It errs, however, by maintaining a
myopic focus on a trigger’s mechanics rather than on how a shooter
uses a trigger to initiate fire. Ibid. Nothing about those definitions suggests that
“function of the trigger” means the mechanism by which the trigger
resets mechanically to fire a second shot. See ante , at 8–11
(explaining the interior mechanics of an AR–15 trigger mechanism),
as opposed to the process that a pull of the trigger on a
bump-stock-equipped semiautomatic rifle sets in motion. The most
important “function” of a “trigger” is what it enables a shooter to
do; what “force or mechanism” it sets “in action.” 11 Oxford
English Dictionary, at 357. A “single function of the trigger” more
naturally means a single initiation of the firing sequence.
Regardless of what is happening in the internal mechanics of a
firearm, if a shooter must activate the trigger only a single time
to initiate a firing sequence that will shoot “automatically more
than one shot,” that firearm is a “machinegun.” §5845(b).
Evidence of contemporaneous usage overwhelmingly
supports that interpretation. The term “ ‘function of the
trigger’ ” was proposed by the president of the National Rifle
Association (NRA) during a hearing on the National Firearms Act
before the House. See National Firearms Act: Hearings on H. R.
9066 before the House Committee on Ways and Means, 73d Cong., 2d
Sess., 38–40 (1934). He understood the “distinguishing feature of a
machine gun [to be] that by a single pull of the trigger the gun
continues to fire.” Id ., at 40. He emphasized that a firearm
“which is capable of firing more than one shot by a single pull of
the trigger, a single function of the trigger, is properly regarded
. . . as a machine gun.” Ibid. Distinguishing a
machinegun from a pistol, the NRA president emphasized that for a
pistol “[y]ou must release the trigger and pull it again for the
second shot to be fired.” Id ., at 41. He did not say “the
hammer slips off the disconnector just as the square point of the
trigger rises into the notch on the hammer . . . thereby
reset[ting the trigger mechanism] to the original position.” Ante, at 11. He instead emphasized the action of the
shooter, who must repeatedly activate the trigger for each shot.
Predictably, the House and Senate Reports reflect the same
understanding of the phrase. See H. R. Rep. No. 1780, 73d
Cong., 2d Sess., 2 (1934) (reporting that the statute “contains the
usual definition of machine gun as a weapon designed to shoot more
than one shot without reloading and by a single pull of the
trigger”); S. Rep. No. 1444, 73d Cong., 2d Sess., 2 (1934)
(same).
The majority cannot disregard these statements
as evidence of legislative purpose.[ 2 ] They are, along with contemporaneous dictionary
definitions, some of the best evidence of contemporaneous
understanding. Cf. McDonald v. Chicago , 561 U.S.
742 , 828 (2010) (Thomas, J., concurring in part and concurring
in judgment) (“Statements by legislators can assist . . .
to the extent they demonstrate the manner in which the public used
or understood a particular word or phrase”). Indeed, at oral
argument, when asked what evidence there was “that as of 1934, the
ordinary understanding of the phrase ‘function of the trigger’
referred to the mechanics of the gun rather than . . .
the shooter’s motion,” respondent’s lawyer could not point to a
single piece of evidence that supports the majority’s reading. Tr.
of Oral Arg. 98; see id ., at 98–101. He even agreed that
Congress used the word “function” to ensure that the statute
covered a wide variety of trigger mechanisms, including both push
and pull triggers. Id ., at 101–102. In short, the majority
disregards the unrefuted evidence of the text’s ordinary and
contemporaneous meaning, substituting instead its own understanding
of the internal mechanics of an AR–15 without looking at the
actions of the shooter.
This Court itself has also previously read the
definition of “machinegun” in this exact statute to refer to the
action of the shooter rather than the firing mechanism. In Staples v. United States , 511
U.S. 600 (1994), the Court noted that “a weapon that fires
repeatedly with a single pull of the trigger ” is a
machinegun, as opposed to “a weapon that fires only one shot with
each pull of the trigger,” which is (at most) a semiautomatic
firearm. Id ., at 602, n. 1 (emphasis added). A “pull”
of the trigger necessarily requires human input.
When a shooter initiates the firing sequence on
a bump-stock-equipped semiautomatic rifle, he does so with “a
single function of the trigger” under that term’s ordinary meaning.
Just as the shooter of an M16 need only pull the trigger and
maintain backward pressure (on the trigger), a shooter of a
bump-stock-equipped AR–15 need only pull the trigger and maintain
forward pressure (on the gun). Both shooters pull the trigger only
once to fire multiple shots. The only difference is that for an
M16, the shooter’s backward pressure makes the rifle fire
continuously because of an internal mechanism: The curved lever of
the trigger does not move. In a bump-stock-equipped AR–15, the
mechanism for continuous fire is external: The shooter’s forward
pressure moves the curved lever back and forth against his
stationary trigger finger. Both rifles require only one initial
action (that is, one “single function of the trigger”) from the
shooter combined with continuous pressure to activate continuous
fire.[ 3 ]
The majority resists this ordinary understanding
of the term “function of the trigger” with two technical
arguments.[ 4 ] First, it
attempts to contrast the action required to fire an M16 from that
required to fire a bump-stock-equipped AR–15. The majority argues
that “holding the trigger down on a fully automatic rifle is not
manual input in addition to a trigger’s function—it is what causes
the trigger to function in the first place” whereas “pushing on the
front grip [of a bump-stock equipped semiautomatic rifle] will not
cause the weapon to fire unless the shooter also engages the
trigger with his other hand.” Ante, at 16. The shooter of a
bump-stock-equipped AR–15, however, need not “pull” the trigger to
fire. Instead, he need only place a finger on the finger rest and
push forward on the front grip or barrel with his other hand.
Instead of pulling the trigger, the forward motion pushes the bump
stock into his finger.
Second, the majority tries to cabin “single
function of the trigger” to a single mechanism for activating
continuous fire. See ante, at 14–15. A shooter can fire a
bump-stock-equipped semiautomatic rifle in two ways. First, he can
choose to fire single shots via distinct pulls of the trigger
without exerting any additional pressure. Second, he can fire
continuously via maintaining constant forward pressure on the
barrel or front grip. The majority holds that the forward pressure
cannot constitute a “single function of the trigger” because a
shooter can also fire single shots by pulling the trigger. That
logic, however, would also exclude a Tommy Gun and an M16, the
paradigmatic examples of regulated machineguns in 1934 and today.
Both weapons can fire either automatically or semiautomatically. A
shooter using a Tommy Gun in automatic mode could choose to fire
single shots with distinct pulls of the trigger, or continuous
shots by maintaining constant backward pressure on the trigger. See supra , at 3. An M16 user can toggle the weapon from
semiautomatic mode, which allows only one shot per pull of the
trigger, to automatic mode, which enables continuous fire. See M16
Field Manual, Section III, p. 4-8. In 1934 as now, there is no
commonsense difference between a firearm where a shooter must hold
down a trigger or flip a switch to initiate rapid fire and one
where a shooter must push on the front grip or barrel to do the
same.
The majority’s logic simply does not overcome
the overwhelming textual and contextual evidence that “single
function of the trigger” means a single action by the shooter to
initiate a firing sequence, including pulling a trigger and pushing
forward on a bump-stock-equipped semiautomatic rifle.
B
Next, consider what makes a machinegun
“automatic.” A bump-stock-equipped semiautomatic rifle is a
“machinegun” because with a “single function of the trigger” it
“shoot[s], automatically more than one shot, without manual
reloading.” §5845(b). Put simply, the bump stock automates the
process of firing more than one shot.
Before automatic weapons, a person who wanted to
fire multiple shots from a firearm had to do two things after
pulling the trigger the first time: (1) he had to reload the gun;
and (2) he had to pull the trigger again. A semiautomatic weapon
like an AR–15 already automates the first process. The bump stock
automates the second.[ 5 ] In a
fully automatic rifle like an M16, that automation is internal.
After a shooter pulls the trigger, if he maintains continuous
backward pressure on the trigger, the curved lever itself will not
move. Instead, an internal mechanism allows continuous fire. On a
bump-stock-equipped semiautomatic rifle, the automation is
external. After a shooter pulls the trigger, if he maintains
continuous forward pressure on the gun, the bump stock harnesses
the recoil to move the curved lever back and forth against his
finger. That external automated motion creates continuous fire.
When a shooter “bump” fires a semiautomatic
weapon without a bump stock, he must control several things using
his own strength and skill: (1) the backward recoil of each
shot, including both the direction in which the rifle moves and how
far it moves when recoiling; (2) the trigger finger, by
maintaining a stationary position with a loose enough hold on the
trigger that the rapidly moving gun will hit his finger each time;
and (3) the forward motion of the rifle after it recoils
backward. A bump stock automates those processes. The replacement
stock controls the direction and distance of the recoil, and the
finger rest obviates the need to maintain a stationary finger
position. All a shooter must do is rest his finger and press
forward on the front grip or barrel for the rifle to fire
continuously.
The majority nevertheless concludes that a
bump-stock-equipped semiautomatic rifle requires too much human
input to fire “automatic[ally]” because it requires the “proper
amount of forward pressure on the front grip” to maintain
continuous fire. Ante, at 16. “Automati[c],” however, does
not mean zero human input. An M16 requires the shooter to exert the
“proper amount of [backward] pressure on the” trigger to maintain
continuous fire. Ibid. So, too, a machinegun that requires a
user to hold down a button. Makers of automatic weapons may require
continuous human input for safety purposes; an accidental trigger
pull that activates rapid fire is less harmful if it does not
require affirmative human action to stop. Requiring continuous
pressure for continuous fire, however, does not prevent a firearm
from “shoot[ing], automatically more than one shot.” §5845(b).
C
This Court has repeatedly avoided
interpretations of a statute that would facilitate its ready
“evasion” or “enable offenders to elude its provisions in the most
easy manner.” The Emily , 9 Wheat. 381, 389–390 (1824); see
also Abramski v. United States , 573 U.S.
169 , 181–182, 185 (2014) (declining to read a gun statute in a
way that would permit ready “evasion,” “defeat the point” of the
law, or “easily bypass the scheme”). Justice Scalia called this
interpretive principle the “presumption against ineffectiveness.”
A. Scalia & B. Garner, Reading Law: The Interpretation of Legal
Texts 63 (2012). The majority arrogates Congress’s policymaking
role to itself by allowing bump-stock users to circumvent
Congress’s ban on weapons that shoot rapidly via a single action of
the shooter.
“The presumption against ineffectiveness ensures
that a text’s manifest purpose is furthered, not hindered.” Ibid. Before machineguns, a shooter could fire a gun only as
fast as his finger could pull the trigger. Congress sought to
restrict the civilian use of machineguns because they eliminated
the need for a person rapidly to pull the trigger himself to fire
continuously. A bump stock serves that function. Even a skilled
sport shooter can fire an AR–15 at a rate of only 180 rounds per
minute by rapidly pulling the trigger. Anyone shooting a
bump-stock-equipped AR–15 can fire at a rate between 400 and 800
rounds per minute with a single pull of the trigger.
Moreover, bump stocks are not the only devices
that transform semiautomatic rifles into weapons capable of rapid
fire with a single function of the trigger. Recognizing the
creativity of gun owners and manufacturers, Congress wrote a
statute “loaded with anticircumvention devices.” Tr. of Oral Arg.
68. The definition of “machinegun” captures “any weapon which
shoots, is designed to shoot, or can be readily restored to shoot,
automatically more than one shot, without manual reloading, by a
single function of the trigger.” §5845(b). Not “more than four,
five, or six shots,” not “single pull” or “single push” of the
trigger.” Following that definition, the Bureau of Alcohol,
Tobacco, Firearms and Explosives (ATF) has reasonably classified
many transformative devices other than bump stocks as
“machinegun[s].”[ 6 ] For
instance, ATF has long classified “forced reset triggers” as
machineguns. See Brief for Petitioners 28. A forced reset trigger
includes a device that forces the trigger back downward after the
shooter’s initial pull, repeatedly pushing the curved lever against
the shooter’s stationary trigger finger. See ibid. To a
shooter, a semiautomatic rifle equipped with a forced reset trigger
feels much like an M16. He must pull the trigger only once and then
maintain pressure to achieve continuous fire. See ibid. Gun owners themselves also have built motorized
devices that will repeatedly pull a semiautomatic firearm’s curved
lever to enable continuous fire. ATF has classified such devices as
“machinegun[s]” since 1982. See Record 1077. In 2003, the Fifth
Circuit held that such a contraption qualified as a “machinegun”
under the statute. See United States v. Camp , 343 F.3d 743 , 745. An owner of a semiautomatic rifle had placed
a fishing reel inside the weapon’s trigger guard. Id ., at
744. When he pulled a switch behind the original trigger, the
switch supplied power to a motor connected to the fishing reel. Ibid. The motor caused the reel to rotate, and that rotation
manipulated the curved lever, causing it to fire in rapid
succession. Ibid. ATF in 2017 also classified as a
“machinegun” a wearable glove that a shooter could activate to
initiate a mechanized piston moving back and forth, repeatedly
pulling and releasing a semiautomatic rifle’s curved lever. See
Record 1074–1076.[ 7 ]
The majority tosses aside the presumption
against ineffectiveness, claiming that its interpretation only
“draws a line more narrowly than one of [Congress’s] conceivable
statutory purposes might suggest” because the statute still
regulates “all traditional machineguns” like M16s. Ante, at
18. Congress’s ban on M16s, however, is far less effective if a
shooter can instead purchase a bump stock or construct a device
that enables his AR–15 to fire at the same rate. Even bump-stock
manufacturers recognize that they are exploiting a loophole, with
one bragging on its website “Bumpfire Stocks are the closest you
can get to full auto and still be legal.” Midsouth Shooters,
BUMPFIRE SYSTEMS,
https://www.midsouthshooterssupply.com/b/bumpfire- systems. The
majority creates a definition of the statute that bans only
“traditional” machineguns, even though its definition renders
Congress’s clear intent readily evadable.
Every Member of the majority has previously
emphasized that the best way to respect congressional intent is to
adhere to the ordinary understanding of the terms Congress uses.
See, e . g ., Jam v. International Finance
Corp. , 586 U.S. 199, 209 (2019) (Roberts, C. J., for the
Court) (“ ‘[T]he legislative purpose is expressed by the
ordinary meaning of the words used’ ”); Gross v. FBL
Financial Services, Inc. , 557 U.S.
167 , 175 (2009) (Thomas, J., for the Court) (“ ‘Statutory
construction must begin with the language employed by Congress and
the assumption that the ordinary meaning of that language
accurately expresses the legislative purpose’ ”); Wall v. Kholi , 562 U.S.
545 , 551 (2011) (Alito, J., for the Court) (“ ‘We give the
words of a statute their ordinary, contemporary, common meaning,
absent an indication Congress intended them to bear some different
import’ ”); BP p.l.c. v. Mayor and City Council of
Baltimore , 593 U.S. 230, 237 (2021) (Gorsuch, J., for the
Court) (“When called on to interpret a statute, this Court
generally seeks to discern and apply the ordinary meaning of its
terms at the time of their adoption”); Sackett v. EPA , 598 U.S. 651, 723, 727 (2023) (Kavanaugh, J.,
concurring in judgment) (reasoning that departing from “all
indications of ordinary meaning” will “create regulatory
uncertainty for the Federal Government . . . and
regulated parties”); Bartenwerfer v. Buckley , 598
U.S. 69, 77, 83 (2023) (Barrett, J., for the Court) (declining to
“artificially narrow ordinary meaning” to “second-guess
[Congress’s] judgment”). Today, the majority forgets that principle
and substitutes its own view of what constitutes a “machinegun” for
Congress’s.
* * *
Congress’s definition of “machinegun”
encompasses bump stocks just as naturally as M16s. Just like a
person can shoot “automatically more than one shot” with an M16
through a “single function of the trigger” if he maintains
continuous backward pressure on the trigger, he can do the same
with a bump-stock-equipped semiautomatic rifle if he maintains
forward pressure on the gun. §5845(b). Today’s decision to reject
that ordinary understanding will have deadly consequences. The
majority’s artificially narrow definition hamstrings the
Government’s efforts to keep machineguns from gunmen like the Las
Vegas shooter. I respectfully dissent. Notes 1 Congress has twice
strengthened the regulation of machineguns over the years without
substantially updating the definition. See Gun Control Act of 1968,
82Stat. 1213 (expanding registration requirements and strengthening
criminal penalties); Firearms Owners’ Protection Act, 100Stat.
452–453 (making it a federal crime “ ‘to transfer or possess a
machinegun’ ”). 2 Of course, “authoritative
legislative history can be useful, even when the meaning can be
discerned from the statute’s language, to reinforce or to confirm a
court’s sense of the text.” R. Katzmann, Judging Statutes 35
(2014). 3 The majority thinks that
this logic should apply just as well to manual bump firing. Ante, at 14. As described supra , at 5, and infra , at 13, however, bump firing requires much more from
the shooter than the simple forward pressure required to fire a
bump-stock-equipped semiautomatic rifle. 4 The majority claims that
these arguments explain only “why, even assuming a semiautomatic
rifle equipped with a bump stock could fire more than one shot by a
single function of the trigger, it could not do so
‘automatically.’ ” Ante, at 13, n. 6. That is
correct, as far as the majority’s reasoning goes. The majority
defines “ ‘single function of the trigger’ ” as a reset
of a rifle’s internal trigger mechanism. Ante, at 11. A more
accurate definition is the human action required to initiate the
firing sequence. Supra , at 7–10. The majority’s argument for
why “something more than a ‘single function of the trigger’ is
required to fire multiple shots,” ante, at 15, is therefore
relevant to both its discussion of “automatically” and my
discussion of “single function of the trigger.” 5 The majority attempts to
analogize a bump stock to the Model 37 shotgun, which allows the
user to “fire multiple shots by holding down the trigger while
operating the shotgun’s pump action.” Ante, at 16. The Model
37 automates the second process ( i . e ., pulling the
trigger for each shot), as long as the shooter maintains pressure
on the trigger. Unlike a semiautomatic rifle, however, the Model 37
does not automate the first, as the shooter “must manually operate
the pump action with his nontrigger hand” to “ejec[t ] the
spent cartridge and loa[d ] a new one into the chamber.” Ibid. 6 The majority emphasizes
that ATF previously took the position that certain bump-stock
devices were not “machinegun[s]” under the statute. See ante, at 3, 19. ATF, however, has repeatedly classified
other devices that modify semiautomatic rifles by allowing a single
activation of the shooter to automate repeat fire as machineguns.
See, e . g ., 83 Fed. Reg. 66518, n. 4 (referencing
ATF classifications of trigger reset devices); Akins v. United States , 312 F. Appx. 197, 200–201 (CA11 2009)
( per curiam ) (upholding classification of Akins
Accelerator, a spring-operated bump stock); United States v. Camp , 343 F.3d 743 , 745 (CA5 2003) (upholding classification of
fishing reel attached to a rifle trigger that, upon activation,
repeatedly operated the curved lever of the rifle). 7 Respondent does not today
challenge ATF’s classification of these devices as “machinegun[s].”
His lawyer noted at oral argument, however, that “forced reset
triggers” would be part of a category of “harder cases” where
“there may be a question as to what exactly the trigger is and then
how does that trigger function.” Tr. of Oral Arg. 82. That
ambiguity stems from the majority’s loophole for weapons that
require multiple mechanical actions to fire continuously, even when
a shooter initiates that fire with a single human
action. | The Supreme Court held that a bump stock, an accessory that increases the rate of fire for a semiautomatic rifle, does not convert the rifle into a machine gun as defined by the National Firearms Act of 1934 and affirmed the lower court's decision. The Court's decision centered on the interpretation of the phrase "single function of the trigger," with the majority defining it as the internal trigger mechanism's mechanical process, and the minority arguing it should be defined as the human action required to initiate firing. This decision has implications for the regulation of bump stocks and similar devices, with potential loopholes for weapons that require multiple mechanical actions to fire continuously. |
Gun Rights | McDonald v. City of Chicago | https://supreme.justia.com/cases/federal/us/561/742/ | OPINION OF THE COURT MCDONALD V. CHICAGO 561 U. S. ____ (2010) SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES NO. 08-1521 OTIS McDONALD, et al., PETITIONERS v. CITY OF CHICAGO, ILLINOIS, et al.
on writ of certiorari to the united states court of
appeals for the seventh circuit
[June 28, 2010]
Justice Alito announced the
judgment of the Court and delivered the opinion of the Court with
respect to Parts I, II–A, II–B, II–D, III–A, and III–B, in which
The Chief Justice, Justice Scalia, Justice Kennedy, and Justice
Thomas join, and an opinion with respect to Parts II–C, IV, and V,
in which The Chief Justice, Justice Scalia, and Justice Kennedy
join.
Two years ago, in District of
Columbia v. Heller , 554 U. S. ___ (2008), we held
that the Second Amendment protects the right to keep and bear arms
for the purpose of self-defense, and we struck down a District of
Columbia law that banned the possession of handguns in the home.
The city of Chicago (City) and the village of Oak Park, a Chicago
suburb, have laws that are similar to the District of Columbia’s,
but Chicago and Oak Park argue that their laws are constitutional
because the Second Amendment has no application to the States. We
have previously held that most of the provisions of the Bill of
Rights apply with full force to both the Federal Government and the
States. Applying the standard that is well established in our case
law, we hold that the Second Amendment right is fully applicable to
the States.
I
Otis McDonald, Adam Orlov,
Colleen Lawson, and David Lawson (Chicago petitioners) are Chicago
residents who would like to keep handguns in their homes for
self-defense but are prohibited from doing so by Chicago’s firearms
laws. A City ordinance provides that “[n]o person shall … possess …
any firearm unless such person is the holder of a valid
registration certificate for such firearm.” Chicago, Ill.,
Municipal Code §8–20–040(a) (2009). The Code then prohibits
registration of most handguns, thus effectively banning handgun
possession by almost all private citizens who reside in the City.
§8–20–050(c). Like Chicago, Oak Park makes it “unlawful for any
person to possess … any firearm,” a term that includes “pistols,
revolvers, guns and small arms … commonly known as handguns.” Oak
Park, Ill., Municipal Code §§27–2–1 (2007), 27–1–1 (2009).
Chicago enacted its handgun ban
to protect its residents “from the loss of property and injury or
death from firearms.” See Chicago, Ill., Journal of Proceedings of
the City Council, p. 10049 (Mar. 19, 1982). The Chicago petitioners
and their amici , however, argue that the handgun ban has
left them vulnerable to criminals. Chicago Police Department
statistics, we are told, reveal that the City’s handgun murder rate
has actually increased since the ban was enacted[ Footnote 1 ] and that Chicago residents now face
one of the highest murder rates in the country and rates of other
violent crimes that exceed the average in comparable
cities.[ Footnote 2 ]
Several of the Chicago petitioners have been
the targets of threats and violence. For instance, Otis McDonald,
who is in his late seventies, lives in a high-crime neighborhood.
He is a community activist involved with alternative policing
strategies, and his efforts to improve his neighborhood have
subjected him to violent threats from drug dealers. App. 16–17;
Brief for State Firearm Associations as Amici Curiae 20–21; Brief for State of Texas et al. as Amici
Curiae 7–8. Colleen Lawson is a Chicago resident whose home
has been targeted by burglars. “In Mrs. Lawson’s judgment,
possessing a handgun in Chicago would decrease her chances of
suffering serious injury or death should she ever be threatened
again in her home.”[ Footnote 3 ]
McDonald, Lawson, and the other Chicago petitioners own handguns
that they store outside of the city limits, but they would like to
keep their handguns in their homes for protection. See App. 16–19,
43–44 (McDonald), 20–24 (C. Lawson), 19, 36 (Orlov), 20–21, 40 (D.
Lawson).
After our decision in Heller , the
Chicago petitioners and two groups[ Footnote 4 ] filed suit against the City in the United
States District Court for the Northern District of Illinois. They
sought a declaration that the handgun ban and several related
Chicago ordinances violate the Second and Fourteenth Amendments to
the United States Constitution. Another action challenging the Oak
Park law was filed in the same District Court by the National Rifle
Association (NRA) and two Oak Park residents. In addition, the NRA
and others filed a third action challenging the Chicago ordinances.
All three cases were assigned to the same District Judge.
The District Court rejected plaintiffs’
argument that the Chicago and Oak Park laws are unconstitutional.
See App. 83–84; NRA, Inc. v. Oak Park , 617
F. Supp. 2d 752, 754 (ND Ill. 2008). The court noted that the
Seventh Circuit had “squarely upheld the constitutionality of a ban
on handguns a quarter century ago,” id ., at 753 (citing Quilici v. Morton Grove , 695 F. 2d 261 (CA7
1982)), and that Heller had explicitly refrained from
“opin[ing] on the subject of incorporation vel non of the Second
Amendment,” NRA , 617 F. Supp. 2d, at 754. The court
observed that a district judge has a “duty to follow established
precedent in the Court of Appeals to which he or she is beholden,
even though the logic of more recent caselaw may point in a
different direction.” Id., at 753.
The Seventh Circuit affirmed, relying on three
19th-century cases— United States v. Cruikshank , 92 U.
S. 542 (1876), Presser v. Illinois , 116 U. S. 252 (1886), and Miller v. Texas , 153 U. S. 535 (1894)—that were decided
in the wake of this Court’s interpretation of the Privileges or
Immunities Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment in the Slaughter-House Cases, 16 Wall. 36 (1873) . The
Seventh Circuit described the rationale of those cases as “defunct”
and recognized that they did not consider the question whether the
Fourteenth Amendment’s Due Process Clause incorporates the Second
Amendment right to keep and bear arms. NRA, Inc. v. Chicago , 567 F. 3d 856, 857, 858 (2009).
Nevertheless, the Seventh Circuit observed that it was obligated to
follow Supreme Court precedents that have “direct application,” and
it declined to predict how the Second Amendment would fare under
this Court’s modern “selective incorporation” approach. Id., at 857–858 (internal quotation marks omitted).
We granted certiorari. 557 U. S. ___
(2009).
II
A
Petitioners argue that the
Chicago and Oak Park laws violate the right to keep and bear arms
for two reasons. Petitioners’ primary submission is that this right
is among the “privileges or immunities of citizens of the United
States” and that the narrow interpretation of the Privileges or
Immunities Clause adopted in the Slaughter-House Cases , supra , should now be rejected. As a secondary argument,
petitioners contend that the Fourteenth Amendment’s Due Process
Clause “incorporates” the Second Amendment right.
Chicago and Oak Park (municipal
respondents) maintain that a right set out in the Bill of Rights
applies to the States only if that right is an indispensable
attribute of any “ ‘civilized’ ” legal system.
Brief for Municipal Respondents 9. If it is possible to imagine a
civilized country that does not recognize the right, the municipal
respondents tell us, then that right is not protected by due
process. Ibid. And since there are civilized countries
that ban or strictly regulate the private possession of handguns,
the municipal respondents maintain that due process does not
preclude such measures. Id. , at 21–23. In light of the
parties’ far-reaching arguments, we begin by recounting this
Court’s analysis over the years of the relationship between the
provisions of the Bill of Rights and the States.
B
The Bill of Rights, including the
Second Amendment, originally applied only to the Federal
Government. In Barron ex rel. Tiernan v. Mayor of
Baltimore , 7 Pet. 243 (1833), the Court, in an opinion by
Chief Justice Marshall, explained that this question was “of great
importance” but “not of much difficulty.” Id ., at 247. In
less than four pages, the Court firmly rejected the proposition
that the first eight Amendments operate as limitations on the
States, holding that they apply only to the Federal Government. See
also Lessee of Livingston v. Moore , 7 Pet. 469,
551–552 (1833) (“[I]t is now settled that those amendments [in the
Bill of Rights] do not extend to the states”).
The constitutional Amendments
adopted in the aftermath of the Civil War fundamentally altered our
country’s federal system. The provision at issue in this case, §1
of the Fourteenth Amendment, provides, among other things, that a
State may not abridge “the privileges or immunities of citizens of
the United States” or deprive “any person of life, liberty, or
property, without due process of law.”
Four years after the adoption of the
Fourteenth Amendment, this Court was asked to interpret the
Amendment’s reference to “the privileges or immunities of citizens
of the United States.” The Slaughter-House Cases , supra , involved challenges to a Louisiana law permitting
the creation of a state-sanctioned monopoly on the butchering of
animals within the city of New Orleans. Justice Samuel Miller’s
opinion for the Court concluded that the Privileges or Immunities
Clause protects only those rights “which owe their existence to the
Federal government, its National character, its Constitution, or
its laws.” Id. , at 79. The Court held that other
fundamental rights—rights that predated the creation of the Federal
Government and that “the State governments were created to
establish and secure”—were not protected by the Clause. Id. , at 76.
In drawing a sharp distinction between the
rights of federal and state citizenship, the Court relied on two
principal arguments. First, the Court emphasized that the
Fourteenth Amendment’s Privileges or Immunities Clause spoke of
“the privileges or immunities of citizens of the United
States ,” and the Court contrasted this phrasing with the
wording in the first sentence of the Fourteenth Amendment and in
the Privileges and Immunities Clause of Article IV, both of which
refer to state citizenship.[ Footnote 5 ] (Emphasis added.) Second, the Court stated
that a contrary reading would “radically chang[e] the whole theory
of the relations of the State and Federal governments to each other
and of both these governments to the people,” and the Court refused
to conclude that such a change had been made “in the absence of
language which expresses such a purpose too clearly to admit of
doubt.” Id. , at 78. Finding the phrase “privileges or
immunities of citizens of the United States” lacking by this high
standard, the Court reasoned that the phrase must mean something
more limited.
Under the Court’s narrow reading, the
Privileges or Immunities Clause protects such things as the
right
“to come to the seat of government to assert any
claim [a citizen] may have upon that government, to transact any
business he may have with it, to seek its protection, to share its
offices, to engage in administering its functions … [and to]
become a citizen of any State of the Union by a bonâ fide residence therein, with the same rights as other citizens of that
State.” Id. , at 79–80 (internal quotation marks
omitted).
Finding no constitutional
protection against state intrusion of the kind envisioned by the
Louisiana statute, the Court upheld the statute. Four Justices
dissented. Justice Field, joined by Chief Justice Chase and
Justices Swayne and Bradley, criticized the majority for reducing
the Fourteenth Amendment’s Privileges or Immunities Clause to “a
vain and idle enactment, which accomplished nothing, and most
unnecessarily excited Congress and the people on its passage.” Id. , at 96; see also id. , at 104. Justice Field
opined that the Privileges or Immunities Clause protects rights
that are “in their nature … fundamental,” including the right of
every man to pursue his profession without the imposition of
unequal or discriminatory restrictions. Id. , at 96–97.
Justice Bradley’s dissent observed that “we are not bound to resort
to implication … to find an authoritative declaration of some of
the most important privileges and immunities of citizens of the
United States. It is in the Constitution itself.” Id ., at
118. Justice Bradley would have construed the Privileges or
Immunities Clause to include those rights enumerated in the
Constitution as well as some unenumerated rights. Id. , at
119. Justice Swayne described the majority’s narrow reading of the
Privileges or Immunities Clause as “turn[ing] … what was meant for
bread into a stone.” Id ., at 129 (dissenting opinion).
Today, many legal scholars dispute the
correctness of the narrow Slaughter-House interpretation.
See, e.g. , Saenz v. Roe , 526 U. S. 489 , 522,
n. 1, 527 (1999) (Thomas, J., dissenting) (scholars of the
Fourteenth Amendment agree “that the Clause does not mean what the
Court said it meant in 1873”); Amar, Substance and Method in the
Year 2000, 28 Pepperdine L. Rev. 601, 631, n. 178 (2001)
(“Virtually no serious modern scholar—left, right, and
center—thinks that this [interpretation] is a plausible reading of
the Amendment”); Brief for Constitutional Law Professors as Amici Curiae 33 (claiming an “overwhelming consensus among
leading constitutional scholars” that the opinion is “egregiously
wrong”); C. Black, A New Birth of Freedom 74–75 (1997).
Three years after the decision in the Slaughter-House Cases, the Court decided Cruikshank, the first of the three 19th-century cases on
which the Seventh Circuit relied. 92 U.
S. 542 . In that case, the Court reviewed convictions stemming
from the infamous Colfax Massacre in Louisiana on Easter Sunday
1873. Dozens of blacks, many unarmed, were slaughtered by a rival
band of armed white men.[ Footnote
6 ] Cruikshank himself allegedly marched unarmed
African-American prisoners through the streets and then had them
summarily executed.[ Footnote 7 ]
Ninety-seven men were indicted for participating in the massacre,
but only nine went to trial. Six of the nine were acquitted of all
charges; the remaining three were acquitted of murder but convicted
under the Enforcement Act of 1870, 16 Stat. 140, for banding and
conspiring together to deprive their victims of various
constitutional rights, including the right to bear arms.[ Footnote 8 ]
The Court reversed all of the convictions,
including those relating to the deprivation of the victims’ right
to bear arms. Cruikshank , 92 U. S., at 553, 559. The Court
wrote that the right of bearing arms for a lawful purpose “is not a
right granted by the Constitution” and is not “in any manner
dependent upon that instrument for its existence.” Id. , at
553. “The second amendment,” the Court continued, “declares that it
shall not be infringed; but this … means no more than that it shall
not be infringed by Congress.” Ibid. “Our later decisions
in Presser v. Illinois, 116 U. S. 252 , 265 (1886), and Miller v. Texas, 153 U. S. 535 , 538 (1894), reaffirmed
that the Second Amendment applies only to the Federal Government.” Heller , 554 U. S., at ___, n. 23 (slip op., at 48,
n. 23).
C
As previously noted, the Seventh
Circuit concluded that Cruikshank , Presser , and Miller doomed petitioners’ claims at the Court of Appeals
level. Petitioners argue, however, that we should overrule those
decisions and hold that the right to keep and bear arms is one of
the “privileges or immunities of citizens of the United States.” In
petitioners’ view, the Privileges or Immunities Clause protects all
of the rights set out in the Bill of Rights, as well as some
others, see Brief for Petitioners 10, 14, 15–21, but petitioners
are unable to identify the Clause’s full scope, Tr. of Oral Arg.
5–6, 8–11. Nor is there any consensus on that question among the
scholars who agree that the Slaughter-House Cases’ interpretation is flawed. See Saenz , supra , at
522, n. 1 (Thomas, J., dissenting).
We see no need to reconsider that
interpretation here. For many decades, the question of the rights
protected by the Fourteenth Amendment against state infringement
has been analyzed under the Due Process Clause of that Amendment
and not under the Privileges or Immunities Clause. We therefore
decline to disturb the Slaughter-House holding.
At the same time, however, this Court’s
decisions in Cruikshank , Presser , and Miller do not preclude us from considering whether the Due
Process Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment makes the Second
Amendment right binding on the States. See Heller , 554 U.
S., at ___, n. 23 (slip op., at 48, n. 23). None of those
cases “engage[d] in the sort of Fourteenth Amendment inquiry
required by our later cases.” Ibid . As explained more
fully below, Cruikshank , Presser , and Miller all preceded the era in which the Court began the
process of “selective incorporation” under the Due Process Clause,
and we have never previously addressed the question whether the
right to keep and bear arms applies to the States under that
theory.
Indeed, Cruikshank has not prevented
us from holding that other rights that were at issue in that case
are binding on the States through the Due Process Clause. In Cruikshank , the Court held that the general “right of the
people peaceably to assemble for lawful purposes,” which is
protected by the First Amendment, applied only against the Federal
Government and not against the States. See 92 U. S., at 551–552.
Nonetheless, over 60 years later the Court held that the right of
peaceful assembly was a “fundamental righ[t] … safeguarded by the
due process clause of the Fourteenth Amendment.” De Jonge v. Oregon , 299 U. S. 353 , 364 (1937). We follow
the same path here and thus consider whether the right to keep and
bear arms applies to the States under the Due Process Clause.
D
1
In the late 19th century, the
Court began to consider whether the Due Process Clause prohibits
the States from infringing rights set out in the Bill of Rights.
See Hurtado v. California , 110 U. S. 516 (1884) (due process does
not require grand jury indictment); Chicago, B. & Q.
R. Co. v. Chicago , 166 U. S. 226 (1897) (due process
prohibits States from taking of private property for public use
without just compensation). Five features of the approach taken
during the ensuing era should be noted.
First, the Court viewed the due
process question as entirely separate from the question whether a
right was a privilege or immunity of national citizenship. See Twining v. New Jersey , 211 U. S. 78 , 99 (1908).
Second, the Court explained that the only
rights protected against state infringement by the Due Process
Clause were those rights “of such a nature that they are included
in the conception of due process of law.” Ibid . See also, e.g. , Adamson v. California , 332 U.
S. 46 (1947); Betts v. Brady , 316 U. S. 455 (1942); Palko v. Connecticut, 302 U. S. 319 (1937); Grosjean v. American Press Co. , 297 U. S. 233 (1936); Powell v. Alabama , 287 U. S. 45 (1932).
While it was “possible that some of the personal rights safeguarded
by the first eight Amendments against National action [might] also
be safeguarded against state action,” the Court stated, this was
“not because those rights are enumerated in the first eight
Amendments.” Twining, supra, at 99.
The Court used different formulations in
describing the boundaries of due process. For example, in Twining , the Court referred to “immutable principles of
justice which inhere in the very idea of free government which no
member of the Union may disregard.” 211 U. S., at 102 (internal
quotation marks omitted). In Snyder v. Massachusetts , 291 U. S. 97 , 105 (1934),
the Court spoke of rights that are “so rooted in the traditions and
conscience of our people as to be ranked as fundamental.” And in Palko , the Court famously said that due process protects
those rights that are “the very essence of a scheme of ordered
liberty” and essential to “a fair and enlightened system of
justice.” 302 U. S., at 325.
Third, in some cases decided during this era
the Court “can be seen as having asked, when inquiring into whether
some particular procedural safeguard was required of a State, if a
civilized system could be imagined that would not accord the
particular protection.” Duncan v. Louisiana , 391 U. S. 145 , 149, n. 14 (1968).
Thus, in holding that due process prohibits a State from taking
private property without just compensation, the Court described the
right as “a principle of natural equity, recognized by all
temperate and civilized governments, from a deep and universal
sense of its justice.” Chicago, B. & Q. R. Co.,
supra, at 238. Similarly, the Court found that due process did
not provide a right against compelled incrimination in part because
this right “has no place in the jurisprudence of civilized and free
countries outside the domain of the common law.” Twining,
supra , at 113.
Fourth, the Court during this era was not
hesitant to hold that a right set out in the Bill of Rights failed
to meet the test for inclusion within the protection of the Due
Process Clause. The Court found that some such rights qualified.
See, e.g. , Gitlow v. New York , 268 U. S. 652 , 666 (1925) (freedom of
speech and press); Near v. Minnesota ex rel.
Olson , 283 U. S. 697 (1931) (same); Powell , supra (assistance of counsel in capital
cases); De Jonge , supra (freedom of assembly); Cantwell v. Connecticut , 310 U. S. 296 (1940) (free exercise of
religion). But others did not. See, e.g. , Hurtado,
supra (grand jury indictment requirement); Twining , supra (privilege against self-incrimination).
Finally, even when a right set out in the Bill
of Rights was held to fall within the conception of due process,
the protection or remedies afforded against state infringement
sometimes differed from the protection or remedies provided against
abridgment by the Federal Government. To give one example, in Betts the Court held that, although the Sixth Amendment
required the appointment of counsel in all federal criminal cases
in which the defendant was unable to retain an attorney, the Due
Process Clause required appointment of counsel in state criminal
proceedings only where “want of counsel in [the] particular case …
result[ed] in a conviction lacking in … fundamental fairness.” 316
U. S., at 473. Similarly, in Wolf v. Colorado , 338 U.
S. 25 (1949), the Court held that the “core of the Fourth
Amendment” was implicit in the concept of ordered liberty and thus
“enforceable against the States through the Due Process Clause” but
that the exclusionary rule, which applied in federal cases, did not
apply to the States. Id ., at 27–28, 33.
2
An alternative theory regarding
the relationship between the Bill of Rights and §1 of the
Fourteenth Amendment was championed by Justice Black. This theory
held that §1 of the Fourteenth Amendment totally incorporated all
of the provisions of the Bill of Rights. See, e.g. , Adamson , supra , at 71–72 (Black, J., dissenting); Duncan , supra , at 166 (Black, J., concurring). As
Justice Black noted, the chief congressional proponents of the
Fourteenth Amendment espoused the view that the Amendment made the
Bill of Rights applicable to the States and, in so doing, overruled
this Court’s decision in Barron .[ Footnote 9 ] Adamson , 332 U. S., at 72
(dissenting opinion).[ Footnote
10 ] Nonetheless, the Court never has embraced Justice Black’s
“total incorporation” theory.
3
While Justice Black’s theory was
never adopted, the Court eventually moved in that direction by
initiating what has been called a process of “selective
incorporation,” i.e ., the Court began to hold that the Due
Process Clause fully incorporates particular rights contained in
the first eight Amendments. See, e.g. , Gideon v. Wainright , 372
U. S. 335 , 341 (1963); Malloy v. Hogan , 378 U. S. 1 , 5–6 (1964); Pointer v. Texas , 380 U. S. 400 , 403–404 (1965); Washington v. Texas , 388 U. S. 14 , 18 (1967); Duncan , 391 U. S., at 147–148; Benton v. Maryland , 395 U. S. 784 , 794 (1969).
The decisions during this time
abandoned three of the previously noted characteristics of the
earlier period.[ Footnote 11 ]
The Court made it clear that the governing standard is not whether any “civilized system [can] be imagined that would not
accord the particular protection.” Duncan , 391 U. S., at
149, n. 14. Instead, the Court inquired whether a particular
Bill of Rights guarantee is fundamental to our scheme of
ordered liberty and system of justice. Id ., at 149, and
n. 14; see also id., at 148 (referring to those
“fundamental principles of liberty and justice which lie at the
base of all our civil and political institutions”
(emphasis added; internal quotation marks omitted)).
The Court also shed any reluctance to hold
that rights guaranteed by the Bill of Rights met the requirements
for protection under the Due Process Clause. The Court eventually
incorporated almost all of the provisions of the Bill of
Rights.[ Footnote 12 ] Only a
handful of the Bill of Rights protections remain
unincorporated.[ Footnote
13 ]
Finally, the Court abandoned “the notion that
the Fourteenth Amendment applies to the States only a watered-down,
subjective version of the individual guarantees of the Bill of
Rights,” stating that it would be “incongruous” to apply different
standards “depending on whether the claim was asserted in a state
or federal court.” Malloy , 378 U. S., at 10–11 (internal
quotation marks omitted). Instead, the Court decisively held that
incorporated Bill of Rights protections “are all to be enforced
against the States under the Fourteenth Amendment according to the
same standards that protect those personal rights against federal
encroachment.” Id ., at 10; see also Mapp v. Ohio , 367 U. S. 643 , 655–656 (1961); Ker v. California , 374 U. S. 23 , 33–34
(1963); Aguilar v. Texas , 378 U. S. 1 08, 110 (1964); Pointer , 380 U. S., at 406; Duncan , supra , at 149, 157–158; Benton , 395 U. S., at
794–795; Wallace v. Jaffree , 472 U. S. 38 , 48–49
(1985).[ Footnote 14 ]
Employing this approach, the Court overruled
earlier decisions in which it had held that particular Bill of
Rights guarantees or remedies did not apply to the States. See, e.g. , Mapp , supra (overruling in part Wolf , 338 U.
S. 25 ); Gideon , 372
U. S. 335 (overruling Betts , 316 U. S. 455 ); Malloy , supra (overruling Adamson , 332 U.
S. 46 , and Twining , 211 U. S. 78 ); Benton , supra , at 794 (overruling Palko , 302 U. S. 319 ).
III
With this framework in mind, we
now turn directly to the question whether the Second Amendment
right to keep and bear arms is incorporated in the concept of due
process. In answering that question, as just explained, we must
decide whether the right to keep and bear arms is fundamental to our scheme of ordered liberty, Duncan, 391 U. S.,
at 149, or as we have said in a related context, whether this right
is “deeply rooted in this Nation’s history and tradition,” Washington v. Glucksberg, 521 U. S. 702 , 721 (1997) (internal
quotation marks omitted).
A
Our decision in Heller points unmistakably to the answer. Self-defense is a basic right,
recognized by many legal systems from ancient times to the present
day,[ Footnote 15 ] and in Heller, we held that individual self-defense is “the central component ” of the Second Amendment right. 554 U.
S., at ___ (slip op., at 26); see also id ., at ___ (slip
op., at 56) (stating that the “inherent right of self-defense has
been central to the Second Amendment right”). Explaining that “the
need for defense of self, family, and property is most acute” in
the home, ibid ., we found that this right applies to
handguns because they are “the most preferred firearm in the nation
to ‘keep’ and use for protection of one’s home and family,” id ., at ___ (slip op., at 57) (some internal quotation
marks omitted); see also id ., at ___ (slip op., at 56)
(noting that handguns are “overwhelmingly chosen by American
society for [the] lawful purpose” of self-defense); id .,
at ___ (slip op., at 57) (“[T]he American people have considered
the handgun to be the quintessential self-defense weapon”). Thus,
we concluded, citizens must be permitted “to use [handguns] for the
core lawful purpose of self-defense.” Id ., at ___ (slip
op., at 58). Heller makes it clear
that this right is “deeply rooted in this Nation’s history and
tradition. ” Glucksberg, supra, at 721 (internal
quotation marks omitted). Heller explored the right’s
origins, noting that the 1689 English Bill of Rights explicitly
protected a right to keep arms for self-defense, 554 U. S., at
___–___ (slip op., at 19–20), and that by 1765, Blackstone was able
to assert that the right to keep and bear arms was “one of the
fundamental rights of Englishmen,” id ., at ___ (slip op.,
at 20).
Blackstone’s assessment was shared by the
American colonists. As we noted in Heller , King George
III’s attempt to disarm the colonists in the 1760’s and 1770’s
“provoked polemical reactions by Americans invoking their rights as
Englishmen to keep arms.”[ Footnote 16 ] Id ., at ___ (slip op., at 21); see
also L. Levy, Origins of the Bill of Rights 137–143 (1999)
(hereinafter Levy).
The right to keep and bear arms was considered
no less fundamental by those who drafted and ratified the Bill of
Rights. “During the 1788 ratification debates, the fear that the
federal government would disarm the people in order to impose rule
through a standing army or select militia was pervasive in
Antifederalist rhetoric.” Heller , supra , at ___
(slip op., at 25) (citing Letters from the Federal Farmer III (Oct.
10, 1787), in 2 The Complete Anti-Federalist 234, 242 (H. Storing
ed. 1981)); see also Federal Farmer: An Additional Number of
Letters to the Republican, Letter XVIII (Jan. 25, 1788), in 17
Documentary History of the Ratification of the Constitution 360,
362–363 (J. Kaminski & G. Saladino eds. 1995); S. Halbrook, The
Founders’ Second Amendment 171–278 (2008). Federalists responded,
not by arguing that the right was insufficiently important to
warrant protection but by contending that the right was adequately
protected by the Constitution’s assignment of only limited powers
to the Federal Government. Heller , supra , at ___
(slip op., at 25–26); cf. The Federalist No. 46, p. 296 (C.
Rossiter ed. 1961) (J. Madison). Thus, Antifederalists and
Federalists alike agreed that the right to bear arms was
fundamental to the newly formed system of government. See Levy
143–149; J. Malcolm, To Keep and Bear Arms: The Origins of an
Anglo-American Right 155–164 (1994). But those who were fearful
that the new Federal Government would infringe traditional rights
such as the right to keep and bear arms insisted on the adoption of
the Bill of Rights as a condition for ratification of the
Constitution. See 1 J. Elliot, The Debates in the Several State
Conventions on the Adoption of the Federal Constitution 327–331 (2d
ed. 1854); 3 id. , at 657–661; 4 id. , at 242–246,
248–249; see also Levy 26–34; A. Kelly & W. Harbison, The
American Constitution: Its Origins and Development 110, 118 (7th
ed. 1991). This is surely powerful evidence that the right was
regarded as fundamental in the sense relevant here.
This understanding persisted in the years
immediately following the ratification of the Bill of Rights. In
addition to the four States that had adopted Second Amendment
analogues before ratification, nine more States adopted state
constitutional provisions protecting an individual right to keep
and bear arms between 1789 and 1820. Heller , supra , at ___ (slip op., at 27–30). Founding-era legal
commentators confirmed the importance of the right to early
Americans. St. George Tucker, for example, described the right to
keep and bear arms as “the true palladium of liberty” and explained
that prohibitions on the right would place liberty “on the brink of
destruction.” 1 Blackstone’s Commentaries, Editor’s App. 300 (S.
Tucker ed. 1803); see also W. Rawle, A View of the Constitution of
the United States of America, 125–126 (2d ed. 1829) (reprint 2009);
3 J. Story, Commentaries on the Constitution of the United States
§1890, p. 746 (1833) (“The right of the citizens to keep and
bear arms has justly been considered, as the palladium of the
liberties of a republic; since it offers a strong moral check
against the usurpation and arbitrary power of rulers; and will
generally, even if these are successful in the first instance,
enable the people to resist and triumph over them”).
B
1
By the 1850’s, the perceived
threat that had prompted the inclusion of the Second Amendment in
the Bill of Rights—the fear that the National Government would
disarm the universal militia—had largely faded as a popular
concern, but the right to keep and bear arms was highly valued for
purposes of self-defense. See M. Doubler, Civilian in Peace,
Soldier in War 87–90 (2003); Amar, Bill of Rights 258–259.
Abolitionist authors wrote in support of the right. See L. Spooner,
The Unconstitutionality of Slavery 66 (1860) (reprint 1965); J.
Tiffany, A Treatise on the Unconstitutionality of American Slavery
117–118 (1849) (reprint 1969). And when attempts were made to
disarm “Free-Soilers” in “Bloody Kansas,” Senator Charles Sumner,
who later played a leading role in the adoption of the Fourteenth
Amendment, proclaimed that “[n]ever was [the rifle] more needed in
just self-defense than now in Kansas.” The Crime Against Kansas:
The Apologies for the Crime: The True Remedy, Speech of Hon.
Charles Sumner in the Senate of the United States 64–65 (1856).
Indeed, the 1856 Republican Party Platform protested that in Kansas
the constitutional rights of the people had been “fraudulently and
violently taken from them” and the “right of the people to keep and
bear arms” had been “infringed.” National Party Platforms
1840–1972, p. 27 (5th ed. 1973).[ Footnote 17 ]
After the Civil War, many of the
over 180,000 African Americans who served in the Union Army
returned to the States of the old Confederacy, where systematic
efforts were made to disarm them and other blacks. See Heller , 554 U. S., at ___ (slip op., at 42); E. Foner,
Reconstruction: America’s Unfinished Revolution 1863–1877,
p. 8 (1988) (hereinafter Foner). The laws of some States
formally prohibited African Americans from possessing firearms. For
example, a Mississippi law provided that “no freedman, free negro
or mulatto, not in the military service of the United States
government, and not licensed so to do by the board of police of his
or her county, shall keep or carry fire-arms of any kind, or any
ammunition, dirk or bowie knife.” Certain Offenses of Freedmen,
1865 Miss. Laws p. 165, §1, in 1 Documentary History of
Reconstruction 289 (W. Fleming ed. 1950); see also Regulations for
Freedmen in Louisiana, in id ., at 279–280; H. R.
Exec. Doc. No. 70, 39th Cong., 1st Sess., 233, 236 (1866)
(describing a Kentucky law); E. McPherson, The Political History of
the United States of America During the Period of Reconstruction 40
(1871) (describing a Florida law); id ., at 33 (describing
an Alabama law).[ Footnote
18 ]
Throughout the South, armed parties, often
consisting of ex-Confederate soldiers serving in the state
militias, forcibly took firearms from newly freed slaves. In the
first session of the 39th Congress, Senator Wilson told his
colleagues: “In Mississippi rebel State forces, men who were in the
rebel armies, are traversing the State, visiting the freedmen,
disarming them, perpetrating murders and outrages upon them; and
the same things are done in other sections of the country.” 39th
Cong. Globe 40 (1865). The Report of the Joint Committee on
Reconstruction—which was widely reprinted in the press and
distributed by Members of the 39th Congress to their constituents
shortly after Congress approved the Fourteenth Amendment[ Footnote 19 ]—contained numerous
examples of such abuses. See, e.g. , Joint Committee on
Reconstruction, H. R. Rep. No. 30, 39th Cong., 1st Sess., pt.
2, pp. 219, 229, 272, pt. 3, pp. 46, 140, pt. 4,
pp. 49–50 (1866); see also S. Exec. Doc. No. 2, 39th Cong.,
1st Sess., 23–24, 26, 36 (1865). In one town, the “marshal [took]
all arms from returned colored soldiers, and [was] very prompt in
shooting the blacks whenever an opportunity occur[red].” H. R.
Exec. Doc. No. 70, at 238 (internal quotation marks omitted).
As Senator Wilson put it during the debate on a failed proposal to
disband Southern militias: “There is one unbroken chain of
testimony from all people that are loyal to this country, that the
greatest outrages are perpetrated by armed men who go up and down
the country searching houses, disarming people, committing outrages
of every kind and description.” 39th Cong. Globe 915
(1866).[ Footnote 20 ]
Union Army commanders took steps to secure the
right of all citizens to keep and bear arms,[ Footnote 21 ] but the 39th Congress concluded
that legislative action was necessary. Its efforts to safeguard the
right to keep and bear arms demonstrate that the right was still
recognized to be fundamental.
The most explicit evidence of Congress’ aim
appears in §14 of the Freedmen’s Bureau Act of 1866, which provided
that “the right … to have full and equal benefit of all laws and
proceedings concerning personal liberty, personal security, and the
acquisition, enjoyment, and disposition of estate, real and
personal, including the constitutional right to bear arms ,
shall be secured to and enjoyed by all the citizens … without
respect to race or color, or previous condition of slavery.” 14
Stat. 176–177 (emphasis added).[ Footnote 22 ] Section 14 thus explicitly guaranteed that
“all the citizens,” black and white, would have “the constitutional
right to bear arms.”
The Civil Rights Act of 1866, 14 Stat. 27,
which was considered at the same time as the Freedmen’s Bureau Act,
similarly sought to protect the right of all citizens to keep and
bear arms.[ Footnote 23 ]
Section 1 of the Civil Rights Act guaranteed the “full and equal
benefit of all laws and proceedings for the security of person and
property, as is enjoyed by white citizens.” Ibid . This
language was virtually identical to language in §14 of the
Freedmen’s Bureau Act, 14 Stat. 176–177 (“the right … to have full
and equal benefit of all laws and proceedings concerning personal
liberty, personal security, and the acquisition, enjoyment, and
disposition of estate, real and personal”). And as noted, the
latter provision went on to explain that one of the “laws and
proceedings concerning personal liberty, personal security, and the
acquisition, enjoyment, and disposition of estate, real and
personal” was “the constitutional right to bear arms.” Ibid. Representative Bingham believed that the Civil
Rights Act protected the same rights as enumerated in the
Freedmen’s Bureau bill, which of course explicitly mentioned the
right to keep and bear arms. 39th Cong. Globe 1292. The unavoidable
conclusion is that the Civil Rights Act, like the Freedmen’s Bureau
Act, aimed to protect “the constitutional right to bear arms” and
not simply to prohibit discrimination. See also Amar, Bill of
Rights 264–265 (noting that one of the “core purposes of the Civil
Rights Act of 1866 and of the Fourteenth Amendment was to redress
the grievances” of freedmen who had been stripped of their arms and
to “affirm the full and equal right of every citizen to
self-defense”).
Congress, however, ultimately deemed these
legislative remedies insufficient. Southern resistance,
Presidential vetoes, and this Court’s pre-Civil-War precedent
persuaded Congress that a constitutional amendment was necessary to
provide full protection for the rights of blacks.[ Footnote 24 ] Today, it is generally
accepted that the Fourteenth Amendment was understood to provide a
constitutional basis for protecting the rights set out in the Civil
Rights Act of 1866. See General Building Contractors Assn.,
Inc. v. Pennsylvania , 458 U. S. 375 , 389
(1982); see also Amar, Bill of Rights 187; Calabresi, Two Cheers
for Professor Balkin’s Originalism, 103 Nw. U. L. Rev. 663,
669–670 (2009).
In debating the Fourteenth Amendment, the 39th
Congress referred to the right to keep and bear arms as a
fundamental right deserving of protection. Senator Samuel Pomeroy
described three “indispensable” “safeguards of liberty under our
form of Government.” 39th Cong. Globe 1182. One of these, he said,
was the right to keep and bear arms:
“Every man … should have the
right to bear arms for the defense of himself and family and his
homestead. And if the cabin door of the freedman is broken open and
the intruder enters for purposes as vile as were known to slavery,
then should a well-loaded musket be in the hand of the occupant to
send the polluted wretch to another world, where his wretchedness
will forever remain complete.” Ibid .
Even those who thought the Fourteenth Amendment
unnecessary believed that blacks, as citizens, “have equal right to
protection, and to keep and bear arms for self-defense.” Id ., at 1073 (Sen. James Nye); see also Foner
258–259.[ Footnote 25 ]
Evidence from the period immediately following
the ratification of the Fourteenth Amendment only confirms that the
right to keep and bear arms was considered fundamental. In an 1868
speech addressing the disarmament of freedmen, Representative
Stevens emphasized the necessity of the right: “Disarm a community
and you rob them of the means of defending life. Take away their
weapons of defense and you take away the inalienable right of
defending liberty.” “The fourteenth amendment, now so happily
adopted, settles the whole question.” Cong. Globe, 40th Cong., 2d
Sess., 1967. And in debating the Civil Rights Act of 1871, Congress
routinely referred to the right to keep and bear arms and decried
the continued disarmament of blacks in the South. See Halbrook,
Freedmen 120–131. Finally, legal commentators from the period
emphasized the fundamental nature of the right. See, e.g. ,
T. Farrar, Manual of the Constitution of the United States of
America §118, p. 145 (1867) (reprint 1993); J. Pomeroy, An
Introduction to the Constitutional Law of the United States §239,
pp. 152–153 (3d ed. 1875).
The right to keep and bear arms was also
widely protected by state constitutions at the time when the
Fourteenth Amendment was ratified. In 1868, 22 of the 37 States in
the Union had state constitutional provisions explicitly protecting
the right to keep and bear arms. See Calabresi & Agudo,
Individual Rights Under State Constitutions when the Fourteenth
Amendment was Ratified in 1868: What Rights Are Deeply Rooted in
American History and Tradition? 87 Texas L. Rev. 7, 50
(2008).[ Footnote 26 ] Quite a
few of these state constitutional guarantees, moreover, explicitly
protected the right to keep and bear arms as an individual right to
self-defense. See Ala. Const., Art. I, §28 (1868); Conn. Const.,
Art. I, §17 (1818); Ky. Const., Art. XIII, §25 (1850); Mich.
Const., Art. XVIII, §7 (1850); Miss. Const., Art. I, §15 (1868);
Mo. Const., Art. I, §8 (1865); Tex. Const., Art. I, §13 (1869); see
also Mont. Const., Art. III, §13 (1889); Wash. Const., Art. I, §24
(1889); Wyo. Const., Art. I, §24 (1889); see also State v. McAdams , 714 P. 2d 1236, 1238 (Wyo. 1986). What is
more, state constitutions adopted during the Reconstruction era by
former Confederate States included a right to keep and bear arms.
See, e.g. , Ark. Const., Art. I, §5 (1868); Miss. Const.,
Art. I, §15 (1868); Tex. Const., Art. I, §13 (1869). A clear
majority of the States in 1868, therefore, recognized the right to
keep and bear arms as being among the foundational rights necessary
to our system of Government.[ Footnote 27 ]
In sum, it is clear that the Framers and
ratifiers of the Fourteenth Amendment counted the right to keep and
bear arms among those fundamental rights necessary to our system of
ordered liberty.
2
Despite all this evidence,
municipal respondents contend that Congress, in the years
immediately following the Civil War, merely sought to outlaw
“discriminatory measures taken against freedmen, which it addressed
by adopting a non-discrimination principle” and that even an
outright ban on the possession of firearms was regarded as
acceptable, “so long as it was not done in a discriminatory
manner.” Brief for Municipal Respondents 7. They argue that Members
of Congress overwhelmingly viewed §1 of the Fourteenth Amendment
“as an antidiscrimination rule,” and they cite statements to the
effect that the section would outlaw discriminatory measures. Id ., at 64. This argument is implausible.
First, while §1 of the Fourteenth
Amendment contains “an antidiscrimination rule,” namely, the Equal
Protection Clause, municipal respondents can hardly mean that §1
does no more than prohibit discrimination. If that were so, then
the First Amendment, as applied to the States, would not prohibit
nondiscriminatory abridgments of the rights to freedom of speech or
freedom of religion; the Fourth Amendment, as applied to the
States, would not prohibit all unreasonable searches and seizures
but only discriminatory searches and seizures—and so on. We assume
that this is not municipal respondents’ view, so what they must
mean is that the Second Amendment should be singled out for
special—and specially unfavorable—treatment. We reject that
suggestion.
Second, municipal respondents’ argument
ignores the clear terms of the Freedmen’s Bureau Act of 1866, which
acknowledged the existence of the right to bear arms. If that law
had used language such as “the equal benefit of laws concerning the
bearing of arms,” it would be possible to interpret it as simply a
prohibition of racial discrimination. But §14 speaks of and
protects “the constitutional right to bear arms,” an unmistakable
reference to the right protected by the Second Amendment. And it
protects the “full and equal benefit” of this right in the States.
14 Stat. 176–177. It would have been nonsensical for Congress to
guarantee the full and equal benefit of a constitutional right that
does not exist.
Third, if the 39th Congress had outlawed only
those laws that discriminate on the basis of race or previous
condition of servitude, African Americans in the South would likely
have remained vulnerable to attack by many of their worst abusers:
the state militia and state peace officers. In the years
immediately following the Civil War, a law banning the possession
of guns by all private citizens would have been nondiscriminatory
only in the formal sense. Any such law—like the Chicago and Oak
Park ordinances challenged here—presumably would have permitted the
possession of guns by those acting under the authority of the State
and would thus have left firearms in the hands of the militia and
local peace officers. And as the Report of the Joint Committee on
Reconstruction revealed, see supra , at 24–25, those groups
were widely involved in harassing blacks in the South.
Fourth, municipal respondents’ purely
antidiscrimination theory of the Fourteenth Amendment disregards
the plight of whites in the South who opposed the Black Codes. If
the 39th Congress and the ratifying public had simply prohibited
racial discrimination with respect to the bearing of arms,
opponents of the Black Codes would have been left without the means
of self-defense—as had abolitionists in Kansas in the 1850’s.
Fifth, the 39th Congress’ response to
proposals to disband and disarm the Southern militias is
instructive. Despite recognizing and deploring the abuses of these
militias, the 39th Congress balked at a proposal to disarm them.
See 39th Cong. Globe 914; Halbrook, Freedmen, supra ,
20–21. Disarmament, it was argued, would violate the members’ right
to bear arms, and it was ultimately decided to disband the militias
but not to disarm their members. See Act of Mar. 2, 1867, §6, 14
Stat. 485, 487; Halbrook, Freedmen 68–69; Cramer 858–861. It cannot
be doubted that the right to bear arms was regarded as a
substantive guarantee, not a prohibition that could be ignored so
long as the States legislated in an evenhanded manner.
IV
Municipal respondents’ remaining
arguments are at war with our central holding in Heller :
that the Second Amendment protects a personal right to keep and
bear arms for lawful purposes, most notably for self-defense within
the home. Municipal respondents, in effect, ask us to treat the
right recognized in Heller as a second-class right,
subject to an entirely different body of rules than the other Bill
of Rights guarantees that we have held to be incorporated into the
Due Process Clause.
Municipal respondents’ main
argument is nothing less than a plea to disregard 50 years of
incorporation precedent and return (presumably for this case only)
to a bygone era. Municipal respondents submit that the Due Process
Clause protects only those rights “ ‘recognized by all
temperate and civilized governments, from a deep and universal
sense of [their] justice.’ ” Brief for Municipal Respondents 9
(quoting Chicago, B. & Q. R. Co. , 166 U. S., at
238). According to municipal respondents, if it is possible to
imagine any civilized legal system that does not recognize
a particular right, then the Due Process Clause does not make that
right binding on the States. Brief for Municipal Respondents 9.
Therefore, the municipal respondents continue, because such
countries as England, Canada, Australia, Japan, Denmark, Finland,
Luxembourg, and New Zealand either ban or severely limit handgun
ownership, it must follow that no right to possess such weapons is
protected by the Fourteenth Amendment. Id ., at 21–23.
This line of argument is, of course,
inconsistent with the long-established standard we apply in
incorporation cases. See Duncan , 391 U. S., at 149, and
n. 14. And the present-day implications of municipal
respondents’ argument are stunning. For example, many of the rights
that our Bill of Rights provides for persons accused of criminal
offenses are virtually unique to this country.[ Footnote 28 ] If our understanding of
the right to a jury trial, the right against self-incrimination,
and the right to counsel were necessary attributes of any civilized country, it would follow that the United States is the
only civilized Nation in the world.
Municipal respondents attempt to salvage their
position by suggesting that their argument applies only to
substantive as opposed to procedural rights. Brief for Municipal
Respondents 10, n. 3. But even in this trimmed form, municipal
respondents’ argument flies in the face of more than a half-century
of precedent. For example, in Everson v. Board of Ed.
of Ewing , 330 U. S. 1 , 8 (1947), the Court held
that the Fourteenth Amendment incorporates the Establishment Clause
of the First Amendment. Yet several of the countries that municipal
respondents recognize as civilized have established state
churches.[ Footnote 29 ] If we
were to adopt municipal respondents’ theory, all of this Court’s
Establishment Clause precedents involving actions taken by state
and local governments would go by the boards.
Municipal respondents maintain that the Second
Amendment differs from all of the other provisions of the Bill of
Rights because it concerns the right to possess a deadly implement
and thus has implications for public safety. Brief for Municipal
Respondents 11. And they note that there is intense disagreement on
the question whether the private possession of guns in the home
increases or decreases gun deaths and injuries. Id ., at
11, 13–17.
The right to keep and bear arms, however, is
not the only constitutional right that has controversial public
safety implications. All of the constitutional provisions that
impose restrictions on law enforcement and on the prosecution of
crimes fall into the same category. See, e.g ., Hudson v. Michigan , 547 U. S. 586 , 591
(2006) (“The exclusionary rule generates ‘substantial social
costs,’ United States v. Leon , 468 U. S. 897 , 907
(1984), which sometimes include setting the guilty free and the
dangerous at large”); Barker v. Wingo , 407 U. S. 514 , 522
(1972) (reflecting on the serious consequences of dismissal for a
speedy trial violation, which means “a defendant who may be guilty
of a serious crime will go free”); Miranda v. Arizona , 384 U. S. 436 , 517 (1966) (Harlan, J.,
dissenting); id. , at 542 (White, J., dissenting)
(objecting that the Court’s rule “[i]n some unknown number of cases
… will return a killer, a rapist or other criminal to the streets …
to repeat his crime”); Mapp , 367 U. S., at 659. Municipal
respondents cite no case in which we have refrained from holding
that a provision of the Bill of Rights is binding on the States on
the ground that the right at issue has disputed public safety
implications.
We likewise reject municipal respondents’
argument that we should depart from our established incorporation
methodology on the ground that making the Second Amendment binding
on the States and their subdivisions is inconsistent with
principles of federalism and will stifle experimentation. Municipal
respondents point out—quite correctly—that conditions and problems
differ from locality to locality and that citizens in different
jurisdictions have divergent views on the issue of gun control.
Municipal respondents therefore urge us to allow state and local
governments to enact any gun control law that they deem to be
reasonable, including a complete ban on the possession of handguns
in the home for self-defense. Brief for Municipal Respondents
18–20, 23.
There is nothing new in the argument that, in
order to respect federalism and allow useful state experimentation,
a federal constitutional right should not be fully binding on the
States. This argument was made repeatedly and eloquently by Members
of this Court who rejected the concept of incorporation and urged
retention of the two-track approach to incorporation. Throughout
the era of “selective incorporation,” Justice Harlan in particular,
invoking the values of federalism and state experimentation, fought
a determined rearguard action to preserve the two-track approach.
See, e.g. , Roth v. United States , 354 U. S. 476 ,
500–503 (1957) (Harlan, J., concurring in result in part and
dissenting in part); Mapp , supra , at 678–680
(Harlan, J., dissenting); Gideon , 372 U. S., at 352
(Harlan, J., concurring); Malloy , 378 U. S., at 14–33
(Harlan, J., dissenting); Pointer , 380 U. S., at 408–409
(Harlan, J., concurring in result); Washington , 388 U. S.,
at 23–24 (Harlan, J., concurring in result); Duncan , 391
U. S., at 171–193 (Harlan, J., dissenting); Benton , 395 U.
S., at 808–809 (Harlan, J., dissenting); Williams v. Florida , 399
U. S. 78 , 117 (1970) (Harlan, J., dissenting in part and
concurring in result in part).
Time and again, however, those pleas failed.
Unless we turn back the clock or adopt a special incorporation test
applicable only to the Second Amendment, municipal respondents’
argument must be rejected. Under our precedents, if a Bill of
Rights guarantee is fundamental from an American perspective, then,
unless stare decisis counsels otherwise,[ Footnote 30 ] that guarantee is fully
binding on the States and thus limits (but by no means
eliminates) their ability to devise solutions to social problems
that suit local needs and values. As noted by the 38 States that
have appeared in this case as amici supporting
petitioners, “[s]tate and local experimentation with reasonable
firearms regulations will continue under the Second Amendment.”
Brief for State of Texas et al. as Amici Curiae 23.
Municipal respondents and their amici complain that incorporation of the Second Amendment right will lead
to extensive and costly litigation, but this argument applies with
even greater force to constitutional rights and remedies that have
already been held to be binding on the States. Consider the
exclusionary rule. Although the exclusionary rule “is not an
individual right,” Herring v. United States , 555
U. S. ___ (2009) (slip op., at 5), but a “judicially created rule,” id ., at ___ (slip op., at 4), this Court made the rule
applicable to the States. See Mapp , supra , at
660. The exclusionary rule is said to result in “tens of thousands
of contested suppression motions each year.” Stuntz, The Virtues
and Vices of the Exclusionary Rule, 20 Harv. J. Law & Pub.
Pol’y, 443, 444 (1997).
Municipal respondents assert that, although
most state constitutions protect firearms rights, state courts have
held that these rights are subject to “interest-balancing” and have
sustained a variety of restrictions. Brief for Municipal
Respondents 23–31. In Heller , however, we expressly
rejected the argument that the scope of the Second Amendment right
should be determined by judicial interest balancing, 554 U. S., at
___–___ (slip op., at 62–63), and this
Court decades ago abandoned “the notion that the Fourteenth
Amendment applies to the States only a watered-down, subjective
version of the individual guarantees of the Bill of Rights,” Malloy , supra , at 10–11 (internal quotation marks
omitted). As evidence that the
Fourteenth Amendment has not historically been understood to
restrict the authority of the States to regulate firearms,
municipal respondents and supporting amici cite a variety
of state and local firearms laws that courts have upheld. But what
is most striking about their research is the paucity of precedent
sustaining bans comparable to those at issue here and in Heller . Municipal respondents cite precisely one case
(from the late 20th century) in which such a ban was sustained. See
Brief for Municipal Respondents 26–27 (citing Kalodimos v. Morton Grove , 103 Ill. 2d 483, 470 N. E. 2d 266
(1984)); see also Reply Brief for Respondents NRA et al. 23,
n. 7 (asserting that no other court has ever upheld a complete ban
on the possession of handguns). It is important to keep in mind
that Heller , while striking down a law that prohibited the
possession of handguns in the home, recognized that the right to
keep and bear arms is not “a right to keep and carry any weapon
whatsoever in any manner whatsoever and for whatever purpose.” 554
U. S., at ___ (slip op., at 54). We made it clear in Heller that our holding did not cast doubt on such
longstanding regulatory measures as “prohibitions on the possession
of firearms by felons and the mentally ill,” “laws forbidding the
carrying of firearms in sensitive places such as schools and
government buildings, or laws imposing conditions and
qualifications on the commercial sale of arms.” Id ., at
___–___ (slip op., at 54–55). We repeat those assurances here.
Despite municipal respondents’ doomsday proclamations,
incorporation does not imperil every law regulating
firearms. Municipal respondents
argue, finally, that the right to keep and bear arms is unique
among the rights set out in the first eight Amendments “because the
reason for codifying the Second Amendment (to protect the militia)
differs from the purpose (primarily, to use firearms to engage in
self-defense) that is claimed to make the right implicit in the
concept of ordered liberty.” Brief for Municipal Respondents 36–37.
Municipal respondents suggest that the Second Amendment right
differs from the rights heretofore incorporated because the latter
were “valued for [their] own sake.” Id ., at 33. But we
have never previously suggested that incorporation of a right turns
on whether it has intrinsic as opposed to instrumental value, and
quite a few of the rights previously held to be incorporated—for
example the right to counsel and the right to confront and subpoena
witnesses—are clearly instrumental by any measure. Moreover, this
contention repackages one of the chief arguments that we rejected
in Heller , i.e. , that the scope of the Second
Amendment right is defined by the immediate threat that led to the
inclusion of that right in the Bill of Rights. In Heller ,
we recognized that the codification of this right was prompted by
fear that the Federal Government would disarm and thus disable the
militias, but we rejected the suggestion that the right was valued
only as a means of preserving the militias. 554 U. S., at ___ (slip
op., at 26). On the contrary, we stressed that the right was also
valued because the possession of firearms was thought to be
essential for self-defense. As we put it, self-defense was “the central component of the right itself.” Ibid . V A We turn,
finally, to the two dissenting opinions. Justice Stevens’ eloquent
opinion covers ground already addressed, and therefore little need
be added in response. Justice Stevens would “ ‘ground the
prohibitions against state action squarely on due process, without
intermediate reliance on any of the first eight Amendments.’ ” Post, at 8 (quoting Malloy , 378 U. S., at 24
(Harlan, J., dissenting)). The question presented in this case, in
his view, “is whether the particular right asserted by petitioners
applies to the States because of the Fourteenth Amendment itself,
standing on its own bottom.” Post , at 27. He would hold
that “[t]he rights protected against state infringement by the
Fourteenth Amendment’s Due Process Clause need not be identical in
shape or scope to the rights protected against Federal Government
infringement by the various provisions of the Bill of Rights.” Post , at 9. As we
have explained, the Court, for the past half-century, has moved
away from the two-track approach. If we were now to accept Justice
Stevens’ theory across the board, decades of decisions would be
undermined. We assume that this is not what is proposed. What is
urged instead, it appears, is that this theory be revived solely
for the individual right that Heller recognized, over
vigorous dissents. The relationship
between the Bill of Rights’ guarantees and the States must be
governed by a single, neutral principle. It is far too late to
exhume what Justice Brennan, writing for the Court 46 years ago,
derided as “the notion that the Fourteenth Amendment applies to the
States only a watered-down, subjective version of the individual
guarantees of the Bill of Rights.” Malloy , supra ,
at 10–11 (internal quotation marks omitted). B Justice
Breyer’s dissent makes several points to which we briefly respond.
To begin, while there is certainly room for disagreement about Heller ’s analysis of the history of the right to keep and
bear arms, nothing written since Heller persuades us to
reopen the question there decided. Few other questions of original
meaning have been as thoroughly explored. Justice
Breyer’s conclusion that the Fourteenth Amendment does not
incorporate the right to keep and bear arms appears to rest
primarily on four factors: First, “there is no popular consensus”
that the right is fundamental, post , at 9; second, the
right does not protect minorities or persons neglected by those
holding political power, post , at 10; third, incorporation
of the Second Amendment right would “amount to a significant
incursion on a traditional and important area of state concern,
altering the constitutional relationship between the States and the
Federal Government” and preventing local variations, post ,
at 11; and fourth, determining the scope of the Second Amendment
right in cases involving state and local laws will force judges to
answer difficult empirical questions regarding matters that are
outside their area of expertise, post , at 11–16. Even if
we believed that these factors were relevant to the incorporation
inquiry, none of these factors undermines the case for
incorporation of the right to keep and bear arms for
self-defense. First, we have never
held that a provision of the Bill of Rights applies to the States
only if there is a “popular consensus” that the right is
fundamental, and we see no basis for such a rule. But in this case,
as it turns out, there is evidence of such a consensus. An amicus brief submitted by 58 Members of the Senate and 251
Members of the House of Representatives urges us to hold that the
right to keep and bear arms is fundamental. See Brief for Senator
Kay Bailey Hutchison et al . as Amici Curiae 4.
Another brief submitted by 38 States takes the same position. Brief
for State of Texas et al. as Amici Curiae 6. Second, petitioners
and many others who live in high-crime areas dispute the
proposition that the Second Amendment right does not protect
minorities and those lacking political clout. The plight of
Chicagoans living in high-crime areas was recently highlighted when
two Illinois legislators representing Chicago districts called on
the Governor to deploy the Illinois National Guard to patrol the
City’s streets.[ Footnote 31 ]
The legislators noted that the number of Chicago homicide victims
during the current year equaled the number of American soldiers
killed during that same period in Afghanistan and Iraq and that 80%
of the Chicago victims were black.[ Footnote 32 ] Amici supporting incorporation of
the right to keep and bear arms contend that the right is
especially important for women and members of other groups that may
be especially vulnerable to violent crime.[ Footnote 33 ] If, as petitioners believe, their
safety and the safety of other law-abiding members of the community
would be enhanced by the possession of handguns in the home for
self-defense, then the Second Amendment right protects the rights
of minorities and other residents of high-crime areas whose needs
are not being met by elected public officials. Third, Justice Breyer
is correct that incorporation of the Second Amendment right will to
some extent limit the legislative freedom of the States, but this
is always true when a Bill of Rights provision is incorporated.
Incorporation always restricts experimentation and local
variations, but that has not stopped the Court from incorporating
virtually every other provision of the Bill of Rights. “[T]he
enshrinement of constitutional rights necessarily takes certain
policy choices off the table.” Heller , 554 U. S., at __
(slip op., at 64). This conclusion is no more remarkable with
respect to the Second Amendment than it is with respect to all the
other limitations on state power found in the
Constitution. Finally, Justice
Breyer is incorrect that incorporation will require judges to
assess the costs and benefits of firearms restrictions and thus to
make difficult empirical judgments in an area in which they lack
expertise. As we have noted, while his opinion in Heller recommended an interest-balancing test, the Court specifically
rejected that suggestion. See supr a, at 38–39. “The very
enumeration of the right takes out of the hands of government—even
the Third Branch of Government—the power to decide on a
case-by-case basis whether the right is really worth insisting upon.” Heller , supra , at ___ (slip op.,
at 62–63). * * * In Heller , we held that the Second Amendment protects the
right to possess a handgun in the home for the purpose of
self-defense. Unless considerations of stare decisis counsel otherwise, a provision of the Bill of Rights that protects
a right that is fundamental from an American perspective applies
equally to the Federal Government and the States. See Duncan , 391 U. S., at 149, and n. 14. We therefore
hold that the Due Process Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment
incorporates the Second Amendment right recognized in Heller . The judgment of the Court of Appeals is reversed,
and the case is remanded for further proceedings. It is so
ordered. Footnote
1 See Brief for
Heartland Institute as Amicus Curiae 6–7 (noting that
handgun murder rate was 9.65 in 1983 and 13.88 in
2008). Footnote
2 Brief for Buckeye
Firearms Foundation, Inc., et al. as Amici Curiae 8–9
(“In 2002 and again in 2008, Chicago had more murders than any
other city in the U. S., including the much larger Los Angeles and
New York” (internal quotation marks omitted)); see also Brief for
International Law Enforcement Educators and Trainers Association et
al. as Amici Curiae 17–21, and App. A (providing
comparisons of Chicago’s rates of assault, murder, and robbery to
average crime rates in 24 other large cities). Footnote
3 Brief for Women State
Legislators et al. as Amici Curiae 2. Footnote
4 The Illinois State
Rifle Association and the Second Amendment Foundation,
Inc. Footnote
5 The first sentence of
the Fourteenth Amendment makes “[a]ll persons born or naturalized
in the United States and subject to the jurisdiction thereof …
citizens of the United States and of the State wherein they
reside .” (Emphasis added.) The Privileges and Immunities
Clause of Article IV provides that “[t]he Citizens of each State
shall be entitled to all Privileges and Immunities of Citizens
in the several States .” (Emphasis added.) Footnote
6 See C. Lane, The Day
Freedom Died 265–266 (2008); see also Brief for NAACP Legal Defense
& Education Fund, Inc., as Amicus Curiae 3, and
n. 2. Footnote
7 See Lane, supra , at 106. Footnote
8 United
States v. Cruikshank , 92 U.
S. 542 , 544–545 (statement of the case), 548, 553 (opinion of
the Court) (1875); Lawrence, Civil Rights and Criminal Wrongs: The
Mens Rea of Federal Civil Rights Crimes, 67 Tulane L. Rev.
2113, 2153 (1993). Footnote
9 Senator Jacob Howard,
who spoke on behalf of the Joint Committee on Reconstruction and
sponsored the Amendment in the Senate, stated that the Amendment
protected all of “the personal rights guarantied and secured by the
first eight amendments of the Constitution.” Cong. Globe, 39th
Cong., 1st Sess., 2765 (1866) (hereinafter 39th Cong. Globe).
Representative John Bingham, the principal author of the text of
§1, said that the Amendment would “arm the Congress … with the
power to enforce the bill of rights as it stands in the
Constitution today.” Id ., at 1088; see also id. ,
at 1089–1090; A. Amar, The Bill of Rights: Creation and
Reconstruction 183 (1998) (hereinafter Amar, Bill of Rights). After
ratification of the Amendment, Bingham maintained the view that the
rights guaranteed by §1 of the Fourteenth Amendment “are chiefly
defined in the first eight amendments to the Constitution of the
United States.” Cong. Globe, 42d Cong., 1st Sess., App. 84 (1871).
Finally, Representative Thaddeus Stevens, the political leader of
the House and acting chairman of the Joint Committee on
Reconstruction, stated during the debates on the Amendment that
“the Constitution limits only the action of Congress, and is not a
limitation on the States. This amendment supplies that defect, and
allows Congress to correct the unjust legislation of the States.”
39th Cong. Globe 2459; see also M. Curtis, No State Shall Abridge:
The Fourteenth Amendment and the Bill of Rights 112 (1986)
(counting at least 30 statements during the debates in Congress
interpreting §1 to incorporate the Bill of Rights); Brief for
Constitutional Law Professors as Amici Curiae 20
(collecting authorities and stating that “[n]ot a single senator or
representative disputed [the incorporationist] understanding” of
the Fourteenth Amendment). Footnote
10 The municipal
respondents and some of their amici dispute the
significance of these statements. They contend that the phrase
“privileges or immunities” is not naturally read to mean the rights
set out in the first eight Amendments, see Brief for Historians
et al. as Amici Curiae 13–16, and that “there is
‘support in the legislative history for no fewer than four
interpretations of the … Privileges or Immunities Clause.’ ”
Brief for Municipal Respondents 69 (quoting Currie, The
Reconstruction Congress, 75 U. Chi. L. Rev. 383, 406 (2008);
brackets omitted). They question whether there is sound evidence of
“ ‘any strong public awareness of nationalizing the entire Bill of Rights.’ ” Brief for Municipal
Respondents 69 (quoting Wildenthal, Nationalizing the Bill of
Rights: Revisiting the Original Understanding of the Fourteenth
Amendment in 1866–67, 68 Ohio St. L. J. 1509, 1600 (2007)).
Scholars have also disputed the total incorporation theory. See, e.g ., Fairman, Does the Fourteenth Amendment Incorporate
the Bill of Rights? 2 Stan. L. Rev. 5 (1949); Berger,
Incorporation of the Bill of Rights in the Fourteenth Amendment: A
Nine-Lived Cat, 42 Ohio St. L. J. 435
(1981). Proponents of the view
that §1 of the Fourteenth Amendment makes all of the provisions of
the Bill of Rights applicable to the States respond that the terms
privileges, immunities, and rights were used interchangeably at the
time, see, e.g. , Curtis, supra , at 64–65, and
that the position taken by the leading congressional proponents of
the Amendment was widely publicized and understood, see, e.g ., Wildenthal, supra , at 1564–1565, 1590;
Hardy, Original Popular Understanding of the Fourteenth Amendment
as Reflected in the Print Media of 1866–1868, 30 Whittier L. Rev.
695 (2009). A number of scholars have found support for the total
incorporation of the Bill of Rights. See Curtis, supra , at
57–130; Aynes, On Misreading John Bingham and the Fourteenth
Amendment, 103 Yale L. J. 57, 61 (1993); see also Amar, Bill
of Rights 181–230. We take no position with respect to this
academic debate. Footnote
11 By contrast, the
Court has never retreated from the proposition that the Privileges
or Immunities Clause and the Due Process Clause present different
questions. And in recent cases addressing unenumerated rights, we
have required that a right also be “implicit in the concept of
ordered liberty.” See, e.g ., Washington v. Glucksberg , 521 U. S. 702 , 721 (1997) (internal
quotation marks omitted). Footnote
12 With respect to the
First Amendment, see Everson v. Board of Ed. of
Ewing , 330 U. S. 1 (1947) (Establishment
Clause); Cantwell v. Connecticut , 310 U. S. 296 (1940) (Free Exercise
Clause); De Jonge v. Oregon , 299 U. S. 353 (1937) (freedom of
assembly); Gitlow v. New York , 268 U. S. 652 (1925) (free speech); Near v. Minnesota ex rel. Olson , 283 U. S. 697 (1931) (freedom of the
press). With respect to the
Fourth Amendment, see Aguilar v. Texas , 378 U. S. 1 08 (1964) (warrant
requirement); Mapp v. Ohio , 367 U. S. 643 (1961) (exclusionary
rule); Wolf v. Colorado , 338 U.
S. 25 (1949) (freedom from unreasonable searches and
seizures). With respect to the
Fifth Amendment, see Benton v. Maryland , 395 U. S. 784 (1969) (Double Jeopardy
Clause); Malloy v. Hogan , 378 U. S. 1 (1964) (privilege against
self-incrimination); Chicago, B. & Q. R. Co. v. Chicago , 166 U. S. 226 (1897) (Just
Compensation Clause). With respect to the
Sixth Amendment, see Duncan v. Louisiana , 391 U. S. 145 (1968) (trial by jury in
criminal cases); Washington v. Texas , 388 U. S. 14 (1967) (compulsory
process); Klopfer v. North Carolina , 386 U. S. 213 (1967)
(speedy trial); Pointer v. Texas , 380 U. S. 400 (1965) (right to
confront adverse witness); Gideon v. Wainwright , 372
U. S. 335 (1963) (assistance of counsel); In re
Oliver , 333 U.
S. 257 (1948) (right to a public trial). With respect to the
Eighth Amendment, see Robinson v. California , 370 U. S. 660 (1962) (cruel and unusual punishment); Schilb v. Kuebel , 404
U. S. 357 (1971) (prohibition against excessive
bail). Footnote
13 In addition to the
right to keep and bear arms (and the Sixth Amendment right to a
unanimous jury verdict, see n. 14, infra ), the only
rights not fully incorporated are (1) the Third Amendment’s
protection against quartering of soldiers; (2) the Fifth
Amendment’s grand jury indictment requirement; (3) the Seventh
Amendment right to a jury trial in civil cases; and (4) the Eighth
Amendment’s prohibition on excessive fines. We never have decided
whether the Third Amendment or the Eighth Amendment’s prohibition
of excessive fines applies to the States through the Due Process
Clause. See Browning-Ferris Industries of Vt., Inc. v. Kelco Disposal, Inc. , 492 U. S. 257 , 276, n.
22 (1989) (declining to decide whether the excessive-fines
protection applies to the States); see also Engblom v. Carey , 677 F. 2d 957, 961 (CA2 1982) (holding as a
matter of first impression that the “Third Amendment is
incorporated into the Fourteenth Amendment for application to the
states”). Our governing
decisions regarding the Grand Jury Clause of the Fifth Amendment
and the Seventh Amendment’s civil jury requirement long predate the
era of selective incorporation. Footnote
14 There is one
exception to this general rule. The Court has held that although
the Sixth Amendment right to trial by jury requires a unanimous
jury verdict in federal criminal trials, it does not require a
unanimous jury verdict in state criminal trials. See Apodaca v. Oregon , 406 U. S. 404 (1972);
see also Johnson v. Louisiana , 406 U. S. 356 (1972)
(holding that the Due Process Clause does not require unanimous
jury verdicts in state criminal trials). But that ruling was the
result of an unusual division among the Justices, not an
endorsement of the two-track approach to incorporation. In Apodaca , eight Justices agreed that the Sixth Amendment
applies identically to both the Federal Government and the States.
See Johnson , supra , at 395 (Brennan, J.,
dissenting). Nonetheless, among those eight, four Justices took the
view that the Sixth Amendment does not require unanimous jury
verdicts in either federal or state criminal trials, Apodaca , 406 U. S., at 406 (plurality opinion), and four
other Justices took the view that the Sixth Amendment requires
unanimous jury verdicts in federal and state criminal trials, id ., at 414–415 (Stewart, J., dissenting); Johnson , supra , at 381–382 (Douglas, J.,
dissenting). Justice Powell’s concurrence in the judgment broke the
tie, and he concluded that the Sixth Amendment requires juror
unanimity in federal, but not state, cases. Apodaca ,
therefore, does not undermine the well-established rule that
incorporated Bill of Rights protections apply identically to the
States and the Federal Government. See Johnson , supra , at 395–396 (Brennan, J., dissenting) (footnote
omitted) (“In any event, the affirmance must not obscure that the
majority of the Court remains of the view that, as in the case of
every specific of the Bill of Rights that extends to the States,
the Sixth Amendment’s jury trial guarantee, however it is to be
construed, has identical application against both State and Federal
Governments”). Footnote
15 Citing Jewish, Greek,
and Roman law, Blackstone wrote that if a person killed an
attacker, “the slayer is in no kind of fault whatsoever, not even
in the minutest degree; and is therefore to be totally acquitted
and discharged, with commendation rather than blame.” 4 W.
Blackstone, Commentaries on the Laws of England 182 (reprint
1992). Footnote
16 For example, an
article in the Boston Evening Post stated: “For it is certainly
beyond human art and sophistry, to prove the British subjects, to
whom the privilege of possessing arms is expressly recognized by
the Bill of Rights, and, who live in a province where the law
requires them to be equip’d with arms, &c. are guilty of an
illegal act, in calling upon one another to be provided with them,
as the law directs.” Boston Evening Post, Feb. 6, 1769, in Boston
Under Military Rule 1768–1769, p. 61 (1936) (emphasis
deleted). Footnote
17 Abolitionists and
Republicans were not alone in believing that the right to keep and
bear arms was a fundamental right. The 1864 Democratic Party
Platform complained that the confiscation of firearms by Union
troops occupying parts of the South constituted “the interference
with and denial of the right of the people to bear arms in their
defense.” National Party Platforms 1840–1972, at
34. Footnote
18 In South Carolina,
prominent black citizens held a convention to address the State’s
black code. They drafted a memorial to Congress, in which they
included a plea for protection of their constitutional right to
keep and bear arms: “ ‘We ask that, inasmuch as the
Constitution of the United States explicitly declares that the
right to keep and bear arms shall not be infringed … that the late
efforts of the Legislature of this State to pass an act to deprive
us [of] arms be forbidden, as a plain violation of the
Constitution.’ ” S. Halbrook, Freedmen, The Fourteenth
Amendment, and The Right to Bear Arms, 1866–1876, p. 9 (1998)
(hereinafter Halbrook, Freedmen) (quoting 2 Proceedings of the
Black State Conventions, 1840–1865, p. 302 (P. Foner & G.
Walker eds. 1980)). Senator Charles Sumner relayed the memorial to
the Senate and described the memorial as a request that black
citizens “have the constitutional protection in keeping arms.” 39th
Cong. Globe 337. Footnote
19 See B. Kendrick,
Journal of the Joint Committee of Fifteen on Reconstruction 265–266
(1914); Adamson v. California , 332 U.
S. 46 , 108–109 (1947) (appendix to dissenting opinion of Black,
J.). Footnote
20 Disarmament by bands
of former Confederate soldiers eventually gave way to attacks by
the Ku Klux Klan. In debates over the later enacted Enforcement Act
of 1870, Senator John Pool observed that the Klan would “order the
colored men to give up their arms; saying that everybody would be
Kukluxed in whose house fire-arms were found.” Cong. Globe, 41st
Cong., 2d Sess., 2719 (1870); see also H. R. Exec. Doc. No.
268, 42d Cong., 2d Sess., 2 (1872). Footnote
21 For example, the
occupying Union commander in South Carolina issued an order stating
that “[t]he constitutional rights of all loyal and well disposed
inhabitants to bear arms, will not be infringed.” General Order No.
1, Department of South Carolina, January 1, 1866, in 1 Documentary
History of Reconstruction 208 (W. Fleming ed. 1950). Union
officials in Georgia issued a similar order, declaring that
“ ‘[a]ll men, without the distinction of color, have the right
to keep arms to defend their homes, families or themselves.’ ”
Cramer, “This Right is Not Allowed by Governments That Are Afraid
of The People”: The Public Meaning of the Second Amendment When the
Fourteenth Amendment was Ratified, 17 Geo. Mason L. Rev. 823,
854 (2010) (hereinafter Cramer) (quoting Right to Bear Arms,
Christian Recorder, Feb. 24, 1866, pp. 1–2). In addition, when
made aware of attempts by armed parties to disarm blacks, the head
of the Freedmen’s Bureau in Alabama “made public [his]
determination to maintain the right of the negro to keep and to
bear arms, and [his] disposition to send an armed force into any
neighborhood in which that right should be systematically
interfered with.” Joint Committee on Reconstruction, H. R.
Rep. No. 30, 39th Cong., 1st Sess., pt. 3, p. 140
(1866). Footnote
22 The Freedmen’s Bureau
bill was amended to include an express reference to the right to
keep and bear arms, see 39th Cong. Globe 654 (Rep. Thomas Eliot),
even though at least some Members believed that the unamended
version alone would have protected the right, see id ., at
743 (Sen. Lyman Trumbull). Footnote
23 There can be do doubt
that the principal proponents of the Civil Rights Act of 1866 meant
to end the disarmament of African Americans in the South. In
introducing the bill, Senator Trumbull described its purpose as
securing to blacks the “privileges which are essential to freemen.” Id ., at 474. He then pointed to the previously described
Mississippi law that “prohibit[ed] any negro or mulatto from having
fire-arms” and explained that the bill would “destroy” such laws. Ibid . Similarly, Representative Sidney Clarke cited
disarmament of freedmen in Alabama and Mississippi as a reason to
support the Civil Rights Act and to continue to deny Alabama and
Mississippi representation in Congress: “I regret, sir, that
justice compels me to say, to the disgrace of the Federal
Government, that the ‘reconstructed’ State authorities of
Mississippi were allowed to rob and disarm our veteran soldiers and
arm the rebels fresh from the field of treasonable strife. Sir, the
disarmed loyalists of Alabama, Mississippi, and Louisiana are
powerless to-day, and oppressed by the pardoned and encouraged
rebels of those States. They appeal to the American Congress for
protection. In response to this appeal I shall vote for every just
measure of protection, for I do not intend to be among the
treacherous violators of the solemn pledge of the nation.” Id ., at 1838–1839. Footnote
24 For example, at least
one southern court had held the Civil Rights Act to be
unconstitutional. That court did so, moreover, in the course of
upholding the conviction of an African-American man for violating
Mississippi’s law against firearm possession by freedmen. See
Decision of Chief Justice Handy, Declaring the Civil Rights Bill
Unconstitutional, N. Y. Times, Oct. 26, 1866, p. 2, col.
3. Footnote
25 Other Members of the
39th Congress stressed the importance of the right to keep and bear
arms in discussing other measures. In speaking generally on
reconstruction, Representative Roswell Hart listed the
“ ‘right of the people to keep and bear arms’ ” as among
those rights necessary to a “republican form of government.” 39th
Cong. Globe 1629. Similarly, in objecting to a bill designed to
disarm southern militias, Senator Willard Saulsbury argued that
such a measure would violate the Second Amendment. Id ., at
914–915. Indeed, the bill “ultimately passed in a form that
disbanded militias but maintained the right of individuals to their
private firearms.” Cramer 858. Footnote
26 More generally worded
provisions in the constitutions of seven other States may also have
encompassed a right to bear arms. See Calabresi & Agudo, 87
Texas L. Rev., at 52. Footnote
27 These state
constitutional protections often reflected a lack of law
enforcement in many sections of the country. In the frontier towns
that did not have an effective police force, law enforcement often
could not pursue criminals beyond the town borders. See Brief for
Rocky Mountain Gun Owners et al. as Amici Curiae 15.
Settlers in the West and elsewhere, therefore, were left to
“repe[l] force by force when the intervention of society … [was]
too late to prevent an injury.” District of Columbia v. Heller , 554 U. S. ___ , ___ (2008) (slip op., at 21)
(internal quotation marks omitted). The settlers’ dependence on
game for food and economic livelihood, moreover, undoubtedly
undergirded these state constitutional guarantees. See id ., at ___, ___, ___ (slip. op, at 26, 36,
42). Footnote
28 For example, the
United States affords criminal jury trials far more broadly than
other countries. See, e.g. , Van Kessel, Adversary Excesses
in the American Criminal Trial, 67 Notre Dame L. Rev. 403
(1992); Leib, A Comparison of Criminal Jury Decision Rules in
Democratic Countries, 5 Ohio St. J. Crim. L. 629,
630 (2008); Henderson, The Wrongs of Victim’s Rights, 37 Stan.
L. Rev. 937, 1003, n. 296 (1985); see also Roper v. Simmons , 543 U. S. 551 , 624
(2005) (Scalia, J., dissenting) (“In many significant respects the
laws of most other countries differ from our law—including … such
explicit provisions of our Constitution as the right to jury
trial”). Similarly, our rules governing pretrial interrogation
differ from those in countries sharing a similar legal heritage.
See Dept. of Justice, Office of Legal Policy, Report to the
Attorney General on the Law of Pretrial Interrogation: Truth in
Criminal Justice Report No. 1 (Feb. 12, 1986), reprinted in 22 U.
Mich. J. L. Ref. 437, 534–542 (1989) (comparing the system
envisioned by Miranda v. Arizona , 384 U. S. 436 (1966), with rights
afforded by England, Scotland, Canada, India, France, and Germany).
And the “Court-pronounced exclusionary rule … is distinctively
American.” Roper , supra , at 624 (Scalia, J.,
dissenting) (citing Bivens v. Six Unknown Fed.
Narcotics Agents , 403 U. S. 388 , 415
(1971) (Burger, C. J., dissenting) (noting that exclusionary
rule was “unique to American jurisprudence” (internal quotation
marks omitted))); see also Sklansky, Anti-Inquisitorialism, 122
Harv. L. Rev. 1634, 1648–1656, 1689–1693 (2009) (discussing
the differences between American and European confrontation
rules). Footnote
29 England and Denmark
have state churches. See Torke, The English Religious
Establishment, 12 J. of Law & Religion 399, 417–427 (1995–1996)
(describing legal status of Church of England); Constitutional Act
of Denmark, pt. I, §4 (1953) (“The Evangelical Lutheran Church
shall be the Established Church of Denmark”). The Evangelical
Lutheran Church of Finland has attributes of a state church. See
Christensen, Is the Lutheran Church Still the State Church? An
Analysis of Church-State Relations in Finland, 1995 B. Y. U.
L. Rev. 585, 596–600 (describing status of church under
Finnish law). The Web site of the Evangelical Lutheran Church of
Finland states that the church may be usefully described as both a
“state church” and a “folk church.” See J. Seppo, The Current
Condition of Church-State Relations in Finland, online at
http://evl.fi/EVLen.nsf/Documents/838DDBEF
4A28712AC225730F001F7C67?OpenDocument&lang=EN (all Internet
materials as visited June 23, 2010, and available in Clerk of
Court’s case file). Footnote
30 As noted above, see
n. 13, supra , cases that predate the era of selective
incorporation held that the Grand Jury Clause of the Fifth
Amendment and the Seventh Amendment’s civil jury requirement do not
apply to the States. See Hurtado v. California , 110 U. S. 516 (1884) (indictment); Minneapolis & St. Louis R. Co. v. Bombolis , 241 U. S. 211 (1916) (civil jury). As a result of Hurtado , most States do not require a grand jury
indictment in all felony cases, and many have no grand juries. See
Dept. of Justice, Office of Justice Programs, Bureau of Justice
Statistics, State Court Organization 2004, pp. 213, 215–217 (2006)
(Table 38), online at
http://bjs.ojp.usdoj.gov/content/pub/pdf/sco04.pdf. As a result of Bombolis , cases that would otherwise fall within the
Seventh Amendment are now tried without a jury in state small
claims courts. See, e.g. , Cheung v. Eighth
Judicial Dist. Court , 121 Nev. 867, 124 P. 3d 550 (2005)
(no right to jury trial in small claims court under Nevada
Constitution). Footnote
31 See Mack &
Burnette, 2 Lawmakers to Quinn: Send the Guard to Chicago, Chicago
Tribune, Apr. 26, 2010, p. 6. Footnote
32 Janssen &
Knowles, Send in Troops? Chicago Sun-Times, Apr. 26, 2010,
p. 2; see also Brief for NAACP Legal Defense & Education
Fund, Inc., as Amicus Curiae 5, n. 4 (stating that in
2008, almost three out of every four homicide victims in Chicago
were African Americans); id. , at 5–6 (noting that “each
year [in Chicago], many times more African Americans are murdered
by assailants wielding guns than were killed during the Colfax
massacre” (footnote omitted)). Footnote
33 See Brief for Women
State Legislators et al. as Amici Curiae 9–10, 14–15;
Brief for Jews for the Preservation of Firearms Ownership as Amicus Curiae 3–4; see also Brief for Pink Pistols
et al. as Amici Curiae in District of
Columbia v. Heller , O. T. 2007, No. 07–290, pp.
5–11. OPINION OF THOMAS, J. MCDONALD V. CHICAGO 561 U. S. ____ (2010) SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES NO. 08-1521 OTIS McDONALD, et al., PETITIONERS v. CITY OF CHICAGO, ILLINOIS, et al.
on writ of certiorari to the united states court of
appeals for the seventh circuit
[June 28, 2010]
Justice Thomas, concurring in
part and concurring in the judgment. I agree with the
Court that the Fourteenth Amendment makes the right to keep and
bear arms set forth in the Second Amendment “fully applicable to
the States.” Ante , at 1. I write separately because I
believe there is a more straightforward path to this conclusion,
one that is more faithful to the Fourteenth Amendment’s text and
history. Applying what is now a
well-settled test, the plurality opinion concludes that the right
to keep and bear arms applies to the States through the Fourteenth
Amendment’s Due Process Clause because it is “fundamental” to the
American “scheme of ordered liberty,” ante , at 19 (citing Duncan v. Louisiana , 391 U. S. 145 , 149
(1968)), and “ ‘deeply rooted in this Nation’s history and
tradition,’ ” ante , at 19 (quoting Washington v. Glucksberg , 521 U. S. 702 , 721
(1997)). I agree with that description of the right. But I cannot
agree that it is enforceable against the States through a clause
that speaks only to “process.” Instead, the right to keep and bear
arms is a privilege of American citizenship that applies to the
States through the Fourteenth Amendment’s Privileges or Immunities
Clause. I In District of
Columbia v. Heller , 554 U. S. ___ (2008), this Court
held that the Second Amendment protects an individual right to keep
and bear arms for the purpose of self-defense, striking down a
District of Columbia ordinance that banned the possession of
handguns in the home. Id. , at __ (slip op., at 64). The
question in this case is whether the Constitution protects that
right against abridgment by the States. As the Court
explains, if this case were litigated before the Fourteenth
Amendment’s adoption in 1868, the answer to that question would be
simple. In Barron ex rel. Tiernan v. Mayor of
Baltimore , 7 Pet. 243 (1833), this Court held that the Bill of
Rights applied only to the Federal Government. Writing for the
Court, Chief Justice Marshall recalled that the founding generation
added the first eight Amendments to the Constitution in response to
Antifederalist concerns regarding the extent of federal—not
state—power, and held that if “the framers of these amendments
[had] intended them to be limitations on the powers of the state
governments,” “they would have declared this purpose in plain and
intelligible language.” Id. , at 250. Finding no such
language in the Bill, Chief Justice Marshall held that it did not
in any way restrict state authority. Id. , at 248–250; see Lessee of Livingston v. Moore , 7 Pet. 469,
551–552 (1833) (reaffirming Barron ’s holding); Permoli v. Municipality No. 1 of New Orleans , 3
How. 589, 609–610 (1845) (same). Nearly three decades after Barron , the Nation was splintered by a civil war fought
principally over the question of slavery. As was evident to many
throughout our Nation’s early history, slavery, and the measures
designed to protect it, were irreconcilable with the principles of
equality, government by consent, and inalienable rights proclaimed
by the Declaration of Independence and embedded in our
constitutional structure. See, e.g. , 3 Records of the
Federal Convention of 1787, p. 212 (M. Farrand ed. 1911) (remarks
of Luther Martin) (“[S]lavery is inconsistent with the genius of
republicanism, and has a tendency to destroy those principles on
which it is supported, as it lessens the sense of the equal rights
of mankind” (emphasis deleted)); A. Lincoln, Speech at Peoria, Ill.
(Oct. 16, 1854), reprinted in 2 The Collected Works of Abraham
Lincoln 266 (R. Basler ed. 1953) (“[N]o man is good enough to
govern another man, without that other’s consent . I say
this is the leading principle—the sheet anchor of American
republicanism. . . . Now the relation of masters and slaves is, pro tanto , a total violation of this
principle”). After the war, a series of
constitutional amendments were adopted to repair the Nation from
the damage slavery had caused. The provision at issue here, §1 of
the Fourteenth Amendment, significantly altered our system of
government. The first sentence of that section provides that “[a]ll
persons born or naturalized in the United States and subject to the
jurisdiction thereof, are citizens of the United States and of the
State wherein they reside.” This unambiguously overruled this
Court’s contrary holding in Dred Scott v. Sandford , 19 How. 393 (1857), that the Constitution did
not recognize black Americans as citizens of the United States or
their own State. Id. , at 405–406. The meaning of §1’s next
sentence has divided this Court for many years. That sentence
begins with the command that “[n]o State shall make or enforce any
law which shall abridge the privileges or immunities of citizens of
the United States.” On its face, this appears to grant the persons
just made United States citizens a certain collection of
rights— i.e. , privileges or immunities—attributable to that
status. This Court’s precedents accept
that point, but define the relevant collection of rights quite
narrowly. In the Slaughter-House Cases , 16 Wall. 36
(1873), decided just five years after the Fourteenth Amendment’s
adoption, the Court interpreted this text, now known as the
Privileges or Immunities Clause, for the first time. In a closely
divided decision, the Court drew a sharp distinction between the
privileges and immunities of state citizenship and those of federal
citizenship, and held that the Privileges or Immunities Clause
protected only the latter category of rights from state abridgment. Id. , at 78. The Court defined that category to include
only those rights “which owe their existence to the Federal
government, its National character, its Constitution, or its laws.” Id. , at 79. This arguably left open the possibility that
certain individual rights enumerated in the Constitution could be
considered privileges or immunities of federal citizenship. See ibid. (listing “[t]he right to peaceably assemble” and
“the privilege of the writ of habeas corpus ” as rights
potentially protected by the Privileges or Immunities Clause). But
the Court soon rejected that proposition, interpreting the
Privileges or Immunities Clause even more narrowly in its later
cases. Chief among those cases is United States v. Cruikshank , 92 U. S. 542 (1876). There, the Court
held that members of a white militia who had brutally murdered as
many as 165 black Louisianians congregating outside a courthouse
had not deprived the victims of their privileges as American
citizens to peaceably assemble or to keep and bear arms. Ibid.; see L. Keith, The Colfax Massacre 109 (2008).
According to the Court, the right to peaceably assemble codified in
the First Amendment was not a privilege of United States
citizenship because “[t]he right . . . existed long before the adoption of the Constitution.” 92 U. S., at 551 (emphasis
added). Similarly, the Court held that the right to keep and bear
arms was not a privilege of United States citizenship because it
was not “in any manner dependent upon that instrument for its
existence.” Id. , at 553. In other words, the reason the
Framers codified the right to bear arms in the Second Amendment—its
nature as an inalienable right that pre-existed the Constitution’s
adoption—was the very reason citizens could not enforce it against
States through the Fourteenth. That circular reasoning
effectively has been the Court’s last word on the Privileges or
Immunities Clause.[ Footnote 1 ]
In the intervening years, the Court has held that the Clause
prevents state abridgment of only a handful of rights, such as the
right to travel, see Saenz v. Roe , 526 U. S. 489 , 503
(1999), that are not readily described as essential to
liberty. As a consequence of this
Court’s marginalization of the Clause, litigants seeking federal
protection of fundamental rights turned to the remainder of §1 in
search of an alternative fount of such rights. They found one in a
most curious place—that section’s command that every State
guarantee “due process” to any person before depriving him of
“life, liberty, or property.” At first, litigants argued that this
Due Process Clause “incorporated” certain procedural rights
codified in the Bill of Rights against the States. The Court
generally rejected those claims, however, on the theory that the
rights in question were not sufficiently “fundamental” to warrant
such treatment. See, e.g. , Hurtado v. California , 110 U. S. 516 (1884)
(grand jury indictment requirement); Maxwell v. Dow , 176 U.
S. 581 (1900) (12-person jury requirement); Twining v. New Jersey , 211 U. S. 78 (1908)
(privilege against self-incrimination). That changed with
time. The Court came to conclude that certain Bill of Rights
guarantees were sufficiently fundamental to fall within
§1’s guarantee of “due process.” These included not only procedural
protections listed in the first eight Amendments, see, e.g. , Benton v. Maryland , 395 U. S. 784 (1969)
(protection against double jeopardy), but substantive rights as
well, see, e.g. , Gitlow v. New York , 268 U. S. 652 ,
666 (1925) (right to free speech); Near v. Minnesota
ex rel. Olson , 283 U. S. 697 , 707
(1931) (same). In the process of incorporating these rights against
the States, the Court often applied them differently against the
States than against the Federal Government on the theory that only
those “fundamental” aspects of the right required Due Process
Clause protection. See, e.g. , Betts v. Brady , 316
U. S. 455 , 473 (1942) (holding that the Sixth Amendment
required the appointment of counsel in all federal criminal cases
in which the defendant was unable to retain an attorney, but that
the Due Process Clause required appointment of counsel in state
criminal cases only where “want of counsel . . . result[ed] in a
conviction lacking in . . . fundamental fairness”). In more recent
years, this Court has “abandoned the notion” that the guarantees in
the Bill of Rights apply differently when incorporated against the
States than they do when applied to the Federal Government. Ante , at 17–18 (opinion of the Court) (internal quotation
marks omitted). But our cases continue to adhere to the view that a
right is incorporated through the Due Process Clause only if it is
sufficiently “fundamental,” ante , at 37, 42–44 (plurality
opinion)—a term the Court has long struggled to define. While this Court has at times
concluded that a right gains “fundamental” status only if it is
essential to the American “scheme of ordered liberty” or
“ ‘deeply rooted in this Nation’s history and
tradition,’ ” ante , at 19 (plurality opinion)
(quoting Glucksberg , 521 U. S., at 721), the Court has
just as often held that a right warrants Due Process Clause
protection if it satisfies a far less measurable range of criteria,
see Lawrence v. Texas , 539 U. S. 558 , 562
(2003) (concluding that the Due Process Clause protects “liberty of
the person both in its spatial and in its more transcendent
dimensions”). Using the latter approach, the Court has determined
that the Due Process Clause applies rights against the States that
are not mentioned in the Constitution at all, even without
seriously arguing that the Clause was originally understood to
protect such rights. See, e.g. , Lochner v. New York , 198 U. S. 45 (1905); Roe v. Wade , 410 U. S. 113 (1973); Lawrence , supra . All of this is a legal fiction.
The notion that a constitutional provision that guarantees only
“process” before a person is deprived of life, liberty, or property
could define the substance of those rights strains credulity for
even the most casual user of words. Moreover, this fiction is a
particularly dangerous one. The one theme that links the Court’s
substantive due process precedents together is their lack of a
guiding principle to distinguish “fundamental” rights that warrant
protection from nonfundamental rights that do not. Today’s decision
illustrates the point. Replaying a debate that has endured from the
inception of the Court’s substantive due process jurisprudence, the
dissents laud the “flexibility” in this Court’s substantive due
process doctrine, post , at 14 (Stevens, J., dissenting);
see post , at 6–8 (Breyer, J., dissenting), while the
plurality makes yet another effort to impose principled restraints
on its exercise, see ante , at 33–41. But neither side
argues that the meaning they attribute to the Due Process Clause
was consistent with public understanding at the time of its
ratification. To be sure, the plurality’s
effort to cabin the exercise of judicial discretion under the Due
Process Clause by focusing its inquiry on those rights deeply
rooted in American history and tradition invites less opportunity
for abuse than the alternatives. See post , at 7 (Breyer,
J., dissenting) (arguing that rights should be incorporated against
the States through the Due Process Clause if they are “well-suited
to the carrying out of . . . constitutional promises”); post , at 22 (Stevens, J., dissenting) (warning that there
is no “all-purpose, top-down, totalizing theory of ‘liberty’ ”
protected by the Due Process Clause). But any serious argument over
the scope of the Due Process Clause must acknowledge that neither
its text nor its history suggests that it protects the many
substantive rights this Court’s cases now claim it does. I cannot accept a theory of
constitutional interpretation that rests on such tenuous footing.
This Court’s substantive due process framework fails to account for
both the text of the Fourteenth Amendment and the history that led
to its adoption, filling that gap with a jurisprudence devoid of a
guiding principle. I believe the original meaning of the Fourteenth
Amendment offers a superior alternative, and that a return to that
meaning would allow this Court to enforce the rights the Fourteenth
Amendment is designed to protect with greater clarity and
predictability than the substantive due process framework has so
far managed. I acknowledge the volume of
precedents that have been built upon the substantive due process
framework, and I further acknowledge the importance of stare
decisis to the stability of our Nation’s legal system. But stare decisis is only an “adjunct” of our duty as judges
to decide by our best lights what the Constitution means. Planned Parenthood of Southeastern Pa. v. Casey , 505 U. S. 833 ,
963 (1992) (Rehnquist, C. J., concurring in judgment in part
and dissenting in part). It is not “an inexorable command.” Lawrence , supra , at 577. Moreover, as judges, we
interpret the Constitution one case or controversy at a time. The
question presented in this case is not whether our entire
Fourteenth Amendment jurisprudence must be preserved or revised,
but only whether, and to what extent, a particular clause in the
Constitution protects the particular right at issue here. With the
inquiry appropriately narrowed, I believe this case presents an
opportunity to reexamine, and begin the process of restoring, the
meaning of the Fourteenth Amendment agreed upon by those who
ratified it. II “It cannot be
presumed that any clause in the constitution is intended to be
without effect.” Marbury v. Madison , 1 Cranch
137, 174 (1803) (Marshall, C. J.). Because the Court’s Privileges
or Immunities Clause precedents have presumed just that, I set them
aside for the moment and begin with the text. The Privileges or
Immunities Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment declares that “[n]o
State . . . shall abridge the privileges or immunities of citizens
of the United States.” In interpreting this language, it is
important to recall that constitutional provisions are
“ ‘written to be understood by the voters.’ ” Heller , 554 U. S., at ___ (slip op., at 3) (quoting United States v. Sprague , 282 U. S. 716 , 731
(1931)). Thus, the objective of this inquiry is to discern what
“ordinary citizens” at the time of ratification would have
understood the Privileges or Immunities Clause to mean. 554 U. S.,
at ___ (slip op., at 3). A 1 At the time of
Reconstruction, the terms “privileges” and “immunities” had an
established meaning as synonyms for “rights.” The two words,
standing alone or paired together, were used interchangeably with
the words “rights,” “liberties,” and “freedoms,” and had been since
the time of Blackstone. See 1 W. Blackstone, Commentaries *129
(describing the “rights and liberties” of Englishmen as “private
immunities” and “civil privileges”). A number of antebellum
judicial decisions used the terms in this manner. See, e.g. , Magill v. Brown , 16 F. Cas. 408,
428 (No. 8,952) (CC ED Pa. 1833) (Baldwin, J.) (“The words
‘privileges and immunities’ relate to the rights of persons, place
or property; a privilege is a peculiar right, a private law,
conceded to particular persons or places”). In addition, dictionary
definitions confirm that the public shared this understanding. See, e.g. , N. Webster, An American Dictionary of the English
Language 1039 (C. Goodrich & N. Porter rev. 1865) (defining
“privilege” as “a right or immunity not enjoyed by others or by
all” and listing among its synonyms the words “immunity,”
“franchise,” “right,” and “liberty”); id. , at 661
(defining “immunity” as “[f]reedom from an obligation” or
“particular privilege”); id. , at 1140 (defining “right” as
“[p]rivilege or immunity granted by authority”).[ Footnote 2 ] The fact that a
particular interest was designated as a “privilege” or “immunity,”
rather than a “right,” “liberty,” or “freedom,” revealed little
about its substance. Blackstone, for example, used the terms
“privileges” and “immunities” to describe both the inalienable
rights of individuals and the positive-law rights of corporations.
See 1 Commentaries, at *129 (describing “private immunities” as a
“ residuum of natural liberty,” and “civil privileges” as
those “which society has engaged to provide, in lieu of the natural
liberties so given up by individuals” (footnote omitted)); id. , at *468 (stating that a corporate charter enables a
corporation to “establish rules and orders” that serve as “the
privileges and immunities . . . of the corporation”). Writers in
this country at the time of Reconstruction followed a similar
practice. See, e.g. , Racine & Mississippi R.
Co. v. Farmers’ Loan & Trust Co. , 49 Ill. 331,
334 (1868) (describing agreement between two railroad companies in
which they agreed “ ‘to fully merge and consolidate the[ir]
capital stock, powers, privileges, immunities and
franchises’ ”); Hathorn v. Calef , 53 Me.
471, 483–484 (1866) (concluding that a statute did not “modify any
power, privileges, or immunity, pertaining to the franchise of any
corporation”). The nature of a privilege or immunity thus varied
depending on the person, group, or entity to whom those rights were
assigned. See Lash, The Origins of the Privileges or Immunities
Clause, Part I: “Privileges and Immunities” as an Antebellum Term
of Art, 98 Geo. L. J. 1241, 1256–1257 (2010) (surveying
antebellum usages of these terms). 2 The group of
rights-bearers to whom the Privileges or Immunities Clause applies
is, of course, “citizens.” By the time of Reconstruction, it had
long been established that both the States and the Federal
Government existed to preserve their citizens’ inalienable rights,
and that these rights were considered “privileges” or “immunities”
of citizenship. This tradition
begins with our country’s English roots. Parliament declared the
basic liberties of English citizens in a series of documents
ranging from the Magna Carta to the Petition of Right and the
English Bill of Rights. See 1 B. Schwartz, The Bill of Rights: A
Documentary History 8–16, 19–21, 41–46 (1971) (hereinafter
Schwartz). These fundamental rights, according to the English
tradition, belonged to all people but became legally enforceable
only when recognized in legal texts, including acts of Parliament
and the decisions of common-law judges. See B. Bailyn, The
Ideological Origins of the American Revolution 77–79 (1967). These
rights included many that later would be set forth in our Federal
Bill of Rights, such as the right to petition for redress of
grievances, the right to a jury trial, and the right of
“Protestants” to “have arms for their defence.” English Bill of
Rights (1689), reprinted in 1 Schwartz 41, 43. As English subjects, the
colonists considered themselves to be vested with the same
fundamental rights as other Englishmen. They consistently claimed
the rights of English citizenship in their founding documents,
repeatedly referring to these rights as “privileges” and
“immunities.” For example, a Maryland law provided that “[A]ll the Inhabitants of this
Province being Christians (Slaves excepted) Shall have and enjoy
all such rights liberties immunities priviledges and free
customs within this Province as any naturall born subject of
England hath or ought to have or enjoy in the Realm of England . .
. .” Md. Act for the Liberties of the People (1639), in id., at 68 (emphasis added).[ Footnote 3 ] As tensions
between England and the Colonies increased, the colonists adopted
protest resolutions reasserting their claim to the inalienable
rights of Englishmen. Again, they used the terms “privileges” and
“immunities” to describe these rights. As the Massachusetts
Resolves declared: “ Resolved , That there are certain
essential Rights of the British Constitution of
Government, which are founded in the Law of God and Nature, and are
the common Rights of Mankind—Therefore… . . “Resolved, That no Man
can justly take the Property of another without his Consent: And
that upon this original Principle the Right of
Representation . . . is evidently founded… . Resolved , That this inherent Right, together with
all other, essential Rights, Liberties, Privileges and
Immunities of the People of Great Britain, have been fully confirmed to them by Magna Charta .” The
Massachusetts Resolves (Oct. 29, 1765), reprinted in Prologue to
Revolution: Sources and Documents on the Stamp Act Crisis,
1764–1766, p. 56 (E. Morgan ed. 1959) (some emphasis
added).[ Footnote 4 ] In keeping with
this practice, the First Continental Congress declared in 1774 that
the King had wrongfully denied the colonists “the rights,
liberties, and immunities of free and natural-born subjects …
within the realm of England.” 1 Journals of the Continental
Congress 1774–1789, p. 68 (1904). In an address delivered to the
inhabitants of Quebec that same year, the Congress described those
rights as including the “great” “right[s]” of “trial by jury,”
“Habeas Corpus,” and “freedom of the press.” Address of the
Continental Congress to the Inhabitants of Quebec (1774), reprinted
in 1 Schwartz 221–223. After declaring their
independence, the newly formed States replaced their colonial
charters with constitutions and state bills of rights, almost all
of which guaranteed the same fundamental rights that the former
colonists previously had claimed by virtue of their English
heritage. See, e. g. , Pa. Declaration of Rights
(1776), reprinted in 5 Thorpe 3081–3084 (declaring that “all men
are born equally free and independent, and have certain natural,
inherent and inalienable rights,” including the “right to worship
Almighty God according to the dictates of their own consciences”
and the “right to bear arms for the defence of themselves and the
state”).[ Footnote 5 ] Several years later, the
Founders amended the Constitution to expressly protect many of the
same fundamental rights against interference by the Federal
Government. Consistent with their English heritage, the founding
generation generally did not consider many of the rights identified
in these amendments as new entitlements, but as inalienable rights
of all men, given legal effect by their codification in the
Constitution’s text. See, e.g. , 1 Annals of Cong. 431–432,
436–437, 440–442 (1834) (statement of Rep. Madison) (proposing Bill
of Rights in the first Congress); The Federalist No. 84, pp.
531–533 (B. Wright ed. 1961) (A. Hamilton); see also Heller , 554 U. S., at ___ (slip op., at 19) (“[I]t has
always been widely understood that the Second Amendment, like the
First and Fourth Amendments, codified a pre-existing right”). The Court’s subsequent decision in Barron ,
however, made plain that the codification of these rights in the
Bill made them legally enforceable only against the Federal
Government, not the States. See 7 Pet., at 247. 3 Even though the
Bill of Rights did not apply to the States, other provisions of the
Constitution did limit state interference with individual rights.
Article IV, §2, cl. 1 provides that “[t]he Citizens of each
State shall be entitled to all Privileges and Immunities of
Citizens in the several States.” The text of this provision
resembles the Privileges or Immunities Clause, and it can be
assumed that the public’s understanding of the latter was informed
by its understanding of the former. Article IV, §2 was
derived from a similar clause in the Articles of Confederation, and
reflects the dual citizenship the Constitution provided to all
Americans after replacing that “league” of separate sovereign
States. Gibbons v. Ogden , 9 Wheat. 1, 187 (1824);
see 3 J. Story, Commentaries on the Constitution of the United
States §1800, p. 675 (1833). By virtue of a person’s citizenship in
a particular State, he was guaranteed whatever rights and liberties
that State’s constitution and laws made available. Article IV, §2
vested citizens of each State with an additional right: the
assurance that they would be afforded the “privileges and
immunities” of citizenship in any of the several States in the
Union to which they might travel. What were the “Privileges and
Immunities of Citizens in the several States”? That question was
answered perhaps most famously by Justice Bushrod Washington
sitting as Circuit Justice in Corfield v. Coryell , 6 F. Cas. 546, 551–552 (No. 3,230) (CC ED Pa.
1825). In that case, a Pennsylvania citizen claimed that a New
Jersey law prohibiting nonresidents from harvesting oysters from
the State’s waters violated Article IV, §2 because it deprived him,
as an out-of-state citizen, of a right New Jersey availed to its
own citizens. Id. , at 550. Justice Washington rejected
that argument, refusing to “accede to the proposition” that Article
IV, §2 entitled “citizens of the several states . . . to
participate in all the rights which belong exclusively to
the citizens of any other particular state.” Id. , at 552
(emphasis added). In his view, Article IV, §2 did not guarantee
equal access to all public benefits a State might choose to make
available to its citizens. See id., at 552. Instead, it
applied only to those rights “which are, in their nature, fundamental ; which belong, of right, to the citizens of
all free governments.” Id. , at 551 (emphasis added). Other
courts generally agreed with this principle. See, e.g. , Abbott v. Bayley , 23 Mass. 89, 92–93 (1827)
(noting that the “privileges and immunities” of citizens in the
several States protected by Article IV, §2 are “qualified and not
absolute” because they do not grant a traveling citizen the right
of “suffrage or of eligibility to office” in the State to which he
travels). When describing those
“fundamental” rights, Justice Washington thought it “would perhaps
be more tedious than difficult to enumerate” them all, but
suggested that they could “be all comprehended under” a broad list
of “general heads,” such as “[p]rotection by the government,” “the
enjoyment of life and liberty, with the right to acquire and
possess property of every kind,” “the benefit of the writ of habeas
corpus,” and the right of access to “the courts of the state,”
among others.[ Footnote 6 ] Corfield , supra , at 551–552. Notably, Justice Washington did
not indicate whether Article IV, §2 required States to
recognize these fundamental rights in their own citizens and thus
in sojourning citizens alike, or whether the Clause simply
prohibited the States from discriminating against sojourning
citizens with respect to whatever fundamental rights state law
happened to recognize. On this question, the weight of legal
authorities at the time of Reconstruction indicated that Article
IV, §2 prohibited States from discriminating against sojourning
citizens when recognizing fundamental rights, but did not require
States to recognize those rights and did not prescribe their
content. The highest courts of several States adopted this view,
see, e.g. , Livingston v. Van Ingen , 9
Johns. 507, 561 (N. Y. Sup. Ct. 1812) (Yates, J.); id. , at 577 (Kent, J.); Campbell v. Morris , 3 H. & McH. 535, 553–554 (Md. Gen. Ct. 1797)
(Chase, J.), as did several influential treatise-writers, see T.
Cooley, A Treatise on the Constitutional Limitations Which Rest
Upon the Legislative Power of the State of the American Union
15–16, and n. 3 (1868) (reprint 1972) (describing Article IV, §2 as
designed “to prevent discrimination by the several States against
the citizens and public proceedings of other States”); 2 J. Kent,
Commentaries on American Law 35 (11th ed. 1867) (stating that
Article IV, §2 entitles sojourning citizens “to the privileges that
persons of the same description are entitled to in the state to
which the removal is made, and to none other”). This Court adopted
the same conclusion in a unanimous opinion just one year after the
Fourteenth Amendment was ratified. See Paul v. Virginia , 8 Wall. 168, 180 (1869). * * * The text examined
so far demonstrates three points about the meaning of the
Privileges or Immunities Clause in §1. First, “privileges” and
“immunities” were synonyms for “rights.” Second, both the States
and the Federal Government had long recognized the inalienable
rights of their citizens. Third, Article IV, §2 of the Constitution
protected traveling citizens against state discrimination with
respect to the fundamental rights of state citizenship. Two questions
still remain, both provoked by the textual similarity between §1’s
Privileges or Immunities Clause and Article IV, §2. The first
involves the nature of the rights at stake: Are the privileges or
immunities of “citizens of the United States” recognized by §1 the
same as the privileges and immunities of “citizens in the several
States” to which Article IV, §2 refers? The second involves the
restriction imposed on the States: Does §1, like Article IV, §2,
prohibit only discrimination with respect to certain rights if the State chooses to recognize them, or does it require
States to recognize those rights? I address each question in
turn. B I start with the
nature of the rights that §1’s Privileges or Immunities Clause
protects. Section 1 overruled Dred Scott ’s holding that
blacks were not citizens of either the United States or their own
State and, thus, did not enjoy “the privileges and immunities of
citizens” embodied in the Constitution. 19 How., at 417. The Court
in Dred Scott did not distinguish between privileges and
immunities of citizens of the United States and citizens in the
several States, instead referring to the rights of citizens
generally. It did, however, give examples of what the rights of
citizens were—the constitutionally enumerated rights of “the full
liberty of speech” and the right “to keep and carry arms.” Ibid. Section 1
protects the rights of citizens “of the United States”
specifically. The evidence overwhelmingly demonstrates that the
privileges and immunities of such citizens included individual
rights enumerated in the Constitution, including the right to keep
and bear arms. 1 Nineteenth-century treaties through which
the United States acquired territory from other sovereigns
routinely promised inhabitants of the newly acquired territories
that they would enjoy all of the “rights,” “privileges,” and
“immunities” of United States citizens. See, e.g. , Treaty of
Amity, Settlement, and Limits, Art. 6, Feb. 22, 1819, 8 Stat.
256–258, T. S. No. 327 (entered into force Feb. 19, 1821) (cession
of Florida) (“The inhabitants of the territories which his Catholic
Majesty cedes to the United States, by this Treaty, shall be
incorporated in the Union of the United States, as soon as may be
consistent with the principles of the Federal Constitution, and
admitted to the enjoyment of all the privileges, rights, and
immunities, of the citizens of the United States ” (emphasis
added)).[ Footnote 7 ]
Commentators of the time explained that the
rights and immunities of “citizens of the United States”
recognized in these treaties “undoubtedly mean[t] those privileges
that are common to all citizens of this republic.” Marcus, An
Examination of the Expediency and Constitutionality of Prohibiting
Slavery in the State of Missouri 17 (1819). It is therefore
altogether unsurprising that several of these treaties identify
liberties enumerated in the Constitution as privileges and
immunities common to all United States citizens. For example, the
Louisiana Cession Act of 1803, which codified a treaty between the
United States and France culminating in the Louisiana Purchase,
provided that “The inhabitants of the ceded
territory shall be incorporated in the Union of the United States,
and admitted as soon as possible, according to the principles of
the Federal constitution, to the enjoyments of all the rights,
advantages and immunities of citizens of the United States; and in the mean time they shall be maintained and protected in the free enjoyment of their liberty, property and the religion
which they profess .” Treaty Between the United States of
America and the French Republic, Art. III, Apr. 30, 1803, 8 Stat.
202, T. S. No. 86 (emphasis added).[ Footnote 8 ] The Louisiana
Cession Act reveals even more about the privileges and immunities
of United States citizenship because it provoked an extensive
public debate on the meaning of that term. In 1820, when the
Missouri Territory (which the United States acquired through the
Cession Act) sought to enter the Union as a new State, a debate
ensued over whether to prohibit slavery within Missouri as a
condition of its admission. Some congressmen argued that
prohibiting slavery in Missouri would deprive its inhabitants of
the “privileges and immunities” they had been promised by the
Cession Act. See, e.g. , 35 Annals of Cong. 1083 (1855)
(remarks of Kentucky Rep. Hardin). But those who opposed slavery in
Missouri argued that the right to hold slaves was merely a matter
of state property law, not one of the privileges and immunities of
United States citizenship guaranteed by the Act.[ Footnote 9 ] Daniel Webster was among the
leading proponents of the antislavery position. In his “Memorial to
Congress,” Webster argued that “[t]he rights, advantages and
immunities here spoken of [in the Cession Act] must . . . be such
as are recognized or communicated by the Constitution of the United
States,” not the “rights, advantages and immunities, derived
exclusively from the State governments . . . .” D.
Webster, A Memorial to the Congress of the United States on the
Subject of Restraining the Increase of Slavery in New States to be
Admitted into the Union 15 (Dec. 15, 1819) (emphasis added). “The
obvious meaning” of the Act, in Webster’s view, was that “ the
rights derived under the federal Constitution shall be enjoyed
by the inhabitants of [the territory].” Id. , at 15–16
(emphasis added). In other words, Webster articulated a distinction
between the rights of United States citizenship and the rights of
state citizenship, and argued that the former included those rights
“recognized or communicated by the Constitution.” Since the right
to hold slaves was not mentioned in the Constitution, it was not a
right of federal citizenship. Webster and his allies
ultimately lost the debate over slavery in Missouri and the
territory was admitted as a slave State as part of the now-famous
Missouri Compromise. Missouri Enabling Act of March 6, 1820, ch.
22, §8, 3 Stat. 548. But their arguments continued to inform public
understanding of the privileges and immunities of United States
citizenship. In 1854, Webster’s Memorial was republished in a
pamphlet discussing the Nation’s next major debate on slavery—the
proposed repeal of the Missouri Compromise through the
Kansas-Nebraska Act, see The Nebraska Question: Comprising Speeches
in the United States Senate: Together with the History of the
Missouri Compromise 9–12 (1854). It was published again in 1857 in
a collection of famous American speeches. See The Political
Text-Book, or Encyclopedia: Containing Everything Necessary for the
Reference of the Politicians and Statesmen of the United States
601–604 (M. Cluskey ed. 1857); see also Lash, 98 Geo. L. J.,
at 1294–1296 (describing Webster’s arguments and their
influence). 2 Evidence from the
political branches in the years leading to the Fourteenth
Amendment’s adoption demonstrates broad public understanding that
the privileges and immunities of United States citizenship included
rights set forth in the Constitution, just as Webster and his
allies had argued. In 1868, President Andrew Johnson issued a
proclamation granting amnesty to former Confederates, guaranteeing
“to all and to every person who directly or indirectly participated
in the late insurrection or rebellion, a full pardon and amnesty
for the offence of treason . . . with restoration of all
rights, privileges, and immunities under the Constitution and
the laws which have been made in pursuance thereof.” 15 Stat.
712. Records from the
39th Congress further support this understanding. a After the Civil
War, Congress established the Joint Committee on Reconstruction to
investigate circumstances in the Southern States and to determine
whether, and on what conditions, those States should be readmitted
to the Union. See Cong. Globe, 39th Cong., 1st Sess., 6, 30 (1865)
(hereinafter 39th Cong. Globe); M. Curtis, No State Shall Abridge:
The Fourteenth Amendment and the Bill of Rights 57 (1986)
(hereinafter Curtis). That Committee would ultimately recommend the
adoption of the Fourteenth Amendment, justifying its recommendation
by submitting a report to Congress that extensively catalogued the
abuses of civil rights in the former slave States and argued that
“adequate security for future peace and safety . . . can only be
found in such changes of the organic law as shall determine the
civil rights and privileges of all citizens in all parts of the
republic.” See Report of the Joint Committee on Reconstruction, S.
Rep. No. 112, 39th Cong., 1st Sess., p. 15 (1866); H. R. Rep. No.
30, 39th Cong., 1st Sess., p. XXI (1866). As the Court
notes, the Committee’s Report “was widely reprinted in the press
and distributed by members of the 39th Congress to their
constituents.” Ante , at 24; B. Kendrick, Journal of the
Joint Committee of Fifteen on Reconstruction 264–265 (1914) (noting
that 150,000 copies of the Report were printed and that it was
widely distributed as a campaign document in the election of 1866).
In addition, newspaper coverage suggests that the wider public was
aware of the Committee’s work even before the Report was issued.
For example, the Fort Wayne Daily Democrat (which appears to have
been unsupportive of the Committee’s work) paraphrased a motion
instructing the Committee to “enquire into [the] expediency of
amending the Constitution of the United States so as to declare
with greater certainty the power of Congress to enforce and
determine by appropriate legislation all the guarantees contained
in that instrument .” The Nigger Congress!, Fort Wayne
Daily Democrat, Feb. 1, 1866, p. 4 (emphasis added). b Statements made by
Members of Congress leading up to, and during, the debates on the
Fourteenth Amendment point in the same direction. The record of
these debates has been combed before. See Adamson v. California , 332 U. S. 46 , 92–110
(1947) (Appendix to dissenting opinion of Black, J.) (concluding
that the debates support the conclusion that §1 was understood to
incorporate the Bill of Rights against the States); ante ,
at 14, n. 9, 26–27, n. 23, (opinion of the Court)
(counting the debates among other evidence that §1 applies the
Second Amendment against the States). Before considering that
record here, it is important to clarify its relevance. When
interpreting constitutional text, the goal is to discern the most
likely public understanding of a particular provision at the time
it was adopted. Statements by legislators can assist in this
process to the extent they demonstrate the manner in which the
public used or understood a particular word or phrase. They can
further assist to the extent there is evidence that these
statements were disseminated to the public. In other words, this
evidence is useful not because it demonstrates what the draftsmen
of the text may have been thinking, but only insofar as it
illuminates what the public understood the words chosen by the
draftsmen to mean. (1) Three speeches
stand out as particularly significant. Representative John Bingham,
the principal draftsman of §1, delivered a speech on the floor of
the House in February 1866 introducing his first draft of the
provision. Bingham began by discussing Barron and its
holding that the Bill of Rights did not apply to the States. He
then argued that a constitutional amendment was necessary to
provide “an express grant of power in Congress to enforce by penal
enactment these great canons of the supreme law, securing to all
the citizens in every State all the privileges and immunities of
citizens, and to all the people all the sacred rights of person.”
39th Cong. Globe 1089–1090 (1866). Bingham emphasized that §1 was
designed “to arm the Congress of the United States, by the consent
of the people of the United States, with the power to enforce the
bill of rights as it stands in the Constitution today. It ‘hath
that extent—no more.’ ” Id ., at 1088. Bingham’s
speech was printed in pamphlet form and broadly distributed in 1866
under the title, “One Country, One Constitution, and One People,”
and the subtitle, “In Support of the Proposed Amendment to Enforce
the Bill of Rights.”[ Footnote
10 ] Newspapers also reported his proposal, with the New York
Times providing particularly extensive coverage, including a full
reproduction of Bingham’s first draft of §1 and his remarks that a
constitutional amendment to “enforc[e]” the “immortal bill of
rights” was “absolutely essential to American nationality.” N. Y.
Times, Feb. 27, 1866, p. 8. Bingham’s first draft of §1 was
different from the version ultimately adopted. Of particular
importance, the first draft granted Congress the “power to make all
laws … necessary and proper to secure” the “citizens of each State
all privileges and immunities of citizens in the several States,”
rather than restricting state power to “abridge” the privileges or
immunities of citizens of the United States.[ Footnote 11 ] 39th Cong. Globe 1088. That draft was met with
objections, which the Times covered extensively. A front-page
article hailed the “Clear and Forcible Speech” by Representative
Robert Hale against the draft, explaining—and endorsing—Hale’s view
that Bingham’s proposal would “confer upon Congress all the rights
and power of legislation now reserved to the States” and would “in
effect utterly obliterate State rights and State authority over
their own internal affairs.”[ Footnote 12 ] N. Y. Times, Feb. 28, 1866,
p. 1. Critically, Hale did not object to the draft insofar as it purported to protect
constitutional liberties against state interference. Indeed, Hale
stated that he believed (incorrectly in light of Barron )
that individual rights enumerated in the Constitution were already
enforceable against the States. See 39th Cong. Globe 1064 (“I have,
somehow or other, gone along with the impression that there is that
sort of protection thrown over us in some way, whether with or
without the sanction of a judicial decision that we are so
protected”); see N. Y. Times, Feb. 28, 1866, at 1. Hale’s
misperception was not uncommon among members of the Reconstruction
generation. See infra , at 38–40. But that is secondary to
the point that the Times’ coverage of this debate over §1’s meaning
suggests public awareness of its main contours— i.e. , that
§1 would, at a minimum, enforce constitutionally enumerated rights
of United States citizens against the States. Bingham’s draft was tabled for
several months. In the interim, he delivered a second
well-publicized speech, again arguing that a constitutional
amendment was required to give Congress the power to enforce the
Bill of Rights against the States. That speech was printed in
pamphlet form, see Speech of Hon. John A. Bingham, of Ohio, on the
Civil Rights Bill, Mar. 9, 1866 (Cong. Globe); see 39th Cong. Globe
1837 (remarks of Rep. Lawrence) (noting that the speech was
“extensively published”), and the New York Times covered the speech
on its front page. Thirty-Ninth Congress, N. Y. Times, Mar. 10,
1866, p. 1. By the time the debates on the
Fourteenth Amendment resumed, Bingham had amended his draft of §1
to include the text of the Privileges or Immunities Clause that was
ultimately adopted. Senator Jacob Howard introduced the new draft
on the floor of the Senate in the third speech relevant here.
Howard explained that the Constitution recognized “a mass of
privileges, immunities, and rights, some of them secured by the
second section of the fourth article of the Constitution, . . .
some by the first eight amendments of the Constitution,” and that
“there is no power given in the Constitution to enforce and to
carry out any of these guarantees” against the States. 39th Cong.
Globe 2765. Howard then stated that “the great object” of §1 was to
“restrain the power of the States and compel them at all times to
respect these great fundamental guarantees.” Id. , at 2766.
Section 1, he indicated, imposed “a general prohibition upon all
the States, as such, from abridging the privileges and immunities
of the citizens of the United States.” Id. , at
2765. In describing these rights,
Howard explained that they included “the privileges and immunities
spoken of” in Article IV, §2. Id., at 2765. Although he
did not catalogue the precise “nature” or “extent” of those rights,
he thought “Corfield v. Coryell” provided a useful
description. Howard then submitted that “[t]o these privileges and
immunities, whatever they may be— . . . should be added the
personal rights guarantied and secured by the first eight
amendments of the Constitution ; such as the freedom of speech
and of the press; the right of the people peaceably to assemble and
petition the Government for a redress of grievances, [and] . . . the right to keep and to bear arms .” Ibid. (emphasis added). News of Howard’s
speech was carried in major newspapers across the country,
including the New York Herald, see N. Y. Herald, May 24, 1866, p.
1, which was the best-selling paper in the Nation at that time, see
A. Amar, The Bill of Rights: Creation and Reconstruction 187 (1998)
(hereinafter Amar).[ Footnote
13 ] The New York Times carried the speech as well, reprinting a
lengthy excerpt of Howard’s remarks, including the statements
quoted above. N. Y. Times, May 24, 1866, p. 1. The following
day’s Times editorialized on Howard’s speech, predicting that “[t]o
this, the first section of the amendment, the Union party
throughout the country will yield a ready acquiescence, and the
South could offer no justifiable resistance,” suggesting that
Bingham’s narrower second draft had not been met with the same
objections that Hale had raised against the first. N. Y.
Times, May 25, 1866, p. 4. As a whole, these
well-circulated speeches indicate that §1 was understood to enforce
constitutionally declared rights against the States, and they
provide no suggestion that any language in the section other than
the Privileges or Immunities Clause would accomplish that task. (2) When read
against this backdrop, the civil rights legislation adopted by the
39th Congress in 1866 further supports this view. Between passing
the Thirteenth Amendment—which outlawed slavery alone—and the
Fourteenth Amendment, Congress passed two significant pieces of
legislation. The first was the Civil Rights Act of 1866, which
provided that “all persons born in the United States” were
“citizens of the United States” and that “such citizens, of every
race and color, . . . shall have the same right” to, among other
things, “full and equal benefit of all laws and proceedings for the
security of person and property, as is enjoyed by white citizens.”
Ch. 31, §1, 14 Stat. 27. Both proponents and
opponents of this Act described it as providing the “privileges” of
citizenship to freedmen, and defined those privileges to include
constitutional rights, such as the right to keep and bear arms. See
39th Cong. Globe 474 (remarks of Sen. Trumbull) (stating that the
“the late slaveholding States” had enacted laws “depriving persons
of African descent of privileges which are essential to freemen,”
including “prohibit[ing] any negro or mulatto from having
fire-arms” and stating that “[t]he purpose of the bill under
consideration is to destroy all these discriminations”); id. ,
at 1266–1267 (remarks of Rep. Raymond) (opposing the Act, but
recognizing that to “[m]ake a colored man a citizen of the United
States” would guarantee to him, inter alia , “a defined status . . . a right to defend himself and his wife and
children; a right to bear arms”). Three months later, Congress
passed the Freedmen’s Bureau Act, which also entitled all citizens
to the “full and equal benefit of all laws and proceedings
concerning personal liberty” and “personal security.” Act of July
16, 1866, ch. 200, §14, 14 Stat. 176. The Act stated expressly that
the rights of personal liberty and security protected by the Act
“includ[ed] the constitutional right to bear arms.” Ibid. (3) There is much
else in the legislative record. Many statements by Members of
Congress corroborate the view that the Privileges or Immunities
Clause enforced constitutionally enumerated rights against the
States. See Curtis 112 (collecting examples). I am not aware of any
statement that directly refutes that proposition. That said, the
record of the debates—like most legislative history—is less than
crystal clear. In particular, much ambiguity derives from the fact
that at least several Members described §1 as protecting the
privileges and immunities of citizens “in the several States,”
harkening back to Article IV, §2. See supra , at 28–29
(describing Sen. Howard’s speech). These statements can be read to
support the view that the Privileges or Immunities Clause protects
some or all the fundamental rights of “citizens” described in Corfield . They can also be read to support the view that
the Privileges or Immunities Clause, like Article IV, §2, prohibits
only state discrimination with respect to those rights it covers,
but does not deprive States of the power to deny those rights to
all citizens equally. I examine the rest
of the historical record with this understanding. But for purposes
of discerning what the public most likely thought the Privileges or
Immunities Clause to mean, it is significant that the most widely
publicized statements by the legislators who voted on §1—Bingham,
Howard, and even Hale—point unambiguously toward the conclusion
that the Privileges or Immunities Clause enforces at least those
fundamental rights enumerated in the Constitution against the
States, including the Second Amendment right to keep and bear
arms. 3 Interpretations of
the Fourteenth Amendment in the period immediately following its
ratification help to establish the public understanding of the text
at the time of its adoption. Some of these
interpretations come from Members of Congress. During an 1871
debate on a bill to enforce the Fourteenth Amendment,
Representative Henry Dawes listed the Constitution’s first eight
Amendments, including “the right to keep and bear arms,” before
explaining that after the Civil War, the country “gave the most
grand of all these rights, privileges, and immunities, by one
single amendment to the Constitution, to four millions of American
citizens” who formerly were slaves. Cong. Globe, 42d Cong., 1st
Sess., 475–476 (1871). “It is all these,” Dawes explained, “which
are comprehended in the words ‘American citizen.’ ” Ibid . ; see also id. , at 334 (remarks of
Rep. Hoar) (stating that the Privileges or Immunities Clause
referred to those rights “declared to belong to the citizen by the
Constitution itself”). Even opponents of Fourteenth Amendment
enforcement legislation acknowledged that the Privileges or
Immunities Clause protected constitutionally enumerated individual
rights. See 2 Cong. Rec. 384–385 (1874) (remarks of Rep. Mills)
(opposing enforcement law, but acknowledging, in referring to the
Bill of Rights, that “[t]hese first amendments and some provisions
of the Constitution of like import embrace the ‘privileges and
immunities’ of citizenship as set forth in article 4, section 2 of
the Constitution and in the fourteenth amendment ”
(emphasis added)); see Curtis 166–170 (collecting
examples). Legislation passed in
furtherance of the Fourteenth Amendment demonstrates even more
clearly this understanding. For example, Congress enacted the Civil
Rights Act of 1871, 17 Stat. 13, which was titled in pertinent part
“An Act to enforce the Provisions of the Fourteenth Amendment to
the Constitution of the United States,” and which is codified in
the still-existing 42 U. S. C. §1983. That statute prohibits
state officials from depriving citizens of “any rights, privileges,
or immunities secured by the Constitution .” Rev. Stat.
1979, 42 U. S. C. §1983 (emphasis added). Although the
Judiciary ignored this provision for decades after its enactment,
this Court has come to interpret the statute, unremarkably in light
of its text, as protecting constitutionally enumerated rights. Monroe v. Pape , 365 U. S. 167 , 171
(1961). A Federal Court of Appeals
decision written by a future Justice of this Court adopted the same
understanding of the Privileges or Immunities Clause. See, e.g. , United States v. Hall , 26
F. Cas. 79, 82 (No. 15,282) (CC SD Ala. 1871) (Woods, J.) (“We
think, therefore, that the . . . rights enumerated in the first
eight articles of amendment to the constitution of the United
States, are the privileges and immunities of citizens of the United
States”). In addition, two of the era’s major constitutional
treatises reflected the understanding that §1 would protect
constitutionally enumerated rights from state abridgment.[ Footnote 14 ] A third such treatise
unambiguously indicates that the Privileges or Immunities Clause
accomplished this task. G. Paschal, The Constitution of the United
States 290 (1868) (explaining that the rights listed in §1 had
“already been guarantied” by Article IV and the Bill of Rights, but
that “[t]he new feature declared” by §1 was that these rights,
“which had been construed to apply only to the national government,
are thus imposed upon the States”). Another example of public
understanding comes from United States Attorney Daniel Corbin’s
statement in an 1871 Ku Klux Klan prosecution. Corbin cited Barron and declared: “[T]he fourteenth amendment changes
all that theory, and lays the same restriction upon the States that
before lay upon the Congress of the United States—that, as Congress
heretofore could not interfere with the right of the citizen to
keep and bear arms, now, after the adoption of the fourteenth
amendment, the State cannot interfere with the right of the citizen
to keep and bear arms. The right to keep and bear arms is included
in the fourteenth amendment, under ‘privileges and
immunities.’ ” Proceedings in the Ku Klux Trials at Columbia,
S. C., in the United States Circuit Court, November Term,
1871, p. 147 (1872). * * * This evidence
plainly shows that the ratifying public understood the Privileges
or Immunities Clause to protect constitutionally enumerated rights,
including the right to keep and bear arms. As the Court
demonstrates, there can be no doubt that §1 was understood to
enforce the Second Amendment against the States. See ante ,
at 22–33. In my view, this is because the right to keep and bear
arms was understood to be a privilege of American citizenship
guaranteed by the Privileges or Immunities Clause. C The next question
is whether the Privileges or Immunities Clause merely prohibits
States from discriminating among citizens if they recognize the
Second Amendment’s right to keep and bear arms, or whether the
Clause requires States to recognize the right. The municipal
respondents, Chicago and Oak Park, argue for the former
interpretation. They contend that the Second Amendment, as applied
to the States through the Fourteenth, authorizes a State to impose
an outright ban on handgun possession such as the ones at issue
here so long as a State applies it to all citizens
equally.[ Footnote 15 ] The
Court explains why this antidiscrimination-only reading of §1 as a
whole is “implausible.” Ante , at 31 (citing Brief for
Municipal Respondents 64). I agree, but because I think it is the
Privileges or Immunities Clause that applies this right to the
States, I must explain why this Clause in particular protects
against more than just state discrimination, and in fact
establishes a minimum baseline of rights for all American
citizens. 1 I begin, again,
with the text. The Privileges or Immunities Clause opens with the
command that “ No State shall ” abridge the privileges or
immunities of citizens of the United States. Amdt. 14, §1 (emphasis
added). The very same phrase opens Article I, §10 of the
Constitution, which prohibits the States from “pass[ing] any Bill
of Attainder” or “ex post facto Law,” among other things. Article
I, §10 is one of the few constitutional provisions that limits
state authority. In Barron , when Chief Justice Marshall
interpreted the Bill of Rights as lacking “plain and intelligible
language” restricting state power to infringe upon individual
liberties, he pointed to Article I, §10 as an example of text that
would have accomplished that task. 7 Pet., at 250. Indeed, Chief
Justice Marshall would later describe Article I, §10 as “a bill of
rights for the people of each state.” Fletcher v. Peck , 6 Cranch 87, 138 (1810). Thus, the fact that the
Privileges or Immunities Clause uses the command “[n]o State
shall”—which Article IV, §2 does not—strongly suggests that the
former imposes a greater restriction on state power than the
latter. This interpretation is
strengthened when one considers that the Privileges or Immunities
Clause uses the verb “abridge,” rather than “discriminate,” to
describe the limit it imposes on state authority. The Webster’s
dictionary in use at the time of Reconstruction defines the word
“abridge” to mean “[t]o deprive; to cut off; . . . as, to abridge one of his rights.” Webster, An American
Dictionary of the English Language, at 6. The Clause is thus best
understood to impose a limitation on state power to infringe upon
pre-existing substantive rights. It raises no indication that the
Framers of the Clause used the word “abridge” to prohibit only
discrimination. This most natural
textual reading is underscored by a well-publicized revision to the
Fourteenth Amendment that the Reconstruction Congress rejected.
After several Southern States refused to ratify the Amendment,
President Johnson met with their Governors to draft a compromise.
N. Y. Times, Feb. 5, 1867, p. 5. Their proposal
eliminated Congress’ power to enforce the Amendment (granted in
§5), and replaced the Privileges or Immunities Clause in §1 with
the following: “All persons born or naturalized in
the United States, and subject to the jurisdiction thereof, are
citizens of the United States, and of the States in which they
reside, and the Citizens of each State shall be entitled to all the privileges and immunities of citizens in the several
States .” Draft reprinted in 1 Documentary History of
Reconstruction 240 (W. Fleming ed. 1950) (hereinafter
Fleming). Significantly,
this proposal removed the “[n]o State shall” directive and the verb
“abridge” from §1, and also changed the class of rights to be
protected from those belonging to “citizens of the United States”
to those of the “citizens in the several States.” This phrasing is
materially indistinguishable from Article IV, §2, which generally
was understood as an antidiscrimination provision alone. See supra , at 15–18. The proposal thus strongly indicates that
at least the President of the United States and several southern
Governors thought that the Privileges or Immunities Clause, which
they unsuccessfully tried to revise, prohibited more than just
state-sponsored discrimination. 2 The argument that
the Privileges or Immunities Clause prohibits no more than
discrimination often is followed by a claim that public discussion
of the Clause, and of §1 generally, was not extensive. Because of
this, the argument goes, §1 must not have been understood to
accomplish such a significant task as subjecting States to federal
enforcement of a minimum baseline of rights. That argument
overlooks critical aspects of the Nation’s history that underscored
the need for, and wide agreement upon, federal enforcement of
constitutionally enumerated rights against the States, including
the right to keep and bear arms. a I turn first to
public debate at the time of ratification. It is true that the
congressional debates over §1 were relatively brief. It is also
true that there is little evidence of extensive debate in the
States. Many state legislatures did not keep records of their
debates, and the few records that do exist reveal only modest
discussion. See Curtis 145. These facts are not
surprising. First, however
consequential we consider the question today, the nationalization
of constitutional rights was not the most controversial aspect of
the Fourteenth Amendment at the time of its ratification. The
Nation had just endured a tumultuous civil war, and §§2, 3, and
4—which reduced the representation of States that denied voting
rights to blacks, deprived most former Confederate officers of the
power to hold elective office, and required States to disavow
Confederate war debts—were far more polarizing and consumed far
more political attention. See Wildenthal 1600; Hardy, Original
Popular Understanding of the Fourteenth Amendment as Reflected in
the Print Media of 1866–1868, 30 Whittier L. Rev. 695, 699
(2009). Second, the
congressional debates on the Fourteenth Amendment reveal that many
representatives, and probably many citizens, believed that the
Thirteenth Amendment, the 1866 Civil Rights legislation, or some
combination of the two, had already enforced constitutional rights
against the States. Justice Black’s dissent in Adamson chronicles this point in detail. 332 U. S., at 107–108 (Appendix to
dissenting opinion). Regardless of whether that understanding was
accurate as a matter of constitutional law, it helps to explain why
Congressmen had little to say during the debates about §1. See ibid. Third, while Barron made plain that the Bill of Rights was not legally
enforceable against the States, see supra , at 2, the
significance of that holding should not be overstated. Like the
Framers, see supra , at 14–15, many 19th-century Americans
understood the Bill of Rights to declare inalienable rights that
pre-existed all government. Thus, even though the Bill of Rights
technically applied only to the Federal Government, many believed
that it declared rights that no legitimate government could
abridge. Chief Justice Henry
Lumpkin’s decision for the Georgia Supreme Court in Nunn v. State , 1 Ga. 243 (1846), illustrates this view. In
assessing state power to regulate firearm possession, Lumpkin wrote
that he was “aware that it has been decided, that [the Second
Amendment], like other amendments adopted at the same time, is a
restriction upon the government of the United States, and does not
extend to the individual States.” Id. , at 250. But he
still considered the right to keep and bear arms as “an unalienable
right, which lies at the bottom of every free government, ” and thus found the States bound to honor it. Ibid . Other
state courts adopted similar positions with respect to the right to
keep and bear arms and other enumerated rights.[ Footnote 16 ] Some courts even suggested that
the protections in the Bill of Rights were legally enforceable
against the States, Barron notwithstanding.[ Footnote 17 ] A prominent treatise of the
era took the same position. W. Rawle, A View of the Constitution of
the United States of America 124–125 (2d ed. 1829) (reprint 2009)
(arguing that certain of the first eight Amendments “appl[y] to the
state legislatures” because those Amendments “form parts of the
declared rights of the people, of which neither the state powers
nor those of the Union can ever deprive them”); id. , at
125–126 (describing the Second Amendment “right of the people to
keep and bear arms” as “a restraint on both” Congress and the
States); see also Heller , 554 U. S., at __ (slip op., at
34) (describing Rawle’s treatise as “influential”). Certain
abolitionist leaders adhered to this view as well. Lysander Spooner
championed the popular abolitionist argument that slavery was
inconsistent with constitutional principles, citing as evidence the
fact that it deprived black Americans of the “natural right of all
men ‘to keep and bear arms’ for their personal defence,” which he
believed the Constitution “prohibit[ed] both Congress and the State
governments from infringing.” L. Spooner, The Unconstitutionality
of Slavery 98 (1860). In sum, some appear
to have believed that the Bill of Rights did apply to the
States, even though this Court had squarely rejected that theory.
See, e.g. , supra , at 27–28 (recounting Rep.
Hale’s argument to this effect). Many others believed that the
liberties codified in the Bill of Rights were ones that no State should abridge, even though they understood that the Bill
technically did not apply to States. These beliefs, combined with
the fact that most state constitutions recognized many, if not all,
of the individual rights enumerated in the Bill of Rights, made the
need for federal enforcement of constitutional liberties against
the States an afterthought. See ante , at 29 (opinion of
the Court) (noting that, “[i]n 1868, 22 of the 37 States in the
Union had state constitutional provisions explicitly protecting the
right to keep and bear arms”). That changed with the national
conflict over slavery. b In the
contentious years leading up to the Civil War, those who sought to
retain the institution of slavery found that to do so, it was
necessary to eliminate more and more of the basic liberties of
slaves, free blacks, and white abolitionists. Congressman Tobias
Plants explained that slaveholders “could not hold [slaves] safely
where dissent was permitted,” so they decided that “all dissent
must be suppressed by the strong hand of power.” 39th Cong. Globe
1013. The measures they used were ruthless, repressed virtually
every right recognized in the Constitution, and demonstrated that
preventing only discriminatory state firearms restrictions would
have been a hollow assurance for liberty. Public reaction indicates
that the American people understood this point. The
overarching goal of pro-slavery forces was to repress the spread of
abolitionist thought and the concomitant risk of a slave rebellion.
Indeed, it is difficult to overstate the extent to which fear of a
slave uprising gripped slaveholders and dictated the acts of
Southern legislatures. Slaves and free blacks represented a
substantial percentage of the population and posed a severe threat
to Southern order if they were not kept in their place. According
to the 1860 Census, slaves represented one quarter or more of the
population in 11 of the 15 slave States, nearly half the population
in Alabama, Florida, Georgia, and Louisiana, and more than
50% of the population in Mississippi and South Carolina. Statistics
of the United States (Including Mortality, Property, &c.,) in
1860, The Eighth Census 336–350 (1866). The Southern fear
of slave rebellion was not unfounded. Although there were others,
two particularly notable slave uprisings heavily influenced
slaveholders in the South. In 1822, a group of free blacks and
slaves led by Denmark Vesey planned a rebellion in which they would
slay their masters and flee to Haiti. H. Aptheker, American Negro
Slave Revolts 268–270 (1983). The plan was foiled, leading to the
swift arrest of 130 blacks, and the execution of 37, including
Vesey. Id. , at 271. Still, slaveowners took notice—it was
reportedly feared that as many as 6,600 to 9,000 slaves and free
blacks were involved in the plot. Id. , at 272. A few years
later, the fear of rebellion was realized. An uprising led by Nat
Turner took the lives of at least 57 whites before it was
suppressed. Id. , at 300–302. The fear generated
by these and other rebellions led Southern legislatures to take
particularly vicious aim at the rights of free blacks and slaves to
speak or to keep and bear arms for their defense. Teaching slaves
to read (even the Bible) was a criminal offense punished severely
in some States. See K. Stampp, The Peculiar Institution: Slavery in
the Ante-bellum South 208, 211 (1956). Virginia made it a crime for
a member of an “abolition” society to enter the State and argue
“that the owners of slaves have no property in the same, or
advocate or advise the abolition of slavery.” 1835–1836 Va. Acts
ch. 66, p. 44. Other States prohibited the circulation of
literature denying a master’s right to property in his slaves and
passed laws requiring postmasters to inspect the mails in search of
such material. C. Eaton, The Freedom-of-Thought Struggle in the Old
South 118–143, 199–200 (1964). Many legislatures
amended their laws prohibiting slaves from carrying
firearms[ Footnote 18 ] to
apply the prohibition to free blacks as well. See, e.g. ,
Act of Dec. 23, 1833, §7, 1833 Ga. Acts pp. 226, 228
(declaring that “it shall not be lawful for any free person of
colour in this state, to own, use, or carry fire arms of any
description whatever”); H. Aptheker, Nat Turner’s Slave Rebellion
74–76, 83–94 (1966) (discussing similar Maryland and Virginia
statutes); see also Act of Mar. 15, 1852, ch. 206, 1852 Miss. Laws
p. 328 (repealing laws allowing free blacks to obtain firearms
licenses); Act of Jan. 31, 1831, 1831 Fla. Acts p. 30 (same).
Florida made it the “duty” of white citizen “patrol[s] to search
negro houses or other suspected places, for fire arms.” Act of Feb.
17, 1833, ch. 671, 1833 Fla. Acts pp. 26, 30. If they found
any firearms, the patrols were to take the offending slave or free
black “to the nearest justice of the peace,” whereupon he would be
“severely punished” by “whipping on the bare back, not exceeding
thirty-nine lashes,” unless he could give a “plain and
satisfactory” explanation of how he came to possess the gun. Ibid. Southern
blacks were not alone in facing threats to their personal liberty
and security during the antebellum era. Mob violence in many
Northern cities presented dangers as well. Cottrol & Diamond,
The Second Amendment: Toward an Afro-Americanist Reconsideration,
80 Geo. L. J. 309, 340 (1991) (hereinafter Cottrol) (recounting a
July 1834 mob attack against “churches, homes, and businesses of
white abolitionists and blacks” in New York that involved “upwards
of twenty thousand people and required the intervention of the
militia to suppress”); ibid. (noting an uprising in Boston
nine years later in which a confrontation between a group of white
sailors and four blacks led “a mob of several hundred
whites ” to “attac[k] and severely beat every black they
could find”). c After
the Civil War, Southern anxiety about an uprising among the newly
freed slaves peaked. As Representative Thaddeus Stevens is reported
to have said, “[w]hen it was first proposed to free the slaves, and
arm the blacks, did not half the nation tremble? The prim
conservatives, the snobs, and the male waiting-maids in Congress,
were in hysterics.” K. Stampp, The Era of Reconstruction,
1865–1877, p. 104 (1965) (hereinafter Era of
Reconstruction). As the
Court explains, this fear led to “systematic efforts” in the “old
Confederacy” to disarm the more than 180,000 freedmen who had
served in the Union Army, as well as other free blacks. See ante , at 23. Some States formally prohibited blacks from
possessing firearms. Ante, at 23–24 (quoting 1865 Miss.
Laws p. 165, §1, reprinted in 1 Fleming 289). Others enacted
legislation prohibiting blacks from carrying firearms without a
license, a restriction not imposed on whites. See, e.g. ,
La. Statute of 1865, reprinted in id., at 280.
Additionally, “[t]hroughout the South, armed parties, often
consisting of ex-Confederate soldiers serving in the state
militias, forcibly took firearms from newly freed slaves.” Ante , at 24. As the Court makes
crystal clear, if the Fourteenth Amendment “had outlawed only those
laws that discriminate on the basis of race or previous condition
of servitude, African-Americans in the South would likely have
remained vulnerable to attack by many of their worst abusers: the
state militia and state peace officers.” Ante, at 32. In
the years following the Civil War, a law banning firearm possession
outright “would have been nondiscriminatory only in the formal
sense,” for it would have “left firearms in the hands of the
militia and local peace officers.” Ibid. Evidence suggests
that the public understood this at the time the Fourteenth
Amendment was ratified. The publicly circulated Report of the Joint
Committee on Reconstruction extensively detailed these abuses, see ante, at 23–24 (collecting examples), and statements by
citizens indicate that they looked to the Committee to provide a
federal solution to this problem, see, e.g. , 39th Cong.
Globe 337 (remarks of Rep. Sumner) (introducing “a memorial from
the colored citizens of the State of South Carolina” asking for, inter alia , “constitutional protection in keeping arms, in
holding public assemblies, and in complete liberty of speech and of
the press”). One way in which
the Federal Government responded was to issue military orders
countermanding Southern arms legislation. See, e.g. , Jan.
17, 1866, order from Major General D. E. Sickles, reprinted in E.
McPherson, The Political History of the United States of America
During the Period of Reconstruction 37 (1871) (“The constitutional
rights of all loyal and well-disposed inhabitants to bear arms will
not be infringed”). The significance of these steps was not lost on
those they were designed to protect. After one such order was
issued, The Christian Recorder, published by the African Methodist
Episcopal Church, published the following
editorial: “ ‘We have several times alluded to the
fact that the Constitution of the United States, guaranties to
every citizen the right to keep and bear arms. . . . All men,
without the distinction of color, have the right to keep arms to
defend their homes, families, or themselves.’ “We are glad to
learn that [the] Commissioner for this State . . . has given
freedmen to understand that they have as good a right to keep fire
arms as any other citizens. The Constitution of the United States
is the supreme law of the land, and we will be governed by that at
present.” Right to Bear Arms, Christian Recorder (Phila.), Feb. 24,
1866, pp. 29–30. The
same month, The Loyal Georgian carried a letter to the editor
asking “Have colored persons a right to own and carry fire arms?—A
Colored Citizen.” The editors responded as
follows: “Almost every day, we are asked questions
similar to the above. We answer certainly you have the same right to own and carry fire arms that other citizens have. You are not only free but citizens of the United
States and, as such, entitled to the same privileges granted to
other citizens by the Constitution of the United
States. . . . . . “. . . Article II, of the amendments
to the Constitution of the United States, gives the people the
right to bear arms and states that this right shall not be
infringed. . . . All men, without distinction of color, have the
right to keep arms to defend their homes, families or themselves.”
Letter to the Editor, Loyal Georgian (Augusta), Feb. 3, 1866,
p. 3. These
statements are consistent with the arguments of abolitionists
during the antebellum era that slavery, and the slave States’
efforts to retain it, violated the constitutional rights of
individuals—rights the abolitionists described as among the
privileges and immunities of citizenship. See, e.g. , J.
Tiffany, Treatise on the Unconstitutionality of American Slavery 56
(1849) (reprint 1969) (“pledg[ing] . . . to see that all the
rights, privileges, and immunities, granted by the constitution of
the United States, are extended to all”); id. , at 99
(describing the “right to keep and bear arms” as one of those
rights secured by “the constitution of the United States”). The
problem abolitionists sought to remedy was that, under Dred
Scott , blacks were not entitled to the privileges and
immunities of citizens under the Federal Constitution and that, in
many States, whatever inalienable rights state law recognized did
not apply to blacks. See, e.g. , Cooper v. Savannah , 4 Ga. 68, 72 (1848) (deciding, just two years
after Chief Justice Lumpkin’s opinion in Nunn recognizing
the right to keep and bear arms, see supra , at 39, that
“[f]ree persons of color have never been recognized here as
citizens; they are not entitled to bear arms”). Section 1
guaranteed the rights of citizenship in the United States and in
the several States without regard to race. But it was understood
that liberty would be assured little protection if §1 left each
State to decide which privileges or immunities of United States
citizenship it would protect. As Frederick Douglass explained
before §1’s adoption, “the Legislatures of the South can take from
him the right to keep and bear arms, as they can—they would not
allow a negro to walk with a cane where I came from, they would not
allow five of them to assemble together.” In What New Skin Will the
Old Snake Come Forth? An Address Delivered in New York, New York,
May 10, 1865, reprinted in 4 The Frederick Douglass Papers 79,
83–84 (J. Blassingame & J. McKivigan eds., 1991) (footnote
omitted). “Notwithstanding the provision in the Constitution of the
United States, that the right to keep and bear arms shall not be
abridged,” Douglass explained that “the black man has never had the
right either to keep or bear arms.” Id ., at 84. Absent a
constitutional amendment to enforce that right against the States,
he insisted that “the work of the Abolitionists [wa]s not
finished.” Ibid. This history
confirms what the text of the Privileges or Immunities Clause most
naturally suggests: Consistent with its command that “[n]o State
shall … abridge” the rights of United States citizens, the Clause
establishes a minimum baseline of federal rights, and the
constitutional right to keep and bear arms plainly was among
them.[ Footnote
19 ] III My
conclusion is contrary to this Court’s precedents, which hold that
the Second Amendment right to keep and bear arms is not a privilege
of United States citizenship. See Cruikshank , 92 U. S., at
548–549, 551–553. I must, therefore, consider whether stare decisis requires retention of those
precedents. As mentioned at the outset, my inquiry is limited to
the right at issue here. Thus, I do not endeavor to decide in this
case whether, or to what extent, the Privileges or Immunities
Clause applies any other rights enumerated in the Constitution
against the States.[ Footnote
20 ] Nor do I suggest that the stare decisis considerations surrounding the application of the right to keep and
bear arms against the States would be the same as those surrounding
another right protected by the Privileges or Immunities Clause. I
consider stare decisis only as it applies to the question
presented here. A This
inquiry begins with the Slaughter-House Cases . There, this
Court upheld a Louisiana statute granting a monopoly on livestock
butchering in and around the city of New Orleans to a newly
incorporated company. 16 Wall. 36. Butchers excluded by the
monopoly sued, claiming that the statute violated the Privileges or
Immunities Clause because it interfered with their right to pursue
and “exercise their trade.” Id. , at 60. This Court
rejected the butchers’ claim, holding that their asserted right was
not a privilege or immunity of American citizenship, but one
governed by the States alone. The Court held that the Privileges or
Immunities Clause protected only rights of federal citizenship—those “which owe their existence to the Federal
government, its National character, its Constitution, or its laws,” id. , at 79—and did not protect any of the rights
of state citizenship, id. , at 74. In other words, the
Court defined the two sets of rights as mutually
exclusive. After
separating these two sets of rights, the Court defined the rights
of state citizenship as “embrac[ing] nearly every civil right for
the establishment and protection of which organized government is
instituted”—that is, all those rights listed in Corfield .
16 Wall., at 76 (referring to “those rights” that “Judge
Washington” described). That left very few rights of federal
citizenship for the Privileges or Immunities Clause to protect. The
Court suggested a handful of possibilities, such as the “right of
free access to [federal] seaports,” protection of the Federal
Government while traveling “on the high seas,” and even two rights
listed in the Constitution. Id. , at 79 (noting “[t]he
right to peaceably assemble” and “the privilege of the writ of habeas corpus ”); see supra , at 4. But its
decision to interpret the rights of state and federal citizenship
as mutually exclusive led the Court in future cases to conclude
that constitutionally enumerated rights were excluded from the
Privileges or Immunities Clause’s scope. See Cruikshank , supra . I reject that
understanding. There was no reason to interpret the Privileges or
Immunities Clause as putting the Court to the extreme choice of
interpreting the “privileges and immunities” of federal citizenship
to mean either all those rights listed in Corfield , or
almost no rights at all. 16 Wall., at 76. The record is scant that
the public understood the Clause to make the Federal Government “a
perpetual censor upon all legislation of the States” as the Slaughter-House majority feared. Id. , at 78. For
one thing, Corfield listed the “elective franchise” as one
of the privileges and immunities of “citizens of the several
states,” 6 F. Cas., at 552, yet Congress and the States still found
it necessary to adopt the Fifteenth Amendment—which protects “[t]he
right of citizens of the United States to vote”—two years after the
Fourteenth Amendment’s passage. If the Privileges or Immunities
Clause were understood to protect every conceivable civil right
from state abridgment, the Fifteenth Amendment would have been
redundant. The better view, in
light of the States and Federal Government’s shared history of
recognizing certain inalienable rights in their citizens, is that
the privileges and immunities of state and federal citizenship
overlap. This is not to say that the privileges and immunities of
state and federal citizenship are the same. At the time of the
Fourteenth Amendment’s ratification, States performed many more
functions than the Federal Government, and it is unlikely that,
simply by referring to “privileges or immunities,” the Framers of
§1 meant to transfer every right mentioned in Corfield to
congressional oversight. As discussed, “privileges” and
“immunities” were understood only as synonyms for “rights.” See supra , at 9–11. It was their attachment to a particular
group that gave them content, and the text and history recounted
here indicate that the rights of United States citizens were not
perfectly identical to the rights of citizens “in the several
States.” Justice Swayne, one of the dissenters in Slaughter-House , made the point clear: “The citizen of a State
has the same fundamental rights as a citizen of the United
States, and also certain others , local in their character,
arising from his relation to the State, and in addition, those
which belong to the citizen of the United States, he being in that
relation also. There may thus be a double citizenship, each having
some rights peculiar to itself. It is only over those which belong
to the citizen of the United States that the category here in
question throws the shield of its protection.” 16 Wall., at 126
(emphasis added). Because the privileges
and immunities of American citizenship include rights enumerated in
the Constitution, they overlap to at least some extent with the
privileges and immunities traditionally recognized in citizens in
the several States. A separate question
is whether the privileges and immunities of American citizenship
include any rights besides those enumerated in the Constitution.
The four dissenting Justices in Slaughter-House would have
held that the Privileges or Immunities Clause protected the
unenumerated right that the butchers in that case asserted. See id. , at 83 (Field, J., dissenting); id. , at 111
(Bradley, J., dissenting); id. , at 124 (Swayne, J.,
dissenting). Because this case does not involve an unenumerated
right, it is not necessary to resolve the question whether the
Clause protects such rights, or whether the Court’s judgment in Slaughter-House was correct. Still, it is argued
that the mere possibility that the Privileges or Immunities Clause
may enforce unenumerated rights against the States creates
“ ‘special hazards’ ” that should prevent this Court from
returning to the original meaning of the Clause.[ Footnote 21 ] Post , at 3 (Stevens,
J., dissenting). Ironically, the same objection applies to the
Court’s substantive due process jurisprudence, which illustrates
the risks of granting judges broad discretion to recognize
individual constitutional rights in the absence of textual or
historical guideposts. But I see no reason to assume that such
hazards apply to the Privileges or Immunities Clause. The mere fact
that the Clause does not expressly list the rights it protects does
not render it incapable of principled judicial application. The
Constitution contains many provisions that require an examination
of more than just constitutional text to determine whether a
particular act is within Congress’ power or is otherwise
prohibited. See, e.g. , Art. I, §8, cl. 18 (Necessary
and Proper Clause); Amdt. 8 (Cruel and Unusual Punishments Clause).
When the inquiry focuses on what the ratifying era understood the
Privileges or Immunities Clause to mean, interpreting it should be
no more “hazardous” than interpreting these other constitutional
provisions by using the same approach. To be sure, interpreting the
Privileges or Immunities Clause may produce hard questions. But
they will have the advantage of being questions the Constitution
asks us to answer. I believe those questions are more worthy of
this Court’s attention—and far more likely to yield discernable
answers—than the substantive due process questions the Court has
for years created on its own, with neither textual nor historical
support. Finding these
impediments to returning to the original meaning overstated, I
reject Slaughter-House insofar as it precludes any overlap
between the privileges and immunities of state and federal
citizenship. I next proceed to the stare decisis considerations surrounding the precedent that expressly controls
the question presented here. B Three
years after Slaughter-House , the Court in Cruikshank squarely held that the right to keep and bear
arms was not a privilege of American citizenship, thereby
overturning the convictions of militia members responsible for the
brutal Colfax Massacre. See supra , at 4–5. Cruikshank is not a precedent entitled to any respect. The
flaws in its interpretation of the Privileges or Immunities Clause
are made evident by the preceding evidence of its original meaning,
and I would reject the holding on that basis alone. But, the
consequences of Cruikshank warrant mention as
well. Cruikshank ’s holding that blacks
could look only to state governments for protection of their right
to keep and bear arms enabled private forces, often with the
assistance of local governments, to subjugate the newly freed
slaves and their descendants through a wave of private violence
designed to drive blacks from the voting booth and force them into
peonage, an effective return to slavery. Without federal
enforcement of the inalienable right to keep and bear arms, these
militias and mobs were tragically successful in waging a campaign
of terror against the very people the Fourteenth Amendment had just
made citizens. Take, for example,
the Hamburg Massacre of 1876. There, a white citizen militia sought
out and murdered a troop of black militiamen for no other reason
than that they had dared to conduct a celebratory Fourth of July
parade through their mostly black town. The white militia
commander, “Pitchfork” Ben Tillman, later described this massacre
with pride: “[T]he leading white men of Edgefield” had decided “to
seize the first opportunity that the negroes might offer them to
provoke a riot and teach the negroes a lesson by having the whites
demonstrate their superiority by killing as many of them as was
justifiable.” S. Kantrowitz, Ben Tillman & the Reconstruction
of White Supremacy 67 (2000) (ellipsis, brackets, and internal
quotation marks omitted). None of the perpetrators of the Hamburg
murders was ever brought to justice.[ Footnote 22 ] Organized terrorism
like that perpetuated by Tillman and his cohorts proliferated in
the absence of federal enforcement of constitutional rights.
Militias such as the Ku Klux Klan, the Knights of the White
Camellia, the White Brotherhood, the Pale Faces, and the ’76
Association spread terror among blacks and white Republicans by
breaking up Republican meetings, threatening political leaders, and
whipping black militiamen. Era of Reconstruction, 199–200; Curtis
156. These groups raped, murdered, lynched, and robbed as a means
of intimidating, and instilling pervasive fear in, those whom they
despised. A. Trelease, White Terror: The Ku Klux Klan Conspiracy
and Southern Reconstruction 28–46 (1995). Although Congress
enacted legislation to suppress these activities,[ Footnote 23 ] Klan tactics remained a
constant presence in the lives of Southern blacks for decades.
Between 1882 and 1968, there were at least 3,446 reported lynchings
of blacks in the South. Cottrol 351–352. They were tortured and
killed for a wide array of alleged crimes, without even the
slightest hint of due process. Emmit Till, for example, was killed
in 1955 for allegedly whistling at a white woman. S. Whitfield, A
Death in the Delta: The Story of Emmett Till 15–31 (1988). The
fates of other targets of mob violence were equally depraved. See, e.g. , Lynched Negro and Wife Were First Mutilated,
Vicksburg (Miss.) Evening Post, Feb. 8, 1904, reprinted in R.
Ginzburg, 100 Years of Lynchings 63 (1988); Negro Shot Dead for
Kissing His White Girlfriend, Chi. Defender, Feb. 31, 1915, in id. , at 95 (reporting incident in Florida); La. Negro Is
Burned Alive Screaming “I Didn’t Do It,” Cleveland Gazette, Dec.
13, 1914, in id. , at 93 (reporting incident in
Louisiana). The use of firearms
for self-defense was often the only way black citizens could
protect themselves from mob violence. As Eli Cooper, one target of
such violence, is said to have explained, “ ‘[t]he Negro has
been run over for fifty years, but it must stop now, and pistols
and shotguns are the only weapons to stop a mob.’ ” Church
Burnings Follow Negro Agitator’s Lynching, Chicago Defender, Sept.
6, 1919, in id. , at 124. Sometimes, as in Cooper’s case,
self-defense did not succeed. He was dragged from his home by a mob
and killed as his wife looked on. Ibid. But at other
times, the use of firearms allowed targets of mob violence to
survive. One man recalled the night during his childhood when his
father stood armed at a jail until morning to ward off lynchers.
See Cottrol, 354. The experience left him with a sense, “not ‘of
powerlessness, but of the “possibilities of
salvation” ’ ” that came from standing up to
intimidation. Ibid. In my view, the
record makes plain that the Framers of the Privileges or Immunities
Clause and the ratifying-era public understood—just as the Framers
of the Second Amendment did—that the right to keep and bear arms
was essential to the preservation of liberty. The record makes
equally plain that they deemed this right necessary to include in
the minimum baseline of federal rights that the Privileges or
Immunities Clause established in the wake of the War over slavery.
There is nothing about Cruikshank ’s contrary holding that
warrants its retention. * * * I
agree with the Court that the Second Amendment is fully applicable
to the States. I do so because the right to keep and bear arms is
guaranteed by the Fourteenth Amendment as a privilege of American
citizenship. Footnote
1 In the two decades
after United States v. Cruikshank , 92 U. S. 542 (1876), was decided, this
Court twice reaffirmed its holding that the Privileges or
Immunities Clause does not apply the Second Amendment to the
States. Presser v. Illinois , 116 U. S. 252 , 266–267
(1886); Miller v. Texas , 153 U. S. 535 (1894). Footnote
2 See also 2 C.
Richardson, A New Dictionary of the English Language 1512 (1839)
(defining “privilege” as “an appropriate or peculiar law or rule or
right; a peculiar immunity, liberty, or franchise”); 1 id. , at 1056 (defining “immunity” as “[f]reedom or
exemption, (from duties,) liberty, privilege”); The Philadelphia
School Dictionary; or Expositor of the English Language 152 (3d ed.
1812) (defining “privilege” as a “peculiar advantage”); id. , at 105 (defining “immunity” as “privilege,
exemption”); Royal Standard English Dictionary 411 (1788) (defining
“privilege” as “public right; peculiar
advantage”). Footnote
3 See also, e.g. , Charter of Va. (1606), reprinted in 7 The Federal
and State Constitutions, Colonial Charters, and Other Organic Laws
3783, 3788 (F. Thorpe ed. 1909) (hereinafter Thorpe) (“Declar[ing]”
that “all and every the Persons being our Subjects, . . . shall
Have and enjoy all Liberties, Franchises, and Immunities . . .
as if they had been abiding and born, within this our Realm of England ” (emphasis in original)); Charter of New England
(1620), in 3 id., at 1827, 1839 (“[A]ll and every the
Persons, beinge our Subjects, . . . shall have and enjoy all
Liberties, and ffranchizes, and Immunities of free Denizens and
naturall subjects … as if they had been abidinge and born within
this our Kingdome of England”); Charter of Mass. Bay (1629), in id. at 1846, 1856–1857 (guaranteeing that “all and every
the Subjects of Us, … shall have and enjoy all liberties and
Immunities of free and naturall Subjects … as yf they and everie of
them were borne within the Realme of England”); Grant of the
Province of Me. (1639), in id., at 1625, 1635
(guaranteeing “Liberties Francheses and Immunityes of or belonging
to any the naturall borne subjects of this our Kingdome of
England”); Charter of Carolina (1663), in 5 id., at 2743,
2747 (guaranteeing to all subjects “all liberties franchises and
priviledges of this our kingdom of England”); Charter of R. I.
and Providence Plantations (1663), in 6 id., at 3211, 3220
(“[A]ll and every the subjects of us . . . shall have and enjoye
all libertyes and immunityes of ffree and naturall subjects within
any the dominions of us, our heires, or successours, . . . as if
they, and every of them, were borne within the realme of England”);
Charter of Ga. (1732), in 2 id., at 765, 773 (“[A]ll and
every the persons which shall happen to be born within the said
province … shall have and enjoy all liberties, franchises and
immunities of free denizens and natural born subjects, within any
of our dominions, to all intents and purposes, as if abiding and
born within this our kingdom of Great-Britain”). Footnote
4 See also, e.g., A. Howard, The Road from Runnymede: Magna Carta and
Constitutionalism in America 174 (1968) (quoting 1774 Georgia
resolution declaring that the colony’s inhabitants were entitled to
“ ‘the same rights, privileges, and immunities with their
fellow-subjects in Great Britain ’ ” (emphasis in
original)); The Virginia Resolves, The Resolutions as Printed in
the Journal of the House of Burgesses, reprinted in Prologue to
Revolution: Sources and Documents on the Stamp Act Crisis,
1764–1766, at 46, 48 (“[T]he Colonists aforesaid are declared
entitled to all Liberties, Privileges, and Immunities of Denizens
and natural Subjects, to all Intents and Purposes, as if they had
been abiding and born within the Realm of England ”
(emphasis in original)). Footnote
5 See also Va.
Declaration of Rights (1776), reprinted in 1 Schwartz 234–236; Pa.
Declaration of Rights (1776), in id ., at 263–275; Del.
Declaration of Rights (1776), in id ., at 276–278; Md.
Declaration of Rights (1776), in id ., at 280–285;
N. C. Declaration of Rights (1776), in id .,
286–288. Footnote
6 Justice
Washington’s complete list was as follows: “Protection by the government; the
enjoyment of life and liberty, with the right to acquire and
possess property of every kind, and to pursue and obtain happiness
and safety; subject nevertheless to such restraints as the
government may justly prescribe for the general good of the whole.
The right of a citizen of one state to pass through, or to reside
in any other state, for purposes of trade, agriculture,
professional pursuits, or otherwise; to claim the benefit of the
writ of habeas corpus; to institute and maintain actions of any
kind in the courts of the state; to take, hold and dispose of
property, either real or personal; and an exemption from higher
taxes or impositions than are paid by the other citizens of the
state; may be mentioned as some of the particular privileges and
immunities of citizens, which are clearly embraced by the general
description of privileges deemed to be fundamental: to which may be
added, the elective franchise, as regulated and established by the
laws or constitution of the state in which it is to be exercised.”
6 Fed. Cas., at 551–552. Footnote
7 See also Treaty
Between the United States of America and the Ottawa Indians of
Blanchard’s Fork and Roche De Boeuf, June 24, 1862, 12 Stat. 1237
(“The Ottawa Indians of the United Bands of Blanchard’s Fork and of
Roche de Boeuf, having become sufficiently advanced in
civilization, and being desirous of becoming citizens of the United
States . . . [after five years from the ratification of this
treaty] shall be deemed and declared to be citizens of the United
States, to all intents and purposes, and shall be entitled to all
the rights, privileges, and immunities of such citizens ”
(emphasis added)); Treaty Between the United States of America and
Different Tribes of Sioux Indians, Art. VI, April 29, 1868, 15
Stat. 637 (“[A]ny Indian or Indians receiving a patent for land
under the foregoing provisions, shall thereby and from thenceforth
become and be a citizen of the United States, and be entitled to
all the privileges and immunities of such citizens ”
(emphasis added)). Footnote
8 Subsequent
treaties contained similar guarantees that the inhabitants of the
newly acquired territories would enjoy the freedom to exercise
certain constitutional rights. See Treaty of Peace, Friendship,
Limits, and Settlement with the Republic of Mexico, Art. IX, Feb.
2, 1848, 9 Stat. 930, T. S. No. 207 (cession of Texas) (declaring
that inhabitants of the Territory were entitled “to the enjoyment
of all the rights of citizens of the United States, according to
the principles of the constitution; and in the mean time shall be
maintained and protected in the free enjoyment of their liberty and
property, and secured in the free exercise of their religion
without restriction”); Treaty concerning the Cession of the Russian
Possessions in North America by his Majesty the Emperor of all the
Russians to the United States of America, Art. III, Mar. 30, 1867,
15 Stat. 542, T. S. No. 301 (June 20, 1867) (cession of Alaska)
(“The inhabitants of the ceded territory, … if they should prefer
to remain in the ceded territory, they, with the exception of
uncivilized native tribes, shall be admitted to the enjoyment of
all the rights, advantages, and immunities of citizens of the
United States, and shall be maintained and protected in the free
enjoyment of their liberty, property, and
religion”). Footnote
9 See, e.g. , Speech of Mr. Joseph Hemphill (Pa.) on the Missouri
Question in the House of the Representatives 16 (1820), as
published in pamphlet form and reprinted in 22 Moore Pamphlets,
p. 16 (“If the right to hold slaves is a federal right and attached
merely to citizenship of the United States, [then slavery] could
maintain itself against state authority, and on this principle the
owner might take his slaves into any state he pleased, in defiance
of the state laws, but this would be contrary to the
constitution”); see also Lash, The Origins of the Privileges or
Immunities Clause, Part I: “Privileges and Immunities” as an
Antebellum Term of Art, 98 Geo. L. J. 1241, 1288–1290 (2010)
(collecting other examples). Footnote 10 One Country, One
Constitution, and One People: Speech of Hon. John A. Bingham, of
Ohio, In the House of Representatives, February 28, 1866, In
Support of the Proposed Amendment to Enforce the Bill of Rights
(Cong. Globe). The pamphlet was published by the official reporter
of congressional debates, and was distributed presumably pursuant
to the congressional franking privilege. See B. Wildenthal,
Nationalizing the Bill of Rights: Revisiting the Original
Understanding of the Fourteenth Amendment in 1866–67, 68 Ohio St.
L. J. 1509, 1558, n. 167 (2007) (hereinafter
Wildenthal). Footnote 11 The full text of
Bingham’s first draft of §1 provided as follows: “The Congress shall have power to
make all laws which shall be necessary and proper to secure to the
citizens of each State all privileges and immunities of citizens in
the several States, and to all persons in the several States equal
protection in the rights of life, liberty, and property.” 39th
Cong. Globe 1088. Footnote 12 In a separate
front-page article on the same day, the paper expounded upon Hale’s
arguments in even further detail, while omitting Bingham’s chief
rebuttals. N. Y. Times, Feb. 28, 1866, p. 1. The unbalanced
nature of The New York Times’ coverage is unsurprising. As scholars
have noted, “[m]ost papers” during the time of Reconstruction “had
a frank partisan slant . . . and the Times was no
exception.” Wildenthal 1559. In 1866, the paper “was still
defending” President Johnson’s resistance to Republican reform
measures, as exemplified by the fact that it “supported Johnson’s
veto of the Civil Rights Act of 1866.” Ibid. Footnote 13 Other papers
that covered Howard’s speech include the following: Baltimore
Gazette, May 24, 1866, p. 4; Boston Daily Journal, May 24, 1866, p.
4; Boston Daily Advertiser, May 24, 1866, p. 1; Daily National
Intelligencer, May 24, 1866, p. 3. Springfield Daily Republican,
May 24, 1866, p. 3; Charleston Daily Courier, May 28, 1866, p. 4;
Charleston Daily Courier, May 29, 1866, p. 1; Chicago Tribune, May
29, 1866, p. 2; Philadelphia Inquirer, May 24, 1866, p.
8. Footnote 14 See J.
Pomeroy, An Introduction to the Constitutional Law of the United
States 155–156 (E. Bennett ed. 1886) (describing §1, which the
country was then still considering, as a “needed” “remedy” for
Barron ex rel. Tiernan v. Mayor of
Baltimore, 7 Pet. 243 (1833), which held that the Bill of
Rights was not enforceable against the States); T. Farrar, Manual
of the Constitution of the United States of America 58–59, 145–146,
395–397 (1867) (reprint 1993); id. , at 546 (3d ed. 1872)
(describing the Fourteenth Amendment as having “swept away” the
“decisions of many courts” that “the popular rights guaranteed by
the Constitution are secured only against [the federal]
government”). Footnote 15 The municipal
respondents and Justice Breyer’s dissent raise a most unusual
argument that §1 prohibits discriminatory laws affecting only the
right to keep and bear arms, but offers substantive protection to
other rights enumerated in the Constitution, such as the freedom of
speech. See post , at 24. Others, however, have made the
more comprehensive—and internally consistent—argument that §1 bars
discrimination alone and does not afford protection to any
substantive rights. See, e.g. , R. Berger, Government By
Judiciary: The Transformation of the Fourteenth Amendment (1997). I
address the coverage of the Privileges or Immunities Clause only as
it applies to the Second Amendment right presented here, but I do
so with the understanding that my conclusion may have implications
for the broader argument. Footnote 16 See, e.g. , Raleigh & Gaston R. Co. v. Davis , 19 N. C. 451, 458–462 (1837) (right to just
compensation for government taking of property); Rohan v. Swain , 59 Mass. 281, 285 (1850) (right to be secure from
unreasonable government searches and seizures); State v. Buzzard , 4 Ark. 18, 28 (1842) (right to keep and bear
arms); State v. Jumel , 13 La. Ann. 399, 400
(1858) (same); Cockrum v. State , 24 Tex. 394,
401–404 (1859) (same). Footnote 17 See, e.g. , People v. Goodwin , 18 Johns. Cas.
187, 201 (N. Y. Sup. Ct. 1820); Rhinehart v. Schulyer , 7 Ill. 473, 522 (1845). Footnote 18 See, e.g. , Black Code, ch. 33, §19, 1806 La. Acts pp. 160,
162 (prohibiting slaves from using firearms unless they were
authorized by their master to hunt within the boundaries of his
plantation); Act of Dec. 18, 1819, 1819 S. C. Acts
pp. 29, 31 (same); An Act Concerning Slaves, §6, 1840 Tex.
Laws pp. 42–43 (making it unlawful for “any slave to own
firearms of any description”). Footnote 19 I conclude that
the right to keep and bear arms applies to the States through the
Privileges or Immunities Clause, which recognizes the rights of
United States “citizens.” The plurality concludes that the right
applies to the States through the Due Process Clause, which covers
all “person[s].” Because this case does not involve a claim brought
by a noncitizen, I express no view on the difference, if any,
between my conclusion and the plurality’s with respect to the
extent to which the States may regulate firearm possession by
noncitizens. Footnote 20 I note, however,
that I see no reason to assume that the constitutionally enumerated
rights protected by the Privileges or Immunities Clause should
consist of all the rights recognized in the Bill of Rights and no
others. Constitutional provisions outside the Bill of Rights
protect individual rights, see, e.g., Art. I, §9,
cl. 2 (granting the “Privilege of the Writ of Habeas Corpus”),
and there is no obvious evidence that the Framers of the Privileges
or Immunities Clause meant to exclude them. In addition, certain
Bill of Rights provisions prevent federal interference in state
affairs and are not readily construed as protecting rights that
belong to individuals. The Ninth and Tenth Amendments are obvious
examples, as is the First Amendment’s Establishment Clause, which
“does not purport to protect individual rights.” Elk Grove
Unified School Dist. v. Newdow , 542 U. S. 1 , 50 (2004)
(Thomas, J., concurring in judgment); see Amar
179–180. Footnote 21 To the extent
Justice Stevens is concerned that reliance on the Privileges or
Immunities Clause may invite judges to “write their personal views
of appropriate public policy into the Constitution,” post ,
at 3 (internal quotation marks omitted), his celebration of the
alternative—the “flexibility,” “transcend[ence],” and “dynamism” of
substantive due process—speaks for itself, post , at 14–15,
20. Footnote 22 Tillman went on to
a long career as South Carolina’s Governor and, later, United
States Senator. Tillman’s contributions to campaign finance law
have been discussed in our recent cases on that subject. See Citizens United v. Federal Election Comm’n , 558
U. S. ___, ___ (2010) (Stevens, J., dissenting) (slip. op., at 2,
42, 56, 87) (discussing at length the Tillman Act of 1907, 34 Stat.
864). His contributions to the culture of terrorism that grew in
the wake of Cruikshank had an even more dramatic and
tragic effect. Footnote 23 In an effort to
enforce the Fourteenth Amendment and halt this violence, Congress
enacted a series of civil rights statutes, including the Force
Acts, see Act of May 31, 1870, 16 Stat. 140; Act of Feb. 28, 1871,
16 Stat. 433, and the Ku Klux Klan Act, see Act of Apr. 20, 1871,
17 Stat. 13. SCALIA, J., CONCURRING MCDONALD V. CHICAGO 561 U. S. ____ (2010) SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES NO. 08-1521 OTIS McDONALD, et al., PETITIONERS v. CITY OF CHICAGO, ILLINOIS, et al.
on writ of certiorari to the united states court of
appeals for the seventh circuit
[June 28, 2010]
Justice Scalia, concurring.
I join the Court’s opinion.
Despite my misgivings about Substantive Due Process as an original
matter, I have acquiesced in the Court’s incorporation of certain
guarantees in the Bill of Rights “because it is both long
established and narrowly limited.” Albright v. Oliver , 510
U. S. 266 , 275 (1994) (Scalia, J., concurring). This case does
not require me to reconsider that view, since straightforward
application of settled doctrine suffices to decide it.
I write separately only to respond to some
aspects of Justice Stevens’ dissent. Not that aspect which
disagrees with the majority’s application of our precedents to this
case, which is fully covered by the Court’s opinion. But much of
what Justice Stevens writes is a broad condemnation of the theory
of interpretation which underlies the Court’s opinion, a theory
that makes the traditions of our people paramount. He proposes a
different theory, which he claims is more “cautiou[s]” and
respectful of proper limits on the judicial role. Post , at
57. It is that claim I wish to address.
I
A
After stressing the substantive
dimension of what he has renamed the “liberty clause,” post , at 4–7,[ Footnote
1 ] Justice Stevens proceeds to urge readoption of the theory of
incorporation articulated in Palko v. Connecticut , 302 U. S. 319 , 325
(1937), see post , at 14–20. But in fact he does not favor
application of that theory at all. For whether Palko requires only that “a fair and enlightened system of justice would
be impossible without” the right sought to be incorporated, 302 U.
S., at 325, or requires in addition that the right be rooted in the
“traditions and conscience of our people,” ibid. (internal
quotation marks omitted), many of the rights Justice Stevens thinks
are incorporated could not pass muster under either test: abortion, post , at 7 (citing Planned Parenthood of Southeastern
Pa. v. Casey , 505 U. S. 833 , 847 (1992)); homosexual
sodomy, post , at 16 (citing Lawrence v. Texas , 539 U. S. 558 , 572 (2003)); the right
to have excluded from criminal trials evidence obtained in
violation of the Fourth Amendment, post , at 18 (citing Mapp v. Ohio , 367 U. S. 643 , 650,
655–657 (1961)); and the right to teach one’s children foreign
languages, post , at 7 (citing Meyer v. Nebraska , 262 U. S. 390 , 399–403
(1923)), among others.
That Justice Stevens is not
applying any version of Palko is clear from comparing, on
the one hand, the rights he believes are covered, with, on
the other hand, his conclusion that the right to keep and bear arms
is not covered. Rights that pass his test include not just
those “relating to marriage, procreation, contraception, family
relationships, and child rearing and education,” but also rights
against “[g]overnment action that shocks the conscience,
pointlessly infringes settled expectations, trespasses into
sensitive private realms or life choices without adequate
justification, [or] perpetrates gross injustice.” Post , at
23 (internal quotation marks omitted). Not all such rights
are in, however, since only “ some fundamental aspects of
personhood, dignity, and the like” are protected, post , at
24 (emphasis added). Exactly what is covered is not clear. But
whatever else is in, he knows that the right to keep and
bear arms is out, despite its being as “deeply rooted in this
Nation’s history and tradition,” Washington v. Glucksberg , 521 U. S. 702 , 721
(1997) (internal quotation marks omitted), as a right can be, see District of Columbia v. Heller , 554 U. S. ___,
___–___, ___–___, ___–___ (2008) (slip op., at 20–21, 26–30,
41–44). I can find no other explanation for such certitude except
that Justice Stevens, despite his forswearing of “personal and
private notions,” post , at 21 (internal quotation marks
omitted), deeply believes it should be out.
The subjective nature of Justice Stevens’
standard is also apparent from his claim that it is the courts’
prerogative—indeed their duty —to update the Due Process
Clause so that it encompasses new freedoms the Framers were too
narrow-minded to imagine, post , at 19–20, and n. 21.
Courts, he proclaims, must “do justice to [the Clause’s] urgent
call and its open texture” by exercising the “interpretive
discretion the latter embodies.” Post , at 21. (Why the people are not up to the task of deciding what new rights
to protect, even though it is they who are authorized to
make changes, see U. S. Const., Art. V, is never
explained.[ Footnote 2 ]) And it
would be “judicial abdication” for a judge to “tur[n] his back” on his task of determining what the Fourteenth Amendment
covers by “outsourc[ing]” the job to “historical sentiment,” post , at 20—that is, by being guided by what the American
people throughout our history have thought. It is only we judges,
exercising our “own reasoned judgment,” post , at 15, who
can be entrusted with deciding the Due Process Clause’s scope—which
rights serve the Amendment’s “central values,” post , at
23—which basically means picking the rights we want to protect and
discarding those we do not.
B
Justice Stevens resists this
description, insisting that his approach provides plenty of
“guideposts” and “constraints” to keep courts from “injecting
excessive subjectivity” into the process.[ Footnote 3 ] Post , at 21. Plenty indeed—and
that alone is a problem. The ability of omnidirectional guideposts
to constrain is inversely proportional to their number. But even
individually, each lodestar or limitation he lists either is
incapable of restraining judicial whimsy or cannot be squared with
the precedents he seeks to preserve.
He begins with a brief nod to
history, post , at 21, but as he has just made clear, he
thinks historical inquiry unavailing, post , at 19–20.
Moreover, trusting the meaning of the Due Process Clause to what
has historically been protected is circular, see post , at
19, since that would mean no new rights could get in.
Justice Stevens moves on to the “most basic”
constraint on subjectivity his theory offers: that he would
“esche[w] attempts to provide any all-purpose, top-down, totalizing
theory of ‘liberty.’ ” Post , at 22. The notion that
the absence of a coherent theory of the Due Process Clause will
somehow curtail judicial caprice is at war with reason.
Indeterminacy means opportunity for courts to impose whatever rule
they like; it is the problem, not the solution. The idea that
interpretive pluralism would reduce courts’ ability to
impose their will on the ignorant masses is not merely naïve, but
absurd. If there are no right answers, there are no wrong answers
either.
Justice Stevens also argues that requiring
courts to show “respect for the democratic process” should serve as
a constraint. Post , at 23. That is true, but Justice
Stevens would have them show respect in an extraordinary manner. In
his view, if a right “is already being given careful consideration
in, and subjected to ongoing calibration by, the States, judicial
enforcement may not be appropriate.” Ibid. In other words,
a right, such as the right to keep and bear arms, that has long
been recognized but on which the States are considering
restrictions, apparently deserves less protection, while a
privilege the political branches (instruments of the democratic
process) have withheld entirely and continue to withhold, deserves more . That topsy-turvy approach conveniently accomplishes
the objective of ensuring that the rights this Court held protected
in Casey , Lawrence , and other such cases fit the
theory—but at the cost of insulting rather than respecting the
democratic process.
The next constraint Justice Stevens suggests
is harder to evaluate. He describes as “an important tool for
guiding judicial discretion” “sensitivity to the interaction
between the intrinsic aspects of liberty and the practical
realities of contemporary society.” Post , at 24. I cannot
say whether that sensitivity will really guide judges because I
have no idea what it is. Is it some sixth sense instilled in judges
when they ascend to the bench? Or does it mean judges are more
constrained when they agonize about the cosmic conflict between
liberty and its potentially harmful consequences? Attempting to
give the concept more precision, Justice Stevens explains that
“sensitivity is an aspect of a deeper principle: the need to
approach our work with humility and caution.” Ibid. Both
traits are undeniably admirable, though what relation they bear to
sensitivity is a mystery. But it makes no difference, for the first
case Justice Stevens cites in support, see ibid. , Casey , 505 U. S., at 849, dispels any illusion that he has
a meaningful form of judicial modesty in mind.
Justice Stevens offers no examples to
illustrate the next constraint: stare decisis , post , at 25. But his view of it is surely not very
confining, since he holds out as a “canonical” exemplar of the
proper approach, see post , at 16, 54, Lawrence ,
which overruled a case decided a mere 17 years earlier, Bowers v. Hardwick , 478 U. S. 186 (1986),
see 539 U. S., at 578 (it “was not correct when it was decided, and
it is not correct today”). Moreover, Justice Stevens would apply
that constraint unevenly: He apparently approves those Warren Court
cases that adopted jot-for-jot incorporation of procedural
protections for criminal defendants, post , at 11, but
would abandon those Warren Court rulings that undercut his approach
to substantive rights, on the basis that we have “cut back” on
cases from that era before, post , at 12.
Justice Stevens also relies on the requirement
of a “careful description of the asserted fundamental liberty
interest” to limit judicial discretion. Post , at 25
(internal quotation marks omitted). I certainly agree with that
requirement, see Reno v. Flores , 507 U. S. 292 , 302
(1993), though some cases Justice Stevens approves have not applied
it seriously, see, e.g. , Lawrence , supra , at 562 (“The instant case involves liberty of the
person both in its spatial and in its more transcendent
dimensions”). But if the “careful description” requirement is used
in the manner we have hitherto employed, then the enterprise of
determining the Due Process Clause’s “conceptual core,” post , at 23, is a waste of time. In the cases he cites we
sought a careful, specific description of the right at issue in
order to determine whether that right, thus narrowly defined,
was fundamental . See, e.g. , Glucksberg , 521
U. S., at 722–728; Reno , supra , at 302–306; Collins v. Harker Heights , 503 U. S. 115 , 125–129
(1992); Cruzan v. Director, Mo. Dept. of Health , 497 U. S. 261 ,
269–279 (1990); see also Vacco v. Quill , 521 U. S. 793 , 801–808
(1997). The threshold step of defining the asserted right with
precision is entirely unnecessary, however, if (as Justice Stevens
maintains) the “conceptual core” of the “liberty clause,” post , at 23, includes a number of capacious, hazily
defined categories. There is no need to define the right with much
precision in order to conclude that it pertains to the plaintiff’s
“ability independently to define [his] identity,” his “right to
make certain unusually important decisions that will affect his
own, or his family’s, destiny,” or some aspect of his
“[s]elf-determination, bodily integrity, freedom of conscience,
intimate relationships, political equality, dignity [or] respect.” Ibid. (internal quotation marks omitted). Justice
Stevens must therefore have in mind some other use for the
careful-description requirement—perhaps just as a means of ensuring
that courts “procee[d] slowly and incrementally,” post , at
25. But that could be achieved just as well by having them draft
their opinions in longhand.[ Footnote 4 ]
II
If Justice Stevens’ account of
the constraints of his approach did not demonstrate that they do
not exist, his application of that approach to the case before us
leaves no doubt. He offers several reasons for concluding that the
Second Amendment right to keep and bear arms is not fundamental
enough to be applied against the States.[ Footnote 5 ] None is persuasive, but more pertinent to
my purpose, each is either intrinsically indeterminate, would
preclude incorporation of rights we have already held incorporated,
or both. His approach therefore does nothing to stop a judge from
arriving at any conclusion he sets out to reach.
Justice Stevens begins with the
odd assertion that “firearms have a fundamentally ambivalent
relationship to liberty,” since sometimes they are used to cause
(or sometimes accidentally produce) injury to others. Post , at 35. The source of the rule that only
nonambivalent liberties deserve Due Process protection is never
explained—proof that judges applying Justice Stevens’ approach can
add new elements to the test as they see fit. The criterion,
moreover, is inherently manipulable. Surely Justice Stevens does
not mean that the Clause covers only rights that have zero harmful effect on anyone . Otherwise even the First
Amendment is out. Maybe what he means is that the right to keep and
bear arms imposes too great a risk to others’ physical
well-being. But as the plurality explains, ante , at 35–36,
other rights we have already held incorporated pose similarly
substantial risks to public safety. In all events, Justice Stevens
supplies neither a standard for how severe the impairment on
others’ liberty must be for a right to be disqualified, nor (of
course) any method of measuring the severity.
Justice Stevens next suggests that the Second
Amendment right is not fundamental because it is “different in
kind” from other rights we have recognized. Post , at 37.
In one respect, of course, the right to keep and bear arms is different from some other rights we have held the
Clause protects and he would recognize: It is deeply grounded in
our nation’s history and tradition. But Justice Stevens has a
different distinction in mind: Even though he does “not doubt for a
moment that many Americans . . . see [firearms] as critical to
their way of life as well as to their security,” he pronounces that
owning a handgun is not “critical to leading a life of autonomy,
dignity, or political equality.”[ Footnote 6 ] Post , at 37–38. Who says? Deciding
what is essential to an enlightened, liberty-filled life is an
inherently political, moral judgment—the antithesis of an objective
approach that reaches conclusions by applying neutral rules to
verifiable evidence.[ Footnote
7 ]
No determination of what rights the
Constitution of the United States covers would be complete, of
course, without a survey of what other countries do. Post , at 40–41. When it comes to guns, Justice Stevens
explains, our Nation is already an outlier among “advanced
democracies”; not even our “oldest allies” protect as robust a
right as we do, and we should not widen the gap. Ibid. Never mind that he explains neither which countries qualify as
“advanced democracies” nor why others are irrelevant. For there is
an even clearer indication that this criterion lets judges pick
which rights States must respect and those they can ignore: As the
plurality shows, ante , at 34–35, and nn. 28–29, this
follow-the-foreign-crowd requirement would foreclose rights that we
have held (and Justice Stevens accepts) are incorporated, but that
other “advanced” nations do not recognize—from the exclusionary
rule to the Establishment Clause. A judge applying Justice Stevens’
approach must either throw all of those rights overboard or, as
cases Justice Stevens approves have done in considering
unenumerated rights, simply ignore foreign law when it undermines
the desired conclusion, see, e.g. , Casey, 505 U. S. 833 (making no mention of
foreign law).
Justice Stevens also argues that since the
right to keep and bear arms was codified for the purpose
of “prevent[ing] elimination of the militia,” it should be viewed
as “ ‘a federalism provision’ ” logically incapable of
incorporation. Post , at 41–42 (quoting Elk Grove
Unified School Dist. v. Newdow , 542 U. S. 1 , 45 (2004)
(Thomas, J., concurring in judgment); some internal quotation marks
omitted). This criterion, too, evidently applies only when judges
want it to. The opinion Justice Stevens quotes for the “federalism
provision” principle, Justice Thomas’s concurrence in Newdow , argued that incorporation of the Establishment
Clause “makes little sense” because that Clause was originally
understood as a limit on congressional interference with state
establishments of religion. Id. , at 49–51. Justice
Stevens, of course, has no problem with applying the Establishment
Clause to the States. See, e.g. , id. , at 8,
n. 4 (opinion for the Court by Stevens, J.) (acknowledging
that the Establishment Clause “appl[ies] to the States by
incorporation into the Fourteenth Amendment”). While he insists that Clause is not a “federalism provision,” post , at 42, n. 40, he does not explain why it is
not, but the right to keep and bear arms is (even though
only the latter refers to a “right of the people”). The
“federalism” argument prevents the incorporation of only certain rights.
Justice Stevens next argues that even if the
right to keep and bear arms is “deeply rooted in some important
senses,” the roots of States’ efforts to regulate guns run just as
deep. Post , at 44 (internal quotation marks omitted). But
this too is true of other rights we have held incorporated. No
fundamental right—not even the First Amendment—is absolute. The
traditional restrictions go to show the scope of the right, not its
lack of fundamental character. At least that is what they show
(Justice Stevens would agree) for other rights. Once
again, principles are applied selectively.
Justice Stevens’ final reason for rejecting
incorporation of the Second Amendment reveals, more clearly than
any of the others, the game that is afoot. Assuming that there is a
“plausible constitutional basis” for holding that the right to keep
and bear arms is incorporated, he asserts that we ought not to do
so for prudential reasons . Post , at 47. Even if we had the authority to withhold
rights that are within the Constitution’s command (and we assuredly
do not), two of the reasons Justice Stevens gives for abstention
show just how much power he would hand to judges. The States’
“right to experiment” with solutions to the problem of gun
violence, he says, is at its apex here because “the best solution
is far from clear.” Post , at 47–48 (internal quotation
marks omitted). That is true of most serious social
problems—whether, for example, “the best solution” for rampant
crime is to admit confessions unless they are affirmatively shown
to have been coerced, but see Miranda v. Arizona , 384 U. S. 436 ,
444–445 (1966), or to permit jurors to impose the death penalty
without a requirement that they be free to consider “any relevant
mitigating factor,” see Eddings v. Oklahoma , 455 U. S. 104 ,
112 (1982), which in turn leads to the conclusion that defense
counsel has provided inadequate defense if he has not conducted a
“reasonable investigation” into potentially mitigating factors,
see, e.g. , Wiggins v. Smith , 539 U. S. 510 , 534
(2003), inquiry into which question tends to destroy any prospect
of prompt justice, see, e.g. , Wong v. Belmontes , 558 U. S. ___ (2009) (per curiam) (reversing grant of habeas relief for sentencing on a crime
committed in 1981). The obviousness of the optimal answer is in the
eye of the beholder. The implication of Justice Stevens’ call for
abstention is that if We The Court conclude that They The People’s
answers to a problem are silly, we are free to “interven[e],” post , at 47, but if we too are uncertain of the right
answer, or merely think the States may be on to something, we can
loosen the leash.
A second reason Justice Stevens says we should
abstain is that the States have shown they are “capable” of
protecting the right at issue, and if anything have protected it
too much. Post , at 49. That reflects an assumption that
judges can distinguish between a proper democratic
decision to leave things alone (which we should honor), and a case
of democratic market failure (which we should step in to correct).
I would not—and no judge should—presume to have that sort of
omniscience, which seems to me far more “arrogant,” post ,
at 41, than confining courts’ focus to our own national
heritage.
III
Justice Stevens’ response to this
concurrence, post , at 51–56, makes the usual rejoinder of
“living Constitution” advocates to the criticism that it empowers
judges to eliminate or expand what the people have prescribed: The
traditional, historically focused method, he says, reposes
discretion in judges as well.[ Footnote 8 ] Historical analysis can be difficult; it
sometimes requires resolving threshold questions, and making
nuanced judgments about which evidence to consult and how to
interpret it.
I will stipulate to that.[ Footnote 9 ] But the question to be decided is not
whether the historically focused method is a perfect means of restraining aristocratic judicial
Constitution-writing; but whether it is the best means
available in an imperfect world. Or indeed, even more narrowly
than that: whether it is demonstrably much better than what Justice
Stevens proposes. I think it beyond all serious dispute that it is
much less subjective, and intrudes much less upon the democratic
process. It is less subjective because it depends upon a body of
evidence susceptible of reasoned analysis rather than a variety of
vague ethico-political First Principles whose combined conclusion
can be found to point in any direction the judges favor. In the
most controversial matters brought before this Court—for example,
the constitutionality of prohibiting abortion, assisted suicide, or
homosexual sodomy, or the constitutionality of the death
penalty— any historical methodology, under any plausible standard of proof, would lead to the same
conclusion.[ Footnote 10 ]
Moreover, the methodological differences that divide historians,
and the varying interpretive assumptions they bring to their work, post , at 52–54, are nothing compared to the differences
among the American people (though perhaps not among graduates of
prestigious law schools) with regard to the moral judgments Justice
Stevens would have courts pronounce. And whether or not special
expertise is needed to answer historical questions, judges most
certainly have no “comparative … advantage,” post , at 24 (internal quotation marks omitted), in
resolving moral disputes. What is more, his approach would not
eliminate, but multiply, the hard questions courts must confront,
since he would not replace history with moral philosophy,
but would have courts consider both .
And the Court’s approach intrudes less upon
the democratic process because the rights it acknowledges are those
established by a constitutional history formed by democratic
decisions; and the rights it fails to acknowledge are left to be
democratically adopted or rejected by the people, with the
assurance that their decision is not subject to judicial revision.
Justice Stevens’ approach, on the other hand, deprives the people
of that power, since whatever the Constitution and laws may say,
the list of protected rights will be whatever courts wish it to be.
After all, he notes, the people have been wrong before, post , at 55, and courts may conclude they are wrong in the
future. Justice Stevens abhors a system in which “majorities or
powerful interest groups always get their way,” post , at
56, but replaces it with a system in which unelected and
life-tenured judges always get their way. That such usurpation is
effected unabashedly, see post , at 53—with “the judge’s
cards … laid on the table,” ibid. —makes it even
worse. In a vibrant democracy, usurpation should have to be
accomplished in the dark. It is Justice Stevens’ approach, not the
Court’s, that puts democracy in peril. Footnote 1 I do not entirely understand Justice Stevens’
renaming of the Due Process Clause. What we call it, of course,
does not change what the Clause says, but shorthand should not
obscure what it says. Accepting for argument’s sake the shift in
emphasis—from avoiding certain deprivations without that “process”
which is “due,” to avoiding the deprivations themselves—the Clause
applies not just to deprivations of “liberty,” but also to
deprivations of “life” and even “property.” Footnote 2 Justice Stevens insists that he would not
make courts the sole interpreters of the “liberty clause”;
he graciously invites “[a]ll Americans” to ponder what the Clause
means to them today. Post , at 20, n. 22. The problem is
that in his approach the people’s ponderings do not matter, since
whatever the people decide, courts have the last word. Footnote 3 Justice Breyer is not worried by that
prospect. His interpretive approach applied to incorporation of the
Second Amendment includes consideration of such factors as “the
extent to which incorporation will further other, perhaps more
basic, constitutional aims; and the extent to which incorporation
will advance or hinder the Constitution’s structural aims”; whether
recognizing a particular right will “further the Constitution’s
effort to ensure that the government treats each individual with
equal respect” or will “help maintain the democratic form of
government”; whether it is “inconsistent … with the Constitution’s
efforts to create governmental institutions well suited to the
carrying out of its constitutional promises”; whether it fits with
“the Framers’ basic reason for believing the Court ought to have
the power of judicial review”; courts’ comparative advantage in
answering empirical questions that may be involved in applying the
right; and whether there is a “strong offsetting justification” for
removing a decision from the democratic process. Post , at
7, 11–17 (dissenting opinion). Footnote 4 After defending the careful-description
criterion, Justice Stevens quickly retreats and cautions courts not
to apply it too stringently. Post , at 26. Describing a
right too specifically risks robbing it of its “universal
valence and a moral force it might otherwise have,” ibid. ,
and “loads the dice against its recognition,” post , at 26,
n. 25 (internal quotation marks omitted). That must be
avoided, since it endangers rights Justice Stevens does like. See ibid. (discussing Lawrence v. Texas , 539 U. S. 558 (2003)). To make sure those rights get in, we must leave leeway in our
description, so that a right that has not itself been recognized as
fundamental can ride the coattails of one that has been. Footnote 5 Justice Stevens claims that I mischaracterize
his argument by referring to the Second Amendment right to keep and
bear arms, instead of “the interest in keeping a firearm of one’s
choosing in the home,” the right he says petitioners assert. Post , at 38, n. 36. But it is precisely the “Second
Amendment right to keep and bear arms” that petitioners argue is
incorporated by the Due Process Clause. See, e.g. , Pet.
for Cert. i. Under Justice Stevens’ own approach, that should end
the matter. See post , at 26 (“[W]e must pay close
attention to the precise liberty interest the litigants have asked
us to vindicate”). In any event, the demise of watered-down
incorporation, see ante , at 17–19, means that we no longer
subdivide Bill of Rights guarantees into their theoretical
components, only some of which apply to the States. The First
Amendment freedom of speech is incorporated—not the freedom to
speak on Fridays, or to speak about philosophy. Footnote 6 Justice Stevens goes a step farther
still, suggesting that the right to keep and bear arms is not
protected by the “liberty clause” because it is not really a
liberty at all, but a “property right.” Post , at 38. Never
mind that the right to bear arms sounds mighty like a liberty; and
never mind that the “liberty clause” is really a Due Process Clause
which explicitly protects “property,” see United States v. Carlton , 512
U. S. 26 , 41–42 (1994) (Scalia, J., concurring in judgment).
Justice Stevens’ theory cannot explain why the Takings Clause,
which unquestionably protects property, has been incorporated, see Chicago, B. & Q. R. Co. v. Chicago , 166 U. S. 226 , 241
(1897), in a decision he appears to accept, post , at 14,
n. 14. Footnote 7 As Justice Stevens notes, see post ,
at 51–52, I accept as a matter of stare decisis the
requirement that to be fundamental for purposes of the Due Process
Clause, a right must be “implicit in the concept of ordered
liberty,” Lawrence , supra , at 593, n. 3
(Scalia, J., dissenting) (internal quotation marks omitted). But
that inquiry provides infinitely less scope for judicial invention
when conducted under the Court’s approach, since the field of
candidates is immensely narrowed by the prior requirement
that a right be rooted in this country’s traditions. Justice
Stevens, on the other hand, is free to scan the universe for rights
that he thinks “implicit in the concept, etc.” The point Justice
Stevens makes here is merely one example of his demand that an
historical approach to the Constitution prove itself, not merely
much better than his in restraining judicial invention, but utterly
perfect in doing so. See Part III, infra. Footnote 8 Justice Stevens also asserts that
his approach is “more faithful to this Nation’s constitutional
history” and to “the values and commitments of the American people,
as they stand today,” post , at 54. But what he asserts to
be the proof of this is that his approach aligns (no surprise) with
those cases he approves (and dubs “canonical,” ibid. ).
Cases he disfavors are discarded as “hardly bind[ing]” “excesses,” post , at 12, or less “enduring,” post , at 17,
n. 16. Not proven. Moreover, whatever relevance Justice
Stevens ascribes to current “values and commitments of the American
people” (and that is unclear, see post , at 48–49, n. 47),
it is hard to see how it shows fidelity to them that he disapproves
a different subset of old cases than the Court does. Footnote 9 That is not to say that every historical
question on which there is room for debate is indeterminate, or
that every question on which historians disagree is equally
balanced. Cf. post , at 52–53. For example, the historical
analysis of the principal dissent in Heller is as valid as
the Court’s only in a two-dimensional world that conflates length
and depth. Footnote 10 By the way, Justice Stevens greatly magnifies the
difficulty of an historical approach by suggesting that it was my burden in Lawrence to show the “ancient roots
of proscriptions against sodomy,” post , at 53 (internal
quotation marks omitted). Au contraire , it was his burden (in the opinion he joined) to show the ancient
roots of the right of sodomy. STEVENS, J., DISSENTING MCDONALD V. CHICAGO 561 U. S. ____ (2010) SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES NO. 08-1521 OTIS McDONALD, et al., PETITIONERS v. CITY OF CHICAGO, ILLINOIS, et al.
on writ of certiorari to the united states court of
appeals for the seventh circuit
[June 28, 2010]
Justice Stevens, dissenting.
In District of Columbia v. Heller , 554 U. S. ___, ___ (2008) (slip op., at 1), the
Court answered the question whether a federal enclave’s
“prohibition on the possession of usable handguns in the home
violates the Second Amendment to the Constitution.” The question we
should be answering in this case is whether the Constitution
“guarantees individuals a fundamental right,” enforceable against
the States, “to possess a functional, personal firearm, including a
handgun, within the home.” Complaint ¶34, App. 23. That is a
different—and more difficult—inquiry than asking if the Fourteenth
Amendment “incorporates” the Second Amendment. The so-called
incorporation question was squarely and, in my view, correctly
resolved in the late 19th century.[ Footnote 1 ]
Before the District Court, petitioners focused
their pleadings on the special considerations raised by domestic
possession, which they identified as the core of their asserted
right. In support of their claim that the city of Chicago’s handgun
ban violates the Constitution, they now rely primarily on the
Privileges or Immunities Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment. See
Brief for Petitioners 9–65. They rely secondarily on the Due
Process Clause of that Amendment. See id., at 66–72.
Neither submission requires the Court to express an opinion on
whether the Fourteenth Amendment places any limit on the power of
States to regulate possession, use, or carriage of firearms outside
the home.
I agree with the plurality’s refusal to accept
petitioners’ primary submission. Ante , at 10. Their briefs
marshal an impressive amount of historical evidence for their
argument that the Court interpreted the Privileges or Immunities
Clause too narrowly in the Slaughter-House Cases , 16 Wall.
36 (1873). But the original meaning of the Clause is not as clear
as they suggest[ Footnote 2 ]—and
not nearly as clear as it would need to be to dislodge 137 years of
precedent. The burden is severe for those who seek radical change
in such an established body of constitutional doctrine.[ Footnote 3 ] Moreover, the suggestion
that invigorating the Privileges or Immunities Clause will reduce
judicial discretion, see Reply Brief for Petitioners 22, n. 8,
26; Tr. of Oral Arg. 64–65, strikes me as implausible, if not
exactly backwards. “For the very reason that it has so long
remained a clean slate, a revitalized Privileges or Immunities
Clause holds special hazards for judges who are mindful that their
proper task is not to write their personal views of appropriate
public policy into the Constitution.”[ Footnote 4 ]
I further agree with the plurality that there
are weighty arguments supporting petitioners’ second submission,
insofar as it concerns the possession of firearms for lawful
self-defense in the home. But these arguments are less compelling
than the plurality suggests; they are much less compelling when
applied outside the home; and their validity does not depend on the
Court’s holding in Heller . For that holding sheds no light
on the meaning of the Due Process Clause of the Fourteenth
Amendment. Our decisions construing that Clause to render various
procedural guarantees in the Bill of Rights enforceable against the
States likewise tell us little about the meaning of the word
“liberty” in the Clause or about the scope of its protection of
nonprocedural rights.
This is a substantive due process case.
I
Section 1 of the Fourteenth
Amendment decrees that no State shall “deprive any person of life,
liberty, or property, without due process of law.” The Court has
filled thousands of pages expounding that spare text. As I read the
vast corpus of substantive due process opinions, they confirm
several important principles that ought to guide our resolution of
this case. The principal opinion’s lengthy summary of our
“incorporation” doctrine, see ante , at 5–9, 11–19
(majority opinion), 10–11 (plurality opinion), and its implicit
(and untenable) effort to wall off that doctrine from the rest of
our substantive due process jurisprudence, invite a fresh survey of
this old terrain. Substantive Content The first, and most basic, principle
established by our cases is that the rights protected by the Due
Process Clause are not merely procedural in nature. At first
glance, this proposition might seem surprising, given that the
Clause refers to “process.” But substance and procedure are often
deeply entwined. Upon closer inspection, the text can be read to
“impos[e] nothing less than an obligation to give substantive
content to the words ‘liberty’ and ‘due process of law,’ ” Washington v. Glucksberg , 521 U. S. 702 , 764 (1997) (Souter, J.,
concurring in judgment), lest superficially fair procedures be
permitted to “destroy the enjoyment” of life, liberty, and
property, Poe v. Ullman , 367 U. S. 497 , 541
(1961) (Harlan, J., dissenting), and the Clause’s prepositional
modifier be permitted to swallow its primary command. Procedural
guarantees are hollow unless linked to substantive interests; and
no amount of process can legitimize some deprivations.
I have yet to see a persuasive argument that
the Framers of the Fourteenth Amendment thought otherwise. To the
contrary, the historical evidence suggests that, at least by the
time of the Civil War if not much earlier, the phrase “due process
of law” had acquired substantive content as a term of art within
the legal community.[ Footnote
5 ] This understanding is consonant with the venerable “notion
that governmental authority has implied limits which preserve
private autonomy,”[ Footnote 6 ]
a notion which predates the founding and which finds reinforcement
in the Constitution’s Ninth Amendment, see Griswold v. Connecticut , 381 U. S. 479 , 486–493 (1965)
(Goldberg, J., concurring).[ Footnote 7 ] The Due Process Clause cannot claim to be the
source of our basic freedoms—no legal document ever could, see Meachum v. Fano , 427 U. S. 215 , 230
(1976) (Stevens, J., dissenting)—but it stands as one of their
foundational guarantors in our law.
If text and history are inconclusive on this
point, our precedent leaves no doubt: It has been “settled” for
well over a century that the Due Process Clause “applies to matters
of substantive law as well as to matters of procedure.” Whitney v. California , 274 U. S. 357 , 373
(1927) (Brandeis, J., concurring). Time and again, we have
recognized that in the Fourteenth Amendment as well as the Fifth,
the “Due Process Clause guarantees more than fair process, and the
‘liberty’ it protects includes more than the absence of physical
restraint.” Glucksberg , 521 U. S., at 719. “The Clause
also includes a substantive component that ‘provides heightened
protection against government interference with certain fundamental
rights and liberty interests.’ ” Troxel v. Granville , 530 U. S. 57 , 65 (2000)
(opinion of O’Connor, J., joined by Rehnquist, C. J., and
Ginsburg and Breyer, JJ.) (quoting Glucksberg , 521 U. S.,
at 720). Some of our most enduring precedents, accepted today by
virtually everyone, were substantive due process decisions. See, e.g., Loving v. Virginia , 388 U. S. 1 , 12 (1967) (recognizing
due-process- as well as equal-protection-based right to marry
person of another race); Bolling v. Sharpe , 347 U. S. 497 ,
499–500 (1954) (outlawing racial segregation in District of
Columbia public schools); Pierce v. Society of
Sisters , 268 U. S. 510 , 534–535 (1925)
(vindicating right of parents to direct upbringing and education of
their children); Meyer v. Nebraska , 262 U. S. 390 , 399–403 (1923)
(striking down prohibition on teaching of foreign languages). Liberty The second principle woven through our cases
is that substantive due process is fundamentally a matter of
personal liberty. For it is the liberty clause of the Fourteenth
Amendment that grounds our most important holdings in this field.
It is the liberty clause that enacts the Constitution’s “promise”
that a measure of dignity and self-rule will be afforded to all
persons. Planned Parenthood of Southeastern Pa. v. Casey , 505 U. S. 833 , 847 (1992). It is the
liberty clause that reflects and renews “the origins of the
American heritage of freedom [and] the abiding interest in
individual liberty that makes certain state intrusions on the
citizen’s right to decide how he will live his own life
intolerable.” Fitzgerald v. Porter Memorial
Hospital , 523 F. 2d 716, 720 (CA7 1975) (Stevens, J.).
Our substantive due process cases have episodically invoked values
such as privacy and equality as well, values that in certain
contexts may intersect with or complement a subject’s liberty
interests in profound ways. But as I have observed on numerous
occasions, “most of the significant [20th-century] cases raising
Bill of Rights issues have, in the final analysis, actually
interpreted the word ‘liberty’ in the Fourteenth
Amendment.”[ Footnote 8 ]
It follows that the term “incorporation,” like
the term “unenumerated rights,” is something of a misnomer. Whether
an asserted substantive due process interest is explicitly named in
one of the first eight Amendments to the Constitution or is not
mentioned, the underlying inquiry is the same: We must ask whether
the interest is “comprised within the term liberty.” Whitney , 274 U. S., at 373 (Brandeis, J., concurring). As
the second Justice Harlan has shown, ever since the Court began
considering the applicability of the Bill of Rights to the States,
“the Court’s usual approach has been to ground the prohibitions
against state action squarely on due process, without intermediate
reliance on any of the first eight Amendments.” Malloy v. Hogan , 378 U.
S. 1 , 24 (1964) (dissenting opinion); see also Frankfurter,
Memorandum on “Incorporation” of the Bill of Rights into the Due
Process Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment, 78 Harv. L. Rev.
746, 747–750 (1965). In the pathmarking case of Gitlow v. New York , 268 U. S. 652 , 666
(1925), for example, both the majority and dissent evaluated
petitioner’s free speech claim not under the First Amendment but as
an aspect of “the fundamental personal rights and ‘liberties’
protected by the due process clause of the Fourteenth Amendment
from impairment by the States.”[ Footnote 9 ]
In his own classic opinion in Griswold , 381 U. S., at 500 (concurring in judgment),
Justice Harlan memorably distilled these precedents’ lesson: “While the relevant inquiry may be aided by resort to
one or more of the provisions of the Bill of Rights, it is not
dependent on them or any of their radiations. The Due Process
Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment stands … on its own
bottom.”[ Footnote 10 ]
Inclusion in the Bill of Rights is neither necessary nor sufficient
for an interest to be judicially enforceable under the Fourteenth
Amendment. This Court’s “ ‘selective incorporation’ ”
doctrine, ante , at 15, is not simply “related” to
substantive due process, ante , at 19; it is a subset
thereof. Federal/State Divergence The third precept to emerge from
our case law flows from the second: The rights protected against
state infringement by the Fourteenth Amendment’s Due Process Clause
need not be identical in shape or scope to the rights protected
against Federal Government infringement by the various provisions
of the Bill of Rights. As drafted, the Bill of Rights directly
constrained only the Federal Government. See Barron ex rel.
Tiernan v. Mayor of Baltimore , 7 Pet. 243 (1833).
Although the enactment of the Fourteenth Amendment profoundly
altered our legal order, it “did not unstitch the basic federalist
pattern woven into our constitutional fabric.” Williams v. Florida , 399 U.
S. 78 , 133 (1970) (Harlan, J., concurring in result). Nor, for
that matter, did it expressly alter the Bill of Rights. The
Constitution still envisions a system of divided sovereignty, still
“establishes a federal republic where local differences are to be
cherished as elements of liberty” in the vast run of cases, National Rifle Assn. of Am. Inc. v. Chicago , 567
F. 3d 856, 860 (CA7 2009) (Easterbrook, C. J.), still
allocates a general “police power … to the States and the States
alone,” United States v. Comstock , 560 U. S. ___,
___ (2010) (slip op., at 4) (Kennedy, J., concurring in judgment).
Elementary considerations of constitutional text and structure
suggest there may be legitimate reasons to hold state governments
to different standards than the Federal Government in certain
areas.[ Footnote
11 ] It is true, as the Court
emphasizes, ante , at 15–19, that we have made numerous
provisions of the Bill of Rights fully applicable to the States. It
is settled, for instance, that the Governor of Alabama has no more
power than the President of the United States to authorize
unreasonable searches and seizures. Ker v. California , 374 U. S. 23 (1963). But
we have never accepted a “total incorporation” theory of the
Fourteenth Amendment, whereby the Amendment is deemed to subsume
the provisions of the Bill of Rights en masse. See ante ,
at 15. And we have declined to apply several provisions to the
States in any measure. See, e.g., Minneapolis &
St. Louis R. Co. v. Bombolis , 241 U. S. 211 (1916)
(Seventh Amendment); Hurtado v. California , 110 U. S. 516 (1884) (Grand Jury Clause). We have, moreover, resisted a uniform
approach to the Sixth Amendment’s criminal jury guarantee,
demanding 12-member panels and unanimous verdicts in federal
trials, yet not in state trials. See Apodaca v. Oregon , 406
U. S. 404 (1972) (plurality opinion); Williams , 399 U.
S. 78 . In recent years, the Court has repeatedly declined to
grant certiorari to review that disparity.[ Footnote 12 ] While those denials have no
precedential significance, they confirm the proposition that the
“incorporation” of a provision of the Bill of Rights into the
Fourteenth Amendment does not, in itself, mean the provision must
have precisely the same meaning in both contexts. It is true, as well, that during
the 1960’s the Court decided a number of cases involving procedural
rights in which it treated the Due Process Clause as if it
transplanted language from the Bill of Rights into the Fourteenth
Amendment. See, e.g., Benton v. Maryland , 395 U. S. 784 ,
795 (1969) (Double Jeopardy Clause); Pointer v. Texas , 380
U. S. 400 , 406 (1965) (Confrontation Clause). “Jot-for-jot”
incorporation was the norm in this expansionary era. Yet at least
one subsequent opinion suggests that these precedents require
perfect state/federal congruence only on matters “ ‘at the
core’ ” of the relevant constitutional guarantee. Crist v. Bretz , 437 U. S. 28 , 37 (1978);
see also id., at 52–53 (Powell, J., dissenting). In my
judgment, this line of cases is best understood as having concluded
that, to ensure a criminal trial satisfies essential standards of
fairness, some procedures should be the same in state and federal
courts: The need for certainty and uniformity is more pressing, and
the margin for error slimmer, when criminal justice is at issue.
That principle has little relevance to the question whether a non procedural rule set forth in the Bill of Rights
qualifies as an aspect of the liberty protected by the Fourteenth
Amendment. Notwithstanding some overheated
dicta in Malloy , 378 U. S., at 10–11, it is therefore an
overstatement to say that the Court has “abandoned,” ante ,
at 16, 17 (majority opinion), 39 (plurality opinion), a “two-track
approach to incorporation,” ante , at 37 (plurality
opinion). The Court moved away from that approach in the area of
criminal procedure. But the Second Amendment differs in fundamental
respects from its neighboring provisions in the Bill of Rights, as
I shall explain in Part V, infra; and if some 1960’s
opinions purported to establish a general method of incorporation,
that hardly binds us in this case. The Court has not hesitated to
cut back on perceived Warren Court excesses in more areas than I
can count. I do not mean to deny that there
can be significant practical, as well as esthetic, benefits from
treating rights symmetrically with regard to the State and Federal
Governments. Jot-for-jot incorporation of a provision may entail
greater protection of the right at issue and therefore greater
freedom for those who hold it; jot-for-jot incorporation may also
yield greater clarity about the contours of the legal rule. See Johnson v. Louisiana , 406 U. S. 356 , 384–388
(1972) (Douglas, J., dissenting); Pointer , 380 U. S., at
413–414 (Goldberg, J., concurring). In a federalist system such as
ours, however, this approach can carry substantial costs. When a
federal court insists that state and local authorities follow its
dictates on a matter not critical to personal liberty or procedural
justice, the latter may be prevented from engaging in the kind of
beneficent “experimentation in things social and economic” that
ultimately redounds to the benefit of all Americans. New State
Ice Co. v. Liebmann , 285 U. S. 262 , 311
(1932) (Brandeis, J., dissenting). The costs of federal courts’
imposing a uniform national standard may be especially high when
the relevant regulatory interests vary significantly across
localities, and when the ruling implicates the States’ core police
powers. Furthermore, there is a real risk
that, by demanding the provisions of the Bill of Rights apply
identically to the States, federal courts will cause those
provisions to “be watered down in the needless pursuit of
uniformity.” Duncan v. Louisiana , 391 U. S. 145 , 182,
n. 21 (1968) (Harlan, J., dissenting). When one legal standard
must prevail across dozens of jurisdictions with disparate needs
and customs, courts will often settle on a relaxed standard. This
watering-down risk is particularly acute when we move beyond the
narrow realm of criminal procedure and into the relatively vast
domain of substantive rights. So long as the requirements of
fundamental fairness are always and everywhere respected, it is not
clear that greater liberty results from the jot-for-jot application
of a provision of the Bill of Rights to the States. Indeed, it is
far from clear that proponents of an individual right to keep and
bear arms ought to celebrate today’s decision.[ Footnote 13 ] II So far, I have
explained that substantive due process analysis generally requires
us to consider the term “liberty” in the Fourteenth Amendment, and
that this inquiry may be informed by but does not depend upon the
content of the Bill of Rights. How should a court go about the
analysis, then? Our precedents have established, not an exact
methodology, but rather a framework for decisionmaking. In this
respect, too, the Court’s narrative fails to capture the continuity
and flexibility in our doctrine. The basic inquiry was
described by Justice Cardozo more than 70 years ago. When
confronted with a substantive due process claim, we must ask
whether the allegedly unlawful practice violates values “implicit
in the concept of ordered liberty.” Palko v. Connecticut , 302 U. S. 319 , 325 (1937).[ Footnote 14 ] If the practice in
question lacks any “oppressive and arbitrary” character, if
judicial enforcement of the asserted right would not materially
contribute to “a fair and enlightened system of justice,” then the
claim is unsuitable for substantive due process protection. Id., at 327, 325. Implicit in Justice Cardozo’s test is a
recognition that the postulates of liberty have a universal
character. Liberty claims that are inseparable from the customs
that prevail in a certain region, the idiosyncratic expectations of
a certain group, or the personal preferences of their champions,
may be valid claims in some sense; but they are not of
constitutional stature. Whether conceptualized as a “rational
continuum” of legal precepts, Poe , 367 U. S., at 543
(Harlan, J., dissenting), or a seamless web of moral commitments,
the rights embraced by the liberty clause transcend the local and
the particular. Justice Cardozo’s test undeniably
requires judges to apply their own reasoned judgment, but that does
not mean it involves an exercise in abstract philosophy. In
addition to other constraints I will soon discuss, see Part III, infra , historical and empirical data of various kinds
ground the analysis. Textual commitments laid down elsewhere in the
Constitution, judicial precedents, English common law, legislative
and social facts, scientific and professional developments,
practices of other civilized societies,[ Footnote 15 ] and, above all else, the
“ ‘traditions and conscience of our people,’ ” Palko , 302 U. S., at 325 (quoting Snyder v. Massachusetts , 291 U. S. 97 , 105
(1934)), are critical variables. They can provide evidence about
which rights really are vital to ordered liberty, as well as a spur
to judicial action. The Court errs both in its
interpretation of Palko and in its suggestion that later
cases rendered Palko ’s methodology defunct. Echoing Duncan , the Court advises that Justice Cardozo’s test will
not be satisfied “ ‘if a civilized system could be imagined
that would not accord the particular protection.’ ” Ante , at 12 (quoting 391 U. S., at 149, n. 14). Palko does contain some language that could be read to set
an inordinate bar to substantive due process recognition, reserving
it for practices without which “neither liberty nor justice would
exist.” 302 U. S., at 326. But in view of Justice Cardozo’s broader
analysis, as well as the numerous cases that have upheld liberty
claims under the Palko standard, such readings are plainly
overreadings. We have never applied Palko in such a
draconian manner. Nor, as the Court intimates, see ante , at 16, did Duncan mark an irreparable break
from Palko , swapping out liberty for history. Duncan limited its discussion to “particular procedural
safeguard[s]” in the Bill of Rights relating to “criminal
processes,” 391 U. S., at 149, n. 14; it did not purport to
set a standard for other types of liberty interests. Even with
regard to procedural safeguards, Duncan did not jettison
the Palko test so much as refine it: The judge is still
tasked with evaluating whether a practice “is fundamental … to
ordered liberty,” within the context of the “Anglo-American”
system. Duncan , 391 U. S., at 149–150, n. 14. Several
of our most important recent decisions confirm the proposition that
substantive due process analysis—from which, once again,
“incorporation” analysis derives—must not be wholly backward
looking. See, e.g., Lawrence v. Texas , 539
U. S. 558 , 572 (2003) (“[H]istory and tradition are the
starting point but not in all cases the ending point of the
substantive due process inquiry” (internal quotation marks
omitted)); Michael H. v. Gerald D. , 491 U. S. 110 , 127–128, n. 6
(1989) (garnering only two votes for history-driven methodology
that “consult[s] the most specific tradition available”); see also post , at 6–7 (Breyer, J., dissenting) (explaining that
post- Duncan “incorporation” cases continued to rely on
more than history).[ Footnote
16 ] The Court’s flight from Palko leaves its analysis, careful and scholarly though it
is, much too narrow to provide a satisfying answer to this case.
The Court hinges its entire decision on one mode of intellectual
history, culling selected pronouncements and enactments from the
18th and 19th centuries to ascertain what Americans thought about
firearms. Relying on Duncan and Glucksberg , the
plurality suggests that only interests that have proved
“fundamental from an American perspective,” ante , at 37,
44, or “ ‘deeply rooted in this Nation’s history and
tradition,’ ” ante , at 19 (quoting Glucksberg , 521 U. S., at 721), to the Court’s
satisfaction, may qualify for incorporation into the Fourteenth
Amendment. To the extent the Court’s opinion could be read to imply
that the historical pedigree of a right is the exclusive or
dispositive determinant of its status under the Due Process Clause,
the opinion is seriously mistaken. A rigid historical test is
inappropriate in this case, most basically, because our substantive
due process doctrine has never evaluated substantive rights in
purely, or even predominantly, historical terms. When the Court
applied many of the procedural guarantees in the Bill of
Rights to the States in the 1960’s, it often asked whether the
guarantee in question was “fundamental in the context of the
criminal processes maintained by the American States.”[ Footnote 17 ] Duncan , 391 U.
S., at 150, n. 14. That inquiry could extend back through
time, but it was focused not so much on historical conceptions of
the guarantee as on its functional significance within the States’
regimes. This contextualized approach made sense, as the choice to
employ any given trial-type procedure means little in the abstract.
It is only by inquiring into how that procedure intermeshes with
other procedures and practices in a criminal justice system that
its relationship to “liberty” and “due process” can be
determined. Yet when the Court has used the
Due Process Clause to recognize rights distinct from the trial
context—rights relating to the primary conduct of free
individuals—Justice Cardozo’s test has been our guide. The right to
free speech, for instance, has been safeguarded from state
infringement not because the States have always honored it, but
because it is “essential to free government” and “to the
maintenance of democratic institutions”—that is, because the right
to free speech is implicit in the concept of ordered liberty. Thornhill v. Alabama , 310 U. S. 88 , 95, 96 (1940); see also, e.g., Loving , 388 U. S., at 12 (discussing right to marry
person of another race); Mapp v. Ohio , 367 U. S. 643 , 650, 655–657 (1961)
(discussing right to be free from arbitrary intrusion by police); Schneider v. State (Town of Irvington) , 308 U. S. 147 , 161
(1939) (discussing right to distribute printed matter).[ Footnote 18 ] While the verbal
formula has varied, the Court has largely been consistent in its
liberty-based approach to substantive interests outside of the
adjudicatory system. As the question before us indisputably
concerns such an interest, the answer cannot be found in a granular
inspection of state constitutions or congressional
debates. More fundamentally, a rigid
historical methodology is unfaithful to the Constitution’s command.
For if it were really the case that the Fourteenth Amendment’s
guarantee of liberty embraces only those rights “so rooted in our
history, tradition, and practice as to require special protection,” Glucksberg , 521 U. S., at 721, n. 17, then the
guarantee would serve little function, save to ratify those rights
that state actors have already been according the most
extensive protection.[ Footnote
19 ] Cf. Duncan , 391 U. S., at 183 (Harlan, J.,
dissenting) (critiquing “circular[ity]” of historicized test for
incorporation). That approach is unfaithful to the expansive
principle Americans laid down when they ratified the Fourteenth
Amendment and to the level of generality they chose when they
crafted its language; it promises an objectivity it cannot deliver
and masks the value judgments that pervade any analysis of what
customs, defined in what manner, are sufficiently
“ ‘rooted’ ”; it countenances the most revolting
injustices in the name of continuity,[ Footnote 20 ] for we must never forget that not only
slavery but also the subjugation of women and other rank forms of
discrimination are part of our history; and it effaces this Court’s
distinctive role in saying what the law is, leaving the development
and safekeeping of liberty to majoritarian political processes. It
is judicial abdication in the guise of judicial modesty. No, the liberty safeguarded by the
Fourteenth Amendment is not merely preservative in nature but
rather is a “dynamic concept.” Stevens, The Bill of Rights: A
Century of Progress, 59 U. Chi. L. Rev. 13, 38 (1972). Its
dynamism provides a central means through which the Framers enabled
the Constitution to “endure for ages to come,” McCulloch v. Maryland , 4 Wheat. 316, 415 (1819), a central example
of how they “wisely spoke in general language and left to
succeeding generations the task of applying that language to the
unceasingly changing environment in which they would live,”
Rehnquist, The Notion of a Living Constitution, 54 Tex.
L. Rev. 693, 694 (1976). “The task of giving concrete meaning
to the term ‘liberty,’ ” I have elsewhere explained at some
length, “was a part of the work assigned to future generations.”
Stevens, The Third Branch of Liberty, 41 U. Miami L. Rev. 277,
291 (1986).[ Footnote 21 ] The
judge who would outsource the interpretation of “liberty” to
historical sentiment has turned his back on a task the Constitution
assigned to him and drained the document of its intended
vitality.[ Footnote
22 ] III At this point a
difficult question arises. In considering such a majestic term as
“liberty” and applying it to present circumstances, how are we to
do justice to its urgent call and its open texture—and to the grant
of interpretive discretion the latter embodies—without injecting
excessive subjectivity or unduly restricting the States’ “broad
latitude in experimenting with possible solutions to problems of
vital local concern,” Whalen v. Roe , 429 U. S. 589 , 597
(1977)? One part of the answer, already discussed, is that we must
ground the analysis in historical experience and reasoned judgment,
and never on “merely personal and private notions.” Rochin v. California , 342 U. S. 165 , 170
(1952). Our precedents place a number of additional constraints on
the decisional process. Although “guideposts for responsible
decisionmaking in this unchartered area are scarce and open-ended,” Collins v. Harker Heights , 503 U. S. 115 , 125
(1992), significant guideposts do exist.[ Footnote 23 ] The most basic is
that we have eschewed attempts to provide any all-purpose,
top-down, totalizing theory of “liberty.”[ Footnote 24 ] That project is bound to end in failure
or worse. The Framers did not express a clear understanding of the
term to guide us, and the now-repudiated Lochner line of
cases attests to the dangers of judicial overconfidence in using
substantive due process to advance a broad theory of the right or
the good. See, e.g., Lochner v. New
York , 198 U. S.
45 (1905). In its most durable precedents, the Court “has not
attempted to define with exactness the liberty … guaranteed” by the
Fourteenth Amendment. Meyer , 262 U. S., at 399; see also, e.g., Bolling , 347 U. S. at 499. By its very
nature, the meaning of liberty cannot be “reduced to any formula;
its content cannot be determined by reference to any code.” Poe , 367 U. S., at 542 (Harlan, J.,
dissenting). Yet while “the ‘liberty’ specially
protected by the Fourteenth Amendment” is “perhaps not capable of
being fully clarified,” Glucksberg , 521 U. S., at 722, it
is capable of being refined and delimited. We have insisted that
only certain types of especially significant personal interests may
qualify for especially heightened protection. Ever since “the
deviant economic due process cases [were] repudiated,” id., at 761 (Souter, J., concurring in judgment), our
doctrine has steered away from “laws that touch economic problems,
business affairs, or social conditions,” Griswold , 381 U.
S., at 482, and has instead centered on “matters relating to
marriage, procreation, contraception, family relationships, and
child rearing and education,” Paul v. Davis , 424 U. S. 693 ,
713 (1976). These categories are not exclusive. Government action
that shocks the conscience, pointlessly infringes settled
expectations, trespasses into sensitive private realms or life
choices without adequate justification, perpetrates gross
injustice, or simply lacks a rational basis will always be
vulnerable to judicial invalidation. Nor does the fact that an
asserted right falls within one of these categories end the
inquiry. More fundamental rights may receive more robust judicial
protection, but the strength of the individual’s liberty interests
and the State’s regulatory interests must always be assessed and
compared. No right is absolute. Rather than seek a categorical
understanding of the liberty clause, our precedents have thus
elucidated a conceptual core. The clause safeguards, most
basically, “the ability independently to define one’s identity,” Roberts v. United States Jaycees , 468 U. S. 609 , 619
(1984), “the individual’s right to make certain unusually important
decisions that will affect his own, or his family’s, destiny,” Fitzgerald , 523 F. 2d, at 719, and the right to be
respected as a human being. Self-determination, bodily integrity,
freedom of conscience, intimate relationships, political equality,
dignity and respect—these are the central values we have found
implicit in the concept of ordered liberty. Another key constraint on
substantive due process analysis is respect for the democratic
process. If a particular liberty interest is already being given
careful consideration in, and subjected to ongoing calibration by,
the States, judicial enforcement may not be appropriate. When the
Court declined to establish a general right to physician-assisted
suicide, for example, it did so in part because “the States [were]
currently engaged in serious, thoughtful examinations of
physician-assisted suicide and other similar issues,” rendering
judicial intervention both less necessary and potentially more
disruptive. Glucksberg , 521 U. S., at 719, 735.
Conversely, we have long appreciated that more “searching” judicial
review may be justified when the rights of “discrete and insular
minorities”—groups that may face systematic barriers in the
political system—are at stake. United States v. Carolene Products Co. , 304 U. S. 144 , 153,
n. 4 (1938). Courts have a “comparative … advantage” over the
elected branches on a limited, but significant, range of legal
matters. Post , at 8. Recognizing a new liberty right is
a momentous step. It takes that right, to a considerable extent,
“outside the arena of public debate and legislative action.” Glucksberg , 521 U. S., at 720. Sometimes that momentous
step must be taken; some fundamental aspects of personhood,
dignity, and the like do not vary from State to State, and demand a
baseline level of protection. But sensitivity to the interaction
between the intrinsic aspects of liberty and the practical
realities of contemporary society provides an important tool for
guiding judicial discretion. This sensitivity is an aspect of a
deeper principle: the need to approach our work with humility and
caution. Because the relevant constitutional language is so
“spacious,” Duncan , 391 U. S., at 148, I have emphasized
that “[t]he doctrine of judicial self-restraint requires us to
exercise the utmost care whenever we are asked to break new ground
in this field.” Collins , 503 U. S., at 125. Many of my
colleagues and predecessors have stressed the same point, some with
great eloquence. See, e.g., Casey , 505 U. S., at
849; Moore v. East Cleveland , 431 U. S. 494 , 502–503 (1977)
(plurality opinion); Poe , 367 U. S., at 542–545 (Harlan,
J., dissenting); Adamson v. California , 332 U. S. 46 , 68 (1947) (Frankfurter,
J., concurring). Historical study may discipline as well as enrich
the analysis. But the inescapable reality is that no serious theory
of Section 1 of the Fourteenth Amendment yields clear answers in
every case, and “[n]o formula could serve as a substitute, in this
area, for judgment and restraint.” Poe , 367 U. S., at 542
(Harlan, J., dissenting). Several rules of the judicial
process help enforce such restraint. In the substantive due process
field as in others, the Court has applied both the doctrine of stare decisis —adhering to precedents, respecting reliance
interests, prizing stability and order in the law—and the
common-law method—taking cases and controversies as they present
themselves, proceeding slowly and incrementally, building on what
came before. This restrained methodology was evident even in the
heyday of “incorporation” during the 1960’s. Although it would have
been much easier for the Court simply to declare certain Amendments
in the Bill of Rights applicable to the States in toto ,
the Court took care to parse each Amendment into its component
guarantees, evaluating them one by one. This piecemeal approach
allowed the Court to scrutinize more closely the right at issue in
any given dispute, reducing both the risk and the cost of
error. Relatedly, rather than evaluate
liberty claims on an abstract plane, the Court has “required in
substantive-due-process cases a ‘careful description’ of the
asserted fundamental liberty interest.” Glucksberg , 521 U.
S., at 721 (quoting Reno v. Flores , 507 U. S. 292 , 302
(1993); Collins , 503 U. S., at 125; Cruzan v. Director, Mo. Dept. of Health , 497 U. S. 261 , 277–278
(1990)). And just as we have required such careful description from
the litigants, we have required of ourselves that we “focus on the
allegations in the complaint to determine how petitioner describes
the constitutional right at stake.” Collins , 503 U. S., at
125; see also Stevens, Judicial Restraint, 22 San Diego
L. Rev. 437, 446–448 (1985). This does not mean that we must
define the asserted right at the most specific level, thereby
sapping it of a universal valence and a moral force it might
otherwise have.[ Footnote 25 ]
It means, simply, that we must pay close attention to the precise
liberty interest the litigants have asked us to
vindicate. Our holdings should be similarly
tailored. Even if the most expansive formulation of a claim does
not qualify for substantive due process recognition, particular
components of the claim might. Just because there may not be a
categorical right to physician-assisted suicide, for example, does
not “ ‘foreclose the possibility that an individual plaintiff
seeking to hasten her death, or a doctor whose assistance was
sought, could prevail in a more particularized challenge.’ ” Glucksberg , 521 U. S., at 735, n. 24 (quoting id., at 750 (Stevens, J., concurring in judgments)); see
also Vacco v. Quill , 521 U. S. 793 , 809,
n. 13 (1997) (leaving open “ ‘the possibility that some
applications of the [New York prohibition on assisted suicide] may
impose an intolerable intrusion on the patient’s freedom’ ”).
Even if a State’s interest in regulating a certain matter must be
permitted, in the general course, to trump the individual’s
countervailing liberty interest, there may still be situations in
which the latter “is entitled to constitutional protection.” Glucksberg , 521 U. S., at 742 (Stevens, J., concurring in
judgments). As this discussion reflects, to
acknowledge that the task of construing the liberty clause requires
judgment is not to say that it is a license for unbridled judicial
lawmaking. To the contrary, only an honest reckoning with our
discretion allows for honest argumentation and meaningful
accountability. IV The question in this
case, then, is not whether the Second Amendment right to keep and
bear arms (whatever that right’s precise contours) applies to the
States because the Amendment has been incorporated into the
Fourteenth Amendment. It has not been. The question, rather, is
whether the particular right asserted by petitioners applies to the
States because of the Fourteenth Amendment itself, standing on its
own bottom. And to answer that question, we need to determine,
first, the nature of the right that has been asserted and, second,
whether that right is an aspect of Fourteenth Amendment “liberty.”
Even accepting the Court’s holding in Heller , it remains
entirely possible that the right to keep and bear arms identified
in that opinion is not judicially enforceable against the States,
or that only part of the right is so enforceable.[ Footnote 26 ] It is likewise possible for
the Court to find in this case that some part of the Heller right applies to the States, and then to find in
later cases that other parts of the right also apply, or apply on
different terms. As noted at the
outset, the liberty interest petitioners have asserted is the
“right to possess a functional, personal firearm, including a
handgun, within the home.” Complaint ¶34, App. 23. The city of
Chicago allows residents to keep functional firearms, so long as
they are registered, but it generally prohibits the possession of
handguns, sawed-off shotguns, machine guns, and short-barreled
rifles. See Chicago, Ill., Municipal Code §8–20–050
(2009).[ Footnote 27 ]
Petitioners’ complaint centered on their desire to keep a handgun
at their domicile—it references the “home” in nearly every
paragraph, see Complaint ¶¶3–4, 11–30, 32, 34, 37, 42, 44, 46, App.
17, 19–26—as did their supporting declarations, see, e.g., App. 34, 36, 40, 43, 49–52, 54–56. Petitioners now frame the
question that confronts us as “[w]hether the Second Amendment right
to keep and bear arms is incorporated as against the States by the
Fourteenth Amendment’s Privileges or Immunities or Due Process
Clauses.” Brief for Petitioners, p. i. But it is our duty “to
focus on the allegations in the complaint to determine how
petitioner describes the constitutional right at stake,” Collins , 503 U. S., at 125, and the gravamen of this
complaint is plainly an appeal to keep a handgun or other firearm
of one’s choosing in the home. Petitioners’ framing of their
complaint tracks the Court’s ruling in Heller . The
majority opinion contained some dicta suggesting the possibility of
a more expansive arms-bearing right, one that would travel with the
individual to an extent into public places, as “in case of
confrontation.” 554 U. S., at ___ (slip op., at 19). But the Heller plaintiff sought only dispensation to keep an
operable firearm in his home for lawful self-defense, see id., at ___ (slip op., at 2, and n. 2), and the
Court’s opinion was bookended by reminders that its holding was
limited to that one issue, id., at ___, ___ (slip op., at
1, 64); accord, ante , at 44 (plurality opinion). The
distinction between the liberty right these petitioners have
asserted and the Second Amendment right identified in Heller is therefore evanescent. Both are rooted to the
home. Moreover, even if both rights have the logical potential to
extend further, upon “future evaluation,” Heller , 554 U.
S., at ___ (slip op., at 63), it is incumbent upon us, as federal
judges contemplating a novel rule that would bind all 50 States, to
proceed cautiously and to decide only what must be
decided. Understood as a plea to keep their
preferred type of firearm in the home, petitioners’ argument has
real force.[ Footnote 28 ] The
decision to keep a loaded handgun in the house is often motivated
by the desire to protect life, liberty, and property. It is
comparable, in some ways, to decisions about the education and
upbringing of one’s children. For it is the kind of decision that
may have profound consequences for every member of the family, and
for the world beyond. In considering whether to keep a handgun,
heads of households must ask themselves whether the desired safety
benefits outweigh the risks of deliberate or accidental misuse that
may result in death or serious injury, not only to residents of the
home but to others as well. Millions of Americans have answered
this question in the affirmative, not infrequently because they
believe they have an inalienable right to do so—because they
consider it an aspect of “the supreme human dignity of being master
of one’s fate rather than a ward of the State,” Indiana v. Edwards , 554 U. S. 164 , 186
(2008) (Scalia, J., dissenting). Many such decisions have been
based, in part, on family traditions and deeply held beliefs that
are an aspect of individual autonomy the government may not
control.[ Footnote
29 ] Bolstering petitioners’ claim, our
law has long recognized that the home provides a kind of special
sanctuary in modern life. See, e.g., U. S. Const., Amdts.
3, 4; Lawrence , 539 U. S., at 562, 567; Payton v. New York , 445 U. S. 573 , 585–590
(1980); Stanley v. Georgia , 394 U. S. 557 , 565–568
(1969); Griswold , 381 U. S., at 484–485. Consequently, we
have long accorded special deference to the privacy of the home,
whether a humble cottage or a magnificent manse. This veneration of
the domestic harkens back to the common law. William Blackstone
recognized a “right of habitation,” 4 Commentaries *223, and opined
that “every man’s house is looked upon by the law to be his castle
of defence and asylum,” 3 id., at *288. Heller carried forward this legacy, observing that “the need for defense
of self, family, and property is most acute” in one’s abode, and
celebrating “the right of law-abiding, responsible citizens to use
arms in defense of hearth and home.” 554 U. S., at ___, ___ (slip
op., at 56, 63). While the individual’s interest in
firearm possession is thus heightened in the home, the State’s
corresponding interest in regulation is somewhat weaker. The State
generally has a lesser basis for regulating private as compared to
public acts, and firearms kept inside the home generally pose a
lesser threat to public welfare as compared to firearms taken
outside. The historical case for regulation is likewise stronger
outside the home, as many States have for many years imposed
stricter, and less controversial, restrictions on the carriage of
arms than on their domestic possession. See, e.g., id., at ___ (slip op., at 54) (noting that “the majority
of the 19th-century courts to consider the question held that
prohibitions on carrying concealed weapons were lawful under the
Second Amendment or state analogues”); English v. State , 35 Tex. 473, 478–479 (1871) (observing that
“almost, if not every one of the States of this Union have [a
prohibition on the carrying of deadly weapons] upon their statute
books,” and lambasting claims of a right to carry such weapons as
“little short of ridiculous”); Miller, Guns as Smut: Defending the
Home-Bound Second Amendment, 109 Colum. L. Rev. 1278,
1321–1336 (2009). It is significant, as well, that a
rule limiting the federal constitutional right to keep and bear
arms to the home would be less intrusive on state prerogatives and
easier to administer. Having unleashed in Heller a tsunami
of legal uncertainty, and thus litigation,[ Footnote 30 ] and now on the cusp of imposing a
national rule on the States in this area for the first time in
United States history, the Court could at least moderate the
confusion, upheaval, and burden on the States by adopting a rule
that is clearly and tightly bounded in scope. In their briefs to this Court,
several amici have sought to bolster petitioners’ claim
still further by invoking a right to individual
self-defense.[ Footnote 31 ]
As petitioners note, the Heller majority discussed this
subject extensively and remarked that “[t]he inherent right of
self-defense has been central to the Second Amendment right.” 554
U. S., at ___ (slip op., at 56). And it is true that if a State
were to try to deprive its residents of any reasonable means of
defending themselves from imminent physical threats, or to deny
persons any ability to assert self-defense in response to criminal
prosecution, that might pose a significant constitutional problem.
The argument that there is a substantive due process right to be
spared such untenable dilemmas is a serious one.[ Footnote 32 ] But that is not the case before
us. Petitioners have not asked that we establish a constitutional
right to individual self-defense; neither their pleadings in the
District Court nor their filings in this Court make any such
request. Nor do petitioners contend that the city of Chicago—which,
recall, allows its residents to keep most rifles and shotguns, and
to keep them loaded—has unduly burdened any such right. What
petitioners have asked is that we “incorporate” the Second
Amendment and thereby establish a constitutional entitlement,
enforceable against the States, to keep a handgun in the
home. Of course, owning a handgun may be
useful for practicing self-defense. But the right to take a certain
type of action is analytically distinct from the right to acquire
and utilize specific instrumentalities in furtherance of that
action. And while some might favor handguns, it is not clear that
they are a superior weapon for lawful self-defense, and nothing in
petitioners’ argument turns on that being the case. The notion that
a right of self-defense implies an auxiliary right to own
a certain type of firearm presupposes not only controversial
judgments about the strength and scope of the (posited)
self-defense right, but also controversial assumptions about the
likely effects of making that type of firearm more broadly
available. It is a very long way from the proposition that the
Fourteenth Amendment protects a basic individual right of
self-defense to the conclusion that a city may not ban
handguns.[ Footnote
33 ] In short, while the utility of
firearms, and handguns in particular, to the defense of hearth and
home is certainly relevant to an assessment of petitioners’
asserted right, there is no freestanding self-defense claim in this
case. The question we must decide is whether the interest in
keeping in the home a firearm of one’s choosing—a handgun, for
petitioners—is one that is “comprised within the term liberty” in
the Fourteenth Amendment. Whitney , 274 U. S., at 373
(Brandeis, J., concurring). V While I agree with
the Court that our substantive due process cases offer a principled
basis for holding that petitioners have a constitutional right to
possess a usable fiream in the home, I am ultimately persuaded that
a better reading of our case law supports the city of Chicago. I
would not foreclose the possibility that a particular
plaintiff—say, an elderly widow who lives in a dangerous
neighborhood and does not have the strength to operate a long
gun—may have a cognizable liberty interest in possessing a handgun.
But I cannot accept petitioners’ broader submission. A number of
factors, taken together, lead me to this conclusion. First, firearms have
a fundamentally ambivalent relationship to liberty. Just as they
can help homeowners defend their families and property from
intruders, they can help thugs and insurrectionists murder innocent
victims. The threat that firearms will be misused is far from
hypothetical, for gun crime has devastated many of our communities. Amici calculate that approximately one million Americans
have been wounded or killed by gunfire in the last decade.[ Footnote 34 ] Urban areas such as
Chicago suffer disproportionately from this epidemic of violence.
Handguns contribute disproportionately to it. Just as some
homeowners may prefer handguns because of their small size, light
weight, and ease of operation, some criminals will value them for
the same reasons. See Heller , 554 U. S., at ___ (Breyer,
J., dissenting) (slip op., at 32–33). In recent years, handguns
were reportedly used in more than four-fifths of firearm murders
and more than half of all murders nationwide.[ Footnote 35 ] Hence, in evaluating an asserted
right to be free from particular gun-control regulations, liberty
is on both sides of the equation. Guns may be useful for
self-defense, as well as for hunting and sport, but they also have
a unique potential to facilitate death and destruction and thereby
to destabilize ordered liberty. Your interest in keeping
and bearing a certain firearm may diminish my interest in
being and feeling safe from armed violence. And while granting you
the right to own a handgun might make you safer on any given
day—assuming the handgun’s marginal contribution to self-defense
outweighs its marginal contribution to the risk of accident,
suicide, and criminal mischief—it may make you and the community
you live in less safe overall, owing to the increased number of
handguns in circulation. It is at least reasonable for a
democratically elected legislature to take such concerns into
account in considering what sorts of regulations would best serve
the public welfare. The practical impact of various
gun-control measures may be highly controversial, but this basic
insight should not be. The idea that deadly weapons pose a
distinctive threat to the social order—and that reasonable
restrictions on their usage therefore impose an acceptable burden
on one’s personal liberty—is as old as the Republic. As The Chief
Justice observed just the other day, it is a foundational premise
of modern government that the State holds a monopoly on legitimate
violence: “A basic step in organizing a civilized society is to
take [the] sword out of private hands and turn it over to an
organized government, acting on behalf of all the people.” Robertson v. United States ex rel. Watson , ante , at ___ (slip op., at 11) (dissenting opinion). The
same holds true for the handgun. The power a man has in the state
of nature “of doing whatsoever he thought fit for the preservation
of himself and the rest of mankind, he gives up,” to a significant
extent, “to be regulated by laws made by the society.”
J. Locke, Second Treatise of Civil Government §129, p. 64
(J. Gough ed. 1947). Limiting the federal
constitutional right to keep and bear arms to the home complicates
the analysis but does not dislodge this conclusion. Even though the
Court has long afforded special solicitude for the privacy of the
home, we have never understood that principle to “infring[e] upon”
the authority of the States to proscribe certain inherently
dangerous items, for “[i]n such cases, compelling reasons may exist
for overriding the right of the individual to possess those
materials.” Stanley , 394 U. S., at 568, n. 11. And,
of course, guns that start out in the home may not stay in the
home. Even if the government has a weaker basis for restricting
domestic possession of firearms as compared to public carriage—and
even if a blanket, statewide prohibition on domestic possession
might therefore be unconstitutional—the line between the two is a
porous one. A state or local legislature may determine that a
prophylactic ban on an especially portable weapon is necessary to
police that line. Second, the right to possess a
firearm of one’s choosing is different in kind from the liberty
interests we have recognized under the Due Process Clause. Despite
the plethora of substantive due process cases that have been
decided in the post- Lochner century, I have found none
that holds, states, or even suggests that the term “liberty”
encompasses either the common-law right of self-defense or a right
to keep and bear arms. I do not doubt for a moment that many
Americans feel deeply passionate about firearms, and see them as
critical to their way of life as well as to their security.
Nevertheless, it does not appear to be the case that the ability to
own a handgun, or any particular type of firearm, is critical to
leading a life of autonomy, dignity, or political equality: The
marketplace offers many tools for self-defense, even if they are
imperfect substitutes, and neither petitioners nor their amici make such a contention. Petitioners’ claim is not
the kind of substantive interest, accordingly, on which a uniform,
judicially enforced national standard is presumptively
appropriate.[ Footnote
36 ] Indeed, in some respects the
substantive right at issue may be better viewed as a property
right. Petitioners wish to acquire certain types of
firearms, or to keep certain firearms they have previously
acquired. Interests in the possession of chattels have
traditionally been viewed as property interests subject to
definition and regulation by the States. Cf. Stop the Beach
Renourishment, Inc. v. Florida Dept. of Environmental
Protection , 560 U. S. ___, ___ (2010) (slip op., at 1)
(opinion of Scalia, J.) (“Generally speaking, state law defines
property interests”). Under that tradition, Chicago’s ordinance is
unexceptional.[ Footnote
37 ] The liberty interest asserted by
petitioners is also dissimilar from those we have recognized in its
capacity to undermine the security of others. To be sure, some of
the Bill of Rights’ procedural guarantees may place “restrictions
on law enforcement” that have “controversial public safety
implications.” Ante , at 36 (plurality opinion); see also ante , at 9 (opinion of Scalia, J.). But those implications
are generally quite attenuated. A defendant’s invocation of his
right to remain silent, to confront a witness, or to exclude
certain evidence cannot directly cause any threat. The defendant’s
liberty interest is constrained by (and is itself a constraint on)
the adjudicatory process. The link between handgun ownership and
public safety is much tighter. The handgun is itself a tool for
crime; the handgun’s bullets are the violence. Similarly, it is undeniable that
some may take profound offense at a remark made by the soapbox
speaker, the practices of another religion, or a gay couple’s
choice to have intimate relations. But that offense is moral,
psychological, or theological in nature; the actions taken by the
rights-bearers do not actually threaten the physical safety of any
other person.[ Footnote 38 ]
Firearms may be used to kill another person. If a legislature’s
response to dangerous weapons ends up impinging upon the liberty of
any individuals in pursuit of the greater good, it invariably does
so on the basis of more than the majority’s “ ‘own moral
code,’ ” Lawrence , 539 U. S., at 571 (quoting Casey , 505 U. S., at 850). While specific policies may of
course be misguided, gun control is an area in which it “is quite
wrong … to assume that regulation and liberty occupy mutually
exclusive zones—that as one expands, the other must contract.”
Stevens, 41 U. Miami L. Rev., at 280. Third, the experience of other
advanced democracies, including those that share our British
heritage, undercuts the notion that an expansive right to keep and
bear arms is intrinsic to ordered liberty. Many of these countries
place restrictions on the possession, use, and carriage of firearms
far more onerous than the restrictions found in this Nation. See
Municipal Respondents’ Brief 21–23 (discussing laws of England,
Canada, Australia, Japan, Denmark, Finland, Luxembourg, and New
Zealand). That the United States is an international outlier in the
permissiveness of its approach to guns does not suggest that our
laws are bad laws. It does suggest that this Court may not need to
assume responsibility for making our laws still more
permissive. Admittedly, these other countries
differ from ours in many relevant respects, including their
problems with violent crime and the traditional role that firearms
have played in their societies. But they are not so different from
the United States that we ought to dismiss their experience
entirely. Cf. ante , at 34–35 (plurality opinion); ante , at 10–11 (opinion of Scalia, J.). The fact that our
oldest allies have almost uniformly found it appropriate to
regulate firearms extensively tends to weaken petitioners’
submission that the right to possess a gun of one’s choosing is
fundamental to a life of liberty. While the “American perspective”
must always be our focus, ante , at 37, 44 (plurality
opinion), it is silly—indeed, arrogant—to think we have nothing to
learn about liberty from the billions of people beyond our
borders. Fourth, the Second Amendment
differs in kind from the Amendments that surround it, with the
consequence that its inclusion in the Bill of Rights is not merely
unhelpful but positively harmful to petitioners’ claim. Generally,
the inclusion of a liberty interest in the Bill of Rights points
toward the conclusion that it is of fundamental significance and
ought to be enforceable against the States. But the Second
Amendment plays a peculiar role within the Bill, as announced by
its peculiar opening clause.[ Footnote 39 ] Even accepting the Heller Court’s
view that the Amendment protects an individual right to keep and
bear arms disconnected from militia service, it remains undeniable
that “the purpose for which the right was codified” was “to prevent
elimination of the militia.” Heller , 554 U. S., at ___
(slip op., at 26); see also United States v. Miller , 307
U. S. 174 , 178 (1939) (Second Amendment was enacted “[w]ith
obvious purpose to assure the continuation and render possible the
effectiveness of [militia] forces”). It was the States, not private
persons, on whose immediate behalf the Second Amendment was
adopted. Notwithstanding the Heller Court’s efforts to
write the Second Amendment’s preamble out of the Constitution, the
Amendment still serves the structural function of protecting the
States from encroachment by an overreaching Federal
Government. The Second Amendment, in other
words, “is a federalism provision,” Elk Grove Unified School
Dist. v. Newdow , 542 U. S. 1 , 45 (2004) (Thomas, J.,
concurring in judgment). It is directed at preserving the autonomy
of the sovereign States, and its logic therefore “resists”
incorporation by a federal court against the States. Ibid. No one suggests that the Tenth Amendment, which
provides that powers not given to the Federal Government remain
with “the States,” applies to the States; such a reading would
border on incoherent, given that the Tenth Amendment exists (in
significant part) to safeguard the vitality of state governance.
The Second Amendment is no different.[ Footnote 40 ] The Court is surely correct that
Americans’ conceptions of the Second Amendment right evolved over
time in a more individualistic direction; that Members of the
Reconstruction Congress were urgently concerned about the safety of
the newly freed slaves; and that some Members believed that,
following ratification of the Fourteenth Amendment, the Second
Amendment would apply to the States. But it is a giant leap from
these data points to the conclusion that the Fourteenth Amendment
“incorporated” the Second Amendment as a matter of original meaning
or postenactment interpretation. Consider, for example, that the
text of the Fourteenth Amendment says nothing about the Second
Amendment or firearms; that there is substantial evidence to
suggest that, when the Reconstruction Congress enacted measures to
ensure newly freed slaves and Union sympathizers in the South
enjoyed the right to possess firearms, it was motivated by
antidiscrimination and equality concerns rather than arms-bearing
concerns per se;[ Footnote
41 ] that many contemporaneous courts and commentators did
not understand the Fourteenth Amendment to have had an
“incorporating” effect; and that the States heavily regulated the
right to keep and bear arms both before and after the Amendment’s
passage. The Court’s narrative largely elides these facts. The
complications they raise show why even the most dogged historical
inquiry into the “fundamentality” of the Second Amendment right (or
any other) necessarily entails judicial judgment—and therefore
judicial discretion—every step of the way. I accept that the evolution in
Americans’ understanding of the Second Amendment may help shed
light on the question whether a right to keep and bear arms is
comprised within Fourteenth Amendment “liberty.” But the reasons
that motivated the Framers to protect the ability of militiamen to
keep muskets available for military use when our Nation was in its
infancy, or that motivated the Reconstruction Congress to extend
full citizenship to the freedmen in the wake of the Civil War, have
only a limited bearing on the question that confronts the homeowner
in a crime-infested metropolis today. The many episodes of brutal
violence against African-Americans that blight our Nation’s
history, see ante , at 23–29 (majority opinion); ante , at 41–44, 53–55 (Thomas, J., concurring in part and
concurring in judgment), do not suggest that every American must be
allowed to own whatever type of firearm he or she desires—just that
no group of Americans should be systematically and discriminatorily
disarmed and left to the mercy of racial terrorists. And the fact
that some Americans may have thought or hoped that the Fourteenth
Amendment would nationalize the Second Amendment hardly suffices to
justify the conclusion that it did. Fifth, although it may be true
that Americans’ interest in firearm possession and state-law
recognition of that interest are “deeply rooted” in some important
senses, ante , at 19 (internal quotation marks omitted), it
is equally true that the States have a long and unbroken history of
regulating firearms. The idea that States may place substantial
restrictions on the right to keep and bear arms short of complete
disarmament is, in fact, far more entrenched than the notion that
the Federal Constitution protects any such right. Federalism is a
far “older and more deeply rooted tradition than is a right to
carry,” or to own, “any particular kind of weapon.” 567 F. 3d
856, 860 (CA7 2009) (Easterbrook, C. J.). From the early days of the
Republic, through the Reconstruction era, to the present day,
States and municipalities have placed extensive licensing
requirements on firearm acquisition, restricted the public carriage
of weapons, and banned altogether the possession of especially
dangerous weapons, including handguns. See Heller , 554 U.
S., at ___ (Breyer, J., dissenting) (slip op., at 4–7) (reviewing
colonial laws); Cornell & DeDino, A Well Regulated Right: The
Early American Origins of Gun Control, 73 Fordham L. Rev. 487,
502–516 (2004) (reviewing pre-Civil War laws); Brief for 34
Professional Historians and Legal Historians as Amici
Curiae 4–22 (reviewing Reconstruction-era laws); Winkler,
Scrutinizing the Second Amendment, 105 Mich. L. Rev. 683,
711–712, 716–726 (2007) (reviewing 20th-century laws); see
generally post , at 21–31.[ Footnote 42 ] After the 1860’s just as before, the state
courts almost uniformly upheld these measures: Apart from making
clear that all regulations had to be constructed and applied in a
nondiscriminatory manner, the Fourteenth Amendment hardly made a
dent. And let us not forget that this Court did not recognize any non-militia-related interests under the Second
Amendment until two Terms ago, in Heller . Petitioners do
not dispute the city of Chicago’s observation that “[n]o other
substantive Bill of Rights protection has been regulated nearly as
intrusively” as the right to keep and bear arms. Municipal
Respondents’ Brief 25.[ Footnote
43 ] This history of intrusive
regulation is not surprising given that the very text of the Second
Amendment calls out for regulation,[ Footnote 44 ] and the ability to respond to the social
ills associated with dangerous weapons goes to the very core of the
States’ police powers. Our precedent is crystal-clear on this
latter point. See, e.g., Gonzales v. Oregon , 546 U. S. 243 ,
270 (2006) (“[T]he structure and limitations of federalism … allow
the States great latitude under their police powers to legislate as
to the protection of the lives, limbs, health, comfort, and quiet
of all persons” (internal quotation marks omitted)); United
States v. Morrison , 529 U. S. 598 , 618
(2000) (“[W]e can think of no better example of the police power,
which the Founders denied the National Government and reposed in
the States, than the suppression of violent crime and vindication
of its victims”); Kelley v. Johnson , 425 U. S. 238 , 247
(1976) (“The promotion of safety of persons and property is
unquestionably at the core of the State’s police power”); Automobile Workers v. Wisconsin Employment Relations
Bd. , 351 U. S.
266 , 274 (1956) (“The dominant interest of the State in
preventing violence and property damage cannot be questioned. It is
a matter of genuine local concern”). Compared with today’s ruling,
most if not all of this Court’s decisions requiring the States to
comply with other provisions in the Bill of Rights did not exact
nearly so heavy a toll in terms of state sovereignty. Finally, even apart from the
States’ long history of firearms regulation and its location at the
core of their police powers, this is a quintessential area in which
federalism ought to be allowed to flourish without this Court’s
meddling. Whether or not we can assert a plausible
constitutional basis for intervening, there are powerful reasons
why we should not do so. Across the Nation, States and
localities vary significantly in the patterns and problems of gun
violence they face, as well as in the traditions and cultures of
lawful gun use they claim. Cf. post , at 16–17. The city of
Chicago, for example, faces a pressing challenge in combating
criminal street gangs. Most rural areas do not. The city of Chicago
has a high population density, which increases the potential for a
gunman to inflict mass terror and casualties. Most rural areas do
not.[ Footnote 45 ] The city
of Chicago offers little in the way of hunting opportunities.
Residents of rural communities are, one presumes, much more likely
to stock the dinner table with game they have personally
felled. Given that relevant background
conditions diverge so much across jurisdictions, the Court ought to
pay particular heed to state and local legislatures’ “right to
experiment.” New State Ice , 285 U. S., at 311 (Brandeis,
J., dissenting). So long as the regulatory measures they have
chosen are not “arbitrary, capricious, or unreasonable,” we should
be allowing them to “try novel social and economic” policies. Ibid. It “is more in keeping … with our status as a court
in a federal system,” under these circumstances, “to avoid imposing
a single solution … from the top down.” Smith v. Robbins , 528 U. S. 259 , 275
(2000). It is all the more unwise for this
Court to limit experimentation in an area “where the best solution
is far from clear.” United States v. Lopez , 514 U. S. 549 ,
581 (1995) (Kennedy, J., concurring). Few issues of public policy
are subject to such intensive and rapidly developing empirical
controversy as gun control. See Heller , 554 U. S., at ___
(slip op., at 20–25) (Breyer, J., dissenting). Chicago’s handgun
ban, in itself, has divided researchers. Compare Brief for
Professors of Criminal Justice as Amici Curiae (arguing
that ordinance has been effective at reducing gun violence), with
Brief for International Law Enforcement Educators and Trainers
Association et al. as Amici Curiae 17–26 (arguing
that ordinance has been a failure).[ Footnote 46 ] Of course, on some matters the Constitution
requires that we ignore such pragmatic considerations. But the
Constitution’s text, history, and structure are not so clear on the
matter before us—as evidenced by the groundbreaking nature of
today’s fractured decision—and this Court lacks both the technical
capacity and the localized expertise to assess “the wisdom, need,
and propriety” of most gun-control measures. Griswold , 381
U. S., at 482.[ Footnote
47 ] Nor will the Court’s intervention
bring any clarity to this enormously complex area of law. Quite to
the contrary, today’s decision invites an avalanche of litigation
that could mire the federal courts in fine-grained determinations
about which state and local regulations comport with the Heller right—the precise contours of which are far from
pellucid—under a standard of review we have not even established.
See post , at 12–15. The plurality’s “assuranc[e]” that
“incorporation does not imperil every law regulating firearms,” ante , at 40, provides only modest comfort. For it is also
an admission of just how many different types of regulations are
potentially implicated by today’s ruling, and of just how
ad hoc the Court’s initial attempt to draw distinctions among
them was in Heller . The practical significance of the
proposition that “the Second Amendment right is fully applicable to
the States,” ante , at 1 (majority opinion), remains to be
worked out by this Court over many, many years. Furthermore, and critically, the
Court’s imposition of a national standard is still more unwise
because the elected branches have shown themselves to be perfectly
capable of safeguarding the interest in keeping and bearing arms.
The strength of a liberty claim must be assessed in connection with
its status in the democratic process. And in this case, no one
disputes “that opponents of [gun] control have considerable
political power and do not seem to be at a systematic disadvantage
in the democratic process,” or that “the widespread commitment to
an individual right to own guns … operates as a safeguard against
excessive or unjustified gun control laws.”[ Footnote 48 ] Sunstein, Second Amendment
Minimalism: Heller as Griswold , 122 Harv.
L. Rev. 246, 260 (2008). Indeed, there is a good deal of
evidence to suggest that, if anything, American lawmakers tend to under regulate guns, relative to the policy views expressed
by majorities in opinion polls. See K. Goss, Disarmed: The Missing
Movement for Gun Control in America 6 (2006). If a particular State
or locality has enacted some “improvident” gun-control measures, as
petitioners believe Chicago has done, there is no apparent reason
to infer that the mistake will not “eventually be rectified by the
democratic process.” Vance v. Bradley , 440 U. S. 93 , 97
(1979). This is not a case, then, that
involves a “special condition” that “may call for a correspondingly
more searching judicial inquiry.” Carolene Products , 304
U. S., at 153, n. 4. Neither petitioners nor those most
zealously committed to their views represent a group or a claim
that is liable to receive unfair treatment at the hands of the
majority. On the contrary, petitioners’ views are supported by
powerful participants in the legislative process. Petitioners have
given us no reason to believe that the interest in keeping and
bearing arms entails any special need for judicial lawmaking, or
that federal judges are more qualified to craft appropriate rules
than the people’s elected representatives. Having failed to show
why their asserted interest is intrinsic to the concept of ordered
liberty or vulnerable to maltreatment in the political arena, they
have failed to show why “the word liberty in the Fourteenth
Amendment” should be “held to prevent the natural outcome of a
dominant opinion” about how to deal with the problem of handgun
violence in the city of Chicago. Lochner , 198 U. S., at 76
(Holmes, J., dissenting). VI The preceding sections have
already addressed many of the points made by Justice Scalia in his
concurrence. But in light of that opinion’s fixation on this one,
it is appropriate to say a few words about Justice Scalia’s broader
claim: that his preferred method of substantive due process
analysis, a method “that makes the traditions of our people
paramount,” ante , at 1, is both more restrained and more
facilitative of democracy than the method I have outlined. Colorful
as it is, Justice Scalia’s critique does not have nearly as much
force as does his rhetoric. His theory of substantive due process,
moreover, comes with its own profound difficulties. Although Justice Scalia aspires to
an “objective,” “neutral” method of substantive due process
analysis, ante , at 10, his actual method is nothing of the
sort. Under the “historically focused” approach he advocates, ante , at 13, numerous threshold questions arise before one
ever gets to the history. At what level of generality should one
frame the liberty interest in question? See n. 25, supra . What does it mean for a right to be “ ‘deeply
rooted in this Nation’s history and tradition,’ ” ante , at 3 (quoting Glucksberg , 521 U. S., at
721)? By what standard will that proposition be tested? Which types
of sources will count, and how will those sources be weighed and
aggregated? There is no objective, neutral answer to these
questions. There is not even a theory—at least, Justice Scalia
provides none—of how to go about answering them. Nor is there any escaping Palko , it seems. To qualify for substantive due process
protection, Justice Scalia has stated, an asserted liberty right
must be not only deeply rooted in American tradition, “but it must also be implicit in the concept of ordered liberty.” Lawrence , 539 U. S., at 593, n. 3 (dissenting
opinion) (internal quotation marks omitted). Applying the latter, Palko -derived half of that test requires precisely the
sort of reasoned judgment—the same multifaceted evaluation of the
right’s contours and consequences—that Justice Scalia mocks in his
concurrence today. So does applying the first half.
It is hardly a novel insight that history is not an objective
science, and that its use can therefore “point in any direction the
judges favor,” ante , at 14 (opinion of Scalia, J.). Yet 21
years after the point was brought to his attention by Justice
Brennan, Justice Scalia remains “oblivious to the fact that [the
concept of ‘tradition’] can be as malleable and elusive as
‘liberty’ itself.” Michael H. , 491 U. S., at 137
(dissenting opinion). Even when historical analysis is focused on a
discrete proposition, such as the original public meaning of the
Second Amendment, the evidence often points in different
directions. The historian must choose which pieces to credit and
which to discount, and then must try to assemble them into a
coherent whole. In Heller , Justice Scalia preferred to
rely on sources created much earlier and later in time than the
Second Amendment itself, see, e.g., 554 U. S., at ___
(slip op., at 4–5) (consulting late 19th-century treatises to
ascertain how Americans would have read the Amendment’s preamble in
1791); I focused more closely on sources contemporaneous with the
Amendment’s drafting and ratification.[ Footnote 49 ] No mechanical yardstick can measure which
of us was correct, either with respect to the materials we chose to
privilege or the insights we gleaned from them. The malleability and elusiveness
of history increase exponentially when we move from a pure question
of original meaning, as in Heller , to Justice Scalia’s
theory of substantive due process. At least with the former sort of
question, the judge can focus on a single legal provision; the
temporal scope of the inquiry is (or should be) relatively bounded;
and there is substantial agreement on what sorts of authorities
merit consideration. With Justice Scalia’s approach to substantive
due process, these guideposts all fall away. The judge must canvas
the entire landscape of American law as it has evolved through
time, and perhaps older laws as well, see, e.g., Lawrence , 539 U. S., at 596 (Scalia, J., dissenting)
(discussing “ ‘ancient roots’ ” of proscriptions against
sodomy (quoting Bowers v. Hardwick , 478 U. S. 186 , 192 (1986)), pursuant
to a standard (deeply rootedness) that has never been defined. In
conducting this rudderless, panoramic tour of American legal
history, the judge has more than ample opportunity to “look over
the heads of the crowd and pick out [his] friends,” Roper v. Simmons , 543 U. S. 551 , 617
(2005) (Scalia, J., dissenting). My point is not to criticize
judges’ use of history in general or to suggest that it always
generates indeterminate answers; I have already emphasized that
historical study can discipline as well as enrich substantive due
process analysis. My point is simply that Justice Scalia’s defense
of his method, which holds out objectivity and restraint as its
cardinal—and, it seems, only—virtues, is unsatisfying on its own
terms. For a limitless number of subjective judgments may be
smuggled into his historical analysis. Worse, they may be buried in the analysis. At least with my approach, the
judge’s cards are laid on the table for all to see, and to
critique. The judge must exercise judgment, to be sure. When
answering a constitutional question to which the text provides no
clear answer, there is always some amount of discretion; our
constitutional system has always depended on judges’ filling in the
document’s vast open spaces.[ Footnote 50 ] But there is also transparency. Justice Scalia’s approach is even
less restrained in another sense: It would effect a major break
from our case law outside of the “incorporation” area. Justice
Scalia does not seem troubled by the fact that his method is
largely inconsistent with the Court’s canonical substantive due
process decisions, ranging from Meyer , 262 U. S. 390 , and Pierce , 268 U. S. 510 , in the 1920’s, to Griswold , 381 U. S. 479 , in the 1960’s, to Lawrence , 539
U. S. 558 , in the 2000’s. To the contrary, he seems to embrace
this dissonance. My method seeks to synthesize dozens of cases on
which the American people have relied for decades. Justice Scalia’s
method seeks to vaporize them. So I am left to wonder, which of us
is more faithful to this Nation’s constitutional history? And which
of us is more faithful to the values and commitments of the
American people, as they stand today? In 1967, when the Court held
in Loving , 388 U. S. 1 , that adults have a
liberty-based as well as equality-based right to wed persons of
another race, interracial marriage was hardly “deeply rooted” in
American tradition. Racial segregation and subordination were
deeply rooted. The Court’s substantive due process holding was
nonetheless correct—and we should be wary of any interpretive
theory that implies, emphatically, that it was not. Which leads me to the final set of
points I wish to make: Justice Scalia’s method invites not only bad
history, but also bad constitutional law. As I have already
explained, in evaluating a claimed liberty interest (or any
constitutional claim for that matter), it makes perfect sense to
give history significant weight: Justice Scalia’s position is
closer to my own than he apparently feels comfortable
acknowledging. But it makes little sense to give history
dispositive weight in every case. And it makes especially little sense to answer questions like whether the right to bear
arms is “fundamental” by focusing only on the past, given that both
the practical significance and the public understandings of such a
right often change as society changes. What if the evidence had
shown that, whereas at one time firearm possession contributed
substantially to personal liberty and safety, nowadays it
contributes nothing, or even tends to undermine them? Would it
still have been reasonable to constitutionalize the
right? The concern runs still deeper. Not
only can historical views be less than completely clear or
informative, but they can also be wrong. Some notions that many
Americans deeply believed to be true, at one time, turned out not
to be true. Some practices that many Americans believed to be
consistent with the Constitution’s guarantees of liberty and
equality, at one time, turned out to be inconsistent with them. The
fact that we have a written Constitution does not consign this
Nation to a static legal existence. Although we should always
“pa[y] a decent regard to the opinions of former times,” it “is not
the glory of the people of America” to have “suffered a blind
veneration for antiquity.” The Federalist No. 14, p. 99, 104 (C.
Rossiter ed. 1961) (J. Madison). It is not the role of federal
judges to be amateur historians. And it is not fidelity to the
Constitution to ignore its use of deliberately capacious language,
in an effort to transform foundational legal commitments into
narrow rules of decision. As for “the democratic process,” ante , at 14, 15, a method that looks exclusively to
history can easily do more harm than good. Just consider this case.
The net result of Justice Scalia’s supposedly objective analysis is
to vest federal judges—ultimately a majority of the judges on this
Court—with unprecedented lawmaking powers in an area in which they
have no special qualifications, and in which the give-and-take of
the political process has functioned effectively for decades. Why
this “intrudes much less upon the democratic process,” ante , at 14, than an approach that would defer to the
democratic process on the regulation of firearms is, to say the
least, not self-evident. I cannot even tell what, under Justice
Scalia’s view, constitutes an “intrusion.” It is worth pondering,
furthermore, the vision of democracy that underlies Justice
Scalia’s critique. Because very few of us would welcome a system in
which majorities or powerful interest groups always get their way.
Under our constitutional scheme, I would have thought that a
judicial approach to liberty claims such as the one I have
outlined—an approach that investigates both the intrinsic nature of
the claimed interest and the practical significance of its judicial
enforcement, that is transparent in its reasoning and sincere in
its effort to incorporate constraints, that is guided by history
but not beholden to it, and that is willing to protect some rights
even if they have not already received uniform protection from the
elected branches—has the capacity to improve, rather than
“[im]peril,” ante , at 15, our democracy. It all depends on
judges’ exercising careful, reasoned judgment. As it always has,
and as it always will. VII The fact that the
right to keep and bear arms appears in the Constitution should not
obscure the novelty of the Court’s decision to enforce that right
against the States. By its terms, the Second Amendment does not
apply to the States; read properly, it does not even apply to
individuals outside of the militia context. The Second Amendment
was adopted to protect the States from federal
encroachment. And the Fourteenth Amendment has never been
understood by the Court to have “incorporated” the entire Bill of
Rights. There was nothing foreordained about today’s
outcome. Although the Court’s
decision in this case might be seen as a mere adjunct to its
decision in Heller , the consequences could prove far more
destructive—quite literally—to our Nation’s communities and to our
constitutional structure. Thankfully, the Second Amendment right
identified in Heller and its newly minted Fourteenth
Amendment analogue are limited, at least for now, to the home. But
neither the “assurances” provided by the plurality, ante ,
at 40, nor the many historical sources cited in its opinion should
obscure the reality that today’s ruling marks a dramatic change in
our law—or that the Justices who have joined it have brought to
bear an awesome amount of discretion in resolving the legal
question presented by this case. I would proceed more cautiously. For the reasons set out at length above, I cannot
accept either the methodology the Court employs or the conclusions
it draws. Although impressively argued, the majority’s decision to
overturn more than a century of Supreme Court precedent and to
unsettle a much longer tradition of state practice is not, in my
judgment, built “upon respect for the teachings of history, solid
recognition of the basic values that underlie our society, and wise
appreciation of the great roles that the doctrines of federalism
and separation of powers have played in establishing and preserving
American freedoms.” Griswold , 381 U. S., at 501 (Harlan,
J., concurring in judgment). Accordingly, I
respectfully dissent. Footnote
1 See United
States v. Cruikshank , 92 U. S. 542 , 553 (1876); Presser v. Illinois , 116 U. S. 252 , 265
(1886); Miller v. Texas , 153 U. S. 535 , 538
(1894). This is not to say that I agree with all other aspects of
these decisions. Footnote
2 Cf., e.g., Currie, The Reconstruction Congress, 75 U. Chi. L. Rev. 383,
406 (2008) (finding “some support in the legislative history for no
fewer than four interpretations” of the Privileges or Immunities
Clause, two of which contradict petitioners’ submission); Green,
The Original Sense of the (Equal) Protection Clause: Subsequent
Interpretation and Application, 19 Geo. Mason U. Civ. Rights
L. J. 219, 255–277 (2009) (providing evidence that the Clause
was originally conceived of as an antidiscrimination measure,
guaranteeing equal rights for black citizens); Rosenthal, The New
Originalism Meets the Fourteenth Amendment: Original Public Meaning
and the Problem of Incorporation, 18 J. Contemporary Legal Issues
361 (2009) (detailing reasons to doubt that the Clause was
originally understood to apply the Bill of Rights to the States);
Hamburger, Privileges or Immunities, 105 Nw. U. L. Rev.
(forthcoming 2011), online at http://ssrn.com/abstract=1557870 (as
visited June 25, 2010, and available in Clerk of Court’s case file)
(arguing that the Clause was meant to ensure freed slaves were
afforded “the Privileges and Immunities” specified in Article IV,
§2, cl. 1 of the Constitution). Although he urges its elevation in
our doctrine, Justice Thomas has acknowledged that, in seeking to
ascertain the original meaning of the Privileges or Immunities
Clause, “[l]egal scholars agree on little beyond the conclusion
that the Clause does not mean what the Court said it meant in
1873.” Saenz v. Roe , 526 U. S. 489 , 522,
n. 1 (1999) (dissenting opinion); accord, ante , at 10
(plurality opinion). Footnote
3 It is no secret that
the desire to “displace” major “portions of our equal protection
and substantive due process jurisprudence” animates some of the
passion that attends this interpretive issue. Saenz , 526
U. S., at 528 (Thomas, J., dissenting). Footnote
4 Wilkinson, The
Fourteenth Amendment Privileges or Immunities Clause, 12 Harv.
J. L. & Pub. Pol’y 43, 52 (1989). Judge Wilkinson’s point
is broader than the privileges or immunities debate. As he
observes, “there may be more structure imposed by provisions
subject to generations of elaboration and refinement than by a
provision in its pristine state. The fortuities of uneven
constitutional development must be respected, not cast aside in the
illusion of reordering the landscape anew.” Id., at 51–52;
see also Washington v. Glucksberg , 521 U. S. 702 , 759, n. 6 (1997)
(Souter, J., concurring in judgment) (acknowledging that, “[t]o a
degree,” the Slaughter-House “decision may have led the
Court to look to the Due Process Clause as a source of substantive
rights”). Footnote
5 See, e.g., Ely, The Oxymoron Reconsidered: Myth and Reality in the Origins of
Substantive Due Process, 16 Const. Commentary 315, 326–327 (1999)
(concluding that founding-era “American statesmen accustomed to
viewing due process through the lens of [Sir Edward] Coke and
[William] Blackstone could [not] have failed to understand due
process as encompassing substantive as well as procedural terms”);
Gedicks, An Originalist Defense of Substantive Due Process: Magna
Carta, Higher-Law Constitutionalism, and the Fifth Amendment, 58
Emory L. J. 585, 594 (2009) (arguing “that one widely shared
understanding of the Due Process Clause of the Fifth Amendment in
the late eighteenth century encompassed judicial recognition and
enforcement of unenumerated substantive rights”); Maltz, Fourteenth
Amendment Concepts in the Antebellum Era, 32 Am. J. Legal Hist.
305, 317–318 (1988) (explaining that in the antebellum era a
“substantial number of states,” as well as antislavery advocates,
“imbued their [constitutions’] respective due process clauses with
a substantive content”); Tribe, Taking Text and Structure
Seriously: Reflections on Free-Form Method in Constitutional
Interpretation, 108 Harv. L. Rev. 1221, 1297, n. 247
(1995) (“[T]he historical evidence points strongly toward
the conclusion that, at least by 1868 even if not in 1791, any
state legislature voting to ratify a constitutional rule banning
government deprivations of ‘life, liberty, or property, without due
process of law’ would have understood that ban as having
substantive as well as procedural content, given that era’s premise
that, to qualify as ‘law,’ an enactment would have to meet
substantive requirements of rationality, non-oppressiveness, and
evenhandedness”); see also Stevens, The Third Branch of Liberty, 41
U. Miami L. Rev. 277, 290 (1986) (“In view of the number of
cases that have given substantive content to the term liberty, the
burden of demonstrating that this consistent course of decision was
unfaithful to the intent of the Framers is surely a heavy
one”). Footnote
6 1 L. Tribe, American
Constitutional Law §8–1, p. 1335 (3d ed.
2000). Footnote
7 The Ninth Amendment
provides: “The enumeration in the Constitution, of certain rights,
shall not be construed to deny or disparage others retained by the
people.” Footnote
8 Stevens, The Bill of
Rights: A Century of Progress, 59 U. Chi. L. Rev. 13, 20
(1992); see Fitzgerald , 523 F. 2d, at 719–720;
Stevens, 41 U. Miami L. Rev., at 286–289; see also Greene, The
So-Called Right to Privacy, 43 U. C. D. L. Rev. 715,
725–731 (2010). Footnote
9 See also Gitlow , 268 U. S., at 672 (Holmes, J., dissenting) (“The
general principle of free speech, it seems to me, must be taken to
be included in the Fourteenth Amendment, in view of the scope that
has been given to the word ‘liberty’ as there used, although
perhaps it may be accepted with a somewhat larger latitude of
interpretation than is allowed to Congress by the sweeping language
that governs or ought to govern the laws of the United States”).
Subsequent decisions repeatedly reaffirmed that persons hold free
speech rights against the States on account of the Fourteenth
Amendment’s liberty clause, not the First Amendment per
se . See, e.g., NAACP v. Alabama ex rel.
Patterson , 357
U. S. 449 , 460, 466 (1958); Cantwell v. Connecticut , 310 U. S. 296 , 303
(1940); Thornhill v. Alabama , 310 U. S. 88 , 95, and n. 7 (1940);
see also McIntyre v. Ohio Elections Comm’n , 514 U. S. 334 ,
336, n. 1 (1995) (“The term ‘liberty’ in the Fourteenth
Amendment to the Constitution makes the First Amendment applicable
to the States”). Classic opinions written by Justice Cardozo and
Justice Frankfurter endorsed the same basic approach to
“incorporation,” with the Fourteenth Amendment taken as a distinct
source of rights independent from the first eight Amendments. Palko v. Connecticut , 302 U. S. 319 , 322–328 (1937) (opinion
for the Court by Cardozo, J.); Adamson v. California , 332 U. S. 46 , 59–68 (1947)
(Frankfurter, J., concurring). Footnote
10 See also Wolf v. Colorado , 338 U. S. 25 , 26 (1949)
(“The notion that the ‘due process of law’ guaranteed by the
Fourteenth Amendment is shorthand for the first eight amendments of
the Constitution … has been rejected by this Court again and again,
after impressive consideration. … The issue is closed”). Wolf ’s holding on the exclusionary rule was overruled by Mapp v. Ohio , 367 U. S. 643 (1961), but the
principle just quoted has never been disturbed. It is notable that Mapp , the case that launched the modern “doctrine of ad hoc ,” “ ‘jot-for-jot’ ” incorporation, Williams v. Florida , 399 U.
S. 78 , 130–131 (1970) (Harlan, J., concurring in result),
expressly held “that the exclusionary rule is an essential part of
both the Fourth and Fourteenth Amendments.” 367 U. S., at
657 (emphasis added). Footnote
11 I can hardly improve
upon the many passionate defenses of this position that Justice
Harlan penned during his tenure on the Court. See Williams , 399 U. S., at 131, n. 14 (opinion
concurring in result) (cataloguing opinions). Footnote
12 See, e.g., Pet. for Cert. in Bowen v. Oregon , O. T.
2009, No. 08–1117, p. i, cert. denied, 558 U. S. ___ (2009)
(request to overrule Apodaca ); Pet. for Cert. in Lee v. Louisiana , O. T. 2008, No. 07–1523,
p. i, cert. denied, 555 U. S. ___ (2008) (same); Pet. for Cert. in Logan v. Florida , O. T. 2007, No. 07–7264,
pp. 14–19, cert. denied, 552 U. S. 1189 (2008)
(request to overrule Williams ). Footnote
13 The vast majority of
States already recognize a right to keep and bear arms in their own
constitutions, see Volokh, State Constitutional Rights to Keep and
Bear Arms, 11 Tex. Rev. L. & Pol. 191 (2006) (cataloguing
provisions); Brief for Petitioners 69 (observing that “[t]hese
Second Amendment analogs are effective and consequential”), but the
States vary widely in their regulatory schemes, their traditions
and cultures of firearm use, and their problems relating to gun
violence. If federal and state courts must harmonize their review
of gun-control laws under the Second Amendment, the resulting
jurisprudence may prove significantly more deferential to those
laws than the status quo ante . Once it has been
established that a single legal standard must govern nationwide,
federal courts will face a profound pressure to reconcile that
standard with the diverse interests of the States and their long
history of regulating in this sensitive area. Cf. Williams , 399 U. S., at 129–130 (Harlan, J., concurring in
result) (noting “ ‘backlash’ ” potential of jot-for-jot
incorporation); Grant, Felix Frankfurter: A Dissenting Opinion, 12
UCLA L. Rev. 1013, 1038 (1965) (“If the Court will not reduce
the requirements of the fourteenth amendment below the federal
gloss that now overlays the Bill of Rights, then it will have to
reduce that gloss to the point where the states can live with it”). Amici argue persuasively that, post-“incorporation,”
federal courts will have little choice but to fix a highly flexible
standard of review if they are to avoid leaving federalism and the
separation of powers—not to mention gun policy—in shambles. See
Brief for Brady Center to Prevent Gun Violence et al. as Amici Curiae (hereinafter Brady Center
Brief). Footnote
14 Justice Cardozo’s
test itself built upon an older line of decisions. See, e.g., Chicago, B. & Q. R. Co. v. Chicago , 166 U. S. 226 , 237 (1897) (discussing
“limitations on [state] power, which grow out of the essential
nature of all free governments [and] implied reservations of
individual rights, . . . and which are respected by all
governments entitled to the name” (internal quotation marks
omitted)). Footnote
15 See Palko ,
302 U. S., at 326, n. 3; see also, e.g., Lawrence v. Texas , 539
U. S. 558 , 572–573, 576–577 (2003); Glucksberg , 521 U.
S., at 710–711, and n. 8. Footnote
16 I acknowledge that
some have read the Court’s opinion in Glucksberg as an
attempt to move substantive due process analysis, for all purposes,
toward an exclusively historical methodology—and thereby to
debilitate the doctrine. If that were ever Glucksberg ’s
aspiration, Lawrence plainly renounced it. As between Glucksberg and Lawrence , I have little doubt
which will prove the more enduring precedent. Footnote
17 The Court almost
never asked whether the guarantee in question was deeply rooted in
founding-era practice. See Brief for Respondent City of Chicago
et al. 31, n. 17 (hereinafter Municipal Respondents’
Brief) (noting that only two opinions extensively discussed such
history). Footnote
18 Cf. Robinson v. California , 370 U. S. 660 , 666–668
(1962) (invalidating state statute criminalizing narcotics
addiction as “cruel and unusual punishment in violation of the
Fourteenth Amendment” based on nature of the alleged
“ ‘crime,’ ” without historical analysis); Brief for
Respondent National Rifle Association of America, Inc., et al.
29 (noting that “lynchpin” of incorporation test has always been
“the importance of the right in question to … ‘liberty’ ” and
to our “system of government”). Footnote
19 I do not mean to
denigrate this function, or to imply that only “ new rights”—whatever one takes that term to mean—ought to “get in” the
substantive due process door. Ante , at 5 (Scalia, J.,
concurring). Footnote
20 See Bowers v. Hardwick , 478 U. S. 186 , 199 (1986) (Blackmun,
J., dissenting) (“Like Justice Holmes, I believe that ‘[i]t is
revolting to have no better reason for a rule of law than that so
it was laid down in the time of Henry IV. It is still more
revolting if the grounds upon which it was laid down have vanished
long since, and the rule simply persists from blind imitation of
the past’ ” (quoting Holmes, The Path of the Law, 10 Harv.
L. Rev. 457, 469 (1897))). Footnote
21 Justice Kennedy has
made the point movingly: “Had those who drew
and ratified the Due Process Clauses of the Fifth Amendment or the
Fourteenth Amendment known the components of liberty in its
manifold possibilities, they might have been more specific. They
did not presume to have this insight. They knew times can blind us
to certain truths and later generations can see that laws once
thought necessary and proper in fact serve only to oppress. As the
Constitution endures, persons in every generation can invoke its
principles in their own search for greater freedom.” Lawrence , 539 U. S., at 578–579. Footnote
22 Contrary to
Justice Scalia’s suggestion, I emphatically do not believe that
“only we judges” can interpret the Fourteenth Amendment, ante , at 4, or any other constitutional provision. All
Americans can; all Americans should. I emphatically do believe that
we judges must exercise—indeed, cannot help but exercise—our own
reasoned judgment in so doing. Justice Scalia and I are on common
ground in maintaining that courts should be “guided by what the
American people throughout our history have thought.” Ibid. Where we part ways is in his view that courts should
be guided only by historical
considerations. There is, moreover, a
tension between Justice Scalia’s concern that “courts have the last
word” on constitutional questions, ante , at 3, n. 2,
on the one hand, and his touting of the Constitution’s Article V
amendment process, ante , at 3, on the other. The American
people can of course reverse this Court’s rulings through that same
process. Footnote
23 In assessing concerns
about the “open-ended[ness]” of this area of law, Collins ,
503 U. S., at 125, one does well to keep in view the malleability
not only of the Court’s “deeply rooted”/fundamentality standard but
also of substantive due process’ constitutional cousin, “equal
protection” analysis. Substantive due process is sometimes accused
of entailing an insufficiently “restrained methodology.” Glucksberg , 521 U. S., at 721. Yet “the word ‘liberty’ in
the Due Process Clause seems to provide at least as much meaningful
guidance as does the word ‘equal’ in the Equal Protection Clause.”
Post, The Supreme Court 2002 Term—Foreword: Fashioning the Legal
Constitution: Culture, Courts, and Law, 117 Harv. L. Rev. 4,
94, n. 440 (2003). And “[i]f the objection is that the text of
the [Due Process] Clause warrants providing only protections of
process rather than protections of substance,” “it is striking that
even those Justices who are most theoretically opposed to
substantive due process, like Scalia and Rehnquist, are also
nonetheless enthusiastic about applying the equal protection
component of the Due Process Clause of the Fifth Amendment to the
federal government.” Ibid. (citing Adarand
Constructors, Inc. v. Peńa , 515 U. S. 200 , 213–231
(1995)). Footnote
24 That one eschews a
comprehensive theory of liberty does not, pace Justice
Scalia, mean that one lacks “a coherent theory of the Due Process
Clause,” ante , at 5. It means that one lacks the hubris to
adopt a rigid, context-independent definition of a constitutional
guarantee that was deliberately framed in open-ended
terms. Footnote
25 The notion that we
should define liberty claims at the most specific level available
is one of Justice Scalia’s signal contributions to the theory of
substantive due process. See, e.g., Michael H. v. Gerald D. , 491 U. S. 110 , 127–128, n. 6
(1989) (opinion of Scalia, J.); ante , at 7 (opinion of
Scalia, J.). By so narrowing the asserted right, this approach
“loads the dice” against its recognition, Roosevelt, Forget the
Fundamentals: Fixing Substantive Due Process, 8 U. Pa. J.
Const. L. 983, 1002, n. 73 (2006): When one defines the
liberty interest at issue in Lawrence as the freedom to
perform specific sex acts, ante , at 2, the interest starts
to look less compelling. The Court today does not follow Justice
Scalia’s “particularizing” method, Katzenbach v. Morgan , 384
U. S. 641 , 649 (1966), as it relies on general historical
references to keeping and bearing arms, without any close study of
the States’ practice of regulating especially dangerous
weapons. Footnote
26 In District of
Columbia v. Heller , 554 U. S. ___, ___ (slip op., at
22), the Court concluded, over my dissent, that the Second
Amendment confers “an individual right to keep and bear arms”
disconnected from militia service. If that conclusion were wrong,
then petitioners’ “incorporation” claim clearly would fail, as they
would hold no right against the Federal Government to be free from
regulations such as the ones they challenge. Cf. post , at
8. I do not understand petitioners or any of their amici to dispute this point. Yet even if Heller had never been
decided—indeed, even if the Second Amendment did not exist—we would
still have an obligation to address petitioners’ Fourteenth
Amendment claim. Footnote
27 The village of Oak
Park imposes more stringent restrictions that may raise additional
complications. See ante , at 2 (majority opinion) (quoting
Oak Park, Ill., Municipal Code §§27–2–1 (2007), 27–1–1 (2009)). The
Court, however, declined to grant certiorari on the National Rifle
Association’s challenge to the Oak Park restrictions. Chicago is
the only defendant in this case. Footnote
28 To the extent that
petitioners contend the city of Chicago’s registration requirements
for firearm possessors also, and separately, violate the
Constitution, that claim borders on the frivolous. Petitioners make
no effort to demonstrate that the requirements are unreasonable or
that they impose a severe burden on the underlying right they have
asserted. Footnote
29 Members of my
generation, at least, will recall the many passionate statements of
this view made by the distinguished actor, Charlton
Heston. Footnote
30 See Municipal
Respondents’ Brief 20, n. 11 (stating that at least 156 Second
Amendment challenges were brought in time between Heller ’s
issuance and brief’s filing); Brady Center Brief 3 (stating that
over 190 Second Amendment challenges were brought in first 18
months since Heller ); Brief for Villages of Winnetka and
Skokie, Illinois, et al. as Amici Curiae 15 (stating
that, in wake of Heller , municipalities have “repealed
longstanding handgun laws to avoid costly
litigation”). Footnote
31 See, e.g., Brief for Professors of Philosophy, Criminology, Law, and Other
Fields as Amici Curiae; Brief for International Law
Enforcement Educators and Trainers Association et al. as Amici Curiae 29–45; Brief for 34 California District
Attorneys et al. as Amici Curiae 12–31. Footnote
32 The argument that
this Court should establish any such right, however, faces steep
hurdles. All 50 States already recognize self-defense as a defense
to criminal prosecution, see 2 P. Robinson, Criminal Law Defenses
§132, p. 96 (1984 and Supp. 2009), so this is hardly an
interest to which the democratic process has been insensitive. And
the States have always diverged on how exactly to implement this
interest, so there is wide variety across the Nation in the types
and amounts of force that may be used, the necessity of retreat,
the rights of aggressors, the availability of the “castle
doctrine,” and so forth. See Brief for Oak Park Citizens Committee
for Handgun Control as Amicus Curiae 9–21; Brief for
American Cities et al. as Amici Curiae 17–19; 2 W.
LaFave, Substantive Criminal Law §10.4, pp. 142–160 (2d ed.
2003). Such variation is presumed to be a healthy part of our
federalist system, as the States and localities select different
rules in light of different priorities, customs, and
conditions. As a historical and
theoretical matter, moreover, the legal status of self-defense is
far more complicated than it might first appear. We have generally
understood Fourteenth Amendment “liberty” as something one holds
against direct state interference, whereas a personal right of
self-defense runs primarily against other individuals; absent
government tyranny, it is only when the state has failed to interfere with (violent) private conduct that self-help becomes
potentially necessary. Moreover, it was a basic tenet of
founding-era political philosophy that, in entering civil society
and gaining “the advantages of mutual commerce” and the protections
of the rule of law, one had to relinquish, to a significant degree,
“that wild and savage liberty” one possessed in the state of
nature. 1 W. Blackstone, Commentaries *125; see also, e.g., J. Locke, Second Treatise of Civil Government §128,
pp. 63–64 (J. Gough ed. 1947) (in state of nature man has
power “to do whatever he thinks fit for the preservation of himself
and others,” but this “he gives up when he joins in a … particular
political society”); Green v. Biddle , 8 Wheat. 1,
63 (1823) (“It is a trite maxim, that man gives up a part of his
natural liberty when he enters into civil society, as the price of
the blessings of that state: and it may be said, with truth, that
this liberty is well exchanged for the advantages which flow from
law and justice”). Some strains of founding-era thought took a very
narrow view of the right to armed self-defense. See, e.g., Brief of Historians on Early American Legal, Constitutional, and
Pennsylvania History as Amici Curiae 6–13 (discussing Whig
and Quaker theories). Just because there may be a natural or
common-law right to some measure of self-defense, it hardly follows
that States may not place substantial restrictions on its exercise
or that this Court should recognize a constitutional right to the
same. Footnote
33 The Second Amendment
right identified in Heller is likewise clearly distinct
from a right to protect oneself. In my view, the Court badly
misconstrued the Second Amendment in linking it to the value of
personal self-defense above and beyond the functioning of the state
militias; as enacted, the Second Amendment was concerned with
tyrants and invaders, and paradigmatically with the federal
military, not with criminals and intruders. But even still, the
Court made clear that self-defense plays a limited role in
determining the scope and substance of the Amendment’s guarantee.
The Court struck down the District of Columbia’s handgun ban not
because of the utility of handguns for lawful
self-defense, but rather because of their popularity for
that purpose. See 554 U. S., at ___ (slip op., at 57–58). And the
Court’s common-use gloss on the Second Amendment right, see id., at ___ (slip op., at 55), as well as its discussion
of permissible limitations on the right, id., at ___ (slip
op., at 54–55), had little to do with
self-defense. Footnote
34 Brady Center Brief 11
(extrapolating from Government statistics); see also Brief for
American Public Health Association et al. as Amici
Curiae 6–7 (reporting estimated social cost of firearm-related
violence of $100 billion per year). Footnote
35 Bogus, Gun Control
and America’s Cities: Public Policy and Politics, 1 Albany Govt.
L. Rev. 440, 447 (2008) (drawing on FBI data); see also Heller , 554 U. S., at ___ (slip op., at 18–19) (Breyer,
J., dissenting) (providing additional statistics on handgun
violence); Municipal Respondents’ Brief 13–14
(same). Footnote
36 Justice Scalia
worries that there is no “objective” way to decide what is
essential to a “liberty-filled” existence: Better, then, to ignore
such messy considerations as how an interest actually affects
people’s lives. Ante , at 10. Both the constitutional text
and our cases use the term “liberty,” however, and liberty is not a
purely objective concept. Substantive due process analysis does not
require any “political” judgment, ibid. It does require
some amount of practical and normative judgment. The only way to
assess what is essential to fulfilling the Constitution’s guarantee
of “liberty,” in the present day, is to provide reasons that apply
to the present day. I have provided many; Justice Scalia and the
Court have provided virtually none. Justice Scalia also
misstates my argument when he refers to “the right to keep and bear
arms,” without qualification. Ante , at 9. That is what the
Second Amendment protects against Federal Government infringement.
I have taken pains to show why the Fourteenth Amendment liberty
interest asserted by petitioners—the interest in keeping a firearm
of one’s choosing in the home—is not necessarily coextensive with
the Second Amendment right. Footnote
37 It has not escaped my
attention that the Due Process Clause refers to “property” as well
as “liberty.” Cf. ante , at 2, n. 1, 9–10, n. 6
(opinion of Scalia, J.). Indeed, in Moore v. East
Cleveland , 431 U. S. 494 (1977) (plurality
opinion), I alone viewed “the critical question” as “whether East
Cleveland’s housing ordinance [was] a permissible restriction on
appellant’s right to use her own property as she sees fit,” id., at 513 (opinion concurring in judgment). In that
case, unlike in this case, the asserted property right was
coextensive with a right to organize one’s family life, and I could
find “no precedent” for the ordinance at issue, which “exclude[d]
any of an owner’s relatives from the group of persons who may
occupy his residence on a permanent basis.” Id., at 520. I
am open to property claims under the Fourteenth Amendment. This
case just involves a weak one. And ever since the Court
“incorporated” the more specific property protections of the
Takings Clause in 1897, see Chicago, B. & Q. R. Co. , 166 U. S. 226 , substantive due process
doctrine has focused on liberty. Footnote
38 Cf. Planned
Parenthood of Southeastern Pa. v. Casey , 505 U. S. 833 , 913–914 (1992)
(Stevens, J., concurring in part and dissenting in
part). Footnote
39 The Second Amendment
provides: “A well regulated Militia, being necessary to the
security of a free State, the right of the people to keep and bear
Arms, shall not be infringed.” Footnote
40 Contrary to Justice
Scalia’s suggestion, this point is perfectly compatible with my
opinion for the Court in Elk Grove Unified School Dist. v. Newdow , 542 U. S. 1 (2004). Cf. ante ,
at 11. Like the Court itself, I have never agreed with Justice
Thomas’ view that the Establishment Clause is a federalism
provision. But I agree with his underlying logic: If a clause in
the Bill of Rights exists to safeguard federalism interests, then
it makes little sense to “incorporate” it. Justice Scalia’s further
suggestion that I ought to have revisited the Establishment Clause
debate in this opinion, ibid. , is simply
bizarre. Footnote
41 See post , at
24–25; Municipal Respondents’ Brief 62–69; Brief for 34
Professional Historians and Legal Historians as Amici
Curiae 22–26; Rosenthal, Second Amendment Plumbing After Heller: Of Standards of Scrutiny, Incorporation,
Well-Regulated Militias, and Criminal Street Gangs, 41 Urb. Law. 1,
73–75 (2009). The plurality insists that the Reconstruction-era
evidence shows the right to bear arms was regarded as “a
substantive guarantee, not a prohibition that could be ignored so
long as the States legislated in an evenhanded manner.” Ante , at 33. That may be so, but it does not resolve the
question whether the Fourteenth Amendment’s Due Process Clause was
originally understood to encompass a right to keep and bear arms,
or whether it ought to be so construed now. Footnote
42 I am unclear what the
plurality means when it refers to “the paucity of precedent
sustaining bans comparable to those at issue here.” Ante ,
at 39. There is only one ban at issue here—the city of Chicago’s
handgun prohibition—and the municipal respondents cite far more
than “one case,” ibid. , from the post-Reconstruction
period. See Municipal Respondents’ Brief 24–30. The evidence
adduced by respondents and their amici easily establishes
their contentions that the “consensus in States that recognize a
firearms right is that arms possession, even in the home, is …
subject to interest-balancing,” id., at 24; and that the
practice of “[b]anning weapons routinely used for self-defense,”
when deemed “necessary for the public welfare,” “has ample
historical pedigree,” id., at 28. Petitioners do not even
try to challenge these contentions. Footnote
43 I agree with Justice
Scalia that a history of regulation hardly proves a right is not
“of fundamental character.” Ante , at 12. An unbroken
history of extremely intensive, carefully considered regulation
does, however, tend to suggest that it is not. Footnote
44 The Heller majority asserted that “the adjective ‘well-regulated’ ” in
the Second Amendment’s preamble “implies nothing more than the
imposition of proper discipline and training.” 554 U. S., at ___
(slip op., at 23). It is far from clear that this assertion is
correct. See, e.g., U. S. Const., Art. 1, §4, cl. 1;
§8, cls. 3, 5, 14; §9, cl. 6; Art. 3, §2, cl. 2; Art. 4,
§2, cl. 3; §3, cl. 2 (using “regulate” or “Regulation” in
manner suggestive of broad, discretionary governmental authority);
Art. 1, §8, cl. 16 (invoking powers of “disciplining” and
“training” Militia in manner suggestive of narrower authority); Heller , 554 U. S., at ___ (slip op., at 6–7)
(investigating Constitution’s separate references to “people” as
clue to term’s meaning in Second Amendment); cf. Cornell &
DeDino, A Well Regulated Right: The Early American Origins of Gun
Control, 73 Fordham L. Rev. 487, 504 (2004) (“The authors of
this curious interpretation of the Second Amendment have
constructed a fantasy world where words mean their opposite, and
regulation is really anti-regulation”). But even if the assertion
were correct, the point would remain that the preamble envisions an
active state role in overseeing how the right to keep and bear arms
is utilized, and in ensuring that it is channeled toward productive
ends. Footnote
45 Cf. Heller ,
554 U. S., at ___ (slip op., at 19) (Breyer, J., dissenting)
(detailing evidence showing that a “disproportionate amount of
violent and property crimes occur in urban areas, and urban
criminals are more likely than other offenders to use a firearm
during the commission of a violent crime”). Footnote
46 The fact that
Chicago’s handgun murder rate may have “actually increased since
the ban was enacted,” ante , at 2 (majority opinion), means
virtually nothing in itself. Countless factors unrelated to the
policy may have contributed to that trend. Without a sophisticated
regression analysis, we cannot even begin to speculate as to the
efficacy or effects of the handgun ban. Even with such an analysis,
we could never be certain as to the determinants of the city’s
murder rate. Footnote
47 In some sense, it is
no doubt true that the “best” solution is elusive for many “serious
social problems.” Ante , at 12 (opinion of Scalia, J.). Yet
few social problems have raised such heated empirical controversy
as the problem of gun violence. And few, if any, of the liberty
interests we have recognized under the Due Process Clause have
raised as many complications for judicial oversight as the interest
that is recognized today. See post , at
11–16. I agree with the
plurality that for a right to be eligible for substantive due
process recognition, there need not be “a ‘popular consensus’ that
the right is fundamental.” Ante , at 42. In our remarkably
diverse, pluralistic society, there will almost never be such
uniformity of opinion. But to the extent that popular consensus is
relevant, I do not agree with the Court that the amicus brief filed in this case by numerous state attorneys general
constitutes evidence thereof. Ante , at 42–43. It is
puzzling that so many state lawmakers have asked us to limit their option to regulate a dangerous item. Cf. post , at
9–10. Footnote
48 Likewise, no one
contends that those interested in personal self-defense—every
American, presumably—face any particular disadvantage in the
political process. All 50 States recognize self-defense as a
defense to criminal prosecution. See n. 32, supra . Footnote
49 See Heller ,
554 U. S., at ___ (slip op., at 27) (Stevens, J., dissenting)
(“Although it gives short shrift to the drafting history of the
Second Amendment, the Court dwells at length on four other sources:
the 17th-century English Bill of Rights; Blackstone’s Commentaries
on the Laws of England; postenactment commentary on the Second
Amendment; and post-Civil War legislative history”); see also post , at 2–5 (discussing professional historians’
criticisms of Heller ). Footnote
50 Indeed, this is truly
one of our most deeply rooted legal traditions. BREYER, J., DISSENTING MCDONALD V. CHICAGO 561 U. S. ____ (2010) SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES NO. 08-1521 OTIS McDONALD, et al., PETITIONERS v. CITY OF CHICAGO, ILLINOIS, et al.
on writ of certiorari to the united states court of
appeals for the seventh circuit
[June 28, 2010]
Justice Breyer, with whom Justice
Ginsburg and Justice Sotomayor join, dissenting.
In my view, Justice Stevens has
demonstrated that the Fourteenth Amendment’s guarantee of
“substantive due process” does not include a general right to keep
and bear firearms for purposes of private self-defense. As he
argues, the Framers did not write the Second Amendment with this
objective in view. See ante, at 41–44 (dissenting
opinion). Unlike other forms of substantive liberty, the carrying
of arms for that purpose often puts others’ lives at risk. See ante, at 35–37. And the use of arms for private
self-defense does not warrant federal constitutional protection
from state regulation. See ante, at 44–51.
The Court, however, does not expressly rest
its opinion upon “substantive due process” concerns. Rather, it
directs its attention to this Court’s “incorporation” precedents
and asks whether the Second Amendment right to private self-defense
is “fundamental” so that it applies to the States through the
Fourteenth Amendment. See ante, at 11–19.
I shall therefore separately consider the
question of “incorporation.” I can find nothing in the Second
Amendment’s text, history, or underlying rationale that could
warrant characterizing it as “fundamental” insofar as it seeks to
protect the keeping and bearing of arms for private self-defense
purposes. Nor can I find any justification for interpreting the
Constitution as transferring ultimate regulatory authority over the
private uses of firearms from democratically elected legislatures
to courts or from the States to the Federal Government. I therefore
conclude that the Fourteenth Amendment does not “incorporate” the
Second Amendment’s right “to keep and bear Arms.” And I
consequently dissent.
I
The Second Amendment says: “A
well regulated Militia, being necessary to the security of a free
State, the right of the people to keep and bear Arms, shall not be
infringed.” Two years ago, in District of Columbia v. Heller , 554 U. S. ___ (2008), the Court rejected the
pre-existing judicial consensus that the Second Amendment was
primarily concerned with the need to maintain a “well regulated
Militia.” See id., at ___ (Stevens, J., dissenting) (slip
op., at 2–3, and n. 2, 38–45); United States v. Miller , 307
U. S. 174 , 178 (1939). Although the Court acknowledged that
“the threat that the new Federal Government would destroy the
citizens’ militia by taking away their arms was the reason that right … was codified in a written Constitution,” the Court
asserted that “individual self defense … was the central
component of the right itself.” Heller, supra , at ___
(slip op., at 26) (first emphasis added). The Court went on to hold
that the Second Amendment restricted Congress’ power to regulate
handguns used for self-defense, and the Court found
unconstitutional the District of Columbia’s ban on the possession
of handguns in the home. Id. , at ___ (slip op., at
64).
The Court based its conclusions
almost exclusively upon its reading of history. But the relevant
history in Heller was far from clear: Four dissenting
Justices disagreed with the majority’s historical analysis. And
subsequent scholarly writing reveals why disputed history provides
treacherous ground on which to build decisions written by judges
who are not expert at history.
Since Heller, historians, scholars,
and judges have continued to express the view that the Court’s
historical account was flawed. See, e.g., Konig, Why the
Second Amendment Has a Preamble: Original Public Meaning and the
Political Culture of Written Constitutions in Revolutionary
America, 56 UCLA L. Rev. 1295 (2009); Finkelman, It Really Was
About a Well Regulated Militia, 59 Syracuse L. Rev. 267
(2008); P. Charles, The Second Amendment: The Intent and Its
Interpretation by the States and the Supreme Court (2009); Merkel, The District of Columbia v. Heller and
Antonin Scalia’s Perverse Sense of Originalism, 13 Lewis &
Clark L. Rev. 349 (2009); Kozuskanich, Originalism in a
Digital Age: An Inquiry into the Right to Bear Arms, 29 J. Early
Republic 585 (2009); Cornell, St. George Tucker’s Lecture Notes,
the Second Amendment, and Originalist Methodology, 103 Nw.
U. L. Rev. 1541 (2009); Posner, In Defense of Looseness:
The Supreme Court and Gun Control, New Republic, Aug. 27, 2008, pp.
32–35; see also Epstein, A Structural Interpretation of the Second
Amendment: Why Heller is (Probably) Wrong on Originalist
Grounds, 59 Syracuse L. Rev. 171 (2008).
Consider as an example of these critiques an amici brief filed in this case by historians who
specialize in the study of the English Civil Wars. They tell us
that Heller misunderstood a key historical point. See
Brief for English/Early American Historians as Amici
Curiae (hereinafter English Historians’ Brief) (filed by 21
professors at leading universities in the United States, United
Kingdom, and Australia). Heller ’s conclusion that
“individual self-defense” was “the central component ” of
the Second Amendment’s right “to keep and bear Arms” rested upon
its view that the Amendment “codified a pre-existing right” that had “nothing whatever to do with service in a militia.”
554 U. S., at ___ (slip op., at 26, 19–20). That view in turn
rested in significant part upon Blackstone having described the
right as “ ‘the right of having and using arms for
self-preservation and defence,’ ” which reflected the
provision in the English Declaration of Right of 1689 that gave the
King’s Protestant “ ‘subjects’ ” the right to
“ ‘have Arms for their defence suitable to their Conditions,
and as allowed by law.’ ” Id. , at ___ (slip op., at
19–20) (quoting 1 W. Blackstone, Commentaries on the Laws of
England 140 (1765) (hereinafter Blackstone) and 1 W. & M., c.
2, §7, in 3 Eng. Stat. at Large 441 (1689)). The Framers, said the
majority, understood that right “as permitting a citizen to
‘repe[l] force by force’ when ‘the intervention of society in his
behalf, may be too late to prevent an injury.’ ” 554 U. S., at
___ (slip op., at 21) (quoting St. George Tucker, 1 Blackstone’s
Commentaries 145–146, n. 42 (1803)).
The historians now tell us, however, that the
right to which Blackstone referred had, not nothing , but everything , to do with the militia. As properly understood
at the time of the English Civil Wars, the historians claim, the
right to bear arms “ensured that Parliament had the power”
to arm the citizenry: “to defend the realm” in the case of a
foreign enemy, and to “secure the right of
‘self-preservation,’ ” or “self-defense,” should “ the
sovereign usurp the English Constitution.” English Historians’
Brief 3, 8–13, 23–24 (emphasis added). Thus, the Declaration of
Right says that private persons can possess guns only “as allowed
by law.” See id., at 20–24. Moreover, when Blackstone
referred to “ ‘the right of having and using arms for
self-preservation and defence,’ ” he was referring to the
right of the people “ to take part in the militia to defend
their political liberties ,” and to the right of
Parliament (which represented the people) to raise a
militia even when the King sought to deny it that power. Id., at 4, 24–27 (emphasis added) (quoting 1 Blackstone
140). Nor can the historians find any convincing reason to believe
that the Framers had something different in mind than what
Blackstone himself meant. Compare Heller, supra, at ___
(slip op., at 21–22) with English Historians’ Brief 28–40. The
historians concede that at least one historian takes a different
position, see id., at 7, but the Court, they imply, would
lose a poll taken among professional historians of this period,
say, by a vote of 8 to 1.
If history, and history alone, is what
matters, why would the Court not now reconsider Heller in
light of these more recently published historical views? See Leegin Creative Leather Products, Inc. v. PSKS,
Inc. , 551 U. S.
877 , 923–924 (2007) (Breyer, J., dissenting) (noting that stare decisis interests are at their lowest with respect
to recent and erroneous constitutional decisions that create
unworkable legal regimes); Citizens United v. Federal
Election Comm’n , 558 U. S. ___, ___ (2010) (slip op., at 47)
(listing similar factors); see also Wallace v. Jaffree , 472
U. S. 38 , 99 (1985) (Rehnquist, J., dissenting) (“ [S]tare
decisis may bind courts as to matters of law, but it cannot
bind them as to matters of history”). At the least, where Heller ’s historical foundations are so uncertain, why
extend its applicability?
My aim in referring to this history is to
illustrate the reefs and shoals that lie in wait for those
nonexpert judges who place virtually determinative weight upon
historical considerations. In my own view, the Court should not
look to history alone but to other factors as well—above all, in
cases where the history is so unclear that the experts themselves
strongly disagree. It should, for example, consider the basic
values that underlie a constitutional provision and their
contemporary significance. And it should examine as well the
relevant consequences and practical justifications that might, or
might not, warrant removing an important question from the
democratic decisionmaking process. See ante , at 16–20
(Stevens, J., dissenting) (discussing shortcomings of an
exclusively historical approach).
II
A
In my view, taking Heller as a given, the Fourteenth Amendment does not
incorporate the Second Amendment right to keep and bear arms for
purposes of private self-defense. Under this Court’s precedents, to
incorporate the private self-defense right the majority must show
that the right is, e.g. , “fundamental to the American
scheme of justice,” Duncan v. Louisiana , 391 U. S. 145 , 149 (1968); see ibid. , n. 14; see also ante, at 44
(plurality opinion) (finding that the right is “fundamental” and
therefore incorporated). And this it fails to do.
The majority here, like that in Heller, relies almost exclusively upon history to make the
necessary showing. Ante, at 20–33. But to do so for
incorporation purposes is both wrong and dangerous. As Justice
Stevens points out, our society has historically made mistakes—for
example, when considering certain 18th- and 19th-century property
rights to be fundamental. Ante, at 19 (dissenting
opinion). And in the incorporation context, as elsewhere, history
often is unclear about the answers. See Part I, supra; Part III, infra. Accordingly, this Court, in
considering an incorporation question, has never stated that the
historical status of a right is the only relevant consideration.
Rather, the Court has either explicitly or implicitly made clear in
its opinions that the right in question has remained fundamental
over time. See, e.g., Apodaca v. Oregon , 406 U. S. 404 , 410
(1972) (plurality opinion) (stating that the incorporation “inquiry
must focus upon the function served” by the right in question in
“ contemporary society ” (emphasis added)); Duncan v. Louisiana , 391 U. S. 145 , 154 (1968) (noting that
the right in question “continues to receive strong support”); Klopfer v. North Carolina , 386 U. S. 213 , 226
(1967) (same). And, indeed, neither of the parties before us in
this case has asked us to employ the majority’s history-constrained
approach. See Brief for Petitioners 67–69 (arguing for
incorporation based on trends in contemporary support for the
right); Brief for Respondents City of Chicago et al. 23–31
(hereinafter Municipal Respondents) (looking to current state
practices with respect to the right).
I thus think it proper, above all where
history provides no clear answer, to look to other factors in
considering whether a right is sufficiently “fundamental” to remove
it from the political process in every State. I would include among
those factors the nature of the right; any contemporary
disagreement about whether the right is fundamental; the extent to
which incorporation will further other, perhaps more basic,
constitutional aims; and the extent to which incorporation will
advance or hinder the Constitution’s structural aims, including its
division of powers among different governmental institutions (and
the people as well). Is incorporation needed, for example, to
further the Constitution’s effort to ensure that the government
treats each individual with equal respect? Will it help maintain
the democratic form of government that the Constitution foresees?
In a word, will incorporation prove consistent, or inconsistent,
with the Constitution’s efforts to create governmental institutions
well suited to the carrying out of its constitutional promises?
Finally, I would take account of the Framers’
basic reason for believing the Court ought to have the power of
judicial review. Alexander Hamilton feared granting that power to
Congress alone, for he feared that Congress, acting as judges,
would not overturn as unconstitutional a popular statute that it
had recently enacted, as legislators. The Federalist No. 78, p. 405
(G. Carey & J. McClellan eds. 2001) (A. Hamilton) (“This
independence of the judges is equally requisite to guard the
constitution and the rights of individuals from the effects of
those ill humours, which” can, at times, lead to “serious
oppressions of the minor part in the community”). Judges, he
thought, may find it easier to resist popular pressure to suppress
the basic rights of an unpopular minority. See United
States v. Carolene Products Co. , 304 U. S. 144 , 152,
n. 4 (1938). That being so, it makes sense to ask whether that
particular comparative judicial advantage is relevant to the case
at hand. See, e.g., J. Ely, Democracy and Distrust
(1980).
B How do these
considerations apply here? For one thing, I would apply them only
to the private self-defense right directly at issue. After all, the
Amendment’s militia-related purpose is primarily to protect States from federal regulation, not to protect
individuals from militia-related regulation. Heller , 554
U. S., at ___ (slip op., at 26); see also Miller , 307 U.
S., at 178. Moreover, the Civil War Amendments, the electoral
process, the courts, and numerous other institutions today help to
safeguard the States and the people from any serious threat of
federal tyranny. How are state militias additionally necessary? It
is difficult to see how a right that, as the majority concedes, has
“largely faded as a popular concern” could possibly be so
fundamental that it would warrant incorporation through the
Fourteenth Amendment. Ante , at 22. Hence, the
incorporation of the Second Amendment cannot be based on the
militia-related aspect of what Heller found to be more
extensive Second Amendment rights.
For another thing, as Heller concedes, the private self-defense right that the
Court would incorporate has nothing to do with “the reason ” the Framers “codified” the right to keep and bear
arms “in a written Constitution.” 554 U. S., at ___ (slip op., at
26) (emphasis added). Heller immediately adds that the
self-defense right was nonetheless “the central component of the right.” Ibid. In my view, this is the historical
equivalent of a claim that water runs uphill. See Part I, supra . But, taking it as valid, the Framers’ basic reasons for including language in the Constitution would
nonetheless seem more pertinent (in deciding about the contemporary importance of a right) than the particular scope 17th- or 18th-century listeners would have then assigned to the
words they used. And examination of the Framers’ motivation tells
us they did not think the private armed self-defense right was of
paramount importance. See Amar, The Bill of Rights as a
Constitution, 100 Yale L. J. 1131, 1164 (1991) (“[T]o see the
[Second] Amendment as primarily concerned with an individual right
to hunt, or protect one’s home,” would be “like viewing the heart
of the speech and assembly clauses as the right of persons to meet
to play bridge”); see also, e.g., Rakove, The Second
Amendment: The Highest Stage of Originalism, 76 Chi.-Kent
L. Rev. 103, 127–128 (2000); Brief for Historians on Early
American Legal, Constitutional, and Pennsylvania History as Amici Curiae 22–33.
Further, there is no popular consensus that
the private self-defense right described in Heller is
fundamental. The plurality suggests that two amici briefs
filed in the case show such a consensus, see ante , at
42–43, but, of course, numerous amici briefs have been
filed opposing incorporation as well. Moreover, every State
regulates firearms extensively, and public opinion is sharply
divided on the appropriate level of regulation. Much of this
disagreement rests upon empirical considerations. One side believes
the right essential to protect the lives of those attacked in the
home; the other side believes it essential to regulate the right in
order to protect the lives of others attacked with guns. It seems
unlikely that definitive evidence will develop one way or the
other. And the appropriate level of firearm regulation has thus
long been, and continues to be, a hotly contested matter of
political debate. See, e.g., Siegel, Dead or Alive:
Originalism as Popular Constitutionalism in Heller , 122
Harv. L. Rev. 191, 201–246 (2008). (Numerous sources
supporting arguments and data in Part II–B can be found in the
Appendix, infra. )
Moreover, there is no reason here to believe
that incorporation of the private self-defense right will further
any other or broader constitutional objective. We are aware of no
argument that gun-control regulations target or are passed with the
purpose of targeting “discrete and insular minorities.” Carolene Products Co. , supra , at 153, n. 4;
see, e.g., ante, at 49–51 (Stevens, J.,
dissenting). Nor will incorporation help to assure equal respect
for individuals. Unlike the First Amendment’s rights of free
speech, free press, assembly, and petition, the private
self-defense right does not comprise a necessary part of the
democratic process that the Constitution seeks to establish. See, e.g., Whitney v. California , 274 U. S. 357 , 377
(1927) (Brandeis, J., concurring). Unlike the First Amendment’s
religious protections, the Fourth Amendment’s protection against
unreasonable searches and seizures, the Fifth and Sixth Amendments’
insistence upon fair criminal procedure, and the Eighth Amendment’s
protection against cruel and unusual punishments, the private
self-defense right does not significantly seek to protect
individuals who might otherwise suffer unfair or inhumane treatment
at the hands of a majority. Unlike the protections offered by many
of these same Amendments, it does not involve matters as to which
judges possess a comparative expertise, by virtue of their close
familiarity with the justice system and its operation. And, unlike
the Fifth Amendment’s insistence on just compensation, it does not
involve a matter where a majority might unfairly seize for itself
property belonging to a minority. Finally, incorporation of the right will work a significant disruption in the constitutional
allocation of decisionmaking authority, thereby interfering with
the Constitution’s ability to further its objectives. First, on any reasonable accounting,
the incorporation of the right recognized in Heller would
amount to a significant incursion on a traditional and important
area of state concern, altering the constitutional relationship
between the States and the Federal Government. Private gun
regulation is the quintessential exercise of a State’s “police
power”— i.e. , the power to “protec[t] … the lives, limbs,
health, comfort, and quiet of all persons, and the protection of
all property within the State,” by enacting “all kinds of
restraints and burdens” on both “persons and property.” Slaughter-House Cases , 16 Wall. 36, 62 (1873) (internal
quotation marks omitted). The Court has long recognized that the
Constitution grants the States special authority to enact laws
pursuant to this power. See, e.g., Medtronic, Inc. v. Lohr , 518
U. S. 470 , 475 (1996) (noting that States have “great latitude”
to use their police powers (internal quotation marks omitted)); Metropolitan Life Ins. Co. v. Massachusetts , 471 U. S. 724 ,
756 (1985). A decade ago, we wrote that there is “no better example
of the police power” than “the suppression of violent crime.” United States v. Morrison , 529 U. S. 598 , 618
(2000). And examples in which the Court has deferred to state
legislative judgments in respect to the exercise of the police
power are legion. See, e.g., Gonzales v. Oregon , 546
U. S. 243 , 270 (2006) (assisted suicide); Washington v. Glucksberg, 521 U. S. 702 , 721
(1997) (same); Berman v. Parker , 348 U. S. 26 , 32 (1954)
(“We deal, in other words, with what traditionally has been known
as the police power. An attempt to define its reach or trace its
outer limits is fruitless …”). Second, determining the
constitutionality of a particular state gun law requires finding
answers to complex empirically based questions of a kind that
legislatures are better able than courts to make. See, e.g., Los Angeles v. Alameda Books,
Inc. , 535 U. S.
425 , 440 (2002) (plurality opinion); Turner Broadcasting
System, Inc. v. FCC , 520 U. S. 180 , 195–196
(1997). And it may require this kind of analysis in virtually every
case.
Government regulation of the right to bear
arms normally embodies a judgment that the regulation will help
save lives. The determination whether a gun regulation is
constitutional would thus almost always require the weighing of the
constitutional right to bear arms against the “primary concern of
every government—a concern for the safety and indeed the lives of
its citizens.” United States v. Salerno , 481 U. S. 739 , 755
(1987). With respect to other incorporated rights, this sort of
inquiry is sometimes present. See, e.g., Brandenburg v. Ohio , 395 U. S. 444 , 447
(1969) (per curiam) (free speech); Sherbert v. Verner , 374
U. S. 398 , 403 (1963) (religion); Brigham City v. Stuart , 547
U. S. 398 , 403–404 (2006) (Fourth Amendment); New York v. Quarles , 467 U. S. 649 , 655
(1984) (Fifth Amendment); Salerno, supra , at 755 (bail).
But here, this inquiry—calling for the fine tuning of protective
rules—is likely to be part of a daily judicial diet.
Given the competing interests, courts will
have to try to answer empirical questions of a particularly
difficult kind. Suppose, for example, that after a gun regulation’s
adoption the murder rate went up. Without the gun regulation would
the murder rate have risen even faster? How is this conclusion
affected by the local recession which has left numerous people
unemployed? What about budget cuts that led to a downsizing of the
police force? How effective was that police force to begin with?
And did the regulation simply take guns from those who use them for
lawful purposes without affecting their possession by
criminals?
Consider too that countless gun regulations of
many shapes and sizes are in place in every State and in many local
communities. Does the right to possess weapons for self-defense
extend outside the home? To the car? To work? What sort of guns are
necessary for self-defense? Handguns? Rifles? Semiautomatic
weapons? When is a gun semi-automatic? Where are different kinds of
weapons likely needed? Does time-of-day matter? Does the presence
of a child in the house matter? Does the presence of a convicted
felon in the house matter? Do police need special rules permitting
patdowns designed to find guns? When do registration requirements
become severe to the point that they amount to an unconstitutional
ban? Who can possess guns and of what kind? Aliens? Prior drug
offenders? Prior alcohol abusers? How would the right interact with
a state or local government’s ability to take special measures
during, say, national security emergencies? As the questions
suggest, state and local gun regulation can become highly complex,
and these “are only a few uncertainties that quickly come to mind.” Caperton v. A. T. Massey Coal Co. , 556 U. S. ___,
___ (2009) (Roberts, C. J., dissenting) (slip op., at 10).
The difficulty of finding answers to these
questions is exceeded only by the importance of doing so. Firearms
cause well over 60,000 deaths and injuries in the United States
each year. Those who live in urban areas, police officers, women,
and children, all may be particularly at risk. And gun regulation
may save their lives. Some experts have calculated, for example,
that Chicago’s handgun ban has saved several hundred lives, perhaps
close to 1,000, since it was enacted in 1983. Other experts argue
that stringent gun regulations “can help protect police officers
operating on the front lines against gun violence,” have reduced
homicide rates in Washington, D. C., and Baltimore, and have
helped to lower New York’s crime and homicide rates.
At the same time, the opponents of regulation
cast doubt on these studies. And who is right? Finding out may
require interpreting studies that are only indirectly related to a
particular regulatory statute, say one banning handguns in the
home. Suppose studies find more accidents and suicides where there
is a handgun in the home than where there is a long gun in the home
or no gun at all? To what extent do such studies justify a ban?
What if opponents of the ban put forth counter studies?
In answering such questions judges cannot
simply refer to judicial homilies, such as Blackstone’s
18th-century perception that a man’s home is his castle. See 4
Blackstone 223. Nor can the plurality so simply reject, by mere
assertion, the fact that “incorporation will require judges to
assess the costs and benefits of firearms restrictions.” Ante , at 44. How can the Court assess the strength of the
government’s regulatory interests without addressing issues of
empirical fact? How can the Court determine if a regulation is
appropriately tailored without considering its impact? And how can
the Court determine if there are less restrictive alternatives
without considering what will happen if those alternatives are
implemented?
Perhaps the Court could lessen the difficulty
of the mission it has created for itself by adopting a
jurisprudential approach similar to the many state courts that
administer a state constitutional right to bear arms. See infra , at 19–20 (describing state approaches). But the
Court has not yet done so. Cf. Heller, 544 U. S., at ___
(slip op., at 57–64) (rejecting an “ ‘interest-balancing’
approach” similar to that employed by the States); ante ,
at 44 (plurality opinion). Rather, the Court has haphazardly
created a few simple rules, such as that it will not touch
“prohibitions on the possession of firearms by felons and the
mentally ill,” “laws forbidding the carrying of firearms in
sensitive places such as schools and government buildings,” or
“laws imposing conditions and qualifications on the commercial sale
of arms.” Heller , 544 U. S., at ___ (slip op., at 54–55); Ante, at 39 (plurality opinion). But why these rules and
not others? Does the Court know that these regulations are
justified by some special gun-related risk of death? In fact, the
Court does not know. It has simply invented rules that sound
sensible without being able to explain why or how Chicago’s handgun
ban is different.
The fact is that judges do not know the
answers to the kinds of empirically based questions that will often
determine the need for particular forms of gun regulation. Nor do
they have readily available “tools” for finding and evaluating the
technical material submitted by others. District Attorney’s
Office for Third Judicial Dist. v. Osborne , 557 U. S.
___, ___ (2009) (slip op., at 21); see also Turner
Broadcasting , 520 U. S., at 195–196 . Judges cannot
easily make empirically based predictions; they have no way to
gather and evaluate the data required to see if such predictions
are accurate; and the nature of litigation and concerns about stare decisis further make it difficult for judges to
change course if predictions prove inaccurate. Nor can judges rely
upon local community views and values when reaching judgments in
circumstances where prediction is difficult because the basic facts
are unclear or unknown.
At the same time, there is no institutional
need to send judges off on this “mission-almost-impossible.”
Legislators are able to “amass the stuff of actual experience and
cull conclusions from it.” United States v. Gainey , 380
U. S. 63 , 67 (1965). They are far better suited than judges to
uncover facts and to understand their relevance. And legislators,
unlike Article III judges, can be held democratically responsible
for their empirically based and value-laden conclusions. We have
thus repeatedly affirmed our preference for “legislative not
judicial solutions” to this kind of problem, see, e.g., Patsy v. Board of Regents of Fla. , 457 U. S. 496 , 513
(1982), just as we have repeatedly affirmed the Constitution’s
preference for democratic solutions legislated by those whom the
people elect.
In New State Ice Co. v. Liebmann , 285 U. S. 262 , 310–311
(1932), Justice Brandeis stated in dissent:
“Some people assert that our present plight is due,
in part, to the limitations set by courts upon experimentation in
the fields of social and economic science; and to the
discouragement to which proposals for betterment there have been
subjected otherwise. There must be power in the States and the
Nation to remould, through experimentation, our economic practices
and institutions to meet changing social and economic needs. I
cannot believe that the framers of the Fourteenth Amendment, or the
States which ratified it, intended to deprive us of the power to
correct [the social problems we face].”
There are 50 state legislatures.
The fact that this Court may already have refused to take this wise
advice with respect to Congress in Heller is no reason to
make matters worse here. Third, the ability of States to
reflect local preferences and conditions—both key virtues of
federalism—here has particular importance. The incidence of gun
ownership varies substantially as between crowded cities and
uncongested rural communities, as well as among the different
geographic regions of the country. Thus, approximately 60% of
adults who live in the relatively sparsely populated Western States
of Alaska, Montana, and Wyoming report that their household keeps a
gun, while fewer than 15% of adults in the densely populated
Eastern States of Rhode Island, New Jersey, and Massachusetts say
the same.
The nature of gun violence also varies as
between rural communities and cities. Urban centers face
significantly greater levels of firearm crime and homicide, while
rural communities have proportionately greater problems with
nonhomicide gun deaths, such as suicides and accidents. And
idiosyncratic local factors can lead to two cities finding
themselves in dramatically different circumstances: For example, in
2008, the murder rate was 40 times higher in New Orleans than it
was in Lincoln, Nebraska.
It is thus unsurprising that States and local
communities have historically differed about the need for gun
regulation as well as about its proper level. Nor is it surprising
that “primarily, and historically,” the law has treated the
exercise of police powers, including gun control, as “matter[s] of
local concern.” Medtronic, 518 U. S., at 475 (internal
quotation marks omitted). Fourth, although incorporation of any
right removes decisions from the democratic process, the
incorporation of this particular right does so without strong
offsetting justification—as the example of Oak Park’s handgun ban
helps to show. See Oak Park, Ill., Municipal Code, §27–2–1 (1995).
Oak Park decided to ban handguns in 1983, after a local attorney
was shot to death with a handgun that his assailant had smuggled
into a courtroom in a blanket. Brief for Oak Park Citizens
Committee for Handgun Control as Amicus Curiae 1, 21
(hereinafter Oak Park Brief). A citizens committee spent months
gathering information about handguns. Id., at 21. It
secured 6,000 signatures from community residents in support of a
ban. Id., at 21–22. And the village board enacted a ban
into law. Id., at 22.
Subsequently, at the urging of ban opponents
the Board held a community referendum on the matter. Ibid. The citizens committee argued strongly in favor of the ban. Id., at 22–23. It pointed out that most guns owned in Oak
Park were handguns and that handguns were misused more often than
citizens used them in self-defense. Id., at 23. The ban
opponents argued just as strongly to the contrary. Ibid .
The public decided to keep the ban by a vote of 8,031 to 6,368. Ibid. And since that time, Oak Park now tells us, crime
has decreased and the community has seen no accidental handgun
deaths. Id., at 2.
Given the empirical and local value-laden
nature of the questions that lie at the heart of the issue, why, in
a Nation whose Constitution foresees democratic decisionmaking, is
it so fundamental a matter as to require taking that power
from the people? What is it here that the people did not know? What
is it that a judge knows better?
* * *
In sum, the police power, the
superiority of legislative decisionmaking, the need for local
decisionmaking, the comparative desirability of democratic
decisionmaking, the lack of a manageable judicial standard, and the
life-threatening harm that may flow from striking down regulations
all argue against incorporation. Where the incorporation of other
rights has been at issue, some of these problems have
arisen. But in this instance all these problems are
present, all at the same time, and all are likely
to be present in most, perhaps nearly all, of the cases in which
the constitutionality of a gun regulation is at issue. At the same
time, the important factors that favor incorporation in other
instances— e.g. , the protection of broader constitutional
objectives—are not present here. The upshot is that all factors
militate against incorporation—with the possible exception of
historical factors.
III
I must, then, return to history.
The plurality, in seeking to justify incorporation, asks whether
the interests the Second Amendment protects are “ ‘deeply
rooted in this Nation’s history and tradition.’ ” Ante , at 19 (quoting Glucksberg , 521 U. S., at
721; internal quotation marks omitted). It looks to selected
portions of the Nation’s history for the answer. And it finds an
affirmative reply.
As I have made clear, I do not
believe history is the only pertinent consideration. Nor would I
read history as broadly as the majority does. In particular, since
we here are evaluating a more particular right—namely, the right to
bear arms for purposes of private self-defense—general historical
references to the “right to keep and bear arms” are not always
helpful. Depending upon context, early historical sources may mean
to refer to a militia-based right—a matter of considerable
importance 200 years ago—which has, as the majority points out,
“largely faded as a popular concern.” Ante , at 22. There
is no reason to believe that matters of such little contemporary
importance should play a significant role in answering the
incorporation question. See Apodaca , 406 U. S., at 410
(incorporation “inquiry must focus upon the function served” by the
right in question in “contemporary society”); Wolf v. Colorado , 338 U. S. 25 , 27 (1949)
(incorporation must take into account “the movements of a free
society” and “the gradual and empiric process of inclusion and
exclusion” (internal quotation marks omitted)); cf. U. S. Const.,
Art. I, §910 (prohibiting federal officeholders from accepting a
“Title, of any kind whatever, from [a] foreign State”—presumably a
matter of considerable importance 200 years ago).
That said, I can find much in the historical
record that shows that some Americans in some places at certain
times thought it important to keep and bear arms for private
self-defense. For instance, the reader will see that many States
have constitutional provisions protecting gun possession. But, as
far as I can tell, those provisions typically do no more than
guarantee that a gun regulation will be a reasonable police power regulation. See Winkler, Scrutinizing the Second
Amendment, 105 Mich. L. Rev. 683, 686, 716–717 (2007) (the
“courts of every state to consider the question apply a deferential
‘reasonable regulation’ standard”) (hereinafter Winkler,
Scrutinizing); see also id. , at 716–717 (explaining the
difference between that standard and ordinary rational-basis
review). It is thus altogether unclear whether such provisions
would prohibit cities such as Chicago from enacting laws, such as
the law before us, banning handguns. See id., at 723. The
majority, however, would incorporate a right that is likely inconsistent with Chicago’s law; and the majority would
almost certainly strike down that law. Cf. Heller, 554 U. S., at ___ (slip op., at 57–64) (striking
down the District of Columbia’s handgun ban).
Thus, the specific question before us is not
whether there are references to the right to bear arms for
self-defense throughout this Nation’s history—of course there
are—or even whether the Court should incorporate a simple
constitutional requirement that firearms regulations not
unreasonably burden the right to keep and bear arms, but rather
whether there is a consensus that so substantial a private
self-defense right as the one described in Heller applies
to the States. See, e.g., Glucksberg , supra, at 721 (requiring “a careful description” of the
right at issue when deciding whether it is “deeply rooted in this
Nation’s history and tradition” (internal quotation marks
omitted)). On this question, the reader will have to make up his or
her own mind about the historical record that I describe in part
below. In my view, that record is insufficient to say that the
right to bear arms for private self-defense, as explicated by Heller , is fundamental in the sense relevant to the
incorporation inquiry. As the evidence below shows, States and
localities have consistently enacted firearms regulations,
including regulations similar to those at issue here, throughout
our Nation’s history. Courts have repeatedly upheld such
regulations. And it is, at the very least, possible, and perhaps
likely, that incorporation will impose on every, or nearly every,
State a different right to bear arms than they currently
recognize—a right that threatens to destabilize settled state legal
principles. Cf. 554 U. S., at ___ (slip op., at 57–64) (rejecting
an “ ‘interest-balancing’ approach” similar to that employed
by the States).
I thus cannot find a historical consensus with
respect to whether the right described by Heller is
“fundamental” as our incorporation cases use that term. Nor can I
find sufficient historical support for the majority’s conclusion
that that right is “deeply rooted in this Nation’s history and
tradition.” Instead, I find no more than ambiguity and uncertainty
that perhaps even expert historians would find difficult to
penetrate. And a historical record that is so ambiguous cannot
itself provide an adequate basis for incorporating a private right
of self-defense and applying it against the States. The Eighteenth Century The opinions in Heller collect much
of the relevant 18th-century evidence. See 554 U. S., at ___ (slip
op., at 5–32); id. , at ___ (Stevens, J., dissenting) (slip
op., at 5–31); id., at ___ (Breyer, J., dissenting) (slip
op., at 4–7). In respect to the relevant question—the “deeply
rooted nature” of a right to keep and bear arms for purposes of
private self-defense—that evidence is inconclusive, particularly
when augmented as follows: First , as I have noted earlier in
this opinion, and Justice Stevens argued in dissent, the history
discussed in Heller shows that the Second Amendment was
enacted primarily for the purpose of protecting militia-related
rights. See supra , at 4; Heller, supra, at ___
(slip op., at 5–31). Many of the scholars and historians who have
written on the subject apparently agree. See supra , at
2–5. Second , historians now tell us that
the right to which Blackstone referred, an important link in the Heller majority’s historical argument, concerned the right
of Parliament (representing the people) to form a militia to oppose
a tyrant (the King) threatening to deprive the people of their
traditional liberties (which did not include an unregulated right
to possess guns). Thus, 18th-century language referring to a “right
to keep and bear arms” does not ipso facto refer to a
private right of self-defense—certainly not unambiguously so. See
English Historians’ Brief 3–27; see also supra , at
2–5. Third , scholarly articles indicate
that firearms were heavily regulated at the time of the
framing—perhaps more heavily regulated than the Court in Heller believed. For example, one scholar writes that
“[h]undreds of individual statutes regulated the possession and use
of guns in colonial and early national America.” Churchill, Gun
Regulation, the Police Power, and the Right to Keep Arms, 25 Law
& Hist. Rev. 139, 143 (2007). Among these statutes was a ban on
the private firing of weapons in Boston, as well as comprehensive
restrictions on similar conduct in Philadelphia and New York. See
Acts and Laws of Massachusetts, p. 208 (1746); 5 J. Mitchell, &
H. Flanders, Statutes at Large of Pennsylvania From 1682 to 1801,
pp. 108–109 (1898); 4 Colonial Laws of New York ch. 1233, p. 748
(1894); see also Churchill, supra , at 162–163 (discussing
bans on the shooting of guns in Pennsylvania and New York). Fourth , after the Constitution was
adopted, several States continued to regulate firearms possession
by, for example, adopting rules that would have prevented the
carrying of loaded firearms in the city, Heller , 554 U.
S., at ___ (slip op., at 5–7) (Breyer, J., dissenting); see also id. , at ___ (slip op., at 59–60). Scholars have thus
concluded that the primary Revolutionary era limitation on a
State’s police power to regulate guns appears to be only that
regulations were “aimed at a legitimate public purpose” and
“consistent with reason.” Cornell, Early American Gun Regulation
and the Second Amendment, 25 Law & Hist. Rev. 197, 198
(2007). The Pre-Civil War Nineteenth Century I would also augment the majority’s account of
this period as follows: First , additional States began to
regulate the discharge of firearms in public places. See, e.g., Act of Feb. 17, 1831, §6, reprinted in 3 Statutes of
Ohio and the Northwestern Territory 1740 (S. Chase ed. 1835); Act
of Dec. 3, 1825, ch. CCXCII, §3, 1825 Tenn. Priv. Acts 306. Second , States began to regulate the
possession of concealed weapons, which were both popular and
dangerous. See, e.g., C. Cramer, Concealed Weapon Laws of
the Early Republic 143–152 (1999) (collecting examples); see also
1837–1838 Tenn. Pub. Acts ch. 137, pp. 200–201 (banning the
wearing, sale, or giving of Bowie knives); 1847 Va. Acts ch. 7, §8,
p. 110, (“Any free person who shall habitually carry about his
person, hidden from common observation, any pistol, dirk, bowie
knife, or weapon of the like kind, from the use of which the death
of any person might probably ensue, shall for every offense be
punished by [a] fine not exceed fifty dollars”).
State courts repeatedly upheld the validity of
such laws, finding that, even when the state constitution granted a
right to bear arms, the legislature was permitted to, e.g. , “abolish” these small, inexpensive, “most dangerous
weapons entirely from use,” even in self-defense. Day v. State , 37 Tenn. 496, 500 (1857); see also, e.g. , State v. Jumel , 13 La. Ann. 399, 400 (1858)
(upholding concealed weapon ban because it “prohibited only a particular mode of bearing arms which is found dangerous
to the peace of society”); State v. Chandler , 5
La. Ann. 489, 489–490 (1850) (upholding concealed weapon ban and
describing the law as “absolutely necessary to counteract a vicious
state of society, growing out of the habit of carrying concealed
weapons”); State v. Reid , 1 Ala. 612, 616–617
(1840). The Post-Civil War Nineteenth Century It is important to read the majority’s account
with the following considerations in mind: First, the Court today properly
declines to revisit our interpretation of the Privileges or
Immunities Clause. See ante , at 10. The Court’s case for
incorporation must thus rest on the conclusion that the right to
bear arms is “fundamental.” But the very evidence that it advances
in support of the conclusion that Reconstruction-era Americans
strongly supported a private self-defense right shows with equal
force that Americans wanted African-American citizens to have the same rights to possess guns as did white citizens. Ante, at 22–33. Here, for example is what Congress said
when it enacted a Fourteenth Amendment predecessor, the Second
Freedman’s Bureau Act. It wrote that the statute, in order to
secure “the constitutional right to bear arms … for all citizens,”
would assure that each citizen:
“shall have … full and equal benefit of
all laws and proceedings concerning personal liberty, personal
security, and the acquisition, enjoyment, and disposition of
estate, real and personal, including the constitutional right to
bear arms, [by securing] … to … all the citizens of [every] … State
or district without respect to race or color, or previous
condition of slavery.” §14, 14 Stat. 176–177 (emphasis
added).
This sounds like an antidiscrimination provision. See Rosenthal, The New Originalism Meets the Fourteenth
Amendment: Original Public Meaning and the Problem of
Incorporation, 18 J. Contemp. Legal Issues 361, 383–384 (2009)
(discussing evidence that the Freedmen’s Bureau was focused on
discrimination).
Another Fourteenth Amendment predecessor, the
Civil Rights Act of 1866, also took aim at discrimination. See §1, 14 Stat. 27 (citizens of “every race and color, without
regard to any previous condition of slavery or involuntary
servitude . . . shall have the same right [to engage in various
activities] and to full and equal benefit of all laws … as is
enjoyed by white citizens”). And, of course, the Fourteenth
Amendment itself insists that all States guarantee their citizens
the “equal protection of the laws.”
There is thus every reason to believe that the fundamental concern of the Reconstruction Congress was the
eradication of discrimination, not the provision of a new
substantive right to bear arms free from reasonable state police
power regulation. See, e.g., Brief for Municipal
Respondents 62–69 (discussing congressional record evidence that
Reconstruction Congress was concerned about discrimination).
Indeed, why would those who wrote the Fourteenth Amendment have
wanted to give such a right to Southerners who had so recently
waged war against the North, and who continued to disarm and
oppress recently freed African-American citizens? Cf. Act of Mar.
2, 1867, §6, 14 Stat. 487 (disbanding Southern militias because
they were, inter alia , disarming the freedmen). Second, firearms regulation in the
later part of the 19th century was common. The majority is correct
that the Freedmen’s Bureau points to a right to bear arms, and it
stands to reason, as the majority points out, that “[i]t would have
been nonsensical for Congress to guarantee the … equal benefit of a
… right that does not exist.” Ante , at 32. But the
majority points to no evidence that there existed during this
period a fundamental right to bear arms for private self-defense
immune to the reasonable exercise of the state police power. See
Emberton, The Limits of Incorporation: Violence, Gun Rights, and
Gun Regulation in the Reconstruction South, 17 Stan. L. & Pol’y
Rev. 615, 621–622 (2006) (noting that history shows that
“nineteenth-century Americans” were “not opposed to the idea that
the state should be able to control the use of firearms”).
To the contrary, in the latter half of the
19th century, a number of state constitutions adopted or amended
after the Civil War explicitly recognized the legislature’s general
ability to limit the right to bear arms. See Tex. Const., Art. I,
§13 (1869) (protecting “the right to keep and bear arms,” “under
such regulations as the legislature may prescribe”); Idaho Const.,
Art. I, §11 (1889) (“The people have the right to bear arms …; but
the Legislature shall regulate the exercise of this right by law”);
Utah Const., Art. I, §6 (1896) (same). And numerous other state
constitutional provisions adopted during this period explicitly
granted the legislature various types of regulatory power over
firearms. See Brief for Thirty-Four Professional Historians
et al. as Amici Curiae 14–15 (hereinafter Legal
Historians’ Brief).
Moreover, four States largely banned the
possession of all nonmilitary handguns during this period. See 1879
Tenn. Pub. Acts ch. 186, §1 (prohibiting citizens from carrying
“publicly or privately, any … belt or pocket pistol, revolver, or
any kind of pistol, except the army or navy pistol, usually used in
warfare, which shall be carried openly in the hand”); 1876 Wyo.
Comp. Laws ch. 52, §1 (forbidding “concealed or ope[n]” bearing of
“any fire arm or other deadly weapon, within the limits of any
city, town or village”); Ark. Act of Apr. 1, 1881, ch. 96, §1
(prohibiting the “wear[ing] or carry[ng]” of “any pistol … except
such pistols as are used in the army or navy,” except while
traveling or at home); Tex. Act of Apr. 12, 1871, ch. 34
(prohibiting the carrying of pistols unless there are “immediate
and pressing” reasonable grounds to fear “immediate and pressing”
attack or for militia service). Fifteen States banned the concealed
carry of pistols and other deadly weapons. See Legal Historians’
Brief 16, n. 14. And individual municipalities enacted
stringent gun controls, often in response to local conditions—Dodge
City, Kansas, for example, joined many western cattle towns in
banning the carrying of pistols and other dangerous weapons in
response to violence accompanying western cattle drives. See Brief
for Municipal Respondents 30 (citing Dodge City, Kan., Ordinance
No. 16, §XI (Sept. 22, 1876)); D. Courtwright, The Cowboy
Subculture, in Guns in America: A Reader 96 (J. Dizard et al.
eds. 1999) (discussing how Western cattle towns required cowboys to
“check” their guns upon entering town).
Further, much as they had during the period
before the Civil War, state courts routinely upheld such
restrictions. See, e.g., English v. State , 35
Tex. 473 (1871); Hill v. State , 53 Ga. 472, 475
(1874); Fife v. State , 31 Ark. 455, 461 (1876); State v. Workman , 35 W. Va. 367, 373 (1891).
The Tennessee Supreme Court, in upholding a ban on possession of
nonmilitary handguns and certain other weapons, summarized the
Reconstruction understanding of the states’ police power to
regulate firearms:
“Admitting the right of self-defense in its
broadest sense, still on sound principle every good citizen is
bound to yield his preference as to the means to be used, to the
demands of the public good; and where certain weapons are
forbidden to be kept or used by the law of the land , in order
to the prevention of [sic] crime—a great public end— no
man can be permitted to disregard this general end, and demand of
the community the right, in order to gratify his whim or willful
desire to use a particular weapon in his particular
self-defense . The law allows ample means of self-defense,
without the use of the weapons which we have held may be rightfully
prescribed by this statute. The object being to banish these
weapons from the community by an absolute prohibition for the
prevention of crime, no man’s particular safety, if such case could
exist, ought to be allowed to defeat this end.” Andrews v. State , 50 Tenn. 165, 188–189 (1871) (emphasis added). The Twentieth and Twenty-First
Centuries Although the majority does not discuss 20th-
or 21st-century evidence concerning the Second Amendment at any
length, I think that it is essential to consider the recent history
of the right to bear arms for private self-defense when considering
whether the right is “fundamental.” To that end, many States now
provide state constitutional protection for an individual’s right
to keep and bear arms. See Volokh, State Constitutional Rights to
Keep and Bear Arms, 11 Tex. Rev. L. & Pol. 191, 205 (2006)
(identifying over 40 States). In determining the importance of this
fact, we should keep the following considerations in mind: First , by the end of the 20th
century, in every State and many local communities, highly detailed
and complicated regulatory schemes governed (and continue to
govern) nearly every aspect of firearm ownership: Who may sell guns
and how they must be sold; who may purchase guns and what type of
guns may be purchased; how firearms must be stored and where they
may be used; and so on. See generally Legal Community Against
Violence, Regulating Guns In America (2008), available at http://
www.lcav.org/publications-briefs/regulating_guns. asp (all Internet
materials as visited June 24, 2010, and available in Clerk of
Court’s case file) (detailing various arms regulations in every
State).
Of particular relevance here, some
municipalities ban handguns, even in States that constitutionally
protect the right to bear arms. See Chicago, Ill., Municipal Code,
§8–20–050(c) (2009); Oak Park, Ill., Municipal Code, §§27–2–1,
27–1–1 (1995); Toledo, Ohio, Municipal Code, ch. 549.25 (2010).
Moreover, at least seven States and Puerto Rico ban assault weapons
or semiautomatic weapons. See Cal. Penal Code Ann. §12280(b) (West
Supp. 2009); Conn. Gen. Stat. Ann. §53–202c (2007); Haw. Rev. Stat.
§134–8 (1993); Md. Crim. Law Code Ann. §4–303(a) (Lexis 2002);
Mass. Gen. Laws, ch. 140, §131M (West 2006); N. J. Stat. Ann.
§2C:39-5 (West Supp. 2010); N. Y. Penal Law Ann. §265.02(7) (West
Supp. 2008); 25 Laws P. R. Ann. §456m (Supp. 2006); see also 18 U.
S. C. §922 (o) (federal machinegun ban).
Thirteen municipalities do the same. See
Albany, N. Y., City Code §193–16(A) (2005); Aurora, Ill., Code of
Ordinances §29–49(a) (2009); Buffalo, N. Y., City Code §180–1(F)
(2000); Chicago, Ill., Municipal Code §8–24–025(a) (2010);
Cincinnati, Ohio, Municipal Code §708–37(a) (2008); Cleveland,
Ohio, Codified Ordinances §628.03(a) (2008); Columbus, Ohio, City
Code §2323.31 (2007); Denver, Colo., Municipal Code §38–130(e)
(2008); Morton Grove, Ill., Village Code §6–2–3(A); N. Y. C. Admin.
Code §10–303.1 (2009); Oak Park, Ill., Village Code §27–2–1 (2009);
Rochester, N. Y., City Code §47–5(F) (2008); Toledo, Ohio,
Municipal Code §549.23(a). And two States, Maryland and Hawaii, ban
assault pistols. See Haw. Rev. Stat. Ann. §134–8; Md. Crim. Law
Code Ann. §4–303 (Lexis 2002). Second, as I stated earlier, state
courts in States with constitutions that provide gun rights have
almost uniformly interpreted those rights as providing protection
only against unreasonable regulation of guns. See, e.g., Winkler, Scrutinizing 686 (the “courts of every
state to consider” a gun regulation apply the “ ‘reasonable
regulation’ ” approach); State v. McAdams ,
714 P. 2d 1236, 1238 (Wyo. 1986); Robertson v. City & County of Denver , 874 P. 2d 325, 328
(Colo. 1994).
When determining reasonableness those courts
have normally adopted a highly deferential attitude towards
legislative determinations. See Winkler, Scrutinizing 723
(identifying only six cases in the 60 years before the article’s
publication striking down gun control laws: three that banned “the
transportation of any firearms for any purpose whatsoever,” a
single “permitting law,” and two as-applied challenges in “unusual
circumstances”). Hence, as evidenced by the breadth of existing
regulations, States and local governments maintain substantial
flexibility to regulate firearms—much as they seemingly have
throughout the Nation’s history—even in those States with an arms
right in their constitutions.
Although one scholar implies that state
courts are less willing to permit total gun prohibitions, see
Volokh, Implementing the Right to Keep and Bear Arms for
Self-Defense: An Analytical Framework and a Research Agenda, 56
UCLA L. Rev. 1443, 1458 (2009), I am aware of no instances in
the past 50 years in which a state court has struck down as
unconstitutional a law banning a particular class of firearms, see
Winkler, Scrutinizing 723.
Indeed, state courts have specifically upheld
as constitutional (under their state constitutions) firearms
regulations that have included handgun bans. See Kalodimos v. Village of Morton Grove , 103 Ill. 2d 483, 499, 470
N. E. 2d 266, 273 (1984) (upholding a handgun ban because the
arms right is merely a right “to possess some form of weapon
suitable for self-defense or recreation”); Cleveland v. Turner, No. 36126, 1977 WL 201393, *5 (Ohio Ct. App., Aug.
4, 1977) (handgun ban “does not absolutely interfere with the right
of the people to bear arms, but rather proscribes possession of a
specifically defined category of handguns”); State v. Bolin 378 S. C. 96, 99, 662 S. E. 2d 38, 39
(2008) (ban on handgun possession by persons under 21 did not
infringe arms right because they can “posses[s] other types of
guns”). Thus, the majority’s decision to incorporate the private
self-defense right recognized in Heller threatens to alter
state regulatory regimes, at least as they pertain to handguns. Third , the plurality correctly points
out that only a few state courts, a “paucity” of state
courts, have specifically upheld handgun bans. Ante, at
39. But which state courts have struck them down? The absence of
supporting information does not help the majority find support. Cf. United States v. Wells , 519 U. S. 482 , 496
(1997) (noting that it is “treacherous to find in congressional
silence alone the adoption of a controlling rule of law” (internal
quotation marks omitted)). Silence does not show or tend to show a
consensus that a private self-defense right (strong enough to
strike down a handgun ban) is “deeply rooted in this Nation’s
history and tradition.”
* * *
In sum, the Framers did not write
the Second Amendment in order to protect a private right of armed
self-defense. There has been, and is, no consensus that the right
is, or was, “fundamental.” No broader constitutional interest or
principle supports legal treatment of that right as fundamental. To
the contrary, broader constitutional concerns of an institutional
nature argue strongly against that treatment.
Moreover, nothing in 18th-,
19th-, 20th-, or 21st-century history shows a consensus that the
right to private armed self-defense, as described in Heller , is “deeply rooted in this Nation’s history or
tradition” or is otherwise “fundamental.” Indeed, incorporating the
right recognized in Heller may change the law in many of
the 50 States. Read in the majority’s favor, the historical
evidence is at most ambiguous. And, in the absence of any other
support for its conclusion, ambiguous history cannot show that the
Fourteenth Amendment incorporates a private right of self-defense
against the States.
With respect, I dissent.
APPENDIX
Sources Supporting Data in Part II–B Popular Consensus Please see the following sources to support the paragraph on
popular opinion on pages 9–10:
•Briefs filed in this case that argue against incorporation
include: Brief for United States Conference of Mayors as Amicus
Curiae 1, 17–33 (organization representing “all United States
cities with populations of 30,000 or more”); Brief for American
Cities et al. as Amici Curiae 1–3 (brief filed on
behalf of many cities, e.g. , Philadelphia, Seattle, San
Francisco, Oakland, Cleveland); Brief for Representative Carolyn
McCarthy et al. as Amici Curiae 5–10; Brief for State
of Illinois et al. as Amici Curiae 7–35.
•Wilkinson, Of Guns, Abortions, and the Unraveling Rule of Law,
95 Va. L. Rev. 253, 301 (2009) (discussing divided public
opinion over the correct level of gun control). Data on Gun Violence Please see the following sources to support
the sentences concerning gun violence on page 13:
•Dept. of Justice, Bureau of Justice Statistics, M. Zawitz &
K. Strom, Firearm Injury and Death from Crime, 1993–1997, p. 2
(Oct. 2000) (over 60,000 deaths and injuries caused by firearms
each year).
•Campbell, et al., Risk Factors for Femicide in Abusive
Relationships: Results from a Multisite Case Control Study, 93 Am.
J. of Pub. Health 1089, 1092 (2003) (noting that an abusive
partner’s access to a firearm increases the risk of homicide
eightfold for women in physically abusive relationship).
•American Academy of Pediatrics, Firearm-Related Injuries
Affecting the Pediatric Population, 105 Pediatrics 888 (2000)
(noting that in 1997 “firearm-related deaths accounted for 22.5% of
all injury deaths” for individuals between 1 and 19).
•Dept. of Justice, Federal Bureau of Investigation, Law
Enforcement Officers Killed & Assaulted, 2006, (Table) 27
(noting that firearms killed 93% of the 562 law enforcement
officers feloniously killed in the line of duty between 1997 and
2006), online at http://www.fbi.gov/ucr/killed/2006/
table27.html.
•Dept. of Justice, Bureau of Justice Statistics, D. Duhart,
Urban, Suburban, and Rural Victimization, 1993–1998, pp. 1, 9 (Oct.
2000) (those who live in urban areas particularly at risk of
firearm violence).
•Wintemute, The Future of Firearm Violence Prevention, 281 JAMA
475 (1999) (“half of all homicides occurred in 63 cities with 16%
of the nation’s population”). Data on the Effectiveness of Regulation Please see the following sources to support
the sentences concerning the effectiveness of regulation on page
13:
•See Brief for Professors of Criminal Justice as Amici
Curiae 13 (noting that Chicago’s handgun ban saved several
hundred lives, perhaps close to 1,000, since it was enacted in
1983).
•Brief for Association of Prosecuting Attorneys et al. as Amici Curiae 13–16, 20 (arguing that stringent gun
regulations “can help protect police officers operating on the
front lines against gun violence,” and have reduced homicide rates
in Washington, D. C., and Baltimore).
•Brief for United States Conference of Mayors as Amici
Curiae 4–13 (arguing that gun regulations have helped to lower
New York’s crime and homicide rates). Data on Handguns in the Home Please see the following sources referenced in
the sentences discussing studies concerning handguns in the
home on pages 13–14:
•Brief for Organizations Committed to Protecting the Public’s
Health, Safety, and Well-Being as Amici Curiae in Support
of Respondents 13–16 (discussing studies that show handgun
ownership in the home is associated with increased risk of
homicide).
•Wiebe, Firearms in US Homes as a Risk Factor for Unintentional
Gunshot Fatality, 35 Accident Analysis and Prevention 711, 713–714
(2003) (showing that those who die in firearms accidents are nearly
four times more likely than average to have a gun in their
home).
•Kellerman et al., Suicide in the Home in Relation to Gun
Ownership, 327 New England J. Medicine 467, 470 (1992)
(demonstrating that “homes with one or more handguns were
associated with a risk of suicide almost twice as high as that in
homes containing only long guns”). Data on Regional Views and Conditions Please see the following sources referenced in
the section on the diversity of regional views and conditions on
page 16:
•Okoro, et al., Prevalence of Household Firearms and
Firearm-Storage Practices in the 50 States and the District of
Columbia: Findings From the Behavioral Risk Factor Surveillance
System, 2002, 116 Pediatrics 370, 372 (2005) (presenting data on
firearm ownership by State).
•Heller, 554 U. S., at ___ (Breyer, J., dissenting) (slip op.,
at 19–20) (discussing various sources showing that gun violence
varies by state, including Wintemute, The Future of Firearm
Violence Prevention, 281 JAMA 475 (1999)).
•Heller, supra, at ___ (Breyer, J., dissenting) (slip op., at
19–20) (citing Branas, Nance, Elliott, Richmond, & Schwab,
Urban-Rural Shifts in Intentional Firearm Death, 94 Am. J. Public
Health 1750, 1752 (2004)) (discussing the fact that urban centers
face significantly greater levels of firearm crime and homicide,
while rural communities have proportionately greater problems with
nonhomicide gun deaths, such as suicides and accidents).
•Dept. of Justice, Federal Bureau of Investigation, 2008 Crime
in the United States, tbl. 6 (noting that murder rate is 40 times
higher in New Orleans than it is in Lincoln, Nebraska). | In McDonald v. Chicago, the Supreme Court ruled that the Second Amendment, which protects the right to keep and bear arms for self-defense, applies to state and local governments in addition to the federal government. This means that Chicago and Oak Park's handgun bans were unconstitutional. The Court considered data on handgun ownership and regional conditions but ultimately sided with the petitioners, who argued that the handgun ban left them vulnerable to criminals. |
Equal Protection | Fisher v. University of Texas | https://supreme.justia.com/cases/federal/us/570/297/ | NOTICE: This opinion is subject to
formal revision before publication in the preliminary print of the
United States Reports. Readers are requested to notify the
Reporter of Decisions, Supreme Court of the United States,
Washington, D. C. 20543, of any typographical or other formal
errors, in order that corrections may be made before the
preliminary print goes to press.
SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES
_________________
No. 11–345
_________________
ABIGAIL NOEL FISHER, PETITIONER v. UNIVERSITY
OF TEXAS AT AUSTIN et al.
on writ of certiorari to the united states
court of appeals for the fifth circuit
[June 24, 2013]
Justice Kennedy
delivered the opinion of the Court.
The University of Texas
at Austin considers race as one of various factors in its
undergraduate admissions process. Race is not itself assigned a
numerical value for each ap-plicant, but the University has
committed itself to increasing racial minority enrollment on
campus. It refers to this goal as a “critical mass.”
Petitioner, who is Caucasian, sued the University after her
application was re-jected. She contends that the University’s
use of race in the admissions process violated the Equal Protection
Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment.
The parties asked the
Court to review whether the judgment below was consistent with
“this Court’s deci-sions interpreting the Equal
Protection Clause of the Four- teenth Amendment, including Grutter
v. Bollinger, 539 U. S. 306 (2003) .” Pet. for Cert. i.
The Court concludes that the Court of Appeals did not hold the
University to the demanding burden of strict scrutiny articulated
in Grutter and Regents of Univ. of Cal. v. Bakke, 438 U. S.
265, 305 (1978) (opinion of Powell, J.). Because the Court of
Appeals did not apply the correct standard of strict scrutiny, its
decision affirming the District Court’s grant of summary
judgment to the University was incorrect. That decision is vacated,
and the case is remanded for further proceedings.
I
A
Located in Austin,
Texas, on the most renowned campus of the Texas state university
system, the University is one of the leading institutions of higher
education in the Nation. Admission is prized and competitive. In
2008, when petitioner sought admission to the University’s
entering class, she was 1 of 29,501 applicants. From this group
12,843 were admitted, and 6,715 accepted and enrolled. Petitioner
was denied admission.
In recent years the
University has used three different programs to evaluate candidates
for admission. The first is the program it used for some years
before 1997, when the University considered two factors: a
numerical score reflecting an applicant’s test scores and
academic perform-ance in high school (Academic Index or AI), and
the applicant’s race. In 1996, this system was held
unconstitutional by the United States Court of Appeals for the
Fifth Circuit. It ruled the University’s consideration of
race violated the Equal Protection Clause because it did not
further any compelling government interest. Hopwood v. Texas, 78
F. 3d 932, 955 (1996).
The second program was
adopted to comply with the Hopwood decision. The University stopped
considering race in admissions and substituted instead a new
holistic metric of a candidate’s potential contribution to
the University, to be used in conjunction with the Academic Index.
This “Personal Achievement Index” (PAI) measures a
student’s leadership and work experience, awards,
extracurricular activities, community service, and other special
circumstances that give insight into a student’s background.
These included growing up in a single-parent home, speaking a
language other than English at home, significant family
responsibilities assumed by the applicant, and the general
socioeconomic condition of the student’s family. Seeking to
address the decline in minority enrollment after Hopwood, the
University also expanded its outreach programs.
The Texas State
Legislature also responded to the Hop-wood decision. It enacted a
measure known as the Top Ten Percent Law, codified at Tex. Educ.
Code Ann. §51.803 (West 2009). Also referred to as H. B.
588, the Top Ten Percent Law grants automatic admission to any
public state college, including the University, to all students in
the top 10% of their class at high schools in Texas that comply
with certain standards.
The University’s
revised admissions process, coupled with the operation of the Top
Ten Percent Law, resulted in a more racially diverse environment at
the University. Before the admissions program at issue in this
case, in the last year under the post-Hopwood AI/PAI system that
did not consider race, the entering class was 4.5% African-American
and 16.9% Hispanic. This is in contrast with the 1996 pre-Hopwood
and Top Ten Percent regime, when race was explicitly considered,
and the University’s entering freshman class was 4.1%
African-American and 14.5% Hispanic.
Following this
Court’s decisions in Grutter v. Bollinger, supra, and Gratz
v. Bollinger, 539 U. S. 244 (2003) , the University adopted a
third admissions program, the 2004 program in which the University
reverted to explicit consideration of race. This is the program
here at issue. In Grutter, the Court upheld the use of race as one
of many “plus factors” in an admissions program that
considered the overall individual contribution of each candidate.
In Gratz, by contrast, the Court held unconstitutional
Michigan’s undergraduate admissions program, which
automatically awarded points to applicants from certain racial
minorities.
The University’s
plan to resume race-conscious admissions was given formal
expression in June 2004 in an in-ternal document entitled Proposal
to Consider Race and Ethnicity in Admissions (Proposal). Supp. App.
1a. The Proposal relied in substantial part on a study of a subset
of undergraduate classes containing between 5 and 24 students. It
showed that few of these classes had significant enrollment by
members of racial minorities. In addition the Proposal relied on
what it called “anecdotal” reports from students
regarding their “interaction in the classroom.” The
Proposal concluded that the University lacked a “critical
mass” of minority students and that to remedy the deficiency
it was necessary to give explicit consideration to race in the
undergraduate admissions program.
To implement the
Proposal the University included a student’s race as a
component of the PAI score, begin- ning with applicants in the fall
of 2004. The University asks students to classify themselves from
among five predefined racial categories on the application. Race is
not assigned an explicit numerical value, but it is undisputed that
race is a meaningful factor.
Once applications have
been scored, they are plotted on a grid with the Academic Index on
the x-axis and the Personal Achievement Index on the y-axis. On
that grid students are assigned to so-called cells based on their
individual scores. All students in the cells falling above a
certain line are admitted. All students below the line are not.
Each college—such as Liberal Arts or Engineering—admits
students separately. So a student is considered initially for her
first-choice college, then for her second choice, and finally for
general admission as an undeclared major.
Petitioner applied for
admission to the University’s 2008 entering class and was
rejected. She sued the University and various University officials
in the United States District Court for the Western District of
Texas. She alleged that the University’s consideration of
race in admissions violated the Equal Protection Clause. The
parties cross-moved for summary judgment. The District Court
granted summary judgment to the University. The United States Court
of Appeals for the Fifth Circuit affirmed. It held that Grutter
required courts to give substantial deference to the University,
both in the definition of the compelling interest in
diversity’s benefits and in deciding whether its specific
plan was narrowly tailored to achieve its stated goal. Applying
that standard, the court upheld the University’s admissions
plan. 631 F. 3d 213, 217–218 (2011).
Over the dissent of
seven judges, the Court of Appeals denied petitioner’s
request for rehearing en banc. See 644 F. 3d 301, 303 (CA5
2011) (per curiam). Petitioner sought a writ of certiorari.
The writ was granted. 565 U. S. ___ (2012).
B
Among the
Court’s cases involving racial classifications in education,
there are three decisions that directly address the question of
considering racial minority status as a positive or favorable
factor in a university’s admissions process, with the goal of
achieving the educational benefits of a more diverse student body:
Bakke, 438 U. S. 265 ; Gratz, supra; and Grutter, 539
U. S. 306 . We take those cases as given for purposes of
deciding this case.
We begin with the
principal opinion authored by Justice Powell in Bakke, supra. In
Bakke, the Court considered a system used by the medical school of
the University of California at Davis. From an entering class of
100 students the school had set aside 16 seats for minority
applicants. In holding this program impermissible under the Equal
Protection Clause Justice Powell’s opinion stated certain
basic premises. First, “decisions based on race or ethnic
origin by faculties and administrations of state universities are
reviewable under the Fourteenth Amend-ment.” Id., at 287
(separate opinion). The principle of equal protection admits no
“artificial line of a ‘two- class
theory’ ” that “permits the recognition of
special wards entitled to a degree of protection greater than that
accorded others.” Id., at 295. It is therefore irrelevant
that a system of racial preferences in admissions may seem benign.
Any racial classification must meet strict scrutiny, for when
government decisions “touch upon an individual’s race
or ethnic background, he is entitled to a judicial determination
that the burden he is asked to bear on that basis is precisely
tailored to serve a compelling governmental interest.” Id.,
at 299.
Next, Justice Powell
identified one compelling interest that could justify the
consideration of race: the interest in the educational benefits
that flow from a diverse student body. Redressing past
discrimination could not serve as a compelling interest, because a
university’s “broad mission [of] education” is
incompatible with making the “judicial, legislative, or
administrative findings of constitutional or statutory
violations” necessary to justify remedial racial
classification. Id., at 307–309.
The attainment of a
diverse student body, by contrast, serves values beyond race alone,
including enhanced class-room dialogue and the lessening of racial
isolation and stereotypes. The academic mission of a university is
“a special concern of the First Amendment.” Id., at
312. Part of “ ‘the business of a university [is]
to provide that atmosphere which is most conducive to speculation,
experiment, and creation,’ ” and this in turn
leads to the question of “ ‘who may be admitted to
study.’ ” Sweezy v. New Hampshire, 354 U. S.
234, 263 (1957) (Frankfurter, J., concurring in judgment).
Justice Powell’s
central point, however, was that this interest in securing
diversity’s benefits, although a permissible objective, is
complex. “It is not an interest in simple ethnic diversity,
in which a specified percentage of the student body is in effect
guaranteed to be members of selected ethnic groups, with the
remaining percentage an undifferentiated aggregation of students.
The diversity that furthers a compelling state interest encompasses
a far broader array of qualifications and characteristics of which
racial or ethnic origin is but a single though important
element.” Bakke, 438 U. S., at 315 (separate
opinion).
In Gratz, 539
U. S. 244 , and Grutter, supra, the Court endorsed the
precepts stated by Justice Powell. In Grutter, the Court reaffirmed
his conclusion that obtaining the educational benefits of
“student body diversity is a compelling state interest that
can justify the use of race in university admissions.” Id.,
at 325.
As Gratz and Grutter
observed, however, this follows only if a clear precondition is
met: The particular admissions process used for this objective is
subject to judicial review. Race may not be considered unless the
admissions process can withstand strict scrutiny. “Nothing in
Justice Powell’s opinion in Bakke signaled that a university
may employ whatever means it desires to achieve the stated goal of
diversity without regard to the limits imposed by our strict
scrutiny analysis.” Gratz, supra, at 275. “To be
narrowly tailored, a race-conscious admissions program cannot use a
quota system,” Grutter, 539 U. S., at 334, but instead
must “remain flexible enough to ensure that each applicant is
evaluated as an individual and not in a way that makes an
applicant’s race or ethnicity the defining feature of his or
her application,” id., at 337. Strict scru-tiny requires the
university to demonstrate with clarity that its “purpose or
interest is both constitutionally permissible and substantial, and
that its use of the classification is necessary . . . to
the accomplishment of its purpose.” Bakke, 438 U. S., at
305 (opinion of Powell, J.) (internal quotation marks omitted).
While these are the
cases that most specifically address the central issue in this
case, additional guidance may be found in the Court’s broader
equal protection jurisprudence which applies in this context.
“Distinctions between citizens solely because of their
ancestry are by their very nature odious to a free people,”
Rice v. Cayetano, 528 U. S. 495, 517 (2000) (internal
quotation marks omitted), and therefore “are contrary to our
traditions and hence constitutionally suspect,” Bolling v.
Sharpe, 347 U. S. 497, 499 (1954) .
“ ‘[B]ecause racial characteristics so seldom
provide a relevant basis for disparate
treatment,’ ” Richmond v. J. A. Croson Co., 488
U. S. 469, 505 (1989) (quoting Fullilove v. Klutznick, 448
U. S. 448 –534 (1980) (Stevens, J., dissenting)),
“the Equal Protection Clause demands that racial
classifications . . . be subjected to the
‘most rigid scrutiny.’ ” Loving v. Virginia,
388 U. S. 1, 11 (1967) .
To implement these
canons, judicial review must begin from the position that
“any official action that treats a person differently on
account of his race or ethnic origin is inherently suspect.”
Fullilove, supra, at 523 (Stewart, J., dissenting); McLaughlin v.
Florida, 379 U. S. 184, 192 (1964) . Strict scrutiny is a
searching examination, and it is the government that bears the
burden to prove “ ‘that the reasons for any
[racial] classification [are] clearly iden-tified and
unquestionably legitimate,’ ” Croson, supra, at
505 (quoting Fullilove, 448 supra, at 533–535 (Stevens, J.,
dissenting)).
II
Grutter made clear
that racial “classifications are constitutional only if they
are narrowly tailored to further compelling governmental
interests.” 539 U. S., at 326. And Grutter endorsed
Justice Powell’s conclusion in Bakke that “the
attainment of a diverse student body . . . is a
consti-tutionally permissible goal for an institution of higher
education.” 438 U. S., at 311–312 (separate
opinion). Thus, under Grutter, strict scrutiny must be applied to
any admissions program using racial categories or
classifications.
According to Grutter, a
university’s “educational judgment that such diversity
is essential to its educational mission is one to which we
defer.” 539 U. S., at 328. Grutter concluded that the
decision to pursue “the educational benefits that flow from
student body diversity,” id., at 330, that the University
deems integral to its mission is, in substantial measure, an
academic judgment to which some, but not complete, judicial
deference is proper under Grutter. A court, of course, should
ensure that there is a reasoned, principled explanation for the
academic decision. On this point, the District Court and Court of
Appeals were correct in finding that Grutter calls for de-ference
to the University’s conclusion, “ ‘based on
its experience and expertise,’ ” 631 F. 3d,
at 230 (quoting 645 F. Supp. 2d 587, 603 (WD Tex. 2009)), that
a diverse student body would serve its educational goals. There is
disagreement about whether Grutter was consistent with the
principles of equal protection in approving this compelling
interest in diversity. See post, at 1 (Scalia, J., concurring);
post, at 4–5 (Thomas, J., concurring); post, at 1–2
(Ginsburg, J., dissenting). But the parties here do not ask the
Court to revisit that aspect of Grutter’s holding.
A university is not
permitted to define diversity as “some specified percentage
of a particular group merely because of its race or ethnic
origin.” Bakke, supra, at 307 (opinion of Powell, J.).
“That would amount to outright racial balancing, which is
patently unconstitutional.” Grutter, supra, at 330.
“Racial balancing is not transformed from ‘patently
unconstitutional’ to a compelling state interest simply by
relabeling it ‘racial diversity.’ ” Parents
Involved in Community Schools v. Seattle School Dist. No. 1, 551
U. S. 701, 732 (2007) .
Once the University has
established that its goal of di-versity is consistent with strict
scrutiny, however, there must still be a further judicial
determination that the admissions process meets strict scrutiny in
its implementation. The University must prove that the means chosen
by the University to attain diversity are narrowly tailored to that
goal. On this point, the University receives no deference. Grutter
made clear that it is for the courts, not for university
administrators, to ensure that “[t]he means chosen to
accomplish the [government’s] asserted purpose must be
specifically and narrowly framed to accomplish that purpose.”
539 U. S., at 333 (internal quotation marks omitted). True, a
court can take account of a university’s experience and
expertise in adopting or rejecting certain admissions processes.
But, as the Court said in Grutter, it remains at all times the
University’s obligation to demonstrate, and the
Judiciary’s obligation to determine, that admissions
processes “ensure that each applicant is evaluated as an
individual and not in a way that makes an applicant’s race or
ethnicity the defining feature of his or her application.”
Id., at 337.
Narrow tailoring also
requires that the reviewing court verify that it is
“necessary” for a university to use race to achieve the
educational benefits of diversity. Bakke, supra, at 305. This
involves a careful judicial inquiry into whether a university could
achieve sufficient diversity without using racial classifications.
Although “[n]arrow tailoring does not require exhaustion of
every conceivable race-neutral alternative,” strict scrutiny
does require a court to examine with care, and not defer to, a
university’s “serious, good faith consideration of
workable race-neutral alternatives.” See Grutter, 539
U. S., at 339–340 (emphasis added). Consideration by the
university is of course necessary, but it is not sufficient to
satisfy strict scrutiny: The reviewing court must ultimately be
satisfied that no workable race-neutral alternatives would produce
the edu-cational benefits of diversity. If “ ‘a
nonracial approach . . . could promote the substantial
interest about as well and at tolerable administrative
expense,’ ” Wygant v. Jackson Bd. of Ed., 476
U. S. 267 , n. 6 (1986) (quoting Greenawalt, Judicial
Scrutiny of “Benign” Racial Preference in Law School
Admissions, 75 Colum. L. Rev. 559, 578–579 (1975)), then
the university may not consider race. A plaintiff, of course, bears
the burden of placing the validity of a university’s adoption
of an affirmative action plan in issue. But strict scrutiny imposes
on the univer-sity the ultimate burden of demonstrating, before
turning to racial classifications, that available, workable
race-neutral alternatives do not suffice.
Rather than perform
this searching examination, however, the Court of Appeals held
petitioner could challenge only “whether [the
University’s] decision to reintroduce race as a factor in
admissions was made in good faith.” 631 F. 3d, at 236.
And in considering such a challenge, the court would “presume
the University acted in good faith” and place on petitioner
the burden of rebutting that presumption. Id., at 231–232.
The Court of Appeals held that to “second-guess the
merits” of this aspect of the University’s decision was
a task it was “ill-equipped to perform” and that it
would attempt only to “ensure that [the University’s]
decision to adopt a race-conscious admissions policy followed from
[a process of] good faith consideration.” Id., at 231. The
Court of Appeals thus concluded that “the narrow-tailoring
inquiry—like the compelling-interest inquiry—is
undertaken with a degree of deference to the Universit[y].”
Id., at 232. Because “the efforts of the University have been
studied, serious, and of high purpose,” the Court of Appeals
held that the use of race in the admissions program fell within
“a constitutionally protected zone of discretion.” Id.,
at 231.
These expressions of
the controlling standard are at odds with Grutter’s command
that “all racial classifications imposed by government
‘must be analyzed by a reviewing court under strict
scrutiny.’ ” 539 U. S., at 326 (quoting
Adarand Constructors, Inc. v. Peña, 515 U. S. 200, 227
(1995) ). In Grutter, the Court approved the plan at issue upon
concluding that it was not a quota, was sufficiently flexible, was
limited in time, and followed “serious, good faith
consideration of workable race-neutral alternatives.” 539
U. S., at 339. As noted above, see supra, at 1, the parties do
not challenge, and the Court therefore does not consider, the
correctness of that determination.
Grutter did not hold
that good faith would forgive an impermissible consideration of
race. It must be remembered that “the mere recitation of a
‘benign’ or legitimate purpose for a racial
classification is entitled to little or no weight.” Croson,
488 U. S., at 500. Strict scrutiny does not permit a court to
accept a school’s assertion that its admissions process uses
race in a permissible way without a court giving close analysis to
the evidence of how the process works in practice.
The higher education
dynamic does not change the narrow tailoring analysis of strict
scrutiny applicable in other contexts. “[T]he analysis and
level of scrutiny applied to determine the validity of [a racial]
classification do not vary simply because the objective appears
acceptable . . . . While the validity and importance
of the objective may affect the outcome of the analysis, the
analysis itself does not change.” Mississippi Univ. for Women
v. Hogan, 458 U. S. 718 , n. 9 (1982).
The District Court and
Court of Appeals confined the strict scrutiny inquiry in too narrow
a way by deferring to the University’s good faith in its use
of racial classifications and affirming the grant of summary
judgment on that basis. The Court vacates that judgment, but
fairness to the litigants and the courts that heard the case
requires that it be remanded so that the admissions process can be
considered and judged under a correct analysis. See Adarand, supra,
at 237. Unlike Grutter, which was decided after trial, this case
arises from cross-motions for summary judgment. In this case, as in
similar cases, in determining whether summary judgment in favor of
the University would be appropriate, the Court of Appeals must
assess whether the University has offered sufficient evidence that
would prove that its admissions program is narrowly tailored to
obtain the educational benefits of diversity. Whether this
record—and not “simple . . . assurances of
good intention,” Croson, supra, at 500—is sufficient is
a question for the Court of Appeals in the first instance.
* * *
Strict scrutiny must
not be “ ‘strict in theory, but fatal in
fact,’ ” Adarand, supra, at 237; see also Grutter,
supra, at 326. But the opposite is also true. Strict scrutiny must
not be strict in theory but feeble in fact. In order for judicial
review to be meaningful, a university must make a showing that its
plan is narrowly tailored to achieve the only interest that this
Court has approved in this context: the benefits of a student body
diversity that “encompasses a . . . broa[d] array
of qualifications and characteristics of which racial or ethnic
origin is but a single though important element.” Bakke, 438
U. S., at 315 (opinion of Powell, J.). The judgment of the
Court of Appeals is vacated, and the case is remanded for further
proceedings consistent with this opinion.
It is so ordered.
Justice Kagan took no
part in the consideration or decision of this case. SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES
_________________
No. 11–345
_________________
ABIGAIL NOEL FISHER, PETITIONER v. UNIVERSITY
OF TEXAS AT AUSTIN et al.
on writ of certiorari to the united states
court of appeals for the fifth circuit
[June 24, 2013]
Justice Scalia,
concurring.
I adhere to the view I
expressed in Grutter v. Bollinger: “The Constitution
proscribes government discrimination on the basis of race, and
state-provided education is no exception.” 539 U. S.
306, 349 (2003) (opinion concurring in part and dissenting in
part). The petitioner in this case did not ask us to overrule
Grutter’s holding that a “compelling interest” in
the educational benefits of diversity can justify racial
preferences in university admissions. Tr. of Oral Arg. 8–9. I
therefore join the Court’s opinion in full. SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES
_________________
No. 11–345
_________________
ABIGAIL NOEL FISHER, PETITIONER v. UNIVERSITY
OF TEXAS AT AUSTIN et al.
on writ of certiorari to the united states
court of appeals for the fifth circuit
[June 24, 2013]
Justice Thomas,
concurring.
I join the
Court’s opinion because I agree that the Court of Appeals did
not apply strict scrutiny to the University of Texas at
Austin’s (University) use of racial discrimi- nation in
admissions decisions. Ante, at 1. I write separately to explain
that I would overrule Grutter v. Bollinger, 539 U. S. 306
(2003) , and hold that a State’s use of race in higher
education admissions decisions is categorically prohibited by the
Equal Protection Clause.
I
A
The Fourteenth
Amendment provides that no State shall “deny to any person
. . . the equal protection of the laws.” The Equal
Protection Clause guarantees every person the right to be treated
equally by the State, without regard to race. “At the heart
of this [guarantee] lies the principle that the government must
treat citizens as individuals, and not as members of racial,
ethnic, or religious groups.” Missouri v. Jenkins, 515
U. S. 70 –121 (1995) (Thomas, J., concurring). “It
is for this reason that we must subject all racial classifications
to the strictest of scrutiny.” Id., at 121.
Under strict scrutiny,
all racial classifications are categorically prohibited unless they
are “ ‘necessary to further a compelling
governmental interest’ ” and “narrowly
tailored to that end.” Johnson v. California, 543 U. S.
499, 514 (2005) (quoting Grutter, supra, at 327). This most
exacting standard “has proven automatically fatal” in
almost every case. Jenkins, supra, at 121 (Thomas, J., concurring).
And rightly so. “Purchased at the price of immeasurable human
suffering, the equal protection principle reflects our
Nation’s understanding that [racial] classifications
ultimately have a destructive impact on the individual and our
society.” Adarand Constructors, Inc. v. Peña, 515
U. S. 200, 240 (1995) (Thomas, J., concurring in part and
concurring in judgment). “The Constitution abhors
classifications based on race” because “every time the
government places citizens on racial registers and makes race
relevant to the provision of burdens or benefits, it demeans us
all.” Grutter, supra, at 353 (Thomas, J., concurring in part
and dissenting in part).
B
1
The Court first
articulated the strict-scrutiny standard in Korematsu v. United
States, 323 U. S. 214 (1944) . There, we held that
“[p]ressing public necessity may sometimes justify the
existence of [racial discrimination]; racial antagonism never
can.” Id., at 216. [ 1 ]
Aside from Grutter, the Court has recognized only two instances in
which a “[p]ressing public necessity” may justify
racial discrimination by the government. First, in Korematsu, the
Court recognized that protecting national security may satisfy this
exacting standard. In that case, the Court upheld an evacuation
order directed at “all persons of Japanese ancestry” on
the grounds that the Nation was at war with Japan and that the
order had “a definite and close relationship to the
prevention of espionage and sabotage.” 323 U. S., at
217–218. Second, the Court has recognized that the government
has a compelling interest in remedying past discrimination for
which it is responsible, but we have stressed that a government
wishing to use race must provide “a ‘strong basis in
evidence for its conclusion that remedial action [is]
necessary.’ ” Richmond v. J. A. Croson Co., 488
U. S. 469, 500, 504 (1989) (quoting Wygant v. Jackson Bd. of
Ed., 476 U. S. 267, 277 (1986) (plurality opinion)).
In contrast to these
compelling interests that may, in a narrow set of circumstances,
justify racial discrimination, the Court has frequently found other
asserted interests insufficient. For example, in Palmore v. Sidoti,
466 U. S. 429 (1984) , the Court flatly rejected a claim that
the best interests of a child justified the government’s
racial discrimination. In that case, a state court awarded custody
to a child’s father because the mother was in a mixed-race
marriage. The state court believed the child might be stigmatized
by living in a mixed-race household and sought to avoid this
perceived problem in its custody determination. We acknowledged the
possibility of stigma but nevertheless concluded that “the
reality of private biases and the possible injury they might
inflict” do not justify racial discrimination. Id., at 433.
As we explained, “The Constitution cannot control such
prejudices but neither can it tolerate them. Private biases may be
outside the reach of the law, but the law cannot, directly or
indirectly, give them effect.” Ibid.
Two years later, in
Wygant, supra, the Court held that even asserted interests in
remedying societal discrimination and in providing role models for
minority students could not justify governmentally imposed racial
discrimination. In that case, a collective-bargaining agreement
between a school board and a teacher’s union favored teachers
who were “ ‘Black, American Indian, Oriental, or
of Spanish descendancy.’ ” Id., at 270–271,
and n. 2 (plurality opinion). We rejected the interest in
remedying societal discrimination because it had no logical
stopping point. Id., at 276. We similarly rebuffed as inadequate
the interest in providing role models to minority students and
added that the notion that “black students are better off
with black teachers could lead to the very system the Court
rejected in Brown v. Board of Education, 347 U. S. 483 (1954)
.” Ibid.
2
Grutter was a radical
departure from our strict-scrutiny precedents. In Grutter, the
University of Michigan Law School (Law School) claimed that it had
a compelling reason to discriminate based on race. The reason it
advanced did not concern protecting national security or remedying
its own past discrimination. Instead, the Law School argued that it
needed to discriminate in admissions decisions in order to obtain
the “educational benefits that flow from a diverse student
body.” 539 U. S., at 317. Contrary to the very meaning of
strict scrutiny, the Court deferred to the Law School’s
determination that this interest was sufficiently compelling to
justify racial discrimination. Id., at 325.
I dissented from that
part of the Court’s decision. I explained that “only
those measures the State must take to provide a bulwark against
anarchy, or to prevent violence, will constitute a ‘pressing
public necessity’ ” sufficient to satisfy strict
scrutiny. Id., at 353. Cf. Lee v. Washington, 390 U. S. 333,
334 (1968) (Black, J., concurring) (protecting prisoners from
violence might justify narrowly tailored discrimination); J. A.
Croson, supra, at 521 (Scalia, J., concurring in judgment)
(“At least where state or local action is at issue, only a
social emergency rising to the level of imminent danger to life and
limb . . . can justify [racial discrimination]”). I
adhere to that view today. As should be obvious, there is nothing
“pressing” or “necessary” about obtaining
whatever educational benefits may flow from racial diversity.
II
A
The University claims
that the District Court found that it has a compelling interest in
attaining “a diverse stu- dent body and the educational
benefits flowing from such diversity.” Brief for Respondents
18. The use of the conjunction, “and,” implies that the
University believes its discrimination furthers two distinct
interests. The first is an interest in attaining diversity for its
own sake. The sec- ond is an interest in attaining educational
benefits that allegedly flow from diversity.
Attaining diversity for
its own sake is a nonstarter. As even Grutter recognized, the
pursuit of diversity as an end is nothing more than impermissible
“racial balancing.” 539 U. S., at 329–330
(“The Law School’s interest is not simply ‘to
assure within its student body some specified percentage of a
particular group merely because of its race or ethnic
origin.’ That would amount to outright racial balancing,
which is patently unconstitutional” (quoting Regents of Univ.
of Cal. v. Bakke, 438 U. S. 265, 307 (1978) ; citation
omitted)); see also id., at 307 (“Preferring members of any
one group for no reason other than race or ethnic origin is
discrimination for its own sake. This the Constitution
forbids”). Rather, diversity can only be the means by which
the University obtains educational benefits; it cannot be an end
pursued for its own sake. Therefore, the educational benefits
allegedly produced by diversity must rise to the level of a
compelling state interest in order for the program to survive
strict scrutiny.
Unfortunately for the
University, the educational benefits flowing from student body
diversity—assuming they exist—hardly qualify as a
compelling state interest. Indeed, the argument that educational
benefits justify racial discrimination was advanced in support of
racial segregation in the 1950’s, but emphatically rejected
by this Court. And just as the alleged educational benefits of
segregation were insufficient to justify racial discrimination
then, see Brown v. Board of Education, 347 U. S. 483 (1954) ,
the alleged educational benefits of diversity cannot justify racial
discrimination today.
1
Our desegregation
cases establish that the Constitution prohibits public schools from
discriminating based on race, even if discrimination is necessary
to the schools’ survival. In Davis v. School Bd. of Prince
Edward Cty., decided with Brown, supra, the school board argued
that if the Court found segregation unconstitutional, white
students would migrate to private schools, funding for public
schools would decrease, and public schools would either decline in
quality or cease to exist altogether. Brief for Appellees in Davis
v. School Bd. of Prince Edward Cty., O. T. 1952, No. 191,
p. 30 (hereinafter Brief for Appellees in Davis)
(“Virginians . . . would no longer permit sizeable
appropriations for schools on either the State or local level;
private segregated schools would be greatly increased in number and
the masses of our people, both white and Negro, would suffer
terribly. . . . [M]any white parents would withdraw
their children from the public schools and, as a result, the
program of providing better schools would be abandoned”
(internal quotation marks omitted)). The true victims of
desegregation, the school board asserted, would be black students,
who would be unable to afford private school. See id., at 31
(“[W]ith the demise of segregation, education in Virginia
would receive a serious setback. Those who would suffer most would
be the Negroes who, by and large, would be economically less able
to afford the private school”); Tr. of Oral Arg. in Davis v.
School Bd. of Prince Edward Cty., O. T. 1954, No. 3, p. 208
(“What is worst of all, in our opinion, you impair the public
school system of Virginia and the victims will be the children of
both races, we think the Negro race worse than the white race,
because the Negro race needs it more by virtue of these
disadvantages under which they have labored. We are up against the
proposition: What does the Negro profit if he procures an immediate
detailed decree from this Court now and then impairs or mars or
destroys the public school system in Prince Edward County”).
[ 2 ]
Unmoved by this
sky-is-falling argument, we held that segregation violates the
principle of equality enshrined in the Fourteenth Amendment. See
Brown, supra, at 495 (“[I]n the field of public education the
doctrine of ‘separate but equal’ has no place. Separate
educational facilities are inherently unequal”); see also
Allen v. School Bd. of Prince Edward Cty., 249 F. 2d 462, 465
(CA4 1957) (per curiam) (“The fact that the schools might be
closed if the order were enforced is no reason for not enforcing
it. A person may not be denied enforcement of rights to which he is
entitled under the Constitution of the United States because of
action taken or threatened in defiance of such rights”).
Within a matter of years, the warning became reality: After being
ordered to desegregate, Prince Edward County closed its public
schools from the summer of 1959 until the fall of 1964. See R.
Sarratt, The Ordeal of Desegregation 237 (1966). Despite this fact,
the Court never backed down from its rigid enforcement of the Equal
Protection Clause’s antidiscrimination principle.
In this case, of
course, Texas has not alleged that the University will close if it
is prohibited from discriminating based on race. But even if it
had, the foregoing cases make clear that even that consequence
would not justify its use of racial discrimination. It follows,
a fortiori, that the putative educational benefits of student
body diversity cannot justify racial discrimination: If a State
does not have a compelling interest in the existence of a
university, it certainly cannot have a compelling interest in the
supposed benefits that might accrue to that university from racial
discrimination. See Grutter, 539 U. S., at 361 (opinion of
Thomas, J.) (“[A] marginal improvement in legal education
cannot justify racial discrimination where the Law School has no
compelling interest either in its exis- tence or in its current
educational and admissions policies”). If the Court were
actually applying strict scrutiny, it would require Texas either to
close the University or to stop discriminating against applicants
based on their race. The Court has put other schools to that
choice, and there is no reason to treat the University
differently.
2
It is also noteworthy
that, in our desegregation cases, we rejected arguments that are
virtually identical to those advanced by the University today. The
University asserts, for instance, that the diversity obtained
through its discriminatory admissions program prepares its students
to become leaders in a diverse society. See, e.g., Brief for
Respondents 6 (arguing that student body diversity “prepares
students to become the next generation of leaders in an
increasingly diverse society”). The segregationists likewise
defended segregation on the ground that it provided more leadership
opportunities for blacks. See, e.g., Brief for Respondents in
Sweatt 96 (“[A] very large group of Northern Negroes [comes]
South to attend separate colleges, suggesting that the Negro does
not secure as well-rounded a college life at a mixed college, and
that the separate college offers him positive advantages; that
there is a more normal social life for the Negro in a separate
college; that there is a greater opportunity for full participation
and for the development of leadership; that the Negro is inwardly
more ‘secure’ at a college of his own people”);
Brief for Appellees in Davis 25–26 (“The Negro child
gets an opportunity to participate in segregated schools that I
have never seen accorded to him in non-segregated schools. He is
important, he holds offices, he is accepted by his fellows, he is
on athletic teams, he has a full place there” (internal
quotation marks omitted)). This argument was unavailing. It is
irrelevant under the Fourteenth Amendment whether segregated or
mixed schools produce better leaders. Indeed, no court today would
accept the suggestion that segregation is permissible because
historically black colleges produced Booker T. Washington, Thurgood
Marshall, Martin Luther King, Jr., and other prominent leaders.
Likewise, the University’s racial discrimination cannot be
justified on the ground that it will produce better leaders.
The University also
asserts that student body diversity improves interracial relations.
See, e.g., Brief for Respondents 6 (arguing that student body
diversity promotes “cross-racial understanding” and
breaks down racial and ethnic stereotypes). In this argument, too,
the University repeats arguments once marshaled in support of
segregation. See, e.g., Brief for Appellees in Davis 17
(“Virginia has established segregation in certain fields as a
part of her public policy to prevent violence and reduce
resentment. The result, in the view of an overwhelming Virginia
majority, has been to improve the relationship between the
different races”); id., at 25 (“If segregation be
stricken down, the general welfare will be definitely harmed
. . . there would be more friction developed”
(internal quotation marks omitted)); Brief for Respondents in
Sweatt 93 (“Texas has had no serious breaches of the peace in
recent years in connection with its schools. The separation of the
races has kept the conflicts at a minimum”); id., at
97–98 (“The legislative acts are based not only on the
belief that it is the best way to provide education for both races,
and the knowledge that separate schools are necessary to keep
public support for the public schools, but upon the necessity to
maintain the public peace, harmony, and welfare”); Brief for
Appellees in Briggs 32 (“The southern Negro, by and large,
does not want an end to segregation in itself any more than does
the southern white man. The Negro in the South knows that
discriminations, and worse, can and would multiply in such
event” (internal quotation marks omitted)). We flatly
rejected this line of arguments in McLaurin v. Oklahoma State
Regents for Higher Ed., 339 U. S. 637 (1950) , where we held
that segregation would be unconstitutional even if white students
never tolerated blacks. Id., at 641 (“It may be argued that
appellant will be in no better position when these restrictions are
removed, for he may still be set apart by his fellow students. This
we think irrelevant. There is a vast difference—a
Constitutional difference—between restrictions imposed by the
state which prohibit the intellectual commingling of students, and
the refusal of individuals to commingle where the state presents no
such bar”). It is, thus, entirely irrelevant whether the
University’s racial discrimination increases or decreases
tolerance.
Finally, while the
University admits that racial discrimination in admissions is not
ideal, it asserts that it is a temporary necessity because of the
enduring race consciousness of our society. See Brief for
Respondents 53–54 (“Certainly all aspire for a
colorblind society in which race does not matter
. . . . But in Texas, as in America, ‘our
highest aspirations are yet unfulfilled’ ”). Yet
again, the University echoes the hollow justifications advanced by
the segregationists. See, e.g., Brief for State of Kansas on
Reargument in Brown v. Board of Education, O. T. 1953, No. 1,
p. 56 (“We grant that segregation may not be the ethical or
political ideal. At the same time we recognize that practical
considerations may prevent realization of the ideal”); Brief
for Respondents in Sweatt 94 (“The racial consciousness and
feeling which exists today in the minds of many people may be
regrettable and unjustified. Yet they are a reality which must be
dealt with by the State if it is to preserve harmony and peace and
at the same time furnish equal education to both groups”);
id., at 96 (“ ‘[T]he mores of racial relationships
are such as to rule out, for the present at least, any possibility
of admitting white persons and Negroes to the same
institutions’ ”); Brief for Appellees in Briggs
26–27 (“[I]t would be unwise in administrative practice
. . . to mix the two races in the same schools at the
present time and under present conditions”); Brief for
Appellees on Reargument in Briggs v. Elliott, O. T. 1953, No.
2, p. 79 (“It is not ‘racism’ to be cognizant of
the fact that mankind has struggled with race problems and racial
tensions for upwards of sixty centuries”). But these
arguments too were unavailing. The Fourteenth Amendment views
racial bigotry as an evil to be stamped out, not as an excuse for
perpetual racial tinkering by the State. See DeFunis v. Odegaard,
416 U. S. 312, 342 (1974) (Douglas, J., dissenting)
(“The Equal Protection Clause commands the elimination of
racial barriers, not their creation in order to satisfy our theory
as to how society ought to be organized”). The
University’s arguments to this effect are similarly
insufficient to justify discrimination. [ 3 ]
3
The
University’s arguments today are no more persuasive than they
were 60 years ago. Nevertheless, despite rejecting identical
arguments in Brown, the Court in Grutter deferred to the
University’s determination that the diversity obtained by
racial discrimination would yield educational benefits. There is no
principled distinction between the University’s assertion
that diversity yields educational benefits and the
segregationists’ assertion that segregation yielded those
same benefits. See Grutter, 539 U. S., at 365–366 (opinion of
Thomas, J.) (“Con- tained within today’s majority
opinion is the seed of a new constitutional justification for a
concept I thought long and rightly rejected—racial
segregation”). Educational benefits are a far cry from the
truly compelling state interests that we previously required to
justify use of racial classifications.
B
My view of the
Constitution is the one advanced by the plaintiffs in Brown:
“[N]o State has any authority under the equal-protection
clause of the Fourteenth Amendment to use race as a factor in
affording educational opportunities among its citizens.” Tr.
of Oral Arg. in Brown v. Board of Education, O. T. 1952, No.
8, p. 7; see also Juris. Statement in Davis v. School Bd. of
Prince Edward Cty., O. T. 1952, No. 191, p. 8
(“[W]e take the unqualified position that the Fourteenth
Amendment has totally stripped the state of power to make race and
color the basis for governmental action”); Brief for
Appellants in Brown v. Board of Education, O. T. 1952, No. 8,
p. 5 (“The Fourteenth Amendment precludes a state from
imposing distinctions or classifications based upon race and color
alone”); Brief for Appellants in Nos. 1, 2, and 4, and for
Respondents in No. 10 on Reargument in Brown v. Board of Education,
O. T. 1953, p. 65 (“That the Constitution is color blind
is our dedicated belief”). The Constitution does not pander
to faddish theories about whether race mixing is in the public
interest. The Equal Protection Clause strips States of all
authority to use race as a factor in providing education. All
applicants must be treated equally under the law, and no benefit in
the eye of the beholder can justify racial discrimination.
This principle is
neither new nor difficult to understand. In 1868, decades before
Plessy, the Iowa Supreme Court held that schools may not
discriminate against applicants based on their skin color. In Clark
v. Board of Directors, 24 Iowa 266 (1868), a school denied
admission to a student because she was black, and “public
sentiment [was] opposed to the intermingling of white and colored
children in the same schools.” Id., at 269. The Iowa Supreme
Court rejected that flimsy justification, holding that “all
the youths are equal before the law, and there is no discretion
vested in the board . . . or elsewhere, to interfere with
or disturb that equality.” Id., at 277. “For the courts
to sustain a board of school directors . . . in limiting
the rights and privileges of persons by reason of their [race],
would be to sanction a plain violation of the spirit of our laws
not only, but would tend to perpetuate the national differences of
our people and stimulate a constant strife, if not a war of
races.” Id., at 276. This simple, yet fundamental, truth was
lost on the Court in Plessy and Grutter.
I would overrule
Grutter and hold that the University’s admissions program
violates the Equal Protection Clause because the University has not
put forward a compelling interest that could possibly justify
racial discrimination.
III
While I find the
theory advanced by the University to justify racial discrimination
facially inadequate, I also believe that its use of race has little
to do with the alleged educational benefits of diversity. I suspect
that the University’s program is instead based on the
benighted notion that it is possible to tell when discrimination
helps, rather than hurts, racial minorities. See post, at 3
(Ginsburg, J., dissenting) (“[G]overnment actors, including
state universities, need not be blind to the lingering effects of
‘an overtly discriminatory past,’ the legacy of
‘centuries of law-sanctioned inequality’ ”).
But “[h]istory should teach greater humility.” Metro
Broadcasting, Inc. v. FCC, 497 U. S. 547, 609 (1990)
(O’Connor, J., dissenting). The worst forms of racial
discrimination in this Nation have always been accompanied by
straight-faced representations that discrimination helped
minorities.
A
Slaveholders argued
that slavery was a “positive good” that civilized
blacks and elevated them in every dimension of life. See, e.g.,
Calhoun, Speech in the U. S. Senate, 1837, in P. Finkelman,
Defending Slavery 54, 58–59 (2003) (“Never before has
the black race of Central Africa, from the dawn of history to the
present day, attained a condition so civilized and so improved, not
only physically, but morally and
intellectually. . . . [T]he relation now existing in
the slaveholding States between the two [races], is, instead of an
evil, a good—a positive good”); Harper, Memoir on
Slavery, in The Ideology of Slavery 78, 115–116 (D. Faust ed.
1981) (“Slavery, as it is said in an eloquent article
published in a Southern periodical work . . . ‘has
done more to elevate a degraded race in the scale of humanity; to
tame the savage; to civilize the barbarous; to soften the
ferocious; to enlighten the ignorant, and to spread the blessings
of [C]hristianity among the heathen, than all the missionaries that
philanthropy and religion have ever sent
forth’ ”); Hammond, The Mudsill Speech, 1858, in
Defending Slavery, supra, at 80, 87 (“They are elevated from
the condition in which God first created them, by being made our
slaves”).
A century later,
segregationists similarly asserted that segregation was not only
benign, but good for black students. They argued, for example, that
separate schools protected black children from racist white
students and teachers. See, e.g., Brief for Appellees in Briggs
33–34 (“ ‘I have repeatedly seen wise and
loving colored parents take infinite pains to force their little
children into schools where the white children, white teachers, and
white parents despised and resented the dark child, made mock of
it, neglected or bullied it, and literally rendered its life a
living hell. Such parents want their child to “fight”
this thing out,—but, dear God, at what a cost!
. . . We shall get a finer, better balance of spirit; an
infinitely more capable and rounded personality by putting children
in schools where they are wanted, and where they are happy and
inspired, than in thrusting them into hells where they are
ridiculed and hated’ ” (quoting DuBois, Does the
Negro Need Separate Schools? 4 J. of Negro Educ. 328, 330–331
(1935))); Tr. of Oral Arg. in Bolling v. Sharpe, O. T. 1952,
No. 413, p. 56 (“There was behind these [a]cts a kindly
feeling [and] an intention to help these people who had been in
bondage. And there was and there still is an intention by the
Congress to see that these children shall be educated in a
healthful atmosphere, in a wholesome atmosphere, in a place where
they are wanted, in a place where they will not be looked upon with
hostility, in a place where there will be a receptive atmosphere
for learning for both races without the hostility that undoubtedly
Congress thought might creep into these situations”). And
they even appealed to the fact that many blacks agreed that
separate schools were in the “best interests” of both
races. See, e.g., Brief for Appellees in Davis 24–25
(“ ‘It has been my experience, in working with the
people of Virginia, including both white and Negro, that the
customs and the habits and the traditions of Virginia citizens are
such that they believe for the best interests of both the white and
the Negro that the separate school is
best’ ”).
Following in these
inauspicious footsteps, the University would have us believe that
its discrimination is likewise benign. I think the lesson of
history is clear enough: Racial discrimination is never benign.
“ ‘[B]enign’ carries with it no independent
meaning, but reflects only acceptance of the current
generation’s conclusion that a politically acceptable burden,
imposed on particular citizens on the basis of race, is
reasonable.” See Metro Broadcasting, 497 U. S., at 610
(O’Connor, J., dissenting). It is for this reason that the
Court has repeatedly held that strict scrutiny applies to all
racial classifications, regardless of whether the government has
benevolent motives. See, e.g., Johnson, 543 U. S., at 505
(“We have insisted on strict scrutiny in every context, even
for so-called ‘benign’ racial classifications”);
Adarand, 515 U. S., at 227 (“[A]ll racial
classifications, imposed by whatever federal, state, or local
governmental actor, must be analyzed by a reviewing court under
strict scrutiny”); J. A. Croson, 488 U. S., at 500
(“Racial classifications are suspect, and that means that
simple legislative assurances of good intention cannot
suffice”). The University’s professed good intentions
cannot excuse its outright racial discrimination any more than such
intentions justified the now denounced arguments of slaveholders
and segregationists.
B
While it does not,
for constitutional purposes, matter whether the University’s
racial discrimination is benign, I note that racial engineering
does in fact have insidious consequences. There can be no doubt
that the University’s discrimination injures white and Asian
applicants who are denied admission because of their race. But I
believe the injury to those admitted under the University’s
discriminatory admissions program is even more harmful.
Blacks and Hispanics
admitted to the University as a result of racial discrimination
are, on average, far less prepared than their white and Asian
classmates. In the University’s entering class of 2009, for
example, among the students admitted outside the Top Ten Percent
plan, blacks scored at the 52d percentile of 2009 SAT takers
nationwide, while Asians scored at the 93d percentile. Brief for
Richard Sander et al. as Amici Curiae 3–4, and
n. 4. Blacks had a mean GPA of 2.57 and a mean SAT score of
1524; Hispanics had a mean GPA of 2.83 and a mean SAT score of
1794; whites had a mean GPA of 3.04 and a mean SAT score of 1914;
and Asians had a mean GPA of 3.07 and a mean SAT score of 1991. [ 4 ] Ibid.
Tellingly, neither the
University nor any of the 73 amici briefs in support of racial
discrimination has presented a shred of evidence that black and
Hispanic students are able to close this substantial gap during
their time at the University. Cf. Thernstrom & Thernstrom,
Reflections on the Shape of the River, 46 UCLA L. Rev. 1583,
1605–1608 (1999) (discussing the failure of defenders of
racial discrimination in admissions to consider the fact that its
“beneficiaries” are underperforming in the classroom).
“It is a fact that in virtually all selective schools
. . . where racial preferences in admission is practiced,
the majority of [black] students end up in the lower quarter of
their class.” S. Cole & E. Barber, Increasing Faculty
Diversity: The Occupational Choices of High-Achieving Minority
Students 124 (2003). There is no reason to believe this is not the
case at the University. The University and its dozens of amici are
deafeningly silent on this point.
Furthermore, the
University’s discrimination does nothing to increase the
number of blacks and Hispanics who have access to a college
education generally. Instead, the University’s discrimination
has a pervasive shifting effect. See T. Sowell, Affirmative Action
Around the World 145–146 (2004). The University admits
minorities who otherwise would have attended less selective
colleges where they would have been more evenly matched. But, as a
result of the mismatching, many blacks and Hispanics who likely
would have excelled at less elite schools are placed in a position
where underperformance is all but inevitable because they are less
academically prepared than the white and Asian students with whom
they must compete. Setting aside the damage wreaked upon the
self-confidence of these overmatched students, there is no evidence
that they learn more at the University than they would have learned
at other schools for which they were better prepared. Indeed, they
may learn less.
The Court of Appeals
believed that the University needed to enroll more blacks and
Hispanics because they remained “clustered in certain
programs.” 631 F. 3d 213, 240 (CA5 2011)
(“[N]early a quarter of the undergraduate students in [the
University’s] College of Social Work are Hispanic, and more
than 10% are [black]. In the College of Education, 22.4% of
students are Hispanic and 10.1% are [black]”). But racial
discrimination may be the cause of, not the solution to, this
clustering. There is some evidence that students admitted as a
result of racial discrimination are more likely to abandon their
initial aspirations to become scientists and engineers than are
students with similar qualifications who attend less selective
schools. See, e.g., Elliott, Strenta, Adair, Matier, & Scott,
The Role of Ethnicity in Choosing and Leaving Science in Highly
Selective Institutions, 37 Research in Higher Educ. 681,
699–701 (1996). [ 5 ]
These students may well drift towards less competitive majors
because the mismatch caused by racial discrimination in admissions
makes it difficult for them to compete in more rigorous majors.
Moreover, the
University’s discrimination “stamp[s] [blacks and
Hispanics] with a badge of inferiority.” Adarand, 515
U. S., at 241 (opinion of Thomas, J.). It taints the
accomplishments of all those who are admitted as a result of racial
discrimination. Cf. J. McWhorter, Losing the Race: Self-Sabotage in
Black America 248 (2000) (“I was never able to be as proud of
getting into Stanford as my classmates could
be. . . . [H]ow much of an achievement can I truly
say it was to have been a good enough black person to be admitted,
while my colleagues had been considered good enough people to be
admitted”). And, it taints the accomplishments of all those
who are the same race as those admitted as a result of racial
discrimination. In this case, for example, most blacks and
Hispanics attending the University were admitted without
discrimination under the Top Ten Percent plan, but no one can
distinguish those students from the ones whose race played a role
in their admission. “When blacks [and Hispanics] take
positions in the highest places of government, industry, or
academia, it is an open question . . . whether
their skin color played a part in their advancement.” See
Grutter, 539 U. S., at 373 (opinion of Thomas, J.). “The
question itself is the stigma—because either racial
discrimination did play a role, in which case the person may be
deemed ‘otherwise unqualified,’ or it did not, in which
case asking the question itself unfairly marks those
. . . who would succeed without discrimination.”
Ibid. Al- though cloaked in good intentions, the University’s
racial tinkering harms the very people it claims to be helping.
* * *
For the foregoing
reasons, I would overrule Grutter. However, because the Court
correctly concludes that the Court of Appeals did not apply strict
scrutiny, I join its opinion. Notes 1 The standard of
“pressing public necessity” is more frequently called a
“compelling governmental interest.” I use the terms
interchangeably. 2 Similar arguments were
advanced unsuccessfully in other cases as well. See, e.g., Brief
for Respondents in Sweatt v. Painter, O. T. 1949, No. 44, pp.
94–95 (hereinafter Brief for Respondents in Sweatt)
(“[I]f the power to separate the students were terminated,
. . . it would be as a bonanza to the private white
schools of the State, and it would mean the migration out of the
schools and the turning away from the public schools of the
influence and support of a large number of children and of the
parents of those children . . . who are the largest
contributors to the cause of public education, and whose financial
support is necessary for the continued progress of public
education. . . . Should the State be required to mix the
public schools, there is no question but that a very large group of
students would transfer, or be moved by their parents, to private
schools with a resultant deterioration of the public schools”
(internal quotation marks omitted)); Brief for Appellees in Briggs
v. Elliott, O. T. 1952, No. 101, p. 27 (hereinafter Brief
for Appellees in Briggs) (“[I]t would be impossible to have
sufficient acceptance of the idea of mixed groups attending the
same schools to have public education on that basis at all
. . . . [I]t would eliminate the public schools in
most, if not all, of the communities in the
State”). 3 While the arguments
advanced by the University in defense of discrimination are the
same as those advanced by the segregationists, one obvious
difference is that the segregationists argued that it was
segregation that was necessary to obtain the alleged benefits,
whereas the University argues that diversity is the key. Today, the
segre-gationists’ arguments would never be given serious
considera-tion. But see M. Plocienniczak, Pennsylvania School
Experiments with ‘Segregation,’ CNN (Jan. 27, 2011),
http://www.cnn.com/2011/US/01/27/pennsylvania.segregation/?_s=PM:US
(as visited June 21, 2013, and available in Clerk of Court’s
case file). We should be equally hostile to the University’s
repackaged version of the same arguments in support of its favored
form of racial discrimination. 4 The lowest possible score
on the SAT is 600, and the highest possible score is
2400. 5 The success of
historically black colleges at producing graduates who go on to
earn graduate degrees in science and engineering is well
documented. See, e.g., National Science Foundation, J. Burrelli
& A. Rapoport, InfoBrief, Role of HBCUs as Baccalaureate-Origin
Institutions of Black S&E Doctorate Recipients 6 (2008) (Table
2) (showing that, from 1997–2006, Howard University had more
black students who went on to earn science and engineering
doctorates than any other undergraduate institution, and that 7
other historically black colleges ranked in the top 10); American
Association of Medical Colleges, Diversity in Medical Education:
Facts & Figures 86 (2012) (Table 19) (showing that, in 2011,
Xavier University had more black students who went on to earn
medical degrees than any other undergraduate institution and that
Howard University was second). SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES
_________________
No. 11–345
_________________
ABIGAIL NOEL FISHER, PETITIONER v. UNIVERSITY
OF TEXAS AT AUSTIN et al.
on writ of certiorari to the united states
court of appeals for the fifth circuit
[June 24, 2013]
Justice Ginsburg,
dissenting.
The University of Texas
at Austin (University) is candid about what it is endeavoring to
do: It seeks to achieve student-body diversity through an
admissions policy patterned after the Harvard plan referenced as
exemplary in Justice Powell’s opinion in Regents of Univ. of
Cal. v. Bakke, 438 U. S. 265 –317 (1978). The University
has steered clear of a quota system like the one struck down in
Bakke, which excluded all nonminority candidates from competition
for a fixed number of seats. See id., at 272–275, 315,
319–320 (opinion of Powell, J.). See also Gratz v. Bollinger,
539 U. S. 244, 293 (2003) (Souter, J., dissenting)
(“Justice Powell’s opinion in [Bakke] rules out a
racial quota or set-aside, in which race is the sole fact of
eligibility for certain places in a class.”). And, like so
many educational institutions across the Nation, [ 1 ] the University has taken care to follow
the model approved by the Court in Grutter v. Bollinger, 539
U. S. 306 (2003) . See 645 F. Supp. 2d 587, 609 (WD Tex.
2009) (“[T]he parties agree [that the University’s]
policy was based on the [admissions] policy [upheld in
Grutter].”).
Petitioner urges that
Texas’ Top Ten Percent Law and race-blind holistic review of
each application achieve significant diversity, so the University
must be content with those alternatives. I have said before and
reiterate here that only an ostrich could regard the supposedly
neutral alternatives as race unconscious. See Gratz, 539
U. S., at 303–304, n. 10 (dissenting opinion). As
Justice Souter observed, the vaunted alternatives suffer from
“the disadvantage of deliberate obfuscation.” Id., at
297–298 (dissenting opinion).
Texas’ percentage
plan was adopted with racially segregated neighborhoods and schools
front and center stage. See House Research Organization, Bill
Analysis, HB 588, pp. 4–5 (Apr. 15, 1997) (“Many
regions of the state, school districts, and high schools in Texas
are still predominantly composed of people from a single racial or
ethnic group. Because of the persistence of this segregation,
admitting the top 10 percent of all high schools would provide a
diverse population and ensure that a large, well qualified pool of
minority students was admitted to Texas universities.”). It
is race consciousness, not blindness to race, that drives such
plans. [ 2 ] As for holistic
review, if universities cannot explicitly include race as a factor,
many may “resort to camouflage” to “maintain
their minority enrollment.” Gratz, 539 U. S., at 304
(Ginsburg, J., dissenting).
I have several times
explained why government actors, including state universities, need
not be blind to the lingering effects of “an overtly
discriminatory past,” the legacy of “centuries of
law-sanctioned inequality.” Id., at 298 (dissenting opinion).
See also Adarand Constructors, Inc. v. Peña, 515 U. S.
200 –274 (1995) (dissenting opinion). Among constitutionally
permissible options, I remain convinced, “those that candidly
disclose their consideration of race [are] preferable to those that
conceal it.” Gratz, 539 U. S., at 305, n. 11
(dissenting opinion).
Accordingly, I would
not return this case for a second look. As the thorough opinions
below show, 631 F. 3d 213 (CA5 2011); 645 F. Supp. 2d
587, the University’s admissions policy flexibly considers
race only as a “factor of a factor of a factor of a
factor” in the calculus, id., at 608; followed a yearlong
review through which the University reached the reasonable,
good-faith judgment that supposedly race-neutral initiatives were
insufficient to achieve, in appropriate measure, the educational
benefits of student-body diversity, see 631 F. 3d, at
225–226; and is sub- ject to periodic review to ensure that
the consideration of race remains necessary and proper to achieve
the Uni- versity’s educational objectives, see id., at 226. [ 3 ] Justice Powell’s
opinion in Bakke and the Court’s decision in Grutter require
no further determinations. See Grutter, 539 U. S., at
333–343; Bakke, 438 U. S., at 315–320.
The Court rightly
declines to cast off the equal protection framework settled in
Grutter. See ante, at 5. Yet it stops short of reaching the
conclusion that framework warrants. Instead, the Court vacates the
Court of Appeals’ judgment and remands for the Court of
Appeals to “assess whether the University has offered
sufficient evidence [to] prove that its admissions program is
narrowly tailored to obtain the educational benefits of
diversity.” Ante, at 13. As I see it, the Court of Appeals
has already completed that inquiry, and its judgment, trained on
this Court’s Bakke and Grutter pathmarkers, merits our
approbation. [ 4 ]
* * *
For the reasons
stated, I would affirm the judgment of the Court of Appeals. Notes 1 See Brief for Amherst
College et al. as Amici Curiae 33–35; Brief for
Association of American Law Schools as Amicus Curiae 6; Brief for
Association of American Medical Colleges et al. as Amici
Curiae 30–32; Brief for Brown University et al. as Amici
Curiae 2–3, 13; Brief for Robert Post et al. as Amici
Curiae 24–27; Brief for Fordham University et al. as
Amici Curiae 5–6; Brief for University of Delaware
et al. as Amici Curiae 16–21. 2 The notion that
Texas’ Top Ten Percent Law is race neutral calls to mind
Professor Thomas Reed Powell’s famous statement: “If
you think that you can think about a thing inextricably attached to
something else without thinking of the thing which it is attached
to, then you have a legal mind.” T. Arnold, The Symbols of
Government 101 (1935) (internal quotation marks omitted). Only that
kind of legal mind could conclude that an admissions plan
specifically designed to produce racial diversity is not race
conscious. 3 As the Court said in
Grutter v. Bollinger, , “[n]arrow tailoring . . .
require[s] serious, good faith consideration of workable
race-neutral alternatives that will achieve the diversity the
university seeks.” But, Grutter also explained, it does not
“require a university to choose between maintaining a
reputation for excellence [and] fulfilling a commitment to provide
educational opportunitiesto members of all racial groups.”
Ibid. I do not read the Court tosay otherwise. See ante, at 10
(acknowledging that, in determining whether a race-conscious
admissions policy satisfies Grutter’s narrow-tailoring
requirement, “a court can take account of a
university’s experience and expertise in adopting or
rejecting certain admissions processes”). 4 Because the
University’s admissions policy, in my view, is constitutional
under Grutter, there is no need for the Court in this case
“to revisit whether all governmental classifications by race,
whether designed to benefit or to burden a historically
disadvantaged group, should be subject to the same standard of
judicial review.” 539 U. S., at 346, n. (Ginsburg, J.,
concurring). See also Gratz v. Bollinger, (Ginsburg, J.,
dissenting) (“Actions designed to burden groups long denied
full citizenship stature are not sensibly ranked with measures
taken to hasten the day when entrenched discrimination and its
aftereffects have been extirpated.”). | The University of Texas at Austin's use of race as a factor in its undergraduate admissions process was challenged by Abigail Fisher, a Caucasian applicant who was denied admission. The Supreme Court concluded that the lower court did not hold the University to the strict scrutiny standard required in such cases, and remanded the case for further review. Justice Ginsburg dissented, arguing that the lower court had applied the correct standard and that the University's admissions policy was constitutional under existing precedent. |
Gun Rights | United States v. Rahimi | https://supreme.justia.com/cases/federal/us/602/22-915/ | NOTICE: This opinion is subject to
formal revision before publication in the United States Reports.
Readers are requested to notify the Reporter of Decisions, Supreme
Court of the United States, Washington, D. C. 20543,
[email protected], of any typographical or other formal
errors.
SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES
_________________
No. 22–915
_________________
UNITED STATES, PETITIONER v. ZACKEY
RAHIMI
on writ of certiorari to the united states
court of appeals for the fifth circuit
[June 21, 2024]
Chief Justice Roberts delivered the opinion of
the Court.
A federal statute prohibits an individual
subject to a domestic violence restraining order from possessing a
firearm if that order includes a finding that he “represents a
credible threat to the physical safety of [an] intimate partner,”
or a child of the partner or individual. 18 U. S. C.
§922(g)(8). Respondent Zackey Rahimi is subject to such an order.
The question is whether this provision may be enforced against him
consistent with the Second Amendment.
I
A
In December 2019, Rahimi met his girlfriend,
C. M., for lunch in a parking lot. C. M. is also the
mother of Rahimi’s young child, A. R. During the meal, Rahimi
and C. M. began arguing, and Rahimi became enraged. Brief for
United States 2. C. M. attempted to leave, but Rahimi grabbed
her by the wrist, dragged her back to his car, and shoved her in,
causing her to strike her head against the dashboard. When he
realized that a bystander was watching the altercation, Rahimi
paused to retrieve a gun from under the passenger seat. C. M.
took advantage of the opportunity to escape. Rahimi fired as she
fled, although it is unclear whether he was aiming at C. M. or
the witness. Rahimi later called C. M. and warned that he
would shoot her if she reported the incident. Ibid .
Undeterred by this threat, C. M. went to
court to seek a restraining order. In the affidavit accompanying
her application, C. M. recounted the parking lot incident as
well as other assaults. She also detailed how Rahimi’s conduct had
endangered A. R. Although Rahimi had an opportunity to contest
C. M.’s testimony, he did not do so. On February 5, 2020, a
state court in Tarrant County, Texas, issued a restraining order
against him. The order, entered with the consent of both parties,
included a finding that Rahimi had committed “family violence.”
App. 2. It also found that this violence was “likely to occur
again” and that Rahimi posed “a credible threat” to the “physical
safety” of C. M. or A. R. Id ., at 2–3. Based on
these findings, the order prohibited Rahimi from threatening
C. M. or her family for two years or contacting C. M.
during that period except to discuss A. R. Id ., at 3–7.
It also suspended Rahimi’s gun license for two years. Id .,
at 5–6. If Rahimi was imprisoned or confined when the order was set
to expire, the order would instead terminate either one or two
years after his release date, depending on the length of his
imprisonment. Id ., at 6–7.
In May, however, Rahimi violated the order by
approaching C. M.’s home at night. He also began contacting
her through several social media accounts.
In November, Rahimi threatened a different woman
with a gun, resulting in a charge for aggravated assault with a
deadly weapon. And while Rahimi was under arrest for that assault,
the Texas police identified him as the suspect in a spate of at
least five additional shootings.
The first, which occurred in December 2020,
arose from Rahimi’s dealing in illegal drugs. After one of his
customers “started talking trash,” Rahimi drove to the man’s home
and shot into it. Brief for United States 3. While driving the next
day, Rahimi collided with another car, exited his vehicle, and
proceeded to shoot at the other car. Three days later, he fired his
gun in the air while driving through a residential neighborhood. A
few weeks after that, Rahimi was speeding on a highway near
Arlington, Texas, when a truck flashed its lights at him. Rahimi
hit the brakes and cut across traffic to chase the truck. Once off
the highway, he fired several times toward the truck and a nearby
car before fleeing. Two weeks after that, Rahimi and a friend were
dining at a roadside burger restaurant. When the restaurant
declined his friend’s credit card, Rahimi pulled a gun and shot
into the air.
The police obtained a warrant to search Rahimi’s
residence. There they discovered a pistol, a rifle, ammunition—and
a copy of the restraining order.
B
Rahimi was indicted on one count of possessing
a firearm while subject to a domestic violence restraining order,
in violation of 18 U. S. C. §922(g)(8). At the time, such
a violation was punishable by up to 10 years’ imprisonment (since
amended to 15 years). §924(a)(2); see Bipartisan Safer Communities
Act, Pub. L. 117–159, §12004(c)(2), 136Stat. 1329, 18
U. S. C. §924(a)(8). A prosecution under Section
922(g)(8) may proceed only if three criteria are met. First, the
defendant must have received actual notice and an opportunity to be
heard before the order was entered. §922(g)(8)(A). Second, the
order must prohibit the defendant from either “harassing, stalking,
or threatening” his “intimate partner” or his or his partner’s
child, or “engaging in other conduct that would place [the] partner
in reasonable fear of bodily injury” to the partner or child.
§922(g)(8)(B). A defendant’s “intimate partner[s]” include his
spouse or any former spouse, the parent of his child, and anyone
with whom he cohabitates or has cohabitated. §921(a)(32). Third,
under Section 922(g)(8)(C), the order must either contain a finding
that the defendant “represents a credible threat to the physical
safety” of his intimate partner or his or his partner’s child,
§922(g)(8)(C)(i), or “by its terms explicitly prohibit[ ] the
use,” attempted use, or threatened use of “physical force” against
those individuals, §922(g)(8)(C)(ii).
Rahimi’s restraining order met all three
criteria. First, Rahimi had received notice and an opportunity to
be heard before the order was entered. App. 2. Second, the order
prohibited him from communicating with or threatening C. M. Id ., at 3–4. Third, the order met the requirements of
Section 922(g)(8)(C)(i), because it included a finding that Rahimi
represented “a credible threat to the physical safety” of
C. M. or her family. Id ., at 2–3. The order also
“explicitly prohibit[ed]” Rahimi from “the use, attempted use, or
threatened use of physical force” against C. M., satisfying
the independent basis for liability in Section 922(g)(8)(C)(ii). Id ., at 3.
Rahimi moved to dismiss the indictment, arguing
that Section 922(g)(8) violated on its face the Second Amendment
right to keep and bear arms. No. 4:21–cr–00083 (ND Tex., May 7,
2021), ECF Doc. 17. Concluding that Circuit precedent foreclosed
Rahimi’s Second Amendment challenge, the District Court denied his
motion. Rahimi then pleaded guilty. On appeal, he again raised his
Second Amendment challenge. The appeal was denied, and Rahimi
petitioned for rehearing en banc.
While Rahimi’s petition was pending, this Court
decided New York State Rifle & Pistol Assn., Inc . v. Bruen , 597 U.S. 1 (2022). In Bruen , we explained that
when a firearm regulation is challenged under the Second Amendment,
the Government must show that the restriction “is consistent with
the Nation’s historical tradition of firearm regulation.” Id ., at 24.
In light of Bruen , the panel withdrew the
prior opinion and ordered additional briefing. A new panel then
heard oral argument and reversed. 61 F. 4th 443, 448 (CA5
2023). Surveying the evidence that the Government had identified,
the panel concluded that Section 922(g)(8) does not fit within our
tradition of firearm regulation. Id ., at 460–461. Judge Ho
wrote separately to express his view that the panel’s ruling did
not conflict with the interest in protecting people from violent
individuals. Id ., at 461–462 (concurring opinion).
We granted certiorari. 600 U. S. ___
(2023)
II
When a restraining order contains a finding
that an individual poses a credible threat to the physical safety
of an intimate partner, that individual may—consistent with the
Second Amendment—be banned from possessing firearms while the order
is in effect. Since the founding, our Nation’s firearm laws have
included provisions preventing individuals who threaten physical
harm to others from misusing firearms. As applied to the facts of
this case, Section 922(g)(8) fits comfortably within this
tradition.
A
We have held that the right to keep and bear
arms is among the “fundamental rights necessary to our system of
ordered liberty.” McDonald v. Chicago , 561 U.S.
742 , 778 (2010). Derived from English practice and codified in
the Second Amendment, the right secures for Americans a means of
self-defense. Bruen , 597 U. S., at 17. The spark that
ignited the American Revolution was struck at Lexington and
Concord, when the British governor dispatched soldiers to seize the
local farmers’ arms and powder stores. In the aftermath of the
Civil War, Congress’s desire to enable the newly freed slaves to
defend themselves against former Confederates helped inspire the
passage of the Fourteenth Amendment, which secured the right to
bear arms against interference by the States. McDonald , 561
U. S., at 771–776. As a leading and early proponent of
emancipation observed, “Disarm a community and you rob them of the
means of defending life. Take away their weapons of defense and you
take away the inalienable right of defending liberty.” Cong. Globe,
40th Cong., 2d Sess., 1967 (1868) (statement of Rep. Stevens).
“Like most rights,” though, “the right secured
by the Second Amendment is not unlimited.” District of
Columbia v. Heller , 554 U.S.
570 , 626 (2008). In Heller , this Court held that the
right applied to ordinary citizens within the home. Even as we did
so, however, we recognized that the right was never thought to
sweep indiscriminately. “From Blackstone through the 19th-century
cases, commentators and courts routinely explained that the right
was not a right to keep and carry any weapon whatsoever in any
manner whatsoever and for whatever purpose.” Ibid . At the
founding, the bearing of arms was subject to regulations ranging
from rules about firearm storage to restrictions on gun use by
drunken New Year’s Eve revelers. Act of Mar. 1, 1783, 1783 Mass.
Acts and Laws ch.13, pp. 218–219; 5 Colonial Laws of New York ch.
1501, pp. 244–246 (1894). Some jurisdictions banned the carrying of
“dangerous and unusual weapons.” 554 U. S., at 627 (citing 4
W. Blackstone, Commentaries on the Laws of England 148–149 (1769)).
Others forbade carrying concealed firearms. 554 U. S., at
626.
In Heller , our inquiry into the scope of
the right began with “constitutional text and history.” Bruen , 597 U. S., at 22. In Bruen , we directed
courts to examine our “historical tradition of firearm regulation”
to help delineate the contours of the right. Id ., at 17. We
explained that if a challenged regulation fits within that
tradition, it is lawful under the Second Amendment. We also
clarified that when the Government regulates arms-bearing conduct,
as when the Government regulates other constitutional rights, it
bears the burden to “justify its regulation.” Id. , at
24.
Nevertheless, some courts have misunderstood the
methodology of our recent Second Amendment cases. These precedents
were not meant to suggest a law trapped in amber. As we explained
in Heller , for example, the reach of the Second Amendment is
not limited only to those arms that were in existence at the
founding. 554 U. S., at 582. Rather, it “extends, prima facie,
to all instruments that constitute bearable arms, even those that
were not [yet] in existence.” Ibid. By that same logic, the
Second Amendment permits more than just those regulations identical
to ones that could be found in 1791. Holding otherwise would be as
mistaken as applying the protections of the right only to muskets
and sabers.
As we explained in Bruen , the appropriate
analysis involves considering whether the challenged regulation is
consistent with the principles that underpin our regulatory
tradition. 597 U. S., at 26–31. A court must ascertain whether
the new law is “relevantly similar” to laws that our tradition is
understood to permit, “apply[ing] faithfully the balance struck by
the founding generation to modern circumstances.” Id ., at
29, and n. 7. Discerning and developing the law in this way is “a
commonplace task for any lawyer or judge.” Id ., at 28.
Why and how the regulation burdens the right are
central to this inquiry. Id ., at 29. For example, if laws at
the founding regulated firearm use to address particular problems,
that will be a strong indicator that contemporary laws imposing
similar restrictions for similar reasons fall within a permissible
category of regulations. Even when a law regulates arms-bearing for
a permissible reason, though, it may not be compatible with the
right if it does so to an extent beyond what was done at the
founding. And when a challenged regulation does not precisely match
its historical precursors, “it still may be analogous enough to
pass constitutional muster.” Id ., at 30 . The law must
comport with the principles underlying the Second Amendment, but it
need not be a “dead ringer” or a “historical twin.” Ibid. (emphasis deleted).[ 1 ]
B
Bearing these principles in mind, we conclude
that Section 922(g)(8) survives Rahimi’s challenge.
1
Rahimi challenges Section 922(g)(8) on its
face. This is the “most difficult challenge to mount successfully,”
because it requires a defendant to “establish that no set of
circumstances exists under which the Act would be valid.” United
States v. Salerno , 481 U.S.
739 , 745 (1987). That means that to prevail, the Government
need only demonstrate that Section 922(g)(8) is constitutional in
some of its applications. And here the provision is constitutional
as applied to the facts of Rahimi’s own case.
Recall that Section 922(g)(8) provides two
independent bases for liability. Section 922(g)(8)(C)(i) bars an
individual from possessing a firearm if his restraining order
includes a finding that he poses “a credible threat to the physical
safety” of a protected person. Separately, Section 922(g)(8)(C)(ii)
bars an individual from possessing a firearm if his restraining
order “prohibits the use, attempted use, or threatened use of
physical force.” Our analysis starts and stops with Section
922(g)(8)(C)(i) because the Government offers ample evidence that
the Second Amendment permits the disarmament of individuals who
pose a credible threat to the physical safety of others. We need
not decide whether regulation under Section 922(g)(8)(C)(ii) is
also permissible.
2
This Court reviewed the history of American
gun laws extensively in Heller and Bruen . From the
earliest days of the common law, firearm regulations have included
provisions barring people from misusing weapons to harm or menace
others. The act of “go[ing] armed to terrify the King’s subjects”
was recognized at common law as a “great offence.” Sir John
Knight’s Case , 3 Mod. 117, 118, 87 Eng. Rep. 75, 76 (K. B.
1686). Parliament began codifying prohibitions against such conduct
as early as the 1200s and 1300s, most notably in the Statute of
Northampton of 1328. Bruen , 597 U. S., at 40. In the
aftermath of the Reformation and the English Civil War, Parliament
passed further restrictions. The Militia Act of 1662, for example,
authorized the King’s agents to “seize all Armes in the custody or
possession of any person . . . judge[d] dangerous to the
Peace of the Kingdome.” 14 Car. 2 c. 3, §13 (1662); J. Greenlee,
The Historical Justification for Prohibiting Dangerous Persons From
Possessing Arms, 20 Wyo. L. Rev. 249, 259 (2020).
The Glorious Revolution cut back on the power of
the Crown to disarm its subjects unilaterally. King James II had
“caus[ed] several good Subjects being Protestants to be disarmed at
the same Time when Papists were . . . armed.” 1 Wm. &
Mary c. 2, §6, in 3 Eng. Stat. at Large 440 (1689). By way of
rebuke, Parliament adopted the English Bill of Rights, which
guaranteed “that the Subjects which are Protestants, may have Arms
for their Defence suitable to their Conditions, and as allowed by
Law.” §7, id ., at 441. But as the document itself
memorialized, the principle that arms-bearing was constrained “by
Law” remained. Ibid .
Through these centuries, English law had
disarmed not only brigands and highwaymen but also political
opponents and disfavored religious groups. By the time of the
founding, however, state constitutions and the Second Amendment had
largely eliminated governmental authority to disarm political
opponents on this side of the Atlantic. See Heller , 554
U. S., at 594–595, 600–603. But regulations targeting
individuals who physically threatened others persisted. Such
conduct was often addressed through ordinary criminal laws and
civil actions, such as prohibitions on fighting or private suits
against individuals who threatened others. See 4 W. Blackstone,
Commentaries on the Laws of England 145–146, 149–150 (10th ed.
1787) (Blackstone); 3 id ., at 120. By the 1700s and early
1800s, however, two distinct legal regimes had developed that
specifically addressed firearms violence.
The first were the surety laws. A form of
“preventive justice,” these laws derived from the ancient practice
of frankpledges. 4 id ., at 251–253. Reputedly dating to the
time of Canute, the frankpledge system involved compelling adult
men to organize themselves into ten-man “tithing[s].” A. Lefroy,
Anglo-Saxon Period of English Law, Part II, 26 Yale L. J. 388,
391 (1917). The members of each tithing then “mutually pledge[d]
for each other’s good behaviour.” 4 Blackstone 252. Should any of
the ten break the law, the remaining nine would be responsible for
producing him in court, or else face punishment in his stead. D.
Levinson, Collective Sanctions, 56 Stan. L. Rev. 345, 358
(2003).
Eventually, the communal frankpledge system
evolved into the individualized surety regime. Under the surety
laws, a magistrate could “oblig[e] those persons, [of] whom there
is a probable ground to suspect of future misbehaviour, to
stipulate with and to give full assurance . . . that such
offence . . . shall not happen[,] by finding pledges or
securities.” 4 Blackstone 251. In other words, the law authorized
magistrates to require individuals suspected of future misbehavior
to post a bond. Ibid . If an individual failed to post a
bond, he would be jailed. See, e . g ., Mass. Rev.
Stat., ch. 134, §6 (1836). If the individual did post a bond and
then broke the peace, the bond would be forfeit. 4 Blackstone
253 . Well entrenched in the common law, the surety
laws could be invoked to prevent all forms of violence, including
spousal abuse. As Blackstone explained, “[w]ives [could] demand
[sureties] against their husbands; or husbands, if necessary,
against their wives.” Id ., at 254. These often took the form
of a surety of the peace, meaning that the defendant pledged to
“keep the peace.” Id ., at 252–253; see R. Bloch, The
American Revolution, Wife Beating, and the Emergent Value of
Privacy, 5 Early American Studies 223, 232–233, 234–235 (2007)
(Bloch) (discussing peace bonds). Wives also demanded sureties for
good behavior, whereby a husband pledged to “demean and behave
himself well.” 4 Blackstone 253; see Bloch 232–233, 234–235, and n.
34.
While communities sometimes resorted to public
shaming or vigilante justice to chastise abusers, sureties provided
the public with a more measured solution. B. McConville, The Rise
of Rough Music, in Riot and Revelry in Early America 90–100 (W.
Pencak, M. Dennis, & S. Newman eds. 2002). In one widely
reported incident, Susannah Wyllys Strong, the wife of a
Connecticut judge, appeared before Tapping Reeve in 1790 to make a
complaint against her husband. K. Ryan, “The Spirit of
Contradiction”: Wife Abuse in New England, 1780–1820, 13 Early
American Studies 586, 602 (2015). Newspapers carried the story in
Connecticut, Massachusetts, and New York. Ibid . Reeve
ultimately ordered the man to post a bond of £1,000. Id ., at
603.
Importantly for this case, the surety laws also
targeted the misuse of firearms. In 1795, for example,
Massachusetts enacted a law authorizing justices of the peace to
“arrest” all who “go armed offensively [and] require of the
offender to find sureties for his keeping the peace.” 1795 Mass.
Acts ch. 2, in Acts and Resolves of Massachusetts, 1794–1795, ch.
26, pp. 66–67 (1896). Later, Massachusetts amended its surety laws
to be even more specific, authorizing the imposition of bonds from
individuals “[who went] armed with a dirk, dagger, sword, pistol,
or other offensive and dangerous weapon.” Mass. Rev. Stat., ch.
134, §16; see ibid. (marginal note) (referencing the earlier
statute). At least nine other jurisdictions did the same. See Bruen , 597 U. S., at 56, and n. 23.
These laws often offered the accused significant
procedural protections. Before the accused could be compelled to
post a bond for “go[ing] armed,” a complaint had to be made to a
judge or justice of the peace by “any person having reasonable
cause to fear” that the accused would do him harm or breach the
peace. Mass. Rev. Stat., ch. 134, §§1, 16. The magistrate would
take evidence, and—if he determined that cause existed for the
charge—summon the accused, who could respond to the allegations.
§§3–4. Bonds could not be required for more than six months at a
time, and an individual could obtain an exception if he needed his
arms for self-defense or some other legitimate reason. §16.
While the surety laws provided a mechanism for
preventing violence before it occurred, a second regime provided a
mechanism for punishing those who had menaced others with firearms.
These were the “going armed” laws, a particular subset of the
ancient common-law prohibition on affrays.
Derived from the French word “affraier,” meaning
“to terrify,” 4 Blackstone 145, the affray laws traced their origin
to the Statute of Northampton, 2 Edw. 3 c. 3 (1328). Although the
prototypical affray involved fighting in public, commentators
understood affrays to encompass the offense of “arm[ing]” oneself
“to the Terror of the People,” T. Barlow, The Justice of the Peace:
A Treatise 11 (1745). Moreover, the prohibitions—on fighting and
going armed—were often codified in the same statutes. E . g ., 2 Edw. 3 c. 3; Acts and Laws of His Majesty’s
Province of New-Hampshire in New-England 2 (1761).
Whether classified as an affray law or a
distinct prohibition, the going armed laws prohibited “riding or
going armed, with dangerous or unusual weapons, [to]
terrify[ ] the good people of the land.” 4 Blackstone 149
(emphasis deleted). Such conduct disrupted the “public order” and
“le[d] almost necessarily to actual violence.” State v. Huntly , 25 N. C. 418, 421–422 (1843)
( per curiam ). Therefore, the law punished these acts
with “forfeiture of the arms . . . and imprisonment.” 4
Blackstone 149.
In some instances, prohibitions on going armed
and affrays were incorporated into American jurisprudence through
the common law. See, e . g ., Huntly , 25
N. C., at 421–422; O’Neill v. State , 16 Ala. 65,
67 (1849); Hickman v. State , 193 Md. App. 238,
253–255, 996 A.2d 974, 983 (2010) (recognizing that common-law
prohibition on fighting in public remains even now chargeable in
Maryland). More- over, at least four States—Massachusetts, New
Hampshire, North Carolina, and Virginia—expressly codified
prohibitions on going armed. 1786 Va. Acts ch. 21; 2 Laws of the
Commonwealth of Massachusetts from Nov. 28, 1780 to Feb. 28, 1807,
pp. 652–653 (1807); Acts and Laws of His Majesty’s Province of
New-Hampshire in New-England 2 (1761); Collection of All of the
Public Acts of Assembly, of the Province of North-Carolina: Now in
Force and Use 131 (1751) (1741 statute).
3
Taken together, the surety and going armed
laws confirm what common sense suggests: When an individual poses a
clear threat of physical violence to another, the threatening
individual may be disarmed. Section 922(g)(8) is by no means
identical to these founding era regimes, but it does not need to
be. See Bruen , 597 U. S., at 30. Its prohibition on the
possession of firearms by those found by a court to present a
threat to others fits neatly within the tradition the surety and
going armed laws represent.
Like the surety and going armed laws, Section
922(g)(8)(C)(i) applies to individuals found to threaten the
physical safety of another. This provision is “relevantly similar”
to those founding era regimes in both why and how it burdens the
Second Amendment right. Id ., at 29. Section 922(g)(8)
restricts gun use to mitigate demonstrated threats of physical
violence, just as the surety and going armed laws do. Unlike the
regulation struck down in Bruen , Section 922(g)(8) does not
broadly restrict arms use by the public generally.
The burden Section 922(g)(8) imposes on the
right to bear arms also fits within our regulatory tradition. While
we do not suggest that the Second Amendment prohibits the enactment
of laws banning the possession of guns by categories of persons
thought by a legislature to present a special danger of misuse, see Heller , 554 U. S., at 626, we note that Section
922(g)(8) applies only once a court has found that the defendant
“represents a credible threat to the physical safety” of another.
§922(g)(8)(C)(i). That matches the surety and going armed laws,
which involved judicial determinations of whether a particular
defendant likely would threaten or had threatened another with a
weapon.
Moreover, like surety bonds of limited duration,
Section 922(g)(8)’s restriction was temporary as applied to Rahimi.
Section 922(g)(8) only prohibits firearm possession so long as the
defendant “is” subject to a restraining order. §922(g)(8). In
Rahimi’s case that is one to two years after his release from
prison, according to Tex. Fam. Code Ann. §85.025(c) (West 2019).
App. 6–7.
Finally, the penalty—another relevant aspect of
the burden—also fits within the regulatory tradition. The going
armed laws provided for imprisonment, 4 Blackstone 149, and if
imprisonment was permissible to respond to the use of guns to
threaten the physical safety of others, then the lesser restriction
of temporary disarmament that Section 922(g)(8) imposes is also
permissible.
Rahimi argues Heller requires us to
affirm, because Section 922(g)(8) bars individuals subject to
restraining orders from possessing guns in the home, and in Heller we invalidated an “absolute prohibition of handguns
. . . in the home.” 554 U. S., at 636; Brief for
Respondent 32. But Heller never established a categorical
rule that the Constitution prohibits regulations that forbid
firearm possession in the home. In fact, our opinion stated that
many such prohibitions, like those on the possession of firearms by
“felons and the mentally ill,” are “presumptively lawful.” 554
U. S., at 626, 627, n. 26.
Our analysis of the surety laws in Bruen also does not help Rahimi. In Bruen , we explained that the
surety laws were not a proper historical analogue for New York’s
gun licensing regime. 597 U. S., at 55–60. What distinguished
the regimes, we observed, was that the surety laws “presumed that
individuals had a right to . . . carry,” whereas New
York’s law effectively presumed that no citizen had such a right,
absent a special need. Id ., at 56 (emphasis deleted).
Section 922(g)(8)(C)(i) does not make the same faulty presumption.
To the contrary, it presumes, like the surety laws before it, that
the Second Amendment right may only be burdened once a defendant
has been found to pose a credible threat to the physical safety of
others. See ibid .
While we also noted that the surety laws applied
different penalties than New York’s special-need regime, we did so
only to emphasize just how severely the State treated the rights of
its citizens. Id ., at 57. But as we have explained, our
Nation’s tradition of firearm regulation distinguishes citizens who
have been found to pose a credible threat to the physical safety of
others from those who have not. The conclusion that focused
regulations like the surety laws are not a historical analogue for
a broad prohibitory regime like New York’s does not mean that they
cannot be an appropriate analogue for a narrow one.
4
In short, we have no trouble concluding that
Section 922(g)(8) survives Rahimi’s facial challenge. Our tradition
of firearm regulation allows the Government to disarm individuals
who present a credible threat to the physical safety of others.
Section 922(g)(8) can be applied lawfully to Rahimi.
The dissent reaches a contrary conclusion,
primarily on the ground that the historical analogues for Section
922(g)(8) are not sufficiently similar to place that provision in
our historical tradition. The dissent does, however, acknowledge
that Section 922(g)(8) is within that tradition when it comes to
the “why” of the appropriate inquiry. The objection is to the
“how.” See post , at 18 (opinion of Thomas, J.). For the
reasons we have set forth, however, we conclude that Section
922(g)(8) satisfies that part of the inquiry as well. See supra , at 7, 13–15. As we said in Bruen , a
“historical twin ” is not required. 597 U. S., at
30.
For its part, the Fifth Circuit made two errors.
First, like the dissent, it read Bruen to require a
“historical twin” rather than a “historical analogue.” Ibid .
(emphasis deleted). Second, it did not correctly apply our
precedents governing facial challenges. 61 F. 4th, at 453. As
we have said in other contexts, “[w]hen legislation and the
Constitution brush up against each other, [a court’s] task is to
seek harmony, not to manufacture conflict.” United States v. Hansen , 599 U.S. 762, 781 (2023). Rather than consider the
circumstances in which Section 922(g)(8) was most likely to be
constitutional, the panel instead focused on hypothetical scenarios
where Section 922(g)(8) might raise constitutional concerns. See 61
F. 4th, at 459; id ., at 465–467 (Ho, J., concurring).
That error left the panel slaying a straw man.[ 2 ]
5
Finally, in holding that Section 922(g)(8) is
constitutional as applied to Rahimi, we reject the Government’s
contention that Rahimi may be disarmed simply because he is not
“responsible.” Brief for United States 6; see Tr. of Oral Arg.
8–11. “Responsible” is a vague term. It is unclear what such a rule
would entail. Nor does such a line derive from our case law. In Heller and Bruen , we used the term “responsible” to
describe the class of ordinary citizens who undoubtedly enjoy the
Second Amendment right. See, e . g ., Heller , 554
U. S., at 635; Bruen , 597 U. S., at 70. But those
decisions did not define the term and said nothing about the status
of citizens who were not “responsible.” The question was simply not
presented.
* * *
In Heller , McDonald , and Bruen , this Court did not “undertake an exhaustive
historical analysis . . . of the full scope of the Second
Amendment.” Bruen , 597 U. S., at 31. Nor do we do so
today. Rather, we conclude only this: An individual found by a
court to pose a credible threat to the physical safety of another
may be temporarily disarmed consistent with the Second
Amendment.
The judgment of the Court of Appeals for the
Fifth Circuit is reversed, and the case is remanded for further
proceedings consistent with this opinion.
It is so ordered. Notes 1 We also recognized in Bruen the “ongoing scholarly debate onwhether courts should
primarily rely on the prevailing understanding of an individual
right when the Fourteenth Amendment was ratified in 1868 when
defining its scope (as well as the scope of the right against the
Federal Government).” 597 U. S., at 37. We explained that
under the circumstances, resolving the dispute was unnecessary to
decide the case. Id ., at 37–38. The same is true
here. 2 Many of the potential
faults that the Fifth Circuit identifies in Section 922(g)(8)
appear to sound in due process rather than the Second Amendment. E . g ., 61 F. 4th, at 459; id ., at 465–467
(Ho, J., concurring). As we have explained, unless these
hypothetical faults occur in every case, they do not justify
invalidating Section 922(g)(8) on its face. See United
States v. Salerno , 481 U.S.
739 , 745 (1987) (a facial challenge fails if the law is
constitutional in at least some of its applications). In any event,
we need not address any due process concern here because this
challenge was not litigated as a due process challenge and there is
no such claim before us. See this Court’s Rule
14.1(a). SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES
_________________
No. 22–915
_________________
UNITED STATES, PETITIONER v. ZACKEY
RAHIMI
on writ of certiorari to the united states
court of appeals for the fifth circuit
[June 21, 2024]
Justice Sotomayor, with whom Justice Kagan
joins, concurring.
Today, the Court applies its decision in New
York State Rifle & Pistol Assn., Inc. v. Bruen , 597
U.S. 1 (2022), for the first time. Although I continue to believe
that Bruen was wrongly decided, see id ., at 83–133
(Breyer, J., joined by Sotomayor and Kagan, JJ., dissenting), I
join the Court’s opinion applying that precedent to uphold 18
U. S. C. §922(g)(8).
The Court today emphasizes that a challenged
regulation “must comport with the principles underlying the Second
Amendment,” but need not have a precise historical match. Ante, at 7–8. I agree. I write separately to highlight why
the Court’s interpretation of Bruen , and not the dissent’s,
is the right one. In short, the Court’s interpretation permits a
historical inquiry calibrated to reveal something useful and
transferable to the present day, while the dissent would make the
historical inquiry so exacting as to be useless, a too-sensitive
alarm that sounds whenever a regulation did not exist in an
essentially identical form at the founding.
I
Even under Bruen , this is an easy case.
Section 922(g)(8) prohibits an individual subject to a domestic
violence restraining order from possessing a firearm, so long as
certain criteria are met. See ante, at 3–4. Section
922(g)(8) is wholly consistent with the Nation’s history and
tradition of firearm regulation.
The Court correctly concludes that “the Second
Amendment permits the disarmament of individuals who pose a
credible threat to the physical safety of others.” Ante, at
8. That conclusion finds historical support in both the surety
laws, which “provided a mechanism for preventing violence before it
occurred” by requiring an individual who posed a credible threat of
violence to another to post a surety, and the “going armed” laws,
which “provided a mechanism for punishing those who had menaced
others with firearms” through forfeiture of the arms or
imprisonment. Ante, at 12. “Taken together, the surety and
going armed laws confirm what common sense suggests: When an
individual poses a clear threat of physical violence to another,
the threatening individual may be disarmed.” Ante, at 13.
Section 922(g)(8)’s prohibition on gun possession for individuals
subject to domestic violence restraining orders is part of that
“tradition of firearm regulation allow[ing] the Government to
disarm individuals who present a credible threat to the physical
safety of others,” ante, at 16, as are the similar
restrictions that have been adopted by 48 States and Territories,
see Brief for United States 34–35, and nn. 22–23 (collecting
statutes).
The Court’s opinion also clarifies an important
methodological point that bears repeating: Rather than asking
whether a present-day gun regulation has a precise historical
analogue, courts applying Bruen should “conside[r] whether
the challenged regulation is consistent with the principles that underpin our regulatory tradition.” Ante, at 7
(emphasis added); see also ante, at 7–8 (“The law must
comport with the principles underlying the Second Amendment, but it
need not be a ‘dead ringer’ or a ‘historical twin’ ” (quoting Bruen , 597 U. S., at 30)). Here, for example, the
Government has not identified a founding-era or Reconstruction-era
law that specifically disarmed domestic abusers, see, e . g ., Tr. of Oral Arg. 40 (conceding as much), but it
did not need to do so. Although §922(g)(8) “is by no means
identical” to the surety or going armed laws, ante, at 13,
it “restricts gun use to mitigate demonstrated threats of physical
violence, just as the surety and going armed laws d[id],” ante, at 14. That shared principle is sufficient.
II
The dissent reaches a different conclusion by
applying the strictest possible interpretation of Bruen . It
picks off the Government’s historical sources one by one, viewing
any basis for distinction as fatal. See, e . g ., post , at 18 (opinion of Thomas, J.) (“Although surety laws
shared a common justification with §922(g)(8), surety laws imposed
a materially different burden”); post , at 25–26 (explaining
that “[a]ffray laws are wide of the mark” because they “expressly
carve out the very conduct §922(g)(8) was designed to prevent
(interpersonal violence in the home)”). The dissent urges a close
look “at the historical law’s justification as articulated during
the relevant time period,” post , at 28, and a “careful
parsing of regulatory burdens” to ensure that courts do not “stray
too far from [history] by eliding material differences between
historical and modern laws,” post , at 15. The dissent
criticizes this Court for adopting a more “piecemeal approach” that
distills principles from a variety of historical evidence rather
than insisting on a precise historical analogue. Post , at
21.
If the dissent’s interpretation of Bruen were the law, then Bruen really would be the “one-way
ratchet” that I and the other dissenters in that case feared,
“disqualify[ing] virtually any ‘representative historical analogue’
and mak[ing] it nearly impossible to sustain common-sense
regulations necessary to our Nation’s safety and security.” 597
U. S., at 112 (Breyer, J., dissenting). Thankfully, the Court
rejects that rigid approach to the historical inquiry. As the Court
puts it today, Bruen was “not meant to suggest a law trapped
in amber.” Ante, at 7.
This case lays bare the perils of the dissent’s
approach. Because the dissent concludes that Ҥ922(g)(8) addresses
a societal problem—the risk of interpersonal violence—‘that has
persisted since the 18th century,’ ” it insists that the means
of addressing that problem cannot be “ ‘materially
different’ ” from the means that existed in the 18th century. Post , at 7. That is so, it seems, even when the weapons in
question have evolved dramatically. See R. Roth, Why Guns Are and
Are Not the Problem, in A Right To Bear Arms?: The Contested Role
of History in Contemporary Debates on the Second Amendment 117 (J.
Tucker, B. Hacker, & M. Vining eds. 2019) (explaining that guns
in the 18th century took a long time to load, typically fired only
one shot, and often misfired). According to the dissent, the
solution cannot be “materially different” even when societal
perception of the problem has changed, and even if it is now clear
to everyone that the historical means of addressing the problem had
been wholly inadequate. Given the fact that the law at the founding
was more likely to protect husbands who abused their spouses than
offer some measure of accountability, see, e . g ., R.
Siegel, “The Rule of Love”: Wife Beating as Prerogative and
Privacy, 105 Yale L. J. 2117, 2154–2170 (1996), it is no
surprise that that generation did not have an equivalent to
§922(g)(8). Under the dissent’s approach, the legislatures of today
would be limited not by a distant generation’s determination that
such a law was unconstitutional, but by a distant generation’s
failure to consider that such a law might be necessary. History has
a role to play in Second Amendment analysis, but a rigid adherence
to history, (particularly history predating the inclusion of women
and people of color as full members of the polity), impoverishes
constitutional interpretation and hamstrings our democracy.
III
The Court today clarifies Bruen ’s
historical inquiry and rejects the dissent’s exacting historical
test. I welcome that development. That being said, I remain
troubled by Bruen ’s myopic focus on history and tradition,
which fails to give full consideration to the real and present
stakes of the problems facing our society today. In my view, the
Second Amendment allows legislators “to take account of the serious
problems posed by gun violence,” Bruen , 597 U. S., at
91 (Breyer, J., dissenting), not merely by asking what their
predecessors at the time of the founding or Reconstruction thought,
but by listening to their constituents and crafting new and
appropriately tailored solutions. Under the means-end scrutiny that
this Court rejected in Bruen but “regularly use[s]
. . . in cases involving other constitutional
provisions,” id ., at 106, the constitutionality of
§922(g)(8) is even more readily apparent.[ 1 ]*
To start, the Government has a compelling
interest in keeping firearms out of the hands of domestic abusers.
A woman who lives in a house with a domestic abuser is five times
more likely to be murdered if the abuser has access to a gun. See
A. Kivisto & M. Porter, Firearm Use Increases Risk of Multiple
Victims in Domestic Homicides, 48 J. Am. Acad. Psychiatry & L.
26 (2020). With over 70 people shot and killed by an intimate
partner each month in the United States, the seriousness of the
problem can hardly be overstated. See Centers for Disease Control
and Prevention, WISQARS Nat. Violent Death Reporting System,
Violent Deaths Report 2020, https://wisqars.cdc.gov/nvdrs (showing
that 863 people were killed with a firearm by a spouse or other
intimate partner in 2020). Because domestic violence is rarely
confined to the intimate partner that receives the protective
order, the Government’s interest extends even further. In roughly a
quarter of cases where an abuser killed an intimate partner, the
abuser also killed someone else, such as a child, family member, or
roommate. See S. Smith, K. Fowler, & P. Niolon, Intimate
Partner Homicide and Corollary Victims in 16 States: National
Violent Death Reporting System, 2003–2009, 104 Am. J. Pub. Health
461, 463–464 (2014). Moreover, one study found that domestic
disputes were the most dangerous type of call for responding
officers, causing more officer deaths with a firearm than any other
type of call. See N. Breul & M. Keith, Deadly Calls and Fatal
Encounters: Analysis of U. S. Law Enforcement Line of Duty
Deaths When Officers Responded to Dispatched Calls for Service and
Conducted Enforcement, 2010–2014, p. 15 (2016).
While the Second Amendment does not yield
automatically to the Government’s compelling interest, §922(g)(8)
is tailored to the vital objective of keeping guns out of the hands
of domestic abusers. See ante, at 3–4, 14. Section 922(g)(8)
should easily pass constitutional muster under any level of
scrutiny.
Although I continue to think that the means-end
approach to Second Amendment analysis is the right one, neither
party asks the Court to reconsider Bruen at this time, and
that question would of course involve other considerations than
whether Bruen was rightly decided. Whether considered under Bruen or under means-end scrutiny, §922(g)(8) clears the
constitutional bar. I join in full the Court’s opinion, which
offers a more helpful model than the dissent for lower courts
struggling to apply Bruen . Notes 1 *By “means-end scrutiny,” I
refer to the mode of analysis that would permit courts “to consider
the State’s interest in preventing gun violence, the effectiveness
of the contested law in achieving that interest, the degree to
which the law burdens the Second Amendment right, and, if
appropriate, any less restrictive alternatives.” Bruen , 597
U. S., at 131 (Breyer, J., dissenting). Prior to Bruen ,
the Courts of Appeals would apply a level of means-end scrutiny
“ ‘proportionate to the severity of the burden that the law
imposes on the right’: strict scrutiny if the burden is severe, and
intermediate scrutiny if it is not.” Id ., at
103. SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES
_________________
No. 22–915
_________________
UNITED STATES, PETITIONER v. ZACKEY RAHIMI
on writ of certiorari to the united states court of appeals for
the fifth circuit
[June 21, 2024]
Justice Gorsuch, concurring.
Mr. Rahimi pursues the “most difficult challenge to mount
successfully”: a facial challenge. United States v. Salerno , 481 U.S.
739 , 745 (1987). He contends that 18 U. S. C.
§922(g)(8) violates the Second Amendment “in all its applications.” Bucklew v. Precythe , 587 U.S. 119, 138 (2019). To
prevail, he must show “no set of circumstances” exists in which
that law can be applied without violating the Second Amendment. Salerno , 481 U. S., at 745. I agree with the Court that
he has failed to make that showing. Ante , at 8.
That is not because the Constitution has little to say about the
matter. The Second Amendment protects the “right of the people to
keep and bear Arms.” “ ‘[T]ext and history’ ” dictate the
contours of that right. Ante , at 6 (quoting New York
State Rifle Pistol Assn., Inc. v. Bruen , 597 U.S. 1, 22
(2022)). As this Court has recognized, too, the Amendment’s text
“ ‘guarantee[s] the individual right to possess and carry
weapons in case of confrontation.’ ” Id ., at 32
(quoting District of Columbia v. Heller , 554 U.S.
570 , 592 (2008)). And where that “text covers an individual’s
conduct,” a law regulating that conduct may be upheld only if it is
“consistent with this Nation’s historical tradition of firearms
regulation.” 597 U. S., at 17; see ante , at 6.
In this case, no one questions that the law Mr. Rahimi
challenges addresses individual conduct covered by the text of the
Second Amendment. So, in this facial challenge, the question
becomes whether that law, in at least some of its applications, is
consistent with historic firearm regulations. To prevail, the
government need not show that the current law is a “ ‘dead
ringer’ ” for some historical analogue. Ante , at 8
(quoting Bruen , 597 U. S., at 30). But the government
must establish that, in at least some of its applications, the
challenged law “impose[s] a comparable burden on the right of armed
self-defense” to that imposed by a historically recognized
regulation. Id ., at 29; see ante , at 7. And it must
show that the burden imposed by the current law “is comparably
justified.” Bruen , 597 U. S., at 29; see ante ,
at 7.
Why do we require those showings? Through them, we seek to honor
the fact that the Second Amendment “codified a pre-existing right” belonging to the American people, one that carries the same
“scope” today that it was “understood to have when the people
adopted” it. Heller , 554 U. S., at 592, 634–635. When
the people ratified the Second Amendment, they surely understood an
arms-bearing citizenry posed some risks. But just as surely they
believed that the right protected by the Second Amendment was
itself vital to the preservation of life and liberty. See, e . g ., 1 Blackstone’s Commentaries, Editor’s App. 300
(St. George Tucker ed. 1803) (observing that the Second Amendment
may represent the “palladium of liberty,” for “[t]he right of self
defence is the first law of nature,” and “in most governments[,] it
has been the study of rulers to confine this right within the
narrowest limits”); 3 J. Story, Commentaries on the Constitution of
the United States §1890, p. 746 (1833) (“The right of the citizens
to keep and bear arms has justly been considered, as the palladium
of the liberties of a republic”).
We have no authority to question that judgment. As judges
charged with respecting the people’s directions in the
Constitution—directions that are “trapped in amber,” see ante , at 7—our only lawful role is to apply them in the
cases that come before us. Developments in the world may change,
facts on the ground may evolve, and new laws may invite new
challenges, but the Constitution the people adopted remains our
enduring guide. Bruen , 597 U. S., at 27–28; see, e . g ., United States v. Jones , 565 U.S.
400 , 404–405 (2012); Caetano v. Massachusetts , 577 U.S.
411 , 411–412 (2016) ( per curiam ). If changes are to
be made to the Constitution’s directions, they must be made by the
American people. Nor is there anything remotely unusual about any
of this. Routinely, litigants and courts alike must consult history
when seeking to discern the meaning and scope of a constitutional
provision. See post , at 6–16 (Kavanaugh, J., concurring)
(offering examples). And when doing so, litigants and courts “must
exercise care.” See post , at 3, n. (Barrett, J.,
concurring).
Consider just one example. We have recognized that the Sixth
Amendment enshrines another pre-existing right: the right of a
defendant to confront his accusers at trial. Crawford v. Washington , 541 U.S.
36 , 54 (2004). Just as here, we have recognized that, in
placing this right in the Constitution, the people set its scope,
“admitting only those exceptions established at the time of the
founding.” Ibid. And, just as here, when a party asks us to
sustain some modern exception to the confrontation right, we
require them to point to a close historic analogue to justify it.
See Giles v. California , 554
U.S. 353 , 358–361 (2008). Just as here, too, we have expressly
rejected arguments that courts should proceed differently, such as
by trying to glean from historic exceptions overarching “policies,”
“ ‘purposes,’ ” or “values” to guide them in future
cases. See id ., at 374–375 (opinion of Scalia, J.). We have
rejected those paths because the Constitution enshrines the
people’s choice to achieve certain policies, purposes, and values
“through very specific means”: the right of confrontation as
originally understood at the time of the founding. Id ., at
375. As we have put it, a court may not “extrapolate” from the
Constitution’s text and history “the values behind [that right],
and then . . . enforce its guarantees only to the extent
they serve (in the courts’ views) those underlying values.” Ibid. Proceeding that way, we have warned, risks handing
judges a license to turn “the guarantee of confrontation” into “no
guarantee at all.” Ibid . As there, so too here: Courts must
proceed with care in making comparisons to historic firearms
regulations, or else they risk gaming away an individual right the
people expressly preserved for themselves in the Constitution’s
text.
Proceeding with this well in mind today, the Court rightly holds
that Mr. Rahimi’s facial challenge to §922(g)(8) cannot succeed. It
cannot because, through surety laws and restrictions on “going
armed,” the people in this country have understood from the start
that the government may disarm an individual temporarily after a
“judicial determinatio[n]” that he “likely would threaten or ha[s]
threatened another with a weapon.” Ante , at 14. And, at
least in some cases, the statute before us works in the same way
and does so for the same reasons: It permits a court to disarm a
person only if, after notice and hearing, it finds that he
“represents a credible threat to the physical safety” of others.
§§922(g)(8)(A), (g)(8)(C)(i). A court, too, may disarm an
individual only for so long as its order is in effect. §922(g)(8).
In short, in at least some applications, the challenged law does
not diminish any aspect of the right the Second Amendment was
originally understood to protect. See Bruen , 597 U. S.,
at 24.
I appreciate that one of our colleagues sees things differently. Post , at 6–7 (Thomas, J., dissenting). But if reasonable
minds can disagree whether §922(g)(8) is analogous to past
practices originally understood to fall outside the Second
Amendment’s scope, we at least agree that is the only proper
question a court may ask. Post , at 5. Discerning what the
original meaning of the Constitution requires in this or that case
may sometimes be difficult. Asking that question, however, at least
keeps judges in their proper lane, seeking to honor the supreme law
the people have ordained rather than substituting our will for
theirs. And whatever indeterminacy may be associated with seeking
to honor the Constitution’s original meaning in modern disputes,
that path offers surer footing than any other this Court has
attempted from time to time. Come to this Court with arguments from
text and history, and we are bound to reason through them as best
we can. (As we have today.) Allow judges to reign unbounded by
those materials, or permit them to extrapolate their own broad new
principles from those sources, and no one can have any idea how
they might rule. (Except the judges themselves.) Faithful adherence
to the Constitution’s original meaning may be an imperfect guide,
but I can think of no more perfect one for us to follow.
Just consider how lower courts approached the Second Amendment
before our decision in Bruen . They reviewed firearm
regulations under a two-step test that quickly “devolved” into an
interest-balancing inquiry, where courts would weigh a law’s burden
on the right against the benefits the law offered. See Rogers v. Grewal , 590 U. S. ___, ___, and n. 1
(2020) (Thomas, J., joined by Kavanaugh, J., dissenting from denial
of certiorari) (slip op., at 5, and n. 1); see also, e . g ., Peruta v. County of San Diego ,
742 F.3d 1144, 1167–1168, 1176–1177 (CA9 2014); Drake v. Filko , 724 F.3d 426, 457 (CA3 2013) (Hardiman, J.,
dissenting). Some judges expressed concern that the prevailing
two-step test had become “just window dressing for judicial
policymaking.” Duncan v. Bonta , 19 F. 4th 1087, 1148
(CA9 2021) (en banc) (Bumatay, J., dissenting). To them, the
inquiry worked as a “black box regime” that gave a judge broad
license to support policies he “[f]avored” and discard those he
disliked. Ibid. How did the government fare under that
regime? In one circuit, it had an “undefeated, 50–0 record.” Id ., at 1167, n. 8 (VanDyke, J., dissenting). In Bruen , we rejected that approach for one guided by
constitutional text and history. 597 U. S., at 19. Perhaps
judges’ jobs would be easier if they could simply strike the policy
balance they prefer. And a principle that the government always
wins surely would be simple for judges to implement. But either
approach would let judges stray far from the Constitution’s
promise. See Heller , 554 U. S., at 634.
One more point: Our resolution of Mr. Rahimi’s facial challenge
to §922(g)(8) necessarily leaves open the question whether the
statute might be unconstitutional as applied in “particular
circumstances.” Salerno , 481 U. S., at 751. So, for
example, we do not decide today whether the government may disarm a
person without a judicial finding that he poses a “credible threat”
to another’s physical safety. §922(g)(8)(C)(i); see ante , at
8. We do not resolve whether the government may disarm an
individual permanently. See ante , at 14 (stressing that,
“like surety bonds of limited duration, Section 922(g)(8)’s
restriction was temporary as applied to [Mr.] Rahimi”). We do not
determine whether §922(g)(8) may be constitutionally enforced
against a person who uses a firearm in self-defense. Notably, the
surety laws that inform today’s decision allowed even an individual
found to pose a threat to another to “obtain an exception if he
needed his arms for self-defense.” Ante , at 12; see also post , at 23 (Thomas, J., dissenting). Nor do we purport to
approve in advance other laws denying firearms on a categorical
basis to any group of persons a legislature happens to deem, as the
government puts it, “not ‘responsible.’ ” Ante , at 17
(quoting Brief for United States 6); see Tr. of Oral Arg. 31–32;
see also post , at 27 (opinion of Thomas, J.) (“Not a single
Member of the Court adopts the Government’s theory”).
We do not resolve any of those questions (and perhaps others
like them) because we cannot. Article III of the Constitution vests
in this Court the power to decide only the “ ‘actual
cas[e]’ ” before us, “ ‘not abstractions.’ ” Public Workers v. Mitchell , 330 U.S.
75 , 89 (1947). And the case before us does not pose the
question whether the challenged statute is always lawfully applied,
or whether other statutes might be permissible, but only whether
this one has any lawful scope. Nor should future litigants
and courts read any more into our decision than that. As this Court
has long recognized, what we say in our opinions must “be taken in
connection with the case in which those expressions are used,” Cohens v. Virginia , 6 Wheat. 264, 399 (1821), and may
not be “stretch[ed] . . . beyond their context,” Brown v. Davenport , 596 U.S. 118, 141 (2022).
Among all the opinions issued in this case, its central messages
should not be lost. The Court reinforces the focus on text,
history, and tradition, following exactly the path we described in Bruen . Ante , at 5–8. And after carefully consulting
those materials, the Court “conclude[s] only this”: “An
individual found by a court to pose a credible threat to the
physical safety of another may be temporarily disarmed consistent
with the Second Amendment.” Ante , at 17 (emphasis added).
With these observations, I am pleased to concur. SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES
_________________
No. 22–915
_________________
UNITED STATES, PETITIONER v. ZACKEY RAHIMI
on writ of certiorari to the united states court of appeals for
the fifth circuit
[June 21, 2024]
Justice Kavanaugh, concurring.
The Framers of the Constitution and Bill of Rights wisely sought
the best of both worlds: democratic self-government and the
protection of individual rights against excesses of that form of
government. In justiciable cases, this Court determines whether a
democratically enacted law or other government action infringes on
individual rights guaranteed by the Constitution. When performing
that Article III duty, the Court does not implement its own policy
judgments about, for example, free speech or gun regulation.
Rather, the Court interprets and applies the Constitution by
examining text, pre-ratification and post-ratification history, and
precedent. The Court’s opinion today does just that, and I join it
in full.
The concurring opinions, and the briefs of the parties and amici in this case, raise important questions about judicial
reliance on text, history, and precedent, particularly in Second
Amendment cases. I add this concurring opinion to review the proper
roles of text, history, and precedent in constitutional
interpretation.
I
The American people established an enduring American
Constitution. The first and most important rule in constitutional
interpretation is to heed the text—that is, the actual words of the
Constitution—and to interpret that text according to its ordinary
meaning as originally understood. The text of the Constitution is
the “Law of the Land.” Art. VI. As a general matter, the text of
the Constitution says what it means and means what it says. And
unless and until it is amended, that text controls.
In many important provisions, the Constitution is a document of
majestic specificity with “strikingly clean prose.” A. Amar,
America’s Constitution xi (2005). Two Houses of Congress. A House
elected every two years. Senators serve 6-year terms. Two Senators
per State. A State’s equal suffrage in the Senate may not be
changed without the State’s consent. A two-thirds House vote to
expel a Member of the House. The same for the Senate.
Appropriations are made by law. Bicameralism and presentment. The
Presidential veto. The Presidential pardon. The President serves a
4-year term. A maximum of two elected terms for a President. The
salary of a sitting President may not be increased or decreased. A
vote of a majority of the House and two-thirds of the Senate to
remove a President. The President nominates and the Senate confirms
principal executive officers. One Supreme Court. Tenure and salary
protection for Supreme Court and other federal judges. Two-thirds
of each House of Congress together with three-fourths of the States
may amend the Constitution. Congress meets at noon on January 3rd
unless otherwise specified by Congress. The District of Columbia
votes in Presidential elections. The list goes on.
Those and many other constitutional provisions are relatively
clear. And when the “framers of the Constitution employed words in
their natural sense; and where they are plain and clear, resort to
collateral aids to interpretation is unnecessary and cannot be
indulged in to narrow or enlarge the text.” McPherson v. Blacker , 146 U.S.
1 , 27 (1892).
Of course, some provisions of the Constitution are broadly
worded or vague—to put it in Madison’s words, “more or less obscure
and equivocal.” The Federalist No. 37, p. 229 (C. Rossiter ed.
1961). As Chief Justice Rehnquist explained, the Constitution is in
some parts “obviously not a specifically worded document but one
couched in general phraseology.” W. Rehnquist, The Notion of a
Living Constitution, 54 Texas L. Rev. 693, 697 (1976).
That is especially true with respect to the broadly worded or
vague individual-rights provisions. (I will use the terms “broadly
worded” and “vague” interchangeably in this opinion.) For example,
the First Amendment provides that “Congress shall make no law”
“abridging the freedom of speech.” And the Second Amendment, at
issue here, guarantees that “the right of the people to keep and
bear Arms” “shall not be infringed.”
Read literally, those Amendments might seem to grant absolute protection, meaning that the government could never
regulate speech or guns in any way. But American law has long
recognized, as a matter of original understanding and original
meaning, that constitutional rights generally come with
exceptions.
With respect to the First Amendment, for example, this Court’s
“jurisprudence over the past 216”—now 233—“years has rejected an
absolutist interpretation.” Federal Election Comm’n v. Wisconsin Right to Life, Inc. , 551 U.S.
449 , 482 (2007) (opinion of Roberts, C. J.); see R. Bork,
Neutral Principles and Some First Amendment Problems, 47 Ind.
L. J. 1, 21–22 (1971). From 1791 to the present, “the First
Amendment has permitted restrictions upon the content of speech in
a few limited areas”—including obscenity, defamation, fraud, and
incitement. United States v. Stevens , 559 U.S.
460 , 468 (2010) (quotation marks omitted). So too with respect
to the Second Amendment: “Like most rights, the right secured by
the Second Amendment is not unlimited”; it is “not a right to keep
and carry any weapon whatsoever in any manner whatsoever and for
whatever purpose.” District of Columbia v. Heller , 554
U.S. 570 , 626 (2008).
II
A recurring and difficult issue for judges, therefore, is how to
interpret vague constitutional text. That issue often arises (as
here) in the context of determining exceptions to textually
guaranteed individual rights. To what extent does the Constitution
allow the government to regulate speech or guns, for
example?[ 1 ]
In many cases, judicial precedent informs or controls the answer
(more on that later). But absent precedent, there are really only
two potential answers to the question of how to determine
exceptions to broadly worded constitutional rights: history or
policy.
Generally speaking, the historical approach examines the laws,
practices, and understandings from before and after ratification
that may help the interpreter discern the meaning of the
constitutional text and the principles embodied in that text. The
policy approach rests on the philosophical or policy dispositions
of the individual judge.
History, not policy, is the proper guide.
For more than 200 years, this Court has relied on history when
construing vague constitutional text in all manner of
constitutional disputes. For good reason. History can supply
evidence of the original meaning of vague text. History is far less
subjective than policy. And reliance on history is more consistent
with the properly neutral judicial role than an approach where
judges subtly (or not so subtly) impose their own policy views on
the American people.
Judges are like umpires, as The Chief Justice has aptly
explained. And in a constitutional system that counts on an
independent Judiciary, judges must act like umpires. To be an
umpire, the judge “must stick close to the text and the history,
and their fair implications,” because there “is no principled way”
for a neutral judge “to prefer any claimed human value to any
other.” R. Bork, Neutral Principles and Some First Amendment
Problems, 47 Ind. L. J. 1, 8 (1971). History establishes a
“criterion that is conceptually quite separate from the preferences
of the judge himself.” A. Scalia, Originalism: The Lesser Evil, 57
U. Cin. L. Rev. 849, 864 (1989). When properly applied, history
helps ensure that judges do not simply create constitutional
meaning “out of whole cloth.” A. Scalia, The Rule of Law as a Law
of Rules, 56 U. Chi. L. Rev. 1175, 1183 (1989).[ 2 ]
Absent precedent, therefore, history guides the interpretation
of vague constitutional text. Of course, this Court has been
deciding constitutional cases for about 230 years, so relevant
precedent often exists. As the Court’s opinions over time amply
demonstrate, precedent matters a great deal in constitutional
interpretation.
I now turn to explaining how courts apply pre-ratification
history, post-ratification history, and precedent when analyzing
vague constitutional text.
A Pre-ratification history . When interpreting vague
constitutional text, the Court typically scrutinizes the stated
intentions and understandings of the Framers and Ratifiers of the
Constitution (or, as relevant, the Amendments). The Court also
looks to the understandings of the American people from the
pertinent ratification era. Those intentions and understandings do
not necessarily determine meaning, but they may be strong evidence
of meaning. See generally, e.g. , The Federalist (C. Rossiter
ed. 1961); Records of the Federal Convention of 1787 (M. Farrand
ed. 1911); Debates on the Federal Constitution (J. Elliot ed.
1836).
Especially for the original Constitution and the Bill of Rights,
the Court also examines the pre-ratification history in the
American Colonies, including pre-ratification laws and practices.
And the Court pays particular attention to the historical laws and
practices in the United States from Independence in 1776 until
ratification in 1788 or 1791. Pre-ratification American history can
shed light on constitutional meaning in various ways.
For example, some provisions of the Constitution use language
that appeared in the Articles of Confederation or state
constitutional provisions. And when the language that appeared in
the Articles of Confederation or in state constitutions is the same
as or similar to the language in the U. S. Constitution, the
history of how people understood the language in the Articles or
state constitutions can inform interpretation of that language in
the U. S. Constitution. See, e . g ., Moore v. Harper , 600 U.S. 1, 33 (2023) (the “Framers did not write
the Elections Clause on a blank slate—they instead borrowed from
the Articles of Confederation” as evidenced by their use of
“closely parallel” language); District of Columbia v. Heller , 554 U.S.
570 , 600–601 (2008) (“Our interpretation is confirmed by
analogous arms-bearing rights in state constitutions that preceded
and immediately followed adoption of the Second Amendment”); United States Steel Corp . v. Multistate Tax Comm’n , 434 U.S.
452 , 460, and n. 10 (1978) (“The history of interstate
agreements under the Articles of Confederation suggests the same
distinction between ‘treaties, alliances, and confederations’ on
the one hand, and ‘agreements and compacts’ on the other,” as the
distinction made in the Constitution’s Treaty and Compact
Clauses).
Similarly, other pre-ratification national or state laws and
practices may sometimes help an interpreter discern the meaning of
particular constitutional provisions. Those pre-ratification
American laws and practices formed part of the foundation on which
the Framers constructed the Constitution and Bill of Rights.
Indeed, the Constitution did not displace but largely co-exists
with state constitutions and state laws, except to the extent they
conflict with federal law. See Art. VI.
On the other hand, some pre-ratification history can be
probative of what the Constitution does not mean. The
Framers drafted and approved many provisions of the Constitution
precisely to depart from rather than adhere to certain
pre-ratification laws, practices, or understandings.
For example, the “defects” of the Articles of Confederation
inspired some of the key decisions made by the Framers in
Philadelphia and by the First Congress in drafting the Bill of
Rights. The Federalist No. 37, at 224 (J. Madison); see, e . g ., id ., at 226 (“the existing Confederation
is founded on principles which are fallacious; that we must
consequently change this first foundation, and with it the
superstructure resting upon it”); PennEast Pipeline Co. v. New Jersey , 594 U.S. 482, 508 (2021) (“When the
Framers met in Philadelphia in the summer of 1787, they sought to
create a cohesive national sovereign in response to the failings of
the Articles of Confederation”); Sosa v. Alvarez-Machain , 542 U.S.
692 , 716–717 (2004) (“The Continental Congress was hamstrung by
its inability to ‘cause infractions of treaties, or of the law of
nations to be punished,’ ” and the “Framers responded by
vesting the Supreme Court with original jurisdiction over ‘all
Cases affecting Ambassadors, other public ministers and Consuls,’
and the First Congress followed through” (citation omitted)); U. S. Term Limits, Inc. v. Thornton , 514 U.S.
779 , 803 (1995) (“After the Constitutional Convention convened,
the Framers were presented with, and eventually adopted a variation
of, a plan not merely to amend the Articles of Confederation but to
create an entirely new National Government with a National
Executive, National Judiciary, and a National Legislature”
(quotation marks omitted)).
The pre-ratification history of America’s many objections to
British laws and the system of oppressive British rule over the
Colonies—identified most prominently in the Declaration of
Independence—can likewise inform interpretation of some of the
crucial provisions of the original Constitution and Bill of Rights.
Compare Declaration of Independence ¶11 (under British rule, the
King “made Judges dependent on his Will alone, for the tenure of
their offices, and the amount and payment of their salaries”) with
U. S. Const., Art. III, §1 (“The Judges, both of the
supreme and inferior Courts, shall hold their Offices during good
Behaviour, and shall, at stated Times, receive for their Services,
a Compensation, which shall not be diminished during their
Continuance in Office”); see, e . g ., The Federalist
No. 37, at 226 (“The most that the convention could do” “was to
avoid the errors suggested by the past experience of other
countries, as well as of our own”); 1 Annals of Cong. 436 (1789)
(J. Madison) (“The freedom of the press and rights of conscience,
those choicest privileges of the people, are unguarded in the
British Constitution”).
This Court has recognized, for example, that no “purpose in
ratifying the Bill of Rights was clearer than that of securing for
the people of the United States much greater freedom of religion,
expression, assembly, and petition than the people of Great Britain
had ever enjoyed.” Bridges v. California , 314 U.S.
252 , 265 (1941). Ratified as it was “while the memory of many
oppressive English restrictions on the enumerated liberties was
still fresh,” the Bill of Rights “cannot reasonably be taken as
approving prevalent English practices.” Ibid .; see, e . g ., Hosanna-Tabor Evangelical Lutheran Church
and School v. EEOC , 565 U.S.
171 , 183 (2012) (“Familiar with life under the established
Church of England, the founding generation sought to foreclose the
possibility of a national church” through the First Amendment’s
Establishment Clause); Powell v. Alabama , 287 U.S.
45 , 60 (1932) (right to counsel under the Sixth Amendment
reflected America’s rejection of the English common law rule that a
“person charged with treason or felony was denied the aid of
counsel”).[ 3 ]
The Equal Protection Clause provides another example. Ratified
in 1868, that Clause sought to reject the Nation’s history of
racial discrimination, not to backdoor incorporate racially
discriminatory and oppressive historical practices and laws into
the Constitution. See generally Flowers v. Mississippi , 588 U.S. 284 (2019); Batson v. Kentucky , 476 U.S.
79 (1986); Loving v. Virginia , 388 U.S. 1 (1967); Brown v. Board of Education , 347 U.S.
483 (1954).
In short, pre-ratification American history—that is,
pre-ratification laws, practices, and understandings—can inform
interpretation of vague constitutional provisions in the original
Constitution and Bill of Rights. The same principle of looking to
relevant pre-ratification history applies when interpreting broadly
worded language in the later amendments, including the Fourteenth
Amendment ratified in 1868. But in using pre-ratification history,
courts must exercise care to rely only on the history that the
Constitution actually incorporated and not on the history that the
Constitution left behind.
B Post-ratification history . As the Framers made clear, and
as this Court has stated time and again for more than two
centuries, post-ratification history—sometimes referred to as
tradition—can also be important for interpreting vague
constitutional text and determining exceptions to individual
constitutional rights. When the text is vague and the
pre-ratification history is elusive or inconclusive,
post-ratification history becomes especially important. Indeed,
absent precedent, there can be little else to guide a judge
deciding a constitutional case in that situation, unless the judge
simply defaults to his or her own policy preferences.
After ratification, the National Government and the state
governments began interpreting and applying the Constitution’s
text. They have continued to do so ever since. As the national and
state governments over time have enacted laws and implemented
practices to promote the general welfare, those laws and practices
have often reflected and reinforced common understandings of the
Constitution’s authorizations and limitations.
Post-ratification interpretations and applications by government
actors—at least when reasonably consistent and longstanding—can be
probative of the meaning of vague constitutional text. The
collective understanding of Americans who, over time, have
interpreted and applied the broadly worded constitutional text can
provide good guidance for a judge who is trying to interpret that
same text decades or centuries later. See, e . g ., Republican Party of Minn. v. White , 536 U.S.
765 , 785 (2002) (a “universal and long-established tradition of
prohibiting certain conduct creates a strong presumption that the
prohibition is constitutional” (quotation marks omitted)); United States v. Midwest Oil Co. , 236 U.S.
459 , 472–473 (1915) (“officers, law-makers and citizens
naturally adjust themselves to any long-continued action” of the
government “on the presumption that” unconstitutional “acts would
not have been allowed to be so often repeated as to crystallize
into a regular practice”); McPherson v. Blacker , 146 U.S.
1 , 27 (1892) (when constitutional text is vague,
“contemporaneous and subsequent practical construction are entitled
to the greatest weight”).[ 4 ]
Importantly, the Framers themselves intended that
post-ratification history would shed light on the meaning of vague
constitutional text. They understood that some constitutional text
may be “more or less obscure and equivocal” such that questions
“daily occur in the course of practice.” The Federalist No. 37, at
228–229. Madison explained that the meaning of vague text would be
“liquidated and ascertained by a series of particular discussions
and adjudications.” Id ., at 229. In other words, Madison
articulated the Framers’ expectation and intent that
post-ratification history would be a proper and important tool to
help constitutional interpreters determine the meaning of vague
constitutional text.
From early on, this Court followed Madison’s lead. In 1819, in
one of its most important decisions ever, the Court addressed the
scope of Article I’s Necessary and Proper Clause. McCulloch v. Maryland , 4 Wheat. 316 (1819). Writing for the Court,
Chief Justice Marshall invoked post-ratification history to
conclude that Congress’s authority to establish a national bank
could “scarcely be considered as an open question.” Id ., at
401. The constitutionality of the national bank had “been
recognised by many successive legislatures,” and an “exposition of
the constitution, deliberately established by legislative acts, on
the faith of which an immense property has been advanced, ought not
to be lightly disregarded.” Ibid. Marshall added: The
“respective powers of those who are equally the representatives of
the people, are to be adjusted; if not put at rest by the practice
of the government, ought to receive a considerable impression from
that practice.” Ibid .
In relying on post-ratification history as a proper tool to
discern constitutional meaning, Madison and Marshall make for a
formidable duo. Moving from distant American history to more recent
times, one can add Justice Scalia. Throughout his consequential
30-year tenure on this Court, Justice Scalia repeatedly emphasized
that constitutional interpretation must take account of text,
pre-ratification history, and post-ratification history—the last of
which he often referred to as “tradition.” In his words, when
judges interpret vague or broadly worded constitutional text, the
“traditions of our people” are “paramount.” McDonald v. Chicago , 561 U.S.
742 , 792 (2010) (Scalia, J., concurring). Constitutional
interpretation should reflect “the principles adhered to, over
time, by the American people, rather than those favored by the
personal (and necessarily shifting) philosophical dispositions of a
majority of this Court.” Rutan v. Republican Party of
Ill. , 497 U.S.
62 , 96 (1990) (Scalia, J., dissenting).
The U. S. Reports are well stocked with Scalia opinions
looking to post-ratification history and tradition.[ 5 ] In Heller , Justice Scalia wrote for
the Court that “a critical tool of constitutional interpretation”
is “the examination of a variety of legal and other sources to
determine the public understanding of a legal text in the
period after its enactment or ratification.” 554 U. S., at 605
(emphasis in original); see also ibid . (“We now address how
the Second Amendment was interpreted from immediately after its
ratification through the end of the 19th century”). Heller echoed years of earlier Scalia opinions. To take
one: “Where the meaning of a constitutional text (such as ‘the
freedom of speech’) is unclear, the widespread and long-accepted
practices of the American people are the best indication of what
fundamental beliefs it was intended to enshrine.” McIntyre v. Ohio Elections Comm’n , 514
U.S. 334 , 378 (1995) (Scalia, J., dissenting). Or another: A
“venerable and accepted tradition is not to be laid on the
examining table and scrutinized for its conformity to some abstract
principle” of “adjudication devised by this Court. To the contrary,
such traditions are themselves the stuff out of which the Court’s
principles are to be formed. They are, in these uncertain areas,
the very points of reference by which the legitimacy or
illegitimacy of other practices is to be figured out.” Rutan , 497 U. S., at 95–96 (Scalia, J., dissenting)
(emphasis in original).
As leading actors and theorists in the earliest and latest
chapters of the American constitutional story, Madison, Marshall,
and Scalia made clear that courts should look to post-ratification
history as well as pre-ratification history to interpret vague
constitutional text.
For more than two centuries—from the early 1800s to this
case—this Court has done just that. The Court has repeatedly
employed post-ratification history to determine the meaning of
vague constitutional text. Reliance on post-ratification history
“has shaped scores of Court cases spanning all domains of
constitutional law, every era of the nation’s history, and Justices
of every stripe.” S. Girgis, Living Traditionalism, 98 N. Y. U. L.
Rev. 1477, 1480 (2023); see, e.g. , Consumer Financial
Protection Bureau v. Community Financial Services Assn. of
America, Ltd. , 601 U.S. 416, 441–445 (2024) (Kagan, J.,
concurring); Trump v. Anderson , 601 U.S. 100, 113–115
(2024) ( per curiam ); Moore v. Harper , 600
U.S. 1, 22, 32–34 (2023); Kennedy v. Bremerton School Dist. , 597 U.S. 507, 535–536, 540–541, and n. 6
(2022); New York State Rifle Pistol Assn., Inc. v. Bruen , 597 U.S. 1, 35–37, 50–70 (2022); City of
Austin v. Reagan Nat. Advertising of Austin, LLC , 596
U.S. 61, 75 (2022); Houston Community College System v. Wilson , 595 U.S. 468, 474–477 (2022); PennEast Pipeline
Co. v. New Jersey , 594 U.S. 482, 494–497, 508 (2021); TransUnion LLC v. Ramirez , 594 U.S. 413, 424–425,
432–434 (2021); Torres v. Madrid , 592 U.S. 306, 314
(2021); Trump v. Mazars USA, LLP , 591 U.S. 848,
858–862 (2020); Chiafalo v. Washington , 591 U.S. 578,
592–597 (2020); American Legion v. American Humanist
Assn. , 588 U.S. 29, 58–66 (2019); Zivotofsky v. Kerry , 576 U.S.
1 , 15–17, 23–28 (2015); Town of Greece v. Galloway , 572 U.S.
565 , 575–579 (2014); District of Columbia v. Heller , 554 U.S.
570 , 605–619, 626–628 (2008); Crawford v. Washington , 541 U.S.
36 , 47–50 (2004); Apprendi v. New Jersey , 530 U.S.
466 , 481–483, and n. 10 (2000); Medina v. California , 505 U.S.
437 , 445–448 (1992); Holland v. Illinois , 493 U.S.
474 , 481–482, and n. 1 (1990); Marsh v. Chambers , 463 U.S.
783 , 786–792 (1983); Dames Moore v. Regan , 453 U.S.
654 , 678–682 (1981); Walz v. Tax Comm’n of City of
New York , 397 U.S.
664 , 676–680 (1970); Powell v. McCormack , 395
U.S. 486 , 522, 541–547 (1969); Youngstown Sheet Tube Co. v. Sawyer , 343 U.S.
579 , 610–613 (1952) (Frankfurter, J., concurring); United
States v. Curtiss-Wright Export Corp. , 299 U.S.
304 , 321–329 (1936); The Pocket Veto Case , 279 U.S.
655 , 688–691 (1929); Myers v. United States , 272 U.S.
52 , 155–158 (1926); United States v. Midwest Oil
Co. , 236 U.S.
459 , 469–475 (1915); Marshall Field Co. v. Clark , 143 U.S.
649 , 683–692 (1892); Murray’s Lessee v. Hoboken Land
Improvement Co. , 18 How. 272, 279–280 (1856); McCulloch v. Maryland , 4 Wheat. 316, 400–401 (1819).[ 6 ]
C Precedent . With a Constitution and a Supreme Court that
are both more than two centuries old, this Court and other courts
are rarely interpreting a constitutional provision for the first
time. Rather, a substantial body of Supreme Court precedent already
exists for many provisions of the Constitution.
Precedent is fundamental to day-to-day constitutional
decisionmaking in this Court and every American court. The
“judicial Power” established in Article III incorporates the
principle of stare decisis , both vertical and horizontal. As
Hamilton stated, to “avoid an arbitrary discretion in the courts,
it is indispensable that they should be bound down by strict rules
and precedents” that will “unavoidably swell to a very considerable
bulk” and “serve to define and point out their duty in every
particular case that comes before them.” The Federalist No. 78, at
471 (A. Hamilton).
Courts must respect precedent, while at the same time
recognizing that precedent on occasion may appropriately be
overturned. See, e . g ., Brown , 347 U.S.
483 ; West Coast Hotel Co. v. Parrish , 300 U.S.
379 (1937); see also Ramos v. Louisiana , 590 U.S.
83, 115–132 (2020) (Kavanaugh, J., concurring in part). In light of
the significant amount of Supreme Court precedent that has built up
over time, this Court and other courts often decide constitutional
cases by reference to those extensive bodies of precedent.
Even then, however, text and history still matter a great deal.
When determining how broadly or narrowly to read a precedent; when
determining whether to extend, limit, or narrow a precedent; or in
relatively infrequent cases, when determining whether to overrule a
precedent, a court often will consider how the precedent squares
with the Constitution’s text and history. Therefore, the text, as
well as pre-ratification and post-ratification history, may
appropriately function as a gravitational pull on the Court’s
interpretation of precedent. See Free Enterprise Fund v. Public Company Accounting Oversight Bd. , 537 F.3d
667, 698 (CADC 2008) (Kavanaugh, J., dissenting) (“We should
resolve questions about the scope of those precedents in light of
and in the direction of the constitutional text and constitutional
history”).
But the first stop in this Court’s constitutional decisionmaking
is the Court’s precedents—the accumulated wisdom of jurists from
Marshall and Story to Harlan and Taft; from Hughes and Black to
Jackson and White; from Rehnquist and O’Connor to Kennedy and
Scalia; and so on.
III
Some say that courts should determine exceptions to broadly
worded individual rights, including the Second Amendment, by
looking to policy. Uphold a law if it is a good idea; strike it
down if it is not. True, the proponents of a policy-based approach
to interpretation of broadly worded or vague constitutional text
usually do not say so explicitly (although some do). Rather, they
support a balancing approach variously known as means-end scrutiny,
heightened scrutiny, tiers of scrutiny, rational basis with bite,
or strict or intermediate or intermediate-plus or rigorous or
skeptical scrutiny. Whatever the label of the day, that balancing
approach is policy by another name. It requires judges to weigh the
benefits against the burdens of a law and to uphold the law as
constitutional if, in the judge’s view, the law is sufficiently
reasonable or important. See M. Barnes E. Chemerinsky, The Once and
Future Equal Protection Doctrine?, 43 Conn. L. Rev. 1059, 1080
(2011) (“The levels of scrutiny are essentially balancing
tests”).
To begin, as I have explained, that kind of balancing approach
to constitutional interpretation departs from what Framers such as
Madison stated, what jurists such as Marshall and Scalia did, what
judges as umpires should strive to do, and what this Court has
actually done across the constitutional landscape for the last two
centuries.
The balancing tests (heightened scrutiny and the like) are a
relatively modern judicial innovation in constitutional
decisionmaking. The “tiers of scrutiny have no basis in the text or
original meaning of the Constitution.” J. Alicea J. Ohlendorf,
Against the Tiers of Constitutional Scrutiny, National Affairs 72,
73 (2019). And before the late 1950s, “what we would now call
strict judicial scrutiny did not exist.” R. Fallon, The Nature of
Constitutional Rights: The Invention and Logic of Strict Judicial
Scrutiny 30 (2019).
The Court “appears to have adopted” heightened-scrutiny tests
“by accident” in the 1950s and 1960s in a series of Communist
speech cases, “rather than as the result of a considered judgment.” Simon Schuster, Inc. v. Members of N. Y. State Crime
Victims Bd. , 502 U.S.
105 , 125 (1991) (Kennedy, J., concurring in judgment). The
Court has employed balancing only in discrete areas of
constitutional law—and even in those cases, history still tends to
play a far larger role than overt judicial policymaking.[ 7 ]
To be clear, I am not suggesting that the Court overrule cases
where the Court has applied those heightened-scrutiny tests. But I
am challenging the notion that those tests are the ordinary
approach to constitutional interpretation. And I am arguing against
extending those tests to new areas, including the Second
Amendment.
One major problem with using a balancing approach to determine
exceptions to constitutional rights is that it requires highly
subjective judicial evaluations of how important a law is—at least
unless the balancing test itself incorporates history, in which
case judges might as well just continue to rely on history
directly.
The subjective balancing approach forces judges to act more like
legislators who decide what the law should be, rather than judges
who “say what the law is.” Marbury v. Madison , 1
Cranch 137, 177 (1803). That is because the balancing approach
requires judges to weigh the benefits of a law against its
burdens—a value-laden and political task that is usually reserved
for the political branches. And that power in essence vests judges
with “a roving commission to second-guess” legislators and
administrative officers “concerning what is best for the country.”
W. Rehnquist, The Notion of a Living Constitution, 54 Texas L. Rev.
693, 698 (1976). Stated otherwise, when a court “does not have a
solid textual anchor or an established social norm from which to
derive the general rule, its pronouncement appears uncomfortably
like legislation.” A. Scalia, The Rule of Law as a Law of Rules, 56
U. Chi. L. Rev. 1175, 1185 (1989).
Moreover, the balancing approach is ill-defined. Some judges
will apply heightened scrutiny with a presumption in favor of
deference to the legislature. Other judges will apply heightened
scrutiny with a presumption in favor of the individual right in
question. Because it is unmoored, the balancing approach presents
the real “danger” that “judges will mistake their own predilections
for the law.” A. Scalia, Originalism: The Lesser Evil, 57 U. Cin.
L. Rev. 849, 863 (1989). Under the balancing approach, to use
Justice Scalia’s characteristically vivid description, if “We The
Court conclude that They The People’s answers to a problem” are
unwise, “we are free to intervene,” but if we “think the States may
be on to something, we can loosen the leash.” McDonald v. Chicago , 561 U.S.
742 , 803 (2010) (concurring opinion) (quotation marks
omitted).
The balancing approach can be antithetical to the principle that
judges must act like umpires. It turns judges into players. Justice
Black once protested that the Court should not balance away bedrock
free speech protections for the perceived policy needs of the
moment. He argued that “the balancing approach” “disregards all of
the unique features of our Constitution” by giving “the Court,
along with Congress, a greater power, that of overriding the plain
commands of the Bill of Rights on a finding of weighty public
interest.” H. Black, The Bill of Rights, 35 N. Y. U. L. Rev. 865,
878–879 (1960). Like Justice Black, the Court in Heller cautioned that a “constitutional guarantee subject to future
judges’ assessments of its usefulness is no constitutional
guarantee at all.” 554 U.S.
570 , 634 (2008).
Some respond that history can be difficult to decipher. It is
true that using history to interpret vague text can require
“nuanced judgments,” McDonald , 561 U. S., at 803–804
(Scalia, J., concurring), and is “sometimes inconclusive,” Scalia,
Originalism: The Lesser Evil, 57 U. Cin. L. Rev., at 864. But
at a minimum, history tends to narrow the range of possible
meanings that may be ascribed to vague constitutional language. A
history-based methodology supplies direction and imposes a neutral
and democratically infused constraint on judicial
decisionmaking.
The historical approach is not perfect. But “the question to be
decided is not whether the historically focused method is a perfect means of restraining aristocratic judicial
Constitution-writing; but whether it is the best means
available in an imperfect world.” McDonald , 561
U. S., at 804 (Scalia, J., concurring) (emphasis in original).
And the historical approach is superior to judicial policymaking.
The historical approach “depends upon a body of evidence
susceptible of reasoned analysis rather than a variety of vague
ethico-political First Principles whose combined conclusion can be
found to point in any direction the judges favor.” Ibid .
Moreover, the historical approach “intrudes less upon the
democratic process because the rights it acknowledges are those
established by a constitutional history formed by democratic
decisions; and the rights it fails to acknowledge are left to be
democratically adopted or rejected by the people.” Id. , at
805.
IV
This Court’s Second Amendment jurisprudence has carefully
followed and reinforced the Court’s longstanding approach to
constitutional interpretation—relying on text, pre-ratification and
post-ratification history, and precedent.
In Heller , the Court began with the baseline point that
the Second Amendment textually guarantees an individual right. The
Court then explained that the Second Amendment right is, of course,
“not a right to keep and carry any weapon whatsoever in any manner
whatsoever and for whatever purpose” and is subject to “important”
limitations. 554
U.S. 570 , 626–627 (2008).
Although Heller declined to “undertake an exhaustive
historical analysis,” it recognized a few categories of traditional
exceptions to the right. Id ., at 626. For example, Heller indicated that: (i) “prohibitions on carrying
concealed weapons were lawful”; (ii) the Second Amendment attaches
only to weapons “in common use” because “that limitation is fairly
supported by the historical tradition of prohibiting the carrying
of dangerous and unusual weapons”; and (iii) “longstanding
prohibitions on the possession of firearms by felons and the
mentally ill, or laws forbidding the carrying of firearms in
sensitive places such as schools and government buildings, or laws
imposing conditions and qualifications on the commercial sale of
arms” are presumptively constitutional. Id ., at 626–627
(quotation marks omitted).
In McDonald , the Court held that the Second Amendment was
incorporated against the States. In so holding, the Court
reiterated the presumed constitutionality of the “longstanding
regulatory measures” identified in Heller . 561 U.S.
742 , 786 (2010) (plurality opinion).
Then, in Bruen , the Court repeated that the “Nation’s
historical tradition of firearm regulation” guides the
constitutional analysis of gun regulations and exceptions to the
right to bear arms. 597 U.S. 1, 17 (2022); see id ., at 79–81
(Kavanaugh, J., concurring).
This Court’s approach in those three recent Second Amendment
cases—and in the Court’s opinion today—is entirely consistent with
the Court’s longstanding reliance on history and precedent to
determine the meaning of vague constitutional text. Heller rested on “constitutional text and history,” ante , at 6
(quotation marks omitted), and laid the foundation for McDonald and then Bruen .
In today’s case, the Court carefully builds on Heller , McDonald , and Bruen . The Court applies the historical
test that those precedents have set forth—namely, “whether the new
law is relevantly similar to laws that our tradition is understood
to permit.” Ante , at 7 (quotation marks omitted). The Court
examines “our historical tradition of firearm regulation,” ante , at 6 (quotation marks omitted), and correctly holds
that America’s “tradition of firearm regulation allows the
Government to disarm individuals who present a credible threat to
the physical safety of others,” ante , at 16. The law before
us “fits neatly within the tradition the surety and going armed
laws represent.” Ante , at 13–14.
As the Court’s decision today notes, Second Amendment
jurisprudence is still in the relatively early innings, unlike the
First, Fourth, and Sixth Amendments, for example. That is because
the Court did not have occasion to recognize the Second Amendment’s
individual right until recently. See generally Heller v. District of Columbia , 670 F.3d 1244, 1269–1296 (CADC 2011)
(Kavanaugh, J., dissenting). Deciding constitutional cases in a
still-developing area of this Court’s jurisprudence can sometimes
be difficult. But that is not a permission slip for a judge to let
constitutional analysis morph into policy preferences under the
guise of a balancing test that churns out the judge’s own policy
beliefs.
* * *
As exemplified by Heller , McDonald , Bruen ,
and the Court’s opinion today, constitutional interpretation
properly takes account of text, pre-ratification and
post-ratification history, and precedent. Those are the tools of
the trade for an American judge interpreting the American
Constitution. Of course, difficult subsidiary questions can arise
about how to apply those tools, both generally and in particular
cases. And in some cases, text, history, and precedent may point in
somewhat different directions. In law as in life, nothing is
perfect. But in Second Amendment cases as in other constitutional
cases, text, history, and precedent must remain paramount. Notes 1 There are two ways to
frame this point—either (i) determining the exceptions to a
constitutional right or (ii) determining the affirmative scope or
contours of that constitutional right. Either way, the analysis is
the same—does the constitutional provision, as originally
understood, permit the challenged law? This opinion uses the term
“exceptions,” which underscores that the constitutional baseline is
protection of the textually enumerated right. See Federal
Election Comm’n v. Wisconsin Right to Life, Inc. , 551 U.S.
449 , 482 (2007) (opinion of Roberts, C. J.) (stating in a
First Amendment case that “it is worth recalling the language we
are applying”). 2 The historical approach
applies when the text is vague. But the text of the Constitution
always controls. So history contrary to clear text is not to be
followed. See, e.g. , INS v. Chadha , 462 U.S.
919 , 945–959 (1983); Powell v. McCormack , 395 U.S.
486 , 546–547 (1969); Brown v. Board of Education , 347 U.S.
483 , 490–495, and n. 5 (1954); cf. Sedition Act of 1798, ch.
74, 1 Stat. 596. In some cases, there may be debate about whether
the relevant text is sufficiently clear to override contrary
historical practices. See, e.g. , NLRB v. Noel Canning , 573
U.S. 513 , 613 (2014) (Scalia, J., concurring in judgment)
(“What the majority needs to sustain its judgment is an ambiguous
text and a clear historical practice. What it has is a clear text
and an at-best-ambiguous historical practice”). The basic principle
remains: Text controls over contrary historical
practices. 3 To be sure, as the
Court’s cases reveal, pre-ratification English law and practices
may supply background for some constitutional provisions. But the
Constitution, including the Bill of Rights, did not purport to take
English law or history wholesale and silently download it into the
U. S. Constitution. See, e.g. , Harmelin v. Michigan , 501
U.S. 957 , 975 (1991) (opinion of Scalia, J.) (“Unless one
accepts the notion of a blind incorporation, however, the ultimate
question is not what ‘cruell and unusuall punishments’ meant in the
[English] Declaration of Rights, but what its meaning was to the
Americans who adopted the Eighth Amendment”). Therefore,
reflexively resorting to English law or history without careful
analysis can sometimes be problematic because America had fought a
war—and would soon fight another in 1812—to free itself from
British law and practices and rid itself of tyrannical British
rule. See The Federalist No. 45, p. 289 (C. Rossiter ed. 1961) (J.
Madison) (“Was, then, the American Revolution effected, was the
American Confederacy formed, was the precious blood of thousands
spilt, and the hard-earned substance of millions lavished, not that
the people of America should enjoy peace, liberty, and safety,” but
that they should continue to be subject to the “impious doctrine in
the old world, that the people were made for kings, not kings for
the people”?). 4 Post-ratification history
is sometimes also referred to as tradition, liquidation, or
historical gloss. Those concepts are probably not identical in all
respects. In any event, in applying those concepts in
constitutional interpretation, some important questions can arise,
such as: (i) the level of generality at which to define a
historical practice; (ii) how widespread a historical
practice must have been; (iii) how long ago it must have
started; and (iv) how long it must have endured. Although this
Court’s constitutional precedents routinely rely on
post-ratification history, those precedents do not supply a
one-size-fits-all answer to those various methodological questions.
See, e . g ., Noel Canning , 573 U. S., at
522–556; Youngstown Sheet Tube Co. v. Sawyer , 343 U.S.
579 , 610–611 (1952) (Frankfurter, J., concurring). And I will
not attempt to answer all of those questions here. Respected
scholars are continuing to undertake careful analysis. See
generally J. Alicea, Practice-Based Constitutional Theories, 133
Yale L. J. 568 (2023); R. Barnett L. Solum, Originalism After Dobbs , Bruen , and Kennedy : The Role of History
and Tradition, 118 Nw. U. L. Rev. 433 (2023); M. DeGirolami,
Traditionalism Rising, 24 J. Contemp. Legal Issues 9 (2023); S.
Girgis, Living Traditionalism, 98 N. Y. U. L. Rev. 1477 (2023); W.
Baude, Constitutional Liquidation, 71 Stan. L. Rev. 1 (2019); C.
Bradley, Doing Gloss, 84 U. Chi. L. Rev. 59 (2017); C. Bradley
T. Morrison, Historical Gloss and the Separation of Powers, 126
Harv. L. Rev. 411 (2012); A. Amar, America’s Constitution (2005);
C. Nelson, Originalism and Interpretive Conventions, 70 U. Chi. L.
Rev. 519 (2003); M. McConnell, Tradition and Constitutionalism
Before the Constitution, 1998 U. Ill. L. Rev. 173. 5 Justice Scalia’s opinions
“made extensive use of post-ratification history,” and “his
assessment of post-ratification history” in those opinions extended
“far beyond the time of enactment.” M. Ramsey, Beyond the Text:
Justice Scalia’s Originalism in Practice, 92 Notre Dame
L. Rev. 1945, 1957, 1960 (2017). Justice Scalia did not
necessarily “use[ ] tradition as an independent source of
interpretive authority; rather, he had a very broad view of what
traditions might be indicative of original meaning.” Id ., at
1962, n. 79; see, e . g ., NLRB v. Noel
Canning , 573 U.S.
513 , 584–593, 602–615 (2014) (Scalia, J., concurring in
judgment); District of Columbia v. Heller , 554 U.S.
570 , 605–619, 626–628 (2008); McCreary County v. American Civil Liberties Union of Ky. , 545 U.S.
844 , 886–900 (2005) (Scalia, J., dissenting); Hamdi v. Rumsfeld , 542 U.S.
507 , 558–563 (2004) (Scalia, J., dissenting); Crawford v. Washington , 541 U.S.
36 , 47–50 (2004); Mitchell v. United States , 526 U.S.
314 , 334–336, and n. 1 (1999) (Scalia, J., dissenting); Department of Commerce v. United States House of
Representatives , 525 U.S.
316 , 347–349 (1999) (Scalia, J., concurring in part); Clinton v. City of New York , 524
U.S. 417 , 465–469 (1998) (Scalia, J., concurring in part and
dissenting in part); Printz v. United States , 521 U.S.
898 , 905–918 (1997); United States v. Gaudin , 515 U.S.
506 , 515–519 (1995); McIntyre v. Ohio Elections
Comm’n , 514 U.S.
334 , 375–378, and nn. 1–2 (1995) (Scalia, J., dissenting); Plaut v. Spendthrift Farm, Inc. , 514 U.S.
211 , 223–225 (1995); Board of Ed. of Kiryas Joel Village
School Dist. v. Grumet , 512 U.S.
687 , 732, 744 (1994) (Scalia, J., dissenting); Herrera v. Collins , 506 U.S.
390 , 427–428 (1993) (Scalia, J., concurring); Richmond v. Lewis , 506 U.S.
40 , 54 (1992) (Scalia, J., dissenting); Harmelin v. Michigan , 501 U.S.
957 , 979–985 (1991) (opinion of Scalia, J.); Rutan v. Republican Party of Ill. , 497 U.S.
62 , 95–97 (1990) (Scalia, J., dissenting); McKoy v. North Carolina , 494 U.S.
433 , 466, 471 (1990) (Scalia, J., dissenting); Holland v. Illinois , 493 U.S.
474 , 481–482, and n. 1 (1990). 6 The Court has similarly
relied on history when deciding cases involving textually
unenumerated rights under the Due Process Clause or the Privileges
or Immunities Clause. In those contexts, the baseline is
180-degrees different: The text supplies no express protection of
any asserted substantive right. The Court has recognized exceptions
to that textual baseline, but in doing so has regularly observed
that the Fourteenth Amendment “specially protects those fundamental
rights and liberties which are, objectively, deeply rooted in this
Nation’s history and tradition.” Washington v. Glucksberg , 521 U.S.
702 , 720–721 (1997) (quotation marks omitted); see, e . g ., Pierce v. Society of Sisters , 268 U.S.
510 , 534–535 (1925) (“liberty of parents and guardians to
direct the upbringing and education of children under their
control”). 7 The Court has articulated
a heightened-scrutiny test in some pockets of free-speech
jurisprudence. But even when invoking heightened scrutiny in that
context, the Court still often relies directly on history. See, e.g. , City of Austin v. Reagan Nat. Advertising of
Austin, LLC , 596 U.S. 61, 75 (2022) (a city’s regulation of
solely off-premises billboards was within “the Nation’s history of
regulating off-premises signs” as “federal, state, and local
jurisdictions have repeatedly relied upon on-/off-premises
distinctions” “for the last 50-plus years”); Perry Ed. Assn. v. Perry Local Educators’ Assn. , 460 U.S.
37 , 45–46 (1983) (“In places which by long tradition” “have
been devoted to assembly and debate, the rights of the State to
limit expressive activity are sharply circumscribed”). The Court
has also used heightened scrutiny in certain equal protection
cases. As discussed above, the Equal Protection Clause rejected the
history of racially discriminatory laws and practices. SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES
_________________
No. 22–915
_________________
UNITED STATES, PETITIONER v. ZACKEY RAHIMI
on writ of certiorari to the united states court of appeals for
the fifth circuit
[June 21, 2024]
Justice Jackson, concurring.
This case tests our Second Amendment jurisprudence as shaped in
particular by New York State Rifle Pistol Assn., Inc. v. Bruen , 597 U.S. 1 (2022). I disagree with the methodology of
that decision; I would have joined the dissent had I been a Member
of the Court at that time. See generally id. , at 83–133
(Breyer, J., dissenting). But Bruen is now binding law.
Today’s decision fairly applies that precedent, so I join the
opinion in full.
I write separately because we now have two years’ worth of
post- Bruen cases under our belts, and the experiences of
courts applying its history-and-tradition test should bear on our
assessment of the workability of that legal standard. This case
highlights the apparent difficulty faced by judges on the ground.
Make no mistake: Today’s effort to clear up “misunderst[andings],” ante, at 7, is a tacit admission that lower courts are
struggling. In my view, the blame may lie with us, not with
them.
I
The Court today expounds on the history-and-tradition inquiry
that Bruen requires. Ante , at 7–8. We emphasize that
the Second Amendment is “not . . . a law trapped in
amber.” Ante, at 7. It “permits more than just those
regulations identical to ones that could be found in 1791”; indeed,
“a challenged regulation [that] does not precisely match its
historical precursors . . . ‘still may be analogous
enough to pass constitutional muster.’ ” Ibid . (quoting Bruen , 597 U. S., at 30). Gun regulations need only
“comport with the principles underlying the Second Amendment.” Ante, at 7–8. These clarifying efforts are welcome, given
the many questions Bruen left unanswered.
When this Court adopts a new legal standard, as we did in Bruen , we do not do so in a vacuum. The tests we establish
bind lower court judges, who then apply those legal standards to
the cases before them. In my view, as this Court thinks of, and
speaks about, history’s relevance to the interpretation of
constitutional provisions, we should be mindful that our common-law
tradition of promoting clarity and consistency in the application
of our precedent also has a lengthy pedigree. So when courts
signal they are having trouble with one of our standards, we should
pay attention. Cf. Garcia v. San Antonio Metropolitan
Transit Authority , 469 U.S.
528 , 538–539 (1985).
The message that lower courts are sending now in Second
Amendment cases could not be clearer. They say there is little
method to Bruen ’s madness.[ 1 ] It isn’t just that Bruen ’s history-and-tradition
test is burdensome (though that is no small thing to courts with
heavier caseloads and fewer resources than we have). The more
worrisome concern is that lower courts appear to be diverging in
both approach and outcome as they struggle to conduct the inquiry Bruen requires of them. Scholars report that lower courts
applying Bruen ’s approach have been unable to produce
“consistent, principled results,” Brief for Second Amendment Law
Scholars as Amici Curiae 4, and, in fact, they “have come to
conflicting conclusions on virtually every consequential Second
Amendment issue to come before them,” id. , at 4–5; see also id ., at 5–6 (collecting examples). Given this, it appears
indisputable that, after Bruen , “confusion plagu[es] the
lower courts.” Id ., at 6.
II
This discord is striking when compared to the relative harmony
that had developed prior to Bruen . To be sure, our decision
in District of Columbia v. Heller , 554 U.S.
570 (2008), which first recognized an individual right to keep
and bear arms for self-defense, see id ., at 628, was
disruptive in its own way. After all, before Heller , “[t]he
meaning of the Second Amendment ha[d] been considered settled by
courts and legislatures for over two centuries,” and “judges and
legislators . . . properly believed . . . that
the Second Amendment did not reach possession of firearms for
purely private activities.” Id ., at 676, n. 38
(Stevens, J., dissenting). Nonetheless, after Heller , lower
courts took up the necessary work of reviewing burdens on this
newly unearthed right. By the time this Court decided Bruen ,
every court of appeals evaluating whether a firearm regulation was
consistent with the Second Amendment did so using a two-step
framework that incorporated means-end scrutiny. See Bruen ,
597 U. S., at 103 (Breyer, J., dissenting).
Rejecting that “two-step approach” as having “one step too
many,” id ., at 19, the Bruen majority subbed in
another two-step evaluation. Courts must, first, determine whether
“the Second Amendment’s plain text covers an individual’s conduct.” Id ., at 24. If it does, “[t]he government must then justify
its regulation by demonstrating that it is consistent with the
Nation’s historical tradition of firearm regulation.” Ibid. No one seems to question that “[h]istory has a role to play in
Second Amendment analysis.” Ante, at 4 (Sotomayor, J.,
concurring). But, per Bruen , courts evaluating a Second
Amendment challenge must consider history to the exclusion of
all else . This means legislators must locate and produce—and
courts must sift through—troves of centuries-old documentation
looking for supportive historical evidence.[ 2 ]
This very case provides a prime example of the pitfalls of Bruen ’s approach. Having been told that a key marker of a
constitutional gun regulation is “a well-established and
representative historical analogue,” Bruen , 597 U. S.,
at 30 (emphasis deleted), Rahimi argued below that “there is little
or no historical evidence suggesting disarmament for those who
committed domestic violence; and there is certainly no tradition of
disarming people subject to a no-contact order related to domestic
violence.” Supp. Brief for Appellant in No. 21–11001 (CA5),
p. 15 (emphasis deleted). The Government then proffered what
it maintained were sufficient historical analogues to 18
U. S. C. §922(g)(8), including surety and going armed
laws. Supp. Brief for Appellee in No. 21–11001 (CA5), pp. 23,
n. 2, 27–31. But the Fifth Circuit concluded that the federal
statute was unconstitutional because the Government’s analogues
were not “ ‘relevantly similar.’ ” 61 F. 4th 443, 460–461
(2023).
Neither the parties nor the Fifth Circuit had the benefit of
today’s decision, in which we hold that the Government had in fact
offered “ample evidence that the Second Amendment permits the
disarmament of individuals who pose a credible threat to the
physical safety of others.” Ante, at 8. But even setting
aside whether the historical examples the Government found were
sufficiently analogous, just canvassing the universe of historical
records and gauging the sufficiency of such evidence is an
exceedingly difficult task.[ 3 ]
Consistent analyses and outcomes are likely to remain elusive
because whether Bruen’ s test is satisfied in a particular
case seems to depend on the suitability of whatever historical
sources the parties can manage to cobble together, as well as the
level of generality at which a court evaluates those
sources—neither of which we have as yet adequately clarified.
And the unresolved questions hardly end there. Who is protected
by the Second Amendment, from a historical perspective? To what
conduct does the Second Amendment’s plain text apply? To what
historical era (or eras) should courts look to divine a historical
tradition of gun regulation? How many analogues add up to a
tradition? Must there be evidence that those analogues were
enforced or subject to judicial scrutiny? How much support can
nonstatutory sources lend? I could go on—as others have. See, e . g ., United States v. Daniels , 77 F.
4th 337, 358–360 (CA5 2023) (Higginson, J., concurring) (providing
a similarly nonexhaustive list). But I won’t.
III
Maybe time will resolve these and other key questions. Maybe
appellate courts, including ours, will find a way to “[b]rin[g]
discipline to the increasingly erratic and unprincipled body of law
that is emerging after Bruen .” J. Blocher E. Ruben,
Originalism-by-Analogy and Second Amendment Adjudication, 133 Yale
L. J. 99, 174 (2023). Indeed, “[m]any constitutional standards
involve undoubted gray areas,” and “it normally might be fair to
venture the assumption that case-by-case development [will] lead to
a workable standard.” Garcia , 469 U. S., at 540
(internal quotation marks and alteration omitted). By underscoring
that gun regulations need only “comport with the principles underlying the Second Amendment,” ante, at 7–8 (emphasis
added), today’s opinion inches that ball forward.
But it is becoming increasingly obvious that there are miles to
go.[ 4 ] Meanwhile, the Rule of
Law suffers. That ideal—key to our democracy—thrives on legal
standards that foster stability, facilitate consistency, and
promote predictability. So far, Bruen ’s history-focused test
ticks none of those boxes.
* * *
I concur in today’s decision applying Bruen . But, in my
view, the Court should also be mindful of how its legal standards
are actually playing out in real life. We must remember that
legislatures, seeking to implement meaningful reform for their
constituents while simultaneously respecting the Second Amendment,
are hobbled without a clear, workable test for assessing the
constitutionality of their proposals. See Tr. of Oral Arg. 54–57;
cf. Bruen , 597 U. S., at 90–91 (Breyer, J.,
dissenting). And courts, which are currently at sea when it comes
to evaluating firearms legislation, need a solid anchor for
grounding their constitutional pronouncements. The public, too,
deserves clarity when this Court interprets our Constitution. Notes 1 See, e.g ., Barris v. Stroud Twp. , ___ Pa. ___, ___, 310 A.3d
175, 190 (2024) (“[M]ore guidance in this challenging and
ever-shifting area of the law is welcome”); State v. Wilson , 154 Haw. 8, 21, 543 P.3d 440, 453 (2024) (“[B]y
turning the test into history and nothing else, [ Bruen ]
dismantles workable methods to interpret firearms laws”); United
States v. Dubois , 94 F. 4th 1284, 1293 (CA11 2024) (“We
require clearer instruction from the Supreme Court before we may
reconsider the constitutionality of [18 U. S. C.
§]922(g)(1)”); United States v. Daniels , 77 F. 4th
337, 358 (CA5 2023) (Higginson, J., concurring) (“[C]ourts,
operating in good faith, are struggling at every stage of the Bruen inquiry. Those struggles encompass numerous, often
dispositive, difficult questions”); Atkinson v. Garland , 70 F. 4th 1018, 1024 (CA7 2023) (“[T]he historical
analysis required by Bruen will be difficult and no doubt
yield some measure of indeterminancy”); id ., at 1036 (Wood,
J., dissenting) (“As other courts have begun to apply Bruen ,
[the] need for further research and further guidance has become
clear”); Gonyo v. D. S ., 210
N. Y. S. 3d 612, 615, 2024 N. Y. Slip Op. 24018
(Jan. 19, 2024) (“Interpretations and applications of Bruen by lower courts have been widely divergent and thus, very difficult
to apply as precedent”); United States v. Sing-Ledezma , ___ F. Supp. 3d ___, ___, 2023 WL 8587869, *3
(WD Tex. Dec. 11, 2023) (“[T]he Court pauses to join the choir of
lower courts urging the Supreme Court to resolve the many
unanswered questions left in Bruen ’s wake”); United
States v. Bartucci , 658 F. Supp. 3d 794, 800 (ED Cal.
2023) (“[T]he unique test the Supreme Court announced in Bruen does not provide lower courts with clear guidance as
to how analogous modern laws must be to founding-era gun laws. In
the short time post- Bruen , this has caused disarray among
the lower courts”); United States v. Bullock , 679
F. Supp. 3d 501, 534 (SD Miss. 2023) (raising
methodological questions “in hopes that future judges and justices
can answer them with enough detail to enable trial courts to
perform their duties”); Fraser v. Bureau of Alcohol,
Tobacco , Firearms and Explosives , 672 F. Supp. 3d
118, 137, n. 20 (ED Va. 2023) (“The Court is staffed by
lawyers who are neither trained nor experienced in making the
nuanced historical analyses called for by Bruen .
. . . The analytical construct specified by Bruen is thus a difficult one for non-historians”); United States v. Jackson , 661 F. Supp. 3d 392, 406 (Md. 2023) (noting
“the challenges created by Bruen’s assignment”); United
States v. Love , 647 F. Supp. 3d 664, 670 (ND Ind.
2022) (“By . . . announcing an inconsistent and amorphous
standard, the Supreme Court has created mountains of work for
district courts that must now deal with Bruen -related
arguments in nearly every criminal case in which a firearm is
found”). 2 It is not clear what
qualifies policymakers or their lawyers (who do not ordinarily have
the specialized education, knowledge, or training of professional
historians) to engage in this kind of assessment. And dutiful
legislators are not the only stakeholders who are far outside their
depth: Bruen also conscripts parties and judges into service
as amateur historians, casting about for similar historical
circumstances. 3 The mad scramble for
historical records that Bruen requires also suggests that
only those solutions that States implemented in the distant past
comport with the Constitution. That premise is questionable
because, given the breadth of some of the Constitution’s
provisions, it is likely that the Founders understood that new
solutions would be needed over time, even for traditional problems,
and that the principles they were adopting would allow for such
flexibility. See District of Columbia v. Heller , 554 U.S.
570 , 722 (2008) (Breyer, J., dissenting) (expressing doubt that
the Framers “intended future generations to ignore [modern-day]
matters”). It stifles both helpful innovation and democratic
engagement to read the Constitution to prevent advancement in this
way. In any event, what we see now is that Bruen ’s
history-and-tradition test is not only limiting legislative
solutions, it also appears to be creating chaos. 4 Extremely pertinent
inquiries relevant to consistent application of Bruen ’s
standard await resolution. For example, in Bruen we
acknowledged the existence of “an ongoing scholarly debate on
whether courts should primarily rely on the prevailing
understanding of an individual right when the Fourteenth Amendment
was ratified in 1868 when defining its scope (as well as the scope
of the right against the Federal Government).” 597 U. S., at
37. We saw no need to address the issue in Bruen . Id ., at 38. We similarly decline to resolve that dispute
today. Ante , at 8, n. 1. SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES
_________________
No. 22–915
_________________
UNITED STATES, PETITIONER v. ZACKEY RAHIMI
on writ of certiorari to the united states court of appeals for
the fifth circuit
[June 21, 2024]
Justice Barrett, concurring.
Despite its unqualified text, the Second Amendment is not
absolute. It codified a pre-existing right, and pre-existing limits
on that right are part and parcel of it. District of
Columbia v. Heller , 554 U.S.
570 , 595, 627 (2008). Those limits define the scope of “the
right to bear arms” as it was originally understood; to identify
them, courts must examine our “historical tradition of firearm
regulation.” New York State Rifle Pistol Assn., Inc. v. Bruen , 597 U.S. 1, 17, 19 (2022). That evidence marks where
the right stops and the State’s authority to regulate begins. A
regulation is constitutional only if the government affirmatively
proves that it is “consistent with the Second Amendment’s text and
historical understanding.” Id ., at 26.
Because the Court has taken an originalist approach to the
Second Amendment, it is worth pausing to identify the basic
premises of originalism. The theory is built on two core
principles: that the meaning of constitutional text is fixed at the
time of its ratification and that the “discoverable historical
meaning . . . has legal significance and is authoritative
in most circumstances.” K. Whittington, Originalism: A Critical
Introduction, 82 Ford. L. Rev. 375, 378 (2013) (Whittington).
Ratification is a democratic act that renders constitutional text
part of our fundamental law, see Arts. V, VII, and that text
“remains law until lawfully altered,” S. Sachs, Originalism:
Standard and Procedure, 135 Harv. L. Rev. 777, 782 (2022). So
for an originalist, the history that matters most is the history
surrounding the ratification of the text; that backdrop illuminates
the meaning of the enacted law. History (or tradition) that long
postdates ratification does not serve that function. To be sure,
postenactment history can be an important tool. For example, it can
“reinforce our understanding of the Constitution’s original
meaning”; “liquidate ambiguous constitutional provisions”; provide
persuasive evidence of the original meaning; and, if stare
decisis applies, control the outcome. See Vidal v. Elster , 602 U. S. ___, ___–___ (2024) (Barrett, J.,
concurring in part) (slip op., at 13–14). But generally speaking,
the use of postenactment history requires some justification other
than originalism simpliciter.
In Bruen , the Court took history beyond the founding era,
considering gun regulations that spanned the 19th century. 597
U. S., at 50–70. I expressed reservations about the scope of
that inquiry but concluded that the timing question did not matter
to Bruen ’s holding. Id ., at 81–83 (concurring
opinion). It bears emphasis, however, that my questions were about
the time period relevant to discerning the Second Amendment’s
original meaning—for instance, what is the post-1791 cutoff for
discerning how the Second Amendment was originally understood? Id ., at 82 (“How long after ratification may subsequent
practice illuminate original public meaning?”). My doubts were not about whether “tradition,” standing alone, is
dispositive. Id ., at 83 (“[T]oday’s decision should not be
understood to endorse freewheeling reliance on historical practice
from the mid-to-late 19th century to establish the original meaning
of the Bill of Rights”). As I have explained elsewhere, evidence of
“tradition” unmoored from original meaning is not binding law. Vidal , 602 U. S., at ___–___ (Barrett, J., concurring
in part) (slip op., at 13–15). And scattered cases or regulations
pulled from history may have little bearing on the meaning of the
text. Samia v. United States , 599 U.S. 635, 656–657
(2023) (Barrett, J., concurring in part and concurring in
judgment).
“Original history”— i.e., the generally dispositive
kind—plays two roles in the Second Amendment context. It elucidates
how contemporaries understood the text—for example, the meaning of
the phrase “bear Arms.” See Heller , 554 U. S., at
582–592. It also plays the more complicated role of determining the
scope of the pre-existing right that the people enshrined in our
fundamental law.[ 1 ]* In
Rahimi’s case, the Court uses history in this latter way. Call this
“original contours” history: It looks at historical gun regulations
to identify the contours of the right.
Courts have struggled with this use of history in the wake of Bruen . One difficulty is a level of generality problem: Must
the government produce a founding-era relative of the challenged
regulation—if not a twin, a cousin? Or do founding-era gun
regulations yield concrete principles that mark the borders of the
right?
Many courts, including the Fifth Circuit, have understood Bruen to require the former, narrower approach. But Bruen emphasized that “analogical reasoning” is not a
“regulatory straightjacket.” 597 U. S., at 30. To be consistent with historical limits, a challenged regulation
need not be an updated model of a historical counterpart. Besides,
imposing a test that demands overly specific analogues has serious
problems. To name two: It forces 21st-century regulations to follow
late-18th-century policy choices, giving us “a law trapped in
amber.” Ante , at 7. And it assumes that founding-era
legislatures maximally exercised their power to regulate, thereby
adopting a “use it or lose it” view of legislative authority. Such
assumptions are flawed, and originalism does not require them.
“Analogical reasoning” under Bruen demands a wider lens:
Historical regulations reveal a principle, not a mold. See, e . g ., 597 U. S., at 28–29 (explaining that the
Amendment does not apply only to the catalogue of arms that existed
in the 18th century, but rather to all weapons satisfying the
“ general definition ” of “bearable arms” (emphasis added)); id ., at 30–31 (discussing the “ ‘sensitive
places’ ” principle that limits the right to public carry);
cf. Vidal , 602 U. S., at ___–___ (Barrett, J.,
concurring in part) (slip op., at 7–9); Whittington 386 (“The
insight to be gleaned is not the authoritative status of the
expected application, but the apparent rule at play given that such
an application is expected to follow from it”). To be sure, a court
must be careful not to read a principle at such a high level of
generality that it waters down the right. Pulling principle from
precedent, whether case law or history, is a standard feature of
legal reasoning, and reasonable minds sometimes disagree about how
broad or narrow the controlling principle should be.
Here, though, the Court settles on just the right level of
generality: “Since the founding, our Nation’s firearm laws have
included provisions preventing individuals who threaten physical
harm to others from misusing firearms.” Ante , at 5; see also Kanter v. Barr , 919 F.3d 437, 451, 464–465 (CA7 2019)
(Barrett, J., dissenting) (“History is consistent with common
sense: it demonstrates that legislatures have the power to prohibit
dangerous people from possessing guns”). Section 922(g)(8)(C)(i)
fits well within that principle; therefore, Rahimi’s facial
challenge fails. Harder level-of-generality problems can await
another day. Notes 1 *To my mind, this use of
history walks a fine line between original meaning (which controls)
and expectations about how the text would apply (which do not). See
Whittington 383 (“Specific expectations about the consequences of a
legal rule are distinct from the meaning of the rule
itself ”). Contemporary government actors might have been
“wrong about the consequences of their own constitutional rule,” or
they “might not have fully and faithfully implemented the adopted
constitutional rule themselves.” Id. , at 384. Thus, while
early applications of a constitutional rule can help illuminate its
original scope, an interpreter must exercise care in considering
them. Id. , at 385–386. In the Second Amendment context,
particular gun regulations—even if from the ratification era—do not
themselves have the status of constitutional law. SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES
_________________
No. 22–915
_________________
UNITED STATES, PETITIONER v. ZACKEY
RAHIMI
on writ of certiorari to the united states
court of appeals for the fifth circuit
[June 21, 2024]
Justice Thomas, dissenting.
After New York State Rifle & Pistol
Assn., Inc. v. Bruen , 597 U.S. 1 (2022), this Court’s
directive was clear: A firearm regulation that falls within the
Second Amendment’s plain text is unconstitutional unless it is
consistent with the Nation’s historical tradition of firearm
regulation. Not a single historical regulation justifies the
statute at issue, 18 U. S. C. §922(g)(8). Therefore, I
respectfully dissent.
I
Section 922(g)(8) makes it unlawful for an
individual who is subject to a civil restraining order to possess
firearms or ammunition. To trigger §922(g)(8)’s prohibition, a
restraining order must bear three characteristics. First, the order
issues after a hearing where the accused “received actual notice”
and had “an opportunity to participate.” §922(g)(8)(A). Second, the
order restrains the accused from engaging in threatening behavior
against an intimate partner or child. §922(g)(8)(B). Third, the
order has either “a finding that [the accused] represents a
credible threat to the physical safety of [an] intimate partner or
child,” or an “explici[t] prohibit[ion]” on “the use, attempted
use, or threatened use of physical force against [an] intimate
partner or child.” §922(g)(8)(C). If those three characteristics
are present, §922(g)(8) automatically bans the individual subject
to the order from possessing “any firearm or ammunition.”
§922(g).
Just as important as §922(g)(8)’s express terms
is what it leaves unsaid. Section 922(g)(8) does not require a
finding that a person has ever committed a crime of domestic
violence. It is not triggered by a criminal conviction or a
person’s criminal history, unlike other §922(g) subsections. See
§§922(g)(1), (9). And, §922(g)(8) does not distinguish contested
orders from joint orders—for example, when parties voluntarily
enter a no-contact agreement or when both parties seek a
restraining order.
In addition, §922(g)(8) strips an individual of
his ability to possess firearms and ammunition without any due
process.[ 1 ] Rather, the ban is
an automatic, uncontestable consequence of certain orders. See
§922(g) (“It shall be unlawful for any [qualifying] person [to]
possess in or affecting commerce, any firearm or ammunition”).
There is no hearing or opportunity to be heard on the statute’s
applicability, and a court need not decide whether a person should
be disarmed under §922(g)(8). The only process §922(g)(8) requires
is that provided (or not) for the underlying restraining
order.
Despite §922(g)(8)’s broad scope and lack of
process, it carries strong penalties. Any violation of §922(g)(8)
is a felony punishable by up to 15 years’ imprisonment. §924(a)(8);
see also ante, at 3. And, a conviction for violating
§922(g)(8) itself triggers a permanent, life-long prohibition on
possessing firearms and ammunition. See §922(g)(1).
In 2020, Zackey Rahimi and his ex-girlfriend,
C. M., entered into a qualifying civil restraining order. App.
1. C. M. had requested the order and asserted that Rahimi
assaulted her. See id., at 2. Because the order found that
Rahimi presented a credible threat and prohibited him from using
physical force against C. M., the order automatically
triggered §922(g)(8)’s firearms ban. A year later, officers
discovered firearms in Rahimi’s home. Rahimi pleaded guilty to
violating §922(g)(8).
Before his guilty plea, Rahimi challenged his
conviction under the Second Amendment. He pointed to District of
Columbia v. Heller , 554 U.S.
570 (2008), which held that the Second Amendment protects an
individual right to keep and bear firearms. Section 922(g)(8),
Rahimi argued, violates that right by penalizing firearms
possession. The District Court rejected Rahimi’s claim. At that
time, the Courts of Appeals, including the Fifth Circuit, applied a
form of means-end scrutiny to Second Amendment claims. See, e . g ., United States v. McGinnis , 956
F.3d 747, 753–754 (2020). Applying Circuit precedent, the Fifth
Circuit affirmed the District Court. 2022 WL 2070392 (2022).
Roughly two weeks later, this Court issued its
opinion in New York State Rifle & Pistol Assn., Inc. v. Bruen . The Court rejected the means-end-scrutiny approach
and laid out the appropriate framework for assessing whether a
firearm regulation is constitutional. Bruen , 597 U. S.,
at 17–19. That framework requires the Government to prove that the
“regulation is part of the historical tradition that delimits the
outer bounds of the right to keep and bear arms.” Id ., at
19. The Fifth Circuit withdrew its opinion to apply the correct
framework to Rahimi’s claim. Relying on Bruen , the Fifth
Circuit concluded that the Government failed to present historical
evidence that §922(g)(8) “fits within our Nation’s historical
tradition of firearm regulation.” 61 F. 4th 443, 460 (2023). The
Fifth Circuit, accordingly, vacated Rahimi’s conviction. We granted
certiorari. 600 U. S. ___ (2023).
II
The Second Amendment provides that “[a] well
regulated Militia, being necessary to the security of a free State,
the right of the people to keep and bear Arms, shall not be
infringed.” As the Court recognizes, Bruen provides the
framework for analyzing whether a regulation such as §922(g)(8)
violates the Second Amendment’s mandate. “[W]hen the Second
Amendment’s plain text covers an individual’s conduct, the
Constitution presumptively protects that conduct.” 597 U. S.,
at 17. To overcome this presumption, “the government must
demonstrate that the regulation is consistent with the Nation’s
historical tradition of firearm regulation.” Ibid . The
presumption against restrictions on keeping and bearing firearms is
a central feature of the Second Amendment. That Amendment does not
merely narrow the Government’s regulatory power. It is a barrier,
placing the right to keep and bear arms off limits to the
Government.
When considering whether a modern regulation is
consistent with historical regulations and thus overcomes the
presumption against firearms restrictions, our precedents “point
toward at least two metrics [of comparison]: how and why the
regulations burden a law-abiding citizen’s right to armed
self-defense.” Id ., at 29. A historical law must satisfy
both considerations to serve as a comparator. See ibid .
While a historical law need not be a “historical twin,” it must be
“well-established and representative” to serve as a historical
analogue. Id ., at 30 (emphasis deleted).
In some cases, “the inquiry [is] fairly
straightforward.” Id ., at 26. For instance, “when a
challenged regulation addresses a general societal problem that has
persisted since the 18th century, the lack of a distinctly similar
historical regulation addressing that problem is relevant evidence
that the challenged regulation is inconsistent with the Second
Amendment. Likewise, if earlier generations addressed the societal
problem, but did so through materially different means, that also
could be evidence that a modern regulation is unconstitutional.” Id ., at 26–27.
The Court employed this “straightforward”
analysis in Heller and Bruen . Heller considered the District of Columbia’s “flat ban on the possession
of handguns in the home,” Bruen , 597 U. S., at 27, and Bruen considered New York’s effective ban on carrying a
firearm in public, see id. , at 11–13. The Court determined
that the District of Columbia and New York had “addressed a
perceived societal problem—firearm violence in densely populated
communities—and [they] employed a regulation . . . that
the Founders themselves could have adopted to confront that
problem.” Id ., at 27. Accordingly, the Court “consider[ed]
‘founding-era historical precedent’ ” and looked for a
comparable regulation. Ibid . (quoting Heller , 554
U. S., at 631). In both cases, the Court found no such law and
held the modern regulations unconstitutional. Id. , at 631; Bruen , 597 U. S., at 27.
Under our precedent, then, we must resolve two
questions to determine if §922(g)(8) violates the Second Amendment:
(1) Does §922(g)(8) target conduct protected by the Second
Amendment’s plain text; and (2) does the Government establish
that §922(g)(8) is consistent with the Nation’s historical
tradition of firearm regulation?
III
Section 922(g)(8) violates the Second
Amendment. First, it targets conduct at the core of the Second
Amendment—possessing firearms. Second, the Government failed to
produce any evidence that §922(g)(8) is consistent with the
Nation’s historical tradition of firearm regulation. To the
contrary, the founding generation addressed the same societal
problem as §922(g)(8) through the “materially different means” of
surety laws. Id. , at 26.
A
It is undisputed that §922(g)(8) targets
conduct encompassed by the Second Amendment’s plain text. After
all, the statute bans a person subject to a restraining order from
possessing or using virtually any firearm or ammunition. §922(g)
(prohibiting covered individuals from “possess[ing]” or
“receiv[ing] any firearm or ammunition which has been shipped or
transported in interstate or foreign commerce”). A covered
individual cannot even possess a firearm in his home for
self-defense, “the central component of the [ Second Amendment]
right itself.” Heller , 554 U. S., at 599 (emphasis
deleted). There is no doubt that §922(g)(8) is irreconcilable with
the Second Amendment’s text. Id. , at 628–629.
It is also undisputed that the Second Amendment
applies to Rahimi. By its terms, the Second Amendment extends to
“ ‘the people,’ ” and that “term unambiguously refers to
all members of the political community, not an unspecified subset.” Id. , at 580. The Second Amendment thus recognizes a right
“guaranteed to ‘all Americans.’ ” Bruen , 597
U. S., at 70 (quoting Heller , 554 U. S., at 581).
Since Rahimi is a member of the political community, he falls
within the Second Amendment’s guarantee.
B
The Government fails to carry its burden of
proving that §922(g)(8) is “consistent with the Nation’s historical
tradition of firearm regulation.” 597 U. S., at 24. Despite
canvassing laws before, during, and after our Nation’s founding,
the Government does not identify even a single regulation with an
analogous burden and justification.[ 2 ]
The Government’s failure is unsurprising given
that §922(g)(8) addresses a societal problem—the risk of
interpersonal violence—“that has persisted since the 18th century,”
yet was addressed “through [the] materially different means” of
surety laws. Id ., at 26. Surety laws were, in a nutshell, a
fine on certain behavior. If a person threatened someone in his
community, he was given the choice to either keep the peace or
forfeit a sum of money. Surety laws thus shared the same
justification as §922(g)(8), but they imposed a far less onerous
burden. The Government has not shown that §922(g)(8)’s more severe
approach is consistent with our historical tradition of firearm
regulation.
1
The Government does not offer a single
historical regulation that is relevantly similar to §922(g)(8). As
the Court has explained, the “central considerations” when
comparing modern and historical regulations are whether the
regulations “impose a comparable burden” that is “comparably
justified.” Id ., at 29. The Government offers only two
categories of evidence that are even within the ballpark of
§922(g)(8)’s burden and justification: English laws disarming
persons “dangerous” to the peace of the kingdom, and commentary
discussing peaceable citizens bearing arms. Neither category
ultimately does the job.
i
The Government points to various English laws
from the late 1600s and early 1700s to argue that there is a
tradition of restricting the rights of “dangerous” persons. For
example, the Militia Act of 1662 authorized local officials to
disarm individuals judged “dangerous to the Peace of the Kingdome.”
14 Car. 2 c. 3, §13. And, in the early 1700s, the Crown authorized
lords and justices of the peace to “cause search to be made for
arms in the possession of any persons whom they judge dangerous,
and seize such arms according to law.” Calendar of State Papers
Domestic: William III, 1700–1702, p. 234 (E. Bateson ed. 1937)
(Calendar William III).
At first glance, these laws targeting
“dangerous” persons might appear relevant. After all, if the Second
Amendment right was historically understood to allow an official to
disarm anyone he deemed “dangerous,” it may follow that modern
Congresses can do the same. Yet, historical context compels the
opposite conclusion. The Second Amendment stems from English
resistance against “dangerous” person laws.
The sweeping disarmament authority wielded by
English officials during the 1600s, including the Militia Act of
1662, prompted the English to enshrine an individual right to keep
and bear arms. “[T]he Stuart Kings Charles II and James II
succeeded in using select militias loyal to them to suppress
political dissidents, in part by disarming their opponents.” Heller , 554 U. S., at 592. Englishmen, as a result,
grew “to be extremely wary of concentrated military forces run by
the state and to be jealous of their arms.” Id. , at 593.
Following the Glorious Revolution, they “obtained an assurance
. . . in the Declaration of Right (which was codified as
the English Bill of Rights), that Protestants would never be
disarmed.” Ibid. The English Bill of Rights “has long been
understood to be the predecessor to our Second Amendment.” Ibid. In fact, our Founders expanded on it and made the
Second Amendment even more protective of individual liberty. The
English Bill of Rights assured Protestants “Arms for their
Defence,” but only where “suitable to their Conditions and as
allowed by Law.” 1 Wm. & Mary, ch. 2, (1688), in 6 Statutes of
the Realm 143. The Second Amendment, however, contains no such
qualifiers and protects the right of “the people” generally. In
short, laws targeting “dangerous” persons led to the Second
Amendment. It would be passing strange to permit the Government to
resurrect those selfsame “dangerous” person laws to chip away at
that Amendment’s guarantee.
Even on their own terms, laws targeting
“dangerous” persons cannot support §922(g)(8). Those laws were
driven by a justification distinct from that of §922(g)(8)—quashing
treason and rebellion. The Stuart Kings’ reign was marked by
religious and political conflict, which at that time were often one
and the same. The Parliament of the late 1600s “re-established an
intolerant episcopalian church” through legislation targeting other
sects, including “[a] fierce penal code” to keep those other sects
out of local government and “to criminalize nonconformist worship.”
Oxford Handbook of the English Revolution 212 (M. Braddick ed.
2015) (Oxford Handbook); see G. Clark, The Later Stuarts 1660–1714,
p. 22 (2d ed. 1955). These laws were driven in large part by a
desire to suppress rebellion. “Nonconformist ministers were thought
to preach resistance to divinely ordained monarchs.” Oxford
Handbook 212; see Calendar of State Papers Domestic: Charles II,
1661–1662, p. 161 (M. Green ed. 1861) (Calendar Charles II)
(“[P]reachers go about from county to county, and blow the flames
of rebellion”). Various nonconformist insurrections gave
credibility to these fears. See, e.g., Clark, The Later
Stuarts, at 22; Privy Council to Lord Newport (Mar. 4, 1661), in
Transactions of the Shropshire Archaeological and Natural History
Society, Pt. 2, 3d Ser., Vol. 4, p. 161 (1904).
It is in this turbulent context that the English
kings permitted the disarming of “dangerous persons.” English lords
feared that nonconformists— i . e ., people with
“ ‘wicked and Rebellious Principles’ ”—had
“ ‘furnished themselves with quantities of Arms, and
Ammunition’ ” “ ‘to put in Execution their Trayterus
designs.’ ” Privy Council to Lord Newport (Jan. 8, 1660), in id., at 156; see Calendar Charles II 541 (“The fanatics
. . . are high and insolent, and threaten all loyal
people; they will soon be in arms”). In response, the Crown took
measures to root out suspected rebels, which included “disarm[ing]
all factious and seditious spirits.” Id ., at 538 (Nov. 1,
1662). For example, following “turbulency and difficulties” arising
from the Conventicles Act of 1670, which forbade religious
nonconformists from assembling, the lord mayor of London pressed
that “a special warrant or commission [was] necessary” empowering
commissioners to “resist, fight, kill, and execute such rebels.”
Calendar of State Papers, Domestic Series, 1670, p. 236 (May 25,
1670) (M. Green ed. 1895) (emphasis deleted). King Charles II
ordered the lord mayor “to make strict search in the city and
precincts for dangerous and disaffected persons, seize and secure
them and their arms, and detain them in custody till our further
pleasure.” Id. , at 237 (May 26, 1670).
History repeated itself a few decades later. In
1701, King William III declared that “great quantities of arms, and
other provisions of war” had been discovered in the hands of
“papists and other disaffected persons, who disown [the]
government,” and that such persons had begun to assemble “in great
numbers . . . in the cities of London and Westminster.”
Calendar William III 233. He ordered the lord mayor of London and
the justices of the peace to “secur[e] the government” by disarming
“any persons whom they judge[d] dangerous,” including “any papist,
or reputed papist.” Id. , at 233–234 (emphasis deleted).
Similar disarmaments targeting “Papists and Non-jurors dangerous to
the peace of the kingdom” continued into the 1700s. Privy Council
to the Earl of Carlisle (July 30, 1714), in Historical Manuscripts
Comm’n, Manuscripts of the Earl of Westmoreland et al. 10th
Report, Appx., Pt. 4, p. 343 (1885). As before, disarmament was
designed to stifle “wicked conspirac[ies],” such as “raising a
Rebellion in this Kingdom in favour of a Popish Pretender.” Lord
Lonsdale to Deputy Lieutenants of Cumberland (May 20, 1722), in
Historical Manuscripts Commission, Manuscripts of the Earl of
Carlisle, 15th Report, Appx., Pt. 6, pp. 39–40 (1897).
While the English were concerned about
preventing insurrection and armed rebellion, §922(g)(8) is
concerned with preventing interpersonal violence. “Dangerous”
person laws thus offer the Government no support.
ii
The Government also points to historical
commentary referring to the right of “peaceable” citizens to carry
arms. It principally relies on commentary surrounding two failed
constitutional proposals.[ 3 ]
First, at the Massachusetts convention, Samuel Adams unsuccessfully
proposed that the Bill of Rights deny Congress the power “to
prevent the people of the United States, who are peaceable
citizens, from keeping their own arms.” 6 Documentary History of
the Ratification of the Constitution 1453 (J. Kaminski & G.
Saladino eds. 2000) (Documentary History). Second, Anti-Federalists
at the Pennsylvania convention unsuccessfully proposed a Bill of
Rights providing a “right to bear arms for the defense of
themselves and their own state, or the United States, or for the
purpose of killing game.” 2 id., at 597–598, ¶7 (M. Jensen
ed. 1976). The Anti-Federalists’ Bill of Rights would also state
that “no law shall be passed for disarming the people or any of
them, unless for crimes committed, or real danger of public injury
from individuals.” Id ., at 598.
These proposals carry little interpretative
weight. To begin with, it is “dubious to rely on [drafting] history
to interpret a text that was widely understood to codify a
pre-existing right.” Heller , 554 U. S., at 603.
Moreover, the States rejected the proposals. Samuel Adams withdrew
his own proposal after it “alarmed both Federalists and
Antifederalists.” 6 Documentary History 1453 (internal quotation
marks omitted).[ 4 ] The
Pennsylvania Anti-Federalists’ proposal similarly failed to gain a
majority of the state convention. 2 B. Schwartz, The Bill of
Rights: A Documentary History 628 (1971).
The Government never explains why or how
language excluded from the Constitution could operate to
limit the language actually ratified. The more natural inference
seems to be the opposite—the unsuccessful proposals suggest that
the Second Amendment preserves a more expansive right. After all,
the Founders considered, and rejected, any textual limitations in
favor of an unqualified directive: “[T]he right of the people to
keep and bear Arms, shall not be infringed.”
In addition to the proposals, the Government
throws in a hodgepodge of sources from the mid-to-late 1800s that
use the phrase “peaceable” in relation to firearms. Many of the
sources simply make passing reference to the notion. See, e . g ., H. R. Rep. No. 30, 39th Cong., 1st Sess., pt.
2, p. 229 (1866) (proposed circular explaining freed slaves “have
shown by their peaceful and orderly conduct that they can safely be
trusted with fire-arms, and they need them to kill game for
subsistence”). Other sources are individual musings on firearms
policy. See, e . g ., The Sale of Pistols, N. Y.
Times, June 22, 1874 (advocating for “including pistols in the law
against carrying concealed weapons”). Sources that do discuss
disarmament generally describe nonpeaceable citizens as those who
threaten the public or government. For example, the Government
quotes a Union General’s order that “all loyal and peaceable
citizens in Missouri will be permitted to bear arms.” Headquarters,
Dept. of the Missouri, General Orders, No. 86 (Aug. 25, 1863), in
The War of the Rebellion: A Compilation of the Official Records of
the Union and Confederate Armies, Ser. 1, Vol. 22, Pt. 2, p. 475
(1888). Yet, the Government fails to mention that the Union
General’s order addresses the “[l]arge numbers of men
. . . leaving the broken rebel armies . . . and
returning to Missouri . . . with the purpose of following
a career of plunder and murder.” Id ., at 474. The order
provided that “all those who voluntarily abandon[ed] the rebel
cause” could return to Missouri, but only if they “surrender[ed]
themselves and their arms,” “[took] the oath of allegiance and
[gave] bond for their future good conduct.” Ibid. By
contrast, “all loyal and peaceable citizens in Missouri w[ere]
permitted to bear arms” to “protect themselves from violence” and
“aid the troops.” Id ., at 475. Thus, the term “loyal and
peaceable” distinguished between the former rebels residing in
Missouri who were disarmed to prevent rebellion and those citizens
who would help fight against them.
The Government’s smorgasbord of commentary
proves little of relevance, and it certainly does not establish a
“historical tradition that delimits the outer bounds of the right
to keep and bear arms.” Bruen , 597 U. S., at 19.
iii
The Government’s remaining evidence is even
further afield. The Government points to an assortment of firearm
regulations, covering everything from storage practices to treason
and mental illness. They are all irrelevant for purposes of
§922(g)(8). Again, the “central considerations” when comparing
modern and historical regulations are whether they “impose a
comparable burden” that is “comparably justified.” Id. , at
29 (emphasis deleted; internal quotation marks omitted). The
Government’s evidence touches on one or none of these
considerations.
The Government’s reliance on firearm storage
laws is a helpful example. These laws penalized the improper
storage of firearms with forfeiture of those weapons. See, e.g., Act of Mar. 1, 1783, ch. 46, 1782 Mass. Acts pp.
119–120. First, these storage laws did not impose a “comparable
burden” to that of §922(g)(8). Forfeiture still allows a person to
keep their other firearms or obtain additional ones. It is in no
way equivalent to §922(g)(8)’s complete prohibition on owning or
possessing any firearms.
In fact, the Court already reached a similar
conclusion in Heller . The Court was tasked with comparing
laws imposing “a small fine and forfeiture of the weapon” with the
District of Columbia’s ban on keeping functional handguns at home
for self-defense, which was punishable by a year in prison. 554
U. S., at 633–634. We explained that the forfeiture laws were
“akin to modern penalties for minor public-safety infractions like
speeding or jaywalking.” Id. , at 633. Such inconsequential
punishment would not have “prevented a person in the founding era
from using a gun to protect himself or his family.” Id ., at
634. Accordingly, we concluded that the burdens were not
equivalent. See id ., at 633–634. That analysis applies here
in full force. If a small fine and forfeiture is not equivalent to
the District of Columbia’s handgun ban, it certainly falls short of
§922(g)(8)’s ban on possessing any firearm.
The Government resists the conclusion that
forfeiture is less burdensome than a possession ban, arguing that
“[t]he burdens imposed by bans on keeping, bearing, and obtaining
arms are all comparable.” Reply Brief 10. But, there is surely a
distinction between having no Second Amendment rights and
having some Second Amendment rights. If self-defense is “the
central component of the [ Second Amendment] right,” then common
sense dictates that it matters whether you can defend yourself with
a firearm anywhere, only at home, or nowhere. Heller , 554
U. S., at 599 (emphasis deleted). And, the Government’s
suggestion ignores that we have repeatedly drawn careful
distinctions between various laws’ burdens. See, e.g. , id. , at 632 (explaining that laws that “did not clearly
prohibit loaded weapons . . . do not remotely burden the
right of self-defense as much as an absolute ban on handguns”); see
also Bruen , 597 U. S., at 48.
Our careful parsing of regulatory burdens makes
sense given that the Second Amendment codifies a right with a
“historically fixed meaning.” Id ., at 28. Accordingly,
history is our reference point and anchor. If we stray too far from
it by eliding material differences between historical and modern
laws, we “risk endorsing outliers that our ancestors would never
have accepted.” Id ., at 30 (internal quotation marks and
alteration omitted).
Second, the Government offers no “comparable
justification” between laws punishing firearm storage practices and
§922(g)(8). It posits that both laws punish persons whose “conduct
suggested that he would not use [firearms] responsibly.” Brief for
United States 24. The Government, however, does not even attempt to
ground that justification in historical evidence. See infra ,
at 28–29.
The Government’s proposed justification is also
far too general. Nearly all firearm regulations can be cast as
preventing “irresponsible” or “unfit” persons from accessing
firearms. In addition, to argue that a law limiting access to
firearms is justified by the fact that the regulated groups should
not have access to firearms is a logical merry-go-round. As the
Court has made clear, such overly broad judgments cannot suffice.
In Bruen , New York claimed it could effectively ban public
carry because “the island of Manhattan [is] a ‘sensitive
place.’ ” 597 U. S., at 31. New York defined a “sensitive
place” as “all places where people typically congregate and where
law-enforcement and other public-safety professionals are
presumptively available.” Id. , at 30–31 (internal quotation
marks omitted). The Court rejected that definition as “far too
broa[d]” as it “would in effect exempt cities from the Second
Amendment and would eviscerate the general right to publicly carry
arms for self-defense.” Id ., at 31. Likewise, calling a
modern and historical law comparably justified because they both
prevent unfit persons from accessing firearms would render our
comparable-justification inquiry toothless.[ 5 ]
In sum, the Government has not identified any
historical regulation that is relevantly similar to §922(g)(8).
2
This dearth of evidence is unsurprising
because the Founders responded to the societal problem of
interpersonal violence through a less burdensome regime: surety
laws. Tracing back to early English history, surety laws were a
preventative mechanism for ensuring an individual’s future
peaceable conduct. See D. Feldman, The King’s Peace, the Royal
Prerogative and Public Order, 47 Cambridge L. J. 101, 101–102
(1988); M. Dalton, The Countrey Justice 140–144 (1619). If someone
received a surety demand, he was required to go to a court or
judicial officer with one or more members of the
community— i . e ., sureties—and comply with certain
conditions. 4 W. Blackstone, Commentaries on the Laws of England
249–250 (1769) (Blackstone). Specifically, the person providing
sureties was required to “keep the peace: either generally
. . . or . . . with regard to the person who
crave[d] the security” until a set date. Id ., at 250. If he
kept the peace, the surety obligation dissolved on that
predetermined date. See ibid . If, however, he breached the
peace before that date, he and his sureties would owe a set sum of
money. See id ., at 249–250. Evidence suggests that sureties
were readily available. Even children, who “[we]re incapable of
engaging themselves to answer any debt,” could still find “security
by their friends.” Id ., at 251.
There is little question that surety laws
applied to the threat of future interpersonal violence. “[W]herever
any private man [had] just cause to fear, that another w[ould] burn
his house, or do him a corporal injury, by killing, imprisoning, or
beating him . . . he [could] demand surety of the peace
against such person.” Id ., at 252; see also J. Backus, The
Justice of the Peace 25 (1816) (providing for sureties when a
person “stands in fear of his life, or of some harm to be done to
his person or his estate” (emphasis deleted)).
Surety demands were also expressly available to
prevent domestic violence. Surety could be sought by “a wife
against her husband who threatens to kill her or beat her
outrageously, or, if she have notorious cause to fear he will do
either.” Id ., at 24; see 1 W. Hawkins, Pleas of the Crown
253 (6th ed. 1777) (“[I]t is certain, that a wife may demand [a
surety] against her husband threatening to beat her outrageously,
and that a husband also may have it against his wife”). The right
to demand sureties in cases of potential domestic violence was
recognized not only by treatises, but also the founding-era courts.
Records from before and after the Second Amendment’s ratification
reflect that spouses successfully demanded sureties when they
feared future domestic violence. See, e.g. , Records of the
Courts of Quarter Sessions and Common Pleas of Bucks County,
Pennsylvania, 1684–1700, pp. 80–81 (1943) (detailing surety
demanded upon allegations that a husband was “abusive to [his wife]
that she was afraid of her Life & of her Childrns lifes”); see
also Heyn’s Case , 2 Ves. & Bea. 182, 35 Eng. Rep. 288
(Ch. 1813) (1822) (granting wife’s request to order her husband who
committed “various acts of ill usage and threats” to “find
sufficient sureties”); Anonymous , 1 S. C. Eq. 113
(1785) (order requiring husband to “enter into recognizance
. . . with two sureties . . . for keeping the
peace towards the complainant (his wife)”).
3
Although surety laws shared a common
justification with §922(g)(8), surety laws imposed a materially
different burden. Critically, a surety demand did not alter an
individual’s right to keep and bear arms. After providing sureties,
a person kept possession of all his firearms; could purchase
additional firearms; and could carry firearms in public and
private. Even if he breached the peace, the only penalty was that
he and his sureties had to pay a sum of money. 4 Blackstone 250. To
disarm him, the Government would have to take some other action,
such as imprisoning him for a crime. See Feldman, 47 Cambridge
L. J., at 101.
By contrast, §922(g)(8) strips an individual of
his Second Amendment right. The statute’s breadth cannot be
overstated. For one, §922(g) criminalizes nearly all conduct
related to covered firearms and ammunition. Most fundamentally,
possession is prohibited, except in the rarest of circumstances.
See, e.g., United States v. Rozier , 598 F.3d
768, 771 (CA11 2010) ( per curiam ) (concluding that it
was “irrelevant” whether defendant “possessed the handgun for
purposes of self-defense (in his home)”); United States v. Gant , 691 F.2d 1159, 1162 (CA5 1982) (affirming conviction
of a business owner under §922(g) predecessor statute for briefly
possessing a firearm to ward off suspected robbers). Courts of
Appeals have understood “possession” broadly, upholding convictions
where a person “picked up . . . three firearms for a few
seconds to inspect” each, United States v. Matthews ,
520 F.3d 806, 807 (CA7 2008), or “made direct contact with the
firearm by sitting on it,” United States v. Johnson ,
46 F. 4th 1183, 1189 (CA10 2022). They have also construed
§922(g) to bar “constructive possession” of a firearm, including,
for example, ammunition found in a jointly occupied home. See, e.g., United States v. Stepp , 89 F. 4th 826,
832–835 (CA10 2023).
Moreover, §922(g) captures virtually all
commercially available firearms and ammunition. It prohibits
possessing a firearm “in or affecting commerce” and “receiv[ing]
any firearm or ammunition which has been shipped or transported in
interstate or foreign commerce.” §922(g). As courts have
interpreted that nexus, if a firearm or ammunition has at any point
crossed interstate lines, it is regulated by §922(g). See Scarborough v. United States , 431
U.S. 563 , 566–567 (1977) (holding §922(g)’s predecessor statute
covered firearm that “had previously traveled in interstate
commerce”); United States v. Lemons , 302 F.3d 769 , 772 (CA7 2002) (affirming conviction under
§922(g) for possessing firearm that “crossed into Wisconsin after
its manufacture at some indeterminate moment in time—possibly years
before it was discovered in [the defendant’s]
possession”).[ 6 ] In fact, the
statute goes even further by regulating not only ammunition but
also all constituent parts of ammunition—many of which are
parts with no dangerous function on their own. See 18
U. S. C. §921(a)(17)(A).
These sweeping prohibitions are criminally
enforced. To violate the statute is a felony, punishable by up to
15 years. §924(a)(8). That felony conviction, in turn, triggers a
permanent, life-long prohibition on exercising the Second Amendment
right. See §922(g)(1).
The combination of the Government’s sweeping
view of the firearms and ammunition within its regulatory reach and
the broad prohibition on any conduct regarding covered firearms and
ammunition makes §922(g)(8)’s burden unmistakable: The statute
revokes a citizen’s Second Amendment right while the civil
restraining order is in place. And, that revocation is absolute. It
makes no difference if the covered individual agrees to a
no-contact order, posts a bond, or even moves across the country
from his former domestic partner—the bar on exercising the Second
Amendment right remains. See United States v. Wilkey ,
2020 WL 4464668, *1 (D Mont., Aug. 4, 2020) (defendant agreed to
Florida protection order so he could “ ‘just walk away’ ”
and was prosecuted several years later for possessing firearms in
Montana).
That combination of burdens places §922(g)(8) in
an entirely different stratum from surety laws. Surety laws
preserve the Second Amendment right, whereas §922(g)(8) strips an
individual of that right. While a breach of a surety demand was
punishable by a fine, §922(g)(8) is punishable by a felony
conviction, which in turn permanently revokes an individual’s
Second Amendment right. At base, it is difficult to imagine how
surety laws can be considered relevantly similar to a complete ban
on firearm ownership, possession, and use.
This observation is nothing new; the Court has
already recognized that surety laws impose a lesser relative burden
on the Second Amendment right. In Bruen , the Court explained
that surety laws merely “provide financial incentives for
responsible arms carrying.” 597 U. S., at 59. “[A]n accused
arms-bearer ‘could go on carrying without criminal penalty’ so long
as he ‘post[ed] money that would be forfeited if he breached the
peace or injured others.’ ” Id. , at 56–57 (quoting Wrenn v. District of Columbia , 864 F.3d 650, 661
(CADC 2017); alteration in original). As a result, we held that
surety laws were not analogous to New York’s effective ban on
public carry. 597 U. S., at 55. That conclusion is damning for
§922(g)(8), which burdens the Second Amendment right even more with
respect to covered individuals.
Surety laws demonstrate that this case should
have been a “straightforward” inquiry. Id. , at 27. The
Government failed to produce a single historical regulation that is
relevantly similar to §922(g)(8). Rather, §922(g)(8) addresses a
societal problem—the risk of interpersonal violence—“that has
persisted since the 18th century,” yet was addressed “through [the]
materially different means” of surety laws. Id. , at 26.
C
The Court has two rejoinders, surety and
affray laws. Neither is a compelling historical analogue. As I have
explained, surety laws did not impose a burden comparable to
§922(g)(8). And, affray laws had a dissimilar burden and justification. The Court does not reckon with these vital
differences, asserting that the disagreement is whether surety and
affray laws must be an exact copy of §922(g)(8). Ante , at
16. But, the historical evidence shows that those laws are
worlds—not degrees—apart from §922(g)(8). For this reason, the
Court’s argument requires combining aspects of surety and affray
laws to justify §922(g)(8). This piecemeal approach is not what the
Second Amendment or our precedents countenance.
1
Despite the foregoing evidence, the Court
insists that surety laws in fact support §922(g)(8). To make
its case, the Court studiously avoids discussing the full extent of
§922(g)(8)’s burden as compared to surety laws. The most the Court
does is attack Bruen ’s conclusion that surety laws were less
burdensome than a public carry ban. The Court reasons that Bruen dealt with a “broad prohibitory regime” while
§922(g)(8) applies to only a subset of citizens. Ante, at
15–16. Yet, that was only one way in which Bruen distinguished a public carry ban from surety laws’ burden. True, Bruen noted that, unlike the public carry ban, surety laws
did not restrict the general citizenry. But, Bruen also
plainly held that surety laws did not “constitut[e] a ‘severe’
restraint on public carry, let alone a restriction tantamount to a
ban.” 597 U. S., at 59. In fact, that conclusion is repeated
throughout the opinion. Id ., at 55–59 (surety laws “were not bans on public carry”; “surety laws did not prohibit public carry”; surety laws “were not viewed as substantial
restrictions on public carry”; and “surety statutes did not
directly restrict public carry”). Bruen ’s conclusion is
inescapable and correct. Because surety laws are not equivalent to
an effective ban on public carry, they do not impose a burden
equivalent to a complete ban on carrying and possessing
firearms.
Next, the Court relies on affray laws
prohibiting “riding or going armed, with dangerous or unusual
weapons, [to] terrif[y] the good people of the land.” 4 Blackstone
149 (emphasis deleted). These laws do not justify §922(g)(8)
either. As the Court concedes, why and how a historical regulation
burdened the right of armed self-defense are central
considerations. Ante , at 7. Affray laws are not a fit on
either basis.
First, affray laws had a distinct justification
from §922(g)(8) because they regulated only certain public conduct
that injured the entire community. An affray was a “common
Nusanc[e],” 1 Hawkins, Pleas of the Crown, at 135, defined as “the
fighting of two or more persons in some public place, to the terror
of his majesty’s subjects,” 4 Blackstone 145. Even though an affray
generally required “actual violence,” certain other conduct could
suffice. 1 R. Burn, The Justice of the Peace, and Parish Officer 13
(2d ed. 1756). As relevant here, an affray included arming oneself
“with dangerous and unusual weapons, in such a manner as [to]
naturally cause a terror to the people”— i . e ., “going
armed.” Ibid. Many postfounding going armed laws had a
self-defense exception: A person could “go armed with a[n]
. . . offensive and dangerous weapon” so long as he had
“reasonable cause to fear an assault or other injury.” Mass. Rev.
Stat., ch. 134, §16 (1836); see also 1838 Terr. of Wis. Stat. §16,
p. 381; 1851 Terr. of Minn. Rev. Stat., ch. 112, §18.
Affrays were defined by their public nature and
effect. An affray could occur only in “some public place,” and
captured only conduct affecting the broader public. 4 Blackstone
145. To that end, going armed laws did not prohibit carrying
firearms at home or even public carry generally. See Bruen ,
597 U. S., at 47–50. Instead, they targeted only public carry
that was “accompanied with such circumstances as are apt to terrify
the people.” 1 Burn, Justice of the Peace, at 13; see Bruen ,
597 U. S., at 50 (explaining that going armed laws “prohibit
bearing arms in a way that spreads ‘fear’ or ‘terror’ among the
people”).
Affrays were intentionally distinguished from
assaults and private interpersonal violence on that same basis. See Cash v. State , 2 Tenn. 198, 199 (1813) (“It is
because the violence is committed in a public place, and to the
terror of the people, that the crime is called an affray, instead
of assault and battery”); Nottingham v. State , 227
Md. App. 592, 602, 135 A.3d 541, 547 (Md. 2016) (“[U]nlike assault
and battery,” affray is “not a crime against the person; rather,
affray is a crime against the public” (internal quotation marks
omitted)). As treatises shortly before the founding explain, “there
may be an Assault which will not amount to an Affray; as where it
happens in a private Place, out of the hearing or seeing of any,
except the Parties concerned; in which Case it cannot be said to be
to the Terror of the People.” 1 Hawkins , Pleas of the Crown,
at 134; see 1 Burn, Justice of the Peace, at 13. Affrays thus did
not cover the very conduct §922(g)(8) seeks to
prevent—interpersonal violence in the home.
Second, affray laws did not impose a burden
analogous to §922(g)(8). They regulated a niche subset of Second
Amendment-protected activity. As explained, affray laws prohibited
only carrying certain weapons (“dangerous and unusual”) in a
particular manner (“terrifying the good people of the land” without
a need for self-defense) and in particular places (in public).
Meanwhile, §922(g)(8) prevents a covered person from carrying any
firearm or ammunition, in any manner, in any place, at any time,
and for any reason. Section 922(g)(8) thus bans all Second
Amendment-protected activity. Indeed, this Court has already
concluded that affray laws do not impose a burden “analogous to the
burden created by” an effective ban on public carry. Bruen ,
597 U. S., at 50. Surely, then, a law that imposes a public
and private ban on a covered individual cannot have an analogous
burden either.
The Court counters that since affray laws
“provided for imprisonment,” they imposed a lesser burden than
§922(g)(8)’s disarmament. Ante , at 14. But, that argument
serves only to highlight another fundamental difference: Affray
laws were criminal statutes that penalized past behavior, whereas
§922(g)(8) is triggered by a civil restraining order that seeks to
prevent future behavior. Accordingly, an affray’s burden was vastly
harder to impose. To imprison a person, a State had to prove that
he committed the crime of affray beyond a reasonable doubt. The
Constitution provided a bevy of protections during that
process—including a right to a jury trial, counsel, and protections
against double jeopardy. See Amdts. 5, 6.
The imposition of §922(g)(8)’s burden, however,
has far fewer hurdles to clear. There is no requirement that the
accused has actually committed a crime; instead, he need only be
prohibited from threatening or using force, or pose a “credible
threat” to an “intimate partner or child.” §922(g)(8)(C). Section
922(g)(8) thus revokes a person’s Second Amendment right based on
the suspicion that he may commit a crime in the future. In
addition, the only process required before that revocation is a
hearing on the underlying court order. §922(g)(8)(A). During that
civil hearing—which is not even about §922(g)(8)—a person has fewer
constitutional protections compared to a criminal prosecution for
affray. Gone are the Sixth Amendment’s panoply of rights, including
the rights to confront witnesses and have assistance of counsel, as
well as the Fifth Amendment’s protection against double jeopardy.
See Turner v. Rogers , 564 U.S.
431 , 441 (2011) (“[T]he Sixth Amendment does not govern civil
cases”); Hudson v. United States , 522 U.S.
93 , 99 (1997) (“The [Double Jeopardy] Clause protects only
against the imposition of multiple criminal punishments for
the same offense”). Civil proceedings also do not require proof
beyond a reasonable doubt, and some States even set aside the rules
of evidence, allowing parties to rely on hearsay. See, e.g., Wash. Rule Evid. 1101(c)(4) (2024) (providing the state rules of
evidence “need not be applied” to applications for protection
orders (boldface and capitalization deleted)); Cal. Civ. Proc. Code
Ann. §527.6(i) (West Supp. 2024) (judge “shall receive any
testimony that is relevant” and issue order based on clear and
convincing evidence). The differences between criminal prosecutions
and civil hearings are numerous and consequential.
Affray laws are wide of the mark. While the
Second Amendment does not demand a historical twin, it requires
something closer than affray laws, which expressly carve out the
very conduct §922(g)(8) was designed to prevent (interpersonal
violence in the home). Nor would I conclude that affray
laws—criminal laws regulating a specific type of public carry—are
analogous to §922(g)(8)’s use of a civil proceeding to bar all
Second Amendment-protected activity.
2
The Court recognizes that surety and affray
laws on their own are not enough. So it takes pieces from each to
stitch together an analogue for §922(g)(8). Ante, at 13. Our
precedents foreclose that approach. The question before us is
whether a single historical law has both a comparable burden and
justification as §922(g)(8), not whether several laws can be
cobbled together to qualify. As Bruen explained,
“determining whether a historical regulation is a proper analogue
for a distinctly modern firearm regulation requires a determination
of whether the two regulations”—the historical and modern
regulations—“are ‘relevantly similar.’ ” 597 U. S., at
28–29. In doing so, a court must consider whether that single
historical regulation “impose[s] a comparable burden on the right
of armed self-defense and whether that burden is comparably
justified.” Id ., at 29 (emphasis added).
The Court’s contrary approach of mixing and
matching historical laws—relying on one law’s burden and another
law’s justification—defeats the purpose of a historical inquiry
altogether. Given that imprisonment (which involved disarmament)
existed at the founding, the Government can always satisfy this
newly minted comparable-burden requirement. See ante, at
14–15. That means the Government need only find a historical law
with a comparable justification to validate modern disarmament
regimes. As a result, historical laws fining certain behavior could
justify completely disarming a person for the same behavior. That
is the exact sort of “regulatory blank check” that Bruen warns against and the American people ratified the Second Amendment
to preclude. 597 U. S., at 30.
Neither the Court nor the Government identifies
a single historical regulation with a comparable burden and
justification as §922(g)(8). Because there is none, I would
conclude that the statute is inconsistent with the Second
Amendment.
IV
The Government, for its part, tries to rewrite
the Second Amendment to salvage its case. It argues that the Second
Amendment allows Congress to disarm anyone who is not “responsible”
and “law-abiding.” Not a single Member of the Court adopts the
Government’s theory. Indeed, the Court disposes of it in half a
page—and for good reason. Ante, at 17. The Government’s
argument lacks any basis in our precedents and would eviscerate the
Second Amendment altogether.
A
The Government’s position is a bald attempt to
refashion this Court’s doctrine. At the outset of this case, the
Government contended that the Court has already held the Second
Amendment protects only “responsible, law-abiding” citizens. Brief
for United States 6, 11–12. The plain text of the Second Amendment
quashes this argument. The Amendment recognizes “the right of the people to keep and bear Arms.” (Emphasis added.) When the
Constitution refers to “the people,” the term “unambiguously refers
to all members of the political community.” Heller , 554
U. S., at 580; see also id ., at 581 (beginning its
analysis with the strong “presumption that the Second Amendment
right . . . belongs to all Americans”). The Government’s
claim that the Court already held the Second Amendment protects
only “law-abiding, responsible citizens” is specious at
best.[ 7 ] See ante , at
17.
At argument, the Government invented yet another
position. It explained that when it used the term “responsible” in
its briefs, it really meant “not dangerous.” See Tr. of Oral
Arg. 10–11. Thus, it posited that the Second Amendment protects
only law-abiding and non-dangerous citizens. No matter how
many adjectives the Government swaps out, the fact remains that the
Court has never adopted anything akin to the Government’s test. In
reality, the “law-abiding, dangerous citizen” test is the
Government’s own creation, designed to justify every one of its
existing regulations. It has no doctrinal or constitutional
mooring.
The Government finally tries to cram its
dangerousness test into our precedents. It argues that §922(g)(8)
and its proffered historical laws have a shared justification of
disarming dangerous citizens. The Government, however, does not
draw that conclusion by examining the historical justification for
each law cited. Instead, the Government simply looks—from a modern
vantage point—at the mix of laws and manufactures a possible
connection between them all. Yet, our task is to “assess whether
modern firearms regulations are consistent with the Second
Amendment’s text and historical understanding.” Bruen , 597 U. S., at 26 (emphasis added). To do so, we
must look at the historical law’s justification as articulated
during the relevant time period—not at modern post-hoc speculations. See, e.g ., id ., at 41–42, 48–49; Heller , 554 U. S., at 631–632. As I have explained, a
historically based study of the evidence reveals that the
Government’s position is untenable. Supra , at 7–13.
As it does today, the Court should continue to
rebuff the Government’s attempts to rewrite the Second Amendment
and the Court’s precedents interpreting it.
B
The Government’s “law-abiding, dangerous
citizen” theory is also antithetical to our constitutional
structure. At bottom, its test stems from the idea that the Second
Amendment points to general principles, not a historically grounded
right. And, it asserts that one of those general principles is that
Congress can disarm anyone it deems “dangerous, irresponsible, or
otherwise unfit to possess arms.” Brief for United States 7. This
approach is wrong as a matter of constitutional interpretation, and
it undermines the very purpose and function of the Second
Amendment.
The Second Amendment recognizes a pre-existing
right and that right was “enshrined with the scope” it was
“understood to have when the people adopted [the Amendment].” Heller , 554 U. S., at 634–635. Only a subsequent
constitutional amendment can alter the Second Amendment’s terms,
“whether or not future legislatures or . . . even future
judges think [its original] scope [is] too broad.” Id., at
635.
Yet, the Government’s “law-abiding, dangerous
citizen” test—and indeed any similar, principle-based
approach—would hollow out the Second Amendment of any substance.
Congress could impose any firearm regulation so long as it targets
“unfit” persons. And, of course, Congress would also dictate what
“unfit” means and who qualifies. See Tr. of Oral Arg. 7, 51. The
historical understanding of the Second Amendment right would be
irrelevant. In fact, the Government posits that Congress could
enact a law that the Founders explicitly rejected. See id., at 18 (agreeing that modern judgment would override
“[f]ounding-[e]ra applications”). At base, whether a person could
keep, bear, or even possess firearms would be Congress’s policy
choice under the Government’s test.
That would be the direct inverse of the
Founders’ and ratifying public’s intent. Instead of a substantive
right guaranteed to every individual against Congress, we
would have a right controlled by Congress. “A constitutional
guarantee subject to future judges’ [or Congresses’] assessments of
its usefulness is no constitutional guarantee at all.” Heller , 554 U. S., at 634. The Second Amendment is “the
very product of an interest balancing by the people.” Id ., at 635. It is this policy judgment—not that of modern
and future Congresses—“that demands our unqualified deference.” Bruen , 597 U. S., at 26.
The Government’s own evidence exemplifies the
dangers of approaches based on generalized principles. Before the
Court of Appeals, the Government pointed to colonial statutes
“disarming classes of people deemed to be threats, including
. . . slaves, and native Americans.” Supp. Brief for
United States in No. 21–11001 (CA5), p. 33. It argued that since
early legislatures disarmed groups considered to be “threats,” a
modern Congress has the same authority. Ibid. The problem
with such a view should be obvious. Far from an exemplar of
Congress’s authority, the discriminatory regimes the Government
relied upon are cautionary tales. They warn that when majoritarian
interests alone dictate who is “dangerous,” and thus can be
disarmed, disfavored groups become easy prey. One of many such
examples was the treatment of freed blacks following the Civil War.
“[M]any of the over 180,000 African-Americans who served in the
Union Army returned to the States of the old Confederacy, where
systematic efforts were made to disarm them and other blacks.” McDonald v. Chicago , 561 U.S.
742 , 771 (2010). Some “States formally prohibited African-
Americans from possessing firearms.” Ibid. And,
“[t]hroughout the South, armed parties . . . forcibly
took firearms from newly freed slaves.” Id. , at 772. “In one
town, the marshal took all arms from returned colored soldiers, and
was very prompt in shooting the blacks whenever an opportunity
occurred.” Ibid . (alterations and internal quotation marks
omitted). A constitutional amendment was ultimately “necessary to
provide full protection for the rights of blacks.” Id. , at
775.
The Government peddles a modern version of the
governmental authority that led to those historical evils. Its
theory would allow federal majoritarian interests to determine who
can and cannot exercise their constitutional rights. While Congress
cannot revive disarmament laws based on race, one can easily
imagine a world where political minorities or those with disfavored
cultural views are deemed the next “dangers” to society.
Thankfully, the Constitution prohibits such laws. The “very
enumeration of the [ Second Amendment] right takes out of the hands
of government . . . the power to decide on a case-by-case
basis whether the right is really worth insisting upon.” Heller , 544 U. S., at 634.
The Court rightly rejects the Government’s
approach by concluding that any modern regulation must be justified
by specific historical regulations. See ante , at 10–15. But,
the Court should remain wary of any theory in the future that would
exchange the Second Amendment’s boundary line—“the right of the
people to keep and bear Arms, shall not be infringed”—for vague
(and dubious) principles with contours defined by whoever happens
to be in power.
* * *
This case is not about whether States can
disarm people who threaten others. States have a ready mechanism
for disarming anyone who uses a firearm to threaten physical
violence: criminal prosecution. Most States, including Texas,
classify aggravated assault as a felony, punishable by up to 20
years’ imprisonment. See Tex. Penal Code Ann. §§22.02(b), 12.33
(West 2019 and Supp. 2023). Assuming C. M.’s allegations could
be proved, Texas could have convicted and imprisoned Rahimi for
every one of his alleged acts. Thus, the question before us is not
whether Rahimi and others like him can be disarmed consistent with
the Second Amendment. Instead, the question is whether the
Government can strip the Second Amendment right of anyone subject
to a protective order—even if he has never been accused or
convicted of a crime. It cannot. The Court and Government do not
point to a single historical law revoking a citizen’s Second
Amendment right based on possible interpersonal violence. The
Government has not borne its burden to prove that §922(g)(8) is
consistent with the Second Amendment’s text and historical
understanding.
The Framers and ratifying public understood
“that the right to keep and bear arms was essential to the
preservation of liberty.” McDonald , 561 U. S., at 858
(Thomas, J., concurring in part and concurring in judgment). Yet,
in the interest of ensuring the Government can regulate one subset
of society, today’s decision puts at risk the Second Amendment
rights of many more. I respectfully dissent. Notes 1 Rahimi does not ask the
Court to consider, and I do not address, whether §922(g)(8)
satisfies the Due Process Clause. 2 I agree with the majority
that we need not address the “ ‘ongoing scholarly debate on
whether courts should primarily rely on the prevailing
understanding of an individual right when the Fourteenth Amendment
was ratified in 1868 when defining its scope (as well as the scope
of the right against the Federal Government).’ ” Ante, at 8, n. 1 (quoting New York State Rifle & Pistol
Assn., Inc. v. Bruen , 597 U.S. 1, 37
(2022)). 3 The Government also cites
an amendment to the Massachusetts Constitution providing that “the
people have a right to keep and to bear Arms for their Own and the
Common defence.” The Popular Sources of Political Authority:
Documents on the Massachusetts Constitution of 1780, p. 624
(O. Handlin & M. Handlin eds. 1966). The Government emphasizes
that the amendment’s proponents believed they “Ought Never to be
deprived” of their arms, so long as they “Continue[d] honest and
Lawfull Subjects of Government.” Ibid. Even if the amendment
contemplated disarming dishonest and unlawful subjects, the
Government makes no effort to define those terms or explain why
they necessarily include the individuals covered by §922(g)(8). In
any event, evidence concerning what proponents behind an amendment
to a single state constitution believed is too paltry to define the
Second Amendment right. See Bruen , 597 U. S., at
46. 4 When Anti-Federalists
renewed Samuel Adams’ proposal, not only did the proposal fail, but
Adams himself voted against it. 6 Documentary History
1453. 5 The Government’s other
analogies suffer from the same flaws as the firearm storage laws.
It cites laws restricting firearm sales to and public carry by
various groups such as minors and intoxicated persons; laws
confiscating firearms from rioters; and laws disarming
insurrectionists and rebels. Brief for United States 22–27. These
laws target different groups of citizens, for different reasons,
and through different, less onerous burdens than §922(g)(8). See Bruen , 597 U. S., at 70 (explaining that regulations
“limit[ing] the intent for which one could carry arms, the manner
by which one carried arms, or the exceptional circumstances under
which one could not carry arms” do not justify “broadly
prohibit[ing] the public carry of commonly used firearms for
personal defense”). None establishes that the particular regulation
at issue here would have been within the bounds of the pre-existing
Second Amendment right. 6 The majority correctly
declines to consider Rahimi’s Commerce Clause challenge because he
did not raise it below. See Cutter v. Wilkinson , 544 U.S.
709 , 718, n. 7 (2005) (“[W]e are a court of review, not of
first view”). That said, I doubt that §922(g)(8) is a proper
exercise of Congress’s power under the Commerce Clause. See United States v. Lopez , 514 U.S.
549 , 585 (1995) (Thomas, J., concurring). 7 The only conceivably
relevant language in our precedents is the passing reference in Heller to laws banning felons and others from possessing
firearms. See 554 U. S., at 626–627, and n. 26. That
discussion is dicta. As for Bruen , the Court used the phrase
“ordinary, law-abiding citizens” merely to describe those who were
unable to publicly carry a firearm in New York. See, e.g .,
597 U. S., at 9, 15, 31–32, 71. | Here is a summary of the Supreme Court case United States v. Rahimi:
Issue: Can an individual who is subject to a domestic violence restraining order and deemed a threat to their intimate partner or child be prohibited from possessing a firearm under the Second Amendment?
Holding: Yes. The Supreme Court upheld the federal statute that prohibits individuals under domestic violence restraining orders from possessing firearms if they are deemed a credible threat to their intimate partners or children.
Facts: Rahimi, who was subject to a restraining order due to a violent incident with his girlfriend and the mother of his child, challenged the constitutionality of the federal statute that prohibited him from possessing a firearm.
Reasoning: The Court found that similar firearm regulations existed at the time of the Second Amendment's ratification, suggesting that the regulation did not violate the right to bear arms. The Court also emphasized that Rahimi's violent conduct and the state court's findings justified the restriction. |
Equal Protection | Schuette v. Coalition to Defend Affirmative Action | https://supreme.justia.com/cases/federal/us/572/291/ | NOTICE: This opinion is subject to
formal revision before publication in the preliminary print of the
United States Reports. Readers are requested to notify the
Reporter of Decisions, Supreme Court of the United States,
Washington, D. C. 20543, of any typographical or other formal
errors, in order that corrections may be made before the
preliminary print goes to press.
SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES
_________________
No. 12–682
_________________
BILL SCHUETTE, ATTORNEY GENERAL OF MICHI-GAN,
PETITIONER v. COALITION TO DEFEND AF-FIRMATIVE ACTION, INTEGRATION
AND IMMI-GRANT RIGHTS AND FIGHT FOR EQUALITYBY ANY MEANS NECESSARY
(BAMN), et al.
on writ of certiorari to the united states
court of appeals for the sixth circuit
[April 22, 2014]
Justice Kennedy
announced the judgment of the Court and delivered an opinion, in
which The Chief Justice and Justice Alito join.
The Court in this case
must determine whether an amendment to the Constitution of the
State of Michigan, approved and enacted by its voters, is invalid
under the Equal Protection Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment to
the Constitution of the United States.
In 2003 the Court
reviewed the constitutionality of two admissions systems at the
University of Michigan, one for its undergraduate class and one for
its law school. The undergraduate admissions plan was addressed in
Gratz v. Bollinger, 539 U. S. 244 . The law school admission
plan was addressed in Grutter v. Bollinger, 539 U. S. 306 . Each
admissions process permitted the explicit consideration of an
applicant’s race. In Gratz, the Court invalidated the
undergraduate plan as a violation of the Equal Protection Clause.
539 U. S., at 270. In Grutter, the Court found no
constitutional flaw in the law school admission plan’s more
limited use of race-based preferences. 539 U. S., at 343.
In response to the
Court’s decision in Gratz, the university revised its
undergraduate admissions process, but the revision still allowed
limited use of race-based preferences. After a statewide debate on
the question of racial preferences in the context of governmental
decisionmaking, the voters, in 2006, adopted an amendment to the
State Constitution prohibiting state and other governmental
entities in Michigan from granting certain preferences, including
race-based preferences, in a wide range of actions and decisions.
Under the terms of the amendment, race-based preferences cannot be
part of the admissions process for state universities. That
particular prohibition is central to the instant case.
The ballot proposal was
called Proposal 2 and, after it passed by a margin of 58 percent to
42 percent, the resulting enactment became Article I, §26, of
the Michigan Constitution. As noted, the amendment is in broad
terms. Section 26 states, in relevant part, as follows:
“(1) The
University of Michigan, Michigan State University, Wayne State
University, and any other public college or university, community
college, or school district shall not discriminate against, or
grant preferential treatment to, any individual or group on the
basis of race, sex, color, ethnicity, or national origin in the
operation of public employment, public
education, or public contracting.
“(2) The state
shall not discriminate against, or grant preferential treatment to,
any individual or group on the basis of race, sex, color,
ethnicity, or national origin in the operation of public
employment, public education, or public contracting.
“(3) For the
purposes of this section ‘state’ includes, but is not
necessarily limited to, the state itself, any city, county, any
public college, university, or community college, school district,
or other political subdivision or governmental instrumentality of
or within the State of Michigan not included in sub-section
1.”
Section 26 was
challenged in two cases. Among the plaintiffs in the suits were the
Coalition to Defend Affirmative Action, Integration and Immigrant
Rights and Fight for Equality By Any Means Necessary (BAMN);
students; faculty; and prospective applicants to Michigan public
universities. The named defendants included then-Governor Jennifer
Granholm, the Board of Regents of the University of Michigan, the
Board of Trustees of Michigan State University, and the Board of
Governors of Wayne State University. The Michigan Attorney General
was granted leave to intervene as a defendant. The United States
District Court for the Eastern District of Michigan consolidated
the cases.
In 2008, the District
Court granted summary judgment to Michigan, thus upholding Proposal
2. BAMN v. Regents of Univ. of Mich., 539 F. Supp. 2d 924. The
District Court denied a motion to reconsider the grant of summary
judgment. 592 F. Supp. 2d 948. A panel of the United States
Court of Appeals for the Sixth Circuit reversed the grant of
summary judgment. 652 F. 3d 607 (2011). Judge Gibbons dissented
from that holding. Id., at 633–646. The panel majority held
that Proposal 2 had violated the principles elaborated by this
Court in Washington v. Seattle School Dist. No. 1, 458 U. S. 457
(1982) , and in the cases that Seattle relied upon.
The Court of Appeals,
sitting en banc, agreed with the panel decision. 701 F. 3d 466 (CA6
2012). The majority opinion determined that Seattle “mirrors
the [case] before us.” Id., at 475. Seven judges dissented in
a number of opinions. The Court granted certiorari. 568 U. S.
___ (2013).
Before the Court
addresses the question presented, it is important to note what this
case is not about. It is not about the constitutionality, or the
merits, of race-conscious admissions policies in higher education.
The consideration of race in admissions presents complex questions,
in part addressed last Term in Fisher v. University of Texas at
Austin, 570 U. S. ––– (2013). In Fisher, the
Court did not disturb the principle that the consideration of race
in admissions is permissible, provided that certain conditions are
met. In this case, as in Fisher, that principle is not challenged.
The question here concerns not the permissibility of race-conscious
admissions policies under the Constitution but whether, and in what
manner, voters in the States may choose to prohibit the
consideration of racial preferences in governmental decisions, in
particular with respect to school admissions.
This Court has noted
that some States have decided to prohibit race-conscious admissions
policies. In Grutter, the Court noted: “Universities in
California, Florida, and Washington State, where racial preferences
in admissions are prohibited by state law, are currently engaged in
experimenting with a wide variety of alternative approaches.
Universities in other States can and should draw on the most
promising aspects of these race-neutral alternatives as they
develop.” 539 U. S., at 342 (citing United States v. Lopez,
514 U. S. 549, 581 (1995) (Kennedy, J., concurring) (“[T]he
States may perform their role as laboratories for experimentation
to devise various solutions where the best solution is far from
clear”)). In this way, Grutter acknowledged the significance
of a dialogue regarding this contested and complex policy question
among and within States. There was recognition that our federal
structure “permits ‘ innovation and
experimentation’ ” and “enables greater
citizen ‘ involvement in democratic
processes.’ ” Bond v. United States, 564 U. S.
–––, ––– (2011) (slip op., at
9) (quoting Gregory v. Ashcroft, 501 U. S. 452, 458 (1991) ).
While this case arises in Michigan, the decision by the
State’s voters reflects in part the national dialogue
regarding the wisdom and practicality of race-conscious admissions
policies in higher education. See, e.g., Coalition for Economic
Equity v. Wilson, 122 F. 3d 692 (CA9 1997).
In Michigan, the State
Constitution invests independent boards of trustees with plenary
authority over public universities, including admissions policies.
Mich. Const., Art. VIII, §5; see also Federated Publications,
Inc. v. Board of Trustees of Mich. State Univ., 460 Mich. 75,
86–87, 594 N. W. 2d 491, 497 (1999). Although the members of
the boards are elected, some evidence in the record suggests they
delegated authority over admissions policy to the faculty. But
whether the boards or the faculty set the specific policy,
Michigan’s public universities did consider race as a factor
in admissions decisions before 2006.
In holding §26
invalid in the context of student admissions at state universities,
the Court of Appeals relied in primary part on Seattle, supra,
which it deemed to control the case. But that determination extends
Seattle’s holding in a case presenting quite different issues
to reach a conclusion that is mistaken here. Before explaining this
further, it is necessary to consider the relevant cases that
preceded Seattle and the background against which Seattle itself
arose.
Though it has not been
prominent in the arguments of the parties, this Court’s
decision in Reitman v. Mulkey, 387 U. S. 369 (1967) , is a proper
beginning point for discussing the controlling decisions. In
Mulkey, voters amended the California Constitution to prohibit any
state legislative interference with an owner’s prerogative to
decline to sell or rent residential property on any basis. Two
different cases gave rise to Mulkey. In one a couple could not rent
an apartment, and in the other a couple were evicted from their
apartment. Those adverse actions were on account of race. In both
cases the complaining parties were barred, on account of race, from
invoking the protection of California’s statutes; and, as a
result, they were unable to lease residential property. This Court
concluded that the state constitutional provision was a denial of
equal protection. The Court agreed with the California Supreme
Court that the amendment operated to insinuate the State into the
decision to discriminate by encouraging that practice. The Court
noted the “immediate design and intent” of the
amendment was to “establis[h] a purported constitutional
right to privately discriminate.” Id., at 374 (internal
quotation marks omitted and emphasis deleted). The Court agreed
that the amendment “expressly authorized and
constitutionalized the private right to discriminate.” Id.,
at 376. The effect of the state constitutional amendment was to
“significantly encourage and involve the State in private
racial discriminations.” Id., at 381. In a dissent joined by
three other Justices, Justice Harlan disagreed with the
majority’s holding. Id., at 387. The dissent reasoned that
California, by the action of its voters, simply wanted the State to
remain neutral in this area, so that the State was not a party to
discrimination. Id., at 389. That dissenting voice did not prevail
against the majority’s conclusion that the state action in
question encouraged discrimination, causing real and specific
injury.
The next precedent of
relevance, Hunter v. Erickson, 393 U. S. 385 (1969) , is central to
the arguments the respondents make in the instant case. In Hunter,
the Court for the first time elaborated what the Court of Appeals
here styled the “political process” doctrine. There,
the Akron City Council found that the citizens of Akron consisted
of “ ‘people of different race[s], . . . many of
whom live in circumscribed and segregated areas, under sub-standard
unhealthful, unsafe, unsanitary and overcrowded conditions, because
of discrimination in the sale, lease, rental and financing of
housing.’ ” Id., at 391. To address the problem,
Akron enacted a fair housing ordinance to prohibit that sort of
discrimination. In response, voters amended the city charter to
overturn the ordinance and to require that any additional
antidiscrimination housing ordinance be approved by referendum. But
most other ordinances “regulating the real property
market” were not subject to those threshold requirements.
Id., at 390. The plaintiff, a black woman in Akron, Ohio, alleged
that her real estate agent could not show her certain residences
because the owners had specified they would not sell to black
persons.
Central to the
Court’s reasoning in Hunter was that the charter amendment
was enacted in circumstances where widespread racial discrimination
in the sale and rental of housing led to segregated housing,
forcing many to live in “ ‘unhealthful, unsafe,
unsanitary and overcrowded conditions.’ ” Id., at
391. The Court stated: “It is against this background that
the referendum required by [the charter amendment] must be
assessed.” Ibid. Akron attempted to characterize the charter
amendment “simply as a public decision to move slowly in the
delicate area of race relations” and as a means “to
allow the people of Akron to participate” in the decision.
Id., at 392. The Court rejected Akron’s flawed
“justifications for its discrimination,”justifications
that by their own terms had the effect of acknowledging the
targeted nature of the charter amendment. Ibid. The Court noted,
furthermore, that the charter amendment was unnecessary as a
general means of public control over the city council; for the
people of Akron already were empowered to overturn ordinances by
referendum. Id., at 390, n. 6. The Court found that the city
charter amendment, by singling out antidiscrimination ordinances,
“places special burden on racial minorities within the
governmental process,” thus becoming as impermissible as any
other government action taken with the invidious intent to injure a
racial minority. Id., at 391. Justice Harlan filed a concurrence.
He argued the city charter amendment “has the clear purpose
of making it more difficult for certain racial and religious
minorities to achieve legislation that is in their interest.”
Id., at 395. But without regard to the sentence just quoted, Hunter
rests on the unremarkable principle that the State may not alter
the procedures of government to target racial minorities. The facts
in Hunter established that invidious discrimination would be the
necessary result of the procedural restructuring. Thus, in Mulkey
and Hunter, there was a demonstrated injury on the basis of race
that, by reasons of state encouragement or participation, became
more aggravated.
Seattle is the third
case of principal relevance here. There, the school board adopted a
mandatory busing program to alleviate racial isolation of minority
students in local schools. Voters who opposed the school
board’s busing plan passed a state initiative that barred
busing to desegregate. The Court first determined that, although
“white as well as Negro children benefit from”
diversity, the school board’s plan “inures primarily to
the benefit of the minority.” 458 U. S., at 472. The Court
next found that “the practical effect” of the state
initiative was to “remov[e] the authority to address a racial
problem—and only a racial problem—from the existing
decisionmaking body, in such a way as to burden minority
interests” because advocates of busing “now must seek
relief from the state legislature, or from the statewide
electorate.” Id., at 474. The Court therefore found that the
initiative had “explicitly us[ed] the racial nature of a
decision to determine the decisionmaking process.” Id., at
470 (emphasis deleted).
Seattle is best
understood as a case in which the state action in question (the bar
on busing enacted by the State’s voters) had the serious
risk, if not purpose, of causing specific injuries on account of
race, just as had been the case in Mulkey and Hunter. Although
there had been no judicial finding of de jure segregation with
respect to Seattle’s school district, it appears as though
school segregation in the district in the 1940’s and
1950’s may have been the partial result of school board
policies that “permitted white students to transfer out of
black schools while restricting the transfer of black students into
white schools.” Parents Involved in Community Schools v.
Seattle School Dist. No. 1, 551 U. S. 701 –808 (2007)
(Breyer, J., dissenting). In 1977, the National Association for the
Advancement of Colored People (NAACP) filed a complaint with the
Office for Civil Rights, a federal agency. The NAACP alleged that
the school board had maintained a system of de jure segregation.
Specifically, the complaint alleged “that the Seattle School
Board had created or perpetuated unlawful racial segregation
through, e.g., certain school-transfer criteria, a construction
program that needlessly built new schools in white areas, district
line-drawing criteria, the maintenance of inferior facilities at
black schools, the use of explicit racial criteria in the
assignment of teachers and other staff, and a general pattern of
delay in respect to the implementation of promised desegregation
efforts.” Id., at 810. As part of a settlement with the
Office for Civil Rights, the school board implemented the
“Seattle Plan,” which used busing and mandatory
reassignments between elementary schools to reduce racial imbalance
and which was the subject of the state initiative at issue in
Seattle. See 551 U. S., at 807–812.
As this Court held in
Parents Involved, the school board’s purported remedial
action would not be permissible today absent a showing of de jure
segregation. Id., at 720–721. That holding prompted Justice
Breyer to observe in dissent, as noted above, that one permissible
reading of the record was that the school board had maintained
policies to perpetuate racial segregation in the schools. In all
events we must understand Seattle as Seattle understood itself, as
a case in which neither the State nor the United States
“challenge[d] the propriety of race-conscious student
assignments for the purpose of achieving integration, even absent a
finding of prior de jure segregation.” 458 U. S. at
472, n. 15. In other words the legitimacy and
constitutionality of the remedy in question (busing for
desegregation) was assumed, and Seattle must be understood on that
basis. Ibid. Seattle involved a state initiative that “was
carefully tailored to interfere only with desegregative
busing.” Id., at 471. The Seattle Court, accepting the
validity of the school board’s busing remedy as a predicate
to its analysis of the constitutional question, found that the
State’s disapproval of the school board’s busing remedy
was an aggravation of the very racial injury in which the State
itself was complicit.
The broad language used
in Seattle, however, went well beyond the analysis needed to
resolve the case. The Court there seized upon the statement in
Justice Harlan’s concurrence in Hunter that the procedural
change in that case had “the clear purpose of making it more
difficult for certain racial and religious minorities to achieve
legislation that is in their interest.” 385 U. S., at
395. That language, taken in the context of the facts in Hunter, is
best read simply to describe the necessity for finding an equal
protection violation where specific injuries from hostile
discrimination were at issue. The Seattle Court, however, used the
language from the Hunter concurrence to establish a new and
far-reaching rationale. Seattle stated that where a government
policy “inures primarily to the benefit of the
minority” and “minorities . . . con-sider” the
policy to be “ ‘in their
interest,’ ” then any state action that
“place[s] effective decisionmaking authority over” that
policy “at a different level of government” must be
reviewed under strict scrutiny. 458 U. S., at 472, 474. In
essence, according to the broad reading of Seattle, any state
action with a “racial focus” that makes it “more
difficult for certain racial minorities than for other
groups” to “achieve legislation that is in their
interest” is subject to strict scrutiny. It is this reading
of Seattle that the Court of Appeals found to be controlling here.
And that reading must be rejected.
The broad rationale
that the Court of Appeals adopted goes beyond the necessary holding
and the meaning of the precedents said to support it; and in the
instant case neither the formulation of the general rule just set
forth nor the precedents cited to authenticate it suffice to
invalidate Proposal 2. The expansive reading of Seattle has no
principled limitation and raises serious questions of compatibility
with the Court’s settled equal protection jurisprudence. To
the extent Seattle is read to require the Court to determine and
declare which political policies serve the “interest”
of a group defined in racial terms, that rationale was unnecessary
to the decision in Seattle; it has no support in precedent; and it
raises serious constitu-tional concerns. That expansive language
does not provide a proper guide for decisions and should not be
deemed authoritative or controlling. The rule that the Court of
Appeals elaborated and respondents seek to establish here would
contradict central equal protection principles.
In cautioning against
“impermissible racial stereotypes,” this Court has
rejected the assumption that “members of the same racial
group—regardless of their age, education, economic status, or
the community in which they live—think alike, share the same
political interests, and will prefer the same candidates at the
polls.” Shaw v. Reno, 509 U. S. 630, 647 (1993) ; see also
Metro Broadcasting, Inc. v. FCC, 497 U. S. 547, 636 (1990)
(Kennedy, J., dissenting) (rejecting the “demeaning notion
that members of . . . defined racial groups ascribe to certain
‘minority views’ that must be different from those of
other citizens”). It cannot be entertained as a serious
proposition that all individuals of the same race think alike. Yet
that proposition would be a necessary beginning point were the
Seattle formulation to control, as the Court of Appeals held it did
in this case. And if it were deemed necessary to probe how some
races define their own interest in political matters, still another
beginning point would be to define individuals according to race.
But in a society in which those lines are becoming more blurred,
the attempt to define race-based categories also raises serious
questions of its own. Government action that classifies individuals
on the basis of race is inherently suspect and carries the danger
of perpetuating the very racial divisions the polity seeks to
transcend. Cf. Ho v. San Francisco Unified School Dist., 147
F. 3d 854, 858 (CA9 1998) (school district delineating 13
racial categories for purposes of racial balancing). Were courts to
embark upon this venture not only would it be undertaken with no
clear legal standards or accepted sources to guide judicial
decision but also it would result in, or at least impose a high
risk of, inquiries and categories dependent upon demeaning
stereotypes, classifications of questionable constitutionality on
their own terms.
Even assuming these
initial steps could be taken in a manner consistent with a sound
analytic and judicial framework, the court would next be required
to determine the policy realms in which certain groups—groups
defined by race—have a political interest. That undertaking,
again without guidance from any accepted legal standards, would
risk, in turn, the creation of incentives for those who support or
oppose certain policies to cast the debate in terms of racial
advantage or disadvantage. Thus could racial antagonisms and
conflict tend to arise in the context of judicial decisions as
courts undertook to announce what particular issues of public
policy should be classified as advantageous to some group defined
by race. This risk is inherent in adopting the Seattle
formulation.
There would be no
apparent limiting standards defining what public policies should be
included in what Seattle called policies that “inur[e]
primarily to the benefit of the minority” and that
“minorities . . . consider” to be
“ ‘in their interest.’ ” 458
U. S., at 472, 474. Those who seek to represent the interests
of particular racial groups could attempt to advance those aims by
demanding an equal protection ruling that any number of matters be
foreclosed from voter review or participation. In a nation in which
governmental policies are wide ranging, those who seek to limit
voter participation might be tempted, were this Court to adopt the
Seattle formulation, to urge that a group they choose to define by
race or racial stereotypes are advantaged or disadvantaged by any
number of laws or decisions. Tax policy, housing subsidies, wage
regulations, and even the naming of public schools, highways, and
monuments are just a few examples of what could become a list of
subjects that some organizations could insist should be beyond the
power of voters to decide, or beyond the power of a legislature to
decide when enacting limits on the power of local authorities or
other governmental entities to address certain subjects. Racial
division would be validated, not discouraged, were the Seattle
formulation, and the reasoning of the Court of Appeals in this
case, to remain in force.
Perhaps, when enacting
policies as an exercise of democratic self-government, voters will
determine that race-based preferences should be adopted. The
constitutional validity of some of those choices regarding racial
preferences is not at issue here. The holding in the instant case
is simply that the courts may not disempower the voters from
choosing which path to follow. In the realm of policy discussions
the regular give-and-take of debate ought to be a context in which
rancor or discord based on race are avoided, not invited. And if
these factors are to be interjected, surely it ought not to be at
the invitation or insistence of the courts.
One response to these
concerns may be that objections to the larger consequences of the
Seattle formulation need not be confronted in this case, for here
race was an undoubted subject of the ballot issue. But a number of
problems raised by Seattle, such as racial definitions, still
apply. And this principal flaw in the ruling of the Court of
Appeals does remain: Here there was no infliction of a specific
injury of the kind at issue in Mulkey and Hunter and in the history
of the Seattle schools. Here there is no precedent for extending
these cases to restrict the right of Michigan voters to determine
that race-based preferences granted by Michigan governmental
entities should be ended.
It should also be noted
that the judgment of the Court of Appeals in this case of necessity
calls into question other long-settled rulings on similar state
policies. The California Supreme Court has held that a California
constitutional amendment prohibiting racial preferences in public
contracting does not violate the rule set down by Seattle. Coral
Constr., Inc. v. City and County of San Francisco, 50 Cal. 4th 315,
235 P. 3d 947 (2010). The Court of Appeals for the Ninth
Circuit has held that the same amendment, which also barred racial
preferences in public education, does not violate the Equal
Protection Clause. Wilson, 122 F. 3d 692 (1997). If the Court were
to affirm the essential rationale of the Court of Appeals in the
instant case, those holdings would be invalidated, or at least
would be put in serious question. The Court, by affirming the
judgment now before it, in essence would announce a finding that
the past 15 years of state public debate on this issue have been
improper. And were the argument made that Coral might still stand
because it involved racial preferences in public contracting while
this case concerns racial preferences in university admissions, the
implication would be that the constitutionality of laws forbidding
racial preferences depends on the policy interest at stake, the
concern that, as already explained, the voters deem it wise to
avoid because of its divisive potential. The instant case presents
the question involved in Coral and Wilson but not involved in
Mulkey, Hunter, and Seattle. That question is not how to address or
prevent injury caused on account of race but whether voters may
determine whether a policy of race-based preferences should be
continued.
By approving Proposal 2
and thereby adding §26 to their State Constitution, the
Michigan voters exercised their privilege to enact laws as a basic
exercise of their democratic power. In the federal system States
“respond, through the enactment of positive law, to the
initiative of those who seek a voice in shaping the destiny of
their own times.” Bond, 564 U. S., at –––
(slip op., at 9). Michigan voters used the initiative system to
bypass public officials who were deemed not responsive to the
concerns of a majority of the voters with respect to a policy of
granting race-based preferences that raises difficult and delicate
issues.
The freedom secured by
the Constitution consists, in one of its essential dimensions, of
the right of the individual not to be injured by the unlawful
exercise of governmental power. The mandate for segregated schools,
Brown v. Board of Education, 347 U. S. 483 (1954) ; a wrongful
invasion of the home, Silverman v. United States, 365 U. S.
505 (1961) ; or punishing a protester whose views offend others,
Texas v. Johnson, 491 U. S. 397 (1989) ; and scores of other
examples teach that individual liberty has constitutional
protection, and that liberty’s full extent and meaning may
remain yet to be discovered and affirmed. Yet freedom does not stop
with individual rights. Our constitutional system embraces, too,
the right of citizens to debate so they can learn and decide and
then, through the political process, act in concert to try to shape
the course of their own times and the course of a nation that must
strive always to make freedom ever greater and more secure. Here
Michigan voters acted in concert and statewide to seek consensus
and adopt a policy on a difficult subject against a historical
background of race in America that has been a source of tragedy and
persisting injustice. That history demands that we continue to
learn, to listen, and to remain open to new approaches if we are to
aspire always to a constitutional order in which all persons are
treated with fairness and equal dignity. Were the Court to rule
that the question addressed by Michigan voters is too sensitive or
complex to be within the grasp of the electorate; or that the
policies at issue remain too delicate to be resolved save by
university officials or faculties, acting at some remove from
immediate public scru-tiny and control; or that these matters are
so arcane that the electorate’s power must be limited because
the people cannot prudently exercise that power even after a full
debate, that holding would be an unprecedented restriction on the
exercise of a fundamental right held not just by one person but by
all in common. It is the right to speak and debate and learn and
then, as a matter of political will, to act through a lawful
electoral process.
The respondents in this
case insist that a difficult question of public policy must be
taken from the reach of the voters, and thus removed from the realm
of public discussion, dialogue, and debate in an election campaign.
Quite in addition to the serious First Amendment implications of
that position with respect to any particular election, it is
inconsistent with the underlying premises of a responsible,
functioning democracy. One of those premises is that a democracy
has the capacity—and the duty—to learn from its past
mistakes; to discover and confront persisting biases; and by
respectful, rationale deliberation to rise above those flaws and
injustices. That process is impeded, not advanced, by court decrees
based on the proposition that the public cannot have the requisite
repose to discuss certain issues. It is demeaning to the democratic
process to presume that the voters are not capable of deciding an
issue of this sensitivity on decent and rational grounds. The
process of public discourse and political debate should not be
foreclosed even if there is a risk that during a public campaign
there will be those, on both sides, who seek to use racial division
and discord to their own political advantage. An informed public
can, and must, rise above this. The idea of democracy is that it
can, and must, mature. Freedom embraces the right, indeed the duty,
to engage in a rational, civic discourse in order to determine how
best to form a consensus to shape the destiny of the Nation and its
people. These First Amendment dynamics would be disserved if this
Court were to say that the question here at issue is beyond the
capacity of the voters to debate and then to determine.
These precepts are not
inconsistent with the well-established principle that when hurt or
injury is inflicted on racial minorities by the encouragement or
command of laws or other state action, the Constitution requires
redress by the courts. Cf. Johnson v. California, 543 U. S.
499 –512 (2005) (“[S]earching judicial review
. . . is necessary to guard against invidious
discrimination”); Edmonson v. Leesville Concrete Co., 500
U. S. 614, 619 (1991) (“Racial discrimination” is
“invidious in all contexts”). As already noted, those
were the circumstances that the Court found present in Mulkey,
Hunter, and Seattle. But those circumstances are not present
here.
For reasons already
discussed, Mulkey, Hunter, and Seattle are not precedents that
stand for the conclusion that Michigan’s voters must be
disempowered from acting. Those cases were ones in which the
political restriction in question was designed to be used, or was
likely to be used, to encourage infliction of injury by reason of
race. What is at stake here is not whether injury will be inflicted
but whether government can be instructed not to follow a course
that entails, first, the definition of racial categories and,
second, the grant of favored status to persons in some racial
categories and not others. The electorate’s instruction to
governmental entities not to embark upon the course of race-defined
and race-based preferences was adopted, we must assume, because the
voters deemed a preference system to be unwise, on account of what
voters may deem its latent potential to become itself a source of
the very resentments and hostilities based on race that this Nation
seeks to put behind it. Whether those adverse results would follow
is, and should be, the subject of debate. Voters might likewise
consider, after debate and reflection, that programs designed to
increase diversity—consistent with the Constitution—are
a necessary part of progress to transcend the stigma of past
racism.
This case is not about
how the debate about racial preferences should be resolved. It is
about who may resolve it. There is no authority in the Constitution
of the United States or in this Court’s precedents for the
Judiciary to set aside Michigan laws that commit this policy
determination to the voters. See Sailors v. Board of Ed. of County
of Kent, 387 U. S. 105, 109 (1967) (“Save and unless the
state, county, or municipal government runs afoul of a federally
protected right, it has vast leeway in the management of its
internal affairs”). Deliberative debate on sensitive issues
such as racial preferences all too often may shade into rancor. But
that does not justify removing certain court-determined issues from
the voters’ reach. Democracy does not presume that some
subjects are either too divisive or too profound for public
debate.
The judgment of the
Court of Appeals for the Sixth Circuit is reversed.
It is so ordered.
Justice Kagan took no
part in the consideration or decision of this case. SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES
_________________
No. 12–682
_________________
BILL SCHUETTE, ATTORNEY GENERAL OF MICHI-GAN,
PETITIONER v. COALITION TO DEFEND AF-FIRMATIVE ACTION, INTEGRATION
AND IMMI-GRANT RIGHTS AND FIGHT FOR EQUALITYBY ANY MEANS NECESSARY
(BAMN), et al.
on writ of certiorari to the united states
court of appeals for the sixth circuit
[April 22, 2014]
Justice Breyer,
concurring in the judgment.
Michigan has amended
its Constitution to forbid state universities and colleges to
“discriminate against, or grant preferential treatment to,
any individual or group on the basis of race, sex, color,
ethnicity, or national origin in the operation of public
employment, public education, or public contracting.” Mich.
Const., Art. I, §26. We here focus on the prohibition of
“grant[ing] . . . preferential treatment
. . . on the basis of race . . . in
. . . public education.” I agree with the plurality
that the amendment is consistent with the Federal Equal Protection
Clause. U. S. Const., Amdt. 14. But I believe this for
different reasons.
First, we do not
address the amendment insofar as it forbids the use of
race-conscious admissions programs designed to remedy past
exclusionary racial discrimination or the direct effects of that
discrimination. Application of the amendment in that context would
present different questions which may demand different answers.
Rather, we here address the amendment only as it applies to, and
forbids, programs that, as in Grutter v. Bollinger, 539 U. S.
306 (2003) , rest upon “one justification”: using
“race in the admissions process” solely in order to
“obtai[n] the educational benefits that flow from a diverse
student body,” id., at 328 (internal quotation marks
omitted).
Second, dissenting in
Parents Involved in Community Schools v. Seattle School Dist. No.
1, 551 U. S. 701 (2007) , I explained why I believe
race-conscious programs of this kind are constitutional, whether
implemented by law schools, universities, high schools, or
elementary schools. I concluded that the Constitution does not
“authorize judges” either to forbid or to require the
adoption of diversity-seeking race-conscious
“solutions” (of the kind at issue here) to such serious
problems as “how best to administer America’s
schools” to help “create a society that includes all
Americans.” Id., at 862.
I continue to believe
that the Constitution permits, though it does not require, the use
of the kind of race-conscious programs that are now barred by the
Michigan Constitution. The serious educational problems that faced
Americans at the time this Court decided Grutter endure. See, e.g.,
I. Mullis, M. Martin, P. Foy, & K. Drucker,Progress in
International Reading Literacy Study, 2011 International Results in
Reading 38, Exh. 1.1 (2012)(elementary-school students in numerous
other countries outperform their counterparts in the United States
in reading); I. Mullis, M. Martin, P. Foy, & A. Arora, Trends
in International Mathematics and Science Study (TIMSS), 2011
International Results in Mathematics 40, Exh. 1.1 (2012) (same in
mathematics); M. Martin, I. Mullis, P. Foy, & G. Stanco, TIMSS,
2011 International Results in Science, 38, Exh. 1.1 (2012) (same in
science); Organisation of Economic Co-operation Development (OECD),
Education at a Glance 2013: OECD Indicators 50 (Table A2.1a)
(secondary-school graduation rate lower in the United States than
in numerous other countries); McKinsey & Co., The Economic
Impact of the Achievement Gap in America’s Schools 8 (Apr.
2009) (same; United States ranks 18th of 24 industrialized
nations). And low educational achievement continues to be
correlated with income and race. See, e.g., National Center for
Education Statistics, Digest of Education Statistics, Advance
Release of Selected 2013 Digest Tables (Table 104.20) (White
Americans more likely to have completed high school
thanAfrican-Americans or Hispanic-Americans), online at
http://nces.ed.gov/programs/digest (as visited Apr. 15, 2014, and
available in Clerk of Court’s case file); id., Table 219.75
(Americans in bottom quartile of income most likely to drop out of
high school); id., Table 302.60 (White Americans more likely to
enroll in college than African-Americans or Hispanic-Americans);
id., Table 302.30 (middle- and high-income Americans more likely to
enroll in college than low-income Americans).
The Constitution allows
local, state, and national communities to adopt narrowly tailored
race-conscious programs designed to bring about greater inclusion
and diversity. But the Constitution foresees the ballot box, not
the courts, as the normal instrument for resolving differences and
debates about the merits of these programs. Compare Parents
Involved, 551 U. S., at 839 (Breyer, J., dissenting)
(identifying studies showing the benefits of racially integrated
education), with id., at 761–763 (Thomas, J., concurring)
(identifying studies suggesting racially integrated schools may not
confer educational benefits). In short, the “Constitution
creates a democratic political system through which the people
themselves must together find answers” to disagreements of
this kind. Id., at 862 (Breyer, J., dissenting).
Third, cases such as
Hunter v. Erickson, 393 U. S. 385 (1969) , and Washington v.
Seattle School Dist. No. 1, 458 U. S. 457 (1982) , reflect an
important principle, namely, that an individual’s ability to
participate meaningfully in the political process should be
independent of his race. Although racial minorities, like other
political minorities, will not always succeed at the polls, they
must have the same opportunity as others to secure through the
ballot box policies that reflect their preferences. In my view,
however, neither Hunter nor Seattle applies here. And the parties
do not here suggest that the amendment violates the Equal
Protection Clause if not under the Hunter-Seattle doctrine.
Hunter and Seattle
involved efforts to manipulate the political process in a way not
here at issue. Both cases involved a restructuring of the political
process that changed the political level at which policies were
enacted. In Hunter, decisionmaking was moved from the elected city
council to the local electorate at large. 393 U. S., at
389–390. And in Seattle, decisionmaking by an elected school
board was replaced with decisionmaking by the state legislature and
electorate at large. 458 U. S., at 466.
This case, in contrast,
does not involve a reordering of the political process; it does not
in fact involve the movement of decisionmaking from one political
level to another. Rather, here, Michigan law delegated broad
policymaking authority to elected university boards, see Mich.
Const., Art. VIII, §5, but those boards delegated
admissions-related decisionmaking authority to unelected university
faculty members and administrators, see, e.g., Bylaws of Univ. of
Mich. Bd. of Regents §8.01; Mich. State Univ. Bylaws of Bd. of
Trustees, Preamble; Mich. State Univ. Bylaws for Academic
Governance §4.4.3; Wayne State Univ. Stat.
§§2–34–09, 2–34–12. Although the
boards unquestionably retained the power to set policy regarding
race-conscious admissions, see post, at 25–29 (Sotomayor, J.,
dissenting), in fact faculty members and administrators set the
race-conscious admissions policies in question. (It is often true
that elected bodies—including, for example, school boards,
city councils, and state legislatures—have the power to enact
policies, but in fact delegate that power to administrators.)
Although at limited times the university boards were advised of the
content of their race-conscious admissions policies, see 701
F. 3d 466, 481–482 (CA6 2012), to my knowledge no board
voted to accept or reject any of those policies. Thus, un-elected
faculty members and administrators, not voters or their elected
representatives, adopted the race-conscious admissions programs
affected by Michigan’s constitutional amendment. The
amendment took decisionmaking authority away from these unelected
actors and placed it in the hands of the voters.
Why does this matter?
For one thing, considered conceptually, the doctrine set forth in
Hunter and Seattle does not easily fit this case. In those cases
minorities had participated in the political process and they had
won. The majority’s subsequent reordering of the political
process repealed the minority’s successes and made it more
difficult for the minority to succeed in the future. The majority
thereby diminished the minority’s ability to participate
meaningfully in the electoral process. But one cannot as easily
characterize the movement of the decisionmaking mechanism at issue
here—from an administrative process to an electoral
process—as diminishing the minority’s ability to
participate meaningfully in the political process. There is no
prior electoral process in which the minority participated.
For another thing, to
extend the holding of Hunter and Seattle to reach situations in
which decisionmaking authority is moved from an administrative body
to a political one would pose significant difficulties. The
administrative process encompasses vast numbers of decisionmakers
answering numerous policy questions in hosts of different fields.
See Free Enterprise Fund v. Public Company Accounting Oversight
Bd., 561 U. S. 477 , ___ (2010) (Breyer, J., dissenting).
Administrative bodies modify programs in detail, and decisionmaking
authority within the administrative process frequently moves
around—due to amendments to statutes, new administrative
rules, and evolving agency practice. It is thus particularly
difficult in this context for judges to determine when a change in
the locus of decisionmaking authority places a comparative
structural burden on a racial minority. And to apply Hunter and
Seattle to the administrative process would, by tending to hinder
change, risk discouraging experimentation, interfering with efforts
to see when and how race-conscious policies work.
Finally, the principle
that underlies Hunter and Seattle runs up against a competing
principle, discussed above. This competing principle favors
decisionmaking though the democratic process. Just as this
principle strongly supports the right of the people, or their
elected representatives, to adopt race-conscious policies for
reasons of inclusion, so must it give them the right to vote not to
do so.
As I have said, my
discussion here is limited to circumstances in which decisionmaking
is moved from an un-elected administrative body to a politically
responsive one, and in which the targeted race-conscious admissions
programs consider race solely in order to obtain the educational
benefits of a diverse student body. We need now decide no more than
whether the Federal Constitution permits Michigan to apply its
constitutional amendment in those circumstances. I would hold that
it does. Therefore, I concur in the judgment of the Court. SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES
_________________
No. 12–682
_________________
BILL SCHUETTE, ATTORNEY GENERAL OF MICHI-GAN,
PETITIONER v. COALITION TO DEFEND AF-FIRMATIVE ACTION, INTEGRATION
AND IMMI-GRANT RIGHTS AND FIGHT FOR EQUALITYBY ANY MEANS NECESSARY
(BAMN), et al.
on writ of certiorari to the united states
court of appeals for the sixth circuit
[April 22, 2014]
Justice Scalia, with
whom Justice Thomas joins, concurring in the judgment.
It has come to this.
Called upon to explore the jurisprudential twilight zone between
two errant lines of precedent, we confront a frighteningly bizarre
question: Does the Equal Protection Clause of the Fourteenth
Amendment forbid what its text plainly requires? Needless to say
(except that this case obliges us to say it), the question answers
itself. “The Constitution proscribes government
discrimination on the basis of race, and state-provided education
is no exception.” Grutter v. Bollinger, 539 U. S. 306,
349 (2003) (Scalia, J., concurring in part and dissenting in part).
It is precisely this understanding—the correct
understanding—of the federal Equal Protection Clause that the
people of the State of Michigan have adopted for their own
fundamental law. By adopting it, they did not simultaneously offend
it.
Even taking this
Court’s sorry line of race-based-admissions cases as a given,
I find the question presented only slightly less strange: Does the
Equal Protection Clause forbid a State from banning a practice that
the Clause barely—and only provisionally—permits?
Reacting to those race-based-admissions decisions, some
States—whether deterred by the prospect of costly litigation;
aware that Grutter’s bell may soon toll, see 539 U. S.,
at 343; or simply opposed in principle to the notion of
“benign” racial discrimination—have gotten out of
the racial-preferences business altogether. And with our express
encouragement: “Universities in California, Flor-ida, and
Washington State, where racial preferences in admissions are
prohibited by state law, are currently engaging in experimenting
with a wide variety of alternative approaches. Universities in
other States can and should draw on the most promising aspects of
these race-neutral alternatives as they develop.” Id., at 342
(emphasis added). Respondents seem to think this admonition was
merely in jest.[ 1 ] The
experiment, they maintain, is not only over; it never rightly
began. Neither the people of the States nor their legislatures ever
had the option of directing subordinate public-university officials
to cease considering the race of applicants, since that would deny
members of those minority groups the option of enacting a policy
designed to further their interest, thus denying them the equal
protection of the laws. Never mind that it is hotly disputed
whether the practice of race-based admissions is ever in a racial
minority’s interest. Cf. id., at 371–373 (Thomas, J.,
concurring in part and dissenting in part). And never mind that,
were a public university to stake its defense of a
race-based-admissions policy on the ground that it was designed to
benefit primarily minorities (as opposed to all students,
regardless of color, by enhancing diversity), we would hold the
policy unconstitutional. See id., at 322–325.
But the battleground
for this case is not the constitutionality of race-based
admissions—at least, not quite. Rather, it is the so-called
political-process doctrine, derived from this Court’s
opinions in Washington v. Seattle School Dist. No. 1, 458
U. S. 457 (1982) , and Hunter v. Erickson, 393 U. S. 385
(1969) . I agree with those parts of the plurality opinion that
repudiate this doctrine. But I do not agree with its
reinterpretation of Seattle and Hunter, which makes them stand in
part for the cloudy and doctrinally anomalous proposition that
whenever state action poses “the serious risk . . .
of causing specific injuries on account of race,” it denies
equal protection. Ante, at 9. I would instead reaffirm that the
“ordinary principles of our law [and] of our democratic
heritage” require “plaintiffs alleging equal protection
violations” stemming from fa-cially neutral acts to
“prove intent and causation and not merely the existence of
racial disparity.” Freeman v. Pitts, 503 U. S. 467, 506
(1992) (Scalia, J., concurring) (citing Washington v. Davis, 426
U. S. 229 (1976) ). I would further hold that a law directing
state actors to provide equal protection is (to say the least)
facially neutral, and cannot violate the Constitution. Section 26
of the Michigan Constitution (formerly Proposal 2) rightly
stands.
I
A
The political-process
doctrine has its roots in two of our cases. The first is Hunter. In
1964, the Akron City Council passed a fair-housing ordinance
“ ‘assur[ing] equal opportunity to all persons to
live in decent housing facilities regardless of race, color,
religion, ancestry or national origin.’ ” 393 U.
S., at 386. Soon after, the city’s voters passed an amendment
to the Akron City Charter stating that any ordinance enacted by the
council that “ ‘regulates’ ”
commercial transactions in real property “ ‘on the
basis of race, color, religion, national origin or
ancestry’ ”—including the already enacted
1964 ordinance—“must first be approved by a majority of
the electors voting on the question” at a later referendum.
Id., at 387. The question was whether the charter amendment denied
equal protection. Answering yes, the Court explained that
“although the law on its face treats Negro and white, Jew and
gentile in an identical manner, the reality is that the law’s
impact falls on the minority. The majority needs no protection
against discrimination.” Id., at 391. By placing a
“special burden on racial minorities within the governmental
processes,” the amendment “disadvantage[d]” a
racial minority “by making it more difficult to enact
legislation in its behalf.” Id., at 391, 393.
The reasoning in
Seattle is of a piece. Resolving to “eliminate all [racial]
imbalance from the Seattle public schools,” the city school
board passed a mandatory busing and pupil-reassignment plan of the
sort typically imposed on districts guilty of de jure
segregation. 458 U. S., at 460–461. A year later, the
citizens of the State of Washington passed Initiative 350, which
directed (with exceptions) that “ ‘no school
. . . shall directly or indirectly require any student to
attend a school other than the school which is geographically
nearest or next nearest the student’s place of residence
. . . and which offers the course of study pursued by
such student,’ ” permitting only court-ordered
race-based busing. Id., at 462. The lower courts held Initiative
350 unconstitutional, and we affirmed, announcing in the prelude of
our analysis—as though it were beyond debate—that the
Equal Protection Clause forbade laws that “subtly distor[t]
governmental processes in such a way as to place special burdens on
the ability of minority groups to achieve beneficial
legislation.” Id., at 467.
The first question in
Seattle was whether the subject matter of Initiative 350 was a
“ ‘racial’ issue,” triggering Hunter
and its process doctrine. 458 U. S., at 471–472. It was
“undoubtedly. . . true” that whites and
blacks were “counted among both the supporters and the
opponents of Initiative 350.” Id., at 472. It was
“equally clear” that both white and black children
benefitted from desegre-gated schools. Ibid. Nonetheless, we
concluded that desegre-gation “inures primarily to the
benefit of the minority, and is designed for that purpose.”
Ibid. (emphasis added). In any event, it was “enough that
minorities may consider busing for integration to be
‘legislation that is in their interest.’ ”
Id., at 474 (quoting Hunter, supra, at 395 (Harlan, J.,
concurring)).
So we proceeded to the
heart of the political-process analysis. We held Initiative 350
unconstitutional, since it removed “the authority to address
a racial problem—and only a racial problem—from the
existing decisionmaking body, in such a way as to burden minority
interests.” Seattle, 458 U. S., at 474. Although school
boards in Washington retained authority over other
student-assignment issues and over most matters of educational
policy generally, under Initiative 350, minorities favoring
race-based busing would have to “surmount a considerably
higher hurdle” than the mere petitioning of a local assembly:
They “now must seek relief from the state legislature, or
from the statewide electorate,” a “different level of
government.” Ibid.
The relentless logic of
Hunter and Seattle would point to a similar conclusion in this
case. In those cases, one level of government exercised borrowed
authority over an apparently “racial issue,” until a
higher level of government called the loan. So too here. In those
cases, we deemed the revocation an equal-protection violation
regardless of whether it facially classified according to race or
reflected an invidious purpose to discriminate. Here, the Court of
Appeals did the same.
The plurality sees it
differently. Though it, too, dis-avows the
political-process-doctrine basis on which Hunter and Seattle were
decided, ante, at 10–14, it does not take the next step of
overruling those cases. Rather, it reinterprets them beyond
recognition. Hunter, the plurality suggests, was a case in which
the challenged act had “target[ed] racial minorities.”
Ante, at 8. Maybe, but the Hunter Court neither found that to be so
nor considered it relevant, bypassing the question of intent
entirely, satisfied that its newly minted political-process theory
sufficed to invalidate the charter amendment.
As for Seattle, what
was really going on, according to the plurality, was that
Initiative 350 had the consequence (if not the purpose) of
preserving the harms effected by prior de jure segregation.
Thus, “the political restriction in question was designed to
be used, or was likely to be used, to encourage infliction of
injury by reason of race.” Ante, at 17. That conclusion is
derived not from the opinion but from recently discovered evidence
that the city of Seattle had been a cause of its schools’
racial imbalance all along: “Although there had been no
judicial finding of de jure segregation with respect to
Seattle’s school district, it appears as though school
segregation in the district in the 1940’s and 1950’s
may have been the partial result of school board policies.”
Ante, at 9.[ 2 ] That the
district’s effort to end racial imbalance had been stymied by
Initiative 350 meant that the people, by passing it, somehow had
become complicit in Seattle’s equal-protection-denying status
quo, whether they knew it or not. Hence, therewas in Seattle a
government-furthered “infliction of a
specific”—and, presumably,
constitutional—“injury.” Ante, at 14.
Once again this
describes what our opinion in Seattle might have been, but
assuredly not what it was. The opinion assumes throughout that
Seattle’s schools suffered at most from de facto
segregation, see, e.g., 458 U. S., at 474, 475—that is,
segregation not the “product . . . of state action
but of private choices,” having no “constitutional
implications,” Freeman, 503 U. S., at 495–496. Nor
did it anywhere state that the current racial imbalance was the
(judicially remediable) effect of prior de jure segregation.
Absence of de jure segregation or the effects of de jure
segregation was a necessary premise of the Seattle opinion. That is
what made the issue of busing and pupil reassignment a matter of
political choice rather than judicial mandate.[ 3 ] And precisely because it was a question for the
political branches to decide, the manner—which is to say, the
process—of its resolution implicated the Court’s new
process theory. The opinion itself says this: “[I]n the
absence of a constitutional violation, the desirability and
efficacy of school desegregation are matters to be resolved though
the political process. For present purposes, it is enough [to hold
reallocation of that political decision to a higher level
unconstitutional] that minorities may consider busing for
integration to be legislation that is in their interest.” 458
U. S., at 474 (internal quotation marks omitted).
B
Patently atextual,
unadministrable, and contrary to our traditional equal-protection
jurisprudence, Hunter and Seattle should be overruled.
The problems with the
political-process doctrine begin with its triggering prong, which
assigns to a court the task of determining whether a law that
reallocates policy-making authority concerns a “racial
issue.” Seattle, 458 U. S., at 473. Seattle takes a
couple of dissatisfying cracks at defining this crucial term. It
suggests that an issue is racial if adopting one position on the
question would “at bottom inur[e] primarily to the benefit of
the minority, and is designed for that purpose.” Id., at 472.
It is irrelevant that, as in Hunter and Seattle, 458 U. S., at
472, both the racial minority and the racial majority benefit from
the policy in question, and members of both groups favor it. Judges
should instead focus their guesswork on their own juridical sense
of what is primarily for the benefit of minorities. Cf. ibid.
(regarding as dispositive what “our cases” suggest is
beneficial to minorities). On second thought, maybe judges need
only ask this question: Is it possible “that minorities may
consider” the policy in question to be “in their
interest”? Id., at 474. If so, you can be sure that you are
dealing with a “racial issue.”[ 4 ]
No good can come of
such random judicial musing. The plurality gives two convincing
reasons why. For one thing, it involves judges in the dirty
business of dividing the Nation “into racial blocs,”
Metro Broadcasting, Inc. v. FCC, 497 U. S. 547, 603, 610
(1990) (O’Connor, J., dissenting); ante, at 11–13. That
task is as difficult as it is unappealing. (Does a half-Latino,
half–American Indian have Latino interests, American-Indian
interests, both, half of both?[ 5 ]) What is worse, the exercise promotes the noxious
fiction that, knowing only a person’s color or ethnicity, we
can be sure that he has a predetermined set of policy
“interests,” thus “reinforc[ing] the perception
that members of the same racial group—regardless of their
age, education, economic status, or the community in which they
live—think alike, [and] share the same political
interests.”[ 6 ] Shaw v.
Reno, 509 U. S. 630, 647 (1993) . Whether done by a judge or a
school board, such “racial stereotyping [is] at odds with
equal protection mandates.” Miller v. Johnson, 515 U. S.
900, 920 (1995) .
But that is not the
“racial issue” prong’s only defect. More
fundamentally, it misreads the Equal Protection Clause to protect
“particular group[s],” a construction that we have
tirelessly repudiated in a “long line of casesunderstanding
equal protection as a personal right.” Adarand Constructors,
Inc. v. Peña, 515 U. S. 200, 224, 230 (1995) . It is a
“basic principle that the Fifth and Fourteenth Amendments to
the Constitution protect persons, not groups.” Id., at 227;
Metro Broadcasting, supra, at 636 (Kennedy, J.,
dissenting).[ 7 ] Yet Seattle
insists that only those political-process alterations that burden
racial minorities deny equal protection. “The
majority,” after all, “needs no protection against
discrimination.” 458 U. S., at 468 (quoting Hunter, 393
U. S., at 391). In the years since Seattle, we have repeatedly
rejected “a reading of the guarantee of equal protection
under which the level of scrutiny varies according to the ability
of different groups to defend their interests in the representative
process.” Richmond v. J. A. Croson Co., 488 U. S.
469, 495 (1989) . Meant to obliterate rather than endorse the
practice of racial classifications, the Fourteenth
Amendment’s guarantees “obtai[n] with equal force
regardless of ‘the race of those burdened or
benefitted.’ ” Miller, supra, at 904 (quoting
Croson, supra, at 494 (plurality opinion)); Adarand, supra, at 223,
227. The Equal Protection Clause “cannot mean one thing when
applied to one individual and something else when applied to a
person of another color. If both are not accorded the same
protection it is not equal.” Regents of Univ. of Cal. v.
Bakke, 438 U. S. 265 –290 (1978) (opinion of Powell,
J.).
The dissent trots out
the old saw, derived from dictum in a footnote, that legislation
motivated by “ ‘prejudice against discrete and
insular minorities’ ” merits
“ ‘more exacting judicial
scrutiny.’ ” Post, at 31 (quoting United States v.
Carolene Products, 304 U. S. 144 –153, n. 4). I say derived
from that dictum (expressed by the four-Justice majority of a
seven-Justice Court) because the dictum itself merely said
“[n]or need we enquire . . . whether prejudice
against discrete and insular minorities may be a special
condition,” id., at 153, n. 4 (emphasis added). The dissent
does not argue, of course, that such “prejudice”
produced §26. Nor does it explain why certain racial
minorities in Michigan qualify as
“ ‘insular,’ ” meaning that
“other groups will not form coalitions with them—and,
critically, not because of lack of common interests but because of
‘prejudice.’ ” Strauss, Is Carolene Products
Obsolete? 2010 U. Ill. L. Rev. 1251, 1257. Nor does it even make
the case that a group’s “discreteness” and
“insu-larity” are political liabilities rather than
political strengths[ 8 ]—a
serious question that alone demonstrates the prudence of the
Carolene Products dictumizers in leaving the
“enquir[y]” for another day. As for the question
whether “legislation which restricts those political
processes which can ordinarily be expected to bring about repeal of
undesirable legislation . . . is to be subjected to more
exacting judicial scrutiny,” the Carolene Products Court
found it “unnecessary to consider [that] now.” 304 U.
S., at 152, n. 4. If the dissent thinks that worth considering
today, it should explain why the election of a university’s
governing board is a “political process which can ordinarily
be expected to bring about repeal of undesirable
legislation,” but Michigan voters’ ability to amend
their Constitution is not. It seems to me quite the opposite.
Amending the Constitution requires the approval of only “a
majority of the electors voting on the question.” Mich.
Const., Art. XII, §2. By contrast, voting in a favorable board
(each of which has eight members) at the three major public
universities requires electing by majority vote at least 15
different candidates, several of whom would be running during
different election cycles. See BAMN v. Regents of Univ. of Mich.,
701 F. 3d 466, 508 (CA6 2012) (Sutton, J., dissenting). So if
Michigan voters, instead of amending their Constitution, had
pursued the dissent’s preferred path of electing board
members promising to “abolish race-sensitive admissions
policies,” post, at 3, it would have been harder, not easier,
for racial minorities favoring affirmative action to overturn that
decision. But the more important point is that we should not design
our jurisprudence to conform to dictum in a footnote in a
four-Justice opinion.
C
Moving from the
appalling to the absurd, I turn now to the second part of the
Hunter-Seattle analysis—which is apparently no more
administrable than the first, compare post, at 4–6 (Breyer,
J., concurring in judgment) (“This case . . . does
not involve a reordering of the political process”), with
post, at 25–29 (Sotomayor, J., dissenting) (yes, it does).
This part of the inquiry directs a court to determine whether the
challenged act “place[s] effective decisionmaking authority
over [the] racial issue at a different level of government.”
Seattle, 458 U. S., at 474. The laws in both Hunter and
Seattle were thought to fail this test. In both cases, “the
effect of the challengedaction was to redraw decisionmaking
authority over racial matters—and only over racial
matters—in such a way as to place comparative burdens on
minorities.” 458 U. S., at 475, n. 17. This, we
said, a State may not do.
By contrast, in another
line of cases, we have emphasized the near-limitless sovereignty of
each State to design its governing structure as it sees fit.
Generally, “a State is afforded wide leeway when
experimenting with the appropriate allocation of state legislative
power” and may create “political subdivisions such as
cities and counties . . . ‘as convenient agencies
for exercising such of the governmental powers of the state as may
be entrusted to them.’ ” Holt Civic Club v.
Tuscaloosa, 439 U. S. 60, 71 (1978) (quoting Hunter v.
Pittsburgh, 207 U. S. 161, 178 (1907) ). Accordingly, States
have “absolute discretion” to determine the
“number, nature and duration of the powers conferred upon
[municipal] corporations and the territory over which they shall be
exercised.” Holt Civic Club, supra, at 71. So it would seem
to go without saying that a State may give certain powers to
cities, later assign the same powers to counties, and even reclaim
them for itself.
Taken to the limits of
its logic, Hunter-Seattle is the gaping exception that nearly
swallows the rule of structural state sovereignty. If indeed the
Fourteenth Amendment forbids States to “place effective
decisionmaking authority over” racial issues at
“different level[s] of government,” then it must be
true that the Amendment’s ratification in 1868 worked a
partial ossification of each State’s governing structure,
rendering basically irrevocable the power of any subordinate state
official who, the day before the Fourteenth Amendment’s
passage, happened to enjoy legislatively conferred authority over a
“racial issue.” Under the Fourteenth Amendment, that
subordinate entity (suppose it is a city council) could itself take
action on the issue, action either favorable or unfavorable to
minorities. It could even reverse itself later. What it could not
do, however, is redelegate its power to an even lower level of
state government (such as a city-council committee) without
forfeiting it, since the necessary effect of wresting it back would
be to put an additional obstacle in the path of minorities.
Likewise, no entityor official higher up the state chain (e.g., a
county board) could exercise authority over the issue. Nor, even,
could the state legislature, or the people by constitutional
amendment, revoke the legislative conferral of power to the
subordinate, whether the city council, its subcommittee, or the
county board. Seattle’s logic would createaffirmative-action
safe havens wherever subordinate offi-cials in public universities
(1) traditionally have enjoyed “effective decisionmaking
authority” over admissions policy but (2) have not yet used
that authority to prohibit race-conscious admissions decisions. The
mere existence of a subordinate’s discretion over the matter
would work a kind of reverse pre-emption. It is “a strange
notion—alien to our system—that local governmental
bodies can forever pre-empt the ability of a State—the
sovereign power—to address a matter of compelling concern to
the State.” 458 U. S., at 495 (Powell, J., dissenting).
But that is precisely what the political-process doctrine
contemplates.
Perhaps the spirit of
Seattle is especially disquieted by enactments of constitutional
amendments. That appears to be the dissent’s position. The
problem with §26, it suggests, is that amending
Michigan’s Constitution is simply not a part of that
State’s “existing” political process. E.g., post,
at 4, 41. What a peculiar notion: that a revision of a
State’s fundamental law, made in precisely the manner that
law prescribes, by the very people who are the source of that
law’s authority, is not part of the “political
process” which, but for those people and that law, would not
exist. This will surely come as news to the people of Michigan,
who, since 1914, have amended their Constitution 20 times. Brief
for Gary Segura et al. as Amici Curiae 12. Even so, the
dissent concludes that the amendment attacked here worked an
illicit “chang[ing] [of ] the basic rules of the
political process in that State” in “the middle of the
game.” Post, at 2, 4. Why, one might ask, is not the
amendment provision of the Michigan Constitution one (perhaps the
most basic one) of the rules of the State’s political
process? And why does democratic invocation of that provision not
qualify as working through the “existing political
process,” post, at 41?[ 9 ]
II
I part ways with
Hunter, Seattle, and (I think) the plurality for an additional
reason: Each endorses a version of the proposition that a facially
neutral law may deny equal protection solely because it has a
disparate racial impact. Few equal-protection theories have been so
squarely and soundly rejected. “An unwavering line of cases
from this Court holds that a violation of the Equal Protection
Clause requires state action motivated by discriminatory
intent,” Hernandez v. New York, 500 U. S. 352 –373
(1991) (O’Connor, J., concurring in judgment), and that
“official action will not be held unconstitutional solely
because it results in a racially disproportionate impact,”
Arlington Heights v. Metropolitan Housing Development Corp., 429
U. S. 252 –265 (1977). Indeed, we affirmed this
principle the same day we decided Seattle: “[E]ven when a
neutral law has a disproportionately adverse effect on a racial
minority, the Fourteenth Amendment is violated only if a
discriminatory purpose can be shown.” Crawford v. Board of
Ed. of Los Angeles, 458 U. S. 527 –538 (1982).
Notwithstanding our
dozens of cases confirming the exception-less nature of the
Washington v. Davis rule, the plurality opinion leaves ajar an
effects-test escape hatch modeled after Hunter and Seattle,
suggesting that state action denies equal protection when it
“ha[s] the serious risk, if not purpose, of causing specific
injuries on account of race,” or is either “designed to
be used, or . . . likely to be used, to encourage
infliction of injury by reason of race.” Ante, at 9, 17
(emphasis added). Since these formulations enable a determination
of an equal-protection violation where there is no discriminatory
intent, they are inconsistent with the long Washington v. Davis
line of cases.[ 10 ]
Respondents argue that
we need not bother with the discriminatory-purpose test, since
§26 may be struck more straightforwardly as a racial
“classification.” Admitting (as they must) that
§26 does not on its face “distribut[e] burdens or
benefits on the basis of individual racial classifications,”
Parents Involved in Community Schools v. Seattle School Dist. No.
1, 551 U. S. 701, 720 (2007) , respondents rely on
Seattle’s statement that “when the political process or
the decisionmaking mechanism used to address racially conscious
legislation—and only such legislation—is singled out
for peculiar and disadvantageous treatment,” then that
“singling out” is a racial classification. 458
U. S., at 485, 486, n. 30. But this is just the
political-process theory bedecked in different doctrinal dress. A
law that “neither says nor implies that persons are to be
treated differently on account of their race” is not a racial
classification. Crawford, supra, at 537. That is particularly true
of statutes mandating equal treatment. “[A] law that
prohibits the State from classifying individuals by race
. . . a fortiori does not classify individuals by
race.” Coalition for Economic Equity v. Wilson, 122
F. 3d 692, 702 (CA9 1997) (O’Scannlain, J.).
Thus, the question in
this case, as in every case in which neutral state action is said
to deny equal protection on account of race, is whether the action
reflects a racially discriminatory purpose. Seattle stresses that
“singling out the political processes affecting racial issues
for uniquely disadvantageous treatment inevitably raises dangers of
impermissible motivation.” 458 U. S., at 486, n. 30.
True enough, but that motivation must be proved. And respondents do
not have a prayer of proving it here. The District Court noted
that, under “conventional equal protection” doctrine,
the suit was “doom[ed].” 539 F. Supp. 2d 924, 951
(ED Mich. 2008). Though the Court of Appeals did not opine on this
question, I would not leave it for them on remand. In my view, any
law expressly requiring state actors to afford all persons equal
protection of the laws (such as Initiative 350 in Seattle, though
not the charter amendment in Hunter) does
not—cannot—deny “to any person . . .
equal protection of the laws,” U. S. Const., Amdt. 14,
§1, regardless of whatever evidence of seemingly foul purposes
plaintiffs may cook up in the trial court.
* * *
As Justice Harlan
observed over a century ago, “[o]ur Constitution is
color-blind, and neither knows nor tolerates classes among
citizens.” Plessy v. Ferguson, 163 U. S. 537, 559 (1896)
(dissenting opinion). The people of Michigan wish the same for
their governing charter. It would be shameful for us to stand in
their way.[ 11 ] Notes 1 For simplicity’s
sake, I use “respondent” or “respondents”
throughout the opinion to describe only those parties who are
adverse to petitioner, not Eric Russell, a respondent who supports
petitioner. 2 The plurality cites
evidence from ’s dissent in v. , , to suggest that the city
had been a “partial” cause of its segregation problem.
, at 9.The plurality in criticized that dissent for relying on
irrelevant evidence, for “elid[ing the] distinction between
and segregation,” and for “casually intimat[ing] that
Seattle’s school attendance patterns reflect[ed] illegal
segregation.” 551 U. S., at 736–737, and n. 15.
Today’s plurality sides with the dissent and repeats its
errors. 3 Or so the Court assumed.
See 458 U. S. at 472, n. 15 (“Appellants and the
United States do not challenge the propriety of race-conscious
student assignments for the purpose of achieving integration, even
absent a finding of prior segregation. We therefore do not
specifically pass on that issue”). 4 The dissent’s
version of this test is just as scattershot. Since, according to
the dissent, the doctrine forbids “reconfigur[ing] the
political process in a manner that only a racial minority,” ,
at 5 (opinion of , J.) (emphasis added), it must be that that the
reason the underlying issue (that is, the issue concerning which
the process has been reconfigured) is “racial” is that
the policy in question only a racial minority (if it also
benefitted persons not belonging to a racial majority, then the
political-process reconfiguration would burden them as well). On
second thought: The issue is “racial” if the policy
benefits a racial minority and “ ‘[is] designed
for that purpose,’ ” , at 44. This is the standard
purported to apply. But under that standard, §26 does not
affect a “racial issue,” because under v. , ,
race-based admissions policies may not constitutionally be
“designed for [the] purpose,” , at 472, of benefitting
primarily racial minorities, but must be designed for the purpose
of achieving educational benefits for students of all races, , ,at
322–325. So the dissent must mean that an issue is
“racial” so long as the policy in question has the
incidental effect (an effect not flowing from its design) of
benefiting primarily racial minorities. 5 And how many members of a
particular racial group must take the same position on an issue
before we suppose that the position is in the ’s interest?
Not member, the dissent suggests, , at 44. Beyond that, who knows?
Five percent? Eighty-five percent? 6 The dissent proves my
point. After asserting—without citation, though I and many
others of all races deny it—that it is “common-sense
reality” that affirmative action benefits racial minorities,
, at 16, the dissent suggests throughout, , , at 30, that that view
of “reality” is so necessarily shared by members of
racial minorities that they favor affirmative action. 7 The dissent contends, ,
at 39, that this point “ignores the obvious: Discrimination
against an individual occurs because of that individual’s
membership in a particular group.” No, I do not ignore the
obvious; it is the dissent that misses the point. Of course
discrimination against a group constitutes discrimination against
each member of that group. But since it is persons and not groups
that are protected, one cannot say, as the dissent would, that the
Constitution prohibits discrimination against minority groups, but
not against majority groups. 8 Cf., , Ackerman, Beyond ,
98 Harv. L. Rev. 713, 723–724 (1985) (“Other things
being equal, ‘discreteness and insularity’ will
normally be a source of enormous bargaining advantage, not
disadvantage, for a group engaged in pluralist American politics.
Except for special cases, the concerns that underlie should lead
judges to protect groups that possess the opposite characteristic
from the ones emphasizes—groups that are ‘anonymous and
diffuse’ rather than ‘discrete and insular’
”). 9 The dissent thinks I do
not understand its argument. Only when amending Michigan’s
Constitution violates , it says, is that constitutionally
prescribed activity necessarily not part of the State’s
existing political process. , at 21, n. 7. I understand the
argument quite well; and see quite well that it begs the question.
Why is Michigan’s action here unconstitutional? Because it
violates And why does it violate ? Because it is not part of the
State’s existing political process. And why is it not part of
the State’s existing political process? Because it
violates 10 According to the dissent, - fills an
important doctrinal gap left open by v. , since -’s
rule—unique among equal-protection principles—makes
clear that “the majority” may not alter a political
process with the goal of “prevent[ing] minority groups from
partaking in that process on equal footing.” , at 33.
Nonsense. There is no gap. To “manipulate the ground
rules,” , at 34, or to “ri[g] the contest,” , at
35, in order to harm persons because of their race is to deny equal
protection under v. . 11 And
doubly shameful to equate “the majority” behind
§26 with “the majority” responsible for Jim Crow.
, at 1–2 (, J., dissenting). SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES
_________________
No. 12–682
_________________
BILL SCHUETTE, ATTORNEY GENERAL OF MICHI-GAN,
PETITIONER v. COALITION TO DEFEND AF-FIRMATIVE ACTION, INTEGRATION
AND IMMI-GRANT RIGHTS AND FIGHT FOR EQUALITYBY ANY MEANS NECESSARY
(BAMN), et al.
on writ of certiorari to the united states
court of appeals for the sixth circuit
[April 22, 2014]
Chief Justice
Roberts, concurring.
The dissent devotes 11
pages to expounding its own policy preferences in favor of taking
race into account in college admissions, while nonetheless
concluding that it “do[es] not mean to suggest that the
virtues of adopting race-sensitive admissions policies should
inform the legal question before the Court.” Post, at 57
(opinion of Sotomayor, J.). The dissent concedes that the governing
boards of the State’s various universities could have
implemented a policy making it illegal to “discriminate
against, or grant preferential treatment to,” any individ-ual
on the basis of race. See post, at 3, 34–35. On the
dissent’s view, if the governing boards conclude that drawing
racial distinctions in university admissions is undesirable or
counterproductive, they are permissibly exercising their
policymaking authority. But others who might reach the same
conclusion are failing to take race seriously.
The dissent states that
“[t]he way to stop discrimination on the basis of race is to
speak openly and candidly on the subject of race.” Post, at
46. And it urges that “[r]ace matters because of the slights,
the snickers, the silent judgments that reinforce that most
crippling of thoughts: ‘I do not belong
here.’ ” Ibid. But it is not “out of touch
with reality” to conclude that racial preferences may
themselves have the debilitating effect of reinforcing precisely
that doubt, and—if so—that the preferences do more harm
than good. Post, at 45. To disagree with the dissent’s views
on the costs and benefits of racial preferences is not to
“wish away, rather than confront” racial inequality.
Post, at 46. People can disagree in good faith on this issue, but
it similarly does more harm than good to question the openness and
candor of those on either side of the debate.[ 1 ]* Notes 1 * and question the
relationship between v. , , and v. , . See at 6, n. 2 (, concurring
in judgment); at 23, n. 9 (, dissenting). The plurality today
addresses that issue, explaining that the race-conscious action in
was unconstitutional given the absence of a showing of prior
segregation. , , at 720–721 (majority opinion), 736
(plurality opinion); see at 9. Today’s plurality notes that
the Court in “assumed” the constitutionality of the
busing remedy at issue there, “ ‘even absent a
finding of prior segregation.’ ” at 10 (quoting ,
, at 472, n. 15). The assumption on which proceeded did not
constitute a finding sufficient to justify the race-conscious
action in , though it is doubtless pertinent in analyzing .
“As this Court held in , the [Seattle] school board’s
purported remedial action would not be permissible today absent a
of segregation,” but “we must understand as understood
itself.” at 9–10 (emphasis added). SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES
_________________
No. 12–682
_________________
BILL SCHUETTE, ATTORNEY GENERAL OF MICHI-GAN,
PETITIONER v. COALITION TO DEFEND AF-FIRMATIVE ACTION, INTEGRATION
AND IMMI-GRANT RIGHTS AND FIGHT FOR EQUALITYBY ANY MEANS NECESSARY
(BAMN), et al.
on writ of certiorari to the united states
court of appeals for the sixth circuit
[April 22, 2014]
Justice Sotomayor,
with whom Justice Ginsburg joins, dissenting.
We are fortunate to
live in a democratic society. But without checks, democratically
approved legislation can oppress minority groups. For that reason,
our Constitution places limits on what a majority of the people may
do. This case implicates one such limit: the guarantee of equal
protection of the laws. Although that guarantee is traditionally
understood to prohibit intentional discrimination under existing
laws, equal protection does not end there. Another fundamental
strand of our equal protection jurisprudence focuses on process,
securing to all citizens the right to participate meaningfully and
equally in self-government. That right is the bedrock of our
democracy, for it preserves all other rights.
Yet to know the history
of our Nation is to understand its long and lamentable record of
stymieing the right of racial minorities to participate in the
political process. At first, the majority acted with an open,
invidious purpose. Notwithstanding the command of the Fifteenth
Amendment, certain States shut racial minorities out of the
political process altogether by withholding the right to vote. This
Court intervened to preserve that right. The majority tried again,
replacing outright bans on voting with literacy tests, good
character requirements, poll taxes, and gerrymandering. The Court
was not fooled; it invalidated those measures, too. The majority
persisted. This time, although it allowed the minority access to
the political process, the majority changed the ground rules of the
process so as to make it more difficult for the minority, and the
minority alone, to obtain policies designed to foster racial
integration. Although these political restructurings may not have
been discriminatory in purpose, the Court reaffirmed the right of
minority members of our society to participate meaningfully and
equally in the political process.
This case involves this
last chapter of discrimination: A majority of the Michigan
electorate changed the basic rules of the political process in that
State in a manner that uniquely disadvantaged racial
minorities.[ 1 ] Prior to the
enactment of the constitutional initiative at issue here,all of the
admissions policies of Michigan’s public colleges and
universities—including race-sensitive admissions
poli-cies[ 2 ]—were in the
hands of each institution’s governing board. The members of
those boards are nominated by political parties and elected by the
citizenry in statewide elections. After over a century of being
shut out of Michigan’s institutions of higher education,
racial minorities in Michigan had succeeded in persuading the
elected board representatives to adopt admissions policies that
took into account the benefits of racial diversity. And this Court
twice blessed such efforts—first in Regents of Univ. of Cal.
v. Bakke, 438 U. S. 265 (1978) , and again in Grutter v.
Bollinger, 539 U. S. 306 (2003) , a case that itself concerned
a Michigan admissions policy.
In the wake of Grutter,
some voters in Michigan set out to eliminate the use of
race-sensitive admissions policies. Those voters were of course
free to pursue this end in any number of ways. For example, they
could have persuaded existing board members to change their minds
through individual or grassroots lobbying efforts, or through
general public awareness campaigns. Or they could have mobilized
efforts to vote uncooperative board members out of office,
replacing them with members who would share their desire to abolish
race-sensitive admissions policies. When this Court holds that the
Constitution permits a particular policy, nothing prevents a
majority of a State’s voters from choosing not to adopt that
policy. Our system of government encourages—and indeed,
depends on—that type of democratic action.
But instead, the
majority of Michigan voters changed the rules in the middle of the
game, reconfiguring the existing political process in Michigan in a
manner that burdened racial minorities. They did so in the 2006
election by amending the Michigan Constitution to enact Art. I,
§26, which provides in relevant part that Michigan’s
public universities “shall not discriminate against, or grant
preferential treatment to, any individual or group on the basis of
race, sex, color, ethnicity, or national origin in the operation of
public employment, public education, or public
contracting.”
As a result of
§26, there are now two very different processes through which
a Michigan citizen is permitted to influence the admissions
policies of the State’s universities: one for persons
interested in race-sensitive admissions policies and one for
everyone else. A citizen who is a University of Michigan alumnus,
for instance, can advocate for an admissions policy that considers
an applicant’s legacy status by meeting individually with
members of the Board of Regents to convince them of her views, by
joining with other legacy parents to lobby the Board, or by voting
for and supporting Board candidates who share her position. The
same options are available to a citizen who wants the Board to
adopt admissions policies that consider athleticism, geography,
area of study, and so on. The one and only policy a Michigan
citizen may not seek through this long-established process is a
race-sensitive admissions policy that considers race in an
individualized manner when it is clear that race-neutral
alternatives are not adequate to achieve diversity. For that policy
alone, the citizens of Michigan must undertake the daunting task of
amending the State Constitution.
Our precedents do not
permit political restructurings that create one process for racial
minorities and a separate, less burdensome process for everyone
else. This Court has held that the Fourteenth Amendment does not
tolerate “a political structure that treats all individuals
as equals, yet more subtly distorts governmental processes in such
a way as to place special burdens on the ability of minority groups
to achieve beneficial legislation.” Washington v. Seattle
School Dist. No. 1, 458 U. S. 457, 467 (1982) (internal
quotation marks omitted). Such restructuring, the Court explained,
“is no more permissible than denying [the minority] the
[right to] vote, on an equal basis with others.” Hunter v.
Erickson, 393 U. S. 385, 391 (1969) . In those
cases—Hunter and Seattle—the Court recognized what is
now known as the “political-process doctrine”: When the
majority reconfigures the political process in a manner that
burdens only a racial minority, that alteration triggers strict
judicial scrutiny.
Today, disregarding
stare decisis, a majority of the Court effectively discards those
precedents. The plurality does so, it tells us, because the freedom
actually secured by the Constitution is the freedom of
self-government—because the majority of Michigan citizens
“exercised their privilege to enact laws as a basic exercise
of their democratic power.” Ante, at 15. It would be
“demeaning to the democratic process,” the plurality
concludes, to disturb that decision in any way. Ante, at 17. This
logic embraces majority rule without an important constitutional
limit.
The plurality’s
decision fundamentally misunderstands the nature of the injustice
worked by §26. This case is not, as the plurality imagines,
about “who may resolve” the debate over the use of race
in higher education admissions. Ante, at 18. I agree wholeheartedly
that nothing vests the resolution of that debate exclusively in the
courts or requires that we remove it from the reach of the
electorate. Rather, this case is about how the debate over the use
of race-sensitive admissions policies may be resolved, contra,
ibid.—that is, it must be resolved in constitution-ally
permissible ways. While our Constitution does not guarantee
minority groups victory in the political process, it does guarantee
them meaningful and equal access to that process. It guarantees
that the majority may not win by stacking the political process
against minority groups permanently, forcing the minority alone to
surmount unique obstacles in pursuit of its goals—here,
educational diversity that cannot reasonably be accomplished
through race-neutral measures. Today, by permitting a majority of
the voters in Michigan to do what our Constitution forbids, the
Court ends the debate over race-sensitive admissions policies in
Michigan in a manner that contravenes constitutional protections
long recognized in our precedents.
Like the plurality, I
have faith that our citizenry will continue to learn from this
Nation’s regrettable history; that it will strive to move
beyond those injustices towards a future of equality. And I, too,
believe in the importance of public discourse on matters of public
policy. But I part ways with the plurality when it suggests that
judicial intervention in this case “impede[s]” rather
than “advance[s]” the democratic process and the
ultimate hope of equality. Ante, at 16. I firmly believe that our
role as judges includes policing the process of self-government and
stepping in when necessary to secure the constitutional guarantee
of equal protection. Because I would do so here, I respectfully
dissent.
I
For much of its
history, our Nation has denied to many of its citizens the right to
participate meaningfully and equally in its politics. This is a
history we strive to put behind us. But it is a history that still
informs the society we live in, and so it is one we must address
with candor. Because the political-process doctrine is best
understood against the backdrop of this history, I will briefly
trace its course.
The Fifteenth
Amendment, ratified after the Civil War, promised to racial
minorities the right to vote. But many States ignored this promise.
In addition to outright tactics of fraud, intimidation, and
violence, there are countless examples of States categorically
denying to racial minorities access to the political process.
Consider Texas; there, a 1923 statute prevented racial minorities
from participating in primary elections. After this Court declared
that statute unconstitutional, Nixon v. Herndon, 273 U. S. 536
–541 (1927), Texas responded by changing the rules. It
enacted a new statute that gave political parties themselves the
right to determine who could participate in their primaries.
Predictably, the Democratic Party specified that only white
Democrats could participate in its primaries. Nixon v. Condon, 286
U. S. 73 –82 (1932). The Court invalidated that scheme,
too. Id., at 89; see also Smith v. Allwright, 321 U. S. 649
(1944) ; Terry v. Adams, 345 U. S. 461 (1953) .
Some States were less
direct. Oklahoma was one of many that required all voters to pass a
literacy test. But the test did not apply equally to all voters.
Under a “grandfather clause,” voters were exempt if
their grand-fathers had been voters or had served as soldiers
before 1866. This meant, of course, that black voters had to pass
the test, but many white voters did not. The Court held the scheme
unconstitutional. Guinn v. United States, 238 U. S. 347 (1915)
. In response, Oklahoma changed the rules. It enacted a new statute
under which all voters who were qualified to vote in 1914 (under
the unconstitutional grandfather clause) remained qualified, and
the remaining voters had to apply for registration within a 12-day
period. Lane v. Wilson, 307 U. S. 268 –271 (1939). The
Court struck down that statute as well. Id., at 275.
Racial minorities were
occasionally able to surmount the hurdles to their political
participation. Indeed, in some States, minority citizens were even
able to win elective office. But just as many States responded to
the Fifteenth Amendment by subverting minorities’ access to
the polls, many States responded to the prospect of elected
minority officials by undermining the ability of minorities to win
and hold elective office. Some States blatantly removed black
officials from local offices. See, e.g., H. Rabinowitz, Race
Relations in the Urban South, 1865–1890, pp. 267,
269–270 (1978) (describing events in Tennessee and Virginia).
Others changed the processes by which local officials were elected.
See, e.g., Extension of the Voting Rights Act, Hearings before the
Subcommittee on Civil and Constitutional Rights of the House
Committee on the Judiciary, 97th Cong., 1st Sess., pt. 1, pp.
2016–2017 (1981) (hereinafter 1981 Hearings) (statement of
Professor J. Morgan Kousser) (after a black judge refused to resign
in Alabama, the legislature abolished the court on which he served
and replaced it with one whose judges were appointed by the
Governor); Rabinowitz, supra, at 269–270 (the North Carolina
Legislature divested voters ofthe right to elect justices of the
peace and county commissioners, then arrogated to itself the
authority to select justices of the peace and gave them the power
to select commissioners).
This Court did not
stand idly by. In Alabama, for example, the legislature responded
to increased black voter registration in the city of Tuskegee by
amending the State Constitution to authorize legislative abolition
of the county in which Tuskegee was located, Ala. Const. Amdt. 132
(1957), repealed by Ala. Const. Amdt. 406 (1982), and by redrawing
the city’s boundaries to remove all the black voters
“while not removing a single white voter,” Gomillion v.
Lightfoot, 364 U. S. 339, 341 (1960) . The Court intervened,
finding it “inconceivable that guaranties embedded in the
Constitution” could be “manipulated out of
existence” by being “cloaked in the garb of [political]
realignment.” Id., at 345 (internal quotation marks
omitted).
This Court’s
landmark ruling in Brown v. Board of Education, 347 U. S. 483
(1954) , triggered a new era of political restructuring, this time
in the context of education. In Virginia, the General Assembly
transferred control of student assignment from local school
districts to a State Pupil Placement Board. See B. Muse,
Virginia’s Massive Resistance 34, 74 (1961). And when the
legislature learned that the Arlington County school board had
prepared a desegregation plan, the General Assembly “swiftly
retaliated” by stripping the county of its right to elect its
school board by popular vote and instead making the board an
appointed body. Id., at 24; see also B. Smith, They Closed Their
Schools 142–143 (1965).
Other States similarly
disregarded this Court’s mandate by changing their political
process. See, e.g., Bush v. Orleans Parish School Bd., 187
F. Supp. 42, 44–45 (ED La. 1960) (the Louisiana
Legislature gave the Governor the authority to supersede any school
board’s decision to integrate); Extension of the Voting
Rights Act, Hearings on H. R. 4249 et al. before
Subcommittee No. 5 of the House Committee on the Judiciary, 91st
Cong., 1st Sess., 146–149 (1969) (statement of Thomas E.
Harris, Assoc. Gen. Counsel, American Federation of Labor and
Congress of Industrial Organizations) (the Mississippi Legislature
removed from the people the right to elect superintendents of
education in 11 counties and instead made those positions
appointive).
The Court remained true
to its command in Brown. In Arkansas, for example, it enforced a
desegregation order against the Little Rock school board. Cooper v.
Aaron, 358 U. S. 1, 5 (1958) . On the very day the Court
announced that ruling, the Arkansas Legislature responded by
changing the rules. It enacted a law permitting the Governor to
close any public school in the State, and stripping local school
districts of their decisionmaking authority so long as the Governor
determined that local officials could not maintain
“ ‘a general, suitable, and efficient educational
system.’ ” Aaron v. Cooper, 261 F. 2d 97, 99
(CA8 1958) (per curiam) (quoting Arkansas statute). The
then-Governor immediately closed all of Little Rock’s high
schools. Id., at 99–100; see also S. Breyer, Making Our
Democracy Work 49–67 (2010) (discussing the events in Little
Rock).
The States’
political restructuring efforts in the 1960’s and
1970’s went beyond the context of education. Many States
tried to suppress the political voice of racial minorities more
generally by reconfiguring the manner in which they filled
vacancies in local offices, often transferring authority from the
electorate (where minority citizens had a voice at the local level)
to the States’ executive branch (where minorities wielded
little if any influence). See, e.g., 1981 Hearings, pt. 1, at 815
(report of J. Cox & A. Turner) (the Alabama Legislature changed
all municipal judgeships from elective to appointive offices); id.,
at 1955 (report of R. Hudlin & K. Brimah, Voter Educ. Project,
Inc.) (the Georgia Legislature eliminated some elective offices and
made others appointive when it appeared that a minority candidate
would be victorious); id., at 501 (statement of Frank R. Parker,
Director, Lawyers’ Comm. for Civil Rights Under Law) (the
Mississippi Legislature changed the manner of filling vacancies for
various public offices from election to appointment).
II
It was in this
historical context that the Court intervened in Hunter v. Erickson,
393 U. S. 385 (1969) , and Washington v. Seattle School Dist.
No. 1, 458 U. S. 457 (1982) . Together, Hunter and Seattle
recognized a fundamental strand of this Court’s equal
protection jurisprudence: the political-process doctrine. To
understand that doctrine fully, it is necessary to set forth in
detail precisely what the Court had before it, and precisely what
it said. For to understand Hunter and Seattle is to understand why
those cases straightforwardly resolve this one.
A
In Hunter, the City
Council of Akron, Ohio, enacted a fair housing ordinance to
“assure equal opportunity to all persons to live in decent
housing facilities regardless of race, color, religion, ancestry,
or national origin.” 393 U. S., at 386 (internal
quotation marks omitted). A majority of the citizens of Akron
disagreed with the ordinance and overturned it. But the majority
did not stop there; it also amended the city charter to prevent the
City Council from implementing any future ordinance dealing with
racial, religious, or ancestral discrimination in housing without
the approval of the majority of the Akron electorate. Ibid. That
amendment changed the rules of the political process in Akron. The
Court described the result of the change as follows:
“[T]o enact an ordinance barring
housing discrimination on the basis of race or religion, proponents
had to obtain the approval of the City Council and of a majority of
the voters citywide. To enact an ordinance preventing housing
discrimination on other grounds, or to enact any other type of
housing ordinance, proponents needed the support of only the City
Council.” Seattle, 458 U. S., at 468 (describing Hunter;
emphasis deleted).
The Court invalidated
the Akron charter amendment under the Equal Protection Clause. It
concluded that the amendment unjustifiably “place[d] special
burdens on racial minorities within the governmental
process,” thus effecting “a real, substantial, and
invidious denial of the equal protection of the laws.”
Hunter, 393 U. S., at 391, 393. The Court characterized the
amendment as “no more permissible” than denying racial
minorities the right to vote on an equal basis with the majority.
Id., at 391. For a “State may no more disadvantage any
particular group by making it more difficult to enact legislation
in its behalf than it may dilute any person’s vote or give
any group a smaller representation than another of comparable
size.” Id., at 392–393. The vehicle for the
change—a popular referendum—did not move the Court:
“The sovereignty of the people,” it explained,
“is itself subject to . . . constitutional
limitations.” Id., at 392.
Justice Harlan, joined
by Justice Stewart, wrote in his concurrence that although a State
can normally allocate political power according to any general
principle, it bears a “far heavier burden of
justification” when it reallocates political power based on
race, because the selective reallocation necessarily makes it far
more difficult for racial minorities to “achieve legislation
that is in their interest.” Id., at 395 (internal quotation
marks omitted).
In Seattle, a case that
mirrors the one before us, the Court applied Hunter to invalidate a
statute, enacted by a majority of Washington State’s
citizens, that prohibited racially integrative busing in the wake
of Brown. As early as 1963, Seattle’s School District No. 1
began taking steps to cure the de facto racial segregation in its
schools. 458 U. S., at 460–461. Among other measures, it
enacted a desegregation plan that made extensive use of busing and
mandatory assignments. Id., at 461. The district was under no
obligation to adopt the plan; Brown charged school boards with a
duty to integrate schools that were segregated because of
de jure racial discrimination, but there had been no finding
that the de facto segregation in Seattle’s schools was the
product of de jure discrimination. 458 U. S., at 472,
n. 15. Several residents who opposed the desegregation efforts
formed a committee and sued to enjoin implementation of the plan.
Id., at 461. When these efforts failed, the committee sought to
change the rules of the political process. It drafted a statewide
initiative “designed to terminate the use of mandatory busing
for purposes of racial integration.” Id., at 462. A major-ity
of the State’s citizens approved the initiative. Id., at
463–464.
The Court invalidated
the initiative under the Equal Protection Clause. It began by
observing that equal protection of the laws “guarantees
racial minorities the right to full participation in the political
life of the community.” Id., at 467. “It is beyond
dispute,” the Court explained, “that given racial or
ethnic groups may not be denied the franchise, or precluded from
entering into the political process in a reliable and meaningful
manner.” Ibid. But the Equal Protection Clause reaches
further, the Court stated, reaffirming the principle espoused in
Hunter—that while “laws structuring political
institutions or allocating political power according to neutral
principles” do not violate the Constitution, “a
different analysis is required when the State allocates
governmental power nonneutrally, by explicitly using the racial
nature of a decision to determine the decisionmaking
process.” 458 U. S., at 470. That kind of state action,
it observed, “places special burdens on racial minorities
within the governmental process,” by making it “more
difficult for certain racial and religious minorities” than
for other members of the community “to achieve legislation
. . . in their interest.” Ibid.
Rejecting the argument
that the initiative had no racial focus, the Court found that the
desegregation of public schools, like the Akron housing ordinance,
“inure[d] primarily to the benefit of the minority, and [was]
designed for that purpose.” Id., at 472. Because minorities
had good reason to “consider busing for integration to be
‘legislation that is in their interest,’ ”
the Court concluded that the “racial focus of [the
initiative] . . . suffice[d] to trigger application of
the Hunter doctrine.” Id., at 474 (quoting Hunter, 393
U. S., at 395) (Harlan, J. concurring)).
The Court next
concluded that “the practical effect of [the initiative was]
to work a reallocation of power of the kind condemned in
Hunter.” Seattle, 458 U. S., at 474. It explained:
“Those favoring the elimination of de facto school
segregation now must seek relief from the state legislature, or
from the statewide electorate. Yet authority over all other student
assignment decisions, as well as over most other areas of
educational policy, remains vested in the local school
board.” Ibid. Thus, the initiative required those in favor of
racial integration in public schools to “surmount a
considerably higher hurdle than persons seeking comparable
legislative action” in different contexts. Ibid.
The Court reaffirmed
that the “ ‘simple repeal or modification of
desegregation or antidiscrimination laws, without more, never has
been viewed as embodying a presump-tively invalid racial
classification.’ ” Id., at 483 (quoting Crawford
v. Board of Ed. of Los Angeles, 458 U. S. 527, 539 (1982) ).
But because the initiative burdened future attempts to integrate by
lodging the decisionmaking authority at a “new and remote
level of government,” it was more than a “mere
repeal”; it was an unconstitutionally discriminatory change
to the political process.[ 3 ]
Seattle, 458 U. S., at 483–484.
B
Hunter and Seattle
vindicated a principle that is as elementary to our equal
protection jurisprudence as it is essential: The majority may not
suppress the minority’s right to participate on equal terms
in the political process. Under this doctrine, governmental action
deprives minor-ity groups of equal protection when it (1) has
a racial focus, targeting a policy or program that “inures
primarily to the benefit of the minority,” Seattle, 458
U. S., at 472; and (2) alters the political process in a
manner that uniquely burdens racial minorities’ ability to
achieve their goals through that process. A faithful application of
the doctrine resoundingly resolves this case in respondents’
favor.
1
Section 26 has a
“racial focus.” Seattle, 458 U. S., at 474. That
is clear from its text, which prohibits Michigan’s public
colleges and universities from “grant[ing] preferential
treatment to any individual or group on the basis of race.”
Mich. Const., Art. I, §26. Like desegregation of public
schools, race-sensitive admissions policies “inur[e]
primarily to the benefit of the minority,” 458 U. S., at
472, as they are designed to increase minorities’ access to
institutions of higher education.[ 4 ]
Petitioner argues that
race-sensitive admissions policies cannot “inur[e] primarily
to the benefit of the minority,” ibid., as the Court has
upheld such policies only insofar as they further “the
educational benefits that flow from a diverse student body,”
Grutter, 539 U. S., at 343. But there is no conflict between
this Court’s pronouncement in Grutter and the common-sense
reality that race-sensitive admissions policies benefit minorities.
Rather, race-sensitive admissions policies further a compelling
state interest in achieving a diverse student body precisely
because they increase minority enrollment, which necessarily
benefits minority groups. In other words, constitutionally
permissible race-sensitive admissions policies can both serve the
compelling interest of obtaining the educational benefits that flow
from a diverse student body, and inure to the benefit of racial
minorities. There is nothing mutually exclusive about the two. Cf.
Seattle, 458 U. S., at 472 (concluding that the desegregation
plan had a racial focus even though “white as well as Negro
children bene-fit from exposure to ‘ethnic and racial
diversity in the classroom’ ”).
It is worth
emphasizing, moreover, that §26 is relevant only to admissions
policies that have survived strict scrutiny under Grutter; other
policies, under this Court’s rulings, would be forbidden with
or without §26. A Grutter-compliant admissions policy must use
race flexibly, not maintain a quota; must be limited in time; and
must be employed only after “serious, good faith
consideration of workable race-neutral alternatives,” 539
U. S., at 339. The policies banned by §26 meet all these
requirements and thus already constitute the least restrictive ways
to advance Michigan’s compelling interest in diversity in
higher education.
2
Section 26
restructures the political process in Michigan in a manner that
places unique burdens on racial minorities. It establishes a
distinct and more burdensome political process for the enactment of
admissions plans that consider racial diversity.
Long before the
enactment of §26, the Michigan Constitution granted plenary
authority over all matters relating to Michigan’s public
universities, including admissions criteria, to each
university’s eight-member governing board. See Mich. Const.,
Art. VIII, §5 (establishing the Board of Regents of the
University of Michigan, the Board of Trustees of Michigan State
University, and the Board of Governors of Wayne State University).
The boards have the “power to enact ordinances, by-laws and
regulations for the government of the university.” Mich.
Comp. Laws Ann. §390.5 (West 2010); see also §390.3
(“The government of the university is vested in the board of
regents”). They are “ ‘constitutional
corporation[s] of independent authority, which, within the scope of
[their] functions, [are] co-ordinate with and equal to
. . . the legislature.’ ” Federated
Publications, Inc. v. Board of Trustees of Mich. State Univ., 460
Mich. 75, 84, n. 8, 594 N. W. 2d 491, 496, n. 8
(1999).
The boards are
indisputably a part of the political process in Michigan. Each
political party nominates two candidates for membership to each
board, and board members are elected to 8-year terms in the general
statewide election. See Mich. Comp. Laws Ann. §§168.282,
168.286 (West 2008); Mich. Const., Art. VIII, §5. Prior to
§26, board candidates frequently included their views on
race-sensitive admissions in their campaigns. For example, in 2005,
one candidate pledged to “work to end so-called
‘Affirmative-Action,’ a racist, degrading
system.” See League of Women Voters, 2005 General Election
Voter Guide, online at http://www.lwvka.org/guide04/regents/html
(all Internet materials as visited Apr. 18, 2014, and available in
Clerk of Court’s case file); see also George, U-M Regents
Race Tests Policy, Detroit Free Press, Oct. 26, 2000, p. 2B (noting
that one candidate “opposes affirmative action admissions
policies” because they “ ‘basically sa[y]
minority students are not qualified’ ”).
Before the enactment of
§26, Michigan’s political structure permitted both
supporters and opponents of race-sensitive admissions policies to
vote for their candidates of choice and to lobby the elected and
politically accountable boards. Section 26 reconfigured that
structure. After §26, the boards retain plenary authority over
all admissions criteria except for race-sensitive admissions
policies.[ 5 ] To change
admissions policies on this one issue, a Michigan citizen must
instead amend the Michigan Constitution. That is no small task. To
place a proposed constitutional amendment on the ballot requires
either the support of two-thirds of both Houses of the Michigan
Legislature or a vast number of signatures from Michigan
voters—10 percent of the total number of votes cast in the
preceding gubernatorial election. See Mich. Const., Art. XII,
§§1, 2. Since more than 3.2 million votes were cast in
the 2010 election for Governor, more than 320,000 signatures are
currently needed to win a ballot spot. See Brief for Gary Segura
et al. as Amici Curiae 9 (hereinafter Segura Brief). Moreover,
“[t]o account for invalid and duplicative signatures,
initiative sponsors ‘need to obtain substantially more than
the actual required number of signatures, typically by a 25% to 50%
margin.’ ” Id., at 10 (quoting Tolbert,
Lowenstein, & Donovan, Election Law and Rules for Using
Initiatives, in Citizens as Legislators: Direct Democracy in the
United States 27, 37 (S. Bowler, T. Donovan, & C. Tolbert eds.,
1998)).
And the costs of
qualifying an amendment are significant. For example, “[t]he
vast majority of petition efforts . . . require
initiative sponsors to hire paid petition circulators, at
significant expense.” Segura Brief 10; see also T. Donovan,
C. Mooney, & D. Smith, State and Local Politics: Institutions
and Reform 96 (2012) (hereinafter Donovan) (“In many states,
it is difficult to place a measure on the ballot unless
professional petition firms are paid to collect some or all the
signatures required for qualification”); Tolbert, supra, at
35 (“ ‘Qualifying an initiative for the statewide
ballot is . . . no longer so much a measure of general citizen
interest as it is a test of fundraising
ability’ ”). In addition to the cost of collecting
signatures, campaigning for a majority of votes is an expensive
endeavor, and “organizations advocating on behalf of
marginalized groups remain . . . outmoneyed by corporate,
business, and professional organizations.” Strolovitch &
Forrest, Social and Economic Justice Movements and Organizations,
in The Oxford Handbook of American Political Parties and Interest
Groups 468, 471 (L. Maisel & J. Berry eds., 2010). In 2008, for
instance, over $800 million was spent nationally on state-level
initiative and referendum campaigns, nearly $300 million more than
was spent in the 2006 cycle. Donovan 98. “In several states,
more money [is] spent on ballot initiative campaigns than for all
other races for political office combined.” Ibid. Indeed, the
amount spent on state-level initiative and referendum campaigns in
2008 eclipsed the $740.6 million spent by President Obama in his
2008 presidential campaign, Salant, Spending Doubled as Obama Led
Billion-Dollar Campaign, Bloomberg News, Dec. 27, 2008, online at
http://www.bloomberg.com/apps/news?pid=newsarchive&sid=anLDS9WWPQW8.
Michigan’s
Constitution has only rarely been amended through the initiative
process. Between 1914 and 2000, voters have placed only 60
statewide initiatives on the Michigan ballot, of which only 20 have
passed. See Segura Brief 12. Minority groups face an especially
uphill battle. See Donovan 106 (“[O]n issues dealing with
racial and ethnic matters, studies show that racial and ethnic
minorities do end up more on the losing side of the popular
vote”). In fact, “[i]t is difficult to find even a
single statewide initiative in any State in which voters approved
policies that explicitly favor racial or ethnic minority
groups.”[ 6 ] Segura Brief
13.
This is the onerous
task that §26 forces a Michigan citizen to complete in order
to change the admissions policies of Michigan’s public
colleges and universities with respect to racial sensitivity. While
substantially less grueling paths remain open to those advocating
for any other admissions policies, a constitutional amendment is
the only avenue by which race-sensitive admissions policies may be
obtained. The effect of §26 is that a white graduate of a
public Michigan university who wishes to pass his historical
privilege on to his children may freely lobby the board of that
university in favor of an expanded legacy admissions policy,
whereas a black Michigander who was denied the opportunity to
attend that very university cannot lobby the board in favor of a
policy that might give his children a chance that he never had and
that they might never have absent that policy.
Such reordering of the
political process contravenes Hunter and Seattle.[ 7 ] See Seattle, 458 U. S., at 467 (the
Equal Protection Clause prohibits “ ‘a political
structure that treats all individuals as equals,’ yet more
subtly distorts governmental processes in such a way as to place
special burdens on the ability of minority groups to achieve
beneficial legislation” (citation omitted)). Where, as here,
the majority alters the political process to the detriment of a
racial minority, the governmental action is subject to strict
scrutiny. See id., at 485, n. 28. Michigan does not assert
that §26 satisfies a compelling state interest. That should
settle the matter.
C
1
The plurality sees it
differently. Disregarding the language used in Hunter, the
plurality asks us to contort that case into one that “rests
on the unremarkable principle that the State may not alter the
procedures of government to target racial minorities.” Ante,
at 8. And the plurality recasts Seattle “as a case in which
the state action in question . . . had the serious risk,
if not purpose, of causing specific injuries on account of
race.” Ante, at 8–9. According to the plurality, the
Hunter and Seattle Courts were not concerned with efforts to
reconfigure the political process to the detriment of racial
minorities; rather, those cases invalidated governmental actions
merely because they reflected an invidious purpose to discriminate.
This is not a tenable reading of those cases.
The plurality
identifies “invidious discrimination” as the
“necessary result” of the restructuring in Hunter.
Ante, at 8. It is impossible to assess whether the housing
amendment in Hunter was motivated by discriminatory purpose, for
the opinion does not discuss the question of intent.[ 8 ] What is obvious, however, is that the
possibility of invidious discrimination played no role in the
Court’s reasoning. We ordinarily understand our precedents to
mean what they actually say, not what we later think they could or
should have said. The Hunter Court was clear about why it
invalidated the Akron charter amendment: It was impermissible as a
restructuring of the political process, not as an action motivated
by discriminatory intent. See 393 U. S., at 391 (striking down
the Akron charter amendment because it “places a special
burden on racial minorities within the governmental
process”).
Similarly, the
plurality disregards what Seattle actually says and instead opines
that “the political restriction in question was designed to
be used, or was likely to be used, to encourage infliction of
injury by reason of race.” Ante, at 17. Here, the plurality
derives its conclusion not from Seattle itself, but from evidence
unearthed more than a quarter-century later in Parents Involved in
Community Schools v. Seattle School Dist. No. 1, 551 U. S. 701
(2007) : “Although there had been no judicial finding of
de jure segregation with respect to Seattle’s school
district, it appears as though school desegregation in the district
in the 1940’s and 1950’s may have been the partial
result of school board policies that ‘permitted white
students to transfer out of black schools while restricting the
transfer of black students into white
schools.’ ”[ 9 ]
Ante, at 9 (quoting Parents Involved, 551 U. S., at 807–808
(Breyer, J., dissenting) (emphasis added). It follows, according to
the plurality, that Seattle’s desegregation plan was
constitutionally required, so that the initiative halting the plan
was an instance of invidious discrimination aimed at inflicting a
racial injury.
Again, the plurality
might prefer that the Seattle Court had said that, but it plainly
did not. Not once did the Court suggest the presence of
de jure segregation in Seattle. Quite the opposite: The
opinion explicitly suggested the desegregation plan was adopted to
remedy de facto rather than de jure segregation. See 458
U. S., at 472, n. 15 (referring to the
“absen[ce]” of “a finding of prior de jure
segregation”). The Court, moreover, assumed that no
“constitutional violation” through de jure
segregation had occurred. Id., at 474. And it unmistakably rested
its decision on Hunter, holding Seattle’s initiative invalid
because it “use[d] the racial nature of an issue to define
the governmental decisionmaking structure, and thus impose[d]
substantial and unique burdens on racial minorities.” 458
U. S., at 470.
It is nothing short of
baffling, then, for the plurality to insist—in the face of
clear language in Hunter and Seattle saying otherwise—that
those cases were about nothing more than the intentional and
invidious infliction of a racial injury. Ante, at 8 (describing the
injury in Hunter as “a demonstrated injury on the basis of
race”); ante, at 8–9 (describing the injury in Seattle
as an “injur[y] on account of race”). The
plurality’s attempt to rewrite Hunter and Seattle so as to
cast aside the political-process doctrine sub silentio is
impermissible as a matter of stare decisis. Under the doctrine of
stare decisis, we usually stand by our decisions, even if we
disagree with them, because people rely on what we say, and they
believe they can take us at our word.
And what now of the
political-process doctrine? After the plurality’s revision of
Hunter and Seattle, it is unclear what is left. The plurality
certainly does not tell us. On this point, and this point only, I
agree with Justice Scalia that the plurality has rewritten those
precedents beyond recognition. See ante, at 5–7 (opinion
concurring in judgment).
2
Justice Breyer
concludes that Hunter and Seattle do not apply. Section 26, he
reasons, did not move the relevant decisionmaking authority from
one political level to another; rather, it removed that authority
from “unelected actors and placed it in the hands of the
voters.” Ante, at 5 (opinion concurring in judgment). He
bases this conclusion on the premise that Michigan’s elected
boards “delegated admissions-related decisionmaking authority
to unelected university faculty members and administrators.”
Ibid. But this premise is simply incorrect.
For one thing, it is
undeniable that prior to §26, board candidates often pledged
to end or carry on the use of race-sensitive admissions policies at
Michigan’s public universities. See supra, at 18. Surely
those were not empty promises. Indeed, the issue of race-sensitive
admissions policies often dominated board elections. See, e.g.,
George, Detroit Free Press, at 2B (observing that “[t]he race
for the University of Michigan Board of Regents could determine . .
. the future of [the University’s] affirmative action
policies”); Kosseff, UM Policy May Hang On Election,
Crain’s Detroit Business, Sept. 18, 2000, p. 1 (noting
that an upcoming election could determine whether the University
would continue to defend its affirmative action policies);
University of Michigan’s Admissions Policy Still an Issue for
Regents’ Election, Black Issues in Higher Education, Oct. 21,
2004, p. 17 (commenting that although “the Supreme Court
struck down the University of Michigan’s undergraduate
admissions policy as too formulaic,” the issue “remains
an important [one] to several peo-ple running” in an upcoming
election for the Board of Regents).
Moreover, a careful
examination of the boards and their governing structure reveals
that they remain actively involved in setting admissions policies
and procedures. Take Wayne State University, for example. Its Board
of Governors has enacted university statutes that govern the
day-to-day running of the institution. See Wayne State Univ. Stat.,
online at http://bog.wayne.edu/code. A number of those statutes
establish general admissions procedures, see §2.34.09
(establishing undergraduate admissions procedures); §2.34.12
(establishing graduate admissions procedures), and some set out
more specific instructions for university officials, see, e.g.,
§2.34.09.030 (“Admissions decisions will be based on a
full evaluation of each student’s academic record, and on
empirical data reflecting the characteristics of students who have
successfully graduated from [the university] within the four years
prior to the year in which the student applies”);
§§2.34.12.080, 2.34.12.090 (setting the requisite grade
point average for graduate applicants).
The Board of Governors
does give primary responsibility over day-to-day admissions matters
to the university’s President. §2.34.09.080. But the
President is “elected by and answerable to the Board.”
Brief for Respondent Board of Governors of Wayne State University
et al. 15. And while university officials and faculty members
“serv[e] an important advisory role in recommending
educational policy,” id., at 14, the Board alone ultimately
controls educational policy and decides whether to adopt (or
reject) program-specific admissions recommendations. For example,
the Board has voted on recommendations “to revise guidelines
for establishment of honors curricula, including admissions
criteria”; “to modify the honor point criteria for
graduate admission”; and “to modify the maximum number
of transfer credits that the university would allow in certain
cases where articulation agreements rendered modification
appropriate.” Id., at 17; see also id., at 18–20
(providing examples of the Board’s “review[ing] and
pass[ing] upon admissions requirements in the course of voting on
broader issues, such as the implementation of new academic
programs”). The Board also “engages in robust and
regular review of administrative actions involving admissions
policy and related matters.” Id., at 16.
Other public
universities more clearly entrust admissions policy to university
officials. The Board of Regents of the
University of Michigan, for example, gives primary responsibility
for admissions to the Associate Vice Provost, Executive Director of
Undergraduate Admissions, and Directors of Admissions. Bylaws
§8.01, online at http://www.regents.umich.edu/bylaws. And the
Board of Trustees of Michigan State University relies on the
President to make recommendations regarding admissions policies.
Bylaws, Art. 8, online at http://www.trustees.msu.edu/bylaws. But
the bylaws of the Board of Regents and the Board of Trustees
“make clear that all university operations remain subject to
their control.” Brief for Respondents Regents of the
University of Michigan, the Board of Trustees of Michigan State
University et al. 13–14.
The boards retain
ultimate authority to adopt or reject admissions policies in at
least three ways. First, they routinely meet with university
officials to review admissions policies, including race-sensitive
admissions policies. For example, shortly after this Court’s
decisions in Gratz v. Bollinger, 539 U. S. 244 (2003) , and
Grutter, 539 U. S., at 306, the President of the University of
Michigan appeared before the University’s Board of Regents to
discuss the impact of those decisions on the University.
SeeProceedings 2003–2004, pp. 10–12 (July 2003),
onlineat http://name.umdl.umich.edu/ACW7513.2003.001. Six members
of the Board voiced strong support for the University’s use
of race as a factor in admissions. Id., at 11–12. In June
2004, the President again appeared before the Board to discuss
changes to undergraduate admissions policies. Id., at 301 (June
2004). And in March 2007, the University’s Provost appeared
before the Board of Regents to present strategies to increase
diversity in light of the passage of Proposal 2. Proceedings
2006–2007, pp. 264–265 (Mar. 2007), online at
http://name.umdl.umich.edu/ACW7513.2006.001.
Second, the boards may
enact bylaws with respect to specific admissions policies and may
alter any admissions policies set by university officials. The
Board of Regents may amend any bylaw “at any regular meeting
of the board, or at any special meeting, provided notice is given
to each regent one week in advance.” Bylaws §14.03. And
Michigan State University’s Board of Trustees may,
“[u]pon the recommendation of the President[,]
. . . determine and establish the qualifications of
students for admissions at any level.” Bylaws, Art. 8. The
boards may also permanently remove certain admissions decisions
from university officials.[ 10 ] This authority is not merely theoretical. Between
2008 and 2012, the University of Michigan’s Board of Regents
“revised more than two dozen of its bylaws, two of which fall
within Chapter VIII, the section regulating admissions
practices.” App. to Pet. for Cert. 30a.
Finally, the boards may
appoint university officials who share their admissions goals, and
they may remove those officials if the officials’ goals
diverge from those of the boards. The University of
Michigan’s Board of Regents “directly appoints [the
University’s] Associate Vice Provost and Executive Director
of Undergraduate Admissions,” and Michigan State
University’s Board of Trustees elects that
institution’s President. Brief for Respondents Regents of the
University of Michigan, the Board of Trustees of Michigan State
University et al. 14.
The salient point is
this: Although the elected and politically accountable boards may
well entrust university officials with certain day-to-day
admissions responsibilities, they often weigh in on admissions
policies themselves and, at all times, they retain complete
supervisory authority over university officials and over all
admissionsdecisions.
There is no question,
then, that the elected boards in Michigan had the power to
eliminate or adopt race-sensitive admissions policies prior to
§26. There is also no question that §26 worked an
impermissible reordering of the political process; it removed that
power from the elected boards and placed it instead at a higher
level of thepolitical process in Michigan. See supra, at
17–22. This case is no different from Hunter and Seattle in
that respect. Just as in Hunter and Seattle, minorities in Michigan
“participated in the political process and won.” Ante,
at 5 (Breyer, J., concurring in judgment). And just as in Hunter
and Seattle, “the majority’s subsequent reordering of
the political process repealed the minority’s successes and
made it more difficult for the minority to succeed in the
future,” thereby “diminish[ing] the minority’s
ability to participate meaningfully in the electoral
process.” Ibid. There is therefore no need to consider
“extend[ing] the holding of Hunter and Seattle to reach
situations in which decisionmaking authority is moved from an
administrative body to a political one,” ibid. Such a
scenario is not be-fore us.
III
The political-process
doctrine not only resolves this case as a matter of stare decisis;
it is correct as a matter of first principles.
A
Under our
Constitution, majority rule is not without limit. Our system of
government is predicated on an equilibrium between the notion that
a majority of citizens may determine governmental policy through
legislation enacted by their elected representatives, and the
overriding principle that there are nonetheless some things the
Constitution forbids even a majority of citizens to do. The
political-process doctrine, grounded in the Fourteenth Amendment,
is a central check on majority rule.
The Fourteenth
Amendment instructs that all who act for the government may not
“deny to any person . . . the equal protection of
the laws.” We often think of equal protection as a guarantee
that the government will apply the law in an equal
fashion—that it will not intentionally discriminate against
minority groups. But equal protection of the laws means more than
that; it also secures the right of all citizens to participate
meaningfully and equally in the process through which laws are
created.
Few rights are as
fundamental as the right to participate meaningfully and equally in
the process of government. See Yick Wo v. Hopkins, 118 U. S.
356, 370 (1886) (political rights are “fundamental”
because they are “preservative of all rights”). That
right is the bedrock of our democracy, recognized from its very
inception. See J. Ely, Democracy and Distrust 87 (1980) (the
Constitution “is overwhelmingly concerned, on the one hand,
with procedural fairness in the resolution of individual
disputes,” and on the other, “with ensuring broad
participation in the processes and distributions of
government”).
This should come as no
surprise. The political process is the channel of change. Id., at
103 (describing the importance of the judiciary in policing the
“channels of political change”). It is the means by
which citizens may both obtain desirable legislation and repeal
undesirable legislation. Of course, we do not expect minority
members of our society to obtain every single result they seek
through the political process—not, at least, when their views
conflict with those of the majority. The minority plainly does not
have a right to prevail over majority groups in any given political
contest. But the minority does have a right to play by the same
rules as the majority. It is this right that Hunter and Seattle so
boldly vindicated.
This right was hardly
novel at the time of Hunter and Seattle. For example, this Court
focused on the vital importance of safeguarding minority
groups’ access to the political process in United States v.
Carolene Products Co., 304 U. S. 144 (1938) , a case that
predated Hunter by 30 years. In a now-famous footnote, the Court
explained that while ordinary social and economic legislation
carries a presumption of constitutionality, the same may not be
true of legislation that offends fundamental rights or targets
minority groups. Citing cases involving restrictions on the right
to vote, restraints on the dissemination of information,
interferences with political organizations, and prohibition of
peaceable assembly, the Court recognized that “legislation
which restricts those political processes which can ordinarily be
expected to bring about repeal of undesirable legislation”
could be worthy of “more exacting judicial scrutiny under the
general prohibitions of the Fourteenth Amendment than are most
other types of legislation.” Id., at 152, n. 4; see also
Ely, supra, at 76 (explaining that “[p]aragraph two [of
Carolene Products footnote 4] suggests that it is an appropriate
function of the Court to keep the machinery of democratic
government running as it should, to make sure the channels of
political participation and communication are kept open”).
The Court also noted that “prejudice against discrete and
insular minorities may be a special condition, which tends
seriously to curtail the operation of those political pro-cesses
ordinarily to be relied upon to protect minorities, and which may
call for a correspondingly more search-ing judicial inquiry.”
Carolene Products, 304 U. S., at 153, n. 4, see also Ely,
supra, at 76 (explaining that “[p]aragraph three [of Carolene
Products footnote 4] suggests that the Court should also concern
itself with what majorities do to minorities, particularly
mentioning laws ‘directed at’ religious, national and
racial minorities and those infected by prejudice against
them”).
The values identified
in Carolene Products lie at the heart of the political-process
doctrine. Indeed, Seattle explicitly relied on Carolene Products.
See 458 U. S., at 486 (“[W]hen the State’s
allocation of power places unusual burdens on the ability of racial
groups to enact legisla-tion specifically designed to overcome the
‘special condition’ of prejudice, the governmental
action seriously‘curtail[s] the operation of those political
processes ordinarily to be relied upon to protect
minorities’ ” (quoting Carolene Products, 304
U. S., at 153, n. 4)). These values are central tenets of
our equal protection jurisprudence.
Our cases recognize at
least three features of the right to meaningful participation in
the political process. Two of them, thankfully, are
uncontroversial. First, every eligible citizen has a right to vote.
See Shaw v. Reno, 509 U. S. 630, 639 (1993) . This, woefully,
has not always been the case. But it is a right no one would take
issue with today. Second, the majority may not make it more
difficult for the minority to exercise the right to vote. This,
too, is widely accepted. After all, the Court has invalidated
grandfather clauses, good character requirements, poll taxes, and
gerrymandering provisions.[ 11 ] The third feature, the one the plurality dismantles
today, is that a majority may not reconfigure the existing
political process in a manner that creates a two-tiered system of
political change, subjecting laws designed to protect or benefit
discrete and insular minorities to a more burdensome political
process than all other laws. This is the political-process doctrine
of Hunter and Seattle.
My colleagues would
stop at the second. The plurality embraces the freedom of
“self-government” without limits. See ante, at 13. And
Justice Scalia values a “near-limitless” notion of
state sovereignty. See ante, at 13 (opinion concurring in
judgment). The wrong sought to be corrected by the
political-process doctrine, they say, is not one that should
concern us and is in any event beyond the reach of the Fourteenth
Amendment. As they see it, the Court’s role in protecting the
political process ends once we have removed certain barriers to the
minority’s participation in that process. Then, they say, we
must sit back and let the majority rule without the key
constitutional limit recognized in Hunter and Seattle.
That view drains the
Fourteenth Amendment of one of its core teachings. Contrary to
today’s decision, protecting the right to meaningful
participation in the political process must mean more than simply
removing barriers to participation. It must mean vigilantly
policing the political process to ensure that the majority does not
use other methods to prevent minority groups from partaking in that
process on equal footing. Why? For the same reason we guard the
right of every citizen to vote. If “[e]fforts to reduce the
impact of minority votes, in contrast to direct attempts to block
access to the ballot,” were
“ ‘second-generation barriers’ ”
to minority voting, Shelby County v. Holder, 570 U. S. ___, ___
(2013) (Ginsburg, J., dissenting) (slip op., at 5), efforts to
reconfigure the political process in ways that uniquely
disadvantage minority groups who have already long been
disadvantaged are third-generation barriers. For as the Court
recognized in Seattle, “minorities are no less powerless with
the vote than without it when a racial criterion is used to assign
governmental power in such a way as to exclude particular racial
groups ‘from effective participation in the political
proces[s].’ ”[ 12 ] 458 U. S., at 486.
To accept the first two
features of the right to meaningful participation in the political
process, while renouncing the third, paves the way for the majority
to do what it has done time and again throughout our Nation’s
history: afford the minority the opportunity to participate, yet
manipulate the ground rules so as to ensure the minority’s
defeat. This is entirely at odds with our idea of equality under
the law.
To reiterate, none of
this is to say that the political-process doctrine prohibits the
exercise of democratic self-government. Nothing prevents a majority
of citizens from pursuing or obtaining its preferred outcome in a
political contest. Here, for instance, I agree with the plurality
that Michiganders who were unhappy with Grutter were free to pursue
an end to race-sensitive admissions policies in their State. See
ante, at 16–17. They were free to elect governing boards that
opposed race-sensitive admissions policies or, through public
discourse and dialogue, to lobby the existing boards toward that
end. They were also free to remove from the boards the authority to
make any decisions with respect to admissions policies, as opposed
to only decisions concerning race-sensitive admissions policies.
But what the majority could not do, consistent with the
Constitution, is change the ground rules of the political process
in a manner that makes it more difficult for racial minorities
alone to achieve their goals. In doing so, the majority effectively
rigs the contest to guarantee a particular outcome. That is the
very wrong the political-process doctrine seeks to remedy. The
doctrine “hews to the unremarkable notion that when two
competitors are running a race, one may not require the other to
run twice as far or to scale obstacles not present in the first
runner’s course.” BAMN v. Regents of Univ. of Michigan,
701 F. 3d 466, 474 (CA6 2012).
B
The political-process
doctrine also follows from the rest of our equal protection
jurisprudence—in particular, our reapportionment and vote
dilution cases. In those cases, the Court described the right to
vote as “ ‘the essence of a democratic
society.’ ” Shaw, 509 U. S., at 639. It
rejected States’ use of ostensibly race-neutral measures to
prevent minorities from exercising their political rights. See id.,
at 639–640. And it invalidated practices such as at-large
electoral systems that reduce or nullify a minority group’s
ability to vote as a cohesive unit, when those practices were
adopted with a discriminatory purpose. Id., at 641. These cases,
like the political-process doctrine, all sought to preserve the
political rights of the minority.
Two more recent cases
involving discriminatory restructurings of the political process
are also worthy of mention: Romer v. Evans, 517 U. S. 620
(1996) , and League of United Latin American Citizens v. Perry, 548
U. S. 399 (2006) (LULAC).
Romer involved a
Colorado constitutional amendment that removed from the local
political process an issue primarily affecting gay and lesbian
citizens. The amendment, enacted in response to a number of local
ordinances prohibiting discrimination against gay citizens,
repealed these ordinances and effectively prohibited the adoption
of similar ordinances in the future without another amendment to
the State Constitution. 517 U. S., at 623–624. Although
the Court did not apply the political-process doctrine in
Romer,[ 13 ] the case
resonates with the principles undergirding the political-process
doctrine. The Court rejected an attempt by the majority to transfer
decision-making authority from localities (where the targeted
minority group could influence the process) to state government
(where it had less ability to participate effec-tively). See id.,
at 632 (describing this type of political restructuring as a
“disability” on the minority group). Rather than being
able to appeal to municipalities for policy changes, the Court
commented, the minority was forced to “enlis[t] the citizenry
of Colorado to amend the State Constitution,” id., at
631—just as in this case.
LULAC, a Voting Rights
Act case, involved an enactment by the Texas Legislature that
redrew district lines for a number of Texas seats in the House of
Representatives. 548 U. S., at 409 (plurality opinion). In
striking down the enactment, the Court acknowledged the
“ ‘long, well-documented history of
discrimination’ ” in Texas that
“ ‘touched upon the rights of . . .
Hispanics to register, to vote, or to participate otherwise in the
electoral process,’ ” id., at 439, and it observed
that that the “ ‘political, social, and economic
legacy of past discrimination’ . . . may well
[have] ‘hinder[ed] their ability to participate effectively
in the political process,’ ” id., at 440. Against
this backdrop, the Court found that just as “Latino voters
were poised to elect their candidate of choice,” id., at 438,
the State’s enactment “took away [their] opportunity
because [they] were about to exercise it,” id., at 440. The
Court refused to sustain “the resulting vote dilution of a
group that was beginning to achieve [the] goal of overcoming prior
electoral discrimination.” Id., at 442.
As in Romer, the LULAC
Court—while using a different analytic
framework—applied the core teaching of Hunter and Seattle:
The political process cannot be restructured in a manner that makes
it more difficult for a traditionally excluded group to work
through the existing process to seek beneficial policies. And the
events giving rise to LULAC are strikingly similar to those here.
Just as redistricting prevented Latinos in Texas from attaining a
benefit they had fought for and were poised to enjoy,
§26prevents racial minorities in Michigan from enjoying a
last-resort benefit that they, too, had fought for through the
existing political processes.
IV
My colleagues claim
that the political-process doctrine is unadministrable and contrary
to our more recent equal protection precedents. See ante, at
11–15 (plurality opinion); ante, at 7–17 (Scalia, J.,
concurring in judgment). It is only by not acknowledging certain
strands of our jurisprudence that they can reach such a
conclusion.
A
Start with the claim
that Hunter and Seattle are no longer viable because of the cases
that have come after them. I note that in the view of many, it is
those precedents that have departed from the mandate of the Equal
Protection Clause in the first place, by applying strict scrutiny
to actions designed to benefit rather than burden the minority. See
Gratz, 539 U. S., at 301 (Ginsburg, J., dissenting)
(“[A]s I see it, government decisionmakers may properly
distinguish between policies of exclusion and inclusion. Actions
designed to burden groups long denied full citizenship stature are
not sensibly ranked with measures taken to hasten the day when
entrenched discrimination and its aftereffects have been
extirpated” (citation omitted)); id., at 282 (Breyer, J.,
concurring in judgment) (“I agree . . . that, in
implementing the Constitution’s equality instruction,
government decisionmakers may properly distinguish between policies
of inclusion and exclusion, for the former are more likely to prove
consistent with the basic constitutional obligation that the law
respect each individual equally” (citation omitted)); Adarand
Constructors, Inc. v. Peña, 515 U. S. 200, 243 (1995)
(Stevens, J., dissenting) (“There is no moral or
constitutional equivalence between a policy that is designed to
perpetuate a caste system and one that seeks to eradicate racial
subordination. Invidious discrimination is an engine of oppression,
subjugating a disfavored group to enhance or maintain the power of
the majority. Remedial race-based preferences reflect the opposite
impulse: a desire to foster equality in society”); Wygant v.
Jackson Bd. of Ed., 476 U. S. 267 –302 (1986) (Marshall,
J., dissenting) (when dealing with an action to eliminate
“pernicious vestiges of past discrimination,” a
“less exacting standard of review is appropriate”);
Fullilove v. Klutznick, 448 U. S. 448 –519 (1980)
(Marshall, J., concurring in judgment) (race-based governmental
action designed to “remed[y] the continuing effects of past
racial discrimination . . . should not be subjected to
conventional ‘strict scrutiny’ ”); Bakke,
438 U. S., at 359 (Brennan, White, Marshall, and Blackmun,
JJ., concurring in judgment in part and dissenting in part)
(“racial classifications designed to further remedial
purposes” should be subjected only to intermediate
scrutiny).
But even assuming that
strict scrutiny should apply to policies designed to benefit racial
minorities, that view is not inconsistent with Hunter and Seattle.
For nothing the Court has said in the last 32 years undermines the
principles announced in those cases.
1
Justice Scalia first
argues that the political-process doctrine “misreads the
Equal Protection Clause to protect ‘particular
group[s],’ ” running counter to a line of cases
that treat “ ‘equal protection as a personal
right.’ ” Ante, at 9 (opinion concurring in
judgment) (quoting Adarand, 515 U. S., at 230). Equal
protection, he says, protects “ ‘persons, not
groups.’ ” Ante, at 10 (quoting Adarand, 515
U. S., at 227). This criticism ignores the obvious:
Discrimination against an individual occurs because of that
individual’s membership in a particular group. Yes, equal
protection is a personal right, but there can be no equal
protection violation unless the injured individual is a member of a
protected group or a class of individuals. It is membership in the
group—here the racial minority—that gives rise to an
equal protection violation.
Relatedly, Justice
Scalia argues that the political-process doctrine is inconsistent
with our precedents because it protects only the minority from
political restructurings. This aspect of the doctrine, he says,
cannot be tolerated because our precedents have rejected
“ ‘a reading of the guarantee of equal protection
under which the level of scrutiny varies according to the ability
of different groups to defend their interests in the representative
process.’ ” Ante, at 10 (quoting Richmond v. J. A.
Croson Co., 488 U. S., 469, 495 (1989) (plurality opinion)).
Equal protection, he continues, “ ‘cannot mean one
thing when applied to one individual and something else when
applied to a person of another color.’ ” Ante, at
10 (quoting Bakke, 438 U. S., at 289–290) (opinion of
Powell, J.).
Justice Scalia is
troubled that the political-process doctrine has not been applied
to trigger strict scrutiny for political restructurings that burden
the majority. But the doctrine is inapplicable to the majority. The
minority cannot achieve such restructurings against the majority,
for the majority is, well, the majority. As the Seattle Court
explained, “ ‘[t]he majority needs no protection
against discriminat[ory restructurings], and if it did, a
referendum, [for instance], might be bothersome but no more than
that.’ ” 458 U. S., at 468. Stated
differently, the doctrine protects only the minority because it
implicates a problem that affects only the minority. Nothing in my
opinion suggests, as Justice Scalia says, that under the
political-process doctrine, “the Constitution prohibits
discrimination against minority groups, but not against majority
groups.” Ante, at 10, n. 7. If the minority somehow managed
to effectuate a political restructuring that burdened only the
majority, we could decide then whether to apply the
political-process doctrine to safeguard the political right of the
majority. But such a restructuring is not before us, and I cannot
fathom how it could be achieved.
2
Justice Scalia next
invokes state sovereignty, arguing that “we have emphasized
the near-limitless sovereignty of each State to design its
governing structure as it sees fit.” Ante, at 13 (opinion
concurring in judgment). But state sovereignty is not absolute; it
is subject to constitutional limits. The Court surely did not
offend state sovereignty by barring States from changing their
voting procedures to exclude racial minorities. So why does
thepolitical-process doctrine offend state sovereignty? The
doctrine takes nothing away from state sovereignty that the Equal
Protection Clause does not require. All it says is that a State may
not reconfigure its existing political processes in a manner that
establishes a distinct and more burdensome process for minority
members of our society alone to obtain legislation in their
interests.
More broadly, Justice
Scalia is troubled that the political-process doctrine would create
supposed “affirmative-action safe havens” in places
where the ordinary political process has thus far produced
race-sensitive admissions policies. Ante, at 13–14. It would
not. As explained previously, the voters in Michigan who opposed
race-sensitive admissions policies had any number of options
available to them to challenge those policies. See supra, at
34–35. And in States where decisions regarding race-sensitive
admissions policies are not subject to the political process in the
first place, voters are entirely free to eliminate such policies
via a constitutional amendment because that action would not
reallocate power in the manner condemned in Hunter and Seattle
(and, of course, present here). The Seattle Court recognized this
careful balance between state sovereignty and constitutional
protections:
“[W]e do not undervalue the
magnitude of the State’s interest in its system of education.
Washington could have reserved to state officials the right to make
all decisions in the areas of education and student assignment. It
has chosen, however, to use a more elaborate system; having done
so, the State is obligated to operate that system within the
confines of the Fourteenth Amendment.” 458 U. S., at
487.
The same is true of Michigan.
3
Finally, Justice
Scalia disagrees with “the proposition that a facially
neutral law may deny equal protection solely because it has a
disparate racial impact.” Ante,at 15 (opinion concurring in
judgment). He would acknowledge, however, that an act that draws
racial distinctions or makes racial classifications triggers strict
scrutiny regardless of whether discriminatory intent is shown. See
Adarand, 515 U. S., at 213. That should settle the matter:
Section 26 draws a racial distinction. As the Seattle Court
explained, “when the political process or the decisionmaking
mechanism used to address racially conscious legislation—and
only such legislation—is singled out for peculiar and
disadvantageous treatment, the governmental action plainly rests on
‘distinctions based on race.’ ” 458
U. S., at 485 (some internal quotation marks omitted); see
also id., at 470 (noting that although a State may
“ ‘allocate governmental power on the basis of any
general principle,’ ” it may not use racial
considerations “to define the governmental decisionmaking
structure”).
But in Justice
Scalia’s view, cases like Washington v. Davis, 426 U. S.
229 (1976) , and Arlington Heights v. Metropolitan Housing
Development Corp., 429 U. S. 252 (1977) , call Seattle into
question. It is odd to suggest that prior precedents call into
question a later one. Seattle (decided in 1982) postdated both
Washington v. Davis (1976) and Arlington Heights (1977). Justice
Scalia’s suggestion that Seattle runs afoul of the principles
established in Washington v. Davis and Arlington Heights would come
as a surprise to Justice Blackmun, who joined the majority opinions
in all three cases. Indeed, the Seattle Court explicitly rejected
the argument that Hunter had been effectively overruled by
Washington v. Davis and Arlington Heights:
“There is one immediate and crucial
difference between Hunter and [those cases]. While decisions such
as Washington v. Davis and Arlington Heights considered
classifications facially unrelated to race, the charter amendment
at issue in Hunter dealt in explicitly racial terms with
legislation designed to benefit minorities ‘as
minorities,’ not legislation intended to benefit some larger
group of underprivileged citizens among whom minorities were
disproportionately represented.” 458 U. S., at 485.
And it concluded that both the Hunter amendment
and the Seattle initiative rested on distinctions based on race.
458 U. S., at 485. So does §26.[ 14 ]
B
My colleagues also
attack the first prong of the doctrine as “rais[ing] serious
constitutional concerns,” ante, at 11 (plurality opinion),
and being “unadministrable,” ante, at 7 (Scalia, J.,
concurring in judgment). Justice Scalia wonders whether judges are
equipped to weigh in on what constitutes a “racial
issue.” See ante, at 8. The plurality, too, thinks courts
would be “with no clear legal standards or accepted sources
to guide judicial decision.” Ante, at 12. Yet as Justice
Scalia recognizes, Hunter and Seattle provide a standard: Does the
public policy at issue “inur[e] primarily to the benefit of
the minority, and [was it] designed for that purpose”?
Seattle, 458 U. S., at 472; see ante, at 8. Surely this is the
kind of factual inquiry that judges are capable of making. Justice
Scalia, for instance, accepts the standard announced in Washington
v. Davis, which requires judges to determine whether discrimination
is intentional or whether it merely has a discriminatory effect.
Such an inquiry is at least as difficult for judges as the one
called for by Hunter and Seattle. In any event, it is clear that
the constitutional amendment in this case has a racial focus; it is
facially race-based and, by operation of law, disadvantages only
minorities. See supra, at 15–16.
“No good can
come” from these inquiries, Justice Scalia responds, because
they divide the Nation along racial lines and perpetuate racial
stereotypes. Ante, at 9. The plurality shares that view; it tells
us that we must not assume all individuals of the same race think
alike. See ante, at 11–12. The same could have been said
about desegregation: Not all members of a racial minority in
Seattle necessarily regarded the integration of public schools as
good policy. Yet the Seattle Court had little difficulty saying
that school integration as a general matter “inure[d]
. . . to the benefit of” the minority. 458
U. S., at 472.
My colleagues are of
the view that we should leave race out of the picture entirely and
let the voters sort it out. See ante, at 13 (plurality opinion)
(“Racial division would be validated, not discouraged, were
the Seattle formulation . . . to remain in force”);
ante, at 9 (Scalia, J., concurring in judgment)
(“ ‘[R]acial stereotyping [is] at odds with equal
protection mandates’ ”). We have seen this
reasoning before. See Parents Involved, 551 U. S., at 748
(“The way to stop discrimination on the basis of race is to
stop discriminating on the basis of race”). It is a sentiment
out of touch with reality, one not required by our Constitution,
and one that has properly been rejected as “not
sufficient” to resolve cases of this nature. Id., at 788
(Kennedy, J., concurring in part and concurring in judgment). While
“[t]he enduring hope is that race should not matter[,] the
reality is that too often it does.” Id., at 787.
“[R]acial discrimination . . . [is] not ancient
history.” Bartlett v. Strickland, 556 U. S. 1, 25 (2009)
(plurality opinion).
Race matters. Race
matters in part because of the long history of racial
minorities’ being denied access to the political process. See
Part I, supra; see also South Carolina v. Katzenbach, 383
U. S. 301, 309 (1966) (describingracial discrimination in
voting as “an insidious and pervasive evil which had been
perpetuated in certain parts of our country through unremitting and
ingenious defiance of the Constitution”). And although we
have made great strides, “voting discrimination still exists;
no one doubts that.” Shelby County, 570 U. S., at __ (slip
op., at 2).
Race also matters
because of persistent racial inequality in society—inequality
that cannot be ignored and that has produced stark socioeconomic
disparities. See Gratz, 539 U. S., at 298–300 (Ginsburg,
J., dissenting) (cataloging the many ways in which “the
effects of centuries of law-sanctioned inequality remain painfully
evident in our communities and schools,” in areas like
employment, poverty, access to health care, housing, consumer
transactions, and education); Adarand, 515 U. S., at 273
(Ginsburg, J., dissenting) (recognizing that the “lingering
effects” of discrimination, “reflective of a system of
racial caste only recently ended, are evident in our workplaces,
markets, and neighborhoods”).
And race matters for
reasons that really are only skin deep, that cannot be discussed
any other way, and that cannot be wished away. Race matters to a
young man’s view of society when he spends his teenage years
watching others tense up as he passes, no matter the neighborhood
where he grew up. Race matters to a young woman’s sense of
self when she states her hometown, and then is pressed, “No,
where are you really from?”, regardless of how many
generations her family has been in the country. Race matters to a
young person addressed by a stranger in a foreign language, which
he does not understand because only English was spoken at home.
Race matters because of the slights, the snickers, the silent
judgments that reinforce that most crippling of thoughts: “I
do not belong here.”
In my colleagues’
view, examining the racial impact of legislation only perpetuates
racial discrimination. This refusal to accept the stark reality
that race matters is regrettable. The way to stop discrimination on
the basis of race is to speak openly and candidly on the subject of
race, and to apply the Constitution with eyes open to the
unfortunate effects of centuries of racial discrimination. As
members of the judiciary tasked with intervening to carry out the
guarantee of equal protection, we ought not sit back and wish away,
rather than confront, the racial inequality that exists in our
society. It is this view that works harm, by perpetuating the
facile notion that what makes race matter is acknowledging the
simple truth that race does matter.
V
Although the only
constitutional rights at stake in this case are process-based
rights, the substantive policy at issue is undeniably of some
relevance to my colleagues. See ante, at 18 (plurality opinion)
(suggesting that race-sensitive admissions policies have the
“potential to become . . . the source of the
very resentments and hostilities based on race that this Nation
seeks to put behind it”). I will therefore speak in
response.
A
For over a century,
racial minorities in Michigan fought to bring diversity to their
State’s public colleges and universities. Before the advent
of race-sensitive admissions policies, those institutions, like
others around the country, were essentially segregated. In 1868,
two black students were admitted to the University of Michigan, the
first of their race. See Expert Report of James D. Anderson 4, in
Gratz v. Bollinger, No. 97–75231 (ED Mich.). In 1935, over
six decades later, there were still only 35 black students at the
University. Ibid. By 1954, this number had risen to slightly below
200. Ibid. And by 1966, to around 400, among a total student
population of roughly 32,500—barely over 1 percent. Ibid. The
numbers at the University of Michigan Law School are even more
telling. Duringthe 1960’s, the Law School produced 9 black
graduates among a total of 3,041—less than three-tenths of 1
percent. See App. in Grutter v. Bollinger, O. T. 2002, No.
02–241, p. 204.
The housing and
extracurricular policies at these institutions also perpetuated
open segregation. For instance, incoming students were permitted to
opt out of rooming with black students. Anderson, supra, at
7–8. And some fraternities and sororities excluded black
students from membership. Id., at 6–7.
In 1966, the Defense
Department conducted an investigation into the University’s
compliance with Title VI of the Civil Rights Act, and made 25
recommendations for increasing opportunities for minority students.
Id., at 9. In 1970, a student group launched a number of protests,
including a strike, demanding that the University increase its
minority enrollment. Id., at 16–23. The University’s
Board of Regents responded, adopting a goal of 10 percent black
admissions by the fall of 1973. Id., at 23.
During the
1970’s, the University continued to improve its admissions
policies,[ 15 ] encouraged by
this Court’s 1978 decision in Bakke. In that case, the Court
told our Nation’s colleges and universities that they could
consider race in admissions as part of a broader goal to create a
diverse student body, in which students of different backgrounds
would learn together, and thereby learn to live together. A little
more than a decade ago, in Grutter, the Court reaffirmed this
understanding. In upholding the admissions policy of the Law
School, the Court laid to rest any doubt whether student body
diversity is a compelling interest that may justify the use of
race.
Race-sensitive
admissions policies are now a thing of the past in Michigan after
§26, even though—as experts agree and as research
shows—those policies were making a difference in achieving
educational diversity. In Grutter, Michigan’s Law School
spoke candidly about the strides the institution had taken
successfully because of race-sensitive admissions. One expert
retained by the Law School opined that a race-blind admissions
system would have a “very dramatic, negative effect on
underrepresented minority admissions.” Grutter, 539
U. S., at 320 (inter-nal quotation marks omitted). He
testified that the school had admitted 35 percent of
underrepresented minority students who had applied in 2000, as
opposed to only 10 percent who would have been admitted had race
not been considered. Ibid. Underrepresented minority students would
thus have constituted 4 percent, as opposed to the actual 14.5
percent, of the class that entered in 2000. Ibid.
Michigan’s public
colleges and universities tell us the same today. The Board of
Regents of the University of Michigan and the Board of Trustees of
Michigan State University inform us that those institutions cannot
achieve the benefits of a diverse student body without
race-sensitive admissions plans. See Brief for Respondents Regents
of the University of Michigan, the Board of Trustees of Michigan
State University et al. 18–25. During proceedings before
the lower courts, several university officials testified that
§26 would depress minority enrollment at Michigan’s
public universities. The Director of Undergraduate Admissions at
the University of Michigan “expressed doubts over the ability
to maintain minority enrollment through the use of a proxy, like
socioeconomic status.” Supp. App. to Pet. for Cert. 285a. He
explained that university officials in States with laws similar to
§26 had not “ ‘achieve[d] the same sort of
racial and ethnic diversity that they had prior to such measures
. . . without considering race.’ ” Ibid.
Similarly, the Law School’s Dean of Admissions testified that
she expected “a decline in minority admissions because, in
her view, it is impossible ‘to get a critical mass of
underrepresented minorities . . . without
considering race.’ ” Ibid. And the Dean of Wayne
State University Law School stated that “although some
creative approaches might mitigate the effects of [§26], he
‘did not think that any one of these proposals or any
combination of these proposals was reasonably likely to result in
the admission of a class that had the same or similar or higher
numbers of African Americans, Latinos and Native Americans as the
prior policy.’ ” Ibid.
Michigan tells a
different story. It asserts that although the statistics are
difficult to track, “the number of underrepresented
minorities . . . [in] the entering freshman class at
Michigan as a percentage changed very little” after §26.
Tr. of Oral Arg. 15. It also claims that “the statistics in
California across the 17 campuses in the University of California
system show that today the underrepresented minority percentage is
better on 16 out of those 17 campuses”—all except
Berkeley—than before California’s equivalent initiative
took effect. Id., at 16. As it turns out, these statistics
weren’t “ ‘even good enough to be
wrong.’ ” Reference Manual on Scientific Evidence
4 (2d ed. 2000) (Introduction by Stephen G. Breyer (quoting
Wolfgang Pauli)).
Section 26 has already
led to decreased minority enrollment at Michigan’s public
colleges and universities. In 2006 (before §26 took effect),
underrepresented minorities made up 12.15 percent of the University
of Michigan’s freshman class, compared to 9.54 percent in
2012—a roughly 25 percent decline. See University of
Michigan—New Freshman Enrollment Overview, Office of the
Registrar, online at
http://www.ro.umich.edu/report/10enrolloverview.pdf and
http://www.ro.umich.edu/report/12enrollmentsummary.pdf.[ 16 ] Moreover, the total number of
college-aged underrepresented minorities in Michigan has increased
even as the number of underrepresented minorities admitted to the
University has decreased. For example, between 2006 and 2011, the
proportion of black freshmen among those enrolled at the University
of Michigan declined from 7 percent to 5 percent, even though the
proportion of black college-aged persons in Michigan increased from
16 to 19 percent. See Fessenden and Keller, How Minorities Have
Fared in States with Affirmative Action Bans, N. Y. Times,
June 24, 2013, online at
http://www.nytimes.com/interactive/2013/06/24/us/affirmative-action-bans.html.
UNIVERSITY OF MICHIGAN
Black Students[ 17 ]
A recent study also
confirms that §26 has decreased minority degree attainment in
Michigan. The University of Michigan’s graduating class of
2012, the first admitted after §26 took effect, is quite
different from previous classes. The proportion of black students
among those attaining bachelor’s degrees was 4.4 percent, the
lowest since 1991; the proportion of black students among those
attaining master’s degrees was 5.1 percent, the lowest since
1989; the proportion of black students among those attaining
doctoral degrees was 3.9 percent, the lowest since 1993; and the
proportion of black students among those attaining professional
school degrees was 3.5 percent, the lowest since the
mid-1970’s. See Kidder, Restructuring Higher Education
Opportunity?: African American Degree Attainment After
Michigan’s Ban on Affirmative Action, p. 1 (Aug. 2013),
online at http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/abstract=2318523.
The President and
Chancellors of the University of California (which has 10 campuses,
not 17) inform us that “[t]he abandonment of race-conscious
admissions policies resulted in an immediate and precipitous
decline in the rates at which underrepresented-minority students
applied to, were admitted to, and enrolled at” the
university. Brief for President and Chancellors of the University
of California as Amici Curiae 10 (hereinafter President and
Chancellors Brief). At the University of California, Los Angeles
(UCLA), for example, admission rates for underrepresented
minorities plummeted from 52.4 percent in 1995 (before
California’s ban took effect) to 24 percentin 1998. Id., at
12. As a result, the percentage of underrepresented minorities fell
by more than half: from 30.1 percent of the entering class in 1995
to 14.3 percent in 1998. Ibid. The admissions rate for
underrepresented minorities at UCLA reached a new low of 13.6
percent in 2012. See Brief for California Social Science
Researchers and Admissions Experts as Amici Curiae 28.
The elimination of
race-sensitive admissions policies in California has been
especially harmful to black students. In 2006, for example, there
were fewer than 100 black students in UCLA’s incoming class
of roughly 5,000, the lowest number since at least 1973. See id.,
at 24.
The University of
California also saw declines in minor-ity representation at its
graduate programs and professional schools. In 2005,
underrepresented minorities made up 17 percent of the
university’s new medical students, which is actually a lower
rate than the 17.4 percent reported in 1975, three years before
Bakke. President and Chancellors Brief 13. The numbers at the law
schools are even more alarming. In 2005, underrepresented
minorities made up 12 percent of entering law students, well below
the 20.1 percent in 1975. Id., at 14.
As in Michigan, the
declines in minority representation at the University of California
have come even as the minority population in California has
increased. At UCLA, for example, the proportion of Hispanic
freshmen among those enrolled declined from 23 percent in 1995 to
17 percent in 2011, even though the proportion of Hispanic
college-aged persons in California increased from 41 percent to 49
percent during that same period. See Fessenden and Keller.
UCLA
Hispanic Students[ 18 ]
And the proportion of
black freshmen among those enrolled at UCLA declined from 8 percent
in 1995 to 3 percent in 2011, even though the proportion of
blackcollege-aged persons in California increased from 8 percent to
9 percent during that same period. See ibid.
UCLA
Black Students[ 19 ]
While the minority
admissions rates at UCLA and Berkeley have decreased, the number of
minorities enrolled at colleges across the county has increased.
See Phillips, Colleges Straining to Restore Diversity: Bans on
Race-Conscious Admissions Upend Racial Makeup at California
Schools, Wall Street Journal, Mar. 7, 2014,p. A3.
BERKELEY AND UCLA[ 20 ]
The President and
Chancellors assure us that they have tried. They tell us that
notwithstanding the university’s efforts for the past 15
years “to increase diversity on [the University of
California’s] campuses through the use of race-neutral
initiatives,” enrollment rates have “not rebounded
. . . [or] kept pace with the demographic changes among
California’s graduating high-school population.”
President and Chancellors Brief 14. Since Proposition 209 took
effect, the university has spent over a half-billion dollars on
programs and policies designed to increase diversity. Phillips,
supra, at A3. Still, it has been unable to meet its diversity
goals. Ibid. Proposition 209, it says, has
“ ‘completely changed the character’ of the
university.” Ibid. (quoting the Associate President and Chief
Policy Advisor of the University of California).
B
These statistics may
not influence the views of some of my colleagues, as they question
the wisdom of adopting race-sensitive admissions policies and would
prefer if our Nation’s colleges and universities were to
discard those policies altogether. See ante, at 2 (Roberts,
C. J., concurring) (suggesting that race-sensitive admissions
policies might “do more harm than good”); ante, at 9,
n. 6 (Scalia, J., concurring in judgment); Grutter, 539
U. S., at 371–373 (Thomas, J., concurring in part and
dissenting in part); id., at 347–348 (Scalia, J., concurring
in part and dissenting in part). That view is at odds with our
recognition in Grutter, and more recently in Fisher v. University
of Texas at Austin, 570 U. S. ___ (2013), that race-sensitive
admissions policies are necessary to achieve a diverse student body
when race-neutral alternatives have failed. More fundamentally, it
ignores the importance of diversity in institutions of higher
education and reveals how little my colleagues understand about the
reality of race in America.
This Court has
recognized that diversity in education is paramount. With good
reason. Diversity ensures that the next generation moves beyond the
stereotypes, the assumptions, and the superficial perceptions that
students coming from less-heterogeneous communities may harbor,
consciously or not, about people who do not look like them.
Recognizing the need for diversity acknowledges that, “[j]ust
as growing up in a particular region or having particular
professional experiences is likely to affect an individual’s
views, so too is one’s own, unique experience of being a
racial minority in a society, like our own, in which race
unfortunately still matters.” Grutter, 539 U. S., at
333. And it acknowledges that “to cultivate a set of leaders
with legitimacy in the eyes of the citizenry, it is necessary that
the path to leadership be visibly open to talented and qualified
individuals of every race and ethnicity.” Id., at 332.
Colleges and
universities must be free to prioritize the goal of diversity. They
must be free to immerse their students in a multiracial environment
that fosters frequent and meaningful interactions with students of
other races, and thereby pushes such students to transcend any
assumptions they may hold on the basis of skin color. Without
race-sensitive admissions policies, this might well be impossible.
The statistics I have described make that fact glaringly obvious.
We should not turn a blind eye to something we cannot help but
see.
To be clear, I do not
mean to suggest that the virtues of adopting race-sensitive
admissions policies should inform the legal question before the
Court today regarding the constitutionality of §26. But I
cannot ignore the unfortunate outcome of today’s decision:
Short of amending the State Constitution, a Herculean task, racial
minorities in Michigan are deprived of even an opportunity to
convince Michigan’s public colleges and universities to
consider race in their admissions plans when other attempts to
achieve racial diversity have proved unworkable, and those
institutions are unnecessarily hobbled in their pursuit of a
diverse student body.
* * *
The Constitution does
not protect racial minorities from political defeat. But neither
does it give the majority free rein to erect selective barriers
against racial minorities. The political-process doctrine polices
the channels of change to ensure that the majority, when it wins,
does so without rigging the rules of the game to ensure its
success. Today, the Court discards that doctrine without good
reason.
In doing so, it permits
the decision of a majority of the voters in Michigan to strip
Michigan’s elected university boards of their authority to
make decisions with respect to constitutionally permissible
race-sensitive admissions policies, while preserving the
boards’ plenary authority to make all other educational
decisions. “In a most direct sense, this implicates the
judiciary’s special role in safeguarding the interests of
those groups that are relegated to such a position of political
powerlessness as to command extraordinary protection from the
majoritarian political process.” Seattle, 458 U. S., at
486 (internal quotation marks omitted). The Court abdicates that
role, permitting the majority to use its numerical advantage to
change the rules mid-contest and forever stack the deck against
racial minorities in Michigan. The result is that Michigan’s
public colleges and universities are less equipped to do their part
in ensuring that students of all races are “better prepare[d]
. . . for an increasingly diverse workforce and society
. . .” Grutter, 539 U. S., at 330 (internal
quotation marks omitted).
Today’s decision
eviscerates an important strand of our equal protection
jurisprudence. For members of historically marginalized groups,
which rely on the federal courts to protect their constitutional
rights, the decision can hardly bolster hope for a vision of
democracy that preserves for all the right to participate
meaningfully and equally in self-government.
I respectfully
dissent. Notes 1 I of course do not mean
to suggest that Michigan’s voters acted with anything like
the invidious intent, see n. 8, , of those who historically
stymied the rights of racial minorities. Contra, at 18, n. 11
(, concurring in judgment). But like earlier chapters of political
restructuring, the Michigan amendment at issue in this case changed
the rules of the political process to the disadvantage of minor-ity
members of our society. 2 Although the term
“affirmative action” is commonly used to describe
colleges’ and universities’ use of race in crafting
admissions policies, I instead use the term “race-sensitive
admissions policies.” Some comprehend the term
“affirmative action” as connoting intentional
preferential treatment based on race alone—for example, the
use of a quota system, whereby a certain proportion of seats in an
institution’s incoming class must be set aside for racial
minorities; the use of a “points” system, whereby an
institution accords a fixed numerical advantage to an applicant
because of her race; or the admission of otherwise unqualified
students to an institution solely on account of their race. None of
this is an accurate description of the practices that public
universities are permitted to adopt after this Court’s
decision in v. , . There, we instructed that institutions of higher
education could consider race in admissions in only a very limited
way in an effort to create a diverse student body. To comport with
, colleges and universities must use race flexibly, at 334, and
must not maintain a quota, And even this limited sensitivity to
race must be limited in time, at 341–343, and must be
employed only after “serious, good faith consideration of
workable race-neutral alternatives,” at 339. -compliant
admissions plans, like the ones in place at Michigan’s
institutions, are thus a far cry from affirmative action plans that
confer preferential treatment intention-ally and solely on the
basis of race. 3 In , the Court confronted
an amendment to the California Constitution prohibiting state
courts from mandating pupil assignments unless a federal court
would be required to do so under the Equal Protection Clause. We
upheld the amendment as nothing more than a repeal of existing
legislation: The standard previously required by California went
beyond what was federally required; the amendment merely moved the
standard back to the federal baseline. The Court distinguished the
amendment from the one in because it left the rules of the
political game unchanged. Racial minorities in , unlike racial
minorities in , could still appeal to their local school districts
for relief. 4 accuses me of crafting my
own version (or versions) of the racial-focus prong. See at
8–9, n. 4 (opinion concurring in judgment). I do not. I
simply apply the test announced in : whether the policy in question
“inures primarily to the benefit of the minority.” 458
U. S., at 472. ignores this analysis, see Part II–B–1,
, and instead purports to identify three versions of the test that
he thinks my opinion advances. The first—whether
“ ‘the policy in question only a racial
minority, ’ ” at 8, n. 4 (quoting at
5)—misunderstands the doctrine and misquotes my opinion. The
racial-focus prong has never required a policy to benefit a
minority group. The sentence from which appears to quote makes the
altogether different point that the political-process doctrine is
obviously not implicated in the first place by a restructuring that
burdens members of society equally. This is the second prong of the
political-process doctrine. See at 5 (explaining that the
political-process doctrine is implicated “[w]hen the majority
reconfigures the political process in a manner that burdens only a
racial minority”). The second version—which asks
whether a policy “benefits a racial minority,” at 8,
n. 4—is the one articulated by the Court and, as I have
explained, see at 15 and this page, it is easily met in this case.
And the third—whether the policy has “the incidental
effect” of benefitting racial minorities,” at
8–9, n. 4—is not a test I advance at
all. 5 By stripping the
governing boards of the authority to decide whether to adopt
race-sensitive admissions policies, the majority removed the
decision from bodies well suited to make that decision: boards
engaged in the arguments on both sides of a matter, which
deliberate andthen make and refine “considered
judgment[s]” about racial diversity and admissions policies,
see , 539 U. S., at 387 (, J., dissenting). 6 In the face of this
overwhelming evidence, claims that it is actually easier, not
harder, for minorities to effectuate change at the constitutional
amendment level than at the board level. See at 11–12
(opinion concurring in judgment) (“voting in a favorable
board (each of which has eight members) at the three major public
universities requires electing by majority vote at least 15
different candidates, several of whom would be running during
different election cycles”). This claim minimizes just how
difficult it is to amend the State Constitution. See , at
18–20. It is also incorrect in its premise that minorities
must elect an entirely new slate of board members in order to
effectuate change at the board level. overlooks the fact that
minorities need not elect any new board members in order to effect
change; they may instead seek to persuade existing board members to
adopt changes in their interests. 7 I do not take the
position, as asserts, that the process of amending the Michigan
Constitution is not a part of Michigan’s existing political
process. See at 13–14 (opinion concurring in judgment). It
clearly is. The problem with §26 is not that “amending
Michigan’s Constitution is simply not a part of that
State’s ‘existing political
process.’ ” at 14. It is that §26
reconfigured the political process in Michigan such that it is now
more difficult for racial minorities, and racial minorities alone,
to achieve legislation in their interest. Section 26 elevated the
issue of race-sensitive admissions policies,and not any other kinds
of admissions policies, to a higher plane ofthe existing political
process in Michigan: that of a constitutional
amendment. 8 It certainly is fair to
assume that some voters may have supported the amendment because of
discriminatory animus. But others may have been motivated by their
strong beliefs in the freedom of contract or the freedom to
alienate property. Similarly, here, although some Michiganders may
have voted for §26 out of racial animus, some may have been
acting on a personal belief, like that of some of my colleagues
today, that using race-sensitive admissions policies in higher
education is unwise. The presence (or absence) of invidious
discrimination has no place in the current analysis. That is the
very purpose of the political-process doctrine; it operates
irrespective of discriminatory intent, for it protects a
process-based right. 9 The plurality relies on s
dissent in to conclude that “one permissible reading of the
record was that the school board had maintained policies to
perpetuate racial segregation in the schools.” at 9–10.
Remarkably, some Members of today’s plurality criticized
’s reading of the record in itself. See 551 U. S., at
736. 10 Under
the bylaws of the University of Michigan’s Board of Regents,
“[a]ny and all delegations of authority made at any time and
from time to time by the board to any member of the university
staff, or to any unit of the university may be revoked by the board
at any time, and notice of such revocation shall be given in
writing.” Bylaws §14.04, online at
http://www.regents.umich.edu/bylaws. 11 Attempts by the majority to make it
more difficult for the minority to exercise its right to vote are,
sadly, not a thing of the past. See v. , 570 U. S. ___, ___
(2013) (slip op., at 15–17) ( dissenting) (describing recent
examples of discriminatory changes to state voting laws, including
a 1995 dual voter registration system in Mississippi to
disfranchise black voters, a 2000 redistricting plan in Georgia to
decrease black voting strength, and a 2003 proposal to change the
voting mechanism for school board elections in South Carolina).
Until this Court’s decision last Term in , the preclearance
requirement of §5 of the Voting Rights Act of 1965 blocked
those and many other discriminatory changes to voting
procedures. 12 Preserving the right to participate
meaningfully and equally in the process of government is especially
important with respect to education policy. I do not mean to
suggest that “the constitutionality of laws forbidding racial
preferences depends on the policy interest at stake.” , at
14–15 (plurality opinion). I note only that we have long
recognized that “ ‘education . . . is
the very foundation of good citizenship.’ ” , 539
U. S., at 331 (quoting v. , ). Our Nation’s colleges and
universities “represent the training ground for a large
number of our Nation’s leaders,” and so there is
special reason to safeguard the guarantee “ ‘that
public institutions are open and available to all segments of
American society, including people of all races and
ethnicities.’ ” 539 U. S., at
331–332. 13 The
Court invalidated Amendment 2 on the basis that it lacked any
rational relationship to a legitimate end. It concluded that the
amendment “impose[d] a broad and undifferentiated disability
on a single named group,” and was “so discontinuous
with the reasons offered for it that [it] seem[ed] inexplicable by
anything but animus toward the class it affect[ed].” , 517
U. S., at 632 14 The
plurality raises another concern with respect to precedent. It
points to decisions by the California Supreme Court and the United
States Court of Appeals for the Ninth Circuit upholding as
constitutional Proposition 209, a California constitutional
amendment identical in substance to §26. , at 14. The
plurality notes that if we were to affirm the lower court’s
decision in this case, “those holdings would be invalidated
. . . .” I fail to see the significance. We
routinely resolve conflicts between lower courts; the necessary
result, of course, is that decisions of courts on one side of the
debate are invalidated or called into question. I am unaware of a
single instance where that (inevitable) fact influenced the
Court’s decision one way or the other. Had the lower courts
proceeded in opposite fashion—had the California Supreme
Court and Ninth Circuit invalidated Proposition 209 and the Sixth
Circuit upheld §26—would the plurality come out the
other way? 15 In
1973, the Law School graduated 41 black students (out of a class of
446) and the first Latino student in its history. App. in v. ,
O. T. 2002, No. 02–241, p. 204. In 1976, it graduated
its first Native American student. On the whole, during the
1970’s, the Law School graduated 262 black students, compared
to 9 in the previous decade, along with 41 Latino
students. 16 These
percentages include enrollment statistics for black students,
Hispanic students, Native American students, and students who
identify as members of two or more underrepresented minority
groups. 17 This
chart is reproduced from Fessenden and Keller, How Minorities Have
Fared in States with Affirmative Action Bans, N. Y. Times, June 24,
2013, online at
http://www.nytimes.com/interactive/2013/06/24/us/affirmative-action-bans.html. 18 19 20 This
chart is reproduced from Phillips, Colleges Straining to Restore
Diversity: Bans on Race-Conscious Admissions Upend Racial Makeup at
California Schools, Wall Street Journal, Mar. 7, 2014, p.
A3. | The Supreme Court of the United States reviewed the constitutionality of a Michigan state constitutional amendment (Proposal 2) that prohibited state universities from considering race in admissions decisions. The Court found that the amendment did not violate the Equal Protection Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment, overturning the Sixth Circuit Court of Appeals' decision. The Court's decision affirmed the validity of similar amendments in other states, such as California's Proposition 209. The Court's ruling highlighted the importance of public education and the role of universities in fostering diverse leadership, but ultimately concluded that the Michigan amendment did not impose a burden on racial minorities with respect to the educational benefits afforded by the university. The Court also noted the significant increase in minority enrollment and graduation rates at the university post-Proposal 2, underscoring the amendment's positive impact on minority groups. |
Immigration & National Security | Yick Wo v. Hopkins | https://supreme.justia.com/cases/federal/us/118/356/ | U.S. Supreme Court Yick Wo v. Hopkins, 118
U.S. 356 (1886) Yick Wo v. Hopkins Submitted April 14,
1886 Decided May 10, 1886 118
U.S. 356 APPEAL FROM THE CIRCUIT COURT OF
THE UNITED STATES FOR THE DISTRICT OF
CALIFORNIA Syllabus In a suit brought to this court from a State court which
involves the constitutionality of ordinances made by a municipal
corporation in the State, this court will, when necessary, put its
own independent construction upon the ordinances.
A municipal ordinance to regulate the carrying on of public
laundries within the limits of the municipality violates the
provisions of the Constitution of the United States if it confers
upon the municipal authorities arbitrary power, at their own will,
and without regard to discretion in the legal sense of the term, to
give or withhold consent as to persons or places, without regard to
the competency of the persons applying, or the propriety of the
place selected, for the carrying on of the business.
An administration of a municipal ordinance for the carrying on
of a lawful business within the corporate limits violates the
provisions of the Constitution of the United States if it makes
arbitrary and unjust discriminations, founded on differences of
race between persons otherwise in similar circumstances.
The guarantees of protection contained in the Fourteenth
Amendment to the Constitution extend to all persons within the
territorial jurisdiction of the United States, without regard to
differences of race, of color, or of nationality.
Those subjects of the Emperor of China who have the right to
temporarily or permanently reside within the United States, are
entitled to enjoy the protection guaranteed by the Constitution and
afforded by the laws.
These two cases were argued as one, and depended upon precisely
the same state of facts; the first coming here upon a writ of error
to the Supreme Court of the State of California, the second on
appeal from the Circuit Court of the United States for that
district. The plaintiff in error, Yick Wo, on August 4, 1885,
petitioned the Supreme Court of California for a writ of habeas
corpus, alleging that he was illegally deprived of his personal Page 118 U. S. 357 liberty by the defendant as sheriff of the city and county of
San Francisco.
The sheriff made return to the writ that he held the petitioner
in custody by virtue of a sentence of the Police Judges Court, No.
2, of the city and county of San Francisco, whereby he was found
guilty of a violation of certain ordinances of the board of
supervisors of that county, and adjudged to pay a fine of $10, and,
in default of payment, be imprisoned in the county jail at the rate
of one day for each dollar of fine until said fine should be
satisfied, and a commitment in consequence of nonpayment of said
fine.
The ordinances for the violation of which he had been found
guilty were set out as follows:
Order No. 156, passed May 26, 1880, prescribing the kind of
buildings in which laundries may be located.
"The people of the city and county of San Francisco do ordain as
follows:"
"SEC. 1. It shall be unlawful, from and after the passage of
this order, for any person or persons to establish, maintain, or
carry on a laundry within the corporate limits of the city and
county of San Francisco without having first obtained the consent
of the board of supervisors, except the same be located in a
building constructed either of brick or stone."
"SEC. 2. It shall be unlawful for any person to erect, build, or
maintain, or cause to be erected, built, or maintained, over or
upon the roof of any building now erected or which may hereafter be
erected within the limits of said city and county, any scaffolding
without first obtaining the written permission of the board of
supervisors, which permit shall state fully for what purpose said
scaffolding is to be erected and used, and such scaffolding shall
not be used for any other purpose than that designated in such
permit."
"SEC. 3. Any person who shall violate any of the provisions of
this order shall be deemed guilty of a misdemeanor, and upon
conviction thereof shall be punished by a fine of not more than one
thousand dollars, or by imprisonment in the county jail not more
than six months, or by both such fine and imprisonment. " Page 118 U. S. 358 Order No. 1587, passed July 28, 1880, the following section:
"SEC. 68. It shall be unlawful, from and after the passage of
this order, for any person or persons to establish, maintain, or
carry on a laundry within the corporate limits of the city and
county of San Francisco without having first obtained the consent
of the board of supervisors, except the same be located in a
building constructed either of brick or stone."
The following facts were also admitted on the record: that
petitioner is a native of China and came to California in 1861, and
is still a subject of the Emperor of China; that he has been
engaged in the laundry business in the same premises and building
for twenty-two years last past; that he had a license from the
board of fire wardens, dated March 3, 1884, from which it
appeared
"that the above described premises have been inspected by the
board of fire wardens, and upon such inspection said board found
all proper arrangements for carrying on the business; that the
stoves, washing and drying apparatus, and the appliances for
heating smoothing irons are in good condition, and that their use
is not dangerous to the surrounding property from fire, and that
all proper precautions have been taken to comply with the
provisions of order No. 1617, defining 'the fire limits of the city
and county of San Francisco and making regulations concerning the
erection and use of buildings in said city and county,' and of
order No. 1670, 'prohibiting the kindling, maintenance, and use of
open fires in houses;' that he had a certificate from the health
officer that the same premises had been inspected by him, and that
he found that they were properly and sufficiently drained, and that
all proper arrangements for carrying on the business of a laundry,
without injury to the sanitary condition of the neighborhood, had
been complied with; that the city license of the petitioner was in
force and expired October 1st, 1885, and that the petitioner
applied to the board of supervisors, June 1st, 1885, for consent of
said board to maintain and carry on his laundry, but that said
board, on July 1st, 1885, refused said consent."
It is also admitted to be true, as alleged in the petition,
that, on February 24, 1880,
"there were about 320 laundries in the city and county of San
Francisco, of which Page 118 U. S. 359 about 240 were owned and conducted by subjects of China, and of
the whole number, viz., 320, about 310 were constructed of
wood, the same material that constitutes nine-tenths of the houses
in the city of San Francisco. The capital thus invested by the
subjects of China was not less than two hundred thousand dollars,
and they paid annually for rent, license, taxes, gas, and water
about one hundred and eighty thousand dollars."
It was alleged in the petition, that
"your petitioner and more than one hundred and fifty of his
countrymen have been arrested upon the charge of carrying on
business without having such special consent, while those who are
not subjects of China, and who are conducting eighty odd laundries
under similar conditions, are left unmolested and free to enjoy the
enhanced trade and profits arising from this hurtful and unfair
discrimination. The business of your petitioner, and of those of
his countrymen similarly situated, is greatly impaired, and in many
cases practically ruined, by this system of oppression to one kind
of men and favoritism to all others."
The statement therein contained as to the arrest, &c., was
admitted to be true, with the qualification only that the eighty
odd laundries referred to are in wooden buildings without scaffolds
on the roofs.
It was also admitted
"that petitioner and 200 of his countrymen similarly situated
petitioned the board of supervisors for permission to continue
their business in the various houses which they had been occupying
and using for laundries for more than twenty years, and such
petitions were denied, and all the petitions of those who were not
Chinese, with one exception of Mrs. Mary Meagles, were
granted."
By section 2 of article I of the Constitution of California, it
is provided that
"any county, city town, or township may make and enforce within
its limits all such local, police, sanitary, and other regulations
as are not in conflict with general laws."
By section 74 of the Act of April 19, 1856, usually known as the
consolidation act, the board of supervisors is empowered, among
other things,
"to provide by regulation for the prevention and summary removal
of nuisances to public health, the Page 118 U. S. 360 prevention of contagious diseases; . . . to prohibit the
erection of wooden buildings within any fixed limits where the
streets shall have been established and graded; . . . to regulate
the sale, storage, and use of gunpowder or other explosive or
combustible materials and substances, and make all needful
regulations for protection against fire; to make such regulations
concerning the erection and use of buildings as may be necessary
for the safety of the inhabitants."
The Supreme Court of California, in the opinion pronouncing the
judgment in this case, said:
"The board of supervisors, under the several statutes conferring
authority upon them, has the power to prohibit or regulate all
occupations which are against good morals, contrary to public order
and decency, or dangerous to the public safety. Clothes washing is
certainly not opposed to good morals or subversive of public order
or decency, but, when conducted in given localities, it may be
highly dangerous to the public safety. Of this fact, the
supervisors are made the judges, and, having taken action in the
premises, we do not find that they have prohibited the
establishment of laundries, but that they have, as they well might
do, regulated the places at which they should be established, the
character of the buildings in which they are to be maintained, etc.
The process of washing is not prohibited by thus regulating the
places at which and the surroundings by which it must be exercised.
The order No. 1569 and section 68 of order No. 1587 are not in
contravention of common right or unjust, unequal, partial, or
oppressive in such sense as authorizes us in this proceeding to
pronounce them invalid."
After answering the position taken in behalf of the petitioner,
that the ordinances in question had been repealed, the court
added:
"We have not deemed it necessary to discuss the question in the
light of supposed infringement of petitioner's rights under the
Constitution of the United States, for the reason that we think the
principles upon which contention on that head can be based have in
effect been set at rest by the cases of Barbier v.
Connolly, 113 U. S. 27 , and Soon Hing
v. Crowley, 113 U. S. 703 ."
The writ was accordingly discharged, and the prisoner
remanded. Page 118 U. S. 361 In the other case, the appellant, Wo Lee, petitioned for his
discharge from an alleged illegal imprisonment upon a state of
facts shown upon the record precisely similar to that in the case
of Yick Wo. In disposing of the application, the learned Circuit
Judge, Sawyer, in his opinion, 26 Fed.Rep. 471, after quoting the
ordinance in question, proceeded at length as follows:
"Thus, in a territory some ten miles wide by fifteen or more
miles long, much of it still occupied as mere farming and pasturage
lands and much of it unoccupied sand banks, in many places without
a building within a quarter or half a mile of each other, including
the isolated and almost wholly unoccupied Goat Island, the right to
carry on this, when properly guarded, harmless and necessary
occupation, in a wooden building is not made to depend upon any
prescribed conditions giving a right to anybody complying with
them, but upon the consent or arbitrary will of the board of
supervisors. In three-fourths of the territory covered by the
ordinance, there is no more need of prohibiting or regulating
laundries than if they were located in any portion of the farming
regions of the State. Hitherto, the regulation of laundries has
been limited to the thickly settled portions of the city. Why this
unnecessary extension of the limits affected, if not designed to
prevent the establishment of laundries, after a compulsory removal
from their present locations, within practicable reach of the
customers or their proprietors? And the uncontradicted petition
shows that all Chinese applications are, in fact, denied, and those
of Caucasians granted -- thus, in fact, making the discriminations
in the administration of the ordinance, which its terms permit. The
fact that the right to give consent is reserved in the ordinance
shows that carrying on the laundry business in wooden buildings is
not deemed, of itself, necessarily dangerous. It must be apparent
to every well informed mind that a fire, properly guarded, for
laundry purposes, in a wooden building, is just as necessary, and
no more dangerous, than a fire for cooking purposes or for warming
a house. If the ordinance under consideration is valid, then the
board of supervisors can pass a valid ordinance preventing the
maintenance, in a wooden Page 118 U. S. 362 building, of a cooking stove, heating apparatus, or a
restaurant, within the boundaries of the city and county of San
Francisco, without the consent of that body, arbitrarily given or
withheld, as their prejudices or other motives may dictate. If it
is competent for the board of supervisors to pass a valid ordinance
prohibiting the inhabitants of San Francisco from following any
ordinary, proper, and necessary calling within the limits of the
city and county except at its arbitrary and unregulated discretion
and special consent, and it can do so if this ordinance is valid,
then it seems to us that there has been a wide departure from the
principles that have heretofore been supposed to guard and protect
the rights, property, and liberties of the American people. And if,
by an ordinance, general in its terms and form like the one in
question, by reserving an arbitrary discretion in the enacting body
to grant or deny permission to engage in a proper and necessary
calling, a discrimination against any class can be made in its
execution, thereby evading and, in effect, nullifying the
provisions of the National Constitution, then the insertion of
"
brk:
provisions to guard the rights of every class and person in that
instrument was a vain and futile act. The effect of the execution
of this ordinance in the manner indicated in the record would seem
to be necessarily to close up the many Chinese laundries now
existing, or compel their owners to pull down their present
buildings and reconstruct of brick or stone, or to drive them
outside the city and county of San Francisco to the adjoining
counties, beyond the convenient reach of customers, either of which
results would be little short of absolute confiscation of the large
amount of property shown to be now, and to have been for a long
time, invested in these occupations. If this would not be depriving
such parties of their property without due process of law, it would
be difficult to say what would effect that prohibited result. The
necessary tendency, if not the specific purpose, of this ordinance,
and of enforcing it in the manner indicated in the record, is to
drive out of business all the numerous small laundries, especially
those owned by Chinese, and give a monopoly of the business to the
large institutions established and carried on by means of large
associated Caucasian capital. If the facts appearing on the
face Page 118 U. S. 363 of the ordinance, on the petition and return, and admitted in
the case and shown by the notorious public and municipal history of
the times indicate a purpose to drive out the Chinese laundrymen,
and not merely to regulate the business for the public safety, does
it not disclose a case of violation of the provisions of the
Fourteenth Amendment to the National Constitution, and of the
treaty between the United States and China, in more than one
particular? . . . If this means prohibition of the occupation and
destruction of the business and property of the Chinese laundrymen
in San Francisco -- and it seems to us this must be the effect of
executing the ordinance -- and not merely the proper regulation of
the business, then there is discrimination and a violation of other
highly important rights secured by the Fourteenth Amendment and the
treaty. That it does mean prohibition as to the Chinese it seems to
us must be apparent to every citizen of San Francisco who has been
here long enough to be familiar with the cause of an active and
aggressive branch of public opinion and of public notorious events.
Can a court be blind to what must be necessarily known to every
intelligent person in the State? See Ah Kow v. Nunan, 5
Sawyer, 552, 560; Sparrow v.
Strong , 3 Wall. 97, 70 U. S. 104 ; Brown v. Piper, 91 U. S. 37 , 91 U. S. 42 .
But, in deference to the decision of the Supreme Court of
California in the case of Yick Wo, and contrary to his own
opinion as thus expressed, the circuit judge discharged the writ
and remanded the prisoner. Page 118 U. S. 365 Mr. JUSTICE MATTHEWS delivered the opinion of the court.
In the case of the petitioner, brought here by writ of error to
the Supreme Court of California, our jurisdiction is limited to the
question whether the plaintiff in error has been denied a right in
violation of the Constitution, laws, or treaties of the United
States. The question whether his imprisonment is illegal under the
constitution and lass of the State is not open to us. And although
that question might have been considered Page 118 U. S. 366 in the Circuit Court in the application made to it, and by this
court on appeal from its order, yet judicial propriety is best
consulted by accepting the judgment of the State court upon the
points involved in that inquiry.
That, however, does not preclude this court from putting upon
the ordinances of the supervisors of the county and city of San
Francisco an independent construction, for the determination of the
question whether the proceedings under these ordinances and in
enforcement of them are in conflict with the Constitution and laws
of the United States necessarily involves the meaning of the
ordinance, which, for that purpose, we are required to ascertain
and adjudge.
We are consequently constrained, at the outset, to differ from
the Supreme Court of California upon the real meaning of the
ordinances in question. That court considered these ordinances as
vesting in the board of supervisors a not unusual discretion in
granting or withholding their assent to the use of wooden buildings
as laundries, to be exercised in reference to the circumstances of
each case with a view to the protection of the public against the
dangers of fire. We are not able to concur in that interpretation
of the power conferred upon the supervisors. There is nothing in
the ordinances which points to such a regulation of the business of
keeping and conducting laundries. They seem intended to confer, and
actually do confer, not a discretion to be exercised upon a
consideration of the circumstances of each case, but a naked and
arbitrary power to give or withhold consent not only as to places,
but as to persons. So that, if an applicant for such consent, being
in every way a competent and qualified person and having complied
with every reasonable condition demanded by any public interest,
should, failing to obtain the requisite consent of the supervisors
to the prosecution of his business, apply for redress by the
judicial process of mandamus to require the supervisors to consider
and act upon his case, it would be a sufficient answer for them to
say that the law had conferred upon them authority to withhold
their assent without reason and without responsibility. The power
given to them is not confided to their discretion in the legal
sense of that term, but is granted Page 118 U. S. 367 to their mere will. It is purely arbitrary, and acknowledges
neither guidance nor restraint.
This erroneous view of the ordinances in question led the
Supreme Court of California into the further error of holding that
they were justified by the decisions of this court in the cases of Barbier v. Connolly, 113 U. S. 27 , and Soon Hing v. Crowley, 113 U. S. 703 . In
both of these cases, the ordinance involved was simply a
prohibition to carry on the washing and ironing of clothes in
public laundries and washhouses within certain prescribed limits of
the city and county of San Francisco from ten o'clock at night
until six o'clock in the morning of the following day. This
provision was held to be purely a police regulation within the
competency of any municipality possessed of the ordinary powers
belonging to such bodies, a necessary measure of precaution in a
city composed largely of wooden buildings like San Francisco, in
the application of which there was no invidious discrimination
against anyone within the prescribed limits, all persons engaged in
the same business being treated alike, and subject to the same
restrictions and entitled to the same privileges under similar
conditions.
For these reasons, that ordinance was adjudged not to be within
the prohibitions of the Fourteenth Amendment to the Constitution of
the United States, which, it was said in the first case cited,
"undoubtedly intended not only that there should be no arbitrary
deprivation of life or liberty, or arbitrary spoliation of
property, but that equal protection and security should be given to
all under like circumstances in the enjoyment of their personal and
civil rights; that all persons should be equally entitled to pursue
their happiness and acquire and enjoy property; that they should
have like access to the courts of the country for the protection of
their persons and property, the prevention and redress of wrongs,
and the enforcement of contracts; that no impediment should be
interposed to the pursuits of anyone except as applied to the same
pursuits by others under like circumstances; that no greater
burdens should be laid upon one than are laid upon others in the
same calling and condition; and that, in the administration of
criminal justice no different or higher punishment should be
imposed upon Page 118 U. S. 368 one than such as is prescribed to all for like offences. . . .
Class legislation, discriminating against some and favoring others,
is prohibited, but legislation which, in carrying out a public
purpose, is limited in its application if, within the sphere of its
operation, it affects alike all persons similarly situated, is not
within the amendment."
The ordinance drawn in question in the present case is of a very
different character. It does not prescribe a rule and conditions
for the regulation of the use of property for laundry purposes to
which all similarly situated may conform. It allows without
restriction the use for such purposes of buildings of brick or
stone, but, as to wooden buildings, constituting nearly all those
in previous use, it divides the owners or occupiers into two
classes, not having respect to their personal character and
qualifications for the business, nor the situation and nature and
adaptation of the buildings themselves, but merely by an arbitrary
line, on one side of which are those who are permitted to pursue
their industry by the mere will and consent of the supervisors, and
on the other those from whom that consent is withheld at their mere
will and pleasure. And both classes are alike only in this, that
they are tenants at will, under the supervisors, of their means of
living. The ordinance, therefore, also differs from the not unusual
case where discretion is lodged by law in public officers or bodies
to grant or withhold licenses to keep taverns, or places for the
sale of spirituous liquors, and the like, when one of the
conditions is that the applicant shall be a fit person for the
exercise of the privilege, because, in such cases, the fact of
fitness is submitted to the judgment of the officer, and calls for
the exercise of a discretion of a judicial nature.
The rights of the petitioners, as affected by the proceedings of
which they complain, are not less because they are aliens and
subjects of the Emperor of China. By the third article of the
treaty between this Government and that of China, concluded
November 17, 1880, 22 Stat. 827, it is stipulated:
"If Chinese laborers, or Chinese of any other class, now either
permanently or temporarily residing in the territory of the United
States, meet with ill treatment at the hands of any other
persons, Page 118 U. S. 369 the Government of the United States will exert all its powers to
devise measures for their protection, and to secure to them the
same rights, privileges, immunities and exemptions as may be
enjoyed by the citizens or subjects of the most favored nation, and
to which they are entitled by treaty."
The Fourteenth Amendment to the Constitution is not confined to
the protection of citizens. It says:
"Nor shall any State deprive any person of life, liberty, or
property without due process of law; nor deny to any person within
its jurisdiction the equal protection of the laws."
These provisions are universal in their application to all
persons within the territorial jurisdiction, without regard to any
differences of race, of color, or of nationality, and the equal
protection of the laws is a pledge of the protection of equal laws.
It is accordingly enacted by § 1977 of the Revised Statutes,
that
"all persons within the jurisdiction of the United States shall
have the same right in every State and Territory to make and
enforce contracts, to sue, be parties, give evidence, and to the
full and equal benefit of all laws and proceedings for the security
of persons and property as is enjoyed by white citizens and shall
be subject to like punishment, pains, penalties, taxes, licenses,
and exactions of every kind, and to no other."
The questions we have to consider and decide in these cases,
therefore, are to be treated as invoking the rights of every
citizen of the United States equally with those of the strangers
and aliens who now invoke the jurisdiction of the court.
It is contended on the part of the petitioners that the
ordinances for violations of which they are severally sentenced to
imprisonment are void on their face as being within the
prohibitions of the Fourteenth Amendment, and, in the alternative,
if not so, that they are void by reason of their administration,
operating unequally so as to punish in the present petitioners what
is permitted to others as lawful, without any distinction of
circumstances -- an unjust and illegal discrimination, it is
claimed, which, though not made expressly by the ordinances, is
made possible by them.
When we consider the nature and the theory of our institutions
of government, the principles upon which they are supposed Page 118 U. S. 370 to rest, and review the history of their development, we are
constrained to conclude that they do not mean to leave room for the
play and action of purely personal and arbitrary power. Sovereignty
itself is, of course, not subject to law, for it is the author and
source of law; but, in our system, while sovereign powers are
delegated to the agencies of government, sovereignty itself remains
with the people, by whom and for whom all government exists and
acts. And the law is the definition and limitation of power. It is,
indeed, quite true that there must always be lodged somewhere, and
in some person or body, the authority of final decision, and in
many cases of mere administration, the responsibility is purely
political, no appeal lying except to the ultimate tribunal of the
public judgment, exercised either in the pressure of opinion or by
means of the suffrage. But the fundamental rights to life, liberty,
and the pursuit of happiness, considered as individual possessions,
are secured by those maxims of constitutional law which are the
monuments showing the victorious progress of the race in securing
to men the blessings of civilization under the reign of just and
equal laws, so that, in the famous language of the Massachusetts
Bill of Rights, the government of the commonwealth "may be a
government of laws, and not of men." For the very idea that one man
may be compelled to hold his life, or the means of living, or any
material right essential to the enjoyment of life at the mere will
of another seems to be intolerable in any country where freedom
prevails, as being the essence of slavery itself.
There are many illustrations that might be given of this truth,
which would make manifest that it was self-evident in the light of
our system of jurisprudence. The case of the political franchise of
voting is one. Though not regarded strictly as a natural right, but
as a privilege merely conceded by society according to its will
under certain conditions, nevertheless it is regarded as a
fundamental political right, because preservative of all
rights.
In reference to that right, it was declared by the Supreme
Judicial Court of Massachusetts, in Capen v. Foster, 12
Pick. 485, 489, in the words of Chief Justice Shaw,
"that, in all Page 118 U. S. 371 cases where the constitution has conferred a political right or
privilege, and where the constitution has not particularly
designated the manner in which that right is to be exercised, it is
clearly within the just and constitutional limits of the
legislative power to adopt any reasonable and uniform regulations,
in regard to the time and mode of exercising that right, which are
designed to secure and facilitate the exercise of such right, in a
prompt, orderly, and convenient manner;"
nevertheless,
"such a construction would afford no warrant for such an
exercise of legislative power as, under the pretence and color of
regulating, should subvert or injuriously restrain the right
itself."
It has accordingly been held generally in the States that,
whether the particular provisions of an act of legislation
establishing means for ascertaining the qualifications of those
entitled to vote, and making previous registration in lists of
such, a condition precedent to the exercise of the right were or
were not reasonable regulations, and accordingly valid or void, was
always open to inquiry as a judicial question. See Daggett v.
Hudson, 1 Western Reporter 9, decided by the Supreme Court of
Ohio, where many of the cases are collected; Monroe v.
Collins, 17 Ohio St. 665.
The same principle has been more freely extended to the quasi -legislative acts of inferior municipal bodies, in
respect to which it is an ancient jurisdiction of judicial
tribunals to pronounce upon the reasonableness and consequent
validity of their by laws. In respect to these, it was the doctrine
that every bylaw must be reasonable, not inconsistent with the
charter of the corporation, nor with any statute of Parliament, nor
with the general principles of the common law of the land,
particularly those having relation to the liberty of the subject or
the rights of private property. Dillon on Municipal Corporations,
3d ed., § 319, and cases cited in notes. Accordingly, in the case
of The State of Ohio ex rel. &c. v. The Cincinnati
Gas-Light and Coke Company, 18 Ohio St. 232, 300, an ordinance
of the city council purporting to fix the price to be charged for
gas, under an authority of law giving discretionary power to do so,
was held to be bad, if passed in bad faith, fixing an unreasonable
price, for the fraudulent purpose of compelling Page 118 U. S. 372 the gas company to submit to an unfair appraisement of their
works. And a similar question, very pertinent to the one in the
present cases, was decided by the Court of Appeals of Maryland in
the case of the City of Baltimore v. Radecke, 49 Maryland
217. In that case, the defendant had erected and used a steam
engine in the prosecution of his business as a carpenter and
box-maker in the city of Baltimore, under a permit from the mayor
and city council, which contained a condition that the engine was
"to be removed after six months' notice to that effect from the
mayor." After such notice and refusal to conform to it, a suit was
instituted to recover the penalty provided by the ordinance, to
restrain the prosecution of which a bill in equity was filed. The
court holding the opinion that
"there may be a case in which an ordinance, passed under grants
of power like those we have cited, is so clearly unreasonable, so
arbitrary, oppressive, or partial, as to raise the presumption that
the legislature never intended to confer the power to pass it, and
to justify the courts in interfering and setting it aside as a
plain abuse of authority,"
it proceeds to speak, with regard to the ordinance in question,
in relation to the use of steam engines, as follows:
"It does not profess to prescribe regulations for their
construction, location, or use, nor require such precautions and
safeguards to be provided by those who own and use them as are best
calculated to render them less dangerous to life and property, nor
does it restrain their use in box factories and other similar
establishments within certain defined limits, nor in any other way
attempt to promote their safety and security without destroying
their usefulness. But it commits to the unrestrained will of a
single public officer the power to notify every person who now
employs a steam engine in the prosecution of any business in the
city of Baltimore to cease to do so, and, by providing compulsory
fines for every day's disobedience of such notice and order of
removal, renders his power over the use of steam in that city
practically absolute, so that he may prohibit its use altogether.
But if he should not choose to do this, but only to act in
particular cases, there is nothing in the ordinance to guide or
control his action. It lays down no Page 118 U. S. 373 rules by which its impartial execution can be
secured or partiality and oppression prevented. It is clear that
giving and enforcing these notices may, and quite likely will,
bring ruin to the business of those against whom they are directed,
while others, from whom they are withheld, may be actually
benefited by what is thus done to their neighbors; and, when we
remember that this action or nonaction may proceed from emnity or
prejudice, from partisan zeal or animosity, from favoritism and
other improper influences and motives easy of concealment and
difficult to be detected and exposed, it becomes unnecessary to
suggest or to comment upon the injustice capable of being brought
under cover of such a power, for that becomes apparent to everyone
who gives to the subject a moment's consideration. In fact, an
ordinance which clothes a single individual with such power hardly
falls within the domain of law, and we are constrained to
pronounce it inoperative and void."
This conclusion, and the reasoning on which it is based, are
deductions from the face of the ordinance, as to its necessary
tendency and ultimate actual operation. In the present cases, we
are not obliged to reason from the probable to the actual, and pass
upon the validity of the ordinances complained of, as tried merely
by the opportunities which their terms afford, of unequal and
unjust discrimination in their administration. For the cases
present the ordinances in actual operation, and the facts shown
establish an administration directed so exclusively against a
particular class of persons as to warrant and require the
conclusion that, whatever may have been the intent of the
ordinances as adopted, they are applied by the public authorities
charged with their administration, and thus representing the State
itself, with a mind so unequal and oppressive as to amount to a
practical denial by the State of that equal protection of the laws
which is secured to the petitioners, as to all other persons, by
the broad and benign provisions of the Fourteenth Amendment to the
Constitution of the United States. Though the law itself be fair on
its face and impartial in appearance, yet, if it is applied and
administered by public authority with an evil eye and an
unequal Page 118 U. S. 374 hand, so as practically to make unjust and illegal
discriminations between persons in similar circumstances, material
to their rights, the denial of equal justice is still within the
prohibition of the Constitution. This principle of interpretation
has been sanctioned by this court in Henderson v. Mayor of New
York, 92 U. S. 259 ; Chy Lung v. Freeman, 92 U. S. 275 ; Ex parte Virginia, 100 U. S. 339 ; Neal v. Delaware, 103 U. S. 370 , and
S Soon Hing v. Crowley, 113 U. S. 703 .
The present cases, as shown by the facts disclosed in the
record, are within this class. It appears that both petitioners
have complied with every requisite deemed by the law or by the
public officers charged with its administration necessary for the
protection of neighboring property from fire or as a precaution
against injury to the public health. No reason whatever, except the
will of the supervisors, is assigned why they should not be
permitted to carry on, in the accustomed manner, their harmless and
useful occupation, on which they depend for a livelihood. And while
this consent of the supervisors is withheld from them and from two
hundred others who have also petitioned, all of whom happen to be
Chinese subjects, eighty others, not Chinese subjects, are
permitted to carry on the same business under similar conditions.
The fact of this discrimination is admitted. No reason for it is
shown, and the conclusion cannot be resisted that no reason for it
exists except hostility to the race and nationality to which the
petitioners belong, and which, in the eye of the law, is not
justified. The discrimination is, therefore, illegal, and the
public administration which enforces it is a denial of the equal
protection of the laws and a violation of the Fourteenth Amendment
of the Constitution. The imprisonment of the petitioners is,
therefore, illegal, and they must be discharged. To this end, The judgment of the Supreme Court of California in the case
of Yick Wo, and that of the Circuit Court of the United States for
the District of California in the case of Wo Lee, are severally
reversed, and the cases remanded, each to the proper court, with
directions to discharge the petitioners from custody and
imprisonment. | Here is a summary of the key points from the case:
- Yick Wo v. Hopkins was a landmark Supreme Court case that dealt with racial discrimination and equal protection under the law.
- The case involved two Chinese immigrants, Yick Wo and Wo Lee, who were denied business licenses to operate their laundries in San Francisco due to discriminatory city ordinances.
- The Supreme Court held that the administration of the ordinances violated the Fourteenth Amendment's guarantee of equal protection under the law, as it made arbitrary and unjust discriminations based on race.
- The Court found that the ordinances were applied with "an evil eye and an unequal hand," resulting in illegal discrimination against Chinese subjects.
- The Court emphasized that the protections of the Fourteenth Amendment extend to all persons within the territorial jurisdiction of the United States, regardless of race, color, or nationality.
- As a result, the Court reversed the lower court decisions and ordered the petitioners to be discharged from custody.
This case set an important precedent for equal protection jurisprudence and established that discriminatory administration of laws, even if fair on their face, can violate the Constitution. |
Gun Rights | New York State Rifle & Pistol Association, Inc. v. Bruen | https://supreme.justia.com/cases/federal/us/597/20-843/ | NOTICE: This opinion is subject to
formal revision before publication in the preliminary print of the
United States Reports. Readers are requested to notify the Reporter
of Decisions, Supreme Court of the United States, Washington,
D. C. 20543, of any typographical or other formal errors, in
order that corrections may be made before the preliminary print
goes to press.
SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES
_________________
No. 20–843
_________________
New York State Rifle & Pistol Association,
Inc., et al., PETITIONERS v. Kevin P. Bruen, in his
official capacity as Superintendent of New York State Police,
et al.
on writ of certiorari to the united states
court of appeals for the second circuit
[June 23, 2022]
Justice Thomas delivered the opinion of the
Court.
In District of Columbia v. Heller , 554 U.S.
570 (2008), and McDonald v. Chicago , 561 U.S.
742 (2010), we recognized that the Second and Fourteenth
Amendments protect the right of an ordinary, law-abiding citizen to
possess a handgun in the home for self-defense. In this case,
petitioners and respondents agree that ordinary, law-abiding
citizens have a similar right to carry handguns publicly for their
self-defense. We too agree, and now hold, consistent with Heller and McDonald , that the Second and Fourteenth
Amendments protect an individual’s right to carry a handgun for
self-defense outside the home.
The parties nevertheless dispute whether New
York’s licensing regime respects the constitutional right to carry
handguns publicly for self-defense. In 43 States, the government
issues licenses to carry based on objective criteria. But in six
States, including New York, the government further conditions
issuance of a license to carry on a citizen’s showing of some
additional special need. Because the State of New York issues
public-carry licenses only when an applicant demonstrates a special
need for self-defense, we conclude that the State’s licensing
regime violates the Constitution.
I
A
New York State has regulated the public carry
of handguns at least since the early 20th century. In 1905, New
York made it a misdemeanor for anyone over the age of 16 to “have
or carry concealed upon his person in any city or village of [New
York], any pistol, revolver or other firearm without a written
license . . . issued to him by a police magistrate.” 1905
N. Y. Laws ch. 92, §2, pp. 129–130; see also 1908
N. Y. Laws ch. 93, §1, pp. 242–243 (allowing justices of
the peace to issue licenses). In 1911, New York’s “Sullivan Law”
expanded the State’s criminal prohibition to the possession of all
handguns—concealed or otherwise—without a government-issued
license. See 1911 N. Y. Laws ch. 195, §1, p. 443. New
York later amended the Sullivan Law to clarify the licensing
standard: Magistrates could “issue to [a] person a license to have
and carry concealed a pistol or revolver without regard to
employment or place of possessing such weapon” only if that person
proved “good moral character” and “proper cause.” 1913 N. Y.
Laws ch. 608, §1, p. 1629.
Today’s licensing scheme largely tracks that of
the early 1900s. It is a crime in New York to possess “any firearm”
without a license, whether inside or outside the home, punishable
by up to four years in prison or a $5,000 fine for a felony
offense, and one year in prison or a $1,000 fine for a misdemeanor.
See N. Y. Penal Law Ann. §§265.01–b (West 2017), 261.01(1)
(West Cum. Supp. 2022), 70.00(2)(e) and (3)(b), 80.00(1)(a) (West
2021), 70.15(1), 80.05(1). Meanwhile, possessing a loaded firearm
outside one’s home or place of business without a license is a
felony punishable by up to 15 years in prison. §§265.03(3) (West
2017), 70.00(2)(c) and (3)(b), 80.00(1)(a).
A license applicant who wants to possess a
firearm at home (or in his place of business) must convince
a “licensing officer”—usually a judge or law enforcement
officer—that, among other things, he is of good moral character,
has no history of crime or mental illness, and that “no good cause
exists for the denial of the license.” §§400.00(1)(a)–(n) (West
Cum. Supp. 2022). If he wants to carry a firearm outside his
home or place of business for self-defense, the applicant must
obtain an unrestricted license to “have and carry” a concealed
“pistol or revolver.” §400.00(2)(f ). To secure that license,
the applicant must prove that “proper cause exists” to issue it. Ibid. If an applicant cannot make that showing, he can
receive only a “restricted” license for public carry, which allows
him to carry a firearm for a limited purpose, such as hunting,
target shooting, or employment. See, e.g. , In re
O’Brien , 87 N.Y.2d 436 , 438–439, 663 N.E.2d 316 , 316–317 (1996); Babernitz v. Police
Dept. of City of New York , 65 App. Div. 2d 320, 324, 411
N.Y.S.2d 309, 311 (1978); In re O’Connor , 154 Misc. 2d
694, 696–698, 585 N.Y.S.2d 1000, 1003 (Westchester Cty. 1992).
No New York statute defines “proper cause.” But
New York courts have held that an applicant shows proper cause only
if he can “demonstrate a special need for self-protection
distinguishable from that of the general community.” E.g. , In re Klenosky , 75 App. Div. 2d 793, 428 N.Y.S.2d 256,
257 (1980). This “special need” standard is demanding. For example,
living or working in an area “ ‘noted for criminal
activity’ ” does not suffice. In re Bernstein , 85
App. Div. 2d 574, 445 N.Y.S.2d 716, 717 (1981). Rather, New York
courts generally require evidence “of particular threats, attacks
or other extraordinary danger to personal safety.” In re
Martinek , 294 App. Div. 2d 221, 222, 743 N.Y.S.2d 80, 81
(2002); see also In re Kaplan , 249 App. Div. 2d 199,
201, 673 N.Y.S.2d 66, 68 (1998) (approving the New York City Police
Department’s requirement of “ ‘extraordinary personal danger,
documented by proof of recurrent threats to life or safety’ ”
(quoting 38 N. Y. C. R. R. §5–03(b))).
When a licensing officer denies an application,
judicial review is limited. New York courts defer to an officer’s
application of the proper-cause standard unless it is “arbitrary
and capricious.” In re Bando , 290 App. Div. 2d 691,
692, 735 N.Y.S.2d 660, 661 (2002). In other words, the decision
“must be upheld if the record shows a rational basis for it.” Kaplan , 249 App. Div. 2d, at 201, 673 N. Y. S. 2d,
at 68. The rule leaves applicants little recourse if their local
licensing officer denies a permit.
New York is not alone in requiring a permit to
carry a handgun in public. But the vast majority of States—43 by
our count—are “shall issue” jurisdictions, where authorities must
issue concealed-carry licenses whenever applicants satisfy certain
threshold requirements, without granting licensing officials
discretion to deny licenses based on a perceived lack of need or
suitability.[ 1 ] Meanwhile, only
six States and the District of Columbia have “may issue” licensing
laws, under which authorities have discretion to deny
concealed-carry licenses even when the applicant satisfies the
statutory criteria, usually because the applicant has not
demonstrated cause or suitability for the relevant license. Aside
from New York, then, only California, the District of Columbia,
Hawaii, Maryland, Massachusetts, and New Jersey have analogues to
the “proper cause” standard.[ 2 ]
All of these “proper cause” analogues have been upheld by the
Courts of Appeals, save for the District of Columbia’s, which has
been permanently enjoined since 2017. Compare Gould v. Morgan , 907 F.3d 659, 677 (CA1 2018); Kachalsky v. County of Westchester , 701 F.3d 81, 101 (CA2 2012); Drake v. Filko , 724 F.3d 426, 440 (CA3 2013); United States v. Masciandaro , 638 F.3d 458, 460 (CA4
2011); Young v. Hawaii , 992 F.3d 765, 773 (CA9 2021)
(en banc), with Wrenn v. District of Columbia , 864
F.3d 650, 668 (CADC 2017).
B
As set forth in the pleadings below,
petitioners Brandon Koch and Robert Nash are law-abiding, adult
citizens of Rensselaer County, New York. Koch lives in Troy, while
Nash lives in Averill Park. Petitioner New York State Rifle &
Pistol Association, Inc., is a public-interest group organized to
defend the Second Amendment rights of New Yorkers. Both Koch and
Nash are members.
In 2014, Nash applied for an unrestricted
license to carry a handgun in public. Nash did not claim any unique
danger to his personal safety; he simply wanted to carry a handgun
for self-defense. In early 2015, the State denied Nash’s
application for an unrestricted license but granted him a
restricted license for hunting and target shooting only. In late
2016, Nash asked a licensing officer to remove the restrictions,
citing a string of recent robberies in his neighborhood. After an
informal hearing, the licensing officer denied the request. The
officer reiterated that Nash’s existing license permitted him “to
carry concealed for purposes of off road back country, outdoor
activities similar to hunting,” such as “fishing, hiking &
camping etc.” App. 41. But, at the same time, the officer
emphasized that the restrictions were “intended to prohibit [Nash] from carrying concealed in ANY LOCATION typically open to
and frequented by the general public.” Ibid. Between 2008 and 2017, Koch was in the same
position as Nash: He faced no special dangers, wanted a handgun for
general self-defense, and had only a restricted license permitting
him to carry a handgun outside the home for hunting and target
shooting. In late 2017, Koch applied to a licensing officer to
remove the restrictions on his license, citing his extensive
experience in safely handling firearms. Like Nash’s application,
Koch’s was denied, except that the officer permitted Koch to “carry
to and from work.” Id ., at 114.
C
Respondents are the superintendent of the New
York State Police, who oversees the enforcement of the State’s
licensing laws, and a New York Supreme Court justice, who oversees
the processing of licensing applications in Rensselaer County.
Petitioners sued respondents for declaratory and injunctive relief
under Rev. Stat. 1979, 42 U. S. C. §1983, alleging that
respondents violated their Second and Fourteenth Amendment rights
by denying their unrestricted-license applications on the basis
that they had failed to show “proper cause,” i.e. , had
failed to demonstrate a unique need for self-defense.
The District Court dismissed petitioners’
complaint and the Court of Appeals affirmed. See 818 Fed. Appx. 99,
100 (CA2 2020). Both courts relied on the Court of Appeals’ prior
decision in Kachalsky , 701 F.3d 81, which had sustained New
York’s proper-cause standard, holding that the requirement was
“substantially related to the achievement of an important
governmental interest.” Id. , at 96.
We granted certiorari to decide whether New
York’s denial of petitioners’ license applications violated the
Constitution. 593 U. S. ___ (2021).
II
In Heller and McDonald , we held
that the Second and Fourteenth Amendments protect an individual
right to keep and bear arms for self-defense. In doing so, we held
unconstitutional two laws that prohibited the possession and use of
handguns in the home. In the years since, the Courts of Appeals
have coalesced around a “two-step” framework for analyzing Second
Amendment challenges that combines history with means-end
scrutiny.
Today, we decline to adopt that two-part
approach. In keeping with Heller , we hold that when the
Second Amendment’s plain text covers an individual’s conduct, the
Constitution presumptively protects that conduct. To justify its
regulation, the government may not simply posit that the regulation
promotes an important interest. Rather, the government must
demonstrate that the regulation is consistent with this Nation’s
historical tradition of firearm regulation. Only if a firearm
regulation is consistent with this Nation’s historical tradition
may a court conclude that the individual’s conduct falls outside
the Second Amendment’s “unqualified command.” Konigsberg v. State Bar of Cal ., 366 U.S.
36 , 50, n. 10 (1961).[ 3 ]
A
Since Heller and McDonald , the
two-step test that Courts of Appeals have developed to assess
Second Amendment claims proceeds as follows. At the first step, the
government may justify its regulation by “establish[ing] that the
challenged law regulates activity falling outside the scope of the
right as originally understood.” E.g. , Kanter v. Barr , 919 F.3d 437, 441 (CA7 2019) (internal quotation marks
omitted). But see United States v. Boyd , 999 F.3d
171, 185 (CA3 2021) (requiring claimant to show “ ‘a burden on
conduct falling within the scope of the Second Amendment’s
guarantee’ ”). The Courts of Appeals then ascertain the
original scope of the right based on its historical meaning. E.g. , United States v. Focia , 869 F.3d 1269,
1285 (CA11 2017). If the government can prove that the regulated
conduct falls beyond the Amendment’s original scope, “then the
analysis can stop there; the regulated activity is categorically
unprotected.” United States v. Greeno , 679 F.3d 510,
518 (CA6 2012) (internal quotation marks omitted). But if the
historical evidence at this step is “inconclusive or suggests that
the regulated activity is not categorically unprotected,”
the courts generally proceed to step two. Kanter , 919
F. 3d, at 441 (internal quotation marks omitted).
At the second step, courts often analyze “how
close the law comes to the core of the Second Amendment right and
the severity of the law’s burden on that right.” Ibid. (internal quotation marks omitted) . The Courts of Appeals
generally maintain “that the core Second Amendment right is limited
to self-defense in the home .” Gould , 907 F. 3d,
at 671 (emphasis added). But see Wrenn , 864 F. 3d, at
659 (“[T]he Amendment’s core generally covers carrying in public
for self defense”). If a “core” Second Amendment right is burdened,
courts apply “strict scrutiny” and ask whether the Government can
prove that the law is “narrowly tailored to achieve a compelling
governmental interest.” Kolbe v. Hogan , 849 F.3d 114,
133 (CA4 2017) (internal quotation marks omitted). Otherwise, they
apply intermediate scrutiny and consider whether the Government can
show that the regulation is “substantially related to the
achievement of an important governmental interest.” Kachalsky , 701 F. 3d, at 96.[ 4 ] Both respondents and the United States largely agree
with this consensus, arguing that intermediate scrutiny is
appropriate when text and history are unclear in attempting to
delineate the scope of the right. See Brief for Respondents 37;
Brief for United States as Amicus Curiae 4.
B
Despite the popularity of this two-step
approach, it is one step too many. Step one of the predominant
framework is broadly consistent with Heller , which demands a
test rooted in the Second Amendment’s text, as informed by history.
But Heller and McDonald do not support applying
means-end scrutiny in the Second Amendment context. Instead, the
government must affirmatively prove that its firearms regulation is
part of the historical tradition that delimits the outer bounds of
the right to keep and bear arms.
1
To show why Heller does not support
applying means-end scrutiny, we first summarize Heller ’s
methodological approach to the Second Amendment.
In Heller , we began with a “textual
analysis” focused on the “ ‘normal and ordinary’ ”
meaning of the Second Amendment’s language. 554 U. S., at
576–577, 578. That analysis suggested that the Amendment’s
operative clause—“the right of the people to keep and bear Arms
shall not be infringed”—“guarantee[s] the individual right to
possess and carry weapons in case of confrontation” that does not
depend on service in the militia. Id. , at 592.
From there, we assessed whether our initial
conclusion was “confirmed by the historical background of the
Second Amendment.” Ibid. We looked to history because “it
has always been widely understood that the Second Amendment
. . . codified a pre-existing right.” Ibid. The Amendment “was not intended to lay down a novel principle but
rather codified a right inherited from our English ancestors.” Id. , at 599 (alterations and internal quotation marks
omitted). After surveying English history dating from the late
1600s, along with American colonial views leading up to the
founding, we found “no doubt, on the basis of both text and
history, that the Second Amendment conferred an individual right to
keep and bear arms.” Id. , at 595.
We then canvassed the historical record and
found yet further confirmation. That history included the
“analogous arms-bearing rights in state constitutions that preceded
and immediately followed adoption of the Second Amendment,” id. , at 600–601, and “how the Second Amendment was
interpreted from immediately after its ratification through the end
of the 19th century,” id. , at 605. When the principal
dissent charged that the latter category of sources was
illegitimate “postenactment legislative history,” id. , at
662, n. 28 (opinion of Stevens, J.), we clarified that
“examination of a variety of legal and other sources to determine the public understanding of a legal text in the period after
its enactment or ratification” was “a critical tool of
constitutional interpretation,” id. , at 605 (majority
opinion).
In assessing the postratification history, we
looked to four different types of sources. First, we reviewed
“[t]hree important founding-era legal scholars [who] interpreted
the Second Amendment in published writings.” Ibid. Second,
we looked to “19th-century cases that interpreted the Second
Amendment” and found that they “universally support an individual
right” to keep and bear arms. Id. , at 610. Third, we
examined the “discussion of the Second Amendment in Congress and in
public discourse” after the Civil War, “as people debated whether
and how to secure constitutional rights for newly freed slaves.” Id. , at 614. Fourth, we considered how post-Civil War
commentators understood the right. See id. , at 616–619.
After holding that the Second Amendment
protected an individual right to armed self-defense, we also relied
on the historical understanding of the Amendment to demark the
limits on the exercise of that right. We noted that, “[l]ike most
rights, the right secured by the Second Amendment is not
unlimited.” Id. , at 626. “From Blackstone through the
19th-century cases, commentators and courts routinely explained
that the right was not a right to keep and carry any weapon
whatsoever in any manner whatsoever and for whatever purpose.” Ibid. For example, we found it “fairly supported by the
historical tradition of prohibiting the carrying of ‘dangerous and
unusual weapons’ ” that the Second Amendment protects the
possession and use of weapons that are “ ‘in common use at the
time.’ ” Id. , at 627 (first citing 4 W. Blackstone,
Commentaries on the Laws of England 148–149 (1769); then quoting United States v. Miller , 307
U.S. 174 , 179 (1939)). That said, we cautioned that we were not
“undertak[ing] an exhaustive historical analysis today of the full
scope of the Second Amendment” and moved on to considering the
constitutionality of the District of Columbia’s handgun ban. 554
U. S., at 627 . We assessed the lawfulness of that handgun ban
by scrutinizing whether it comported with history and tradition.
Although we noted that the ban “would fail constitutional muster”
“[u]nder any of the standards of scrutiny that we have applied to
enumerated constitutional rights,” id. , at 628–629, we did
not engage in means-end scrutiny when resolving the constitutional
question. Instead, we focused on the historically unprecedented
nature of the District’s ban, observing that “[f]ew laws in the
history of our Nation have come close to [that] severe
restriction.” Id. , at 629. Likewise, when one of the
dissents attempted to justify the District’s prohibition with
“founding-era historical precedent,” including “various restrictive
laws in the colonial period,” we addressed each purported analogue
and concluded that they were either irrelevant or “d[id] not
remotely burden the right of self-defense as much as an absolute
ban on handguns.” Id. , at 631–632; see id. , at
631–634. Thus, our earlier historical analysis sufficed to show
that the Second Amendment did not countenance a “complete
prohibition” on the use of “the most popular weapon chosen by
Americans for self-defense in the home.” Id. , at 629.
2
As the foregoing shows, Heller ’s
methodology centered on constitutional text and history. Whether it
came to defining the character of the right (individual or militia
dependent), suggesting the outer limits of the right, or assessing
the constitutionality of a particular regulation, Heller relied on text and history. It did not invoke any means-end test
such as strict or intermediate scrutiny.
Moreover, Heller and McDonald expressly rejected the application of any “judge-empowering
‘interest-balancing inquiry’ that ‘asks whether the statute burdens
a protected interest in a way or to an extent that is out of
proportion to the statute’s salutary effects upon other important
governmental interests.’ ” Heller , 554 U. S., at
634 (quoting id. , at 689–690 (Breyer, J., dissenting)); see
also McDonald , 561 U. S., at 790–791 (plurality
opinion) (the Second Amendment does not permit—let alone
require—“judges to assess the costs and benefits of firearms
restrictions” under means-end scrutiny). We declined to engage in
means-end scrutiny because “[t]he very enumeration of the right
takes out of the hands of government—even the Third Branch of
Government—the power to decide on a case-by-case basis whether the
right is really worth insisting upon.” Heller , 554
U. S., at 634. We then concluded: “A constitutional guarantee
subject to future judges’ assessments of its usefulness is no
constitutional guarantee at all.” Ibid. Not only did Heller decline to engage in
means-end scrutiny generally, but it also specifically ruled out
the intermediate-scrutiny test that respondents and the United
States now urge us to adopt. Dissenting in Heller , Justice
Breyer’s proposed standard—“ask[ing] whether [a] statute burdens a
protected interest in a way or to an extent that is out of
proportion to the statute’s salutary effects upon other important
governmental interests,” id. , at 689–690 (dissenting
opinion)—simply expressed a classic formulation of intermediate
scrutiny in a slightly different way, see Clark v. Jeter , 486 U.S.
456 , 461 (1988) (asking whether the challenged law is
“substantially related to an important government objective”). In
fact, Justice Breyer all but admitted that his Heller dissent advocated for intermediate scrutiny by repeatedly invoking
a quintessential intermediate- scrutiny precedent. See Heller , 554 U. S., at 690, 696, 704–705 (citing Turner Broadcasting System , Inc. v. FCC , 520 U.S.
180 (1997)). Thus, when Heller expressly rejected that
dissent’s “interest-balancing inquiry,” 554 U. S., at 634
(internal quotation marks omitted), it necessarily rejected
intermediate scrutiny.[ 5 ]
In sum, the Courts of Appeals’ second step is
inconsistent with Heller ’s historical approach and its
rejection of means-end scrutiny. We reiterate that the standard for
applying the Second Amendment is as follows: When the Second
Amendment’s plain text covers an individual’s conduct, the
Constitution presumptively protects that conduct. The government
must then justify its regulation by demonstrating that it is
consistent with the Nation’s historical tradition of firearm
regulation. Only then may a court conclude that the individual’s
conduct falls outside the Second Amendment’s “unqualified command.” Konigsberg , 366 U. S., at 50, n. 10.
C
This Second Amendment standard accords with
how we protect other constitutional rights. Take, for instance, the
freedom of speech in the First Amendment, to which Heller repeatedly compared the right to keep and bear arms. 554
U. S., at 582, 595, 606, 618, 634–635. In that context,
“[w]hen the Government restricts speech, the Government bears the
burden of proving the constitutionality of its actions.” United
States v. Playboy Entertainment Group , Inc. , 529 U.S.
803 , 816 (2000); see also Philadelphia Newspapers , Inc. v. Hepps , 475 U.S.
767 , 777 (1986). In some cases, that burden includes showing
whether the expressive conduct falls outside of the category of
protected speech. See Illinois ex rel. Madigan v. Telemarketing Associates , Inc. , 538 U.S.
600 , 620, n. 9 (2003). And to carry that burden, the
government must generally point to historical evidence about
the reach of the First Amendment’s protections. See, e.g. , United States v. Stevens , 559
U.S. 460 , 468–471 (2010) (placing the burden on the government
to show that a type of speech belongs to a “historic and
traditional categor[y]” of constitutionally unprotected speech
“long familiar to the bar” (internal quotation marks omitted)).
And beyond the freedom of speech, our focus on
history also comports with how we assess many other constitutional
claims. If a litigant asserts the right in court to “be confronted
with the witnesses against him,” U. S. Const., Amdt. 6, we
require courts to consult history to determine the scope of that
right. See, e.g. , Giles v. California , 554 U.S.
353 , 358 (2008) (“admitting only those exceptions [to the
Confrontation Clause] established at the time of the founding”
(internal quotation marks omitted)). Similarly, when a litigant
claims a violation of his rights under the Establishment Clause,
Members of this Court “loo[k] to history for guidance.” American
Legion v. American Humanist Assn. , 588 U. S. ___,
___ (2019) (plurality opinion) (slip op., at 25). We adopt a
similar approach here.
To be sure, “[h]istorical analysis can be
difficult; it sometimes requires resolving threshold questions, and
making nuanced judgments about which evidence to consult and how to
interpret it.” McDonald , 561 U. S., at 803–804 (Scalia,
J., concurring). But reliance on history to inform the meaning of
constitutional text—especially text meant to codify a pre-existing right—is, in our view, more legitimate, and
more administrable, than asking judges to “make difficult empirical
judgments” about “the costs and benefits of firearms restrictions,”
especially given their “lack [of] expertise” in the field. Id. , at 790–791 (plurality opinion).[ 6 ]
If the last decade of Second Amendment
litigation has taught this Court anything, it is that federal
courts tasked with making such difficult empirical judgments
regarding firearm regulations under the banner of “intermediate
scrutiny” often defer to the determinations of legislatures. But
while that judicial deference to legislative interest balancing is
understandable—and, elsewhere, appropriate—it is not deference that
the Constitution demands here. The Second Amendment “is the very product of an interest balancing by the people” and it
“surely elevates above all other interests the right of
law-abiding, responsible citizens to use arms” for self-defense. Heller , 554 U. S., at 635. It is this balance—struck by
the traditions of the American people—that demands our unqualified
deference.
D
The test that we set forth in Heller and apply today requires courts to assess whether modern firearms
regulations are consistent with the Second Amendment’s text and
historical understanding. In some cases, that inquiry will be
fairly straightforward. For instance, when a challenged regulation
addresses a general societal problem that has persisted since the
18th century, the lack of a distinctly similar historical
regulation addressing that problem is relevant evidence that the
challenged regulation is inconsistent with the Second Amendment.
Likewise, if earlier generations addressed the societal problem,
but did so through materially different means, that also could be
evidence that a modern regulation is unconstitutional. And if some
jurisdictions actually attempted to enact analogous regulations
during this timeframe, but those proposals were rejected on
constitutional grounds, that rejection surely would provide some
probative evidence of unconstitutionality. Heller itself exemplifies this kind of
straightforward historical inquiry. One of the District’s
regulations challenged in Heller “totally ban[ned] handgun
possession in the home.” Id ., at 628. The District in Heller addressed a perceived societal problem—firearm
violence in densely populated communities—and it employed a
regulation—a flat ban on the possession of handguns in the
home—that the Founders themselves could have adopted to confront
that problem. Accordingly, after considering “founding-era
historical precedent,” including “various restrictive laws in the
colonial period,” and finding that none was analogous to the
District’s ban, Heller concluded that the handgun ban was
unconstitutional. Id., at 631; see also id., at 634
(describing the claim that “there were somewhat similar
restrictions in the founding period” a “false proposition”).
New York’s proper-cause requirement concerns the
same alleged societal problem addressed in Heller : “handgun
violence,” primarily in “urban area[s].” Ibid. Following the
course charted by Heller , we will consider whether
“historical precedent” from before, during, and even after the
founding evinces a comparable tradition of regulation. Id., at 631. And, as we explain below, we find no such tradition in the
historical materials that respondents and their amici have
brought to bear on that question. See Part III–B, infra .
While the historical analogies here and in Heller are relatively simple to draw, other cases
implicating unprecedented societal concerns or dramatic
technological changes may require a more nuanced approach. The
regulatory challenges posed by firearms today are not always the
same as those that preoccupied the Founders in 1791 or the
Reconstruction generation in 1868. Fortunately, the Founders
created a Constitution—and a Second Amendment—“intended to endure
for ages to come, and consequently, to be adapted to the various
crises of human affairs.” McCulloch v. Maryland , 4
Wheat. 316, 415 (1819) (emphasis deleted). Although its meaning is
fixed according to the understandings of those who ratified it, the
Constitution can, and must, apply to circumstances beyond those the
Founders specifically anticipated. See, e.g., United
States v. Jones , 565 U.S.
400 , 404–405 (2012) (holding that installation of a tracking
device was “a physical intrusion [that] would have been considered
a ‘search’ within the meaning of the Fourth Amendment when it was
adopted”).
We have already recognized in Heller at
least one way in which the Second Amendment’s historically fixed
meaning applies to new circumstances: Its reference to “arms” does
not apply “only [to] those arms in existence in the 18th century.”
554 U. S., at 582. “Just as the First Amendment protects
modern forms of communications, and the Fourth Amendment applies to
modern forms of search, the Second Amendment extends, prima facie,
to all instruments that constitute bearable arms, even those that
were not in existence at the time of the founding.” Ibid. (citations omitted). Thus, even though the Second Amendment’s
definition of “arms” is fixed according to its historical
understanding, that general definition covers modern instruments
that facilitate armed self-defense. Cf. Caetano v. Massachusetts , 577 U.S. 411, 411–412 (2016) ( per
curiam ) (stun guns).
Much like we use history to determine which
modern “arms” are protected by the Second Amendment, so too does
history guide our consideration of modern regulations that were
unimaginable at the founding. When confronting such present-day
firearm regulations, this historical inquiry that courts must
conduct will often involve reasoning by analogy—a commonplace task
for any lawyer or judge. Like all analogical reasoning, determining
whether a historical regulation is a proper analogue for a
distinctly modern firearm regulation requires a determination of
whether the two regulations are “relevantly similar.” C. Sunstein,
On Analogical Reasoning, 106 Harv. L. Rev. 741, 773 (1993).
And because “[e]verything is similar in infinite ways to everything
else,” id., at 774, one needs “some metric enabling the
analogizer to assess which similarities are important and which are
not,” F. Schauer & B. Spellman, Analogy, Expertise, and
Experience, 84 U. Chi. L. Rev. 249, 254 (2017). For instance,
a green truck and a green hat are relevantly similar if one’s
metric is “things that are green.” See ibid. They are not
relevantly similar if the applicable metric is “things you can
wear.”
While we do not now provide an exhaustive survey
of the features that render regulations relevantly similar under
the Second Amendment, we do think that Heller and McDonald point toward at least two metrics: how and why the
regulations burden a law-abiding citizen’s right to armed
self-defense. As we stated in Heller and repeated in McDonald , “individual self-defense is ‘the central
component ’ of the Second Amendment right.” McDonald , 561
U. S., at 767 (quoting Heller , 554 U. S., at 599);
see also id., at 628 (“the inherent right of self-defense
has been central to the Second Amendment right”). Therefore,
whether modern and historical regulations impose a comparable
burden on the right of armed self-defense and whether that burden
is comparably justified are “ ‘ central ’ ”
considerations when engaging in an analogical inquiry. McDonald , 561 U. S., at 767 (quoting Heller , 554
U. S., at 599).[ 7 ]
To be clear, analogical reasoning under the
Second Amendment is neither a regulatory straightjacket nor a
regulatory blank check. On the one hand, courts should not “uphold
every modern law that remotely resembles a historical analogue,”
because doing so “risk[s] endorsing outliers that our ancestors
would never have accepted.” Drummond v. Robinson , 9
F. 4th 217, 226 (CA3 2021). On the other hand, analogical reasoning
requires only that the government identify a well-established and
representative historical analogue , not a historical twin . So even if a modern-day regulation is not a dead
ringer for historical precursors, it still may be analogous enough
to pass constitutional muster.
Consider, for example, Heller ’s
discussion of “longstanding” “laws forbidding the carrying of
firearms in sensitive places such as schools and government
buildings.” 554 U. S. , at 626. Although the historical
record yields relatively few 18th- and 19th-century “sensitive
places” where weapons were altogether prohibited— e.g., legislative assemblies, polling places, and courthouses—we are also
aware of no disputes regarding the lawfulness of such prohibitions.
See D. Kopel & J. Greenlee, The “Sensitive Places” Doctrine, 13
Charleston L. Rev. 205, 229–236, 244–247 (2018); see also
Brief for Independent Institute as Amicus Curiae 11–17. We
therefore can assume it settled that these locations were
“sensitive places” where arms carrying could be prohibited
consistent with the Second Amendment. And courts can use analogies
to those historical regulations of “sensitive places” to determine
that modern regulations prohibiting the carry of firearms in new and analogous sensitive places are constitutionally
permissible.
Although we have no occasion to comprehensively
define “sensitive places” in this case, we do think respondents err
in their attempt to characterize New York’s proper-cause
requirement as a “sensitive-place” law. In their view, “sensitive
places” where the government may lawfully disarm law-abiding
citizens include all “places where people typically congregate and
where law-enforcement and other public-safety professionals are
presumptively available.” Brief for Respondents 34. It is true that
people sometimes congregate in “sensitive places,” and it is
likewise true that law enforcement professionals are usually
presumptively available in those locations. But expanding the
category of “sensitive places” simply to all places of public
congregation that are not isolated from law enforcement defines the
category of “sensitive places” far too broadly. Respondents’
argument would in effect exempt cities from the Second Amendment
and would eviscerate the general right to publicly carry arms for
self-defense that we discuss in detail below. See Part III–B, infra . Put simply, there is no historical basis for New York
to effectively declare the island of Manhattan a “sensitive place”
simply because it is crowded and protected generally by the New
York City Police Department.
Like Heller , we “do not undertake an
exhaustive historical analysis . . . of the full scope of
the Second Amendment.” 554 U. S., at 626. And we acknowledge
that “applying constitutional principles to novel modern conditions
can be difficult and leave close questions at the margins.” Heller v. District of Columbia , 670 F.3d 1244, 1275
(CADC 2011) (Kavanaugh, J., dissenting). “But that is hardly unique
to the Second Amendment. It is an essential component of judicial
decisionmaking under our enduring Constitution.” Ibid. We
see no reason why judges frequently tasked with answering these
kinds of historical, analogical questions cannot do the same for
Second Amendment claims.
III
Having made the constitutional standard
endorsed in Heller more explicit, we now apply that standard
to New York’s proper-cause requirement.
A
It is undisputed that petitioners Koch and
Nash—two ordinary, law-abiding, adult citizens—are part of “the
people” whom the Second Amendment protects. See Heller , 554
U. S., at 580. Nor does any party dispute that handguns are
weapons “in common use” today for self-defense. See id. , at
627; see also Caetano , 577 U. S., at 411–412. We
therefore turn to whether the plain text of the Second Amendment
protects Koch’s and Nash’s proposed course of conduct—carrying
handguns publicly for self-defense.
We have little difficulty concluding that it
does. Respondents do not dispute this. See Brief for Respondents
19. Nor could they. Nothing in the Second Amendment’s text draws a
home/public distinction with respect to the right to keep and bear
arms. As we explained in Heller , the “textual elements” of
the Second Amendment’s operative clause— “the right of the people
to keep and bear Arms, shall not be infringed”—“guarantee the
individual right to possess and carry weapons in case of
confrontation.” 554 U. S., at 592. Heller further
confirmed that the right to “bear arms” refers to the right to
“wear, bear, or carry . . . upon the person or in the
clothing or in a pocket, for the purpose . . . of being
armed and ready for offensive or defensive action in a case of
conflict with another person.” Id. , at 584 (quoting Muscarello v. United States , 524
U.S. 125 , 143 (1998) (Ginsburg, J., dissenting); internal
quotation marks omitted).
This definition of “bear” naturally encompasses
public carry. Most gun owners do not wear a holstered pistol at
their hip in their bedroom or while sitting at the dinner table.
Although individuals often “keep” firearms in their home, at the
ready for self-defense, most do not “bear” ( i.e. , carry)
them in the home beyond moments of actual confrontation. To confine
the right to “bear” arms to the home would nullify half of the
Second Amendment’s operative protections.
Moreover, confining the right to “bear” arms to
the home would make little sense given that self-defense is “the central component of the [ Second Amendment] right itself.” Heller , 554 U. S., at 599; see also McDonald ,
561 U. S., at 767. After all, the Second Amendment guarantees
an “individual right to possess and carry weapons in case of
confrontation,” Heller , 554 U. S., at 592, and
confrontation can surely take place outside the home.
Although we remarked in Heller that the
need for armed self-defense is perhaps “most acute” in the home, id. , at 628, we did not suggest that the need was
insignificant elsewhere. Many Americans hazard greater danger
outside the home than in it. See Moore v. Madigan ,
702 F.3d 933, 937 (CA7 2012) (“[A] Chicagoan is a good deal more
likely to be attacked on a sidewalk in a rough neighborhood than in
his apartment on the 35th floor of the Park Tower”). The text of
the Second Amendment reflects that reality.
The Second Amendment’s plain text thus
presumptively guarantees petitioners Koch and Nash a right to
“bear” arms in public for self-defense.
B
Conceding that the Second Amendment guarantees
a general right to public carry, contra, Young , 992
F. 3d, at 813, respondents instead claim that the Amendment
“permits a State to condition handgun carrying in areas ‘frequented
by the general public’ on a showing of a non- speculative need for
armed self-defense in those areas,” Brief for Respondents 19
(citation omitted).[ 8 ] To
support that claim, the burden falls on respondents to show that
New York’s proper-cause requirement is consistent with this
Nation’s historical tradition of firearm regulation. Only if
respondents carry that burden can they show that the pre-existing
right codified in the Second Amendment, and made applicable to the
States through the Fourteenth, does not protect petitioners’
proposed course of conduct.
Respondents appeal to a variety of historical
sources from the late 1200s to the early 1900s. We categorize these
periods as follows: (1) medieval to early modern England;
(2) the American Colonies and the early Republic; (3)
antebellum America; (4) Reconstruction; and (5) the late-19th and
early-20th centuries.
We categorize these historical sources because,
when it comes to interpreting the Constitution, not all history is
created equal. “Constitutional rights are enshrined with the scope
they were understood to have when the people adopted them .” Heller , 554 U. S., at 634–635 (emphasis added). The
Second Amendment was adopted in 1791; the Fourteenth in 1868.
Historical evidence that long predates either date may not
illuminate the scope of the right if linguistic or legal
conventions changed in the intervening years. It is one thing for
courts to “reac[h] back to the 14th century” for English practices
that “prevailed up to the ‘period immediately before and after the
framing of the Constitution.’ ” Sprint Communications
Co. v. APCC Services , Inc. , 554 U.S.
269 , 311 (2008) (Roberts, C. J., dissenting). It is quite
another to rely on an “ancient” practice that had become “obsolete
in England at the time of the adoption of the Constitution” and
never “was acted upon or accepted in the colonies.” Dimick v. Schiedt , 293 U.S.
474 , 477 (1935).
As with historical evidence generally, courts
must be careful when assessing evidence concerning English
common-law rights. The common law, of course, developed over time. Associated Gen. Contractors of Cal. , Inc. v. Carpenters , 459 U.S.
519 , 533, n. 28 (1983); see also Rogers v. Tennessee , 532 U.S.
451 , 461 (2001). And English common-law practices and
understandings at any given time in history cannot be
indiscriminately attributed to the Framers of our own Constitution.
Even “the words of Magna Charta ”—foundational as they were
to the rights of America’s forefathers—“stood for very different
things at the time of the separation of the American Colonies from
what they represented originally” in 1215. Hurtado v. California , 110 U.S.
516 , 529 (1884). Sometimes, in interpreting our own
Constitution, “it [is] better not to go too far back into antiquity
for the best securities of our liberties,” Funk v. United
States , 290 U.S.
371 , 382 (1933), unless evidence shows that medieval law
survived to become our Founders’ law. A long, unbroken line of
common-law precedent stretching from Bracton to Blackstone is far
more likely to be part of our law than a short-lived, 14th-century
English practice.
Similarly, we must also guard against giving
postenactment history more weight than it can rightly bear. It is
true that in Heller we reiterated that evidence of “how the
Second Amendment was interpreted from immediately after its
ratification through the end of the 19th century” represented a
“critical tool of constitutional interpretation.” 554 U. S.,
at 605. We therefore examined “a variety of legal and other sources
to determine the public understanding of [the Second
Amendment] after its . . . ratification.” Ibid. And, in other contexts, we have explained that “ ‘a regular
course of practice’ can ‘liquidate & settle the meaning
of ’ disputed or indeterminate ‘terms & phrases’ ” in
the Constitution. Chiafalo v. Washington , 591
U. S. ___, ___ (2020) (slip op., at 13) (quoting Letter from
J. Madison to S. Roane (Sept. 2, 1819), in 8 Writings of James
Madison 450 (G. Hunt ed. 1908)); see also, e.g., Houston
Community College System v. Wilson , 595 U. S. ___,
___ (2022) (slip op., at 5) (same); The Federalist No. 37, p. 229
(C. Rossiter ed. 1961) (J. Madison); see generally C. Nelson, Stare Decisis and Demonstrably Erroneous Precedents, 87 Va.
L. Rev. 1, 10–21 (2001); W. Baude, Constitutional Liquidation,
71 Stan. L. Rev. 1 (2019). In other words, we recognize that
“where a governmental practice has been open, widespread, and
unchallenged since the early days of the Republic, the practice
should guide our interpretation of an ambiguous constitutional
provision.” NLRB v. Noel Canning , 573 U.S.
513 , 572 (2014) (Scalia, J., concurring in judgment); see also Myers v. United States , 272 U.S.
52 , 174 (1926); Printz v. United States , 521 U.S.
898 , 905 (1997).
But to the extent later history contradicts what
the text says, the text controls. “ ‘[L]iquidating’
indeterminacies in written laws is far removed from expanding or
altering them.” Gamble v. United States , 587
U. S. ___, ___ (2019) (Thomas, J., concurring) (slip op., at
13); see also Letter from J. Madison to N. Trist (Dec. 1831), in 9
Writings of James Madison 477 (G. Hunt ed. 1910). Thus, “post-
ratification adoption or acceptance of laws that are inconsistent with the original meaning of the constitutional
text obviously cannot overcome or alter that text.” Heller ,
670 F. 3d, at 1274, n. 6 (Kavanaugh, J., dissenting); see
also Espinoza v. Montana Dept. of Revenue , 591
U. S. ___, ___ (2020) (slip op., at 15).
As we recognized in Heller itself,
because post-Civil War discussions of the right to keep and bear
arms “took place 75 years after the ratification of the Second
Amendment, they do not provide as much insight into its original
meaning as earlier sources.” 554 U. S., at 614; cf. Sprint
Communications Co. , 554 U. S., at 312 (Roberts,
C. J., dissenting) (“The belated innovations of the mid- to
late-19th-century courts come too late to provide insight into the
meaning of [the Constitution in 1787]”). And we made clear in Gamble that Heller ’s interest in mid- to
late-19th-century commentary was secondary. Heller considered this evidence “only after surveying what it regarded as
a wealth of authority for its reading—including the text of the
Second Amendment and state constitutions.” Gamble , 587
U. S., at ___ (majority opinion) (slip op., at 23). In other
words, this 19th-century evidence was “treated as mere confirmation
of what the Court thought had already been established.” Ibid. A final word on historical method: Strictly
speaking, New York is bound to respect the right to keep and bear
arms because of the Fourteenth Amendment, not the Second. See, e.g. , Barron ex rel. Tiernan v. Mayor of
Baltimore , 7 Pet. 243, 250–251 (1833) (Bill of Rights applies
only to the Federal Government). Nonetheless, we have made clear
that individual rights enumerated in the Bill of Rights and made
applicable against the States through the Fourteenth Amendment have
the same scope as against the Federal Government. See, e.g. , Ramos v. Louisiana , 590 U. S. ___, ___ (2020)
(slip op., at 7); Timbs v. Indiana , 586 U. S.
___, ___–___ (2019) (slip op., at 2–3); Malloy v. Hogan , 378 U.S.
1 , 10–11 (1964). And we have generally assumed that the scope
of the protection applicable to the Federal Government and States
is pegged to the public understanding of the right when the Bill of
Rights was adopted in 1791. See, e.g ., Crawford v. Washington , 541 U.S.
36 , 42–50 (2004) ( Sixth Amendment); Virginia v. Moore , 553 U.S.
164 , 168–169 (2008) ( Fourth Amendment); Nevada Comm’n on
Ethics v. Carrigan , 564 U.S.
117 , 122–125 (2011) ( First Amendment).
We also acknowledge that there is an ongoing
scholarly debate on whether courts should primarily rely on the
prevailing understanding of an individual right when the Fourteenth
Amendment was ratified in 1868 when defining its scope (as well as
the scope of the right against the Federal Government). See, e.g. , A. Amar, The Bill of Rights: Creation and
Reconstruction xiv, 223, 243 (1998); K. Lash, Re-Speaking the Bill
of Rights: A New Doctrine of Incorporation (Jan. 15, 2021)
(manuscript, at 2), https://papers.ssrn
.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=3766917 (“When the people adopted
the Fourteenth Amendment into existence, they readopted the
original Bill of Rights, and did so in a manner that invested those
original 1791 texts with new 1868 meanings”). We need not address
this issue today because, as we explain below, the public
understanding of the right to keep and bear arms in both 1791 and
1868 was, for all relevant purposes, the same with respect to
public carry.
* * *
With these principles in mind, we turn to
respondents’ historical evidence. Throughout modern Anglo-American
history, the right to keep and bear arms in public has
traditionally been subject to well-defined restrictions governing
the intent for which one could carry arms, the manner of carry, or
the exceptional circumstances under which one could not carry arms.
But apart from a handful of late-19th-century jurisdictions, the
historical record compiled by respondents does not demonstrate a
tradition of broadly prohibiting the public carry of commonly used
firearms for self-defense. Nor is there any such historical
tradition limiting public carry only to those law-abiding citizens
who demonstrate a special need for self-defense.[ 9 ] We conclude that respondents have failed
to meet their burden to identify an American tradition justifying
New York’s proper-cause requirement. Under Heller ’s
text-and-history standard, the proper-cause requirement is
therefore unconstitutional.
1
Respondents’ substantial reliance on English
history and custom before the founding makes some sense given our
statement in Heller that the Second Amendment “codified a
right ‘inherited from our English ancestors.’ ” 554
U. S., at 599 (quoting Robertson v. Baldwin , 165
U.S. 275 , 281 (1897)); see also Smith v. Alabama , 124 U.S.
465 , 478 (1888). But this Court has long cautioned that the
English common law “is not to be taken in all respects to be that
of America.” Van Ness v. Pacard , 2 Pet. 137, 144
(1829) (Story, J., for the Court); see also Wheaton v. Peters , 8 Pet. 591, 659 (1834); Funk , 290 U. S.,
at 384. Thus, “[t]he language of the Constitution cannot be
interpreted safely except by reference to the common law and to
British institutions as they were when the instrument was framed
and adopted ,” not as they existed in the Middle Ages. Ex parte Grossman , 267 U.S.
87 , 108–109 (1925) (emphasis added); see also United
States v. Reid , 12 How. 361, 363 (1852).
We interpret the English history that
respondents and the United States muster in light of these
interpretive principles. We find that history ambiguous at best and
see little reason to think that the Framers would have thought it
applicable in the New World. It is not sufficiently probative to
defend New York’s proper-cause requirement.
To begin, respondents and their amici point to several medieval English regulations from as early as 1285
that they say indicate a longstanding tradition of restricting the
public carry of firearms. See 13 Edw. 1, 102. The most prominent is
the 1328 Statute of Northampton (or Statute), passed shortly after
Edward II was deposed by force of arms and his son, Edward III,
took the throne of a kingdom where “tendency to turmoil and
rebellion was everywhere apparent throughout the realm.” N.
Trenholme, The Risings in the English Monastic Towns in 1327, 6 Am.
Hist. Rev. 650, 651 (1901). At the time, “[b]ands of malefactors,
knights as well as those of lesser degree, harried the country,
committing assaults and murders,” prompted by a more general
“spirit of insubordination” that led to a “decay in English
national life.” K. Vickers, England in the Later Middle Ages 107
(1926).
The Statute of Northampton was, in part, “a
product of . . . the acute disorder that still plagued
England.” A. Verduyn, The Politics of Law and Order During the
Early Years of Edward III, 108 Eng. Hist. Rev. 842, 850 (1993). It
provided that, with some exceptions, Englishmen could not “come
before the King’s Justices, or other of the King’s Ministers doing
their office, with force and arms, nor bring no force in affray of
the peace, nor to go nor ride armed by night nor by day, in Fairs,
Markets, nor in the presence of the Justices or other Ministers,
nor in no part elsewhere, upon pain to forfeit their Armour to the
King, and their Bodies to Prison at the King’s pleasure.” 2 Edw. 3
c. 3 (1328).
Respondents argue that the prohibition on
“rid[ing]” or “go[ing] . . . armed” was a sweeping
restriction on public carry of self-defense weapons that would
ultimately be adopted in Colonial America and justify onerous
public-carry regulations. Notwithstanding the ink the parties spill
over this provision, the Statute of Northampton—at least as it was
understood during the Middle Ages—has little bearing on the Second
Amendment adopted in 1791. The Statute of Northampton was enacted
nearly 20 years before the Black Death, more than 200 years before
the birth of Shakespeare, more than 350 years before the Salem
Witch Trials, more than 450 years before the ratification of the
Constitution, and nearly 550 years before the adoption of the
Fourteenth Amendment.
The Statute’s prohibition on going or riding
“armed” obviously did not contemplate handguns, given they did not
appear in Europe until about the mid-1500s. See K. Chase, Firearms:
A Global History to 1700, p. 61 (2003). Rather, it appears to
have been centrally concerned with the wearing of armor. See, e.g. , Calendar of the Close Rolls, Edward III, 1330–1333,
p. 131 (Apr. 3, 1330) (H. Maxwell-Lyte ed. 1898); id. ,
at 243 (May 28, 1331); id. , Edward III, 1327–1330, at 314
(Aug. 29, 1328) (1896). If it did apply beyond armor, it applied to
such weapons as the “launcegay,” a 10- to 12-foot-long lightweight
lance. See 7 Rich. 2 c. 13 (1383); 20 Rich. 2 c. 1 (1396).
The Statute’s apparent focus on armor and,
perhaps, weapons like launcegays makes sense given that armor and
lances were generally worn or carried only when one intended to
engage in lawful combat or—as most early violations of the Statute
show—to breach the peace. See, e.g. , Calendar of the Close
Rolls, Edward III, 1327–1330, at 402 (July 7, 1328); id. ,
Edward III, 1333–1337, at 695 (Aug. 18, 1336) (1898). Contrast
these arms with daggers. In the medieval period, “[a]lmost everyone
carried a knife or a dagger in his belt.” H. Peterson, Daggers and
Fighting Knives of the Western World 12 (2001). While these knives
were used by knights in warfare, “[c]ivilians wore them for
self-protection,” among other things. Ibid. Respondents
point to no evidence suggesting the Statute applied to the smaller
medieval weapons that strike us as most analogous to modern
handguns.
When handguns were introduced in England during
the Tudor and early Stuart eras, they did prompt royal efforts at
suppression. For example, Henry VIII issued several proclamations
decrying the proliferation of handguns, and Parliament passed
several statutes restricting their possession. See, e.g. , 6
Hen. 8 c. 13, §1 (1514); 25 Hen. 8 c. 17, §1 (1533); 33 Hen. 8 c. 6
(1541); Prohibiting Use of Handguns and Crossbows (Jan. 1537), in 1
Tudor Royal Proclamations 249 (P. Hughes & J. Larkin eds.
1964). But Henry VIII’s displeasure with handguns arose not
primarily from concerns about their safety but rather their
inefficacy. Henry VIII worried that handguns threatened
Englishmen’s proficiency with the longbow—a weapon many believed
was crucial to English military victories in the 1300s and 1400s,
including the legendary English victories at Crécy and Agincourt.
See R. Payne-Gallwey, The Crossbow 32, 34 (1903); L. Schwoerer, Gun
Culture in Early Modern England 54 (2016) (Schwoerer).
Similarly, James I considered small
handguns—called dags—“utterly unserviceable for defence, Militarie
practise, or other lawful use.” A Proclamation Against Steelets,
Pocket Daggers, Pocket Dagges and Pistols (R. Barker printer 1616).
But, in any event, James I’s proclamation in 1616 “was the last one
regarding civilians carrying dags,” Schwoerer 63. “After this the
question faded without explanation.” Ibid. So, by the time
Englishmen began to arrive in America in the early 1600s, the
public carry of handguns was no longer widely proscribed.
When we look to the latter half of the 17th
century, respondents’ case only weakens. As in Heller , we
consider this history “[b]etween the [Stuart] Restoration [in 1660]
and the Glorious Revolution [in 1688]” to be particularly
instructive. 554 U. S., at 592. During that time, the Stuart
Kings Charles II and James II ramped up efforts to disarm their
political opponents, an experience that “caused Englishmen
. . . to be jealous of their arms.” Id. , at
593.
In one notable example, the government charged
Sir John Knight, a prominent detractor of James II, with violating
the Statute of Northampton because he allegedly “did walk about the
streets armed with guns, and that he went into the church of St.
Michael, in Bristol, in the time of divine service, with a gun, to
terrify the King’s subjects.” Sir John Knight’s Case , 3 Mod.
117, 87 Eng. Rep. 75, 76 (K. B. 1686). Chief Justice Holt explained
that the Statute of Northampton had “almost gone in desuetudinem ,” Rex v. Sir John Knight , 1 Comb.
38, 38–39, 90 Eng. Rep. 330 (K. B. 1686), meaning that the Statute
had largely become obsolete through disuse.[ 10 ] And the Chief Justice further explained that
the act of “go[ing] armed to terrify the King’s subjects”
was “a great offence at the common law ” and that the Statute
of Northampton “is but an affirmance of that law.” 3 Mod., at 118,
87 Eng. Rep., at 76 (first emphasis added). Thus, one’s conduct
“will come within the Act,”— i.e. , would terrify the King’s
subjects—only “where the crime shall appear to be malo animo,” 1
Comb., at 39, 90 Eng. Rep., at 330, with evil intent or malice.
Knight was ultimately acquitted by the jury.[ 11 ]
Just three years later, Parliament responded by
writing the “predecessor to our Second Amendment” into the 1689
English Bill of Rights, Heller , 554 U. S., at 593,
guaranteeing that “Protestants . . . may have Arms for
their Defence suitable to their Conditions, and as allowed by Law,”
1 Wm. & Mary c. 2, §7, in 3 Eng. Stat. at Large 417 (1689).
Although this right was initially limited—it was restricted to
Protestants and held only against the Crown, but not Parliament—it
represented a watershed in English history. Englishmen had “never
before claimed . . . the right of the individual to
arms.” Schwoerer 156.[ 12 ]
And as that individual right matured, “by the time of the
founding,” the right to keep and bear arms was “understood to be an
individual right protecting against both public and private
violence.” Heller , 554 U. S., at 594.
To be sure, the Statute of Northampton survived
both Sir John Knight’s Case and the English Bill of Rights,
but it was no obstacle to public carry for self-defense in the
decades leading to the founding. Serjeant William Hawkins, in his
widely read 1716 treatise, confirmed that “no wearing of Arms is
within the meaning of [the Statute of Northampton], unless it be
accompanied with such Circumstances as are apt to terrify the
People.” 1 Pleas of the Crown 136. To illustrate that proposition,
Hawkins noted as an example that “Persons of Quality” were “in no
Danger of Offending against this Statute by wearing common Weapons”
because, in those circumstances, it would be clear that they had no
“Intention to commit any Act of Violence or Disturbance of the
Peace.” Ibid. ; see also T. Barlow, The Justice of Peace 12
(1745). Respondents do not offer any evidence showing that, in the
early 18th century or after, the mere public carrying of a handgun
would terrify people. In fact, the opposite seems to have been
true. As time went on, “domestic gun culture [in England] softened”
any “terror” that firearms might once have conveyed. Schwoerer 4.
Thus, whatever place handguns had in English society during the
Tudor and Stuart reigns, by the time we reach the 18th century—and
near the founding—they had gained a fairly secure footing in
English culture.
At the very least, we cannot conclude from this
historical record that, by the time of the founding, English law
would have justified restricting the right to publicly bear arms
suited for self-defense only to those who demonstrate some special
need for self-protection.
2
Respondents next point us to the history of
the Colonies and early Republic, but there is little evidence of an
early American practice of regulating public carry by the general
public. This should come as no surprise—English subjects founded
the Colonies at about the time England had itself begun to
eliminate restrictions on the ownership and use of handguns.
In the colonial era, respondents point to only
three restrictions on public carry. For starters, we doubt that three colonial regulations could suffice to show a tradition
of public-carry regulation. In any event, even looking at these
laws on their own terms, we are not convinced that they regulated
public carry akin to the New York law before us.
Two of the statutes were substantively
identical. Colonial Massachusetts and New Hampshire both authorized
justices of the peace to arrest “all Affrayers, Rioters,
Disturbers, or Breakers of the Peace, and such as shall ride or go
armed Offensively . . . by Night or by Day, in Fear or
Affray of Their Majesties Liege People.” 1692 Mass. Acts and Laws
no. 6, pp. 11–12; see 1699 N. H. Acts and Laws ch. 1.
Respondents and their amici contend that being “armed
offensively” meant bearing any offensive weapons, including
firearms. See Brief for Respondents 33. In particular, respondents’ amici argue that “ ‘offensive’ ” arms in the 1600s
and 1700s were what Blackstone and others referred to as
“ ‘dangerous or unusual weapons,’ ” Brief for Professors
of History and Law as Amici Curiae 7 (quoting 4 Blackstone,
Commentaries, at 148–149), a category that they say included
firearms, see also post, at 40–42 (Breyer, J.,
dissenting).
Respondents, their amici , and the dissent
all misunderstand these statutes. Far from banning the carrying of
any class of firearms, they merely codified the existing common-law
offense of bearing arms to terrorize the people, as had the Statute
of Northampton itself. See supra , at 34–37. For instance,
the Massachusetts statute proscribed “go[ing] armed Offensively
. . . in Fear or Affray” of the people, indicating that
these laws were modeled after the Statute of Northampton to the
extent that the statute would have been understood to limit public
carry in the late 1600s . Moreover, it makes very little
sense to read these statutes as banning the public carry of all
firearms just a few years after Chief Justice Holt in Sir John
Knight’s Case indicated that the English common law did not do
so.
Regardless, even if respondents’ reading of
these colonial statutes were correct, it would still do little to
support restrictions on the public carry of handguns today .
At most, respondents can show that colonial legislatures sometimes
prohibited the carrying of “dangerous and unusual weapons”—a fact
we already acknowledged in Heller . See 554 U. S., at
627. Drawing from this historical tradition, we explained there
that the Second Amendment protects only the carrying of weapons
that are those “in common use at the time,” as opposed to those
that “are highly unusual in society at large.” Ibid. (internal quotation marks omitted). Whatever the likelihood that
handguns were considered “dangerous and unusual” during the
colonial period, they are indisputably in “common use” for
self-defense today. They are, in fact, “the quintessential
self-defense weapon.” Id. , at 629. Thus, even if these
colonial laws prohibited the carrying of handguns because they were
considered “dangerous and unusual weapons” in the 1690s, they
provide no justification for laws restricting the public carry of
weapons that are unquestionably in common use today.
The third statute invoked by respondents was
enacted in East New Jersey in 1686. It prohibited the concealed
carry of “pocket pistol[s]” or other “unusual or unlawful weapons,”
and it further prohibited “planter[s]” from carrying all pistols
unless in military service or, if “strangers,” when traveling
through the Province. An Act Against Wearing Swords, &c., ch.
9, in Grants, Concessions, and Original Constitutions of the
Province of New Jersey 290 (2d ed. 1881) (Grants and Concessions).
These restrictions do not meaningfully support respondents. The law
restricted only concealed carry, not all public carry, and its
restrictions applied only to certain “unusual or unlawful weapons,”
including “pocket pistol[s].” Ibid . It also did not apply to
all pistols, let alone all firearms. “Pocket pistols” had barrel
lengths of perhaps 3 or 4 inches, far smaller than the 6-inch to
14-inch barrels found on the other belt and hip pistols that were
commonly used for lawful purposes in the 1600s. J. George, English
Pistols and Revolvers 16 (1938); see also, e.g. , 14 Car. 2
c. 3, §20 (1662); H. Peterson, Arms and Armor in Colonial
America, 1526–1783, p. 208 (1956) (Peterson). Moreover, the
law prohibited only the concealed carry of pocket pistols;
it presumably did not by its terms touch the open carry of larger,
presumably more common pistols, except as to “planters.”[ 13 ] In colonial times, a “planter”
was simply a farmer or plantation owner who settled new territory.
R. Lederer, Colonial American English 175 (1985); New Jersey State
Archives, J. Klett, Using the Records of the East and West Jersey
Proprietors 31 (rev. ed. 2014),
https://www.nj.gov/state/archives/pdf/proprietors.pdf. While the
reason behind this singular restriction is not entirely clear,
planters may have been targeted because colonial-era East New
Jersey was riven with “strife and excitement” between planters and
the Colony’s proprietors “respecting titles to the soil.” See W.
Whitehead, East Jersey Under the Proprietary Governments 150–151
(rev. 2d ed. 1875); see also T. Gordon, The History of New Jersey
49 (1834).
In any event, we cannot put meaningful weight on
this solitary statute. First, although the “planter” restriction
may have prohibited the public carry of pistols, it did not
prohibit planters from carrying long guns for
self-defense—including the popular musket and carbine. See Peterson
41. Second, it does not appear that the statute survived for very
long. By 1694, East New Jersey provided that no slave “be permitted
to carry any gun or pistol . . . into the woods, or
plantations” unless their owner accompanied them. Grants and
Concessions 341. If slave-owning planters were prohibited from
carrying pistols, it is hard to comprehend why slaves would have
been able to carry them in the planter’s presence. Moreover, there
is no evidence that the 1686 statute survived the 1702 merger of
East and West New Jersey. See 1 Nevill, Acts of the General
Assembly of the Province of New-Jersey (1752). At most eight years
of history in half a Colony roughly a century before the founding
sheds little light on how to properly interpret the Second
Amendment.
Respondents next direct our attention to three
late-18th-century and early-19th-century statutes, but each
parallels the colonial statutes already discussed. One 1786
Virginia statute provided that “no man, great nor small, [shall] go
nor ride armed by night nor by day, in fairs or markets, or in
other places, in terror of the Country.” Collection of All Such
Acts of the General Assembly of Virginia ch. 21, p. 33
(1794).[ 14 ] A Massachusetts
statute from 1795 commanded justices of the peace to arrest “all
affrayers, rioters, disturbers, or breakers of the peace, and such
as shall ride or go armed offensively, to the fear or terror of the
good citizens of this Commonwealth.” 1795 Mass. Acts and Laws ch.
2, p. 436, in Laws of the Commonwealth of Massachusetts. And
an 1801 Tennessee statute likewise required any person who would
“publicly ride or go armed to the terror of the people, or
privately carry any dirk, large knife, pistol or any other
dangerous weapon, to the fear or terror of any person” to post a
surety; otherwise, his continued violation of the law would be
“punished as for a breach of the peace, or riot at common law.”
1801 Tenn. Acts pp. 260–261.
A by-now-familiar thread runs through these
three statutes: They prohibit bearing arms in a way that spreads
“fear” or “terror” among the people. As we have already explained,
Chief Justice Holt in Sir John Knight’s Case interpreted
this in Terrorem Populi element to require something more
than merely carrying a firearm in public. See supra , at
34–35. Respondents give us no reason to think that the founding
generation held a different view. Thus, all told, in the century
leading up to the Second Amendment and in the first decade after
its adoption, there is no historical basis for concluding that the
pre-existing right enshrined in the Second Amendment permitted
broad prohibitions on all forms of public carry.
3
Only after the ratification of the Second
Amendment in 1791 did public-carry restrictions proliferate.
Respondents rely heavily on these restrictions, which generally
fell into three categories: common-law offenses, statutory
prohibitions, and “surety” statutes. None of these restrictions
imposed a substantial burden on public carry analogous to the
burden created by New York’s restrictive licensing regime. Common-Law Offenses . As during the
colonial and founding periods, the common-law offenses of “affray”
or going armed “to the terror of the people” continued to impose
some limits on firearm carry in the antebellum period. But as with
the earlier periods, there is no evidence indicating that these
common-law limitations impaired the right of the general population
to peaceable public carry.
For example, the Tennessee attorney general once
charged a defendant with the common-law offense of affray, arguing
that the man committed the crime when he “ ‘arm[ed] himself
with dangerous and unusual weapons, in such a manner as will
naturally cause terror to the people.’ ” Simpson v. State , 13 Tenn. 356, 358 (1833). More specifically, the
indictment charged that Simpson “with force and arms being arrayed
in a warlike manner . . . unlawfully, and to the great
terror and disturbance of divers good citizens, did make an
affray.” Id ., at 361. The Tennessee Supreme Court quashed
the indictment, holding that the Statute of Northampton was never
part of Tennessee law. Id. , at 359. But even assuming that
Tennesseans’ ancestors brought with them the common law associated
with the Statute, the Simpson court found that if the
Statute had made, as an “independent ground of affray,” the mere
arming of oneself with firearms, the Tennessee Constitution’s
Second Amendment analogue had “completely abrogated it.” Id. , at 360. At least in light of that constitutional
guarantee, the court did not think that it could attribute to the
mere carrying of arms “a necessarily consequent operation as terror
to the people.” Ibid. Perhaps more telling was the North Carolina
Supreme Court’s decision in State v. Huntly , 25
N. C. 418 (1843) ( per curiam ). Unlike the Tennessee
Supreme Court in Simpson , the Huntly court held that
the common-law offense codified by the Statute of Northampton was
part of the State’s law. See 25 N. C., at 421–422. However,
consistent with the Statute’s long-settled interpretation, the
North Carolina Supreme Court acknowledged “that the carrying of a
gun” for a lawful purpose “ per se constitutes no
offence.” Id. , at 422–423. Only carrying for a “wicked
purpose” with a “mischievous result . . . constitute[d a]
crime.” Id. , at 423; see also J. Haywood, The Duty and
Office of Justices of Peace 10 (1800); H. Potter, The Office and
Duties of a Justice of the Peace 39 (1816).[ 15 ] Other state courts likewise recognized that
the common law did not punish the carrying of deadly weapons per se , but only the carrying of such weapons “for the
purpose of an affray, and in such manner as to strike terror to the
people.” O’Neil v. State , 16 Ala. 65, 67 (1849).
Therefore, those who sought to carry firearms publicly and
peaceably in antebellum America were generally free to do so. Statutory Prohibitions . In the early to
mid-19th century, some States began enacting laws that proscribed
the concealed carry of pistols and other small weapons. As we
recognized in Heller , “the majority of the 19th-century
courts to consider the question held that [these] prohibitions on
carrying concealed weapons were lawful under the Second Amendment
or state analogues.” 554 U. S., at 626. Respondents
unsurprisingly cite these statutes[ 16 ]—and decisions upholding them[ 17 ]—as evidence that States were historically
free to ban public carry.
In fact, however, the history reveals a
consensus that States could not ban public carry altogether.
Respondents’ cited opinions agreed that concealed-carry
prohibitions were constitutional only if they did not similarly
prohibit open carry. That was true in Alabama. See State v. Reid , 1 Ala. 612, 616, 619–621
(1840).[ 18 ] It was also true
in Louisiana. See State v. Chandler , 5 La. 489, 490
(1850).[ 19 ] Kentucky,
meanwhile, went one step further—the State Supreme Court invalidated a concealed-carry prohibition. See Bliss v. Commonwealth , 12 Ky. 90 (1822) . [ 20 ]
The Georgia Supreme Court’s decision in Nunn v. State , 1 Ga. 243 (1846), is particularly
instructive. Georgia’s 1837 statute broadly prohibited “wearing” or
“carrying” pistols “as arms of offence or defence,” without
distinguishing between concealed and open carry. 1837 Ga. Acts 90,
§1. To the extent the 1837 Act prohibited “carrying certain weapons secretly ,” the court explained, it was “valid.” Nunn ,
1 Ga., at 251. But to the extent the Act also prohibited “bearing
arms openly ,” the court went on, it was “in conflict with
the Constitutio[n] and void .” Ibid. ; see also Heller , 554 U. S., at 612. The Georgia Supreme Court’s
treatment of the State’s general prohibition on the public carriage
of handguns indicates that it was considered beyond the
constitutional pale in antebellum America to altogether prohibit
public carry.
Finally, we agree that Tennessee’s prohibition
on carrying “publicly or privately” any “belt or pocket pisto[l],”
1821 Tenn. Acts ch. 13, p. 15, was, on its face, uniquely
severe, see Heller , 554 U. S., at 629. That said, when
the Tennessee Supreme Court addressed the constitutionality of a
substantively identical successor provision, see 1870 Tenn. Acts
ch. 13, §1, p. 28, the court read this language to permit the
public carry of larger, military-style pistols because any
categorical prohibition on their carry would “violat[e] the
constitutional right to keep arms.” Andrews v. State ,
50 Tenn. 165, 187 (1871); see also Heller , 554 U. S.,
at 629 (discussing Andrews ).[ 21 ]
All told, these antebellum state-court decisions
evince a consensus view that States could not altogether prohibit
the public carry of “arms” protected by the Second Amendment or
state analogues.[ 22 ] Surety Statutes . In the mid-19th century,
many jurisdictions began adopting surety statutes that required
certain individuals to post bond before carrying weapons in public.
Although respondents seize on these laws to justify the
proper-cause restriction, their reliance on them is misplaced.
These laws were not bans on public carry, and they typically
targeted only those threatening to do harm.
As discussed earlier, Massachusetts had
prohibited riding or going “armed offensively, to the fear or
terror of the good citizens of this Commonwealth” since 1795. 1795
Mass. Acts and Laws ch. 2, at 436, in Laws of the Commonwealth of
Massachusetts. In 1836, Massachusetts enacted a new law
providing:
“If any person shall go armed with a dirk,
dagger, sword, pistol, or other offensive and dangerous weapon,
without reasonable cause to fear an assault or other injury, or
violence to his person, or to his family or property, he may, on
complaint of any person having reasonable cause to fear an injury,
or breach of the peace, be required to find sureties for keeping
the peace, for a term not exceeding six months, with the right of
appealing as before provided.” Mass. Rev. Stat., ch. 134, §16.
In short, the Commonwealth required any person
who was reasonably likely to “breach the peace,” and who, standing
accused, could not prove a special need for self-defense, to post a
bond before publicly carrying a firearm. Between 1838 and 1871,
nine other jurisdictions adopted variants of the Massachusetts
law.[ 23 ]
Contrary to respondents’ position, these
“reasonable-cause laws” in no way represented the “direct
precursor” to the proper-cause requirement. Brief for Respondents
27. While New York presumes that individuals have no public
carry right without a showing of heightened need, the surety
statutes presumed that individuals had a right to public
carry that could be burdened only if another could make out a
specific showing of “reasonable cause to fear an injury, or breach
of the peace.” Mass. Rev. Stat., ch. 134, §16 (1836).[ 24 ] As William Rawle explained in an
influential treatise, an individual’s carrying of arms was
“sufficient cause to require him to give surety of the peace” only
when “attended with circumstances giving just reason to fear that
he purposes to make an unlawful use of them.” A View of the
Constitution of the United States of America 126 (2d ed. 1829).
Then, even on such a showing, the surety laws did not prohibit public carry in locations frequented by the general
community. Rather, an accused arms-bearer “could go on carrying
without criminal penalty” so long as he “post[ed] money that would
be forfeited if he breached the peace or injured others—a
requirement from which he was exempt if he needed
self-defense.” Wrenn , 864 F. 3d, at 661.
Thus, unlike New York’s regime, a showing of
special need was required only after an individual was
reasonably accused of intending to injure another or breach the
peace. And, even then, proving special need simply avoided a fee
rather than a ban. All told, therefore, “[u]nder surety laws
. . . everyone started out with robust carrying rights”
and only those reasonably accused were required to show a special
need in order to avoid posting a bond. Ibid. These
antebellum special-need requirements “did not expand carrying for
the responsible; it shrank burdens on carrying by the (allegedly)
reckless.” Ibid. One Court of Appeals has nonetheless remarked
that these surety laws were “a severe constraint on anyone thinking
of carrying a weapon in public.” Young , 992 F. 3d, at
820. That contention has little support in the historical record.
Respondents cite no evidence showing the average size of surety
postings. And given that surety laws were “intended merely for
prevention” and were “not meant as any degree of punishment,” 4
Blackstone, Commentaries, at 249, the burden these surety statutes
may have had on the right to public carry was likely too
insignificant to shed light on New York’s proper-cause standard—a
violation of which can carry a 4-year prison term or a $5,000 fine.
In Heller , we noted that founding-era laws punishing
unlawful discharge “with a small fine and forfeiture of the weapon
. . . , not with significant criminal penalties,”
likely did not “preven[t] a person in the founding era from using a
gun to protect himself or his family from violence, or that if he
did so the law would be enforced against him.” 554 U. S., at
633–634. Similarly, we have little reason to think that the
hypothetical possibility of posting a bond would have prevented
anyone from carrying a firearm for self-defense in the 19th
century.
Besides, respondents offer little evidence that
authorities ever enforced surety laws. The only recorded case that
we know of involved a justice of the peace declining to
require a surety, even when the complainant alleged that the
arms-bearer “ ‘did threaten to beat, wou[n]d, mai[m], and
kill’ ” him. Brief for Professor Robert Leider et al. as Amici Curiae 31 (quoting Grover v. Bullock ,
No. 185 (Worcester Cty., Aug. 13, 1853)); see E. Ruben & S.
Cornell, Firearm Regionalism and Public Carry: Placing Southern
Antebellum Case Law in Context, 125 Yale L. J. Forum 121, 130,
n. 53 (2015). And one scholar who canvassed 19th-century
newspapers—which routinely reported on local judicial matters—found
only a handful of other examples in Massachusetts and the District
of Columbia, all involving black defendants who may have been
targeted for selective or pretextual enforcement. See R. Leider,
Constitutional Liquidation, Surety Laws, and the Right To Bear Arms
15–17, in New Histories of Gun Rights and Regulation (J. Blocher,
J. Charles, & D. Miller eds.) (forthcoming); see also Brief for
Professor Robert Leider et al. as Amici Curiae 31–32.
That is surely too slender a reed on which to hang a historical
tradition of restricting the right to public carry.[ 25 ]
Respondents also argue that surety statutes were
severe restrictions on firearms because the “reasonable cause to
fear” standard was essentially pro forma , given that
“merely carrying firearms in populous areas breached the peace” per se . Brief for Respondents 27. But that is a
counterintuitive reading of the language that the surety statutes
actually used. If the mere carrying of handguns breached the peace,
it would be odd to draft a surety statute requiring a complainant
to demonstrate “reasonable cause to fear an injury, or breach of
the peace,” Mass. Rev. Stat., ch. 134, §16, rather than a
reasonable likelihood that the arms-bearer carried a covered
weapon. After all, if it was the nature of the weapon rather than
the manner of carry that was dispositive, then the “reasonable
fear” requirement would be redundant.
Moreover, the overlapping scope of surety
statutes and criminal statutes suggests that the former were not
viewed as substantial restrictions on public carry. For example,
when Massachusetts enacted its surety statute in 1836, it
reaffirmed its 1794 criminal prohibition on “go[ing] armed
offensively, to the terror of the people.” Mass. Rev. Stat., ch.
85, §24. And Massachusetts continued to criminalize the carrying of
various “dangerous weapons” well after passing the 1836 surety
statute. See, e.g. , 1850 Mass. Acts ch. 194, §1,
p. 401; Mass. Gen. Stat., ch. 164, §10 (1860). Similarly,
Virginia had criminalized the concealed carry of pistols since
1838, see 1838 Va. Acts ch. 101, §1, nearly a decade before it
enacted its surety statute, see 1847 Va. Acts ch. 14, §16. It is
unlikely that these surety statutes constituted a “severe”
restraint on public carry, let alone a restriction tantamount to a
ban, when they were supplemented by direct criminal prohibitions on
specific weapons and methods of carry.
To summarize: The historical evidence from
antebellum America does demonstrate that the manner of
public carry was subject to reasonable regulation. Under the common
law, individuals could not carry deadly weapons in a manner likely
to terrorize others. Similarly, although surety statutes did not
directly restrict public carry, they did provide financial
incentives for responsible arms carrying. Finally, States could
lawfully eliminate one kind of public carry—concealed carry—so long
as they left open the option to carry openly . None of these historical limitations on the
right to bear arms approach New York’s proper-cause requirement
because none operated to prevent law-abiding citizens with ordinary
self-defense needs from carrying arms in public for that
purpose.
4
Evidence from around the adoption of the
Fourteenth Amendment also fails to support respondents’ position.
For the most part, respondents and the United States ignore the
“outpouring of discussion of the [right to keep and bear arms] in
Congress and in public discourse, as people debated whether and how
to secure constitutional rights for newly free slaves” after the
Civil War. Heller , 554 U. S., at 614. Of course, we are
not obliged to sift the historical materials for evidence to
sustain New York’s statute. That is respondents’ burden.
Nevertheless, we think a short review of the public discourse
surrounding Reconstruction is useful in demonstrating how public
carry for self-defense remained a central component of the
protection that the Fourteenth Amendment secured for all
citizens.
A short prologue is in order. Even before the
Civil War commenced in 1861, this Court indirectly affirmed the
importance of the right to keep and bear arms in public. Writing
for the Court in Dred Scott v. Sandford , 19 How. 393
(1857), Chief Justice Taney offered what he thought was a parade of
horribles that would result from recognizing that free blacks were
citizens of the United States. If blacks were citizens, Taney
fretted, they would be entitled to the privileges and immunities of
citizens, including the right “to keep and carry arms wherever
they went .” Id. , at 417 (emphasis added). Thus, even
Chief Justice Taney recognized (albeit unenthusiastically in the
case of blacks) that public carry was a component of the right to
keep and bear arms—a right free blacks were often denied in
antebellum America.
After the Civil War, of course, the exercise of
this fundamental right by freed slaves was systematically thwarted.
This Court has already recounted some of the Southern abuses
violating blacks’ right to keep and bear arms. See McDonald ,
561 U. S., at 771 (noting the “systematic efforts” made to
disarm blacks); id. , at 845–847 (Thomas, J., concurring in
part and concurring in judgment); see also S. Exec. Doc. No. 43,
39th Cong., 1st Sess., 8 (1866) (“Pistols, old muskets, and
shotguns were taken away from [freed slaves] as such weapons would
be wrested from the hands of lunatics”).
In the years before the 39th Congress proposed
the Fourteenth Amendment, the Freedmen’s Bureau regularly kept it
abreast of the dangers to blacks and Union men in the postbellum
South. The reports described how blacks used publicly carried
weapons to defend themselves and their communities. For example,
the Bureau reported that a teacher from a Freedmen’s school in
Maryland had written to say that, because of attacks on the school,
“[b]oth the mayor and sheriff have warned the colored people to go
armed to school, (which they do,)” and that the “[t]he
superintendent of schools came down and brought [the teacher] a
revolver” for his protection. Cong. Globe, 39th Cong., 1st Sess.,
658 (1866); see also H. R. Exec. Doc. No. 68, 39th Cong., 2d
Sess., 91 (1867) (noting how, during the New Orleans riots, blacks
under attack “defended themselves . . . with such pistols
as they had”).
Witnesses before the Joint Committee on
Reconstruction also described the depredations visited on Southern
blacks, and the efforts they made to defend themselves. One
Virginia music professor related that when “[t]wo Union men were
attacked . . . they drew their revolvers and held their
assailants at bay.” H. R. Rep. No. 30, 39th Cong., 1st Sess.,
pt. 2, p. 110 (1866). An assistant commissioner to the Bureau
from Alabama similarly reported that men were “robbing and
disarming negroes upon the highway,” H. R. Exec. Doc. No. 70,
39th Cong., 1st Sess., 297 (1866), indicating that blacks indeed
carried arms publicly for their self- protection, even if not
always with success. See also H. R. Exec. Doc. No. 329, 40th
Cong., 2d Sess., 41 (1868) (describing a Ku Klux Klan outfit that
rode “through the country . . . robbing every one they
come across of money, pistols, papers, &c.”); id. , at 36
(noting how a black man in Tennessee had been murdered on his way
to get book subscriptions, with the murderer taking, among other
things, the man’s pistol).
Blacks had “procured great numbers of old army
muskets and revolvers, particularly in Texas,” and “employed them
to protect themselves” with “vigor and audacity.” S. Exec. Doc. No.
43, 39th Cong., 1st Sess., at 8. Seeing that government was
inadequately protecting them, “there [was] the strongest desire on
the part of the freedmen to secure arms, revolvers particularly.”
H. R. Rep. No. 30, 39th Cong., 1st Sess., pt. 3, at 102.
On July 6, 1868, Congress extended the 1866
Freedmen’s Bureau Act, see 15Stat. 83, and reaffirmed that freedmen
were entitled to the “full and equal benefit of all laws and
proceedings concerning personal liberty [and] personal security
. . . including the constitutional right to keep and
bear arms .” §14, 14Stat. 176 (1866) (emphasis added). That same
day, a Bureau official reported that freedmen in Kentucky and
Tennessee were still constantly under threat: “No Union man or
negro who attempts to take any active part in politics, or the
improvement of his race, is safe a single day; and nearly all sleep
upon their arms at night, and carry concealed weapons during the
day.” H. R. Exec. Doc. No. 329, 40th Cong., 2d Sess., at
40.
Of course, even during Reconstruction the right
to keep and bear arms had limits. But those limits were consistent
with a right of the public to peaceably carry handguns for
self-defense. For instance, when General D. E. Sickles issued a
decree in 1866 pre-empting South Carolina’s Black Codes—which
prohibited firearm possession by blacks—he stated: “The
constitutional rights of all loyal and well- disposed inhabitants
to bear arms will not be infringed; nevertheless this shall not be
construed to sanction the unlawful practice of carrying concealed
weapons. . . . And no disorderly person, vagrant, or
disturber of the peace, shall be allowed to bear arms.” Cong.
Globe, 39th Cong., 1st Sess., at 908–909; see also McDonald ,
561 U. S., at 847–848 (opinion of Thomas, J.).[ 26 ] Around the same time, the editors of
The Loyal Georgian, a prominent black-owned newspaper, were asked
by “A Colored Citizen” whether “colored persons [have] a right to
own and carry fire arms.” The editors responded that blacks had
“the same right to own and carry fire arms that other citizens have.” The Loyal Georgian, Feb. 3, 1866, p. 3, col.
4. And, borrowing language from a Freedmen’s Bureau circular, the
editors maintained that “[a]ny person, white or black, may be
disarmed if convicted of making an improper or dangerous use of
weapons,” even though “no military or civil officer has the right
or authority to disarm any class of people, thereby placing them at
the mercy of others.” Ibid. (quoting Circular No. 5,
Freedmen’s Bureau, Dec. 22, 1865); see also McDonald , 561
U. S., at 848–849 (opinion of Thomas, J.).[ 27 ]
As for Reconstruction-era state regulations,
there was little innovation over the kinds of public-carry
restrictions that had been commonplace in the early 19th century.
For instance, South Carolina in 1870 authorized the arrest of “all
who go armed offensively, to the terror of the people,” 1870
S. C. Acts p. 403, no. 288, §4, parroting earlier
statutes that codified the common-law offense. That same year,
after it cleaved from Virginia, West Virginia enacted a surety
statute nearly identical to the one it inherited from Virginia. See
W. Va. Code, ch. 153, §8. Also in 1870, Tennessee essentially
reenacted its 1821 prohibition on the public carry of handguns but,
as explained above, Tennessee courts interpreted that statute to
exempt large pistols suitable for military use. See supra ,
at 46.
Respondents and the United States, however,
direct our attention primarily to two late-19th-century cases in
Texas. In 1871, Texas law forbade anyone from “carrying on or about
his person . . . any pistol . . . unless he has
reasonable grounds for fearing an unlawful attack on his person.”
1871 Tex. Gen. Laws §1. The Texas Supreme Court upheld that
restriction in English v. State , 35 Tex. 473 (1871).
The Court reasoned that the Second Amendment, and the State’s
constitutional analogue, protected only those arms “as are useful
and proper to an armed militia,” including holster pistols, but not
other kinds of handguns. Id. , at 474–475. Beyond that
constitutional holding, the English court further opined
that the law was not “contrary to public policy,” id. , at
479, given that it “ma[de] all necessary exceptions” allowing
deadly weapons to “be carried as means of self-defense,” and
therefore “fully cover[ed] all wants of society,” id. , at
477.
Four years later, in State v. Duke , 42 Tex. 455 (1875), the Texas Supreme Court modified
its analysis. The court reinterpreted Texas’ State Constitution to
protect not only military-style weapons but rather all arms “as are
commonly kept, according to the customs of the people, and are
appropriate for open and manly use in self-defense.” Id. , at
458. On that understanding, the court recognized that, in addition
to “holster pistol[s],” the right to bear arms covered the carry of
“such pistols at least as are not adapted to being carried
concealed.” Id. , at 458–459. Nonetheless, after expanding
the scope of firearms that warranted state constitutional
protection, Duke held that requiring any pistol-bearer to
have “ ‘reasonable grounds fearing an unlawful attack on
[one’s] person’ ” was a “legitimate and highly proper”
regulation of handgun carriage. Id. , at 456, 459–460. Duke thus concluded that the 1871 statute “appear[ed] to
have respected the right to carry a pistol openly when needed for
self-defense.” Id. , at 459.
We acknowledge that the Texas cases support New
York’s proper-cause requirement, which one can analogize to Texas’
“reasonable grounds” standard. But the Texas statute, and the
rationales set forth in English and Duke , are
outliers. In fact, only one other State, West Virginia, adopted a
similar public-carry statute before 1900. See W. Va. Code, ch. 148,
§7 (1887). The West Virginia Supreme Court upheld that prohibition,
reasoning that no handguns of any kind were protected by the
Second Amendment, a rationale endorsed by no other court during
this period. See State v. Workman , 35 W. Va.
367, 371–374, 14 S.E. 9, 11 (1891). The Texas decisions therefore
provide little insight into how postbellum courts viewed the right
to carry protected arms in public.
In the end, while we recognize the support that
postbellum Texas provides for respondents’ view, we will not give
disproportionate weight to a single state statute and a pair of
state-court decisions. As in Heller , we will not “stake our
interpretation of the Second Amendment upon a single law, in effect
in a single [State], that contradicts the overwhelming weight of
other evidence regarding the right to keep and bear arms for
defense” in public. 554 U. S., at 632.
5
Finally, respondents point to the slight
uptick in gun regulation during the late-19th century—principally
in the Western Territories. As we suggested in Heller ,
however, late-19th-century evidence cannot provide much insight
into the meaning of the Second Amendment when it contradicts
earlier evidence. See id. , at 614; supra , at
28.[ 28 ] Here, moreover,
respondents’ reliance on late-19th-century laws has several serious
flaws even beyond their temporal distance from the founding.
The vast majority of the statutes that
respondents invoke come from the Western Territories. Two
Territories prohibited the carry of pistols in towns, cities, and
villages, but seemingly permitted the carry of rifles and other
long guns everywhere. See 1889 Ariz. Terr. Sess. Laws no. 13, §1,
p. 16; 1869 N. M. Laws ch. 32, §§1–2,
p. 72.[ 29 ] Two others
prohibited the carry of all firearms in towns, cities, and
villages, including long guns. See 1875 Wyo. Terr. Sess. Laws ch.
52, §1; 1889 Idaho Terr. Gen. Laws §1, p. 23. And one
Territory completely prohibited public carry of pistols everywhere , but allowed the carry of “shot-guns or rifles”
for certain purposes. See 1890 Okla. Terr. Stats., Art. 47, §§1–2,
5, p. 495.
These territorial restrictions fail to justify
New York’s proper-cause requirement for several reasons. First, the
bare existence of these localized restrictions cannot overcome the
overwhelming evidence of an otherwise enduring American tradition
permitting public carry. For starters, “[t]he very transitional and
temporary character of the American [territorial] system” often
“permitted legislative improvisations which might not have been
tolerated in a permanent setup.” E. Pomeroy, The Territories and
the United States 1861–1890, p. 4 (1947). These territorial
“legislative improvisations,” which conflict with the Nation’s
earlier approach to firearm regulation, are most unlikely to
reflect “the origins and continuing significance of the Second
Amendment” and we do not consider them “instructive.” Heller , 554 U. S., at 614.
The exceptional nature of these western
restrictions is all the more apparent when one considers the
miniscule territorial populations who would have lived under them.
To put that point into perspective, one need not look further than
the 1890 census. Roughly 62 million people lived in the United
States at that time. Arizona, Idaho, New Mexico, Oklahoma, and
Wyoming combined to account for only 420,000 of those
inhabitants—about two-thirds of 1% of the population. See Dept. of
Interior, Compendium of the Eleventh Census: 1890, Part
I.–Population 2 (1892). Put simply, these western restrictions were
irrelevant to more than 99% of the American population. We have
already explained that we will not stake our interpretation of the
Second Amendment upon a law in effect in a single State, or a
single city, “that contradicts the overwhelming weight of other
evidence regarding the right to keep and bear arms” in public for
self-defense. Heller , 554 U. S., at 632; see supra, at 57–58. Similarly, we will not stake our
interpretation on a handful of temporary territorial laws that were
enacted nearly a century after the Second Amendment’s adoption,
governed less than 1% of the American population, and also
“contradic[t] the overwhelming weight” of other, more
contemporaneous historical evidence. Heller , 554 U. S.,
at 632.
Second, because these territorial laws were
rarely subject to judicial scrutiny, we do not know the basis of
their perceived legality. When States generally prohibited both
open and concealed carry of handguns in the late-19th century,
state courts usually upheld the restrictions when they exempted
army revolvers, or read the laws to exempt at least that category
of weapons. See, e.g. , Haile v. State , 38 Ark.
564, 567 (1882); Wilson v. State , 33 Ark. 557, 560
(1878); Fife v. State , 31 Ark. 455, 461 (1876); State v. Wilburn , 66 Tenn. 57, 60 (1872); Andrews , 50 Tenn., at 187.[ 30 ] Those state courts that upheld broader prohibitions
without qualification generally operated under a fundamental
misunderstanding of the right to bear arms, as expressed in Heller . For example, the Kansas Supreme Court upheld a
complete ban on public carry enacted by the city of Salina in 1901
based on the rationale that the Second Amendment protects only “the
right to bear arms as a member of the state militia, or some other
military organization provided for by law.” Salina v. Blaksley , 72 Kan. 230, 232, 83 P. 619, 620 (1905). That was
clearly erroneous. See Heller , 554 U. S., at 592.
Absent any evidence explaining why these
unprecedented prohibitions on all public carry were
understood to comport with the Second Amendment, we fail to see how
they inform “the origins and continuing significance of the
Amendment.” Id. , at 614; see also The Federalist No. 37,
at 229 (explaining that the meaning of ambiguous
constitutional provisions can be “liquidated and ascertained by
a series of particular discussions and adjudications ” (emphasis
added)).
Finally, these territorial restrictions deserve
little weight because they were—consistent with the transitory
nature of territorial government—short lived. Some were held
unconstitutional shortly after passage. See In re
Brickey , 8 Idaho 597, 70 P. 609 (1902). Others did not survive
a Territory’s admission to the Union as a State. See Wyo. Rev.
Stat., ch. 3, §5051 (1899) (1890 law enacted upon statehood
prohibiting public carry only when combined with “intent, or avowed
purpose, of injuring [one’s] fellow-man”). Thus, they appear more
as passing regulatory efforts by not-yet-mature jurisdictions on
the way to statehood, rather than part of an enduring American
tradition of state regulation.
Beyond these Territories, respondents identify
one Western State—Kansas—that instructed cities with more than
15,000 inhabitants to pass ordinances prohibiting the public carry
of firearms. See 1881 Kan. Sess. Laws §§1, 23, pp. 79,
92.[ 31 ] By 1890, the only
cities meeting the population threshold were Kansas City, Topeka,
and Wichita. See Compendium of the Eleventh Census: 1890, at
442–452. Even if each of these three cities enacted prohibitions by
1890, their combined population (93,000) accounted for only 6.5% of
Kansas’ total population. Ibid. Although other Kansas cities
may also have restricted public carry unilaterally,[ 32 ] the lone late-19th-century state law
respondents identify does not prove that Kansas meaningfully
restricted public carry, let alone demonstrate a broad tradition of
States doing so.
* * *
At the end of this long journey through the
Anglo-American history of public carry, we conclude that
respondents have not met their burden to identify an American
tradition justifying the State’s proper-cause requirement. The
Second Amendment guaranteed to “all Americans” the right to bear
commonly used arms in public subject to certain reasonable,
well-defined restrictions. Heller , 554 U. S., at 581.
Those restrictions, for example, limited the intent for which one
could carry arms, the manner by which one carried arms, or the
exceptional circumstances under which one could not carry arms,
such as before justices of the peace and other government
officials. Apart from a few late-19th-century outlier
jurisdictions, American governments simply have not broadly
prohibited the public carry of commonly used firearms for personal
defense. Nor, subject to a few late-in-time outliers, have American
governments required law-abiding, responsible citizens to
“demonstrate a special need for self-protection distinguishable
from that of the general community” in order to carry arms in
public. Klenosky , 75 App. Div., at 793, 428
N. Y. S. 2d, at 257.
IV
The constitutional right to bear arms in
public for self-defense is not “a second-class right, subject to an
entirely different body of rules than the other Bill of Rights
guarantees.” McDonald , 561 U. S., at 780 (plurality
opinion). We know of no other constitutional right that an
individual may exercise only after demonstrating to government
officers some special need. That is not how the First Amendment
works when it comes to unpopular speech or the free exercise of
religion. It is not how the Sixth Amendment works when it comes to
a defendant’s right to confront the witnesses against him. And it
is not how the Second Amendment works when it comes to public carry
for self-defense.
New York’s proper-cause requirement violates the
Fourteenth Amendment in that it prevents law-abiding citizens with
ordinary self-defense needs from exercising their right to keep and
bear arms. We therefore reverse the judgment of the Court of
Appeals and remand the case for further proceedings consistent with
this opinion.
It is so ordered. Notes 1 See Ala. Code §13A–11–75
(Cum. Supp. 2021); Alaska Stat. §18.65.700 (2020); Ariz. Rev. Stat.
Ann. §13–3112 (Cum. Supp. 2021); Ark. Code Ann. §5–73–309 (Supp.
2021); Colo. Rev. Stat. §18–12–206 (2021); Fla. Stat. §790.06
(2021); Ga. Code Ann. §16–11–129 (Supp. 2021); Idaho Code Ann.
§18–3302K (Cum. Supp. 2021); Ill. Comp. Stat., ch. 430, §66/10
(West Cum. Supp. 2021); Ind. Code §35–47–2–3 (2021); Iowa Code
§724.7 (2022); Kan. Stat. Ann. §75–7c03 (2021); Ky. Rev. Stat. Ann.
§237.110 (Lexis Cum. Supp. 2021); La. Rev. Stat. Ann. §40:1379.3
(West Cum. Supp. 2022); Me. Rev. Stat. Ann., Tit. 25, §2003 (Cum.
Supp. 2022); Mich. Comp. Laws §28.425b (2020); Minn. Stat. §624.714
(2020); Miss. Code Ann. §45–9–101 (2022); Mo. Rev. Stat. §571.101
(2016); Mont. Code Ann. §45–8–321 (2021); Neb. Rev. Stat. §69–2430
(2019); Nev. Rev. Stat. §202.3657 (2021); N. H. Rev. Stat.
Ann. §159:6 (Cum. Supp. 2021); N. M. Stat. Ann. §29–19–4
(2018); N. C. Gen. Stat. Ann. §14–415.11 (2021); N. D.
Cent. Code Ann. §62.1–04–03 (Supp. 2021); Ohio Rev. Code Ann.
§2923.125 (2020); Okla. Stat., Tit. 21, §1290.12 (2021); Ore. Rev.
Stat. §166.291 (2021); 18 Pa. Cons. Stat. §6109 (Cum. Supp. 2016);
S. C. Code Ann. §23–31–215(A) (Cum. Supp. 2021); S. D.
Codified Laws §23–7–7 (Cum. Supp. 2021); Tenn. Code Ann.
§39–17–1366 (Supp. 2021); Tex. Govt. Code Ann. §411.177 (West Cum.
Supp. 2021); Utah Code §53–5–704.5 (2022); Va. Code Ann.
§18.2–308.04 (2021); Wash. Rev. Code §9.41.070 (2021); W. Va. Code
Ann. §61–7–4 (2021); Wis. Stat. §175.60 (2021); Wyo. Stat. Ann.
§6–8–104 (2021). Vermont has no permitting system for the concealed
carry of handguns. Three States—Connecticut, Delaware, and Rhode
Island—have discretionary criteria but appear to operate like
“shall issue” jurisdictions. See Conn. Gen. Stat. §29–28(b) (2021);
Del. Code, Tit. 11, §1441 (2022); R. I. Gen. Laws §11–47–11
(2002). Although Connecticut officials have discretion to deny a
concealed-carry permit to anyone who is not a “suitable person,”
see Conn. Gen. Stat. §29–28(b), the “suitable person” standard
precludes permits only to those “individuals whose conduct has
shown them to be lacking the essential character of temperament
necessary to be entrusted with a weapon.” Dwyer v. Farrell , 193 Conn. 7, 12, 475 A.2d 257, 260 (1984) (internal
quotation marks omitted). As for Delaware, the State has thus far
processed 5,680 license applications and renewals in fiscal year
2022 and has denied only 112. See Del. Courts, Super. Ct., Carrying
Concealed Deadly Weapon (June 9, 2022),
https://courts.delaware.gov/forms/download.aspx?ID=125408.
Moreover, Delaware appears to have no licensing requirement for
open carry. Finally, Rhode Island has a suitability requirement,
see R. I. Gen. Laws §11–47–11, but the Rhode Island Supreme
Court has flatly denied that the “[d]emonstration of a proper
showing of need” is a component of that requirement. Gadomski v. Tavares , 113 A.3d 387, 392 (2015).
Additionally, some “shall issue” jurisdictions have so-called
“constitutional carry” protections that allow certain individuals
to carry handguns in public within the State without any permit whatsoever. See, e.g. , A. Sherman, More States Remove
Permit Requirement To Carry a Concealed Gun, PolitiFact (Apr. 12,
2022),
https://www.politifact.com/article/2022/apr/12/more-states-remove-permit-requirement-carry-concea/
(“Twenty-five states now have permitless concealed carry laws
. . . The states that have approved permitless carry laws
are: Alabama, Alaska, Arizona, Arkansas, Idaho, Indiana, Iowa,
Georgia, Kansas, Kentucky, Maine, Mississippi, Missouri, Montana,
New Hampshire, North Dakota, Ohio, Oklahoma, South Dakota,
Tennessee, Texas, Utah, Vermont, West Virginia, and
Wyoming”). 2 See Cal. Penal Code Ann.
§26150 (West 2021) (“Good cause”); D. C. Code §§7–2509.11(1)
(2018), 22–4506(a) (Cum. Supp. 2021) (“proper reason,” i.e. ,
“special need for self-protection”); Haw. Rev. Stat. §§134–2 (Cum.
Supp. 2018), 134–9(a) (2011) (“exceptional case”); Md. Pub. Saf.
Code Ann. §5–306(a)(6)(ii) (2018) (“good and substantial reason”);
Mass. Gen. Laws, ch. 140, §131(d) (2020) (“good reason”);
N. J. Stat. Ann. §2C:58–4(c) (West Cum. Supp. 2021)
(“justifiable need”). 3 Rather than begin with
its view of the governing legal framework, the dissent chronicles,
in painstaking detail, evidence of crimes committed by individuals
with firearms. See post, at 1–9 (opinion of Breyer, J.). The
dissent invokes all of these statistics presumably to justify
granting States greater leeway in restricting firearm ownership and
use. But, as Members of the Court have already explained, “[t]he
right to keep and bear arms . . . is not the only
constitutional right that has controversial public safety
implications.” McDonald v. Chicago , 561 U.S.
742 , 783 (2010) (plurality opinion). 4 See Association of
N. J. Rifle & Pistol Clubs , Inc. v. Attorney General N. J. , 910 F.3d 106, 117 (CA3 2018);
accord, Worman v. Healey , 922 F.3d 26, 33, 36–39 (CA1
2019); Libertarian Party of Erie Cty. v. Cuomo , 970
F.3d 106, 127–128 (CA2 2020); Harley v. Wilkinson ,
988 F.3d 766, 769 (CA4 2021); National Rifle Assn. of Am. , Inc. v. Bureau of Alcohol , Tobacco , Firearms , and Explosives , 700 F.3d 185, 194–195 (CA5
2012); United States v. Greeno , 679 F.3d 510, 518
(CA6 2012); Kanter v. Barr , 919 F.3d 437, 442 (CA7
2019); Young v. Hawaii , 992 F.3d 765, 783 (CA9 2021)
(en banc); United States v. Reese , 627 F.3d 792,
800–801 (CA10 2010); GeorgiaCarry.Org , Inc. v. Georgia , 687 F.3d 1244, 1260, n. 34 (CA11 2012); United States v. Class , 930 F.3d 460, 463 (CADC
2019). 5 The dissent asserts that
we misread Heller to eschew means-end scrutiny because Heller mentioned that the District of Columbia’s handgun ban
“would fail constitutional muster” “[u]nder any of the standards of
scrutiny that we have applied to enumerated constitutional rights.” Heller , 554 U. S., at 628–629; see post, at 23
(opinion of Breyer, J.). But Heller ’s passing observation
that the District’s ban would fail under any heightened “standar[d]
of scrutiny” did not supplant Heller ’s focus on
constitutional text and history. Rather, Heller ’s comment
“was more of a gilding-the-lily observation about the extreme
nature of D.C.’s law,” Heller v. District of
Columbia , 670 F.3d 1244, 1277 (CADC 2011) (Kavanaugh, J.,
dissenting), than a reflection of Heller ’s methodology or
holding. 6 The dissent claims that Heller ’s text-and-history test will prove unworkable
compared to means-end scrutiny in part because judges are
relatively ill equipped to “resolv[e] difficult historical
questions” or engage in “searching historical surveys.” Post , at 26, 30. We are unpersuaded. The job of judges is
not to resolve historical questions in the abstract; it is to
resolve legal questions presented in particular cases or
controversies. That “legal inquiry is a refined subset” of a
broader “historical inquiry,” and it relies on “various evidentiary
principles and default rules” to resolve uncertainties. W. Baude
& S. Sachs, Originalism and the Law of the Past, 37 L. &
Hist. Rev. 809, 810–811 (2019). For example, “[i]n our adversarial
system of adjudication, we follow the principle of party
presentation.” United States v. Sineneng-Smith , 590
U. S. ___, ___ (2020) (slip op., at 3). Courts are thus
entitled to decide a case based on the historical record compiled
by the parties. 7 This does not mean that
courts may engage in independent means-end scrutiny under the guise
of an analogical inquiry. Again, the Second Amendment is the
“product of an interest balancing by the people ,” not the
evolving product of federal judges. Heller , 554 U. S.,
at 635 (emphasis altered). Analogical reasoning requires judges to
apply faithfully the balance struck by the founding generation to
modern circumstances, and contrary to the dissent’s assertion,
there is nothing “[i]roni[c]” about that undertaking. Post, at 30. It is not an invitation to revise that balance through
means-end scrutiny. 8 The dissent claims that
we cannot answer the question presented without giving respondents
the opportunity to develop an evidentiary record fleshing out “how
New York’s law is administered in practice, how much discretion
licensing officers in New York possess, or whether the proper cause
standard differs across counties.” Post, at 20. We disagree.
The dissent does not dispute that any applicant for an unrestricted
concealed-carry license in New York can satisfy the proper-cause
standard only if he has “ ‘ “a special need for
self-protection distinguishable from that of the general
community.” ’ ” Post, at 13 (quoting Kachalsky v. County of Westchester , 701 F.3d 81, 86
(CA2 2012)). And in light of the text of the Second Amendment,
along with the Nation’s history of firearm regulation, we conclude
below that a State may not prevent law-abiding citizens from
publicly carrying handguns because they have not demonstrated a
special need for self-defense. See infra , at 62. That
conclusion does not depend upon any of the factual questions raised
by the dissent. Nash and Koch allege that they were denied
unrestricted licenses because they had not “demonstrate[d] a
special need for self-defense that distinguished [them] from the
general public.” App. 123, 125. If those allegations are proven
true, then it simply does not matter whether licensing officers
have applied the proper-cause standard differently to other
concealed-carry license applicants; Nash’s and Koch’s
constitutional rights to bear arms in public for self-defense were
still violated. 9 To be clear, nothing in
our analysis should be interpreted to suggest the
unconstitutionality of the 43 States’ “shall-issue” licensing
regimes, under which “a general desire for self-defense is
sufficient to obtain a [permit].” Drake v. Filko , 724
F.3d 426, 442 (CA3 2013) (Hardiman, J., dissenting). Because these
licensing regimes do not require applicants to show an atypical
need for armed self-defense, they do not necessarily prevent
“law-abiding, responsible citizens” from exercising their Second
Amendment right to public carry. District of Columbia v. Heller , 554 U.S.
570 , 635 (2008). Rather, it appears that these shall-issue
regimes, which often require applicants to undergo a background
check or pass a firearms safety course, are designed to ensure only
that those bearing arms in the jurisdiction are, in fact,
“law-abiding, responsible citizens.” Ibid. And they likewise
appear to contain only “narrow, objective, and definite standards”
guiding licensing officials, Shuttlesworth v. Birmingham , 394 U.S.
147 , 151 (1969), rather than requiring the “appraisal of facts,
the exercise of judgment, and the formation of an opinion,” Cantwell v. Connecticut , 310
U.S. 296 , 305 (1940)—features that typify proper-cause
standards like New York’s. That said, because any permitting scheme
can be put toward abusive ends, we do not rule out constitutional
challenges to shall-issue regimes where, for example, lengthy wait
times in processing license applications or exorbitant fees deny
ordinary citizens their right to public carry. 10 Another medieval firearm
restriction—a 1541 statute enacted under Henry VIII that limited
the ownership and use of handguns (which could not be shorter than
a yard) to those subjects with annual property values of at least
£100, see 33 Hen. 8 c. 6, §§1–2—fell into a similar obsolescence.
As far as we can discern, the last recorded prosecutions under the
1541 statute occurred in 1693, neither of which appears to have
been successful. See King and Queen v. Bullock , 4 Mod. 147, 87 Eng. Rep. 315 (K. B. 1693); King v. Litten , 1 Shower, K. B. 367, 89 Eng. Rep. 644
(K. B. 1693). It seems that other prosecutions under the 1541
statute during the late 1600s were similarly unsuccessful. See King v. Silcot , 3 Mod. 280, 280–281, 87 Eng. Rep. 186
(K. B. 1690); King v. Lewellin , 1 Shower, K. B. 48,
89 Eng. Rep. 440 (K. B. 1689); cf. King and Queen v. Alsop , 4 Mod. 49, 50–51, 87 Eng. Rep. 256, 256–257 (K. B.
1691). By the late 1700s, it was widely recognized that the 1541
statute was “obsolete.” 2 R. Burn, The Justice of the Peace, and
Parish Officer 243, n. (11th ed. 1769); see also, e.g., The
Farmer’s Lawyer 143 (1774) (“entirely obsolete”); 1 G. Jacob,
Game-Laws II, Law-Dictionary (T. Tomlins ed. 1797); 2 R. Burn, The
Justice of the Peace, and Parish Officer 409 (18th ed. 1797)
(calling the 1541 statute “a matter more of curiosity than use”).
In any event, lest one be tempted to put much evidentiary weight on
the 1541 statute, it impeded not only public carry, but further
made it unlawful for those without sufficient means to “kepe in his
or their houses” any “handgun.” 33 Hen. 8 c. 6, §1. Of course, this
kind of limitation is inconsistent with Heller ’s historical
analysis regarding the Second Amendment’s meaning at the founding
and thereafter. So, even if a severe restriction on keeping
firearms in the home may have seemed appropriate in the mid-1500s,
it was not incorporated into the Second Amendment’s scope. We see
little reason why the parts of the 1541 statute that address public
carry should not be understood similarly. We note also that even
this otherwise restrictive 1541 statute, which generally prohibited
shooting firearms in any city, exempted discharges “for the defence
of [one’s] p[er]son or house.” §4. Apparently, the paramount need
for self-defense trumped the Crown’s interest in firearm
suppression even during the 16th century. 11 The
dissent discounts Sir John Knight’s Case , 3 Mod. 117, 87
Eng. Rep. 75, because it only “arguably” supports the view that an
evil-intent requirement attached to the Statute of Northampton by
the late 1600s and early 1700s. See post , at 37. But again,
because the Second Amendment’s bare text covers petitioners’ public
carry, the respondents here shoulder the burden of demonstrating
that New York’s proper-cause requirement is consistent with the
Second Amendment’s text and historical scope. See supra, at
15. To the extent there are multiple plausible interpretations of Sir John Knight’s Case , we will favor the one that is more
consistent with the Second Amendment’s command. 12 Even
Catholics, who fell beyond the protection of the right to have
arms, and who were stripped of all “Arms, Weapons, Gunpowder, [and]
Ammunition,” were at least allowed to keep “such necessary Weapons
as shall be allowed . . . by Order of the Justices of the
Peace . . . for the Defence of his House or Person.” 1
Wm. & Mary c. 15, §4, in 3 Eng. Stat. at Large 399
(1688). 13 Even
assuming that pocket pistols were, as East Jersey in 1686 deemed
them, “unusual or unlawful,” it appears that they were commonly
used at least by the founding. See, e.g. , G. Neumann, The
History of Weapons of the American Revolution 150–151 (1967); see
also H. Hendrick, P. Paradis, & R. Hornick, Human Factors
Issues in Handgun Safety and Forensics 44 (2008). 14 The
Virginia statute all but codified the existing common law in this
regard. See G. Webb, The Office and Authority of a Justice of Peace
92 (1736) (explaining how a constable “may take away Arms from such
who ride, or go, offensively armed, in Terror of the
People”). 15 The
dissent concedes that Huntly , 25 N. C. 418, recognized
that citizens were “ ‘at perfect liberty’ to carry for
‘lawful purpose[s].’ ” Post , at 42 (quoting Huntly , 25 N. C., at 423). But the dissent disputes
that such “lawful purpose[s]” included self-defense, because Huntly goes on to speak more specifically of carrying arms
for “business or amusement.” Id. , at 422–423. This is an
unduly stingy interpretation of Huntly . In particular, Huntly stated that “the citizen is at perfect liberty to
carry his gun” “[f]or any lawful purpose,” of which
“business” and “amusement” were then mentioned. Ibid. (emphasis added). Huntly then contrasted these “lawful
purpose[s]” with the “wicked purpose . . . to terrify and
alarm.” Ibid. Because there is no evidence that Huntly considered self-defense a “wicked purpose,” we think
the best reading of Huntly would sanction public carry for
self-defense, so long as it was not “in such [a] manner as
naturally will terrify and alarm.” Id. , at 423. 16 Beginning in 1813 with Kentucky, six
States (five of which were in the South) enacted laws prohibiting
the concealed carry of pistols by 1846. See 1813 Ky. Acts §1,
p. 100; 1813 La. Acts p. 172; 1820 Ind. Acts p. 39;
Ark. Rev. Stat. §13, p. 280 (1838); 1838 Va. Acts ch. 101, §1,
p. 76; 1839 Ala. Acts no. 77, §1. During this period, Georgia
enacted a law that appeared to prohibit both concealed and open
carry, see 1837 Ga. Acts §§1, 4, p. 90, but the Georgia
Supreme Court later held that the prohibition could not extend to
open carry consistent with the Second Amendment. See infra ,
at 45–46. Between 1846 and 1859, only one other State, Ohio, joined
this group. 1859 Ohio Laws §1, p. 56. Tennessee, meanwhile,
enacted in 1821 a broader law that prohibited carrying, among other
things, “belt or pocket pistols, either public or private,” except
while traveling. 1821 Tenn. Acts ch. 13, §1, p. 15. And the
Territory of Florida prohibited concealed carry during this same
timeframe. See 1835 Terr. of Fla. Laws p. 423. 17 See State v. Mitchell , 3 Blackf. 229 (Ind. 1833); State v. Reid , 1 Ala. 612, 616 (1840); State v. Buzzard , 4 Ark. 18 (1842); Nunn v. State , 1
Ga. 243 (1846); State v. Chandler , 5 La. 489 (1850); State v. Smith , 11 La. 633 (1856); State v. Jumel , 13 La. 399 (1858). But see Bliss v. Commonwealth , 12 Ky. 90 (1822). See generally 2 J. Kent,
Commentaries on American Law *340, n. b . 18 See Reid , 1 Ala., at 619 (holding that “the Legislature cannot
inhibit the citizen from bearing arms openly”); id. , at 621
(noting that there was no evidence “tending to show that the
defendant could not have defended himself as successfully, by
carrying the pistol openly, as by secreting it about his
person”). 19 See, e.g. , Chandler , 5 La., at 490 (Louisiana
concealed-carry prohibition “interfered with no man’s right to
carry arms (to use its words) ‘in full open view,’ which places men
upon an equality”); Smith , 11 La., at 633 (The “arms”
described in the Second Amendment “are such as are borne by a
people in war, or at least carried openly”); Jumel , 13 La.,
at 399–400 (“The statute in question does not infringe the right of
the people to keep or bear arms. It is a measure of police,
prohibiting only a particular mode of bearing arms which is
found dangerous to the peace of society”). 20 With
respect to Indiana’s concealed-carry prohibition, the Indiana
Supreme Court’s reasons for upholding it are unknown because the
court issued a one-sentence per curiam order holding the law
“not unconstitutional.” Mitchell , 3 Blackf., at 229.
Similarly, the Arkansas Supreme Court upheld Arkansas’ prohibition,
but without reaching a majority rationale. See Buzzard , 4
Ark. 18. The Arkansas Supreme Court would later adopt Tennessee’s
approach, which tolerated the prohibition of all public carry of
handguns except for military-style revolvers. See, e.g. , Fife v. State , 31 Ark. 455 (1876). 21 Shortly after Andrews , 50
Tenn. 165, Tennessee codified an exception to the State’s handgun
ban for “an[y] army pistol, or such as are commonly carried and
used in the United States Army” so long as they were carried
“openly in [one’s] hands.” 1871 Tenn. Pub. Acts ch. 90, §1; see
also State v. Wilburn , 66 Tenn. 57, 61–63 (1872); Porter v. State , 66 Tenn. 106, 107–108
(1874). 22 The
Territory of New Mexico made it a crime in 1860 to carry “any class
of pistols whatever” “concealed or otherwise.” 1860 Terr. of
N. M. Laws §§1–2, p. 94. This extreme restriction is an
outlier statute enacted by a territorial government nearly 70 years
after the ratification of the Bill of Rights, and its
constitutionality was never tested in court. Its value in
discerning the original meaning of the Second Amendment is
insubstantial. Moreover, like many other stringent carry
restrictions that were localized in the Western Territories, New
Mexico’s prohibition ended when the Territory entered the Union as
a State in 1911 and guaranteed in its State Constitution that
“[t]he people have the right to bear arms for their security and
defense, but nothing herein shall be held to permit the carrying of
concealed weapons.” N. M. Const., Art. II, §6 (1911); see infra , at 61. 23 See
1838 Terr. of Wis. Stat. §16, p. 381; Me. Rev. Stat., ch. 169,
§16 (1840); Mich. Rev. Stat., ch. 162, §16 (1846); 1847 Va. Acts
ch. 14, §16; Terr. of Minn. Rev. Stat., ch. 112, §18 (1851); 1854
Ore. Stat. ch. 16, §17, p. 220; D. C. Rev. Code ch. 141,
§16 (1857); 1860 Pa. Laws p. 432, §6; W. Va. Code, ch. 153, §8
(1868). 24 It is
true that two of the antebellum surety laws were unusually broad in
that they did not expressly require a citizen complaint to trigger
the posting of a surety. See 1847 Va. Acts ch. 14, §16; W. Va.
Code, ch. 153, §8 (1868). 25 The
dissent speculates that the absence of recorded cases involving
surety laws may simply “show that these laws were normally
followed.” Post, at 45. Perhaps. But again, the burden rests
with the government to establish the relevant tradition of
regulation, see supra, at 15, and, given all of the other
features of surety laws that make them poor analogues to New York’s
proper-cause standard, we consider the barren record of enforcement
to be simply one additional reason to discount their
relevance. 26 Respondents invoke General Orders No.
10, which covered the Second Military District (North and South
Carolina), and provided that “[t]he practice of carrying deadly
weapons, except by officers and soldiers in the military service of
the United States, is prohibited.” Headquarters Second Military
Dist., Gen. Orders No. 10 (Charleston, S. C., Apr. 11, 1867),
in S. Exec. Doc. No. 14, 40th Cong., 1st Sess., 64 (1867). We put
little weight on this categorical restriction given that the order
also specified that a violation of this prohibition would “render
the offender amenable to trial and punishment by military
commission,” ibid. , rather than a jury otherwise guaranteed
by the Constitution. There is thus little indication that these
military dictates were designed to align with the Constitution’s
usual application during times of peace. 27 That
said, Southern prohibitions on concealed carry were not always
applied equally, even when under federal scrutiny. One lieutenant
posted in Saint Augustine, Florida, remarked how local enforcement
of concealed-carry laws discriminated against blacks: “To sentence
a negro to several dollars’ fine for carrying a revolver concealed
upon his person, is in accordance with an ordinance of the town;
but still the question naturally arises in my mind, ‘Why is this
poor fellow fined for an offence which is committed hourly by every
other white man I meet in the streets?’ ” H. R. Exec. Doc. No.
57, 40th Cong., 2d Sess., 83 (1867); see also H. R. Rep. No. 16,
39th Cong., 2d Sess., 427 (1867). 28 We
will not address any of the 20th-century historical evidence
brought to bear by respondents or their amici . As with their
late-19th-century evidence, the 20th-century evidence presented by
respondents and their amici does not provide insight into
the meaning of the Second Amendment when it contradicts earlier
evidence. 29 The
New Mexico restriction allowed an exception for individuals
carrying for “the lawful defence of themselves, their families or
their property, and the same being then and there threatened with
danger.” 1869 Terr. of N. M. Laws ch. 32, §1, p. 72. The
Arizona law similarly exempted those who have “reasonable ground
for fearing an unlawful attack upon his person.” 1889 Ariz. Terr.
Sess. Laws no. 13, §2, p. 17. 30 Many
other state courts during this period continued the antebellum
tradition of upholding concealed carry regimes that seemingly
provided for open carry. See, e.g. , State v. Speller , 86 N. C. 697 (1882); Chatteaux v. State , 52 Ala. 388 (1875); Eslava v. State , 49
Ala. 355 (1873); State v. Shelby , 90 Mo. 302, 2 S.W.
468 (1886); Carroll v. State , 28 Ark. 99 (1872); cf. Robertson v. Baldwin , 165
U.S. 275 , 281–282 (1897) (remarking in dicta that “the right of
the people to keep and bear arms . . . is not infringed
by laws prohibiting the carrying of concealed
weapons”). 31 In
1875, Arkansas prohibited the public carry of all pistols. See 1875
Ark. Acts p. 156, §1. But this categorical prohibition was
also short lived. About six years later, Arkansas exempted “pistols
as are used in the army or navy of the United States,” so long as
they were carried “uncovered, and in [the] hand.” 1881 Ark. Acts
p. 191, no. 96, §§1, 2. 32 In
1879, Salina, Kansas, prohibited the carry of pistols but broadly
exempted “cases when any person carrying [a pistol] is engaged in
the pursuit of any lawful business, calling or employment” and the
circumstances were “such as to justify a prudent man in carrying
such weapon, for the defense of his person, property or family.”
Salina, Kan., Rev. Ordinance No. 268, §2. SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES
_________________
No. 20–843
_________________
New York State Rifle & Pistol Association,
Inc., et al., PETITIONERS v. Kevin P. Bruen, in his
official capacity as Superintendent of New York State Police,
et al.
on writ of certiorari to the united states
court of appeals for the second circuit
[June 23, 2022]
Justice Alito, concurring.
I join the opinion of the Court in full but add
the following comments in response to the dissent.
I
Much of the dissent seems designed to obscure
the specific question that the Court has decided, and therefore it
may be helpful to provide a succinct summary of what we have
actually held. In District of Columbia v. Heller , 554 U.S.
570 (2008), the Court concluded that the Second Amendment
protects the right to keep a handgun in the home for self-defense. Heller found that the Amendment codified a preexisting right
and that this right was regarded at the time of the Amendment’s
adoption as rooted in “ ‘the natural right of resistance and
self-preservation.’ ” Id., at 594. “[T]he inherent
right of self-defense,” Heller explained, is “central to the
Second Amendment right.” Id ., at 628.
Although Heller concerned the possession
of a handgun in the home, the key point that we decided was that
“the people,” not just members of the “militia,” have the right to
use a firearm to defend themselves. And because many people face a
serious risk of lethal violence when they venture outside their
homes, the Second Amendment was understood at the time of adoption
to apply under those circumstances. The Court’s exhaustive
historical survey establishes that point very clearly, and today’s
decision therefore holds that a State may not enforce a law, like
New York’s Sullivan Law, that effectively prevents its law-abiding
residents from carrying a gun for this purpose.
That is all we decide. Our holding decides
nothing about who may lawfully possess a firearm or the
requirements that must be met to buy a gun. Nor does it decide
anything about the kinds of weapons that people may possess. Nor
have we disturbed anything that we said in Heller or McDonald v. Chicago , 561 U.S.
742 (2010), about restrictions that may be imposed on the
possession or carrying of guns.
In light of what we have actually held, it is
hard to see what legitimate purpose can possibly be served by most
of the dissent’s lengthy introductory section. See post , at
1–8 (opinion of Breyer, J.). Why, for example, does the
dissent think it is relevant to recount the mass shootings that
have occurred in recent years? Post , at 4–5. Does the
dissent think that laws like New York’s prevent or deter such
atrocities? Will a person bent on carrying out a mass shooting be
stopped if he knows that it is illegal to carry a handgun outside
the home? And how does the dissent account for the fact that one of
the mass shootings near the top of its list took place in Buffalo?
The New York law at issue in this case obviously did not stop that
perpetrator.
What is the relevance of statistics about the
use of guns to commit suicide? See post , at 5–6. Does the
dissent think that a lot of people who possess guns in their homes
will be stopped or deterred from shooting themselves if they cannot
lawfully take them outside?
The dissent cites statistics about the use of
guns in domestic disputes, see post, at 5, but it does not
explain why these statistics are relevant to the question presented
in this case. How many of the cases involving the use of a gun in a
domestic dispute occur outside the home, and how many are prevented
by laws like New York’s?
The dissent cites statistics on children and
adolescents killed by guns, see post, at 1, 4, but what does
this have to do with the question whether an adult who is licensed
to possess a handgun may be prohibited from carrying it outside the
home? Our decision, as noted, does not expand the categories of
people who may lawfully possess a gun, and federal law generally
forbids the possession of a handgun by a person who is under the
age of 18, 18 U. S. C. §§922(x)(2)–(5), and bars the sale
of a handgun to anyone under the age of 21, §§922(b)(1),
(c)(1).[ 1 ]
The dissent cites the large number of guns in
private hands—nearly 400 million—but it does not explain what this
statistic has to do with the question whether a person who already
has the right to keep a gun in the home for self-defense is likely
to be deterred from acquiring a gun by the knowledge that the gun
cannot be carried outside the home. See post , at 3. And
while the dissent seemingly thinks that the ubiquity of guns and
our country’s high level of gun violence provide reasons for
sustaining the New York law, the dissent appears not to understand
that it is these very facts that cause law-abiding citizens to feel
the need to carry a gun for self-defense.
No one apparently knows how many of the 400
million privately held guns are in the hands of criminals, but
there can be little doubt that many muggers and rapists are armed
and are undeterred by the Sullivan Law. Each year, the New York
City Police Department (NYPD) confiscates thousands of
guns,[ 2 ] and it is fair to
assume that the number of guns seized is a fraction of the total
number held unlawfully. The police cannot disarm every person who
acquires a gun for use in criminal activity; nor can they provide
bodyguard protection for the State’s nearly 20 million residents or
the 8.8 million people who live in New York City. Some of these
people live in high-crime neighborhoods. Some must traverse dark
and dangerous streets in order to reach their homes after work or
other evening activities. Some are members of groups whose members
feel especially vulnerable. And some of these people reasonably
believe that unless they can brandish or, if necessary, use a
handgun in the case of attack, they may be murdered, raped, or
suffer some other serious injury.
Ordinary citizens frequently use firearms to
protect themselves from criminal attack. According to survey data,
defensive firearm use occurs up to 2.5 million times per year.
Brief for Law Enforcement Groups et al. as Amici Curiae 5. A
Centers for Disease Control and Prevention report commissioned by
former President Barack Obama reviewed the literature surrounding
firearms use and noted that “[s]tudies that directly assessed the
effect of actual defensive uses of guns . . . have found
consistently lower injury rates among gun-using crime victims
compared with victims who used other self-protective strategies.”
Institute of Medicine and National Research Council, Priorities for
Research To Reduce the Threat of Firearm-Related Violence 15–16
(2013) (referenced in Brief for Independent Women’s Law Center as Amicus Curiae 19–20).
Many of the amicus briefs filed in this
case tell the story of such people. Some recount incidents in which
a potential victim escaped death or serious injury only because
carrying a gun for self-defense was allowed in the jurisdiction
where the incident occurred. Here are two examples. One night in
1987, Austin Fulk, a gay man from Arkansas, “was chatting with
another man in a parking lot when four gay bashers charged them
with baseball bats and tire irons. Fulk’s companion drew his pistol
from under the seat of his car, brandished it at the attackers, and
fired a single shot over their heads, causing them to flee and
saving the would-be victims from serious harm.” Brief for DC
Project Foundation et al. as Amici Curiae 31 (footnote
omitted).
On July 7, 2020, a woman was brutally assaulted
in the parking lot of a fast food restaurant in Jefferson City,
Tennessee. Her assailant slammed her to the ground and began to
drag her around while strangling her. She was saved when a
bystander who was lawfully carrying a pistol pointed his gun at the
assailant, who then stopped the assault and the assailant was
arrested. Ibid. (citing C. Wethington, Jefferson City
Police: Legally Armed Good Samaritan Stops Assault, ABC News 6,
WATE.com (July 9, 2020),
https://www.wate.com/news/local-news/jefferson-city-police-legally-armed-good-samaritan-stops-assault/).
In other incidents, a law-abiding person was
driven to violate the Sullivan Law because of fear of victimization
and as a result was arrested, prosecuted, and incarcerated. See
Brief for Black Attorneys of Legal Aid et al. as Amici
Curiae 22–25.
Some briefs were filed by members of groups
whose members feel that they have special reasons to fear attacks.
See Brief for Asian Pacific American Gun Owners Association as Amicus Curiae ; Brief for DC Project Foundation et al.
as Amici Curiae ; Brief for Black Guns Matter
et al . as Amici Curiae ; Brief for Independent
Women’s Law Center as Amicus Curiae ; Brief for National
African American Gun Association, Inc., as Amicus
Curiae .
I reiterate: All that we decide in this case is
that the Second Amendment protects the right of law-abiding people
to carry a gun outside the home for self-defense and that the
Sullivan Law, which makes that virtually impossible for most New
Yorkers, is unconstitutional.
II
This brings me to Part II–B of the dissent, post , at 11–21, which chastises the Court for deciding this
case without a trial and factual findings about just how hard it is
for a law-abiding New Yorker to get a carry permit. The record
before us, however, tells us everything we need on this score. At
argument, New York’s solicitor general was asked about an ordinary
person who works at night and must walk through dark and
crime-infested streets to get home. Tr. of Oral Arg. 66–67. The
solicitor general was asked whether such a person would be issued a
carry permit if she pleaded: “[T]here have been a lot of muggings
in this area, and I am scared to death.” Id., at 67. The
solicitor general’s candid answer was “in general,” no. Ibid. To get a permit, the applicant would have to show
more—for example, that she had been singled out for attack. Id., at 65; see also id., at 58. A law that dictates
that answer violates the Second Amendment.
III
My final point concerns the dissent’s
complaint that the Court relies too heavily on history and should
instead approve the sort of “means-end” analysis employed in this
case by the Second Circuit. Under that approach, a court, in most
cases, assesses a law’s burden on the Second Amendment right and
the strength of the State’s interest in imposing the challenged
restriction. See post , at 20. This mode of analysis places
no firm limits on the ability of judges to sustain any law
restricting the possession or use of a gun. Two examples illustrate
the point.
The first is the Second Circuit’s decision in a
case the Court decided two Terms ago, New York State Rifle &
Pistol Assn., Inc. v. City of New York , 590 U. S.
___ (2020). The law in that case affected New York City residents
who had been issued permits to keep a gun in the home for self-
defense. The city recommended that these permit holders practice at
a range to ensure that they are able to handle their guns safely,
but the law prohibited them from taking their guns to any range
other than the seven that were spread around the city’s five
boroughs. Even if such a person unloaded the gun, locked it in the
trunk of a car, and drove to the nearest range, that person would
violate the law if the nearest range happened to be outside city
limits. The Second Circuit held that the law was constitutional,
concluding, among other things, that the restriction was
substantially related to the city’s interests in public safety and
crime prevention. See New York State Rifle & Pistol Assn.,
Inc. v. New York , 883 F.3d 45, 62–64 (2018). But after
we agreed to review that decision, the city repealed the law and
admitted that it did not actually have any beneficial effect on
public safety. See N. Y. Penal Law Ann. §400.00(6) (West Cum.
Supp. 2022); Suggestion of Mootness in New York State Rifle
& Pistol Assn., Inc. v. City of New York , O. T.
2019, No. 18–280, pp. 5–7.
Exhibit two is the dissent filed in Heller by Justice Breyer, the author of today’s dissent. At
issue in Heller was an ordinance that made it impossible for
any District of Columbia resident to keep a handgun in the home for
self-defense. See 554 U. S., at 574–575. Even the respondent,
who carried a gun on the job while protecting federal facilities,
did not qualify. Id., at 575–576. The District of Columbia
law was an extreme outlier; only a few other jurisdictions in the
entire country had similar laws. Nevertheless, Justice Breyer’s
dissent, while accepting for the sake of argument that the Second
Amendment protects the right to keep a handgun in the home,
concluded, based on essentially the same test that today’s dissent
defends, that the District’s complete ban was constitutional. See id., at 689, 722 (under “an interest-balancing
inquiry. . .” the dissent would “conclude that the
District’s measure is a proportionate, not a disproportionate,
response to the compelling concerns that led the District to adopt
it”).
Like that dissent in Heller , the real
thrust of today’s dissent is that guns are bad and that States and
local jurisdictions should be free to restrict them essentially as
they see fit.[ 3 ] That argument
was rejected in Heller , and while the dissent protests that
it is not rearguing Heller , it proceeds to do just that. See post , at 25–28. Heller correctly recognized that the
Second Amendment codifies the right of ordinary law-abiding
Americans to protect themselves from lethal violence by possessing
and, if necessary, using a gun. In 1791, when the Second Amendment
was adopted, there were no police departments, and many families
lived alone on isolated farms or on the frontiers. If these people
were attacked, they were on their own. It is hard to imagine the
furor that would have erupted if the Federal Government and the
States had tried to take away the guns that these people needed for
protection.
Today, unfortunately, many Americans have good
reason to fear that they will be victimized if they are unable to
protect themselves. And today, no less than in 1791, the Second
Amendment guarantees their right to do so. Notes 1 The dissent makes no
effort to explain the relevance of most of the incidents and
statistics cited in its introductory section ( post , at 1–8)
(opinion of Breyer, J.). Instead, it points to studies (summarized
later in its opinion) regarding the effects of “shall issue”
licensing regimes on rates of homicide and other violent crimes. I
note only that the dissent’s presentation of such studies is
one-sided. See RAND Corporation, Effects of Concealed-Carry Laws on
Violent Crime (Apr. 22,
2022), https://www.rand.org/research/gun-policy/analysis/concealed-carry/violent-crime-html;
see also Brief for William English et al. as Amici Curiae 3
(“The overwhelming weight of statistical analysis on the effects of
[right-to-carry] laws on violent crime concludes that RTC laws do
not result in any statistically significant increase in violent
crime rates”); Brief for Arizona et al. as Amici Curiae 12 (“[P]opulation-level data on licensed carry is extensive, and
the weight of the evidence confirms that objective,
non-discriminatory licensed-carry laws have two results: (1)
statistically significant reductions in some types of violent
crime, or (2) no statistically significant effect on overall
violent crime”); Brief for Law Enforcement Groups et al. as Amici Curiae 12 (“[O]ver the period 1991–2019 the inventory
of firearms more than doubled; the number of concealed carry
permits increased by at least sevenfold,” but “murder rates fell by
almost half, from 9.8 per 100,000 people in 1991 to 5.0 per 100,000
in 2019” and “[v]iolent crimes plummeted by over
half ”). 2 NYPD statistics show
approximately 6,000 illegal guns were seized in 2021. A. Southall,
This Police Captain’s Plan To Stop Gun Violence Uses More Than
Handcuffs, N. Y. Times, Feb. 4, 2022. According to recent
remarks by New York City Mayor Eric Adams, the NYPD has confiscated
3,000 firearms in 2022 so far. City of New York, Transcript: Mayor
Eric Adams Makes Announcement About NYPD Gun Violence Suppression
Division (June 6, 2022),
https://www1.nyc.gov/office-of-the-mayor/news/369-22/trascript-mayor-eric-adams-makes-announcement-nypd-gun-violence-suppression-division. 3 If we put together the
dissent in this case and Justice Breyer’s Heller dissent,
States and local governments would essentially be free to ban the
possession of all handguns, and it is unclear whether its approach
would impose any significant restrictions on laws regulating long
guns. The dissent would extend a very large measure of deference to
legislation implicating Second Amendment rights, but it does not
claim that such deference is appropriate when any other
constitutional right is at issue. SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES
_________________
No. 20–843
_________________
New York State Rifle & Pistol Association,
Inc., et al., PETITIONERS v. Kevin P. Bruen, in his
official capacity as Superintendent of New York State Police,
et al.
on writ of certiorari to the united states
court of appeals for the second circuit
[June 23, 2022]
Justice Kavanaugh, with whom The Chief Justice
joins, concurring.
The Court employs and elaborates on the text,
history, and tradition test that Heller and McDonald require for evaluating whether a government regulation infringes on
the Second Amendment right to possess and carry guns for
self-defense. See District of Columbia v. Heller , 554 U.S.
570 (2008); McDonald v. Chicago , 561 U.S.
742 (2010). Applying that test, the Court correctly holds that
New York’s outlier “may-issue” licensing regime for carrying
handguns for self-defense violates the Second Amendment.
I join the Court’s opinion, and I write
separately to underscore two important points about the limits of
the Court’s decision. First , the Court’s decision does not
prohibit States from imposing licensing requirements for carrying a
handgun for self-defense. In particular, the Court’s decision does
not affect the existing licensing regimes—known as “shall-issue”
regimes—that are employed in 43 States.
The Court’s decision addresses only the unusual
discretionary licensing regimes, known as “may-issue” regimes, that
are employed by 6 States including New York. As the Court explains,
New York’s outlier may-issue regime is constitutionally problematic
because it grants open-ended discretion to licensing officials and
authorizes licenses only for those applicants who can show some
special need apart from self-defense. Those features of New York’s
regime—the unchanneled discretion for licensing officials and the
special-need requirement—in effect deny the right to carry handguns
for self-defense to many “ordinary, law-abiding citizens.” Ante , at 1; see also Heller , 554 U. S., at 635.
The Court has held that “individual self-defense is ‘the central
component ’ of the Second Amendment right.” McDonald , 561
U. S., at 767 (quoting Heller , 554 U. S., at 599).
New York’s law is inconsistent with the Second Amendment right to
possess and carry handguns for self-defense.
By contrast, 43 States employ objective
shall-issue licensing regimes. Those shall-issue regimes may
require a license applicant to undergo fingerprinting, a background
check, a mental health records check, and training in firearms
handling and in laws regarding the use of force, among other
possible requirements. Brief for Arizona et al. as Amici
Curiae 7. Unlike New York’s may-issue regime, those shall-issue
regimes do not grant open-ended discretion to licensing officials
and do not require a showing of some special need apart from
self-defense. As petitioners acknowledge, shall-issue licensing
regimes are constitutionally permissible, subject of course to an
as-applied challenge if a shall-issue licensing regime does not
operate in that manner in practice. Tr. of Oral Arg. 50−51.
Going forward, therefore, the 43 States that
employ objective shall-issue licensing regimes for carrying
handguns for self-defense may continue to do so. Likewise, the 6
States including New York potentially affected by today’s decision
may continue to require licenses for carrying handguns for
self-defense so long as those States employ objective licensing
requirements like those used by the 43 shall-issue States. Second , as Heller and McDonald established and the Court today again explains, the
Second Amendment “is neither a regulatory straightjacket nor a
regulatory blank check.” Ante , at 21. Properly interpreted,
the Second Amendment allows a “variety” of gun regulations. Heller , 554 U. S., at 636. As Justice Scalia wrote in
his opinion for the Court in Heller , and Justice Alito
reiterated in relevant part in the principal opinion in McDonald :
“Like most rights, the right secured by the
Second Amendment is not unlimited. From Blackstone through the
19th-century cases, commentators and courts routinely explained
that the right was not a right to keep and carry any weapon
whatsoever in any manner whatsoever and for whatever
purpose. . . . [N]othing in our opinion should be
taken to cast doubt on longstanding prohibitions on the possession
of firearms by felons and the mentally ill, or laws forbidding the
carrying of firearms in sensitive places such as schools and
government buildings, or laws imposing conditions and
qualifications on the commercial sale of arms. [Footnote 26: We
identify these presumptively lawful regulatory measures only as
examples; our list does not purport to be exhaustive.]
“We also recognize another important limitation
on the right to keep and carry arms. Miller said, as we have
explained, that the sorts of weapons protected were those in common
use at the time. We think that limitation is fairly supported by
the historical tradition of prohibiting the carrying of dangerous
and unusual weapons.” Heller , 554 U. S., at 626−627,
and n. 26 (citations and quotation marks omitted); see also McDonald , 561 U. S., at 786 (plurality opinion).
* * *
With those additional comments, I join the
opinion of the Court. SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES
_________________
No. 20–843
_________________
New York State Rifle & Pistol Association,
Inc., et al., PETITIONERS v. Kevin P. Bruen, in his
official capacity as Superintendent of New York State Police,
et al.
on writ of certiorari to the united states
court of appeals for the second circuit
[June 23, 2022]
Justice Barrett, concurring.
I join the Court’s opinion in full. I write
separately to highlight two methodological points that the Court
does not resolve. First, the Court does not conclusively determine
the manner and circumstances in which postratification practice may
bear on the original meaning of the Constitution. See ante ,
at 24–29. Scholars have proposed competing and potentially
conflicting frameworks for this analysis, including liquidation,
tradition, and precedent. See, e.g. , Nelson, Originalism and
Interpretive Conventions, 70 U. Chi. L. Rev. 519 (2003);
McConnell, Time, Institutions, and Interpretation, 95 B. U. L.
Rev. 1745 (2015). The limits on the permissible use of history may
vary between these frameworks (and between different articulations
of each one). To name just a few unsettled questions: How long
after ratification may subsequent practice illuminate original
public meaning? Cf. McCulloch v. Maryland , 4 Wheat.
316, 401 (1819) (citing practice “introduced at a very early period
of our history”). What form must practice take to carry weight in
constitutional analysis? See Myers v. United States , 272 U.S.
52 , 175 (1926) (citing a “legislative exposition of the
Constitution . . . acquiesced in for a long term of
years”). And may practice settle the meaning of individual rights
as well as structural provisions? See Baude, Constitutional
Liquidation, 71 Stan. L. Rev. 1, 49–51 (2019) (canvassing
arguments). The historical inquiry presented in this case does not
require us to answer such questions, which might make a difference
in another case. See ante , at 17–19.
Second and relatedly, the Court avoids another
“ongoing scholarly debate on whether courts should primarily rely
on the prevailing understanding of an individual right when the
Fourteenth Amendment was ratified in 1868” or when the Bill of
Rights was ratified in 1791. Ante , at 29. Here, the lack of
support for New York’s law in either period makes it unnecessary to
choose between them. But if 1791 is the benchmark, then New York’s
appeals to Reconstruction-era history would fail for the
independent reason that this evidence is simply too late (in
addition to too little). Cf. Espinoza v. Montana Dept. of
Revenue , 591 U. S. ___, ___–___ (2020) (slip op., at
15–16) (a practice that “arose in the second half of the 19th
century . . . cannot by itself establish an early
American tradition” informing our understanding of the First
Amendment). So today’s decision should not be understood to endorse
freewheeling reliance on historical practice from the mid-to-late
19th century to establish the original meaning of the Bill of
Rights. On the contrary, the Court is careful to caution “against
giving postenactment history more weight than it can rightly bear.” Ante , at 26. SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES
_________________
No. 20–843
_________________
New York State Rifle & Pistol Association,
Inc., et al., PETITIONERS v. Kevin P. Bruen, in his
official capacity as Superintendent of New York State Police,
et al.
on writ of certiorari to the united states
court of appeals for the second circuit
[June 23, 2022]
Justice Breyer, with whom Justice Sotomayor
and Justice Kagan join, dissenting.
In 2020, 45,222 Americans were killed by
firearms. See Centers for Disease Control and Prevention, Fast
Facts: Firearm Violence Prevention (last updated May 4, 2022) (CDC,
Fast Facts), https://www.cdc.gov/violenceprevention/
firearms/fastfact.html. Since the start of this year (2022), there
have been 277 reported mass shootings—an average of more than one
per day. See Gun Violence Archive (last visited June 20, 2022),
https://www.gunviolence archive.org. Gun violence has now surpassed
motor vehicle crashes as the leading cause of death among children
and adolescents. J. Goldstick, R. Cunningham, & P. Carter,
Current Causes of Death in Children and Adolescents in the United
States, 386 New England J. Med. 1955 (May 19, 2022)
(Goldstick).
Many States have tried to address some of the
dangers of gun violence just described by passing laws that limit,
in various ways, who may purchase, carry, or use firearms of
different kinds. The Court today severely burdens States’ efforts
to do so. It invokes the Second Amendment to strike down a New York
law regulating the public carriage of concealed handguns. In my
view, that decision rests upon several serious mistakes.
First, the Court decides this case on the basis
of the pleadings, without the benefit of discovery or an
evidentiary record. As a result, it may well rest its decision on a
mistaken understanding of how New York’s law operates in practice.
Second, the Court wrongly limits its analysis to focus nearly
exclusively on history. It refuses to consider the government
interests that justify a challenged gun regulation, regardless of
how compelling those interests may be. The Constitution contains no
such limitation, and neither do our precedents. Third, the Court
itself demonstrates the practical problems with its history-only
approach. In applying that approach to New York’s law, the Court
fails to correctly identify and analyze the relevant historical
facts. Only by ignoring an abundance of historical evidence
supporting regulations restricting the public carriage of firearms
can the Court conclude that New York’s law is not “consistent with
the Nation’s historical tradition of firearm regulation.” See ante, at 15.
In my view, when courts interpret the Second
Amendment, it is constitutionally proper, indeed often necessary,
for them to consider the serious dangers and consequences of gun
violence that lead States to regulate firearms. The Second Circuit
has done so and has held that New York’s law does not violate the
Second Amendment. See Kachalsky v. County of
Westchester , 701 F.3d 81, 97–99, 101 (2012). I would affirm
that holding. At a minimum, I would not strike down the law based
only on the pleadings, as the Court does today—without first
allowing for the development of an evidentiary record and without
considering the State’s compelling interest in preventing gun
violence. I respectfully dissent.
I
The question before us concerns the extent to
which the Second Amendment prevents democratically elected
officials from enacting laws to address the serious problem of gun
violence. And yet the Court today purports to answer that question
without discussing the nature or severity of that problem.
In 2017, there were an estimated 393.3 million
civilian-held firearms in the United States, or about 120 fire-
arms per 100 people. A. Karp, Estimating Global Civilian-Held
Firearms Numbers, Small Arms Survey 4 (June 2018),
https://www.smallarmssurvey.org/sites/default/files/
resources/SAS-BP-Civilian-Firearms-Numbers.pdf. That is more guns
per capita than in any other country in the world. Ibid. (By
comparison, Yemen is second with about 52.8 firearms per 100
people—less than half the per capita rate in the United States—and
some countries, like Indonesia and Japan, have fewer than one
firearm per 100 people. Id., at 3–4.)
Unsurprisingly, the United States also suffers a
disproportionately high rate of firearm-related deaths and
injuries. Cf. Brief for Educational Fund To Stop Gun Violence
et al. as Amici Curiae 17–18 (Brief for Educational
Fund) (citing studies showing that, within the United States,
“states that rank among the highest in gun ownership also rank
among the highest in gun deaths” while “states with lower rates of
gun ownership have lower rates of gun deaths”). In 2015,
approximately 36,000 people were killed by firearms nationwide. M.
Siegel et al., Easiness of Legal Access to Concealed Firearm
Permits and Homicide Rates in the United States, 107 Am. J. Pub.
Health 1923 (2017). Of those deaths, 22,018 (or about 61%) were
suicides, 13,463 (37%) were homicides, and 489 (1%) were
unintentional injuries. Ibid . On top of that, firearms
caused an average of 85,694 emergency room visits for nonfatal
injuries each year between 2009 and 2017. E. Kaufman et al.,
Epidemiological Trends in Fatal and Nonfatal Firearm Injuries in
the US, 2009–2017, 181 JAMA Internal Medicine 237 (2021)
(Kaufman).
Worse yet, gun violence appears to be on the
rise. By 2020, the number of firearm-related deaths had risen to
45,222, CDC, Fast Facts, or by about 25% since 2015. That means
that, in 2020, an average of about 124 people died from gun
violence every day. Ibid . As I mentioned above, gun violence
has now become the leading cause of death in children and
adolescents, surpassing car crashes, which had previously been the
leading cause of death in that age group for over 60 years.
Goldstick 1955; J. Bates, Guns Became the Leading Cause of Death
for American Children and Teens in 2020, Time, Apr. 27, 2022,
https://www. time.com/6170864/cause-of-death-children-guns/. And
the consequences of gun violence are borne disproportionately by
communities of color, and Black communities in particular. See CDC,
Age-Adjusted Rates of Firearm-Related Homicide, by Race, Hispanic
Origin, and Sex—National Vital Statistics System, United States,
2019, at 1491 (Oct. 22, 2021),
https://www.cdc.gov/mmwr/volumes/70/wr/pdfs/ mm7042a6-H.pdf
(documenting 34.9 firearm-related homicides per 100,000 population
for non-Hispanic Black men in 2019, compared to 7.7 such homicides
per 100,000 population for men of all races); S. Kegler
et al., CDC, Vital Signs : Changes in Firearm Homicide
and Suicide Rates—United States, 2019–2020, at 656–658 (May 13,
2022), https://
www.cdc.gov/mmwr/volumes/71/wr/pdfs/mm7119e1-H.pdf.
The dangers posed by firearms can take many
forms. Newspapers report mass shootings occurring at an
entertainment district in Philadelphia, Pennsylvania (3 dead and 11
injured); an elementary school in Uvalde, Texas (21 dead); a
supermarket in Buffalo, New York (10 dead and 3 injured); a series
of spas in Atlanta, Georgia (8 dead); a busy street in an
entertainment district of Dayton, Ohio (9 dead and 17 injured); a
nightclub in Orlando, Florida (50 dead and 53 injured); a church in
Charleston, South Carolina (9 dead); a movie theater in Aurora,
Colorado (12 dead and 50 injured); an elementary school in Newtown,
Connecticut (26 dead); and many, many more. See, e.g., R.
Todt, 3 Dead, 11 Wounded in Philadelphia Shooting on Busy Street,
Washington Post, June 5, 2022; A. Hernández, J. Slater, D. Barrett,
& S. Foster-Frau, At Least 19 Children, 2 Teachers Killed at
Texas Elementary School, Washington Post, May 25, 2022; A. Joly, J.
Slater, D. Barrett, & A. Hernandez, 10 Killed in Racially
Motivated Shooting at Buffalo Grocery Store, Washington
Post , May 14, 2022; C. McWhirter & V. Bauerlein,
Atlanta-Area Shootings at Spas Leave Eight Dead, Wall Street
Journal, Mar. 17, 2021; A. Hassan, Dayton Gunman Shot 26 People in
32 Seconds, Police Timeline Reveals, N. Y. Times, Aug. 13,
2019; L. Alvarez & R. Pérez-Peña, Orlando Gunman Attacks Gay
Nightclub, Leaving 50 Dead, N. Y. Times, June 12, 2016; J.
Horowitz, N. Corasaniti, & A. Southall, Nine Killed in Shooting
at Black Church in Charleston, N. Y. Times, June 17, 2015; R.
Lin, Gunman Kills 12 at ‘Dark Knight Rises’ Screening in Colorado,
L. A. Times, July 20, 2012; J. Barron, Nation Reels After
Gunman Massacres 20 Children at School in Connecticut, N. Y.
Times, Dec. 14, 2012. Since the start of this year alone (2022),
there have already been 277 reported mass shootings—an average of
more than one per day. Gun Violence Archive; see also Gun Violence
Archive, General Methodology,
https://www.gunviolencearchive.org/methodology (defining mass
shootings to include incidents in which at least four victims are
shot, not including the shooter).
And mass shootings are just one part of the
problem. Easy access to firearms can also make many other aspects
of American life more dangerous. Consider, for example, the effect
of guns on road rage. In 2021, an average of 44 people each month
were shot and either killed or wounded in road rage incidents,
double the annual average between 2016 and 2019. S. Burd-Sharps
& K. Bistline, Everytown for Gun Safety, Reports of Road Rage
Shootings Are on the Rise (Apr. 4, 2022),
https://www.everytownresearch.org/reports-of-road-rage-shootings-are-on-the-rise/;
see also J. Dono- hue, A. Aneja, & K. Weber, Right-to-Carry
Laws and Violent Crime: A Comprehensive Assessment Using Panel Data
and a State-Level Synthetic Control Analysis, 16 J. Empirical Legal
Studies 198, 204 (2019). Some of those deaths might have been
avoided if there had not been a loaded gun in the car. See ibid. ; Brief for American Bar Association as Amicus
Curiae 17–18; Brief for Educational Fund 20–23 (citing studies
showing that the presence of a firearm is likely to increase
aggression in both the person carrying the gun and others who see
it).
The same could be said of protests: A study of
30,000 protests between January 2020 and June 2021 found that armed
protests were nearly six times more likely to become violent or
destructive than unarmed protests. Everytown for Gun Safety, Armed
Assembly: Guns, Demonstrations, and Political Violence in America
(Aug. 23, 2021), https://
www.everytownresearch.org/report/armed- assembly-guns-demonstrations-and-political-violence-in-america/
(finding that 16% of armed protests turned violent, compared to
less than 3% of unarmed protests). Or domestic disputes: Another
study found that a woman is five times more likely to be killed by
an abusive partner if that partner has access to a gun. Brief for
Educational Fund 8 (citing A. Zeoli, R. Malinski, & B. Turchan,
Risks and Targeted Interventions: Firearms in Intimate Partner
Violence, 38 Epidemiologic Revs. 125 (2016); J. Campbell
et al., Risk Factors for Femicide in Abusive Relationships:
Results From a Multisite Case Control Study, 93 Am. J. Pub. Health
1089, 1092 (2003)). Or suicides: A study found that men who own
handguns are three times as likely to commit suicide than men who
do not and women who own handguns are seven times as likely to
commit suicide than women who do not. D. Studdert et al.,
Handgun Ownership and Suicide in California, 382 New England J.
Med. 2220, 2224 (June 4, 2020).
Consider, too, interactions with police
officers. The presence of a gun in the hands of a civilian poses a
risk to both officers and civilians. Amici prosecutors and
police chiefs tell us that most officers who are killed in the line
of duty are killed by firearms; they explain that officers in
States with high rates of gun ownership are three times as likely
to be killed in the line of duty as officers in States with low
rates of gun ownership. Brief for Prosecutors Against Gun Violence
as Amicus Curiae 23–24; Brief for Former Major City Police
Chiefs as Amici Curiae 13–14, and n. 21, (citing D.
Swedler, M. Simmons, F. Dominici, & D. Hemenway, Firearm
Prevalence and Homicides of Law Enforcement Officers in the United
States, 105 Am. J. Pub. Health 2042, 2045 (2015)). They also say
that States with the highest rates of gun ownership report four
times as many fatal shootings of civilians by police officers
compared to States with the lowest rates of gun ownership. Brief
for Former Major City Police Chiefs as Amici Curiae 16
(citing D. Hemenway, D. Azrael, A. Connor, & M. Miller,
Variation in Rates of Fatal Police Shootings Across US States: The
Role of Firearm Availability, 96 J. Urb. Health 63, 67 (2018)).
These are just some examples of the dangers that
firearms pose. There is, of course, another side to the story. I am
not simply saying that “guns are bad.” See ante, at 8
(Alito, J., concurring). Some Americans use guns for legitimate
purposes, such as sport ( e.g., hunting or target shooting),
certain types of employment ( e.g., as a private security
guard), or self-defense. Cf. ante, at 4–6 (Alito, J.,
concurring). Balancing these lawful uses against the dangers of
firearms is primarily the responsibility of elected bodies, such as
legislatures. It requires consideration of facts, statistics,
expert opinions, predictive judgments, relevant values, and a host
of other circumstances, which together make decisions about how,
when, and where to regulate guns more appropriately legislative
work. That consideration counsels modesty and restraint on the part
of judges when they interpret and apply the Second Amendment.
Consider, for one thing, that different types of
firearms may pose different risks and serve different purposes. The
Court has previously observed that handguns, the type of firearm at
issue here, “are the most popular weapon chosen by Americans for
self-defense in the home.” District of Columbia v. Heller , 554 U.S.
570 , 629 (2008). But handguns are also the most popular weapon
chosen by perpetrators of violent crimes. In 2018, 64.4% of firearm
homicides and 91.8% of nonfatal firearm assaults were committed
with a handgun. Dept. of Justice, Bureau of Justice Statistics, G.
Kena & J. Truman, Trends and Patterns in Firearm Violence,
1993–2018, pp. 5–6 (Apr. 2022). Handguns are also the most commonly
stolen type of firearm—63% of burglaries resulting in gun theft
between 2005 and 2010 involved the theft of at least one handgun.
Dept. of Justice, Bureau of Justice Statistics, L. Langton,
Firearms Stolen During Household Burglaries and Other Property
Crimes, 2005–2010, p. 3 (Nov. 2012).
Or consider, for another thing, that the dangers
and benefits posed by firearms may differ between urban and rural
areas. See generally Brief for City of Chicago et al. as Amici Curiae (detailing particular concerns about gun
violence in large cities). Firearm-related homicides and assaults
are significantly more common in urban areas than rural ones. For
example, from 1999 to 2016, 89.8% of the 213,175 firearm-related
homicides in the United States occurred in “metropolitan” areas. M.
Siegel et al., The Impact of State Firearm Laws on Homicide Rates
in Suburban and Rural Areas Compared to Large Cities in the United
States, 1991–2016, 36 J. Rural Health 255 (2020); see also Brief
for Partnership for New York City as Amicus Curiae 10;
Kaufman 237 (finding higher rates of fatal assault injuries from
firearms in urban areas compared to rural areas); C. Branas, M.
Nance, M. Elliott, T. Richmond, & C. Schwab, Urban-Rural Shifts
in Intentional Firearm Death: Different Causes, Same Results, 94
Am. J. Pub. Health 1750, 1752 (2004) (finding higher rates of
firearm homicide in urban counties compared to rural counties).
Justice Alito asks why I have begun my opinion
by reviewing some of the dangers and challenges posed by gun
violence and what relevance that has to today’s case. Ante, at 2–4 (concurring opinion). All of the above considerations
illustrate that the question of firearm regulation presents a
complex problem—one that should be solved by legislatures rather
than courts. What kinds of firearm regulations should a State
adopt? Different States might choose to answer that question
differently. They may face different challenges because of their
different geographic and demographic compositions. A State like New
York, which must account for the roughly 8.5 million people living
in the 303 square miles of New York City, might choose to adopt
different (and stricter) firearms regulations than States like
Montana or Wyoming, which do not contain any city remotely
comparable in terms of population or density. See U. S. Census
Bureau, Quick Facts: New York City (last updated July 1, 2021)
(Quick Facts: New York City), https://
www.census.gov/quickfacts/newyorkcitynewyork/; Brief for City of
New York as Amicus Curiae 8, 22. For a variety of reasons,
States may also be willing to tolerate different degrees of risk
and therefore choose to balance the competing benefits and dangers
of firearms differently.
The question presented in this case concerns the
extent to which the Second Amendment restricts different States
(and the Federal Government) from working out solutions to these
problems through democratic processes. The primary difference
between the Court’s view and mine is that I believe the Amendment
allows States to take account of the serious problems posed by gun
violence that I have just described. I fear that the Court’s
interpretation ignores these significant dangers and leaves States
without the ability to address them.
II
A
New York State requires individuals to obtain
a license in order to carry a concealed handgun in public.
N. Y. Penal Law Ann. §400.00(2) (West Cum. Supp. 2022). I
address the specifics of that licensing regime in greater detail in
Part II–B below. Because, at this stage in the proceedings, the
parties have not had an opportunity to develop the evidentiary
record, I refer to facts and representations made in petitioners’
complaint and in amicus briefs filed before us.
Under New York’s regime, petitioners Brandon
Koch and Robert Nash have obtained restricted licenses that permit
them to carry a concealed handgun for certain purposes and at
certain times and places. They wish to expand the scope of their
licenses so that they can carry a concealed handgun without
restriction.
Koch and Nash are residents of Rensselaer
County, New York. Koch lives in Troy, a town of about 50,000,
located eight miles from New York’s capital city of Albany, which
has a population of about 98,000. See App. 100; U. S. Census
Bureau, Quick Facts: Troy City, New York (last updated July 1,
2021), https://www.census.gov/quickfacts/ troycitynewyork; id. , Albany City, New York, https://www.
census.gov/quickfacts/albanycitynewyork. Nash lives in Averill
Park, a small town 12.5 miles from Albany. App. 100.
Koch and Nash each applied for a license to
carry a concealed handgun. Both were issued restricted licenses
that allowed them to carry handguns only for purposes of hunting
and target shooting. Id ., at 104, 106. But they wanted
“unrestricted” licenses that would allow them to carry concealed
handguns “for personal protection and all lawful purposes.” Id ., at 112; see also id ., at 40. They wrote to the
licensing officer in Rensselaer County—Justice Richard McNally, a
justice of the New York Supreme Court—requesting that the hunting
and target shooting restrictions on their licenses be removed. Id., at 40, 111–113. After holding individual hearings for
each petitioner, Justice McNally denied their requests. Id., at 31, 41, 105, 107, 114. He clarified that, in addition to hunting
and target shooting, Koch and Nash could “carry concealed for
purposes of off road back country, outdoor activities similar to
hunting, for example fishing, hiking & camping.” Id., at
41, 114. He also permitted Koch, who was employed by the New York
Court System’s Division of Technology, to “carry to and from work.” Id ., at 111, 114. But he reaffirmed that Nash was prohibited
from carrying a concealed handgun in locations “typically open to
and frequented by the general public.” Id. , at 41. Neither
Koch nor Nash alleges that he appealed Justice McNally’s decision.
Brief for Respondents 13; see App. 122–126.
Instead, petitioners Koch and Nash, along with
the New York State Rifle & Pistol Association, Inc., brought
this lawsuit in federal court against Justice McNally and other
State representatives responsible for enforcing New York’s firearms
laws. Petitioners claimed that the State’s refusal to modify Koch’s
and Nash’s licenses violated the Second Amendment. The District
Court dismissed their complaint. It followed Second Circuit
precedent holding that New York’s licensing regime was
constitutional. See Kachalsky , 701 F. 3d, at 101. The
Court of Appeals for the Second Circuit affirmed. We granted
certiorari to review the constitutionality of “New York’s denial of
petitioners’ license applications.” Ante, at 8 (majority
opinion).
B
As the Court recognizes, New York’s licensing
regime traces its origins to 1911, when New York enacted the
“Sullivan Law,” which prohibited public carriage of handguns
without a license. See 1911 N. Y. Laws ch. 195, §1, p. 443.
Two years later in 1913, New York amended the law to establish
substantive standards for the issuance of a license. See 1913
N. Y. Laws ch. 608, §1, pp. 1627–1629. Those standards have
remained the foundation of New York’s licensing regime ever since—a
regime that the Court now, more than a century later, strikes down
as unconstitutional.
As it did over 100 years ago, New York’s law
today continues to require individuals to obtain a license before
carrying a concealed handgun in public. N. Y. Penal Law Ann.
§400.00(2); Kachalsky , 701 F. 3d, at 85–86. Because the
State does not allow the open carriage of handguns at all, a
concealed-carry license is the only way to legally carry a handgun
in public . Id ., at 86. This licensing requirement
applies only to handguns ( i.e., “pistols and revolvers”) and
short-barreled rifles and shotguns, not to all types of firearms. Id. , at 85. For instance, the State does not require a
license to carry a long gun ( i.e., a rifle or a shotgun over
a certain length) in public. Ibid. ; §265.00(3) (West
2022).
To obtain a concealed-carry license for a
handgun, an applicant must satisfy certain eligibility criteria.
Among other things, he must generally be at least 21 years old and
of “good moral character.” §400.00(1). And he cannot have been
convicted of a felony, dishonorably discharged from the military,
or involuntarily committed to a mental hygiene facility. Ibid . If these and other eligibility criteria are satisfied,
New York law provides that a concealed-carry license “shall be
issued” to individuals working in certain professions, such as
judges, corrections officers, or messengers of a “banking
institution or express company.” §400.00(2). Individuals who
satisfy the eligibility criteria but do not work in one of these
professions may still obtain a concealed-carry license, but they
must additionally show that “proper cause exists for the issuance
thereof.” §400.00(2)(f ).
The words “proper cause” may appear on their
face to be broad, but there is “a substantial body of law
instructing licensing officials on the application of this
standard.” Id. , at 86. New York courts have interpreted
proper cause “to include carrying a handgun for target practice,
hunting, or self-defense.” Ibid . When an applicant seeks a
license for target practice or hunting, he must show “ ‘a
sincere desire to participate in target shooting and
hunting.’ ” Ibid . (quoting In re O’Connor ,
154 Misc. 2d 694, 697, 585 N.Y.S.2d 1000, 1003 (Westchester Cty.
1992)). When an applicant seeks a license for self-defense, he must
show “ ‘a special need for self-protection distinguishable
from that of the general community.’ ” 701 F. 3d, at 86
(quoting In re Klenosky , 75 App. Div. 2d 793,
793, 428 N.Y.S.2d 256, 257 (1980)). Whether an applicant meets
these proper cause standards is determined in the first instance by
a “licensing officer in the city or county . . . where
the applicant resides.” §400.00(3). In most counties, the licensing
officer is a local judge. Kachalsky , 701 F. 3d, at 87,
n. 6. For example, in Rensselaer County, the licensing officer
who denied petitioners’ requests to remove the restrictions on
their licenses was a justice of the New York Supreme Court. App.
31. If the officer denies an application, the applicant can obtain
judicial review under Article 78 of New York’s Civil Practice Law
and Rules. Kachalsky , 701 F. 3d, at 87. New York courts
will then review whether the denial was arbitrary and capricious. Ibid. In describing New York’s law, the Court recites
the above facts but adds its own gloss. It suggests that New York’s
licensing regime gives licensing officers too much discretion and
provides too “limited” judicial review of their decisions, ante, at 4; that the proper cause standard is too
“demanding,” ante, at 3; and that these features make New
York an outlier compared to the “vast majority of States,” ante, at 4. But on what evidence does the Court base these
characterizations? Recall that this case comes to us at the
pleading stage. The parties have not had an opportunity to conduct
discovery, and no evidentiary hearings have been held to develop
the record. See App. 15–26. Thus, at this point, there is no record
to support the Court’s negative characterizations, as we know very
little about how the law has actually been applied on the
ground.
Consider each of the Court’s criticisms in turn.
First, the Court says that New York gives licensing officers too
much discretion and “leaves applicants little recourse if their
local licensing officer denies a permit.” Ante , at 4. But
there is nothing unusual about broad statutory language that can be
given more specific content by judicial interpretation. Nor is
there anything unusual or inadequate about subjecting licensing
officers’ decisions to arbitrary-and-capricious review. Judges
routinely apply that standard, for example, to determine whether an
agency action is lawful under both New York law and the
Administrative Procedure Act. See, e.g., N. Y. Civ.
Prac. Law Ann. §7803(3) (2021); 5 U. S. C. §706(2)(A).
The arbitrary-and-capricious standard has thus been used to review
important policies concerning health, safety, and immigration, to
name just a few examples. See, e.g., Biden v. Missouri , 595 U. S. ___, ___ (2022)
( per curiam ) (slip op., at 8); Department of
Homeland Security v. Regents of Univ. of Cal. , 591
U. S. ___, ___, ___ (2020) (slip op., at 9, 17); Department
of Commerce v. New York , 588 U. S. ___, ___ (2019)
(slip op., at 16); Motor Vehicle Mfrs. Assn. of United States,
Inc. v. State Farm Mut. Automobile Ins. Co. , 463 U.S.
29 , 41, 46 (1983).
Without an evidentiary record, there is no
reason to assume that New York courts applying this standard fail
to provide license applicants with meaningful review. And there is
no evidentiary record to support the Court’s assumption here. Based
on the pleadings alone, we cannot know how often New York courts
find the denial of a concealed-carry license to be arbitrary and
capricious or on what basis. We do not even know how a court would
have reviewed the licensing officer’s decisions in Koch’s and
Nash’s cases because they do not appear to have sought judicial
review at all. See Brief for Respondents 13; App. 122–126.
Second, the Court characterizes New York’s
proper cause standard as substantively “demanding.” Ante, at
3. But, again, the Court has before it no evidentiary record to
demonstrate how the standard has actually been applied. How
“demanding” is the proper cause standard in practice? Does that
answer differ from county to county? How many license applications
are granted and denied each year? At the pleading stage, we do not
know the answers to these and other important questions, so the
Court’s characterization of New York’s law may very well be
wrong.
In support of its assertion that the law is
“demanding,” the Court cites only to cases originating in New York
City. Ibid . (citing In re Martinek , 294 App. Div. 2d
221, 743 N.Y.S.2d 80 (2002) (New York County, i.e., Manhattan); In re Kaplan , 249 App. Div. 2d 199, 673 N.Y.S.2d
66 (1998) (same); In re Klenosky , 75 App. Div. 2d 793, 428
N.Y.S.2d 256 (same); In re Bernstein , 85 App. Div. 2d 574,
445 N.Y.S.2d 716 (1981) (Bronx County)). But cases from New York
City may not accurately represent how the proper cause standard is
applied in other parts of the State, including in Rensselaer County
where petitioners reside.
To the contrary, amici tell us that New
York’s licensing regime is purposefully flexible: It allows
counties and cities to respond to the particular needs and
challenges of each area. See Brief for American Bar Association as Amicus Curiae 12; Brief for City of New York as Amicus
Curiae 20–29. Amici suggest that some areas may
interpret words such as “proper cause” or “special need” more or
less strictly, depending upon each area’s unique circumstances. See ibid . New York City, for example, reports that it “has
applied the [proper cause] requirement relatively rigorously”
because its densely populated urban areas pose a heightened risk of
gun violence. Brief for City of New York as Amicus Curiae 20. In comparison, other (perhaps more rural) counties “have
tailored the requirement to their own circumstances, often issuing
concealed-carry licenses more freely than the City.” Ibid. ;
see also In re O’Connor , 154 Misc. 2d, at 698, 585
N. Y. S. 2d, at 1004 (“The circumstances which exist in
New York City are significantly different than those which exist in
Oswego or Putnam Counties. . . . The licensing
officers in each county are in the best position to determine
whether any interest of the population of their county is furthered
by the use of restrictions on pistol licenses”); Brief for Citizens
Crime Commission of New York City as Amicus Curiae 18–19.
Given the geographic variation across the State, it is too sweeping
for the Court to suggest, without an evidentiary record, that the
proper cause standard is “demanding” in Rensselaer County merely
because it may be so in New York City.
Finally, the Court compares New York’s licensing
regime to that of other States. Ante, at 4–6. It says that
New York’s law is a “may issue” licensing regime, which the Court
describes as a law that provides licensing officers greater
discretion to grant or deny licenses than a “shall issue” licensing
regime. Ante, at 4–5. Because the Court counts 43 “shall
issue” jurisdictions and only 7 “may issue” jurisdictions, it
suggests that New York’s law is an outlier. Ibid .; see also ante, at 1–2 (Kavanaugh, J., concurring). Implicitly, the
Court appears to ask, if so many other States have adopted the more
generous “shall issue” approach, why can New York not be required
to do the same?
But the Court’s tabulation, and its implicit
question, overlook important context. In drawing a line between
“may issue” and “shall issue” licensing regimes, the Court ignores
the degree of variation within and across these categories. Not all
“may issue” regimes are necessarily alike, nor are all “shall
issue” regimes. Conversely, not all “may issue” regimes are as
different from the “shall issue” regimes as the Court assumes. For
instance, the Court recognizes in a footnote that three States
(Connecticut, Delaware, and Rhode Island) have statutes with
discretionary criteria, like so-called “may issue” regimes do. Ante, at 5, n. 1. But the Court nonetheless counts them
among the 43 “shall issue” jurisdictions because, it says, these
three States’ laws operate in practice more like “shall issue”
regimes. Ibid. ; see also Brief for American Bar Association
as Amicus Curiae 10 (recognizing, conversely, that some
“shall issue” States, e.g., Alabama, Colorado, Georgia,
Oregon, and Virginia, still grant some degree of discretion to
licensing authorities).
As these three States demonstrate, the line
between “may issue” and “shall issue” regimes is not as clear cut
as the Court suggests, and that line depends at least in part on
how statutory discretion is applied in practice. Here, because the
Court strikes down New York’s law without affording the State an
opportunity to develop an evidentiary record, we do not know how
much discretion licensing officers in New York have in practice or
how that discretion is exercised, let alone how the licensing
regimes in the other six “may issue” jurisdictions operate.
Even accepting the Court’s line between “may
issue” and “shall issue” regimes and assuming that its tally (7
“may issue” and 43 “shall issue” jurisdictions) is correct, that
count does not support the Court’s implicit suggestion that the
seven “may issue” jurisdictions are somehow outliers or anomalies.
The Court’s count captures only a snapshot in time. It forgets that
“shall issue” licensing regimes are a relatively recent
development. Until the 1980s, “may issue” regimes predominated. See id ., at 9; R. Grossman & S. Lee, May Issue Versus Shall
Issue: Explaining the Pattern of Concealed-Carry Handgun Laws,
1960–2001, 26 Contemp. Econ. Pol’y 198, 200 (2008) (Grossman). As
of 1987, 16 States and the District of Columbia prohibited
concealed carriage outright, 26 States had “may issue” licensing
regimes, 7 States had “shall issue” regimes, and 1 State (Vermont)
allowed concealed carriage without a permit. Congressional Research
Service, Gun Control: Concealed Carry Legislation in the 115th
Congress 1 (Jan. 30, 2018). Thus, it has only been in the last few
decades that States have shifted toward “shall issue” licensing
laws. Prior to that, most States operated “may issue” licensing
regimes without legal or practical problem.
Moreover, even considering, as the Court does,
only the present state of play, its tally provides an incomplete
picture because it accounts for only the number of States with “may
issue” regimes, not the number of people governed by those regimes.
By the Court’s count, the seven “may issue” jurisdictions are New
York, California, Hawaii, Maryland, Massachusetts, New Jersey, and
the District of Columbia. Ante, at 5–6. Together, these
seven jurisdictions comprise about 84.4 million people and account
for over a quarter of the country’s population. U. S. Census
Bureau, 2020 Pop- ulation and Housing State Data (Aug. 12, 2021)
(2020 Population), https://www.census.gov/library/visualizations/
interactive/2020-population-and-housing-state-data.html. Thus, “may
issue” laws can hardly be described as a marginal or outdated
regime.
And there are good reasons why these seven
jurisdictions may have chosen not to follow other States in
shifting toward “shall issue” regimes. The seven remaining “may
issue” jurisdictions are among the most densely populated in the
United States: the District of Columbia (with an average of
11,280.0 people/square mile in 2020), New Jersey (1,263.0),
Massachusetts (901.2), Maryland (636.1), New York (428.7),
California (253.7), and Hawaii (226.6). U. S. Census Bureau,
Historical Population Density (1910–2020) (Apr. 26, 2001),
https://www.census.gov/data/tables/time-series/dec/density-data-text.html.
In comparison, the average population density of the United States
as a whole is 93.8 people/square mile, and some States have
population densities as low as 1.3 (Alaska), 5.9 (Wyoming), and 7.4
(Montana) people/square mile. Ibid . These numbers reflect in
part the fact that these “may issue” jurisdictions contain some of
the country’s densest and most populous urban areas, e.g., New York City, Los Angeles, San Francisco, the District of
Columbia, Honolulu, and Boston. U. S. Census Bureau, Urban
Area Facts (Oct. 8, 2021), https://www.census
. gov/programs-surveys/geography/guidance/geo-areas/
urban-rural/ua-facts.html. New York City, for example, has a
population of about 8.5 million people, making it more populous
than 38 States, and it squeezes that population into just over 300
square miles. Quick Facts: New York City; 2020 Population; Brief
for City of New York as Amicus Curiae 8, 22.
As I explained above, supra, at 8–9,
densely populated urban areas face different kinds and degrees of
dangers from gun violence than rural areas. It is thus easy to see
why the seven “may issue” jurisdictions might choose to regulate
firearm carriage more strictly than other States. See Grossman 199
(“We find strong evidence that more urban states are less likely to
shift to ‘shall issue’ than rural states”).
New York and its amici present
substantial data justifying the State’s decision to retain a “may
issue” licensing regime. The data show that stricter gun
regulations are associated with lower rates of firearm-related
death and injury. See, e.g., Brief for Citizens Crime
Commission of New York City as Amicus Curiae 9–11; Brief for
Former Major City Police Chiefs as Amici Curiae 9–12; Brief
for Educational Fund 25–28; Brief for Social Scientists et al.
as Amici Curiae 9–19. In particular, studies have shown that
“may issue” licensing regimes, like New York’s, are associated with
lower homicide rates and lower violent crime rates than “shall
issue” licensing regimes. For example, one study compared homicide
rates across all 50 States during the 25-year period from 1991 to
2015 and found that “shall issue” laws were associated with 6.5%
higher total homicide rates, 8.6% higher firearm homicide rates,
and 10.6% higher handgun homicide rates. Siegel, 107 Am. J. Pub.
Health, at 1924–1925, 1927. Another study longitudinally followed
33 States that had adopted “shall-issue” laws between 1981 and 2007
and found that the adoption of those laws was associated with a
13%–15% increase in rates of violent crime after 10 years. Donohue,
16 J. Empirical Legal Studies, at 200, 240. Numerous other studies
show similar results. See, e.g., Siegel, 36 J. Rural
Health , at 261 (finding that “may issue” laws are associated
with 17% lower firearm homicide rates in large cities); C. Crifasi
et al., Association Between Firearm Laws and Homicide in Urban
Counties, 95 J. Urb. Health 383, 387 (2018) (finding that “shall
issue” laws are associated with a 4% increase in firearm homicide
rates in urban counties); M. Doucette, C. Crifasi, & S.
Frattaroli, Right-to-Carry Laws and Firearm Workplace Homicides: A
Longitudinal Analysis (1992–2017), 109 Am. J. Pub. Health 1747,
1751 (Dec. 2019) (finding that States with “shall issue” laws
between 1992 and 2017 experienced 29% higher rates of
firearm-related workplace homicides); Brief for Social Scientists
et al. as Amici Curiae 15–16, and nn. 17–20 (citing
“thirteen . . . empirical papers from just the last few
years linking [“shall issue”] laws to higher violent crime”).
Justice Alito points to competing empirical
evidence that arrives at a different conclusion. Ante, at 3,
n. 1 (concurring opinion). But these types of disagreements
are exactly the sort that are better addressed by legislatures than
courts. The Court today restricts the ability of legislatures to
fulfill that role. It does so without knowing how New York’s law is
administered in practice, how much discretion licensing officers in
New York possess, or whether the proper cause standard differs
across counties. And it does so without giving the State an
opportunity to develop the evidentiary record to answer those
questions. Yet it strikes down New York’s licensing regime as a
violation of the Second Amendment.
III
A
How does the Court justify striking down New
York’s law without first considering how it actually works on the
ground and what purposes it serves? The Court does so by purporting
to rely nearly exclusively on history. It requires “the government
[to] affirmatively prove that its firearms regulation is part of
the historical tradition that delimits the outer bounds of ‘the
right to keep and bear arms.’ ” Ante, at 10. Beyond
this historical inquiry, the Court refuses to employ what it calls
“means-end scrutiny.” Ibid. That is, it refuses to consider
whether New York has a compelling interest in regulating the
concealed carriage of handguns or whether New York’s law is
narrowly tailored to achieve that interest. Although I agree that
history can often be a useful tool in determining the meaning and
scope of constitutional provisions, I believe the Court’s
near-exclusive reliance on that single tool today goes much too
far.
The Court concedes that no Court of Appeals has
adopted its rigid history-only approach. See ante, at 8. To
the contrary, every Court of Appeals to have addressed the question
has agreed on a two-step framework for evaluating whether a firearm
regulation is consistent with the Second Amendment. Ibid. ; ante, at 10, n. 4 (majority opinion) (listing cases
from the First, Second, Third, Fourth, Fifth, Sixth, Seventh,
Ninth, Tenth, Eleventh, and D. C. Circuits). At the first
step, the Courts of Appeals use text and history to determine
“whether the regulated activity falls within the scope of the
Second Amendment.” Ezell v. Chicago , 846 F.3d 888,
892 (CA7 2017). If it does, they go on to the second step and
consider “ ‘the strength of the government’s justification for
restricting or regulating’ ” the Second Amendment right. Ibid . In doing so, they apply a level of “means-ends”
scrutiny “that is proportionate to the severity of the burden that
the law imposes on the right”: strict scrutiny if the burden is
severe, and intermediate scrutiny if it is not. National Rifle
Assn. of Am., Inc. v. Bureau of Alcohol, Tobacco, Firearms,
and Explosives , 700 F.3d 185, 195, 198, 205 (CA5 2012).
The Court today replaces the Courts of Appeals’
consensus framework with its own history-only approach. That is
unusual. We do not normally disrupt settled consensus among the
Courts of Appeals, especially not when that consensus approach has
been applied without issue for over a decade. See Brief for Second
Amendment Law Professors as Amici Curiae 4, 13–15; see also
this Court’s Rule 10. The Court attempts to justify its deviation
from our normal practice by claiming that the Courts of Appeals’
approach is inconsistent with Heller . See ante, at
10. In doing so, the Court implies that all 11 Courts of Appeals
that have considered this question misread Heller .
To the contrary, it is this Court that misreads Heller . The opinion in Heller did focus primarily on
“constitutional text and history,” ante, at 13 (majority
opinion), but it did not “rejec[t] . . . means-end
scrutiny,” as the Court claims, ante, at 15. Consider what
the Heller Court actually said. True, the Court spent many
pages in Heller discussing the text and historical context
of the Second Amendment. 554 U. S., at 579–619. But that is
not surprising because the Heller Court was asked to answer
the preliminary question whether the Second Amendment right to
“bear Arms” encompasses an individual right to possess a firearm in
the home for self-defense. Id. , at 577. The Heller Court concluded that the Second Amendment’s text and history were
sufficiently clear to resolve that question: The Second Amendment,
it said, does include such an individual right. Id ., at
579–619. There was thus no need for the Court to go further—to look
beyond text and history, or to suggest what analysis would be
appropriate in other cases where the text and history are not
clear.
But the Heller Court did not end its
opinion with that preliminary question. After concluding that the
Second Amendment protects an individual right to possess a firearm
for self-defense, the Heller Court added that that right is
“not unlimited.” Id., at 626. It thus had to determine
whether the District of Columbia’s law, which banned handgun
possession in the home, was a permissible regulation of the right. Id. , at 628–630. In answering that second question, it said:
“Under any of the standards of scrutiny that we have applied to
enumerated constitutional rights , banning from the home ‘the
most preferred firearm in the nation to “keep” and use for
protection of one’s home and family’ would fail constitutional
muster.” Id., at 628–629 (emphasis added; footnote and
citation omitted). That language makes clear that the Heller Court understood some form of means-end scrutiny to apply. It did
not need to specify whether that scrutiny should be intermediate or
strict because, in its view, the District’s handgun ban was so
“severe” that it would have failed either level of scrutiny. Id., at 628–629; see also id., at 628, n. 27
(clarifying that rational-basis review was not the proper level of
scrutiny).
Despite Heller ’s express invocation of
means-end scrutiny, the Court today claims that the majority in Heller rejected means-end scrutiny because it rejected my
dissent in that case. But that argument misreads both my dissent
and the majority opinion. My dissent in Heller proposed
directly weighing “the interests protected by the Second Amendment
on one side and the governmental public-safety concerns on the
other.” Id., at 689. I would have asked “whether the statute
burdens a protected interest in a way or to an extent that is out
of proportion to the statute’s salutary effects upon other
important governmental interests.” Id., at 689–690. The
majority rejected my dissent, not because I proposed using
means-end scrutiny, but because, in its view, I had done the
opposite. In its own words, the majority faulted my dissent for
proposing “a freestanding ‘interest-balancing’ approach”
that accorded with “ none of the traditionally expressed
levels [of scrutiny] (strict scrutiny, intermediate scrutiny,
rational basis).” Id., at 634 (emphasis added).
The majority further made clear that its
rejection of freestanding interest balancing did not extend
to traditional forms of means-end scrutiny. It said: “We know of no
other enumerated constitutional right whose core protection has
been subjected to a freestanding ‘interest-balancing’ approach.” Ibid. To illustrate this point, it cited as an example the
First Amendment right to free speech. Id. , at 635. Judges,
of course, regularly use means-end scrutiny, including both strict
and intermediate scrutiny, when they interpret or apply the First
Amendment. See, e.g., United States v. Playboy
Entertainment Group, Inc. , 529 U.S.
803 , 813 (2000) (applying strict scrutiny); Turner
Broadcasting System, Inc. v. FCC , 520 U.S.
180 , 186, 189–190 (1997) (applying intermediate scrutiny). The
majority therefore cannot have intended its opinion, consistent
with our First Amendment jurisprudence, to be read as rejecting all
traditional forms of means-end scrutiny.
As Heller ’s First Amendment example
illustrates, the Court today is wrong when it says that its
rejection of means-end scrutiny and near-exclusive focus on history
“accords with how we protect other constitutional rights.” Ante, at 15. As the Court points out, we do look to history
in the First Amendment context to determine “whether the expressive
conduct falls outside of the category of protected speech.” Ibid. But, if conduct falls within a category of protected
speech, we then use means-end scrutiny to determine whether a
challenged regulation unconstitutionally burdens that speech. And
the degree of scrutiny we apply often depends on the type of speech
burdened and the severity of the burden. See, e.g., Arizona Free
Enterprise Club’s Freedom Club PAC v. Bennett , 564 U.S.
721 , 734 (2011) (applying strict scrutiny to laws that burden
political speech); Ward v. Rock Against Racism , 491 U.S.
781 , 791 (1989) (applying intermediate scrutiny to time, place,
and manner restrictions); Central Hudson Gas & Elec.
Corp. v. Public Serv. Comm’n of N. Y. , 447 U.S.
557 , 564–566 (1980) (applying intermediate scrutiny to laws
that burden commercial speech).
Additionally, beyond the right to freedom of
speech, we regularly use means-end scrutiny in cases involving
other constitutional provisions. See, e.g., Church of
Lukumi Babalu Aye, Inc. v. Hialeah , 508 U.S.
520 , 546 (1993) (applying strict scrutiny under the First
Amendment to laws that restrict free exercise of religion in a way
that is not neutral and generally applicable); Adarand
Constructors, Inc. v. Peña , 515
U.S. 200 , 227 (1995) (applying strict scrutiny under the Equal
Protection Clause to race-based classifications); Clark v. Jeter , 486 U.S.
456 , 461 (1988) (applying intermediate scrutiny under the Equal
Protection Clause to sex-based classifications); see also Virginia v. Moore , 553 U.S.
164 , 171 (2008) (“When history has not provided a conclusive
answer, we have analyzed a search or seizure in light of
traditional standards of reasonableness”).
The upshot is that applying means-end scrutiny
to laws that regulate the Second Amendment right to bear arms would
not create a constitutional anomaly. Rather, it is the Court’s
rejection of means-end scrutiny and adoption of a rigid
history-only approach that is anomalous.
B
The Court’s near-exclusive reliance on history
is not only unnecessary, it is deeply impractical. It imposes a
task on the lower courts that judges cannot easily accomplish.
Judges understand well how to weigh a law’s objectives (its “ends”)
against the methods used to achieve those objectives (its “means”).
Judges are far less accustomed to resolving difficult historical
questions. Courts are, after all, staffed by lawyers, not
historians. Legal experts typically have little experience
answering contested historical questions or applying those answers
to resolve contemporary problems.
The Court’s insistence that judges and lawyers
rely nearly exclusively on history to interpret the Second
Amendment thus raises a host of troubling questions. Consider, for
example, the following. Do lower courts have the research resources
necessary to conduct exhaustive historical analyses in every Second
Amendment case? What historical regulations and decisions qualify
as representative analogues to modern laws? How will judges
determine which historians have the better view of close historical
questions? Will the meaning of the Second Amendment change if or
when new historical evidence becomes available? And, most
importantly, will the Court’s approach permit judges to reach the
outcomes they prefer and then cloak those outcomes in the language
of history? See S. Cornell, Heller , New Originalism, and Law
Office History: “Meet the New Boss, Same as the Old Boss,” 56 UCLA
L. Rev. 1095, 1098 (2009) (describing “law office history” as
“a results oriented methodology in which evidence is selectively
gathered and interpreted to produce a preordained conclusion”).
Consider Heller itself. That case,
fraught with difficult historical questions, illustrates the
practical problems with expecting courts to decide important
constitutional questions based solely on history. The majority in Heller undertook 40 pages of textual and historical analysis
and concluded that the Second Amendment’s protection of the right
to “keep and bear Arms” historically encompassed an “individual
right to possess and carry weapons in case of confrontation”—that
is, for self-defense. 554 U. S. , at 592; see also id., at 579–619. Justice Stevens’ dissent conducted an
equally searching textual and historical inquiry and concluded, to
the contrary, that the term “bear Arms” was an idiom that protected
only the right “to use and possess arms in conjunction with service
in a well-regulated militia.” Id., at 651. I do not intend
to relitigate Heller here . I accept its holding as a
matter of stare decisis. I refer to its historical analysis
only to show the difficulties inherent in answering historical
questions and to suggest that judges do not have the expertise
needed to answer those questions accurately.
For example, the Heller majority relied
heavily on its interpretation of the English Bill of Rights. Citing
Blackstone, the majority claimed that the English Bill of Rights
protected a “ ‘right of having and using arms for
self-preservation and defence.’ ” Id. , at 594 (quoting
1 Commentaries on the Laws of England 140 (1765)). The majority
interpreted that language to mean a private right to bear arms for
self-defense, “having nothing whatever to do with service in a
militia.” 554 U. S., at 593. Two years later, however, 21
English and early American historians (including experts at top
universities) told us in McDonald v. Chicago , 561 U.S.
742 (2010), that the Heller Court had gotten the history
wrong: The English Bill of Rights “did not . . . protect
an individual’s right to possess, own, or use arms for private
purposes such as to defend a home against burglars.” Brief for
English/Early American Historians as Amici Curiae in McDonald v. Chicago , O. T. 2009, No. 08–1521, p. 2.
Rather, these amici historians explained, the English right
to “have arms” ensured that the Crown could not deny Parliament
(which represented the people) the power to arm the landed gentry
and raise a militia—or the right of the people to possess arms to
take part in that militia—“should the sovereign usurp the laws,
liberties, estates, and Protestant religion of the nation.” Id., at 2–3. Thus, the English right did protect a right of
“self-preservation and defence,” as Blackstone said, but that right
“was to be exercised not by individuals acting privately or
independently, but as a militia organized by their elected
representatives,” i.e., Parliament. Id., at 7–8. The
Court, not an expert in history, had misread Blackstone and other
sources explaining the English Bill of Rights.
And that was not the Heller Court’s only
questionable judgment. The majority rejected Justice Stevens’
argument that the Second Amendment’s use of the words “bear Arms”
drew on an idiomatic meaning that, at the time of the founding,
commonly referred to military service. 554 U. S., at 586.
Linguistics experts now tell us that the majority was wrong to do
so. See, e.g., Brief for Corpus Linguistics Professors and
Experts as Amici Curiae (Brief for Linguistics
Professors); Brief for Neal Goldfarb as Amicus Curiae ; Brief
for Americans Against Gun Violence as Amicus Curiae 13–15.
Since Heller was decided, experts have searched over 120,000
founding-era texts from between 1760 and 1799, as well as 40,000
texts from sources dating as far back as 1475, for historical uses
of the phrase “bear arms,” and they concluded that the phrase was
overwhelmingly used to refer to “ ‘war, soldiering, or other
forms of armed action by a group rather than an individual.’ ”
Brief for Linguistics Professors 11, 14; see also D. Baron, Corpus
Evidence Illuminates the Meaning of Bear Arms, 46 Hastings Const.
L. Q. 509, 510 (2019) (“Non-military uses of bear arms in reference to hunting or personal self-defense are not just rare,
they are almost nonexistent”); id. , at 510–511 (reporting
900 instances in which “bear arms” was used to refer to military or
collective use of firearms and only 7 instances that were either
ambiguous or without a military connotation).
These are just two examples. Other scholars have
continued to write books and articles arguing that the Court’s
decision in Heller misread the text and history of the
Second Amendment. See generally, e.g., M. Waldman, The
Second Amendment (2014); S. Cornell, The Changing Meaning of the
Right To Keep and Bear Arms: 1688–1788, in Guns in Law 20–27 (A.
Sarat, L. Douglas, & M. Umphrey eds. 2019); P. Finkelman, The
Living Constitution and the Second Amendment: Poor History, False
Originalism, and a Very Confused Court, 37 Cardozo L. Rev. 623
(2015); D. Walker, Necessary to the Security of Free States: The
Second Amendment as the Auxiliary Right of Federalism, 56 Am. J.
Legal Hist. 365 (2016); W. Merkel, Heller as Hubris, and How McDonald v. City of Chicago May Well Change the
Constitutional World as We Know It, 50 Santa Clara L. Rev. 1221
(2010).
I repeat that I do not cite these arguments in
order to relitigate Heller . I wish only to illustrate the
difficulties that may befall lawyers and judges when they attempt
to rely solely on history to interpret the Constitution. In Heller , we attempted to determine the scope of the Second
Amendment right to bear arms by conducting a historical analysis,
and some of us arrived at very different conclusions based on the
same historical sources. Many experts now tell us that the Court
got it wrong in a number of ways. That is understandable given the
difficulty of the inquiry that the Court attempted to undertake.
The Court’s past experience with historical analysis should serve
as a warning against relying exclusively, or nearly exclusively, on
this mode of analysis in the future.
Failing to heed that warning, the Court today
does just that. Its near-exclusive reliance on history will pose a
number of practical problems. First, the difficulties attendant to
extensive historical analysis will be especially acute in the lower
courts. The Court’s historical analysis in this case is over 30
pages long and reviews numerous original sources from over 600
years of English and American history. Ante, at 30–62. Lower
courts—especially district courts—typically have fewer research
resources, less assistance from amici historians, and higher
caseloads than we do. They are therefore ill equipped to conduct
the type of searching historical surveys that the Court’s approach
requires. Tellingly, even the Courts of Appeals that have addressed
the question presented here (namely, the constitutionality of
public carriage restrictions like New York’s) “have, in large part,
avoided extensive historical analysis.” Young v. Hawaii , 992 F.3d 765, 784–785 (CA9 2021) (collecting cases).
In contrast, lawyers and courts are well equipped to administer
means-end scrutiny, which is regularly applied in a variety of
constitutional contexts, see supra, at 24–25.
Second, the Court’s opinion today compounds
these problems, for it gives the lower courts precious little
guidance regarding how to resolve modern constitutional questions
based almost solely on history. See, e.g., ante, at 1
(Barrett, J., concurring) (“highlight[ing] two methodological
points that the Court does not resolve”). The Court declines to
“provide an exhaustive survey of the features that render
regulations relevantly similar under the Second Amendment.” Ante, at 20. Other than noting that its history-only
analysis is “neither a . . . straightjacket nor a
. . . blank check,” the Court offers little explanation
of how stringently its test should be applied. Ante, at 21.
Ironically, the only two “relevan[t]” metrics that the Court does
identify are “how and why” a gun control regulation “burden[s the]
right to armed self-defense.” Ante, at 20. In other words,
the Court believes that the most relevant metrics of comparison are
a regulation’s means (how) and ends (why)—even as it rejects the
utility of means-end scrutiny.
What the Court offers instead is a laundry list
of reasons to discount seemingly relevant historical evidence. The
Court believes that some historical laws and decisions cannot
justify upholding modern regulations because, it says, they were
outliers. It explains that just two court decisions or three
colonial laws are not enough to satisfy its test. Ante, at
37, 57. But the Court does not say how many cases or laws would
suffice “to show a tradition of public-carry regulation.” Ante, at 37. Other laws are irrelevant, the Court claims,
because they are too dissimilar from New York’s concealed-carry
licensing regime. See, e.g., ante, at 48–49. But the Court
does not say what “representative historical analogue,” short of a
“twin” or a “dead ringer,” would suffice. See ante, at 21
(emphasis deleted). Indeed, the Court offers many and varied
reasons to reject potential representative analogues, but very few
reasons to accept them. At best, the numerous justifications that
the Court finds for rejecting historical evidence give judges ample
tools to pick their friends out of history’s crowd. At worst, they
create a one-way ratchet that will disqualify virtually any
“representative historical analogue” and make it nearly impossible
to sustain common-sense regulations necessary to our Nation’s
safety and security.
Third, even under ideal conditions, historical
evidence will often fail to provide clear answers to difficult
questions. As an initial matter, many aspects of the history of
firearms and their regulation are ambiguous, contradictory, or
disputed. Unsurprisingly, the extent to which colonial statutes
enacted over 200 years ago were actually enforced, the basis for an
acquittal in a 17th-century decision, and the interpretation of
English laws from the Middle Ages (to name just a few examples) are
often less than clear. And even historical experts may reach
conflicting conclusions based on the same sources. Compare, e.g., P. Charles, The Faces of the Second Amendment Outside
the Home: History Versus Ahistorical Standards of Review, 60 Clev.
St. L. Rev. 1, 14 (2012), with J. Malcolm, To Keep and Bear Arms:
The Origins of an Anglo-American Right 104 (1994). As a result,
history, as much as any other interpretive method, leaves ample
discretion to “loo[k] over the heads of the [crowd] for one’s
friends.” A. Scalia & B. Garner, Reading Law: The
Interpretation of Legal Texts 377 (2012).
Fourth, I fear that history will be an
especially inadequate tool when it comes to modern cases presenting
modern problems. Consider the Court’s apparent preference for
founding-era regulation. See ante, at 25–28. Our country
confronted profoundly different problems during that time period
than it does today. Society at the founding was “predominantly
rural.” C. McKirdy, Misreading the Past: The Faulty Historical
Basis Behind the Supreme Court’s Decision in District of Columbia
v. Heller, 45 Capital U. L. Rev. 107, 151 (2017). In 1790,
most of America’s relatively small population of just four million
people lived on farms or in small towns. Ibid. Even New York
City, the largest American city then, as it is now, had a
population of just 33,000 people. Ibid. Small founding-era
towns are unlikely to have faced the same degrees and types of
risks from gun violence as major metropolitan areas do today, so
the types of regulations they adopted are unlikely to address
modern needs. Id., at 152 (“For the most part, a population
living on farms and in very small towns did not create conditions
in which firearms created a significant danger to the public
welfare”); see also supra, at 8–9.
This problem is all the more acute when it comes
to “modern-day circumstances that [the Framers] could not have
anticipated.” Heller , 554 U. S., at 721–722 (Breyer,
J., dissenting). How can we expect laws and cases that are over a
century old to dictate the legality of regulations targeting “ghost
guns” constructed with the aid of a three-dimensional printer? See, e.g., White House Briefing Room, FACT SHEET: The Biden
Administration Cracks Down on Ghost Guns, Ensures That ATF Has the
Leadership It Needs To Enforce Our Gun Laws (Apr. 11, 2022),
https:// whitehouse.gov/briefing-room/statements-releases/2022/
04/11 /fact-sheet-the-biden-administration-cracks-down-on-ghost-guns-ensures-that-atf-has-the-leadership-it-needs-to-enforce-our-gun-laws/.
Or modern laws requiring all gun shops to offer smart guns, which
can only be fired by authorized users? See, e.g., N. J.
Stat. Ann. §2C:58–2.10(a) (West Cum. Supp. 2022). Or laws imposing
additional criminal penalties for the use of bullets capable of
piercing body armor? See, e.g., 18 U. S. C.
§§921(a)(17)(B), 929(a).
The Court’s answer is that judges will simply
have to employ “analogical reasoning.” Ante, at 19–20. But,
as I explained above, the Court does not provide clear guidance on
how to apply such reasoning. Even seemingly straightforward
historical restrictions on firearm use may prove surprisingly
difficult to apply to modern circumstances. The Court affirms Heller ’s recognition that States may forbid public carriage
in “sensitive places.” Ante, at 21–22. But what, in
21st-century New York City, may properly be considered a sensitive
place? Presumably “legislative assemblies, polling places, and
courthouses,” which the Court tells us were among the “relatively
few” places “where weapons were altogether prohibited” in the 18th
and 19th centuries. Ante, at 21. On the other hand, the
Court also tells us that “expanding the category of ‘sensitive
places’ simply to all places of public congregation that are not
isolated from law enforcement defines th[at] category
. . . far too broadly.” Ante, at 22. So where does
that leave the many locations in a modern city with no obvious
18th- or 19th-century analogue? What about subways, nightclubs,
movie theaters, and sports stadiums? The Court does not say.
Although I hope—fervently—that future courts
will be able to identify historical analogues supporting the
validity of regulations that address new technologies, I fear that
it will often prove difficult to identify analogous technological
and social problems from Medieval England, the founding era, or the
time period in which the Fourteenth Amendment was ratified. Laws
addressing repeating crossbows, launcegays, dirks, dagges, skeines,
stilladers, and other ancient weapons will be of little help to
courts confronting modern problems. And as technological progress
pushes our society ever further beyond the bounds of the Framers’
imaginations, attempts at “analogical reasoning” will become
increasingly tortured. In short, a standard that relies solely on
history is unjustifiable and unworkable.
IV
Indeed, the Court’s application of its
history-only test in this case demonstrates the very pitfalls
described above. The historical evidence reveals a 700-year
Anglo-American tradition of regulating the public carriage of
firearms in general, and concealed or concealable firearms in
particular. The Court spends more than half of its opinion trying
to discredit this tradition. But, in my view, the robust evidence
of such a tradition cannot be so easily explained away. Laws
regulating the public carriage of weapons existed in England as
early as the 13th century and on this Continent since before the
founding. Similar laws remained on the books through the
ratifications of the Second and Fourteenth Amendments through to
the present day. Many of those historical regulations imposed
significantly stricter restrictions on public carriage than New
York’s licensing requirements do today. Thus, even applying the
Court’s history-only analysis, New York’s law must be upheld
because “historical precedent from before, during, and
. . . after the founding evinces a comparable tradition
of regulation.” Ante, at 18 (majority opinion) (internal
quotation marks omitted).
A. England.
The right codified by the Second Amendment was
“ ‘inherited from our English ancestors.’ ” Heller , 554 U. S., at 599 (quoting Robertson v. Baldwin , 165 U.S.
275 , 281 (1897)); see also ante, at 30 (majority
opinion). And some of England’s earliest laws regulating the public
carriage of weapons were precursors of similar American laws
enacted roughly contemporaneously with the ratification of the
Second Amendment. See infra, at 40–42. I therefore begin, as
the Court does, ante, at 30–31, with the English ancestors
of New York’s laws regulating public carriage of firearms.
The relevant English history begins in the
late-13th and early-14th centuries, when Edward I and Edward II
issued a series of orders to local sheriffs that prohibited any
person from “going armed.” See 4 Calendar of the Close Rolls,
Edward I, 1296–1302, p. 318 (Sept. 15, 1299) (1906); id., at
588 (July 16, 1302); 5 id ., Edward I, 1302–1307, at 210
(June 10, 1304) (1908); id ., Edward II, 1307–1313, at 52
(Feb. 9, 1308) (1892); id., at 257 (Apr. 9, 1310); id., at 553 (Oct. 12, 1312); id ., Edward II,
1323–1327, at 560 (Apr. 28, 1326) (1898); 1 Calendar of Plea and
Memoranda Rolls of the City of London, 1323–1364, p. 15 (Nov. 1326)
(A. Thomas ed. 1926). Violators were subject to punishment,
including “forfeiture of life and limb.” See, e.g., 4
Calendar of the Close Rolls, Edward I, 1296–1302, at 318 (Sept. 15,
1299) (1906). Many of these royal edicts contained exemptions for
persons who had obtained “the king’s special licence.” See ibid. ; 5 id ., Edward I, 1302–1307, at 210 (June 10,
1304); id ., Edward II, 1307–1313, at 553 (Oct. 12, 1312); id. , Edward II, 1323–1327, at 560 (Apr. 28, 1326). Like New
York’s law, these early edicts prohibited public carriage absent
special governmental permission and enforced that prohibition on
pain of punishment.
The Court seems to suggest that these early
regulations are irrelevant because they were enacted during a time
of “turmoil” when “malefactors . . . harried the country,
committing assaults and murders.” Ante, at 31 (internal
quotation marks omitted). But it would seem to me that what the
Court characterizes as a “right of armed self-defense” would be
more, rather than less, necessary during a time of “turmoil.” Ante, at 20. The Court also suggests that laws that were
enacted before firearms arrived in England, like these early edicts
and the subsequent Statute of Northampton, are irrelevant. Ante, at 32. But why should that be? Pregun regulations
prohibiting “going armed” in public illustrate an entrenched
tradition of restricting public carriage of weapons. That tradition
seems as likely to apply to firearms as to any other lethal
weapons—particularly if we follow the Court’s instruction to use
analogical reasoning. See ante, at 19–20. And indeed, as we
shall shortly see, the most significant prefirearm regulation of
public carriage—the Statute of Northampton—was in fact applied to
guns once they appeared in England. See Sir John Knight’s
Case , 3 Mod. 117, 87 Eng. Rep. 75, 76 (K. B. 1686)
The Statute of Northampton was enacted in 1328.
2 Edw. 3, 258, c. 3. By its terms, the statute made it a criminal
offense to carry arms without the King’s authorization. It provided
that, without such authorization, “no Man great nor small, of what
Condition soever he be,” could “go nor ride armed by night nor by
day, in Fairs, Markets, nor in the presence of the Justices or
other Ministers, nor in no part elsewhere, upon pain to forfeit
their Armour to the King, and their Bodies to Prison at the King’s
pleasure.” Ibid. For more than a century following its
enactment, England’s sheriffs were routinely reminded to strictly
enforce the Statute of Northampton against those going armed
without the King’s permission. See Calendar of the Close Rolls,
Edward III, 1330–1333, at 131 (Apr. 3, 1330) (1898); 1 Calendar of
the Close Rolls, Richard II, 1377–1381, at 34 (Dec. 1, 1377)
(1914); 2 id ., Richard II, 1381–1385, at 3 (Aug. 7, 1381)
(1920); 3 id ., Richard II, 1385–1389, at 128 (Feb. 6, 1386)
(1921); id., at 399–400 (May 16, 1388); 4 id ., Henry
VI, 1441–1447, at 224 (May 12, 1444) (1937); see also 11 Tudor
Royal Proclamations, The Later Tudors: 1553–1587, pp. 442–445
(Proclamation 641, 21 Elizabeth I, July 26, 1579) (P. Hughes &
J. Larkin eds. 1969).
The Court thinks that the Statute of Northampton
“has little bearing on the Second Amendment,” in part because it
was “enacted . . . more than 450 years before the
ratification of the Constitution.” Ante, at 32. The statute,
however, remained in force for hundreds of years, well into the
18th century. See 4 W. Blackstone, Commentaries 148–149 (1769)
(“The offence of riding or going armed , with
dangerous or unusual weapons, is a crime against the public peace,
by terrifying the good people of the land; and is particularly
prohibited by the Statute of Northampton ” (first emphasis in
original, second emphasis added)). It was discussed in the writings
of Blackstone, Coke, and others. See ibid. ; W. Hawkins, 1
Pleas of the Crown 135 (1716) (Hawkins); E. Coke, The Third Part of
the Institutes of the Laws of England 160 (1797). And several
American Colonies and States enacted restrictions modeled on the
statute. See infra, at 40–42. There is thus every reason to
believe that the Framers of the Second Amendment would have
considered the Statute of Northampton a significant chapter in the
Anglo-American tradition of firearms regulation.
The Court also believes that, by the end of the
17th century, the Statute of Northampton was understood to contain
an extratextual intent element: the intent to cause terror in
others. Ante, at 34–38, 41. The Court relies on two sources
that arguably suggest that view: a 1686 decision, Sir John
Knight’s Case , and a 1716 treatise written by Serjeant William
Hawkins. Ante, at 34–37. But other sources suggest that
carrying arms in public was prohibited because it naturally
tended to terrify the people. See, e.g., M. Dalton, The
Country Justice 282–283 (1690) (“[T]o wear Armor, or Weapons not
usually worn, . . . seems also be a breach, or means of
breach of the Peace . . . ; for they strike a fear
and terror in the People” (emphasis added)). According to these
sources, terror was the natural consequence—not an additional
element—of the crime.
I find this view more persuasive in large part
because it is not entirely clear that the two sources the Court
relies on actually support the existence of an intent-to-terrify
requirement. Start with Sir John Knight’s Case , which,
according to the Court, considered Knight’s arrest for walking
“ ‘about the streets’ ” and into a church “ ‘armed
with guns.’ ” Ante, at 34 (quoting Sir John Knight’s
Case , 3 Mod. 117, 87 Eng. Rep., at 76). The Court thinks that
Knight’s acquittal by a jury demonstrates that the Statute of
Northampton only prohibited public carriage of firearms with an
intent to terrify. Ante, at 34–35. But by now the legal
significance of Knight’s acquittal is impossible to reconstruct.
Brief for Patrick J. Charles as Amicus Curiae 23, n. 9. The
primary source describing the case (the English Reports) was
notoriously incomplete at the time Sir John Knight’s Case was decided. Id., at 24–25. And the facts that historians
can reconstruct do not uniformly support the Court’s
interpretation. The King’s Bench required Knight to pay a surety to
guarantee his future good behavior, so it may be more accurate to
think of the case as having ended in “a conditional pardon” than
acquittal. Young , 992 F. 3d, at 791; see also Rex v. Sir John Knight , 1 Comb. 40, 90 Eng.
Rep. 331 (K. B. 1686). And, notably, it appears that Knight based
his defense on his loyalty to the Crown, not a lack of intent to
terrify. 3 The Entring Book of Roger Morrice 1677–1691: The Reign
of James II, 1685–1687, pp. 307–308 (T. Harris ed. 2007).
Similarly, the passage from the Hawkins treatise
on which the Court relies states that the Statute of Northampton’s
prohibition on the public carriage of weapons did not apply to the
“wearing of Arms . . . unless it be accompanied with such
Circumstances as are apt to terrify the People.” Hawkins 136. But
Hawkins goes on to enumerate relatively narrow circumstances where
this exception applied: when “Persons of Quality . . .
wea[r] common Weapons, or hav[e] their usual Number of Attendants
with them, for their Ornament or Defence, in such Places, and upon
such Occasions, in which it is the common Fashion to make use of
them,” or to persons merely wearing “privy Coats of Mail.” Ibid . It would make little sense if a narrow exception for
nobility, see Oxford English Dictionary (3d ed., Dec. 2012),
https://www.oed.com/view/Entry/155878 (defining “quality,”
A.I.5.a), and “privy coats of mail” were allowed to swallow the
broad rule that Hawkins (and other commentators of his time)
described elsewhere. That rule provided that “there may be an
Affray where there is no actual Violence; as where a Man arms
himself with dangerous and unusual Weapons, in such a Manner as
will naturally cause a Terror to the People, which is
. . . strictly prohibited by [the Statute of
Northampton].” Hawkins 135. And it provided no exception for those
who attempted to “excuse the wearing such Armour in Publick, by
alleging that . . . he wears it for the Safety of his
Person from . . . Assault.” Id., at 136. In my
view, that rule announces the better reading of the Statute of
Northampton—as a broad prohibition on the public carriage of
firearms and other weapons, without an intent-to-terrify
requirement or exception for self-defense.
Although the Statute of Northampton is
particularly significant because of its breadth, longevity, and
impact on American law, it was far from the only English
restriction on firearms or their carriage. See, e.g., 6 Hen.
8 c. 13, §1 (1514) (restricting the use and ownership of handguns);
25 Hen. 8 c. 17, §1 (1533) (same); 33 Hen. 8 c. 6, §§1–2 (1541)
(same); 25 Edw. 3, st. 5, c. 2 (1350) (making it a “Felony or
Trespass” to “ride armed covertly or secretly with Men of Arms
against any other, to slay him, or rob him, or take him, or retain
him till he hath made Fine or Ransom for to have his Deliverance”)
(brackets and footnote omitted). Whatever right to bear arms we
inherited from our English forebears, it was qualified by a robust
tradition of public carriage regulations.
As I have made clear, I am not a historian. But
if the foregoing facts, which historians and other scholars have
presented to us, are even roughly correct, it is difficult to see
how the Court can believe that English history fails to support
legal restrictions on the public carriage of firearms.
B. The Colonies.
The American Colonies continued the English
tradition of regulating public carriage on this side of the
Atlantic. In 1686, the colony of East New Jersey passed a law
providing that “no person or persons . . . shall presume
privately to wear any pocket pistol, skeines, stilladers, daggers
or dirks, or other unusual or unlawful weapons within this
Province.” An Act Against Wearing Swords, &c., ch. 9, in
Grants, Concessions, and Original Constitutions of the Province of
New Jersey 290 (2d ed. 1881). East New Jersey also specifically
prohibited “planter[s]” from “rid[ing] or go[ing] armed with sword,
pistol, or dagger.” Ibid . Massachusetts Bay and New
Hampshire followed suit in 1692 and 1771, respectively, enacting
laws that, like the Statute of Northampton, provided that those who
went “armed Offensively” could be punished. An Act for the
Punishing of Criminal Offenders, 1692 Mass. Acts and Laws no. 6,
pp. 11–12; An Act for the Punishing of Criminal Offenders, 1771
N. H. Acts and Laws ch. 6, §5, p. 17.
It is true, as the Court points out, that these
laws were only enacted in three colonies. Ante, at 37. But
that does not mean that they may be dismissed as outliers. They
were successors to several centuries of comparable laws in England,
see supra, at 34–40, and predecessors to numerous similar
(in some cases, materially identical) laws enacted by the States
after the founding, see infra, at 41–42. And while it may be
true that these laws applied only to “dangerous and unusual
weapons,” see ante, at 38 (majority opinion), that category
almost certainly included guns, see Charles, 60 Clev. St.
L. Rev., at 34, n. 181 (listing 18th century sources
defining “ ‘offensive weapons’ ” to include “ ‘Fire
Arms’ ” and “ ‘Guns’ ”); State v. Huntly , 25 N. C. 418, 422 (1843)
( per curiam ) (“A gun is an ‘unusual weapon,’ wherewith
to be armed and clad”). Finally, the Court points out that New
Jersey’s ban on public carriage applied only to certain people or
to the concealed carriage of certain smaller firearms. Ante, at 39–40. But the Court’s refusal to credit the relevance of East
New Jersey’s law on this basis raises a serious question about
what, short of a “twin” or a “dead ringer,” qualifies as a relevant
historical analogue. See ante, at 21 (majority opinion)
(emphasis deleted).
C. The Founding Era.
The tradition of regulations restricting
public carriage of firearms, inherited from England and adopted by
the Colonies, continued into the founding era. Virginia, for
example, enacted a law in 1786 that, like the Statute of
Northampton, prohibited any person from “go[ing] nor rid[ing] armed
by night nor by day, in fairs or markets, or in other places, in
terror of the Country.” 1786 Va. Acts, ch. 21. And, as the Court
acknowledges, “public-carry restrictions proliferate[d]” after the
Second Amendment’s ratification five years later in 1791. Ante, at 42. Just a year after that, North Carolina enacted
a law whose language was lifted from the Statute of Northampton
virtually verbatim (vestigial references to the King included).
Collection of Statutes, pp. 60–61, ch. 3 (F. Martin ed. 1792).
Other States passed similar laws in the late-18th and 19th
centuries. See, e.g., 1795 Mass. Acts and Laws ch. 2, p.
436; 1801 Tenn. Acts pp. 260–261; 1821 Me. Laws p. 285; see also
Charles, 60 Clev. St. L. Rev., at 40, n. 213 (collecting
sources).
The Court discounts these laws primarily because
they were modeled on the Statute of Northampton, which it believes
prohibited only public carriage with the intent to terrify. Ante, at 41. I have previously explained why I believe that
preventing public terror was one reason that the Statute of
Northampton prohibited public carriage, but not an element of the crime. See supra, at 37–39. And, consistent with that
understanding, American regulations modeled on the Statute of
Northampton appear to have been understood to set forth a broad
prohibition on public carriage of firearms without any
intent-to-terrify requirement. See Charles, 60 Clev. St.
L. Rev., at 35, 37–41; J. Haywood, A Manual of the Laws of
North-Carolina, pt. 2, p. 40 (3d ed.1814); J. Ewing, The Office and
Duty of a Justice of the Peace 546 (1805).
The Court cites three cases considering
common-law offenses, ante, at 42–44, but those cases do not
support the view that only public carriage in a manner likely to
terrify violated American successors to the Statute of Northampton.
If anything, they suggest that public carriage of firearms was not
common practice. At least one of the cases the Court cites, State v. Huntly , wrote that the Statute of
Northampton codified a pre-existing common-law offense, which
provided that “riding or going armed with dangerous or unusual
weapons, is a crime against the public peace, by terrifying
the good people of the land.” 25 N. C., at 420–421 (quoting 4
Blackstone, Commentaries, at 149; emphasis added). Huntly added that “[a] gun is an ‘unusual weapon’ ” and that “[n]o
man amongst us carries it about with him, as one of his every-day
accoutrements—as a part of his dress—and never, we trust, will the
day come when any deadly weapon will be worn or wielded in our
peace-loving and law-abiding State, as an appendage of manly
equipment.” 25 N. C., at 422. True, Huntly recognized
that citizens were nonetheless “at perfect liberty” to carry for
“lawful purpose[s]”—but it specified that those purposes were
“business or amusement.” Id., at 422–423. New York’s law
similarly recognizes that hunting, target shooting, and certain
professional activities are proper causes justifying lawful
carriage of a firearm. See supra, at 12–13. The other two
cases the Court cites for this point similarly offer it only
limited support—either because the atextual intent element the
Court advocates was irrelevant to the decision’s result, see O’Neill v. State , 16 Ala. 65 (1849), or because the
decision adopted an outlier position not reflected in the other
cases cited by the Court, see Simpson v. State , 13
Tenn. 356, 360 (1833); see also ante, at 42–43, 57 (majority
opinion) (refusing to give “a pair of state-court decisions”
“disproportionate weight”). The founding-era regulations—like the
colonial and English laws on which they were modeled—thus
demonstrate a longstanding tradition of broad restrictions on
public carriage of firearms.
D. The 19th Century.
Beginning in the 19th century, States began to
innovate on the Statute of Northampton in at least two ways. First,
many States and Territories passed bans on concealed carriage or on
any carriage, concealed or otherwise, of certain concealable
weapons. For example, Georgia made it unlawful to carry, “unless in
an open manner and fully exposed to view, any pistol, (except
horseman’s pistols,) dirk, sword in a cane, spear, bowie-knife, or
any other kind of knives, manufactured and sold for the purpose of
offence and defence.” Ga. Code §4413 (1861). Other States and
Territories enacted similar prohibitions. See, e.g., Ala.
Code §3274 (1852) (banning, with limited exceptions, concealed
carriage of “a pistol, or any other description of fire arms”); see
also ante, at 44, n. 16 (majority opinion) (collecting
sources). And the Territory of New Mexico appears to have banned
all carriage whatsoever of “any class of pistols whatever,” as well
as “bowie kni[ves,] . . . Arkansas toothpick[s], Spanish
dagger[s], slung-shot[s], or any other deadly weapon.” 1860 Terr.
of N. M. Laws §§1–2, p. 94. These 19th-century bans on
concealed carriage were stricter than New York’s law, for they
prohibited concealed carriage with at most limited exceptions,
while New York permits concealed carriage with a lawfully obtained
license. See supra, at 12. Moreover, as Heller recognized, and the Court acknowledges, “the majority of the
19th-century courts to consider the question held that [these types
of] prohibitions on carrying concealed weapons were lawful under the Second Amendment or state analogues.” 554 U. S., at
626 (emphasis added); see also ante, at 44.
The Court discounts this history because, it
says, courts in four Southern States suggested or held that a ban
on concealed carriage was only lawful if open carriage or carriage
of military pistols was allowed. Ante, at 44–46. (The Court
also cites Bliss v. Commonwealth , 12 Ky. 90 (1822),
which invalidated Kentucky’s concealed-carry prohibition as
contrary to that State’s Second Amendment analogue. Id., at
90–93. Bliss was later overturned by constitutional
amendment and was, as the Court appears to concede, an outlier. See Peruta v. County of San Diego , 824 F.3d 919, 935–936
(CA9 2016); ante, at 45.) Several of these decisions,
however, emphasized States’ leeway to regulate firearms carriage as
necessary “to protect the orderly and well disposed citizens from
the treacherous use of weapons not even designed for any purpose of
public defence.” State v. Smith , 11 La. 633 (1856);
see also Andrews v. State , 50 Tenn. 165, 179–180
(1871) (stating that “the right to keep ” rifles, shotguns,
muskets, and repeaters could not be “ infringed or forbidden ,” but “[t]heir use [may] be subordinated to
such regulations and limitations as are or may be authorized by the
law of the land, passed to subserve the general good, so as not to
infringe the right secured and the necessary incidents to the
exercise of such right”); State v. Reid , 1 Ala. 612,
616 (1840) (recognizing that the constitutional right to bear arms
“necessarily . . . leave[s] with the Legislature the
authority to adopt such regulations of police, as may be dictated
by the safety of the people and the advancement of public morals”).
And other courts upheld concealed-carry restrictions without any
reference to an exception allowing open carriage, so it is far from
clear that the cases the Court cites represent a consensus view.
See State v. Mitchell , 3 Blackf. 229 (Ind. 1833); State v. Buzzard , 4 Ark. 18 (1842). And, of course,
the Court does not say whether the result in this case would be
different if New York allowed open carriage by law-abiding citizens
as a matter of course.
The second 19th-century innovation, adopted in a
number of States, was surety laws. Massachusetts’ surety law, which
served as a model for laws adopted by many other States, provided
that any person who went “armed with a dirk, dagger, sword, pistol,
or other offensive and dangerous weapon,” and who lacked
“reasonable cause to fear an assualt [ sic ],” could be made
to pay a surety upon the “complaint of any person having reasonable
cause to fear an injury, or breach of the peace.” Mass. Rev. Stat.,
ch. 134, §16 (1836). Other States and Territories enacted identical
or substantially similar laws. See, e.g., Me. Rev. Stat.,
ch. 169, §16 (1840); Mich. Rev. Stat., ch. 162, §16 (1846); Terr.
of Minn. Rev. Stat., ch. 112, §18 (1851); 1854 Ore. Stat., ch. 16,
§17; W. Va. Code, ch. 153, §8 (1868); 1862 Pa. Laws p. 250, §6.
These laws resemble New York’s licensing regime in many, though
admittedly not all, relevant respects. Most notably, like New
York’s proper cause requirement, the surety laws conditioned public
carriage in at least some circumstances on a special showing of
need. Compare supra, at 13, with Mass. Rev. Stat., ch. 134,
§16.
The Court believes that the absence of recorded
cases involving surety laws means that they were rarely enforced. Ante, at 49–50. Of course, this may just as well show that
these laws were normally followed. In any case, scholars cited by
the Court tell us that “traditional case law research is not
especially probative of the application of these restrictions”
because “in many cases those records did not survive the passage of
time” or “are not well indexed or digitally searchable.” E. Ruben
& S. Cornell, Firearms Regionalism and Public Carry: Placing
Southern Antebellum Case Law in Context, 125 Yale L. J. Forum 121,
130–131, n. 53 (2015). On the contrary, “the fact that restrictions
on public carry were well accepted in places like Massachusetts and
were included in the relevant manuals for justices of the peace”
suggests “that violations were enforced at the justice of peace
level, but did not result in expensive appeals that would have
produced searchable case law.” Id ., at 131, n. 53 (citation
omitted). The surety laws and broader bans on concealed carriage
enacted in the 19th century demonstrate that even relatively
stringent restrictions on public carriage have long been understood
to be consistent with the Second Amendment and its state
equivalents.
E. Postbellum Regulation.
After the Civil War, public carriage of
firearms remained subject to extensive regulation. See, e.g., Cong. Globe, 39th Cong., 1st Sess., 908 (1866) (“The
constitutional rights of all loyal and well-disposed inhabitants to
bear arms will not be infringed; nevertheless this shall not be
construed to sanction the unlawful practice of carrying concealed
weapons”). Of course, during this period, Congress provided (and
commentators recognized) that firearm regulations could not be
designed or enforced in a discriminatory manner. See ibid. ;
Act of July 16, 1866, §14, 14Stat. 176–177 (ensuring that all
citizens were entitled to the “full and equal benefit of all laws
. . . including the constitutional right to keep and bear
arms . . . without respect to race or color, or previous
condition of slavery”); see also The Loyal Georgian, Feb. 3, 1866,
p. 3, col. 4. But that by-now uncontroversial proposition says
little about the validity of nondiscriminatory restrictions on
public carriage, like New York’s.
What is more relevant for our purposes is the
fact that, in the postbellum period, States continued to enact
generally applicable restrictions on public carriage, many of which
were even more restrictive than their predecessors. See S. Cornell
& J. Florence, The Right to Bear Arms in the Era of the
Fourteenth Amendment: Gun Rights or Gun Regulation? 50 Santa Clara
L. Rev. 1043, 1066 (2010). Most notably, many States and Western
Territories enacted stringent regulations that prohibited any public carriage of firearms, with only limited
exceptions. For example, Texas made it a misdemeanor to carry in
public “any pistol, dirk, dagger, slung-shot, sword-cane, spear,
brass-knuckles, bowie-knife, or any other kind of knife
manufactured or sold for the purpose of offense or defense” absent
“reasonable grounds for fearing an [immediate and pressing]
unlawful attack.” 1871 Tex. Gen. Laws ch. 34, §1. Similarly, New
Mexico made it “unlawful for any person to carry deadly weapons,
either concealed or otherwise, on or about their persons within any
of the settlements of this Territory.” 1869 Terr. of N. M.
Laws ch. 32, §1. New Mexico’s prohibition contained only narrow
exceptions for carriage on a person’s own property, for
self-defense in the face of immediate danger, or with official
authorization. Ibid. Other States and Territories adopted
similar laws. See, e.g., 1875 Wyo. Terr. Sess. Laws ch. 52,
§1; 1889 Idaho Terr. Gen. Laws §1, p. 23; 1881 Kan. Sess. Laws
§23, p. 92; 1889 Ariz. Terr. Sess. Laws no. 13, §1, p. 16.
When they were challenged, these laws were
generally upheld. P. Charles, The Faces of the Second Amendment
Outside the Home, Take Two: How We Got Here and Why It Matters, 64
Clev. St. L. Rev. 373, 414 (2016); see also ante, at 56–57
(majority opinion) (recognizing that postbellum Texas law and court
decisions support the validity of New York’s licensing regime); Andrews , 50 Tenn., at 182 (recognizing that “a man may well
be prohibited from carrying his arms to church, or other public
assemblage,” and that the carriage of arms other than rifles, shot
guns, muskets, and repeaters “may be prohibited if the Legislature
deems proper, absolutely, at all times, and under all
circumstances”).
The Court’s principal answer to these broad
prohibitions on public carriage is to discount gun control laws
passed in the American West. Ante, at 58–61. It notes that
laws enacted in the Western Territories were “rarely subject to
judicial scrutiny.” Ante, at 60. But, of course, that may
well mean that “[w]e . . . can assume it settled that
these” regulations were “consistent with the Second Amendment.” See ante, at 21 (majority opinion). The Court also reasons that
laws enacted in the Western Territories applied to a relatively
small portion of the population and were comparatively short lived.
See ante, 59–61. But even assuming that is true, it does not
mean that these laws were historical aberrations. To the contrary,
bans on public carriage in the American West and elsewhere
constitute just one chapter of the centuries-old tradition of
comparable firearms regulations described above.
F. The 20th Century.
The Court disregards “20th-century historical
evidence.” Ante, at 58, n. 28. But it is worth noting
that the law the Court strikes down today is well over 100 years
old, having been enacted in 1911 and amended to substantially its
present form in 1913. See supra, at 12. That alone gives it
a longer historical pedigree than at least three of the four types
of firearms regulations that Heller identified as
“presumptively lawful.” 554 U. S., at 626–627, and n. 26;
see C. Larson, Four Exceptions in Search of a Theory: District
of Columbia v. Heller and Judicial Ipse Dixit , 60
Hastings L. J. 1371, 1374–1379 (2009) (concluding that
“ ‘prohibitions on the possession of firearms by felons and
the mentally ill [and] laws imposing conditions and qualifications
on the commercial sale of arms’ ” have their origins in the
20th century); Kanter v. Barr , 919 F.3d 437, 451 (CA7
2019) (Barrett, J., dissenting) (“Founding-era legislatures did not
strip felons of the right to bear arms simply because of their
status as felons”). Like Justice Kavanaugh, I understand the
Court’s opinion today to cast no doubt on that aspect of Heller ’s holding. Ante, at 3 (concurring opinion).
But unlike Justice Kavanaugh, I find the disconnect between Heller ’s treatment of laws prohibiting, for example,
firearms possession by felons or the mentally ill, and the Court’s
treatment of New York’s licensing regime, hard to square. The
inconsistency suggests that the Court today takes either an
unnecessarily cramped view of the relevant historical record or a
needlessly rigid approach to analogical reasoning.
* * *
The historical examples of regulations similar
to New York’s licensing regime are legion. Closely analogous
English laws were enacted beginning in the 13th century, and
similar American regulations were passed during the colonial
period, the founding era, the 19th century, and the 20th century.
Not all of these laws were identical to New York’s, but that is
inevitable in an analysis that demands examination of seven
centuries of history. At a minimum, the laws I have recounted resembled New York’s law, similarly restricting the right to
publicly carry weapons and serving roughly similar purposes. That
is all that the Court’s test, which allows and even encourages
“analogical reasoning,” purports to require. See ante, at 21
(disclaiming the necessity of a “historical twin ”).
In each instance, the Court finds a reason to
discount the historical evidence’s persuasive force. Some of the
laws New York has identified are too old. But others are too
recent. Still others did not last long enough. Some applied to too
few people. Some were enacted for the wrong reasons. Some may have
been based on a constitutional rationale that is now impossible to
identify. Some arose in historically unique circumstances. And some
are not sufficiently analogous to the licensing regime at issue
here. But if the examples discussed above, taken together, do not
show a tradition and history of regulation that supports the
validity of New York’s law, what could? Sadly, I do not know the
answer to that question. What is worse, the Court appears to have
no answer either.
V
We are bound by Heller insofar as Heller interpreted the Second Amendment to protect an
individual right to possess a firearm for self-defense. But Heller recognized that that right was not without limits and
could appropriately be subject to government regulation . 554
U. S., at 626–627. Heller therefore does not require
holding that New York’s law violates the Second Amendment. In so
holding, the Court goes beyond Heller .
It bases its decision to strike down New York’s
law almost exclusively on its application of what it calls
historical “analogical reasoning.” Ante, at 19–20. As I have
admitted above, I am not a historian, and neither is the Court. But
the history, as it appears to me, seems to establish a robust
tradition of regulations restricting the public carriage of
concealed firearms. To the extent that any uncertainty remains
between the Court’s view of the history and mine, that uncertainty
counsels against relying on history alone. In my view, it is
appropriate in such circumstances to look beyond the history and
engage in what the Court calls means-end scrutiny. Courts must be
permitted to consider the State’s interest in preventing gun
violence, the effectiveness of the contested law in achieving that
interest, the degree to which the law burdens the Second Amendment
right, and, if appropriate, any less restrictive alternatives.
The Second Circuit has previously done just
that, and it held that New York’s law does not violate the Second
Amendment. See Kachalsky , 701 F. 3d, at 101. It first
evaluated the degree to which the law burdens the Second Amendment
right to bear arms. Id., at 93–94. It concluded that the law
“places substantial limits on the ability of law-abiding citizens
to possess firearms for self-defense in public,” but does not
burden the right to possess a firearm in the home, where Heller said “ ‘the need for defense of self, family,
and property is most acute.’ ” Kachalsky , 701
F. 3d, at 93–94 (quoting Heller, 554 U. S., at
628). The Second Circuit therefore determined that the law should
be subject to heightened scrutiny, but not to strict scrutiny and
its attendant presumption of unconstitutionality. 701 F. 3d, at
93–94. In applying such heightened scrutiny, the Second Circuit
recognized that “New York has substantial, indeed compelling,
governmental interests in public safety and crime prevention.” Id., at 97. I agree. As I have demonstrated above, see supra, at 3–9, firearms in public present a number of
dangers, ranging from mass shootings to road rage killings, and are
responsible for many deaths and injuries in the United States. The
Second Circuit then evaluated New York’s law and concluded that it
is “substantially related” to New York’s compelling interests. Kachalsky , 701 F. 3d, at 98–99. To support that
conclusion, the Second Circuit pointed to “studies and data
demonstrating that widespread access to handguns in public
increases the likelihood that felonies will result in death and
fundamentally alters the safety and character of public spaces.” Id., at 99. We have before us additional studies confirming
that conclusion. See, e.g., supra, at 19–20
(summarizing studies finding that “may issue” licensing regimes are
associated with lower rates of violent crime than “shall issue”
regimes). And we have been made aware of no less restrictive, but
equally effective, alternative. After considering all of these
factors, the Second Circuit held that New York’s law does not
unconstitutionally burden the right to bear arms under the Second
Amendment. I would affirm that holding.
New York’s Legislature considered the empirical
evidence about gun violence and adopted a reasonable licensing law
to regulate the concealed carriage of handguns in order to keep the
people of New York safe. The Court today strikes down that law
based only on the pleadings. It gives the State no opportunity to
present evidence justifying its reasons for adopting the law or
showing how the law actually operates in practice, and it does not
so much as acknowledge these important considerations. Because I
cannot agree with the Court’s decision to strike New York’s law
down without allowing for discovery or the development of any
evidentiary record, without considering the State’s compelling
interest in preventing gun violence and protecting the safety of
its citizens, and without considering the potentially deadly
consequences of its decision, I respectfully dissent. | The Supreme Court ruled that the Second and Fourteenth Amendments protect an individual's right to carry a handgun for self-defense outside the home, striking down New York's law requiring a special need for a public-carry license as a violation of the Constitution. |
Lawsuits & Legal Procedures | Capron v. Van Noorden | https://supreme.justia.com/cases/federal/us/6/126/ | U.S. Supreme Court CAPRON
v. VAN NOORDEN, 6 U.S. 126 (1804) 6 U.S. 126 (Cranch) CAPRON v. VAN NOORDEN. February Term, 1804 Harper,
for the plaintiff in error, stated the only question to be whether
the plaintiff had a right to assign for error, the want of
jurisdiction in that Court to which he had chosen to resort. ERROR to the Circuit Court of North-Carolina. The proceedings
stated Van Noorden to be late of Pitt county, but did not allege
Capron, the plaintiff, to be an alien, nor a citizen of any state,
nor the place of his residence. Upon the general issue, in an action of trespass on the case, a
verdict was found for the defendant, Van Noorden, upon which
judgment was rendered. The writ of Error was sued out by Capron, the plaintiff below, who
assigned for error, among other things, first "That the circuit
court aforesaid is a court "of limited jurisdiction, and that by
the record aforesaid "it doth not appear, as it ought to have done,
that "either the said George Capron, or the said Hadrianus " Van
Noorden was an alien at the time of the commencement "of said suit,
or at any other time, or that one of "the said parties was at that
or any other time, a citizen "of the state of North-Carolina where
the suit was "brought, and the other a citizen of another state; or
"that they the said George and Hadrianus were for "any cause
whatever, persons within the jurisdiction of "the said court, and
capable of suing and being sued "there." And secondly, "That by the record aforesaid it manifestly
"appeareth that the said Circuit Court had not "any jurisdiction of
the cause aforesaid, nor ought to "have held plea thereof, or given
judgment therein, but "ought to have dismissed the same, whereas
the said "Court hath proceeded to final judgment therein." It is true, as a general rule, that a man cannot reverse a judgment
for error in process or delay, unless he can shew that the error
was to his disadvantage; but it is also a rule, that he may reverse
a judgment for an error of the Court, even though it be for his
advantage. As if a verdict be found for the debt, damages, and
costs; and the judgment be only for the debt and damages, the
defendant may assign for error that the judgment was not also for
costs, although the error is for his advantage. Here it was the duty of the Court to see that they had
jurisdiction, for the consent of parties could not give it. It is therefore an error of the Court, and the plaintiff has a
right to take advantage of it. 2 Bac. Ab. Tit. Error. (K. 4.) — 8
Co. 59. (a) Beecher's case. — 1 Roll. Ab. 759. — Moor 692. — 1 Lev.
289. Bernard v. Bernard. The defendant in error did not appear, but the citation having been
duly served, the judgment was reversed. | The U.S. Supreme Court case Capron v. Van Noorden (1804) centered on the question of whether a plaintiff could assign error based on a lack of jurisdiction in the chosen court. The case involved a writ of error from the plaintiff, Capron, who sought to challenge the judgment of the Circuit Court of North Carolina in an action of trespass.
The Court held that a party could reverse a judgment for an error in the court's jurisdiction, even if the error was advantageous to them. In this case, the Circuit Court's failure to establish jurisdiction over the parties, regardless of their consent, was an error that the plaintiff had the right to raise.
The defendant in error did not appear, and the judgment was reversed. |
Immigration & National Security | Elk v. Wilkins | https://supreme.justia.com/cases/federal/us/112/94/ | U.S. Supreme Court Elk v. Wilkins, 112 U.S.
94 (1884) Elk v. Wilkins Argued April 28, 1884 Decided November 3,
1884 112 U.S.
94 I N ERROR TO THE CIRCUIT COURT OF THE
UNITED STATES FOR THE DISTRICT OF
NEBRASKA Syllabus An Indian, born a member of one of the Indian tribes within the
United States, which still exists and is recognized as a tribe by
the government of the United States, who has voluntarily separated
himself from his tribe, and taken up his residence among the white
citizens of a state, but who has not been naturalized, or taxed, or
recognized as a citizen either by the United States or by the
state, is not a citizen of the United States within the meaning of
the first section of the Fourteenth Article of Amendment of the
Constitution.
A petition alleging that the plaintiff is an Indian, and was
born within the United States, and has severed his tribal relation
to the Indian tribes, and fully and completely surrendered himself
to the jurisdiction of the United States, and still so continues
subject to the jurisdiction of the United States, and is a bona
fide resident of the Nebraska and City of Omaha, does not show
that he is a citizen of the United States under the Fourteenth
Article of Amendment of the Constitution.
This is an action brought by an Indian in the Circuit Court of
the United States for the District of Nebraska against the
registrar of one of the wards of the City of Omaha for refusing to
register him as a qualified voter therein. The petition was as
follows:
This is an action brought by an Indian, in the Circuit Court of
the United States for the District of Nebraska, against the
registrar of one of the wards of the City of Omaha, for refusing to
register him as a qualified voter therein. The petition was as
follows: Page 112 U. S. 95 "John Elk, plaintiff, complains of Charles Wilkins, defendant,
and avers that the matter in dispute herein exceeds the sum of five
hundred dollars, to-wit, the sum of six thousand dollars, and that
the matter in dispute herein arises under the Constitution and laws
of the United States, and, for cause of action against the
defendant, avers that he, the plaintiff, is an Indian, and was born
within the United States; that more than one year prior to the
grievances hereinafter complained of he had severed his tribal
relation to the Indian tribes, and had fully and completely
surrendered himself to the jurisdiction of the United States, and
still so continues subject to the jurisdiction of the United
States, and avers that, under and by virtue of the Fourteenth
Amendment to the Constitution of the United States, he is a citizen
of the United States, and entitled to the right and privilege of
citizens of the United States."
"That on the sixth day of April, 1880, there was held in the
City of Omaha (a City of the first class, incorporated under the
general laws of the State of Nebraska, providing for the
incorporation of cities of the first class) a general election for
the election of members of the city council and other officers for
said city."
"That the defendant, Charles Wilkins, held the office of and
acted as registrar in the Fifth Ward of said city, and that as such
registrar it was the duty of such defendant to register the names
of all persons entitled to exercise the elective franchise in said
ward of said city at said general election."
"That this plaintiff was a citizen of and had been a bona
fide resident of the State of Nebraska for more than six
months prior to said sixth day of April, 1880, and had been a bona fide resident of Douglas County, wherein the City of
Omaha is situate, for more than forty days, and in the Fifth Ward
of said city more than ten days prior to the said sixth day of
April, and was such citizen and resident at the time of said
election, and at the time of his attempted registration, as
hereinafter set forth, and was in every way qualified, under the
laws of the State of Nebraska and of the City of Omaha, to be
registered as a voter, and to cast a vote at said election, and
complied with the laws of the city and state in that behalf. " Page 112 U. S. 96 "That on or about the fifth day of April, 1880, and prior to
said election, this plaintiff presented himself to said Charles
Wilkins, as such registrar at his office, for the purpose of having
his name registered as a qualified voter, as provided by law, and
complied with all the provisions of the statutes in that regard,
and claimed that, under the Fourteenth and Fifteenth Amendments to
the Constitution of the United States, he was a citizen of the
United States, and was entitled to exercise the elective franchise,
regardless of his race and color, and that said Wilkins,
designedly, corruptly, willfully, and maliciously, did then and
there refuse to register this plaintiff, for the sole reason that
the plaintiff was an Indian, and therefore not a citizen of the
United States, and not therefore entitled to vote, and on account
of his race and color, and with the willful, malicious, corrupt,
and unlawful design to deprive this plaintiff of his right to vote
at said election, and of his rights, and all other Indians of their
rights, under said Fourteenth and Fifteenth amendments to the
Constitution of the United States, on account of his and their race
and color."
"That on the sixth day of April, this plaintiff presented
himself at the place of voting in said ward, and presented a
ballot, and requested the right to vote, where said Wilkins, who
was then acting as one of the judges of said election in said ward,
in further carrying out his willful and malicious designs as
aforesaid, declared to the plaintiff and to the other election
officers that the plaintiff was an Indian, and not a citizen, and
not entitled to vote, and said judges and clerks of election
refused to receive the vote of the plaintiff, for that he was not
registered as required by law."
"Plaintiff avers the fact to be that by reason of said willful,
unlawful, corrupt, and malicious refusal of said defendant to
register this plaintiff, as provided by law, he was deprived of his
right to vote at said election, to his damage in the sum of
$6,000."
"Wherefore, plaintiff prays judgment against defendant for
$6,000, his damages, with costs of suit."
The defendant filed a general demurrer for the following causes:
1st, that the petition did not state facts sufficient to Page 112 U. S. 97 constitute a cause of action; 2d, that the court had no
jurisdiction of the person of the defendant; 3d, that the court had
no jurisdiction of the subject of the action.
The demurrer was argued before Judge McCrary and Judge Dundy,
and sustained, and, the plaintiff electing to stand by his
petition, judgment was rendered for the defendant, dismissing the
petition, with costs. The plaintiff sued out this writ of
error.
By the Constitution of the State of Nebraska, article 7 section
1,
"Every male person of the age of twenty-one years or upwards,
belonging to either of the following classes, who shall have
resided in the state six months, and in the county, precinct, or
ward for the term provided by law, shall be an elector. First,
citizens of the United States. Second, persons of foreign birth who
shall have declared their intention to become citizens, conformably
to the laws of the United States on the subject of naturalization
at least thirty days prior to an election."
By the statutes of Nebraska, every male person of the age of
twenty-one years or upward, belonging to either of the two classes
so defined in the constitution of the state, who shall have resided
in the state six months, in the county forty days, and in the
precinct, township, or ward ten days, shall be an elector; the
qualifications of electors in the several wards of cities of the
first class (of which Omaha is one) shall be the same as in
precincts; it is the duty of the registrar to enter in the register
of qualified voters the name of every person who applies to him to
be registered, and satisfies him that he is qualified to vote under
the provisions of the election laws of the state, and at all
municipal, as well as county or state elections, the judges of
election are required to check the name, and receive and deposit
the ballot, of any person whose name appears on the register.
Compiled Statutes of Nebraska of 1881, c. 26, § 3; c. 13, § 14; c.
76, §§ 6, 13, 19. Page 112 U. S. 98 MR. JUSTICE GRAY delivered the opinion of the Court. He stated
the facts in the foregoing language, and continued:
The plaintiff, in support of his action, relies on the first
clause of the first section of the Fourteenth Article of Amendment
of the Constitution of the United States, by which
"All persons born or naturalized in the United States, and
subject to the jurisdiction thereof, are citizens of the United
States and of the state wherein they reside,"
and on the Fifteenth Article of Amendment, which provides
that
"The right of citizens of the United States to vote shall not be
denied or abridged by the United States or by any state on account
of race, color, or previous condition of servitude."
This being a suit at common law in which the matter in dispute
exceeds $500, arising under the Constitution of the United States,
the circuit court had jurisdiction of it under the Act of March 3,
1875, c. 137, § 1, even if the parties were citizens of the same
state. 18 Stat. 470; Ames v. Kansas, 111 U.
S. 449 . The judgment of that court, dismissing the
action with costs, must have proceeded upon the merits, for if the
dismissal had been for want of jurisdiction, no costs could have
been awarded. Mayor v.
Cooper , 6 Wall. 247; Mansfield & Coldwater
Railway v. Swan, 111 U. S. 379 . And
the only point argued by the defendant in this Court is whether the
petition sets forth facts enough to constitute a cause of
action.
The decision of this point, as both parties assume in their
briefs, depends upon the question whether the legal conclusion that
under and by virtue of the Fourteenth Amendment of the Constitution
the plaintiff is a citizen of the United States is supported by the
facts alleged in the petition and admitted by the demurrer, to-wit,
the plaintiff is an Indian and was born in the United States and
has severed his tribal relation to the Indian tribes and fully and
completely surrendered himself to the jurisdiction of the United
States, and still continues to be subject to the jurisdiction of
the United States, and is a bona fide resident of the
State of Nebraska and City of Omaha. The petition, while it does
not show of what Indian tribe the plaintiff was a member, yet, by
the allegations that he "is Page 112 U. S. 99 an Indian, and was born within the United States," and that "he
had severed his tribal relations to the Indian tribes," clearly
implies that he was born a member of one of the Indian tribes
within the limits of the United States which still exists and is
recognized as a tribe by the government of the United States.
Though the plaintiff alleges that he "had fully and completely
surrendered himself to the jurisdiction of the United States," he
does not allege that the United States accepted his surrender, or
that he has ever been naturalized, or taxed, or in any way
recognized or treated as a citizen by the state or by the United
States. Nor is it contended by his counsel that there is any
statute or treaty that makes him a citizen.
The question, then, is whether an Indian, born a member of one
of the Indian tribes within the United States, is, merely by reason
of his birth within the United States and of his afterwards
voluntarily separating himself from his tribe and taking up his
residence among white citizens, a citizen of the United States
within the meaning of the first section of the Fourteenth Amendment
of the Constitution. Under the Constitution of the United States as
originally established, "Indians not taxed" were excluded from the
persons according to whose numbers representatives and direct taxes
were apportioned among the several states, and Congress had and
exercised the power to regulate commerce with the Indian tribes,
and the members thereof, whether within or without the boundaries
of one of the states of the Union. The Indian tribes, being within
the territorial limits of the United States, were not, strictly
speaking, foreign states, but they were alien nations, distinct
political communities, with whom the United States might and
habitually did deal as they thought fit, either through treaties
made by the President and Senate or through acts of Congress in the
ordinary forms of legislation. The members of those tribes owed
immediate allegiance to their several tribes, and were not part of
the people of the United States. They were in a dependent
condition, a state of pupilage, resembling that of a ward to his
guardian. Indians and their property, exempt from taxation by
treaty or statute of the United States, could not be taxed Page 112 U. S. 100 by any state. General acts of Congress did not apply to Indians
unless so expressed as to clearly manifest an intention to include
them. Constitution, Article I, Sections 2, 8; Article II, Section
2; Cherokee Nation v.
Georgia , 5 Pet. 1; Worcester
v. Georgia , 6 Pet. 515; United
States v. Rogers , 4 How. 567; United
States v. Holliday , 3 Wall. 407; Case of
the Kansas Indians , 5 Wall. 737; Case of
the New York Indians , 5 Wall. 761; Case of
the Cherokee Tobacco , 11 Wall. 616; United
States v. Whisky, 93 U. S. 188 ; Pennock v. Commissioners, 103 U. S.
44 ; Crow Dog's Case, 109 U.
S. 556 ; Goodell v. Jackson, 20 Johns. 693; Hastings v. Farmer, 4 N.Y. 293.
The alien and dependent condition of the members of the Indian
tribes could not be put off at their own will without the action or
assent of the United States. They were never deemed citizens of the
United States except under explicit provisions of treaty or statute
to that effect either declaring a certain tribe, or such members of
it as chose to remain behind on the removal of the tribe westward,
to be citizens or authorizing individuals of particular tribes to
become citizens on application to a court of the United States for
naturalization and satisfactory proof of fitness for civilized
life, for examples of which see treaties in 1817 and 1835 with the
Cherokees, and in 1820, 1825, and 1830 with the Choctaws, 7 Stat.
159, 211, 236, 335, 483, 488; Wilson v. Wall , 6 Wall. 83; Opinion of Attorney General Taney, 2 Opinions of
Attorneys General 462; in 1855 with the Wyandotts, 10 Stat. 1159; Karrahoo v. Adams, 1 Dillon 344, 346; Gray v.
Coffman, 3 Dillon 393; Hicks v. Butrick, 3 Dillon
413; in 1861 and in March, 1866 with the Pottawatomies, 12 Stat.
1192; 14 Stat. 763; in 1862 with the Ottawas, 12 Stat. 1237; and
the Kickapoos, 13 Stat. 624; and Acts of Congress of March 3, 1839,
c. 83, § 7, concerning the Brothertown Indians, and of March 3,
1843, c. 101 § 7, August 6, 1846, c. 88, and March 3, 1865, c. 127
§ 4, concerning the Stockbridge Indians, 5 Stat. 351, 647; 9 Stat.
55; 13 Stat. 562. See also treaties with the Stockbridge
Indians in 1848 and 1856, 9 Stat. 955; 11 Stat. 667; 7 Opinions of
Attorneys General 746.
Chief Justice Taney, in the passage cited for the plaintiff Page 112 U. S. 101 from his opinion in Scott v.
Sandford , 19 How. 393, 60 U. S. 404 ,
did not affirm or imply that either the Indian tribes, or
individual members of those tribes, had the right, beyond other
foreigners, to become citizens of their own will, without being
naturalized by the United States. His words were:
"They [the Indian tribes] may without doubt, like the subjects
of any foreign government, be naturalized by the authority of
Congress and become citizens of a state and of the United States,
and if an individual should leave his nation or tribe, and take up
his abode among the white population, he would be entitled to all
the rights and privileges which would belong to an emigrant from
any other foreign people."
But an emigrant from any foreign state cannot become a citizen
of the United States without a formal renunciation of his old
allegiance, and an acceptance by the United States of that
renunciation through such form of naturalization as may be required
law.
The distinction between citizenship by birth and citizenship by
naturalization is clearly marked in the provisions of the
Constitution, by which
"No person, except a natural born citizen or a citizen of the
United States at the time of the adoption of this Constitution
shall be eligible to the office of President,"
and "The Congress shall have power to establish an uniform rule
of naturalization." Constitution, Article II, Section 1; Article I,
Section 8. By the Thirteenth Amendment of the Constitution, slavery
was prohibited. The main object of the opening sentence of the
Fourteenth Amendment was to settle the question, upon which there
had been a difference of opinion throughout the country and in this
Court, as to the citizenship of free negroes ( Scott v.
Sandford , 19 How. 393), and to put it beyond doubt
that all persons, white or black, and whether formerly slaves or
not, born or naturalized in the United States, and owing no
allegiance to any alien power, should be citizens of the United
States and of the state in which they reside. Slaughterhouse
Cases , 16 Wall. 36, 83 U. S. 73 ; Strauder v. West Virginia, 100 U.
S. 303 , 100 U. S.
306 .
This section contemplates two sources of citizenship, and two
sources only: birth and naturalization. The persons declared Page 112 U. S. 102 to be citizens are "all persons born or naturalized in the
United States, and subject to the jurisdiction thereof." The
evident meaning of these last words is not merely subject in some
respect or degree to the jurisdiction of the United States, but
completely subject to their political jurisdiction and owing them
direct and immediate allegiance. And the words relate to the time
of birth in the one case, as they do to the time of naturalization
in the other. Persons not thus subject to the jurisdiction of the
United States at the time of birth cannot become so afterwards
except by being naturalized, either individually, as by proceedings
under the naturalization acts, or collectively, as by the force of
a treaty by which foreign territory is acquired.
Indians born within the territorial limits of the United States,
members of and owing immediate allegiance to one of the Indiana
tribes (an alien though dependent power), although in a
geographical sense born in the United States, are no more "born in
the United States and subject to the jurisdiction thereof," within
the meaning of the first section of the Fourteenth Amendment, than
the children of subjects of any foreign government born within the
domain of that government, or the children born within the United
States of ambassadors or other public ministers of foreign
nations.
This view is confirmed by the second section of the Fourteenth
Amendment, which provides that
"Representatives shall be apportioned among the several states
according to their respective numbers, counting the whole number of
persons in each state, excluding Indians not taxed."
Slavery having been abolished, and the persons formerly held as
slaves made citizens, this clauses fixing the apportionment of
representatives has abrogated so much of the corresponding clause
of the original Constitution as counted only three-fifths of such
persons. But Indians not taxed are still excluded from the count
for the reason that they are not citizens. Their absolute exclusion
from the basis of representation in which all other persons are now
included is wholly inconsistent with their being considered
citizens. So the further provision of the second section for a
proportionate Page 112 U. S. 103 reduction of the basis of the representation of any state in
which the right to vote for Presidential electors, representatives
in Congress, or executive or judicial officers or members of the
legislature of a state is denied, except for participation in
rebellion or other crime, to "any of the male inhabitants of such
state, being twenty-one years of age and citizens of the United
States," cannot apply to a denial of the elective franchise to
Indians not taxed, who form no part of the people entitled to
representation.
It is also worthy of remark that the language used about the
same time by the very Congress which framed the Fourteenth
Amendment, in the first section of the Civil Rights Act of April 9,
1866, declaring who shall be citizens of the United States, is "all
persons born in the United States, and not subject to any foreign
power, excluding Indians not taxed." 14 Stat. 27; Rev.Stat. §
1992.
Such Indians, then, not being citizens by birth, can only become
citizens in the second way mentioned in the Fourteenth Amendment,
by being "naturalized in the United States," by or under some
treaty or statute.
The action of the political departments of the government, not
only after the proposal of the amendment by Congress to the states
in June, 1866, but since the proclamation in July, 1868, of its
ratification by the requisite number of states, accords with this
construction.
While the amendment was pending before the legislatures of the
several states, treaties containing provisions for the
naturalization of members of Indian tribes as citizens of the
United States were made on July 4, 1866, with the Delawares, in
1867 with various tribes in Kansas, and with the Pottawatomies, and
in April, 1868, with the Sioux. 14 Stat. 794, 796; 15 Stat. 513,
532, 533, 637.
The treaty of 1867 with the Kansas Indians strikingly
illustrates the principle that no one can become a citizen of a
nation without its consent, and directly contradicts the
supposition that a member of an Indian tribe can at will be
alternately a citizen of the United States and a member of the
tribe.
That treaty not only provided for the naturalization of
members Page 112 U. S. 104 of the Ottawa, Miami, Peoria, and other tribes, and their
families, upon their making declaration before the district court
of the United States of their intention to become citizens, 15
Stat. 517, 520, 521; but, after reciting that some of the
Wyandotts, who had become citizens under the treaty of 1855, were
"unfitted for the responsibilities of citizenship" and enacting
that a register of the whole people of this tribe, resident in
Kansas or elsewhere, should be taken, under the direction of the
Secretary of the Interior, showing the names of "all who declare
their desire to be and remain Indians and in a tribal condition,"
and of incompetents and orphans as described in the treaty of 1855,
and that such persons, and those only, should thereafter constitute
the tribe, it provided that
"No one who has heretofore consented to become a citizen, nor
the wife or children of any such person, shall be allowed to become
members of the tribe except by the free consent of the tribe after
its new organization and unless the agent shall certify that such
party is, through poverty or incapacity, unfit to continue in the
exercise of the responsibilities of citizenship of the United
States and likely to become a public charge."
15 Stat. 514, 516.
Since the ratification of the Fourteenth Amendment, Congress has
passed several acts for naturalizing Indians of certain tribes,
which would have been superfluous if they were, or might become
without any action of the government, citizens of the United
States. By the Act of July 15, 1870, c. 296, § 10, for instance, it
was provided that if at any time thereafter any of the Winnebago
Indians in the State of Minnesota should desire to become citizens
of the United States, they should make application to the District
Court of the United States for the District of Minnesota, and in
open court make the same proof, and take the same oath of
allegiance as is provided by law for the naturalization of aliens,
and should also make proof, to the satisfaction of the court, that
they were sufficiently intelligent and prudent to control their
affairs and interests, that they had adopted the habits of
civilized life, and had for at least five years before been able to
support themselves and their families, and thereupon Page 112 U. S. 105 they should be declared by the court to be citizens of the
United States, the declaration entered of record, and a certificate
thereof given to the applicant, and the Secretary of the Interior,
upon presentation of that certificate, might issue to them patents
in fee simple, with power of alienation, of the lands already held
by them in severalty, and might cause to be paid to them their
proportion of the money and effects of the tribe held in trust
under any treaty or law of the United States, and thereupon such
persons should cease to be members of the tribe, and the lands so
patented to them should be subject to levy, taxation, and sale in
like manner with the property of other citizens. 16 Stat. 361. By
the Act of March 3, 1873, c. 332, § 3, similar provision was made
for the naturalization of any adult members of the Miami tribe in
Kansas, and of their minor children. 17 Stat. 632. And the Act of
March 3, 1865, c. 127, before referred to, making corresponding
provision for the naturalization of any of the chiefs, warriors, or
heads of families of the Stockbridge Indians, is reenacted in §
2312 of the Revised Statutes.
The Act of January 25, 1871, c. 38, for the relief of the
Stockbridge and Munsee Indians in the State of Wisconsin, provided
that "for the purpose of determining the persons who are members of
said tribes, and the future relation of each to the government of
the United States," two rolls should be prepared under the
direction of the Commissioner of Indian Affairs, signed by the
sachem and councilors of the tribe, certified by the person
selected by the commissioner to superintend the same, and returned
to the commissioner, the one, to be denominated the citizen roll,
of the names of all such persons of full age, and their families,
"as signify their desire to separate their relations with said
tribe and to become citizens of the United States," and the other
to be denominated the Indian roll, of the names of all such "as
desire to retain their tribal character and continue under the care
and guardianship of the United States," and that those rolls, so
made and returned, should be held as a full surrender and
relinquishment, on the part of all those of the first class, of all
claims to be known or considered as members of the tribe, or to be
interested Page 112 U. S. 106 in any provision made or to be made by the United States for its
benefit, "and they and their descendants shall thenceforth be
admitted to all the rights and privileges of citizens of the United
States." 16 Stat. 406.
The Pension Act exempts Indian claimants of pensions for service
in the army or navy from the obligation to take the oath to support
the Constitution of the United States. Act of March 3, 1873, c.
234, § 28, 17 Stat. 574; Rev.Stat. § 4721.
The recent statutes concerning homesteads are quite inconsistent
with the theory that Indians do or can make themselves independent
citizens by living apart from their tribe. The Act of March 3,
1875, c. 131, § 15, allowed to "any Indian born in the United
States, who is the head of a family, or who has arrived at the age
of twenty-one years, and who has abandoned, or may hereafter
abandon, his tribal relations" the benefit of the homestead acts,
but only upon condition of his "making satisfactory proof of such
abandonment, under rules to be prescribed by the Secretary of the
Interior," and further provided that his title in the homestead
should be absolutely inalienable for five years from the date of
the patent, and that he should be entitled to share in all
annuities, tribal funds, lands, and other property, as if he had
maintained his tribal relations. 18 Stat. 420. And the Act of March
3, 1884, c. 180, § 1, while it allows Indians "located on public
lands" to "avail themselves of the homestead laws as fully, and to
the same extent, as may now be done by citizens of the United
States," provides that the form and the legal effect of the patent
shall be that the United States does and will hold the land for
twenty-five years in trust for the Indian making the entry, and his
widow and heirs, and will then convey it in fee to him or them. 23
Stat. 96.
The national legislation has tended more and more toward the
education and civilization of the Indians, and fitting them to be
citizens. But the question whether any Indian tribes, or any
members thereof, have become so far advanced in civilization that
they should be let out of the state of pupilage, and admitted to
the privileges and responsibilities of citizenship, is a question
to be decided by the nation whose wards they are Page 112 U. S. 107 and whose citizens they seek to become, and not by each Indian
for himself. There is nothing in the statutes or decisions referred
to by counsel to control the conclusion to which we have been
brought by a consideration of the language of the Fourteenth
Amendment and of the condition of the Indians at the time of its
proposal and ratification.
The Act of July 27, 1868, c. 249, declaring the right of
expatriation to be a natural and inherent right of all people, and
reciting that "in the recognition of this principle this government
has freely received emigrants from all nations, and invested them
with the rights of citizenship," while it affirms the right of
every man to expatriate himself from one country, contains nothing
to enable him to become a citizen of another without being
naturalized under its authority. 15 Stat. 223; Rev.Stat. §
1999.
The provision of the Act of Congress of March 3, 1871, c. 120,
that
"Hereafter no Indian nation or tribe within the territory of the
United States shall be acknowledged or recognized as an independent
nation, tribe, or power with whom the United States may contract by
treaty"
is coupled with a provision that the obligation of any treaty
already lawfully made is not to be thereby invalidated or impaired,
and its utmost possible effect is to require the Indian tribes to
be dealt with for the future through the legislative and not
through the treatymaking power. 16 Stat. 566; Rev.Stat. § 2079.
In the case of United States v. Elm, 23 Int.Rev.Rec.
419, decided by Judge Wallace in the District Court of the United
States for the Northern District of New York, the Indian who was
held to have a right to vote in 1876 was born in the State of New
York, one of the remnants of a tribe which had ceased to exist as a
tribe in that state, and by a statute of the state it had been
enacted that any native Indian might purchase, take, hold, and
convey lands, and whenever he should have become a freeholder to
the value of $100 should be liable to taxation and to the civil
jurisdiction of the courts in the same manner and to the same
extent as a citizen. N.Y. Stat. 1843, c. 87. The condition of the
tribe from which he Page 112 U. S. 108 derived his origin, so far as any fragments of it remained
within the State of New York, resembled the condition of those
Indian nations of which Mr. Justice Johnson said in Fletcher v.
Peck , 6 Cranch 87, 10 U. S. 146 ,
that they "have totally extinguished their national fire, and
submitted themselves to the laws of the states," and which Mr.
Justice McLean had in view when he observed in Worcester
v. Georgia , 6 Pet. 515, 31 U. S. 580 ,
that in some of the old states
"where small remnants of tribes remain, surrounded by white
population, and who, by their reduced numbers, had lost the power
of self-government, the laws of the state have been extended over
them, for the protection of their persons and property." See also, as to the condition of Indians in
Massachusetts, remnants of tribes never recognized by the treaties
or legislative or executive acts of the United States as distinct
political communities, Danzell v. Webquish, 108 Mass. 133; Pells v. Webquish, 129 Mass. 469; Mass. Stat. 1862, c.
184; 1869, c. 463.
The passages cited as favorable to the plaintiff, from the
opinions delivered in Ex Parte Kenyon, 5 Dillon 385, 390,
in Ex Parte Reynolds, 5 Dillon 394, 397, and in United
States v. Crook, 5 Dillon 453, 464, were obiter
dicta. The Case of Reynolds was an indictment, in the
Circuit Court of the United States for the Western District of
Arkansas, for a murder in the Indian country, of which that court
had jurisdiction if either the accused or the dead man was not an
Indian, and was decided by Judge Parker in favor of the
jurisdiction, upon the ground that both were white men and that,
conceding the one to be an Indian by marriage, the other never was
an Indian in any sense. 5 Dillon 397, 404. Each of the other two
cases was a writ of habeas corpus, and any person, whether a
citizen or not, unlawfully restrained of his liberty, is entitled
to that writ. Case of the Hottentot Venus, 13 East 195; Case of Dos Santos, 2 Brock. 493; In re
Kaine , 14 How. 103. In Kenyon's Case, Judge Parker held that the court in which the prisoner had been
convicted had no jurisdiction of the subject matter because the
place of the commission of the act was beyond the territorial
limits of its jurisdiction, and, as was truly said, "this alone
would be conclusive of this case." 5 Dillon Page 112 U. S. 109 390. In United States v. Crook, the Ponca Indians were
discharged by Judge Dundy because the military officers who held
them were taking them to the Indian Territory by force and without
any lawful authority, 5 Dillon 468, and in the case at bar, as the
record before us shows, that learned judge concurred in the
judgment below for the defendant.
The law upon the question before us has been well stated by
Judge Deady in the District Court of the United States for the
District of Oregon. In giving judgment against the plaintiff in a
case resembling the case at bar, he said:
"Being born a member of 'an independent political community' --
the Chinook -- he was not born subject to the jurisdiction of the
United States -- not born in its allegiance." McKay v. Campbell, 2 Sawyer 118, 134. And in a later
case, he said:
"But an Indian cannot make himself a citizen of the United
States without the consent and cooperation of the government. The
fact that he has abandoned his nomadic life or tribal relations and
adopted the habits and manners of civilized people may be a good
reason why he should be made a citizen of the United States, but
does not of itself make him one. To be a citizen of the United
States is a political privilege which no one not born to can assume
without its consent in some form. The Indians in Oregon, not being
born subject to the jurisdiction of the United States, were not
born citizens thereof, and I am not aware of any law or treaty by
which any of them have been made so since." United States v. Osborne, 6 Sawyer 406, 409.
Upon the question whether any action of a state can confer
rights of citizenship on Indians of a tribe still recognized by the
United States as retaining its tribal existence, we need not and do
not express an opinion, because the State of Nebraska is not shown
to have taken any action affecting the condition of this plaintiff. See Chirac v.
Chirac , 2 Wheat. 259; Fellows v.
Blacksmith , 19 How. 366; United
States v. Holliday , 3 Wall. 407, 70 U. S. 420 ; United States v. Joseph, 94 U. S. 614 , 94 U. S. 618 .
The plaintiff, not being a citizen of the United States under the
Fourteenth Amendment of the Constitution, has been deprived of no
right secured by the Fifteenth Amendment, and cannot maintain this
action. Judgment affirmed. Page 112 U. S. 110 MR. JUSTICE HARLAN, with whom concurred MR. JUSTICE WOODS,
dissenting.
MR. JUSTICE WOODS and myself feel constrained to express our
dissent from the interpretation which our brethren give to that
clause of the Fourteenth Amendment which provides that
"All persons born or naturalized in the United States, and
subject to the jurisdiction thereof, are citizens of the United
States and of the state wherein they reside."
The case, as presented by the record, is this:
John Elk, the plaintiff in error, is a person of the Indian
race. He was born within the territorial limits of the United
States. His parents were, at the time of his birth, members of one
of the Indian tribes in this country. More than a year, however,
prior to his application to be registered as a voter in the City of
Omaha, he had severed all relations with his tribe and, as he
alleges, fully and completely surrendered himself to the
jurisdiction of the United States. Such surrender was, of course,
involved in his act of becoming, as the demurrer to the petition
admits that he did become, a bona fide resident of the
State of Nebraska. When he applied in 1880 to be registered as a
voter, he possessed, as is also admitted, the qualifications of age
and residence in state, county, and ward, required for electors by
the constitution and laws of that state. It is likewise conceded
that he was entitled to be so registered if at the time of his
application, he was a citizen of the United States, for, by the
Constitution and laws of Nebraska, every citizen of the United
States having the necessary qualifications of age and residence in
state, county, and ward is entitled to vote. Whether he was such
citizen is the question presented by this writ of error.
It is said that the petition contains no averment that Elk was
taxed in the state in which he resides, or had ever been treated by
her as a citizen. It is evident that the court would not have held
him to be a citizen of the United States even if the petition had
contained a direct averment that he was taxed, because its
judgment, in legal effect, is that, although born within the
territorial limits of the United States, he could not, if at his
birth a member of an Indian tribe, acquire national citizenship Page 112 U. S. 111 by force of the Fourteenth Amendment, but only in pursuance of
some statute or treaty providing for his naturalization. It would
therefore seem unnecessary to inquire whether he was taxed at the
time of his application to be registered as a voter, for if the
words "all persons born . . . in the United States and subject to
the jurisdiction thereof" were not intended to embrace Indians born
in tribal relations, but who subsequently became bona fide residents of the several states, then manifestly the legal status
of such Indians is not altered by the fact that they are taxed in
those states.
While denying that national citizenship, as conferred by that
amendment, necessarily depends upon the inquiry whether the person
claiming it is taxed in the state of his residence or has property
therein from which taxes may be derived, we submit that the
petition does sufficiently show that the plaintiff was taxed --
that is, belongs to the class which, by the laws of Nebraska, are
subject to taxation. By the Constitution and laws of Nebraska, all
real and personal property in that state are subject to assessment
and taxation. Every person of full age and sound mind, being a
resident thereof, is required to list his personal property for
taxation. Const.Neb. art. 9, § 1; Compiled Stat. of Neb., c. 77,
pp. 400, 401. Of these provisions upon the subject of taxation this
Court will take judicial notice. Good pleading did not require that
they should be set forth at large in the petition. Consequently an
averment that the plaintiff is a citizen and bona fide resident of Nebraska implies in law that he is subject to taxation,
and is taxed, in that state. Further: The plaintiff has become so
far incorporated with the mass of the people of Nebraska that
being, as the petition avers, a citizen and resident thereof, he
constitutes a part of her militia. Compiled Stat.Neb. c. 56. He
may, being no longer a member of an Indian tribe, sue and be sued
in her courts. And he is counted in every apportionment of
representation in the legislature, for the requirement of her
Constitution is that
"The legislature shall apportion the Senators and
representatives according to the number of inhabitants, excluding
Indians not taxed, and soldiers and officers of the United States
army."
Const.Neb., art. 3 § 1. Page 112 U. S. 112 At the adoption of the Constitution there were, in many of the
states, Indians, not members of any tribe, who constituted a part
of the people for whose benefit the state governments were
established. This is apparent from that clause of Article I,
Section 3, which requires, in the apportionment of representatives
and direct taxes among the several states "according to their
respective numbers," the exclusion of "Indians not taxed." This
implies that there were at that time, in the United States, Indians
who were taxed -- that is, were subject to taxation by the laws of
the State of which they were residents. Indians not taxed were
those who held tribal relations, and therefore were not subject to
the authority of any state, and were subject only to the authority
of the United States, under the power conferred upon Congress in
reference to Indian tribes in this country. The same provision is
retained in the Fourteenth Amendment; for now, as at the adoption
of the Constitution, Indians in the several states, who are taxed
by their laws, are counted in establishing the basis of
representation in Congress.
By the Act of April 9, 1866, entitled "An act to protect all
persons in the United States in their civil rights, and furnish
means for their vindication," 14 Stat. 27, it is provided that
"all persons born in the United States, and not subject to any
foreign power, excluding Indians not taxed, are hereby declared to
be citizens of the United States."
This, so far as we are aware, is the first general enactment
making persons of the Indian race citizens of the United States.
Numerous statutes and treaties previously provided for all the
individual members of particular Indian tribes becoming, in certain
contingencies, citizens of the United States. But the act of 1866
reached Indians not in tribal relations. Beyond question, by that
act, national citizenship was conferred directly upon all persons
in this country, of whatever race (excluding only "Indians not
taxed") who were born within the territorial limits of the United
States, and were not subject to any foreign power. Surely everyone
must admit that an Indian residing in one of the states and subject
to taxation there became, by force alone of the act of 1866, a
citizen of the United States, although Page 112 U. S. 113 he may have been, when born, a member of a tribe. The exclusion
of Indians not taxed evinced a purpose to include those subject to
taxation in the state of their residence. Language could not
express that purpose with more distinctness than does the act of
1866. Any doubt upon the subject, in respect to persons of the
Indian race residing in the United States or territories, and not
members of a tribe, will be removed by an examination of the
debates, in which many distinguished statesmen and lawyers
participated in the Senate of the United States when the act of
1866 was under consideration.
In the bill as originally reported from the Judiciary Committee
there were no words excluding "Indians not taxed" from the
citizenship proposed to be granted. Attention being called to this
fact, the friends of the measure disclaimed any purpose to make
citizens of those who were in tribal relations, with governments of
their own. In order to meet that objection, while conforming to the
wishes of those desiring to invest with citizenship all Indians
permanently separated from their tribes, and who, by reason of
their residence away from their tribes, constituted a part of the
people under the jurisdiction of the United States, Mr. Trumbull,
who reported the bill, modified it by inserting the words
"excluding Indians not taxed." What was intended by that
modification appears from the following language used by him in
debate:
"Of course, we cannot declare the wild Indians who do not
recognize the government of the United States, who are not subject
to our laws, with whom we make treaties, who have their own laws,
who have their own regulations, whom we do not intend to interfere
with or punish for the commission of crimes one upon the other, to
be the subjects of the United States in the sense of being
citizens. They must be excepted. The Constitution of the United
States excludes them from the enumeration of the population of the
United States when it says that Indians not taxed are to be
excluded. It has occurred to me that, perhaps, the amendment would
meet the views of all gentlemen, which used these constitutional
words, and said that all persons born in the United States,
excluding Page 112 U. S. 114 Indians not taxed, and not subject to any foreign power, shall
be deemed citizens of the United States."
Cong.Globe, 1st Sess. 39th Congress, p. 527.
In replying to the objections urged by Mr. Hendricks to the bill
even as amended, Mr. Trumbull said:
"Does the Senator from Indiana want the wild roaming Indians,
not taxed, not subject to our authority, to be citizens of the
United States -- persons that are not to be counted, in our
government? If he does not, let him not object to this amendment
that brings in even [only] the Indian when he shall
have cast off his wild habits, and submitted to the laws of
organized society and become a citizen. " Ibid., 528.
The entire debate shows, with singular clearness, indeed, with
absolute certainty, that no Senator who participated in it,
whether, in favor of or in opposition to the measure, doubted that
the bill as passed admitted, and was intended to admit, to national
citizenship Indians who abandoned their tribal relations and became
residents of one of the states or territories, within the full
jurisdiction of the United States. It was so interpreted by
President Johnson, who, in his veto message, said:
"By the first section of the bill all persons born in the United
States, and not subject to any foreign power, excluding Indians not
taxed, are declared to be citizens of the United States. This
provision comprehends the Chinese of the Pacific states, Indians subject to taxation, the people called gypsies, as
well as the entire race designated as blacks, persons of color,
negroes, mulattoes, and persons of African blood. Every individual
of those races, born in the United States, is, by the bill, made a
citizen of the United States."
It would seem manifest, from this brief review of the history of
the act of 1866, that one purpose of that legislation was to confer
national citizenship upon a part of the Indian race in this country
-- such of them at least, as resided in one of the states or
territories, and were subject to taxation and other public burdens.
And it is to be observed that, whoever was included within the
terms of the grant contained in that act, became citizens of the
United States without any record of Page 112 U. S. 115 their names being made. The citizenship conferred was made to
depend wholly upon the existence of the facts which the statute
declared to be a condition precedent to the grant taking
effect.
At the same session of the Congress which passed the act of
1866, the Fourteenth Amendment was approved and submitted to the
states for adoption. Those who sustained the former urged the
adoption of the latter. An examination of the debates, pending the
consideration of the amendment, will show that there was no purpose
on the part of those who framed it, or of those who sustained it by
their votes, to abandon the policy inaugurated by the act of 1866,
of admitting to national citizenship such Indians as were separated
from their tribes and were residents of one of the states or
territories outside of any reservation set apart for the exclusive
use and occupancy of Indian tribes.
Prior to the adoption of the Fourteenth Amendment, numerous
statutes were passed with reference to particular bodies of
Indians, under which the individual members of such bodies, upon
the dissolution of their tribal relations, or upon the division of
their lands derived from the government, became, or were entitled
to become, citizens of the United States by force alone of the
statute, without observing the forms required by the naturalization
laws in the case of a foreigner becoming a citizen of the United
States. Such was the statute of March 3, 1839, 5 Stat. 349,
relating to the Brothertown Indians in the then Territory of
Wisconsin. Congress consented that the lands reserved for their use
might be partitioned among the individuals composing the tribe. The
act required the petition to be evidenced by a report and map to be
filed with the Secretary of the Interior, by whom it should be
transmitted to the President; whereupon the act proceeded:
"The said Brothertown Indians, and each and every of them, shall
then be deemed to be, and from that time forth are hereby declared
to be, citizens of the United States to all intents and purposes,
and shall be entitled to all the rights, privileges, and immunities
of such citizens,"
etc. Similar legislation was enacted with Page 112 U. S. 116 reference to the Stockbridge Indians. 5 Stat. 646-647.
Legislation of this character has an important bearing upon the
present question, for it shows that prior to the adoption of the
Fourteenth Amendment it had often been the policy of Congress to
admit persons of the Indian race to citizenship upon their ceasing
to have tribal relations, and without the slightest reference to
the fact that they were born in tribal relations. It shows also
that the citizenship thus granted was not in every instance
required to be evidenced by the record of a court.
If it be said that the statutes prior to 1866, providing for the
admission of Indians to citizenship, required in their execution
that a record be made of the names of those who thus acquired
citizenship, our answer is that it was entirely competent for
Congress to dispense, as it did in the act of 1866, with any such
record being made in a court or in any department of the
government. And certainly it must be conceded that, except in cases
of persons "naturalized in the United States," which phrase refers
only to those who are embraced by the naturalization laws, and not
to Indians, the Fourteenth Amendment does not require the
citizenship granted by it to be evidenced by the record of any
court, or of any department of the government. Such citizenship
passes to the person of whatever race who is embraced by its
provisions, leaving the fact of citizenship to be determined, when
it shall become necessary to do so in the course of legal inquiry,
in the same way that questions as to one's nativity, domicile, or
residence are determined.
If it be also said that since the adoption of the Fourteenth
Amendment, Congress has enacted statutes providing for the
citizenship of Indians, our answer is that those statutes had
reference to tribes the members of which could not, while they
continued in tribal relations, acquire the citizenship granted by
the Fourteenth Amendment. Those statutes did not deal with
individual Indians who had severed their tribal connections and
were residents within the states of the Union, under the complete
jurisdiction of the United States.
There is nothing in the history of the adoption of the
Fourteenth Amendment which in our opinion justifies the
conclusion Page 112 U. S. 117 that only those Indians are included in its grant of citizenship
who were at the time of their birth, subject to the complete
jurisdiction of the United States. As already stated, according to
the doctrines of the Court in this case -- if we do not wholly
misapprehend the effect of its decision -- the plaintiff, if born
while his parents were members of an Indian tribe, would not be
embraced by the amendment even had he been at the time it was
adopted, a permanent resident of one of the states, subject to
taxation and in fact paying property and personal taxes, to the
full extent required of the white race in the same state.
When the Fourteenth Amendment was pending in the Senate of the
United States, Mr. Doolittle moved to insert after the words
"subject to the jurisdiction thereof" the words "excluding Indians
not taxed." His avowed object in so amending the measure was to
exclude beyond all question from the proposed grant of national
citizenship, tribal Indians who -- since they were, in a sense,
subject to the jurisdiction of the United States -- might be
regarded as embraced in the grant. The proposition was opposed by
Mr. Trumbull and other friends of the proposed constitutional
amendment upon the ground that the words "Indians not taxed" might
be misconstrued, and also because those words were unnecessary, in
that the phrase "subject to the jurisdiction thereof" embraced only
those who were subject to the complete jurisdiction of the United
States, which could not be properly said of Indians in tribal
relations. But it was distinctly announced by the friends of the
amendment that they intended to include in the grant of national
citizenship Indians who were within the jurisdiction of the states
and subject to their laws, because such Indians would be completely
under the jurisdiction of the United States. Said Mr. Trumbull:
"It is only those who come completely within our jurisdiction,
who are subject to our laws, that we think of making citizens, and
there can be no objection to the proposition that such persons
should be citizens."
Cong.Globe, Pt. 4, 1st Sess. 39th Cong., pp. 2890-2893. Alluding
to the phrase "Indians not taxed," he remarked that the language of
the proposed constitutional amendment was Page 112 U. S. 118 better than that of the act of 1866 passed at the same session.
He observed:
"There is a difficulty about the words 'Indians not taxed.'
Perhaps one of the reasons why I think so is because of the
persistency with which the Senator from Indiana himself insisted
that the phrase 'Indians not taxed,' the very words which the
Senator from Wisconsin wishes to insert here, would exclude
everybody that did not pay a tax; that that was the meaning of it;
we must take it literally. The Senator from Maryland did not agree
to that, nor did I; but, if the Senator from Indiana was right, it
would receive a construction which, I am sure, the Senator from
Wisconsin would not be for, for if these Indians come within our
limits and within our jurisdiction and are civilized, he would just
as soon make a citizen of a poor Indian as of the rich Indian." Ibid., 2894.
A careful examination of all that was said by Senators and
representatives, pending the consideration by Congress of the
Fourteenth Amendment, justifies us in saying that everyone who
participated in the debates, whether for or against the amendment,
believed that, in the form in which it was approved by Congress, it
granted, and was intended to grant, national citizenship to every
person of the Indian race in this country who was unconnected with
any tribe, and who resided, in good faith, outside of Indian
reservations and within one of the states or territories of the
Union. This fact is, we think, entitled to great weight in
determining the meaning and scope of the amendment. Lithographic Co. v. Sarony, 111 U.
S. 57 .
In this connection, we refer to an elaborate report made by Mr.
Carpenter, to the Senate of the United States, in behalf of its
Judiciary Committee, on the 14th of December, 1870. The report was
made in obedience to an instruction to inquire as to the effect of
the Fourteenth Amendment upon the treaties which the United States
had with various Indian tribes of the country. The report says:
"For these reasons your committee do not hesitate to say that
the Indian tribes within the limits of the United States, and the
individuals, members of such tribes, while they adhere to and form
a part of the tribes to which they belong, are not, within the
meaning of the Page 112 U. S. 119 Fourteenth Amendment, 'subject to the jurisdiction' of the
United States, and therefore that such Indians have not
become citizens of the United States by virtue of that amendment;
and, if your committee are correct in this conclusion, it follows
that the treaties heretofore made between the United States and the
Indian tribes are not annulled by that amendment."
The report closes with this significant language:
"It is pertinent to say, in concluding this report, that treaty
relations can properly exist with Indian tribes or nations only,
and that, when the members of any Indian tribe are scattered,
they are merged in the mass of our people, and become equally
subject to the jurisdiction of the United States. "
The question before us has been examined by a writer upon
constitutional law whose views are entitled to great respect. Judge
Cooley, referring to the definition of national citizenship as
contained in the Fourteenth Amendment, says:
"By the express terms of the amendment, persons of foreign
birth, who have never renounced the allegiance to which they were
born, though they may have a residence in this country, more or
less permanent, for business, instruction, or pleasure, are not
citizens. Neither are the aboriginal inhabitants of the country
citizens, so long as they preserve their tribal relations and
recognize the headship of their chiefs, notwithstanding that, as
against the action of our own people, they are under the protection
of the laws, and may be said to owe a qualified allegiance to the
government. When living within territory over which the laws,
either state or territorial, are extended, they are protected by,
and at the same time, held amenable to, those laws in all their
intercourse with the body politic, and with the individuals
composing it; but they are also, as a quasi -foreign
people, regarded as being under the direction and tutelage of the
general government, and subjected to peculiar regulations as
dependent communities. They are 'subject to the jurisdiction' of
the United States only in a much qualified sense, and it would be
obviously inconsistent with the semi-independent character of such
a tribe, and with the obedience they are expected to render to
their tribal head, that they should be vested with the complete
rights, or, on the other Page 112 U. S. 120 hand, subjected to the full responsibilities of American
citizens. It would not for a moment be contended that such was the
effect of this amendment."
"When, however, the tribal relations are dissolved, when the
headship of the chief or the authority of the tribe is no longer
recognized, and the individual Indian, turning his back upon his
former mode of life, makes himself a member of the civilized
community, the case is wholly altered. He then no longer
acknowledges a divided allegiance; he joins himself to the body
politic; he gives evidence of his purpose to adopt the habits and
customs of civilized life; and, as his case is then within the
terms of this amendment, it would seem that his right to
protection, in person, property, and privilege, must be as complete
as the allegiance to the government to which he must then be held;
as complete, in short, as that of any other native-born
inhabitant."
2 Story's Const., Cooley's ed., § 1933, p. 654.
To the same effect are Ex Parte Kenyon, 5 Dillon 390; Ex Parte Reynolds, ib., 307; United States v. Crook,
ib., 454; United States v. Elm, Dist.Ct. U.S.,
N.D.N.Y. 23 Int.Rev.Rec. 419.
It seems to us that the Fourteenth Amendment, insofar as it was
intended to confer national citizenship upon persons of the Indian
race, is robbed of its vital force by a construction which excludes
from such citizenship those who, although born in tribal relations,
are within the complete jurisdiction of the United States. There
were, in some of our states and territories at the time the
amendment was submitted by Congress, many Indians who had finally
left their tribes and come within the complete jurisdiction of the
United States. They were as fully prepared for citizenship as were
or are vast numbers of the white and colored races in the same
localities. Is it conceivable that the statesmen who framed, the
Congress which submitted, and the people who adopted that amendment
intended to confer citizenship, national and state, upon the entire
population in this country of African descent (the larger part of
which was shortly before held in slavery), and, by the same
constitutional provision, to exclude from such citizenship
Indians Page 112 U. S. 121 who had never been in slavery and who, by becoming bona
fide residents of states and territories within the complete
jurisdiction of the United States, had evinced a purpose to abandon
their former mode of life, and become a part of the people of the
United States? If this question be answered in the negative, as we
think it must be, then we are justified in withholding our assent
to the doctrine which excludes the plaintiff from the body of
citizens of the United States upon the ground that his parents
were, when he was born, members of an Indian tribe, for, if he can
be excluded upon any such ground, it must necessarily follow that
the Fourteenth Amendment did not grant citizenship even to Indians
who, although born in tribal relations, were at its adoption,
severed from their tribes, subject to the complete jurisdiction as
well of the United States as of the state or territory in which
they resided.
Our brethren, it seems to us, construe the Fourteenth Amendment
as if it read:
"All persons born subject to the jurisdiction of, or
naturalized in, the United States, are citizens of the United
States and of the state in which they reside,"
whereas the amendment, as it is, implies in respect of persons
born in this country that they may claim the rights of national
citizenship from and after the moment they become subject to the
complete jurisdiction of the United States. This would not include
the children born in this country of a foreign minister, for the
reason that, under the fiction of extraterritoriality as recognized
by international law, such minister, "though actually in a foreign
country, is considered still to remain within the territory of his
own state," and, consequently, he continues
"subject to the laws of his own country, both with respect to
his personal status and his rights of property, and his children,
though born in a foreign country, are considered as natives."
Halleck's International Law, c. 10 § 12. Nor was plaintiff born
without the jurisdiction of the United States in the same sense
that the subject of a foreign state, born within the territory of
that state, may be said to have been born without the jurisdiction
of our government. For, according to the decision in Cherokee Page 112 U. S. 122 Nation v. Georgia, 5 Pet. 17, the tribe of which the
parents of plaintiff were members was not "a foreign state, in the
sense of the Constitution," but a domestic dependent people, "in a
state of pupilage," and
"so completely under the sovereignty and dominion of the United
States that any attempt to acquire their lands, or to form a
political connection with them, would be considered an invasion of
our territory and an act of hostility."
They occupied territory which the court, in that case, said
composed "a part of the United States," the title to which this
nation asserted independent of their will. "In all our intercourse
with foreign nations," said Chief Justice Marshall in the same
case,
"In our commercial regulations, in any attempt at intercourse
between Indians and foreign nations, they are considered as within
the jurisdictional limits of the United States, subject to many of
those restraints which are imposed upon our citizens. . . . They
look to our government for protection; rely upon its kindness and
its power; appeal to it for relief to their wants, and address the
President as their great father."
And, again, in United States v.
Rogers , 4 How. 572, this Court, speaking by Chief
Justice Taney, said that it was
"too firmly and clearly established to admit of dispute that the
Indian tribes, residing within the territorial limits of the United
States, are subject to their authority." The Cherokee
Tobacco , 11 Wall. 616.
Born, therefore, in the territory, under the dominion and within
the jurisdictional limits of the United States, plaintiff has
acquired, as was his undoubted right, a residence in one of the
states, with her consent, and is subject to taxation and to all
other burdens imposed by her upon residents of every race. If he
did not acquire national citizenship on abandoning his tribe and
becoming, by residence in one of the states, subject to the
complete jurisdiction of the United States, then the Fourteenth
Amendment has wholly failed to accomplish, in respect of the Indian
race, what, we think, was intended by it, and there is still in
this country a despised and rejected class of persons with no
nationality whatever, who, born in our territory, owing no
allegiance to any foreign power, and subject, as residents of the
states, to all the burdens of government, Page 112 U. S. 123 are yet not members of any political community, nor entitled to
any of the rights, privileges, or immunities of citizens of the
United States. | In the case of Elk v. Wilkins, the Supreme Court decided that an Indian born in the United States and belonging to a recognized tribe is not automatically a citizen of the country, even if they have severed ties with their tribe and reside among white citizens. The Court's decision hinged on the interpretation of the Fourteenth Amendment, with the Court concluding that the amendment did not extend citizenship to Indians who had voluntarily left their tribes. This meant that Indians who had assimilated into white society were not granted the right to vote or other privileges of citizenship. The Court's ruling perpetuated the legal status of Indians as a separate class of people, neither foreign nationals nor full citizens, and subject to the jurisdiction and laws of the United States without the corresponding rights and protections. |
Immigration & National Security | Nishimura Ekiu v. U.S. | https://supreme.justia.com/cases/federal/us/142/651/ | U.S. Supreme Court Nishimura Ekiu v. United States, 142
U.S. 651 (1892) Nishimura Ekiu v. United
States No. 1393 Argued and submitted December 16,
1891 Decided January 18,
1892 142
U.S. 651 APPEAL FROM THE CIRCUIT COURT OF
THE UNITED STATES FOR THE NORTHERN DISTRICT OF
CALIFORNIA Syllabus The Act of March 3, 1591, c. 551, forbidding certain classes of
alien immigrants to land in the United States, is constitutional
and valid.
Upon a writ of habeas corpus, if sufficient ground for the
prisoner's detention by the government is shown, he is not to be
discharged for defects in the original arrest or commitment. Page 142 U. S. 652 Inspectors of immigration under the Act of March 3, 1891, c.
551, are to be appointed by the Secretary of the Treasury.
The decision of an inspector of immigration, within the
authority conferred upon him by the Act of March 3, 1891, c. 651,
that an alien immigrant shall not be permitted to land because
within one of the classes specified in that act, is final and
conclusive against his right to land, except upon appeal to the
Commissioner of Immigration and the Secretary of the Treasury, and
cannot be reviewed on habeas corpus even if it is not shown that
the inspector took or recorded any evidence on the question.
Habeas corpus, sued out May 13, 1891, by a female subject of the
Emperor of Japan restrained of her liberty and detained at San
Francisco upon the ground that she should not be permitted to land
in the United States. The case, as appearing by the papers filed
and by the report of a commissioner of the circuit court, to whom
the case was referred by that court "to find the facts and his
conclusions of law, and to report a judgment therein," and by the
admissions of counsel at the argument in this Court, was as
follows:
The petitioner arrived at the port of San Francisco on the
steamship Belgic from Yokohama, Japan, on May 7, 1891.
William H. Thornley, Commissioner of Immigration of the State of
California, and claiming to act under instructions from and
contract with the Secretary of the Treasury of the United States,
refused to allow her to land, and on May 13, 1891, in a
"report of alien immigrants forbidden to land under the
provisions of the Act of Congress approved August 3, 1882 at the
port of San Francisco, being passengers upon the steamer Belgic, Walker, master, which arrived May 7, 1891, from
Yokohama,"
made these statements as to the petitioner:
"Sex, female; age, 25. Passport states that she comes to San
Francisco in company with her husband, which is not a fact. She
states that she has been married two years, and that her husband
has been in the United States one year, but she does not know his
address. She has $22, and is to stop at some hotel until her
husband calls for her."
With this report Thornley sent a letter to the collector stating
that after a careful examination of the alien immigrants on board
the Belgic, he was satisfied that the petitioner and five
others were "prohibited from landing by the existing Page 142 U. S. 653 immigration laws" for reasons specifically stated with regard to
each, and that, pending the collector's final decision as to their
right to land, he had "placed them temporarily in the Methodist
Chinese Mission, as the steamer was not a proper place to detain
them, until the date of sailing." On the same day, the collector
wrote to Thornley, approving his action.
Thereafter, on the same day, this writ of habeas corpus was
issued to Thornley, and he made the following return thereon:
"In obedience to the within writ, I hereby produce the body of
Nishimura Ekiu, as within directed, and return that I hold her in
my custody by direction of the customs authorities of the port of
San Francisco, California, under the provisions of the immigration
act; that, by an understanding between the United States attorney
and the attorney for petitioner, said party will remain in the
custody of the Methodist Episcopal Japanese and Chinese Mission
pending a final disposition of the writ."
The petitioner remained at the mission house until the final
order of the circuit court.
Afterwards, and before a hearing, the following proceedings took
place: on May 16th the district attorney of the United States
intervened in opposition to the writ of habeas corpus, insisting
that the finding and decision of Thornley and the collector were
final and conclusive, and could not be reviewed by the court. John
L. Hatch, having been appointed on May 14, by the Secretary of the
Treasury, inspector of immigration at the port of San Francisco, on
May 16th made the inspection and examination required by the Act of
March 3, 1891, c. 551, entitled "An act in amendment to the various
acts relative to immigration and the importation of aliens under
contract or agreement to perform labor," the material provisions of
which are set out in the margin, * and refused
to Page 142 U. S. 654 allow the petitioner to land, and made a report to the collector
in the very words of Thornley's report, except in stating Page 142 U. S. 655 the date of the act of Congress, under which he acted, as March
3, 1891, instead of August 3, 1882, and, on May 18th, Page 142 U. S. 656 Hatch intervened in opposition to the writ of habeas corpus,
stating these doings of his, and that upon said examination he
found the petitioner to be "an alien immigrant from Yokohama,
empire of Japan," and "a person without means of support, without
relatives or friends in the United States," and
"a person unable to care for herself, and liable to become a
public charge,and therefore inhibited from landing under the
provisions of said act of 1891, and previous acts of which said act
is amendatory,"
and insisting that his finding and decision were reviewable by
the Superintendent of immigration and the Secretary of the Treasury
only.
At the hearing before the commissioner of the circuit court, the
petitioner offered to introduce evidence as to her right to land,
and contended that the act of 1891, if construed as vesting in the
officers named therein exclusive authority to determine that right,
was insofar unconstitutional, as depriving her of her liberty
without due process of law, and that by the Constitution she had a
right to the writ of habeas corpus, which carried with it the right
to a determination by the court as to the legality of her
detention, and therefore, necessarily, the right to inquire into
the facts relating thereto.
The commissioner excluded the evidence offered as to the
petitioner's right to land, and reported that the question of that
right had been tried and determined by a duly constituted and
competent tribunal having jurisdiction in the premises; that the
decision of Hatch, as Inspector of Immigration, was conclusive on
the right of the petitioner to land, and could not be reviewed by
the court, but only by the Commissioner of Immigration and the
Secretary of the Treasury, and that the petitioner was not
unlawfully restrained of her liberty.
On July 24, 1891, the circuit court confirmed its commissioner's
report, and ordered
"that she be remanded by the marshal to the custody from which
she has been taken, to-wit, to the custody of J. L. Hatch,
immigration inspector for the port of San Francisco, to be dealt
with as he may find that Page 142 U. S. 657 the law requires, upon either the present testimony before him
or that and such other as he may deem proper to take."
The petitioner appealed to this Court. Page 142 U. S. 658 MR. JUSTICE GRAY, after stating the case as above, delivered the
opinion of the Court.
As this case involves the constitutionality of a law of the
United States, it is within the appellate jurisdiction of this Page 142 U. S. 659 Court notwithstanding the appeal was taken since the act
establishing circuit courts of appeals took effect. Act March 3,
1891, c. 517, § 5, 26 Stat. 827, 828, 1115.
It is an accepted maxim of international law that every
sovereign nation has the power, as inherent in sovereignty and
essential to self-preservation, to forbid the entrance of
foreigners within its dominions or to admit them only in such cases
and upon such conditions as it may see fit to prescribe. Vattel,
lib. 2, §§ 94, 100; 1 Phillimore (3d ed.) c. 10, § 220. In the
United States, this power is vested in the national government, to
which the Constitution has committed the entire control of
international relations, in peace as well as in war. It belongs to
the political department of the government, and may be exercised
either through treaties made by the President and Senate or through
statutes enacted by Congress, upon whom the Constitution has
conferred power to regulate commerce with foreign nations,
including the entrance of ships, the importation of goods, and the
bringing of persons into the ports of the United States; to
establish a uniform rule of naturalization; to declare war, and to
provide and maintain armies and navies, and to make all laws which
may be necessary and proper for carrying into effect these powers
and all other powers vested by the Constitution in the government
of the United States, or in any department or officer thereof.
Constitution, Art. I, sec. 8; Head Money Cases, 112 U. S. 580 ; Chae Chan Ping v. United States, 130 U.
S. 581 , 130 U. S.
604 -609.
The supervision of the admission of aliens into the United
States may be entrusted by Congress either to the Department of
State, having the general management of foreign relations, or to
the Department of the Treasury, charged with the enforcement of the
laws regulating foreign commerce, and Congress has often passed
acts forbidding the immigration of particular classes of
foreigners, and has committed the execution of these acts to the
Secretary of the Treasury, to collectors of customs, and to
inspectors acting under their authority. See, for
instance, Acts of March 3, 1875, c. 141, 18 Stat. 477; August
3, 1882, c. 376, 22 Stat. 214; February 23, 1887, c. Page 142 U. S. 660 220, 24 Stat. 414; October 19, 1888, c. 1210, 25 Stat. 566, as
well as the various acts for the exclusion of the Chinese.
An alien immigrant, prevented from landing by any such officer
claiming authority to do so under an act of Congress and thereby
restrained of his liberty, is doubtless entitled to a writ of
habeas corpus to ascertain whether the restraint is lawful. Chew Heong v. United States, 112 U.
S. 536 ; United States v. Jung Ah Lung, 124 U. S. 621 ; Wan Shing v. United States, 140 U.
S. 424 ; Lau Ow Bew, Petitioner, 141 U.
S. 583 . And Congress may, if it sees fit, as in the
statutes in question in United States v. Jung Ah Lung, just cited, authorize the courts to investigate and ascertain the
facts on which the right to land depends. But, on the other hand,
the final determination of those facts may be in trusted by
Congress to executive officers, and in such a case, as in all
others, in which a statute gives a discretionary power to an
officer, to be exercised by him upon his own opinion of certain
facts, he is made the sole and exclusive judge of the existence of
those facts, and no other tribunal, unless expressly authorized by
law to do so, is at liberty to reexamine or controvert the
sufficiency of the evidence on which he acted. Martin v.
Mott , 12 Wheat. 19, 25 U. S. 31 ; Philadelphia & Trenton
Railroad v. Stimpson , 14 Pet. 448, 39 U. S. 458 ; Benson v. McMahon, 127 U. S. 457 ; In re Oteiza, 136 U. S. 330 . It
is not within the province of the judiciary to order that
foreigners who have never been naturalized, nor acquired any
domicile or residence within the United States, nor even been
admitted into the country pursuant to law shall be permitted to
enter in opposition to the constitutional and lawful measures of
the legislative and executive branches of the national government.
As to such persons, the decisions of executive or administrative
officers, acting within powers expressly conferred by Congress, are
due process of law. Murray v. Hoboken
Co. , 18 How. 272; Hilton v. Merritt, 110 U. S. 97 .
The immigration Act of August 3, 1882, c. 376, which was held to
be constitutional in the Head-Money Cases, above cited,
imposed a duty of fifty cents for each alien passenger coming by
vessel into any port of the United States, to be Page 142 U. S. 661 paid to the collector of customs, and by him into the Treasury,
to constitute an immigrant fund; by § 2, the Secretary of the
Treasury was charged with the duty of execution the provisions of
the act, and with the supervision of the business of immigration to
the United States, and, for these purposes, was empowered to make
contracts with any state commission, board, or officers, and it was
made their duty to go on board vessels and examine the condition of
immigrants,
"and if on such examination there shall be found among such
passengers any convict, lunatic, idiot, or any person unable to
take care of himself or herself without becoming a public charge,
they shall report the same in writing to the collector of such
port, and such persons shall not be permitted to land,"
and by section 3, the Secretary of the Treasury was authorized
to establish rules and regulations, and to issue instructions, to
carry out this and other immigration laws of the United States. 22
Stat. 214.
The doings of Thornley, the state commissioner of immigration,
in examining and detaining the petitioner, and in reporting to the
collector appear to have been under that act, and would be
justified by the second section thereof unless that section should
be taken to have been impliedly repealed by the last paragraph of
section 8 of the Act of March 3, 1891, c. 551, by which all duties
imposed and powers conferred by that section upon state
commissions, boards, or officers, acting under contract with the
Secretary of the Treasury, "shall be performed and exercised, as
occasion may arise, by the inspection officers of the United
States." 26 Stat. 1085.
But it is unnecessary to express a definite opinion on the
authority of Thornley to inspect and detain the petitioner.
Putting her in the mission house as a more suitable place than
the steamship, pending the decision of the question of her right to
land, and keeping her there, by agreement between her attorney and
the attorney for the United States, until final judgment upon the
writ of habeas corpus, left her in the same position, so far as
regarded her right to land in the United States, as if she never
had been removed from the steamship.
Before the hearing upon the writ of habeas corpus, Hatch Page 142 U. S. 662 was appointed by the Secretary of the Treasury inspector of
immigration at the port of San Francisco, and, after making the
inspection and examination required by the act of 1891, refused to
allow the petitioner to land, and made a report to the collector of
customs stating facts which tended to show, and which the inspector
decided did show, that she was a "person likely to become a public
charge," and so within one of the classes of aliens "excluded from
admission into the United States" by the first section of that act.
And Hatch intervened in the proceedings on the writ of habeas
corpus, setting up his decision in bar of the writ.
A writ of habeas corpus is not like an action to recover damages
for an unlawful arrest or commitment, but its object is to
ascertain whether the prisoner can lawfully be detained in custody,
and, if sufficient ground for his detention by the government is
shown, he is not to be discharged for defects in the original
arrest or commitment. Ex part Bollman , 4 Cranch 75, 114 [argument of counsel -- omitted], 8 U. S. 125 ; Coleman v. Tennessee, 97 U. S. 509 , 97 U. S. 519 ; United States v. McBratney, 104 U.
S. 621 , 104 U. S. 624 ; Kelley v. Thomas, 15 Gray 192; King v. Marks, 3
East, 157; Shuttleworth's Case, 9 Q.B. 651.
The case must therefore turn on the validity and effect of the
action of Hatch as Inspector of Immigration.
Section 7 of the act of 1891 establishes the office of
Superintendent of Immigration, and enacts that he "shall be an
officer in the Treasury Department, under the control and
supervision of the Secretary of the Treasury." By § 8, "the proper
inspection officers" are required to go on board any vessel
bringing alien immigrants and to inspect and examine them, and may
for this purpose remove and detain them on shore, without such
removal's being considered a landing; and
"shall have power to administer oaths, and to take and consider
testimony touching the right of any such aliens to enter the United
States, all of which shall be entered of record. . . . All
decisions made by the inspection officers or their assistants
touching the right of any alien to land, when adverse to such
right, shall be final unless appeal be taken to the Superintendent
of Immigration, whose action shall be subject to review by the
Secretary Page 142 U. S. 663 of the Treasury,"
and the Secretary of the Treasury may prescribe rules for
inspection along the borders of Canada, British Columbia, and
Mexico, "provided that not exceeding one inspector shall be
appointed for each customs district."
It was argued that the appointment of Hatch was illegal because
it was made by the Secretary of the Treasury, and should have been
made by the Superintendent of Immigration. But the Constitution
does not allow Congress to vest the appointment of inferior
officers elsewhere than "in the President alone, in the courts of
law, or in the heads of departments." The act of 1891 manifestly
contemplates and intends that the inspectors of immigration shall
be appointed by the Secretary of the Treasury, and appointments of
such officers by the Superintendent of Immigration could be upheld
only by presuming them to be made with the concurrence or approval
of the Secretary of the Treasury, his official head. Constitution,
Art. II, Section 2; United States v.
Hartwell , 6 Wall. 385; Stanton v.
Wilkeson, 8 Ben. 357; Price v. Abbott, 17 F. 506.
It was also argued that Hatch's proceedings did not conform to
section 8 of the act of 1891 because it did not appear that he took
testimony on oath, and because there was no record of any testimony
or of his decision. But the statute does not require inspectors to
take any testimony at all, and allows them to decide on their own
inspection and examination the question of the right of any alien
immigrant to land. The provision relied on merely empowers
inspectors to administer oaths, and to take and consider testimony,
and requires only testimony so taken to be entered of record.
The decision of the Inspector of Immigration being in conformity
with the act of 1891, there can be no doubt that it was final and
conclusive against the petitioner's right to land in the Unites
states. The words of section 8 are clear to that effect, and were
manifestly intended to prevent the question of an alien immigrant's
right to land, when once decided adversely by an inspector, acting
within the jurisdiction conferred upon him, from being impeached or
reviewed, in the courts or otherwise, save only by appeal to the
inspector's Page 142 U. S. 664 official superiors, and in accordance with the provisions of the
act. Section 13, by which the circuit and district courts of the
United States are "invested with full and concurrent jurisdiction
of all causes, civil and criminal, arising under any of the
provisions of this act," evidently refers to causes of judicial
cognizance, already provided for, whether civil actions in the
nature of debt for penalties under sections 3 and 4, or indictments
for misdemeanors under section 6, 8, and 10. Its intention was to
vest concurrent jurisdiction of such causes in the circuit and
district courts, and it is impossible to construe it as giving the
courts jurisdiction to determine matters which the act has
expressly committed to the final determination of executive
officers.
The result is that the act of 1891 is constitutional and valid;
the Inspector of Immigration was duly appointed; his decision
against the petitioner's right to land in the United States was
within the authority conferred upon him by that act; no appeal
having been taken to the Superintendent of Immigration, that
decision was final and conclusive; the petitioner is not unlawfully
restrained of her liberty, and the order of the circuit court
is Affirmed. MR. JUSTICE BREWER dissented.
*
"SEC. 1. The following classes of aliens shall be excluded from
admission into the United States in accordance with the existing
acts regulating immigration other than those concerning Chinese
laborers: all idiots, insane persons, paupers or persons likely to
become a public charge, persons suffering from a loathsome or a
dangerous contagious disease, persons who have been convicted of a
felony or other infamous crime or misdemeanor involving moral
turpitude,"
etc.
By sections 3 and 4, certain offenses are defined and subjected
to the penalties imposed by the Act of February 26, 1885, c. 164,
section 3, namely, penalties of $1,000,
"which may be sued for and recovered by the United States, or by
any person who shall first bring his action therefor, . . . as
debts of like amount are now recovered in the circuit courts of the
United States, the proceeds to be paid into the Treasury of the
United States."
23 Stat. 333.
"SEC. 6. Any person who shall bring into or land in the United
States by vessel or otherwise, or who shall aid to bring into or
land in the United States by vessel or otherwise, any alien not
lawfully entitled to enter the United States, shall be deemed
guilty of a misdemeanor, and shall, on conviction, be punished by a
fine not exceeding one thousand dollars or by imprisonment for a
term not exceeding one year, or by both such fine and
imprisonment."
"SEC. 7. The office of Superintendent of Immigration is hereby
created and established, and the President, by and with the advice
and consent of the Senate, is authorized and directed to appoint
such officer, whose salary shall be four thousand dollars per
annum, payable monthly. The Superintendent of Immigration shall be
an officer in the Treasury Department, under the control and
supervision of the Secretary of the Treasury, to whom he shall make
annual reports in writing of the transactions of his office,
together with such special reports in writing as the Secretary of
the Treasury shall require."
"SEC. 8. Upon the arrival by water at any place within the
United States of any alien immigrants, it shall be the duty of the
commanding officer and the agents of the steam or sailing vessel by
which they came to report the name, nationality, last residence,
and destination of every such alien, before any of them are landed,
to the proper inspection officers, who shall thereupon go or send
competent assistants on board such vessel, and there inspect all
such aliens, or the inspection officers may order a temporary
removal of such aliens for examination at a designated time and
place, and then and there detain them until a thorough inspection
is made. But such removal shall not be considered a landing during
the pendency of such examination. The medical examination shall be
made by surgeons of the marine hospital service. In cases where the
services of a marine hospital surgeon cannot be obtained without
causing unreasonable delay, the inspector may cause an alien to be
examined by a civil surgeon, and the Secretary of the Treasury
shall fix the compensation for such examination. The inspection
officers and their assistants shall have power to administer oaths,
and to take and consider testimony touching the right of any such
aliens to enter the United States, all of which shall be entered of
record. During such inspection, after temporary removal, the
superintendent shall cause such aliens to be properly housed, fed,
and cared for, and also, in his discretion, such as are delayed in
proceeding to their destination after inspection. All decisions
made by the inspection officers or their assistants touching the
right of any alien to land, when adverse to such right, shall be
final unless appeal be taken to the Superintendent of Immigration,
whose action shall be subject to review by the Secretary of the
Treasury. It shall be the duty of the aforesaid officers and agents
of such vessel to adopt due precautions to prevent the landing of
any alien immigrant at any place or time other than that designated
by the inspection officers, and any such officer or agent or person
in charge of such vessel who shall either knowingly or negligently
land or permit to land any alien immigrant at any place or time
other than that designated by the inspection officers shall be
deemed guilty of a misdemeanor, and punished by a fine not
exceeding one thousand dollars or by imprisonment for a term not
exceeding one year, or by both such fine and imprisonment."
"The Secretary of the Treasury may prescribe rules for
inspection along the borders of Canada, British Columbia, and
Mexico so as not to obstruct or unnecessarily delay, impede, or
annoy passengers in ordinary travel between said countries,
provided that not exceeding one inspector shall be appointed for
each customs district, and whose salary shall not exceed twelve
hundred dollars per year."
"All duties imposed and powers conferred by the second section
of the Act of August third, eighteen hundred and eighty-two, upon
state commissioners, boards, or officers acting under contract with
the Secretary of the Treasury, shall be performed and exercised, as
occasion may arise, by the inspection officers of the United
States."
"SEC. 10. All aliens who may unlawfully come to the United
States shall, if practicable, be immediately sent back on the
vessel by which they were brought in. The cost of their maintenance
while on land, as well as the expense of the return of such aliens,
shall be borne by the owner or owners of the vessel on which such
aliens came, and if any master, agent, consignee, or owner of such
vessel shall refuse to receive back on board the vessel such
aliens, or shall neglect to detain them thereon, or shall refuse or
neglect to return them to the port from which they came, or to pay
the cost of their maintenance while on land, such master, agent,
consignee, or owner shall be deemed guilty of a misdemeanor, and
shall be punished by a fine not less than three hundred dollars for
each and every offense, and any such vessel shall not have
clearance from any port of the United States while any such fine is
unpaid."
Section 11 provides for the return within one year of any alien
coming into the United States in violation of law.
Section 12 saves all prosecutions and proceedings, criminal or
civil, begun under any act hereby amended.
By section 13, the circuit and district courts of the United
States are "invested with full and concurrent jurisdiction of all
causes, civil and criminal, arising under any of the provisions of
this act," and the act is to go into effect on April 1, 1891. 26
Stat. 1084-1086. | In Nishimura Ekiu v. United States (1892), the U.S. Supreme Court upheld the constitutionality of the Act of March 3, 1891, which forbade certain classes of alien immigrants from landing in the United States. The case involved a female Japanese subject who was detained at San Francisco and denied entry by an immigration inspector. She challenged her detention through a writ of habeas corpus.
The Court ruled that the decision of an inspector, within their conferred authority, is final and cannot be reviewed through habeas corpus, even if no evidence was recorded. The Court also stated that if there is sufficient ground for the government's detention of an individual, defects in the original arrest or commitment are not grounds for discharge. This case affirmed the power of the federal government to regulate immigration and established the finality of immigration officials' decisions. |
Immigration & National Security | Chae Chan Ping v. U.S. | https://supreme.justia.com/cases/federal/us/130/581/ | U.S. Supreme Court The Chinese Exclusion Case, 130
U.S. 581 (1889) The Chinese Exclusion
Case No. 1448 Argued March 28-29,
1889 Decided May 13, 1889 130
U.S. 581 APPEAL FROM THE CIRCUIT COURT OF
THE UNITED STATES FOR THE NORTHERN DISTRICT OF
CALIFORNIA Syllabus In their relations with foreign governments and their subjects
or citizens, the United States are a nation, invested with the
powers which belong to independent nations.
So far as a treaty made by the United States with any foreign
power can become the subject of judicial cognizance in the courts
of this country, it is subject to such acts as Congress may pass
for its enforcement, modification, or appeal. The Head Money
Cases, 112 U. S. 580 , and Whitney v. Robertson, 124 U. S. 190 ,
followed.
The abrogation of a treaty, like the repeal of a law, operates
only on future transactions, leaving unaffected those executed
under it previous to the abrogation.
The rights and interests created by a treaty, which have become
so vested that its expiration or abrogation will not destroy or
impair them, are such as are connected with and lie in property,
capable of sale and transfer or other disposition, and not such as
are personal and untransferable in their character.
The power of the legislative department of the government to
exclude aliens from the United States is an incident of sovereignty
which cannot be surrendered by the treaty making power.
The Act of October 1, 1888, 25 Stat. 504, c. 1064, excluding
Chinese laborers from the United States, was a constitutional
exercise of legislative power, and, so far as it conflicted with
existing treaties between the United States and China, it operated
to that extent to abrogate them as part of the municipal law of the
United States.
A certificate issued to a Chinese laborer under the fourth and
fifth sections of the Act of May 6, 1882, 22 Stat. 58, c. 126, as
amended July 5, 1884, 23 Stat. 115, c. 220, conferred upon him no
right to return to the United States of which he could not be
deprived by a subsequent act of Congress.
The history of Chinese immigration into the United States
stated, together with a review of the treaties and legislation
affecting it.
The Court stated the case as follows in its opinion:
This case comes before us on appeal from an order of the Circuit
Court of the United States for the Northern District of California
refusing to release the appellant, on a writ of habeas corpus, from
his alleged unlawful detention by Capt. Walker, Page 130 U. S. 582 master of the steamship Belgic, lying within the harbor
of San Francisco. The appellant is a subject of the Emperor of
China, and a laborer by occupation. He resided at San Francisco,
California, following his occupation, from sometime in 1875 until
June 2, 1887, when he left for China on the steamship Gaelic, having in his possession a certificate in terms
entitling him to return to the United States, bearing date on that
day, duly issued to him by the collector of customs of the port of
San Francisco, pursuant to the provisions of § 4 of the Restriction
Act of May 6, 1882, as amended by the Act of July 5, 1884, 22 Stat.
59, c. 126; 23 Stat. 115, c. 220.
On the 7th of September, 1888, the appellant, on his return to
California, sailed from Hong Kong in the steamship Belgic, which arrived within the port of San Francisco on the 8th of
October following. On his arrival, he presented to the proper
custom house officers his certificate and demanded permission to
land. The collector of the port refused the permit solely on the
ground that under the Act of Congress approved October 1, 1888,
supplementary to the Restriction Acts of 1882 and 1884, the
certificate had been annulled and his right to land abrogated, and
he had been thereby forbidden again to enter the United States. 25
Stat. 504, c. 1064. The captain of the steamship therefore detained
the appellant on board the steamer. Thereupon a petition on his
behalf was presented to the Circuit Court of the United States for
the Northern District of California, alleging that he was
unlawfully restrained of his liberty and praying that a writ of
habeas corpus might be issued directed to the master of the
steamship commanding him to have the body of the appellant, with
the cause of his detention, before the court at a time and place
designated, to do and receive what might there be considered in the
premises. A writ was accordingly issued, and in obedience to it the
body of the appellant was produced before the court. Upon the
hearing which followed, the court, after finding the facts
substantially as stated, held as conclusions of law that the
appellant was not entitled to enter the United States and was not
unlawfully restrained of his liberty, and ordered that he be
remanded to the custody of the master of the steamship from Page 130 U. S. 583 which he had been taken under the writ. From this order an
appeal was taken to this Court. Page 130 U. S. 589 MR. JUSTICE FIELD delivered the opinion of the Court.
The appeal involves a consideration of the validity of the Act
of Congress of October 1, 1888, prohibiting Chinese laborers from
entering the United States who had departed before its passage,
having a certificate issued under the act of 1882 as amended by the
act of 1884, granting them permission to return. The validity of
the act is assailed as being in effect an expulsion from the
country of Chinese laborers, in violation of existing treaties
between the United States and the government of China, and of
rights vested in them under the laws of Congress.
It will serve to present with greater clearness the nature and
force of the objections to the act if a brief statement be made of
the general character of the treaties between the two countries and
of the legislation of Congress to carry them into execution. Page 130 U. S. 590 The first treaty between the United States and the Empire of
China was concluded on the 3d of July, 1844, and ratified in
December of the following year. 8 Stat. 592. Previous to that time,
there had been an extensive commerce between the two nations, that
to China being confined to a single port. It was not, however,
attended by any serious disturbances between our people there and
the Chinese. In August, 1842, as the result of a war between
England and China, a treaty was concluded stipulating for peace and
friendship between them, and, among other things, that British
subjects, with their families and establishments, should be allowed
to reside for the purpose of carrying on mercantile pursuits at the
five principal ports of the empire. 6 Hertslet's Commercial
Treaties 221; 3 Nouveau Recueil General de Traites (1842) 484.
Actuated by a desire to establish by treaty friendly relations
between the United States and the Chinese empire and to secure to
our people the same commercial privileges which had been thus
conceded to British subjects, Congress placed at the disposal of
the President the means to enable him to establish future
commercial relations between the two countries "on terms of
national equal reciprocity." Act March, 1843, c. 90, 5 Stat. 624. A
mission was accordingly sent by him to China at the head of which
was placed Mr. Caleb Cushing, a gentleman of large experience in
public affairs. He found the Chinese government ready to concede by
treaty to the United States all that had been reluctantly yielded
to England through compulsion. As the result of his negotiations,
the treaty of 1844 was concluded. It stipulated, among other
things, that there should be a "perfect, permanent, and universal
peace, and a sincere and cordial amity" between the two nations;
that the five principal ports of the empire should be opened to the
citizens of the United States, who should be permitted to reside
with their families and trade there, and to proceed with their
vessels and merchandise to and from any foreign port and either of
said five ports, and while peaceably attending to their affairs
should receive the protection of the Chinese authorities. Senate
Document No. 138, 28th Cong. 2d Sess. Page 130 U. S. 591 The treaty between England and China did not have the effect of
securing permanent peace and friendship between those countries.
British subjects in China were often subjected not only to the
violence of mobs, but to insults and outrages from local
authorities of the country, which led to retaliatory measures for
the punishment of the aggressors. To such an extent were these
measures carried and such resistance offered to them that in 1856,
the two countries were in open war. England then determined with
the cooperation of France, between which countries there seemed to
be perfect accord, to secure from the government of China, among
other things, a recognition of the right of other powers to be
represented there by accredited ministers, an extension of
commercial intercourse with that country, and stipulations for
religious freedom to all foreigners there and for the suppression
of piracy. England requested of the President the concurrence and
active cooperation of the United States similar to that which
France had accorded, and to authorize our naval and political
authorities to act in concert with the allied forces. As this
proposition involved a participation in existing hostilities, the
request could not be acceded to, and the Secretary of State, in his
communication to the English government, explained that the
warmaking power of the United States was not vested in the
President, but in Congress, and that he had no authority therefore
to order aggressive hostilities to be undertaken. But as the rights
of citizens of the United States might be seriously affected by the
results of existing hostilities, and commercial intercourse between
the United States and China be disturbed, it was deemed advisable
to send to China a minister plenipotentiary to represent our
government and watch our interests there. Accordingly, Mr. William
B. Reed, of Philadelphia, was appointed such minister, and
instructed, while abstaining from any direct interference, to aid
by peaceful cooperation the objects the allied forces were seeking
to accomplish. Senate Document No. 47, 35th Cong. 1st Sess. Through
him a new treaty was negotiated with the Chinese government. It was
concluded in June, 1858, and ratified in August of the following
year. Page 130 U. S. 592 12 Stat. 1023. It reiterated the pledges of peace and friendship
between the two nations, renewed the promise of protection to all
citizens of the United States in China peaceably attending to their
affairs, and stipulated for security to Christians in the
profession of their religion.
Neither the treaty of 1844 nor that of 1858 touched upon the
migration and emigration of the citizens and subjects of the two
nations, respectively, from one country to the other. But in 1868,
a great change in the relations of the two nations was made in that
respect. In that year, a mission from China, composed of
distinguished functionaries of that empire, came to the United
States with the professed object of establishing closer relations
between the two countries and their peoples. At its head was placed
Mr. Anson Burlingame, an eminent citizen of the United States who
had at one time represented this country as commissioner to China.
He resigned his office under our government to accept the position
tendered to him by the Chinese government. The mission was hailed
in the United States as the harbinger of a new era in the history
of China -- as the opening up to free intercourse with other
nations and peoples a country that for ages had been isolated and
closed against foreigners, who were allowed to have intercourse and
to trade with the Chinese only at a few designated places, and the
belief was general, and confidently expressed, that great benefits
would follow to the world generally, and especially to the United
States. On its arrival in Washington, additional articles to the
treaty of 1858 were agreed upon which gave expression to the
general desire that the two nations and their peoples should be
drawn closer together. The new articles, eight in number, were
agreed to on the 28th of July, 1868, and ratifications of them were
exchanged at Pekin in November of the following year. 16 Stat. 739.
Of these articles, the fifth, sixth, and seventh are as
follows:
"ARTICLE V. The United States of America and the emperor of
China cordially recognize the inherent and inalienable right of man
to change his home and allegiance, and also the mutual advantage of
the free migration and emigration of their citizens and subjects
respectively from the one country Page 130 U. S. 593 to the other for purposes of curiosity, of trade, or as
permanent residents. The high contracting parties therefore join in
reprobating any other than an entirely voluntary emigration for
these purposes. They consequently agree to pass laws making it a
penal offense for a citizen of the United States or Chinese
subjects to take Chinese subjects either to the United States or to
any other foreign country, or for a Chinese subject or citizen of
the United States to take citizens of the United States to China or
to any other foreign country without their free and voluntary
consent, respectively."
"ARTICLE VI. Citizens of the United States visiting or residing
in China shall enjoy the same privileges, immunities, or exemptions
in respect to travel or residence as may there be enjoyed by the
citizens or subjects of the most favored nation, and reciprocally,
Chinese subjects visiting or residing in the United shall enjoy the
same privileges, immunities, and exemptions in respect to travel or
residence as may there be enjoyed by the citizens or subjects of
the most favored nation. But nothing herein contained shall be held
to confer naturalization upon citizens of the United States in
China, nor upon the subjects of China in the United States."
"ARTICLE VII. Citizens of the United States shall enjoy all the
privileges of the public educational institutions under the control
of the government of China, and, reciprocally, Chinese subjects
shall enjoy all the privileges of the public educational
institutions under the control of the government of the United
States, which are enjoyed in the respective countries by the
citizens or subjects of the most favored nation. The citizens of
the United States may freely establish and maintain schools within
the empire of China at those places where foreigners are by treaty
permitted to reside; and, reciprocally, Chinese subjects may enjoy
the same privileges and immunities in the United States."
But notwithstanding these strong expressions of friendship and
goodwill, and the desire they evince for free intercourse, events
were transpiring on the Pacific coast which soon dissipated the
anticipations indulged as to the benefits to follow the immigration
of Chinese to this country. The previous Page 130 U. S. 594 treaties of 1844 and 1858 were confined principally to mutual
declarations of peace and friendship and to stipulations for
commercial intercourse at certain ports in China and for protection
to our citizens while peaceably attending to their affairs. It was
not until the additional articles of 1868 were adopted that any
public declaration was made by the two nations that there were
advantages in the free migration and emigration of their citizens
and subjects, respectively, from one country to the other, and
stipulations given that each should enjoy in the country of the
other, with respect to travel or residence, the "privileges,
immunities, and exemptions" enjoyed by citizens or subjects of the
most favored nation. Whatever modifications have since been made to
these general provisions have been caused by a well founded
apprehension -- from the experience of years -- that a limitation
to the immigration of certain classes from China was essential to
the peace of the community on the Pacific coast, and possibly to
the preservation of our civilization there. A few words on this
point may not be deemed inappropriate here, they being confined to
matters of public notoriety which have frequently been brought to
the attention of Congress. Report of Committee of H.R. No. 872,
46th Cong. 2d Sess.
The discovery of gold in California in 1848, as is well known,
was followed by a large immigration thither from all parts of the
world, attracted not only by the hope of gain from the mines, but
from the great prices paid for all kinds of labor. The news of the
discovery penetrated China, and laborers came from there in great
numbers, a few with their own means, but by far the greater number
under contract with employers for whose benefit they worked. These
laborers readily secured employment, and, as domestic servants, and
in various kinds of outdoor work, proved to be exceedingly useful.
For some years little opposition was made to them except when they
sought to work in the mines, but, as their numbers increased, they
began to engage in various mechanical pursuits and trades, and thus
came in competition with our artisans and mechanics, as well as our
laborers in the field. The competition steadily increased as the
laborers came in Page 130 U. S. 595 crowds on each steamer that arrived from China, or Hong Kong, an
adjacent English port. They were generally industrious and frugal.
Not being accompanied by families except in rare instances, their
expenses were small and they were content with the simplest fare,
such as would not suffice for our laborers and artisans. The
competition between them and our people was for this reason
altogether in their favor, and the consequent irritation,
proportionately deep and bitter, was followed, in many cases, by
open conflicts, to the great disturbance of the public peace.
The differences of race added greatly to the difficulties of the
situation. Notwithstanding the favorable provisions of the new
articles of the treaty of 1868, by which all the privileges,
immunities, and exemptions were extended to subjects of China in
the United States which were accorded to citizens or subjects of
the most favored nation, they remained strangers in the land,
residing apart by themselves and adhering to the customs and usages
of their own country. It seemed impossible for them to assimilate
with our people or to make any change in their habits or modes of
living. As they grew in numbers each year, the people of the coast
saw, or believed they saw, in the facility of immigration and in
the crowded millions of China, where population presses upon the
means of subsistence, great danger that at no distant day that
portion of our country would be overrun by them unless prompt
action was taken to restrict their immigration. The people there
accordingly petitioned earnestly for protective legislation.
In December, 1878, the convention which framed the present
Constitution of California, being in session, took this subject up
and memorialized Congress upon it, setting forth in substance that
the presence of Chinese laborers had a baneful effect upon the
material interests of the state, and upon public morals; that their
immigration was in numbers approaching the character of an Oriental
invasion, and was a menace to our civilization; that the discontent
from this cause was not confined to any political party, or to any
class or nationality, but was well nigh universal; that they
retained the habits and customs of their own country, and in fact
constituted a Page 130 U. S. 596 Chinese settlement within the state, without any interest in our
country or its institutions, and praying Congress to take measures
to prevent their further immigration. This memorial was presented
to Congress in February, 1879. So urgent and constant were the
prayers for relief against existing and anticipated evils, both
from the public authorities of the Pacific coast and from private
individuals that Congress was impelled to act on the subject. Many
persons, however, both in and out of Congress, were of opinion that
so long as the treaty remained unmodified, legislation restricting
immigration would be a breach of faith with China. A statute was
accordingly passed appropriating money to send commissioners to
China to act with our minister there in negotiating and concluding
by treaty a settlement of such matters of interest between the two
governments as might be confided to them. 21 Stat. 133, c. 88. Such
commissioners were appointed, and as the result of their
negotiations the supplementary treaty of November 17, 1880, was
concluded and ratified in May of the following year. 22 Stat. 826.
It declares in its first article that
"Whenever, in the opinion of the government of the United
States, the coming of Chinese laborers to the United States or
their residence therein affects or threatens to affect the
interests of that country or to endanger the good order of the said
country or of any locality within the territory thereof, the
government of China agrees that the government of the United States
may regulate, limit, or suspend such coming or residence, but may
not absolutely prohibit it. The limitation or suspension shall be
reasonable, and shall apply only to Chinese who may go to the
United States as laborers, other classes not being included in the
limitations. Legislation taken in regard to Chinese laborers will
be of such a character only as is necessary to enforce the
regulation, limitation, or suspension of immigration, and
immigrants shall not be subject to personal maltreatment or
abuse."
In its second article it declares that
"Chinese subjects, whether proceeding to the United States as
teachers, students, merchants, or from curiosity, together with
their body and household servants, and Chinese laborers who are now
in the United States, shall Page 130 U. S. 597 be allowed to go and come of their own free will and accord, and
shall be accorded all the rights, privileges, immunities, and
exemptions which are accorded to the citizens and subjects of the
most favored nation."
The government of China thus agreed that notwithstanding the
stipulations of former treaties, the United States might regulate,
limit, or suspend the coming of Chinese laborers, or their
residence therein, without absolutely forbidding it, whenever in
their opinion the interests of the country, or of any part of it,
might require such action. Legislation for such regulation,
limitation, or suspension was entrusted to the discretion of our
government, with the condition that it should only be such as might
be necessary for that purpose, and that the immigrants should not
be maltreated or abused. On the 6th of May, 1882, an act of
Congress was approved to carry this supplementary treaty into
effect. 22 Stat. 58, c. 126. It is entitled "An act to execute
certain treaty stipulations relating to Chinese." Its first section
declares that after 90 days from the passage of the act, and for
the period of ten years from its date, the coming of Chinese
laborers to the United States is suspended, and that it shall be
unlawful for any such laborer to come, or, having come, to remain
within the United States. The second makes it a misdemeanor,
punishable by fine, to which imprisonment may be added, for the
master of any vessel knowingly to bring within the United States
from a foreign country, and land, any such Chinese laborer. The
third provides that those two sections shall not apply to Chinese
laborers who were in the United States November 17, 1880, or who
shall come within ninety days after the passage of the act. The
fourth declares that, for the purpose of identifying the laborers
who were here on the 17th of November, 1880, or who should come
within the ninety days mentioned, and to furnish them with "the
proper evidence" of their right to go from and come to the United
States, the
"collector of customs of the district from which any such
Chinese laborer shall depart from the United States shall, in
person or by deputy, go on board each vessel having on board any
such Chinese laborer and cleared or about to sail Page 130 U. S. 598 from his district for a foreign port, and on such vessel make a
list of all such Chinese laborers, which shall be entered in
registry books to be kept for that purpose, in which shall be
stated the name, age, occupation, last place of residence, physical
marks or peculiarities, and all facts necessary for the
identification of each of such Chinese laborers, which books shall
be safely kept in the custom house,"
and each laborer thus departing shall be entitled to receive,
from the collector or his deputy, a certificate containing such
particulars, corresponding with the registry, as may serve to
identify him. "The certificate herein provided for," says the
section,
"shall entitle the Chinese laborer to whom the same is issued to
return to and reenter the United States upon producing and
delivering the same to the collector of customs of the district at
which such Chinese laborer shall seek to reenter."
The enforcement of this act with respect to laborers who were in
the United States on November 17, 1880, was attended with great
embarrassment from the suspicious nature, in many instances, of the
testimony offered to establish the residence of the parties,
arising from the loose notions entertained by the witnesses of the
obligation of an oath. This fact led to a desire for further
legislation restricting the evidence receivable, and the amendatory
Act of July 5, 1884, was accordingly passed. 23 Stat. 115, c. 220.
The committee of the House of Representatives on foreign affairs,
to whom the original bill was referred, in reporting it
recommending its passage, stated that there had been such manifold
evasions as well as attempted evasions of the act of 1882 that it
had failed to meet the demands which called it into existence.
Report in H.R. No. 614, 48th Cong. 1st Sess. To obviate the
difficulties attending its enforcement, the amendatory act of 1884
declared that the certificate which the laborer must obtain "shall
be the only evidence permissible to establish his right of reentry"
into the United States.
This act was held by this Court not to require the certificate
from laborers who were in the United States on the 17th of
November, 1880, who had departed out of the country before May 6,
1882, and remained out until after July 5, 1884. Page 130 U. S. 599 Chew Heong v. United States, 112 U.
S. 536 . The same difficulties and embarrassments
continued with respect to the proof of their former residence.
Parties were able to pass successfully the required examination as
to their residence before November 17, 1880, who, it was generally
believed, had never visited our shores. To prevent the possibility
of the policy of excluding Chinese laborers being evaded, the Act
of October 1, 1888, the validity of which is the subject of
consideration in this case, was passed. It is entitled "An act a
supplement to an act entitled An act to execute certain treaty
stipulations relating to Chinese,' approved the 6th day of May,
eighteen hundred and eighty-two." 25 Stat. 504, c. 1064. It is as
follows: " Be it enacted by the Senate and House of Representatives of
the United States of America, in Congress assembled, that from
and after the passage of this act, it shall be unlawful for and
Chinese laborer who shall at any time heretofore have been, or who
may now or hereafter be, a resident within the United States, and
who shall have departed, or shall depart, therefrom, and shall not
have returned before the passage of this act, to return to or
remain the United States."
"SEC. 2. That no certificates of identity provided for in the
fourth and fifth sections of the act to which this is a supplement
shall hereafter be issued, and every certificate heretofore issued
in pursuance thereof is hereby declared void and of no effect, and
the Chinese laborer claiming admission by virtue thereof shall not
be permitted to enter the United States."
"SEC. 3. That all the duties prescribed, liabilities, penalties,
and forfeitures imposed, and the powers conferred, by the second,
tenth, eleventh, and twelfth sections of the act to which this is a
supplement are hereby extended, and made applicable to the
provisions of this act."
"SEC. 4. That all such part or parts of the act to which this is
a supplement as are inconsistent herewith are hereby repealed."
"Approved October 1, 1888."
The validity of this act, as already mentioned, is assailed as
being in effect an expulsion from the country of Chinese Page 130 U. S. 600 laborers in violation of existing treaties between the United
States and the government of China and of rights vested in them
under the laws of Congress. The objection that the act is in
conflict with the treaties was earnestly pressed in the court
below, and the answer to it constitutes the principal part of its
opinion. 36 F. 431. Here, the objection made is that the act of
1888 impairs a right vested under the treaty of 1880, as a law of
the United States, and the statutes of 1882 and of 1884 passed in
execution of it. It must be conceded that the act of 1888 is in
contravention of express stipulations of the treaty of 1868 and of
the supplemental treaty of 1880, but it is not on that account
invalid, or to be restricted in its enforcement. The treaties were
of no greater legal obligation than the act of Congress. By the
Constitution, laws made in pursuance thereof, and treaties made
under the authority of the United States, are both declared to be
the supreme law of the land, and no paramount authority is given to
one over the other. A treaty, it is true, is in its nature a
contract between nations, and is often merely promissory in its
character, requiring legislation to carry its stipulations into
effect. Such legislation will be open to future repeal or
amendment. If the treaty operates by its own force and relates to a
subject within the power of Congress, it can be deemed in that
particular only the equivalent of a legislative act, to be repealed
or modified at the pleasure of Congress. In either case, the last
expression of the sovereign will must control.
The effect of legislation upon conflicting treaty stipulations
was elaborately considered in The Head-Money Cases, and it
was there adjudged
"that so far as a treaty made by the United States with any
foreign nation can become the subject of judicial cognizance in the
courts of this country, it is subject to such acts as Congress may
pass for its enforcement, modification, or repeal." 112 U. S. 112 U.S.
580, 112 U. S. 599 .
This doctrine was affirmed and followed in Whitney v.
Robertson, 124 U. S. 190 , 124 U. S. 195 .
It will not be presumed that the legislative department of the
government will lightly pass laws which are in conflict with the
treaties of the country, but that circumstances may arise which
would not only justify the government in disregarding Page 130 U. S. 601 their stipulations, but demand in the interests of the country
that it should do so, there can be no question. Unexpected events
may call for a change in the policy of the country. Neglect or
violation of stipulations on the part of the other contracting
party may require corresponding action on our part. When a
reciprocal engagement is not carried out by one of the contracting
parties, the other may also decline to keep the corresponding
engagement. In 1798, the conduct toward this country of the
government of France was of such a character that Congress declared
that the United States were freed and exonerated from the
stipulations of previous treaties with that country. Its act on the
subject was as follows:
" An act to declare the treaties heretofore concluded
with France " " no longer obligatory on the United
States " "Whereas, the treaties concluded between the United States and
France have been repeatedly violated on the part of the French
government, and the just claims of the United States for reparation
of the injuries so committed have been refused, and their attempts
to negotiate an amicable adjustment of all complaints between the
two nations have been repelled with indignity, and whereas, under
authority of the French government, there is yet pursued against
the United States a system of predatory violence, infracting the
said treaties, and hostile to the rights of a free and independent
nation,"
" Be it enacted by the Senate and House of Representatives of
the United States of America, in Congress assembled, that the
United States are of right freed and exonerated from the
stipulations of the treaties, and of the consular convention,
heretofore concluded between the United States and France, and that
the same shall not henceforth be regarded as legally obligatory on
the government or citizens of the United States."
1 Stat. 578, c. 67.
This act, as seen, applied in terms only to the future. Of
course, whatever of a permanent character had been executed or
vested under the treaties was not affected by it. In that respect,
the abrogation of the obligations of a treaty operates, Page 130 U. S. 602 like the repeal of a law, only upon the future, leaving
transactions executed under it to stand unaffected. The validity of
this legislative release from the stipulations of the treaties was,
of course, not a matter for judicial cognizance. The question
whether our government is justified in disregarding its engagements
with another nation is not one for the determination of the courts.
This subject was fully considered by Mr. Justice Curtis, while
sitting at the circuit, in Taylor v. Morton, 2 Curtis 454,
459, and he held that while it would always be a matter of the
utmost gravity and delicacy to refuse to execute a treaty, the
power to do so was prerogative of which no nation could be deprived
without deeply affecting its independence; but whether a treaty
with a foreign sovereign had been violated by him, whether the
consideration of a particular stipulation of a treaty had been
voluntarily withdrawn by one party so as to no longer be obligatory
upon the other, and whether the views and acts of a foreign
sovereign, manifested through his representative, had given just
occasion to the political departments of our government to withhold
tax execution of a promise contained in a treaty or to act in
direct contravention of such promise were not judicial questions;
that the power to determine them has not been confided to the
judiciary, which has no suitable means to execute it, but to the
executive and legislative departments of the government, and that
it belongs to diplomacy and legislation, and not to the
administration of existing laws. And the learned justice added, as
a necessary consequence of these conclusions, that if Congress has
this power it is wholly immaterial to inquire whether it has, by
the statute complained of, departed from the treaty or not -- or,
if it has, whether such departure was accidental or designed --
and, if the latter, whether the reasons therefor were good or bad.
These views were reasserted and fully adopted by this Court in Whitney v. Robertson, 124 U. S. 190 , 124 U. S. 195 .
And we may add to the concluding observation of the learned justice
that if the power mentioned is vested in Congress, any reflection
upon its motives or the motives of any of its members in exercising
it would be entirely uncalled for. This Court is not a censor of
the morals Page 130 U. S. 603 of other departments of the government; it is not invested with
any authority to pass judgment upon the motives of their conduct.
When once it is established that Congress possesses the power to
pass an act, our province ends with its construction and its
application to cases as they are presented for determination.
Congress has the power under the Constitution to declare war, and
in two instances where the power has been exercised -- in the war
of 1812 against Great Britain and in 1846 against Mexico -- the
propriety and wisdom and justice of its action were vehemently
assailed by some of the ablest and best men in the country, but no
one doubted the legality of the proceeding, and any imputation by
this or any other court of the United States upon the motives of
the members of Congress who in either case voted for the
declaration would have been justly the cause of animadversion. We
do not mean to intimate that the moral aspects of legislative acts
may not be proper subjects of consideration. Undoubtedly they may
be at proper times and places, before the public, in the halls of
Congress, and in all the modes by which the public mind can be
influenced. Public opinion thus enlightened, brought to bear upon
legislation, will do more than all other causes to prevent abuses;
but the province of the courts is to pass upon the validity of
laws, not to make them, and when their validity is established, to
declare their meaning and apply their provisions. All else lies
beyond their domain.
There being nothing in the treaties between China and the United
States to impair the validity of the act of Congress of October 1,
1888, was it on any other ground beyond the competency of Congress
to pass it? If so, it must be because it was not within the power
of Congress to prohibit Chinese laborers who had at the time
departed from the United States, or should subsequently depart,
from returning to the United States. Those laborers are not
citizens of the United States; they are aliens. That the government
of the United States, through the action of the legislative
department, can exclude aliens from its territory is a proposition
which we do not think open to controversy. Jurisdiction over its
own territory to that extent is an incident of every independent
nation. It is a part of its independence. Page 130 U. S. 604 If it could not exclude aliens, it would be to that extent
subject to the control of another power. As said by this Court in
the case of The Exchange , 7 Cranch 116, 11 U. S. 136 ,
speaking by Chief Justice Marshall:
"The jurisdiction of the nation within its own territory is
necessarily exclusive and absolute. It is susceptible of no
limitation not imposed by itself. Any restriction upon it deriving
validity from an external source would imply a diminution of its
sovereignty to the extent of the restriction and an investment of
that sovereignty to the same extent in that power which could
impose such restriction. All exceptions, therefore, to the full and
complete power of a nation within its own territories must be
traced up to the consent of the nation itself. They can flow from
no other legitimate source."
While under our Constitution and form of government the great
mass of local matters is controlled by local authorities, the
United States, in their relation to foreign countries and their
subjects or citizens, are one nation, invested with powers which
belong to independent nations, the exercise of which can be invoked
for the maintenance of its absolute independence and security
throughout its entire territory. The powers to declare war, make
treaties, suppress insurrection, repel invasion, regulate foreign
commerce, secure republican governments to the states, and admit
subjects of other nations to citizenship are all sovereign powers,
restricted in their exercise only by the Constitution itself and
considerations of public policy and justice which control, more or
less, the conduct of all civilized nations. As said by this Court
in the case of Cohens v.
Virginia , 6 Wheat. 264, 19 U. S. 413 ,
speaking by the same great Chief Justice:
"That the United States form, for many, and for most important
purposes, a single nation, has not yet been denied. In war, we are
one people. In making peace, we are one people. In all commercial
regulations, we are one and the same people. In many other
respects, the American people are one, and the government which is
alone capable of controlling and managing their interests in all
these respects is the government of the union. It is their
government, and in that character they have no other. America has
chosen to Page 130 U. S. 605 be in many respects, and to many purposes, a nation, and for all
these purposes her government is complete; to all these objects, it
is competent. The people have declared that in the exercise of all
powers given for these objects, it is supreme. It can, then, in
effecting these objects, legitimately control all individuals or
governments within the American territory. The Constitution and
laws of a state, so far as they are repugnant to the Constitution
and laws of the United States, are absolutely void. These states
are constituent parts of the United States. They are members of one
great empire -- for some purposes sovereign, for some purposes
subordinate."
The same view is expressed in a different form by MR. JUSTICE
BRADLEY in Knox v. Lee , 12 Wall. 457, 79 U. S. 555 ,
where he observes that
"the United States is not only a government, but it is a
national government, and the only government in this country that
has the character of nationality. It is invested with power over
all the foreign relations of the country, war, peace, and
negotiations and intercourse with other nations, all of which are
forbidden to the state governments. It has jurisdiction over all
those general subjects of legislation and sovereignty which affect
the interests of the whole people equally and alike, and which
require uniformity of regulations and laws, such as the coinage,
weights, and measures, bankruptcies, the postal system, patent and
copyright laws, the public lands, and interstate commerce -- all
which subjects are expressly or impliedly prohibited to the state
governments. It has power to suppress insurrections as well as to
repel invasions, and to organize, arm, discipline, and call into
service the militia of the whole country. The President is charged
with the duty and invested with the power to take care that the
laws be faithfully executed. The judiciary has jurisdiction to
decide controversies between the states, and between their
respective citizens, as well as questions of national concern, and
the government is clothed with power to guaranty to every state a
republican government and to protect each of them against invasion
and domestic violence."
The control of local matters being left to local authorities,
and national matters being entrusted to the government of the Page 130 U. S. 606 union, the problem of free institutions existing over a widely
extended country, having different climates and varied interests,
has been happily solved. For local interests, the several states of
the union exist, but for national purposes, embracing our relations
with foreign nations, we are but one people, one nation, one
power.
To preserve its independence, and give security against foreign
aggression and encroachment, is the highest duty of every nation,
and to attain these ends nearly all other considerations are to be
subordinated. It matters not in what form such aggression and
encroachment come, whether from the foreign nation acting in its
national character, or from vast hordes of its people crowding in
upon us. The government, possessing the powers which are to be
exercised for protection and security, is clothed with authority to
determine the occasion on which the powers shall be called forth,
and its determinations, so far as the subjects affected are
concerned, are necessarily conclusive upon all its departments and
officers. If, therefore, the government of the United States,
through its legislative department, considers the presence of
foreigners of a different race in this country, who will not
assimilate with us, to be dangerous to its peace and security,
their exclusion is not to be stayed because at the time there are
no actual hostilities with the nation of which the foreigners are
subjects. The existence of war would render the necessity of the
proceeding only more obvious and pressing. The same necessity, in a
less pressing degree, may arise when war does not exist, and the
same authority which adjudges the necessity in one case must also
determine it in the other. In both cases, its determination is
conclusive upon the judiciary. If the government of the country of
which the foreigners excluded are subjects is dissatisfied with
this action, it can make complaint to the executive head of our
government, or resort to any other measure which in its judgment
its interests or dignity may demand, and there lies its only
remedy.
The power of the government to exclude foreigners from the
country whenever in its judgment the public interests require such
exclusion has been asserted in repeated instances, Page 130 U. S. 607 and never denied by the executive or legislative departments. In
a communication made in December, 1852, to Mr. A. Dudley Mann at
one time a special agent of the Department of State in Europe, Mr.
Everett, then Secretary of State under President Fillmore,
writes:
"This government could never give up the right of excluding
foreigners whose presence it might deem a source of danger to the
United States. . . . Nor will this government consider such
exclusion of American citizens from Russia necessarily a matter of
diplomatic complaint to that country."
In a dispatch to Mr. Fay, our minister to Switzerland, in March,
1856, Mr. Marcy, Secretary of State under President Pierce,
writes:
"Every society possesses the undoubted right to determine who
shall compose its members, and it is exercised by all nations, both
in peace and war. . . . It may always be questionable whether a
resort to this power is warranted by the circumstances or what
department of the government is empowered to exert it, but there
can be no doubt that it is possessed by all nations and that each
may decide for itself when the occasion arises demanding its
exercise."
In a communication in September, 1869, to Mr. Washburne, our
minister to France, Mr. Fish, Secretary of State under President
Grant, uses this language:
"The control of the people within its limits, and the right to
expel from its territory persons who are dangerous to the peace of
the state, are too clearly within the essential attributes of
sovereignty to be seriously contested. Strangers visiting or
sojourning in a foreign country voluntarily submit themselves to
its laws and customs, and the municipal laws of France, authorizing
the expulsion of strangers, are not of such recent date, nor has
the exercise of the power by the government of France been so
infrequent, that sojourners within her territory can claim surprise
when the power is put in force."
In a communication to Mr. Foster, our minister to Mexico, in
July, 1879, Mr. Evarts, Secretary of State under President Hayes,
referring to the power vested in the Constitution of Mexico to
expel objectionable foreigners, says:
"The admission that, as that constitution now stands and is
interpreted, foreigners who render themselves harmful or
objectionable to the general government Page 130 U. S. 608 must expect to be liable to the exercise of the power adverted
to, even in time of peace, remains, and no good reason is seen for
departing from that conclusion now. But while there may be no
expedient basis on which to found objection, on principle and in
advance of a special case thereunder, to the constitutional right
thus asserted by Mexico, yet the manner of carrying out such
asserted right may be highly objectionable. You would be fully
justified in making earnest remonstrances should a citizen of the
United States be expelled from Mexican territory without just steps
to assure the grounds of such expulsion, and in bringing the fact
to the immediate knowledge of the department."
In a communication to Mr. W. J. Stillman, under date of August
3, 1882, Mr. Frelinghuysen, Secretary of State under President
Arthur, writes: "Thus, government cannot contest the right of
foreign governments to exclude, on police or other grounds,
American citizens from their shores." Wharton's International Law
Digest § 206.
The exclusion of paupers, criminals, and persons afflicted with
incurable diseases, for which statutes have been passed, is only an
application of the same power to particular classes of persons,
whose presence is deemed injurious or a source of danger to the
country. As applied to them, there has never been any question as
to the power to exclude them. The power is constantly exercised;
its existence is involved in the right of self-preservation. As to
paupers, it makes no difference by whose aid they are brought to
the country. As Mr. Fish, when Secretary of State, wrote in a
communication under date of December 26, 1872, to Mr. James
Moulding, of Liverpool, the government of the United States
"is not willing and will not consent to receive the pauper class
of any community who may be sent or may be assisted in their
immigration at the expense of government or of municipal
authorities."
As to criminals, the power of exclusion has always been
exercised, even in the absence of any statute on the subject. In a
dispatch to Mr. Cramer, our minister to Switzerland, in December,
1881, Mr. Blaine, Secretary of State under President Arthur,
writes:
"While, under the Constitution and Page 130 U. S. 609 the laws, this country is open to the honest and the industrious
immigrant, it has no room outside of its prisons or almshouses for
depraved and incorrigible criminals or hopelessly dependent paupers
who may have become a pest or burden, or both, to their own
country."
Wharton's Int.Law Dig., supra. The power of exclusion of foreigners being an incident of
sovereignty belonging to the government of the United States as a
part of those sovereign powers delegated by the Constitution, the
right to its exercise at any time when, in the judgment of the
government, the interests of the country require it, cannot be
granted away or restrained on behalf of anyone.
The powers of government are delegated in trust to the United
States, and are incapable of transfer to any other parties. They
cannot be abandoned or surrendered. Nor can their exercise be
hampered, when needed for the public good, by any considerations of
private interest. The exercise of these public trusts is not the
subject of barter or contract. Whatever license, therefore, Chinese
laborers may have obtained, previous to the Act of October 1, 1888,
to return to the United States after their departure is held at the
will of the government, revocable at any time at its pleasure.
Whether a proper consideration by our government of its previous
laws or a proper respect for the nation whose subjects are affected
by its action ought to have qualified its inhibition and made it
applicable only to persons departing from the country after the
passage of the act are not questions for judicial determination. If
there be any just ground of complaint on the part of China, it must
be made to the political department of our government, which is
alone competent to act upon the subject. The rights and interests
created by a treaty, which have become so vested that its
expiration or abrogation will not destroy or impair them, are such
as are connected with and lie in property capable of sale and
transfer, or other disposition, not such as are personal and
untransferable in their character. Thus, in The Head-Money
Cases, the Court speaks of certain rights being in some
instances conferred upon the citizens or subjects of one nation
residing in the territorial limits of the other, which are "capable
of enforcement as Page 130 U. S. 610 between private parties in the courts of the country." "An
illustration of this character," it adds,
"is found in treaties which regulate the mutual rights of
citizens and subjects of the contracting nations in regard to
rights of property by descent or inheritance, when the individuals
concerned are aliens." 112 U. S. 112 U.S.
580, 112 U. S. 598 .
The passage cited by counsel from the language of Mr. Justice
Washington in Society for the Propagation of
the Gospel v. New Haven , 8 Wheat. 464, 21 U. S. 493 ,
also illustrates this doctrine. There, the learned Justice observes
that
"if real estate be purchased or secured under a treaty, it would
be most mischievous to admit that the extinguishment of the treaty
extinguished the right to such estate. In truth, it no more affects
such rights than the repeal of a municipal law affects rights
acquired under it."
Of this doctrine there can be no question in this Court; but far
different is this case, where a continued suspension of the
exercise of a governmental power is insisted upon as a right
because, by the favor and consent of the government, it has not
heretofore been exerted with respect to the appellant or to the
class to which he belongs. Between property rights not affected by
the termination or abrogation of a treaty and expectations of
benefits from the continuance of existing legislation there is as
wide a difference as between realization and hopes.
During the argument, reference was made by counsel to the Alien
Law of June 25, 1798, and to opinions expressed at the time by men
of great ability and learning against its constitutionality. 1
Stat. 570, c. 58. We do not attach importance to those opinions in
their bearing upon this case. The act vested in the President power
to order all such aliens as he should judge dangerous to the peace
and safety of the United States, or should have reasonable grounds
to suspect were concerned in any treasonable or secret machination
against the government, to depart out of the territory of the
United States within such time as should be expressed in his order.
There were other provisions also distinguishing it from the act
under consideration. The act was passed during a period of great
political excitement, and it was attacked and defended with
great Page 130 U. S. 611 zeal and ability. It is enough, however, to say that it is
entirely different from the act before us, and the validity of its
provisions was never brought to the test of judicial decision in
the courts of the United States. Order affirmed. | Here is a summary of the key points from the case:
- The United States, as a sovereign nation, has the power to exclude aliens from entering the country, and this power cannot be surrendered through treaty-making.
- The Chinese Exclusion Act of 1888, which excluded Chinese laborers from entering the United States, was a constitutional exercise of legislative power. It took precedence over existing treaties with China, effectively abrogating them to that extent.
- Certificates issued to Chinese laborers under previous legislation did not confer an irrevocable right to return to the United States; Congress had the authority to revoke or modify those rights through subsequent acts.
- The Court affirmed the lower court's order, upholding the detention of the Chinese laborer and his exclusion from the United States under the Chinese Exclusion Act.
This case established the principle that the power to exclude aliens is an inherent aspect of national sovereignty and that Congress has the authority to enact legislation restricting immigration, even if it conflicts with existing treaties. |
Lawsuits & Legal Procedures | Strawbridge v. Curtiss | https://supreme.justia.com/cases/federal/us/7/267/ | U.S. Supreme Court Strawbridge v. Curtiss, 7 U.S. 3
Cranch 267 267 (1806) Strawbridge v.
Curtiss 7 U.S. (3 Cranch) 267 APPEAL FROM THE CIRCUIT COURT
OF THE DISTRICT OF
MASSACHUSETTS Syllabus If there be two or more joint plaintiffs, and two or more joint
defendants, each of the plaintiffs must be capable of suing each of
the defendants in the courts of the United States to sustain the
jurisdiction of the court.
The Court understands the expressions in the act of Congress
giving jurisdiction to the courts of the United States "when an
alien is a party, or the suit is between a citizen of the state
where the suit is brought, and a citizen of another state" to mean
that each distinct interest should be represented by persons all of
whom are entitled to sue or may be sued in the federal courts --
that is, where the interest is joint, each of the persons concerned
in that interest must be competent to sue or liable to be sued in
those courts.
This was an appeal from a decree of the Circuit Court for the
District of Massachusetts, which dismissed the complainants' bill
in chancery for want of jurisdiction.
Some of the complainants were alleged to be citizens of the
State of Massachusetts. The defendants were also stated to be
citizens of the same state, excepting Curtiss, who was averred to
be a citizen of the State of Vermont, and upon whom the subpoena
was served in that state.
MR. CHIEF JUSTICE MARSHALL delivered the opinion of the
Court.
The Court has considered this case and is of opinion that the
jurisdiction cannot be supported.
The words of the act of Congress are "where an alien is a party
or the suit is between a citizen of a state where the suit is
brought and a citizen of another state."
The Court understands these expressions to mean that each
distinct interest should be represented by persons all of whom are
entitled to sue or may be sued in the federal courts. That is, that
where the interest is joint, each of the persons concerned in that
interest must be competent to sue or liable to be sued in those
courts.
But the Court does not mean to give an opinion in the case where
several parties represent several distinct interests Page 7 U. S. 268 and some of those parties are and others are not competent to
sue or liable to be sued in the courts of the United States. Decree affirmed. | Here is a summary of the Supreme Court case Strawbridge v. Curtiss (1806):
Summary:
In Strawbridge v. Curtiss, the Supreme Court interpreted a provision in the Judiciary Act of 1789 that granted federal courts jurisdiction in cases involving diversity of citizenship. The Court held that for a federal court to have jurisdiction over a case with multiple plaintiffs and defendants, each plaintiff must be capable of suing each defendant in federal court. In other words, there must be complete diversity of citizenship between the plaintiffs and defendants.
Facts:
The case involved an appeal from a decree of the Circuit Court for the District of Massachusetts, which dismissed a bill in chancery (a type of equitable relief) for lack of jurisdiction. Some of the plaintiffs were citizens of Massachusetts, and the defendants were also citizens of the same state, except for one defendant who was a citizen of Vermont.
Issue:
The question before the Supreme Court was whether the federal court had jurisdiction over the case, given the diversity of citizenship requirement in the Judiciary Act of 1789.
Holding:
The Supreme Court held that the jurisdiction could not be supported. The Court interpreted the relevant provision in the Judiciary Act to mean that each distinct interest in a case should be represented by persons all of whom are entitled to sue or be sued in federal court. In other words, there must be complete diversity of citizenship between the plaintiffs and defendants for a federal court to have jurisdiction.
Effect:
The decision in Strawbridge v. Curtiss established the complete diversity requirement for federal court jurisdiction in cases involving multiple parties. This requirement has been a significant factor in shaping federal court jurisdiction and has been reaffirmed and clarified in subsequent Supreme Court cases. |
Lawsuits & Legal Procedures | Pennoyer v. Neff | https://supreme.justia.com/cases/federal/us/95/714/ | U.S. Supreme Court Pennoyer v. Neff, 95 U.S.
714 (1878) Pennoyer v. Neff 95 U.S.
714 ERROR TO THE CIRCUIT COURT OF THE
UNITED STATES FOR THE DISTRICT OF
OREGON Syllabus 1. A statute of Oregon, after providing for service of summons
upon parties or their representatives, personally or at their
residence, declares that, when service cannot be thus made, and the
defendant, after due diligence, cannot be found within the State,
and
"that fact appears, by affidavit, to the satisfaction of the
court or judge thereof, and it, in like manner, appears that a
cause of action exists against the defendant, or that he is a
proper party to an action relating to real property in the State,
such court or judge may grant an order that the service be made by
publication of summons . . . when the defendant is not a resident
of the State, but has property therein, and the court has
jurisdiction of the subject of the action,"
-- the order to designate a newspaper of the county where the
action is commenced in which the publication shall be made -- and
that proof of such publication shall be "the affidavit of the
printer, or his foreman, or his principal clerk." Held, that defects in the affidavit for the order can
only be taken advantage of on appeal, or by some other direct
proceeding, and cannot be urged to impeach the judgment
collaterally, and that the provision as to proof of the publication
is satisfied when the affidavit is made by the editor of the
paper.
2. A personal judgment is without any validity if it be rendered
by a State court in an action upon a money demand against a
nonresident of the State who was served by a publication of
summons, but upon whom no personal service of process within the
State was made, and who did not appear; and no title to property
passes by a sale under an execution issued upon such a
judgment.
3. The State, having within her territory property of a
nonresident, may hold and appropriate it to satisfy the claims of
her citizens against him, and her tribunals may inquire into his
obligations to the extent necessary to control the disposition of
that property. If he has no property in the State, there is nothing
upon which her tribunals can adjudicate.
4. Substituted service by publication, or in any other
authorized form, is sufficient to inform a nonresident of the
object of proceedings taken where Page 95 U. S. 715 property is once brought under the control of the court by
seizure or some equivalent act, but where the suit is brought to
determine his personal rights and obligations, that is, where it is
merely in personam, such service upon him is ineffectual
for any purpose.
5. Process from the tribunals of one State cannot run into
another State and summon a party there domiciled to respond to
proceedings against him, and publication of process or of notice
within the State in which the tribunal sits cannot create any
greater obligation upon him to appear. Process sent to him out of
the State, and process published within it, are equally unavailing
in proceedings to establish his personal liability.
6. Except in cases affecting the personal status of the
plaintiff, and in those wherein that mode of service may be
considered to have been assented to in advance, the substituted
service of process by publication allowed by the law of Oregon and
by similar laws in other States where actions are brought against
nonresidents is effectual only where, in connection with process
against the person for commencing the action, property in the State
is brought under the control of the court and subjected to its
disposition by process adapted to that purpose, or where the
judgment is sought as a means of reaching such property or
affecting some interest therein; in other words, where the action
is in the nature of a proceeding in rem. 7. Whilst the courts of the United States are not foreign
tribunals in their relations to the State courts, they are
tribunals of a different sovereignty, and are bound to give a
judgment of a State court only the same faith and credit to which
it is entitled in the courts of another State.
8. The term "due process of law," when applied to judicial
proceedings, means a course of legal proceedings according to those
rules and principles which have been established by our
jurisprudence for the protection and enforcement of private rights.
To give such proceedings any validity, there must be a competent
tribunal to pass upon their subject matter, and if that involves
merely a determination of the personal liability of the defendant,
he must be brought within its jurisdiction by service of process
within the State, or by his voluntary appearance.
This action was brought by Neff against Pennoyer for the
recovery of a tract of land situated in Multnomah County, Oregon.
Pennoyer, in his answer, denied Neff's title and right to
possession, and set up a title in himself.
By consent of parties, and in pursuance of their written
stipulation filed in the case, the cause was tried by the court,
and a special verdict given, upon which judgment was rendered in
favor of Neff; whereupon Pennoyer sued out this writ of error.
The parties respectively claimed title as follows: Neff under a
patent issued to him by the United States, March 19, Page 95 U. S. 716 1866; and Pennoyer by virtue of a sale made by the sheriff of
said county, under an execution sued out upon a judgment against
Neff, rendered Feb. 19, 1866, by the Circuit Court for said county,
in an action wherein he was defendant and J. H. Mitchell was
plaintiff. Neff was then a nonresident of Oregon.
In Mitchell v. Neff, jurisdiction of Neff was obtained
by service of summons by publication. Pennoyer offered in evidence
duly certified copies of the complaint, summons, order for
publication of summons, affidavit of service by publication, and
the judgment in that case, to the introduction of which papers the
plaintiff objected because, 1, said judgment is in
personam, and appears to have been given without the
appearance of the defendant in the action or personal service of
the summons upon him, and while he was a nonresident of the State,
and is, therefore, void; 2, said judgment is not in rem, and therefore constitutes no basis of title in the defendant; 3,
said copies of complaint, &c., do not show jurisdiction to give
the judgment alleged, either in rem or personam; and, 4, it appears from said papers that no proof of service by
publication was ever made, the affidavit thereof being made by the
"editor" of the "Pacific Christian Advocate," and not by "the
printer, or his foreman or principal clerk." The court admitted the
evidence subject to the objections.
The finding of the court in regard to the facts bearing upon the
asserted jurisdiction of the State court is as follows: --
That, on Nov. 13, 1865, Mitchell applied to said Circuit Court,
upon his own affidavit of that date, for an order allowing the
service of the summons in said action to be made upon Neff by
publication thereof, whereupon said court made said order, in the
words following:
"Now, at this day, comes the plaintiff in his proper person, and
by his attorneys, Mitchell and Dolph, and files affidavit of
plaintiff, and motion for an order of publication of summons, as
follows, to wit:"
"Now comes the plaintiff, by his attorneys, and upon the
affidavit of plaintiff, herewith filed, moves the court for an
order of publication of summons against defendant, as required by
law, he being a nonresident;"
"and it appearing to the satisfaction of the court that the
defendant cannot, after due diligence, be Page 95 U. S. 717 found in this State, and that he is a nonresident thereof, that
his place of residence is unknown to plaintiff, and cannot, with
reasonable diligence, be ascertained by him, and that the plaintiff
has a cause of action of action against defendant, and that
defendant has property in this county and State, it is ordered and
adjudged by the court that service of the summons in this action be
made by publication for six weeks successively in the 'Pacific
Christian Advocate,' a weekly newspaper published in Multnomah
County, Oregon, and this action is continued for such service."
That the affidavit of plaintiff, referred to in said order, is
in the words following:
"I, J. H. Mitchell, being first duly sworn, say that the
defendant, Marcus Neff, is a nonresident of this State; that he
resides somewhere in the State of California, at what place affiant
knows not, and he cannot be found in this State; that plaintiff has
a just cause of action against defendant for a money demand on
account; that this court has jurisdiction of such action; that the
defendant has property in this county and State."
That the complaint in said action was verified and filed on Nov.
3, 1865, and contained facts tending to prove that, at that date,
said Mitchell had a cause of action against said Neff for services
as an attorney, performed "between Jan. 1, 1862, and May 15, 1863."
That the entry of judgment in said action contained the following
averments:
"And it appearing to the court that the defendant was, at the
time of the commencement of this action, and ever since has been, a
nonresident of this State; and it further appearing that he has
property in this State, and that defendant had notice of the
pendency of this action by publication of the summons for six
successive weeks in the 'Pacific Christian Advocate,' a weekly
newspaper of general circulation published in Multnomah County,
State of Oregon, the last issue of which was more than twenty days
before the first day of this term."
That the affidavit showing the publication of the summons in the
"Advocate" aforesaid was made as stated therein by the "editor" of
that paper. That said complaint, summons, affidavit of Mitchell and
of the "editor" of the "Advocate" aforesaid, and entry of judgment,
were in the judgment roll, made up by the clerk in the case, but
the order for publication of the summons aforesaid was not placed
in said roll Page 95 U. S. 718 by said clerk, but remains on the files of said court; and that,
when said court made said order for publication, and gave said
judgment against Neff, the only evidence it had before it to prove
the facts necessary to give it jurisdiction therefor, and
particularly to authorize it to find and state that Neff's
residence was unknown to Mitchell, and could not, with reasonable
diligence, be ascertained by him, and that Neff had notice of the
pendency of said action by the publication of the summons as
aforesaid, was, so far as appears by the said roll and the records
and files of the said court, the said complaint and affidavits of
Mitchell and the editor of the "Advocate."
The statute of Oregon at the time of the commencement of the
suit against Neff was as follows: --
"SECT. 55. When service of the summons cannot be made as
prescribed in the last preceding section, and the defendant, after
due diligence, cannot be found within the State, and when that fact
appears, by affidavit, to the satisfaction of the court or judge
thereof, or justice in an action in a justice's court, and it also
appears that a cause of action exists against the defendant, or
that he is a proper party to an action relating to real property in
this State, such court or judge or justice may grant an order that
the service be made by publication of summons in either of the
following cases: . . ."
"3. When the defendant is not a resident of the State, but has
property therein, and the court has jurisdiction of the subject of
the action."
"SECT. 56. The order shall direct the publication to be made in
a newspaper published in the county where the action is commenced,
and, if no newspaper be published in the county, then in a
newspaper to be designated as most likely to give notice to the
person to be served, and for such length of time as may be deemed
reasonable, not less than once a week for six weeks. In case of
publication, the court or judge shall also direct a copy of the
summons and complaint to be forthwith deposited in the post office,
directed to the defendant, at his place of residence, unless it
shall appear that such residence is neither known to the party
making the application, nor can, with reasonable diligence, be
ascertained by him. When publication is ordered, personal service
of a copy of the summons and complaint out of the State shall be
equivalent to publication and deposit in the post office. In either
case, the defendant shall appear and answer by the first day of the
term following the Page 95 U. S. 719 expiration of the time prescribed in the order for publication;
and, if he does not, judgment may be taken against him for want
thereof. In case of personal service out of the State, the summons
shall specify the time prescribed in the order for
publication."
"SECT. 57. The defendant against whom publication is ordered, or
his personal representatives, on application and sufficient cause
shown, at any time before judgment, shall be allowed to defend the
action; and the defendant against whom publication is ordered, or
his representatives, may in like manner, upon good cause shown, and
upon such terms as may be proper, be allowed to defend after
judgment, and within one year after the entry of such judgment, on
such terms as may be just; and, if the defence be successful, and
the judgment or any part thereof have been collected or otherwise
enforced, such restitution may thereupon be compelled as the court
shall direct. But the title to property sold upon execution issued
on such judgment to a purchaser in good faith shall not be thereby
affected."
"SECT. 60. Proof of the service of summons shall be, in case of
publication, the affidavit of the printer, or his foreman, or his
principal clerk, showing the same."
MR. JUSTICE FIELD delivered the opinion of the court.
This is an action to recover the possession of a tract of land,
of the alleged value of $15,000, situated in the State of Oregon.
The plaintiff asserts title to the premises by a patent of the
United States issued to him in 1866, under the act of Congress of
Sept. 27, 1850, usually known as the Donation Law of Oregon. The
defendant claims to have acquired the premises under a sheriff's
deed, made upon a sale of the property on execution issued upon a
judgment recovered against the plaintiff in one of the circuit
courts of the State. The case turns upon the validity of this
judgment.
It appears from the record that the judgment was rendered in
February, 1866, in favor of J. H. Mitchell, for less than $300,
including costs, in an action brought by him upon a demand for
services as an attorney; that, at the time the action was commenced
and the judgment rendered, the defendant therein, the plaintiff
here, was a nonresident of the State; Page 95 U. S. 720 that he was not personally served with process, and did not
appear therein; and that the judgment was entered upon his default
in not answering the complaint, upon a constructive service of
summons by publication.
The Code of Oregon provides for such service when an action is
brought against a nonresident and absent defendant who has property
within the State. It also provides, where the action is for the
recovery of money or damages, for the attachment of the property of
the nonresident. And it also declares that no natural person is
subject to the jurisdiction of a court of the State
"unless he appear in the court, or be found within the State, or
be a resident thereof, or have property therein; and, in the last
case, only to the extent of such property at the time the
jurisdiction attached."
Construing this latter provision to mean that, in an action for
money or damages where a defendant does not appear in the court,
and is not found within the State, and is not a resident thereof,
but has property therein, the jurisdiction of the court extends
only over such property, the declaration expresses a principle of
general, if not universal, law. The authority of every tribunal is
necessarily restricted by the territorial limits of the State in
which it is established. Any attempt to exercise authority beyond
those limits would be deemed in every other forum, as has been said
by this Court, an illegitimate assumption of power, and be resisted
as mere abuse. D'Arcy v. Ketchum et
al. , 11 How. 165. In the case against the
plaintiff, the property here in controversy sold under the judgment
rendered was not attached, nor in any way brought under the
jurisdiction of the court. Its first connection with the case was
caused by a levy of the execution. It was not, therefore, disposed
of pursuant to any adjudication, but only in enforcement of a
personal judgment, having no relation to the property, rendered
against a nonresident without service of process upon him in the
action or his appearance therein. The court below did not consider
that an attachment of the property was essential to its
jurisdiction or to the validity of the sale, but held that the
judgment was invalid from defects in the affidavit upon which the
order of publication was obtained and in the affidavit by which the
publication was proved. Page 95 U. S. 721 There is some difference of opinion among the members of this
Court as to the rulings upon these alleged defects. The majority
are of opinion that, inasmuch as the statute requires, for an order
of publication, that certain facts shall appear by affidavit to the
satisfaction of the court or judge, defects in such affidavit can
only be taken advantage of on appeal, or by some other direct
proceeding, and cannot be urged to impeach the judgment
collaterally. The majority of the court are also of opinion that
the provision of the statute requiring proof of the publication in
a newspaper to be made by the "affidavit of the printer, or his
foreman, or his principal clerk" is satisfied when the affidavit is
made by the editor of the paper. The term "printer," in their
judgment, is there used not to indicate the person who sets up the
type -- he does not usually have a foreman or clerks -- it is
rather used as synonymous with publisher. The Supreme Court of New
York so held in one case; observing that, for the purpose of making
the required proof, publishers were "within the spirit of the
statute." Bunce v. Reed, 16 Barb. (N. Y.) 350. And,
following this ruling, the Supreme Court of California held that an
affidavit made by a "publisher and proprietor" was sufficient. Sharp v. Daugney, 33 Cal. 512. The term "editor," as used
when the statute of New York was passed, from which the Oregon law
is borrowed, usually included not only the person who wrote or
selected the articles for publication, but the person who published
the paper and put it into circulation. Webster, in an early edition
of his Dictionary, gives as one of the definitions of an editor, a
person "who superintends the publication of a newspaper." It is
principally since that time that the business of an editor has been
separated from that of a publisher and printer, and has become an
independent profession.
If, therefore, we were confined to the rulings of the court
below upon the defects in the affidavits mentioned, we should be
unable to uphold its decision. But it was also contended in that
court, and is insisted upon here, that the judgment in the State
court against the plaintiff was void for want of personal service
of process on him, or of his appearance in the action in which it
was rendered and that the premises in controversy could not be
subjected to the payment of the demand Page 95 U. S. 722 of a resident creditor except by a proceeding in rem, that is, by a direct proceeding against the property for that
purpose. If these positions are sound, the ruling of the Circuit
Court as to the invalidity of that judgment must be sustained
notwithstanding our dissent from the reasons upon which it was
made. And that they are sound would seem to follow from two well
established principles of public law respecting the jurisdiction of
an independent State over persons and property. The several States
of the Union are not, it is true, in every respect independent,
many of the right and powers which originally belonged to them
being now vested in the government created by the Constitution.
But, except as restrained and limited by that instrument, they
possess and exercise the authority of independent States, and the
principles of public law to which we have referred are applicable
to them. One of these principles is that every State possesses
exclusive jurisdiction and sovereignty over persons and property
within its territory. As a consequence, every State has the power
to determine for itself the civil status and capacities of its
inhabitants; to prescribe the subjects upon which they may
contract, the forms and solemnities with which their contracts
shall be executed, the rights and obligations arising from them,
and the mode in which their validity shall be determined and their
obligations enforced; and also the regulate the manner and
conditions upon which property situated within such territory, both
personal and real, may be acquired, enjoyed, and transferred. The
other principle of public law referred to follows from the one
mentioned; that is, that no State can exercise direct jurisdiction
and authority over persons or property without its territory.
Story, Confl. Laws, c. 2; Wheat. Int. Law, pt. 2, c. 2. The several
States are of equal dignity and authority, and the independence of
one implies the exclusion of power from all others. And so it is
laid down by jurists as an elementary principle that the laws of
one State have no operation outside of its territory except so far
as is allowed by comity, and that no tribunal established by it can
extend its process beyond that territory so as to subject either
persons or property to its decisions. "Any exertion of authority of
this sort beyond this limit," says Story, "is a mere nullity, and
incapable of binding Page 95 U. S. 723 such persons or property in any other tribunals." Story,
Confl.Laws, sect. 539.
But as contracts made in one State may be enforceable only in
another State, and property may be held by nonresidents, the
exercise of the jurisdiction which every State is admitted to
possess over persons and property within its own territory will
often affect persons and property without it. To any influence
exerted in this way by a State affecting persons resident or
property situated elsewhere, no objection can be justly taken;
whilst any direct exertion of authority upon them, in an attempt to
give ex-territorial operation to its laws, or to enforce an
ex-territorial jurisdiction by its tribunals, would be deemed an
encroachment upon the independence of the State in which the
persons are domiciled or the property is situated, and be resisted
as usurpation.
Thus the State, through its tribunals, may compel persons
domiciled within its limits to execute, in pursuance of their
contracts respecting property elsewhere situated, instruments in
such form and with such solemnities as to transfer the title, so
far as such formalities can be complied with; and the exercise of
this jurisdiction in no manner interferes with the supreme control
over the property by the State within which it is situated. Penn v. Lord Baltimore, 1 Ves. 444; Massie v.
Watts , 6 Cranch 148; Watkins v.
Holman , 16 Pet. 25; Corbett v.
Nutt , 10 Wall. 464.
So the State, through its tribunals, may subject property
situated within its limits owned by nonresidents to the payment of
the demand of its own citizens against them, and the exercise of
this jurisdiction in no respect infringes upon the sovereignty of
the State where the owners are domiciled. Every State owes
protection to its own citizens, and, when nonresidents deal with
them, it is a legitimate and just exercise of authority to hold and
appropriate any property owned by such nonresidents to satisfy the
claims of its citizens. It is in virtue of the State's jurisdiction
over the property of the nonresident situated within its limits
that its tribunals can inquire into that nonresident's obligations
to its own citizens, and the inquiry can then be carried only to
the extent necessary to control the disposition of the property. If
the nonresident Page 95 U. S. 724 have no property in the State, there is nothing upon which the
tribunals can adjudicate.
These views are not new. They have been frequently expressed,
with more or less distinctness, in opinions of eminent judges, and
have been carried into adjudications in numerous cases. Thus, in Picquet v. Swan, 5 Mas. 35, Mr. Justice Story said:--
"Where a party is within a territory, he may justly be subjected
to its process, and bound personally by the judgment pronounced on
such process against him. Where he is not within such territory,
and is not personally subject to its laws, if, on account of his
supposed or actual property being within the territory, process by
the local laws may, by attachment, go to compel his appearance,
and, for his default to appear, judgment may be pronounced against
him, such a judgment must, upon general principles, be deemed only
to bind him to the extent of such property, and cannot have the
effect of a conclusive judgment in personam, for the plain
reason, that, except so far as the property is concerned, it is a
judgment coram non judice. "
And in Boswell's Lessee v.
Otis , 9 How. 336, where the title of the plaintiff
in ejectment was acquired on a sheriff's sale under a money decree
rendered upon publication of notice against nonresidents, in a suit
brought to enforce a contract relating to land, Mr. Justice McLean
said:--
"Jurisdiction is acquired in one of two modes: first, as against
the person of the defendant by the service of process; or,
secondly, by a procedure against the property of the defendant
within the jurisdiction of the court. In the latter case, the
defendant is not personally bound by the judgment beyond the
property in question. And it is immaterial whether the proceeding
against the property be by an attachment or bill in chancery. It
must be substantially a proceeding in rem. "
These citations are not made as authoritative expositions of the
law, for the language was perhaps not essential to the decision of
the cases in which it was used, but as expressions of the opinion
of eminent jurists. But in Cooper v. Reynolds, reported in
the 10th of Wallace, it was essential to the disposition of the
case to declare the effect of a personal action against an absent
party, without the jurisdiction of the court, not served Page 95 U. S. 725 with process or voluntarily submitting to the tribunal, when it
was sought to subject his property to the payment of a demand of a
resident complainant; and, in the opinion there delivered, we have
a clear statement of the law as to the efficacy of such actions,
and the jurisdiction of the court over them. In that case, the
action was for damages for alleged false imprisonment of the
plaintiff; and, upon his affidavit that the defendants had fled
from the State, or had absconded or concealed themselves so that
the ordinary process of law could not reach them, a writ of
attachment was sued out against their property. Publication was
ordered by the court, giving notice to them to appear and plead,
answer or demur, or that the action would be taken as confessed and
proceeded in ex parte as to them. Publication was had, but
they made default, and judgment was entered against them, and the
attached property was sold under it. The purchaser having been put
into possession of the property, the original owner brought
ejectment for its recovery. In considering the character of the
proceeding, the Court, speaking through Mr. Justice Miller,
said:--
"Its essential purpose or nature is to establish, by the
judgment of the court, a demand or claim against the defendant, and
subject his property lying within the territorial jurisdiction of
the court to the payment of that demand. But the plaintiff is met
at the commencement of his proceedings by the fact that the
defendant is not within the territorial jurisdiction, and cannot be
served with any process by which he can be brought personally
within the power of the court. For this difficulty, the statute has
provided a remedy. It says that, upon affidavit's being made of
that fact, a writ of attachment may be issued and levied on any of
the defendant's property, and a publication may be made warning him
to appear; and that thereafter the court may proceed in the case,
whether he appears or not. If the defendant appears, the cause
becomes mainly a suit in personam, with the added incident
that the property attached remains liable, under the control of the
court, to answer to any demand which may be established against the
defendant by the final judgment of the court. But if there is no
appearance of the defendant, and no service of process on him, the
case becomes in its essential nature a proceeding in rem, the only effect of which is to subject the property attached to the
payment of the demand which the court may find to be due to the
plaintiff. That such is Page 95 U. S. 726 the nature of this proceeding in this latter class of cases is
clearly evinced by two well established propositions: first, the
judgment of the court, though in form a personal judgment against
the defendant, has no effect beyond the property attached in that
suit. No general execution can be issued for any balance unpaid
after the attached property is exhausted. No suit can be maintained
on such a judgment in the same court, or in any other; nor can it
be used as evidence in any other proceeding not affecting the
attached property; nor could the costs in that proceeding be
collected of defendant out of any other property than that attached
in the suit. Second, the court in such a suit cannot proceed unless
the officer finds some property of defendant on which to levy the
writ of attachment. A return that none can be found is the end of
the case, and deprives the court of further jurisdiction, though
the publication may have been duly made and proven in court."
The fact that the defendants in that case had fled from the
State, or had concealed themselves, so as not to be reached by the
ordinary process of the court, and were not nonresidents, was not
made a point in the decision. The opinion treated them as being
without the territorial jurisdiction of the court, and the grounds
and extent of its authority over persons and property thus situated
were considered when they were not brought within its jurisdiction
by personal service or voluntary appearance.
The writer of the present opinion considered that some of the
objections to the preliminary proceedings in the attachment suit
were well taken, and therefore dissented from the judgment of the
Court, but, to the doctrine declared in the above citation, he
agreed, and he may add that it received the approval of all the
judges. It is the only doctrine consistent with proper protection
to citizens of other States. If, without personal service,
judgments in personam, obtained ex parte against
nonresidents and absent parties, upon mere publication of process,
which, in the great majority of cases, would never be seen by the
parties interested, could be upheld and enforced, they would be the
constant instruments of fraud and oppression. Judgments for all
sorts of claims upon contracts and for torts, real or pretended,
would be thus obtained, under which property would be seized, when
the evidence of the transactions upon Page 95 U. S. 727 which they were founded, if they ever had any existence, had
perished.
Substituted service by publication, or in any other authorized
form, may be sufficient to inform parties of the object of
proceedings taken where property is once brought under the control
of the court by seizure or some equivalent act. The law assumes
that property is always in the possession of its owner, in person
or by agent, and it proceeds upon the theory that its seizure will
inform him not only that it is taken into the custody of the court,
but that he must look to any proceedings authorized by law upon
such seizure for its condemnation and sale. Such service may also
be sufficient in cases where the object of the action is to reach
and dispose of property in the State, or of some interest therein,
by enforcing a contract or a lien respecting the same, or to
partition it among different owners, or, when the public is a
party, to condemn and appropriate it for a public purpose. In other
words, such service may answer in all actions which are
substantially proceedings in rem. But where the entire
object of the action is to determine the personal rights and
obligations of the defendants, that is, where the suit is merely in personam, constructive service in this form upon a
nonresident is ineffectual for any purpose. Process from the
tribunals of one State cannot run into another State, and summon
parties there domiciled to leave its territory and respond to
proceedings against them. Publication of process or notice within
the State where the tribunal sits cannot create any greater
obligation upon the nonresident to appear. Process sent to him out
of the State, and process published within it, are equally
unavailing in proceedings to establish his personal liability.
The want of authority of the tribunals of a State to adjudicate
upon the obligations of nonresidents, where they have no property
within its limits, is not denied by the court below: but the
position is assumed, that, where they have property within the
State, it is immaterial whether the property is in the first
instance brought under the control of the court by attachment or
some other equivalent act, and afterwards applied by its judgment
to the satisfaction of demands against its owner; or such demands
be first established in a personal action, and Page 95 U. S. 728 the property of the nonresident be afterwards seized and sold on
execution. But the answer to this position has already been given
in the statement that the jurisdiction of the court to inquire into
and determine his obligations at all is only incidental to its
jurisdiction over the property. Its jurisdiction in that respect
cannot be made to depend upon facts to be ascertained after it has
tried the cause and rendered the judgment. If the judgment be
previously void, it will not become valid by the subsequent
discovery of property of the defendant, or by his subsequent
acquisition of it. The judgment, if void when rendered, will always
remain void; it cannot occupy the doubtful position of being valid
if property be found, and void if there be none. Even if the
position assumed were confined to cases where the nonresident
defendant possessed property in the State at the commencement of
the action, it would still make the validity of the proceedings and
judgment depend upon the question whether, before the levy of the
execution, the defendant had or had not disposed of the property.
If, before the levy, the property should be sold, then, according
to this position, the judgment would not be binding. This doctrine
would introduce a new element of uncertainty in judicial
proceedings. The contrary is the law: the validity of every
judgment depends upon the jurisdiction of the court before it is
rendered, not upon what may occur subsequently. In Webster v.
Reid, reported in 11th of Howard, the plaintiff claimed title
to land sold under judgments recovered in suits brought in a
territorial court of Iowa, upon publication of notice under a law
of the territory, without service of process; and the court
said:
"These suits were not a proceeding in rem against the
land, but were in personam against the owners of it.
Whether they all resided within the territory or not does not
appear, nor is it a matter of any importance. No person is required
to answer in a suit on whom process has not been served, or whose
property has not been attached. In this case, there was no personal
notice, nor an attachment or other proceeding against the land,
until after the judgments. The judgments, therefore, are nullities,
and did not authorize the executions on which the land was sold.
" Page 95 U. S. 729 The force and effect of judgments rendered against nonresidents
without personal service of process upon them, or their voluntary
appearance, have been the subject of frequent consideration in the
courts of the United States and of the several States, as attempts
have been made to enforce such judgments in States other than those
in which they were rendered, under the provision of the
Constitution requiring that "full faith and credit shall be given
in each State to the public acts, records, and judicial proceedings
of every other State;" and the act of Congress providing for the
mode of authenticating such acts, records, and proceedings, and
declaring that, when thus authenticated,
"they shall have such faith and credit given to them in every
court within the United States as they have by law or usage in the
courts of the State from which they are or shall or taken."
In the earlier cases, it was supposed that the act gave to all
judgments the same effect in other States which they had by law in
the State where rendered. But this view was afterwards qualified so
as to make the act applicable only when the court rendering the
judgment had jurisdiction of the parties and of the subject matter,
and not to preclude an inquiry into the jurisdiction of the court
in which the judgment was rendered, or the right of the State
itself to exercise authority over the person or the subject matter. M'Elmoyle v.
Cohen , 13 Pet. 312. In the case of D'Arcy v.
Ketchum, reported in the 11th of Howard, this view is stated
with great clearness. That was an action in the Circuit Court of
the United States for Louisiana, brought upon a judgment rendered
in New York under a State statute, against two joint debtors, only
one of whom had been served with process, the other being a
nonresident of the State. The Circuit Court held the judgment
conclusive and binding upon the nonresident not served with
process, but this Court reversed its decision, observing, that it
was a familiar rule that countries foreign to our own disregarded a
judgment merely against the person, where the defendant had not
been served with process nor had a day in court; that national
comity was never thus extended; that the proceeding was deemed an
illegitimate assumption of power, and resisted as mere abuse; that
no faith and credit or force and effect had been given to such
judgments by any State of the Union, so far Page 95 U. S. 730 as known; and that the State courts had uniformly, and in many
instances, held them to be void. "The international law," said the
court,
"as it existed among the States in 1790, was that a judgment
rendered in one State, assuming to bind the person of a citizen of
another, was void within the foreign State, when the defendant had
not been served with process or voluntarily made defence, because
neither the legislative jurisdiction nor that of courts of justice
had binding force."
And the Court held that the act of Congress did not intend to
declare a new rule, or to embrace judicial records of this
description. As was stated in a subsequent case, the doctrine of
this Court is that the act
"was not designed to displace that principle of natural justice
which requires a person to have notice of a suit before he can be
conclusively bound by its result, nor those rules of public law
which protect persons and property within one State from the
exercise of jurisdiction over them by another." The Lafayette Insurance Co. v.
French et al. , 18 How. 404.
This whole subject has been very fully and learnedly considered
in the recent case of Thompson v.
Whitman , 18 Wall. 457, where all the authorities
are carefully reviewed and distinguished, and the conclusion above
stated is not only reaffirmed, but the doctrine is asserted that
the record of a judgment rendered in another State may be
contradicted as to the facts necessary to give the court
jurisdiction against its recital of their existence. In all the
cases brought in the State and Federal courts, where attempts have
been made under the act of Congress to give effect in one State to
personal judgments rendered in another State against nonresidents,
without service upon them, or upon substituted service by
publication, or in some other form, it has been held, without an
exception, so far as we are aware, that such judgments were without
any binding force except as to property, or interests in property,
within the State, to reach and affect which was the object of the
action in which the judgment was rendered, and which property was
brought under control of the court in connection with the process
against the person. The proceeding in such cases, though in the
form of a personal action, has been uniformly treated, where
service was not obtained, and the party did not voluntarily Page 95 U. S. 731 appear, as effectual and binding merely as a proceeding in
rem, and as having no operation beyond the disposition of the
property, or some interest therein. And the reason assigned for
this conclusion has been that which we have already stated -- that
the tribunals of one State have no jurisdiction over persons beyond
its limits, and can inquire only into their obligations to its
citizens when exercising its conceded jurisdiction over their
property within its limits. In Bissell v. Briggs, decided
by the Supreme Court of Massachusetts as early as 1813, the law is
stated substantially in conformity with these views. In that case,
the court considered at length the effect of the constitutional
provision, and the act of Congress mentioned, and after stating
that, in order to entitle the judgment rendered in any court of the
United States to the full faith and credit mentioned in the
Constitution, the court must have had jurisdiction not only of the
cause, but of the parties, it proceeded to illustrate its position
by observing, that, where a debtor living in one State has goods,
effects, and credits in another, his creditor living in the other
State may have the property attached pursuant to its laws, and, on
recovering judgment, have the property applied to its satisfaction,
and that the party in whose hands the property was would be
protected by the judgment in the State of the debtor against a suit
for it, because the court rendering the judgment had jurisdiction
to that extent; but that, if the property attached were
insufficient to satisfy the judgment, and the creditor should sue
on that judgment in the State of the debtor, he would fail because
the defendant was not amenable to the court rendering the judgment.
In other words, it was held that over the property within the State
the court had jurisdiction by the attachment, but had none over his
person, and that any determination of his liability, except so far
as was necessary for the disposition of the property, was
invalid.
In Kilbourn v. Woodworth, 5 Johns. (N.Y.) 37, an action
of debt was brought in New York upon a personal judgment recovered
in Massachusetts. The defendant in that judgment was not served
with process, and the suit was commenced by the attachment of a
bedstead belonging to the defendant, accompanied with a summons to
appear, served on his wife after she had left her place in
Massachusetts. The court held that Page 95 U. S. 732 the attachment bound only the property attached as a proceeding in rem, and that it could not bind the defendant,
observing, that to bind a defendant personally when he was never
personally summoned or had notice of the proceeding would be
contrary to the first principles of justice, repeating the language
in that respect of Chief Justice DeGrey, used in the case of Fisher v. Lane, 3 Wils. 297, in 1772. See also Borden
v. Fitch, 15 Johns. (N. Y.) 121, and the cases there cited,
and Harris v. Hardeman et
al. , 14 How. 334. To the same purport, decisions
are found in all the State courts. In several of the cases, the
decision has been accompanied with the observation that a personal
judgment thus recovered has no binding force without the State in
which it is rendered, implying that, in such State, it may be valid
and binding. But if the court has no jurisdiction over the person
of the defendant by reason of his nonresidence, and consequently no
authority to pass upon his personal rights and obligations; if the
whole proceeding, without service upon him or his appearance, is coram non judice and void; if to hold a defendant bound by
such a judgment is contrary to the first principles of justice --
it is difficult to see how the judgment can legitimately have any
force within the State. The language used can be justified only on
the ground that there was no mode of directly reviewing such
judgment or impeaching its validity within the State where
rendered, and that therefore it could be called in question only
when its enforcement was elsewhere attempted. In later cases, this
language is repeated with less frequency than formerly, it
beginning to be considered, as it always ought to have been, that a
judgment which can be treated in any State of this Union as
contrary to the first principles of justice, and as an absolute
nullity, because rendered without any jurisdiction of the tribunal
over the party, is not entitled to any respect in the State where
rendered. Smith v. McCutchen, 38 Mo. 415; Darrance v.
Preston, 18 Iowa, 396; Hakes v. Shupe, 27 id. 465; Mitchell's Administrator v. Gray, 18
Ind. 123.
Be that as it may, the courts of the United States are not
required to give effect to judgments of this character when any
right is claimed under them. Whilst they are not foreign tribunals
in their relations to the State courts, they are tribunals Page 95 U. S. 733 of a different sovereignty, exercising a distinct and
independent jurisdiction, and are bound to give to the judgments of
the State courts only the same faith and credit which the courts of
another State are bound to give to them.
Since the adoption of the Fourteenth Amendment to the Federal
Constitution, the validity of such judgments may be directly
questioned, and their enforcement in the State resisted, on the
ground that proceedings in a court of justice to determine the
personal rights and obligations of parties over whom that court has
no jurisdiction do not constitute due process of law. Whatever
difficulty may be experienced in giving to those terms a definition
which will embrace every permissible exertion of power affecting
private rights, and exclude such as is forbidden, there can be no
doubt of their meaning when applied to judicial proceedings. They
then mean a course of legal proceedings according to those rules
and principles which have been established in our systems of
jurisprudence for the protection and enforcement of private rights.
To give such proceedings any validity, there must be a tribunal
competent by its constitution -- that is, by the law of its
creation -- to pass upon the subject matter of the suit; and if
that involves merely a determination of the personal liability of
the defendant, he must be brought within its jurisdiction by
service of process within the State, or his voluntary
appearance.
Except in cases affecting the personal status of the plaintiff
and cases in which that mode of service may be considered to have
been assented to in advance, as hereinafter mentioned, the
substituted service of process by publication, allowed by the law
of Oregon and by similar laws in other States, where actions are
brought against nonresidents, is effectual only where, in
connection with process against the person for commencing the
action, property in the State is brought under the control of the
court, and subjected to its disposition by process adapted to that
purpose, or where the judgment is sought as a means of reaching
such property or affecting some interest therein; in other words,
where the action is in the nature of a proceeding in rem. As stated by Cooley in his Treatise on Constitutional Limitations
405, for any other purpose than to subject the property of a
nonresident to valid claims against Page 95 U. S. 734 him in the State, "due process of law would require appearance
or personal service before the defendant could be personally bound
by any judgment rendered."
It is true that, in a strict sense, a proceeding in rem is one taken directly against property, and has for its object the
disposition of the property, without reference to the title of
individual claimants; but, in a larger and more general sense, the
terms are applied to actions between parties where the direct
object is to reach and dispose of property owned by them, or of
some interest therein. Such are cases commenced by attachment
against the property of debtors, or instituted to partition real
estate, foreclose a mortgage, or enforce a lien. So far as they
affect property in the State, they are substantially proceedings in rem in the broader sense which we have mentioned.
It is hardly necessary to observe that, in all we have said, we
have had reference to proceedings in courts of first instance, and
to their jurisdiction, and not to proceedings in an appellate
tribunal to review the action of such courts. The latter may be
taken upon such notice, personal or constructive, as the State
creating the tribunal may provide. They are considered as rather a
continuation of the original litigation than the commencement of a
new action. Nations et al. v. Johnson et
al. , 24 How. 195.
It follows from the views expressed that the personal judgment
recovered in the State court of Oregon against the plaintiff
herein, then a nonresident of the State, was without any validity,
and did not authorize a sale of the property in controversy.
To prevent any misapplication of the views expressed in this
opinion, it is proper to observe that we do not mean to assert by
anything we have said that a State may not authorize proceedings to
determine the status of one of its citizens towards a nonresident
which would be binding within the State, though made without
service of process or personal notice to the nonresident. The
jurisdiction which every State possesses to determine the civil
status and capacities of all its inhabitants involves authority to
prescribe the conditions on which proceedings affecting them may be
commenced and carried on within its territory. The State, for
example, has absolute Page 95 U. S. 735 right to prescribe the conditions upon which the marriage
relation between its own citizens shall be created, and the causes
for which it may be dissolved. One of the parties guilty of acts
for which, by the law of the State, a dissolution may be granted
may have removed to a State where no dissolution is permitted. The
complaining party would, therefore, fail if a divorce were sought
in the State of the defendant; and if application could not be made
to the tribunals of the complainant's domicile in such case, and
proceedings be there instituted without personal service of process
or personal notice to the offending party, the injured citizen
would be without redress. Bish. Marr. and Div., sect. 156.
Neither do we mean to assert that a State may not require a
nonresident entering into a partnership or association within its
limits, or making contracts enforceable there, to appoint an agent
or representative in the State to receive service of process and
notice in legal proceedings instituted with respect to such
partnership, association, or contracts, or to designate a place
where such service may be made and notice given, and provide, upon
their failure, to make such appointment or to designate such place
that service may be made upon a public officer designated for that
purpose, or in some other prescribed way, and that judgments
rendered upon such service may not be binding upon the nonresidents
both within and without the State. As was said by the Court of
Exchequer in Vallee v. Dumergue, 4 Exch. 290,
"It is not contrary to natural justice that a man who has agreed
to receive a particular mode of notification of legal proceedings
should be bound by a judgment in which that particular mode of
notification has been followed, even though he may not have actual
notice of them." See also The Lafayette Insurance Co. v.
French et al. , 18 How. 404, and Gillespie v.
Commercial Mutual Marine Insurance Co., 12 Gray (Mass.), 201.
Nor do we doubt that a State, on creating corporations or other
institutions for pecuniary or charitable purposes, may provide a
mode in which their conduct may be investigated, their obligations
enforced, or their charters revoked, which shall require other than
personal service upon their officers or members. Parties becoming
members of such corporations or institutions would hold their Page 95 U. S. 736 interest subject to the conditions prescribed by law. Copin
v. Adamson, Law Rep. 9 Ex. 345.
In the present case, there is no feature of this kind, and
consequently no consideration of what would be the effect of such
legislation in enforcing the contract of a nonresident can arise.
The question here respects only the validity of a money judgment
rendered in one State in an action upon a simple contract against
the resident of another without service of process upon him or his
appearance therein. Judgment affirmed. MR. JUSTICE HUNT dissenting.
I am compelled to dissent from the opinion and judgment of the
court, and, deeming the question involved to be important, I take
leave to record my views upon it.
The judgment of the court below was placed upon the ground that
the provisions of the statute were not complied with. This is of
comparatively little importance, as it affects the present case
only. The judgment of this Court is based upon the theory that the
legislature had no power to pass the law in question; that the
principle of the statute is vicious, and every proceeding under it
void. It, therefore, affects all like cases, past and future, and
in every State.
The precise case is this: a statute of Oregon authorizes suits
to be commenced by the service of a summons. In the case of a
nonresident of the State, it authorizes the service of the summons
to be made by publication for not less than six weeks, in a
newspaper published in the county where the action is commenced. A
copy of the summons must also be sent by mail, directed to the
defendant at his place of residence, unless it be shown that the
residence is not known and cannot be ascertained. It authorizes a
judgment and execution to be obtained in such proceeding. Judgment
in a suit commenced by one Mitchell in the Circuit Court of
Multnomah County, where the summons was thus served, was obtained
against Neff, the present plaintiff, and the land in question,
situate in Multnomah County, was bought by the defendant Pennoyer
at a sale upon the judgment in such suit. This court now holds
that, by reason of the absence of a personal service of Page 95 U. S. 737 the summons on the defendant, the Circuit Court of Oregon had no
jurisdiction, its judgment could not authorize the sale of land in
said county, and, as a necessary result, a purchaser of land under
it obtained no title; that, as to the former owner, it is a case of
depriving a person of his property without due process of law.
In my opinion, this decision is at variance with the long
established practice under the statutes of the States of this
Union, is unsound in principle, and, I fear, may be disastrous in
its effects. It tends to produce confusion in titles which have
been obtained under similar statutes in existence for nearly a
century; it invites litigation and strife, and overthrows a well
settled rule of property.
The result of the authorities on the subject, and the sound
conclusions to be drawn from the principles which should govern the
decision, as I shall endeavor to show, are these:--
1. A sovereign State must necessarily have such control over the
real and personal property actually being within its limits, as
that it may subject the same to the payment of debts justly due to
its citizens.
2. This result is not altered by the circumstance that the owner
of the property is nonresident, and so absent from the State that
legal process cannot be served upon him personally.
3. Personal notice of a proceeding by which title to property is
passed is not indispensable; it is competent to the State to
authorize substituted service by publication or otherwise, as the
commencement of a suit against nonresidents, the judgment in which
will authorize the sale of property in such State.
4. It belongs to the legislative power of the State to determine
what shall be the modes and means proper to be adopted to give
notice to an absent defendant of the commencement of a suit; and if
they are such as are reasonably likely to communicate to him
information of the proceeding against him, and are in good faith
designed to give him such information, and an opportunity to defend
is provided for him in the event of his appearance in the suit, it
is not competent to the judiciary to declare that such proceeding
is void as not being by due process of law.
5. Whether the property of such nonresident shall be seized Page 95 U. S. 738 upon attachment as the commencement of a suit which shall be
carried into judgment and execution, upon which it shall then be
sold, or whether it shall be sold upon an execution and judgment
without such preliminary seizure, is a matter not of constitutional
power, but of municipal regulation only.
To say that a sovereign State has the power to ordain that the
property of nonresidents within its territory may be subjected to
the payment of debts due to its citizens, if the property is levied
upon at the commencement of a suit, but that it has not such power
if the property is levied upon at the end of the suit, is a
refinement and a depreciation of a great general principle that, in
my judgment, cannot be sustained.
A reference to the statutes of the different States, and to the
statutes of the United States, and to the decided cases, and a
consideration of the principles on which they stand, will more
clearly exhibit my view of the question.
The statutes are of two classes: first, those which authorize
the commencement of actions by publication, accompanied by an
attachment which is levied upon property, more or less, of an
absent debtor; second, those giving the like mode of commencing a
suit without an attachment.
The statute of Oregon relating to publication of summons, supra, p. 95 U. S. 718 ,
under which the question arises, is nearly a transcript of a series
of provisions contained in the New York statute, adopted thirty
years since. The latter authorizes the commencement of a suit
against a nonresident by the publication of an order for his
appearance, for a time not less than six weeks, in such newspapers
as shall be most likely to give notice to him, and the deposit of a
copy of the summons and complaint in the post office, directed to
him at his residence, if it can be ascertained; and provides for
the allowance to defend the action before judgment, and within
seven years after its rendition, upon good cause shown, and that,
if the defence be successful, restitution shall be ordered. It then
declares: "But the title to property sold under such judgment to a
purchaser in good faith shall not be thereby affected." Code,
sects. 34, 35; 5 Edm.Rev.Stat. of N.Y., pp. 37-39.
Provisions similar in their effect, in authorizing the
commencement of suits by attachment against absent debtors, in Page 95 U. S. 739 which all of the property of the absent debtor, real and
personal, not merely that seized upon the attachment, is placed
under the control of trustees, who sell it for the benefit of all
the creditors, and make just distribution thereof, conveying
absolute title to the property sold have been upon the statute book
of New York for more than sixty years. 2 id., p. 2 and
following; 1 Rev.Laws, 1813, p. 157.
The statute of New York, before the Code, respecting proceedings
in chancery where absent debtors are parties, had long been in use
in that State, and was adopted in all cases of chancery
jurisdiction. Whenever a defendant resided out of the State, his
appearance might be compelled by publication in the manner pointed
out. A decree might pass against him, and performance be compelled
by sequestration of his real or personal property, or by causing
possession of specific property to be delivered, where that relief
is sought. T he relief was not confined to cases of mortgage
foreclosure, or where there was a specific claim upon the property,
but included cases requiring the payment of money as well. 2
Edm.Rev.Stat. N.Y., pp. 193-195; 186, m.
I doubt not that many valuable titles are now held by virtue of
the provisions of these statutes.
The statute of California authorizes the service of a summons on
a nonresident defendant by publication, permitting him to come in
and defend upon the merits within one year after the entry of
judgment. Code, sects. 10,412, 10,473. In its general character, it
is like the statutes of Oregon and New York already referred
to.
The Code of Iowa, sect. 2618, that of Nevada, sect. 1093, and
that of Wisconsin, are to the same general effect. The Revised
Statutes of Ohio, sects. 70, 75, 2 Swan & Critchfield, provide
for a similar publication, and that the defendant may come in to
defend within five years after the entry of the judgment, but that
the title to property held by any purchaser in good faith under the
judgment shall not be affected thereby.
The attachment laws of New Jersey, Nixon Dig. (4th ed.), p. 55,
are like those of New York already quoted, by which title may be
transferred to all the property of a nonresident debtor. And the
provisions of the Pennsylvania statute regulating Page 95 U. S. 740 proceedings in equity, Brightly's Purden's Dig., p. 5988, sects.
51, 52, give the same authority in substance, and the same result
is produced as under the New York statute.
Without going into a wearisome detail of the statutes of the
various States, it is safe to say that nearly every State in the
Union provides a process by which the lands and other property of a
nonresident debtor may be subjected to the payment of his debts,
through a judgment or decree against the owner, obtained upon a
substituted service of the summons or writ commencing the
action.
The principle of substituted service is also a rule of property
under the statutes of the United States.
The act of Congress "to amend the law of the District of
Columbia in relation to judicial proceedings therein," approved
Feb. 23, 1867, 14 Stat. 403, contains the same general provisions.
It enacts (sect. 7) that publication may be substituted for
personal service when the defendant cannot be found in suits for
partition, divorce, by attachment, for the foreclosure of mortgages
and deeds of trust, and for the enforcement of mechanics' liens and
all other liens against real or personal property, and in all
actions at law or in equity having for their immediate object the
enforcement or establishment of any lawful right, claim, or demand
to or against any real or personal property within the jurisdiction
of the court.
A following section points out the mode of proceeding, and
closes in these words:
"The decree, besides subjecting the thing upon which the lien
has attached to the satisfaction of the plaintiff's demand against
the defendant, shall adjudge that the plaintiff recover his demand
against the defendant, and that he may have execution thereof as at
law."
Sect. 10.
A formal judgment against the debtor is thus authorized by means
of which any other property of the defendant within the
jurisdiction of the court, in addition to that which is the subject
of the lien, may be sold, and the title transferred to the
purchaser.
All these statutes are now adjudged to be unconstitutional and
void. The titles obtained under them are not of the value Page 95 U. S. 741 of the paper on which they are recorded, except where a
preliminary attachment was issued.
Some of the statutes and several of the authorities I cite go
further than the present case requires. In this case, property
lying in the State where the suit was brought, owned by the
nonresident debtor, was sold upon the judgment against him, and it
is on the title to that property that the controversy turns.
The question whether, in a suit commenced like the present one,
a judgment can be obtained which, if sued upon in another State,
will be conclusive against the debtor, is not before us; nor does
the question arise as to the faith and credit to be given in one
State to a judgment recovered in another. The learning on that
subject is not applicable. The point is simply whether land lying
in the same State may be subjected to process at the end of a suit
thus commenced.
It is here necessary only to maintain the principle laid down by
Judge Cooley in his work on Constitutional Limitations, p. 404, and
cited by Mr. Justice Field in Galpin v. Page, 3 Sawyer 93,
in these words:
"The fact that process was not personally served is a conclusive
objection to the judgment as a personal claim, unless the defendant
caused his appearance to be entered in the attachment proceedings.
Where a party has property in a State, and resides elsewhere, his
property is justly subject to all valid claims that may exist
against him there; but, beyond this, due process of law would
require appearance or personal service before the defendant could
be personally bound by any judgment rendered."
The learned author does not make it a condition that there
should be a preliminary seizure of the property by attachment; he
lays down the rule that all a person's property in a State may be
subjected to all valid claims there existing against him.
The objection now made that suits commenced by substituted
service, as by publication, and judgments obtained without actual
notice to the debtor, are in violation of that constitutional
provision that no man shall be deprived of his property "without
due process of law," has often been presented.
In Matter of the Empire City Bank, 18 N.Y. 199,
which Page 95 U. S. 742 was a statutory proceeding to establish and to enforce the
responsibility of the stockholders of a banking corporation, and
the proceedings in which resulted in a personal judgment against
the stockholders for the amount found due, the eminent and learned
Judge Denio, speaking as the organ of the Court of Appeals,
says:
"The notice of hearing is to be personal, or by service at the
residence of the parties who live in the county, or by
advertisement as to others. It may therefore happen that some of
the persons who are made liable will not have received actual
notice, and the question is whether personal service of process or
actual notice to the party is essential to constitute due process
of law. We have not been referred to any adjudication holding that
no man's right of property can be affected by judicial proceedings
unless he have personal notice. It may be admitted that a statute
which should authorize any debt or damages to be adjudged against a
person upon a purely ex parte proceeding, without a
pretence of notice or any provision for defending, would be a
violation of the Constitution, and be void; but where the
legislature has prescribed a kind of notice by which it is
reasonably probable that the party proceeded against will be
apprised of what is going on against him, and an opportunity is
afforded him to defend, I am of the opinion that the courts have
not the power to pronounce the proceeding illegal. The legislature
has uniformly acted upon that understanding of the
Constitution."
Numerous provisions of the statutes of the State are commented
upon, after which he proceeds:
"Various prudential regulations are made with respect to these
remedies; but it may possibly happen, notwithstanding all these
precautions, that a citizen who owes nothing, and has done none of
the acts mentioned in the statute, may be deprived of his estate
without any actual knowledge of the process by which it has been
taken from him. If we hold, as we must in order to sustain this
legislation, that the Constitution does not positively require
personal notice in order to constitute a legal proceeding due
process of law, it then belongs to the legislature to determine
whether the case calls for this kind of exceptional legislation,
and what manner of constructive notice shall be sufficient to
reasonably apprise the party proceeded against of the legal steps
which are taken against him. " Page 95 U. S. 743 In Happy v. Mosher, 48 id. 313, the court
say:
"An approved definition of due process of law is 'law in its
regular administration through courts of justice.' 2 Kent Com. 13.
It need not be a legal proceeding according to the course of the
common law, neither must there be personal notice to the party
whose property is in question. It is sufficient if a kind of notice
is provided by which it is reasonably probable that the party
proceeded against will be apprised of what is going on against him,
and an opportunity afforded him to defend."
The same language is used in Westervelt v. Gregg, 12 id. 202, and in Campbell v. Evans, 45 id. 356. Campbell v. Evans and The Empire
City Bank are cases not of proceedings against property to
enforce a lien or claim, but, in each of them, a personal judgment
in damages was rendered against the party complaining.
It is undoubtedly true, that, in many cases where the question
respecting due process of law has arisen, the case in hand was that
of a proceeding in rem. It is true also, as is asserted,
that the process of a State cannot be supposed to run beyond its
own territory. It is equally true, however, that, in every instance
where the question has been presented, the validity of substituted
service, which is used to subject property within the State
belonging to a nonresident to a judgment obtained by means thereof
has been sustained. I have found no case in which it is adjudged
that a statute must require a preliminary seizure of such property
as necessary to the validity of the proceeding against it, or that
there must have been a previous specific lien upon it; that is, I
have found no case where such has been the judgment of the court
upon facts making necessary the decision of the point. On the
contrary, in the case of the attachment laws of New York and of New
Jersey, which distribute all of the nonresident's property, not
merely that levied on by the attachment, and in several of the
reported cases already referred to, where the judgment was
sustained, neither of these preliminary facts existed.
The case of Galpin v.
Page , reported in 18 Wall. 350 and again in 3
Sawyer 93, is cited in hostility to the views I have expressed.
There may be general expressions which will justify Page 95 U. S. 744 this suggestion, but the judgment is in harmony with those
principles. In the case as reported in this Court, it was held that
the title of the purchaser under a decree against a nonresident
infant was invalid, for two reasons: 1st, that there was no
jurisdiction of the proceeding under the statute of California, on
account of the entire absence of an affidavit of nonresidence, and
of diligent inquiry for the residence of the debtor; 2d, the
absence of any order for publication in Eaton's case -- both of
which are conditions precedent to the jurisdiction of the court to
take any action on the subject. The title was held void, also, for
the reason that the decree under which it was obtained had been
reversed in the State court, and the title was not taken at the
sale, nor held then by a purchaser in good faith, the purchase
being made by one of the attorneys in the suit, and the title being
transferred to his law partner after the reversal of the decree.
The court held that there was a failure of jurisdiction in the
court under which the plaintiff claimed title, and that he could
not recover. The learned justice who delivered the opinion in the
Circuit Court and in this Court expressly affirms the authority of
a State over persons not only, but property as well, within its
limits, and this by means of a substituted service. The judgment so
obtained, he insists, can properly be used as a means of reaching
property within the State, which is thus brought under the control
of the court and subjected to its judgment. This is the precise
point in controversy in the present action.
The case of Cooper v.
Reynolds , 10 Wall. 308, is cited for the same
purpose. There, the judgment of the court below, refusing to give
effect to a judgment obtained upon an order of publication against
a nonresident, was reversed in this Court. The suit was commenced,
or immediately accompanied (it is not clear which), by an
attachment which was levied upon the real estate sold, and for the
recovery of which this action was brought. This Court sustained the
title founded upon the suit commenced against the nonresident by
attachment. In the opinion delivered in that case, there may be
remarks, by way of argument or illustration, tending to show that a
judgment obtained in a suit not commenced by the levy of an
attachment will not give title to land purchased under it. They
are, Page 95 U. S. 745 however, extrajudicial, the decision itself sustaining the
judgment obtained under the State statute by publication. Webster v.
Reid , 11 How. 437, is also cited. There, the action
involved the title to certain lands in the State of Iowa, being
lands formerly belonging to the half-breeds of the Sac and Fox
tribes; and title was claimed against the Indian right under the
statutes of June 2, 1838, and January, 1839. By these statutes,
commissioners were appointed who were authorized to hear claims for
accounts against the Indians, and commence actions for the same,
giving a notice thereof of eight weeks in the Iowa "Territorial
Gazette," and to enter up judgments which should be a lien on the
lands. It was provided that it should not be necessary to name the
defendants in the suits, but the words "owners of the half-breed
lands lying in Lee County" should be a sufficient designation of
the defendants in such suits; and it provided that the trials
should be by the court, and not by a jury. It will be observed that
the lands were not only within the limits of the territory of Iowa,
but that all the Indians who were made defendants under the name
mentioned were also residents of Iowa, and, for aught that appears
to the contrary, of the very county of Lee in which the proceeding
was taken. Nonresidence was not a fact in the case. Moreover, they
were Indians, and, presumptively, not citizens of any State, and
the judgments under which the lands were sold were rendered by the
commissioners for their own services under the act.
The court found abundant reasons, six in number, for refusing to
sustain the title thus obtained. The act was apparently an attempt
dishonestly to obtain the Indian title, and not intended to give a
substitution for a personal service which would be likely, or was
reasonably designed, to reach the persons to be affected.
The case of Voorhees v.
Jackson , 10 Pet. 449, affirmed the title levied
under the attachment laws of Ohio, and laid down the principle of
assuming that all had been rightly done by a court having general
jurisdiction of the subject matter.
In Cooper v. Smith, 25 Iowa, 269, it is said that where
no process is served on the defendant, nor property attached, nor
garnishee charged, nor appearance entered, a judgment based Page 95 U. S. 746 on a publication of the pendency of the suit will be void, and
may be impeached, collaterally or otherwise, and forms no bar to a
recovery in opposition to it, nor any foundation for a title
claimed under it. The language is very general, and goes much
beyond the requirement of the case, which was an appeal from a
personal judgment obtained by publication against the defendant,
and where, as the court say, the petition was not properly
verified. All that the court decided was that this judgment should
be reversed. This is quite a different question from the one before
us. Titles obtained by purchase at a sale upon an erroneous
judgment are generally good, although the judgment itself be
afterwards reversed. McGoon v.
Scales , 9 Wall. 311.
In Darrance v. Preston, 18 Iowa, 396, the distinction
is pointed out between the validity of a judgment as to the amount
realized from the sale of property within the jurisdiction of the
court and its validity beyond that amount. Picquet v.
Swan, 5 Mas. 35; Bissell v. Briggs, 9 Mass. 462; Ewer v. Coffin, 1 Cush. (Mass.) 23, are cited, but neither
of them in its facts touches the question before us.
In Drake on Attachment, the rule is laid down in very general
language; but none of the cases cited by him will control the
present case. They are the following:-- Eaton v. Bridger, 33 N. H. 228, was decided upon the
peculiar terms of the New Hampshire statute, which forbids the
entry of a judgment unless the debtor was served with process, or
actually appeared and answered in the suit. The court say the
judgment was "not only unauthorized by law, but rendered in
violation of its express provisions." Johnson v. Dodge was a proceeding in the same action to
obtain a reversal on appeal of the general judgment, and did not
arise upon a contest for property sold under the judgment. Carleton v. Washington Insurance Co., 35 id. 162,
and Bruce v. Cloutman, 45 id. 37, are to the same
effect and upon the same statute. Smith v. McCutchen, 38 Mo. 415, was a motion in the
former suit to set aside the execution by a garnishee, and it was
held that the statute was intended to extend to that class of
cases. Abbott v. Shepard, 44 id. 273, is to the
same effect, and is based upon Smith v. McCutchen,
supra. Page 95 U. S. 747 So, in Eastman v. Wadleigh, 65 Me. 251, the question
arose in debt on the judgment, not upon a holding of land purchased
under the judgment. It was decided upon the express language of the
statute of Maine, strongly implying the power of the legislature to
make it otherwise, had they so chosen.
It is said that the case where a preliminary seizure has been
made, and jurisdiction thereby conferred, differs from that where
the property is seized at the end of the action, in this: in the
first case, the property is supposed to be so near to its owner
that, if seizure is made of it, he will be aware of the fact, and
have his opportunity to defend, and jurisdiction of the person is
thus obtained. This, however, is matter of discretion and of
judgment only. Such seizure is not in itself notice to the
defendant, and it is not certain that he will by that means receive
notice. Adopted as a means of communicating it, and although a very
good means, it is not the only one, nor necessarily better than a
publication of the pendency of the suit, made with an honest
intention to reach the debtor. Who shall assume to say to the
legislature that, if it authorizes a particular mode of giving
notice to a debtor, its action may be sustained, but, if it adopts
any or all others, its action is unconstitutional and void? The
rule is universal that modes, means, questions of expediency or
necessity are exclusively within the judgment of the legislature,
and that the judiciary cannot review them. This has been so held in
relation to a bank of the United States, to the legal tender act,
and to cases arising under other provisions of the
Constitution.
In Jarvis v. Barrett, 14 Wis. 591, such is the holding.
The court say:
"The essential fact on which the publication is made to depend
is property of the defendant in the State, and not whether it has
been attached. . . . There is no magic about the writ [of
attachment] which should make it the exclusive remedy. The same
legislative power which devised it can devise some other, and
declare that it shall have the same force and effect. The
particular means to be used are always within the control of the
legislature, so that the end be not beyond the scope of legislative
power."
If the legislature shall think that publication and deposit in
the post office are likely to give the notice, there seems to
be Page 95 U. S. 748 nothing in the nature of things to prevent their adoption in
lieu of the attachment. The point of power cannot be thus
controlled.
That a State can subject land within its limits belonging to
nonresident owners to debts due to its own citizens as it can
legislate upon all other local matters -- that it can prescribe the
mode and process by which it is to be reached -- seems to me very
plain.
I am not willing to declare that a sovereign State cannot
subject the land within its limits to the payment of debts due to
its citizens, or that the power to do so depends upon the fact
whether its statute shall authorize the property to be levied upon
at the commencement of the suit or at its termination. This is a
matter of detail, and I am of opinion that, if reasonable notice be
given, with an opportunity to defend when appearance is made, the
question of power will be fully satisfied. | Here is a summary of the case verdict:
In Pennoyer v. Neff, the U.S. Supreme Court ruled on the validity of personal judgments made by state courts against non-residents who were served through publication of summons but had no personal service of process and did not appear. The Court held that such judgments are invalid and that no title to property can be transferred through sales under these judgments. While states have the right to hold and appropriate property within their territory to satisfy claims of their citizens, they cannot run processes into other states to summon defendants. Substituted service by publication is acceptable when determining property rights, but not for personal rights and obligations. The Court also discussed the discretion of legislatures in devising means of giving notice to debtors, emphasizing that this is a matter of expediency and necessity within legislative judgment. |
Lawsuits & Legal Procedures | Louisville & Nashville R. Co. v. Mottley | https://supreme.justia.com/cases/federal/us/211/149/ | U.S. Supreme Court Louisville & Nashville R. Co. v.
Mottley, 211
U.S. 149 (1908) Louisville and Nashville Railroad
Company v. Mottley No. 37 Argued October 13,
1908 Decided November 16,
1908 211
U.S. 149 APPEAL FROM THE CIRCUIT COURT OF
THE UNITED STATES FOR THE WESTERN DISTRICT OF
KENTUCKY Syllabus The jurisdiction of the circuit court is defined and limited by
statute; and, even if not questioned by either party, this Court
will, of its own motion, see to it that such jurisdiction is not
exceeded.
A suit arises under the Constitution and laws of the United
States, so as to give the circuit court jurisdiction on that
ground, only when plaintiff's statement of his own cause is based
thereon; that jurisdiction cannot be based on an alleged
anticipated defense which may Page 211 U. S. 150 be set up and which is invalid under some law or provision of
the Constitution of the United States.
The circuit court has no jurisdiction, in the absence of diverse
citizenship, of a suit brought against a railroad corporation to
enforce an alleged contract for an annual pass because, as stated
in the bill, the refusal is based solely on the anti-pass
provisions of the Hepburn Interstate Commerce Act of June 29, 1906,
c. 3591, 34 Stat. 584.
The practice in such cases is to reverse the judgment and remit
the case to the Circuit Court with instructions to dismiss the suit
for want of jurisdiction.
The appellees (husband and wife), being residents and citizens
of Kentucky, brought this suit in equity in the Circuit Court of
the United States for the Western District of Kentucky against the
appellant, a railroad company and a citizen of the same state. The
object of the suit was to compel the specific performance of the
following contract:
"Louisville, Ky., Oct. 2nd 1871"
"The Louisville & Nashville Railroad Company, in
consideration that E. L. Mottley and wife, Annie E. Mottley, have
this day released company from all damages or claims for damages
for injuries received by them on the 7th of September, 1871, in
consequence of a collision of trains on the railroad of said
company at Randolph's Station, Jefferson County, Kentucky, hereby
agrees to issue free passes on said railroad and branches now
existing or to exist, to said E. L. & Annie E. Mottley for the
remainder of the present year, and thereafter to renew said passes
annually during the lives of said Mottley and wife or either of
them."
The bill alleged that, in September, 1871, plaintiffs, while
passengers upon the defendant railroad, were injured by the
defendant's negligence, and released their respective claims for
damages in consideration of the agreement for transportation during
their lives, expressed in the contract. It is alleged that the
contract was performed by the defendant up to January 1, 1907, when
the defendant declined to renew the passes. The bill then alleges
that the refusal to comply with the contract Page 211 U. S. 151 was based solely upon that part of the Act of Congress of June
29, 1906, 34 Stat. 584, c. 3591, which forbids the giving of free
passes or free transportation. The bill further alleges: first,
that the act of Congress referred to does not prohibit the giving
of passes under the circumstances of this case, and second, that,
if the law is to be construed as prohibiting such passes, it is in
conflict with the Fifth Amendment of the Constitution, because it
deprives the plaintiffs of their property without due process of
law. The defendant demurred to the bill. The judge of the circuit
court overruled the demurrer, entered a decree for the relief
prayed for, and the defendant appealed directly to this Court.
MR. JUSTICE MOODY, after making the foregoing statement,
delivered the opinion of the Court.
Two questions of law were raised by the demurrer to the bill,
were brought here by appeal, and have been argued before us. They
are, first, whether that part of the Act of Congress of June 29,
1906, 34 Stat. 584, c. 3591, which forbids the giving of free
passes or the collection of any different compensation for
transportation of passengers than that specified in the tariff
filed makes it unlawful to perform a contract for transportation of
persons who, in good faith, before the passage of the act, had
accepted such contract in satisfaction of a valid cause of action
against the railroad; and, second, whether the statute, if it
should be construed to render such a contract unlawful, is in Page 211 U. S. 152 violation of the Fifth Amendment of the Constitution of the
United States. We do not deem it necessary, however, to consider
either of these questions, because, in our opinion, the court below
was without jurisdiction of the cause. Neither party has questioned
that jurisdiction, but it is the duty of this Court to see to it
that the jurisdiction of the circuit court, which is defined and
limited by statute, is not exceeded. This duty we have frequently
performed of our own motion. Mansfield &c. Railway Company
v. Swan, 111 U. S. 379 , 111 U. S. 382 ; King Bridge Company v. Otoe County, 120 U.
S. 225 ; Blacklock v. Small, 127 U. S.
96 , 127 U. S. 105 ; Cameron v. Hodges, 127 U. S. 322 , 127 U. S. 326 ; Metcalf v. Watertown, 128 U. S. 586 , 128 U. S. 587 ; Continental National Bank v. Buford, 191
U. S. 120 .
There was no diversity of citizenship, and it is not and cannot
be suggested that there was any ground of jurisdiction except that
the case was a "suit . . . arising under the Constitution or laws
of the United States." 25 Stat. 434, c. 866. It is the settled
interpretation of these words, as used in this statute, conferring
jurisdiction, that a suit arises under the Constitution and laws of
the United States only when the plaintiff's statement of his own
cause of action shows that it is based upon those laws or that
Constitution. It is not enough that the plaintiff alleges some
anticipated defense to his cause of action, and asserts that the
defense is invalidated by some provision of the Constitution of the
United States. Although such allegations show that very likely, in
the course of the litigation, a question under the Constitution
would arise, they do not show that the suit -- that is, the
plaintiff's original cause of action -- arises under the
Constitution. In Tennessee v. Union & Planters' Bank, 152 U. S. 454 , the
plaintiff, the State of Tennessee, brought suit in the circuit
court of the United States to recover from the defendant certain
taxes alleged to be due under the laws of the state. The plaintiff
alleged that the defendant claimed an immunity from the taxation by
virtue of its charter, and that therefore the tax was void because
in violation of the provision of the Constitution of the United Page 211 U. S. 153 states, which forbids any state from passing a law impairing the
obligation of contracts. The cause was held to be beyond the
jurisdiction of the circuit court, the court saying, by Mr. Justice
Gray (p. 152 U. S.
464 ):
"A suggestion of one party that the other will or may set up a
claim under the Constitution or laws of the United States does not
make the suit one arising under that Constitution or those
laws."
Again, in Boston & Montana Consolidated Copper &
Silver Mining Company v. Montana Ore Purchasing Company, 188 U. S. 632 , the
plaintiff brought suit in the circuit court of the United States
for the conversion of copper ore and for an injunction against its
continuance. The plaintiff then alleged, for the purpose of showing
jurisdiction, in substance, that the defendant would set up in
defense certain laws of the United States. The cause was held to be
beyond the jurisdiction of the circuit court, the Court saying, by
MR. JUSTICE PECKHAM (pp. 188 U. S.
638 -639):
"It would be wholly unnecessary and improper, in order to prove
complainant's cause of action, to go into any matters of defense
which the defendants might possibly set up, and then attempt to
reply to such defense, and thus, if possible, to show that a
federal question might or probably would arise in the course of the
trial of the case. To allege such defense and then make an answer
to it before the defendant has the opportunity to itself plead or
prove its own defense is inconsistent with any known rule of
pleading, so far as we are aware, and is improper."
"The rule is a reasonable and just one that the complainant in
the first instance shall be confined to a statement of its cause of
action, leaving to the defendant to set up in his answer what his
defense is, and, if anything more than a denial of complainant's
cause of action, imposing upon the defendant the burden of proving
such defense."
"Conforming itself to that rule, the complainant would not, in
the assertion or proof of its cause of action, bring up a single
federal question. The presentation of its cause of action would not
show that it was one arising under the Constitution or laws of the
United States. " Page 211 U. S. 154 "The only way in which it might be claimed that a federal
question was presented would be in the complainant's statement of
what the defense of defendants would be, and complainant's answer
to such defense. Under these circumstances, the case is brought
within the rule laid down in Tennessee v. Union & Planters'
Bank, supra. That case has been cited and approved many times
since."
The interpretation of the act which we have stated was first
announced in Metcalf v. Watertown, 128
U. S. 286 , and has since been repeated and applied in Colorado Central Consolidating Mining Company v. Turck, 150 U. S. 138 , 150 U. S. 142 ; Tennessee v. Union & Planters' Bank, 152 U.
S. 454 , 152 U. S. 459 ; Chappell v. Waterworth, 155 U. S. 102 , 155 U. S. 107 ; Postal Telegraph Cable Company v. Alabama, 155 U.
S. 482 , 155 U. S. 487 ; Oregon Short Line & Utah Northern Railway Company v.
Skottowe, 162 U. S. 490 , 162 U. S. 494 ; Walker v. Collins, 167 U. S. 57 , 167 U. S. 59 ; Muse v. Arlington Hotel Co., 168 U.
S. 430 , 168 U. S. 436 ; Galveston &c. Railway v. Texas, 170 U.
S. 226 , 170 U. S. 236 ; Third Street & Suburban Railway Company v. Lewis, 173 U. S. 457 , 173 U. S. 460 ; Florida Central & Peninsular Railroad Company v. Bell, 176 U. S. 321 , 176 U. S. 327 ; Houston & Texas Central Railroad Company v. Texas, 177 U. S. 66 , 177 U. S. 78 ; Arkansas v. Kansas & Texas Coal Company, 183 U.
S. 185 , 183 U. S. 188 ; Vicksburg Waterworks Company v. Vicksburg, 185 U. S.
65 , 185 U. S. 68 ; Boston & Montana Consolidated Copper & Silver Mining
Company v. Montana Ore Purchasing Co., 188 U.
S. 632 , 188 U. S. 639 ; Minnesota v. Northern Securities Company, 194 U. S.
48 , 194 U. S. 63 ; Joy v. City of St. Louis, 201 U.
S. 332 , 201 U. S. 340 ; Devine v. Los Angeles, 202 U. S. 313 , 202 U. S. 334 .
The application of this rule to the case at bar is decisive against
the jurisdiction of the circuit court.
It is ordered that the Judgment be reversed, and the case remitted to the circuit
court with instructions to dismiss the suit for want of
jurisdiction. | The Supreme Court reversed the lower court's decision and ordered the case to be dismissed for lack of jurisdiction. The Court held that the case did not arise under the Constitution or laws of the United States, as the plaintiffs' claim was based solely on a contract dispute with the railroad company, and the anticipated defense related to the Hepburn Interstate Commerce Act was not sufficient to establish federal jurisdiction. |
Lawsuits & Legal Procedures | Hess v. Pawloski | https://supreme.justia.com/cases/federal/us/274/352/ | U.S. Supreme Court Hess v. Pawloski, 274
U.S. 352 (1927) Hess v. Pawloski No. 263 Argued April 18, 1927 Decided May 16, 1927 274
U.S. 352 ERROR TO THE SUPERIOR COURT
OF WORCESTER COUNTY,
MASSACHUSETTS Syllabus Massachusetts Gen. Ls., c. 90, as amended by Stat. 1923, c. 431,
§ 2, which declares that use of the state's highways by a
nonresident motorist shall be deemed equivalent to an appointment
by him of the registrar as his attorney upon whom process may be
served Page 274 U. S. 353 in any action growing out of any accident or collision in which
the nonresident may be involved while operating a motor vehicle
upon such highway, and which provides for service in such case by
leaving a copy of the process and a fee with the registrar or in
his office, but conditions the sufficiency of the service upon the
sending of notice of it forthwith and a copy of the process to the
defendant by registered mail and upon his actually receiving and
receipting for the same, and which allows the nonresident when so
served such continuances as may be necessary to afford him a
reasonable opportunity to defend the action, held not in
conflict with the Due Process Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment. Kane v. New Jersey, 242 U. S. 160 . P. 274 U. S.
355 .
20 Mass. 22, 253 Mass. 478 affirmed.
Error to a judgment of the Superior Court of Worcester County,
Massachusetts, entered on rescript from the Supreme Judicial Court,
sustaining a verdict for damages in an action for personal injuries
inflicted on Pawloski, the plaintiff, by the negligent driving of a
motor vehicle, by Hess, nonresident defendant, on a Massachusetts
highway.
MR. JUSTICE BUTLER delivered the opinion of the Court.
This action was brought by defendant in error to recover damages
for personal injuries. The declaration alleged that plaintiff in
error negligently and wantonly drove a motor vehicle on a public
highway in Massachusetts, and that, by reason thereof, the vehicle
struck and injured defendant in error. Plaintiff in error is a
resident of Pennsylvania. No personal service was made on him, and
no property belonging to him was attached. The service of process
was made in compliance with c. Page 274 U. S. 354 90, General Laws of Massachusetts, as amended by Stat. 1923, c.
431, § 2, the material parts of which follow:
"The acceptance by a nonresident of the rights and privileges
conferred by section three or four, as evidence by his operating a
motor vehicle thereunder, or the operation by a nonresident of a
motor vehicle on a public way in the commonwealth other than under
said sections, shall be deemed equivalent to an appointment by such
nonresident of the registrar or his successor in office to be his
true and lawful attorney upon whom may be served all lawful
processes in any action or proceeding against him growing out of
any accident or collision in which said nonresident may be involved
while operating a motor vehicle on such a way, and said acceptance
or operation shall be a signification of his agreement that any
such process against him which is so served shall be of the same
legal force and validity as if served on him personally. Service of
such process shall be made by leaving a copy of the process with a
fee of two dollars in the hands of the registrar, or in his office,
and such service shall be sufficient service upon the said
nonresident, provided that notice of such service and a copy of the
process are forthwith sent by registered mail by the plaintiff to
the defendant, and the defendant's return receipt and the
plaintiff's affidavit of compliance herewith are appended to the
writ and entered with the declaration. The court in which the
action is pending may order such continuances as may be necessary
to afford the defendant reasonable opportunity to defend the
action."
Plaintiff in error appeared specially for the purpose of
contesting jurisdiction, and filed an answer in abatement and moved
to dismiss on the ground that the service of process, if sustained,
would deprive him of his property without due process of law in
violation of the Fourteenth Amendment. The court overruled the
answer in abatement and denied the motion. The Supreme Judicial Page 274 U. S. 355 Court held the statute to be a valid exercise of the police
power, and affirmed the order. Pawloski v. Hess, 250 Mass.
22. At the trial, the contention was renewed, and again denied.
Plaintiff in error excepted. The jury returned a verdict for
defendant in error. The exceptions were overruled by the Supreme
Judicial Court. Pawloski v. Hess, 253 Mass. 478. Thereupon
the superior court entered judgment. The writ of error was allowed
by the chief justice of that court.
The question is whether the Massachusetts enactment contravenes
the due process clause of the Fourteenth Amendment.
The process of a court of one state cannot run into another and
summon a party there domiciled to respond to proceedings against
him. Notice sent outside the state to a nonresident is unavailing
to give jurisdiction in an action against him personally for money
recovery. Pennoyer v. Neff, 95 U.
S. 741 . There must be actual service within the state of
notice upon him or upon some one authorized to accept service for
him. Goldey v. Morning News, 156 U.
S. 518 . A personal judgment rendered against a
nonresident, who has neither been served with process nor appeared
in the suit, is without validity. McDonald v. Mabee, 243 U. S. 90 . The
mere transaction of business in a state by nonresident natural
persons does not imply consent to be bound by the process of its
courts. Flexner v. Farson, 248 U.
S. 289 . The power of a state to exclude foreign
corporations, although not absolute, but qualified, is the ground
on which such an implication is supported as to them. Pennsylvania Fire Insurance Co. v. Gold Issue Mining Co., 243 U. S. 93 , 243 U. S. 96 .
But a state may not withhold from nonresident individuals the right
of doing business therein. The privileges and immunities clause of
the Constitution, § 2, Art. IV, safeguards to the citizens of one
state the right "to pass through, or to reside in any other state
for purposes of trade, agriculture, professional pursuits, or
otherwise." Page 274 U. S. 356 And it prohibits state legislation discriminating against
citizens of other states. Corfield v. Coryell, 4 Wash.
C.C. 371, 381. Ward v.
Maryland , 12 Wall. 418, 79 U. S. 430 ; Paul v.
Virginia , 8 Wall. 168, 75 U. S.
180 .
Motor vehicles are dangerous machines, and, even when skillfully
and carefully operated, their use is attended by serious dangers to
persons and property. In the public interest, the state may make
and enforce regulations reasonable calculated to promote care on
the part of all, residents and nonresidents alike, who use its
highways. The measure in question operates to require a nonresident
to answer for his conduct in the state where arise causes of action
alleged against him, as well as to provide for a claimant a
convenient method by which he may sue to enforce his rights. Under
the statute, the implied consent is limited to proceedings growing
out of accidents or collisions on a highway in which the
nonresident may be involved. It is required that he shall actually
receive and receipt for notice of the service and a copy of the
process. And it contemplates such continuances as may be found
necessary to give reasonable time and opportunity for defense. It
makes no hostile discrimination against nonresidents, but tends to
put them on the same footing as residents. Literal and precise
equality in respect of this matter is not attainable; it is not
required. Canadian Northern Ry. Co. v. Eggen, 252 U.
S. 553 , 252 U. S.
561 -562. The state's power to regulate the use of its
highways extends to their use by nonresidents, as well as by
residents. Hendrick v. Maryland, 235 U.
S. 610 , 235 U. S. 622 .
And, in advance of the operation of a motor vehicle on its highway
by a nonresident, the state may require him to appoint one of its
officials as his agent on whom process may be served in proceedings
growing out of such use. Kane v. New Jersey, 242 U.
S. 160 , 242 U. S. 167 .
That case recognized power of the state to exclude a nonresident
until the formal appointment is made. And, having the power so to
exclude, the state Page 274 U. S. 357 may declare that the use of the highway by the nonresident is
the equivalent of the appointment of the registrar as agent on whom
process may be served. Cf. Pennsylvania Fire Insurance Co. v.
Gold Issue Mining Co., supra, 243 U. S. 96 ; Lafayette Ins. Co. v.
French , 18 How. 404, 59 U. S.
407 -408. The difference between the formal and implied
appointment is not substantial, so far as concerns the application
of the due process clause of the Fourteenth Amendment. Judgment affirmed. | The Supreme Court upheld a Massachusetts law that allowed for service of process on nonresident motorists involved in accidents in the state by serving the registrar of motor vehicles, with notice sent to the nonresident by registered mail. The Court found that the law did not violate the Due Process Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment, as it provided sufficient notice and opportunities for defense, and treated nonresidents and residents equally in terms of legal responsibilities when using state highways. |
Lawsuits & Legal Procedures | Shoshone Mining Co. v. Rutter | https://supreme.justia.com/cases/federal/us/177/505/ | U.S. Supreme Court Shoshone Mining Co. v. Rutter, 177
U.S. 505 (1900) Shoshone Mining Co. v.
Rutter No. 208 Argued March 21, 1900 Decided April 30,
1900 177
U.S. 505 APPEAL FROM THE CIRCUIT
COURT OF APPEALS FOR THE NINTH
CIRCUIT Syllabus A suit brought in support of an adverse claim under Rev.Stat. §§
2325, 2326, is not a suit arising under the laws of the United
States in such a sense as to confer jurisdiction on a federal
court, regardless of the citizenship of the parties. Blackburn v. Portland Gold Mining Co., 175 U.
S. 571 , reexamined and affirmed to this point.
Although suits like the present one may sometimes so present
questions arising under the Constitution or laws of the United
States that a federal court will have jurisdiction, yet the mere
fact that a suit is an adverse suit, authorized by the statutes of
Congress, is not, in and of itself, sufficient to vest jurisdiction
in the federal courts.
The case is stated in the opinion.
MR. JUSTICE BREWER delivered the opinion of the court.
In Blackburn v. Portland Gold Mining Company, 175 U. S. 571 ,
decided January 8, 1900, we held that a suit brought in support of
an adverse claim under sections 2325 and 2326 of the Revised
Statutes was not a suit arising under the laws of the United States
in such a sense as to confer jurisdiction on a federal court,
regardless of the citizenship of the parties. In this case, the
same question is again presented, and has been elaborately argued
by counsel against the opinion we then announced. Its importance,
as well as the great ability with which it was argued by counsel
for appellee, have induced a careful reexamination of the question.
While it may be conceded Page 177 U. S. 506 that the matter is not free from doubt, nevertheless our
reexamination has not led us to change our former views. We deem it
unnecessary to restate all the reasons given in the opinion then
delivered, and yet some matters may appropriately be noticed.
By the Constitution, Article III, Section 2, the judicial power
of the United States extends "to all cases, in law and equity,
arising under this Constitution, the laws of the United States" and
to controversies "between citizens of different states." By Article
IV, Section 3, cl. 2, Congress is given "power to dispose of and
make all needful rules and regulations respecting the territory or
other property belonging to the United States." Under these
clauses, Congress might doubtless provide that any controversy of a
judicial nature arising in or growing out of the disposal of the
public lands should be litigated only in the courts of the United
States. The question therefore is not one of the power of Congress,
but of its intent. It has so constructed the judicial system of the
United States that the great bulk of litigation respecting rights
of property, although those rights may in their inception go back
to some law of the United States, is in fact carried on in the
courts of the several states. It has provided that the federal
courts shall have exclusive jurisdiction of admiralty and patent
litigation, and jurisdiction concurrent with the state courts of
suits arising under the Constitution or laws of the United States.
Rev.Stat. § 629; 25 Stat. 433, c. 866.
When, in section 2326, Rev.Stat., Congress authorized that which
is familiarly known in the mining regions as an "adverse suit," it
simply declared that the adverse claimant should commence
proceedings "in a court of competent jurisdiction." It did not in
express language prescribe either a federal or a state court, and
did not provide for exclusive or concurrent jurisdiction. If it had
intended that the jurisdiction should be vested only in the federal
courts, it would undoubtedly have said so. If it had intended that
any new rule of demarcation between the jurisdiction of the federal
and state courts should apply, it would likewise undoubtedly have
said so. Leaving the matter as it did, it unquestionably meant that
the competency of Page 177 U. S. 507 the court should be determined by rules theretofore prescribed
in respect to the jurisdiction of the federal courts. In that view,
if the adverse suit were between citizens of different states, and
the value of the thing in controversy exceeded $2,000, then, by
virtue of the general provisions of the statutes, the federal
courts might take jurisdiction, or, if the suit was one arising
under the Constitution or the laws of the United States, and the
amount in controversy was over $2,000, then also the federal courts
might take jurisdiction. Conversely, it would be true that if the
amount in controversy was not in excess of $2,000 or if the parties
were not citizens of different states and the suit was not one
arising under the Constitution or laws of the United States, the
federal courts could not take jurisdiction.
In the present case, diverse citizenship does not exist.
Jurisdiction must therefore depend upon the question whether the
suit is one arising under the Constitution or laws of the United
States.
We pointed out in the former opinion that it was well settled
that a suit to enforce a right which takes its origin in the laws
of the United States is not necessarily one arising under the
Constitution or laws of the United States within the meaning of the
jurisdiction clauses, for if it did, every action to establish
title to real estate (at least in the newer states) would be such a
one, as all titles in those states come from the United States or
by virtue of its laws. As said by Mr. Chief Justice Waite, in Gold Washing & Water Co. v. Keyes, 96 U. S.
199 , 96 U. S.
203 .
"The suit must, in part at least, arise out of a controversy
between the parties in regard to the operation and effect of the
Constitution or laws upon the facts involved. . . . Before,
therefore, a circuit court can be required to retain a cause under
this jurisdiction, it must in some form appear upon the record by a
statement of facts, 'in legal and logical form' such as is required
in good pleading, . . . that the suit is one which 'really and
substantially involves a dispute or controversy' as to a right
which depends upon the construction or effect of the Constitution
or some law or treaty of the United States."
The adverse suit, Rev.Stat. sec. 2326, is "to determine the
question of the right of possession." That right may or may Page 177 U. S. 508 not involve the construction or effect of the Constitution or a
law or treaty of the United States. By sections 2319, 2324 and
2332, Revised Statutes, it is expressly provided that this right of
possession may be determined by "local customs of rules of miners
in the several mining districts, so far as the same are applicable
and not inconsistent with the laws of the United States," or "by
the statute of limitations for mining claims of the state or
territory where the same may be situated." So that, in a given
case, the right of possession may not involve any question under
the Constitution or laws of the United States, but simply a
determination of local rules and customs, or state statutes, or
even only a mere matter of fact.
The recognition by Congress of local customs and statutory
provisions as at times controlling the right of possession does not
incorporate them into the body of federal law. Section 2 of Article
I of the Constitution provides that the electors in each State of
members of the House of Representatives "shall have the
qualifications requisite for electors of the most numerous branch
of the state legislature," but this does not make the statutes and
constitutional provisions of the various states in reference to the
qualifications of electors parts of the Constitution or laws of the
United States.
On August 8, 1890, Congress enacted (26 Stat. 313, c. 728) that
intoxicating liquors transported into any state or territory "shall
upon arrival in such state or territory be subject to the operation
and effect of the laws of such state or territory," etc., and in In re Rahrer, 140 U. S. 545 , 140 U. S. 561 ,
this Court said:
"Congress has not attempted to delegate the power to regulate
commerce, or to exercise any power reserved to the states, or to
grant a power not possessed by the states, or to adopt state
laws."
In Miller v. Swann, 150 U. S. 132 , 150 U. S. 136 ,
it appeared that the State of Alabama had passed an act containing
this provision:
"The said Alabama & Chattanooga Railroad Company shall have
the privilege and right of selling said lands or any part thereof
in accordance with the acts of Congress granting the same,"
and it was held:
"The question is not what rights passed to the state under Page 177 U. S. 509 the acts of Congress, but what authority the railroad company
had under the statute of the state. The construction of such a
statute is a matter for the state court, and its determination
thereof is binding on this Court. The fact that the state statute
and the mortgage refer to certain acts of Congress as prescribing
the rule and measure of the rights granted by the state does not
make the determination of such rights a federal question. A state
may prescribe the procedure in the federal courts as the rule of
practice in its own tribunals; it may authorize the disposal of its
own lands in accordance with the provisions for the sale of the
public lands of the United States, and in such cases an examination
may be necessary of the acts of Congress, the rules of the federal
courts, and the practices of the Land Department, and yet the
questions for decision would not be of a federal character. The
inquiry along federal lines is only incidental to a determination
of the local question of what the state has required and
prescribed. The matter decided is one of state rule and practice.
The facts by which that state rule and practice are determined may
be of a federal origin."
Inasmuch, therefore, as the "adverse suit" to determine the
right of possession may not involve any question as to the
construction or effect of the Constitution or laws of the United
States, but may present simply a question of fact as to the time of
the discovery of mineral, the location of the claim on the ground,
or a determination of the meaning and effect of certain local rules
and customs prescribed by the miners of the district, or the effect
of state statutes, it would seem to follow that it is not one which
necessarily arises under the Constitution and laws of the United
States.
As against this, we are met by these suggestions: first, that a
corporation created by Congress has a right to invoke the
jurisdiction of the federal courts in respect to any litigation
which it may have, except as specifically restricted by some act of
Congress. Osborn v. Bank of United
States , 9 Wheat. 738; Pacific Railroad Removal
Cases, 115 U. S. 1 . The
argument of Chief Justice Marshall in support of this was, briefly,
that a corporation has no powers and can incur no obligations
except as authorized or provided for in its charter. Its power to
do Page 177 U. S. 510 any act which it assumes to do, and its liability to any
obligation which is sought to be cast upon it, depend upon its
charter, and when such charter is given by one of the laws of the
United States, there is the primary question of the extent and
meaning of that law. In other words, as to every act or obligation,
the first question is whether that act or obligation is within the
scope of the law of Congress, and that being the matter which must
be first determined, a suit by or against the corporation is one
which involves a construction of the terms of its charter -- in
other words, a question arising under the law of Congress. But that
argument is not pertinent here. The right of the contestants in an
adverse suit, as we have seen, does not always call for any
construction of an act of Congress. It may depend solely on local
rules or customs or state statutes, and in that case does not
involve a dispute or controversy
"which depends upon the construction or effect of the
Constitution, or some law or treaty of the United States. . . . In
most actions concerning mining claims, the parties agree as to the
proper rule of construction to be applied to the mining laws, and
the controversies are usually limited to questions of fact relating
to the compliance with these laws. In such cases, the federal
courts have no original jurisdiction unless there is a diversity of
citizenship; but in cases arising under section 2326 of the Revised
Statutes, the authority for the action is found in the
legislation of Congress. Without this authority, the action for the
purposes avowed by the statute could not be maintained."
2 Lindley on Mines, sec. 748. A statute authorizing an action to
establish a right is very different from one which creates a right
to be established. An action brought under the one may involve no
controversy as to the scope and effect of the statute, while in the
other case it necessarily involves such a controversy, for the
thing to be decided is the extent of the right given by the
statute.
Again, it is said that this adverse suit is one step in the
administration of the laws of the United States in respect to
mineral lands, and therefore it must be presumed that Congress
intended that such step should rightfully be taken in one of the
courts of the United States. This suggestion was open to the Page 177 U. S. 511 consideration of Congress when it was determining where the
adverse suit should be brought, but that it did not consider it
vital is evident from the conceded fact that, unless the amount in
controversy is over $2,000, no jurisdiction attaches to the federal
court. In other words, Congress did not deem the matter of the
jurisdiction of those courts so essential a part of the
administration of the land laws of the United States as to vest in
them jurisdiction of all such controversies, but left a large, if
not a major, portion of them to be determined in the state courts.
It evidently contemplated the fact that a controversy about a right
of possession might as appropriately be decided in a state as in a
federal court, and, not prescribing in which court it should be
litigated, left the matter to be determined by the ordinary rules
in respect to the jurisdiction of the federal courts.
Counsel also calls our attention to the difference in the
procedure in the disposal of agricultural and mineral lands. With
respect to the former, all proceedings are carried on in the Land
Department, and it is only after the legal title has passed by
patent that inquiry is permissible in the courts, while in respect
to the latter, the aid of the courts is invoked before the issue of
a patent and in order to determine, to some extent, the right
thereto. Noticing this distinction, he also notes the fact that a
contest in respect to the validity of a patent for agricultural
lands can be litigated in the federal courts, and hence draws the
inference that a contest preliminary to a patent for mineral lands,
and involving the right thereto, must also be one which can be
litigated in the same courts. But we think the true inference from
this difference of procedure is to the contrary, because, in
respect to agricultural lands, it is settled that all questions of
fact are determined by the Land Department, and that, after the
issue of a patent, only questions of law are open for consideration
in the courts, and as the laws of Congress alone determine the
matter of the disposal of the public lands, it follows that the
questions of law which are thus open for consideration are those
arising under the acts of Congress. While on the other hand, as we
have heretofore shown, in these adverse suits preliminary to a
patent of mineral lands, not merely questions Page 177 U. S. 512 of law arising under the statutes of the United States, but
questions of fact and questions arising under local rules and
customs and state statutes are open for consideration. The scope of
the inquiry which is permissible in the two cases emphasizes the
fact that, in the latter case, the controversy may be one not
arising under the Constitution or laws of Congress.
Again, it is said that Congress has in these cases prescribed a
specific rule of limitation which is ordinarily different from that
obtaining under state statutes in respect to actions for the
recovery of possession; that it has authorized decrees in peculiar
form, some partly for and partly against each of the different
parties, and also some adversely to both. 21 Stat. 505, c. 140; Richmond Mining Co. v. Rose, 114 U.
S. 576 , 114 U. S. 585 ; Perego v. Dodge, 163 U. S. 160 , 163 U. S. 167 .
But incidental matters such as these are not decisive, especially
as confessedly the statute leaves the jurisdiction over those cases
in which the matter in controversy does not exceed $2,000 in value
in the state courts. This fact shows conclusively that Congress was
not intending to carve out a new jurisdiction for the federal
courts, and also that it did not doubt that the state courts would
carry into effect its enactments in reference to limitations and
procedure.
And finally it is said that Congress cannot confer any
jurisdiction on the state courts, that they may decline to
entertain these adverse suits, and that Congress cannot compel them
to do so. But here again we are met with the fact that Congress has
left all controversies in respect to right of possession, not
exceeding $2,000 in value, to the state courts. It evidently
proceeded upon the supposition (which is a rightful one) that, as
by the express terms of the Constitution, Article VI, clause 2,
"this Constitution, and the laws of the United States which
shall be made in pursuance thereof, . . . shall be the supreme law
of the land, and the judges in every state shall be bound thereby,
anything in the constitution or laws of any state to the contrary
notwithstanding,"
no courts, national or state, would decline to carry into effect
the acts of Congress. Whether, if a state court should refuse to
act under these statutes, the matter is one which could be
corrected by error in this Court is immaterial. Page 177 U. S. 513 If it shall appear that state courts decline to entertain such
jurisdiction, and that it cannot be enforced upon them, Congress
may further legislate. Evidently, thus far in these cases, as in
many others, there has been no reason to suppose that any state
court would decline to enforce the laws of the United States or to
carry into effect their provisions. And, as well said by Mr.
Justice Miller in Iron Silver Mining Co. v. Campbell, 135 U. S. 286 , 135 U. S.
299 :
"The purpose of the statute seems to be that where there are two
claimants to the same mine, neither of whom has yet acquired the
title from the government, they shall bring their respective claims
to the same property, in the manner prescribed in the statute,
before some judicial tribunal located in the neighborhood where the
property is, and that the result of this judicial investigation
shall govern the action of the officers of the Land Department in
determining which of these claimants shall have the patent, the
final evidence of title, from the government."
If every adverse suit could be taken into the federal courts,
obviously in some of the larger western states the litigation would
not be "before some judicial tribunal located in the neighborhood
where the property is," for in them the federal courts are often
held only in the capital or chief city of the state and at a great
distance from certain parts of the mining regions therein.
So we conclude, as we did in the prior case, that although these
suits may sometimes so present questions arising under the
Constitution or laws of the United States that the federal courts
will have jurisdiction, yet the mere fact that a suit is an adverse
suit authorized by the statutes of Congress is not, in and of
itself, sufficient to vest jurisdiction in the federal courts.
It appears that there were two cases in the Circuit Court of
Idaho, that they were there consolidated for trial, and the
consolidated case taken on appeal to the circuit court of appeals.
Of the two original cases, No. 81 on the docket of the circuit
court was commenced by the appellees in that court. The other, No.
102, was commenced by the appellant in the District Court of the
First Judicial District of the State of Idaho in and Page 177 U. S. 514 for Shoshone County, and by the appellees removed to the federal
court. The matters involved in the two cases were similar, and
hence the consolidation. Under these circumstances, and in view of
the conclusion to which we have arrived, the order will be that The judgment of the United States Circuit Court of Appeals
for the Ninth Circuit is reversed, and the case remanded to the
Circuit Court, Northern Division, District of Idaho, with
instructions to reverse its decree and enter a decree dismissing
case No. 81, and an order remanding case No. 102 to the state
court. MR. JUSTICE WHITE did not hear the argument and took no part in
the decision of this case.
MR. JUSTICE McKENNA dissents. | Shoshone Mining Co. v. Rutter (1900) concerns a dispute over mining claims and the jurisdiction of federal courts in such cases. The Supreme Court ruled that a lawsuit supporting an adverse claim under specific Revised Statutes does not constitute a case arising under US laws, thus federal courts cannot preside over such cases solely based on the nature of the claim. The Court acknowledged the importance of Congress's role in regulating disputes over public lands but emphasized that federal courts should not assume jurisdiction unless the case presents substantial questions arising under the Constitution or US laws. The decision highlights the Court's interpretation of federal judicial power and its deference to state courts in certain matters. |